J&f-.'g^ , CORNELL ^nfy- UNIVERSITY 75- LIBRARY F5/ I9ZI IIMMlllllliiiii?" ^y^'^i^^tic theology / 3 1924 010 376 030 DATE DUE j^ia.tJN 1 A "'^'WPHWMfe L V »B«sigjW*T' pW5«-fr»U4-. % CAYLORO ^NINTEDIN U S.A. Cornell University Library The original of tiiis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924010376030 LECTURES ON SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY EEV. CHARLES GRANDISON FIN>fEY, D.D. C^LECTURES ON SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY BY REV. CHARLES GRANDISON FINNEY, D.D. LATE PRESIDENT OF OBERLIN COLtEGE AND PROFESSOR OF THEOLOGY EDITED BY REV. J. H. FAIRCHILD LATE PRESIDENT OF OBERLIN COLLEGE WITH A PREFACE BY REV. GEORGE REDFORD, D.D. EDITOR OF THE ENGLISH EDITION NEW SiPjy YORK- ' >" '']0S GEORGE H. DORAN COMPANY.' X'- -< COPYRIGHT, 1878. BY E. I. GOODRICH PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA PXJBLISHER'S NOTE For over twenty years the plates of Rev. Charles G. Finney's Lectures on Systematic Theologt have been lost. The first edi- tion of this great work was published in 1846. The author was then President of Oberlin College as well as Professor of Theology in that institution. The work, like its author, made a profound impression on both sides of the Atlantic. In 1851 an edition was issued in [England. Dr. Finney revised and enlarged the copy for this edition, which contained a Preface by Rev. George Redford, D. D., of Wor- cester, England, who appeared on its title page as Editor. In 1878 a new American Edition, based on the English Edition, was issued by E. J. Goodrich, Oberlin, Ohio. This was condensed somewhat from the English Edition, but we are assured by the Editor that no changes whatever were made in Dr. Finney's thought. In 1899 the last Edition to be made before the plates were lost was published by E. J. Goodrich. This Edition was edited by Dr. J. H. Fairfield, the President of Oberlin College. The plates disap- peared soon afterward, and, the publishers having sold out the Edi- tion, the book became scarce and much sought after in second-hand editions. A few months ago Mr. Haylor, the present proprietor of the E. J. Goodrich Bookstore at Oberlin, searching in a dark and unused corner of the basement under the store, found some cases filled with metal which, upon being brought to the light, proved to be the long lost plates of the Systematic Theology. The work is now reissued in this new and improved form to carry on the message of its author to generations yet to come. NOTE BY THE EDITOR. Two editions of President Finney's Lectures on Systematic Theology have been published — ^the first in this country in 1846, the second in England in 1851, — the English edition being somewhat more full than its predecessor. Both editions have been exhausted, and the book has disappeared from the market. The present edition has been prepared from the English edition by a process of condensation, omitting, to some extent, restatements or repetitions of the argument, paragraphs of a hortatory character, and other parts not essential to the ex- pression or elucidation of the doctrine. Aside from these omissions, no changes have been made. No liberties have been taken with the author's style or thought. Every sentence is his own, and even in those parts where, in the judgment of the editor, the author's views are not elaborated with perfect consistency, as in the presentation of sin as selfish- ness, and in the lectures on sanctification, no attempt has been made to secure consistency, as might have been done by judi- cious omissions. The author was in the habit of thinking and speaking for himself while living, and no one can undertake to speak for him now that he is dead. This condensed edition, it is believed, will not be less valu- able, as an exponent of Mr. Finney's teaching, than the English edition, but even more valuable. Unnecessary bulk in a volume is a hinderance and discouragement to the reader. The topics will be found to be presented with all necessary fulness. J. H. F. OBBBLIN CJOIiLEOE, 1878. PREFACE, BY EEV. GEOEGE EEDFORD, D.D, EDrrOB OF THB ENGLISH EDITIOIT. The Lectures of the Rev. Pbopesbob Finitet, which are here given to the British public, were first delivered to the class of theological students at the Oberlin College, America, and subsequently published there. They were unknown in this country, except to a few of the Author's personal friends, until his arrival in England, about two years since. His name, however, was well known, and several of his works had been extensively read. The Editor having had the pleasure and honor of forming a per. sonal acquaintance with the Author soon after his arrival in this coun> try, did not long remain ignorant of his Theological Lectures. After his first hasty perusal of them, he ventured strongly to recommend their publication, both for the sake of making the British churches better acquainted with the Author's doctrinal views, and also on account of the direct benefit which students, and other inquirers into the theory of gospel doctrines, would be likely to derive from a work BO argumentative, and so unlike all the works on systematic and dog> matic theology known to the English schools. After due consultation and deliberation, the Author pressed upon the Editor the work of revision, and placed the Lectures in his hands, with the request that he would read them carefully, and suggest such alterations as he might deem desirable to adapt the work to the English reader ; and then submit the whole to the Author's adoption or rejection. This task the Editor undertook, and has performed in the best manner his time and ability would allow. The Author has carefully examined every part of his work again, and made such corrections and alterations as to him seemed needful. The Editor has merely per- formed the part of a friend, in suggesting such improvements as might VI PREFACE BY DR. REDFORD. make the Author's meaning better nnderstood ; but without interfer- ing with that meaning, and without intending to give it an unqualified approbation. In fact, the Lectures have been to a considerable extent re-written by the Author, and in this edition proceed as strictly from his own pen, as in the American edition. The Editor, however, would not have ventured to recommend the publication of these Lectures in this country, if he had not deemed them, as a whole, eminently deserving the attention and examination of British theologians. When they first came into his hands, they struck him as so pleasingly unlike all the other systems of dogmatic theology and moral philosophy it had ever beer his lot to peruse, so thorough in their grappling with difficulties, and often so successful in the solution of them; so skillfully adjusted to modern metaphysical speculations, and so comprehensive of what is valuable in them ; so manifestly the production of a masculine intellect and independent thinker, that he was not only pleased with the air of freshness and originality thrown over old themes of dry and elaborate discussion, but greatly benefited and instructed by some of the Author's views of important moral and theological questions. It may not be the same with all the Author's English readers ; but assuredly few will rise from the perusal of the whole work without confessing that, at least, they have seen some points in a new and impressive light, have been con- strained to think more closely of the opinions they hold, and in other respects have been benefited by the perusal. As a contribution to theological science, in an age when vague speculation and philosophical theories are bewildering many among all denominations of Christians, this work will be considered by all com- petent judges to be both valuable and seasonable. Upon several important and difficult subjects the Author has thrown a clear and valuable light which will guide many a student through perplexities and difficulties which he had long sought unsuccessfully to explain. The Editor frankly confesses, that when a student he would gladly have bartered half the books in his library to have gained a single perusal of these Lectures; and he cannot refrain from expressing the belief, that no young student of theology will ever regret the purchase or perusal of Mr. Finney's Lectures. One recommendation he begs respectfully to offer to all readers whether old or young ; it is this : suspend your judgment of the Author and his theology until you have gone completely through his woi'k. On many subjects, at the outset of the discussion, startling propositions may be found which will clash with your settled opinions ; PREFACE BY DR. REDFORD. vii bnt if you will calmly and patiently await the Author's explanation, and observe how he qualifies some strong or novel assertions, you will most probably find in the issue, that you have less reason than you supposed to object to his statements. In many respects Mr. Finney's theological and moral system will be found to differ both from the Oalvinistic and Arminian. In fact, it is a system of his own, if not in its separate portions, yet in its con- struction ; and as a whole is at least unique and compact ; a system which the Author has wrought out for himself, with little other aid than what he has derived from the fount itself of heavenly truth, and his own clear and strong perception of the-immutable moral principles and laws by which the glorious Author of the universe governs all his intellectual creatures. There is one circumstance that will recommend the volume, and ought to recommend it, to impartial inquirers who are not bound to the words of any master save their Divine one ; it is, that the Author in his youth was trained in none of the theological schools of his country, and had imbibed, therefore, no educational preference for one system more than another. He had been disciplined to argumenta- tion, logicf and the laws of evidence, in a very different arena ; and had advanced in the science of the Law before he had felt the truth of Christianity, or thought of studying its doctrines. His views, there- fore, will be found more deserving of attention and examination, from the fact of his mental independence in the formation of them. Should the work be read in a calm, devout, unprejudiced and jfiberal spirit, there can be no doubt that the reader will derive both pleasure and instruction. The earnestness, single-mindedness, deep piety, and eminent usefulness of the Author, both as a preacher and lecturer, justly entitle this production of his pen to the candid and patient investigation of English divines. Apart from the peculiarities which will be observed, and the criti- cal objections to which some will deem his theology justly liable, there can be no doubt that many will find in it a treasure of inestimable worth, a key to many perplexing enigmas, and a powerful reinforce- ment of their faith in the Christian verities. With at least the hope that such will be the effects of its publication in England, the Editor has cheerfully contributed his humble aid, and now commits the work to the blessing of Him by whose Word of Truth its real value must be finally tested. G. K. Worcettw, (Eng.) 1861. PEEFAOE BT THE ATJTHOE. 1. To a great extent, the truths of the blessed gospel have been hid- den under a false philosophy. In my early inquiries on the snbject of religion, I found myself wholly unable to understand either the oral or written instructions of uninspired religious teachers. They seemed to me to resolve all religion into states either of the intellect or of the sensi- bility, which my consciousness assured me were wholly passive or in- voluntary. When I sought for definitions and explanations, I felt as- sured that they did not well understand themselves. I was struck with the fact that they so seldom defined, even to themselves, their own posi- tions. Among the words of most frequent use, I could find scarcely a single term intelligibly defined. I inquired in what sense the terms " re- generation," "faith," "repentance," "love," etc., were used, but could obtain no answer, at which it did not appear to me that both reason and revelation revolted. The doctrines of a nature, sinful per ae, of a neces- sitated will, of inability, and of physical regeneration, and physical Divine influence in regeneration, with their kindred and resulting dog- mas, embarrassed and even confounded me at every step. I often said to myself, " If these things are really taught in the Bible, I must be an infidel." But the more I read my Bible, the more clearly I saw that these things were not found there upon any fair principles of interpreta- tion, such as would be admitted in a court of justice. I could not but perceive that the true idea of moral government had no place in the the- ology of the church ; and, on the contrary, that underlying the whole system were the assumptions that all government was physical, as op- posed to moral, and that sin and holiness are rather natural attributes, than moral, voluntary acts. These errors were not stated in words, but I could not fail to see that they were assumed. The distinction between original and actual sin, and the utter absence of a distinction between physical and moral depravity, embarrassed me. Indeed, I was satisfied either that I must be an infidel, or that these were errors that had no place in the Bible. I was often warned against reasoning and leaning to my own understanding. I found that the discriminating teachers of re- ligion were driven to confess that they could not establish the logical at PREFACE. consistency of their system, and that they were obliged to shut their eyes and believe, when revelation seemed to conflict with the affirmations of reason. But this course I could not take. I found, or thought I found, nearly all the doctrines of Christianity embarrassed by the assumptions above-named. But the Spirit of God conducted me through the dark- ness, and delivered me from ,the labyrinth and fog of a false philosophy, and set my feet upon the rock of truth, as I trust. But to this day I meet with those who seem to me to be in much confusion upon most of the practical doctrines of Christianity. They will admit, that sin and holiness must be voluntary, and yet speak of regeneration as consisting in anything but a voluntary change, and of Divine influence in regenera- tion, as anything but moral or persuasive. They seem not at all aware of what must follow from, and be implied in, the admission of the exist- ence of moral government, and that sin and holiness must be free and voluntary acts and states of mind. In this work I have endeavored to define the terms used by Christian divines, and the doctrines of Chris- tianity, as I understand them, and to push to their logical consequences the cardinal admissions of the more recent and standard theological writers. Especially do I urge, to their logical consequences, the two ad- missions that the.liFill js free, and that sin and holiness are voluntary acts of mifidt j I willf]^ot presume that I have satisfied others upon the points I .have disQus^ed, but I have succeeded at least in satisfying myself. I re- gard; the assertion, that the doctrines of theology cannot preserve a logi- cal consistency throughout, as both dangerous and ridiculous. 3. My principal design in publishing on Systematic Theology at first, was to furnish my pupils with a class or text-book, wherein many points and questions were discussed of great practical importance, but which have not, to my knowledge, been discussed in any system of theological instruction extant. I also hoped to benefit other studious and pious minds. 3. I have written for those who are willing to take the trouble of thinking and of forming opinions of their own on theological questions. It has been no part of my aim to spare my pupils or any one else the trouble of intense thought. Had I desired to do so, the subjects dis- cussed would have rendered such an attempt abortive. 4. There are many questions of great practical importance, and ques- tions in which multitudes are taking a deep interest at present, that can- not be intelligently settled without instituting fundamental inquiries in- volving the discussion of those questions that lie at the foundation of morality and religion. 5. Most of the subjects of dispute among Christians at the present day are founded in misconceptions upon the subjects discussed in this volume. ' If I have succeeded in settling the questions which I have discussed we PREFACE. X\ ■hall see, that in a future volume most of the suhjects of disagi'eement among Christians ab the present day can be satisfactorily adjusted with comparative ease. 6. What I have said on " Moral Law " and on the " Foundation of Moral Obligation " is the key to the whole subject. Whoever masters and understands these can readily understand all the rest. But he who will not possess himself of my meaning upon these subjects, will not understand the rest. 7. Let no one despair in commencing the book, nor stumble at the definitions, thinking that he can never understand so abstruse a subject. Remember that what follows is an expansion and an explanation by way of application, of what you find so condensed in the first pages of the book. My brother, sister, friend — read, study, think, and read again. You were made to think. It will do you good to think ; to develop your powers by study. God designed that religion should requii-e thought intense thought, and should thoroughly develop our powers of thought. The Bible itself is written in a style so condensed as to require much intense study. Many know nothing of the Bible or of religion, because they will not think and study. I do not pretend to so explain theology as to dispense with the labor of thinking. I have no ability and no wish to do so. 8. K any of my brethren think to convince me of error, they must first understand me, and show that they have read the book through, and that they understand it, and are candidly inquiring after truth and not "striving for masteries." If my brother is inquiring after truth, I will, by the grace of God, '< hear with both ears, and then judge." But I will not promise to attend to all that cavillers may say, nor to notice what those impertinent talkers and writers may say or write who must have controversy. But to all honest inquirers after truth I would say. Hail ! my brother ! Let us be thorough. Truth shall do us good. 9. It will be seen that the present volume contains only a part of a course of Systematic Theology. Should the entire course ever appear before the public, one volume will precede, and another succeed the present one. I published this volume first, because it contains all the points upon which I have been supposed to differ from the commonly received views. As a teacher of theology, I thought it due to the church and to the world, to give them my views upon those points upon which I had been accused of departing from the common opinions of Christians. 10. I have not yet been able to stereotype my theological views, and have ceased to expect ever to do so. The idea is preposterous. None but an omniscient mind can continue to maintain a precise identity of views and opinions. Finite minds, unless they are asleep or stultified by prejudice, must advance in knowledge. The discovery of new truth Xll PREFACE. will modify old views and opinions, and there is perhaps no end to thia process with finite minds in any world. True Christian consistency does not consist in stereotyping our opinions and views, and in refusing to make any improvement lest we should be guilty of change, but it consists in holding our minds open to receive the rays of truth from every quarter and in changing our views and language and practice as often and as fast, as we can obtain further information. I call this Christian consist- ency, because this course alone accords with a Christian profession. A Christian profession implies the profession of candor and of a disposi- tion to know and obey all truth. It must follow, that Christian consist- ency implies continued investigation and change of views and practice corresponding with increasing knowledge. No Christian, therefore, and no theologian should be afraid to change his views, his language, or his practices in conformity with increasing light. The prevalence of such a fear would keep the world, at best, at a perpetual stand-still, on all subjects of science, and consequently all improvements would be precluded. Every uninspired attempt to frame for the church an anthoritative standard of opinion which shall be regarded as an unquestionable exposi- tion of the word of God, is not only impious in itself, but it is also a tacit assumption of the fundamental dogma of Papacy. The Assembly of Divines did more than to assume the necessity of a Pope to give law to the opinions of men ; they assumed to create an immortal one, or rather to embalm their own creed, and preserve it as the Pope of all genera- tions ; or it is more just to say, that those who have adopted that con- fession of faith and catechism as an authoritative standard of doctrine, have absurdly adopted the most obnoxious principle of Popery, and elevated their confession and catechism to the Papal throne and into the place of the Holy Ghost. That the instrument framed by that assembly should in the nineteenth century be recognized as the standard of the church, or of an intelligent branch of it, is not only amazing, but I must say that it is highly ridiculous. It is as absurd in theology as it would be in any other branch of science, and as injurious and stultifying as it is absurd and ridiculous. It is better to have a living than a dead Pope. If we must have an authoritative expounder of the word of God, let us have a living one, so as not to preclude the hope of improvement. " A living dog is better than a dead lion ;" so a living Pope is better than a dead and stereotyped confession of faith, that holds all men bound to subscribe to its unalterable dogmas and its unvarying terminology. 11. I hold myself sacredly bound, not to defend these positions at all events, but on the contrary, to subject every one of them to the most thorough discussion, and to hold and treat them as I would the opinions of any one else ; that is, if upon further discussion and invesiiga'tion I PREFACE. XUl see no cause to change, I hold them fast ; but if I can see a flaw in any one of them, I shall amend or wholly reject it, as further light shall de- mand. Should I refuse or fail to do this, I should need to blush for my folly and inconsistency, for I say again, that true Christian consistency implies progress in knowledge and holiness, and such changes in theory and in practice as are demanded by increasing light. On the strictly fundamental questions in theology, my views have not, for many years, undergone any change, except as I have clearer appre- hensions of them than formerly, and should now state some of them, per- haps, in some measure, differently from what I should then have done. THE AUTHOR, CONTENTS. LECTUKE I. Moral Government. VAsa Definition of the term law. — Distinction between physical and moral law. — The essential attributes of moral law. — Subjectivity — Objectivity. — Liberty, as opposed to necessity. — Fitness. — Universality. — Impartiality. — Practicabil- ity. — Independence. — Immutability. — Unity. — Expediency. — Exclusivenesa. X LEOTUEE II. MOBAL Government — Qontinued. Definition of the term government. — Distinction between moral and physical government. — The fundamental reason of moral government. — Whose right it is to govern. — What is implied in the right to govern. — The limits of I3ii8 Hght. — Moral obligation. — The conditions of moral obligation 8 LEOTUEE III. MoBAi. Obligation. Man a sabject of moral obligation. — ^Extent of moral obligation 19 LEOTUEE IV. Foundation of Mobal Obligation. What is intended by the foundation of moral obligation. — Self-evident princi- ples. — That the sovereign will of God is not the foundation of moral obliga- tion. — The theory of Paley. — The utilitarian philosophy 37 LEOTUEE V. Foundation op Mobal Obligation. False Thbobibs. Right as the foundation of obligation 88 LEOTUEE VL Foundation of Mobal Obligation. False Thboeies. The goodness or moral excellence of God as the foundation of obligation 49 XVI CONTENTS. LECTUKE 711. Foundation of Moral Obliqatiow. False Theobieb. FAOB Moral order as the foundation of obligation. — The nature and relations of moral beings as the true foundation of obligation. — Moral obligation as founded in the idea of duty. — The complexity of the founf!*tion of obligation. — Sum- ming up 64 LECTURE VIII. Foundation of Moiial Obligation. Pbactical BRMaiNos of the diffek- ENT THEOBIES. The theory that regards the sovereign will of God as tU« foundation of moral obligation. — The theory of the selfish school. — The n'ttural and necessary results of utilitarianism.— ^Practical bearings and tendency of rightarianism. —The practical bearings of the true theory of the found^'^ln of obligation 8C LECTUEE IX. Unity of Mobal Action. What constitutes obedience to moral law. — Obedience cannot be p tW.— Possi- ble suppositions. — Objections considered 95 LECTURE X. Obedience entieb. Nothing virtue but obedience to the law of God. — No rule of duty b» w<»wl law. — Condition of justification ., , 116 LECTURE XI. Obedience to the Mobal Law. . What 1b not implied in entire obedience to the law. of God 'j« LECTURE Xn. Attributes op Love. Certain facts revealed in consciousness. — Attributes of that love which const!- tutes obedience to the law. — Voluntariness. — Liberty. — Intelligence. — Vir- tuousness. — Disinterestedness. — Impartial) ty. — Universality 13J LECTURE XIII. Attributes op Love — Continued. Efficiency.— Complacency. — Opposition to sin. — Compassion , 145 CONTENTS. XVU LECTURE XIV. Attbibutbb of Lovb — Continued. vua Meioy^— Jnatioe. — Yeracity 167 LECTURE XV. Attbibdtes of Love — Continued. Patience. — Meekness. — Self-denial. — Condescension. — Stability. — Holiness, or Purity ; 166 LECTURE XVI. DiBOBEDIEKCE TO MOKAL LiAW. What disobedience to moral law cannot consist in. — What disohedience to moral law must consist in 180 LECTURE XVIL Attributes of Selfishness. Voluntariness. — Liberty. — Intelligence. — Unreasonableness. — Interestedness.— Partiality. — Efficiency. — Opposition to benevolence or to virtue. — Cruelty. — Injustice 188 LECTURE XVIIL Attributes of Selfishness — Continued. Falsehood, or lying. — ^Pride. — Intemperance. — Total moral depravity 196 LECTURE XIX. Sanctions of Moral Law. What constitutes the sanctions of law. — In what light sanctions are to be re- garded. — Duration of the penal sanctions of the law of God 208 LECTURE XX. Human Government. rhe ultimate end of God in Creation. — Providential and moral governments in- dispensable to the highest good of the universe. — Human governments a necessity of human nature. — This necessity will continue as long as human beings exist in this world. — Human governments are plainly recognized in the Bible as a part of the moral government of God. — Objections answered. — The limits gt ihe right of governpient. .,.,,,,..,.,,,..,.,.,.,,,...,,.,,. 314 XVUl CONTENTS. LEOTUEB XXL HtJMAN Government — Oontinued. PAOX No form of civil government univerBally obligatory. — Revolutions. — In what cases human legislation is valid, and in what cases it is null and void. — The rights and duties of governments and subjects in relation to the execution of the penalties of law 222 LEOTUEB XXII. I Moral Depravity. Definition. — Distinction between physical and moral depravity. — Mankind both physically and morally depraved. — Moral depravity of mankind universal. — Moral depravity total 228 LEOTUEB XXIIL Moral Depravity — Continued. Proper method of accounting for moral depravity. — Dr. Woods' view of physical and moral depravity examined. — Standards of the Presbyterian Church ex- amined 236 LEOTUEB XXIV. Moral Depravity — Gontinued. Further arguments in support of the position that human nature is in itself sin- ful. — The proper method of accounting for moral depravity. — Summary of the truth on this subject. — Remarks 845 LEOTUEB XXV. Atonement. Established governmental principles. — The term atonement. — Affirmations of reason upon the subject. — The fact of atonement. — Christ's obedience did not constitute the atonement. — The atonement not a commercial transaction. — The atonement a satisfaction of public justice 25B LEOTUEB XXVL Extent of Atonement. For whose benefit the atonement was intended. — Objections answered 974 LEOTUEB XXVIL Regeneration. The common distinction between regeneration and conversion. The assigned reasons for this distinction. — Objections to this distinction. — What regenera- CONTENTS. xix FAGS tion ia. — The univereal neceseity ot regeneration. — Agencies employed in regeneration. — Insti^imentalities employed in the work. — The subject both passive and active. — What is implied in regeneration 282 LEOTURB XXVIII. Bbgbneration — Continued. Different theories of regeneration examined. — The taste scheme. — The divine efficiency scheme. — The susceptibility scheme. — Theory of a divine moral suasion. — Objections to this theory. — Bemarks 291 LECTURE XXIX. Evidences of Regeneration. Wherein saints and sinners may agree. — Remarks 800 LECTURE XXX. Evidences of Regeneration— Coraimtted.; Wherein saints and sinners must difier 309 LEOTURB XXXL Natural Abilitt. The Edwardean notion of ability and of natural inability. — Natural ability identi- cal with freedom or liberty of will. — The human will free.— Moral inability according to the Edwardean school. — This distinction between natural and moral inability nonsensical. — Fundamental error of the Edwardean school ' on the subject of ability. — Another scheme of inability 320 LECTURE XXXIL Gracious Abilitt. What is intended by the term. — ^This doctrine absurd. — In what sense a gracious ability is possible 341 LECTURE XXXIIL The Notion of Inabilitt. Proper mode of accounting for it 858 LECTURE XXXIV. Repentance and Impenitence. What repentance is not, and what it is. — What is implied in it. — What impeni- tence is not. — What it is. — Some things that are implied in it. — Some evi- dences of it. ..,...,,.,. ,.., , ,....,...,... f 804 XX CONTENTS. LECTURE XXXV. Faith and Unbelief. TAmm What evangelicfil faith is not. — What it is. — What is implied in it. — What nn- belief is not. — What it is. — What is implied in it. — Ckinditions of both faith and unbelief. — The guilt of unbelief. — Consequences of both faith and un- belief 373 LECTURE XXXVL JUSTIPICATION. What justification is not. — What it is. — Conditions of justification. — Foundation of justification 883 LECTURE XXXVIL Sanctification; Some points that have been settled. — Definition of terms. — The real question. — Entire sanctification attainable in this life .' 40S LECTURE XXXVIIL Sanctificatiow. Panl entirely sanctified 438 LECTURE XXXIX. Sanctification. Conditions of its attainmeTit. — Relations of Christ to the soul 438 LECTURE XL. Sanctification. Objections answered 448 LECTURE XLL Sanctification. Objections continued 401 LECTURE XLIL Sanctification. CONTENTS. XXI LECTURE XLIII. BleotloB /..... 481 LECTURE XLIV. ReprobatirtD 499 LECTURE XLV. Divine Sovereignty 619 LECTURE XLVL PurpoBes of Qod 634 LECTURE XLVIL Perseverance op Saints. The different kinds of certainty. — What is not intended by the perseverance of the saints 644 LECTURE XLVIIL Perseverance of Saints. The doctrine proved 654 LECTURE XLIX. Perseverance ov Saints. Farther proof 668 LECTURE L. Perseverance of Saints. Objections considered S85 LECTURE LL Pbkseyerancb of Saints. Tarther objeotions , 60S LECTURES ON SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY SYSTEMATIC THEOLOaY. LECTURE I. MORAL LAW. Law, in a sense of the term both sufficiently popular and scientific for my purpose, is A eulb of action. In its generic signification, it is applicable to every kind of action, whether of matter or of mind— whether intelligent or unintelligent — whether free or necessary action. Physical law is a term that represents the order of sequence, in all the changes that occur under the law of necessity, whether in matter or mind. I mean all changes whether of state or action, that do not consist in the states or actions of free will. Physical law is the law of the ma- terial universe. It is also the law of mind, so far as its states and changes are involuntary. All mental states or actions, which are not free and sovereign actions of will, must occur under, and be subject to, physical law. They cannot possibly be accounted for, except as they are ascribed to the law of necessity or force. Moral law is a rule of moral action with sanctions. It is that rule to which moral agents ought to conform all their voluntary actions, and is enforced by sanctions equal to the value of the precept. It is the rule for the government of free and intelligent action, as opposed to neces- sary and unintelligent action. It is the law of liberty, as opposed to the law of necessity — of motive and free choice, as opposed to force of every kind. Moral law is primarily a rule for the direction of the action of free will, and strictly of free will only. But secondarily, and less strictly, it is the rule for the regulation of all those actions and states of mind and body, that follow the free actions of will by a law of necessity. Thus, moral law controls involuntary mental states and outward action only by securing conformity of the actions of free will to its precept. The essential attributes of moral law, are, 1. Subjectivity. It is, and must be, an idea of reason developed in the mind of the subject. It is an idea, or conception, of that state of will, 2 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. or course of action, which is obligatory upon a moral agent, No one can be a moral agent, or the subject of moral law, unless he has this idea developed ; for this idea is identical with the law. It is the law devel- oped or revealed within himself ; and thus he becomes " a law to him- self," his own reason aflBrming his obligation to conform to this idea, or law. 3. Objectivity. Moral law may be regarded as a rule of duty, pre- jcribed by the supreme Lawgiver, and external tp self. When thus con- templated, it is objective. 3. Liberty, as opposed to necessity. The precept must lie developed in ihe reason, as a rule of duty — a law of moral obligation — a rule of choice, or of ultimate intention, declaring that which a moral agent ought to choose, will, intend. But it does not, must not, can not possess the attribute of necessity in its relations to the actions of free will. It must not, cannot, possess an element or attribute of force, in any such sense as to render conformity of will to its precept unavoidable. This would confound it with physical law. 4. Fitness. It must be the law of nature, that is, its precept must prescribe and require just those actions of the will which are suitable to the nature and relations of moral beings, and nothing more nor less ; that is, the intrinsic value of the well-being of God and of the uni- verse being given as the ground, and the nature and relations of moral beings as the condition of the obligation, the reason hereupon necessarily affirms the intrinsic propriety and fitness of choosing this good, and of consecrating the whole being to its promotion. This is what is intended by the law of nature. It is the law or rule of action imposed on us by God, in and by the nature which he has given us. 5. Universality. The conditions and circumstances being the same, it requires, and must require, of all moral agents, the same things, in whatever world they may be found. 6. Impartiality. Moral law is no respecter of persons — ^knows no privileged classes. It demands one thing of all, without regard to any- thing, except the fact that they are moral agents. By this it is not in- tended that the same course of outward conduct is required of all ; but the same state of heart in all — that all shall have one ultimate intention — that all shall consecrate themselves to one end — that all shall entirely conform, in heart and life, to their nature and relations. 7. Practicability. That which the precept demands must be possible to the subject. That which demands a natural impossibility is not, and cannot be, moral law. The true definition of law excludes the supposi- tion that it can, under any circumstances, demand an absolute impossi- bility. Such a demand could not be in accordance with the nature and relations of moral agents, and therefore practicability must always be an MORAL LAW. 3 attribute of moral law. To talk of inability to obey moral law is to talk nonsense. "~- 8. Independence. It is an eternal and necessary idea of the divine reason. It is the eternal, self-existent rule of the divine conduct, the law which the intelligence of God prescribes to himself. Moral law, as we shall see hereafter more fully, does not, and cannot originate in the will of God. It eternally existed in the divine reason. It is the idea of that state of will which is obligatory upon God, upon condition of his natural attributes, or, in other words, upon condition of his nature. As a law, it is entirely independent of his will, just as his own existence is. It is obligatory also upon every moral agent, entirely independent of the will of God. Their nature and relations being given, and their intelli- gence being developed, moral law must be obligatory upon them, and it lies not in the option of any being to make it otherwise. Their nature and relations being given, to pursue a course of conduct suited to their nature and relations, is necessarily and self- evidently obligatory, inde- pendent of the will of any being. 9. Immutability. Moral law can never change, or be changed. It always requires of every moral agent a state of heart, and course of con- duct, precisely suited to his nature and relations. Whatever his nature is, his capacity and relations are, entire conformity to just that nature, those capacities and relations, so far as he is able to understand them, is required at every moment, and nothing more or less. If capacity is en- larged, the subject is not thereby rendered capable of works of superero- gation — of doing more than the law demands ; for the law still, as always, requires the full consecration of his whole being to the public in- terests. If by any means whatever, his ability is abridged, moral law, always and necessarily consistent with itself, still requires that what is left — ^nothing more or less — shall be consecrated to the same end as be- fore. Whatever demands more or less than entire, universal, and con- stant conformity of heart and life, to the nature, capacity and relations of moral agents, be they what they may, is not, and cannot be moral law. If therefore, the capacity is by any means abridged, the subject does not thereby become incapable of rendering full obedience ; for the law still demands and urges, that the heart and life shall be fully conformed to the present, existing nature, capacity, and relations. Anything that re- quires more or less than this, cannot be moral law. Moral law invari- ably holds one language. It never changes its requirement. "Thou shalt love," or be perfectly benevolent, is its uniform and its only demand. This demand it never varies, and never can vary. It is as immutable as God is, and for the same reason. To talk of letting down, or altering moral law, is to talk absurdly. The thing is naturally impossible. No being has the right or the power to do so. The supposition overlooks the very I ststematic theology. nature of moral law. Moral law is not a statute, an enactment, that baa its origin or its foundation in the win of any being. It is the law of nature, the law which the nature or constitution of every moral agent imposes on himself and which God imposes upon us because it is entirely mited to our nature and relations, and is therefore naturally obligatory upon us. It is the unalterable demand of the reason, that the whole be- ing, whatever there is of it at any time, shall be entirely consecrated to i;he highest good of universal being, and for this reason God requires this }f us, with all the weight of his authority. 10. Unity. Moral law proposes but one ultimate end of pursuit to Uod, and to all moral agents. All its requisitions, in their spirit, are summed up and expressed in one word, love or henevolence. This I only announce here. It will more fully appear hereafter. Moral law is a pure and simple idea of the reason. It is the idea of perfect, universal, and constant consecration of the whole being to the highest good of being. Just this is, and nothing more nor less can be, moral law ; for just this, and nothing more nor less, is a state of heart and a course of life exactly suited to the nature and relations of moral agents, which is the only true definition of moral law. 11. Expediency. That which is upon the whole most wise is expedi- ent. That which is upon the whole expedient is demanded by moral law. True expediency and the spirit of moral law are always identicaL Expediency may be inconsistent with the letter, but never with the spirit of moral law. Law in the form of commandment is a revelation or dec- laration of that course which is expedient. It is expediency revealed, as in the case of the decalogue, and the same is true of every precept of the Bible, it reveals to us what is expedient. A revealed law or command- ment is never to be set aside by our views of expediency. We may know with certainty that what is required is expedient. The command is the expressed judgment of God in the case, and reveals with unerring cer- tainty the true path of expediency. When Paul says, " All things are lawful unto me, but all things are not expedient," we must not under- stand him as meaning that all things in the absolute sense were lawful to him, or that anything that was not expedient was lawful to him. But he '^'^"btless intended, that many things were inexpedient that are not expressly prohibited by the letter of the law, — that the spirit of the law prohibited many things not expressly forbidden by the letter. It should nRver be forgotten that that which is plainly demanded by the highest good of the universe is law. It is expedient. It is wise. The true spirit of the moral law does and must demand it. So, on the other hand, whatever is plainly inconsistent with the highest good of the universe is illegal, unwise, inexpedient, and must be prohibited by the spirit of moral law. But let the thought be repeated, that the Bible precepts always MORAL LAW. 5 NTeal that whicli is traly expedient, and in no case are we at liberty to Bet aside the spirit of any commandment upon the supposition that ex- pediency requires it. Some have denounced the doctrine of expediency altogether, as at all times inconsistent with the law of right. These philosophers proceed upon the assumption that the law of right and the law of benevolence are not identical but inconsistent with each other. This is a common but fundamental mistake, which leads me to remark that — ^Law proposes the highest good of universal being as its end, aad re- quires all moral agents to consecrate themselves to the promotion of this end. Consequently, expediency must be one of its attributes. That which is upon the whole in the highest degree useful to the universe must be demanded by moral law. Moral law must, from its own nature, require just that course of willing and acting that is upon the whole in the high- est degree promotive of the public good, — in other words, that which is upon the whole in the highest degree useful, and therefore expedient. It has been strangely and absurdly maintained that right would be ob- ligatory if it necessarily tended to and resulted in universal and perfect misery. Than which a more nonsensical afQrmation was never made. The afQrmation assumes that the law of right and of good-will are not only distinct, but may be antagonistic. It also assumes that that can be law that is not suited to the nature and relations of moral agents. Cer- tainly it will not be pretended that that course of willing and acting that necessarily tends to, and results in, universal misery, can be consistent with the nature and relations of moral agents. Nothing is or can be suited to their nature and relations, that is not upon the whole promo- tive of their highest well-being. Expediency and right are always and necessarily at one. They can never be inconsistent. That which is upon the whole most expedient is right, and that which is right is upon the whole expedient. 12. Exclusiveness. Moral law is the only possible inile of moral ob- ligation. A distinction is usually made between moral, ceremonial, civil and positive laws. This distinction is in some respects convenient, but is liable to mislead, and to create an impression that something can be ob- ligatory, in other words can be law, that has not the attributes of moral law. Nothing can be law, in any proper sense of the term, that is not and would not be universally obligatory upon moral agents under the game circumstances. It is law because, and only because, under all the circumstances of the case, the course prescribed is fit, proper, suitable, to their natures, relations, and circumstances. There can be no other rule of action for moral agents but moral law, or the law of benevolence. Every other rule is absolutely excluded by the very nature of moral law. Surely there can be no law that is or can be obligatory upon moral agents but one suited to, and founded in their nature, relations, and cir- 6 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. cumstancelB. This is and must be the law of love or benevolence. This is the law of right, and nothing else is or can be. Every thing else that claims to be law, and to impose obligation upon moral agents, mast be an imposition and " a thing of nought." LECTURE 11. MOEAL GOVERNMENT. The primary idea of government, is that of direction, guidance, control by, or in accordance with, rule or law. All government is, and must be, either moral or physical ; that is, all guidance and control must be exercised in accordance with either moral or physical law ; for there can be no laws that are neither moral nor physical. Physical government is control, exercised by a law of necessity or force, as distinguished from the law of free will, or liberty. It is the control of substance, as opposed to free will. The only government of which substance, as distinguished from free will, is capable, is and must be physical. This is true, whether the substance be material or imma- terial, whether matter or mind. States and changes, whether of matter or mind, that are not actions of free will, must be subject to the law of necessity. They must therefore belong to the department of physical government. Physical government, then, is the administration of phys- ical law, or the law of force. Moral government consists in the declaration and administration of moral law. It is the government of free will by motives as distinguished from the government of substance by force. Physical government pre- sides over and controls physical states and changes of substance or con- stitution, and all involuntary states and changes, Moral government presides over and controls, or seeks to control the actions of free will : it presides over intelligent and voluntary states and changes of mind. It is a government of motive, as opposed to a government of force — con- trol exercised, or sought to be exercised, in accordance with the law of liberty, as opposed to the law of necessity. It is the administration of moral as opposed to physical law. Moral government includes the dispensation of rewards and punish- ments ; and is administered by means as complicated and vast as the whole of the works, and providence, and ways, and grace of God. MORAL GOVERNMENT. 1 7%e fundamental reason of moral government. Government must be founded in a good and sufficient reason, or it is not right. No one has a right to prescribe rules for, and control the conduct of another, unless there is some good reason for his doing so. There must be a necessity for moral government, or the administration of it is tyranny. Moral government is indispensable to the highest well- being of the universe of moral agents. The universe is dependent upon this as a means of securing the highest good. This dependence is a good and sufficient reason for the existence of moral government. Let it be understood, then, that moral government is a necessity of moral beings, and therefore right. Our nature and circumstances demand that we should be under a moral government ; because no community can perfectly harmonize in all their views and feelings, without perfect knowledge, or to say the least, the same degree of knowledge on all subjects on which they are called to act. But no community ever existed, or will exist, in which all possess exactly the same amount of knowledge, and where the mem- bers are, therefore, entirely agreed in all their thoughts, views, and opinions. But if they are not agreed in opinion, or have not exactly the same amount of knowledge, they will not, in every thing, harmonize, as it respects their courses of conduct. There must, therefore, be in every community, some standard or rule of duty, to which sill the subjects of the community are to conform themselves. There must be some head or controlling mind, whose will shall be law, and whose decision shall be regarded as infallible, by all the subjects of the government. However diverse their intellectual attainments are, in this they must all agree, that the will of the lawgiver is right, and universally the rule of duty. This will must be authoritative, and not merely advisory. There must of necessity be a penalty attached to, and incurred by, every act of dis- obedience to this will. If disobedience be persisted in, exclusion from the privileges of the government is the lowest penalty that can consis- tently be inflicted. The good, then, of the universe imperiously requires that there should be a moral governor. Whose right is it to govern ? We have just seen that the highest well-being of the universe demands, and is the end of moral government. It must, therefore, be his right and duty to govern, whose attributes, physical and moral, best qualify him to secure the end of government. To him all eyes and hearts should be directed, to fill this station, to exercise this control, to administer all just and necessary rewards and punishments. It is both his right and duty to govern. That God is a moral governor, we infer— 8 SrSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. 1. From our own nature. From the very laws of our being, we naturally affirm onr responsibility to him for our conduct. As God is our creator, we are naturally responsible to him for the right exercise of our powers. And as our good and his glory depend upon our conformity to the same rule to which he conforms his whole being, he is under a moral obligation to require us to be holy, as he is holy. 2. His natural attributes qualify him to sustain the relation of a moral governor to the universe. 3. His moral character also qualifies him to sustain this relation. 4. His relation to the universe as creator and preserver, when con- sidered in connection with the necessity of government, and with his nature and attributes, confers on him the right of universal government. 5. His relation to the universe, and our relations to him and to each other, render it obligatory upon him to establish and administer a moral government over the universe. It would be wrong for him to create a universe of moral beings, and then refuse or neglect to administer over them a moral government, since government is a necessity of their nature and relations. 6. His happiness must demand it, as he could not be happy unless he acted in accordance with his conscience. 7. If God is not a moral governor he is not wise. Wisdom consists in the choice of the best ends, and in the use of the most appropriate means to accomplish those ends. If God is not a moral governor, it is inconceivable that he should have had any important end in view in the creation of moral beings, or that he should have chosen the best or any suitable means for the promotion of their happiness as the most desirable end. 8. The conduct or providence of God plainly indicates a design to exert a moral influence over moral agents. 9. His providence plainly indicates that the universe of mind is governed by moral laws, or by laws suited to the nature of moral agents. 10. If God is not a moral governor, the whole universe, so far as we have the means of knowing it, is calculated to mislead mankind in respect to this fundamental truth. All nations have believed that God is a moral governor. 11. We must disapprove the character of God, if we ever come to a knowledge of the fact that he created moral agents, and then exercised over them no moral government. 12. The Bible, which has been proved to be a revelation from God, contains a most simple and yet comprehensive system of moral govern- ment. 13. If we are deceived in respect to our being subjects of moral gov- ernment, we are sure of nothing. MORAL GOVERNMENT. What is implied in the right to govern f 1. From what has just been said, it mnst be evident, that the right to govern implies the necessity of government, as a means of securing an intrinsically valuable end. 2. Also that the right to govern implies the duty, or obligation to govern. There can be no right, in this case, without corresponding obli- gation ; for the right to govern is founded in the necessity of govern- ment, and the necessity of government imposes obligation to govern. 3. The right to govern, implies obligation, on the part of the subject, to obey. It cannot be the right, or duty, of the governor to govern, un- less it is the duty of the subject to obey. The governor and subjects are alike dependent upon government, as the indispensable means of pro- moting the highesl^ good. The governor and the subject must, there- fore, be under reciprocal obligation, the one to govern, and the other to be governed, or to obey. The one must seek to govern, the other must submit to be governed. 4 The right to -govern, implies the right and duty to dispense just and necessary rewards and punishments — distribute rewards proportioned to merit, and penalties proportioned to demerit, whenever the public in- terest demands their execution. 5. It implies obligation, on the part of the subject, cheerfully to ac- quiesce in any measure that may be necessary to secure the end of gov- ernment, and in case of disobedience, to submit to merited punishment, and also, if necessary, to aid in the infliction of the penalty of law. 6. It implies obligation, on the part both of the ruler and the ruled, to be always ready, and when occasion arises, actually to make any per- sonal and private sacrifice demanded by the higher public good — to cheerfully meet any emergency, and exercise any degree of self-denial, that can, and will, result in a good of greater value to the public than that sacrificed by the individual, or by any number of individuals, it always being understood, that present voluntary sacrifices shall have an ultimate reward. 7. It implies the right and duty to employ any degree of force, which is indispensable to the maintenance of order, the execution of wholesome laws, the suppression of insurrections, the punishment of rebels and dis- organizers, and sustaining the supremacy of moral law. It is impossible that the right to govern should not imply this ; and to deny this right, is to deny the right to govern. Should an emergency occur, in which a ruler had no right to use the indispensable means of securing order, and the supremacy of law, the moment this emergency occurred, his right to govern would, and must, cease : for it is impossible that it should be his right to govern, unless it be at the game time, and for the same reason, 10 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. his duty to govern ; and it is absurd to say, that it is his right and duty to govern, and yet at the same time, that he has not a right to use the in- dispensable means of government. If it be asked, whether an emer^ncy like the one under consideration is possible, and if so what might justly, be regarded as such an emergency, I answer, that should circum- stances occur under which the sacrifice necessary to sustain, would overbalance the good to be derived from the prevalence of government, this would create the emergency under consideration, in which the right to govern would cease. The limits of this right. The right to govern is, and must be, just co-extensive with the neces- sity of government. We have seen, that the right to govern is founded in the necessities of moral beings. In other words, the right to govern is founded upon the fact, that the highest good of moral agents cannot be secured, but by means of government. But to avoid mistake, and to correct erroneous impressions, which are sometimes entertained, I must show what is not the foundation of the right to govern. The boundary of the right must, as will be seen, depend upon the foundation of the right. The right must be as broad as the reason for it. If the reason of the right be mistaken, then the limits of the right cannot be ascer- tained, and must necessarily be mistaken also. 1. The right to govern the universe cannot be founded in the fact, that God sustains to it the relation of Creator. This is by itself no rea- son why he should govern it, unless it needs to be governed — unless some good will result from government. Unless there is some necessity for government, the fact that God created the universe can give him no right to govern it. 2. The fact that God is owner and sole proprietor of the universe is no reason why he should govern it. Unless either his own good or the good of the universe, or of both together, demand government, the relation of owner cannot confer the right to govern. Neither God, nor any other being, can own moral beings, in such a sense as to have a right to govern them, when government is wholly unnecessary, and can result in no good whatever to God, or to his creatures. Government, in such a case, would be perfectly arbitrary and unreasonable, and consequently an un- just, tyrannical and wicked act. God has no such right No such right can, by possibility, in any case exist. 3. The right to govern cannot be founded in the fact, that God pos- sesses all the attributes, natural and moral, that are requisite to the ad- ministration of moral government. This fact is no doubt a condition of the right ; for without these qualifications he could have no right, how- ever necessary government might be'. But the possession of these attri- MORAL GOVERNMENT. 11 bntes cannot confer the right independently of the necessity of govern- ment : for however well qualified he may be to govern, still, unless gov- ernment is necessary to securipg his own glory and the highest well- being of the universe, he has no right to govern it. Possessing the requisite qualifications is the condition, and the necessity of government is the foundation of the right to govern. More strictly, the right is founded in the intrinsic value of the interests to be secured by govern- ment, ^nd conditioned upon the fact, that government is the necessary means of securing the end. 4. Nor is the right to govern conferred by the value of the interests to be secured, nor by the circumstance of the necessity of government merely, without respect to the condition just above mentioned. Did not God's natural and moral attributes qualify him to sustain that relation better than any one else, the right could not be conferred on him by any other fact or relation. 6. The right to govern is not, and cannot be, an abstract right based on no reason whatever. The idea of this right is not an ultimate idea in such a sense, that our intelligence affirms the right without assigning any reason on which it is founded. The human intelligence cannot say that God has a right to govern, because he has such a right ; and that this is reason enough, and all the reason that can be given. Our reason does not affirm that government is right because it is right; and that this is a first truth, and an ultimate idea. If this were so, then God's arbitrary will would be law, and no bounds could possibly be assigned to the right to govern. If God's right to govern be a first truth, an ultimate truth, fact, and idea, founded in no assignable reason, then he has the right to legislate as little, and as much, and as arbitrarily, as unnecessarily, as absurdly, and injuriously as possible, and no injustice is, or can be done ; for he has, by the supposition, a right to govern, founded in no reason, and of course without any limit. Assign any other reason, as the foun- dation of the right to govern, than the value of the interests to be secured and the necessity of government, and you may search in vain for any limit to the right. But the moment the foundation and the condition of the right are discovered, we see instantly, that the right must be co-extensive with the reason upon which it is founded, or in other words, must be limited by, and only by the fact, that thus far, and no farther, govern- ment is necessary to the highest good of the universe. No legislation can be valid in heaven or earth — no enactments can impose obligation, except upon the condition, that such legislation is demanded by the highest good of the governor and the governed. Unnecessary legislation is inva- lid legislation. Unnecessary government is tyranny. It can, in no case be founded in right. It should, however, be observed, that it is often, and in the government of God universally true, that the sovereign, and 12 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOQT. not the subject, is to be the judge of what is necessary legislation and government. Under no government, therefore, are laws to be despised or rejected because we are unable to see at once their necessity, and hence their wisdom. Unless they are palpably unnecessary, and therefore un- wise and unjust, they are to be respected and obeyed as a less evil than contempt and disobedience, though at present we are unable to see their wisdom. Under the government of God there can never be any doubt nor of course any ground for distrust and hesitancy as it respects the duty of obedience. MoBAL Obligation. The idea of obligation, or of oughtness, is an idea of the pure reason. It is a simple, rational conception, and, strictly speaking, does not admit of a definition, since there are no terms more simple by which it may be defined. Obligation is a term by which we express a conception or idea which all men have, as is manifest from the universal language of men. All men have the ideas of right and wrong, and have words by which these ideas are expressed, and, perhaps, no idea among men more fre- quently reveals itself in words than that of oughtness or obligation. The term cannot be defined, for the simple reason that it is too well and too universally understood to need or even to admit of being expressed in any language more simple and definite than the word obligation itself. The conditions of moral obligation. There is a distinction of fundamental importance between the condi- tion and the ground of obligation. The ground of obligation is the con- sideration which creates or imposes obligation, the fundamental reason of the obligation. Of this I shall inquire in its proper place. At pres- ent I am to define the conditions of obligation. But I must in this place observe that there are various forms of obligation. For example, obligation to choose an ultimate end of life as the highest good of the universe ; obligation to choose the necessary conditions of this end, as holiness, for example ; and obligation to put forth executive efforts to secure this end. The conditions of obligation vary with the form of obli- gation, as we shall fully perceive in the course of our investigations. A condition of obligation in any particular form is a sine qua non of obligation in that particular form. It is that, without which, obligation in that form could not exist, and yet is not the fundamental reason of the obligation. For example, the possession of the powers of moral agency is a condition of the obligation to choose the highest good of being in general, as an ultimate end, or for its own sake. But the intrinsic value of this good is the ground of the obligation. This obligation could pot exipt without t)je possessipij oj t^Jiese powers ; hpt the poss^ssjoi^ pf MORAL OBLIGATION. 1^ these powers cannot of itself create the obligation to choose the good in preference to the ill of being. The intrinsic difference between the good and the ill of being is the gronnd of the obligation to will the one rather than the other. I will first define the conditions upon which all obliga- tion depends, and without which obligation in no form can exist, and afterward proceed to point oat the conditions of distinct forms of obli- gation. 1. Moral agency is universally a condition of moral obligation. The attributes of moral agency are intellect, sensihility, &nA free-will. (1.) Intellect includes, among other f auctions which I need not name, reason, conscience, and self-consciousness. As has been said on a former occasion, reason is the intuitive faculty or function of the intel- lect. It gives by direct intuition the following among other truths : the absolute — for example, right and wrong ; the necessary — space exists ; the infinite — space is infinite ; the perfect — God is perfect — God's law is perfect, etc. In short, it is the faculty that intuits moral relations and afSrms moral obligation to act in conformity with perceived moral rela- tions. It is that faculty that postulates all the ot priori truths of science whether mathematical, philosophical, theological, or logical. Conscience is the faculty or function of the intellect that recognizes the conformity or disconformity of the heart and life to the moral law as it lies revealed in the reason, and also awards praise to conformity, and blame to disconformity to that law. It also afiBrms that conformity to the moral law deserves reward, and that disconformity deserves pun- ishment. It also possesses a propelling or impulsive power, by which it urges the conformity, and denounces the nonconformity of will to moral law. It seems, in a certain sense, to possess the power of retribution. Consciousness is the faculty or function of self-knowledge. It is the faculty that recognizes our own existence, mental actions, and states, together with the attributes of liberty or necessity, belonging to those actions or states. " Consciousness is the mind in the act of knowing itself." By con- sciousness I know that I am — that I affirm that space is, — that I also affirm that the whole is equal to all its parts — that every event mast have a cause, and many such like truths. I am conscious not only of these affirmations, but also that necessity is the law of these affirmations, that I cannot affirm otherwise than I do, in respect to this class of truths. I am also conscious of choosing to sit at my desk and write, and I am just as conscious that liberty is the law of this clioice. That is, I am con- scious of necessarily regarding myself as entirely free in this choice, and affirming my own ability to have chosen not to sit at my desk, and of being now able to choose not to sit and write. I am just as conscious of affirming the liberty or necessity of my mental states as I am of the 14 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. states themselves. Consciousness gives us our existence and attributes, our mental acts and states, and all the attributes and phenomena of our being, of which we have any knowledge. In short, all our knowledge is given to us by consciousness. The intellect is a receptivity as distin- guished from a voluntary power. All the acts and states of the intellect are under the law of necessity, or physical law. The will can command the attention of the intellect. Its thoughts, perceptions, aflSrmations, and all its phenomena are involuntary, and under a law of necessity. Of this we are conscious. Another faculty indispensable to moral agency is — • (3.) Sensibility. This is the faculty or susceptibility of feeling. All sensation, desire, emotion, passion, pain, pleasure, and, in short, every kind and degi'ee of feeling, as the term feeling is commonly used, is a phenomenon of this faculty. This faculty supplies the chronological condition of the idea of the valuable, and hence of right and wrong, and of moral obligation. The experience of pleasure or happiness develops the idea of the valuable, just as the perception of body develops the idea of space. But for this faculty the mind could have no idea of the valuable, and hence of moral obligation to will the valuable, nor of right and wrong, nor of praise-worthiness and blame- worthiness. Self-love is a phenomenon of this department of the mind. It con- sists in a constitutional desire of happiness, and implies a corresponding dread of misery. It is doubtless through, or by, this constitutional ten- dency that the rational idea of the intrinsic value of happiness or enjoy- ment is at first developed. Animals, doubtless, have enjoyment, but we have no evidence that they possess the faculty of reason in the sense in which I have defined the term. Consequently they have not, as we sup- pose, the rational conception of the intrinsic worth or value of enjoy- ment. They seek enjoyment from a mere impulse of their animal nature, without, as we suppose, so much as a conception of moral law, obligation, right or wrong. But we know that moral agents have these ideas. Self-love is consti- tutional. Its gratification is the chronological condition of the develop- ment of the reason's idea of the intrinsically valuable to being. This idea develops that of moral law, or in other words, the aflBrmation that this intrinsic good ought to be universally chosen and sought for its own sake. The sensibility, like the intellect, is a receptivity or purely a passive, distinguished from a voluntary faculty. All its phenomena are under the law of necessity. I am conscious that I cannot, by any direct effort, feel when and as I will. This faculty is so correlated to the intellect that when the intellect is intensely occupied with certain considerations, the sensibility is afEected in a certain manner, and certain feelings exist in MORAL OBLIGATION. 15 the sensibility by a law of necessity. I am conscious that when certain conditions are fulfilled, I necessarily have certain feelings, and that when these conditions are not fulfilled, I cannot be the subject of those feelings. I know by consciousness that my feelings and all the states and phenom- ena of the sensibility are only indirectly under the control of my will. By willing I can direct my intellect to the consideration of certain sub- jects, and in this way alone afEecb my sensibility, and produce a given state of feeling. So on the other hand, if certain feelings exist in the sensibility which I wish to suppress, I know that I cannot annihilate them by directly willing them out of existence, but by diverting my at- tention from the cause of them, they cease to exist of course and of necessity. Thus, feeling is only indirectly under the control of the will. (3.) Moral agency implies the possession of free-will. By free-will is intended the power of choosing, or refusing to choose, in every instance, in compliance with moral obligation. Eree-will implies the power of originating and deciding our own choices, and of exercising our own sovereignty, in every instance of choice upon moral questions — of decid- ing or choosing in conformity with duty or otherwise in all cases of moral obligation. That man cannot be under a moral obligation to perform an absolute impossibility, is a first truth of reason. But man's causality, his whole power of causality to perform or do anything, lies in his will. If he cannot will, he can do nothing. His whole liberty or freedom must consist in his power to will. His outward actions and his mental states are connected with the actions of his will by a law of necessity. If I will to move my muscles, they must move, unless there be a paralysis of the nerves of voluntary motion, or unless some resistance be opposed that overcomes the power of my volitions. The sequences of choice or volition are always under the law of necessity, and unless the will is free, man has no freedom ; and if he has no freedom he is not a moral agent, that is, he is incapable of moral action and also of moral character. Free-will then, in the above defined sense, must be a condition of moral agency, and of course, of moral obligation. As consciousness gives the rational affirmation that necessity is an attribute of the affirmations of the reason, and of the states of sensibility, so it just as unequivocally gives the reason's affirmation that liberty is an attribute of the actions of the will. I am as conscious of the affirmation that I could will differently from what I do in every instance of moral obligation, as I am of the affirmation that I cannot affirm, in regard to truths of intuition, otherwise than I do. I am as conscious of affirming that I am free in willing, as I am of affirming that I am not fi-ee or volun- tary in my feelings and intuitions. Consciousness of affirming the freedom of the will, that is, of power to will in accordance with moral obligation, or to refuse thus to will, is a 16 BYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. necessary condition of the aflBrmation of obligation. For example, no man affirms, or can affirm, his obligation to undo all the acts of his past life, and to live his life over again. He cannot affirm himself to be un- der this obligation, simply because he cannot but affirm the impossibility of it. He cannot but affirm his obligation to repent and obey God in future, because he is conscious of affirming his ability to do this. Con- sciousness of the affirmation of ability to comply with any requisition, is a necessary condition of the affirmation of obligation to comply with that requisition. Then no moral agent can affirm himself to be under obligation to perform an impossibility. 3. A second condition of moral obligation is light, or so much knowl- edge of our moral relations as to develop the idea of oughtness. This implies — (1.) The perception or idea of the intrinsically yaluable. (2.) The affirmation of obligation to will the valuable for its own sake. Before I can affirm my obligation to will, I must perceive some- thing in that which I am required to will as an ultimate end, that ren- ders it worthy of being chosen. I must have an object of choice. That object must possess, in itself, that which commends itself to my intelli- gence as worthy of being chosen. All choice must respect means or ends. That is, everything must be willed either as an end or a means. I cannot be under obligation to will the means until I know the end. I cannot know an end, or that which can possibly be chosen as an ultimate end, until I know that something is intrinsically valuable. I cannot know that it is right or wrong to choose or refuse a certain end, until I know whether the proposed object of choice is intrinsically valuable or not. It is impossible for me to choose it, as an ultimate end, unless I perceive it to be intrinsically valuable. This is self-evident ; for choosing it as an end is nothing else than choos- ing it for its intrinsic value. Moral obligation, therefore, always and necessarily implies the knowledge that the well-being of God and of the universe is valuable in itself, and the affirmation that it ought to be chosen for its own sake, that is, impartially and on account of its in- trinsic value. It is impossible that the ideas of right and wrong should be developed until the idea of the valuable is developed. Bight and wrong respect intentions, and strictly nothing else, as we shall see. In- tention implies an end intended. Kow that which is chosen as an ulti- mate end, is and must be chosen for its own sake or for its intrinsic value. Until the end is apprehended, no idea or affirmation of obliga- tion can exist respecting it. Consequently, no idea of right or wrong in respect to that end can exist. The end must first be perceived. The idea of the intrinsically valuable must be developed. Simultaneously with the development of the idea of the valuable the intelligence affirms, and MORAL OBLIGATION. 17 must affirm, obligation to will it, or, which is, strictly speaking, the same thing, that it is right to will it, and wrong not to will it. It is impossible that the idea of moral obligation, or of right and wrong, should be developed upon any other conditions than those just specified. Suppose, for instance, it should be said that the idea of the intrinsically^aluable is not necessary to the development of the idea of moral obligation, and of right and wrong. Let us look at it. It ia agreed that moral obligation, and the ideas of right and wrong respect, directly, intentions only. It is also admitted that all intentions must respect either means or ends. It is also admitted that obligation to will means, cannot exist until the end is known. It is also admitted that the choice of an ultimate end implies the choice of a thing for its own sake, or because it is intrinsically valuable. Kow, from these admissions, it follows that the idea of the intrinsically valuable is the condition of moral obligation, and also of the idea of moral obligation. It must follow also that the idea of the valuable must be the condition of the idea that it would be right to choose, or wrong not to choose, the valuable. It is, then, nonsense to affirm that the ideas of right and wrong are developed antecedently to the idea of the valuable. It is the same as to say that I affirm it to be right to will an end, before I have the idea of an end ; or wrong not to will an end when as yet I have no idea or knowledge of any reason why it should be willed, or, in other words, while I have no idea of an ultimate end. Let it be distinctly understood then, that the conditions of moral obligation, in the universal form of obligation to will the highest well- being of God and of the universe, for its own sake, are the possession of the powers, or faculties, and susceptibilities of a moral agent, and light or the development of the ideas of the valuable, of moral obligation, of right and wrong. I have defined the conditions of obligation in its universal form, i. e. obligation to be benevolent, to love God and our neighbor, or to will the. universal good of being for its intrinsic value. Obligation in this form is universal and always a unit, and has always the same conditions. But there are myriads of specific forms of obligation which relate to the con- ditions and means of securing this ultimate end. We shall have occasion hereafter fully to show that obligation respects three classes of the will's actions, viz. the choice of an ultimate end — the choice of the conditions and means of securing that end — and executive volitions or efforts put forth to secure the end. I have already shown that moral agency, with all that is implied in it, has the universal conditions of obligation to choose the highest good of being, as an ultimate end. This must be self-evident. Obligation to choose the conditions of this end, the holiness of God 18 STSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. and of all moral agents, for example, must be conditioned upon the per- ception that these are the conditions. In other words, the perception of the relation of these means to the end must be a condition of the obli- gation to will their existence. The perception of the relation is not the ground hut simply the condition of obligation in this form. The rela- tion of holiness to happiness as a condition of its existence, c8nld not im- pose obligation to will the existence of holiness without reference to the intrinsic value of happiness, as the fundamental reason for willing it as a necessary condition and means. The ground of the obligation to will the existence of holiness, as a means of happiness, is the intrinsic value of happiness, but the perceived relation of holiness to happiness is a con- dition of the obligation. But for this perceived relation the obligation could not exist, yet the perceived relation could not create the obligation. Suppose that holiness is the means of happiness, yet no obligation to will holiness on account of this relation could exist but for the intrinsic value of happiness. Conditions of obligation to put forth executive acts. Having now defined the conditions of obligation in its universal form, and also in the form of obligation to choose the existence of holiness as a necessary means of happiness, I now proceed to point out the conditions of obligation to put forth executive volitions or efforts to secure holiness, and secure the highest good of being. Our busy lives are made up in efforts to secure some ultimate end, upon which the heart is set. The sense in which obligation extends to these executive volitions or acts I shall soon consider ; at present I am concerned only to define the condi- tions of these forms of obligation. These forms of obligation, be it understood, respect volitions and consequent outward acts. Volitions, designed as executive acts, always suppose an existing choice of the end designed to be secured by them. Obligation to put forth executive efforts to secure an end must be conditioned upon the possibility, sup- posed necessity, and utility of such efforts. If the end chosen does not need to be promoted by any efforts of ours, or if such efforts are impossi- ble to us, or if they are seen to be of no use, there can be no obligation to make them. It is important, however, to observe that the utility of ultimate choice, or the choice of an object for its own sake, is not a condition of obligation in that form. Ultimate choice, or the choice of an object for its own sake, or for its intrinsic value, is not an effort designed to secure or obtain that object ; that is, is not put forth with any such design. When the object which the mind perceives to be intrinsically valuable (as the good of be- ing, for example), is perceived by the mind, it cannot but choose or refuse it. Indifference in this case is naturally impossible. The mind, in such circumstances, is under a necessity of choosing one way or the other. MORAL OBLIGATION. 19 The will must embrace or reject it. The reason affirms the obligation to choose the intrinsically valuable for its own sake, and not because choos- ing it will secure it. Nor does the real choice of it imply a pm-pose or an obligation to put forth executive acts to secure it, except upon condi- tion that such acts are seen to be necessary, and possible, and calculated to secure it. Ultimate choice is not put forth with design to secure its object. It is only the will's embracing the object or willing it for its own sake. In regard to ultimate choice the will must choose or refuse the object en- tirely irrespectively of the tendency of the choice to secure the object. Assuming this necessity, the reason affirms that it is right, fit, suitable, or, which is the same thing, that the will ought, or is under obligation to choose, the good or valuable, and not refuse it, because of its intrinsic nature, and without regard to whether the choosing will secure the ob- ject chosen. But executive acts, be it remembered, are, and must be put forth with design to secure their object, and of course, cannot exist unless the design exist, and the design cannot exist unless the mind assumes the possibility, necessity, and utility of such efforts. LECTURE III. MORAL OBLIGATION. Man is a subject of moral obligation. That man has intellect and sensibility, or the powers of knowing and feeling, has not, to my knowledge, been doubted. In theory, the free- dom of the will in man has been denied. Yet the very deniers, have, in their practical judgment, assumed the freedom of the human will, as well, and as fully as the most staunch defenders of human liberty of will. Indeed, nobody ever did or can, in practice, call in question the freedom of the human will, without justly incurring the charge of insanity. By a necessity of his nature, every moral agent knows himself to be free. He can no more hide this fact from himself, or reason himself out of the conviction of its truth, than he can speculate himself into a disbelief of his own existence. He may, in speculation, deny either, but in fact he knows both. That he ts, that he ia free, are truths equally well known, 8ind known precisely in the same way, namely, he intuits them — sees them in their own light, by virtue of the constitution of his being. I have said that man is conscious of possessing the powers of a moral agent. He 20 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. has also the idea of the valuable, of right and of wrong ; of this he la conscious. But nothing else is necessary to constitute man or any other being a subject of moral obligation, and the possession of these powers, together with sufficient light on moral subjects to develop the ideas just mentioned. Man, by a law of necessity, affirms himself to be under moral obliga- tion. He cannot doubt it. He affirms absolutely and necessarily, that he is praise-worthy or blame-worthy as he is benevolent or selfish. Every man assumes this of himself, and of all other men of sound mind. This assumption is irresistible, as well as universal. The truth assumed then is not to be called in question. But if it be called in question in theory, it still remains, and must remain, while reason remains, a truth of certain knowledge, from the presence of which there is, and can be no escape. The spontaneous, universal, and irresist- ible affirmation that men of sound mind are praise-worthy or blame- worthy, as they are selfish or benevolent, shows beyond contradiction, that aH men regard themselves, and others, as the subjects of moral obligation. Extent of moral obligation. By this is intended, to what acts and states of mind does moral obli- gation extend ? This certainly is a solemn and a fundamentally impor- tant question. In the examination of this question, let us inquire first, to what acts and states of mind moral obligation cannot directly extend. 1. Not to external or muscular action. These actions are connected with the actions of the will, by a law of necessity. If I will to move my muscles, they must move, unless the nerves of voluntary motion are par- alyzed, or some resistance is offered to muscular motion, that overpowers the strength of my will, or, if you please, of my muscles. It is generally understood and agreed that moral obligation does not directly extend to bodily or outward action. 3. Kot to the states of the sensibility. I have already remarked that we are conscious, that our feelings are not voluntary, but involuntary states of mind. Moral obligation cannot, therefore, directly extend to them. 3. Not to states of the intellect. The phenomena of this faculty, we also know by consciousness, to be under the law of necessity. It is im- possible that moral obligation should extend directly to any inyolnntary act or state of mind. 4. Not to unintelligent acts of will. There are many unintelligent volitions, or acts of will, to which moral obligation cannot extend, for ex- ample, the volitions of maniacs, or of infants, before the reason is at all developed. They must at birth, be the subjects of volition, as they hav# MORAL OBLIGATION. 21 motion or mnscular action. The volitions of somnambulists are also of this character. Purely instinctive volitions must also come under the category of unintelligent actions of will. For example : a bee lights on my hand, I instantly and instinctively shake him off. I tread on a hot iron, and instinctively move my foot. Indeed there are many actions of will which are put forth under the influence of pure instinct, and before the intellect can affirm obligation to will or not to will. These surely cannot have moral character, and of course moral obligation cannot ex- tend to them. We inquire in the second place, to what acts and states of mind moral obligation must directly extend. 1. To ultimate acts of will. These are and must be free. Intelligent acts of will, as has been before observed, are of three classes. First, the choice of some object for its own sake, i. e., because of its own nature, or for reasons found exclusively in itself, as, for example, the happiness of being. These are called ultimate choices, or intentions. Second, the choice of the conditions and means of securing the object of ultimate choice, as for example, holiness, as the conditions or means of hap- piness. Third, volitions, or executive efforts to secure the object of ulti- mate choice. Obligation must extend to these three classes of the actions of the will. In the most strict and proper sense it may be said, that obligation extends directly only to the ultimate intention. The choice of an end necessitates the choice of the known conditions and means of securing this end. I am free to relinquish, at any moment, my choice of an end, but while I persevere in the choice, or ultimate in- tention, I am not free to refuse the known necessary conditions and means. If I reject the known conditions and means, I, in this act, relinquish the choice of the end. The desire of the end may remain, but the actual choice of it cannot, when the will knowingly rejects the known necessary conditions and means. In this case, the will prefers to let go the end, rather than to choose and use the necessary conditions and means. In the strictest sense the choice of known conditions and means, together with executive volitions, is implied in the ultimate inten- tion or in the choice of an end. When the good or valuable per se, is perceived by a moral agent, ho instantly and necessarily, and without condition, affirms his obligation to choose it. This affirmation is direct and universal, absolute, or with- out condition. Whether he will affirm himself to be under obligation to put forth efforts to secure the good, must depend upon his regarding such acts as necessary, possible, and useful. The obligation, therefore, to put forth ultimate choice, is in the strictest sense direct, absolute and uni- versal. Obligation to choose holiness, (as the holiness of God,) as the means 22 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. of happiness, is indirect in the sense that it is conditioned, first, npon the obligation to choose happiness as a good per sej and, second, npon the knowledge that holiness is the necessary means of happiness. Obligation to put forth executive volitions is also indirect in the sense that it is conditioned ; first, upon obligation to choose an object as an end ; and, second, npon the necessity, possibility, and utility of such acts. It should here be observed, that obligation to choose an object for its own sake, implies, of course, obligation to reject its opposite ; and obli- gation to choose the conditions of an intrinsically valuable object for its own sake, implies obligation to reject the conditions or means of the opposite of this object. Also, obligation to use means to secure an in- trinsically valuable object, implies obligation to use means, if necessary and possible, to prevent the opposite of this end. For example : Obliga- tion to will happiness, for its intrinsic value, implies obligation to reject misery, as an intrinsic evil. Obligation to will the conditions of the happiness of being, implies obligation to reject the conditions of misery. Obligation to use means to promote the happiness of being, implies obli- gation to use means, if necessary and practicable, to prevent the misery of being. Again, the choice of any object, either as an end, or a means, implies the refusal of its opposite. In other words, choice implies preference, refusing is properly only choice in an opposite direction. For this rea- son, in speaking of the actions of the will, it has been common to omit the mention of nilling, or refusing, since such acts are properly included in the categories of choices and volitions. It should also be observed that choice, or willing, necessarily implies an object chosen, and that this object should be such that the mind can regard it as being either intrinsically, or relatively valuable, or important. As choice must con- sist in an act, an intelligent act, the mind must have reason for choice. It cannot choose without a reason, for this is the same as to choose with- out an object of choice. A mere abstraction without any perceived or assumed, intrinsic, or relative importance, to any being in existence, can- not be an object of choice, either ultimate or executive. The ultimate reason which the mind has for choosing is in fact the object of choice ; and where there is no reason there is no object of choice. 2. I have said, that moral obligation respects in the strictest sense and directly the intention only. I am now prepared to say still further, that this is a first truth of reason. It is a truth universally and neces- sarily assumed by all moral agents, their speculations to the contrary, in any wise, notwithstanding. This is evident from the following con- siderations : (1.) Very young children know and assume this truth universally. MORAL OBLIGATION. 23 They always deem it a sufficient vindication of themselves, when accused of any delinquency to say, " I did not mean to," or if accused of short coming, to say, "I meant or intended to have done it — I designed it." Tliis, if true, they assume to be an iiU-sufficient vindication of themselves. They know that this, if believed, must be regarded as a sufficient excuse to justify them in every case. (3.) Every moral agent necessarily regards such an excuse as a perfect justification, in case it be sincerely and truly made. (3.) It is a saying as common as men are, and as true as common, that men are to be judged by their motives, that is, by their designs, in- tentions. It is impossible for us not to assent to this truth. If a man intend evil, though, perchance, he may do us good, we do not excuse him, but hold him guilty of the crime which he intended. So if he in- tend to do us good, and, perchance, do us evil, we do not, and cannot condemn him. For this intention and endeavor to do us goody we can- not blame him, although it has resulted in evil to us. He may be to blame for other things connected with the affair. He may have come to our help too late, and have been to blame for not coming when a differ- ent result would have followed ; or he may have been blamablo for not being better qualified for doing us good. He may have been to blame for many things connected with the transaction, but for a sincere, and of course hearty endeavor to do us good, he is not culpable, nor can he be, however it may result. If he honestly intended to do us good, it is impossible that he should not have used the best means in his power, at the time. This is implied in honesty of intention. And if he did this, reason cannot pronounce him guilty, for it must judge him by his intentions. (4.) Courts of criminal law have always in every enlightened country assumed this as a first truth. They always inquire into the quo animo, that is, the intention, and judge accordingly. (5.) The universally acknowledged truth that lunatics are not moral agents and responsible for their conduct, is but an illustration of the fact that the truth we are considering is regarded, and assumed, as a first truth of reason. (6.) The Bible everywhere either expressly or impliedly recognizes this truth. "If there be a willing mind," that is, a right willing or in- tention, "it is accepted," etc. Again, "All the law is fulfilled in one word," "love." Now this cannot be true, if the spirit of the whole law does not directly respect intentions only. If it extends directly to thoughts, emotions, and outward actions, it cannot be truly said that love is the fulfilling of the law. This love must be good will, for how could involuntary love be obligatory ? The spirit of the Bible every- where respects the intention. If the intention is right, or if there be a 24 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. willing mind, it is accepted as obedience. But if there be not a willing mind, that is, right intention, no outward act is regarded as obedience. The willing is always regarded by the scriptures as the doing. " If a man look on a woman, to lust after her," that is, with licentious inten- tion, or willing, " he hath committed adultery with her already," etc. So on the other hand, if one intends to perform a service for God, which, after all, he is unable to perform, he is regarded as having virtually done it, and is rewarded accordingly. This is too obviously the doctrine of the Bible to need further elucidation. 3. We have seen that the choice of an end implies, and, while the choice continues, necessitates the choice of the known conditions and means of the end, and also the putting forth of volition to secure the end. If this is true, it follows that the choice of the conditions and means of securing an end, and also the volitions put forth as executive efEorts to secure it, must derive their character from the ultimate choice or intention which gives them existence. This shows that moral obli- gation extends, primarily and directly, only to the ultimate intention or choice of an end, though really, but less directly, to the choice of the conditions and means, and also to executive volitions. But I must distinguish more clearly between ultimate and proximate intentions, which discrimination will show, that in the most strict and proper sense, obligation belongs to the former, and only in a less strict and proper sense, to the latter. An ultimate end, be it remembered, is an object chosen for its own sake. A proximate end is an object chosen as a condition or means of secur- ing an ultimate end. An ultimate end is an object chosen because of its intrinsic nature and value. A proximate end is an object chosen for the sake of the end, and npon condition of its relation as a condition or means of the end. Example: — A student labors to get wages, to purchase books, to obtain an education, to preach the gospel, to save souls, and to pleaae God. Another labors to get wages, to purchase books, to get an educa- tion, to preach the gospel, to secure a salary, and his own case and popu- larity. In the first supposition he loves God and souls, and seeks, as his ultimate end, the happiness of souls, and the glory and gratification of God. In the last case supposed, he loves himself supremely, and his ultimate end is his own gratification. Now the proximate ends, or im- mediate objects of pursuit, in these two cases, are precisely alike, while their ultimate ends are entirely opposite. Their first, or nearest, end is to get wages. Their next end is, to obtain books ; and so we follow them, nntil we ascertain their ultimate end, before we learn the moral charac* MORAL OBLIGATION. 26 ter of what they are doing. The means they are using, i. e. their im- mediate objects or proximate ends of pursuit, are the same, but the ulti- mate ends at which they aim are entirely different, and every moral agent, from a necessary law of his intellect, must, as soon as he under- stands the ultimate end of each, pronounce the one virtuous, and the other sinful, in }iis pursuits. One is selfish and the other benevolent. From this illustration it is plain, that strictly speaking, moral character, and, of course, moral obligation, respect directly the ultimate intention only. We shall see, in the proper place, that obligation also extends, but less directly, to the use of means to obtain the end. Our next inquiry is, to what acts and mental states moral obligation indirectly extends. 1. The muscles of the body are, directly, under the control of the will. I will to move, and my muscles must move, unless there be interposed some physical obstruction of sufficient magnitude to overcome the strength of my will. 2. The intellect is also directly under the control of the will. I am conscious that I can control and direct my attention as I please, and think upon one subject or another. 3. The sensibility, I am conscious, is only indirectly controlled by the will. Feeling can be produced only by directing the attention and thoughts to those subjects that excite feeling, by a law of necessity. The way is now prepared to say — 1. That obligation extends indirectly to all intelligent acts of will, in the sense already explained. 2. That moral obligation extends indirectly, to outward or bodily actions. These are often required, in the word of God. The reason is, that, being connected with the actions of the will, by a law of necessity, if the will is right, the outward action must follow, except upon the con- tingencies just named ; and therefore such actions may reasonably be re- quired. But if the contingencies just named intervene, so that out- ward action does not follow the choice or intention, the Bible accepts the will for the deed, invariably. " If there be a willing mind, it is accepted according," etc. 3. Moral obligation extends, but less directly, to the states of the sensibility, so that certain emotions or feelings are required as outward actions are, and for the same reason, namely, the states of the sensibility are connected with the actions of the will, by a law of necessity. But when the sensibility is exhausted, or when, for any reason, the right action of the will does not produce the required feelings, it is accepted upon the principle just named. 4. Moral obliga]tio;a indirectly extends also to the states of the intellect ; 26 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY, consequently the Bible, to a certain extent, and in a certain sense, holds men responsible for their thoughts and opinions. It everywhere assumes that if the heart be constantly right, the thoughts and opinions will cor- respond with the state of the heart, or will ; " If any man will do his will, he shall know the doctrine whether it be of God." " If thine eye be single thy whole body shall be full of light." It is, however mani- fest, that the word of God everywhere assumes that, strictly speaking, aU virtue and vipe belong to the heart or intention. Where this is right, all is regarded as right; and where this is wrong, all is regarded as wrong. It is upon this assumption that the doctrine of total depi'avity rests. It is undeniable that the veriest sinners do many things out- wardly which the law of God requires. Now unless the intention decides the character of these acts, they must be regarded as really virtuous. But when the intention is found to be selfish, then it is ascertained that they are sinful notwithstanding their conformity to the letter of the law of God. The fact is, that moral agents are so constituted that it is impossible for them not to judge themselves, and others, by their subjective motives or intentions. They cannot but assume it as a first truth, that a man's character is as his intention is, and consequently, that moral obligation respects, directly, intention only. 5. Moral obligation then indirectly extends to everything about us, over which the will has direct or indirect control. The moral law, while, strictly, it legislates over intention only, yet in fact, in a sense less ' direct, legislates over the whole being, inasmuch as all our powers are directly or indirectly connected with intention, by a law of necessity. Strictly speaking, however, moral character belongs alone to the inten- tion. In strict propriety of speech, it cannot be said that either outward action, or any state of the intellect, or sensibility, has a moral element or quality belonging to it. Yet in common language, which is suflS- ciently accurate for most practical purposes, we speak of thought, feel- ing, and outward action as holy or unholy. By this, however, all men really mean, that the agent is holy or unholy, is praise-worthy or blame- worthy in his exercises and actions, because they regard them as pr(H ceeding from the state or attitude of the wilL FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 27 LECTURE IV. FOUNDATION OF MOEAL OBLIGATION. Ik the discussion of this question, I will first state what is intended by the foundation, or ground, of obligation. I shall use the terms ground and foundation as synonymous. Obli- gation must be founded on some good and sufficient reason. Be it remembered, that moral obligation respects moral action. That moral action is voluntary action. That properly speaking, obligation respects intentions only. That still more strictly, obligation respects only the ultimate intention. That ultimate intention or choice, which terms I use as synonymous, consists in choosing an object for its own sake, i. e. for what is intrinsic in the object, and for no reason that is not intrinsic in that object. That every object of ultimate choice must, and does, possess that in its own nature, the perception of which necessitates the rational affirmation, that it ought to be universally chosen, by moral agents, for its own sake, or, which is the same thing, because it is what it is, or, in other words still, because it is intrinsically valuable and not on account of its relations. The ground of obligation, then, is that reason, or consideration, in- trinsic in, or belonging to, the nature of an object, which necessitates the rational affirmation, that it ought to be chosen for its own sake. It is that reason, intrinsic in the object, which thus creates obligation by necessitating this affirmation. For example, such is the nature of the good of being that it necessitates the affirmation, that benevolence is a universal duty. I will next call attention to some points of general agreement, and some principles essentially self-evident. 1. In the most strict and proper sense, moral obligation extends to moral actions only. 2. Strictly speaking, involuntary states of mind are not moral actions. 3. Intentions alone are, properly, moral actions. 4. In the most strict and proper sense, ultimate intentions alone are moral actions, ultimate intention being the choice of an object for its own sake, or for what is intrinsic in the object. 5. While, in the strictest sense, obligation respects only the ultimate intention, yet, in a less strict and proper sense, obligation extends to the choice of the conditions and means of securing an intrinsically valuable end, and also to executive acts put forth with design to secure such end. 5ence there are dtfEerent forms of obligation ; for example, obligation to 28 SYSTEMATIC THBOLOGI put forth ultimate choice— to choose the known necessary conditions and means — to put forth executive volitions, etc. 6. These different.forms of obligation must have difEerent conditions. For example, moral agency, including the possession of the requisite powers, together with the development of the ideas of the intrinsically valuable, of obligation, of right and wrong, is a condition of obligation in its universal form, namely, obligation to will the good of bf.ing in general, for its own sake ; while obligation to will the existence of the conditions and means to the end, or to put forth executive efforts to secure the end, have not only the conditions above named, but obli- gation in these forms must be conditional, also, upon the knowledge that there are conditions and means, and what they are, and also that executive efforts are necessary, possible, and useful. 7. The well-being of God, and of the universe of sentient existences, and especially of moral agents, is intrinsically important, or valuable, and all moral agents are under obligation to choose it for its own sake. Entire, universal, uninterrupted consecration to this end, or dis- interested benevolence is the duty of all moral agents. 8. This consecration is really demanded by the law of God, as re- vealed in the two great precepts laid down by Christ, and this benev- olence, when perfect, is in fact a compliance with the entire spirit of the law. This is right in itself, and consequently is always duty and always right, and that in all possible circumstances ; and, of course, no obligation inconsistent With this can ever, in any case, exist. Season and revelation agree in this ; that the law of benevolence is the law of right, the law of nature, and no moral law, inconsistent with this, can exist. 9. Holiness, or obedience to moral law, or, in other words still, - disinterested benevolence, is a natural, and of course necessary condition of the existence of that blessedness which is an ultimate or intrinsic good to moral agents, and ought to be chosen for that reason, i. e., that is a sufficient reason. Of course, the ground of obligation to choose holiness, and to endeavor to promote it in others, as a condition of the highest well-being of the universe, is the intrinsic nature of that good or well- being, and the relation of holiness to this end is a condition of the obli- gation to choose it, as a means to this end. 10. Truth, and conformity of heart and life to all known and prac- tical truths, are conditions and means of the highest good of being. Of course, the obligation to conform to such truths is universal, because of this relation of truth, and of conformity to truth, to the highest good. The intrinsic value of the good must be the ground, and the relation only a condition, of the obligation. JL3L. God's nltimq,te epd, ^pall he do^s, or Q^iit^.is the highest weU- PotJJJbAfioii OS* oSLtOAtion. 29 being bi hiiuself, and of the universe, and in all his acts and dispen- sations, his ultimate object is the promotion of this end. All moral agents should have the same end, and this comprises their whole duty. This intention or consecration to this intrinsically and infinitely valuable end, is virtue, or holiness, in God and in all moral agents. God is infin- itely and equally holy in all things, because he does all things for the same ultimate reason, namely, to promote the highest good of being. 12. All God's moral attributes are only so many attributes of love or of disinterested benevolence ; that is, they are only benevolence existing and contemplated in different relations. Creation and moral government, including both law and gospel, together with the infliction of penal sanctions, are only efforts of benevolence to secure the highest good. 13. He requires, both in his law and gospel, that all moral agents should choose the same end, and do whatever they do for its promo- tion ; that is, this should be the ultimate reason for all they do. Conse- quently, all obligation resolves itself into an obligation to choose the highest good of God, and of being in general, for its own sake, and to choose all the known conditions and means of this end, for the sake of the end. 14. The intrinsic value of this end is the ground of this obligation, both as it respects God and all moral agents in all worlds. The intrinsic value of this end rendered it fit, or right, that God should require moral agents to choose it for its own sake ; and of course, its intrinsic value, and not any arbitrary sovereignty, was, and is, his reason for requiring moral agents to choose it for its own sake. 15. Its known intrinsic value would, of itself, impose obligation on moral agents to choose it for its own sake, even had God never required it ; or, if such a supposition were possible, had he forbidden it. Thus, disinterested benevolence is a universal and an invariable duty. This benevolence consists in willing the highest good of being, in general, for its own sake, or, in other words, in entire consecration to this good as the end of life. The intrinsic value of this good does, of its own nature, impose obligation upon all moral agents to will it for its own sake, and consecrate the whole being, without intermission, to its promotion. Thus it is self-evident that moral character belongs to the ultimate intention, and that a man's character is as the end for which he lives, and moves, and has his being. Virtue consists in consecration to the right end, the end to which God is consecrated. This end is, and must be, by virtue of its own nature, the ground of obligation. That is, the nature of this end is such as to compel the reason of every moral agent to affirm, that it ought to be chosen for its own sake. This end is the good of being, and therefore disinterested benevolence, or good will, is a universal duty. 30 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Now, with these facts distinctly kept in mind, let us proceed to the examination of the various conflicting and inconsistent theories of the ground of obligation. Of the Will of Qod as the ground of obligation. I will first consider the theory of those who hold that the sovereign will of God is the ground, or ultimate reason, of obligation. They hold that God's sovereign will creates, and not merely reveals and enforces, obligation. To this I reply : 1. That moral law legislates directly over voluntary action only — that moral obligation respects, primarily and strictly, the ultimate inten- tion — ^that ultimate intention consists in choosing its object, for its own sake — that ultimate intention must find its reasons exclusively in its object — that the intrinsic nature and value of the object must impose obligation to choose it for its own sake — that therefore this intrinsic value is the ground, and the only possible ground, of obligation to choose it for its own sake. It would be our duty to will the highest good of God and of the universe, even did God not will that we should, or were he to will that we should not. How utterly unfounded then, is the assertion, that the sovereign will of God is the ground of obligation. Obligation to do what ? Why to love God and our neighbor. That is to will their highest good. And does God's will create this obligation ? Should we be under no such obligation, had he not commanded it ? Are we to will this good, not for its own value to God and our neighbor, but because God commands it ? The answer to these questions is too obvious to need so much as to be named. But what consistency is there in holding that disinterested benevolence is a universal duty, and at the same time that the sovereign will of God is the foundation of obligation ; How can men hold, as many do, that the highest good of being ought to be chosen for its own sake — that to choose it for its own sake is disin- terested benevolence — that its intrinsic value imposes obligation to choose it for its own sake, and that this intrinsic value is therefore the ground of obligation, and yet that the will of God is the ground of obhgation ? Why, if the will of God be the ground of obligation, then disin- terested benevolence is sin. If the will of God does of itself create, and not merely reveal obligation, then the will, and not the interest and well-being of God, ought to be chosen for its own sake, and to be the great end of life. God ought to be consecrated to his own will, instead of his own highest good. Benevolence in God, and in all beings, must be sin, upon this hypothesis. A purely arbitrary will and sovereignty in God is, according to this theory, of more value than his highest well- being, and than that of the whole universe. But observe, FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 31 Moral obligation respects ultimate intention, or the choice of an end. The foundation, or fundamental reason for choosing a thing, is that which renders it obligatory to choose it. This reason is the thing on which the choice ought to terminate, or the true end is not chosen. Therefore the reason and the end are identicaL If, then, the will of God be the foundation of obligation, it must also be the ultimate end of choice. But it is impossible for us to will or choose the divine willing as an ultimate end. God's willing reveals a law, a rule of choice, or of inten- tion. It requires something to be intended as an ultimate end, or for its own intrinsic value. This end cannot be the willing, commandment, law, itself. Does God will that I should choose his willing as an ulti- mate end ? This is impossible. It is a plain contradiction to say that moral obligation respects, directly, ultimate intention only, or the choice of an end, for its own intrinsic value, and yet, that the will of God is the foundation, or reason of the obligation. This is affirming at the same breath that the intrinsic value of the end which God requires me to choose, is the reason, or foundation of the obligation to choose it, and yet that this is not the reason, but that the will of God is the reason. Willing can never be an end. God cannot will our willing as an end. Nor can he will his willing as an end. Willing, choosing, always, and necessarily, implies an end willed entirely distinct from the willing, or choice, itself. Willing, cannot be regarded, or wiUed, as an ultimate end, for two reasons : — (1.) Because that on which choice or willing terminates, and not the choice itself, must be regarded as the end. (2.) Because choice or willing is of no intrinsic value and of no rela- tive value, aside from the end willed or chosen. 2. The will of God cannot be the foundation of moral obligation in created moral agents. God has moral character, and is virtuous. This implies that he is the subject of moral obligation, for virtue is nothing else than compliance with obligation. If God is the subject of moral obligation, there is some reason, independent of his own will, why he wills as he does ; some reason, that imposes obligation upon him to will as he does. His will, then, respecting the conduct of moral agents, is not the fundamental reason of their obligation ; but the foundation of their obligation must be the reason which induces God, or makes it obli- gatory on him, to will in respect to the conduct of moral agents, just what he does. 3. If the will of God were the foundation of moral obligation, he could, by willing it, change the nature of virtue and vice, which is absurd, 32 SYSTEMATIC THBOLOUY. 4. If the will of God were the foundation of moral obligation, he n only can change the nature of virtue and vice, but has a right to do bo for if there is nothing back of his will that is as binding upon him as upon his creatures, he has a right, at any time, to make malevolence a virtue, and benevolence a vice. For if his will is the ground of obliga- tion, then his will creates right, and whatever he wills, or might will, is right simply and only because so he wills. 5. If the will of God be the foundation of moral obligation, we have no standard by which to judge of the moral character of his actions, and cannot know whether he is worthy of praise or blame. Upon the sup- position in question, were God a malevolent being, and did he require all his creatures to be selfish, and not benevolent, he would be just as vir- tuous and worthy of praise as now ; for the supposition is, that his sove- reign will creates right, and of course, will as he might, that would be right, simply because he willed it. 6. If the will of God is the foundation of moral obligation, he haa no standard by which to judge of his own character, as he has no rul* but his own will, with which to compare his own actions. 7. If the will of God is the foundation of moral obligation, he is hot himself a subject of moral obligation. But, 8. If God is not a subject of moral obligation, he has no moral char- acter ; for virtue and vice are nothing else but conformity or non-con- formity to moral obligation. The will of God, as expressed in his law, is the rule of duty to moral agents. It defines and marks out the path of duty, but the fundamental reason why moral agents ought to act in conformity to the will of God, is plainly not the will of God itself. 9. The will of no being can be law. Moral law is an idea of the divine reason, and not the willing of any being. If the will of any being were law, that being could not, by natural possibility, will wrong ; for whatever he willed would be right, simply and only because he willed it. 10. But let us bring this philosophy into the light of divine revela- tion. " To the law and to the testimony ; if it agree not therewith, it is because it hath no light in it." The law of God, or the moral law, requires that God shall be loved with all the heart, and our neighbor as ourselves. Now it is manifest that the love required is not mere emotion, btit that it consists in choice, willing, intention — i. e., in the choice of something on account of its own intrinsic value, or in the choice of an ultimate end. Now what is this end ? What is that which we are to choose for its own intrinsic value P Is it the will or command of God ? Are we to will as an ulti- mate end, that God should will that we should thus will ? What can be more absurd, self-contradictory, and ridiculous than this ? But again, wh^t i? this loving, willing, choosing, intending, required by the law ? FOUNDATION OP OBLIGATION. 33 We are commanded to love God and our neighbor. What is this, whaf can it be, but to will the highest good or well-being of Ood and our neighbor ? This is intrinsically and infinitely valuable. This must be the end, and nothing can possibly be law that requires the choice of any other ultimate end. Nor can that, by any possibility, be true philoso- phy, that makes anything else the reason or foundation of moral obli- gation. But it is -said that we are conscious of affirming our obligation to obey the will of God, without reference to any other reason than his will ; and this, it is said, proves that his will is the foundation of obligation. To this I reply, the reason does indeed affirm that we ought to will that which God commands, but it does not and cannot assign his will aa the foundation of the obligation. His'whole will respecting our duty, is summed up in the two precepts of the law. These, as we have seen, require universal good-will to being, or the supreme love of God and the equal love of our neighbor — that we should will the highest well-being of God and of the universe, for its own sake, or for its own intrinsic value. Eeason affirms that we ought thus to will. And can it be so self -contradictory as to affirm that we ought to will the good of God and of the universe, for its own intrinsic value ; yet not for this reason, but because God wills that we should will it ? Impossible I But in this assertion, the objector has reference to some outward act, some condition or means of the end to be chosen, and not to the end itself. But even in respect to any act whatever, his objection does not hold good. For example, God requires me to labor and pray for the salvation of souls, or to do anything else. Now his command is necessarily regarded by me as obligatory, not as an ai'bitrary requirement, but as revealing infallibly the true means or conditions of securing the great and ultimate end, which I am to will for its intrinsic value. I necessarily regard his com- mandment as wise and benevolent, and it is only because I so regard it, that I affirm, or can affirm, my obligation to obey him. Should he com- mand me to choose, as an ultimate end, or for its own intrinsic value, that which my reason affirmed to be of no intrinsic value, I could not possibly affirm my obligation to obey him. Should he command me to do that which my reason affirmed to be unwise and malevolent, it were impos- sible for me to affirm my obligation to obey him. This proves, beyond controversy, that reason does not regard his command as the foundation of the obligation, but only as infallible proof that that which he com- mands is wise and benevolent in itself, and commanded by him for that reason. If the will of God were the foundation of moral obligation, he might command me to violate and trample down all the laws of my being, and to be the' enemy of all good, and I should not only be under obligation, 8 34 STSTBMATIC. THEOLOGY. ■but affirm my obligation to obey him. But this is absurd. This brings us to the conclusion that he who asserts that moral obligation respects the choice of an end for its intrinsic value, and still affirms the will of God to be the foundation of moral obligation, contradicts his own ad- missions, the plainest intuitions of reason and divine revelation. His theory is grossly inconsistent and nonsensical. It overlooks the very na- ture of moral law as an idea of reason, and makes it to consist in arbi- trary willing. Palsy's theory of Self-interest. This theory, as every reader of Paley knows, makes self-interest the ground of moral obligation. TJpon this theory I remark — 1. That if self-interest be the ground of moral obligation, then self- interest is the end to be chosen for its own sake. To be virtuous I must in every instance intend my own interest as the supreme good. Then, according to this theory, disinterested benevolence is sin. To live to God and the universe, is not right. It is not devotion to the right end. This theory affirms self-interest to be the end for which we ought to live. Then selfishness is virtue, and benevolence is vice. These are directly opposite theories. It cannot be a trifle to embrace the wrong view of this subject. If Dr. Paley was right, all are fundamentally wrong who hold the benevolence theory. 3. Upon this hypothesis, I 3,m to treat my own interest as supremely valuable, when it is infinitely less valuable than the interests of God. Thus I am under a moral obligation to prefer an infinitely less good, be- cause it is my own, to one of infinitely greater value that belongs to an- other. This is precisely what every sinner in earth and hell does. 3. But let us examine this theory in the light of the revealed law. If this philosophy 'be correct, the law should read, " Thou shaltlove thyself supremely, and God and thy neighbor not at all." For Dr. Paley holds the only reason of the obligation to be self-interest. If this is so, then I am under an obligation to love myself alone, and never do my duty when I at all love God or my neighbor. He says, it is the utility of any rule alone which constitutes the obligation of it. {Paley's Moral Philos., book ii. chap. 6.) Again he says, "And let it be asked why I am obliged (obligated) to keep my word ? and the answer will be. Because I am urged to do so by a violent motive, namely, the expectation of being after this life rewarded if I do so, or punished if I do not." — (Paley' s Moral Philos., hook ii. chap. 3.) Thus it would seem, that it is the utility of a rule to piyself only, that constitutes the ground of obligation to obey it. But should this be denied, still it cannot be denied that Dr. Paley maintains that self-interest is the ground of moral obligation. If this is if this be the foundation of moral obligation, whether Paley or any FOUNDATION OP OBLIGATION. 35 one else holds it to be true, then, undeniably, the moral law should read, " Thou shalt love thyself supremely, and God and thy neighbor subordi- nately ; " or, more strictly, " Thou shalt love thyself as an end, and God and thy neighbor, only as a means of promoting thine own interest." If this theory be true, all the precepts in the Bible need to be altered. Instead of the injunction, " Whatever you do, do it heartily unto the Lord," it should read, " Whatever you do, do it heartily unto yourself." Instead of the injunction, " Whether, therefore, ye eat or drink, or whatsoever ye do, do all to the glory of God," it should read, "Do all to secure your own interest." Should it be said that this school would say, that the meaning of these precepts is, Do all to the glory of God to secure your own interest thereby, I answer ; This is a contradiction. To do it to or for the glory of God is one thing ; to do it to secure my own inter- est is an entirely difEerent and opposite thing. To do it for the glory of God, is to make his glory my end. But to do it to secure my own inter- est, is to make my own interest the end. 4. But let us look at this theory in the light of the revealed condi- tions of salvation. " Except a man forsake all that he hath he cannot be my disciple." If the theory under consideration be true, it should read : " Except a man make his own interest the supreme end of pur- suit, he cannot be my disciple." Again, "If any man will come after me, let him deny himself and take up his cross," etc. This, in con- formity with the theory in question, should read : " If any man will come after me, let him not deny himself, but cherish and supremely seek his own interest." A multitude of such passages might be quoted, as every reader of the Bible knows. 5. But let us examine this theory in the light of other scripture dec- larations. "It is more blessed to give than to receive." This, accord- ing to the theory we are opposing, should read, " It is more blessed to receive than to give." " Charity (love) seeketh not her own." This should read, " Charity seeketh her own." " No man (thatis, no right- eous man) liveth to himself." This should read, " Every (righteous) man liveth to himself." 6. Let this theory be examined in the light of the spirit and exam- ple of Christ. " Even Christ pleased not himself." This should read, if Christ was holy and did his duty, " Even Christ pleased himself, or which is the same thing, sought his own interest." "I seek not mine own glory, but the glory of him who sent me." This should read, "I seek not the glory of him who sent me, but mine own glory." But enough ; we cannot fail to see that this is a selfish philosophy, and the exact opposite of the truth of God. The Utilitarian philosophy. This maintains that the utility of 'an act or choice renders it obliga- 36 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. tory. That is, utility is the foundation of moral obligation ; that the tendency of an act, choice, or intention, to secure a good or yaluable end, is the foundation of the obligation to put forth that choice or intention. Upon this theory I remark — 1. That utilitarians must hold, in common with others, that it is our duty to will the good of God and our neighbor for its own sake ; and that the intrinsic value of this good creates obligation to will it, and to endeavor to promote it ; that the tendency of choosing it, would be neither useful nor obligatory, but for its intrinsic value. How, then, can they hold that the tendency of choosing to secure its object, instead of the intrinsic value of the object, should be aground of obligation. It is absurd to say that the foundation of the obligation to choose a cer- tain end, is to be found, not in the value of the end itself, but in the ten- dency of the intention to secure the end. The tendency is valuable or otherwise, as the end is valuable or otherwise. It is, and must be, the value of the end, and not the tendency of an intention to secure the end, that constitutes the foundation of the obligation to intend. 2. We have seen that the foundation of obligation to will or choose any end as such, that is, on its own account, must consist in the intrin- sic value of the end, and that nothing else whatever can impose obliga- tion to choose anything as an ultimate end, but its intrinsic value. To affirrn the contrary is to aflSrm a contradiction. It is the same as to say, that I ought to choose a thing as an end, and not yet as an end, that is, for its own sake, but for some other reason, to wit, the tendency of my choice to secure that end. Here I afiBrm at the same breath, that the thing intended is to bean end, that is, chosen for its own intrinsic value, and yet not as an end or for its intrinsic value, but for an entirely differ- ent reason, to wit, the tendency of the choice to secure it. 3. But the very announcement of this theory implies its absurdity. A choice is obligatory, because it tends to secure good. But why secure good rather than evil ? The answer is, because good is valuable. Ah ! here then we have another reason, and one which must be the true rea- son, to wit, the value of the good which the choice tends to secure. Obligation to use means to do good may, and must, be conditioned upon the tendency of those means to secure the end, but the obligation to use them is founded solely in tlie value of the end. 4. Does the law require us to love God and our neighbor, because loving God and our neighbor tends to the well-being either of God, our neighbor, or ourselves ? Is it the tendency or utility of love that makes it obligatory upon us to exercise it ? What ! will good, not from regard to its value, but because willing good will do good I But why do good ? What is this love ? Here let it be distinctly remembered that the love required by the law of God is not a mere emotion or feeling, but willing, FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 37 choosing, intending, in a word, that this love is nothing else than ulti- mate intention. What, then, is to be intended as an end, or for its owa sake ? Is it the tendency of love, or the utility of ultimate intention, that is the end to be intended ? It must be, if utilitarianism is true. According to this theory, when the law requires supreme love to God, and equal love to our neighbor, the meaning is, not that we are to will, choose, intend the well-being of God and our neighbor for its own sake, or because of its intrinsic value, but because of the tendency of the in- tention to promote the good of God, our neighbor and ourselves. But let the tendency of love or intention be what it may, the utility of it depends upon the intrinsic value of that which it tends to promote. Suppose love or intention tends to promote its end, this is a useful ten- dency only because the end is valuable in itself. It is nonsense then to say that love to God and man, or an intention to promote their good, is required, not because of the value of their well-being, but because love tends to promote their well-being. This represents the law as requiring love, not to God and our neighbor as an end, but to tendency as an end. The law in this case should read thus : " Thou shalt love the utility or tendency of love with all thy heart," etc. If the theory under consideration is true, this is the spirit and mean- ing of the law : " Thou shalt love the Lord and thy neighbor, that is, thou shalt choose their good, not for its own sake or as an end, but be- cause choosing it tends to promote it." This is absurd ; for, I ask again, why promote it but for its own value ? If the law of God requires ulti- mate intention, it is a contradiction to aflBrm that the intention ought to terminate on its own tendency as an end. 5. But it is said that we are conscious of afiBrming obligation to do many things, on the ground, that those things are useful, or tend to promote good. I answer, that we are conscious of affirming obligation to do many things upon condition of their tendency to promote good, but that we never affirm obligation to be founded on this tendency. I am under an obligation to use the means to promote good, not for the sake of its in- trinsic value, but for the sake of the tendency of the means to promote it ! This is absurd. I say again, the obligation to use means may and must be condition- ated upon perceived tendency, but never founded in this tendency. Ultimate intention has no such condition. The perceived intrinsic value imposes obligation without any reference to the tendency of the inten- tion. 6. But suppose any utilitarian should deny that moral obligation respects ultimate intention only, and maintain that it alsg respects those volitions and actions that sustain to the ultimate end the relation of 38 STSTEMA.TIC THEOLOGY. means, and therefore assert that the foundation of moral obligation in respect to all those volitions and actions, is their tendency to secure a valuable end. This would not at all relieve the diflaculty of utilitarian- ism ; for in this case tendency could only be a condition of the obligation, while the fundamental reason of the obligation would and must be, the intrinsic value of the end, which these may have a tendency to promote. Tendency to promote an end can impose no obligation. The end must be intrinsically valuable, and this alone imposes obligation to choose the end, and to use the means to promote it. Upon condition that anything is perceived to sustain to this end the relation of a necessary means, we are, for the sake of the end alone, under obligation to use the means. LECTURE V. FOUNDATION OF MORAL OBLIGfATION. The theory of Right as the foundation of obligation. In the examination of this philosophy I must begin by defining terms. What is right ? The primary signification of the term is straight. When used in a moral sense it means fit, suitable, agreeable to the nature and relations of moral agents. Right, in a moral sense, belongs to choice, in- tention, and is an intention straight with, or conformed to, moral law. The inquiry before us is, what is the ground of obligation to put forth choice or intention. Eightarians say that right is the ground of such obligation. This is the answer given to this question by a large school of philosophers and theologians. But what does this assertion mean ? It is generally held by this school, that right, in a moral sense, pertains pri- marily and strictly to intentions only. They maintain, as I do, that obli- gation pertains primarily and strictly to ultimate choice or intentions, and less strictly to executive volitions, and to choice of the conditions and means of securing the object of ultimate choice. Now in what sense of the term right do they regard it as the ground of obligation ? Right is objective and subjective. Eight in the objective sense of the term, has been recently defined to consist in the relation of intrinsic fitness existing between ultimate choice and its object.* For example, the nature or intrinsic value of the highest well-being of God and of the universe, creates the relation of intrinsic fitness between it and choice, and this relation, it is insisted, creates, or is the ground of, obligation. * Mahan'a Moral PbUosophy. FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 39 Subjective right is synonymous with righteousness, uprightness, virtue. It consists in, or is an attribute of, that state of the will which is conformed to objective right or to moral law. It is a term that ex- presses the moral quality, element, or attribute of that ultimate intention which the law of God requires. In other words still, it is conformity of heart to the law of objective right ; or, as I just said, it is more strictly the term that designates the moral character of that state of heart. Some choose to regard subjective right as consisting in this state of heart, and others insist that it is only an element, attribute, or quality of this state of heart, or of this ultimate intention. I shall not contend about words, but shall show that it matters not, so far as the question we are about to examine is concerned, in which of these lights subjective right is regarded, whether as consisting in ultimate intention conformed to law, or, as being an attribute, element, or quality of this intention. The theory under consideration was held by the ancient Greek and Roman philosophers. It was the theory of Kant, and is now the theory of the transcendental school in Europe and America. Cousin, in man- ifest accordance with the views of Kant, states the theory in these words : " Do right for the sake of the right, or rather, will the right for the sake of the right. Morality has to do with the intentions." — {Enunciation of Moral Law — Elements of Psychology, p. 163.) Those who follow Kant, Cousin, and Coleridge state the theory either in the same words, or in words that amount to the same thing. They regard right as the foun- dation of moral obligation. "Will the right for the sake of the right." This must mean, will the right as an ultimate end, that is, for its own sake. Let us examine this very popular philosophy, first, in the light of its own principles, and secondly in the light of revelation. The writer first above alluded to, has professedly given a critical definition of the exact position and teaching of rightarians. They hold, according to him, and I suppose he has rightly defined the position of that school, that subjective right is the ground of obligation. We shall see, hereafter, that subjective right, or righteousness, can never be a gi'ound of moral obligation. We will here attend to the critically defined position of the rightarian who holds that the relation of intrinsic fitness existing between choice and an intrinsically valuable object, is the ground of obligation to choose that object. N"ow observe, this writer strenuously maintains, that the reason for ultimate choice must be found exclusively in the object of such choice, in other words, that ultimate choice, is the choice of its object for its own sake, or for what is intrinsic in the object itself. He also aEBrma repeatedly, that the ground of obligation is, and must be, found exclu- sively in the object of ultimate choice, and also that the ground of obli- gation is the considerafiion, intrinsic in the object of choice, which com- 40 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. pels the reason to aflBrm the obligation to choose it for its own Sake. But all this as flatly as possible contradicts his rightarian theory, as above stated. If the ground of obligation to put forth ultimate choice is to be found, as it certainly must be, in the nature of the object of choice, and in nothing extrinsic to it, how can it consist in the relation of intrinsic fitness existing between the choice and its object ? Plainly it cannot. This relation is not intrinsic in the object of choice. Observe, the obligation is to choose the object of ultimate choice, not for the sake of the relation existing between the choice and its object, but exclusively for the sake of what is intrinsic in the object itself. The relation is not the object of choice, but the relation is created by the object of choice. Choice being what it is, the intrinsic nature or value of the object, as the good of being for example, creates both the relation of Tightness and the obligation to choose the object for its own sake. That which creates the relation of objective rightness must, for the same reason, create the obligation, for it is absurd to say that the in- trinsic value of the object creates the relation of rightness between itself and choice, and yet that it does not impose or create obligation to choose itself for its own sake. It is self-evident then, that since the object ought to be chosen for the sake of its own nature, or for what is intrinsic in it, and not for the sake of the relation in question, the nature of the object, and not the relatioQ, is, and must be, the ground of obligation. But, the writer who has given the above defined position of the right- arians, says that "the intelligence, in judging an act to be right or wrong, does not take into the account the object nor the act by itself, but both together, in their intrinsic relations, as the ground of its affir- mation." But the nature of ultimate choice, and the nature of its object, the good of being, for example, with their intrinsic relations to each other, form a ground of obligation to choose — what ? the choice, the object, and their intrinsic relations ? No, but simply and only to choose the good for its own sake, or solely for the sake of what is intrinsic in it. Observe, it is often affirmed by this writer, that ultimate choice is the choice of an object for its own sake, or for what is intrinsic in the object itself. That the ground of obligation to put forth ultimate choice, must in every case, be intrinsic in the object of choice. But the object of choice in this case is the good of being, and not the nature of the choice and of the good of being, together with the intrinsic relation of rightness existing between them. The form of the obligation discloses the ground of it. The form of the obligation is to choose the good of being, i. e. the object of choice, for what is intrinsic in it. Then, the ground of the obligation must be, the intrinsic nature of the good, i. e. of the object ol FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 41 choice. The nature of choice, and the intrinsic relations of the choice, and the good, are conditions, but not the ground, of the obligation. Had this writer only kept in mind his own most critical definition of ultimate intention, his often repeated assertions that the ground of obli- gation must be, in every case, found intrinsically in the object of ulti- mate choice, and in nothing extraneous to it, he never could have made the statement we have just examined. The duty of universal disinterested benevolence is universally and necessarily aflBrmed and admitted. But if the rightarian be the true theory, then disinterested benevolence is sin. According to this scheme, the right, and not the good of being, is the end to, and for which, God and all moral agents ought to live. According to this theory, disinter- ested benevolence can never be duty, can never be right, but always and necessarily wrong. I do not mean that the advocates of this theory see and avow this conclusion. But it is wonderful that they do not, for nothing is more seK-evident. If moral agents ought to will the right for the sake of the right, or will good, not for the sake of the good, but for the sake of the relation of Tightness existing between the choice and the good, then to will the good for its own sake is sin. It is not willing the right end. It is willing the good and not the right as an ultimate end. These are opposing theories. Both cannot be true. Which is the right to will, the good for its own sake, or the right ? Let universal reason answer. But let us examine this philosophy in the light of the -oracles of God. 1. In the light of the moral law. The whole law is expressed by the great Teacher thus : " Thou shalt love the Lord thy God with all thy heart, and with all thy soul, with all thy might, and with all thy strength ; and thy neighbor as thyself." Paul says : " All the law is fulfilled in one word — love : therefore love is the fulfilling of the law." Now it is admitted by this philosophy, that the love required by the law is not a mere emotion, but that it consists in willing, choice, intention ; that it consists in the choice of an ultimate end, or in the choice of something for its own sake, or, which is the same thing, for its intrinsic value. What is this which the law requires us to will to God and our neighbor ? Is it to will something to, or respecting, God and our neigh- bor, not for the sake of the intrinsic value of that something, but for the sake of the relation of rightness existing between choice and that some- thing ? 'Bhis were absurd. Besides, what has this to do with loving God and our neighbor ? To will the something, the good, for example, of God, and our neighbor, for the sake of the relation in question, is not the same as to love God and our neighbor, as it is not willing their good for its own sake. It is not willing their good, out of any regard to them, but solely out of regard to the relation of fitnesg g^igting between tlje 42 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. willing and the object willed. Suppose it be said, that the law requires as to will the good, or highest blessedness of God and our neighbor, be- cause it is right. This is a contradiction and an impossibility. To will the blessedness of God and our neighbor, in any proper sense, is to will it for its own sake, or as an ultimate end. But this is not to will it be- cause it is right. To will the good of God and our neighbor for its own sake, or its intrinsic value, is right. But to will it, not for the sake of its intrinsic value to them, but for the sake of the relations in question, is not right. To will the good because it is good, or the valuable be- cause it is valuable, is right, because it is willing it for the right reason. But to will it, not for its value, but for the sake of the relation of fitness between the willing and the object, is not right, because it is not willing it for the right reason. The law of God does not, cannot, require us to love right more than God and our neighbor. What ! right of greater value than the highest well being of God and of the universe ? Impos- sible ! It is impossible that the moral law should require anything else than to will the highest good of universal being as an ultimate end, i. e. for its own sake. It is a first truth of reason, that this is the most valu- able thing possible or conceivable ; and that could by no possibility be law, which should require anything else to be chosen as an ultimate end. According to this philosophy, the revealed law should read : " Thou shalt love the right for its own sake, with all thy heart and with all thy soul." The fact is, the law requires the supreme love of God, and the equal love of our neighbor. It says nothing, and implies nothing, about doing right for the sake of the right. Kightarianism is a rejection of the divine revealed law, and a substituting in its stead an entirely different rule of moral obligation : a rule that deifies right, that rejects the claim of God, and exalts right to the throne. 2. " "Whether therefore ye eat or drink, or whatsoever ye do, do all to the glory of God." Does this precept require us to will the glory of God for its intrinsic or relative value, or for the sake of intrinsic fitness between the willing and its object ? The glory and renown of God is of infinite value to him, and to the universe, and for this reason it should be promoted. The thing required here is doing, an executive act. The spirit of the requisition is this : Aim to spread abroad the renown or glory of God, as the means of securing the highest weU-being of the universe. Why ? I answer : for the sake of the intrinsic value of this well-being, and not for the sake of the relation of fitness existing between the willing and the object. 3. " Do good unto all men, as ye have opportunity." Here again, are we required to do the good, for the sake of the good, or for the sake of the relation of rightness, between the doing and the good ? I answer : we are to do the good for the sake of the good. FOUNDATION OP OBLIGATION. 43 4. Take the commands to pray and labor for the saltation of souls. Do such commandments require us to go forth to will or do the right for the sake of the right, or to will the salvation of souls for the intrinsic value of their salvation ? When we pray and preach and converse, must we aim at right, must the love of right, and not the love of God and of souls influence us ? "When I am engaged in prayer, and travail night and day for souls, and have an eye so single to the good of souls and to the glory of God, and am so swallowed up with my subject as not so much as to think of the right, am I all wrong ? Must I pray because it is right, and do all I do, and suffer all I suffer, not from good-will to God and man, but because it is right ? Who does not know, that to intend the right for the sake of the right in all these things, instead of having an eye single to the good of being, would and must be any- thing rather than true religion ? ■" 5. Examine this philosophy in the light of the scripture declaration : " God so loved the world that he gave his only begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him might not perish, but have everlasting life." Now, are we to understand that God gave his Son, not from any regard to the good of souls for its own sake, but for the sake of the right ? Did he will the right for the sake of the right ? Did he give his Son to die for the right, for the sake of the right, or to die to render the salva- tion of souk possible, for the sake of the souls ? Did Christ give himself to labor and die for the right, for the sake of the right, or for souls, from love to souls ? Did prophets, and apostles, and martyrs, and have the saints in all ages, willed the right for the sake of the right, or have they labored and suffered and died for God and souls, from love to them ? 6. But take another passage which is quoted in support of this phi- losophy : "Children, obey your parents in the Lord, for this is right." Now what is the spirit of this requirement ? What is it to obey parents ? Why, if as this philosophy holds, it must resolve itself into ultimate intention, what must the child intend for its own sake ? Must he will good to God and his parents, and obey his parents as the means of securing the highest good, or must he will the right as an end, for the sake of the right, regardless of the good of God or of the universe ? Would it be right to will the right for the sake of the right, rather than to will the good of the universe for the sake of the good, and obey his parents as a means of securing the highest good ? It is right to will the highest good of God and of the universe, and to use all the necessary means, and fulfil all the necessary conditions of this highest well-being. For children to obey their parents, is one of the meatis, and for this reason it is right, and upon no other condi- tion can it be required. But it is said that children affirm their obliga- 44 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. > tion to obey their parents, entirely irrespective of the obedience having any reference, or sustaining any relation, to the good of being. This is a mistake. The child, if he is a moral agent, and does really afiQrm moral obligation, not only does, but must perceive the end upon which his choice or intention ought to terminate. If he really makes an intelligent aflSrmation, ib is and must be, that he ought to wUl an end ; that this end is not, and cannot be the right, as has been shown. He knows that he ought to will his parents' happiness, and his own happi- ness, and the happiness of the world, and of God ; and he knows that obedience to his parents sustains the relation of a means to this end ; The fact is, it is a first truth of reason, that he ought to will the good of his parents, and the good of everybody. He also knows that obe- dience to his parents is a necessary means to this end. If he does not know these things, it is impossible for him to be a moral agent, to make any intelligent afBrmation at all ; and if he has any idea of obedi- ence, it is, and must be, only such as animals have who are actuated wholly by hope, fear and instinct. As well might we say, that an ox or a dog, who gives indication of knowing, in some sense, that he ought to obey us, affirms moral obligation of himself, as to say this of a child in whose mind the idea of the good, or valuable to being is not developed. What ! does moral obligation respect ultimate intention only ; and does ultimate intention consist in the choice of something for its own intrinsic value, and yet is it true that children affirm moral obhgatiou before the idea of the intrinsically valuable is at all developed ? Impos- sible I But this objection assumes that children have the idea of right developed before the idea of the valuable. This cannot be. The end to be chosen must be apprehended by the mind, before the mind can have the idea of moral obligation to choose an end, or of the right or wrong of choosing or not choosing it. The development of the idea of the good or valuable, must precede the development of the ideas of right and of moral obligation. Take this philosophy on its own ground, and suppose the relation of rightness existing between choice and its object to be the ground of obli- gation, it is plain that the intrinsically valuable object must be perceived, before this relation can be perceived. So that the idea of the intrinsi- cally valuable must be developed, as a condition of the existence of the idea of the relation in question. The law of God, then, is not, and can- not be, developed in the mind of a child who has no knowledge or idea of the valuable, and who has, and can have, no reference to the good of any being, in obedience to his parents. It is one thing to intend that, the intending of which is right, and quite another to intend the right as an end. For example, to choose my own gratification as an end, is wrong. But this is not choosing the FOUNDATION OP OBLlGtATlON. 45 wrong as an end. A drunkard chooses to gratify his appetite for strong drink as an end, that is, for its own sake. This is wrong. But the choice does not terminate on the wrong, but on the gratification. The thing intended is not the wrong. The liquor is not chosen, the gratifi- cation is not intended, because it is wrong, but notwithstanding it is wrong. To love God is right, but to suppose that God is loved because it is right, is absurd. It is to suppose that God is loved, not from any regard to God, but from a regard to right. This is an absurdity and a contradiction. To love or will the good of my neighbor, is right. But to will the right, instead of the good of my neighbor, is not right. It is loving right instead of my neighbor ; but this is not right. 1. But it is objected, that I am conscious of affirming to myself that I ought to will the right. This is a mistake. I am conscious of affirm- ing to myself, that I ought to will that, the willing of which is right, to wit, to will the good of God and of being. This is right. But this is not choosing the right as an end. But it is still insisted, that we are conscious of affirming obligation to will, and do, many things, simply and only because it is right thus to wiU, and do, and in view of this rightness. To this I reply, that the immediate reason for the act, thought of ' at the time, and immediately present to the mind, may be the rightness of the act, but in such cases the rightness is only regarded by the mind as a condition and never as the ground of obligation. The act must be ultimate choice, or the choice of conditions and means. In ultimate choice, surely, the mind can never affirm, or think of the relation of rightness between the choice and its object, instead of the intrinsic value of the object, as the ground of obligation. Nor can the mind think of the relation of rightness between the choice of conditions and means, and its object, as the ground of the obligation to choose them. It does, and must, assume, the value of the end, as creating both the obli- gation to choose, and the relation in question. The fact is, the mind necessarily assumes, without always thinking of this assumption, its obli- gation to will the good, for its own sake, together with all the known conditions and means. Whenever therefore it perceives a condition, or a means of good, it instantly and necessarily affirms obligation to choose it, or, which is the same thing, it affirms the rightness of such choice. The rightness of the choice may be, and often is the thing immediately thought of, but the assumption is, and must be, in the mind, that this obligation, and hence the rightness is created by the nature of the object to which this thing sustains the relation of a condition or a means. 2. But it is said again, "I am conscious of affirming to myself that I ought to will the good of being, because it is right." That is, to will the good of being, as a means, and the right as an end ! which ii 46 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. making right the supreme good, and the good of being a, means to that end. This is absurd. But to say, that I am conscious of aflSrming to myself my obligation to love or will the good of God and my neighbor, because it is right, is a contradiction. It is the same as to say, I ought to love, or intend the good of God and my neighbor, as an ultimate end, and yet not to intend the good of God and my neighbor, but intend the right. 3. But it is said, that " I ought to love God in compliance with, and out of respect to my obligation ; that I ought to will it, because and for the reason that I am bound to will it." That is, that in loving God and my neighbor, I must intend to discharge or comply with my obligation ; and this, it is said, is identical with intending the right. But ought my supreme object to be to discharge my duty — to meet obligation, instead of willing the well-being of God and my neighbor for its own sake ? If my end is to do my duty, I do not do it For what is my obligation ? Why, to love, or will the good of God and my neighbor, that is, as an end, or for its own value. To discharge my obligation, then, I must intend the good of God and my neighbor, as an end. That is, I must intend that which I am under an obligation to intend. But I am not under an obligation to intend the right, because it is right, nor do my duty because it is my duty, but to intend the good of God and of my neighbor, because it is good. Therefore, to discharge my obligation, I must intend the good, and not the right — the good of God and my neighbor and not to do my duty. I say again, to intend the good, or valuable, is right but to intend the right is not right. 4. But it is said, that in very many instances, at least, I am conscious of affirming my moral obligation to do the right, without any reference to the good of being, when I can assign no other reason for the affirma- tion of bbligation than the right. For example, I behold virtue ; I affirm spontaneously and necessarily, that I ought to love that virtue. And tliis, it is said, has no reference to the good of being. Is willing the right for the sake of the right, and loving virtue, the same thing ? But what is it to love virtue ? Not a mere feeling of delight or complacency in it. It is agreed that moral obligation, strictly speaking, respects the ultimate intention only. What, then, do I mean by the affirmation that I ought to love virtue ? What is virtue ? It is ultimate intention, or an attribute of ultimate intention. But what is loving virtue ? It consists iu willing its existence. But it is said that I affirm my obligation to love virtue as an end, or for its own sake, and not from any regard to the good of being. This is absurd, and a contradiction. To love virtue, it is said, is to will its existence as an end. But virtue consists in in- tending an end. Kow, to love virtue, it is said, is to will, intend its ex- istence as an end, for its own sake. Then, according to this theory, I FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 47 afiSrm my obligation to intend the intention of a virtuous being as an end, instead of intending the same end thatihe does. This is absurd ; his intention is of no value, is neither naturally good nor morally good, irrespective of the end intended. It is neither right nor wrong, irrespec- tive of the end chosen. It is therefore impossible to will, choose, intend the intention as an end, without reference to the end intended. To love virtue, then, is to love or will the end upon which virtuous intention terminates, namely, the good of being ; or, in other words, to love virtue is to will its existence for the sake of the end it hag in view, which is the same thing as to will the same end. Virtue is intending, choosing an end. Loving virtue is willing that the virtuous intention should exist for the sake of its end. Take away the end, and who would or could will the intention ? Without the end, the virtue, or intention, would not and could not exist. It is not true, therefore, that in the case supposed, I affirm my obligation to will, or intend, without any ref- erence to the good of being. 5. But again, it is said, that when I contemplate the moral excellence of God, I affirm my obligation to love him solely for his goodness, with- out any reference to the good of being, and for no ether reason than because it is right. But to love God because of his moral excellence, and because it is right, are not the same thing. It is a gross contradic- tion to talk of loving God for his moral excellence, because it is right. It is the same as to say, I love God for the reason that he is morally ex- cellent, or worthy, yet not at all for this reason, but for the reason that it is right. To love God for his moral worth, is to will good to him for its own sake upon condition that he deserves it. But to will his moral worth because it is right, is to will the right as an ultimate end, to have supreme regard to right, instead of the moral worth, or the weU-being of God. But it may reasonably be asked, why should rightarians bring forward these objections ? They all assume that moral obligation may respect something else than ultimate intention. Why, I repeat it, should right- arians affirm J;hat the moral excellence of God is the foundation of moral obligation, since they hold that right is the foundation of moral obliga- tion ? Why should the advocates of the theory that the moral excel- lence of God is the foundation of moral obligation, affirm that right is the foundation, or that we are bound to love God for his moral excel- lence, because this is right ? These are gross contradictions. Eightarians hold that disinterested benevolence is a universal duty ; that this benevo- lence consists in willing the highest good of being in general, for its own. sake ; that this good, by virtue of its own nature, imposes obligation to choose it, for its own sake, and therefore, and for this reason, it is right thus to choose it But notwithstanding all this, they most inconsistently 48 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. affirm that right is universally the ground of obligation. Consistency must compel them to deny that disinterested benevolence ever is, or can be, duty and right, or to abandon the nonsensical dogma, that right ia the ground of obligation. There is no end to the absurdities in which error involves its advocates, and it is singular to see the advocates of the different theories, each in his turn, abandon his own and afQrm some other, as an objection to the true theory. It has also been, and still is, common for writers to confound different theories with each other, and to afi&rm, in the compass of a few pages, several different theories. At least this has been done in some instances. Consistent rightarianism is a godless, Christless, loveless philosophy. This Kant saw and acknowledged. He calls it pure legality, tha^t is, he understands the law as imposing obligation by virtue of its own nature, instead of the intrinsic value of the end, which the law requires moral agents to choose. He loses sight of the end, and does not recognize any end whatever. He makes a broad distinction between morality and re- ligion. Morality consists, according to him, in the adoption of the maxim, " Do right for the sake of the right," or, " Act at all times upon a maxim fit for law universal." The adoption of this maxim is morality. But now, having adopted this maxim, the mind goes abroad to carry its maxim into practice. It finds God and being to exist, and sees it to be right to intend their good. This intending the good is religion, accord- ing to him. Thus, he says, ethics lead to or result in religion. — (See Kant, on Religion.) But we feel prompted to inquire whether, when we apprehend God and being, we are to will their well-being as an end, or for its own sake, or because it is right ? If for its own sake, where then is the maxim, " Will the right for the sake of the right ? " For if we are to will the good, not as an ultimate end, but for the sake of the right, then right is the end that is preferred to the highest well-being of God and of the universe. It is impossible that this should be religion. In- deed Kant himself admits that this is not religion. But enough of this cold and loveless philosophy. As it exalts right above all that is called God, and subverts all the teachings of the Bible, it canaot be a light thing to be deluded by it. But it is remarkable and interesting to see Christian rightarians, without being sensible of their inconsistency, so often confound this philosophy with that which teaches that good- will to being constitutes virtue. Numerous examples of it occur everywhere in their writings, which demonstrate that rightarianism is with them only a theory that " plays round the head but comes not near the heart." Fot'NDATloN OP oSLlGtATIoN. 49 LECTURE VI. FOUNDATION OP MORAL OBLIGATION. / now enter upon the discussion of the theory, that the goodness, or moral excellence of God is the foundation of moral olligation. To this philosophy I reply, 1. That the reason of obligation, or that which imposes obligation, is identical with the end on which the intention ought to terminate. If, therefore, the goodness of God be the reason, or foundation of moral ob- ligation, then the goodness of God is the ultimate end to be intended. But as this goodness consists in love or benevolence, it is impossible that it should be regarded or chosen, as an ultimate end ; and to choose it were to choose the divine choice, to intend the divine intention as an ul- timate end, instead of choosing what God chooses, and intending what he intends. Or if the goodness or moral excellence of God is to be re- garded not as identical with, but as an attribute or moral quality of be- nevolence, then, upon the theory under consideration, a moral agent ought to choose a quality or attribute of the divine choice or intention as an ultimate end, instead of the end upon which the divine intention ter- minates. This is absurd. 3. It is impossible that virtue should be the foundation, of moral obli- gation. Virtue consists in a compliance with, moral obligation. But obli- gation must exist before it can be complied with. Now, upon this theory, obligation cannot exist until virtue exists as its foundation. Then this theory amounts to this : virtue is the foundation of moral obligation ; therefore virtue must exist before moral obligation can exist. But as virtue consists in a conformity to moral obligation, moral obligation must exist before virtue can exist. Therefore neither moral obligation nor virtue, can ever by any possibility, exist. God's virtue must have existed prior to his obligation, as its foundation. But as virtue consists in com- pliance with moral obligation, and as obligation could not exist until vir- tue existed as its foundation ; in other words, as obligation could not exist without the previous existence of virtae as its foundation, and as virtue could not exist without the previous existence of obligation, it fol- lows, that neither God nor any other being could ever be virtuous, for the reason that he could never be the subject of moral obligation. Should it be said, that God's holiness is the foundation of our obligation to love him, I ask in what sense it can be so. What is the nature or form of that love, which his virtue lays us under an obligation to exercise ? It cannot be a mere emotion of complacency, for emotions being involuntary states of mind and mere phenomena of the sensibility, are not strictly within 50 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY, the pale of legislation and morality. Is this love resolvable into benevo- lence or good-will ? But why will good to God rather than evil ? Why,- surely, because good is valuable in itself. But if it is valuable in itself, this must be the fundamental reason for willing it as a possible good ; and his virtue must be only a secondary reason or condition of the obli- gation to will his actual blessedness. But again, the foundation of moral obligation must be the same in all worlds, and with all moral agents, for the simple reason that moral law is one and identical in all worlds. If God's virtue is not the foundation of moral- obligation in him, which it cannot be, it cannot be the foundation of obligation in us, as moral law must require him to choose the same end that it requii'es us to choose. His virtue must be a secondary reason of his obligation to will his own actual blessedness, and the condition of our obligation to will his actual and highest blessedness, but cannot be the fundamental reason, that always being the intrinsic value of his well-being. If this theory is true, disinterested benevolence is a sin. Undeniably benevolence consists in willing the highest well-being of God and the universe for its own sake, in devoting the soul and all to this end. But this theory teaches us, either to will the moral excellence of God, for its own sake, or as an ultimate end, or to will his good and the good of the universe, not for its own sake, but because he is morally excellent. The benevolence theory regards blessedness as the end, and holiness or moral excellence only as a condition of the end. This theory regards moral excellence itself as the end. Does the moral excellence of God impose obligation to will his moral excellence for its own sake ? If not, it cannot be a ground of obligation. Does his moral excellence impose obligation to will his highest good, and that of the universe, for its own sake ? No, for this were a contradiction. For, be it remembered, no one thing can be a ground of obligation to choose any other thing, for its own sake. That which creates obligation to choose, by reason of its own nature, must itself be the identical object of choice ; the obligation is to choose that object for its own sake. If the divine moral excellence is the ground of obligation to choose, then this excellence must be the object of this choice, and disinterested benevolence is never right, but always wrong. 2. But for the sake of a somewhat systematic examination of this subject, I will — (1.) Show what virtue, or moral excellence is. (2.) That it cannot be the foundation of moral obligation (3.) Show what moral worth or good desert is. (4.) That it cannot be the foundation of moral obligation. (5.) Show what relation virtue, merit, and moral worth sustain to moral obligation. FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 51 (6.) Answer objections. (1.) Show what virtue, or moral excellence is. Virtue, or moral excellence, consists in conformity of will to moral law. It must either be identical with love or good- will, or it must be the moral attribute or element of good-will or benevolence. (3.) It cannot be the foundation of moral obligation. It is agreed, that the moral law requires love ; and that this term expresses all that it requires. It is also agreed that this love is good- will, or that it resolves itself into choice, or ultimate intention. It must, then, consist in the choice of an ultimate end. Or, in more com- mon language, this love consists in the supreme devotion of heart and soul to God and to the highest good of being. But since virtue either consists in choice, or is an attribute of choice, or benevolence, it is im- possible to will it as an ultimate end. For this would involve the absurdity of choosing choice, or intending intention, as an end, instead of choosing that as an end upon which virtuous choice terminates. Or, if virtue be regarded as the moral attribute of love or benevolence, to make it an ultimate end would be to make an attribute of choice an ultimate end, instead of that on which choice terminates, or ought to terminate. This is absurd. (3.) Show what moral worth, or good desert is. Moral worth, or good desert, is not identical with virtue, or obedience to moral law, but is an attribute of character, resulting from bbedience. Virtue, or holiness, is a state of mind. It is an active and benevolent state of the will. Moral worth is not a state of mind, but is the result of a state of mind. We say that a man's obedience to moral law is val- uable in such a sense that a holy being is worthy, or deserving of good, because of his virtue, or holiness. But this worthiness, this good desert, is not a state of mind, but, as I said, it is a result of benevolence. It is an attribute or quality of character, and not a state of mind. (4.) Moral worth or good desert cannot be the foundation of moral obligation. (a.) It is admitted, that good, or the intrinsically valuable to being, must be the foundation of moral obligation. The law of God requires the choice of an ultimate end. This end must be intrinsically valuable, for it is its intrinsic value that imposes obligation to will it. Nothing, then, can be the foundation of moral obligation but that which is a good, or iatrinsically valuable in itself. (S.) Ultimate good, or the intrinsically valuable, must belong to, and be inseparable from, sentient existences. A block of marble cannot enjoy, or be the subject of, good. That which is intrinsically good to moral agents, must consist in a state of mind. It must be something 62 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY, that is found within the field of consciousness. Kothing can be to them an intrinsic good, but that of which they can be conscious. By this it is not intended that everything of which they are conscious, is to them an ultimate good, or a good in any sense ; but it is intended, that that cannot be to them an ultimate, or intrinsic good, of which they are not conscious. Ultimate good must consist in a conscious state of mind. Whatever conduces to the state of mind that is necessarily regarded by ns as intrinsically good or valuable, is to us a relative good. But the state of mind alone is the ultimate good. From this it is plain, that moral worth, or good desert, cannot be the foundation of moral obligation, because it is not a state of mind, and cannot be an ultimate good. The consciousness of good desert, that is, the consciousness of affirming of ourselves good desert, is an ultimate good. Or, more strictly, the satis- faction which the mind experiences, upon occasion of affirming its good desert, is an ultimate good. But neither the conscious affirmation of good desert, nor the satisfaction occasioned by the affirmation, is identical with moral worth or good desert. Merit, moral worth, good desert, is the condition, or occasion, of the affirmation, and of the resulting con- scious satisfaction, and is therefore a good, but it is not, and cannot be an ultimate, or intrinsic good. It is valuable ; but not intrinsically val- uable. Were it not that moral beings are so constituted, that it meets a demand of the intelligence, and therefore produces satisfaction in its contemplation, it would not be, and could not reasonably be regarded as a good in any sense. But since it meets a demand of the intelligence, it is a relative good, and results in ultimate good. (5.) Show what relation moral excellence, worth, merit, desert, sus- tain to moral obligation. (a.) We have seen, that neither of them can be the foundation of moral obligation ; that neither of them has in it the element of the in- trinsic, or ultimate good, or valuable ; and that, therefore, a moral agent can never be under obligation to will or choose them as an ultimate end. (S.) Worth, merit, good desert, cannot be a distinct ground, or foun- dation, of moral obligation, in such a sense as to impose obligation, irre- spective of the intrinsic value of good. All obligation must respect, strictly, the choice of an object for its own sake, with the necessary con- ditions and means. The intrinsic value of the end is the foundation of the obligation to choose both it and the necessary conditions and means of securing it. But for the intrinsic value of the end there could be no obligation to will the conditions and means. Whenever a thing is seen to be a necessary condition or means of securing an intrinsically valuable end, this perceived relation is the condition of our obligation to will it. The obligation is, and must be, founded in the intrinsic value of the end, and conditionated upon the perceived relation of the object to the FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 53 end. The intelligence of every moral agent, from its nature and laws, afl&rms, that the ultimate good and blessedness of moral beings is, and ought to be, conditionated upon their holiness and good desert. This being a demand of reason, reason can never affirm moral obligation to will the actual blessedness of moral agents, but upon condition of their virtue, and consequent good desert, or merit. The intelligence affirms that it is fit, suitable, proper, that virtue, good desert, merit, holiness, should be rewarded with blessedness. Blessedness is a good in itself, and ought to be willed for that reason, and moral agents are under obli- gation to will that all beings capable of good may be worthy to enjoy, and may, therefore, actually enjoy blessedness. But they are not under obligation to will that every moral being should actually enjoy blessed- ness, but upon condition of holiness and good desert. The relation that holiness, merit, good desert, etc., sustain to moral obligation, is this : they supply the condition of the obligation to will the actual blessedness of the being or beings who are holy. The obligation must be founded in the intrinsic value of the good we are to will to them. For it is ab- surd to say, that we are, or can be, under obligation to will good to them for its own sake, or as an ultimate end, and yet that the obligation should not be founded in the intrinsic value of the good. Were it not for the intrinsic value of their good, we should no sooner affirm obliga- tion to will good to them than evil. The good or blessedness is the thing, or end, we are under obligation to will. But obligation to will an ultimate end cannot possibly be founded in anything else than the intrinsic value of the end. Suppose it should be said, that in the case of merit, or good desert, the obligation is founded in merit, and only conditioned on the intrinsic value of the good I am to will. This would be to make desert the end willed, and good only the condition, or means. This were absurd. (c.) But again, to make merit the ground of the obligation, and the good willed only a condition, amounts to this : I perceive merit, whereupon I affirm my obligation to will — what ? Not good to the de- serving because of its value to him, nor from any disposition to see him enjoy blessedness for its own sake, but because of his merit. But what does he merit ? Why, good, or blessedness. It is good, or blessedness, that I am to will to him, and this is the end I am bound to will ; that is, I am to will his good, or blessedness, for its own intrinsic value. The obligation, then, must be founded in the intrinsic value of the end, that is, his well-being, or blessedness, and only conditioned upon merit. (6.) I am to answer objections. (a.) It is objected, that, if virtue is meritorious, if it merits, de- serves anything, this implies corresponding obligation, and that merit, er desert, must impose, or be the ground of, the obligation to give that 64 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. which is merited. But this objection is either a mere begging of the question, or it is sheer logomachy. It assumes that the words, desert and merit, mean what they cannot mean. Let the objector remember, that he holds that obligation respects ultimate intention. That ultimate intention must find the grounds of its obligation exclusively in its object. Now, if desert or merit is a ground of obligation, then merit or desert must be the object of the intention. Desert, merit, must be willed for its own sake. But is this the thing that is deserved, merited ? Docs a meritorious being deserve that his merit or desert should be willed for its own sake ? Indeed, is this what he deserves ? We understandingly speak of good desert, the desert of good and of evil ; can a being deserve that his desert shall be chosen for its own sake ? If not, then it is impossible that desert or merit should be a ground of obligation; for be it remembered, that whatever is a ground of obligation ought to be chosen for its own sake. But if good desert deserves good, it is self-evident that the intrinsic value of the good is the ground, and merit only a condition, of obligation to will the actual and particular enjoyment of the good by the meritorious individual. Thus merit changes merely the form of obligation. If an individual is wicked, I ought to will his good as valuable in itself, and that he should comply with the necessary conditions of happiness, and thereupon actually enjoy happiness. If he is virtuous, I am to will his good still for its intrinsic value ; and, since he has complied with the conditions of enjoyment, that he actually enjoy happiness. In both cases, I am bound to will his good, and for the same fundamental reason, namely, its intrinsic value. Neither the fact nor the ground of obliga- tion to will his good is changed by his virtue ; the form only of the obli- gation is changed. I may be under obligation to will evil to a particu- lar being, but in this case I am not bound to will the evil for its own sake, and therefore, not as an end or ultimate. I ought sometimes to will the punishment of the guilty, not for its own sake, but for the sake of the public good ; and the intrinsic value of the good to be promoted is the ground of the obligation, and guilt or demerit is only a condition of the obligation in that form. If merit or desert be a ground of obli- gation, then merit or desert ought to be chosen for its own sake. It would follow from this, that ill desert ought to be chosen for its own sake, as well as good desert. But who will pretend that ill desert ought to be willed for its own sake ? But if this is not, cannot be so, then it follows, that desert is not a ground of obligation, and that is not an object of ultimate choice, or of choice at all, only as a means to an end. (b. ) It is asserted, in support of the theory we are examining, that the Bible represents the goodness of God as a reason for loving him, or as a foundation of the obligation to love him. To this I answer, the Bible may assign, and does assign the goodness FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 65 of God as a reason for loving him, but it does not follow, that it affirms, or assumes, that this reason is the foundation, or a foundation of the obligation. The inquiry is, in what sense does the Bible assign the goodness of God as a reason for loving him ? Is it that the goodness of God is the foundation of the obligation, or only a condition of the obligation to will his actual blessedness in particular ? Is his goodness a distinct ground of obligation to love him ? But what is this love that his goodness lays us under an obligation exercise to him ? It is agreed, that it cannot be an emotion, that it must consist in willing something to him. It is said by some, that the obligation is to treat him as worthy. But I ask, worthy of what ? Is he worthy of anything. If so, what is it ? For this is the thing that I ought to will to him. Is he merely worthy that I should will his worthiness for its own sake ? This must be, if his worthiness is the ground of obligation ; for that which is the ground of obligation to choose must be the object of choice. Why, he is worthy of blessing, and honor, and praise. But these must all be em- braced in the single word, love. The law has forever decided the point, that our whole duty to God is expressed by this one term. It has been common to make assertions upon the subject, that involve a contradiction of the Bible. The law of God, as revealed in the two precepts, "Thou shalt love the Lord thy God with all thy heart, and thy neighbor as thy- self," covers the whole ground of moral obligation. It is expressly and repeatedly taught in the Bible, that love to God and our neighbor is the fulfilling of the law. It is, and must be admitted, that this love consists in willing something to God and our neighbor. What, then, is to be willed to them ? The command is, " Thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself." This says nothing about the character of my neighbor. It is the value of his interests, of his well-being, that the law requires me to regard. It does not require me to love my righteous neighbor merely, nor to love my righteous neighbor better than I do my wicked neighbor. It is my neighbor that I am to love. That is, I am to will his well-being, or his good, with the conditions and means thereof, according to its value. If the law contemplated the virtue of any being as a distinct ground of obligation, it could not read as it does. ' It must, in that case, have read as follows : " If thou art righteous, and thy neighbor is as righteous as thou art, thou shalt love him as thyself. But if he is right- eous and thou art not, thou shalt love him and not thyself. If thou art righteous, and he is not, thou shalt love thyself, and not thy neighbor." How far would this be from the gloss of the Jewish rabbles so fully re- buked by Christ, namely, '* Ye have heard that it hath been said by them of old time. Thou slialt love thy neighbor, and hate thine enemy. But I say unto you, Love your enemies ; bless them that curse you ; do good to them that hate you ; and pray for them that despitef ully use and 56 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY, persecute you. For if ye love them that love you, what thank have ye ? Do not even the publicans the same ? " The fact is, the law knows but one ground of moral obligation. It requires us to love God and our neighbor. This love is good will. What else ought we to will, or can we possibly will to God and our neighbor, but their highest good, or well- being, with all the conditions and means thereof ? This is all that, can be of any value to them, and all that we can or ought to, will to them under any circumstances whatever. When we have willed this to them, we have done our whole duty to them. "Love is the fulfilling of the law." We owe them nothing more, absolutely. They can have noth- ing more. But this the law requires us to will to God and our neighbor, on account of the intrinsic value of their good, whatever their character may be ; that is, this is to be willed to God and our neighbor, as a possible good, whether they are holy or unholy, simply because of its intrinsic value. , But while the law requires that this should be willed to all, as a possible and intrinsic good, irrespective of character ; it cannot, and does not require us to will that God, or any moral agent in particular, shall be actually blessed, but upon condition that he be holy. Our obli- gation to the unholy, is to will that they might be holy, and perfectly blessed. Our obligation to the holy, is to will that they be perfectly blessed. As has been said, virtue only modifies the form, but does not change the ground of obligation. The Bible represents love to enemies as one of the highest forms of virtue : " God commendeth his love toward us, in that, while we were yet sinners, Christ died for us." But if love to enemies be a high and a valuable form of vii-tue, it must be only because the true spirit of the law requires the same love to them as to others, and because of the strong inducements not to love them. Who does not regard the virtue of the atonement as being as great as if it had been made for the friends, instead of the enemies of God ? And suppose God were supremely selfish and unreasonably our enemy, who would not regard good- will exercised toward him as being as praiseworthy as it now is. Now if he were unjustly our enemy, would not a hearty good- will to him in such a case be a striking and valuable instance of virtue ? In such a case we could not, might not, will his actual blessedness, but we might and should be under infinite obligation to will that he might become holy, and thereupon be perfectly blessed. We should be under obligation to will his good in such a sense, that should he become holy, we should will his actual blessedness, without any change in our ultimate choice or intention, and without any change in us that would imply an increase of virtue. 80 of our neighbor : we are bound to will his good, even if he is wicked, in such a sense as to need no new intention or ultimate choice, FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 57 to will his actual blessedness, should he become holy. We may be aa holy in loving a sinner, and in seeking his salvation while he is a sinner, as in willing his good after he is converted and becomes a saint. God was as virtuous in loving the world, and seeking to save it while in sin, as he is in loving those in it who are holy. The fact is, if we are truly benevolent, and will the highest well-being of all, with the conditions and means of their blessedness, it follows of course, and of necessity, that when one becomes holy we shall love him with the love of complacency ; that we shall, of course, will his actual blessedness, seeing that he has fulfilled the necessary conditions, and rendered himself worthy of blessedness. It implies no increase of virtue in God, when a sinner repents, to exercise complacency toward him. Complacency, as a state of will or heart, is only benevolence modified by the consideration or relation of right char- acter in the object of it. God, prophets, apostles, martyrs, and saints, in all ages, are as virtuous in their self-denying and untiring labors to save the wicked, as they are in their complacent love to the saints. This is the universal doctrine of the Bible. It is in exact accordance with the spirit and letter of the law. " Thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself ; " that is, whatever his character may be. This is the doctrine of reason, and accords with the convictions of all men. But if this is so, it follows that virtue is not a distinct ground of moral obligation, but only modifies the form of obligation. We are under obligation to will the actual blessedness of a moral being, upon condition of his holiness. We ought to will good or blessedness for its own value, irrespective of character j but we ought to will the enjoyment of it, by an individual, in particular, only upon condition of his holiness. Its intrinsic value is the foundation of the obligation, and his holiness changes not the fact, but form, of the obligation, and is the condition of the obligation to will his actual enjoyment of perfect blessedness in particular. When, there- fore, the Bible calls on us to love God for his goodness, it does not and cannot mean to assign the fundamental reason, or foundation of the ob- ligation to will his good ; for it were absurd to suppose, that his good is to be willed, not for its intrinsic value, but because he is good. Were it not for its intrinsic value, we should as soon affirm our obligation to will evil as good to him. The Bible assumes the first truths of reason. It is a first truth of reason, that God's well-being is of infinite value, and ought to be willed as a possible good whatever his character may be ; and that it ought to be willed as an actual reality upon condition of his holi- ness. Now the Bible does just as in this case might be expected. It asserts JHS actual and infinite holiness, and calls on us to love him, or to S"l his good, for that reason. But this is not asserting nor implying t his holiness is the foundation of the obligation to will his good in any such seosp ^s that we should not be under Qbligq,tion to will it with 58 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. all our heart, and soul, and mind, and strengtn, as a possible good, whether he were holy or not. It is plain that the law contemplates only the intrinsic value of the end to be willed. It would require us to will the well-being of God with all our heart, etc., or as the supreme good, whatever his character might be. Were not this so, it could not be moral law. His interest would be the supreme and the infinite good, in the sense of the intrinsically and infinitely valuable, and we should, for that reason, be under infinite obligation to will that it might be, whether he were holy or sinful, and upon condition of his holiness, to will the actual existence of his perfect and infinite blessedness. Upon our com- ing to the knowledge of his holiness, the obligation is instantly imposed, not merely to will his highest well-being as a possible, but as an actually existing, good. Again, it is impossible that goodness, virtue, good desert, merit, should be a distinct ground or foundation of moral obligation, in such a sense as to impose or properly to increase obligation. It has been shown that neither of these can be an ultimate good and impose obligation to choose itself as an ultimate end, or for its intrinsic value. But if goodness or merit can impose moral obligation to wiU, it must be an obligation to will itself as an iiltimate end. But this we have seen cannot be ; therefore these things cannot be a distinct ground or founda- ti»n of moral obligation. But again, the law does not make virtue, good desert, or merit, the ground of obligation, and require us to love them and to will them as an ultimate end ; but to love God and our neighbor as an ultimate good. It does, no doubt, require us to will God's goodness, good desert, worthi- ness, merit, as a condition and means of his highest well-being, and of the well-being of the universe ; but it is absurd to say that it requires us to will either of these things as an ultimate end, instead of his perfect blessedness, to which these sustain only the relation of a condition. Let it be distinctly understood that nothing can impose moral obligation but that which is an ultimate and an intrinsic good ; for if it impose obliga- tion, it must be an obligation to choose itself for what it is, in and of itself. All obligation must respect the choice either of an end or of means. Obligation to choose means is founded in the value of the end. Whatever, then, imposes obligation must be an ultimate end. It must possess that, in and of itself, that is worthy or deserving of choice as an intrinsic and ultimate good. This we have seen, virtue, merit, etc. cannot be ; therefore they cannot be a foundation of moral obligation. But it is said they can increase obligation to love God and holy beings. But we are under infinite obligation to love God and to will his good with all our power, because of the intrinsic value of his well-being, whether he is holy or sinful. Upon condition that he is holy, we are FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 59 under obligation to will his actual blessedness,but certainly we are under obligation to will it with no more than all our heart, and soul, and mind, and strength. But this we are required to do because of the intrinsic value of his blessedness, whatever his character might be. The fact is, we can do no more, and can be under obligation to do no more, than to will his good with all our power, and this we are bound to do for its own sake ; and no more than this can we be under obligation to do, for any reason whatever. Our obligation is to will his good with all our strength, by virtue of its infinite value, and it cannot be increased by any other consideration than our increased knowledge of its value, which increases our ability. (c.) But it is said that favors received impose obligation to exercise gratitude ; that the relation of benefactor itself imposes obligation to treat the benefactor according to this relation. Answer : I suppose this objection contemplates this relation as a virtuous relation, that is, that the benefactor is truly virtuous and not selfish in his benefaction. If not, then the relation cannot at all modify obligation.^ If the benefactor has in the benefaction obeyed the law of love, if he has done his duty in sustaining this relation, I am under obligation to exercise gratitude toward him. But what is gratitude ? It is not a mere emotion or feeling ; for this is a phenomenon of the sensibility, and, strictly speaking, without the pale both of legislation and morality. Gratitude, when spoken of as a virtue and as that of which moral obli- gation can be aflSrmed, must be an act of will. An obligation to grati- tude must be an obligation to will something to the benefactor. But' what am I under obligation to will to a benefactor, but his actual highest well-being ? If it be God, I am under obligation to will his actual and infinite blessedness with all my heart and with all my soul. If it be my neighbor, I am bound to love him as myself, that is, to will his actual weU-being as I do my own. What else can either God or man possess or enjoy, and what else can I be under obligation to will to them ? I answer, nothing else. To the law and to the testimony ; if any philoso- phy agree not herewith, it is because there is no light in it. The virtuous relation of benefactor modifies obligation, just as any other and every other form of virtue does, and in no other way. Whenever we perceive virtue in any being, this supplies the condition upon which we are bound to will his actual highest well-being. He has done his duty. He has complied with obligation in the relation he sustains. He is truthful, upright, benevolent, just, merciful, no matter what the par- ticular form may be in which the individual presents to me the evidence of his holy character. It is all precisely the same so far as my obligation extends. I am, independently of my knowledge of his character, under fiO SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. obligation to will his highest well-being for its own sake. That is, to will that he may fulfil all the conditions, and thereupon enjoy per- fect blessedness. But I am not under obligation to will his actual enjoyment of blessedness until I have evidence of his virtue. This evidence, however I obtain it, by whatever manifestations of virtue in him or by whatever means, supplies the condition upon which I am under obligation to will his actual enjoyment or highest well-being. This is my whole obligation. It is all he can have, and all I can will to him. All objections of this kind, and indeed all possible objections to the true theory, and in support of the one I am examining, are founded in an erroneous view of the subject of moral obligation, or in a false and anti-scriptural philosophy that contradicts the law of God, and sets up another rule of moral obligation. Again, if gratitude is a moral act, according to this objector, it is an ultimate intention, and as such must terminate on its object, and find its reasons or ground of obligation exclusively in its object. If this is so, then if the relation of benefactor is the ground of obligation te exercise gratitude, gratitude must consist in willing this relation for its own sake, and not at all in willing anything to the benefactor. This is absurd. It is certain that gratitude must consist in willing good to the benefactor, and not in willing the relation for its own sake, and that the ground of the obligation must be the intrinsic value of the good, and the relation only a condition of the obligation in the particular form of willing his enjoyment of good in particular. It is now said, in reply to this, that the " inquiry is not, what is gratitude ? but, why ought we to exercise it ? " But the inquiry is after the ground of the obligation ; this, it is agreed, must be intrinsic in its object ; and is it impertinent to inquire what the object is ? Who can tell what is the ground of the obligation to exercise gratitude until he knows what the object of gratitude is, and consequently what gratitude is ? The objector affirms that the relation of benefactor is a ground of obligation to put forth ultimate choice. Of course, according to him, and in fact, if this relation is the ground of the obligation, it is, and must be, the object chosen for its own sake. To exercise gratitude to a benefactor, then, according to this teaching is, not to wiU any good to him, nor to myself, nor to any being in existence, but simply to. will the relation of bene- factor for its own sake. Not for his sake, as a good to him. Not for my sake as a good to me, but for its own sake. Is not this a sublime philosophy ? (d.) But it is also insisted that when men attempt to assign a reason why they are under moral obligation of any kind, as to love God, they all agree in this, in assigning the divine moral excellence a? the reason of th&i obligation^ FOUNDATION OP OBLKJATION. 61 I answer : — The ooly reason why any man supposes himself to assign the goodness of God as the foundation of the obligation to will good to him is, that he loosely confounds the conditions of the obligation to will his actual blessedness, with the foundation of the obligation to will it for its own sake, or as a possible good. "Were it not for the known intrinsic value of God's highest well-being, we should as soon aflSrm our obligation to will evil as good to him, as has been said. But if the divine moral excellence were the foundation of moral obligation, if God were not holy and good, moral obligation could not exist in any case. That every moral agent ought to will the highest well-being of God and of all the universe for its own sake, as a possible good, whatever their characters may be, is a truth of reason. Reason assigns and can assign no other reason for willing their good as an ultimate end than its intrinsic value ; and to assign any other reason as imposing obligation to will it as an end, or for its own sake, were absurd and self-contradictory. Obliga- tion to will it as an end and for its own sake, implies the obligation to will its actual existence in all cases, and to all persons, when the indispens- able conditions are fulfilled. These conditions are seen to be fulfilled in God, and therefore upon this condition reason affirms obligation to will his actual and highest blessedness for its own sake, the intrinsic value being the fundamental reason of the obligation to will it as an end, and the divine goodness the condition of the obligation to will his highest blessedness in particular. Suppose that I existed and had the idea of blessedness and its intrinsic value duly developed, together with an idea of all the necessary conditions of it ; but that I did not know that any other being than myself existed, and yet I knew their existence and bless- edness possible ; in this case I should be under obligation to will or wish that beings might exist and be blessed. Now suppose that I complied with this obligation, my virtue is just as real and as great as if I knew their existence, and willed their actual blessedness, provided my idea of its intrinsic value were as clear and just as if I knew their existence. And now suppose I came to the knowledge of the actual existence and holiness of all holy beings, I should make no new ultimate choice in will- ing their actual blessedness. This I should do of course, and, remaining benevolent, of necessity ; and if this knowledge did not give me a higher idea of the value of that which I before willed for its own sake, the will- ing of the real existence of their blessedness would not make me a whit more virtuous than when I willed it as a possible good, without knowing that the conditions of its actual existence would ever, in any case, be fulfilled. The Bible reads just as it might be expected to read, and just as we should speak in common life. It being a truth of reason that the well- being of God is of infinite value, and therefore ought to be willed for it» 52 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOQT. own sake, it also being a truth that virtue is an indispensable condition of fulfilling the demands of his own reason and conscience, and of course of his actual blessedness, and of course also a condition of the obligation to will it, we might expect the Bible to exhort and require us to love God or will his actual blessedness, and mention his virtue as the reason or ful- filled condition of the obligation, rather than the intrinsic value of his blessedness as the foundation of the obligation. The foundation of the obligation, being a truth of reason, needs not to be a matter of revelation. Nor needs the fact that virtue is the condition of his blessedness, nor the fact that we are under no obligation to will his actual blessedness but upon condition of his holiness. But that in him this condition is ful- filled, needs to be impressed upon us, and therefore the Bible announces ■ it as a reason or condition of the obligation to love him, that is, to will his actual blessedness. God's moral excellence is naturally, and rightly, assigned by us as a condition, not the ground of obligation to receive his revealed will as our law. Did we not assume the rectitude of the divine will, we could not affirm our obligation to receive it as a rule of duty. This assumption is a condition of the obligation, and is naturally thought of when obligation to obey God is affirmed. But the intrinsic value and importance of the interest he requires us to seek, is the ground of the obligation. (e. ) Again : it is asserted that when men would awaken a sense of moral obligation they universally contemplate the moral excellence of God as constituting the reason of their obligation, and if this contemplation does not awaken their sense of obligation nothing else can or will. I answer : — The only possible reason why men ever do or can take this course, is that they loosely consider religion to consist in feelings of complacency in God, and are endeavoring to awaken these complacent emotions. If they conceive of religion as consisting in these emotions, they will of course conceive themselves to be under obligation to exercise them, and to be sure they take the only possible course to awaken both these and -a sense of obligation to exercise them. But they are mistaken both in regard to their obligation and the nature of religion. Did they conceive of religion as consisting in good-will, or in willing the highest well-being of God and of the universe for its own sake, would they, could they, resort to the process in question, that is, the contemplation of the divine moral excellence, as the only reason for wiUing good to him, instead of considering the infinite value of those interests to the reali- zation of which they ought to consecrate themselves ? If men often do resort to the process in question, it is because they love to feel and have a self-righteous satisfaction in feelings of com- placency in God, and take more pains to awaken these feelings than to quicken and enlarge their benevolence. A purely selfish being may be FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 63 greatly affected by the great goodness and kindness of God to him. I know a man who is a very niggard so far as all benevolent giving and doing for God and the world are concerned, who, I fear, resorts to the rery process in question, and is often much affected with the goodness of God. He can bluster and denounce all who do not feel as he does. But ask him for a dollar to forward any benevolent enterprise, and he wiU evade your request, and ask you how you feel, whether you are engaged in religion, etc. But it may well be asked, why does the Bible and why do we, so often present the character of God and of Christ as a means of awakening a sense of moral obligation and of inducing virtue ? Answer : — It is to lead men to contemplate the infinite value of those interests which we ought to will. Presenting the example of God and of Christ, is the highest moral means that can be used. God's example and man's example is the most impressive and efficient way in which he can declare his views, and hold forth to public gaze the infinite value of those inter- ests upon which all hearts ought to be set. For example, nothing can set the infinite value of the soul in a stronger light than the example of God the Father, Son, and Holy Ghost has done. Nothing can beget a higher sense of obligation to will the glory of the Father and the salvation of souls, than the example of Christ. His example is his loudest preaching, his clearest, most impressive exhibition, not merely of his own goodness, but of the intrinsic and infinite value of the interest he sought and which we ought to seek. It is the love, the care, the self-denial, and the example of God, in his efforts to secure the great ends of benevolence, that hold those interests forth in the strongest light, and thus beget a sense of obligation to seek the same end. But let it be observed, it is not a contemplation of the goodness of God that awakens this sense of obligation, but the contemplation of the value of those interests which he seeks, in the light of his pains-taking and example ; this quickens and gives efficiency to the sense of obligation to will what he wills. Suppose, for example, that I manifest the greatest concern and zeal for the salvation of souls ; it would not be the contem- plation of my goodness that would quicken in a bystander a sense of obli- gation to save souls, but my zeal, and life, and spirit would have the strongest tendency to arouse in him a sense of the infinite and intrinsic value of the soul, and thus quicken a sense of obligation. Should I be- hold multitudes rushing to extinguish a flaming house, it would not be a contemplation of their goodness, but the contemplation of the interests it stake, to the consideration of which their zeal would lead me, that would quicken a sense of obligation in me to hasten to lend my aid. Bevelation is concerned to impress the fact that God is holy, and of SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. course calls on us, in view of his holiness, to love and worship him. Bal in doing this, it does not, cannot mean that his holiness is the founda- tion of the obligation to will his good as an ultimate end. Our obligation, when viewed apart from his character, is to wUl or wish that God might fulfil all the conditions of perfect blessedness, and upon that condition, that he might actually enjoy perfect and infinite satisfaction. But seeing that he meets the demands of his own intelli- gence and the intelligence of the universe, and that he voluntarily fulfils all the necessary conditions of his highest well-being, our obligation is to will his actual and most perfect aud eternal blessedness. I am obliged to repeat much to follow the objector, because all his objections resolve themselves into one, and require to be answered much in the same way. LECTURE VII. FOUNDATION OF MOHAL OBLIGATION. 1 now come to consider the pJdlosophy which teaches that moral order is the foundation of moral obligation. But what is moral order ? The advocates of this theory define it to be identical with the fit, proper, suitable. It is, then, according to them, synonymous with the right. Moral order must be, in their view, either identical with law or with virtue. It must be either an idea of the fit, the right, the proper, the suitable, which is the same as objective right ; or it must consist in conformity of the wiU to this idea or law, which is virtue. It has been repeatedly shown that right, whether ob- jective or subjective, cannot by any possibility be the end at which a moral agent ought to aim, and to which he ought to consecrate himselL If moral order be not synonymous with right in one of these senses, I do not know what it is ; and all that I can say is, that if it be not identical with the highest well-being of God and of the universe, it cannot be the end at which moral agents ought to aim, and cannot be the foundation of moral obligation. But if by moral order, as the phraseology of some would seem to indicate, be meant that state of the universe in which aU law is universally obeyed, and, as a consequence, a state of universal well- being, this theory is only another name for the true one. It is the same as willing the highest well-being of the universe, with the conditions and means thereof. , Or if it be meant, as other phraseology would seem to indicate, that moral order is a state of things in which either all law is obeyed, or in which the disobedient are punished for the sake of promoting the publio FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 6ft gooi ; — if this be what is meant by moral order, it is only another name for the true theory. Willing moral order, is only willing the highest good of the universe for its own sake, with the condition and means thereof. But if by moral order be meant the fit, suitable, in the sense of law, physical or moral, it is absurd to represent moral order as the foundation of moral obligation. If moral order is the ground of obligation, it is identical with the object of ultimate choice. Does God require us to love moral order for its own sake ? Is this identical with loving God and our neighbor ? " Thou shalt will moral order with all thy heart, and with all thy soul ! " Is this the meaning of the moral law ? If this theory is right, benevolence is sin. It is not living to the right end. Again it is maintained that the nature and relations of moral beings are the true foundation of moral obligation. The advocates of this theory confound the conditions of moral obliga- tion with the foundation of obligation. The nature and relations of moral agents to each other, and to the universe, are conditions of their obligation to will the good of being, but not the foundation of the obliga- tion. What I the nature and relations of moral beings the foundation of their obligation to choose an ultimate end ! Then this end must be their nature and relations. This is absurd. Their nature and relations being what they are, their highest well-being is known to them to be of infinite and intrinsic value. But it is and must be the intrinsic value of the end, and not their nature and relations, that imposes obligation to will the highest good of the universe as an ultimate end. If their nature and relations be the ground of obligation, then their 'nature and relations are the gi'eat object of ultimate choice, and should be willed for their own sakes, and not for the sake of any good resulting from their nature and relations. For, be it remembered, the ground of obligation to put forth ultimate choice must be identical with the object of this choice, which object imposes obligation by virtue of its own nature. The natures and relations of moral beings are a condition of obliga- tion to fulfil to each other certain duties. For example, the relation of parent and child is a condition of obligation to endeavor to promote each other's particular well-being, to govern and provide for, on the part of the parent, and to obey, etc., on the part of the child. But the intrinsic value of the good to be sought by both parent and child must be the ground, and their relation only the condition, of those particular forms of obligation. So in every possible case. Kelations can never be a ground of obligation to choose, unless the relations be the object of the choice. The various dn ties of life are executive and not ultimate acts. Obligation 5 W SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. M perform them is founded in the intrinsic nature of the good resulting from their performance. The various relations of life are only conditions 01 obligation to promote particular forms of good, and the good of par- ticular individuals. Writers upon this subject are often falling into the mistake of con- founding the conditions with the foundation of moral obligation. Moral agency is a condition, but not the foundation of obligation. Light, of the knowledge of the intrinsically valuable to being, is a condition, but not the foundation of moral obligation. The intrinsically valuable is the foundation of the obligation ; and light, or the perception of the intrin- sically valuable, is only a condition of the obligation. So the nature and relations of moral beings are a condition of their obligation to will each other's good, and so is light, or a knowledge of the intrinsic value of their blessedness ; but the intrinsic value is alone the foundation of the obliga- tion. It is, therefore, a great mistake to afBrm " that the known nature and relations of moral agents are the true foundation of moral obligation." The next theory tJiat demands attention is that which teaches that moral obligation is founded in the idea of duty. According to this philosophy, the end at which a moral agent ought to aim, is duty. He must in all things " aim at doing his duty." Or, in other words, he must always have respect to his obligation, and aim at discharging it. It is plain that this theory is only another form of stating the right- arian theory. By aiming, intending, to do duty, we must understand the advocates of this theory to mean the adoption of a resolution or maxim, by which to regulate their lives — the formation of a resolve to obey God — to serve God — to do at all times what appears to be right— to meet the demands of conscience — to obey the law — to discharge obliga- tion, etc. I have expressed the thing intended in all these ways because it is common to hear this theory expressed in all these terms, and in others like them. Especially in giving instruction to inquiring sinners, nothing is more common than for those who profess to be spiritual guides to assume the truth of this philosophy, and give instructions ac- cordingly. These philosophers, or theologians, will say to sinners : Make up your mind to serve the Lord ; resolve to do your whole duty, and do it at all times ; resolve to obey God in all things— to keep all his commandments ; resolve to deny yourselves— to forsake all sin — ^to love the Lord with all your heart and your neighbor as yourself. They often represent regeneration as consisting in this resolution or purpose. Such-like phraseology, which is very common and almost universal among rightarian philosophers, demonstrates that they regard virtue or obedience to God as consisting in the adoption of a maxim of life. "With FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 67 them^ duty is the great idea to be realized. All these modes of expres- gion mean the same thing, and amount to just Kant's morality, which he admits does not necessarily imply religion, namely : " act upon a maxim at all times fit for law universal," and to Cousin's, which is the same thing, namely, " will the right for the sake of the right." Now I cannot but regard this philosophy on the one hand, and utilitarianism on the other, as equally wide from the truth, and as lying at the foundar tion of much of the spurious religion with which the church and the world are cursed. Utilitarianism begets one type of selfishness, which it calls religion, and this philosophy begets another, in some respects more specious, but not a whit the less selfish, God-dishonoring and soul-de- stroying. The nearest that this philosophy can be said to approach either to true morality or religion, is, that if the one who forms the reso- lution understood himself he would resolve to become truly moral instead of really becoming so. Bat this is in fact an absurdity and an impossi- bility, and the resolution-maker does not understand what he is about, when he supposes himself to be forming or cherishing a resolution to do his duty. Observe, he intends to do his duty. But to do his duty is to form and cherish an ultimate intention. To intend to do his duty is merely to intend to intend. But this is not doing his duty, as will be shown. He intends to serve God, but this is not serving God, as will also be shown. Whatever he intends, he is neither truly moral nor reli- gious, until he really intends the same end that God does ; and this is not to do his duty, nor to do right, nor to comply with obligation, nor to keep a conscience void of offence, nor to deny himself, nor any such like things. God aims at, and intends, the highest well-being of him- self and the universe, as an ultimate end, and this is doing his duty. It is not resolving or intending to do his duty, but is doing it. It is not resolving to do right for the sake of the right, but it is doing right. It is not resolving to serve himself and the universe, but is actually render- ing that service. It is not resolving to obey the moral law, but is actually obeying it. It is not resolving to love, but actually loving his neighbor as himself. It is not, in other words, resolving to be benevolent, but is being so. It is not resolving to deny self, but is actually deny- ing self. A man may resolve to serve God without any just idea of what it is to serve him. If he had the idea of what the law of God requires him to choose, clearly before his mind — ^if he perceived that to serve God, was nothing less than to consecrate himself to the same end to which God consecrates himself, to love God with all his heart and his neighbor as himself, that is, to will or choose the highest well-being of God and of the universe, as an ultimate end — ^to devote all his being, substance, time, and influence to this end ; — I say, if this idea were clearly before 68 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. his mind, he would not talk of resolving to consecrate himself to God — resolving to do his duty, to do right, to serve God, to keep a conscience void of offence, and such like things. He would see that such resolu- bions were totally absurd and a mere evasion of the claims of God. It has been repeatedly shown, that all virtue resolves itself into the intend- ing of an ultimate end, or of the highest well-being of God and the uni- verse. This is true morality, and nothing else is. This is identical with that love to God and man which the law of God requires. This then is duty. This is serving God. This is keeping a conscience void of offence. This is right, and nothing else is. But to intend or resolve to do this is only to intend to intend, instead of at once intending what God requires. It is resolving to love God and his neighbor, instead of really loving him ; choosing to choose the highest well-being of God and of the universe, instead of really choosing it. It is one thing for a man who actually loves God with all his heart and his neighbor as himself, to resolve to regulate all his outward life by the law of God, and a totally different thing to intend to love God or to intend his highest glory and well-being. Resolutions may respect oat- ward action, but it is totally absurd to intend or resolve to form an ultimate intention. But be it remembered, that morality and religion do not belong to outward action, but to ultimate intentions. It is amazing and aflBicting to witness the alarming extent to which a spuri- ous philosophy has corr opted and is corrupting the church of God. Kant and Cousin and Coleridge have adopted a phraseology, and mani- festly have conceived in idea a philosophy subversive of all true love to God and man, and teach a religion of maxims and resolutions instead of a religion of love. It is a philosophy, as we shall see in a future lecture, which teaches that the moral law or law of right, is entirely distinct from and may be opposite to the law of benevolence or love. The fact is, this philosophy conceives of duty and right as belonging to mere outward action. This must be, for it cannot be confused enough to talk of resolving or intending to form an ultimate intention. Let but the truth of this philosophy be assumed, in giving instructions to the anxious sinner, and it will immediately dry off his tears, and in all probability lead him to settle down in a religion of resolutions instead of a religion of love. Indeed this philosophy will immediately dry off, (if I may be allowed the expression,) the most genuine and powerful re- vival of religion, and run it down into a mere revival of a heart- less, Christless, loveless philosophy. It is much easier to persuade anxious sinners to resolve to do their duty, to resolve to love God, than it is to persuade them really to do their duty, and really to lore God with all their heart and with all their soul, and their neighbor as themselves. FOUNDATION OP OBLIGATION. 69 We now come to the consideration of that philosophy which teaches the complexity of the foundation of moral obligation. This theory maintains that there are several distinct grounds of moral obligation ; that the highest good of being is only one of the grounds of moral obligation, while right, moral order, the nature and relations of moral agents, merit and demerit, truth, duty, and many such like things, are distinct grounds of moral obligation, but that each one of them can by itself impose moral obligation. The advocates of this theory, perceiving its inconsistency with the doctrine that moral obligation respects the ultimate choice or intention only, seem dis- posed to relinquish the position that obligation respects strictly only the choice of an ultimate end, and to maintain that moral obligation respects the ultimate action of the will. By ultimate action of the will they mean, if I understand them, the will's treatment of everything according to its intrinsic nature and character ; that is treating every thing, or taking that attitude in respect to every thing known to the mind, that is exactly suited to what it is in and of itself. For example, right ought to be regarded and treated by the will as right because it is right. Truth ought to be regarded and treated as truth for its own sake, virtue as virtue, merit as merit, demerit as demerit, the useful as useful, the beautiful as beautiful, the good or valuable as valuable, each for ibs own sake ; that in each case the action of the will is ultimate, in the sense that its action terminates on these objects as ultimates ; in other words, that all those actions of the will are ultimate that treat things according to their nature and character, or according to what they are in and of themselves. Now in respect to this theory I would inquire : — What is intended by the will's treating a thing, or taking that attitude in respect to it that is suited to its nature and character ? Are there any other actions of will than volitions, choice, preference, intention ? Are not all the actions of the will comprehended in these ? If there are any other actions than these, are they intelligent actions ? If, so what are those actions of will that consist neither in the choice of ends nor means, nor in volitions or efforts to secure an end ? Can there be intelligent acts of will that neither respect ends nor means ? Can there be moral acts of will when there is no choice or intention ? If there is choice or intention, must not these respect an end or means ? What then can be meant by ulti- mate action of wiU as distinguished from ultimate choice or intention ? Can there be choice without an object of choice ? If there is an object of choice, must not this object be chosen either as an end or as a means ? If as an ultimate end, how does this difEer from ultimate in- tention ? If as a means, how can this be regarded as an ultimate action of the will ? What can be intended by actions of will that are not acts 70 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. of choice nor volition ? I can conceive of no other. But if all acts of will must of necessity consist in willing or nilling, that is in choosing oi refusing, which is the same as willing one way or another, in respect to all objects of choice apprehended by the mind, how can there be any in- telligent act of the will that does not consist in, or that may not and must not, in its last analysis, be resolvable into, and be properly considered as the choice of an end, or of means, or in executive efforts to secure an end ? Can moral law require any other action of will than choice and volition ? What other actions of will are possible to us ? Whatever moral law does require, it must and can only require choices and volitions. It can only require us to choose ends or means. It cannot require us to choose as an ultimate end anything that is not intrinsically worthy of choice — nor as a means any thing that does not sustain that relation. Secondly, let as examine this theory in the light of the revealed law of God. The whole law is fulfilled in one word — ^love. Now we have seen that the will of God cannot be the foundation of moral obligation. Moral obligation must be founded in the nature of that which moral law requires us to choose. Unless there be something in the nature of that which moral law requires us to will that renders it worthy or deserving of choice, we can be under no obligation to will or choose it. It is admit- ted that the love required by the law of God must consist in an act of the will, and not in mere emotions. Now, does this love, willing, choice, embrace several distinct ultimates ? If so, how can they all be expressed in one word — love ? Observe, the law I'equires only love to God and our neighbor as an ultimate. This love or willing must respect and termi- nate on God and our neighbor. The law says nothing about willing right for the sake of the right, or truth for the sake of the truth, or beauty for the sake of beauty, or virtue for the sake of virtue, or moral order for its own sake, or the nature and relations of moral agents for their own sake ; nor can any such thing be implied in the command to love God and our neighbor. All these and innumerable other things are, and must be, conditions and means of the highest well-being of God and our neighbor. As such, the law may, and doubtless does, in requiring us to will the highest well-being of God and our neighbor as an ultimate end, require us to will all these as the necessary conditions and means. The end which the revealed law requires us to will is undeniably simple as op- posed to complex. It requires only love to God and our neighbor. One word expresses the whole of moral obligation. Now certainly this word cannot have a complex signification in such a sense as to include several distinct and ultimate objects of love, or of choice. This love is to termi- nate on God and our neighbor, and not on abstractions, nor on inanimate and insentient existences. I protest against any philosophy that contra- dicts the revealed law of God, and that teaches that anything else thaB FOUNDATION OF OBLIGATION. 71 God and our neighbor is to be loved for its own sake, or that anything else is to be chosen as an ultimate end than the highest well-being of God and our neighbor. In other words, I utterly object to any philoso- phy that makes anything obligatory upon a moral agent that is not ex- pressed or implied in perfect good will to God, and to the universe of sentient existences. To the word and to the testimony ; if any philoso- phy agree not therewith, it is because there is no light in it. The revealed law of God knows but one gi'ound or foundation of moral obli- gation. It requires but one thing ; and that is just that attitude of the will toward God and our neighbor that accords with the intrinsic value of their highest well-being ; that God's moral worth shall be willed as of infinite value, as a condition of his own well-being, and that his actual and perfect blessedness shall be willed for its own sake, and because, or upon condition th^t he is worthy ; that our neighbor's moral worth shall be willed as an indispensable condition of his blessedness, and that if our neighbor is worthy of happiness, his actual and highest happiness shall be willed. This law knows but one end which moral agents are under obligation to seek, and sets at nought all so-called ultimate actions of will that do not terminate on the good of God and our neighbor. The ultimate choice, with the choice of all the conditions and means of the highest well-being of God and the universe, is all that the revealed law recognizes as coming within the pale of its legislation. It requires nothing more and nothing less. But there is another form of the complex theory of moral obligation that I must notice before I dismiss this subject. This view admits and maintains that the good, that is, the valua- ble to being, is the only ground of moral obligation, and that in every possible case the valuable to being, or the good, must be intended- as an end, as a condition of the intention being virtuous. In this respect it maintains that the foundation of moral obligation is simple, a unit. But it also maintains that there are several ultimate goods or several ulti- mates or things which are intrinsically good or valuable in themselves, and are therefore to be chosen for their own sake, or as an ultimate end ; that to choose either of these as an ultimate end, or for its own sake, is virtue. It admits that happiness or blessedness is a good, and should be willed for its own sake, or as an ultimate end, but it maintains that virtue is an ultimate good ; that right is an ultimate good ; that the just and the true are ultimate goods ; in short, that the realization of the ideas of the reason, or the carrying out into concrete existence any idea of the reason, is an ultimate good. For instance : there were in the Divine Mind from eternity certain ideas of the good or valuable, the right, the just, the beautiful, the true, the useful, the holy. The realization of these (T^ SYSTEMATIC THEOLOQf . ideas of the divine reason, according to this theory, was the end which God aimed at or intended in creation ; he aimed at their realization as nltimates or for their own sake, and regarded the concrete realization of every one of these ideas as a separate and ultimate good : and so certain as God is virtuous, so certain it is, says this theory, that an intention on our part to realize these ideas for the sake of the realization is virtue. Then the foundation of moral obligation is complex in the sense that to will either the good or valuable, the right, the true, the just, the virtu- ous, the beautiful, the useful, etc., for its own sake, or as an ultimate end, is virtue ; and there is more than one virtuous ultimate choice or mtontion. Thus any one of several distinct things may be intended as an ultimate end with equal propriety and with equal virtuousness. The soul may at one moment be wholly consecrated to one end, that is, to one ultimate good, and again to another ; that is, |ometimes it may will one good, and sometimes another good, as an ultimate end, and still be equally virtuous. In the discussion of this subject I will inquire : In what does the su- preme and ultimate good consist ? 1. Good may be natural or moral. Natural good man keep the whole law. and yet ofEend in one point, he is guilty of all." What is this but asserting, that if there could be a partial obedience, it would be unavailing, since the law would condemn for any degree of sin ; that partial obedience, did it exist, would not be regarded as acceptable obedience at all ? The doctrine, that a partial obedience, in the sense that the law is not at any time fully obeyed, is accepted of God, is sheer antiaomianism. What I a sinner justified while indulging in rebellion against God ! OBEDIENCE ENTIRE. 121 But it has been generally held in the church, that a sinner must intend fully to obey the law, as a condition of justification ; that, in his purpose and intention, he must forsake all sin ; that nothing short of perfection of aim or intention can be accepted of God. Now, what is intended by this language ? We have seen in former lectures, that moral character belongs properly only to the intention. If, then, perfection of intention be an indispensable condition of justification, what is this, but an admission, after all, that full present obedience is a condition of justification ? But this is what we hold, and they deny. What then can they mean ? It is of importance to ascertain what is intended by the assertion, repeated by them thousands of times, that a sinner can- not be justified but upon condition that he fully purposes and intends to abandon all sin, and to live without sin ; unless he seriously intends to render full obedience to all the commands of Grod. Intends to obey the law ! What constitutes obedience to the law ? Why, love, good- willing, good-intending. Intending to obey the law is intending to intend, willing to will, choosing to choose I This is absurd. What then is the state of mind which is, and must be, the condition of justification ? Not merely an intention to obey, for this is only an intending to intend, but intending what the law requires to be in- tended, to wit, the highest well-being of God and of the universe. Unless he intends this, it is absurd to say that he can intend full obe- dience to the law ; that he intends to live without sin. The supposition is, that he is now sinning ; that is, for nothing else is sin, voluntarily withholding from God and man their due. He chooses, wills, and intends this, and yet the supposition is, that at the same time he chooses, wills, intends, fully to obey the law. What is this but the ridiculous assertion, that he at the same time intends full obedience to the law, and intends not fully to obey, but only to obey in part, volun- tarily withholding from God and man their dues. But again, to the question, can man be justified while sin remains in him ? Surely he cannot, either upon legal or gospel principles, unless the law be repealed. That he cannot be justified by the law, while there is a particle of sin in him, is too plain to need proof. But can he be pardoned and accepted, and then justified, in the gospel sense, while sin, any degree of sin, remains in him ? Certainly not. For the law, unless it be repealed, continues to condemn him while there is any degree of sin in him. It is a contradiction to say, that he can both be pardoned, and at the same time condemned. But if he is all the time coming short of full obedience, there never is a moment in which the law is not uttering its curses against him. " Cursed is every one that continueth not in all things that are written in the book of the law to do tbeni, " Tbe fp^ct is, tl;efe never has bpen, apd there never cap be, any 122 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. such thing as sin without condemnation. " Beloved, if our heart con- demn us, God is greater than our heart;" that is, he much more condemns us. " But if our heart condemn us not, then have we confi- dence towards God." God cannot repeal the law. It is not founded in his arbitrary will. It is as unalterable and unrepealable as his own nature. God can never repeal nor alter it. He can, for Christ's sake, dispense with the execution of the penalty, when the subject has returned to full present obedience to the precept, but in no other case, and upon no other possible conditions. To affirm that he can, is to affirm that God can alter the immutable and eternal principles of moral law and moral government. 8. The next inquiry is, can there be such a thing as a partial repent- ance of sin ? That is, does not true repentance imply a return to present full obedience to the law of God ? To repent is to change the choice, purpose, intention. It is to choose a new end, — to begin a new life, — to turn from self seeking to seeking the highest good of being, — to turn from selfishness to disinter- ested benevolence, — from a state of disobedience to a state of obedience. Certainly, if repentance means and implies anything, it does imply a thorough reformation of heart and life. A reformation of heart consists in turning from selfishness to benevolence. We have seen in a former lecture, that selfishness and benevolence cannot co-exist, at the same time, in the same mind. They are the supreme choice of opposite ends. These ends cannot both be chosen at the same time. To talk of partial repentance as a possible thing is to talk nonsense. It is to overlook the very nature of repentance. What ! a man both turn away from, and hold on to sin at the same time ! Serve God and mammon at one and the same time ! It is impossible. This impossibility is affirmed both by reason and by Christ. But perhaps it will be objected, that the sin of those who render but a partial obedience, and whom God pardons and accepts, is not a voluntary sin. This leads to the inquiry : — 9. Can there be any other than voluntary sin ? What is sin ? Sin is a transgression of the law. The law requires benevolence, good-willing. Sin is not a mere negation, or a not willing, but consists in willing self-gratification. It is a willing contrary to the commandment of God. Sin, as well as holiness, consists in choosing, willing, intending. Sin must be voluntary ; that is, it must be intelligent and voluntary. It consists in willing, and it is nonsense to deny that sin is voluntary. The fact is, there is either no sin, or there is voluntary sm. Benevolence is willing the good of being in general, as an end, and, of course, implies the rejection of self-gratification, as an end. So sin is the choice of self-gratification, as an end, and necessarily implies the rejection of the good of being in general, as an end Sin and holiness, OBEDIENCE ENTIRE. 123 naturally and necessarily, exclude each other. They are eternal opposites and antagonists. Neither can consist with the presence of the other in the heart. They consist in the active state of the will, and there can bo no sin or holiness that does not consist in choice. 10. Must not present sin be sin unrepented of ? Yes, it is impossible for one to repent of present sin. To afiBrm that present sin is repented of, is to aflSrm a contradiction. It is overlooking both the nature of sin, and the nature of repentance. Sin is selfish will- ing; repentance is turning from selfish to benevolent willing. These two states of will, as has just been said, cannot possibly co-exist. Who- ever, then, is at present falling short of full obedience to the law of God, is voluntarily sinning against God, and is impenitent. It is nonsense to say, that he is partly penitent and partly impenitent ; that he is penitent so fai: as he obeys, and impenitent so far as he disobeys. This really seems to be the loose idea of many, that a man can be partly penitent, and partly impenitent at the same time. This idea, doubtless, is founded on the mistake, that repentance consists in sorrow for sin, or is a phe- nomenon of the sensibility. But repentance consists in a change of ultimate intention — a change in the choice of an end — a turning from selfishness to supreme disinterested benevolence. It is, therefore, plainly impossible for one to be partly penitent, and partly impenitent at the same time ; inasmuch as penitence and impenitence consist in supreme opposite choices. So then it is plain, that nothing is accepted as virtue under the gov- ernment of God, but present full obedience to his law. / KEMAEKS. 1. If what has been said is true, we see that the church has fallen into a great and ruinous mistake, in supposing that a state of present sinlessness is a very rare, if not an impossible, attainment in this life. If the doctrine of this lecture be true, it follows that the very beginning of true religion in the soul, implies the renunciation of all sin. Sin ceases where holiness begins. Now, how great and ruinous must that error be, that teaches us to hope for heaven, while living in conscious sin ; to look upon a sinless state, as not to be expected in this world ; that it is a dangerous error to expect to stop sinning, even for an hour or a moment, in this world ; and yet to hope for heaven 1 2. How great and ruinous the error, that justification is conditionated upon a faith that does not purify the heart of the believer ; that one may be in a state of justification who lives in the constant commission of more or less sin ! This' error has slain more souls, I fear, than all the universalism that ever cursed the world. ?. V[e see that^ if a righteous man forsake his righteousness, and die 124 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. in his sin, he must sink to hell. Whenever a Christian sins he comes under condemnation, and must repent and do his first works, or be lost LECTURE XL OBEDIENCE TO THE MORAL LAW, We hare seen, that all the law requires is summarily expressed in the single word, love ; that this word is synonymous with benevolence ; that benevolence consists in the choice of the highest well-being of God and of the universe, as an end, or for its own sake ; that this choice is an ultimate intention. In short, we have seen, that good-will to being in general is obedience to the moral law. Now the question before us is, what is not implied in this good-will, or in this benevolent ultimate in- tention ? Since the law of God, as revealed in the Bible, is the standard, and the only standard, by which the question in regard to what is not, and what is, implied in entire sanctification, is to be decided, it is of funda- mental importance, that we understand what is, and what is not, implied in entire obedience to this law. Our judgment of our own state, or of the state of others, can never be relied upon, till these inquiries are settled. Christ was perfect, and yet so erroneous were the notions of the. Jews, in regard to what constituted perfection, that they thought him possessed with a devil, instead of being holy, as he claimed to be. I wUl state then, what is not implied in entire obedience to the moral law, as I understand it. The law, as epitomized by Christ, " Thou shalt love the Lord thy God with all thy heart, and with all thy soul, and with all thy mind, and with all thy strength, and thy neighbor as thyself," — I un- derstand to lay down the whole duty of man to God, and to his fellow creatures. Now, the questions are, what is not, and what is, implied in perfect obedience to this law ? 1. Entire obedience does not imply any change in the substance of the soul or body, for this the law does not require ; and it would not be obligatory if it did, because the requirement would be inconsistent with natural justice, and, therefore, not law. Entire obedience is the entire consecration of the powers, as they are, to God. It does not imply any change in them, but simply the right use of them. 2. It does not imply the annihilation of any constitutional traits of character, such as constitutional ardor or impetuosity. There is noth- ing, certainly, in the law of God that requirpp supb congtitiftioqal traitg OBEDIENCE TO THE LAW. 125 to be annihilated, but simply that they should be rightly directed in their exercise. 3. It does not imply the annihilation of any of the constitutional appetites or susceptibilities. It seems to be supposed by some, that the constitutional appetites and susceptibilities are in themselves sinful, and that a state of entire conformity to the law of God implies their entire annihilation. I have been not a little surprised to find, that some per- sons who, I had supposed, were far enough from etnbracing the doctrine of physical moral depravity, were, after all, resorting to this assumption, in order to set aside the doctrine of entire sanctification in this life. But let us appeal to the law. Does the law anywhere, expressly or impliedly, condemn the constitution of man, or require the annihilation of any thing that is properly a part of the constitution itself ? Does it require the annihilation of the appetite for food, or is it satisfied merely with regulating its indulgence ? In short, does the law of God any where require any thing more than the consecration of all the powers, appetites, and susceptibilities of body and mind to the service of God ? 4. Entire obedience does not imply the annihilation of natural affec- tion, or natural resentment. By natural affection I mean, that certain persons may be naturally pleasing to us. Christ appears to have had a natural affection for John. By natural resentment I mean, that, from the laws of our being, we must resent or feel opposed to injustice or ill- treatment. Kot that a disposition to retaliate or revenge ourselves is consistent with the law of God. But perfect obedience to the law of God does not imply that we should have no sense of injury and injustice, when we are abused. God has this, and ought to have it, and so has every moral being. To love your neighbor as yourself, does not imply, that if he injure you, you should feel no sense of the injury or injustice, but that you should love him and do him good, notwithstanding his injurious treatment. 5. It does not imply any unhealthy degree of excitement of the mind. Moral law is to be so interpreted as to be consistent with physical law. God's laws certainly do not clash with each other. And the moral law cannot require such a state of constant mental excitement as will destroy the physical constitution. It cannot require any more mental excite- ment than is consistent with all the laws, attributes, and circumstances of both soul and body. It does not imply that any organ or faculty is to be at all times exerted to the^full measure ot its capacity. This would soon exhaust and destroy any and every organ of the body. Whatever may be true of the mind, when separated from the body, it is certain, while it acts through a material organ, that a constant state of excite- ment ia impossible. When the mind is strongly excited, there is of necessity a great determination of blood to the brain. A high degi-ee of 126 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. excitement cannot long continue, without producing inflammation of the brain, and consequent insanity. And the law of God does not require any degree of emotion, or mental excitement, inconsistent with life and health. Our Lord Jesus Christ does not appear to have been in a state of continual mental excitement. When he and his disciples had been in a great excitement for a time, they would turn aside, " and rest a while." Who that has ever philosophized on this subject, does not know that the high degree of excitement which is sometimes witnessed in revivals of religion, must necessarily be short, or that the people must become deranged ? It seems sometimes to be indispensable that a high degree of excitement should prevail for a time, to arrest public and Individual attention, and draw ofE people from other pursuits, to attend to the con- cerns of their souls. But if any suppose that this high degree of excite- ment is either necessary or desirable, or possible to be long continued, they have not well considered the matter. And here is one grand mis- take of the church. They have supposed that the revival consists mostly in this state of excited emotion, rather than in conformity of the human will to the law of God. Hence, when the reasons for much excitement have ceased, and the public mind begins to grow more calm, they begin immediately to say, that the revival is on the decline ; when, in fact, with much less excited emotion, there may be vastly more real religion in the community. Excitement is often important and indispensable, but the vigorous actings of the will are infinitely more important. And this state of mind may exist in the absence of highly excited emotions. Nor does it imply that the same degree of emotion, volition, or intel- lectual effort, is at all times required. All volitions do not need the same strength. They cannot have equal strength, because they are not pro- duced by equally inflviential reasons. Should a man put forth as strong a volition to pick up an apple, as to extinguish the flames of a burning house ? Should a mother, watching over her sleeping nursling, when all is quiet and secure, put forth as powerful volitions, as might be required to snatch it from the devouring flames ? Now, suppose that she were equally devoted to God, in watching her sleeping babe, and in rescuing it from the jaws of death. Her holiness would not consist in the fact, that she exercised equally strong volitions, in both cases ; but that in both cases the volition was equal to the accomplishment of the thing re- quired to be done. So that persons may be entirely holy, and yet con- tinually varying in the strength of their affections, emotions, or volitions, according to their circumstances, the state of their physical system, and the business in which they are engaged. All the powers of body and mind are to be held at the service and dis- posal of God. Just so much of physical, intellectual, and moral energj OBEDIENCE TO THE LAW. 127 are to be expended in the performance of duty, as the nature and the circumstances of the case require. And nothing is further from the truth than that the law of God requires a constant, intense state of emo- tion and mental action, on any and every subject alike. 6. Entire obedience does not imply that God is to be at all times the direct object of attention and affection. This is not only impossible in the nature of the case, but would render it impossible for us to think of or love our neighbor as ourselves. The law of God requires the supreme love of the heart. By this is meant that the mind's supreme preference should be of God — that God should be the great object of its supreme regard. But this state of mind is perfectly consistent with our engaging iu any of the necessary business of life — giving to that business that attention, and exercising about it all those affections and emotions, which its nature and importance demand. K a man love God supremely, and engage in any business for the pro- motion of his glory, if his eye be single, his affections and conduct, so far as they have any moral character, are entirely holy when necessarily engaged in the right transaction of his business, although, for the time being, neither his thoughts nor affections are upon God ; just as a man, who is intensely devoted to his family, may be acting consistently with his supreme affection, and rendering them the most important and per- fect service, while he does not think of them at all. The moral heart is the mind's supreme preference. The natural heart propels the blood through all the physical system, Now there is a striking analogy be- tween this and the moral heart. And the analogy consists in this, that as the natural heart, by its pulsations, diffuses life through the physical system, so the moral heart, or the supreme governing preference, or ulti- mate intention of the mind, is that which gives life and character to man's moral actions. For example, suppose that I am engaged in teach- ing mathematics ; in this, my ultimate intention is to glorify God in this particular calling. Now in demonstrating some of its intricate proposi- tions, I am obliged, for hours together, to give the entire attention of my mind to that object. While my mind is thus intensely employed in one particular business, it is impossible that I should have any thoughts about God, or should exercise any direct affections, or emotions, or voli- tions, towards him. Yet if, in this particular calling, all selfishness is excluded, and my supreme design is to glorify God, my mind is in a state of entire obedience, even though, for the time being, I do not think of God. It should be understood, that while the supreme preference or inten- tion of the mind has such efficiency as to exclude all selfishness, and to call forth just that strength of volition, thought, affection, and emotion, that is requisite to the right discharge of any duty to which the mind 128 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. may be called, the heart is in a right state. By a suitable degree of thought and feeling, to the right discharge of duty, I mean just that in- tensity of thought, and energy of action, that the nature and importance ol the particular duty, to which, for the time being, I am called, demand, in my honest estimation. In making this statement, I take it for granted, that the brain together with all the circumstances of the constitution are such that the requisite amount of thought, feeling, etc., are possible. If the physical constitution be in such a state of exhaustion, as to be unable to put forth that amount of exertion which the nature of the case might otherwise demand, even in this case, the languid efforts, though far below the im- portance of the subject, would be all that the law of God requires. Whoeyer, therefore, supposes that a state of entire obedience implies a state of entire abstraction of mind from everything but God, labors under a grievous mistake. Such a state of mind is as inconsistent with duty, as it is impossible, while we are in the flesh. The fact is that the language and spirit of the law have been and generally are, grossly misunderstood, and interpreted to mean what they never did, or can, mean, consistently with natural justice. Many a mind has been thrown open to the assaults of Satan, and kept in a state of continual bondage and condemnation, because God was not, at aU times, the direct object of thought, affection, and emotion ; and because the mind was not kept in a state of perfect tension, and excited to the utmost at every moment. 7. Nor does it imply a state of continual calmness of mind. Christ was not in a state of continual calmness. The deep peace of his mind was never broken up, but the surface or emotions of his mind were often in a state of great excitement, and at other times, in a state of great calm- ness. And here let me refer to Christ, as we have his history in the Bible, in illustration of the positions I have already taken. For example. Christ had all the constitutional appetites and susceptibilities of human nature. Had it been otherwise, he could not have been '' tempted in all points like as we are ; " nor could he have been tempted in any point as we are, any further than he possessed a constitution similar to our own. Christ also manifested natural affection for his mother and for other friends. He also showed that he had a sense of injury and injustice, and exercised a suitable resentment when he was injured and persecuted. He was not always in a state of great excitement. He appears to have had his seasons of excitement and of calm — of labor and rest — of joy and sorrow, like other good men. Some persons have spoken of entire obe- dience to the law, as implying a state of uniform and universal calmness, and as if every kind and degree of excited feeling, except the feeling of love to God, were inconsistent with this state. But Christ often mani' OBEDIENCE TO THE LAW. 129 fested a great degree of excitement when reproving the enemies of God. In short, his history would lead to the conclusion that his calmness and excitement were various, according to the circumstances of the case. And although he was sometimes so pointed and severe in his reproof, as to be accused of being possessed of a devil, yet his emotions and feelings were only those that were called for, and suited to the occasion. 8. Nor does it imply a state of continual sweetness of min,d, without any indignation or holy anger at sin and sinners. Anger at sin is only a modification of love to being in general. A sense of justice, or a dis- position to have the wicked punished for the benefit of the government, is only another of the modifications of love. And such dispositions are essential to the existence of love, where the circumstances call for their exercise. It is said of Christ, that he was angry. He often manifested anger and holy indignation. " God is angry with the wicked every day." And holiness, or a state of obedience, instead of being inconsistent with, always implies, the existence of anger, whenever circumstances occur which demand its exercise. 9. It does not imply a state of mind that is all compassion, and no sense of justice. Compassion is only one of the modifications of love. Justice, or willing the execution of law and the punishment of sin, is another of its modifications. God, and Christ, and all holy beings, exer- cise all those dispositions that constitute the different modifications of love, under every possible circumstance. 10. It does not imply that we should love or hate all men alike, irre- spective of their value, circumstances, and relations. One being may have a greater capacity for well-being, and be of much more importance to the universe, than another. Impartiality and the law of love require us not to regard all beings and things alike, but all beings and things according to their nature, relations, circumstances, and value. 11. Nor does it imply a perfect knowledge of all our relations. Such an interpretation of the law as would make it necessary, in order to yield obedience, for us to understand all our relations, would imply in us the possession of the attribute of omniscience ; for certainly there is not a being in the universe to whom we do not sustain some relation. And a knowledge of all these relations plainly implies infinite knowledge. It is plain that the law of God cannot require any such thing as this. 12. Nor does it imply freedom from mistake on any subject what- ever. It is maintained by some that the grace of the gospel pledges to every man perfect knowledge, or at least such knowledge as to exempt him from any mistake. I cannot stop here to debate this question, but would merely say, the law does not expressly or impliedly require infalli- bility of judgment in us. It only requires us to make the best use we can of all the light we have. 30 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. 13. It does not imply the same degree of knowledge we might have possessed, had we always improved our time in its acquisition. The law cannot require us to love God or man, as well as we might have been able to love them, had we always improved all our time in obtaining all the knowledge we could, in regard to their nature, character, and interests. If this were implied in the requisition of the law, there is not a saint on earth or in heaven that does, or ever can, perfectly obey. What is lost in this respect is lost, and past neglect can never be so remedied, that we shall ever be able to make up in our acquisitions of knowledge what we have lost. It will no doubt be true to all eternity, that we shall have less knowledge than we might have possessed, had we filled up all our time in its acquisition. We do not, cannot, nor shall we ever be able to, love God as well as we might have loved him, had we always applied our minds to the acquisition of knowledge respecting him. And if en- tire obedience is to be understood as implying that we love God as much as we should, had we all the knowledge we might have had, then I re- peat it, there is not a saint on earth or in heaven, nor ever will be, that is entirely obedient. 14. It does not imply the same amount of service that we might have rendered, had we never sinned. The law of God does not imply or sup- pose, that our powers are in a perfect state ; that our strength of body or mind is what it would have been, had we never sinned. But it sim- ply requires us to use what strength we have. The very wording of the law is proof conclusive, that it extends its demand only to the full amount of what strength we have. And this is true of every moral be- ing, however great or small. The most perfect development and improvement of our powers, must depend upon the most perfect use of them. And every departure from their perfect use, is a diminishing of their highest development, and a curtailing of their capabilities to serve God in the highest and best manner. All sin then does just so much towards crippling and curtailing the powers of body and mind, and rendering them, by just so much, incapable of performing the service they might otherwise have rendered. To this view of the subject it has been objected, that Christ taught an opposite doctrine, in the case of the woman who washed his feet with her tears, when he said, " To whom much is forgiven, the same loveth much." But can it be that Christ intended to be understood as teach- ing, that the more we sin the greater will be our love, and our ultimate virtue ? If this be so, I do not see why it does not follow that the more sin in this life, the better, if so be that we are forgiven. If our virtue is really to be improved by our sins, I see not why it would not be good economy, both for God and man, to sin as much as we can while in this OBEDIENCE TO THE LAW. 131 world. Certainly Christ meant to lay down no such principle as this. He undoubtedly meant to teach that a person who was truly sensible of the greatness of his sins, would exercise more of the love of gratitude than would be exercised by one who had a less affecting sense of ill-desert. 15. Entire obedience does not imply the same degree of faith that might have been exercised but for our ignorance and past sin. We cannot believe anything about God of which we have neither evidence nor knowledge. Our faith must therefore be limited by our intel- lectual perceptions of truth. The heathen are not under obligation to believe in Christ, and thousands of other things of which they have no knowledge. Perfection in a heathen would imply much less faith than in a Christian. Perfection in an adult would imply much more and greater faith than in a child. And perfection in an angel would imply much greater faith than in a man, just in proportion as he knows more of God than man does. Let it be always understood, that entire obedience to God never implies that which is naturally impossible. It is naturally impossible for us to believe that of which we have no knowledge. Entire obedience implies, in this respect, nothing more than the heart's faith or confidence in all the truth that is perceived by the intellect. 16. Nor does it imply the conversion of all men in answer to our prayers. It has been maintained by some, that entire obedience implies the offering of prevailing prayer for the conversion of all men. To this I reply, — Then Christ did not obey, for he offered no such prayer. The law of God makes no such demands, either expressly or impliedly. We have no right to believe that all men will be converted in answer to our prayers, unless we have an express or implied promise to that effect. As, therefore, there is no such promise, we are under no obligation to offer such a prayer. Nor does the non-conversion of the world imply, that there are no saints in the world who fully obey God's law. It does not imply the conversion of any one for whom there is not an express or implied promise in the word of God. The fact that Judas was not converted in answer to Christ's prayer, does not prove that Christ did not fully obey. Nor does it imply that all those things which are expressly or im- pliedly promised, will be granted in answer to our prayers ; or, in other words, that we should pray in faith for them, if we are ignorant of the existence or application of those promises. A state of perfect love implies the discharge of all known duty. And nothing strictly speak- ing can be duty, of which the mind has no knowledge. It cannot, therefore, be our duty to believe a promise of which we are entirely ignorant, or the application of which to any specific object we do not understand. If there is sin in suoh a case as this, it lies in the fact, that the soul 1S2 SrSTEMAtlC THEOLOGY. neglects to know what it ought to know. But it should always be understood that the sin lies in this neglect to know, and not in the neglect of that of which we have no knowledge. Entire obedience is inconsistent with any present neglect to know the truth ; for such neg- lect is sin. But it is not inconsistent with our failing to do that of which we have no knowledge. James says, " He that knoweth to do good and doeth it not, to him it is sin." " If ye were blind," says Christ, "ye should have no sin, but because ye say. We see, therefore your sin remaineth." 17. Entire obedience to the divine law does not imply, that others will of course regard our state of mind, and our outward life, as entirely conformed to the law. It was insisted and positively believed by the Jews, that Jesus Christ was possessed of a wicked instead of a holy spirit. Such were their notions of holiness, that they no doubt supposed him to be actuated by any other than the Spirit of God. They especially supposed so on account of his opposition to the current orthodoxy, and to the ungodliness of the religious teachers of the day. 'Now, who does not see, that when the church is, in a great measure, c6nformed to the world, a spirit of holi- ness in any man would certainly lead him to aim the sharpest rebukes at the spirit and life of those in this state, whether in high or low places ? And who does not see, that this would naturally result in his being accused of possessing a wicked spirit ? And who does not know, that where a religious teacher finds himself under the necessity of attacking a false orthodoxy, he will certainly be hunted, almost as a beast of prey, by the religious teachers of his day, whose authority, influence, and orthodoxy are thus assailed ? 18. Nor does it imply exemption from sorrow or mental suffering. It was not so with Christ. Nor is it inconsistent with our sorrowing for our own past sins, and sorrowing that we have not now the health, and vigor, and knowledge, and love, that we might have had, if we had sinned less ; or sorrow for those around us — sorrow in view of human sinfulness, or suffering. These are all consistent with a state of joyful love to God and man, and indeed are the natural results of it. 19. Nor is it inconsistent with our living in human society — with mingling in the scenes, and engaging in the affairs of this world, as some have supposed. Hence the absurd and ridiculous notions of papists in retiring to monasteries, and convents — in taking the veil, and, as they say, retiring to a life of devotion. Now I suppose this state of voluntary exclusion from human society, to be utterly inconsistent with any degree of holiness, and a manifest violation of the law of love to our neighbor. 20. Nor does it imply moroseness of temper and manners. Nothing is further from the truth than this. It is said of Xavier, than whom, perhaps, few holier men have ever lived, that " he was so cheerful aa OBEDIENCE TO THE LAW. 133 often to be accused of being gay." Cheerfulness is certainly the result of holy love. And entire obedience no more implies moroseness in this world than it does in heaven. In all the discussions I have seen upon the subject of Christian holi- ness, writers seldom or never raise the distinct inquiry : What does obedi- ence to the law of God imply, and what does it not imply ? Instead of bringing everything to this test, they seem to lose sight of it. On the one hand, they include things that the law of God never required of man in his present state. Thus they lay a stumbling-block and a snare for the saints, to keep them in perpetual bondage, supposing that this is the way to keep them humble, to place the standard entirely above their reach. Or, on the other hand, they really abrogate the law, so as to make it no longer binding. Or they so fritter away what is really im- plied in it, as to leave nothing in its requirements, but a sickly, whimsi- cal, inefiBcient sentimentalism, or perfectionism, which in its manifesta- tions and results, appears to me to be anything but that which the law of God requires. 21. It does not imply that we always or ever aim at, or intend to do our duty. That is, it does not imply that the intention always, or ever, terminates on duty as an ultimate end. It is our duty to aim at or in- tend the highest well-being of God and the universe, as an ultimate end, or for its own sake. This is the infinitely valuable end at which we are at all times to aim. It is our duty to aim at this. While we aim at this, we do our duty, but to aim at duty is not doing duty. Nor does it imply that we always think, at the time, of its being duty, or of our moral obligation to intend the good of being. This obligation is a first truth, and is always and necessarily assumed by every moral agent, and this assumption or knowledge is a condition of his moral agency. But it is not at all essential to virtue or true obedience to the moral law, that moral obligation should at all times be present to the thoughts as an object of attention. Nor does it imply that the rightness or moral character of benevo- lence is, at all times, the object of the mind's attention. We may intend the glory of God and the good of our neighbor, without at all times think- ing of the moral character of this intention. But the intention is not the less virtuous on this account. The mind unconsciously, but neces- sarily, assumes the rightness of benevolence, or of willing the good of being, just as it assumes other first truths, without being distinctly con- scious of the assumption. It is not therefore, at all essential to obedi- ence to the law of God, that we should at all times have before our minds the virtuousness or moral character of benevolence. 22. Nor does obedience to the moral law imply, that the law itself should be, at all times^ the object of thought, or of the mind's attention, 134 STSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. The law lies developed in the reason of every moral agent in the form of an idea. It is the idea of that choice or intention which every moral agent is bound to exercise. In other words, the law, as a rule of duty, is a subjective idea always and necessarily developed in the mind of every moral agent. This idea he always and necessarily takes along with him, and he is always and necessarily a law to himself. Never- theless, this law or idea, is not always the object of the mind's attention and thought. A moral agent may exercise good-will or love to God and man, without at the time being conscious of thinking, that this love is required of him by the moral law. Nay, if I am not mistaken, the benevolent mind generally exercises benevolence so spontaneously, as not, for much of the time, even to think that this love to God is required of him. But this state of mind is not the less virtuous on this account. If the infinite value of God's well-being and of his infinite goodness constrains me to love him with all my heart, can any one suppose that this is regarded by him as the less virtuous, because I did not wait to reflect, that God commanded me to love him, and that it was my duty to do so ? The thing upon which the intention must or ought to terminate is the good of being, and not the law that requires me to will it. When I will that end, I will the right end, and this willing is virtue, whether tlie law be so much as thought of or not. Should it be said that I may will that end for a wrong reason, and, therefore, thus willing it is not virtue ; that unless I will it because of my obligation, and intend obe- dience to moral law, or to God, it is not virtue ; I answer, that the objection involves an absurdity and a contradiction. I cannot will the good of God and of being, as an ultimate end, for a wrong reason. The reason of the choice and the end chosen are identical, so that if I will the good of being as an ultimate end, I will it for the right reason. It is impossible to will God's good as an end, out of regard to his authority. This is to make his authority the end chosen, for the reason of a choice is identical with the end chosen. Therefore, to will any- thing for the reason that God requires it, is to will God's requirement as an ultimate end. I cannot, therefore, love God with any acceptable love, primarily, because he commands it. God never expected to in- duce his creatures to love him, or to will his good, by commanding them to do so. 23. Obedience to the moral law does not imply that we should practically treat all interests that are of equal value according to their value. For example, the precept, "Love thy neighbor as thyself," can- not mean that I am to take equal care of my own soul, and the soul of every other human being. This were impossible. Nor does it mean that I should take the same care and oversight of my own, and of all the ATTRIBUTES OF LOVE. 135 families of the earth. Nor that I should divide what little of propei-ty, or time, or talent I have, equally among all mankind. This were — 1.) Impossible. (2.) Uneconomical for the universe. More good will result to the universe by each individual's giving his attention particularly to the pro- motion of those interests that are within his reach, and that are so under his influence that he possesses particular advantages for promoting them. Every interest is to be esteemed according to its relative value ; but our efforts to promote particular interests ^hould depend upon our relations and capacity to promote them. Some interests of great value we may be under no obligation to promote, for the reason that we have no ability to promote them, while we may be under obligation to promote interests of vastly less value, for the reason, that we are able to promote them. We are to aim at promoting those interests that we can most surely and extensively promote, but always in a manner that shall not in- terfere with others promoting other interests, according to their relative value. Every man is bound to promote his own, and the salvation of his family, not because they belong to self, but because they are valuable in themselves, and because they are particularly committed to him, as being directly within his reach. This is a principle everywhere assumed in the government of God, and I wish it to be distinctly borne in mind, as we proceed in our investigations, as it will, on the one hand, prevent misap- prehension, and, on the other, avoid the necessity of circumlocution, when we wish to express the same idea ; the true intent and meaning of the moral law, no doubt, is, that every interest or good known to a moral being shall be esteemed according to its intrinsic value, and that, in our efforts to promote good, we are to aim at securing the greatest practica- ble amount, and to bestow our efforts where, as it appears from our circumstances and relations, we can accomplish the greatest good. This ordinarily can be done, beyond all question, only by each one attending to the promotion of those particular interests which are moat within the reach of his influence. LECTURE XII. ATTRIBUTES OP LOVE. It has been shown that the sum and spirit of the whole law is prop- erly expressed in one word — love. It has also been shown, that this love is benevolence or good willing ; that it consists in choosing the highest good of God and of universal being, for its own intrinsic value, in a spirit 136 ^ SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. of entire consecration to this as the ultimate end of existence. Although the whole law is fulfilled in one word — love, yet there are many things implied in the state of mind expressed by this term. It is, therefore, in- dispensable to a right understanding of this subject, that we inquire into the characteristics or attributes of this love. We must keep steadily in mind certain truths of mental philosophy. I will, therefore — I. Gall attention to certain facts in mental philosophy as they are re- vealed in consciousness. 1. Moral agents possess intellect, or the faculty of knowledge. 2 They also possess sensibility, and sensitivity, or in other words, the faculty or susceptibility of feeling. 3. They also possess will, or the power of choosing or refusing in every case of moral obligation. These primary faculties are so correlated to each other, that the in- tellect or the sensibility may control the will, or the will may, in a cer- tain sense, control them. That is, the mind is free to choose in accord- ance with the demands of the intellect, which is the law-giving faculty, or with the desires and impulses of the sensibility, or to control and direct them both. The will can directly control the attention of the in- tellect, and consequently its perceptions, thoughts, etc. It can indi- rectly control the states of the sensibility, or feeling faculty, by control- ling the perceptions and thoughts of the intellect. "We also know from consciousness, as was shown in a former lecture, that the voluntary muscles of the body are directly controlled by the will, and that the law which obliges the attention, the feelings, and the actions of the body to obey the decisions of the will, is physical law, or the law of necessity. The attention of the intellect and the outward actions are controlled directly, and the feelings indirectly, by the decisions of the will. The will can either command or obey. It can suffer itself to be enslaved by the impulses of the sensibility, or it can assert its sovereignty and control them. The will is not influenced by either the intellect or the sensi- bility, by the law of necessity or force ; so that the will can always re- sist either the demands of the intelligence, or the impulses of the sensi- bility. But while they cannot lord it over the will, through the agency of any law of force, the will has the aid of the law of necessity or force by which to control them. Again : We are conscious of afiSrming to ourselves our obligation to obey the law of the intellect rather than the impulses of the sensibility ; that to act virtuously we must act rationally, or intelligently, and not give ourselves up to the blind impulses of our feelings. Now, inasmuch as the love required by the moral law consists in choice, willing, intention, as before repeatedly shown ; and inasmuch as ATTRIBUTES OF LOVB: 137 choice, willing, intending, controls the states of the intellect and the out- ward actions directly, by a law of necessity, and by the same law controls the feelings or states of the sensibility indirectly, it follows that certain states of the intellect and of the sensibility, and also certain outward ac- tions, must be implied in the existence of the love which the law of God requires. I say, implied in it, not as making a part of it, but as neces- sarily resulting from it. The thoughts, opinions, judgments, feelings, and outward actions must be moulded and modified by the state of the heart or will. Here it is important to remark, that, in common language, the same word is often used to express either an action or attitude of the will, or a state of the sensibility, or both. This is true of all the terms that repre- sent what are called the Christian graces or virtues, or those various modifications of virtue of which Christians are conscious, and which appear in their life and temper. Of this truth we shall be constantly reminded as we proceed in our investigations, for we shall find illustra- tions of it at every step of our progress. Before I proceed to point out the attributes of benevolence, it is im- portant to remark, that all the moral attributes of God and of all holy beings, are only attributes of benevolence. Benevolence is a term that comprehensively expresses them all. God is love. This term ex- presses comprehensively God's whole moral character. This love, as we have repeatedly seen, is benevolence. Benevolence is good-willing, or the choice of the highest good of God and the universe, as an end. But from this comprehensive statement, accurate though it be, we are apt to receive very inadequate conceptions of what really belongs to, as implied in, benevolence. To say that love is the fulfilling of the whole law ; that benevolence is the whole of true religion ; that the whole duty of man to God and his neighbor, is expressed in one word, love — these state- mentsj though true, are so comprehensive as to need with all minds much amplification and explanation. Many things are implied in love or benev- olence. By this is intended, that benevolence needs to be viewed under various aspects and in various relations, and its nature considered in the various relations in which it is called to act. Benevolence is an ultimate intention, or the choice of an ultimate end. Bat if we suppose that this is all that is implied in benevolence, wo shall egregiously err. Unless we inquire into the nature of the end which benevolence chooses, and the means by which it seeks to accomplish that end, we shall understand but little of the import of the word benevolence. Benevolence has many at- tributes or characteristics. These must all harmonize in the selection of its end, and in its efforts to realize it. By this is intended that benevolence is not a blind, but the most intelligent, choice. It is the choice of the best possible end in obedience tp the demand of the reason and of God, and 138 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. implies the choice of the best possible means to secure this end. Both the end and the means are chosen in obedience to the law of God, and of reason. An attribute is a permanent quality of a thing. The attributes of benevolence are those permanent qualities which belong to its very nature. Benevolence is not blind, but intelligent, choice. It is the choice of the highest well-being of moral agents. It seeks this end by means suited to the nature of moral agents. Hence wisdom, justice, mercy, truth, holiness, and many other attributes, as we shall see, are essential elements, or attributes, of benevolence. To understand what true benevolence is, we must inquire into its attributes. Not every- thing that is called love has at all the nature of benevolence. Nor has all that is called benevolence any title to that appellation. There are various kinds of love. Natural affection is called love. Our preference of certain kinds of diet is called love. Hence we say we love fruit, vege- tables, meat, milk, etc. Benevolence is also called love, and is the kind of love, beyond all question, required by the law of God. But there is more than one state of mind that is called benevolence. There is a con- stitutional or phrenological benevolence, which is often mistaken for, and confounded with, the benevolence which constitutes virtue. This so called benevolence is in truth only an imposing form of selfishness ; nevertheless it is called benevolence. Many of its manifestations are like those of true benevolence. Care, therefore, should be taken, in giving religious instruction, to distinguish accurately between them. Benevo- lence, let it be remembered, is the obedience of the will to the law of reason and of God. It is willing good as an end, for its own sake, and not to gratify self. Selfishness consists in the obedience of the will to the impulses of the sensibility. It is a spirit of self-gratification. The will seeks to gratify the desires and propensities, for the pleasure of the gratification. Self-gratification is sought as an end, and as the supreme end. It is preferred to the claims of God and the good of being. Phreno- logical, or constitutional benevolence, is only obedience to the impulse of the sensibility — a yielding to a feeling of compassion. It is only an effort to gratify a desire. It is, therefore, as really selfishness, as is an effort to gratify any constitutional desire whatever. It is impossible to get a just idea of what constitutes obedience to the divine law, and what is implied in it, without considering attentively the various attributes or aspects of benevolence, properly so called. Upon this discussion we are about to enter. But before I commence the enu- meration and definition of these attributes, it is important further to remark that the moral attributes of God, as revealed in his works, provi- dence, and word, throw much light upon the subject before us. Also the many precepts of the Bible, and the developments of benevolence j;berein revealed, will assist us niuch, as we proceed ii^ our inquiries upon ATTRIBUTES OF LOVE. * 139 this important subject. As the Bible expressly affirms that love com- prehends the whole character of God — that it is the whole that the law requires of man — that the end of the commandment is charity or love— we may be assured that every form of true virtue is only a modifi- cation of love or benevolence ; that is, that every state of mind required by the Bible, and recognized as virtue, is, in its last analysis, resolvable into love or benevolence. In other words, every virtue is only benevo- lence viewed under certain aspects, or in certain relations. In other words still, it is only one of the elements, peculiarities, characteristics, or attributes of benevolence. This is true of God's moral attributes. They are, as has been said, only attributes of benevolence. They are only the essential qualities that belong to the very nature of benevolence, which are manifested and brought into activity wherever benevolence is brought into certain circumstances and relations. Benevolence is just, merciful, etc. Such is its nature, that in appropriate circumstances these quali- ties, together with many others, will manifest themselves in executive acts.* This is and must be true of every holy being. H. / will now proceed to point out the attributes of that love which constitutes obedience to the law of GTod. As I proceed I will call attention to the states of the intellect and of the sensibility, and also to the course of outward conduct implied in the existence of this love in any mind — implied in its existence as necessarily resulting from it by the law of cause and efEect. These attributes are^ 1. Voluntariness. That is to say, it is a phenomenon of the will. There is a state of the sensibility often expressed by the term love. Love may, and often does exist, as every one knows, in the form of a mere feeling or emotion. The term is often used to express the emotion of fondness or attachment, as distinct from a voluntary state of mind, or a choice of the will. This emotion or feeling, as we are all aware, is * A recent writer has spoken contemptuously of " being," as he calls it, " sophis ticated into believing, or rather saying, that faith is love, justice is love, humility is love." I would earnestly recommend to that and kindred writers, the study of the thirteenth chapter of the first Corinthians. They will there find a specimen of what they please to call sophistry. If it is " sophistry," or " excessive generalization," as other writers seem to regard it, to represent love as possessing the attributes which comprise the various forms of virtue, it surely is the " generalization " and " sophis- try " of inspiration. Generalization was the great peculiarity of Christ's preaching His epitomizing all the commandments of Clod, and resolving the whole of obediencs into love, is an illustration of this, and in no other way could he have exposed the delusion of those who obeyed the letter, but overlooked and outraged the spirit of the divine commandments. The same was true of the apostles, and so it is of every preacher of the gospel. Every outward act is only the expression of an inward vol- untary state of mind. To understand ourselves or others, we must conceive clearly of the true spirit of moral law, and of heart-obedience to it. 140 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOaY. purely an involuntary state of mind. Because it is a phenomenon of the sensibility, and of course a passive state of mind, it has in itself no moral character. The law of God requires voluntary love or good-will, as has been repeatedly shown. This love consists in choice, intention. It is choosing the highest well-being of God and the universe of sentient beings as an end. Of course voluntariness must be one of its characteristics. The word benevolence expresses this idea. If it consists in choice, if it be a phenomenon of the will, it must control the thoughts and states of the sensibility, as well as the outward action. This love, then, not only consists in a state of consecration to God and the universe, but also implies deep emotions of love to God and man. Though a phenomenon of the will, it implies the existence of all those feelings of love and affection to God and man, that necessarily result from the consecration of the heart or will to their highest well- being. It also implies all that outward course of life that necessarily flows from a state of will consecrated to this end. Let it be borne in mind, that where these feelings do not arise in the sensibility, and where this course of life is not, there the true love or voluntary consecration to God and the universe required by the law, is not. Those follow from this by a law of necessity. Those, that is, feelings or emotions of love, and a correct outward life, may exist without this voluntary love, as I shall have occasion to show in its proper place ; but this love cannot exist without those, as they follow from it by a law of necessity. These emotions will vary in their strength, as constitution and circumstances vary, but exist they must, in some sensible degree, whenever the will is in a benevolent attitude. 2. Liberty is an attribute of this love. The mind is free and spon- taneous in its exercise. It makes this choice when it has the power at every moment to choose self-gratification as an end. Of this every moral agent is conscious. It is a free, and therefore a responsible, choice. 3. Bitelligence. That is, the mind makes choice of this end intelli- gently. It not only knows what it chooses, and why it chooses, but also that it chooses in accordance with the dictates of the intellect, and the law of God ; that the end is worthy of being chosen, and that for this reason the intellect demands that it should be chosen, and also, that for its own intrinsic value it is chosen. Because voluntariness, liberty, and intelligence are natural attributes of this love, therefore, the following are its moral attributes. 4. Virtue is an attribute of it. Virtue is a term that expresses the moral character of benevolence ; it is moral Tightness. Moral rightness is moral perfection, righteousness, or uprightness. The term marks or designates its relation to moral law, and expresses its conformity to it. In the exercise of this love or choice, the mind is conscious of upright- ATTRIBUTES OF LOVE. 141 neas, or of being conformed to moral law or moral obligation. In other ■words, it is conscious of being virtuous or holy, of being like God, of loving what ought to be loved, and of consecration to the right end. Because this choice is in accordance with the demands of the intellect, therefore the mind, in its exercise, is conscious of the approbation of that power of the intellect which we call conscience. The conscience must approve this love, choice, or intention. Again : Because the conscience approves of this choice, therefore, there is and must be in the sensibility a feeling of happiness or satisfac- tion, a feeling of complacency or delight in the love that is in the heart or will. This love, then, always produces self-approbation in the con- science, and a felt satisfaction in the sensibility ; and these feelings are often very acute and joyous, insomuch that the soul, in the exercise of this love of the heart, is sometimes led to rejoice with joy unspeakable and full of glory. This state of mind does not always and necessarily amount to joy. Much depends in this respect on the clearness of the intellectual views, upon the state of the sensibility, and upon the mani- festation of Divine approbation to the soul. But where peace, or approbation of conscience, and consequently a peaceful state of the sensibility are not, this love is not. They are connected with it by a law of necessity, and must of course appear on the field of conscious- ness where this love exists. These, then, are implied in the love that constitutes obedience to the law of God. Conscious peace of mind, and conscious joy in God must be where true love to God exists. 5. Disinterestedness is another attribute of this love. By disinter- estedness, it is not intended that, the mind takes no interest in the object loved, for it does take a supreme interest in it. But this term expresses the mind's choice of an end for its own sake, and not merely upon con- dition that the good belongs to self. This love is disinterested in the sense that the highest well-being of God and the universe is chosen, not upon condition of its relation to self, but for its own intrinsic and infi- nite value. It is this attribute particularly that distinguishes this love from selfish love. Selfish love makes the relation of good to self the con- dition of choosing it. The good of God and of the universe, if chosen at all, is only chosen as a means or condition of promoting the highest good of self. But this love does not make good to self its end ; but good to God and being in general, is its end. As disinterestedness is an attribute of this love, it does not seek its own, but the good of others. " Charity (love) seeketh not her own." It grasps in its comprehensive embrace the good of being in general, and of course, of necessity, secures a corresponding outward life and inward feeling. The intellect will be employed in devising ways and means foi the promotion of its end. The sensibility will be tremblingly alive to 14:2 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOar. the good of all and of each ; will rejoice in the good of others as in iti own, and will grieve at the misery of others as in its own. It " will re- joice with them that do rejoice, and weep with them that weep." There will not, cannot be envy at the prosperity of others, but unfeigned joy, joy as real and often as exquisite as in its own prosperity. Benevolence enjoys everybody's good things, while selfishness is too envious at the ■good things of others even to enjoy its own. There is a Divine economy in benevolence. Each benevolent soul not only enjoys his own good things, but also enjoys the good things of all others so far as he knows their happiness. He drinks at the river of God's pleasure. He not only rejoices in doing good to others, but also in beholding their enjoyment of good things. He joys in God's joy, and in the joy of angels and of saints. He also rejoices in the good things of all sentient existences. He is happy in beholding the pleasure of the beasts of the field, the fowls of the air, and the fishes of the sea. He sympathizes with all joy and all suffering known to him ; nor is his sympathy with the sufferings of others a feeling of unmingled pain. It is a real luxury to sympathize in the woes of others. He would not be without this sympathy. It so accords with his sense of propriety and fitness, that, mingled with the painful emotion, there is a sweet feeling of self-approbation ; so that a benevo- lent sympathy with the woes of others is by no means inconsistent with happiness, and with perfect happiness. God has this sympathy. He often expresses and otherwise manifests it. There is, indeed, a myste- rious and an exquisite luxury in sharing the woes of others. God and angels and all holy beings know what it is. Where this result of love ia not manifested, there love itself is not. Envy at the prosperity, in- fluence, or good of others, the absence of sensible joy in view of the good enjoyed by others, and of sympathy with the sufferings of others, prove conclusively that this love does not exist. There is an expansiveness, an ampleness of embrace, a universality, and a divine disinterestedness in this love, that necessarily manifests itself in the liberal devising of liberal things for Zion, and in the copious outpourings of the floods of sympathetic feeling, both in joys and sorrows, when suitable occasions present themselves before the mind. 6. Impartiality is another attribute of this love. By this term is not intended, that the mind is indifferent to the character of him who is happy or miserable ; that it would be as well pleased to see the wicked as the righteous eternally and perfectly blessed. But it is intended that, other things being equal, it is the intrinsic value of their well-being which is alone regarded by the mind. Other things being equal, it matters not to whom the good belongs. It is no respecter of persons. The good of being is its end, and it seeks to promote every interest according to its relative value. Selfish love is partial. It seeks to ATTRIBUTES OF LOVE. 148 promote self-interest first, and secondarily those interests that sustain such a relation to self as will at least indirectly promote the gratificatio» of self. Selfish love has its favorites, its prejudices, unreasonable and ridiculous. Color, family, nation, and many other things of like nature, modify it. But benevolence knows neither Jew nor Greek, neither bond nor free, white nor black. Barbarian, Scythian, European, Asiatic, African, nor American, but accounts all men as men, and, by virtue of their common manhood, calls every man a brother, and seeks the interests of all and of each. Impartiality, being an attribute of this love, will of course manifest itself in the outward life, and in the temper and spirit of its subject. This love can have no fellowship with those absurd and ridiculous prejudices that are so often rife among nominal Christians. Nor will it cherish them for a moment in the sensibility of him who exercises it. Benevolence recognizes no privileged classes on the one hand, nor proscribed classes on the other. It secures in the sensibiliiy an utter loathing of those discriminations, so odiously manifested and boasted of, and which are founded exclusively in a selfish state of the will. The fact that a man is a man, and not that he is of our party, of our complexion, or of our town, state, or nation — that he is a creature of God, that he is capable of virtue and happiness, these are the con- siderations that are seized upon by this divinely impartial love. It is the intrinsic value of his interests, and not that they are the interests of one connected with self, that the benevolent mind regards. But h«re it is important to repeat the remark, that the economy of benevolence demands, that where two interests are, in themselves con- sidered, of equal value, in order to secure the greatest amount of good, each one should bestow his efEorts where they can be bestowed to the greatest advantage. For example : every man sustains such relations that he can accomplish more good by seeking to promote the interest and happiness of certain persons rather than of others ; his family, his kindred, his companions, his immediate neighT)ors, and those to whom, in the providence of God, he sustains such relations as to give him access to them, and influence over them. It is not unreasonable, it is not partial, but reasonable and impartial, to bestow our efforts more directly upon them. Therefore, while benevolence regards every interest according to its relative value, it reasonably puts forth its efEorts in the direction where there is a prospect of accomplishing the most good. This, I say, is not partiality, but impartiality ; for, be it understood, it is not the particular persons to whom good can be done, but the amount of good that can be accomplished, that directs the efEorts of benevolence. It is not because my family is my own, nor because their well-being is, of course, more valuable in itself than that of my neighbors' families, but because my relations afford me higher facilities for doing them good, IW SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. I am under particular obligation to aim first at promoting their good. Hence the apostle says : " If any man provide not for his own, especially for those of his own household, he hath denied the faith, and is worse than an infidel." Strictly speaking, benevolence esteems every known good according to its intrinsic and relative value ; but practically treats every interest according to the perceived probability of securing on the whole the highest amount of good. This is a truth of great practica. importance. It is developed in the experience and observation of every day and hour. It is manifest in the conduct of God and of Christ, of apostles and martyrs. It is everywhere assumed in the precepts of the Bible, and everywhere manifested in the history of benevolent effort. Let it be understood, then, that impartiality, as an attribute of benevolence, does not imply that its effort to do good wiU be modified by relations and circumstances. But, on the contrary, this attribute implies, that the efforts to secure the great end of benevolence, to wit, the greatest amount of good to God and the universe, will be modified by those rela- tions and circumstances that afford the highest advantages for doing good. The impartiality of benevolence causes it always to lay supreme stress upon God's interests, because his well-being is of infinite value, and of course benevolence must be supreme to him. Benevolence, being impar- tial love, of course accounts God's interests and well-being, as of infinitely greater value than the aggregate of all other interests. Benevolence re- gards our neighbor's interests as our own, simply because they are in their intrinsic value as our own. Benevolence, therefore, is always supreme to God and equal to man. 7. Universality is another attribute of this love. Benevolence chooses the highest good of being in general. It excludes none from its regard ; but on the contrary embosoms all in its ample embrace. But by this it is not intended, that it practically seeks to promote the good of every indi- vidual. It would if it could ; but it seeks the highest practicable amount of good. The interest of every individual is estimated according to its intrinsic value, whatever the circumstances or character of each may be. But character and relations may and must modify the manifestations of benevolence, or its efforts in seeking to promote this end. A wicked character, and governmental relations and considerations, may forbid benevolence to seek the good of some. Nay, they may demand that posi- tive misery shall be inflicted on some, as a warning to others to beware of their destructive ways. By universality, as an attribute of benevo- lence, is intended, that good-will is truly exercised towards all sentient beings, whatever their character and relations may be ; and that, when the higher good of the greater number does not forbid it, the happiness of all and of each will be pursued with a degree of stress equal to their relative value, and the prospect of securing each interest. Enemies as ATTRIBUTES OF LOVE. 145 well as friends, strangers and foreigners as well as relations and immedi- ate neighbors, will be enfolded in its sweet embrace. It is the state of mind required by Christ in the truly divine precept, " I say unto you, Love your enemies, pray for them that hate you, and do good unto them that despitefuUy use and persecute you." This attribute of benevolence is gloriously conspicuous in the character of God. His love to sinners alone accounts for their being to-day out of perdition. His aiming to secure the highest good of the greatest number, is illustrated by the dis- play of his glorious justice in the punishment of the wicked. His uni- versal care for all ranks and conditions of sentient beings, manifested in his works and providence, beautifully and gloriously illustrates the truth, that " his tender mercies are over all his works." It is easy to see that universality must be a modification or attribute of true benevolence. It consists in good-willing, that is, in choosing the highest good of being as such, and for its own sake. Of course it must, to be consistent with itself, seek the good of all and of each, so far as the good of each is consistent with the greatest good upon the whole. Be- nevolence not only wills and seeks the good of moral beings, but also the good of every sentient existence, froni the minutest animalcule to the highest order of beings. It of course produces a state of the sensibility tremblingly alive to all happiness and to all pain. It is pained at the agony of an insect, and rejoices in its joy. God does this, and all holy beings do this. Where this sympathy with the joys and sorrows of universal being is not, there benevolence is not. Observe, good is its end ; where this is promoted by the proper means, the feelings are grati- fied. Where evil is witnessed, the benevolent spirit deeply and necea- sarily sympathizes. LECTURE XIII. ATTRIBUTES OP LOVE. 8. Efficiency is another attribute or characteristic of benevolence. Benevolence consists in choice, intention. Now we know from con- sciousness that choice or intention constitutes the mind's deepest source or power of action. If I honestly intend a thing, I cannot but make efforts to accomplish that which I intend, provided that I believe the thing possible. If I choose an end, this choice must and will energize to secure its end. When benevolence is the supreme choice, preference, or intention of the soul, it is plainly impossible that it should not pro- Ii6 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. duce efforts to secure its end. It must cease to exist, or manifest itself in exertions to secure its end, as soon as, and whenever the intelligence deems it wise to do so. If the will has yielded to the intelligence in the choice of an end, it will certainly obey the intelligence in pursuit of that end. Choice, intention, is the cause of all the outward activity of moral agents. They have all chosen some end, either their own gratification, or the highest good of being ; and all the busy bustle of this world's teeming population, is nothing else than choice or intention seeking to compass its end. EflBciency, therefore, is an attribute of benevolent intention. It must, it will, it does energize in God, in angels, in saints on earth and in heaven. It was this attribute of benevolence, that led God to give his only begotten Son, and that led the Son to give himself, " that whoso- ever believeth in him should not perish, but have everlasting life." If love is eflBcient in producing outward action, and efficient in pro- ducing inward feelings ; it is efficient to wake up the intellect, and set the world of thought in action to devise ways and means for realizing its end. It wields all the infinite natural attributes of God. It is the main- spring that moves all heaven. It is the mighty power that is heaving the mass of mind, and rocking the world like a smothered volcano. Look to the heavens above. It was benevolence that hung them out. It is benevolence that sustains those mighty rolling orbs in their courses. It was good- will endeavoring to realize its end that at first put forth creative power. The same power, for the same reason, still energizes, and will continue to energize for the realization of its end, so long as God is benevolent. And 1 what a glorious thought, that infinite benevolence is wielding, and will forever wield, infinite natural attributes for the pro- motion of good I No hiind but an infinite one can begin to conceive of the amount of good that Jehovah will secure. blessed, glorious thought ! But it is, it must be a reality, as surely as God and the uni- verse exist. It is no vain imagination ; it is one of the most certain, as well as the most glorious, truths in the universe. Mountains of granite are but vapor in comparison with it. But the truly benevolent on earth and in heaven will sympathize with God. The power that energizes in him, energizes in them. One principle animates and moves them all, and that principle is love, good- will to universal being. Well may our souls cry out. Amen, go on, God-speed the work ; let this mighty power heave and wield universal mind, until all the ills of earth shall be put away, and until all that can be made holy are clothed in the garments of everlasting gladness. Since benevolence is necessarily, from its very nature, active and efficient in putting forth efforts to secure its end, and since its end is the highest good of being, it follows that all who are truly religious will, and ATTRIBUTES OP LOVE. 147 must, from the very nature of true religion, be active in endeavoring to promote the good of being. While effort is possible to a Christian, it is as natural to him as his breath. He has within him the very main-spring of activity, a heart set on the promotion of the highest good of universal being. While he has life and activity at all, it will, and it must, be di- rected to this end. Let this never be forgotten. An idle, an inactive, inefiScient Christian is a misnomer. Eeligion is an essentially active principle, and when and while it exists, it must exercise and manifest itself. It is not merely good desire, but it is good-willing. Men may have desires, and hope and live on them, without making efforts to real- ize their desires. They may desire without action. If their will is active, their life must be. If they really choose an ultimate end, this choice must manifest itself. The sinner does and must manifest his selfish choice, and so likewise must the saint manifest his benevolence. 9. Complacency in holiness or moral excellence, is another attribute of benevolence. This consists in benevolence contemplated in its rela- tions to holy beings. This term also expresses both a state of the intelligence and of the sensibility. Moral agents are so constituted, that they necessarily ap- prove of moral worth or excellence ; and when even sinners behold right character, or moral goodness, they are compelled to respect and approve it, by a law of their intelligence. This they not unfrequently regard as evidence of goodness in themselves. But this is doubtless just as com- mon in hell as it is on earth. The veriest sinners on earth or in hell, have, by the unalterable constitution of their nature, the necessity im- posed upon them, of paying intellectual homage to moral excellence. When a moral agent is intensely contemplating moral excellence, and his intellectual approbation is emphatically pronounced, the natural, and often the necessary result, is a corresponding feeling of complacency or delight in the sensibility. But this being altogether an involuntary state of mind, has no moral character. Complacency, as a phenomenon of will, consists in willing the highest actual blessedness of the holy being in particular, as a good in itself, and upon condition of his moral excel- lence. This attribute of benevolence is the cause of a complacent state of the sensibility. It Is true, that feelings of complacency may exist, when complacency of will does not exist. But complacency of feeling surely will exist, when complacency of will exists. Complacency of will im- plies complacency of conscience, or the approbation of the intelligence. When there is a complacency of intelligence and of will, there must fol- low, of course, complacency of the sensibility. It is highly worthy of observation here, that this complacency of feeling is that which is generally termed love to God and to the saints. 148 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. in the common language of Christians, and often in the popular language of the Bible. It is a vivid and pleasant state of the sensibility, and very noticeable by consciousness, of course. Indeed, it is perhaps the general usage now to call this phenomenon of the sensibility, love ; and, for want of just discrimination, to speak of it as constituting religion. Many seem to suppose that this feeling of delight in, and fondness for, God, is the love required by the moral law. They are conscious of not being volun- tary in it, as well they may be. They judge of their religious state, not by the end for which they live, that is, by their choice or intention, but by their emotions. If they find themselves strongly exercised with emotions of love to God, they look upon themselves as in a state well- pleasing to God. But if their feelings or emotions of love are not active, they of course judge themselves to have little or no religion. It is remarkable to what extent religion is regarded as a phenomenon of the sensibility, and as consisting in mere feelings. So common is it, indeed, that almost uniformly, when professed Christians speak of their religion, they speak of their feelings, or the state of their sensibility, instead of speaking of their conscious consecration to God, and the good of being. It is also somewhat common for them to speak of their views of Christ, and of truth, in a manner that shows, that they regard the states of the intellect as constituting a part, at least, of their religion. It is of great importance that just views should prevail among Christians upon this momentous subject. Virtue, or religion, as has been repeatedly said, must be a phenomenon of the will. The attribute of benevolence which we are considering, that is, complacency of will in God, is the most common light in which the scriptures present it, and also the most common form in which it lies revealed on the field of consciousness. The scriptures often assign the goodness of God as a reason for loving him, and Christians are conscious of having much regard to his goodness in their love to him ; I mean in their good- will to him. They will good to him, and ascribe all praise and glory to him, upon the condition that he deserves it. Of this they are conscious. Now, as was shown in a former lecture, in their love or good will to God, they do not regard his goodness as the fundamental reason for willing good to him. Although his goodness is that, which, at the time, most strongly impresses their minds, yet it must be that the intrinsic value of his well-being is as- sumed, and had in view by them, or they would no sooner will good than evil to him. In willing his good they must assume its intrinsic value to him, as the fundamental reason for willing it ; and his goodness as a secondary reason or condition ; but they are conscious of being much influenced in willing his good in particular, by a regard to his goodness. Should you ask the Christian why he loved God, or why he exercised good-will to him, he would probably reply, it is because God ia ATTRIBUTES OF LOVE. 149 good. But, suppose he should be further asked, why he willed good rather than evil to God ; he would say, because good is good or valuable to him. Or, if he returned the same answer as before, to wit, because God is good, he would give this answer, only because he would think it impossible for any one not to assume and to know, that good is willed instead of evil, because of its intrinsic value. The fact is, the intrinsic value of well-being is necessarily taken along with the mind, and always assumed by it, as a first truth. When a virtuous being is perceived, this first truth being spontaneously and necessarily assumed, the mind thinks only of the secondary reason or condition, or the virtue of the being, in willing good to him. Before I dismiss this subject, I must advert again to the subject of complacent love, as a phenomenon of the sensibility, and also as a phe- nomenon of the intellect. If I mistake not, there are sad mistakes, and gross and ruinous delusions, entertained by many upon this subject. The intellect, of necessity, perfectly approves of the character of God where it is apprehended. The intellect is so correlated to the sensibility, that, where it perceives in a strong light the divine excellence, or the excellence of the divine law, the sensibility is affected by the perception of the intellect, as a thing of course and of necessity ; so that emotions of complacency and delight in the law, and in the divine character, may and often do glow and burn in the sensibility, while the will or heart is unaffected. The will remains in a selfish choice, while the intellect and the sensibility are strongly impressed with the perception of the Divine excellence. This state of the intellect and the sensibility is, no doubt, often mistaken for true religion. We have undoubted illustrations of this in the Bible, and similar cases of it in common life. "Yet they seek me daily, and delight to know my ways, as a nation that did right- eousness, and forsook not the ordinance of their God : they ask of me the ordinances of justice, they take delight in approaching to God." Isaiah Iviii. 2. " And, lo, thou art unto them as a very lovely song of one that hath a pleasant voice, and can play well on an instrument : for they hear thy words, but they do them not." Ezek. xxxiii. 32. Nothing is of greater importance, than forever to understand, that religion is always and necessarily a phenomenon of the will ; that it always and necessarily produces outward action and inward feeling ; that, on account of the correlation of the intellect and sensibility, almost any and every variety of feeling may exist in the mind, as produced by the perceptions of the intellect, whatever the state of the will may be ; that unless we are conscious of good-will, or of consecration to God and the good of being — unless we are conscious of living for this end, it avails us nothing, whatever our views and feelings may be. And also it behooves us to consider that, although these views and 150 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. feelings may exist while the heart is wrong, they will certainly exist when the heart is right ; that there may be feeling, and deep feeling, when the heart is in a selfish attitude, yet, that there will and must be deep emotion and strenuous action, when the heart is right. Let it be re- membered, that complacency, as a phenomenon of the will, is always a striking characteristic of true Iotc to God ; that the mind is afEected and consciously influenced, in willing the actual and infinite blessedness of God, by a regard to his goodness. The goodness of God is not, as has been repeatedly shown, the fundamental reason for the good will, but it is one reason or a condition, both of the possibility of willing, and of the obligation to will, his blessedness in particular. It assigns to itself, and to others, his goodness as the reason for willing his good, rather than the intrinsic value of good ; because this last is so universally, and so neces- sarily assumed, that it thinks not of mentioning it, taking it always for granted, that this will and must be understood. 10. Opposition to sin is another attribute or characteristic of true love to God. This attribute certainly is implied in the very essence and nature of benevolence. Benevolence is. good-willing, or willing the highest good of being as an end. Now there is nothing in the universe more destruc- tive of this good than sin. Benevolence cannot do otherwise than be for- ever opposed to sin, as that abominable thing which it necessarily hates. It is absurd and a contradiction to afiBrm, that benevolence is not op- posed to sin. God is love or benevolence. He must, therefore, be the unalterable opponent of sin — of all sin, in every form and degree. But there is a state, both of the intellect and of the sensibility, that is often mistaken for the opposition of the will to sin. Opposition to all sin is, and must be, a phenomenon of the will, and on that ground alone it becomes virtue. But it often exists also as a phenomenon of the in- tellect, and likewise of the sensibility. The intellect cannot contemplate sin without disapprobation. This disapprobation is often mistaken for opposition of hearty or of will. When the intellect strongly disapproves of, and denounces sin, there is naturally and' necessarily a corresponding feeling of opposition to it in the sensibility, an emotion of loathing, of hatred, of abhorrence. This is often mistaken for opposition of the will, or heart. This is manifest from the fact, that often the most notorious sinners manifest strong indignation in view of oppression, injustice, falsehood, and many other forms of sin. This phenomenon of the sensi- bility and of the intellect, as I said, is often mistaken for a virtuous opposition to sin, which it cannot be unless it involve an act of the will. But let it be remembered, that virtuous opposition to sin is a char- acteristic of love to God and man, or of benevolence. This opposition to sin cannot possibly co-exist with any degree of sin in the heart. That ATTRIBUTES OF LOVE. 151 IB, this opposition cannot co-exist with a sinful choice. The will cannot at the same time, be opposed to sin and commit sin. This is impossible, and the supposition involves a contradiction. Opposition to sin as a phenomenon of the intellect, or of the sensibility, may exist ; in other words, the intellect may strongly disapprove of sin, and the sensibility may feel strongly opposed to certain forms of it, while at the same time, the will may cleave to self indulgence in other forms. This fact, no doubt, accounts for the common mistake, that we can, at the same time, exercise a virtuous opposition to sin, and still continue to commit it. Many are, no doubt, laboring under this fatal delusion. They are conscious, not only of an intellectu al disapprobation of sin in certain forms, but also, at times, of sti'ong feelings of opposition to it. And yet they are also conscious of continuing to commit it. They, therefore con- clude, that they have a principle of holiness in them, and also a principle of sin, that they are partly holy and partly sinful at the same time. Their opposition of intellect and of feeling, they suppose to be a holy opposition, when, no doubt, it is just as common in hell, and even more so than it is on earth, for the reason that sin is more naked there than it generally is here. But now the inquiry may arise, how is it that both the intellect and the sensibility are opposed to it, and yet that it is persevered in ? What reason can the mind have for a sinful choice, when urged to it neither by the intellect nor the sensibility ? The philosophy of this phenom- enon needs explanation. Let us attend to it. I am a moral agent. My intellect necessarily disapproves of sin. My sensibility is so correlated to my intellect, that it sympathizes with it, or is affected by its perceptions and its judgments. I contemplate sin. I necessarily disapprove of it, and condemn it. This affects my sensibility. I loathe and abhor it. I nevertheless commit it. Now how is this to be accounted for ? The usual method is by ascribing it to a depravity in the will itself, a lapsed or corrupted state of the faculty, so that it perversely chooses sin for its own sake. Although disapproved by the intellect, and loathed by the sensibility, yet such, it is said, is the inherent depravity of the will, that it pertinaciously cleaves to sin not- withstanding, and will continue to do so, until that faculty is renewed by the Holy Spirit, and a holy bias or inclination is impressed upon the will itself But here is a gross mistake. In order to see the truth upon this subject, it is of indispensable importance to inquire what sin is. It is admitted on all hands, that selfishness is sin. Comparatively few seem to understand that selfishness is the whole of sin, and that every form of sin may be resolved into selfishness, just as every form of virtue may be resolved into benevolence. It is not my purpose now to 152 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. show that selfishness is the whole of sin. It is sufficient for the present to take the admission, that selfishness is sin. But what is selfishness ? It is the choice of self -gratification as an end. It is the preference of our own gratification to the highest good of universal being. Self-gratifica- tion is the supreme end of selfishness. This choice is sinful. That is, the moral of this selfish choice is sin. Now, in no ease, is or can sin be chosen for its own sake, or as an end. Whenever anything is chosen to gratify self, it is not chosen because the choice is sinful, but notwith- standing it is sinful. It is not the sinfulness of the choice upon which the choice fixes, as an end, or for its own sake, but it is the gratification to be afforded by the thing chosen. For example, theft is sinful. But the will, in an act of theft, does not aim at and terminate on the sinful- ness of theft, but upon the gain or gratification expected from the stolen object. Drunkenness is sinful, but the inebriate does not intend or choose the sinfulness for its own sake, or as an end. He does not choose strong drink because the choice is sinful, but notwithstanding it is so. We choose the gratification, but not the sin, as an end. To choose the gratification as an end is sinful, but it is not the sin that is the object of choice. Our mother Eve ate the forbidden fruit. This eating was sin- ful. But the thing that she chose or intended, was not the sinfulness of eating, but the gratification expected from the fruit. It is not, it cannot in any case be true, that sin is chosen as an end, or for its own sake. Sin is only the quality of selfishness. Selfishness is the choice, not of sin as an end, or for its own sake, but of self -gratification ; and this choice of self-gratification as an end is sinful. That is, the moral quality of the choice is sin. To say that sin is, or can be, chosen for its own sake, is untrue and absurd. It is the same as saying that a choice can terminate on an element, quality, or attribute, of itself ; that the thing chosen is really an element of the choice itself. But it is said, that sinners are sometimes conscious of choosing sin for its own sake, or because it is sin ; that they possess such a malicious state of mind, that they love sin for its own sake ; that they " roll sin as a sweet morsel under their tongue ; " that " they eat up the sins of God's people as they eat bread ;" that is, that they love their own sins and the sins of others, as they do their necessary food, and choose it for that reason, or just as they do their food ; that they not only sin themselves with greediness, but also have pleasure in them that do the same. Now all this may be true, yet it does not at all disprove the posi- tion which I have taken, namely, that sin never is, and never can be chosen as an end, or for its own sake. Sin may be sought and loved as a means, but never as an end. The choice of food wiil illustrate this. Food is never chosen as an ultimate end ; it never can be so chosen. It is always as a means. It is the gratification, or the utility of it, in some ATTRIBUTES OF LOVE. 153 point of view, that constitutes the reason for choosing it. Gratification is always the end for which a selfish man eats. It may not be merely the present pleasure of eating which he alone or principally seeks. But, nevertheless, if a selfish man, he has his own gratification in view as an end. It may be that it is not so much a present, as a remote gratification he has in view. Thus he may choose food to give him health and strength to pursue some distant gratification, the acquisition of wealth, or some- thing else that will gratify him. It may happen that a sinner may get into a state of rebellion against God and the universe, of so frightful a character, that he shall take pleasure in willing, and in doing, and saying, things that are sinful, just because they are sinful and displeasing to God and to holy beings. But, even in this case, sin is not chosen as an end, but as a means of gratify- ing this malicious feeling. It is, after all, self-gratification that is chosen as an end, and not sin. Sin is the means, and self-gratification is the end. Now we are prepared to understand how it is that both the intellect and sensibility can often be opposed to sin, and yet the will cleave to the indulgence. An inebriate is contemplating the moral character of drunkenness. He instantly and necessarily condemns the abomination. His sensibility sympathizes with the intellect. He loathes the sinfulness of drinking strong drink, and himself on account of it. He is ashamed, and were it possible, he would spit in his own face. Now, in this state, it would surely be absurd to suppose that he could choose sin, the sin of drinking, as an end, or for ibs own sake. This would be choosing it for an impossible reason, and not for no reason. But still he may choose to continue his drink, not because it is sinful, but notwithstanding it is so. For while the intellect condemns the sin of drinking strong drink, and the sensibility loathes the sinfulness of the indulgence, nevertheless there still exists so strong an appetite, not for the sin, but for the liquor, that the will seeks the gratification, notwithstanding the sinfulness of it. So it is, and so it must be, in every case where sin is committed in the face of the remonsti-ances of the intellect and the loathing of the sensibility. The sensibility loathes the sinfulness, but more strongly desires the thing the choice of which is sinful. The will in a selfish being yields to the strongest impulse of the sensibility, and the end chosen is, in no case, the sinfulness of the act, but the self-gratification. Those who suppose this opposition of the intellect, or of the sensibility, to be a holy princi- ple, are fatally deluded. It is this kind of opposition to sin, that often manifests itself among wicked men, and that leads them to take credit for goodness or virtue, not an atom of which do they possess. They will not believe themselves to be morally and totally depraved, while they are conscious of so much hostility to sin within them. But they should understand, that this opposition is not of the will, or they ppijld not go 164 bxbTEMATIC THEOLOGTf. on in sin ; that it is purely an involuntary state of mind, and has no moral character whatever. Let it be ever remembered, then, that a vir- tuous opposition to sin is always and necessarily an attribute of benevo- lence, a phenomenon of the will ; and that it is naturally impossible, that this opposition of will should co-exist with the commission of sin. As this opposition to sin is plainly implied in, and is an essential at- tribute of, benevolence, or true love to God, it follows, that obedience to the law of God cannot be partial, in the sense that we both love God and sin at the same time. 11. Compassion for the miserable is also an attribute of benevolence, or of pure love to God and man. This is benevolence viewed in its rela- tions to misery and to guilt. There is a compassion also which is a phenomenon of the sensibility. It may, and does often, exist in the form of an emotion. But this emotion being involuntary, has no moral character in itself. The compassion which is a virtue, and which is required of us as a duty, is a phenomenon of the will, and is of course an attribute of benevolence. Benevolence, as has been often said, is good-willing, or willing the highest happiness and well-being of God and the universe for its own sake, or as an end. It is impossible, therefore, from its own nature, that compassion for the miserable should not be one of its attributes. Compassion of will to misery is the choice or wish that it might not exist. Benevolence wills that happiness should exist for its own sake. It must, therefore, wish that misery might not exist. This attribute or peculiarity of beneosed to them, is a uni- versal truth. But that feelings and desires cannot exist contrary to the states or decisions of the will, is not true. If this were a universal truth, temptation, as I have said, could not exist. The outward actions will be as the will is, always ; the feelings, generally. Feelings corre- sponding to the choice of the will, will be the rule, and opposing feelings the exception. But these exceptions may and do exist in perfectly holy beings. They existed in Eve before she consented to sin, and had she resisted them she had not sinned. They doubtless existed in Christ, or he could not have been tempted in all points like as we are. If there be no desires or impulses of the sensibility contrary to the state of the will, there is not properly any temptation. The desire or impulse must appear on the field of consciousness, before it is a motive to action, and of course before it is a temptation to self-indulgence. Just as certainly then as a holy being may be tempted, and not sin, just so certain it is that emotions of any kind, or of any strength, may exist in the sensibil- ity without sin. If they are not indulged, if the will does not consent to them, and to their indulgence or gratification, the soul is not the less virtuous for their presence. Patience as a phenomenon of the will must strengthen and gird itself under such circumstances, so that patience of will may be, and if it exist at all, must be, in exact proportion to the impatience of the sensibility. The more impatience of sensibility there is, the more patience of will there must be, or virtue will cease alto- gether. So that it is not always true, that virtue is strongest when the sensibility is most calm, placid, and patient. When Christ passed through his greatest conflicts, his virtue as a man was undoubtedly most intense. When in his agony in the garden, so great was the an- guish of his sensibility, that he sweat as it were great drops of blood. This, he says, was the hour of the prince of darkness. This was his great trial. But did he sin ? No, indeed. But why ? Was he calm and placid as a summer's evening ? As far from it as possible. Patience, then, as an attribute of benevolence, consists, not in placid feeling, but in perseverance under trials and states of the sensibility that tend to selfishness. This is only benevolence viewed in a certain aspect. It is benevolence under circumstances of discouragement, of trial, or temptation. " This is the patience of the saints." Before dismissing the subject of patience as an emotion, I would observe that, the steadfastness of the heart tends so strongly to secure patience, that if an opposite state of the sensibility is more than of mo- ATTRIBUTKS OP LOVE. 169 mentary duration, there is strong presumption that the heart is not stead- fast in love. The first risings of it will produce an immediate effort to suppress it. If it continues, this is evidence that the attention is allowed to dwell upon the cause of it. This shows that the will is in some sense indulging it. If it so far influences the will as to manifest itself in impatient words and actions, there must be a yielding of the will. Patience, as an attri- bute of benevolence, is overcome. If the sensibility were perfectly and directly under the control of the will, the least degree of impatience would imply sin. But as it is not directly, but indirectly under the con- trol of the will, momentary impatience of feeling, when it does not at all influence the will, and when it is not at all indulged, is not sure evi- dence of a sinful state of the will. It should always be borne in mind, that neither patience nor impatience, in the form of mere feeling, exist- ing for any length of time, and in any degree, is in itself either holy on the one hand, or sinful on the other. All that can be said of these, states of the sensibility is, that they indicate, as a general thing, the at- titude of the will. When the will is for a long time steadfast in its patience, the result is great equanimity of temper, and gr^at patience of feeling. This comes to be a law of the sensibility, insomuch that very advanced saints may, and doubtless do, experience the most entire pa- tience of feeling for many years together. This does not constitute their holiness, but is a sweet fruit of it. It is to be regarded rather in the light of a reward of holiness, than as holiness itself. 16. Another attribute of benevolence is MeeJcness. Meekness, considered as a virtue, is a phenomenon of the will. This term also expresses a state of the sensibility. When used to designate a phenomenon of the sensibility, it is nearly synonymous with patience. It designates a sweet and forbearing temper under provocation. Meek- ness, a phenomenon of the will, and as an attribute of benevolence, is the opposite both of resistance to injury and retaliation. It is properly and strictly forbearance under injurious treatment. This certainly is an attribute of God, as our existence and our being out of hell plainly demonstrate. Christ said of himself that he was " meek and lowly in heart ;" and this surely was no vain boast. How admirably, and how incessantly did this attribute of his love manifest itself 1 The fifty-third chapter of Isaiah is a prophecy exhibiting this attribute in a most affect- ing light. Indeed, scarcely any feature of the character of God and of Christ is more strikingly exhibited than this. It must evidently be an attribute of benevolence. Benevolence is good-will to all beings. We are naturally forbearing toward those whose good we honestly an^ dili- gently seek. If our hearts are set upon doing them good, we shall natu- rally exercise great fgrbearance toward then?. Gpfl has greatly, conj- 170' SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. mended his forbearance to us, in that, while we were yet his enemies, he forbore to punish us, and gaTe his Son to die for us. Forbearance is a sweet and amiable attribute. How affectingly it displayed itself in the hall of Pilate, and on the cross. " He is led as a lamb to the slaughter, and as a sheep before its shearers is dumb, so he opened not his mouth." This attribute has in this world abundant opportunity to develop and display itself in the saints. There are daily occasions for the exer- cise of this form of virtue. Indeed, all the attributes of benevolence are called into frequent exercise in this school of discipline. This is indeed a suitable world in which to train God's children, to develop and strengthen every modification of holiness. This attribute must always appear where benevolence exists, and wherever there is an occasion for its exercise. It is delightful to contemplate the perfection and glory of that love which constitutes obedience to the law of God. As occasions arise, we behold it developing one attribute after another, and there may be many of its attributes and modifications of which we have as yet no idea what- ever. Circumstances will call them into exercise. It is probable, if not certain, that the attributes of benevolence were very imperfectly known in heaven previous to the existence of sin in the universe, and that but for sin many of these attributes would never have been manifested in ex- ercise. But the existence of sin, great as the evil is, has afforded an op- portunity for benevolence to manifest its beautiful phases, and to de- velop its sweet attributes in a most enchanting manner. Thus the divine economy of benevolence brings good out of so great an evil. A hasty and unforbearing spirit is always demonstrative evidence of a want of benevolence, or of true religion. Meekness is, and must be, a peculiar characteristic of the saints in this world, where there is so much - provocation. Christ frequently and strongly enforced the obligation to forbearance. " But I say unto you that ye resist not evil ; but whoso- ever shall smite thee on thy right cheek, turn to him the other also. And if any man will sue thee at the law, and take away thy coat, let him have thy cloak also. And whosoever shall compel thee to go a mile, go with him twain." How beautiful ! 17. Humility is another modification or attribute of love. This term seems often to be used to express a sense of unworthiness, of guilt, of ignorance, and of nothingness, to express a feeling of ill- desert. It seems to be used in common language to express sometimes a state of the intelligence, when it seems to indicate a clear perception of our guilt. When used to designate a state of the sensibility, it represents those feelings of shame and unworthiness, of ignorance, and of nothing- ness, of which those are most deeply conscious who have been enlight- ened by the Holy Spirit, in respect to their true character. ATTRIBUTES OF LOVE. 171 But as a phenomenon of the will, and as an attribute of love, it consists in a willingness to be known and appreciated according to our real character. Humility, as a phenomenon either of the sensibility or of the intelligence, may co-exist with great pride of heart. Pride is a disposition to exalt self, to get above others, to hide our defects, and to pass for more than we are. Deep conviction of sin, and deep feelings of shame, of ignorance, and of desert of hell, may co-exist with a great un- willingness to confess and be known just as we are, and to be appreciated just according to what our real character has been and is. There is no virtue in such humility. But humility, considered as a virtue, consists in the consent of the will to be known, to confess, and to take our proper place in the scale of being. It is that peculiarity of love that wills the good of being so disinterestedly, as to will to pass for no other than we really are. This is an honest, a sweet, and amiable feature of love; It must, perhaps, be peculiar to those who have sinned. It is only love acting under or in a certain relation, or in reference to a peculiar set of circumstances. It would, under the same circumstances, develop and manifest itself in all truly benevolent minds. This attribute will render confession of sin to God and man natural, and even make it a luxury. It is easy to see that, but for this attribute, the saints could not be happy in heaven. God has promised to bring into judgment every work and every secret thing, whether it be good, or whether it be evil. Now while pride exists, it would greatly pain the soul to have all the charac- ter known ; so that, unless this attribute really belongs to the saints, they would be ashamed at the judgment, and filled with confusion even in heaven itself. But this sweet attribute will secure them against that shame and confusion of face that would otherwise render heaven itself a hell to them. They will be perfectly willing and happy to be known> and estimated according to their characters. This attribute will secure in all the saints on earth that confession of faults one to another, which is so often enjoined in the Bible. By this it is not intended, that Chris- tians always think it wise and necessary to make confession of all their secret sins to man. But it is intended, that they will confess to those whom they have injured, and to all to whom benevolence demands that they should confess. This attribute secures its possessor against spiritual pride, against ambition to get above others. It is a modest and unas- suming state of mind. 18. Self-denial is another attribute of love. If we love any being better than ourselves, we of course deny ourselves when our own interests come in competition with his. Love is gbod-will. If I will good to others more than to myself, it is absurd to say that I shall not deny myself when my own inclinations conflict with their good. Now the love required by the law of God, we have repeatedly seen to be 172 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. good will, or willing the highest good of being for its own sake, or as an end. As the interests of self are not at all regarded because they belong to self, but only according to their relative value, it must be certain, that self-denial for the sake of promoting the higher interests of God and of the universe, is and must be a peculiarity or attribute of love. But again: the very idea of disinterested benevolence, and there is no other true benevolence, implies the abandonment of the spirit of self- seeking, or of selfishness. It is impossible to become benevolent, with- out ceasing to be selfish. In other words, perfect self-denial is implied in beginning to be benevolent. Self-indulgence ceases where benevolence begins. This must be. Benevolence is the consecration of our powers to the highest good of being in general as an end. This is utterly incon- sistent with consecration to self-interest or self-gratification. Selfishness makes good to self the end of every choice. Benevolence makes good to being in general the end of every choice. Benevolence, then, implies complete self-denial. That is, it implies that nothing is chosen merely because it belongs to self, but only because of its relative value, and in proportion to it. I said there was no true benevolence, but disinterested benevolence ; no true love, but disinterested love. There is such a thing as interested love or benevolence. That is, the good of others is willed, though not as an end, or for its intrinsic value to them, but as a means of our own happiness, or because of its relative value to us. Thus a man might will the good of his family, or of his neighborhood, or country, or of anybody, or anything that sustained such relations to self as to involve his own in- terests., When the ultimate reason of his willing good to others is, that his own may be promoted, this is selfishness. It is making good to self his. end. This a sinner may do toward God, toward the church, and to- ward the interests of religion in general. This is what I call interested benevolence. It is willing good as an end only to self, and to all others only as a means of promoting our own good. But again : when the will is governed by mere feeling in willing the good of others, this is only the spirit of self-indulgence, and is only in- terested benevolence. For example : the feeling of compassion is strongly excited by the presence of misery. The feeling is intense, and consti- tutes, like all the feelings, a strong impulse or motive to the will to con- sent to its gratification. For the time being, this impulse is stronger than the feeling of avarice, or any other feeling. I yield to it, and then give all the money I have to relieve the sufferer. I even take my clothes from my back, and give them to him. Now in this case, I am just as selfish as if I had sold my clothes to gratify my appetite for strong drink. The gratification of my feelings was my end. This is one of the most specious and most delusive forms of selfishness. AWHlfitffES OJ" LOVEi. 173 Again : when one makes his own salvation the end of prayer, of alms- giving, and of all his religious duties, this is only selfishness and not true religion, however much he may abound in them. This is only inter- ested benevolence, or benevolence to self. Again : from the very nature of true benevolence, it is impossible that every interest should not be regarded according to its relative value. When another interest is seen by me to be more valuable in itself, or of more value to God and the universe thau my own, and when I see that, by denying myself, I can promote it, it is certain, if I am benevolent, that I shall do it. I cannot fail to do it, without failing to be benevolent. Benevolence is an honest and disinterested consecration of the whole be- ing to the highest good of God and of the universe. The benevolent man will, therefore, and must, honestly weigh each interest as it is per- ceived in the balance of his own best judgment, and will always give the preference to the higher interest, provided he believes, that he can by endeavor, and by self-denial, secure it. That self-denial is an attribute of the divine love, is manifested most gloriously and affectingly in God's gift of his Son to die for men. This attribute was also most conspicuously manifested by Christ, in denying himself, and taking up his cross, and suffering for his enemies. Observe, it was not for friends that Christ gave himself. It was not unfortunate nor innocent sufferers for whom God gave his Son, or for whom he gave himself. It was for enemies. It was not that he might make slaves of them that he gave his Son, nor from any selfish consideration whatever, but because he foresaw that, by making this sacrifice himself, he could secure to the universe a greater good than he should sacrifice. It was this attribute of benevolence that caused him to give his Son to suffer so much. It was disinterested benevolence alone that led him to deny himself, for the sake of a greater good to the universe. Now observe, this sacrifice would not have been made, unless it had been regarded by God as the less of two natural evils. That is, the sufferings of Christ, great and overwhelming as they were, were considered as an evil of less magnitude than the eternal sufferings of sinners. This induced him to make the sacrifice, although for his enemies. It mattered not whether for friends or for enemies, if so be he could, by making a less sacrifice, secure a greater good to them. Let it be understood, that a self-indulgent spirit is never, and can never be, consistent with benevolence. No form of self-indulgence, properly so called, can exist where true benevolence exists. The fact is, self-denial must be, and universally is, wherever benevolence reigns. Christ has ex- pressly made whole-hearted self-denial a condition of discipleship ; which is the same thing as to affirm, that it is an essential attribute of holiness or love J that there cannot be the beginning of true virtue w'ithout it. 174 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Again : much that passes for self-denial is only a specious form of self-indulgence. The penances and self-mortifications, as they are falsely called, of the superstitious, what are they after all but a self-indulgent spirit ? A popish priest abstains from marriage to obtain the honor, and emoluments, and the influence of the priestly ofiSce here, and eterna] glorv hereafter. A nun takes the veil and a monk immures himself in a monastery ; a hermit forsakes human society, and shuts himself up in a cave ; a devotee makes a pilgrimiage to Mecca, and a martyr goes to the stake. Now if these things are done with an ultimate reference to their own glory and happiness, although apparently instances of great self-denial, yet they are, in fact, only a spirit of self-indulgence and self- seeking. They are only following the strongest, desire of good to self. There are many mistakes upon this subject. For example : it is com- mon for persons to deny self in one form, for the sake of gratifying self in another form. In one man avarice is the ruling passion. He will labor hard, rise early, and sit up late, eat the bread of carefulness and deny himself even the necessaries of life, for the sake of accumulating wealth. Every one can see, that this is denying self in one form merely for the sake of gratifying self in another form. Yet this man will com- plain bitterly of the self-indulgent spirit manifested by others, their ex- travagance and want of piety. One man will deny all his bodily appe- tites and passions, for the sake of a reputation with men. This is also an instance of the same kind. Another will give the fruit of his body for the sin of his soul — will sacrifice everything else to obtain an eternal inheritance, and be just as selfish as the man who sacrifices to the things of time, his soul and all the riches of eternity. But it should be remarked, that this attribute of benevolence does and must secure the subjugation of all the propensities. It must, either suddenly or gradually, so far subdue and quiet them, that their impe- rious clamor must cease. They will, as it were, be slain, either suddenly or gradually, so that the sensibility will become, in a great measure, dead to those objects that so often and so easily excited it. It is a law of the sensibility — of all the desires and passions, that their indulgence de- velops and strengthens them, and their denial suppresses them. Be- nevolence consists in a refusal to gratify the sensibility, and in obeying the reason. Therefore it must be true, that this denial of the propensi- ties will greatly suppress them ; while the indulgence of the intellect and of the conscience will greatly develop them. Thus selfishness tends to stultify, while benevolence tends greatly to strengthen the intellect. 19. Condescension is another attribute of love. This attribute consists in a tendency to descend to the poor, the igno- rant, or the vile, for the purpose of securing their good. It is a ten- dency to seek the good of those whom Providence has placed in any re- ATTEIBUTES OP LOVE. 175 spect below us, by stooping, descending, coming down to them for this purpose. It is a peculiar form of self-denial. God the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit, manifest infinite condescension in efforts to secure the well-being of sinners, even the most vile and degraded. This attri- bute is called by Christ lowliness of heart. God is said to humble him- self, that is, to condescend, when he beholds the things that are done in heaven. This is true, for every creature is, and must forever be, infi- uitely below Him in every respect. But how much greater must that condescension be, that comes down to earth, and even to the lowest and most degraded of earth's inhabitants, for purposes of benevolence ! This is a lovely modification of benevolence. It seems to be entirely above the gross conceptions of infidelity. Condescension seems to be regarded by most people, and especially by infidels, as rather a weakness than a virtue. Sceptics clothe their imaginary God with attributes in many re- spects the opposite of true virtue. They think it entirely beneath the dignity of God to come down even to notice, and much more to interfere with, the concerns of men. But hear the word of the Lord: "Thus saith the High and Lofty One, who inhabiteth eternity, whose name is Holy : I dwell in the high and holy place ; with him also that is of a contrite and humble spirit, to revive the spirit of the humble, and toi revive the heart of the contrite ones." And again, "Thus saith the Lord, the heaven is my throne and the earth is my footstool, where is the house that ye build unto me ? and where is the place of my rest ? For all those things hath my hand made, and all those things have been, saith the Lord. But to this man will I look, even to him that is poor and of a contrite spirit, and that trembleth at my word." Thas the Bible represents God as clothed with condescension as with a cloak. This is manifestly an attribute both of benevolence and of true great- aess. The natural perfections of God appear all the more wonderful, when we consider, that he can and does know and contemplate and con- trol, not only the highest, but the lowest of all his creatures ; that he is just as able to attend to every want and every creature, as if this were the sole object of attention with him. So his moral attributes appear all the more lovely and engaging when we consider that his " tender mer- cies are over all his works," "that not a sparrow falleth to the ground without him ; '" that he condescends to number the very hairs of the heads of his servants, and that not one of them can fall without him, WTion we consider that no creature is too low, too flltJiy, or too degraded for him to condescend to, — this places his character in a most ravishing light. Benevolence is good-will to all beings. Of course one of its characteristics must be condescension to those who are below us. This in God is manifestly infinite. He is infinitely above all creatures. For bim to hold communion with them is infinite condescensiou. 176 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. This is an attribute essentially belonging to benevolence or love in all benevolent beings. With the lowest of moral beings it may have no other development, than in its relations to sentient existences below the rank of moral agents, for the reason, that there are no moral agents below them to whom they can stoop. God's condescension stoops to all ranks of sentient existences. This is also true with every benevolent mind, as to all inferiors. It seeks the good of being in general, and never thinks any being too low to have his interests attended to and cared for, according to their relative value. Benevolence cannot possi- bly retain its own essential nature, and yet be above any degree of con- descension that can effect the greatest good. Benevolence does not, can- not know anything of that loftiness of spirit that considers it too de- grading to stoop anywhere, or to any being whose interests need to be, and can be, promoted by such condescension. Benevolence has its end, and it cannot but seek this, and it does not, cannot think anything below it that is demanded to secure that end. the shame, the infinite folly and madness of pride, and every form of selfishness ! How infi- nitely unlike God it is 1 Christ could condescend to be born in a manger ; to be brought up in humble life ; to be poorer than the fox of the desert, or the fowls of heaven ; to associate with fishermen ; to mingle with and seek the good of all classes ; to be despised in life, and die between two thieves on the cross. His benevolence "endured the cross and despised the shame." He was "meek and lowly in heart." The Lord of heaven and earth is as much more lowly in heart than any of his creatures, as he is above them in his infinity. He can stoop to anything but to commit sin. He can stoop infinitely low. 20. Stability is another attribute of benevolence. This love is not a mere feeling or emotion, that effervesces for a moment, and then cools down and disappears. But it is choice, not a mere volition which accomplishes its object, and then rests. It is the choice of an end, a supreme end. It is an intelligent choice — the most intelligent choice that can be made. It is considerate choice — none so much so ; a delib- erate choice, a reasonable choice, which will always commend itself to the highest perceptions and intuitions of the intellect. It is intelligent and impartial, and universal consecration to an end, above all others the most important and captivating in its influence. Now, stability must be a characteristic of such a choice as this. By stability, it is not intended that the choice may not be changed. N"or that it never is changed ; but that when the attributes of the choice are considered, it appears as if stability, as opposed to instability, must be an attribute of this choice. It is a new birth, a new nature, a new creature, a new heart, a new life. These and such like are the representations of scripture. Are these representations of an evanescent state ? The beginning of benevolence ATTRIBUTES OP LOVE. 177 in the soul — this choice is represented as the death of sin, as a burial, a being planted, a crucifixion of the old man, and many such like things. Are these representations of what we so often see among professed Christians ? Nay, yerily. The nature of the change itself would seem to be a guarantee of its stability. We might reasonably suppose, that any other choice would be relinquished sooner than this ; that any other state of mind would fail sooner than benevolence. It is vain to reply to this, that facts prove the contrary to be true. I answer what facts ? Who can prove them to be facts ? Shall we appeal to the apparent facts in the instability of many professors of religion ; or shall we appeal to the very nature of the choice, and to the scriptures ? To these doubtless. So far as philosophy can go, we might defy the world to produce an instance of choice which has so many chances for stability. The representations of scripture are such as I have mentioned above. What then shall we conclude of those effervescing professors of religion, who are soon hot and soon cold ; whose religion is a spasm ; " whose goodness is as the morning cloud and the early dew, which goeth away ? " Why, we must conclude, that they never had the root of the matter in them. That they are not dead to sin and to the world, we see. That they are not new creatures, that they have not the spirit of Christ, that they do not keep his commandments, we see. What then shall we con- elude, but this, that they are stony-ground hearers ? 21. Holiness is another attribute of benevolence. This term is used in the Bible, as synonymous with moral purity. In a ceremonial sense it is applied to both persons and things ; to make holy and to sanctify are the same thing. To sanctify and to consecrate, or set apart to a sacred use, are identical. Many things were, in this sense, sanctified, or made holy, under the Jewish economy. The term holiness may, in a general sense, be applied to anything whatever which is set apart to a sacred use. It may be applied to the whole being of a moral agent, who is set apart to the service of God. As an attribute of benevolence, it denotes that quality which leads it to seek to promote the happiness of moral agents, by means of conform- ity to moral law. As a moral attribute of God, it is that peculiarity of his benevolence which secures it against all efforts to obtain its end by other means than those that are morally and perfectly pure. His benevolence aims to se- cure the happiness of the universe of moral agents, by means of moral law and moral government, and of conformity to his own subjective idea of right. In other words, holiness in God is that quality of his love that secures its universal conformity, in all its efforts and manifestations, to the Divine idea of right, as it lies in eternal development in the Infinite Keason. This idea is moral law. It is sometimes used to express the 12 178 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. moral quality, or character of his benevolence generally, or to express the moral character of the Godhead. It sometimes seems to designate an at- tribute, and sometimes a quality of his moral attributes. Holiness is, doubtless, a characteristic, or quality of each and all of his moral attrib- utes. They will harmonize in this, that no one of them can consent to do otherwise than conform to the law of moral purity, as deTeloped and revealed in the Divine Eeason. That holiness is an attribute of God is everywhere assumed, and fre- quently asserted in the Bible. If an attribute of God, it must be an at- tribute of love ; for God is love. This attribute is celebrated in heaven as one of those aspects of the divine character that give inefEable delight. Isaiah saw the seraphim standing around the throne of Jehovah, and crying one to another, " Holy I holy ! holy ! " John also had a vision of the worship of heaven, and says " They rest not day nor night, saying, Holy! holy! holy! Lord God Almighty." When Isaiah beheld the holiness of Jehovah, he cried out " Woe i^ me ! 1 am undone. I am a man of unclean lips, and I dwell in the midst of a people of unclean lips ; for mine eyes have seen the King, the Lord of hosts ! " God's holiness is infinite, and it is no wonder that a perception of it should thus affect the' prophet. Finite holiness must forever feel itself awed in the presence of infinite holiness^ Job says, " I have heard of thee by the hearing of the ear, but now mine eye seeth thee : wherefore I abhor myself, and repent in dust and ashes." There is no comparing finite with infinite. The time will never come when creatures can with open face contemplate the infinite holiness of Jehovah, without being like persons overcome with a harmony too intensely delightful to be calmly borne. Heaven seems not able to endure it without breaking forth into strains of inexpressible rapture. The expressions of Isaiah and Job do not necessarily imply that at the time they were in a sinful state, but their expressions no doubt related to whatever of sin they had at any time been guilty of. In the light of Jehovah's holiness they saw the comparative pollution of their character taken as a whole. This view will always, doubtless, much affect the saints. This must be ; and yet in another sense they may be, and are, as holy, in their measure as he is. They may be as perfectly conformed to what light or truth they have, as he is. This is doubtless what Christ intended when he said, "Be ye perfect, even as your Father which is in heaven is perfect." The meaning is, that they should live to the same end, and be as entirely consecrated to it as he is. This they must be, to be truly virtuous or holy in any degree. But when they are so, a full view of the holiness of God would confound and overwhelm them. If any one doubts this, he has not considered the matter in a proper light. He has not lifted up his thoughts, as he needs to do, to the contempla- ATTRIBUTES OP LOVE. 179 tion of infinite liolinesB. No creature, however benevolent, can witness the divine benevolence without being overwhelmed with a clear vision of it. This is no doubt true of every attribute of the divine love. How- ever perfect creature-virtue may be, it is finite, and, brought into the light of the attributes of infinite virtue, it will appear like the dimmest star in the presence of the sun, lost in the blaze of his glory. Let the most just man on earth or in heaven witness, and have a clear apprehen- sion of, the infinite justice of Jehovah, and it would no doubt fill him with unutterable awe. So, could the most merciful saint on earth, or in heaven, have a clear perception of the divine mercy in its fulness, it would swallow up all thought and imagination, and, no doubt, overwhelm him. And so also of every attribute of God. Oh ! when we speak of the attributes of Jehovah, we often do not know what we say. Should God unveil himself to us, our bodies would instantly perish. "No man," says he, " can see my face and live." When Moses prayed, " Show me thy glory," God condescendingly hid him in the cleft of a rock, and covering him with his hand, he passed by, and let Moses see only his back parts, informing him that he could not behold his face, that is, his unveiled glories, and live. Holiness, or moral harmony of character is, then, an essential attrib- ute of disinterested love. It must be so from the laws of our being, and from the very nature of benevolence. In man it manifests itself in great purity of conversation and deportment, in a great loathing of aU impurity of flesh and spirit. Let no man_^profess piety who has not this attribute developed. The love required by the law of God is pure love. It seeks to make its object happy only by making him holy. It manifests the greatest abhorrence of sin and all uncleanness. In creatures it pants, and doubtless ever wiU pant and struggle, toward infinite purity or holi- ness. It will never find a resting place in such a sense as to desire to ascend no higher. As it perceives more and more of the fulness and in- finity of God's holiness, it will no doubt pant and struggle to ascend the eternal heights where God sits in light too intense for the strongest vision of the highest cherub. Holiness of heart or of will, produces a desire or feeling of purity in the sensibility. The feelings become exceedingly alive to the beauty of holiness and to the hatefulness and deformity of all spiritual, and even physical impurity. This is called the love of holiness. The sensibility becomes ravished with the great loveliness of holiness, and unutterably disgusted with the opposite. The least impurity of conversation or of action exceedingly shocks one who is holy. Impure thoughts, if sug gested to the mind of a holy being, are instantly felt to be exceedingly offensive and painful. The soul heaves and struggles to cast them out as the most loathsome abominations. 180 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. LECTURE XVI. WHAT CONSTITUTES DISOBEDIENCE TO MORAL LAW? Ik discussing this question, I will, I. Show in what disoledience to moral law cannot consist. 1. It cannot consist in malevolence, or in the choice of evil or misery as an ultimate end. This will appear, if we consider, that the choice of an end implies the choice of it, not for no reason, but for a reason, and for its own intrinsic value, or because the mind prizes it on its own account. But moral agents are so constituted, that they cannot regard misery as intrinsically valuable. They cannot, therefore, choose it as an ultimate end, nor prize it on its own account. 2. Disobedience to moral law cannot consist in the constitution of soul or body. The law does not command us to have a certain constitu- tion, nor forbid us to have the constitution with which we came into being. 3. It cannot consist in any unavoidable state, either of the sensibility or of the intelligence ; for these, as we have seen, are involuntary, and are dependent upon the actings of the will. 4. It cannot consist in outward actions, independent of the design with which they are put forth ; for these, we have seen, are controlled by the actions of the will, and, therefore, can have no moral character in themselves. 5. It cannot consist in inaction ; for total inaction is to a moral agent impossible. Moral agents are necessarily active. That is, they cannot exist as moral agents without choice. They must, by a law of necessity, choose either in accordance with, or in opposition to, the law of God. They are free to choose in either direction, but they are not free to abstain from choice altogether. Choose they must. The posses- sion of free-will, and the perception of opposing objects of choice, either exciting desire, or developing the rational affirmation of obligation to choose, render choice one way or the other inevitable. The law directs how they ought to choose. If they do not choose thus, it must be because they choose otherwise, and not because they do not choose at all. 6. It cannot consist in the choice of moral evil, or sin, as an ultimate end. Sin is but an element or attribute of choice or intention, or it is intention itself. If it be intention itself, then to make sin an end of intention, would be to make intention or choice terminate on itself, and the sinner must choose his own choice, or intend his own intention as an end : this is absurd. 7. Disobedience to moral law cannot consist in self-love. Self-love is DISOBEDIENCE TO THE LAW. 181 simply the constitntional desire of happiness. It is altogether an in- voluntary state. It has, as a desire, no moral character, any more than has the desire of food. It is no more sinful to desire happiness, and properly to seek it, than it is wrong to desire food, and properly to seek that. II. What disobedience to moral law must consist in. Disobedience to God's law must consist in the choice of self-gratifica- tion as an end. In other words, it must consist essentially in commit- ting the will, and through the will committing the whole being, to the indulgence of self-love, as the supremo and ultimate end of life. This is selfishness. In other words, it is seeking to gratify the desire of per- sonal good, in a manner prohibited by the law of God. It consists in choosing self-gratification as an end, or for its own sake, instead of choosing, in accordance with the law of the reason and of God, the highest well-being of God and of the universe as an ultimate end. In other words still, sin or disobedience to the moral law, consists m the consecration of the heart and life to the gratification of the consti- tutional and artificial desires, rather than in obedience to the law of the intelligence. Or, once more, sin consists in being governed by impulses of the sensibility, instead of being governed by the law of God, as it lies revealed in the reason. That this is sin, and the whole of sin viewed in its germinating prin- ciples, will appear, if we consider : — 1. That this state of mind, or this choice, is the " carnal mind," or the minding of the flesh, which the apostle affirms to be " enmity against God." It is the universal representation of scripture, that sin consists in the spirit of self-seeking. This spirit of self-seeking is always in the Bible represented as the contrast or opposite of disinterested benevolence, or the love which the law requires. " Bphraim bringeth forth fruit to himself," is the sum of God's charges against sinners. 2. When we come to the consideration of the attributes of selfishness, it will be seen that every form of sin, not only may, but must resolve itself into selfishness, just as we have seen that every form of virtue does and must resolve itself into love or benevolence. 3. From the laws of its constitution, the mind is shut up to the necessity of choosing that, as an ultimate end, which is regarded by the mind as intrinsically good or valuable in itself. This is the very idea of choosing an end, to wit, something chosen for its own sake, or for what \t is in and of itself, or, because it is regarded by the mind as intrinsi- cally valuable to self, or to being in general, or to both. 4. Moral agents are, therefore, shut up to the necessity of willing the good of being, either partially or impartially, either good to self, or good 182 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. to being in general. Nothing else can possibly be chosen as an end or for its own sake. Willing the good of being impartially, we have seen, is virtue. To will it partially is to will it, not for its own sake, except upon condition of its relation to self. That is, it is to will good to self. In other words, it is to will the gratification of self as an end, in opposi- tion to willing the good of universal being as an end, and every good, or the good of every being, according to its intrinsic value. 5. But may not one will the good of a part of being as an end, or for the sake of the intrinsic value of their good ? This would not be benev- olence ; for that, as we have seen, must consist in willing good for its own sake, and implies the willing of every good, and of the highest good of universal being. It would not be selfishness, as it would not be willing good to, or the gratification of, self. It would be sin, for it would be the partial love or choice of good. It would be loving some of my neigh- bors, but not all of them. It would, therefore, be sin, but not selfish- ness. If this can be, then there is such a thing possible, whether actual or not, as sin that does not consist in selfishness. But let us examine whether this supposition would not resolve itself into selfishness. To say that I choose good for its own sake, or because it is valuable to being, that is, in obedience to the law of my reason, and of God, im- plies that I choose all possible good, and every good according to its rel- ative value; If, then, a being chooses his own good, or the good of any being as an ultimate end, in obedience to the law of reason, it must be that he chooses, for the same reason, the highest possible good of all sen- tient being. The partial choice of good implies the choice of it, not merely for its own sake, but upon condition of its relations to self, or to certain par- ticular persons. Its relations conditionate the choice. When its rela- tions to self conditionate the choice, so that it is chosen, not for its in- trinsic value, irrespective of its relations, but for its relations to self, this is selfishness. It is the partial choice of good. If I choose the good of others besides myself, and choose good because of its relations to them, it must be either — (1.) Because I love their persons with the love of fondness, and will their good for that reason, that is, to gratify my afEection for them, which is selfishness ; or — (a.) Because of their relations to me, so that good to them is in soao way a good to me, which also is selfishness ; or — (3.) Upon condition that they are wortny, wnich is benevolence ; for if I will good to a being upon conauion that he is worthy, I must value the good for its own sake, and will it particularly to him, because he deserves it. This is benevolence, and not the partial choice of good, because it is obeying the law of my reason. ATTRIBUTES OP SELFISHNESS. 183 Again : If I will the good of any number of beings, I must do it in obedience to the law either of my intelligence and of God, or of my sen- sibility. But, if I will in obedience to the law of my intelligence, it must be the choice of the highest good of universal being. But if I will in obedience to the law or impulse of my sensibility, it must be to gratify my feelings or desires. This is selfishness. Again : As the will must either follow the law of the reason and of God, or the impulses of the sensibility, it follows that moral agents are shut up to the necessity of being selfish or benevolent, and that there is no third way, because there is no third medium, through which any object of choice can be presented. The mind can absolutely know nothing as an object of choice, that is not recommended by one of these faculties. Selfishness, then, and benevolence, are the only two alter- natives. Let it be remembered, then, that sin is a unit, and always and neces- sarily consists in selfish ultimate intention, and in nothing else. This intention is sin ; and thus we see that every phase of sin resolves itseli into selfishness. This will appear more and more, as we proceed to un fold the subject of moral depravity. LECTURE XVII. ATTRIBUTES OF SELFISHNESS. FoKMEELY we Considered the attributes of benevolence, and also what states of the sensibility and of the intellect, and also what outward actions, were implied in it, as necessarily resulting from it. We are now to take the same course with selfishness : and — 1. Voluntariness is an attribute of selfishness. Selfishness has often been confounded with mere desire. But these things are by no means identical. Desire is constitutional. It is a phenomenon of the sensibility. It is a purely involuntary state of mind, and can in itself produce no action, nor can it, in itself, have moral character. Selfishness is a phenomenon of the will, and consists in committing the will to the gratification of the desires. The desire itself is not selfishness, but submitting the will to be governed by the desire, is selfishness. It should be understood, that no kind of mere desires, and no strength of mere desire, constitutes selfishness. Selfishness commences when the will yields to the desire, and seeks to obey it, in opposition to the law of the intelligence. It matters not what kind ot 18* SYSTEMATIC THEOLOaY. desire it is ; if it is the desire that governs the will, this is selfishness. It must be the will in a state of committal to the gratification of the desire. 2. Liberty is another attribute of selfishness. That is, the choice of self-gratification is not necessitated by desire. But the will is always free to choose in opposition to desire. This every moral agent is as conscious of as of his own existence. The desire is not free, but the choice to gratify it is and must be free. There is a sense, as I shall have occasion to show, in which slavery is an attribute of selfish- ness, but not in the sense that the will chooses, by a law of necessity, to gratify desire. Liberty, in the sense of ability to make an opposite choice, must ever remain an attribute of selfishness, whUe selfishness continues to be a sin, or while it continues to sustain any relation to moral law. 3. Intelligence is another attribute of selfishness. By this it is not intended that intelligence is an attribute or phe- nomenon of will, nor that the choice of self-gratification is in accordance with the demands of the intellect. But it is intended that the choice is made with the knowledge of the moral character that will be involved in it. The mind knows its obligation to make an opposite choice. It is not a mistake. It is not a choice made in ignorance of moral obligation to choose the highest good of being, as an end, in opposition to self- gratification. It is an intelligent choice in the sense, that it is a known resistance of the demands of the intellect. It is a known rejection of its claims. It is a known setting up of self -gratification, and preferring it to all higher interests. 4. Unreasonableness is another attribute of selfishness. By this it is intended, that the selfish choice is in direct opposition to the demands of the reason. The reason was given to rule, that is, to aflBrm obligation, and thus announce the law of God. It affirms law and moral obligation. Obedience to moral law, as it is revealed in the reason, is vir- tue. Obedience to the sensibility in opposition to the reason, is gin. Selfishness consists in this. It is a dethroning of reason from the seat of government, and an enthroning of blind desire in opposition to it. Selfishness is always and necessarily unreasonable. It is a denial of that divine attribute that allies man to God, makes him capable of vir- tue, and is a sinking him to the level of a brute. It is a denial of his manhood, of his rational nature. It is a contempt of the voice of God within him, and a deliberate trampling down the sovereignty of his own intellect. Shame on selfishness I It dethrones human reason, and would dethrone the divine, and place mere blind lust upon the throne of the universe. The very definition of selfishness implies that unreasonableness is one of its attributes, Selfishness consists in the will's yielding itself to the ATTRIBUTES OP SELFISHNESS. 185 impulses of the sensibility, in opposition to the demands of the intelligence. Therefore, every act or choice of the will is necessarily altogether unreason- able. Sinners, while they continue sucli, never say nor do one thing that is in accordance with right reason. Hence the Bible says, that " madness is in their heart while they live." They have made an unreasonable choice of an end, and all their choices of means to secure their end are only a carrying out of their ultimate choice. They are, every one of them, put forth to secure an end contrary to reason. Therefore, no sinner, who has never been converted, has, even in a single instance, chosen otherwise than in direct opposition to reason. They are not merely sometimes unreasonable, but uniformly, and, while they remain selfish, necessarily so. The very first time that a sinner acts or wills reasonably, is when he turns to God, or repents and becomes a Christian. This is the first instance in which he practically acknowledges that he has reason. All previous to this, every one of the actions of his wiU and of his life, is a practical denial of his manhood, of his rational nature, of his obligation to God or his neighbor. "We sometimes hear impenitent sinners spoken of as being unreasonable, and in such a manner as to imply that all sinners are not so. But this only favors the delusion of sinners by leaving them to suppose that they are not all of them, at all times, altogether unreasonable. But the fact is, that there is not, and there never can be, in earth or hell, one impenitent sinner who, in any instance, acts otherwise than in direct and palpable opposi- tion to his reason. It had, therefore, been infinitely better for sinners if they had never been endowed with reason. They do not merely act without consulting their reason, but in stout and determined opposition to it. Again : They act as directly in opposition to it as they possibly can. They not only oppose it, but they oppose it as much, and in as aggravated a manner, as possible. What can be more directly and aggravatedly opposed to reason than the choice which the sinner makes of an end ? Reason was given him to direct him in regard to the choice of the great end of life. It gives him the idea of the eternal and the infinite. It spreads out before him the interests of God and of the universe as of absolutely infinite value. It affirms their value, and the infinite obligation of the sinner to consecrate himself to these interests ; and it promises him endless rewards if he will do so. On the contrary it lays before him the consequences of refusal. It thunders in his eat the terrible sanctions of the law. It points him to the coming doom that awaits his refusal to comply with its demands. But behold, in the face of all this, the sinner, unhesitatingly, in the face of these affirma- tions, demands, and threatenings, turns away and consecrates himself to the gratification of his desires with the certainty that he could not do 186 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. greater despite to his own nature than in this most mad, most preposter- ous, most blasphemous choice. Why do not sinners consider that it is impossible for them to offer a greater insult to God, who gave them reason, or more truly and deeply to shame and degrade themselves, than they do in their beastly selfishness ? Total, universal, and shameless unreasonableness, is the universal characteristic of every selfish mind. 5. Interestedness is another attribute of selfishness. By interestedness is meant self -interestedness. It is not the disinter- ested choice of good, that is, it is not the choice of the good of being in general as an end, but it is the choice of self- good, of good to self. Its relation to self is the condition of the choice of this good. But for its being the good of self, it would not be chosen. The fundamental rea- son, or that which should induce choice, to wit, the intrinsic value of good, is rejected as insufficient ; and the secondary reason, namely, its relation to self, is the condition of determining the will in this direction. This is really making self-good the supreme end. In other words, it i& making self-gratification the end. Nothing is practically regarded as worthy of choice, except as it sustains to self the relation of a means of self -gratification. This attribute of selfishness secures a corresponding state of the sen- sibility. The sensibility, under this indulgence, attains to a monstrous development, either generally, or in some particular directions. Selfish- ness is the committal of the will to the indulgence of the propensities. But from this it by no means follows, that all of the propensities will be indiscriminately indulged, and thereby greatly developed. Sometimes one propensity, and sometimes another, has the greatest natural strength, and thereby gains the ascendancy in the control of the will. Sometimes circumstances tend more strongly to the development of one appetite or passion than another. Whatever propensity is most indulged, will gain the greatest development. The propenisities cannot all be indulged at once, for they are often opposed to each other. But they may all be in- dulged and developed in their turn. For example, the licentious pro- pensities, and various other propensities, cannot be indulged consistently with the simultaneous indulgence of the avaricious propensities, the de- sire of reputation and of ultimate happiness. Each of these, and even all the propensities, may come in for a share, and in some instances may gain so equal a share of indulgence, as upon the whole to be about equally developed. But in general, either from constitutional temperament, or from circumstances, some one or more of the propensities will gain so uniform a control of the will, as to occasion its monstrous development. It may be the love of reputation ; and then there will be at least a pub- lic decent exterior, more or less strict, according to the state of morals in the society in which the individual dwells. If it be amativeness that ATTRIBUTES OF SELFISHNESS. 187 gains the ascendancy over the other propensities, licentiousness will be the result. If it be alimentiveness, then gluttony and Epicurism will be the result. The result of selfishness must be, to develop in general, or in particular, the propensities of the sensibility, and to beget a corre- sponding exterior. If avarice take the control of the will, we have the haggard and ragged miser. All the other propensities wither under the reign of this detestable one. Where the love of knowledge prevails, we have the scholar, the philosopher, the man of learning. This is one of the most decent and respectable forms of selfishness, but is nevertheless as absolutely selfishness as any other form. When compassion, as a feel- ing, prevails, we have, as a result, the philanthropist, and often the re- former ; not the reformer in a virtuous sense, but the selfish reformer. Where love of kindred prevails, we often have the kind husband, the afEectionate father, mother, brother, sister, and so on. These are the amiable sinners, especially among their own kindred. When the love of country prevails, we have the patriot, the statesman, and the soldier. The picture might be drawn at full length, but with these traits I must leave you to fill up the outline. I would only add, that several of these forms of selfishness so nearly resemble certain forms of virtue, as often to be confounded with them, and mistaken for them. Indeed, so far aa the outward life is concerned, they are right, in the letter, but as they do not proceed from disinterestedly benevolent intention, they are only specious forms of selfishness. 6. Partiality is another attribute of selfishness. It consists in giv- ing the preference to certain interests, on account of their being either directly the interests of self, or so connected with self-interest as to be ' preferred on that account. It matters not, whether the interest to which the preference is given be of greater or of less value, if so be it is pre- ferred, not for the reason of its greater value, but because of its relation to self. In some instances the practical' preference may justly bo given to a less interest, on account of its sustaining such a relation to us that we can secure it, when the greater interest could not be secured by us. If the reason of the preference, in such case, be, not that it is self-interest, but an interest that can be secured while the greater cannot, the prefer- ence is a just one, and not partiality. My family, for example, sustain Buch relations to me, that I can more readily and surely secure their in- terests, than I can those of my neighbor, or of a stranger. For this rea- son I am under obligation to give the practical preference to the interests of my own family, not because they are my own, nor because their inter- ests sustain such a relation to my own, but because I can more readily secure their interests than those of any other family. The question in such a case turns upon the amount I am able to se cure, and not on the intrinsic value merely. It is a general truth, that 188 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. we can secure more readily and certainly the interests of those to whom ■we sustain certain relations ; and therefore, God and reason point out these interests as particular objects of our attention and efEort. This is not partiality but impartiality. It is treating interests as they should be treated. But selfishness is always partial. If it gires any interest whatever, the preference, it is because of its relation to self. It always, and, con- tinuing to be selfishness, necessarily, lays the greatest stress upon, and gives the preference to, those interests the promotion of which will gratify self. Here care should be taken to avoid delusion. Oftentimes selfishness appears to be very disinterested and very impartial. For example : here is a man whose compassion, as a mere feeling or state of the sensibility, is greatly developed. He meets a beggar, an object that strongly excites his ruling passion. He empties his pockets, and even takes off his coat and gives it to him, and in his paroxysm he will divide his all with him, or even give him all, Now this would generally pass for most undoubted virtue, as a rare and impressive instance of moral goodness. But there is no virtue, no benevolence in it. It is a mere yielding of the wiU to the control of feeling, and has nothing in it of the nature of virtue. In- numerable examples of this might be adduced, as illustrations of thi§ truth. It is only an instance and an illustration of selfishness. It is the will seeking to gratify the feeling of compassion, which for the time is the strongest desire. "We constitutionally desire not only our own happiness, but also that of men in general, when their happiness in no way conflicts with our own. Hence selfish men will often manifest a deep interest in the wel- fare of those, whose welfare will not interfere with their own. Now, should the will be yielded up to the gratification of this desire, this would often be regarded as virtue. For example : a few years since much interest and feeling were excited in this country by the cause and suffer- ings of the Greeks, in their struggle for liberty ; and since in the cause of the Poles. A spirit of enthusiasm appeared, and many were ready to give and do almost anything for the cause of liberty. They gave up their will to the gratification of this excited state of feeling. This, they may have supposed, was virtue ; but it was not, nor was there a semblance of virtue about it, when it is once understood, that virtue consists in yielding the will to the law of the intelligence, and not to the impulse of excited feelings. Some writers have fallen into the strange mistake of making virtue to consist in seeking the gratification of certain desires, because, as they say, these desires are virtuous. They make some of the desires selfish, apd some benevolept. To yield tj^e wiU to the cojitrol of the selfish pro- ATTRIBUTES OF SELFISHNESS. 189 pensities is sin ; to yield to the control of the benevolent desires, such ui the desire of my neighbor's happiness and of the public happiness, is vir- tue, because these are good desires, while the selfish desires are evil. Now this is, and has been, a very common view of virtue and vice. But it is fundamentally erroneous. None of the constitutional desires are good or evil in themselves ; they are alike involuntary, and all alike ter- minate on their correlated objects. To yield the will to the control of any one of them, no matter which, is sin ; it is following a blind feeling, desire, or impulse of the sensibility, instead of yielding to th^ demands of the intelligence, as the law affirming power. To will the good of my neighbor, or of my country, and of God, because of the intrinsic value of those interests, that is to will them as an end, and in obedience to the law of the reason, is virtue ; but to will them to gratify a constitutional but blind desire, is selfishness and sin. The desires terminate on their respective objects ; but the will, in this case, seeks the objects, not for their own sake, but because they are desired, that is, to gratify the de- sires. This is choosing them, not as an end, but as a means of self-grati- fication. This is making self-gratification the end after all. This must be a universal truth, when a thing is chosen merely in obedience to de- sire. The benevolence of these writers is sheer selfishness, and their vir- tue is vice. The choice of any thing whatever, because it is desired, irrespective of the demands of the reason, is selfishness and sin. It matters not what it is. The very statement, that I choose a thing because I desire it, is only another form of saying, that I choose it for my own sake, or for the sake of appeasing the desire, and not on account of its own intrinsic value. All such choice is always and necessarily partial. It is giving one interest the preference over another, not because of its perceived in- trinsic and superior value, but because it is an object of desire. If I yield to mere desire in any case, it must be to gratify the desire. This is, and in the case supposed must be, the end for which the choice is made. To deny this is to deny that the will seeks the object because it is desired. Partiality consists in giving one thing the preference of an- other for no good reason. That is, not because the intelligence demands this preference, but because the sensibility demands it. Partiality is therefore always and necessarily an attribute of selfishness. 7. Efficiency is another attribute of selfishness. Desire never pro- duces action until it influences the will. It has no eflBciency or causality in itself. It cannot, without the concurrence of the will, command the attention of the intellect, or move a muscle of the body. The whole causality of the mind resides in the will. In it resides the power of a/5- complishment. Again : the whole efficiency of the mind, as it respects accomplish- 190 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. ment, resides in the choice of an end, or in the ultimate intention. All action of the will, or all willing, must consist in choosing either an end, or the means of accomplishing an end. If there is choice, something is chosen. That something is chosen for some reason. To deny this is a denial that any thing is chosen. The xiltimate reason for the choice and the thing chosen, are identical. This we have repeatedly seen. Again : we have seen that the means cannot be chosen until the end IS chosen. The choice of the end is distinct from the volitions or en- deavors of the mind to secure the end. But although the choice of an end is not identical with the subordinate choices and volitions to secure the end, yet it necessitates them. The choice once made, secures or necessitates the executive volitions to secure the end. By this it is not intended that the mind is not free to relinquish its end, and of course to relinquish the use of the means to accomplish it ; but only that, while the choice or intention remains, the choice of the end by the will is effi- cient in producing volitions to realize the end. This is true both of be- nevolence and selfishness. They are both choices of an end, and are necessarily efficient in producing the use of the means to realize this end. They are choices of opposite ends, and, of course, will produce their re- spective results. The Bible represents sinners as having eyes full of adultery, and that cannot cease from sin ; that while the will is committed to the indul- gence of the propensities, they cannot cease from the indulgence. There is no way, therefore, for the sinner to escape from the commission of sin, but to cease to be selfish. While selfishness continues, you may change the form of outward manifestation, you may deny one appetite or desire for the sake of indulging another ; but it is and must be sin still. The desire to escape hell, and to obtain heaven may become the strongest, in which case, selfishness will take on a most sanctimonious type. But if the will is following desire, it is selfishness still ; and all your religious duties, as you call them, are only selfishness robed in the stolen habili- ments of loving obedience to God. Be it remembered, then, that selfishness is, and must be, efficient in producing its effects. It is cause ; the effect must follow. The whole life and activity of sinners is founded in it. It constitutes their life, or rather their spiritual death. They are dead in trespasses and in sins. It is in vain for them to dream of doing anything good, until they relin- quish their selfishness. While this continues, they cannot act at all, except as they use the means to accomplish a selfish end. It is impossi- ble, while the will remains committed to a selfish, end, or to the promo- tion of self-interest or self-gratification, that it should use the means to promote a benevolent end. The first thing is to change the end, and then the sinner can cease from outward sin. Indeed, if the end be ATTRIBUTES OF SELFISHNESS. 191 changed, many of the same acts which were before sinful will become holy. While the selfish end continues, whatever a sinner does, is selfish. Whether he eats, or drinks, or labors, or preaches, or, in short, whatever he does, is to promote some form of self-interest. The end being wrong, all is, and must be, wrong. This is the philosophy of Christ. " Either make the tree good, and his fruit good ; or else make the tree corrupt, and his fruit corrupt : for the tree is known by his fruit. A good man out of the good treasure of the heart bringeth forth good things : and an evil man out of the evil treasure bringeth forth evil things." Matt, xii, 33, 35. " Doth a fountain send forth at the same place sweet water and bitter ? Can the fig-tree, my brethren, bear olive berries ? either a vine figs ? So can no fountain both yield salt water and fresh." James iii. 11, 13. " For a good tree bringeth not forth corrupt fruit ; nether doth a corrupt tree bring forth good fruit. For every tree is known by his own fruit : for of thorns men do not gather figs, nor of a bramble bush gather they grapes. A good man out of the good treasure of his heart, bringeth forth that which is good ; and an evil man out of the evil treasure of his heart, bringeth forth that which is evil ; for out of the abundance of the heart his mouth speaketh." Luke vi. 43-45. 8. Opposition to benevolence or to virtue, or to holiness and true religion, is one of the attributes of selfishness. Selfishness is not, in its relations to benevolence, a mere negation. It cannot be. It is the choice of self-gratification as the supreme and ultimate end of life. While the will is committed to this end, and benevolence, or a mind committed to an opposite end, is contemplated, the will cannot remain in a state of indifference to benevolence. It must either yield its preference of self-indulgence, or resist the benevolence which the intellect perceives. The will cannot remain in the exercise of this selfish choice, without as it were bracing and girding itself against that virtue, which it does not imitate. If it does not imitate it, it must be because it refuses to do so. The intellect does, and must, strongly urge the will to imitate benevolence, and to seek the same end. The ■yill must yield or resist, and the resistance must be more or less resolute and determined, as the demands of the intellect are more or less emphatic. This resistance to benevolence or to the demands of the intellect in view of it, is what the Bible calls, hardening the heart. It is obstinacy of will, under the hght and the presence of true religion, and the admitted claims of benevolence. This opposition to benevolence or true religion, must be developed in specific action, whenever the mind apprehends true religion, or selfishness must be abandoned. Not only must this opposition be developed, or self- ishness abandoned, under such circumstances, but it must be increased 192 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. H8 true religion displays more and more of its loveliness. As the light from the radiant sun of benevolence is poured more and more upon the darkness of selfishness, the opposition of this principle of action must of necessity manifest itself in the same proportion, or selfishness must be abandoned. Thus selfishness remaining under light, must manifest more and more opposition, just in proportion as light increases, and the soul has less the color of an apology for its opposition. This peculiarity of selfishness has always been manifested just in pro- portion as it has been brought into the light of true religion. This accounts for all the opposition that has been made to true religion since the world began. It also proves that where there are impenitent sinners, and they retain their impenitence, and manifest no hostility to the reli- gion which they witness, that there is something defective in the pro- fessed piety which they behold ; or at least they do not contemplate all the attributes of true piety. It also proves, that persecution will always exist where much true religion is manifested to those who hold fast their selfishness. It is indeed true, that selfishness and benevolence are just as much opposed to each other, and just as much and as necessarily at war with each other, as God and Satan, as heaven and hell. There can never be a truce between them ; they are essential and eternal opposites. They are not merely opposites, but they are opposite eflBcient causes. They are essential activities. They are the two, and the only two, great an- tagonistic principles in the universe of mind. Each is heaving and energizing like an earthquake to realize its end. A war of mutual and uncompromising extermination necessarily exists between them. Neither can be in the presence of the other, without repulsion and opposition. Each puts forth all its energy to subdue and overcome the other ; and already selfishness has shed an ocean of the blood of saints, as well as the precious blood of the Prince of life. There is not a more gross and inju- rious mistake, than to suppose that selfishness ever, under any circum- stances, becomes reconciled to benevolence. The supposition is absurd and contradictory ; since for selfishness to become reconciled to benevo- lence, were the same thing as for selfishness to become benevolence. Selfishness may change the mode of attack or of its opposition, but ita real opposition it can never change, while it retains its own nature and continues to be selfishness. This opposition of the heart to benevolence often begets deep opposi- tion of feeling. The opposition of the will engages the intellect in fab- ricating excuses, and cavils, and lies, and refuges, and often greatly per- verts the thoughts, and excites the most bitter feelings imaginable toward God and toward the saints. Selfishness will strive to justify its opposition, and to shield itself against the reproaches of conscience, and ATTRIBUTES OF SELFISHNESS. 193 will resort to every possible expedient to cover up its real hostility to holiness. It will pretend that it is not holiness, hut sin that it opposes. But the fact is, it is not sin but holiness to which it stands forever op- posed. The opposition of feeling is only developed when the heart is brought into a strong light, and makes deep and strong resistance. In such cases, the sensibility sometimes boils over with feelings of bitter op- position to God, and Christ, and all good. The question is often asked. May not this opposition exist in the sen- sibility, and those feelings of hostility to God exist, when the heart is in a truly benevolent state ? To this inquiry, I would reply : If it can, it must be produced by infernal or some other influence that misrepresents God, and places his character before the mind in a false light. Blasphe- mous thoughts may be suggested, and, as it were, injected into the mind. These thoughts may have their natural effect in the sensibility, and feelings of bitterness and hostility may exist without the consent of the will. The will may all the while be endeavoring to repel these sugges- tions, and divert the attention from such thoughts, yet Satan may con- tinue to hurl his fiery darts, and the soul may be racked with torture under the poison of hell, which seems to be taking effect in the sensi- bility. The mind, at such times, seems to itself to be filled, so far as feeling is concerned, with all the bitterness of hell. And so it is, and yet it may be, that in all this there is no selfishness. If the will holds fast its integrity; if it holds out in the struggle, and where God is maligned and misrepresented by the infernal suggestions, it says with Job, " Although he slay me, yet will I trust in him," however sharp the conflict in such cases, we can look back and say, " We are more than conquerors through him that loved us." In such cases it is the selfish- ness of Satan, and not our own selfishness, that kindled up those fires of hell in our sensibility. " Blessed is the man that endureth temptation ; for when he is tried he shall receive the crown of life." 9. Criielty is another attribute of selfishness. This term is often used to designate a state of the sensibility. It then represents that state of feeling which has a barbarous or savage pleasure in the misery of others. Cruelty, as a phenomenon of the will or as an attribute of selfishness, consists, first, in a reckless disregard of the well-being of God and the universe, and secondly, in persevering in a course that must ruin the souls of the subjects of it, and, so far as they have influence, ruin the souls of others. What should we think of a man who was so intent on securing some petty gratification, that he would not give the alarm if a city were on fire, and the sleeping citizens in imminent danger of perish- ing in the flames ? Suppose that sooner than deny himself some mo- mentary gratification, he would jeopard many lives. Should we not call 13 194 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. this cruelty ? Now there are many forms of cruelty. Because sinners are not always brought into circumstances where they exercise certain forma of it, they flatter themselves that they are not cruel. But selfishness is always and necessarily cruel — cruel to the soul and highest interests of the subject of it ; cruel to the souls of others, in neglecting to care and act for their salvation ; cruel to God, in abusing him in ten thousand ways; cruel to the whole universe. If we should be shocked at the cruelty of him who should see his neighbor's house on fire, and the family asleep, and neglect to give them warning, because too self-indul- gent to rise from his bed, what shall we say of the cruelty of one, who shall see his neighbor's soul in peril of eternal death, and yet neglect to give him warning ? Sinners are apt to possess very good dispositions, as they express it. They suppose they are the reverse of being cruel. They possess tender feelings, are often very compassionate in their feelings toward those who are sick and in distress, and who are in circumstances of any affliction. They are ready to do many things for them. Such persons would be shocked, should they be called cruel. And many professors would take their part, and consider them abused. Whatever else, it would be said, is an attribute of their character, surely cruelty is not. Now, it is true that there are certain forms of cruelty with which such persons are not chargeable. But this is only because God has so moulded their consti- tution, that they are not delighted with the misery of their fellow men. However, there is no virtue in their not being gratified at the sight of suffering, nor in their painstaking to prevent it while they continue self- ish. They follow the impulses of their feelings, and if their tempera- ment were such that it would gratify them to inflict misery on others — if this were the strongest tendency of their sensibility, their selfishness would instantly take on that type. But though cruelty, in all its forms, is not common to all selfish persons, it is still true that some form of cruelty is practiced by every sinner. God says, " The tender mercies of the wicked are cruel." The fact that they live in sin, that they set an example of selfishness, that they do nothing for their own souls, nor for the souls of others ; these are really most atrocious forms of cruelty, and infinitely exceed all those comparatively petty forms that relate to the miseries of men in this life. 10. Injustice is another attribute of selfishness. Justice, as an attribute of benevolence, is that quality that disposes it to regard and treat every being and interest with exact equity. Injustice is the opposite of this. It is that quality of selfishness which disposes it to treat the persons and interests of others inequitably, and a disposition to give the preference to self-interest, regardless of the relative value of the interests. The nature of selfishness demonstrates, ATTRIBUTES OF SELPISHNKSS. 195 that injustice is always and necessarily one of its attributes, and one that is universally and constantly manifested. There is the utmost injustice in the end chosen. It is the practical preference of a petty self-interest over infinite interests. This is injus- tice as great as possible. This is universal injustice to God and man. It is the most palpable and most flagrant piece of injustice possible to every being in the universe. Not one kaown by him to exist who has not reason to bring against him the charge of most flagrant and shock- ing injustice. This injustice extends to every act and to every moment of life. He is never, in the least degree, just to any being in the uni- verse. Nay, he is perfectly unjust. He cares nothing for the rights of others as such ; and never, even in appearance, regards them except for selfish reasons. This, then, is, and can be, only the appearance of re- garding them, while in fact, no right of any being in the universe is, or can be, respected by a selfish mind, any further than in appearance. To deny this is to deny his selfishness. He performs no act whatever but for one reason, bhat is, to promote his own gratification. This is his end. For the realization of this end every effort is made, and every in- dividual act and volition put forth, Eemaining selfish, it is impos- sible that he should act at all, but with reference directly or indirectly to this end. But this end has been chosen, and must be pursued, if pursued at all, in the most palpable and outrageous violabion of the rights of God and of every creature in the universe. Justice de- mands that he should devote himself to the promotion of the highest good of God and the universe, that he should love God with all his heart, and, his neighbor as himself. Every sinner is openly, and universally, and as perfectly, unjust as possible, at every moment of his impenitence. It should, therefore, always be understood, that no sinner at any time is at all just to any being in the universe. All his paying of his debts, and all his apparent fairness and justice, are only a specious form of self- ishness. He has, and, if a sinner, it is impossible that he should not have, some selfish reason for all he does, is, says, or omits. His entire activity is selfishness, and while he remains impenitent, it is impossible for him to think, or act, or wiU, or do, or be, or say, anything more or less than he judges expedient to promote his own interests. He is not just. He cannot be just, nor begin in any instance, or in the least degree, to be truly just, either to God or man, until he begins life anew, gives God his heart, and consecrates his entire being to promotion of the good of uni- versal being. This, all this, justice demands. There is no beginning to be just, unless the sinner begins here. Begin and be just in the choice of the great end of life, and then you cannot but be just in the use of means. But be unjust in the choice of an end, and it is impossible for you, in any instance, to be otherwise than totally unjust in the use of 1§6 StSTfiMAtid TltfioLOQt. means. In this case your entire activity is, and can be, nothing cise thatt a tissue of the most abominable injustice. The only reason why every sinner does not openly and daily practice every species of outward commercial injustice is, that he is so circum- stanced that, upon the whole, he judges it not for his interest to prac- tice this injustice. This is the reason universally, and no thanks to any sinner for abstaining, in any instance, from any kind or degree of injus- tice in practice, for he is only restrained and kept from it by selfish consid- erations. That is, he is too selfish to do it. His selfishness, and not the love of God or man, prevents. He may be prevented by a constitutional or phrenological conscientiousness, or sense of justice. But this is only a feeling of the sensibility, and, if restrained only by this, he is just as absolutely selfish as if he had stolen a horse in obedience to acquisitive- ness. God so tempers the constitution as to restrain men, that is, that one form of selfishness shall prevail over and curb another. Ap- probativeness is, in most persons, so large, that a desire to be applauded by their fellow-men so modifies the developments of their selfishness, that it takes on a type of outward decency and appearance of justice. But this is no less selfishness than if it took on altogether a difEerent type. LECTURE XVIII. ATTRIBUTES OP SELFISHNESS. 11. Falsehood, or lying, is another attribute of selfishness. Falsehood may be objective or subjective. Objective falsehood is that which stands opposed to truth. Subjective falsehood is a heart conformed to error and to objective falsehood. Subjective falsehood is a state of mind, or an attribute of selfishness. It is the will in the attitude of resisting truth, and embracing error and lies. This is always and necessarily an attribute of selfishness. Selfishness consists in the choice of an end opposed to all truth, and cannot but proceed to the realization of that end, in conformity with error or falsehood instead of truth. If at any time it seize upon objective truth, as it often does, it is with a false intention. It is with an intention At war with the truth, the nature, and the relations of things. If any sinner, at any time, and under any circumstances, tell the truth, it is for a selfish reason ; it is to compass a false end. He has a lie in his heart, and a lie in his right hand. He stands upon falsehood. He lives for it, and if he does not uniformly and openly falsify the truth, it ia ATTRIBUTES OF SELFISHNESS. 197 because objective truth is consistent with subjective falsehood. His heart is false, as false as it can be. It has embraced and sold itself to the greatest lie in the universe. The selfish man has practically pro- claimed that his good is the supreme good ; nay, that there is no other good but his own ; that there are no other rights bat his own, that all are bound to serve him, and that all interests are to yield to his. Now all this, as I said, is the greatest falsehood that ever was or can be. Yet this is the solemn practical declaration of every sinner. His choice affirms that God has no rights, that he ought not to be loved and obeyed, that he has no right to govern the universe, but that God and all beings ought to obey and serve the sinner. Can there be a greater, a more shameless falsehood than all this ? And shall such an one pretend to regard the truth ? Nay, verily. The very pretence is only an in- stance and an illustration of the truth, that falsehood is an essential element of his character. If every sinner on earth does not openly and at all times falsify the truth, it is not because of the truthfulness of his heart, but for some purely selfish reason. This must be. His heart is utterly false. It is impossible that, remaining a sinner, he should have any true regard to the truth. He is a liar in his heart ; this is an essential and an eternal attribute of his character. It is true that his intellect condemns false- hood and justifies truth, and that oftentimes through the intellect, a deep impression is or may be made on his sensibility, in favor of the truth ; but if the heart is unchanged, it holds on to lies, and perseveres in the practical proclamation of the greatest lies in the universe, to wit, that God ought not to be trusted ; that Christ is not worthy of confi- dence ; that one's own interest is the supreme good ; and that all inter- ests ought to be accounted of less value than one's own. 12. Pride is another attribute of selfishness. Pride is a disposition to exalt self above others, to get out of one's proper place in the scale of being, and to climb up over the heads of our equals or superiors. Pride is a species of injustice, on the one hand, and is nearly allied to ambition on the other. It is not a term of so ex- tensive an import as either injustice or ambition. It sustains to each of them a near relation, but is not identical with either. It is a kind of self-praise, self -worship, self- flattery, self-adulation, a spirit of self -con- sequence, of self-importance. It is a tendency to exalt, not merely one's own interest, but one's person above others, and above God, and above all other beings. A proud being supremely regards himself. He wor- ships and can worship no one but self. He does not, and remaining selfish, he cannot, practically admit that there is any one so good and worthy as himself. He aims at conferring supreme favor upon himself, and practically, admits no claim of any being in the universe to any good 198 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY, or interest, that will interfere with his own. He can stoop to give preference to the interest, the reputation, the authority of no one, no, not of God himself, except outwardly and in appearance. His inward language is, " Who is Jehovah, that I should bow down to him ? " It is impossible that a selfish soul should be humble. Sinners are repre- sented in the Bible as proud, as "flattering themselves in their own eyes." Pride is not a vice distinct from selfishness, but is only a modifica- tion of selfishness. Selfishness is the root, or stock, in which every form of sin inheres. This it is important to show. Selfishness has been scarcely regarded by many as a vice, much less as constituting the whole of vice ; consequently, when selfishness has been most apparent, it has been supposed and assumed that there might be along with it many forms of virtue. It is for this reason that I make thia attempt to show what are the essential elements of selfishness. It has been supposed that self- ishness might exist in any heart without implying every form of sin ; that a man might be selfish and yet not proud. In short, it has been overlooked, that, where selfishness is, there must be every form of sin ; that where there is one form of selfishness manifested, it is virtually a breach of every commandment of God, and implies, in fact, the real ex- istence of every possible form of sin and abomination in the heart. My object is fully to develop the great truth that where selfishness is, there must be, in a state either of development or of undevelopment, every form of sin that exists in earth or hell ; that all sin is a unit, and con- sists of some form of selfishness ; and that where this is, all sin virtually is and must be. The only reason that pride, as a form of selfishness, does not appear in all sinners, in the most disgusting forms, is only this, that their con- stitutional temperament, and providential circumstances, are such as to give a more prominent development to some other attribute of selfish- ness. It is important to remark, that where any one form of unqualified sin exists, there selfishness must exist, and there of course every form of sin must exist, at least in embryo, and waiting only for circumstances to develop it. When therefore, you see any form of sin, know assuredly that selfishness, the root, is there ; and expect nothing else, if selfishness continues, than to see developed, one after another, every form of sin as the occasion shall present itself. Selfishness is a volcano, sometimes smothered, but which must have vent. The providence of God cannot but present occasions upon which its lava-tides will burst forth and carry desolation before them. That all these forms of sin exist, has been known and admitted. But it does not appear to me, that the philosophy of sin has been duly con- sidered by many. It is important that we should get at the fundamen- ATTRIBUTES OP SELFISHNESS. 199 tal or generic form of sin, that form which includes and implies all others, or, more properly, which constitutes the whole of sin. Such is selfishness. " Let it be written with the point of a diamond and en- graved in the rock forever," that it may be known, that where selfishness is, there every precept of the law is violated, there is the whole of sin. Its guilt and ill desert must depend upon the light with which the self- ish mind is surrounded. But sin, the whole of sin, is there. Such ia the very nature of selfishness that it only needs the providential occa- sions, and to be left without restraint, and it will show itself to have em- bodied, in embryo, every form of iniquity. 13. Enmity against God is also an attribute of selfishness. Enmity is hatred. Hatred may exist either as a phenomenon of the sensibility, or as a state or attitude of the will. Of course I am now to speak of enmity of heart or will. It is selfishness viewed in its relations to God. That selfishness is enmity against God will appear^ — (1.) From the Bible. The apostle Paul expressly says that "the carnal mind (minding the flesh) is enmity against God." It is fully evi- dent that the apostle, by the carnal mind, means obeying the propensi- ties or gi'atifying the desires. But this, as I have defined it, is selfish- ness. (2.) Selfishness is directly opposed to the will of God as expressed in his law. That requires benevolence. Selfishness is its opposite, and therefore enmity against the Lawgiver. (3.) Selfishness is as hostile to God's government as it can be. It is directly opposed to every law, and principle, and measure of his govern- ment. (4.) Selfishness is opposition to God's existence. Opposition to a government, is opposition to the wiU of the governor. It is opposition to his existence in that capacity. It is, and must be, enmity against the existence of the ruler, as such. Selfishness must be enmity against the existence of God's government, and as he does and must sustain the re- lation of Sovereign Euler, selfishness must be enmity against his being. Selfishness will brook no restraint in respect to securing its end. There is nothing in the universe it will not sacrifice to self. This is true, or it is not selfishness. . If then God's happiness, or government, or being, come into competition with it, they must be sacrificed, were it possible for selfishness to effect it. But God is the uncompromising enemy of selfishness. It is the abominable thing his soul hateth. He is more in the way of selfishness than all other beings. The opposition of selfish- ness to him is, and must be, supreme and perfect. That selfishness is mortal enmity against God, is not left to conjec- tnre, nor to a mere deduction or inference, God once took to himself hnman nature, and brought Divine benevolence into conflict with human 200 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. selfishness. Men could not brook his presence upon earth, and they rested not until they had murdered him. Enmity against any body or thing besides God, can be overcome more easily than against him. All earthly enmities can be overcome by kind- ness, and change of circumstances ; but what kindness, what change of circumstances, can change the human heart, can overcome the selfishness or enmity to God that reigns there ? Selfishness offers all manner and every possible degree of resistance to God. It disregards God's com- mands. It contemns his authority. It spurns his mercy It outrages his feelings. It provokes his forbearance. Selfishness, in short, is the universal antagonist and adversary of God. It can no more be recon- ciled to his law, than it can cease to be selfish. 14. Intemperance is also a form or attribute of selfishness. Selfishness is self-indulgence not sanctioned by the reason. It con- sists in the committal of the will to the indulgence of the propensities. Of course some one, or more, of the propensities must have taken the control of the will. Generally, there is some ruling passion or propen- sity, the infiuence of which becomes overshadowing, and overrules the will for its own gratification. Sometimes it is acquisitiveness or avarice, the love of gain ; sometimes alimentiveness or Epicureanism ; sometimes it is amativeness or sexual love ; sometimes philoprogenitiveness or the love of our own children ; sometimes self-esteem or a feeling of confi- dence in self ; sometimes one and sometimes another of the great variety of the iiropensities, is so largely developed, as to be the ruling tyrant, that lords it over the will and over all the other propensities. It matters not which of the propensities, or whether their united infiuence gains the mastery of the will : whenever the will is subject to them, this is selfishness. It is the carnal mind. Intemperance consists in the undue or unlawful indulgence of any propensity. It is, therefore, an essential element or attribute of selfish- ness. All selfishness is intemperance : of course it is an unlawful indul- gence of the propensities. Intemperance has as many forms as there are constitutional and artificial appetites to gratify. A selfish mind cannot be temperate. If one or more of the propensities is restrained, it is only restrained for the sake of the undue and unlawful indulgence of another. Sometimes the tendencies are intellectual, and the bodily appetites are denied, for the sake of gratifying the love of study. But this is no less intemperance and selfishness, than the gratification of amativeness or alimentiveness. Selfishness is always, and necessarily, intemperate. It does not always or generally develop every form of intemperance in the outward life, but a spirit of self-indulgence must manifest itself in the intemperate gratification of some one or more of the propensities. Some develop self-indulgence most prominently in the form of intern- ATTRIBUTES OF SELFISHNESS. 201 perance in eating ; others in sleeping ; others in lounging and idleness ; others are gossippers ; others love exercise, and indulge that propensity ; others study and impair health, and induce derangement, or seriously ttnpair the nervous system. Indeed, there is no end to the forms which intemperance assumes, arising from the fact of the gi-eat number of propensities, natural and artificial, that in their turn seek and obtain indulgence. It should be always borne in mind, that any form of self-indulgence, properly so called, is equally an instance of selfishness and wholly incon- sistent with any degree of virtue in the heart. But it may be asked, are we to have no regard whatever to our tastes, appetites and propensities ? I answer, we are to have no such regard to them, as to make their grati- fication the end for which we live, even for a moment. But there is a kind of regard to them which is lawful, and therefore, a virtue. For example : I am on a journey for the service and glory of God. Two ways are before me. One affords nothing to regale the senses ; the other conducts me through variegated scenery, sublime mountain passes, deep ravines ; beside bubbling brooks, and meandering rivulets ; through beds of gayest flowers and woods of richest foliage ; through aromatic groves and forests vocal with feathered songsters. The two paths are equal in distance, and in all respects that have a bearing upon the business I have in hand. Now, reason dictates and demands, that I should take the path that is most agreeable and suggestive of useful thoughts. But this is not being governed by the propensities, but by the reason. It is its voice which I hear and to which I listen, when I take the sunny path. The delights of this path are a real good. As such they are not to be despised or neglected. But if taking this path would embarrass and hinder the end of my journey, I am not to sacrifice the greater public good for a less one of my own. I must not be guided by my feelings, but by my reason and honest judgment in this and in every case of duty. God has not given us propensities to be our masters and to rule us, but to be our servants and to minister to our enjoyment, when we obey the biddings of reason and of God. They are given to render duty pleasant, and as a reward of virtue ; to make the ways of wisdom pleasurable. The propensities are not, therefore, to be despised, nor is their annihilation to be desired. Nor is it true that their gratifi- cation is always selfish, but when their gratification is sanctioned and demanded by the intellect, as in the case just supposed, and in myriads of other cases that occur, the gratification is not a sin but a virtue. It is not selfishness but benevolence. But let it be remembered that the indulgence must not be sought in obedience to the propensity itself, but in obedience to the law of reason and of God. When reason and the will of &o4 »re flot only not consulted, but even violated, it must be selfishness 202 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Intemperance, as a sin, does not consist in the outward act of indul- gence, but in the inward disposition, A dyspeptic who can eat but just enough to sustain life, may be an enormous glutton at heart. He may have a disposition, that is, he may not only desire, but he may be willing, to eat all before him, but for the pain indulgence occasions him. But this is only the spirit of self-indulgence. He denies himself the amount of food he craves in order to gratify a stronger propensity, to wit, the dread of pain. So a man who was never intoxicated in hie life, may be guilty of the crime of drunkenness every day. He may be prevented from drinking to inebriation only by a regard to reputation or health, or by an avaricious disposition. It is only because he is prevented by the greater power of some other propensity. If a man is in such a state of mind that he would indulge all his propensities without restraint, were it not that it is impossible, on account of the indulgence of some being inconsistent with the indulgence of the others, he is just as guilty as if he did indulge them all. For example : he has a disposition, that is a will, to accumulate property. He is avaricious in heart. He also has a strong tendency to luxury, to licentiousness, and prodigality. The in- dulgence of these propensities is inconsistent with the indulgence of ava- rice. But for this contrariety, he would in his state of mind indulge them all. He wishes to do so, but it is impossible. Now he is really guilty of all those forms of vice, and just as blameworthy as if he indulged in them. Intemperance, as a crime, is a state of mind. It is the attitude of the will. It is an attribute of selfishness. It consists in the choice or disposition to gratify the propensities, regardless of the law of benevo- lence. This is intemperance ; and so far as the mind is considered, it is the whole of it. Now, inasmuch as the will is committed to self-indul- gence, and nothing but the contrariety there is between the propensities prevents the unlimited indulgence of them all, it follows, that every self- ish person, or in other words every sinner, is chargeable in the sight of God with every species of intemperance, actual or conceivable. His lusts have the reign. They conduct him whithersoever they list. He has sold himself to self-indulgence. If there is any form of self-indulgence that is not actually developed in him, no thanks to him. The providence of God has restrained the outward indulgence, while there has been in him a readiness to perpetrate any sin and every sin, from which he was not deterred by some overpowering fear of consequences. 15. Total moral depravity is implied in selfishness as one of its at- tributes. By this I intend that every selfish being is at every moment aa wicked and as blameworthy as with his knowledge he can be. It is afiSrmed, both by reason and revelation, that there are degrees of guilt ; that some are more guilty than others ; and that the same indi- yi4nal may be more guilty at one time than at ai;o(il;^|:, ATTRIBUTES OF SELFISHNESS. 203 The same is true of virtue. One person may be more virtuous than another, when both are truly virtuous. And also the same person may be more virtuous at one time than at another, although he may be virtu- ous at all times. In other words, it is affirmed, both by reason and rev- elation, that there is such a thing as growth, both in virtue and vice. It is matter of general belief, also, that the same individual, with the same degree of light or knowledge, is more or less praise or blame- worthy, as he shall do one thing or another ; or, in other words, as he shall pursue one course or another, to accomplish the end he has in view ; or, which is the same thing, that the same individual, with the same knowledge or light, is more or less virtuous or vicious, according to the course of outward life which he shall pursue. This I shall attempt to show is human prejudice, and a serious and most injurious error. It is also generally held that two or more individuals, having pre- cisely the same degree of light or knowledge, and being both equally benevolent or selfish, may, nevertheless, differ in their degree of virtue or vice, according as they pursue different courses of outward conduct. This also, I shall attempt to show, is fundamental error. We can arrive at the truth upon this subject only by clearly under- standing how to measure moral obligation, and of course how to ascer- tain the degree of virtue and sin. The amount or degree of virtue or vice, or of praise-worthiness or blame-worthiness, is and must be decided by reference to the degree of obligation. And here I would remind you — (1.) That moral obligation is founded in the intrinsic value of the highest weU-being of God and the universe : and — (2.) That the conditions of the obligation are the possession of the powers of moral agency and light, or the knowledge of the end to be chosen. (3.) Hence it follows that the obligation is to be measured by the mind's honest apprehension or judgment of the intrinsic value of the end to be chosen. That this, and nothing else, is the rule or standard by which the obligation, and, consequently, the guilt of violating it, is to be measured, will appear if we consider — (1.) That the obligation cannot be measured by the infinity of God, apart from the knowledge of the infinite value of his interests. He is an infinite being, and his well-being must be of intrinsic and of infinite value. But unless this be known to a moral agent, he cannot be under obligation to will it as an ultimate end. If he knows it to be of some value, he is bound to choose it for that reason. But the measure of his obligation must be just equal to the clearness of his apprehension of its intrinsic value. Pesides, if the infinity of God were alone, or without reference to the 204 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. knowledge of the agent, the rule by which moral obligation is to be measured, it would follow, that obligation is in all cases the same, and of course that the guilt of disobedience would also in all cases be the same. But this, as has been said, contradicts both reason and revela- tion. Thus it appears, that moral obligation, and of course guilt, can- not be measured by the infinity of God, without reference to the knowl- edge of the agent. (2.) It cannot be measured by the infinity of his authority, without reference to the knowledge of the agent, for the same reasons as above. (3.) It cannot be measured by the infinity of his moral excellence, without reference, both to the infinite value of his interests, and of the knowledge of the agent ; for his interests are to be chosen as an end, or for their own value, and without knowledge of their value there can be no obligation ; nor can obligation exceed knowledge. (4.) If, again, the infinite excellence of God were alone, or without reference to the knowledge of the agent, to be the rule by which moral obligation is to be measured, it would follow, that guilt in all cases of disobedience, is and must be equal. This we have seen cannot be, (5.) It cannot be measured by the intrinsic value of the good, or well- being of God and the universe, without reference to the knowledge of the agent, for the same reason as above. (6.) It cannot be measured by the particular course -of life pursued by the agent. This will appear, if we consider that moral obligation has directly nothing to do with the outward life. It directly respects the ultimate intention only, and that decides the course of outward ac- tion or life. The guilt of any outward action cannot be decided by refer- ence to the kind of action, without regard to the intention ; for the moral character of the act must be found in the intention, and not in the out- ward act or life. This leads me to remark that — (7.) The degree of moral obligation, and of course the degree of the guilt of disobedience, cannot be properly estimated by reference to the nature of the intention, without respect to the degree of the knowledge of the agent. Selfish intention is, as we have seen, a unit, always the same ; and if this were the standard by which the degree of guilt is to be measured, it would follow that it is always the same. (8.) Nor can obligation, nor the degree of guilt, be measured by the tendency of sin. All sin tends to infinite evil, to ruin the sinner and from its contagious nature, to spread and ruin the universe. Nor can any finite mind know what the ultimate results of any sin may be, nor to what particular evil it may tend. As all sin tends to universal and eternal evil, if this were the criterion by which the guilt is to be esti- mated, all sin would be equally guilty, which cannot be. Again ; That the guilt of gjn panjipt l^e measiarpfi by ^Jip tendenpy 0% ATTRIBUTES OP SELFISHNESS. 205 fiin, is manifest from the fact, that moral obligation is not founded in the tendency of action or intention, but in the intrinsic value of the end to be intended. Estimating moral obligation, or measuring sin or holi- ness, by the mere tendency of actions, is the utilitarian philosophy, which we have shown to be false. Moral obligation respects the choice of an end, and is founded upon the intrinsic value of the end, and is not so much as condition ated upon the tendency of the ultimate choice to secure its end. Therefore, tendency can never be the rule by which ob- ligation can be measured, nor, of course, the rule by which guilt can be estimated. (9.) Nor can moral obligation be estimated by the results of a moral action or course of action. Moral obligation respects intention and re- spects results no further than they were intended. Much good may result, as from the death of Christ, without any virtue in Judas, but with much guilt. So, much evil may result, as from the creation of the world, without guilt in the Creator, but with great virtue. If moral ob- ligation is not founded or conditionated on results, it follows that guilt cannot be duly estimated by results, without reference to knowledge and intention. (10.) What has been said has, I trust, rendered it evident, that moral obligation is to be measured by the mind's honest apprehension or judg- ment of the intrinsic value of the end to be chosen, to wit, the highest well-being of God and the universe. It should be distinctly understood, that selfishness involves the rejec- tion of the interests of God and of the universe, for the sake of one's own. It refuses to will good, but upon condition that it belongs to self. It spurns God's interests and those of the universe, and seeks only self- interest as an ultimate end. It must follow, then, that the selfish man's guilt is just equal to his knowledge of the intrinsic value of those inter- ests that he rejecta. This is undeniably the doctrine of the Bible. Acts xvii. 30, affords a plain instance. The apostle alludes to those past ages when the heathen nations had no written revelation from God, and remarks that "those times of ignorance God winked at." This does not mean that God did not regard their conduct as criminal in any de- gree, but it does mean that he regarded it as a sin of far less aggravation, than that which men would now commit, if they turned away when God commanded them all to repent. True, sin is never absolutely a light thing ; but some sins incur small guilt, when compared with the great guilt of other sins. This is implied in the text quoted above. James iv. 17. — " To him that knoweth to do good, and doeth it not, to him it is sin." This plainly implies that knowledge is indispensable to moral obligation ; and even more than this is implied, namely, that the guilt of any sinner is always equal to the amount of his knowledge 206 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. on the subject. It always corresponds to the mind's perception of the value of the end which should have been chosen, but is rejected. If a man knows he ought, in any given case, to do good, and yet does not do it, to him this is sin — the sin plainly lying in the fact of not doing good when he knew that he could do it, and being measured as to its guilt by the degree of that knowledge. John ix. 41. — " Jesus said unto them. If ye were blind, ye should have no sin : but now ye say, "We see ; therefore, your sin remaineth." Here Christ asserts that men without knowledge would be without sin ; and that men who have knowledge, and sin notwithstanding, are held guilty. This plainly affirms, that the presence of light or knowledge is requisite to the existence of sin, and obviously implies that the amount of knowledge possessed is the measure of the guilt of sin. It is remarkable that the Bible everywhere assumes first truths. It does not stop to prove them, or even assert them — but seems to assume, that every one knows and will admit them. As I have been recently writing on moral government, and studying the Bible as to its teachings on this class of subjects, I have been often struck with this remarkable fact. Luke xii. 47,48. — "And that servant which knew his lord's will, and prepared not himself, neither did according to his will, shall be beaten with many stripes. But he that knew not, and did commit things worthy of stripes, shall be beaten with few stripes. For unto whomso- ever much is given, of him shall be much required ; and to whom men have committed much, of him will they ask the more." Here we have the doctrine laid down and the truth assumed, that men shall be pun- ished according to knowledge. To whom much light is given, of him shall much obedience be required. This is precisely the principle, that God requires of men according to the light they have. Selfishness is the rejecbion of all obligation. It is the violation of all obligation. The sin of selfishness is then complete ; that is, the guilt of selfishness is as great as with its present light it can be. What can make it greater with present light ? Can the course that it takes to realize its end mitigate its guilt ? No ; for whatever course it takes, it is for a selfish reason, and, therefore, it can in nowise lessen the guilt of the intention. Can the course it takes to realize its end without more light, increase the guilt of the sin ? No ; for the sin lies exclusively in having the selfish intention, and the guilt can be measured only by the degree of illumination or knowledge under which the intention is formed . and maintained. The intention necessitates the use of the means ; and whatever means the selfish person uses, it is for one and the same reason, to gratify himself. As I said in a former lecture, if the selfish man were to preach the gospel, it would be only because, upon the whole, it ATTRIBUTES OF SELFISHNESS. 207 was most pleasing or gratifying to himself, and not at all for the sake of the good of being, as an end. If he should become a pirate, it would be for exactly the same reason, to wit, that this course is, upon the whole, most pleasing or gratifying to himself, and not at all for the reason that that course is evil in itself. Whichever course he takes, he takes it for precisely the same ultimate reason ; and with the same degree of light it must involve the same degree of guilt. If light increase, his guilt must increase, but not otherwise. The proposition is, that every selfish being is, at every moment, as blame- worthy as with his present knowledge he can be. Which of these courses may tend ultimately to the most evil, no finite being can say, nor which shall result in the greatest evil. Guilt is not to be measured by unknown tendencies or results, but belongs to the intention ; and its degree is to be measured alone by the mind's ap- prehension of the reason of the obligation violated, namely, the intrinsic value of the good of God and the universe, which selfishness rejects. Now, it should be remembered, that whichever course the sinner takes to realize his end, it is the end at which he aims. He intends the end. If he become a preacher of the gospel for a selfish reason, he has no right regard to the good of being. If he regards it at all, it is only as a means of his own good. So, if he becomes a pirate, it is not from malice, or a disposition to do evil for its own sake, but only to gratify himself. If he has any regard at all to the evil he may do, it is only to gratify himself that he regards it. Whether, therefore, he preach or pray, or rob and plunder upon the high seas, he does it only for one end, that is, for pre- cisely the same ultimate reason ; and of course his sinfulness is complete, in-the sense that it can be varied only by varying light. This I know is contrary to common opinion, but it is the truth, and must be known ; and it is of the highest importance that these fundamental truths of morality and of immorality should be held up to the minds of all. Should the sinner abstain from any course of vice because it is wicked, it cannot be because he is benevolent, for this would contradict the supposition that he is selfish, or that he is a sinner. If, in considera- tion that an act or course is wicked, he abstains from it, it must be for a selfish reason. It may be in obedience to phrenological conscientiousness, or it may be from fear of hell, or of disgrace, or from remorse ; at all events, it cannot but be for some selfish reason. Total moral depravity is an attribute of selfishness, in the sense, that every selfish person is at all times just as wicked and blameworthy aa with his present light he can be. 208 SYSTEMATIC TUEOLOGV. LECTURE XIX. SANCTIONS OF MORAL LAW, NATURAL AND GOVERNMBNTAIi. In the discussion of this subject, I shall show — I, What constitute the sanctions of law. 1. The sanctions of law are the motives to obedience, the natural and the goTernmental consequences or results of obedience and of disobedi- ence. 2. They are remuneratory, that is, they promise reward to obedience. 3. They are yindicatory, that is, they threaten the disobedient with punishment. 4. They are natural, that is, happiness is to some extent naturally connected with, and the necessary consequence of, obedience to moral law, and misery is naturally and necessarily connected with, and results from, disobedience to moral law, or from acting contrary to the nature and relations of moral beings. 5. Sanctions are governmental. By governmental sanctions are in- tended : (1.) The favor of the government as due to obedience. (2.) A positive reward bestowed upon the obedient by government. (3.) The displeasure of government towards the disobedient. (4.) Direct punishment inflicted by the government as due to disobe- dience. All happiness and misery resulting from obedience or disobedience, either natural, or from the favor, or frown of government, are to be re- garded as constituting the sanctions of law. II. In what light sanctions are to be regarded. 1. Sanctions are to be regarded as an expression of the benevolent regard of the lawgiver for his subjects : the motives which he exhibits to induce in the subjects the course of conduct that will secure their high- est well-being. 2. They are to be regarded as an expression of his estimation of the justice, necessity, and value of the precept to the subjects of his govern- ment. 3. They are to be regarded as an expression of the amount or strength of his desire to secure the happiness of his subjects. 4. They are to be regarded as an expression of his opinion in respect to the desert of disobedience. SANCriONS OF THfi LAW 209 The natural sanctions are to be regarded as a demonstration of the justice, necessity and perfection of the precept. III. By what rule sanctions ought to be graduated, 1. "We have seen that moral obligation is founded in the intrinsic value of the well-being of God and of the universe, and conditionated upon the perception of its value ; and, 2. That guilt is always to be measured by the perceived value of the end which moral beings ought to choose. 3. The sanctions of law should be graduated by the intrinsic merit and demerit of holiness atfd sin. IV. God's law has sanctions. 1. That sin, or disobedience to the moral law, is attended with, and results in, misery, is a matter of consciousness. 2. That virtue or holiness is attended with, and results in happiness, is also attested by consciousness. 3. Therefore that God's law has natural sanctions, both remuneratory and vindicatory, is a matter of fact. 4. That there are governmental sanctions added to the natural, must be true, or God, in fact, has no government but that of natural conse- quences. 5. The Bible expressly, and in every variety of form, teaches that God will reward the righteous and punish the wicked. V. The perfection and duration of the remuneratory sanctions of th« law of God. 1. The perfection of the natural reward is, and must be, proportioned to the perfection of virtue. 2. The duration of the remuneratory sanction must be equal to the duration of obedience. This cannot possibly be otherwise. 3. If the existence and virtue of man are immortal, his happiness must be endless. 4. The Bible most unequivocally asserts the immortality both of the existence and virtue of the righteous, and also that their happiness shall be endless. 5. The very design and end of government make it necessary that governmental reward should be as perfect and unending as virtue. VI. Penal inflictions under the government of God must ie endless. Here the inquiry is, what kind of death is intended, where death ia denounced against the transgressor, as the penalty of the law of God f 1. It is not merely natural death, lor — 14 210 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. (1.) This would, in reality, be no penalty at all. But it would be offering a reward to sin. If natural death is all that is intended, and if persons, as soon as they are naturally dead, have suffered the penalty of the law, and their souls go immediately to heaven, the case stands thus : if your obedience is perfect and perpetual, you shall live in this world forever ; but if you sin, you shall die and go immediately to heaven. " This would be hire and salary," and not punishment. (2.) If natural death be the penalty of God's law, the righteous, who are forgiven, should not die a natural death. (3.) If natural death be the penalty of God's law, there is no such thing as forgiveness, but all must actually endure the penalty. (4.) If natural death be the penalty, then infants and animals suffer this penalty, as well as the most abandoned transgressors. (5.) If natural death be the penalty, and the only penalty, it sustains no proportion whatever to the guilt of sin. (6.) Natural death would bono adequate expression of the importance of the precept. 2. The penalty of God's law is not spiritual death. (1. ) Because spiritual death is a state of entire sinfulness. (2. ) To make a state of entire sinfulness the penalty of the law of God, would be to make the penalty and the breach of the precept identical. (3.) It would be making God the author of sin, and would represent him as compelling the sinner to commit one sin as the punishment for another, — as forcing him into a state of total and perpetual rebellion, as the reward of his first transgression. 3. But the penal sanction of the law of God is endless death, or that state of endless suffering which is the natural and governmental result of sin or of spiritual death. Before I proceed to the proof of this, I will notice an objection which is often urged against the doctrine of endless punishment. The objection is one, but it is stated in three different forms. This, and every other objection to the doctrine of endless punishment, with which I am acquainted, is levelled against the justice of such a governmental infliction. (1.) It is said that endless punishment is unjust, because life is so short, that men do not live long enough in this world to commit so great a number of sins as to deserve endless punishment. To this I answer that it is founded in ignorance or disregard of a universal principle of government, viz., that one breach of the precept always incurs the penalty of the law, whatever that penalty is. The length of time employed in committing a sin, has nothing to do with its blameworthi- ness or guilt. It is the design which constitutes the moral character of the action, and not the length of the time required for its accom- SANCTIONS OF THE LAW. 211 plishment. This objection takes for granted, that it is the number of sins, and not the intrinsic guilt of sin, that constituteB its blame- worthiness, whereas it is the intrinsic desert or guilt of sin, as we shall soon see, that renders it deserving of endless punishment. (3.) Another form of the objection is, that a finite creature cannot commit an infinite sin. But none but an infinite sin can deserve endless punishment : therefore endless punishments are unjust. This objection takes for granted that man is so diminutive a creature, so much less than the Creator, that he cannot deserve his endless frown. Which is the greater crime, for a child to insult his playfellow, or his parent ? Which would involve the most guilt, for a man to smite his neighbor and his equal, or his lawful sovereign ? The higher the ruler is exalted above the subject in his nature, character^ and rightful author- ity, the greater is the obligation of the subject to will his good, to render to him obedience, and the greater is the guilt of the transgression in the subject. Therefore, the fact that man is so infinitely below his Maker^ does but enhance the guilt of his rebellion, and render him all the more worthy of his endless frown. (3.) A third form of the objection is, that sin is not an infinite evil ; and therefore, does not deserve endless punishment. This objection may mean either, that sin would not produce infinite mischief if unrestrained, or that it does not involve infinite guilt. It cannot mean the first, for it is agreed on all hands, that misery must continue as long as sin does, and therefore^ that sin unrestrained would produce endless evil. The objection, therefore, must mean, that sin does not involve infinite guilt. Observe, then, the point at issue is, what is the intrinsic demerit or guilt of sin ? What does all sin in its own nature deserve ? They who deny the justice of endless punishment, manifestly consider the guilt of sin as a mere trifle. They who main- tain the justice of endless punishment, consider sin as an evil of immeas- MraJ?e magnitude, and, in its own nature, deserving of endless punish- ment. Proof : — Should a moral agent refuse to choose that as an ultimate end which is of no intrinsic value, he would thereby contract no guilt, because he would violate no obligation. But should he refuse to will the good of God and of his neighbor, he would violate an obligation, and of course contract guilt. This shows that guilt attaches to the violation of obliga- tion, and that a thing is blameworthy because it is the violation of an dbligation. 'I' We have seen that sin is selfishness, that it consists in preferring self- gtatification to the infinite interests of God and of the universe. We have also seen that obligation is founded in the intrinsic value of that good which moral agents ought to will to God and to the universe, S12 SYSTEMATiC THEOLOQlr, and is equal to the aflSrmed value of that good. We have also seen that every moral agent, by a law of his own reason, necessarily affirms that God is infinite, and that the endless happiness and well-being of God and of the universe, is of infinite value. Hence it follows, that refusal to will this good is a violation of infinite or unlimited obligation, and, consequently involves unlimited guilt. It is as certain that the guilt of any sin is unlimited, as that obligation to will the good of God and of the universe is unlimited. To deny consistently that the guilt of sin is unlimited, it must be shown, that obligation to will good to God is, unlimited. To maintain consistently this last, it must be shown, that moral agents have not the idea that God is infinite. Indeed, to deny that the guilt of sin is in any instance less than boundless, is as absurd as to deny the guilt of sin altogether. Having shown that moral obligation is founded in the intrinsic value of the highest well-being of God and of the universe, that it is always equal to the soul's knowledge of the value of those interests, and having shown also, that every moral agent necessarily has the idea more or less clearly developed, that the value of those interests is infinite, it follows that the law is infinitely unjust, if its penal sanctions are not endless. Law must be just in two respects : the precept must be in accordance with the law of nature, and the penalty must be equal to the importance of the precept. That which has not these two peculiarities is not just, and therefore, is not and cannot be law. Either, then, God has no law, or its penal sanctions are endless. That the penal sanctions of the law of God are endless, is evident from the fact, that a less penalty would not exhibit as high motives as the nature of the case admits, to restrain sin and promote virtue. Natural justice demands that God should ex- hibit as high motives to secure obedience as the value of the law demands and the nature of the case admits. The tendency of sin to perpetuate and aggravate itself, affords an- other strong inference, that the sinfulness and misery of the wicked will be eternal. The fact, that punishment has no tendency to originate disinterested love in a selfish mind towards him who inflicts the punishment, also affords a strong presumption, that future punishment will be eternal. But let us examine this question m the light of revelation. The Bible, in a great many ways, represents the future punishment of the wicked as eternal, and never once represents it otherwise. It ex- presses the duration of the future punishment of the wicked by the same terms, and, in every way, as forcibly as it expresses the duration of the future happiness of the righteous. I will here introduce, without comment, some passages of scripture SANCTIONS OP THE LAW. 213 confirmatory of ttis last remark. " The hope of the righteous shall be gladness : but the expectation of the wicked shall perish." — Prov. x. 28. " When a wicked man dieth, his expectation shall perish ; and the hope of unjust men perisheth." — Prov. xi. 7. "And many of them that sleep in the dust of the earth shall awake ; some to everlasting life, and some to shame and everlasting contempt." — Dan. xii. 2. " Then shall he say also unto them on the left hand, Depart from me, ye cursed, into everlasting fire, prepared for the devil and his angels : for I was an hun- gered, and ye gave me no meat : I was thirsty, and ye gave me no drink. And these shall go away into everlasting punishment : but the righteous into life eternal." — Matt. xxv. 41, 42, 46. " And if thy hand offend thee, cut, it off : it is better for thee to enter into life maimed than hav- ing two hands to go into hell, into the fire that never shall be quenched ; where their worm dieth not, and the fire is not quenched." — Mark ix. 43, 44. " Whose fan is in his hand, and he will thoroughly purge his floor ; and will gather the wheat into his garner ; but the chaff he will burn with fire unquenchable." — Luke iii. 17. "And besides all this, between us and you there is a great gulf fixed : so that they which would pass from hence to you, cannot ; neither can they pass to us, that would come from thence." — Luke xvi. 26. "He that believeth on the Son hath everlasting life : and he that believeth not the Son shall not see life; but the wrath of God abideth on him." — John iii. 36. "And to *you who are troubled, rest with us, when the Lord Jesus shall be re- vealed fi'om heaven with his mighty angels, in flaming fire taking ven- geance on them that know not God, and that obey not the gospel of our Lord Jesus Christ ; who shall be punished with everlasting destruction from the presence of the Lord, and from the glory of his power." — 2' Thess. i. 7-9. " And the angels which kept not their first estate, but left their own habitation, he hath reserved in everlasting chains, under darkness, unto. the judgment of the great day. Even as Sodom and Go- morrah, and the cities about them, in like manner, giving themselves over to fornication, and going after strange flesh, are set forth for an example, suffering the vengeance of eternal fire. Eaging waves of the sea, foaming out their own shame ; wandering stars, to whom is reserved the blackne^ of darkness forever." — Jude 6, 7, 13. " And the third angel followed them, saying with a loud voice. If any man worship the beast and his image, and receive his mark in his forehead, or in his hand, the same shall drink of the wine of the wrath of God which is poured out without mixture into the cup of his indignation ; and he shall be tormented with fire and brimstone in the presence of the holy angels, and in the presence of the Lamb : and the smoke of their tor- ment ascendeth up forever and ever : and they have no rest day nor night, who worship the beast and his image, and whosoever receivefcb 214 SYSTEMATIC THBOLOGT. the mark of his name." — Eev. xiv. 9-11. "And the devil that deceived them was cast into the lake of fire and brimstone, where the beast and the false prophet are, and shall be tormented day and night forever and ever." — Eev. xx. 10. But there is scarcely any end to the multitude of passages that teach directly, or by inference, both the fact and the end- lessness of the future punishment of the wicked. LECTURE XX. HUMAN GOVERNMENT. Human governments apart of the moral government of God. In the discussion of this subject I will, — I. Inquire into the ultimate end of God in creation. "We have seen in former lectures, that God is a moral agent, the self- existent and supreme ; and is therefore himself, as ruler of all, subject to, and observant of, moral law in all his conduct. That is, his own in- finite intelligence must affirm that a certain course of willing is suitable, fit, and right in him. This idea, or affirmation, is law to him ; and to this his will must be conformed, or he is not good. This is moral law, a law founded in the eternal and self-existent nature of God. This law does, and must, demand benevolence in God. Benevolence is good-wil- ling. God's intelligence must affirm that he ought to will good for its own intrinsic value. It must affirm his obligation to choose the highest possible good as the great end of his being. If God is good, the highest good of himself, and of the universe, must have been the end which he had in view in the work of creation. This is of infinite value, and ought to be willed by God. If God is good, this must have been his end. We have also seen, — II. Hiat providential and moral governments are indispensable means of securing the highest good of the universe. The highest good of moral agents is conditionated upon their holi- ness. Holiness consists in conformity to moral law. Moral law implies moral government. Moral government is a government of moral law and of motives. Motives are presented by providential government ; and providential government is, therefore, a means of moral government. Providential and moral government must be indispensable to securing the highest good of the universe. HUMAN GOVERNMENT. 215 IIL (Mvil and family governments are indispensable to the seciiring of this end, and are, therefore, really apart of the providential and moral government of God. In the discussion of this question I remark, 1. Human beings will not agree in opinion on any subject without similar degrees of knowledge. No human community exists, or ever will exist, the members of which will agree in opinion on all subjects. This creates a necessity for human legislation and adjudication) to apply the great principles of moral law to all human affairs. There are multitudes of human wants and necessities that cannot properly be met, except through the instrumentality of human governments. 2. This necessity will continue as long as human beings exist in this world. This is as certain as that the human body will always need sus- tenance and clothing ; and that the human soul will always need instruc- tion ; and that the means of instruction will not come spontaneously, with- out expense and labor. It is as certain as that men of all ageS and cir- cumstances will never possess equal talents and degrees of information on all subjects. If all men were perfectly holy and disposed to do right, the necessity for human governments would not be set aside, because this necessity is founded in the ignorance of mankind, though greatly ag- gravated by their wickedness. The decisions of legislators and judges must be authoritative, so as to settle questions of disagreement in opin- ion, and at once to bind and protect all parties. The Bible presents human governments not only as existing, but as deriving their authority and right to punish evil-doers, and to protect the righteous, from God. But — 3. Human governments are plainly recognized in the Bible as a part of the moral government of God. Dan. ii. 21. " He changeth the times and the seasons ; he removeth kings, and setteth up kings : he giveth wisdom unto the wise, and knowl- edge to them that know understanding." Dan. iv. 17, 25. "This mat- ter is by the degree of the watchers, and the demand by the word of the holy ones ; to the intent that the living may know that the Mo^t High rnleth in the kingdom of men, and giveth it to whomsoever he will, and setteth up over it the basest of men." " They shall drive thee from men, and thy dwelling shall be with the beasts of the field, and they shall make thee to eat grass as oxen, and they shall' wet thee with the dew of heaven, and seven times shall pass over thee, till thou know that the Most High ruleth in the kingdom of men, and giveth it to whomsoever he will." Dan. v. 21. " He was driven from the sons of men ; and his heart was made like the beasts, and his dwelling was with the wild asses : they fed him with grass like oxen, and his body was wet with the dew of 216 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOQT. heaven till he knew that the Most High God rnleth in the kingdom of men, and that he appointeth over it whomsoever he will." Rom. xiii. 1-7. " Let every soul be subject unto the higher powers. For there is no power but of God, the powers that be are ordained of God. Whosoever therefore resisteth the power, resisteth the ordinance of God : and they that resist shall receive to themselves damnation. For rulers are not a terror to good works but to the evil. Wilt thou then not be afraid of the power ? Do that which is good, and thou shalt have praise of the same: ior he is the minister of God to thee for good. But if thou do that which is evil, be afraid ; for he beareth not the sword in vain ; for he is ithe minister of God, a revenger to execute wrath upon him that doeth evil. Wherefore ye must needs be subject, not only for wrath but also Ifor conscience' sake. For, for this cause pay ye tribute also : for they are (God's ministers, attending continually upon this very thing. Render, (therefore, to all their dues ; tribute to whom tribute is due ; custom to whom custom ; fear to whom fear ; honor to whom honor." Titus iii. 1. *' Put them in mind to be subject to principalities and powers, to obey magistrates, to be ready to every good work." 1 Peter ii. 13, 14. "Submit yourselves to every ordinance of man for the Lord's sake : whether it be to the king, as supreme, or unto governors, as unto them that are sent by him for the punishment of evil doers, and for the praise of them that do well." These passages prove conclusively, that God establishes human gov- ernment, as parts of moral government. 4. It is the duty of all men to aid in the establishment and support of human government. As the great law of benevolence, or universal good- willing, demands the existence of human governments, all men are under a perpetual and unalterable moral obligation to aid in their establishment and support. In popular or elective governments, every man having a right to vote, every human being who has moral influence, is bound to exert that influ- ence in the promotion of virtue and happiness. And as human govern- Baents are plainly indispensable to the highest good of man, they are bound to exert their influence to secure a legislation that is in accordance with the law of God. The obligation of human beings to support and obey human governments, while they legislate upon the principles of the moral law, is as unalterable as the moral law itself. 5. I will answer objections. Obj. 1. The kingdom of God is represented in the Bible as subvert- ing all other kingdoms. Ans. This is true, but all that can be meant by it is, that the time fihflll come when God shall be regarded as the supreme and universal Bovereign of the universe, when his law shall be regarded as universally obligatory ; when all kings, legislators, and judges shall act as his sor- HUMAN GOVBENMENT. 217 vants, declaring, applying, and administering the great principles of his law to all the affairs of human beings. Thus God will be the supreme sovereign, and earthly rulers will be governors, kings, and judges under him, and acting by his authority as revealed in the Bible. Obj. 3. It is alleged that God only providentially establishes human governments, and that he does not approve of their selfish and wicked administration ; that he only uses them providentially, as he does Satan, for the promotion of his own designs. Ans. God nowhere commands mankind to obey Satan, but he does command them to obey magistrates and rulers. Rom. xiii. 1. "Let every soul be subject unto the higher powers ; for there is no power but of God : the powers that be are ordained of God." 1 Pet. ii. 13, 14. " Submit yourselves to every ordinance of man for the Lord's sake : whether it be to the king as supreme ; or unto governors, as unto them that are sent by him for the punishment of evil doers, and for the praise of them that do well." He nowhere recognizes Satan as his servant, sent and set by him to administer justice and execute wrath upon the wicked ; but he does this in respect to human governments. Rom. xiii. 2-6. "Whosoever there- fore resisteth the power, resisteth the ordinance of God ; and they that resist shall receive to themselves damnation. For rulers are not a terror to good works, but to the evil. Wilt thou then not be afraid of the power ? Do that which is good, arid thou shalt have praise of the same. For he is the minister of God to thee for good. But if thou do that which is evil, be afraid ; for he beareth not the sword in vain : for he is the minister of God, a revenger to execute wrath upon him that doeth evil. Wherefore ye must needs be subject, not only for wrath, but also for conscience' sake. For, for this cause pay ye tribute also ; for they are God's ministers, attending continually upon this very thing." It is true indeed that God approves of nothing that is ungodly and selfish in human governments. Neither did he approve of what was ungodly and selfish in the scribes and Pharisees ; and yet Christ said to his disciples, " The scribes and Pharisees sit in Moses' seat; Therefore, whatsoever things they command you, that observe and do ; but do ye not after their works, for they say, and do not." Here the plain common-sense principle is recognized, that we are to obey when the requirement is not inconsistent with the moral law, whatever may be the character or the motive of the ruler. We are always to obey heartily as unto the Lord, and not unto men, and render obedience to magistrates for the honor and glory of God, and as doing service to him. Obj. 3. It is said that Christians should leave human governments to the management of the ungodly, and not be diverted from thp yrorlj: of Bg,yins souls, to ijiterineddle vjt^ fruipan gover^n)^B|;^, 218 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Ans. To uphold and assist good government is not being diverted from the work of saving soals. The promotion of public and private order and happiness is one of the indispensable means of doing good and saving souls. It is nonsense to admit that Christians are under an ob- ligation to obey human government, and still have nothing to do with the choice of those who shall govern. Obj. 4. It is aflBrmed that we are commanded not to avenge our- selves, that "Vengeance is mine, and I will repay, saith the Lord." It is said, that if I may not avenge or redress my own wrongs in my own person, I may not do it through the instrumentality of human govern- ment. Ans. It does not follow, that because you may not take it upon your- self to redress your own wrongs by a summary and personal infliction of punishment upon the transgressor, that therefore human governments may not punish them. All private wrongs are a public injury ; and irrespective of any particular regard to your personal interest, magistrates are bound to punish crime for the public good. While God has expressly forbidden you to redress your own wrongs, by administering personal and private chastisement, he has expressly recognized the right, and made it the duty of public magistrates to' punish crimes. Obj, 5. It is alleged, that love is so much better than law, that where love reigns in the heart, law can be universally dispensed with. Ans. This supposes that, if there is only love, there need be no rule of duty ; no revelation, directing love in its efforts to secure the end upon which it terminates. But this is as untrue as possible. The ob- jection overlooks the fact, that law is in all worlds the rule of duty, and that legal sanctions make up an indispensable part of that circle of motives that are suited to the nature, relations, and government of moral beings. Obj. 6. It is asserted, that Christians have something else to do be- sides meddling with politics. Ans. In a popular government, politics are an important part of re- ligion. No man can possibly be benevolent or religious, to the full ex- tent of his obligations, without concerning himself, to a greater or less extent, with the affairs of human government. It is true, that Chris- tians have something else to do than to go with a party to do evil, or to meddle with politics in a selfish or ungodly manner. But they are bound to meddle with politics in popular governments, because they are bound to seek the universal good of all men ; and this is one department of human interests, materially afEecting all their higher interests. Obj. 7. It is said that human governments are nowhere expressly authorized in the Bible. Ans. This is a mistake. Both their existence and lawfulness are as HUMAN GOVBENMENT. 219 expressly recognized in the above quoted scriptures as they can be. But if God did not expressly authorize them, it would still be both the right and the duty of mankind to institute human goTernments, because they are plainly demanded by the necessities' of human nature. It is a first truth, that whatever is essential to the highest good of moral beings in any world, they have a right to pursue^ and are bound to pursue accord- ing to the best dictates of reason and experience. So far, therefore, are men from needing any express authority to establish human governments, that no inference from the silence of scripture could avail to render their establishment unlawful. It has been shown, in these lectures on moral government, that moral law is a unit — that it is that rule of action which is in accordance with the nature, relations, and circumstances of moral beings — that whatever is in accordance with, and demanded by the na- ture, relations, and circumstances of moral beings, is obligatory on them. It is moral law, and no power in the universe can set it aside. There- fore, were the scriptures entirely silent (which they are not) on the sub- ject of human governments, and on the subject of family government, as they actually are on a great many important subjects, this would be no objection to the lawfulness and expediency, necessity and duty of es- ^ tablishing human governments. Obj. 8. It is said that human governments are founded in and sus- tained by force, and that this is inconsistent with the spirit of the gospel. Ans. There cannot be a difference between the spirit of the Old and the New Testament, or between the spirit of the law and the gospel, unless God has changed, and unless Christ has undertaken to make void the law through faith, which cannot be. Eom. iii. 32. " Do we then make void the law through faith ? God forbid : yea, we establish the law." Just human governments, and such governments only are contended for, will not exercise force, unless it is demanded to promote the highest pub- lic good. If it be necessary to this end, it can never be wrong. Nay, it must be the duty of human governments to inflict penalties, when their infliction is demanded by the public interest. Obj. 9. It has been said by some persons, that church government is sufiElcient to meet the necessities of the world, without secular or state governments. Ans. What ! Church governments regulate commerce, make internal arrangements, such as roads, bridges, and taxation, and undertake to manage all the business affairs of the world I Preposterous and impossi- ble ! Church government was never established for any such end ; but simply to regulate the spiritual, in distinction from the secular concerns of men — to try offenders and inflict spiritual chastisement, and never to perplex and embarrass itself with managing the business and commercial interests of the world. 220 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Obj. 10. It is said, that were all the world holy, legal penalties would not be needed. Ans. Were all men perfectly holy, the execution of penalties would not be needed ; but still, if there were law, there must be penalties ; and it would be both the right and the duty of magistrates to inflict them, whenever the needful occasion should call for their execution. But the state of the world supposed is not at hand, and while the world is what it is, laws must remain, and be enforced. Obj. 11. It is asserted, that family government is the only form of government approved of God. Ans. This is a ridiculous assertion, because God as expressly com- mands obedience to magistrates as to parents. He makes it as absolutely the duty of magistrates to punish crime, as of parents to punish their own disobedient children. The right of family government, though commanded by God, is not founded in the arbitrary will of God, but in the highest good of human beings ; so that family government would be both necessary and obligatory, had God not commanded it. So the right of human government has not its foundation in the arbitrary will of God, but in the necessities of human beings. The larger the community the more absolute the necessity of government. If in the small circle of the family, laws and penalties are needed, how much more in the larger com- munities of states and nations. Now, neither the ruler of a family, nor any other human ruler, has a right to legislate arbitrarily, or enact, or enforce any other laws, than those that are demanded by the nature, re- lations, and circumstances of human beings. Nothing can be obligatory on moral beings, but that which is consistent with their nature, relations, and circumstances. But human beings are bound to establish family governments, state governments, national governments, and in short, whatever government may be requisite for the universal instruction, gov- ernment, virtue, and happiness of the world, or any portion of it. Christians therefore have something else to do than to confound the right of government with the abuse of this right by the ungodly. Instead of destroying human governments. Christians are bound to reform and uphold them. To attempt to destroy, rather than reform human govern- ments, is the same in principle as is often aimed at, by those who are attempting to destroy, rather than to reform, the church. There are those who, disgusted with the abuses of Christianity practiced in ' the church, seem bent on destroying the church altogether, as the means of saving the world. But what mad policy is this ! It is admitted that selfish men need, and must feel the restraints of law ; but yet it is contended that Christians should have no part in restraining them by law. But suppose the wicked should agree among themselves to have no Uw, and therefore ,should not attpmpjt tp restrain HUMAN GOVERNlVtENi:'. 221 themselves, nor each other by law ; would it be neither the right nor the duty of Christians to attempt their restraint, through the influence of wholesome government ? It would be strange, that selfish men should need the restraints of law, and yet that Christians should have no right to meet this necessity, by supporting governments that will restrain them. It is right and best that there should be law. It is even absolutely necessary that there should be law. Universal benevolence demands it ; can it then be wrong in Christians to have anything to do with it ? IV. Point out the limits or boundaries of the right of government. Observe, the end of government is the highest good of human beings, as a part of universal good. All valid human legislation must propose, this as its end, and no legislation can have any authority that has not the highest good of the whole for its end. No being can arbitrarily create law. All law for the government of moral agents must be moral law : that is, it must be that rule of action best suited to their natures and relations. All valid human legislation must be only declaratory of this one only law. Nothing else than this can by any possibility be law. God puts forth no enactments, but such as are declaratory of the com- mon law of the universe ; and should he do otherwise, they would not be obligatory. Arbitrary legislation can never be really obligatory. The right of human government is founded in the intrinsic value of the good of being, and is conditionated upon its necessity, as a means to that end. So far as legislation and control are indispensable to this end, so far and no farther does the right to govern extend. All legisla- tion and all constitutions not founded upon this basis, and not recogniz- ing the moral law as the only law of the universe, are null and void, arid all attempts to establish and enforce them are odious tyranny and usur- pation. Human beings may form constitutions, establish governments, and enact statutes for the purpose of promoting the highest virtue and happiness of the world, and for the declaration and enforcement of moral law ; and just so far human governments are essential to this end, but absolutely no farther. It follows, that no government is lawful or innocent that does not recognize the moral law as the only universal law, and God as the Su- preme Lawgiver and Judge, to whom nations in their national capacity, as well as all individuals, are amenable. The moral law of God is the only law of individuals and of nations, and nothing can be rightful government but snoh as is established and administered with a view to its support. 222 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY, LECTURE XXI. HUMAN GOVERNMENT. V. I propose now to make several remarks respecting forms of govern- ment, the right and duty of revolution, etc. 1. The particular forms of state gOTernment must, and will, depend upon the virtue and intelligence of the people. When virtue and intelligence are nearly universal, democratic forms of government are well suited to promote the public good. In such a state of society, democracy is greatly conducive to the general diffusion of knowledge on governmental subjects ; and although, in some respects less convenient, yet in a suitable state of society, a democracy is in many respects the most desirable form of government. God has always providentially given to mankind those forms of government that were suited to the degrees of virtue and intelligence among them. If they have been extremely ignorant and vicious, he has restrained them by the iron rod of human despotism. If more intelli- gent and virtuous, he has given them the milder form of limited mon- archies. If still more intelligent and virtuous, he has given them still more liberty, and providentially established republics for their govern- ment. Whenever the general state of intelligence has permitted it, he has put them to the test of self-government and self-restraint, by estab- lishing democracies. If the world ever becomes perfectly virtuous, governments wiU be proportionally modified, and employed in expounding and applying the great principles of moral law. 2. That form of government is obligatory, that is best suited to meet the necessities of the people.' This follows as a self-evident truth, from the consideration, that necessity is the condition of the right of human government. To meet this necessity is the object of government ; and that government is obli- gatory and best which is demanded by the circumstances, intelligence, and morals of the people. Consequently, in certain states of society, it would be a Christian's duty to pray for and sustain even a military despotism ; in a certain other state of society, to pray for and sustain a monarchy ; and in other states, to pray for and sustain a republic ; and in a still more advanced stage of virtue and intelligence, to pray for and sustain a democracy ; if indeed a democracy is the most wholesome form of self government, which may admit of doubt. It is ridiculous to set up the claim of a Divine right HUMAN GOVERNMENT. 223 for any given form of government. That form of government whicli is demanded by the state of society, and the virtue and intelligence of the people, has of necessity the Divine right and sanction, and none other has or can have. 3. Kevolutions become necessary and obligatory, when the virtue and intelligence, or the vice and ignorance, of the people, demand them. This is a thing of course. "When one form of government fails to meet any longer the necessities of the people, it is the duty of the people to revolutionize. In such cases, it is vain to oppose revolution ; for in some way the benevolence of God will bring it about. Upon this prin- ciple alone, can what is generally termed the American Eevolution be justified. The intelligence and virtue of our Puritan forefathers ren- dered a monarchy an unnecessary burden, and a republican form of gov- ernment both appropriate and necessary ; and God always allows his chil- dren as much liberty as they are prepared to enjoy. The stability of our republican institutions must depend upon the progress of general intelligence and virtue. If in these respects the nation falls, if general intelligence, public and private virtue, sink to that point below which self-control becomes practicably impossible, we must fall back into monarchy, limited or absolute ; or into civil or mili- tary despotism ; just according to the national standard of intelligence and virtue. This is just as certain as that God governs the world, or that causes produce their effects. Therefore, it is the maddest conceivable policy, for Christians to attempt to uproot human governments, while they ought to be engaged in sustaining them upon the great principles of the moral law. It is cer- tainly the grossest folly, if not abominable wickedness, to overlook either in theory or pratice, these plain, common sense and universal truths. 4. In what cases are we bound to disobey human governments ? (1.) We may yield obedience, when the thing required does not in- volve a violation of moral obligation. (2.) We are bound to obey when the thing required has no moral character in itself ; upon the principle, that obedience in this case is a less evil than resistance and revolution. But — (3.) We are bound in all cases to disobey, when human legislation contravenes moral law, or invades the rights of conscience. VI. Apply the foregoing principles to the rights and duties of govern- ments and subjects in relation to the execution of the necessary penalties of law : — the suppression of mobs, insurrections, rebellion ; and also in relation to war, slavery, Sabbath desecration, etc^ 1. It is plain that the right and duty to govern for the security and promotion of the public interests, implies the right and duty tp use anj 224 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. means necessary to this result. It is absurd to say that the ruler has the right to govern, and yet that he has not a right to use the necessary means. Some have taken the ground of the inviolability of human life, and have insisted that to take life is wrong per se, and of course that governments are to be sustained without taking life. Others liave gone so far as to assert, that governments have no right to resort to physical force to sustain the authority of law. But this is a most absurd philos- ophy, and amounts just to this : — The ruler has a right to govern while the subject is pleased to obey ; but if the subject refuse obedience, why then the right to govern ceases : for it is impossible that the right to govern should exist when the right to enforce obedience does not exist. This philosophy is, in fact, a denial of the right to use the necessary means for the promotion of the great end for which all moral agents ought to live. And yet, strange to tell, this philosophy professes to deny the right to use force, and to take life in support of goTernment, on the ground of benevolence, that is, that benevolence forbids it. What is this but maintaining that the law of benevolence demands that we should love others too much to use the indispensable means to secure their good F' Or that we should love the whole too much to execute the law upon those who would destroy all good ? Shame on such philosophy 1 It overlooks the foundation of moral obligation, and of all morality and religion. Just as if an enlightened benevolence could forbid the due, wholesome, and necessary execution of law. This philosophy impertinently urges the commandment, " Thou shalt not kill," as prohibiting all taking of human life. But it may be asked, why say human life ? The com- mandment, so far as the letter is concerned, as fully prohibits the kill- ing of animals or vegetables as it does of men. The question is, what kind of killing does this commandment prohibit ? Certainly not all kill- ing of human beings, for in the next chapter the Jews were commanded to kill human beings for certain crimes. The ten commandments are precepts, and the Lawgiver, after laying down the precepts, goes on to specify the penalties that are to be inflicted by men for a violation of these precepts. Some of these penalties are death, and the penalty for the violation of the precept under consideration is death. It is certain that this precept was not intended to prohibit the taking of life for mur- der. A consideration of the law in its tenor and spirit renders it most evident that the precept in question prohibits murder, and the penalty of death is added by the lawgiver to the violation of this precept. Now how absurd and impertinent it is, to quote this precept in prohibition of taking life under the circumstances jnoluded in the precept 1 Men have an undoubted right to do whatever is plainly indispensable to the highest good of man ; and, therefore, nothing can, by any possi- bility be law, that should prohibit the taking of human life, when it be- HUMAN GOVERNMENT. 235 comes indispensable to the great end of government. This right is every where recognized in the Bible, and if it were not, still the right would exist. This philosophy that I am opposing, assumes that the will of God creates law, and that we have no right to take life, without an express warrant from him. But the facts are, that God did give to the Jews, at least, an express warrant and injunction to take life for certain crimes ; »nd, if he had not, it would have been duty to do so whenever the pub- lic good required it. Let it be remembered, that the moral law is the law of nature, and that everything is lawful and right that is plainly de- manded for the promotion of the highest good of being. The philosophy of which I am speaking lays much stress upon what i' calls inalienable rights. It assumes that man has a title or right to '\fe, in such a sense, that he cannot forfeit it by crime. But the fact is, Uiere are no rights inalienable in this sense. There can be no such rights. Whenever any individual by the commission of crime comes into such a relation to the public interest, that his death is a necessary means of se- curing the highest public good, his life is forfeited, and to take the for- feiture at his hands is the duty of the government. 2. It will be seen, that the same principles are equally applicable to insurrections, rebellions, etc. While government is right, it is duty, and while it is right and duty, because necessary as a means to the great end upon which benevolence terminates, it must be both the right and the luty of government, and of all the subjects, to use any indispensable means for the suppression of insurrections, rebellion, etc., as also for the due administration of justice in the execution of law. 3. These principles will guide us in ascertaining the right, and of course the duty of governments in relation to war. Observe, war to be in any case a virtue, or to be less than a crime of infinite magnitude, must not only be honestly believed, by those who en- gage in it, to be demanded by the law of benevolence, but it must also be engaged in by them with an eye single to the glory of God, and the iiighest good of being. That war has been in some instances demanded by the spirit of the moral law, there can be no reasonable doubt, since God has sometimes commanded it, which he could not have done had it not been demanded by the highest good of the universe. In such cases, if those who were commanded to engage in war, had benevolent inten- tions in prosecuting it, as God had in commanding it, it is absurd to say that they sinned. Eulers are represented as God's ministers to execute wrath upon the guilty. If, in the providence of God, he should find it duty to destroy or to rebuke a nation for his own glory, and the highest good of being, he may beyond question command that they should be chastised by the hand of man. But in no case is war anything else than a most horrible crime, unless it is plainly the will of God that it should 15 226 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. exist, and unless it be actually undertaken in obedience to his will. This is true of all, both of rulers and of subjects, who engage in war. Selfish war is wholesale murder. For a nation to declare war, or for per3:;ns to enlist, or in any way designedly to aid or abet, in the declaration or pros- ecution of war, upon any other conditions than those just specified, in- volves the guilt of murder. There can scarcely be conceived a more abominable and fiendish maxim than " our country right or wrong." Recently this maxim seems to have been adopted and avowed in relation to the war of the United States with Mexico. It seems to be supposed by some, that it is the duty of good subjects to sympathize with, and support government in the prosecution of a war in which they have unjustly engaged, and to which they have committed themselves, upon the ground that since it is com- menced it must be prosecuted as the less of two evils. The same class of men seem to have adopted the same philosophy in respect to slavery. Slavery, as it exists in this country, they acknowledge to be indefensible on the ground of right. It is a great evil and a great sin, but it must be let alone as the less of two evils. It exists, say they, and it cannot be abolished without disturbing the friendly relations and federal union of the States, therefore the institution must be sustained. The philosophy is this : war and slavery as they exist in this nation are unjust, but they exist, and to sustain. them is duty, because their existence, under the cir- cumstances, is the less of two evils. Nothing can sanctify any crime but that which renders it no crime, but a virtue. But theKphilosophers, whose views I am examining, must, if consistent, take the ground, that since war and slavery exist, although their commencement was unjust and sinful, yet since they exist, it is no jrime but a virtue to sustain them, as the least of two natural evils. But I would ask, to whom are they the least of two evils ? To ourselves or tc being in general ? The least of two present, or of two ultimate evils ? Our duty is not to calculate the evils in respect merely to ourselves, or tf this nation and those immediately oppressed and injured, but to look abroad upon the world and the universe, and inquire what are the evils resulting, and likely to result, to the world, to the church, and to the universe, from the declaration and prosecution of such a war, and from the support of slavery by a nation professing what we profess — a nation boasting of liberty ; who have drawn the sword and bathed it in blood in defence of the principle, that all men have an inalienable right to liberty ; that they are born free and equal. Such a nation proclaiming such a principle, and fighting in the defence of it, standing with its proud foot on the neck of three millions of crushed and prostrate slaves 1 horri- ble ! This a less evil to the world than emancipation, or even than the dismemberment of our hypocritical union 1 " shame, where is tbj HUMAN QOVBBNMENT. ^^1 biush ! " The prosecution of a war, unjustly engaged in, a less evil than repentance and restitution ! It is impossible. Honesty is always and necessarily the best policy. Nations are bound by the same law as indi- viduals. If they have done wrong, it is always duty, and honorable for them to repent, confess and make restitution. To adopt the niaxim, "Our country right or wrong," and to sympathize with the government, in the prosecution of a war unrighteously waged, must involve the guilt of murder. To adopt the maxim, " Our union, even with perpetual slavery," is an abomination so execrable, as not to be named by a just mind without indignation. 4. The same principles apply to governmental sabbath desecration. The sabbath is plainly a divine institution, founded in the necessities of human beings. The letter of the law of the sabbath forbids all labor of every kind, and under all circumstances on that day. But, as has been said in a former lecture, the spirit of the law of the sabbath, being identical with the law of benevolence, sometimes requires the violation of the letter of the law. Both governments and individuals may do, and it is their duty to do, on the sabbath whatever is plainly required by the great law of benevolence. But nothing more, absolutely. No human legislature can nullify the moral law. No human legislation can make it right or lawful to violate any command of God. All human enact- ments requiring or sanctioning the violation of any command of God, are not only null and void, but they are a blasphemous usurpation and invasion of the prerogative of God. 5. The same principles apply to slavery. No human constitution or enactment can, by any possibility, be law, that recognizes the right of one human being to enslave another, in a sense that implies selfishness on the part of the slaveholder. Selfishness is wrong per se. It is, therefore, always and unalterably wrong. No enactment, human or divine, can legalize selfishness and make it right, under any conceivable circum- stances. Slavery or any other evil, to be a crime, must imply selfishness. It must imply a violation of the command, " Thou shalt love thy neigh- bor as thyself." If it implies a breach of this, it is wrong invariably and necessarily, and no legislation, or any thing else, can make it right. God cannot authorize it. The Bible cannot sanction it, and if both God and the Bible were to sanction it, it could not be lawful. God'a arbitrary will is not law. The moral law, as we have seen, is as inde- pendent of his will, as his own necessary existence is. He cannot alter or repeal it. He could not sanctify selfishness and make it right. Nor can any book be received as of divine authority that sanctions selfishness. Gpd and the Bible quoted to sustain and sanctify slaveholding in a sense implying selfishness ! 'Tis blasphemous ! That slaveholding, as it exists in this country, implies selfishness, at least in almost all instances, is too 228 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOaT. plain to need proof. The sinfulness of slaveholding and war, in almoBt all cases, and in every case where the terms slaveholding and war are used in their popular signiiication, will appear irresistibly, if we consider that sin is selfishness, and that all selfishness is necessarily sinful. Deprive a human being of liberty who has been guilty of no crime ; rob him of himself — his body — his soul — his time, and his earnings, to promote the interest of his master, and attempt to justify this on the principles of moral law ! It is the greatest absurdity, and the mo»t revolting wickedness. LECTURE XXII. MORAL DEPEAVITY Ik discussing the subject of human depravity, I shall, — I. Define the term depravity. The word is derived from the Latin de and pravus. Pravus means '* crooked." De is intensive. Depravatus literally and primarily means " very crooked," not in the sense of original or constitutional crooked- ness, but in the sense of having become crooked. The term does not imply original mal-conformation, but lapsed, fallen, departed from right or straight. It always implies deterioration, or fall from a former state of moral »r physical perfection. Depravity always implies a departure from a state of original integ- rity, or from conformity to the laws of the being who is the subject of depravity. Thus we should not consider that being depraved, who remained in a state of conformity to the original laws of his being, phys- ical and moral. But we justly call a being depraved, who has departed from conformity to those laws, whether those laws be physical or moral, II, Point out the distinction between physical and moral depxavity. Physical depravity, as the word denotes, is the depravity of constitu tion, or substance, as distinguished from depravity of free moral action. It may be predicated of body or of mind. Physical depravity, when predicated of the body, is commonly and rightly called disease. It con- sists in a physical departure from the laws of health ; a lapsed, or fallen state, in which healthy organic action is not sustained, < When physical depravity is predicated of mind, it is intended that the powers of the mind, either in substance, or in consequence of theii MORAL DEPRAVITr. 223 connection with, and dependence upon, the body, are ii a diseased, lapsed, fallen, degenerate state, so that the healthy action of those powers is not sustained. Physical depravity, being depravity of substance as oj posed to de- pravity of the actions of free-will, can have no moral charac ter. It may as we shall see, be caused by moral depravity ; and a moral agent may be blameworthy for having rendered himself physically depraved, either in body or mind. But physical depravity, whether of body or of mind, can have no moral character in itself, for the plain reason that it is in- voluntary, and in its nature is disease, and not sin. Let this be re- membered. Moral depravity is the depravity of free-will, not of the fiiculty itself, but of its free action. It consists in a violation of moral law. Depravity of the will, as a faculty, is, or would be, physical, and net moral de- pravity. It would be depravity of substance, and not of free, responsible choice. Moral depravity is depravity of choice. It is a choice at variance with moral law, moral right. It is synonymous with sin oi sinfulness. It is moral depravity, because it consists in a violation of moral law, and because it has moral character. III. Of what physical depravity can he predicated. 1. It can be predicated of any organized substance. That is, every organized substance is liable to become depraved. Depravity is a possi- ble state of every organized body or substance in existence. 3. Physical depravity may be predicated of mind, as has already been said, especially in its connection with an organized body. As mind, in connection with body, manifests itself through it, acts by means of it, and is dependent upon it, it is plain that if the body become diseased, or physically depraved, the mind cannot but be affected by this state of the body, through and by means of which it acts. The normal manifesta- tions of mind cannot, in such case, be reasonably expected. Physical depravity may be predicated of all the involuntary states of the intellect, and of the sensibility. That is, the actings and states of the intellect may become disordered, depraved, deranged, or fallen from the state of integrity and healthiness. This every one knows, as it is matter of daily experience and observation. Whether this in all cases is, and must be, caused by the state of the bodily organization, that is, whether it is always and necessarily to be ascribed to the depraved state of the brain and nervoas system, it is impossible for us to know. It may, for aught we know, in some instances at least, be a depravity or derangement of the substance of the mind itself. The sensibility, or feeling department of the mind, may be sadly and physically depraved. This is a matter of common experience, Tlxe 230 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. appetites and passions, the desires and cravings, the antipathies and repellencies of the feelings fall into great disorder and anarchy. Numer- ous artificial appetites are generated, and the whole sensibility becomes a wilderness, a chaos of conflicting and clamorous desires, emotions and passions. That this state of the sensibility is often, and perhaps in some measure always, owing to the state of the nervous system with which it is connected, through and by which it manifests itself, there can be but little room to doubt. But whether this is always and necessarily so, no one can tell. We know that the sensibility manifests great physical de- pravity. Whether this depravity belong exclusively to the body, or to the mind, or to both in conjunction, I will not venture to affirm. In the present state of our knowledge, or of my knowledge, I dare not hazard an affirmation upon the sabject. The human body is certainly in a state of physical depravity. The human mind also certainly manifests physi- cal depravity. But observe, physical depravity has in no case any moral character, because it is involuntary. IV. Of what moral depravity can he predicated. 1. Not of substance ; for over involuntary substance the moral law does not directly legislate. 2. Moral depravity cannot be predicated of any involuntary acts or ^tates of mind. These surely cannot be violations of moral law apart .^om the ultimate intention ; for moral law legislates directly only over free, intelligent choices. 3. Moral depravity cannot be predicated of any unintelligent act of will, that is, of acts of will that are put forth in a state of idiocy, of mtellectual derangement, or of sleep. Moral depravity implies moral obligation ; moral obligation implies moral agency ; and moral agency implies intelligence, or knowledge of moral relations. Moral agency im- plies moral law, or the development of the idea of duty, and a knowl- edge of what duty is. 4. Moral depravity can only be predicated of violations of moral law, and of the free volitions by which those violations are perpetrated. Moral law, as we have seen, requires love, and only love, to God and man, or to God and the universe. This love, as we have seen, is goo.d- will, choice, the choice of an end, the choice of the highest well-being of God, and of the universe of sentient existences. Moral depravity is sin. Sin is a violation of moral law. We have seen that sin must consist in choice, in the choice of self-indulgence or self-gratification as an end. 5. Moral depravity cannot consist in any attribute of nature or con- stitution, nor in any lapsed and fallen state of nature ; for this is physical and not moral depravity. MORAL CEPKAVITY. 231 6. It cannot consist in anything that is an original and essential part of mtndj or of body ; nor in any involuntary action or state of either mind or body. 7. It cannot consist in anything back of choice, and that sustains to choice the relation of a cause. Whatever is back of choice, is without the pale of legislation. The law of God, as has been said, requires good- willing only ; and sure it is, that nothing but acts of will can constitute a violation of jnoral law. Outward actions, and involuntary thoughts and feelings, may be said in a certain isense to possess moral character because they are produced by the will. But, strictly speaking, moral character belongs only to choice, or intention. It was shown in a former lecture, that sin does not, and cannot con- sist in malevolence, properly speaking, or in the choice of sin or misery as an end, or for its own sake. It was also shown, that all sin consists, and must consist in selfishness, or in the choice of self-gratification as a final end. Moral depravity then, strictly speaking, can only be predicated of selfish ultimate intention. Moral depravity, as I use the term, does not consist in, nor imply a sinful nature, in the sense that the substance of the human soul is sinful in itself. It is not a constitutional sinfulness. It is not an involuntary sinfulness. Moral depravity, as I use the term, consists in selfishness ; in a state of voluntary committal of the will to self-gratification. It is a spirit of self-seeking, a voluntary and entire consecration to the gratifica- tion of self. It is selfish ultimate intention ; it is the choice of a wrong end of life ; it is moral depravity, because it is a violation of moral law. It is a refusal to consecrate the whole being to the highest well-being of God and of the universe, and obedience to the moral law, and consecrat- ing it to the gratification of self. Moral depravity sustains to the out- ward life, the relation of a cause. This selfish intention, or the will in this committed state, of course, makes efforts to secure its end, and these efforts make up the outward life of the selfish man. Moral depravity is sinfulness, not of nature but of voluntary state. It is a sinfully com- mitted state of the willto self-indulgence. It is not a sinful nature but a sinful heart. It is a sinful ultimate aim, or intention. The Greek term amartia, rendered sin in our English Bible, signifies to miss the mark, to aim at the wrong end. Sin is a wrong aim, or intention. It ia aiming at, or intending self-gratification as the ultimate and supreme end of life, instead of aiming, as the moral law requires, at the highest good of universal being, as the end of life. V. Manhind are both physically and morally depraved. 1. There is, in all probability, no , perfect health of body among all the ranks and classes of human beings that inhabit this world. The 232 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOaY. physical organization of the whole race has become impaired, and boyci-d all doubt has been becoming more and more so since intemperance cf any kind was first introduced into our world. This is illustrated and con- firmed by the comparative shortness of human life. This is a physiiilo- gical fact. 2. As the human mind in this state of existence is dependent ii.pon the body for all its manifestations, and as the human body is universa'ly in a state of greater or less physical depravity or disease, it.follows that the manifestations of mind thns dependent on a physically depraved or- ganization, will be physically depraved manifestations. Especially is this true of the human sensibility. The appetites, passions, and propensities are in a state of most unhealthy development. This is too evident, and too much a matter of universal notoriety, to need proof or illustration. Every person of reflection has observed, that the human mind is greatly out of balance, in consequence of the monstrous development of the sen- sibility. The appetites, passions, and propensities have been indulged, and the intelligence and conscience stultified by selfishness. Selfishness, be it reniembered, consists in a disposition or choice to gratify the pro- pensities, desires, and feelings. This of course, and of necessity, pro- duces just the unhealthy and monstrous developments which we daily see : sometimes one ruling passion or appetite lording it, not only over the intelligence and over the will, but over all the other appetites and passions, crushing and sacrificing them all upon the altar of its own grat- ification. See that bloated wretch, the inebriate ! His appetite for strong drink has played the despot. His whole mind and body, reputa- tion, family, friends, health, time, eternity, all, all are laid by him upon its filthy altar. There is the debauchee, the glutton, the gambler, the miser, and a host of others, each in his turn giving striking and melan- choly proof of the monstrous development and physical depravity cf the human sensibility. 3. That men are morally depraved is one of the most notorious facts of human experience, observation and history. Indeed, I am not awire that it has ever been donbted, when moral depravity has been understood to consist in selfishness. The moral depravity of the human race is everywhere assumed and declared in the Bible, and so universal and notorious is the fact of human selfishness, that should any man practically call it in question — should he, in his business transactions, and in his intercourse with men, assume the contrary, he would justly subject himself to the charge of insanity. There is not a fact in the world more notorious and undeniable than this. Hu- man moral depravity is as palpably evident as human existence. It 3 a fact everywhere assumed in all governments, in all the arrangements of MORAL DBPRAVITT. 233 society, and it has impressed its image, and written its name, upon every thing human. VI. Subsequent to the commencement of moral agency, and previous to regeneration, the moral depravity of mankind is universal. By this it is not intended to deny that, in some instances, the Spirit of God may, from the first moment of moral agency, have so enlightened the mind as to have secured conformity to moral law, as the first moi'al act. This may or may not be true. It is not my present purpose to affirm or to deny this, as a possibility, or as a fact. But by this is intended, that every moral agent of our race is, from the dawn of moral agency to the moment of regeneration by the Holy Spirit, morally depraved, unless we except those possible cases just alluded to. The Bible exhibits proof of it — 1. In those passages that represent all the unregenerate as possessing one common wicked heart or character. " And God saw that the wick- edness of man was great in the earth, and that every imagination of the thoughts of his heart was only evil continually." — Gen. vi. 5. " This ia an evil among all things that are done under the sun, that there is one event unto all : yea, also the heart of the sons of men is full of evil, and madness is in their heart while they live, and after that they go to the dead." — Eccl. ix. 3. " The heart is deceitful above all things and des. perately wicked : who can know it ? " — Jer. xvii. 9. " Because the car- nal mind is enmity against God : for it is not subject to the law of God, neither indeed can be." — Rom. viii. 1. 2. In those passages that declare the universal necessity of regenera- tion. "Jesus answered and said unto him. Verily, verily, I say unto thee. Except a man be born again, he cannot see the kingdom of God."— John iii. 3. 3. Passages tjiat expressly assert the universal moral depravity of all unregenerate moral agents of our race. " What then ? are we better than they ? No, in no wise : for we have before proved both Jews and Gentiles, that they are all under sin ; as it is written. There is none righteous, no, not one. There is none that understandeth, there is none that seeketh after God. They are all gone out of the way, they are to- gether become unprofitable ; there is none that doeth good, no not one. Their throat is an open sepulchre ; with their tongues they have used deceit ; the poison of asps is under their lips : whose mouth is full of sursing and bitterness : their feet are swift to shed blood : destruction »nd misery are in their ways : and the way of peace have they not known: ihere is no fear of God before their eyes. Now we know that what things ioever the law saith, it saith to them who are under the law : that every wonth may be stopped, and all the world may become guilty before God. 234: SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. Therefore hy the deeds of the law there shall no flesh be justified in his sight ; for by the law is the knowledge of sin." — Eom. iii. 9 — 20. 4. Universal history proves it. What is this world's history but the ehameless chronicle of human wickedness ? 5. Universal observation attests it. Who ever saw one unregenerate human being that was not selfish, that did not obey his feelings rather than the law of his intelligence, that was not under some form, or in some way, living to please self ? Such an unregenerate human being, 1 may safely afiirm, was never seen since the fall of Adam. 6. I may also appeal to the universal consciousness of the unregener- ate. They know themselves to be selfish, to be aiming to please them- selves, and they cannot honestly deny it. VII. The moral depravity of the unregenerate moral agents of our race, is total. By this is intended, that the moral depravity of the unregenerate is without any mixture of moral goodness or virtue, that while they remain unregenerate, they never in any instance, nor in any degree, exercise true love to God and to man. It is not intended, that they may not per- form many outward actions, and have many inward feelings, that are such as the regenerate perform and experience : and such too as are ac- counted virtue by those who place virtue in the outward action. But it is intended, that virtue does not consist either in involuntary feelings or in outward actions, and that it consists alone in entire consecration of heart and life to God and the good of being, and that no unregenerate sinner previous to regeneration, is or can be, for one moment, in this state. When virtue is clearly seen to consist in the heart's entire consecra- - tion to God and the good of being, it must be seen, that the unregenerate are not for one moment in»this state. It is amazing, that some philoso- phers and theologians have admitted and maintained, that the unregen- erate do sometimes do that which is truly virtuous. But in these admis- sions they necessarily assume a false philosophy, and overlook that in which all virtue does and must consist, namely, supreme ultimate inten- tion. They speak of virtuous actions and of virtuous feelings, as if vir- tue consisted in them, and not in the intention. Henry P. Tappan, for example, for the most part an able, truthful, and beautiful writer, assumes, or rather aflBrms, that volitions may be put forth inconsistent with, and contrary to the present choice of an end, and that consequently, unregenerate sinners, whom he admits to be in the exercise of a selfish choice of an end, may and do sometimes put forth right voHtions, and perform right actions, that is, right in the sense of virtuous actions. But let us examine this subject. We have MORAL DEPRAVITY. 235 eeen that all choice and all Tolition must respect either an end or means, that isj that everything willed or chosen, is willed or chosen for some reason. To deny this, is the same as to deny that anything is willed or chosen, because the ultimate reason for a choice and the thing chosen are identical. Therefore, it is plain, as was shown in a former lecture, that the will cannot embrace at the same time, two opposite ends ; and that while but one end is chosen, the will cannot put forth volitions to secure some other end, which end is not yet chosen. In other words, it certainly is absurd to say, that the will, while maintaining the chcAce of one end, can use means for the accomplishment of another and op- posite end. When an end is chosen, that choice confines all volition to securing its accomplishment, and for the time being, and until another end is chosen, and this one relinquished, it is impossible for the will to put forth any volition inconsistent with the present choice. It therefore follows, that while sinners are selfish, or unregenerate, it is impossible for them to put forth a holy volition. They are under the necessity of first changing their hearts, or their choice of an end, before they can put forth any volitions to secure any other than a selfish end. And this is plainly the everywhere assumed philosophy of the Bible. That uniformly represents the unregenerate as totally depraved, and calls upon them to repent, to make to themselves a new heart ; and never admibs directly, or by way of implication, that they can do anything good or acceptable to God, while in the exercise of a wicked or selfish heart. LECTURE XXIII. MORAL DEPRAVITY. VIII. Let US consider the proper method of accounting for the univer- sal and total moral depravity of the unregenerate moral agents of our race. In the discussion of this subject, I will — 1. Endeavor to show how it is not to be accounted for. In examining this part of the subject, it is necessary to have distinctly in view that which constitutes moral depravity. All the error that has existed upon this subject, has been founded in false assumptions in regard to the nature or essence of moral depravity. It has been almost universally true, that no distinction has been made between moral and physical depravity ; and consequently, physical depravity has been con- 236 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. founded with and treated of, as moral depravity. This of course has led to vast confusion and nonsense upon this subject. Let the following fact, which has been shown in former lectures, be distinctly borne in mind. That moral depravity consists in selfishness, or in the choice of self- interest, self-gratification, or self-indulgence, as an end. Consequently it cannot consist, (1.) In a sinful constitution, or in a constitutional appetency or crav- ing for sin. This has been shown in a former lecture, on what is not implied in disobedience to the moral law. (3.) Moral depravity is sin itself, and not the cause of sin. It is not something prior to sin, that sustains to it the relation of a cause, but it is the essence and the whole of sin. (3.) It cannot be an attribute of human nature, considered simply as such, for this would be physical, and not moral depravity, (4.) Moral depravity is not then to be accounted for by ascribing it to a nature or constitution sinful in itself. To talk of a sinful nature, or sinful constitution, in the sense of physical sinfulness, is to ascribe sinfulness to the Creator, who is the author of nature. It is to overlook the essential nature of sin, and to make sin a physical virus, instead of a voluntary and responsible choice. Both sound philosophy and the Bible, make sin to consist in obeying the flesh, or in the spirit of self-pleasing, or self-indulgence, or, which is the same thing, in selfishness — in a car- nal mind, or in minding the flesh. But writers on moral depravity have assumed, that moral depravity was distinct from, and the cause of sin, that is, of actual transgression. They call it original sin, indwelling sin, a sinful nature, an appetite for sin, an attribute of human nature, and the like. We shall presently see what has led to this view of the subject. I will, in the next place, notice a modern, and perhaps the most popular view of this subject, which has been taken by any late writer, who has fallen into the error of confounding physical and moral deprav- ity. I refer to the prize essay of Dr. Woods, of Andover, Mass. He defines moral depravity to be the same as " sinfulness." He also, in one part of his essay, holds and maintains, that it is always and necessarily, voluntary. Still, his great effort is to prove that sinfulness or moral depravity, is an attribute of human nature. It is no part of my design to expose the inconsistency of holding moral depravity to be a voluntary state of mind, and yet a natural attribute, but only to examine the philosophy, the logic, and theory of his main argument. The following quotation will show the sense in which he holds moral depravity to belong to the nature of man. At page 54 he says : — " The word depravity, relating as it here does to man's moral char- MORAL DEPKAVlTt. 237 acter, means the same as sinfulness, being the opposite of moi al purity, or holiness. In this use of the word there is a general agreement. But what is the meaning of native, or natural ? Among the variety of mean- ings specified by Johnson, Webster, and others, I refer to the following, as relating particularly to the subject before us. " Native. Produced by nature. Natural, or such as is according to nature ; belonging by birth ; original. Natural has substantially the same meaning : * produced by nature ; not acquired.' — So Crabbe: 'Of a person we say, his worth is native, to designate it as some i valuable property born with him, not foreign to him, or ingrafted upon him ; but we say of his disposition, that it is natural, as opposed to that which is acquired by habit. ' And Johnson defines nature to be ' the native state or properties of any thing, by which it is discriminated from others. ' He quotes the definition of Boyle : ' Nature sometimes means what be- longs to a living creature at its nativity, or accrues to it by its birth, as when we say a man is noble by nature, or a child is naturally froward." ' This,' he says, 'may be expressed by saying, the man was born so.' " After these brief definitions, which come to nearly the same thing, I proceed to inquire, what are the marks or evidences which show any- thing in man to be natural, or native ; and how far these marks are found in relation to depravity." Again, page 66, he says : — " The evil, then, cannot be supposed to originate in any unfavorable external circumstances, such as corrupting examples, or insinuating and strong temptations ; for if we suppose these entirely removed, all human beings would still be sinners. With such a moral nature as they now have, they would not wait for strong temptations to sin. Nay, they would be sinners in opposition to the strongest motives to the contrary. Indeed, we know that human beings will turn those very motives which most powerfully urge to holiness, into occasions of sin. Now, does not the confidence and certainty with which we foretell the commission of sin, and of sin unmixed with moral purity, presuppose a full conviction in us, and a conviction resting upon what we regard as satisfactory evi- dence, that sin, in all its visible actings, arises from that which is within the mind itself, and which belongs to our very nature as moral beings ? Have we not as much evidence that this is the case with moral evil as with any of our natural affections or bodily appetites ? " This quotation, together with the whole argument, shows that he considers moral depravity to be an attribute of human nature, in the same sense that the appetites and passions are. Before I proceed directly to the examination of his argument, that sinfulness, or moral depravity, is an "attribute of human nature," I would premise, that an argument, or fact, that may equally well consist 238 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. with either of two opposing theories, can prove neither. The author in question presents the following facts and considerations in support of his great position, that moral depravity, or sinfulness, is an attribute of human nature ; and three presidents of colleges indorse the soundness and conclusiveness of the argument. He proves his position — first from the "universality of moral de- pravity." To this I answer, that this argument proves nothing to the purpose, unless it be true, and assumed as a major premise, that what- ever is universal among mankind, must be a natural attribute of man as such ; that whatever is common to all men, must be an attribute of human nature. But this assumption is a begging of the question. Sin may be the result of temptation ; temptation may be universal, and of such a nature as uniformly, not necessarily, to result in sin, unless a con- trary result be secured by a Divine moral suasion. This I shall endeavor to show is the fact. This argument assumes, that there is but one method of accounting for the universality of human sinfulness. But this is the question in debate, and is not to be thus assumed as true. Again : Selfishness is common to all unregenerate men. Is selfish- ness a natural attribute ? We have seen, in a former lecture, that it consists in choice. Can choice be an attribute of human nature ? Again : This argument is just as consistent with the opposite theory, to wit, that moral depravity is selfishness. The universality of selfish- ness is just what might be expected, if selfishness consists in the com- mittal of the will to the gratification of self. This will be a thing of course, unless the Holy Spirit interpose, greatly to enlighten the intel- lect, and break up the force of habit, and change the attitude of the will, already, at the first dawn of reason, committed to the impulses of the sensibility. If moral depravity is to be accounted for, as I shall hereafter more fully show, by ascribing it to the influence of temptation, or to a physically depraved constitution, surrounded by the circumstances in which mankind first form their moral character, or put forth their first moral choices, universality might of course be expected to be one of its characteristics. This argument, then, agreeing equally well with either theory, proves neither. His second argument is, that " Moral depravity developes itself in early life." Answer : — This is just what might be expected upon the opposite theory. If moral depravity consist in the choice of self-gratification, it would of course appear in early life. So this argument agrees quite as well with the opposing theory, and therefore proves nothing. But — this argument is good for nothing, unless the following be assumed as a major premise, and unless the fact assumed be indeed a truth, namely, " Whatever is developed in early life, must be an attribute of hitman nature." But MORAL DEPRAVITY. 239 this again is assuming the truth of the point in detate. This argument is based upon the assumption that a course of action common to all men, and commencing at the earliest moment of their moral .igency, can bo accounted for only by ascribing it to an attribute of nature, having the same moral character as that which belongs to the actions themselves. But this is not true. There may be more than one way of accounting for the universal sinfulness of human actions from the dawn of moral agency. It may be ascribed to the universality and peculiar nature of iemptation, as has been said. His third argument is, that "Moral depravity is not owing to any jhange that occurs subsequent to birth." Answer : — No, the circumstances of temptation are sufficient to account for it without supposing the nature to be changed. This argument proves aothing, unless it be true, that the peculiar circumstances of temptation under which moral agents act, from the dawn of moral agency, cannot sufficiently account for their conduct, without supposing a change of nature subsequent to birth. " "What then, does this arguing prove ? " Again, this argument is just as consistent 'with the opposing theory, and therefore proves neither. His fourth argument is, " That moral depravity acts freely and spon- taneously." Answer : — " The moral agent acts freely, and acts selfishly, that is, wickedlifc This argument assumes, thp,t if a moral agent acts freely and wickedly, moral depravity, or sin, must be an attribute of his nature. Or more fairly, if mankind universally, in the exercise of their liberty, act sin- fully, sinfulness must be an attribute of human nature." But what is sin ? "Why sin is a voluntary transgression of law, Dr. "Woods being judge. Can a voluntary transgression of law be denominated an attri- bute of human nature ? But again, this argument alleges nothing but what is equally consist- ent with the opposite theory. If moral depravity consist in the choice of self-gratification as an end, it would of course freely and spontaneously manifest itself. This argument then, is good for nothing. His fifth argument is, " That moral depravity is hard to overcome, and therefore it must bo an attribute of human nature." Answer : — If it were an attribute of human nature, it could not be overcome at all, without a change of the human constitution. It is hard to overcome, just as selfishness naturally would be, in beings of a physically depraved constitution, and in the presence of so many temptations to self- indulgence. If it were an attribute of human nature, it could not be overcome without a change of personal identity. But the fact that it can be overcome without destroying the consciousness of personal iden- tity, proves that it is not an attribute of human nature. 24:0 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. His sixth argument is, that " We can predict with certainty, that in due time it will act itself out." Answer : — Just as might be expected. If moral depravity consists in selfishness, ■we can predict with certainty, that the spirit of self-pleasing will, in due time, and at all times, act itself out. We can also predict, without the gift of prophecy, that with a constitution physically depraved, and sur- rounded with objects to awaken appetite, and with all the circumstances in which human beings first form their moral character, they will seek universally to gratify themselves, unless prevented by the illuminations of the Holy Spirit. This argument is just as consistent with the oppo- site theory, and therefore proves neither. It is unnecessary to occupy any more time with the treatise of Dr. Woods. I will now quote the standards of the Presbyterian church, which will put you in possession of their views upon this subject. At pp. 30, 31, of the Presbyterian Confession of Faith, we have the follow- ing : "By this sin, they (Adam and Eve) fell from their original right- eousness and communion with God, and so became dead in sin, and wholly defiled in all the faculties and parts of soul and body. They being the root of all mankind, the guilt of this sin was imputed, and the same death in sin and corrupted nature conveyed to all their posterity, descending from them by ordinary generation. From this original cor- ruption, whereby we are utterly indisposed, disabled, and made opposite to all good, and wholly inclined to all evil, do proceed all actual trans- gressions." Again, pp. 152-154, Shorter Catechism. "Question 33. Did all mankind fall in that first transgression ? Ans. The covenant being made with Adam as a public person, not for himself only, but for his posterity ; all mankind descending from him by ordinary generation, sinned in him, and fell with him in that first transgression. " Question 33. Into what estate did the fall bring mankind ? Ans. The fall brought mankind into an estate of sin and misery. "Question 34. What is sin ? Ans. Sin is any want of conformity unto, or transgression of, any law of God, given as a rule to the reasona- ble creature. " Question 35. Wherein consists the sinfulness of that estate where- into man fell ? Ans. The sinfulness of that estate whereinto man fell, consisteth in the guilt of Adam's first sin, the want of that righttionsness wherein he was created, and the corruption of his nature, whereby he is utterly indisposed, disabled, and made opposite unto all that is spiritu- ally good, and wholly inclined to all evil, and that continually, which is commonly called original sin, and from which do proceed all actual transgressions. " Question 26. How is original sin conveyed from our first parents MORAL DEPBAVIT?. 24. unto their posterity ? Ans. Original sin is conveyed from our first parents unto their posterity by natural generation, so as all that proceed from them in that way, are conceived and born in sin." These extracts show, that the framers and defenders of this confes- sion of faith, account f 6r the moral depravity of mankind by making it to consist in a sinful nature, inherited by natural generation from Adam. They regard the constitution inherited from Adam, as in itself sinful, and the cause of all actual transgression. They make no distinction between physical and moral depravity. They also distinguish between original and actual sin. Original sin is the sinfulness of the constitution, in which Adam's posterity have no other hand than to inherit it by nat- ural generation, or by birth. This original sin, or sinful nature, renders mankind utterly disabled from all that is spiritually good, and wholly inclined to all that is evil. This is their account of moral depravity. This, it will be seen, is substantially the ground of Dr. Woods. It has been common with those who confound physical with moral depravity, and who maintain that human nature is itself sinful, to quote certain passagtis of Scripture to sustain their position. An examination of these proof texts, must, in the next place, occupy our attention. But before I enter upon this examination, I must first call your attention to certain well settled rules of biblical interpretation. (1.) DifEerent passages must be so intei-preted, if they can be, as not to contradict each other. (2.) Language is to be interpreted according to the subject matter of discourse. (3.) Bespect is always to be had to the general scope and design of the speaker or writer. (4.) Texts that are consistent with either theory, prove neither. (5.) Language is to be so interpreted, if it can be, as not to conflict with sound philosophy, matters of fact, the nature of things, or immu- table justice. Let us now, remembering and applying these plain rules of sound interpretation, proceed to the examination of those passages that are sup- posed to establish the theory of depravity I am examining. Gen. V. 3. — " Adam lived an hundred and thirty years, and begat a son in his own likeness and after his own image, and called his name Seth." It is, not very easy to see, why this text should be pressed into the service of those who hold that human nature is in itself sinful. Why should it be assumed that the likeness and image here spoken of was a moral likeness or image ? But unless this be assumed, the text has nothing to do with the subject. Again : it is generally admitted, that in all probability Adam was a regenerate man at the time and before the birth of Seth. Is it intended 16 242 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. that Adam begat a saint or a sinner ? If, as is supposed, Adam was & saint of God, if this text is anything to the purpose, it affirms that Adam ' begat a saint. But this is the opposite of that in proof of which the text is quoted. Another text is, Job xiv. 4. — " Who can bring a clean thing out of an unclean ? Not one." This text is quoted in support of the position of the Presbyterian Confession of Faith, that children inherit from their parents, by natui-al generation, a sinful nature. Upon this text, I re- mark, that all that can be made of it, even if we read it without regard to the translation or the context, is, that a physically depraved parent will produce a physically depraved offspring. That this is its real mean- ing,, is quite evident, when we look into the context. Job is treating of the frail and dying state of man, and manifestly has in the text and con- text his eye wholly on the physical state, and not on the moral character of man. What he intends is ; who can bring other than a frail, dying offspring from a frail dying parent ? Kot one. This is substantially the view that Professor Stuart takes of this text. The utmost that can be made of it is, that as he belonged to a race of sinners, nothing else could be expected than that he should be a sinner, without meaning to affirm anything in regard to the quo modo of this result. Again : Job xv. 14. — " What is man that he should be clean, and he that is born of a woman that he should be righteous." These are the words of Bliphaz, and it is improper to quote them as inspired truth. For God himself testifies that Job's friends did not hold the truth. But, suppose we receive the text as true, what is its import ? Why, it simply asserts, or rather implies, the righteousness or sinfulness of the whole human race. It expresses the universality of human de- pravity, in the very common way of including all that are born of woman. This certainly says nothing, and implies nothing, respecting a sinful con- stitution. It is just as plain, and just as warrantable, to undersband this passage as implying that mankind have become so physically depraved, that this fact, together with the circumstances under which they come into being, and begin their moral career, will certainly, (not necessarily,) result in moral depravity. I might use just such language as that found in this text, and, naturally enough, express by it my own views of moral depravity, to wit, that it results from a physically depraved constitution ; and the circumstances of temptation under which children come into this world, and begin and prosecute their moral career ; certainly this is the most that can be made of this text. Again : Psalm li. 5. — " Behold, I was shapen in iniquity, and in sin did my mother conceive me." Upon this I remark, that it would seem, if this text is to be under- stood literally, that the Psalmist intended to affirm the sinful state of his MORAL DEPRAVITY. 243 mother, at the time of his conception, and during gestation. But, to interpret these passages as teaching the constitutional sinfulness of man, is to contradict God's own definition of sin, and the only definition that human reason or common sense can receive, to wit, that " sin is a trans- gression of the law." This is, no doubt, the only correct definition of sin. But we have seen that the law does not legislate over substance, requir- ing men to have a certain nature, but over voluntary action only. If the Psalmist really intended to affirm, that the substance of his body was sinful from its conception, then he not only arrays himself against God's own definition of sin, but he also affirms sheer nonsense. The substance of an unborn child sinful ! It is impossible 1 But what did the Psalm- ist mean ? I answer : This verse is found in David's penitential psalm. He was deeply convinced of sin, and was, as he had good reason to be, much excited, and expressed himself, as we all do in similar circum- stances, in strong language. His eye, as was natural and is common in such cases, had been directed back along the pathway of life up to the days of his earliest recollection. He remembered sins among the earli- est acts of his recollected life. He broke out in the language of this text to express, not the anti-scriptural and nonsensical dogma of a sinful con- stitution, but to affirm in his strong, poetic language, that he had been a sinner from the commencement of his moral existence, or from the earli- est moment of his capability of being a sinner. This is the strong language of poetry. Some suppose that, in the passage in question, the Psalmist referred to, and meant to acknowledge and assert, his low and despicable origin, and to say, I was always a sinner, and my mother that conceived me was a sinner, and I am but the degenerate plant of a strange vine, without intending to affirm anything in respect to the absolute sinfulness of his nature. Again, Ps. Iviii. 3. " The wicked are estranged from the womb ; they go astray as soon as they be born, speaking lies." Upon this text I remark that it has been quoted at one time to establish the doctrine of a sinful nature, and at another to prove that infants commit actual sin from the very day and hour of their birth. But certainly no such use can be legitimately made of this text. It does not affirm anything of a sinful nature, but this has been inferred from what it does affirm, that the wicked are estranged from their birth. But does this mean, that they are really and literally estranged from the day and hour of their birth, and that they really go astray the very day they are bom, speaking lies ? This every one knows to be contrary to fact. The text cannot then be pressed to the letter. What then does it mean ? It must mean, like the text last examined, that the wicked are estranged and go astray from the commencement of their moral agency. 24-i SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. If it means more than this, it would contradict other plain passages of scripture. It aflBrms, in strong, graphic, and poetic language, the fact, that the first moral conduct and character of children is sinful. This is all that in truth it can assert ; and it doubtless dates the beginning of their moral depravity at a very early period, and expresses it in very strong language, as if it were literally from the hour of birth. But when it adds, that they go astray, speaking lies, we know that this is not, and cannot be, literally taken, for, as every one knows, children do not speak at all from their birth. Should we understand the Psalmist as aflSrming, that children go astray as soon as they go at all, and speak lies as soon as they speak at all, this would not prove that their nature was in itself sinful, but might well consist with the theory that their physical depravity, together with their circumstances of temptation, led them into selfishness, from the very first moment of their moral existence. Again, John iii. 6. "That which is bom of the flesh is flesh, and that which is born of the Spirit is spirit." Upon this I remark that it may, if literally taken, mean nothing more than this, that the body which is born of flesh is flesh, and that that which is born of the Spirit is spirit ; that is, that this birth of which he was speaking was of the soul, and not of the body. But it may be understood to mean, that that which results from the influence of the flesh is flesh, in the sense of sin ; for this is a common sense of the term flesh in the New Testament, and that which results from the Spirit, is spirit or spiritual, in the sense of holy. This I understand to be the true sense. The text when thus understood, does not at all support the dogma of a sinful nature or constitution, but only this, that the flesh tends to sin, that the appetites and passions are temptations to sin, so that when the will obeys them it sins. Whatever is born of the pro- pensities, in the sense that the will yields to their control, is sinful. And, on the other hand, whatever is bom of the Spirit, that is, whatever results from the agency of the Holy Spirit, in the sense that the will yields to Him, is holy. Again, Eph. ii. 3. "By nature the children of wrath, even as others. " Upon this text I remark that it cannot, consistently with natural justice, be understood to mean, that we are exposed to the wrath of God on account of our nature. It is a monstrous and blasphemous dogma, that a holy God is angry with any creature for possessing a nature with which he was sent into being without his knowledge or consent. The Bible represents God as angry with men for their wicked deeds, and not for their nature. It is common and proper to speak of the first state in which men universally are, as a natural state. Thus we speak of sinners before regeneration, as in a state of nature, as opposed to a changed state MORAL DEPRAVITY. 245 a regenerate state, and a state of grace. By this we do not necessarily mean, that they have a nature sinful in itself, but merely that before regeneration they are universally and morally depraved, that this is their natural, as opposed to their regenerate state. Total moral deprav- ity is the state that follows, and results from their first birth, and is in this sense natural, and in this sense alone, can it truly be said, that they are " by nature children of wrath." Against the use that is made of this text, and all this class of texts, may be arrayed the whole scope of scripture, that represents man as to blame, and to be judged and punished only for his deeds. The subject matter of discourse in these texts is such as to demand that we should understand them as not implying, or asserting, that sin is an essential part of our nature. LECTURE XXIV. MORAL DEPRAVITY. Further examination of the arguments adduced in support of the position, that human nature is in itself sinful. The defenders of the doctrine of constitutional sinfulness, or moral depravity, urge as an additional argument : — That sin is a universal effect of human nature, and therefore human nature must be itself sinful. Answer : — This is a non sequitur. Sin may be, and must be, an abuse of free agency ; and this may be accounted for, as we shall see, by ascribing it to the universality of temptation, and does not at all imply a sinful con- stitution. But if sin necessarily implies a sinful nature, how did Adam and Eve sin ? Had they a sinful nature to account for, and to cause their first sin ? How did angels sin ? Had they also a sinful nature ? Either sin does not imply a sinful nature, or a nature in itself sinful, or Adam and angels must have had sinful natures before their fall. Again : Suppose we regard sin as an event or effect. An effect only implies an adequate cause. Free, responsible will is an adequate cause in the presence of temptation, without the supposition of a sinful consti- tution, as has been demonstrated in the case of Adam and of angels. When we have found an adequate cause, it is unphilosophical to look for and assign another. Again : it is said that no motive to sin could be a motive or a tempta- tion, if there were not a sinful taste, relish, or appetite, inherent in the 24:6 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. constitution, to which the temptation or motive is addressed. For ex- ample, the presence of food, it is said, would be no temptation to eat, were there not a constitutional appetency terminating on food. So the presence of any object could be no inducement to sin, were there not a constitutional appetency or craving for sin. So that, in fact, sin in action were impossible, unless there were sin in the nature. To this I reply,— Suppose this objection be applied to the sin of Adam and of angels. Can we not account for Eve's eating the forbidden fruit without suppos- ing that she had a craving for sin ? The Bible informs us that her crav- ing was for the fruit, for knowledge, and not for sin. The words are, — " And when the woman saw that the tree was good for food, and that it was pleasant to the eyes, and a tree to be desired to make one wise, she took of the fruit thereof and did eat, and gave also unto her husband with her, and he did eat." Here is nothing of a craving for sin. Eating this fruit was indeed sinful ; but the sin consisted in consenting to gratify, in a prohibited manner, the appetites, not for sin, but for food and knowledge. But the advocates of this theory say that there must be an adaptedress in the constitution, a something within answering to the outward motive or temptation, otherwise sin were impossible. This is true. But the question is. What is that something within, which re- sponds to the outward motive ? . Is it a craving for sin ? We have just seen what it was in the case of Adam and Eve. It was simply the cor- relation that existed between the fruit and their constitution, its presence exciting the desires for food and knowledge. This led to prohibited in- dulgence. But all men sin in precisely the same way. They consent to gratify, not a craving for sin, but a craving for other things, and the consent to make self-gratification an end, is the whole of sin. The theologians whose views we are canvassing, maintain that the appetites, passions, desires, and propensities, which are constitutional and entirely involuntary, are in themselves sinful. To this I reply, that Adam and Eve possessed them before they fell. Christ possessed them, or he was not a man, nor, in any proper sense, a human being. No, these appetites, passions, and propensities, are not sinful, though they are the occasions of sin. They are a temptation to the will to seek their unlawful indulgence. When these lusts or appetites are spoken of as the "passions of sin," or as " sinful lusts or passions," it is not because they are sinful in themselves, but because they are the occasions of sin. It has been asked, Why are not the appetites and propensities to be re- garded as sinful, since they are the prevalent temptations to sin ? I reply,— They are involuntary, and moral character can no more be predicated of them, on account of their being temptations, than it could of the fruit MORAL DEPRAVITY. 24? that was a temptation to Eve. They have no design to tempt. They are constitutional, unintelligent, involuntary ; and it is impossible that moral chai-acter should be predicable of them. A moral agent is respon- sible for his emotions, desires, etc., so far as they are under the direct or indirect control of his will, and no further. He is always responsible for the manner in which he gratifies them. If he indulges them in accor- dance with the law of God, he does right. If he makes their gratifica- tion his end, he sins. Again : the death and suffering of infants previous to actual trans- gression, is adduced as an argument to prove, that infants have a sinful nature. To this I reply, — That this argument must assume, that there must be sin wherever there is suffering and death. But this assumption proves too much, as it would prove that mere animals have a sinful nature, or have committed actual sin. An argument that proves too much proves nothing. Physical sufferings prove only physical, and not moral, depravity. Previous to moral agency, infants are no more subjects of moral govern- ment than brutes are ; thereforCj their sufferings and death are to be ac- counted for as are those of brutes, namely, by ascribing them to physical interference with the laws of life and health. Another argument for a sinful constitution is, that unless infants have a sinful nature, they do not need sanctification to fit them for heaven. Answer : — This argument assumes, that, if they are not sinful, they must be holy ; whereas they are neither sinful or holy, until they are moral agents, and render themselves so by obedience or disobedience to the moral law. If they are to go to heaven, they must be made holy or must be sancti- fied. This objection assumes, that previous sinfulness is a condition of the necessity of being holy. This is contrary to fact. Were Adam and angels first sinful before they were sanctified ? But it is assumed that unless moral agents are at first sinners, they do not need the Holy Spirit to induce them to be holy. That is, unless their nature is sinful, they would become holy without the Holy Spirit. But where do we ascertain this ? Suppose that they have no moral character, and that their nature is neither holy nor sinful. ' Will they become holy without being enlight- ened by the Holy Spirit ? Who will assert that they will ? That infants have a sinful nature has been inferred from the institu- tion of circumcision so early as the eighth day after birth. Circumcision, it is truly urged, was designed to teach the necessity of regeneration, and by way of implication, the doctrine of moral depravity. It is claimed, that its being enjoined as obligatory upon the eighth day after birth, was requiring it at the earliest period at which it could be safely performed. 248 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. From this it is inferred, that infants are to be regarded as morally de- praved from their birth. In answer to this I would say, that infant circumcision was doubtless designed to teach the necessity of their being saved by the Holy Spirit from the dominion of the flesh ; that the influence of the flesh must be restrained, and the flesh circumcised, or the soul would be lost. This truth needed to be impressed on the parents, from the birth of their children. This very significant, and bloody, and painful rite, was well calculated to impress this truth upon parents, and to lead them from their birth to watch over the development and indulgence of their propen- sities, and to pray for their sanctification. Requiring it at so early a day was no doubt designed to indicate, that they are from the first under the dominion of their flesh, without however affording -any inference in favor of the idea, that their flesh was in itself sinful, or that the action of their will at that early age was sinful. If reason was not developed, the sub- jection of the will to appetite could not be sinful. But whether this subjection of the will to the gratification of the appetite was sinful or not, the child must be delivered from it, or it could never be fitted for heaven, any more than a mere brute can be fitted for heaven. The fact, that circumcision was required on the eighth day, and not before, seems to indicate, not that they are sinners absolutely from birth, but that they very early become so, even from the commencement of moral agency. Again : the rite must be performed at some time. Unless a partic- ular day were appointed, it would be very apt to be deferred, and finally not performed at all. It is probable, that God commanded that it should be done at the earliest period at which it could be safely done, not only for the reasons already assigned, but to prevent its being neglected too long, and perhaps altogether : and perhaps, also, because it would be less painful and dangerous at that early age, when the infant slept most of the time. The longer it was neglected the greater would be the tempta- tion to neglect it altogether. So painful a rite needed to be enjoined by positive statute, at some particular time ; and it was desirable on all accounts that it should be done as early as it safely could be. This argu- ment, then, for native constitutional moral depravity amounts really to nothing. Again : it is urged, that unless infants have a sinful nature, should they die in infancy, they could not be saved by the grace of Christ. To this I answer, that, in this case they would not, and could not, as a matter of course, be sent to the place of punishment for sinners ; be- cause that were to confound the innocent with the guilty, a thing morally impossible with God. But what grace could there be in saving them from a sinful consti- tution, that is not exercised in saving them from circumstances that MORAL DEPBAVITY. 219 woald certainly result in their becoming sinners, if not snatched from them ? In neither case do they need pardon for sin. Grace is unearned favor — a gratuity. If the child has a sinful nature, it is his misfortune, and not his crime. To save him from this nature is to save him from those circumstances that will certainly result in actual transgression, unless he is rescued by death and by the Holy Spirit. So if his nature is not sin- ful, yet it is certain that his nature and circumstances are such, that he will surely sin unless rescued by death or by the Holy Spirit, before he is capable of sinning. It certainly must be an infinite favor to be rescued from such circumstances, and especially to have eternal life conferred as a mere gratuity. This surely is grace. And as infants belong to a race of sinners who are all, as it were, turned over into the hands of Christ, they doubtless will ascribe their salvation to the infinite grace of Christ. Again : is it not grace that saves us from sinning ? What then is it but grace that saves infants from sinning, by snatching them away from circumstances of temptation ? In what way does grace save adults from sinning, but by keeping them from temptation, or by giving them grace to overcome it ? And is there no grace in rescuing infants from cir- cumstances that are certain, if they are left in them, to lead them into Bin? All that can be justly said in either case is, that if infants are saved at all, which I suppose they are, they are rescued by the benevolence of God from circumstances that would result in certain and eternal death, and are by grace made heirs of eternal life. But after all, it is useless to speculate about the character and destiny of those who are confessedly not moral agents. The benevolence of God will take care of them. It is nonsensical to insist upon their moral depravity before they are moral agents, and it is frivolous to assert, that they must be morally depraved, as a condition of their being saved by grace. We deny that the human constitution is morally depraved, because it is impossible that sin should be a quality of the substance of soul or body. It is, and must be, a quality of choice or intention, and not of substance. To make sin an attribute or quality of substance is contrary to God's definition of sin. "Sin," says the apostle, "is anomia," a "transgression of, or a want of conformity to, the moral law." That is, it consists in a refusal to love God and our neighbor, or, which is the same thing, in loving ourselves supremely. To represent the constitution as sinful, is to represent God, who is the author of the constitution, as the author of sin. To say that God is not the direct former of the constitution, but that sin is conveyed by natural generation from Adam, who made himself sinful, is only to re- move the objection one step farther back, but not to obviate it ; for God ept^Jjlished t}ie physic^} lavs that of ueppssjty bring about this result. 250 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. But how came Adam by a sinful nature ? Did his first sin change his nature ? or did God change it as a penalty for sin ? What ground is there for the assertion that Adam's nature became in itfielf sinfftl by the fall ? This is a groundless, not to say ridiculous, assumption, and an absurdity. Sin an attribute of nature ! A sinful substance ! Sin a substance ! Is it a solid, a fluid, a material, or a spiritual substance ? I have received from a brother the following note on this subject : — " The orthodox creeds are in some cases careful to say that original sin consists in the substance of neither soul nor body. Thus Bretschnei- der, who is reckoned among the rationalists in Germany, says : ' The symbolical books very rightly maintained that original sin is not in any sense the substance of man, his body or soul, as Flacius taught, — but that it has been infused into human nature by Satan, and mixed with it, as poison and wine are mixed.' " They rather expressly guard against the idea that they mean by the phrase ' man's nature,' his substance, but somewhat which is fixed in the substance. They explain original sin, therefore, not as an essential at- tribute of man, that is, a necessary and essential part of his being, but as an accident, that is, somewhat which does not subsist in itself, but as something accidental, which has come into human nature. He quotes the Formula Ooncordantise as saying : ' If ature does not denote the sub- stance itself of man, but something which inheres fixed in the nature or substance.' Accident is defined, 'what does not subsist by itself, but is ia some substance and can be distinguished from it.' " Here, it seems, is sin by itself, and yet not a substance or subsistence — not a part or attribute of soul or body. What can it be ? Does it consist in wrong action ? No, not in action, but is an accident which inheres fixed in the nature of substance. But what can it be ? Not sub- stance, nor yet action. But if it be anything, it must be either substance or action. If it be a state of substance, what is this but substance in a particular state ? Do these writers think by this subtlety and refinement to relieve their doctrine of constitutional moral depravity of its intrinsic absurdity ? I object to the doctrine of constitutional sinfulness, that it makes all sin, original and actual, a mere calamity, and not a crime. For those who hold that sin is an essential and inseparable part of our nature, to call it a crime, is to talk nonsense. What ! a sinful nature the crime of him upon whom it is entailed, without his knowledge or consent ? If the nature is sinful, in such a sense that action must necessarily be sinful, which is the doctrine of the Confession of Faith, then sin in action must be a calamity, and can be no crime. It is the necessary effect of a sinful nature. This cannot be a crime, since the will has nothing to do with it. Of course it must render repentance, either with or witbout the grace MORAL DEPRAVITY. 25.1. of God, impossible, unless grace sets aside our reason. If repentance implies self-condemnation, we can never repent in the exercise of our reason. Constituted as we are, it is impossible that we should condemn ourselves for a sinful nature, or for actions that are unavoidable. The doctrine of original sin, or of a sinful constitution, and of necessary sinful actions, represents the whole moral government of God, the plan of sal- vation by Christ, and indeed every doctrine of the gospel, as a mere farce. Upon this supposition the law is tyranny, and the gospel an insult to the unfortunate. It is diflScult, and, indeed, impossible for those who really 'believe this doctrine to urge immediate repentance and submission on the sinner, feeling that he is infinitely to blame unless he instantly com- ply. It is a contradiction to affirm, that a man can heartily believe in the doctrine in question, and yet truly and heartily blame sinners for not doing what is naturally impossible to them. The secret conviction must be in the mind of such an one, that the sinner is not really to blame for being a sinner. For in fact, if this doctrine is true, he is not to blame for being a sinner, any more than he is to blame for being a human being. This the advocate of this doctrine must know. It is vain for him to set up the pretence that he truly blames sinners for their nature, or for their conduct that was unavoidable. He can no more do it, than he can honestly deny the necessary affirmations of his own reason. Therefore the advocates of this theory must merely hold it as a theory, without believing it, or otherwise they must in their secret conviction excuse the sinner. This doctrine naturally and necessarily leads its advocates, secretly at least, to ascribe the atonement of Christ -rather to justice than to grace — to regard it rather as an expedient to relieve the unfoi'tunate, than to render the forgivenesss of the inexcusable sinner possible. The advocates of the theory cannot but regard the case of the sinner as rather a hard one, and God as under an obligation to provide a way for hini to escape a sinful nature, entailed upon him in spite of himself, and from actual transgressions which result from his nature by a law of necessity. If all this is true, the sinner's case is infinitely hard, and God would appear the most unreasonable and cruel of beings, if he did not provide for their escape. These convictions will, and must, lodge in the mind of him who really believes the dogma of a sinful nature. This, in substance, is sometimes affirmed by the defenders of the doctrine of original sin. The fact that Christ died in the stead and behalf of sinners, proves that God regarded them not as unfortunate, but as criminal and alto- gether without excuse. Surely Christ need not have died to atone for the misfortunes of men, His death was to atone for their gailt, 252 STSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. and not for their misfortunes. But if they are without excuse for sin, they must be without a sinful nature that renders sin unavoidable. If men are without excuse for sin, as the whole law and gospel assume and teach, it cannot possibly be that their nature is sinful, for a sinful nature would be the best of all excuses for sin. This doctrine is a stumbling-block both to the church and the world, infinitely dishonorable to God, and an abomination alike to God and the human intellect, and should be banished from every pulpit, and from every formula of doctrine, and from the world. It is a relic of heathen philosophy, and was foisted in among the doctrines of Christianity by Augustine, as every one may know who will take the trouble to examine for himself. This view of moral depravity that I am opposing, has long been the stronghold of TJniversalism. From it, the Universalists inveigh with resistless force against the idea that sinners should be sent to an. eternal hell. Assuming the long-defended doctrine of original or constitutional sinfulness, they proceeded to show, that it would be in- finitely unreasonable and unjust in God to send them to hell. What ! create them with a sinful nature, from which proceed, by a law of neces- sity, actual transgressions, and then send them to an eternal hell for having this nature, and for transgressions that are unavoidable ! Im- possible ! they say ; and the human intellect responds. Amen. From the dogma of a sinful nature or constitution also, has naturally and irresistibly, fiowed the doctrine of inability to repent, and the necessity of a physical regeneration. These too have been a sad stum- bling-block to Universalists, as every one knows who is at all acquainted with the history of TJniversalism. They infer the salvation of all men, from the fact of God's benevolence and physical omnipotence I God is almighty, and he is love. Men are constitutionally depraved, and are unable to repent. God will not, cannot send them to hell. They do not deserve it. Sin is a calamity, and God can save them, and he ought to do so. This is the substance of their argument. And assuming the truth of their premises, there is no evading their conclusion. But the whole argument is built on "such stuff as dreams are made of." Strike out the erroneous dogma of a sinful nature, and the whole edifice of TJniversalism comes to the ground in a moment. We come now to consider — 2. The proper method of accounting for moral depravity. We have more than once seen that the Bible has given us the history of the introduction of sin into our world ; and that from the narrative, it is plain, that the first sin consisted in selfishness, or in consenting to indulge the excited constitutional propensities in a prohibited manner. In other words, it consisted in yielding the will to the impulses of the ?pnpibiUty, mteai qf p^biding by tjjp }m of Qp^, g,s revpaje4 jn j;hp jpt^ir MORAL DEPRAVITY. 253 ligenoe. Thus the Bible ascribes the first sin of our race to the influence of temptation. The Bible once, and only once, incidentally intimates that Adam's first sin has in some way been the occasion, not the necessary physical cause, of all the sins of men. Kom. v. 13-19. It neither says nor in- timates anything iu relation to the manner in which Adam's sin has oc- casioned this result It only incidentally recognizes the fact, and then leaves it, just as if the quo modo was too obvious to need explanation. In other parts of the Bible we are informed how we are to account for the existence of sin among men. James says, that a man is tempted when he is drawn aside of his own lusts, {miBujiuu " desires ") and enticed. That is, his lusts, or the impulses of his sensibility, are his tempters. When he or his will is overcome of these, he sins. Paul and other inspired writers represent sin as consisting in a carnal or fleshly mind, in the mind of the flesh, or in minding the flesh. It is plain that by the term flesh they mean what we understand by the sensibility, as distinguished from intellect, and that they represent sin as consisting in obeying, minding, the impulses of the sensibility. They represent the world, and the flesh, and Satan, as the three great sources of temptation. It is plain that the world and Satan tempt by appeals to the flesh, or to the sensibility. Hence, the apostles have much to say of the necessity of the destruction of the flesh, of the members, of putting off the old man with his deeds, etc. Now, it is worthy of remark, that all this painstalcing, on the part of Inspiration, to intimate the source from whence our sin proceeds, and to apprise us of the proper method of accounting for it, and also of avoiding it, has probably been the occasion of leading certain philoso- phers and theologians who have not carefully examined the whole sub- ject, to take a view of it which is directly opposed to the truth intended by the inspired writers. Because so much is said of the influence of the . flesh over the mind, they have inferred that the nature and physical con- stitution of man is itself sinful. But the representations of Scripture are, that the body is the^occasion of sin. The law in his members, that warred against the law of his mind, of which Paul speaks, is manifestly the impulse of the sensibility opposed to the law of the reason. This law, that is, the impulse of his sensibility, brings him into captivity, that is, influences his will, in spite of all his convictions to the contrary. Moral depravity consists, remember, in the committal of the will to the gratification or indulgence of self — in the will's following, or sub- mitting itself to be governed by, the impulses and desires of the sensi- bility, instead of submitting itself to the law of God revealed in the reason. This definition of the thing shows how it is to be accounted for, namely : the sensibility acts as a powerful impulse to the will, from the moment of birth, and secures the consent and activity of the will to pro* 254 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. cure its gratification, before the reason is at all developed. The will is thus committed to the gratification of feeling and appetite, when first the idea of moral obligation is developed. This committed state of the will is not moral depravity, and has no moral character, until the idea of moral obligation is developed. The moment this idea is developed, this committal of the will to self-indulgence must be abandoned, or it becomes selfishness, or moral depravity. But, as the will is already in a state of committal, and has to some extent already formed the habit of seeking to gratify feeling, and as the idea of moral obligation is at first but feebly developed, unless the Holy Spirit interferes to shed light on the soul, the will, as might be expected, retains its hold on self-gratification. Here alone moral character commences, and must commence. No one can conceive of its commencing earlier. This selfish choice is the wicked heart — the propensity to sin— that causes what is generally termed actual transgression. This sinful choice is properly enough called indwelling sin. It is the latent, standing, con- trolling preference of the mind, and the cause of all the outward and active life. It is not the choice of sin itself, distinctly conceived of, or chosen as sin, but the choice of self-gratification, which choice is sin. Again : It should be remembered, that the physical depravity of our race has much to do with our moral depravity. A diseased physical sys- tem renders the appetites, passions, tempers, and propensities more clam- orous and despotic in their demands, and of course constantly urging to selfishness, confirms and strengthens it. It should be distinctly remem- bered that physical depravity has no moral character in itself. But yet it is a source of fierce temptation to selfishness. The human sensibility is, manifestly, deeply physically depraved ; and as sin, or moral depravity, consists in committing the will to the gratification of the sensibility, its physical depravity will mightily strengthen moral depravity. Moral de- pravity is then universally owing to temptation. That is, the soul is • tempted to self-indulgence, and yields to the temptation, and this yield- ing, and not the temptation, is sin or moral depravity. This is mani- festly the way in which Adam and Eve became morally depraved. They were tempted, even by undepraved appetite, to prohibited indulgence, and were overcome. The sin did not lie in the constitutional desire of food, or of knowledge, nor in the excited state of these appetites or de- sires, but in the consent of the will to prohibited indulgence. Just in the same way all sinners become such, that is, they become morally de- praved, by yielding to temptation to self-gratification under some form. Indeed, it is impossible that they should become morally depraved in any other way. To deny this were to overlook the very nature of moral depravity. To sum up the truth upon this subject in few words, I would say :— MOEAL DEPRAVITY. 255 1. Moral depravity in our first parents was induced by temptation addressed to the unperverted susceptibilities of their nature. When these susceptibilities became strongly excited, they overcame the will ; that is, the human pair were over-persuaded, and fell under the tempta- tion. This has been repeatedly said, but needs repetition in a sum- ming up. 3. All moral depravity commences in substantially the same way. Proof :— (1.) The impulses of the sensibility are developed, gradually, com- mencing from the birth, and depending on physical development and growth. (3.) The first acts of will are in obedience to these. (3.) Self-gratification is the rule of action previous to the development of reason, (4.) 2fo resistance is ofEered to the will's indulgence of appetite, until a habit of self-indulgence is formed. (5.) When reason afiBrms moral obligation, it finds the will in a state of habitual and constant committal to the impulses of the sensibility. (6.) The demands of the sensibility have become more and more des- potic every hour of indulgence. (7.) In this state of things, unless the Holy Spirit interpose, the idea of moral obligation will be but dimly developed. (8.) The will of course rejects the bidding of reasod, and cleaves to self-indulgence. (9.) This is the settling of a fundamental question. It is deciding in favor of appetite, against the claims of conscience and of God. (10.) -Light once rejected, can be afterwards more easily resisted, un- til it is nearly excluded altogether. (11.) Selfishness confirms, and strengthens, and perpetuates itself by a natural process. It grows with the sinner's growth, and strengthens with his strength ; and will do so for ever, unless overcome by the Holy Spirit through the truth. BliMABES. 1. Adam, being the natural head of the race, would naturally, by the wisest constitution of things, greatly affect for good or evil his whole posterity. 2. His sin in many ways exposed his posterity to aggravated tempta- tion. Kot only the physical constitution of all men, but all the in- fluences under which they first form their moral character, are widely different from what they would have been, if sin had never been intro- duced. 3. When selfishness is understood to be the whole of moral depravity, 256 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. its quo modo, or in what way it comes to exist, is manifest. Clear con- ceptions of the thing will instantly reveal the occasion and manner. 4. The only diflBculty in accounting for it, has been the false assump- tion, that there must be, and is, something lying back of the free actions of the will, which sustains to those actions the relation of a cause, that is itself sinful. 5. If holy Adam, and holy angels could fall under temptations ad- dressed to their undepraved sensibility, how absurd it is to conclude, that sin in those who are born with a physically depraved constitution, cannot be accounted for, without ascribing it to original sin, or to a nature that is in itself sinful. 6. Without divine illumination, the moral character will of course be formed under the influence of the flesh. That is, the lower propensities will of course influence the will, unless the reason be developed by the Holy Spirit. 7. The dogma of constitutional moral depravity, is a part and parcel of the doctrine of a necessitated will. It is a branch of a grossly false and heathenish philosophy. How infinitely absurd, dangerous, and unjust, then, to embody it in a standard of Christian doctrine, to give it the place of an indispensable article of faith, and denounce all who will not swallow its absurdities, as heretics ! 8. We are unable to say precisely at what age infants become moral agents, and of course how early they become sinners. Doubtless there is much difference among children in this respect. Beason is developed in \ one earlier than in another, according to the constitution and circum- stances. A thorough consideration of the subject, will doubtless lead to the conviction, that children become moral agents much earlier than is generally supposed. The conditions of moral agency are, as has been repeatedly said in former lectures, the possession of the powers of moral agency, together with the development of the ideas of the good or valua- ble, of moral obligation or oughtness — of right and wrong — of praise and blameworthiness. I have endeavored to show, in former lectures, that mental satisfaction, blessedness or happiness, is the ultimate good. Sat- isfaction arising from the gratification of the appetites, is one of the earliest experiences of human beings. This no doubt suggests or devel- opes, at a very early period, the idea of the good or the valuable. The idea is doubtless developed, long before the word that expresses it is understood. The child knows that happiness is good, and seeks it in the form of self-gratification, long before the terms that designate this state of mind are at all understood. It knows that its own enjoyment is worth seeking, and doubtless very early has the idea, that the enjoy- ment of others is worth seeking, and affirms to itself, not in words, but MORAL DEPBAVlft 257 in idea, that it ought to please its parents and those around it. It knows, in fact, though language is as yet unknown, that it loves to be gratified, and to be happy, that it loves and seeks enjoyment for itself, and doubtless has the idea that it ought not to displease and dis- tress those around it, but that it ought to endeavor to please and gratify them. This is probably among the first ideas, if not the very first idea, of the pure reason that is developed, that is, the idea of the good, the valuable, the desirable ; and the next must be that of onghtness, or of moral obligation, or of right and wrong, etc. I say again, these ideas are, and must be developed, before the signs or words that express them are at all understood, and the words would never be understood except the idea were first developed. We always find, at the earliest period at which children can understand words, that they have the idea of obliga- tion, of right and wrong. As soon as these words are understood by them, they recognize them as expressing ideas already in their own minds, and which ideas they have had further back than they can remember. Some, and indeed most persons, seem to have the idea, that children aflBrm themselves to be under moral obligation, before they have the idea of the good ; that they affirm their obligation to obey their parents before they know, or have the idea of the good or of the valuable. But this is, and must be a mistake. They may and do affirm obligation to obey their parents, before they can express in lan- guage, and before they would understand, a statement of the ground of their obligation. The idea, however, they have, and must have, or they could not affirm obligation. 9. Why is sin so natural to mankind ? Not because their nature is itself sinful, but because the appetites and passions tend so strongly to self-indulgence. These are temptations to sin, but sin itself consists not in these appetites and propensities, but in the voluntary committal of the will to their indulgence. This committal of the will is selfishness, and when the will is once given up to sin, it is very natural to sin. The will once committed to self-indulgence as its end, selfish actions are in a sense spontaneous. 10. The constitution of a moral being as a whole, when all the powers are developed, does not tend to sin, but strongly in an opposite direction; as is manifest from the fact that when reason is thoroughly developed by the Holy Spirit, it is more than a match for the sensibility, and turns the heart to God. The difficulty is, that the sensibility gets the start of reason, and en- gages the attention in devising means of self-gratification, and thus re- tards, and in a great measure prevents, the development of the ideas of the reason which were designed to control the will. It is this morbid development that the Holy Spirit is given to rectify, by so forcing truth 17 2s>S SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. upon the attention, as to secure the development of the reason. Bj doing this, he brings the will under the influence of truth. Our senses reveal to us the objects correlated to our animal nature and propensities. The Holy Spirit reveals God and the spiritual world, and all that class of objects that are correlated to our higher nature, so as to give reason the control of the will. This is regeneration and sanctification, as we shall see in its proper place. LECTURE XXV. ATONEMENT. We come now to the consideration of a very important feature of the moral government of God ; namely, the atonement. In discussing this subject, I will — I. Gall attention to several well-established principles of government. 1. We have already seen that moral law is not founded in the mere arbitrary will of God or of any other being, but that it has its foundation in the nature and relations of moral agents, that it is that rule of action or of willing which is imposed on them by the law of their own intellect. 2. As the will of no being can create moral law, so the will of no being can repeal or alter moral law. It being just that rule of action that is agreeable to the nature and relations of moral agents, it is as im- mutable as those natures and relations. 3. There is a distinction between the letter and the spirit of moral law. The letter relates to the outward life or action ; the spirit respects the motive or intention from which the act should proceed. For exam- ple : the spirit of the moral law requires disinterested benevolence, and is all expressed in one word — love. The letter of the law is found in the commandments of the decalogue, and in divers other precepts relating to outward acts. 4. To the letter of the law there may be many exceptions, but to the spirit of moral law there can be no exception. That is, the spirit of the moral law may sometimes admit and require, that the letter of the law shall be disregarded or violated ; but the spirit of the law ought never to be disregarded or violated. For example : the letter of the law prohibits all labor on the sabbath day. But the spirit of the law often requires labor on the sabbath. The spirit of the law requires the exercise of uni- ATONEMENT. 259 versal and perfect lore or benevolence to God and man, and the law of benevolence often requires that labor shall be done on the sabbath ; as administering to the sick, relieving the poor, feeding animals ; and in short, whatever is plainly the work' of necessity or mercy, in such a sense that enlightened benevolence demands it, is required by the spirit of moral law upon the sabbath, as well as all other days. This is expressly taught by Christ, both by precept and example. So again, the letter of the law says, " The soul that sinneth, it shall die j" but the spirit of the law admits and requires that upon certain conditions, to be examined in their proper place, the soul that sinneth shall live. The letter of the law is inexorable ; it condemns and sentences to death all violators of its precepts, without regard to atonement or repentance. The spirit of moral law allows and requires that upon condition of satisfaction being made to public justice, and the return of the sinner to obedience, he shall live and not die. 5. In establishing a government and promulgating law, the lawgiver is always understood as pledging himself duly to administer the laws in support of public order, and for the promotion of public morals, to re- ward the innocent with his favor and protection, and to punish the dis- obedient with the loss of his protection and favor. 6. Laws are public property in which every subject of the govern- ment has an interest. Every obedient subject of government is inter- ested to have law supported and obeyed, and wherever the law is violated, every subject of the government is injured, and his rights are invaded ; and each and all have a right to expect the government duly to execute the penalties of law when it is violated. 7. There is an important distinction between retributive and public justice. Retributive justice consists in treating every subject of govern- ment according to his character. It respects the intrinsic merit or de- merit of each individual, and deals with him accordingly. Public jus- tice, in its exercise, consists in the promotion and protection of the public interests, by such legislation and such an administration of law, as is demanded by the highest good of the public. It implies the execu- tion of the penalties of law where the precept is violated, unless some- thing else is done that will as effectually secure the public interests. When this is done, public justice demands, that the execution of the penalty shall be dispensed with, by extending pardon to the criminal. Eetributive justice makes no exceptions, but punishes without mercy in every instance of crime. Public justice makes exceptions, as often as this is permitted or required by the public good. Public justice is iden- tical with the spirit of the moral law, and in its exercise, regards only the law. Betributive justice cleaves to the letter, and makes no excep- tions to the rule, " The soul that sinneth, it shall die." 260 STSTEjtfAtlC TaiEOLoat. 8. The design of legal penalties is to secure obedience to the precept. The same is also the reason for executing them when the precept is violated. The sanctions are to be regarded as an expression of the views of the lawgiver, in respect to the importance of his law ; and the execution of penalties is designed and calculated to evince his sincerity in enacting, and his continued adherence to, and determination to abide by, the prin- ciples of his government as revealed in the law ; his abhorrence of all crime ; his regard to the public interests ; and his unalterable determina- tion to carry out, support and establish, the authority of his law. 9. It is a fact well established by the experience of all ages and na- tions, that the exercise of mercy, in setting aside the execution of penal- ties, is a matter of extreme delicacy and danger. The influence of law, as might be expected, is found very much to depend upon the' certainty felt by the subjects that it will be duly executed. It is found in expe- rience, to be true, that the exercise of mercy in every government where no atonement is made, weakens government, by begetting and fostering a hope of impunity in the minds of those who are tempted to violate the law. It has been asserted, that the same is true when an atonement has been made, and that therefore, the doctrines of atonement and conse- quent forgiveness tend to encourage the hope of impunity in the commis- sion of sin, and for this reason, are dangerous doctrines, subversive of high and sound morality. This assertion I shall notice in its appropri- ate place. 10. Since the head of the government is pledged to protect and pro- mote the public interests, by a due administration of law, if in any in- stance where the precept is violated, he would dispense with the execu- tion of penalties, public justice requires that he shall see, that a substi- tute for the execution of law is provided, or that something is done that shall as effectually secure the influence of law, as the execution of the penalty would do. He cannot make exceptions to the spirit of the law. Either the soul that sinneth must die, according to the letter of the law, or a substitute must be provided in accordance with the spirit of the law. 11. Whatever will as fully evince the lawgiver's regard for his law, his determination to support it, his abhorrence of all violations of its precepts, and withal guard as effectually against the inference, that vio- lators of the precept might expect to escape with impunity, as the exe- cution of the penalty would do, is a full satisfaction of public justice. When these conditions are fulfilled, and the sinner has returned to obedi- ence, public justice not only admits, but absolutely demands, that the penalty shall be set aside by extending pardon to the offender. The offender still deserves to be punished, and, upon the principles of retribu- tive justice, might be punished according to his deserts. But the pub- lic good admits and requires, that upon the above condition he should ATONEMENT. 261 live ; hence, public justice, in compliance with the public interests and the spirit of the law of loTe, spares and pardons him. 12. If mercy or pardon is to be extended to any who have violated law, it ought to be done in a manner and upon some conditions that will . settle the question, and establish the truth, that the execution of penal- ties is not to be dispensed with merely upon condition of the repentance of the offender. In other words, if pardon is to be extended, it should be known to be upon a condition not within the power of the offender. Else he may know, that he can violate the law, and yet be sure to escape with impunity, by fulfilling the conditions of forgiveness, which are upon the supposition, all within his own power. 13. So, if mercy is to be exercised, it should be upon a condition that is not to be repeated. The thing required by public justice is, that noth- ing shall be done to undermine or disturb the influence of law. Hence it cannot consent to have the execution of penalties dispensed with, upon any condition that shall encourage the hope of impunity. Therefore, public justice cannot consent to the pardon of sin but upon condition of an atonement, and also upon the assumption that atonement is not to be repeated, nor to extend its benefits beyond the limits of the race for whom it was made, and that only for a limited time. If an atonement were to extend its benefits to all worlds, and to all eternity, it would nullify its own influence, and encourage the universal hope of impunity, in case the precepts of the law were violated. This would be indefinitely worse than no atonement ; and public justice might as well consent to have mercy ex- ercised, without any regard to securing the authority and influence of law. II. The term Atonement. The English word atonement is synonymous with the Hebrew word cofer. This is a noun from the verb caufar, to cover. The cofer or cover was the name of the lid or cover of the ark of the covenant, and consti- tuted what was called the mercy-seat. The Greek word rendered atone- ment is KaToOayri. This means reconciliation to favor, or more strictly, the means or conditions of reconciliation to favor ; from mTaXhusaa, to " change, or exchange." The term properly means substitution. An examination of these original words, in the connection in which they stand, will show that the atonement is the governmental substitution of the sufferings of Christ for the punishment of sinners. It is a covering of their sins by his sufferings. III. The teachings of natural theology, or the oi priori affirmations of reason upon this subject. The doctrine of atonement has been regarded as so purely a doctrine of revelation as to preclude the supposition, that reason could, & priori, 262 STSTEMATIC THEOLOffY. make any afQrmations about it. It has been generally regarded as lying absolutely without the pale of natural theology, in so high a sense, that, aside from revelation, no assumption could be made, nor even a reason- able conjecture indulged. But there are certain facts in this world's history, that render this assumption exceedingly doubtful. It is true, indeed, that natural theology could not ascertain and establish the fact, that an atonement had been made, or that it certainly would be made ; but if I am not mistaken, it might have been reasonably inferred, the true character of God being known and assumed, that an atonement of some kind would be made to render it consistent with his relations to the universe, to extend mercy to the guilty inhabitants of this world. The manifest necessity of a divine revelation has been supposed to afford a strong presumptive argument, that such a revelation has been or will be made. From the benevolence of God, as aflBrmed by reason, and mani- fested in his works and providence, it has been, as I suppose, justly in- ferred, that he would make arrangements to secure the holiness and sal- vation of men, and as a condition of this result, that he would grant them a further revelation of his will than had been given in creation and providence. The argument stands thms : — 1. From reason and observation we know that this is not a state of retribution ; and from all the facts in the case that lie open to obser- vation, this is evidently a state of trial or probation. 2. The providence of God in this world is manifestly disciplinary, and designed to reform mankind. 3. These facts, taken in connection with the great ignorance and darkness of the human mind on moral and religious subjects, afford a strong presumption that the benevolent Creator vrill make to the inhabitants of this world who are so evidently yet in a state of trial, a further revelation of his will. Now, if this argument is good, so far as it goes, I see not why we may not reasonably go still further. Since the above are facts, and since it is also a fact that when the subject is duly considered, and the more thoroughly the better, there is manifestly a great difficulty in the exercise of mercy without satisfaction being made to public justice ; and since the benevolence of God would not allow him on the one hand to pardon sin at the expense of public justice, nor on the other to punish or execute the penalty of law, if it could be wisely and consistently avoided, these facts being understood and admitted, it might naturally have been inferred, that the wisdom and benevolence of God would devise and execute some liiethod of meet- ing the demands of public justice, that should render the forgiveness of sin possible. That the philosophy of government would render this possible, is to us very manifest. I know, indeed, that with the light the gospel has afforded us, we much more clearly discern this, than they ATONEMENT. 263 could who had no other light than that of nature. Whatever might have been known to the ancients, and those who have not the Bible, I think that when the facts are announced by revelation, we can see that such a governmental expedient was not only possible, but just what might have been expected of the benevolence of God. It would of course have been impossible for us, d, priori, to have devised, or reasonably conjectured, the plan that has been adopted. So little was known or knowable on the subject of the trinity of God, without revelation, that natural theology could, perhaps, in its best estate, have taught nothing further than that, if it was possible, some governmental expedient would be resorted to, and was in contemplation, for the ultimate restoration of the sinning race, who were evidently spared hitherto from the execution of law, and placed under a system of discipline. But since the gospel has announced the fact of the atonement, it appears that natural theology or governmental philosophy can satisfac- torily explain it ; that reason can discern a divine philosophy in it. Natural theology can teach — 1. That the human race is in a fallen state, and that the law of selfish- ness, and not the law of benevolence, is that to which unconverted men conform their lives. 2. It can teach that God is benevolent, and hence that mercy must be an attribute of God ; and that this attribute will be manifested in the actual pardon of sin, when this can be done with safety to the divine government. 3. Consequently that no atonement could be needed to satisfy any implacable spirit in the divine mind ; that he was sufBciently and in- finitely disposed to extend pardon to the penitent, if this could be wisely, benevolently, and safely done. 4 It can also abundantly teach, that there is a real and a great danger in the exercise of mercy under a moral government, and su- premely great under a government so vast and so enduring as the government of God ; that, under such a government, the danger is very great, that the exercise of mercy will be understood as encouraging the hope of impunity in the commission of sin. 5. It c&n also show the indispensable necessity of such an adminis- tration of the divine government as to secure the fullest confidence throughout the universe, in the sincerity of God in promulging his law with its tremendous penalty, and of his unalterable adherence to its spirit, and determination not to falter in carrying out and securing its authority at all events. That this is indispensable to the well-being of the universe, is entirely manifest. 6. Hence it is very obvious to natural theology, that sin cannot be pardoned unless something is done to forbid the otherwise natural infer- 264 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOaY, ence that sin will be forgiven under the government of God upon condi- iion of repentance alone, and of course upon a condition within the power of the sinner himself. It must be manifest, that to proclaim throughout the universe that sin would be pardoned universally upon condition of repentance alone, would be a virtual repeal of the divine law. All creatures would instantly perceive, that no one need to fear punishment, in any case, as his forgiveness was secure, however much he might trample on the divine authority, upon a single condition which he could at will perform. 7. Natural theology is abundantly competent to show, that God could not be just to his own intelligence, just to his character, and hence just to the universe, in dispensing with the execution of divine law, except upon the condition of providing a substitute of such a nature as to reveal as fully, and impress as deeply, the lessons that would be taught by the execution, as the execution itself would do. The great design of penalties is prevention, and this is of course the design of executing pen- alties. The head of every government is pledged to sustain the authority of law, by a. due administration of rewards and punishments, and has no right in any instance to extend pardon, except upon conditions that will as effectually support the authority of law as the execution of its penal- ties would do. It was never found to be safe, or even possible under any government, to make the universal offer of pardon to violators of law, upon the bare condition of repentance, for the very obvious reason already suggested, that it would be a virtual repeal of all law. Public justice, by which every executive magistrate in the universe is bound, sternly and peremptorily forbids that mercy shall be extended to any culprit, without some equivalent being rendered to the government ; that is, without something being done that will fully answer as a substitute for the execution of penalties. This principle God fully admits to be binding upon him ; and hence he affirms that he gave his Son to render it just in him to forgive sin. Eom. iii. 24-36 : " Being justified freely by his grace, through the redemption that is in Christ Jesus, whom God hath set forth to be a propitiation through faith in his blood, to declare his righteousness for the remission of sins that are past, through the for- bearance of God ; to declare, I say, at this time, his righteousness ; that he might be just, and the justifier of him which believeth in Jesus." 8. All nations have felt the necessity of expiatory sacrifices. This is evident from the fact that all nations have offered them. 9. The wisest heathen philosophers, who saw the intrinsic inefiBcacy of animal sacrifices, held that God could not forgive sin. This proves to a demonstration, that they felb the necessity of an atonement, or expiar tory sacrifice. And having too just views of God and his government, to suppose that either animal, or merely human, sacrifices, could be effi- ATONEMENT. 265 cacious uuder the government of God, they were unable to understand npon what principles sin could be forgiven. 10. Public justice required, either that an atonement should be made, or that the law should be executed upon every ofEender. By public jus- tice is intended, that due administration of law, that shall secure in the highest manner which the nature of the case admits, private and public interests, and establish the order and well-being of the universe. In establishing the government of the universe, God had given the pledge, both impliedly and expressly, that he would regard the public interests, and by a due administration of the law, secure and promote, as far as possible, public and individual happiness. 11. Public justice could strictly require only the execution of law ; for God had neither expressly nor impliedly given a pledge to do any- thing more for the promotion of virtue and happiness, than to administer due rewards to the righteous, and due punishment to the wicked. Yet an atonement, as we shall see, would more fully meet the necessities of government, and act as a more efiBcient preventive of sin, and a more powerful persuasive to holiness, than the iniliction of the legal penalty would do. 12. An atonement was needed for the removal of obstacles to the free exercise of benevolence toward our race. Without an atonement, the race of man after the fall sustained to the government of God the rela- tion of rebels and outlaws. And before God, as the great executive magistrate of the universe, could manifest his benevolence toward them, an atonement must be decided upon and made known, as the reason upon which his favorable treatment of them was conditionated. 13. An atonement was needed to promote the glory and influence of God in the universe. But more of this hereafter. 14. An atonement was needed to present overpowering motives to repentance. 15. An atonement was needed, that the offer of pardon might not seem like connivance at sin. 16. An atonement was needed to manifest the sincerity of God in his legal enactments. 17. An atonement was needed to make it safe to present the offer and promise of pardon. 18. Natural theology can inform us, that, if the lawgiver would or could condescend so much to deny himself, as to attest his regard to his law, and his determination to support it by suffering its curse, in such a sense as was possible and consistent with his character and relations, and so far forth as emphatically to inculcate the great lesson, that sin was not to be forgiven upon the bare condition of repentance in any case, and fiH»o to establish th^ universal conviction, that the execution of law was 266 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. not to be dispensed with, but that it is an analterable rule under his divine government, that where there is sin there must be inflicted suffer- ing — this would be so complete a satisfaction of public justice, that sin might safely be forgiven, IV. The fact of atonement. This is purely a doctrine of revelation, and in the establishment of this truth appeal must be made to the scriptures alone. 1. The whole Jewish scriptures, and especially the whole ceremonial dispensation of the Jews, attest, most unequivocally, the necessity of an atonement. 2. The New Testament is just as unequivocal in its testimony to the same point. I shall here take it as established, that Christ was properly " God manifest in the flesh," and proceed to cite a few out of the great multi- tude of passages, that attest the fact of his death, and also its vicarious nature ; that is, that it was for us, and as a satisfaction to public justice for our sins, that his blood was shed. I will first quote a few passages to show that the atonement and redemption through it, was a matter of un- derstanding and covenant between the Father and Son. "I have made a covenant with my chosen, I have sworn unto David my servant. Thy seed will I establish forever, and build up thy throne to all generations. Selah." — Ps. Ixxxix, 3, 4. " Yet it pleased the Lord to bruise him ; he hath put him to grief : when thou shalt make his soul an offering for sin he shall see his seed, he shall prolong his days, and the pleasure of the Lord shall prosper in his hand. He shall see of the travail of his soul, and shall be satisfied ; by his knowledge shall my righteous servant justify many ; for he shall bear their iniquities. Therefore will I divide him a portion with the great, and he shall divide the spoil with the strong ; because he hath poured out his soul unto death : and he was numbered with the transgressors." — Isaiah liii. 10, 11, 12. "All that the Father giveth me shall come to me : and he that cometh to me I will in no wise cast out. For I came down from heaven, not to do mine own will, but the will of him that sent me. And this is the Father's will which hath sent me, that of all which he hath given me I should lose nothing, but should raise it up again at the last day." — John vi. 37, 38, 39. "I have manifested thy name unto the men which thou gavest me out of the world : thine they were, and thou gavest them me ; and they have kept thy word. I pray for them : I pray not for the world, but for them which thou hast given me ; for they are thine. And now I am no more in the world, but these are in the world, and I come to thee. Holy Father, keep through thine own name those whom thou hast girec me, that they may be one, as we arp," — John ?vii. 6, 9, 11, ATONEMENT. 267 I will next quote some passages' to show, that, if sinners were to be Bayed at all, it must be through an atonement. " Neither is there salva- tion in any other : for there is none other name under heaven given among men whereby we must be saved." — Acts iv. 1*. " Be it known unto you therefore, men and brethren, that through this man is preached unto you the forgiveness of sins : And by him all that believe are justified from all things, from which ye could not be justified by the law of Moses." — Acts xiii. 38, 39. " Now we know, that what things soever the law saith, it saith to them who are under the law ; that every mouth may be stopped, and all the world may become guilty before God. Therefore, by the deeds of the law there shall no flesh be justified in his sight : for by the law is the knowledge of sin." — Eom. iii. 19, 30. " Knowing that a man is not justified by the works of the law, but by the faith of Jesus Christ, even we have believed in Jesus Christ, that we might be justified by the faith of Christ, and not by the works of the law : for by the works of the law shall no flesh be justified. I do not frustrate the grace of God : for if righteousness come by the law, then Christ is dead in vain." — Gal. ii. 16, 21. " For as many as are of the works of the law are un- der the curse : for it is written, Cursed is every one that continueth not in all things which are written in the book of the law to do them. But that no man is justified by the law in the sight of God, it is evident : for. The just shall live by faith. And the law is not of faith : but the man that doeth them shall live in them. For if the inheritance be of the law, it is no more of promise : but God gave it to Abraham by promise. Wherefore then serveth the law ? It was added because of transgressions, until the seed should come to whom the promise was made ; and it was ordained by angels in the hand of a mediator. Now a mediator is not a mediator of one, but God is one. Is the law, then, against the promises of God ? God forbid, for if there had been a law given which could have given life, verily righteousness should have been by the law. Where- fore the law was our schoolmaster to bring us unto Christ, that we might be justified by faith."— Gal. iii. 10-13, 18-21, 24. " And almost all things are by the law purged with blood ; and without shedding of blood is no remission. It was therefore necessary that the patterns of things in the heavens should be purified with these ; but the heavenly things themselves with better sacrifices than these." — Heb. ix. 32, 23. I will now cite some passages that establish the fact of the vicarious death of Christ, and redemption through his blood. "But he was wounded for our transgressions, he was bruised for our iniquities : the chastisement of our peace was upon him, and with his stripes we are healed. All we like sheep have gone astray ; we have turned every one to his own way ; and the Lord hath laid on him the iniquity of us all." — Im^fh liii, 5, 6, *' Even as the Son of man came not to be ministered 268 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOur. unto, but to minister, and to give his life a ransom for many." — Matt. XX. 28. " For this is my blood of the new testament which is shed for many for the remission of sins." — Matt. xxvi. 38. "And as Moses lifted up the serpent in the wilderness, even so must the Son of man be lifted up ; that whosoever believeth in him should not perish, but have eternal life." — John iii. 14, 15. "I am the living bread which came down from heaven : if any man eat of this bread, he shall live for ever : and the bread that I will give is my flesh, which I will give for the life of the world." — John vi. 5 1. " Take heed therefore unto yourselves, and to all the flock over the which the Holy Ghost hath made yon overseers, to feed the church of God, which he hath purchased with his own blood." — Acts XX. 28. " Being justified freely by his grace, through the re- demption that is in Christ Jesus. To declare, I say, at this time, his righteousness : that he might be just, and the jnstifier of him which be- lieveth in Jesus. For when we were yet without strength, in due time Christ died for the ungodly. For scarcely for a righteous man will one die : yet peradventure for a good man some would even dare to die. But God commendeth his love toward us, in that while we were yet sinners Christ died for us. Much more then, being now justified by his blood, we shall be saved from wrath through him. And not only so, but we also joy in God through our Lord Jesus Christ, by whom we have now received the atonement. Therefore, as by the offence of one, judgment came upon all men to condemnation ; even so by the righteousness of one the free gift came upon all men unto justification of life. For as by one man's disobedience many were made sinners, so by the obedience of one shall many be made righteous." — Eom. iii. 24-26 ; v. 9-11, 18, 19. " Purge out therefore the old leaven, that ye may be a new lump, as ye are unleavened. For even Christ our passover is sacrificed for us : for I delivered unto you first of all that which I also received, how that Christ died for our sins according to the scriptures." — 1 Cor. v. 7 : xv. 3. "I am crucified with Christ : nevertheless I live : yet not I, but Christ liveth in me : and the life which I now live in the flesh I live by the faith of the Son of God, who loved me, and gave himself for me. Christ hath redeemed us from the curse of the law, being made a curse for us : for it is written. Cursed is every one that hangeth on a tree. That the bless- ing of Abraham might come on the Gentiles through Jesus Christ ; that we might receive the promise of the Spirit through faith." Gal. ii. 20 ; iii. 13, 14. " But now in Christ Jesus ye who sometimes were far off are made nigh by the blood of Christ. And walk in love, as Christ also hath loved us, and hath given himself for us an offering and a sacrifice to God for a sweet smelling savour." — Eph. ii. 13 ; v. 2. " Neither by the blood of goats and calves, but by his own blood he entered in once into the holy place, having obtained eternal redemption for us. For if tho ATONEMENT. 269 blood of bulls and of goats, and the ashes of an heifer sprinkling the un- clean, sanctifieth to the purifying of the flesh ; how much more shall the blood of Christ, who through the eternal Spirit offered himself without spot to God, purge your conscience from dead works to serye the living God ? And almost all things are by the law purged with blood ; and without shedding of blood is no remission. It was therefore necessary that the patterns of things in the heavens should be purified with these, but the heavenly things themselves with better sacrifices than these. For Christ is not entered into the holy places made with hands, which are the figures of the true ; but into heaven itself, now to appear in the pres- ence of God for us. Nor yet that he should offer himself often, as the high priest entereth into the holy place every year with blood of others ; for then must he often have suffered since the foundation of the world : but now once in the end of the world hath he appeared to put away sin by the sacrifice of himself. And as it is appointed unto men once to die, but after this the judgment : so Christ was once offered to bear the sins of many : and unto them that look for him shall he appear the second time without sin unto salvation." — Heb. ix. 13-14, 33-28. " By the which will we are sanctified through the offering of the body of Jesus Christ once for all. And every priest standeth daily ministering and offering oftentimes the same sacrifices, which can never take away sins : but this man, after he had offered one sacrifice for sins, for ever sat down on the right hand of God ; from henceforth expecting till his enemies be made his footstool. For by one offering he hath perfected forever them that are sanctifi^ed." — Heb. x. 10-14. "Having therefore, brethren, boldness to enter into the holiest by the blood of Jesus, by a new and living way which he hath consecrated for us through the vail, that is to say, his flesh," etc. — Heb. x. 19, 20. "Forasmuch as ye know that ye were not redeemed with corruptible things, as silver and gold, from your vain conversation received by tradition from your fathers ; but with the precious blood of Christ, as of a lamb without blemish and without spot." —1 Pet. i. 18, 19. "Who his own self bare our sins in his own body on the tree, that we being dead to sins should live unto righteousness ; by whose stripes ye were healed." — 1 Pet. ii. 34. " For Christ also hath once suffered for sins, the just for the unjust, that he might bring us to God, being put to death in the flesh, but quickened by the Spirit." — 1 Peter iii. 18. " But if we walk in the light as he is in the light, we have fel- lowship one with another, and the blood of Jesus Christ his Son cleans- eth us from all sin." — 1 John i. 1. "And ye know that he was mani- fested to take away our sins ; and in him is no sin^" — 1 John iii. 5. "In this was manifested the love of God toward us, because that God sent his only begotten Son into the world, that we might live through him. 270 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Herein is love, not that we loved God, but that he loved us, and sent his Son to be the propitiation for our sins." — 1 John iv. 9, 10. These, as every reader of the Bible must know, are only some of the passages that teach the doctrine of atonement and redemption by the death of Christ. It is truly wonderful in how many ways this doctrine is taught, assumed, and implied in the Bible. Indeed, it is emphatically the great theme of the Bible. It is expressed or implied upon nearly every page of divine inspiration. V. The next inquiry is what constitutes the atonement. The answer to this inquiry has been already, in part, unavoidably anticipated. Under this head I will show, — 1. That Christ's obedience to the moral law as a covenant of works, did not constitute the atonement. (1.) Christ owed obedience to the moral law, both as God and man. He was under as much obligation to be perfectly benevolent as any moral agent is. It was, therefore, impossible for him to perform any works of supererogation ; that is, so far as obedience to law was concerned, he could, neither as God nor as man, do anything more than fulfil its obli- gations. (3.) Had he obeyed for us, he would not have suffered for us. Were his obedience to be substituted for our obedience, he need not certainly have both fulfilled the law for us, as our substitute, under a covenant of works, and at the same time have suffered as a substitute, in submitting to the penalty of the law. (3.) If he obeyed the law as our substitute, then why should our own return to personal obedience be insisted upon as a sine qud nan of our salvation ? (4) The idea that any part of the atonement consisted in Christ's obeying the law for us, and in our stead and behalf, represents God as requiring : — (i.) The obedience of our substitute. (ii.) The same suffering, as if no obedience had been rendered. (iii.) Our repentance. (iv.) Our return to personal obedience. (v.) And then represents him as, after all, ascribing our salvation to grace. Strange grace this, that requires a debt to be paid several times over, before the obligation is discharged I 2. I must show that the atonement was not a commercial transaction. Some have regarded the atonement simply in the light of the payment of a debt ; and have represented Christ as purchasing the elect of the Father, and paying down the same amount of suffering in his own per- gon that justice would have exacted of them. To this I answer — ATONEMENT. 271 (1.) It is naturally impossible, as it would require that satisfaction should be made to retributive justice. Strictly speaking, retributive justice can never be satisfied, in the sense that the guilty can be punished as much and as long as he deserves ; for this would imply that he was punished until he ceased to be guilty, or became innocent. When law is once violated, the sinner can make no satisfaction. He can never cease to be guilty, or to deserve punishment, and no possible amount of suffer- ing renders him the less guilty or the less deserving of punishment : therefore, to satisfy retributive justice is impossible. (3. ) But, as we have seen in a former lecture, retributive justice must have inflicted on him eternal death. To suppose, therefore, that Chri'st sufEered in amount, all that was due to the elect, is to suppose that he sufEered an eternal punishment multiplied by the whole number of the elect. 3. The atonement of Christ was intended as a satisfaction of public justice. The moral law did not originate in the divine will, but is founded in his self-existence and immutable nature. He cannot therefore repeal or alter it. To the letter of the moral law there may be exceptions. God cannot repeal the precept, and just for this reason, he cannot set aside the spirit of the sanctions. For to dispense with the sanctions were a virtual repeal of the precept. He cannot, therefore, set aside the execu- tion of the penalty when the precept has been violated, without some- thing being done that shall meet the demands of the true spirit of the law. " Being justified freely by his grace through the redemption that is in Christ Jesus : whom God hath set forth to be a propitiation through faith in his blood, to declare his righteousness for the remission of sins that are past, through the forbearance of God ; to declare, I say, at this time his righteousness : that he might be just, and the justifier of him which believeth in Jesus." — Rom. iii. 24r-36. This passage assigns the reason, or declares the design, of the atonement, to have been to justify God in the pardon of sin, or in dispensing with the execution of law. Isa. xliii. 10-13 : " Yet it pleased the Lord to bruise him ; he hath put him to grief : when thou shalt make his soul an offering for sin, he shall see his seed, he shall prolong his days, and the pleasure of the Lord shall prosper in his hand. He shall see of the travail of his soul, and shall be satisfied : by his knowledge shall my righteous servant justify many ; for he shall bear their iniquities. Therefore will I divide him a portion with the great, and he shall divide the spoil with the strong ; because he hath poured out his soul unto death : and he was numbered with the transgressors : and he bare the sin of many, and made interces- sion for the transgressors." I present several further reasons why an atonement in the case of the 272 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. inhabitants of this world was preferable to punishment, or to the execu- tion of the divine law. Several reasons have already been assigned, to which I will add the following, some of which are plainly revealed in the Bible ; others are plainly inferrible from what the Bible does reveal ; and others still are plainly inferrible from the very nature of the case. (1.) God's great and disinterested love to sinners themselves was a prime reason for the atonement. ' John iii. 16. "For God so loved the world, that he gave his only begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him should not perish, but have everlasting life." (2.) His great love to the universe at large must have been another reason, inasmuch as it is impossible that the atonement should not exert an amazing influence over moral beings, in whatever world they might exist, and where the fact of atonement should be known. (3.) Another reason for substituting the sufferings of Christ in the place of the eternal damnation of sinners, is, that an infinite amount of suffering might be prevented. The relation of Christ to the universe rendered his sufferings so infinitely valuable and influential, as an ex- pression of God's abhorrence of sin on the one hand, and his great love to his subjects on the other, that an infinitely less amount of suffering in him than must have been inflicted on sinners, would be equally, and no doubt vastly more, influential in supporting the government of God, than the execution of the law upon them would have been. Be it borne in mind, that Christ was the lawgiver, and his suffering in behalf of sinners is to be regarded as the lawgiver and executive magistrate suf- fering in the behalf and stead of a rebellious province of his empire. As a governmental expedient it is easy to see the great value of such a substitute ; that on the one hand it fully evinced the determination of the ruler not to yield the authority of his law, and on the other, to evince his great and disinterested love for his rebellious subjects. (4.) By this substitution, an immense good might be gained, the eternal happiness of all that can be reclaimed from sin, together with all the augmented happiness of those who have never sinned, that must result from this glorious revelation of God. (5.) Another reason for preferring the atonement to the punishment of sinners must have been, that sin had afforded an opportunity for the highest manifestation of virtue in God : the manifestation of forbear- ance, mercy, self-denial, and suffering for enemies that were within his own power, and for those from whom he could expect no equivalent in return. It is impossible to conceive of a higher order of virtues than are exhibited in the atonement of Christ. It was vastly desirable that God should take advantage'of such an opportunity to exhibit his true charac- AtoKEMfiNT. 2'?3 ter, and sliow to the universe what was in his heart. The strength and stability of any government must depend upon the estimation in which the sovereign is held by his subjects. It was therefore indispensable, that God should improve the opportunity, which sin had afforded, to manifest and make known his true character, and thus secure the highest confi- dence of his subjects. (6.) In the atonement God consulted his own happiness and his own glory. To deny himself for the salvation of sinners, was a part of his own infinite happiness, always intended by him, and therefore always en- joyed. This was not selfishness in him, as his own well-being is of in- finitely greater value than that of all the universe besides ; he ought so to regard and treat it, because of its supreme and intrinsic value. (7. ) The atonement would present to creatures the highest possible motives to virtue. Example is the highest moral influence that can be exerted. If God, or any other being, would make others benevolent, he must manifest benevolence himself. If the benevolence manifested in the atonement does not subdue the selfishness of sinners, their case is hopeless. (8.) The circumstances of his government rendered an atonement necessary ; as the execution of law was not, as a matter of fact, a sufficient preventive of sin. The annihilation of the wicked would not answer the purposes of government. A full revelation of mercy, blended with such an exhibition of justice, was called for by the circumstances of the uni- verse. (9.) To confirm holy beings. Nothing could be more highly calcula- ted to establish and confirm the confidence, love, and obedience of holy beings, than this disinterested manifestation of love to sinners and rebels. (10.) To confound his enemies. How could anything be more di- rectly calculated to silence all cavils, and to shut every mouth, and for- ever close up all opposing lips, than such an exhibition of love and wil- lingness to make sacrifices for sinners ? (11.) The fact, that the execution of the law of God on rebel angels had not arrested, and could not arrest, the progress of rebellion in the universe, proves that something more needed to be done, in support of the authority of law, than would be done in the execution of its penalty upon rebels. While the execution of law may have a strong tendency to prevent the beginning of rebellion among loyal subjects, and to restrain rebels themselves ; yet penal infiictions do not, in fact, subdue the heart, under any government, whether human or divine. As a matter of fact, the law was only exasperating rebels, without confirming holy beings. Paul affirmed, that the action of the law upon his own mind, while in impenitence, was to beget in him all manner of concupiscence. One grand reason for giving the law was, to develop the 18 *-i74 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. nature of sin, and to show that the carnal mind is not subject to the law of God, neither indeed can be. The law was therefore given that the offence might abound, that thereby it might be demonstrated, that with- out an atonement there could be no salvation for rebels under the gov- ernment of God. (12.) The nature, degree, and execution of the penalty of the law, made the holiness and the justice of God so prominent, as to absorb too much of public attention to be safe. Those features of his character were so fully revealed, by the execution of his law upon the rebel angels, that to have pursued the same course with the inhabitants of this world, without the offer of mercy, might have had, and doubtless would have had, an injurious influence upon the universe, by creating more of fear than of love to God and his government. Hence, a fuller revelation of the love and compassion of God was necessary, to guard against the in- fluence of slavish fear. His taking human nature, and obeying unto death, under such cir- cumstances, constituted a good reason for our being treated as right- eous. It is a common practice in human governments, and one that is founded in the nature and laws of mind, to reward distinguished public service by conferring favors on the children of those who have rendered this service, and treating them as if they had rendered it themselves. This is both benevolent and wise. Its governmental, importance, its wis- dom and excellent influence, have been most abundantly attested in the experience of nations. As a governmental transaction, this same prin- ciple prevails, and for the same reason, under the government of God. All that are Christ's children and belong to him, are received for his sake, treated with favor, and the rewards of the righteous are bestowed upon them for his sake. And the public service which he has rendered to the universe, by laying down his life for the support of the divine gov- ernment, has rendered it eminently wise, that all who are united to him by faith should be treated as righteous for his sake. LECTURE XXVI. EXTENT OP ATONEMENT. VI. For whose lenefit the atonement was intended. 1. God does all things for himself ; that is, he consults his own glory and happiness, as the supreme and most influential reason for all his conduct. This is wise and right in him, because his own glory and happiness are infinitely the greatest good in and to the universe. He ATONEMENT. 275 made the atonement to satisfy himself. " God so loved the world, that he gave his only begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him should not perish, but have everlasting life." God himself, then, was greatly benefited by the atonement : in other words, his happiness has in a great measure resulted from its contemplation, execution, and results. 2. He made the atonement for the benefit of the universe. All holy beings are, and must be, benefited by it, from its very nature, as it gives them a higher knowledge of God than ever they had before, or ever could have gained in any other way. The atonement is the greatest work that he could have wrought for them, the most blessed and excel- lent, and benevolent thing he could have done for them. For this reason, angels are described as desiring to look into the atonement. The inhabitants of heaven are represented as being deeply interested in the work of atonement, and those displays of the character of God that are made in it. The atonement is then no doubt one of the greatest bless- ings that ever God conferred upon the universe of holy beings. 3. The atonement was made for the benefit particularly of the inhab- itants of this world, from its very nature, as it is calculated to benefit all the inhabitants of this world ; as it is a most stupendous revelation of God to man. Its nature is adapted to benefit all mankind. All mankind can be pardoned, if they are rightly affected and brought to repentance by it, as well as any part of mankind. 4. All do certainly receive many blessings on account of it. It is probable that, but for the atonement, none of our race, except the first human pair, would ever have had an existence. 5. All the blessings which mankind enjoy, are conferred on them on account of the atonement of Christ ; that is, God could not consistently wait on sinners, and bless, and do all that the nature of the case admits, to save them, were it not for the fact of atonement. 6. That it was made for all mankind, is evident from the fact that it is offered to all indiscriminately. 7. Sinners are universally condemned for not neceiving it. 8. If the atonement is not intended for all mankind, it is impossible for us not to regard God as insincere, in making them the offer of salvar tion through the atonement. 9. If the atonement was made only for a part, no man can know whether he has a right to embrace it, until by a direct revelation God has made known to him that he is one of that part. 10. If ministers do not believe that it was made for all men, they cannot heartily and honestly press its acceptance upon any individual, or congregation in the world ; for they cannot assure any individual, or congregation, that there is any atonement for him or them, any more than there is for Satan. fit6 SYSTEMA*tlC tHEOLOQY. If to this it should be replied, that for fallen angels no atonement has been made, but for some men an atonement has been made, so that it may be true of any individual that it was made for him, and if he will truly believe, he will thereby have the fact revealed, that it was, in fact, made for him ; I reply. What is a sinner to believe, as a condition of salvation ? Is it merely that an atonement was made for somebody ? Is this saving faith ? Must he not embrace it, and personally and indi- vidually commit himself to it, and to Christ ?— trust in it as made for him ? But how is he authorized to do this upon the supposition that tho atonement was made for some men only, and perhaps for him ? Is it saving faith to believe that it was possibly made for him, and by believ- ing this possibility, will he thereby gain the evidence that it was, in fact, made for him ? No, he must have the word of God for it, that it was made for him. Nothing else can warrant the casting of his soul upon it. How then is '"he truly to believe," or trust in the atonement, until he has the evidence, not merely that it possibly may have been, but that it actually vvas made for him ? The mere possibility that an atonement has been made for an individual, is no ground of saving faith. What is he to believe ? Why, that of which he has proof. But the supposition is, that he has proof only that it is possible that the atonement was made for him. He has a right, then, to believe it possi- ble that Christ died for him. And is this saving faith ? No, it is not. What advantage, then, has he over Satan in this respect. Satan knows that the atonement was not made for him ; the sinner upon the sapposi- tion knows that, possibly, it may have been made for him ; but the latter has really no more ground for trust and reliance than the former. He might hope, but he could not rationally believe. But upon this subject of the extent of the atonement, let the Bible speak for itself : " The next day John seeth Jesus coming unto him, and saith. Behold the Lamb of God, which taketh away the sin of the world." "For God so loved the world, that he gave his only begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him should not perish, but have everlasting life. For God sent not his Son into the world, to condemn the world : but that the world through him might be saved." "And said unto the woman, Now we believe, not because of thy saying ; for we have heard him ourselves, and know that this is indeed the Christ, the Saviour of the world."— John i. 29 ; iii. 16, 17 ; iv. 42. " Therefore, as by the offence of one, judgment came upon all men to condemnation ; even so, by the righteousness of one, the free gift came upon all men unto justification of life." — Bom. v. 18. "For the love of Christ constraineth us ; because we thus judge, that if one died for all, then were all deed : and that he died for all, that they which live should not henceforth live unto themselves, but unto him which died for them, and rose again."— ATONEMENT 277 2 Cor. V. 14, 15, "Who gave himself a ransom for all, to be testified in due time." "For therefore we both labor and suffer reproach, because we trust in the living God, who is the Saviour of all men, especially of those that believe." — 1 Tim. ii. 6 ; iv. 10. " And he is the propitia- tion for our sins ; and not for ours only, but also for the sins of the whole world." — 1 John ii. 2. That the atonement is suflBcient for all men, and, in that sense, gen- eral, as opposed to particular, is also evident from the fact, that the in- vitations and promises of the gospel are addressed to all men, and all are freely offered salvation through Christ. " Look unto me, and be ye saved, all the ends of the earth : for I am God and there is none else." " Ho 1 every one that thirstet'h, come ye to the waters, and he that hath no money ; come ye, buy and eat ; yea, come, buy wine and milk without money and without price. Wherefore do ye spend money for that which is not bread, and your labor for that which satisfieth not ? Hearken dili- gently unto me, and eat ye that which is good, and let your soul delight itself in fatness. Incline your ear, and come unto me : hear, and your soul shall live ; and I will make an everlasting covenant with you, even the sure mercies of David." — Isa. xlv. 22; Iv. 1-3. "Come unto me all ye that are weary and heavy laden, and I will give you rest. Take my yoke upon yon, and learn of me ; for I am meek and lowly in heart ; and ye shall find rest unto your souls. For my yoke is easy, and my bur- den is light." "Again, he sent forth other servants, saying, Tell them which are bidden, Behold, I have prepared my dinner ; my oxen and my fatlings are killed, and all things are ready ; come unto the marriage." — Matt. xi. 28-30 ; xxii. 4. " And sent his servant at supper time to say to them that were bidden. Come, for all things are now ready." — Luke xiv. 17. " In the last day, the great day of the feast, Jesus stood and cried, saying, If any man thirst, let him come unto me, and drink." — John vii. 37. " Behold, I stand at the door, and knock ; if any man hear my voice, and open the door, I will come in to him, and will sup with him, and he with me." "And the Spirit and the bride say. Come. And let him that heareth say. Come. And let him that is athirst come. And whosoever will, let him take the water of life freely." — Rev. iii. 20 ; xxii. 17. Again : I infer that the atonement was made, and is sufScient, for all men, from the fact that God not only invites all, but expostulates with them for not accepting his invitations. " Wisdom crieth without ; she uttereth her voice in the streets : she crieth in the chief place of con- course, in the openings of the gates ; in the city she uttereth her words, saying. How long ye simple ones, will ye love simplicity ? and the scorn- ers delight in their scorning, and fools hate knowledge ? Turn you at my reproof : behold I will pour out my Spirit unto you, I will make 278 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. known my words unto you." — Prov, i. 20-23. " Come now, and let us reason together, saitli the Lord : though your sins be as scarlet, they shall be white as snow, though they be red like crimson, they shall be as wool." — Isaiah i. 18. "Thus saith the Lord, thy Redeemer, the Holy One of Israel, I am the Lord thy God which teacheth thee to profit, which leadeth thee by the way that thou shouldest go. Oh that thou hadst hearkened to my commandments ! then had thy peace been as It river, and thy righteousness as the waves of the sea." — Isaiah xlviii. 17, 18. " Say unto them, as I live, saith the Lord God, I have no pleas- ure in the death of the wicked ; hut that the wicked turn from his way and live ; turn ye, turn ye from your evil ways ; for why will ye die, house of Israel?" — Bzek. xxxiii. 11. "Hear ye now what the Lord saith : Arise, contend thou before the mountains, and let the hills hear thy voice. Hear ye, mountains, the Lord's controversy, and ye strong foundations of the earth ; for the Lord hath a controversy with his peo- ple, and he will plead with Israel. my people, what have I done unto thee ? and wherein have I wearied thee ? testify against me." — Micah, vi. 1-3. " Jerusalem, Jerusalem, thou that killest the prophets, and stonest them which are sent unto thee, how often would I have gathered thy children together, even as a hen gathereth her chickens under her wings, and ye would not ! " — Matt, xxiii. 37. Again : the same inference is forced upon us by the fact that God complains of sinners for rejecting his overtures of mercy : " Because I have called, and ye refused ; I have stretched out my hand, and no man regarded." — Prov. i. 24. " But they refused to hearken, and puUed away the shoulder, and stopped their ears, that they should not hear. Yea, they made their hearts as an adamant stone, lest they should hear the law, and the words which the Lord of hosts hath sent in his Spirit by the former prophets : therefore came a great wrath from the Lord of hosts. Therefore it is come to pass ; that as he cried and they would not hear : so they cried, and I would not hear, saith the Lord of hosts." — Zechariah vii. 11, 12, 13. "The kingdom of heaven is like unto a certain king which made a marriage for his son. And sent forth his servant to call them that were bidden to the wedding : and they would not come. Again, he sent forth other servants, saying, Tell them which are bidden. Behold I have prepared my dinner ; my oxen and my fatlings are killed,' and all things are ready ; come unto the marriage. But they made light of it, and went their ways, one to his farm, another to his merchandise : and the remnant took his servants, and treated them spite- fully, and slew them." — Matthew xxii. 2, 3, 4, 5, 6. "And sent hig ser- vant at supper-time to say to them that were bidden. Come ; for all things are now ready. And they all with one consent began to make excuse. The first said unto him, I have bought a piece of ground, and 1 must ATONEMENT. 279 needs go and see it : I pray theie have me excused. And another said, I have bought five yoke of oxen, and I go to prove them : I pray thee have me excused. And another said, I have married a wife ; and therefore I cannot come." — Luke xiv. 17, 18, 19, 20. "And ye will not come to me, that ye might have life." — John v. 40. "Ye stiff-necked and un- circumcised in heart and ears, ye do always resist the Holy Ghost : as your fathers did, so do ye." — Acts vii. 51. "And as he reasoned of righteousness, temperance, and judgment to come, Felix trembled, and answered. Go thy way for this time ; when I have a convenient season I will call for thee." — Acts xxiv. 35. VII. / nmo proceed to answer objections. 1. Objection to the fact of atonement. It is said, that the doctrine of atonement represents God as unmerciful. To this I answer, (1.) This objection supposes that the atonement was demanded to satisfy retributive instead of public justice. (2.) The atonement was the exhibition of a merciful disposition. It was because God was disposed to pardon that he consented to give his own Son to die as the substitute of sinners. (3.) The atonement is infinitely the most illustrious exhibition of mercy ever made in the universe. The mere pardon of sin, as an act of sovereign mercy, could not have been compared, had it been possible, with the merciful disposition displayed in the atonement itself. 2. It is objected that the atonement is unnecessary. The testimony of the world and of the consciences of all men are against this objection. This is universally attested by their expiatory sacrifices. These, as has been said, have been offered by nearly every nation of whose religious history we have any reliable account. This shows that human beings are universally conscious of being sinners, and under the government of a sin-hating God ; that their intelligence de- mands either the punishment of sinners, or that a substitute should be offered to public justice ; that they all have the idea that substitution is conceivable, and hence thej offer their sacrifices as expiatory, A heathen philosopher can answer this objection, and rebuke the folly of him who makes it. 3. It is objected, that it is unjust to punish an innocent being instead of the guilty. (1.) Yes, it would not only be unjust, but it is impossible with God to punish an innocent moral agent at all. Punishment implies guilt An innocent being may suffer, but he cannot be punished. Christ voluntarily " suffered, the just for the unjust." He had a right to exer. cise this self-denial ; and as it was by his own voluntary consent, no in< justice was done to any one. 280 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. (2.) If he had lio right to make an atonement, he had no right to consult and promote his own happiness and the happiness of others ; for it is said that " for the joy that was set before him, he endured the cross, despising the shame." 4. It is objected that the doctrine of atonement is utterly incredible. To this I have replied in a former lecture ; but will here again state, that it would be utterly incredible upon any other supposition, than that God is love. But if God is love, as the Bible expressly affirms that he is, the work of atonement is just what might be expected of him, under the circumstances ; and the doctrine of atonement is then the most rea- sonable doctrine in the universe. 5. It is objected to the doctrine of atonement, that it is of a demoral- izing tendency. There is a broad distinction between the natural tendency of a thing, and such an abuse of a good thing as to make it the instrument of evil. The best things and doctrines may be, and often are, abused, and their natural tendency perverted. Although the doctrine of the atone- ment may be abused, yet its natural tendency is the direct opposite of demoralizing. Is the manifestation of infinitely disinterested love natu- rally calculated to beget enmity ? Who does not know that the natural tendency of manifested love is to excite love in return ? Those who have the most cordially believed in the atonement, have exhibited the purest morality that has ever been in this world ; while the rejecters of the atonement, almost without exception, exhibit a loose morality. This is, as might be expected, from the very nature and moral influence of atonement. 6. To a general atonement, it is objected that the Bible represents Christ as laying down his life for his sheep, or for the elect only, and not for all mankind. (1.) It does indeed represent Christ as laying down his life for his sheep, and also for all mankind. 1 John ii. 3. — " And he is the propi- tiation for our sins ; and not for ours only, but also for the sins of the whole world." John iii. 17 — " For God sent not his Son into the world to condemn the world ; but that the world through him might be saved." Heb. ii. 9 — "But we see Jesus, who was made a little lower than the angels for the suffering of death, crowned with glory and honor ; that he, by the grace of God, should taste death for every man." (2.) Those who object to the general atonement, take substantially the same course to evade this doctrine, that Unitarians do to set aside the doctrine of the Trinity and the Divinity of Christ. They quote those passages that prove the unity of God and the humanity of Christ, and then take it for granted that they have disproved the doctrine of the Trinity and Christ's Divinity. The asserters of limited atonement ATONEMENT. 281 in like manner, quote those passages that prove that Christ died for the elect and for his saints, and then take it for granted that he died for none else. To the Unitarian, we reply, we admit the unity of God and the humanity of Christ, and the full meaning of those passages of scrip- ture which you quote in proof of these doctrines ; but we insist that this is not the whole truth, but that there are still other passages which provo the doctrine of the Trinity, and the Divinity of Christ. Just so to the asserters of limited atonement, we reply, we believe that Christ laid down his life for his sheep, as well as you ; but we also believe that " he tasted death for every man." John iii. 16. — "For God so loved the world, that he gave his only begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him should not perish, but have everlasting life." 7. To the doctrine of general atonement it is objected, that it would be folly in God to provide what he knew would be rejected ; and that to Buffer Christ to die for those who, he foresaw, would not repent, would be a useless expenditure of the blood and suffering of Christ. (1.) This objection assumes that the atonement was a literal payment of a debt, which we have seen does not consist with the nature of the atonement. (2.) If sinners do not accept it, in no view can the atonement be use- less, as the great compassion of God, in providing an atonement and offering them mercy, will forever exalt his character, in the estimation of holy beings, greatly strengthen his government, and therefore benefit the whole universe. (3.) If all men rejected the atonement, it would, nevertheless, be of infinite value to the universe, as the most glorious revelation of God that was ever made. 8. To the general atonement it is objected, that it implies universal salvation. It would indeed imply this, upon the supposition that the atonement is the literal payment of a debt. It was upon this view of the atone- ment, that Universalism first took its stand. Universalists taking it for granted, that Christ had paid the debt of those for whom he died, and finding it fully revealed in the Bible that he died for all mankind, natu- rally, and if this were correct, properly, inferred the doctrine of uni- versal salvation. But we have seen, that this is not the nature of atone- ment. Therefore, this inference falls to the ground. 9. It is objected that, if the atonement was not a payment of the debt of sinners, but general in its nature, as we have maintained, it secures the salvation of no one. It is true, that the atonement, of itself, does not secure the salvation of any one ; but the promise and oath of Ood, that Christ shall have a seed to serve him, provide that sepurity. 282 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. LECTURE XXVIL BEGENEEATION. Ik the examination of this subject I will — I, Point out the common distinction between regeneration and conver- sion. 1. Regeneration is the term used by some theologians to express the divine agency in changing the heart. With them regeneration does not include and imply the activity of the subject, but rather excludes it. These theologians, as will be seen in its place, hold that a change of heart is first effected by the Holy Spirit while the subject is passive, which change lays a foundation for the exercise, by the subject, of repentance, faith, and love. 3. The term conversion with them expresses the activity and turning of the subject, after regeneration is effected by the Holy Spirit. Conver- sion with them does not include or imply the agency of the Holy Spirit, but expresses only the activity of the subject. With them the Holy Spirit first regenerates or changes the heart, alter wnich the sinner turns or converts himself. So that God and the subject work each in turn. God first changes the heart, and as a consequence, the subject afterwards converts himself or turns to God. Thus the subject is passive in regen- eration, but active in conversion. When we come to the examination of the philosophical theories of regeneration, we shall see that the views of these theologians respecting regeneration result naturally and necessarily from their holding the dog- ma of constitutional moral depravity, which we have recently examined. Until their views on that subject are corrected, no change can be ex- pected in their views of this subject. n. The assigned reasons for this distinction. 1. The original term plainly expresses and implies other than the agency of the subject. 3. We need and must adopt a term that will express the Divine agency. 3. Eegeneration is expressly ascribed to the Holy Spirit. 4. Conversion, as it implies and expresses the activity and turning of the subject, does not include and imply any Divine agency, and therefore does not imply or express what is intended by regeneration. 5. As two agencies are actually employed in the regeneration and con- REGENERATION. 283 version of a sinner, it is necessary to adopt terms that will clearly teach this fact, and clearly distinguish between the agency of God and of the creature. 6. The terms regeneration and conversion aptly express this distinc- tion, and therefore should be theologically employed. III. The objections to this distinction. 1. The original term yemaa, with its derivatives, may be rendered, (1.) To beget. (2.) To bear or bring forth. (3.) To be begotten. (4.) To be born, or brought forth. 2. Eegeneration is, in the Bible, the same as the new birth. 3. To be born again is the safoe thing, in the Bible use of the term, as to have a new heart, to be a new creature, to pass from death unto life. In other words, to be born again is to have a new moral character, to be- come holy. To regenerate is to make holy. To be bom of God, no doubt expresses and includes the Divine agency, but it also includes and expresses that which the Divine agency is employed in effecting, namely, making the sinner holy. Certainly, a sinner is not regenerated whose moral character is unchanged. If he were, how could it be truly said, that whosoever is born of God overcometh the world, doth not commit sin, cannot sin, etc.? If regeneration does not imply and include a change of moral character in the subject, how can regeneration be made the condition of salvation ? The fact is, the term regeneration, or the being born of God, is designed to express primarily and principally the thing done, that is, the making of a sinner holy, and expresses also the fact, that God's agency induces the change. Throw out the idea of what is done, that is, the change of moral character in the subject, and he would not be born again, he would not be regenerated, and it could not be truly said, in such a case, that God had regenerated him. It has been objected, that the term really means and expresses only the Divine agency ; and, only by way of implication, embraces the idea of a change of moral character and of course of activity in the subject. To this I reply — (1.) That if it really expresses only the Divine agency, it leaves out of Tiew the thing effected by Divine agency. (2.) That it really and fully expresses not only the Divine agency, but also that which this agency accomplishes. (3.) The thing which the agency of God brings about, is a new or epiritual birth, a resurrection from spiritual death, the inducing of a new and holy life. The thing done is the prominent idea expressed or in- tended by the term. (4.) The thing done implies the turning or activity of the subject. It is nonsense to aflSrm that his moral character is changed without any activity or agency of bis own. Passive holiness is impossible. Holiness 284 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. is obedience to the law of God, the law of love, and of course consists m the activity of the creature. (5.) We have said that regeneration is synonymous, in the Bible, with a new heart. But sinners are required to make to themselves a new heart, which they could not do, if they were not active in this change. If the work is a work of God, in such a sense, that He must first regen- erate the heart or soul before the agency of the sinner begins, it were absurd and unjust to require him to make to himself a new heart, until he is first regenerated. Regeneration is ascribed to man in the gospel, which it could not be, if the term were designed to express only the agency of the Holy Spirit. " For though ye have ten thousand instructors in Christ, yet have ye not many fathers ; for in Christ Jesus I have begotten you through the gospel." — 1 Cor. iv. 15. (6.) Conversion is spoken of in the Bible as the work of another than the subject of it, and cannot therefore have been designed to express only the activity of the subject of it. (i.) It is ascribed to the word of God. — "The law of the Lord is perfect, converting the soul : the testimony of the Lord is sure, making wise the simple." — Ps. xix. 7. (ii.) To man. " Brethren, if any of you do err from the truth, and one convert him ; let him know, that he which converteth the sinner from the error of his way shall save a soul from death, and shall hide a multitude of sins." — James v. 19, 20. Both conversion and regeneration are sometimes in the Bible ascribed to God, sometimes to man, and sometimes to the subject ; which shows clearly that the distinction under examination is arbitrary and theologi- cal, rather than biblical. The fact is, that both terms imply the simultaneous exercise of both human and Divine agency. The fact that a new heart is the thing done, demonstrates the activity of the subject ; and the word regeneration, or the expression " born of the Holy Spirit," asserts the Divine agency. The same is true of conversion, or the turning of the sinner to God. God is said to turn him and he is said to turn himself. God draws him, and he follows. In both alike God and man are both active, and their ac- tivity is simultaneous. God works or draws, and the sinner yields or turns, or which is the same thing, changes his heart, or, in other words, is born again. The sinner is dead in trespasses and sins. God calls on him, " Awake thou that sleepest, and arise from the dead, and Christ shall give thee light." — Eph. v. 14. God calls ; the sinner hears and answers, Here am I. God says. Arise from the dead. The sinner puts forth his activity, and God draws him into life ; or rather, God draws, »nd the sinner coI^es fprth to lij^e, REGENERATION. 285 (t.) The distinction set up is not only not recognized in the Bible, but is plainly of most injurious tendency, for two reasons : — (i.) It assumes and inculcates a false philosophy of depravity and regeneration. (ii.) It leads the sinner to wait to be regenerated, before he repents or turns to God. It is of most fatal tendency to represent the smner aa under a necessity of waiting to be passively regenerated, before he gives himself to God. As the distinction is not only arbitrary, but anti-scriptural and inju- rious, and inasmuch as it is founded in, and is designed to teach a phi- lo^phy false and pernicious on the subject of depravity and regeneration, I shall drop and discard the distinction ; and in our investigations henceforth, let it be understood, that I use regeneration and conversion as synonymous terms. IV. What regeneration is not. It is not a change in the substance of soul or body. If it were, sin- ners could not be required to effect it. Such a change would not consti- tute a change of moral character. No such change is needed, as the sinner has all the faculties and natural attributes requisite to render perfect obedience to God. All he needs is to be induced to use these powers and attributes as he ought. The words conversion and regenera- tion do not imply any change of substance, but only a change of moral state or of moral character. The terms are not used to express a phys- ical, but a moral change. Begeneration does not express or imply the creation of any new faculties or attributes of nature, nor any change what- ever in the constitution of body or mind. I shall remark further upon this point when we come to the examination of the philosophical theories of regeneration before alluded to. V. What regeneration is. " It has been said that regeneration and a change of heart are identical. It is important to inquire into the scriptural use of the term heart. The term, like most others, is used in the Bible in various senses. The heart is often spoken of in the Bible, not only as possessing moral character, but as being the source of moral action, or as the fountain from which good and evil actions flow, and of course as constituting the fountain of holiness or of sin, or, in other words still, as comprehending, strictly speaking, the whole of moral character. " But those things which pro- ceed out of the mouth come forth from the heart ; and they defile the man. ¥or out of the heart proceed evil thoughts, murders, adulteries, fornications, thefts, false witness, blasphemies." — Matt. xv. 18, 19. " generation of vipers, how can ye, being evil, speak good things ? for out 286 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. of the abundance of tlie heart the mouth speaketh. A good man out of the good treasure of the heart bringeth forth good things : and an evil man out of the evil treasure bringeth forth evil things." — Matt. xii. 34, 35. When the heart is thus represented as possessing moral character, and as the fountain of good and evil, it cannot mean, — 1. The bodily organ that propels the blood. 2. It cannot mean the substance of the soul or mind itself : substance cannot in itself possess moral character. 3. It is not any faculty or natural attribute. 4. It cannot consist in any .constitutional taste, relish, or appetite, for these cannot in themselves have moral character. 5. It is not the sensibility or feeling faculty of the mind : for we have seen, that moral character cannot be predicated of it. It is true, and let it be understood, that the term heart is used in the Bible in these senses, but not when the heart is spoken of as the fountain of moral action. "When the heart is represented as possessing moral character, the word cannot be meant to designate any involuntary state of mind. For neither the substance of soul or body, nor any involuntary state of mind can, by any possibility, possess moral character in itself. The very idea of moral character implies, and suggests the idea of, a free action or intention. To deny this, were to deny a first truth. 6. The term heart, when applied to mind, is figurative, and means something in the mind that has some point of resemblance to the bodily organ of tha]L name, and a consideration of the function of the bodUy organ will suggest the true idea of the heart of the mind. The heart of the body propels the vital current, and sustains organic life.' It is the fountain from which the vital fluid flows, from which either life or death may flow, according to the state of the blood. The mind as well as the body has a heart which, as we have seen, is represented as a fountain, or as an eflBcient propelling influence, out of which flows good or evil, ac- cording as the heart is good or evil. This heart is represented, not only as the source or fountain of good and evil, but as being either good or evil in itself, as constituting the character of man, and not merely as be- ing capable of moral character. It is also represented as something over which we have control, for which we are responsible, and which, in case it is wicked, we are bound to change on pain of death. Again : the heart, in the sense in which we are considering it, is that, the radical change of which constitutes a radical change of moral character. This is plain from Matthew xii. 34, 35, and xv. 18, 19, already considered. 7. Our own consciousness, then, must inform us that the heart of the mind that possesses these characteristics, can be nothing else than the supreme ultimate intention of the soul. Regeneration is represented in REGENERATION. 287 the Bible as constituting a radical change of character, as the resurrection from a death in sin, as the beginning of a new and spiritual life, as con- stituting a new creature, as a new creation, not a physical, but a moral or spiritual creation, as conversion, or turning to God, as giving God the heart, as loving God with all our heart, and our neighbor as ourselves. Now we have seen abundantly, that moral character belongs to, or is an attribute of, the ultimate choice or intention of the soul. Kegeneration then is a radical change of the ultimate intention, and, of course, of the end or object of life. We have seen, that the choice of an end is efficient in producing executive volitions, or the use of means to obtain its end. A selfish ultimate choice is, therefore, a wicked heart, out of which flows every evil ; and a benevolent ultimate choice is a good heart, out of which flows every good and commendable deed. Eegeneration, to have the characteristics ascribed to it in the Bible> must consist in a change in the attitude of the will, or a change in its ultimate choice, intention, or preference ; a change from selfishness to benevolence ; from choosing self-gratification as the supreme and ulti- ' mate end of life, to the supreme and ultimate choice of the highest well- being of God and of the universe ; from a state of entire consecration to self-interest, self-indulgence, self -gratification for its own sake or as an end, and as the supreme end of life, tq a state of entire consecration to God, and to the interests of his kingdom as the supreme and ultimate end of life. VI. The universal necessity of regeneration. 1. The necessity of regeneration as a condition of salvation must be co-extensive with moral depravity. This has been shown to be universal among the unregenerate moral agents of our race. It surely is impossi- ble, that a world or a universe of unholy or selfish beings should be happy. It is impossible that heaven should be made up of selfish beings. It is intuitively certain that without benevolence or holiness no moral being can be ultimately happy. Without regeneration, a selfish soul can by no possibility be fitted either for the employments, or for the enjoyments, of heaven. 2. The scriptures expressly tench the universal necessity of regenera- tion. " Jesus answered and said unto him, Verily, verily, I say unto thee. Except a man be born again, he cannot see the kingdom of God." —John iii. 3. " For in Christ Jesus neither circumcision availeth any thing, nor uncircumcision, but a new creature." — Gal. vi. 15. VII. Agencies employed in regeneration. 1. The scriptures often ascribe regeneration to the Spirit of God. " Jesus answered, Verily, verily, I say unto thee, Except a man b? borji 288 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. of water and of the Spirit, he cannot enter into the kingdom of God. That which is born of the flesh is flesh ; and that which is born of the Spirit is spirit."— John iii. 5, 6. " Which were born, not of blood, nor of the will of the flesh, nor of the will of man, but of God." — John i. 15. 2. We have seen that the subject is active in regeneration, that regeneration consists in the sinner changing his ultimate choice, inten- tion, preference ; or in changing from selfishness to love or benevolence ; or, in other words, in turning from the supreme choice of self -gratifica- tion, to the supreme love of God and the equal love of his neighbor. Of course the subject of regeneration must be an agent in the work. 3. There are generally other agents, one or more human beings, concerned in persuading the sinner to turn. The Bible recognizes both the subject and the preacher as agents in the work. Thus Paul says : " I have begotten you through the gospel." Here the same word is used which is used in another case, where regeneration is ascribed to God. Again : an apostle says, " Ye have purified your souls by obeying the truth." Here the work is ascribed to the subject. There are then always two, and generally more than two agents employed in effecting * the work. Several theologians have held that regeneration is the work of the Holy Spirit alone. In proof of this they cite those passages that ascribe it to God. But I might just as lawfully insist that it is the work of man alone, and quote those passages that ascribe it to man, to substan- tiate my position. Or I might assert that it is alone the work of the subject, and in proof of this position quote those passages that ascribe it to the subject. Or again, I might assert that it is efEected by the truth alone, and quote such passages as the following to substantiate my posi- tion : " Of his own will begat He us with the word of truth, that we should be a kind of first-fruits of his creatures." — James i. 18. " Being born again, not of corruptible seed, but of incorruptible by the word of God, which liveth and abideth forever." — 1 Peter i. 23. It has been common to regard the third person as a mere instrument in the work. But the fact is, he is a willing, designing, responsible agent, as really so as God or the subject is. If it be inquired how the Bible can consistently ascribe regeneration at one time to God, at another to the subject, at another to the truth, at another to a third person ; the answer is to be sought in the nature of the work. The work accomplished is a change of choice, in respect to an end or the end of life. The sinner whose choice is changed, must of course act. The end to be chosen must be clearly and forcibly presented ; this is the work of the third person, and of the Holy Spirit. The Spirit takes of the things of Ohrist and shows them to the soul. The truth is employed, or it is truth which must necessarily be employed, as an instra* ment to induce a, change of choice. REGENERATION. 289 VIII. Instrumentalities employed in the worh 1. Truth. This must, from the nature of regeneration, be employed in effecting it, for regeneration is nothing else than the will being duly influenced by trath. 2. There may be, and often are, many providences concerned in en- lightening the mind, and in inducing regeneration. These are instrumen- talities. They are means or instruments of presenting the truth. Mercies, judgments, men, measures, and in short all those things that conduce to enlightening the mind, are instrumentalities employed in effecting it. Those who hold to physical or constitutional moral depravity must hold, of course, to constitutional regeneration ; and, of course, consist- ency compels them to maintain that there is but one agent employed in regeneration, and that is the Holy Spirit, and that no instrument what- ever is employed, because the work is, according to them, an act of creative power ; that the very nature is changed, and of course no instru- ment can be employed, any nlore than in the creation of the world. These theologians have affirmed, over and over again, that regeneration is a miracle ; that there is no tendency whatever in the gospel, however presented, and whether presented by God or man, to regenerate the heart. Dr. Griffin, in his Park Street Lectures, maintains that the gospel, in its natural and necessary tendency, creates and perpetuates only opposition to, and hatred of God, until the heart is changed by the. Holy Spirit. He understands the carnal mind to be not a voluntary state, not a minding of the flesh, but the very nature and constitution of the mind ; and that enmity against God is a part, attribute, or appetite of the nature itself. Consequently, he must deny the adaptability of the gospel to regenerate the soul. It has been proclaimed by this class of theologians, times without number, that there is no philosophical connection between the preaching of the gospel and the regeneration of sinners, no adaptedness in the gospel to produce that result ; but, on the contrary, that it is adapted to produce an opposite result. The favorite illustrations of their views have been Ezekiel's prophesying over the dry bones, and Christ's restoring sight to the blind man by putting clay on his eyes. Ezekiel's prophesying over the dry bones had no tendency to quicken them, they say. And the clay used by the Saviour was calculated rather to destroy than to restore sight. This shows how easy it is for men to adopt a pernicious and absurd philosophy, and then to find, or think they find, it supported by the Bible. What must be the effect of inculcating the dogma, that the gospel has nothing to do with regenerating the sinner ? Instead of telling him that regen- eration is nothing else than his embracing the gospel, to tell him that he must wait, and first have his constitution recreated before he can possi- 290 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. bly do anything but oppose God 1 This is to tell him the greatest and most abominable and ruinous of falsehoods. It is to mock his intelli- gence. What ! call on him, on pain of eternal death, to believe ; to embrace the gospel ; to love God with all his heart, and at the same time represent him as entirely helpless, and constitutionally the enemy of God and of the gospel, and as being under the necessity of waiting for God to regenerate his nature, before it is possible for him to do otherwise than to hate God with all his heart 1 IX. In regeneration the subject is loth passive and active. 1. That he is active is plain from what has been said, and from the very nature of the change. 2. That he is, at the same time, passive, is plain from the fact that he acts only when and as he is acted upon. That is he is passive in the perception of the truth presented by the Holy Spirit. I know that this perception is no" part of regeneration. But it is simultaneous with re- generation. It induces regeneration. It is the condition and the occa- sion of regeneration. Therefore the subject of regeneration must be a passive recipient or percipient of the truth presented by the Holy Spirit, at the moment, and during the act of regeneration. The Spirit acts upon him through or by the truth : thus far he is passive. He closes with the truth : thus far he is active. What a mistake those theologians have fallen into who represent the subject as altogether passive in regen- eration ! This rids the sinner at once of the conviction of any duty or responsibility about it. It is wonderful that such an absurdity should have been so long maintained in the church. But while it is maintained, it is no wonder that sinners are not converted to God. While the sinner believes this, it is impossible, if he has it in mind, that he should be re- generated. He stands and waits for God to do what God requires him to do, and which no one can do for him. Neither God, nor any other being, can regenerate him, if he will not turn. If he will not change his choice, it is impossible that it should be changed. Sinners who have been taught thus and have believed what they have been taught, would never have been regenerated had not the Holy Spirit drawn off their at- tention from this error, and ere they were aware, induced them to close in with the ofEer of life. X. What is implied in regeneration. 1. The nature of the change shows that it must be instantaneous. It is a change of choice, or of intention. This must be instantaneous. The preparatory work of conviction and enlightening the mind may have been gradual and progressive. But when regeneration occurs, it must be in- Btantaneous. THEORIES OP BEGENBRATION. 291 3. It implies an entire present change of moral character, that is, a change from entire sinfulness to entire holiness. We have seen that it consists in a change from selfishness to benevolence. We have also seen that selfishness and benevolence cannot co-exist in the same mind ; that selfishness is a state of supreme and entire consecration to self ; that be- nevolence is a state of entire and supreme consecration to God and the good of the universe. Eegeneration, then, surely implies an entire change of moral character. Again : the Bible represents regeneration as a dying to sin and be- coming alive to God. Death in sin is total depravity. This is generally admitted. Death to sin and becoming alive to God, must imply entire present holiness. 3. The scriptures represent regeneration as the condition of salvation in such a sense, that if the subject should die immediately after regen- eration, and without any further change, he would go immediately to heaven. Again : the scriptures require only perseverance in the first love, as the condition of salvation, in case the regenerate soul should live long in the world subsequently to regeneration. 4. When the scriptures require us to grow in grace, and in the knowledge of the Lord Jesus Christ, this does not imply that there is yet sin remaining in the regenerate heart which we are required to put away by degrees. But the spirit of the requirement must be, that we should acquire as much knowledge as we can of our moral relations, and continue to conform to all truth as fast as we know it. This, and nothing else, is implied in abiding in our first love, or abiding in Christ, living and walk- ing in the Spirit LECTURE XXVIII. REGENERATION. XI. Philosophical theories of regeneration. The principal theories that have been advocated, so far as my knowl- edge extends, are the following : — 1. The taste scheme. 2. The divine efficiency scheme. 3. The sus- ceptibility scheme. 4. The divine moral suasion scheme. 1. The taste scheme. This theory is based upon that view of mental philosophy which re- gards the mental heart as identical with the sensibility. Moral deprav- 292 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. ity, a^jcording to this school, consists in a constitutional relish, taste, or craving for sin. They hold the doctrine of original sin — of a sinful na- ture or constitution, as was shown in my lectures on moral depravity. The heart of the mind, in the estimation of this school, is not identical with choice or intention. They hold that it does not consist in any vol- untary state of mind, hut that it lies hack of, and controls voluntary ac- tion, or the actions of the will. The wicked heart, according to them, consists in an appetency or constitutional taste for sin, and with them, the appetites, passions, and propensities of human nature in its fallen state, are in themselves sinful. They often illustrate their ideas of the sinful taste, craving, or appetite for sin, by reference to the craving of carnivorous animals for flesh. A change of heart, in the view of this philosophy, must consist in a change of constitution. It must be a physical change, and wrought by a physical, as distinguished from a moral agency. It is a change wrought by the direct and physical power of the Holy Spirit in the constitution of the soul, changing its susceptibilities, implanting or creating a new taste, relish, appetite, craving for, or love of, holiness. It is, as they ex- press it, the implantation of a new principle of holiness. It is described as a creation of a new taste or principle, as an infusion of a holy princi- ple, etc. This scheme, of course, holds and teaches that, in regeneration, the subject is entirely passive. With this school, regeneration is exclu- sively the work of the Holy Spirit, the subject having no agency in it. It is an operation performed upon him, may be, while he is asleep, or in a fit of derangement, while he is entirely passive, or perhaps when at the moment he is engaged in flagrant rebellion against God. The agency by which this work is wrought, according to them, is sovereign, irresistible, and creative. They hold that there are of course no means of regenera- tion, as it is a direct act of creation. They hold the distinction already referred to and examined, between regeneration and conversion ; that when the Holy Spirit has performed the sovereign operation and im- planted the new principle, then the subject is active in conversion, or in turning to God. They hold that the soul, in its very nature, is enmity against God j that therefore the gospel has no tendency to regenerate or convert the soul to God ; but, on the contrary, that previous to regeneration by the sovereign and physical agency of the Holy Spirit, every exhibition of God made in the gospel, tends only to inflame and provoke this constitutional enmity. They hold, that when the sinful taste, relish, or craving for sin is weakened, for they deny that it is ever wholly destroyed in this life, or while the soul contijiues connected with the body, and a holy taste, relish, or craving is implanted or infused by the Holy Spirit into the constitu- THEORIES OF BEGBNEBATION. 293 tion of the soul, then, and not till then, the gospel has a tendency to turn or convert the sinner from the error of his ways. As I have said, their philosophy of moral depravity is the basis of their philosophy of regeneration. It assumes the dogma of original sin, as taught in the Presbyterian Confession of Faith, and attempts to har- monize the philosophy of regeneration with that philosophy of sin, op moral depravity. Upon this scheme or theory of regeneration, I remark,— (1.) That it has been sufficiently refuted in the lectures on moral de- pravity. If, as was then shown, moral depravity is altogether voluntary, and consists in selfishness, or in a voluntary state of mind, this philoso- phy of regeneration is of course without foundation. (2.) It was shown in the lectures on moral depravity, that sin is not chosen for its own sake, — that there is no constitutional relish, taste, or craving for sin, — that in sinful choice, sin is not the end or object chosen, but that self-gratification is chosen, and that this choice is sin- ful. If this is so, then the whole philosophy of the taste scheme tarns out to be utterly baseless. The taste, relish, or craving, of which this philosophy speaks, is not a taste, relish or craving for sin, but for certain things and objects, the enjoyment of which is, to a certain extent, and upon certain condi- tions, lawful. But when the will prefers the gratification of taste or ap- petite to higher interests, this choice or act of will is sin. The sin never lies in the appetite, but in the will's consent to unlawful indulgence. (3.) This philosophy confounds appetite or temptation to unlawful indulgence, with sin. Nay, it represents sin as consisting mostly, if not altogether, in that which is only temptation. (4.) It throws the blame of unregeneracy upon God. If the sinner is passive, and has no agency in it ; if it consists in what this philosophy teaches, and is accomplished in the manner which this theory represents, it is self-evident that God alone is responsible for the fact, that any sin- ner is unregenerate. (5.) It renders holiness after regeneration physically necessary, just as sin was before, and perseverance also as physically necessary, and fall- ing from grace as a natural impossibility. In this case holy exercises and living are only the gratification of a constitutional appetite, implanted in regeneration. Let us consider next, — 2. The divine efficiency scheme or theory. This scheme is based upon, or rather is only a carrying out of, an an- cient heathen philosophy, bearing the same name. This ancient philoso- phy denies second causes, and teaches that what we call laws of nature are nothing else than the mode of divine operation. It d^iii^s that th§ 294r SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. universe would even exist for a moment, if the divine upholding were withdrawn. It maintains that the universe exists only by an act of pres- ent and perpetual creation. It denies that matter, or mind, has in itself any inherent properties that can originate laws or motions ; that all ac- tion, whether of matter or mind, is the necessary result of direct divine irresistible efficiency or power ; that this is not only true of the natural universe, but also of all the exercises and actions of moral agents in all worlds. The abettors of the divine efiBciency scheme of regeneration apply this philosophy especially to moral agents. They hold, that all the exercises and actions of moral agents in all worlds, and whether those exercises be holy or sinful, are produced by a divine eflSciency, or by a direct act of Omnipotence ; that holy and sinful acts are alike effects of an irresistible cause, and that this cause is the power and agency, or efficiency, of God. This philosophy denies constitutional moral depravity, or original sin, and maintains that moral character belongs alone to the exercises or choices of -the will ; that regeneration does not consist in the creation of "■ any new taste, relish, or craving, nor in the implantation or infusion of any new principles in the soul : but that it consists in a choice conformed to the law of God, or in a change from selfishness to disinterested benev- olence ; that this change is effected by a direct act of divine power or efficiency, as irresistible as any creative act whatever. This philosophy teaches, that the moral character of every moral agent, whether holy or sinful, is formed by an agency as direct, as sovereign, and as irresistible, as that which first gave existence to the universe ; that true submission to God implies the hearty consent of the will to have the character thus formed, and then to be treated accordingly, for the glory of God. To this theory I make the following objections : — (1.) It tends to produce and perpetuate a sense of divine injustice. To create a character by an agency as direct and irresistible as that of the creation of the world itself, and then treat moral beings according to that character so formed, is wholly inconsistent with aU our ideas of justice. (3.) It contradicts human consciousness. I know it is said, that con- sciousness only gives our mental actions and states, but not the cause of them. This I deny, and affirm that consciousness not only gives us our mental actions and states, but it also gives us the cause of them ; espe- cially it gives the fact, that we ourselves are the sovereign and efficient causes of the choices and actions of our will. I am as conscious of origi- nating in a sovereign manner my choices, as I am of the choices them- selves. We cannot but affirm to ourselves, that we are the efficient causes of our own choices and volitions. THEORIES OF REGENERATION. 295 (3.) The philosophy in question, really represents God as the only agent, in any proper sense of that term, in the universe. If God pro- duces the exercises of moral beings in the manner represented by this philosophy, then they are in fact no more agents than the planets are agents. If their exercises are all directly produced by the power of God, it is ridiculous to call them agents. What we generally call moral beings and moral agents, are no more so than the winds and the waves, or any other substance or thing in the universe. (4.) If this theory be true, no being but God has, or can have, moral character. No other being is the author of his own actions. (5.) This theory obliges its advocates, together with all other necessita- rians, to give a false and nonsensical definition of free agency. Free agency, according to them, consists in doing as we will, while their theory denies the power to will, except as our willings are necessitated by God. But as we have seen in former lectures, this is no true account of freedom, or liberty. Liberty to execute my choices is no liberty at all. Choice is connected with its sequents by a law of necessity ; and if an effect follow my volitions, that effect follows by necessity, and not freely. All freedom of will must, as was formerly shown, consist in the sovereign power to originate our own choices. If I am unable to will, I am unable to do any thing ; and it is absurd to afiSrm, that a being is a moral or a free agent, who has not power to originate his own choices. (6.) If this theory is true, the whole moral government of God is no government at all, distinct from, and superior to, physical government. It overlooks and virtually denies the fundamentally important distinc- tion between moral and physical power, and moral and physical govern- ment. All power and all government, upon this theory, are physical. (7.) This theory involves the delusion of all moral beings. God not only creates our volitions, but also creates the persuasion and affirmation that we are responsible for them. 3. The susceptibility scheme. This theory represents, that the Holy Spirit's influences are both physi- cal and moral ; that he, by a direct and physical influence, excites the susceptibilities of the soul and prepares them' to be afEected by the truth ; that he, thereupon, exerts a moral or persuasive influence by presenting the truth, which moral influence induces regeneration. This philosophy maintains the necessity and the fact of a physical in- fluence superadded to the moral or persuasive inflaence of the Holy Spirit as a sine qud non of regeneration. It admits and maintains, that regen- eration is effected solely by a moral influence, but also that a work pre- paratory to the efficiency of the moral influence, and indispensable to its efficiency, in producing regeneration, is performed by a direct and physi- cal agency of the Holy Spirit upon the constitutional susceptibilities of 296 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. the aoul, to quicken and wake it up, and predispose it to be deeply and duly affected by the truth. It is maintained by the defenders of this scheme, that the representa- tions of the Bible upon the subject of the Holy Spirit's agency in regen- eration, are such as to forbid the supposition, that his influence is alto- gether moral or persuasive, and such as plainly to indicate that he also exerts a physical agency, in preparing the mind to be duly affected by the truth. , In reply to this argument, I observe, — that I fear gi*eatly to dispar- age the agency of the Holy Spirit in the work of man's redemption from sin, and would, by no means, resist or deny, or so much as call in ques- tion, any thing that is plainly taught or implied in the Bible upon this subject. I admit and maintain that regeneration is always induced and effected by the personal agency of the Holy Spirit. The question now before us relates wholly to the mode, and not at all to the fact, of divine agency in regeneration. Let this be distinctly understood, for it has been common for theologians of the old school, as soon as the dogma of a physical regeneration, and of a physical influence in regeneration, has been called in question, to cry out and insist that this is Pelagianism, and that it is a denial of divine influence altogether, and that it is teaching a self-regeneration, independent of any divine influence. I have been ashamed of such representations as these on the part of Christian divines, and have been distressed by their want of candor. It should, however, be distinctly stated that, so far as I know, the defenders of the theory now under consideration have never manifested this want of candor to- ward those who have called in question that part of their theory that re- lates to a physical influence. Since the advocates of this theory admit that the Bible teaches that regeneration is induced by a divine moral suasion, the point of debate is simply, whether the Bible teaches that there is also a physical influence exerted by the Holy Spirit, in exciting the constitutional susceptibilities. We will now attend to their proof texts. " Then opened he their under- standing, that they might understand the scriptures." — Luke xxiv. 45. It is aflSrmed, that this text seems to teach or imply a physical iufluenee in opening their understandings. But what do we mean by such language as this in common life ? Language is to be understood according to the sub- ject- matter of discourse. Here the subject of discourse is the understand- ing. But what can be intended by opening it ? Can this be a physical prying, pulling, or forcing open any department of the constitution ? Such language in common life would be understood only to mean, that such instruction was imparted as to secure a right understanding of the scriptures. Every one knows this, and why should we suppose and assume that anything more is intended here ? The context plainly THEOBIES OF REGENERATION. 297 indicates that this was the thing, and the only thing done in fti.s case. " Then he said unto them, fools, and slow of heart to believe all that the prophets have spoken ! Ought not Christ to have suffered these things, and to enter into his glory ? And beginning at Moses and all ihe prophets, he expounded unto them in all the scriptures the things concerning himself. — And said unto them, thus it is written, and thus it behooved Christ to suffer, and to rise from the dead the third day." — Luke xxiv. 25-37, 46. From these verses it appears that he expounded the scriptures to them, when in the light of what had passed, and in the light of that measure of divine illumination which was then imparted to them, they understood the things which he explained to them. It does not seem to me, that this passage warrants the inference that there was a physical influence exerted. It certainly aflBrms no such thing. "And a certain woman named Lydia, a seller of purple, of the city of Thyatira, which worshipped God, heard us ; whose heart the Lord opened, that she attended unto the things which were spoken of Paul." — ^Acts xvi. 14. Here is an expression similar to that just examined. Here it is said, " that the Lord opened the heart of Lydia, so that she attended," etc. ; that is, the Lord inclined her to attend. But how ? Why, say the advocates of this scheme, by a physical influence. But how does this appear ? What is her heart that it should be pulled, or forced open ? and what can be intended by the assertion, " that the Lord opened her heart ? " All that can be meant is, that the Lord secured her attention, or disposed her to attend, and so enlightened her when she did attend, that she believed. Surely here is no assertion of a physical influence, nor, so far as I can see, any just ground for the inference, that such an influence was exerted. A moral influence can sufficiently explain all the phenomena ; and any text that can equally well consist with either of two opposing theories, can prove neither. Again : there are many passages that represent God as opening the spiritual eyes, and passages in which petitions are offered to God to do this. It is by this theory assumed that such passages strongly imply a physical influence. But this assumption appears to me unwarranta- ble. We are in the habit of using just such language, and speak of opening each other's eyes, when no such thing is intended or implied, as a physical influence, and when nothing more than a moral or persuasive influence is so much as thought of. Why then resort to such an assump- tion here ? Does the nature of the case demand it ? This I know is contended for by those who maintain a constitutional moral depravity. But this dogma has been shown to be false, and it is admitted to be so by those who maintain the theory now under consideration. Admitting, then, that the constitution is not morally depraved, should it be inferroJ that any constitutional change, or physical inflnepce is needed toprpdnce 298 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. regeneration ? I can see no sufficient reason for believing, or affirming, that a physical influence is demanded or exerted. This much I freely admit, that we cannot affirm the impossibility of such an influence, nor the impossibility of the necessity of such an influence. The only ques- tion with me is, does the Bible plainly teach or imply such an influence ? Hitherto I have been unable to see that it does. The passages already quoted are of a piece with all that are relied upon in support of this theory, and as the same answer is a sufficient reply to them all, I will not spend time in citing and remarking upon them. Again : a physical influence has been inferred from the fact, that sinners are represented as dead in trespasses and sins, as asleep, etc. etc. But all such representations are only declaratory of a moral state, a state of voluntary alienation from God. If the death is moral, and the sleep moral, why suppose that a physical influence is needed to correct a moral evil ? Cannot truth, when urged and pressed by the Holy Spirit, effect the requisite change ? But a physical influence is also inferred from the fact, that truth makes so different an impression at one time from what it does at another. Answer : this can well enough be accounted for by the fact, that sometimes the Holy Spirit so presents the truth, that the mind apprehends it and feels its power, whereas at another time he does not. But it is said, that there sometimes appears to have been a prepara- tory work performed by a physical influence pre-disposing the mind to attend to, and be affected by, the truth. Answer : there often is no doubt a preparatory work pre-disposing the mind to attend to, and be affected by, truth. But why assume that this is a physical influence ? Providential occurrences may have had much to do with it. The Holy Spirit may have been directing the thoughts and communicating instruc- - tions in various ways, and preparing the mind to attend and obey. Who then is warranted in the affirmation that this preparatory influence is physical ? I admit that it may be, but I cannot see either that it must be, or that there is any good ground for the assumption that it is. 4. The last theory to be examined is that of a Divine Moral Suasion. This theory teaches — (1.) That regeneration consists in a change in the ultimate intention or preference of the mind, or in a change from selfishness to disinterested benevolence ; and — (3.) That this change is induced and effected by a divine moral in- fluence ; that is, that the Holy Spirit effects it with, through, or by the truth. The advocates of this theory assign the following as the principal reasons in support of it. (1.) The Bible expressly affirms it. "Jesus answered. Verily, verily, I gay unto thee. Except a man be born of water and of the Spirit, he THEORIES OF REGENERATION. 299 cannot enter into the kingdom of God. That which is born of the flesh is flesh ; and that which is born of the Spirit is spirit." — John iii. 5, 6. " Being born again, not of corruptible seed, but of incorruptible, by the word of God, which liveth and abideth for ever." — 1 Pet. i. 23. "Of his own will begat he us with the word of truth, that we should be a kind of first-fruits of his creatures." — James i. 18. " For though ye have ten thousand instructors in Christ, yet have ye not many fathers : for in Christ Jesus I have begotten you through the gospel." — 1 Cor. iv. 15. (3.) Men are represented as being sanctified by and through the truth. " Sanctify them through thy truth : thy word is truth." — John Xvii. 17. " Now ye are clean through the word which I have spoken unto you." — John xv. 3. (3.) The nature of regeneration decides the philosophy of it so far as this, that it must be effected by truth, addressed to the heart through the intelligence. The regenerate are conscious of having been influenced by the truth in turning to God. They are conscious of no other influence than light poured upon the intelligence, or truth presented to the mind. When God aflBrms that he regenerates the soul with or by the truth, we have no right to infer that he does it in some other way. This he does affirm ; therefore the Bible has settled the philosophy of regenera- tion. That he exerts any other than a moral influence, or the influence of divine teaching and illumination, is sheer assumption. EEMAEKS. 1. This scheme honors the Holy Spirit without disparaging the truth of God. 2. Eegeneration by the Holy Spirit through the truth illustrates the wisdom of God. There is a deep and divine philosophy in regeneration. 3. This theory is of great practical importance. For if sinners are to be regenerated by the influence of truth, argument, and persuasion, then ministers can see what they have to do, and how it is that they are to be " workers together with God." 4. So also sinners may see, that they are not to wait for a physical regeneration or influence, but must submit to, and embrace, the truth, if they ever expect to be saved. 5. If this theory is true, sinners are most likely to be regenerated while sitting under the sound of the gospel, while listening to the clear exhibition of truth. 6. Ministers should lay themselves out, and press every consideration upon the attention of sinners, just as heartily and as freely, as if they expected to convert them themselves. They should aim at, and expect the regeneration of sinners, upon the spot, and before they leave the house of God. 300 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOQY. 7. Sinners must not wait for and expect physical omnipotence to re- generate them. The physical omnipotence of God affords no presump- tion that aU men will be converted ; for regeneration is not effected by physical power. God cannot do the sinner's duty, and regenerate him without the right exercise of the sinner's own agency. 8. This view of regeneration shows that the sinner's dependence upon the Holy Spirit arises entirely not of his own voluntary stubbornness, and that his guilt is all the greater, by how much the more perfect this kind of dependence is. 9. Physical regeneration, under every modification of it, is a stum- bling-block. Original or Qonstitutional sinfulness, physical regeneration, and all their kindred and resulting dogmas, are alike subversive of the gospel, and repulsive to the human intelligence ; and should be laid aside as relics of a most unreasonable and confused philosophy. LECTURE XXIX. EVIDENCES OF REGBNEEATION. I. Introductory remarJes. 1. In ascertaining what are, and what are not, evidences of regenera- tion, we must constantly keep in mind what is not, and what is regenera- tion ; what is not, and what is implied in it. 2. We must constantly recognize the fact, that saints and sinners have precisely similar constitutions and constitutional susceptibilities, and therefore that many things are common to both. What is common to both cannot, of course, be an evidence of regeneration. 3. That no state of the sensibility has any moral character in itself. That regeneration does not consist in, or imply, any physical change whatever, either of the intellect, sensibility, or the faculty of will. 4. That the sensibility of the sinner is susceptible of every kind and degree of feeling that is possible to saints. 5. The same is true of the consciences of both saints and sinners, and of the intelligence generally. 6. The inquiry is. What are evidences of a change in the ultimate intention ? What is evidence that benevolence is the ruling choice, preference, intention of the soul ? It is a plain question, and demands, and may have, a plain answer. But so much error prevails as to the nature of regeneration, and, consequently, as to what are evidences of EVIDENCES OF EEQENEHATlON. 301 regeneration, that we need patience, discrimination, and perseverance, and withal candor, to get at the truth upon this subject. II. Wherein the experience and outward life of saints and sinners may agree. It is plain that they may be alike, in whatever does not consist in, or necessarily proceed from, the attitude of their will ; that is, in whatever is constitutional or involuntary. For example :— 1. They may both desire their own happiness. This desire is consti- tutional, and, of course, common to both saints and sinners. 2. They may both desire the happiness of others. This also is con- stitutional, and of course common to both saints and sinners. There is no moral character in these desires, any more than there is in the desire for food and drink. That men have a natural desire for the happiness of others, is evident from the fact that they manifest pleasure when others are happy, unless they have some selfish reason for envy, or unless the happiness of others is in some way inconsistent with their own. They also manifest uneasiness and pain when they see others in misery, unless they have some selfish reason for desiring their misery. 3. Saints and sinners may alike dread their own misery, and the misery of others. This is strictly constitutional, and has therefore no moral character. I have known that very wicked men, and men who had been infidels, when they were convinced of the truths of Christianity, manifested great concern about their families and about their neigh- bors ; and, in one instance, I heard of an aged man of this description who, when convinced of the truth, went and warned his neighbors to flee from the wrath to come, avowing at the same time his conviction, that there was no mercy for him, though he felt deeply concerned for others. Such like cases have repeatedly been witnessed. The case of the rich man in hell seems to have been one of this description, or to have illus- trated the same truth. Although he knew his own case to be hopeless, yet he desired that Lazarus should be sent to warn his five brethren, lest they also should come to that place of torment. In this case and in the case of the aged man just named, it appears that they not only desired that others should avoid misery, but they actually tried to prevent it, and used the means that were within theil: reach to save them. Now it is plain that this desire took control of their will, and, of course, the state of the will was selfish. It sought to gratify desire. It was the pain and dreM of seeing their misery, and of having them miserable, that led them to use means to prevent it. This was not benevolence, but self- ishness. Let it be understood, then, that as both saints and sinners constitu- tionally desire, not only their own happiness, but also the happiness of 302 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. others, they may alike rejoice in the happiness and safety of others, and in converts to Christianity, and may alike grieve at the danger and misery of those who are unconverted. I well recollect, when far from home, and while an impenitent sinner, I received a letter from my young- est brother, informing me that he was converted to God. He, if he was converted, was, as I supposed, the first and the only member of the family who then had a hope of salvation. I was at the time, and both before and after, one of the most careless sinners, and yet on receiving this in- telligence, I actually wept for joy and gratitude, that one of so prayer- less a family was likely to be saved. Indeed, I have repeatedly known sinners to manifest much interest in the conversion of their friends, and express gratitude for their conversion, although they had no religion themselves. These desires have no moral character in themselves. In as far as they control the will, the will yielding to impulse instead of the law of the intelligence, this is selfishness. 4. They may agree in desiring the triumph of truth and righteous- ness, and the suppression of vice and error, for the sake of the bearings of these things on self and friends. These desires are constitutional and natural to both, under certain circumstances. When they do not influ- ence the will, they have in themselves no moral character ; but when they influence the will, their selfishness takes on a religious type. It then manifests zeal in promoting religion. But if desire, and not the intelligence, controls the will, it is selfishness notwithstanding. 5. Moral agents constitutionally approve of what is right and disap- prove of what is wrong. Of course, both saints and sinners may both ap- prove of and delight in goodness. I can recollect weeping at an instance of what, at the time, I supposed to be goodness, while at the same time, I was not religious myself. I have no doubt that wicked men, not only often are conscious of strongly approving the goodness of God, but that they also often take delight in contemplating it. This is constitutional, both as it respects the intellectual approbation, and also as it respects the feeling of delight. It is a great mistake to suppose that sinners are never conscious of feelings of complacency and delight in the goodness of God. The Bible represents sinners as taking delight in drawing near to him. " Yet they seek me daily, and delight to know my ways, as a nation that did righteousness, and forsook not the ordinance of their God : they ask of me the ordinances of justice ; they take delight in approaching to God." — Isa. Iviii. 2. " And lo, thou art unto them as a very lovely song of one that hath a pleasant voice, and can play well on an instru- ment : for they hear thy words, but they do them not." — Ezek. xxxiii. 33. "For I delight in the law of God after the inward man."— Eom. rii. 32. 6. Saints and sinners may alike not only intellectually approve, but EVIDENCES OF REGENERATION. 303 have feelings of deep complacency in, tlie characters of good men, some- times good men of their own time and of their acquaintance, but more frequently good men either of a former age, or, if of their own age, of a distant country. The reason is this : good men of their own day and neighborhood are very apt to render them uneasy in their sins ; to annoy them by their faithful reproofs and rebukes. This ofEends them, and overcomes their natural respect for goodness. But who has not observed the fact, that good and bad men unite in praising, admiring, and loving, — so far as feeling is concerned — ^good men of by-gone days, or good men at a distance, whose life and rebukes have annoyed the wicked in their own neighborhood ? The fact is, that moral agents, from the laws of their being, necessarily approve of goodness wherever they witness it. Multitudes of sinners are conscious of this, and suppose that this is a vir- tuous feeling. It is of no use to deny, that they sometimes have feelings of love and gratitude to God, and of respect for, and complacency in good men. They often have these feelings, and to represent them as always having feelings of hatred and of opposition to God and to good men, is sure either to offend them, or to lead them to deny the truths of religion, if they are told that the Bible teaches this. Or, again, it may lead them to think themselves Christians, because they are conscious of such feel- ings as they are taught to believe are peculiar to Christians. Or again, they may think that, although they are not Christians, yet they are far from being totally depraved, inasmuch as they have so many good de- sires and feelings. It should never be forgotten, that saints and sinners may agree in their opinions and intellectual views and judgments. Many professors of religion, it is to be feared, have supposed religion to consist in desires and feelings, and have entirely mistaken their own character. Indeed, nothing is more common than to hear religion spoken of as consisting altogether in mere feelings, desires, and emotions. Professors relate their feelings, and suppose themselves to be giving an account of their religion. It is infinitely important, that both professors of religion and non-professors, should understand more than most of them do of their mental constitution, and of the true nature of religion. Multi- tudes of professors of religion have, it is to be feared, a hope founded altogether upon desires and feelings that are purely constitutional, and therefore common to both saints and sinners. 7. Saints and sinners agree in this, that they both disapprove of, and are often disgusted with, and deeply abhor, sin. They cannot but disap- prove of sin. Necessity is laid upon every moral agent, whatever his character may be, by the law of his being, to condemn and disapprove of sin. And often the sensibility of sinners, as well as of saints, is filled with deep disgust and loathing in view of sin. I know that representar tions the direct opposite of these are often made. Sinners are repre- 304 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Bented as uniyersally having complacency in sin, as having a constitu tional craving for sin, as they have for food and drink. But such representations are false and most injurious. They contradict the sinner's consciousness, and lead him either to deny his total depravity, or to deny the Bible, or to think himself regenerate. As was shown when upon the subject of moral depravity, sinners do not love sin for ita own sake ; yet they crave other things, and this leads to prohibited in- dulgence, which indulgence is sin. But it is not the sinfulness of the indulgence that was desired. That might have produced disgust and loathing in the sensibility, if it had been considered even at the moment of the indulgence. For example : suppose a licentious man, a drunkard, a gambler, or any other wicked man, engaged in his favorite indulgence, and suppose that the sinfulness of this indulgence should be strongly set before his mind by the Holy Spirit. He might be deeply ashamed and disgusted with himself, and so much so as to feel a great contempt for himself, and feel almost ready, were it possible, to spit in his own face. And yet, unless this feeling becomes more powerful than the desire and feeling which the will is seeking to indulge, the indulgence will be per- severed in, notwithstanding this disgust. If the feeling of disgust should for the time overmatch the opposing desire, the indulgence will be, for the time being, abandoned for the sake of gratifying or appeasing the feeling of disgust. But this is not virtue. It is only a change in the form of selfishness. Feeling still governs, and not the law of the intelli- gence. The indulgence is only abandoned for the time being, to gratify a stronger impulse of the sensibility. The will, will of course return to the indulgence again, when the feelings of fear, disgust, or loathing subside. This, no doubt, accounts for the multitudes of spurious con- versions sometimes witnessed. Sinners are convicted, fears awakened, and disgust and loathing excited. These feelings for the time become stronger than their desires for their former indulgences, and conse- quently they abandon them for a time, in obedience, not to the law of God or of their intelligence, but in obedience to their fear, disgust, and shame. But when conviction subsides, and the consequent feelings are no more, these spurious converts " return like a dog to his vomit, and like a sow that was washed to her wallowing in the mire." It should be distinctly understood, that all these feelings of which I have spoken, and indeed any class or degree of mere feelings, may exist in the sensibility ; and further, that these or any other feelings may, in their turn, control the will, and produce of course a corresponding outward life, and yet the heart be and remain all the while in a selfish state, or in a state of total depravity. Indeed, it is perfectly common to see the impenitent sinner manifest much disgust and opposition to sin in himself and in others, yet this is not principle in him ; it is only the effect of present EVIDENCES OB* REaENERAtlON, 305 feeling. The next day, or perhaps hour, he will repeat his sin, or do that which, when heheld in others, enkindled his indignation. 8. Both saints and sinners approve of, and often delight in, justice. It is common to see in courts of justice, and on various other occasions, impenitent sinners manifest great complacency in the administration of justice, and the greatest indignation at, and abhorrence of, injustice. So strong is this feeling sometimes that it cannot be restrained, but will burst forth like a smothered volcano, and carry desolation before it. It is this natural love of justice, and abhorrence of injustice, common alike to saints and sinners, to which popular tumults and bloodshed are often to be ascribed. This is not virtue, but selfishness. It is the will giving itself up to the gratification of a constitutional impulse. But such feel- ings and such conduct are often supposed to be virtuous. It should always be borne in mind that the love of justice, and the sense of delight in it, and the feeling of opposition to injustice, are not only not peculiar to good men, but that such feelings are no evidence whatever of a regen- erate heart. Thousands of instances might be adduced as proofs and illustrations of this position. But such manifestations are too common to need to be cited, to remind any one of their existence. 9. The same remarks may be made in regard to truth. Both saints and sinners have a constitutional respect for, approbation of, and delight in truth. Who ever knew a sinner to approve of the character of a liar ? What sinner will not resent it, to be accused or even suspected of lying ? All men spontaneously manifest their respect for, complacency in, and approbation of truth. This is constitutional ; so that even the greatest liars do not, and cannot, love lying for its own sake. They lie to gratify, not a love for falsehood on its own account, but to obtain some object which they desire more strongly than they hate f.ilsehood. Sinners, in spite of themselves, venerate, respect, and fear a man of truth. They just as necessarily despise a liar. If they are liars, they despise them- selves for it, just as drunkards and debauchees despise themselves for indulging their filthy lusts, and yet continue in them. 10. Both saints and sinners not only approve of, and delight in good men, when, as I have said, wicked men are not annoyed by them, but they agree in reprobating, disapproving, and abhorring wicked men and devils. Who ever heard of any other sentiment and feeling being ex- pressed either by good or bad men, than of abhorrence and indignation toward the devil ? Nobody ever approved, or can approve, of his charac- ter ; sinners can no more approve of it than holy angels can. If he could approve of and delight in his own character, hell would cease to be hell, and evil would become his good. But no moral agent can, by any possibility, know wickedness and approve it. No man, saint or sinner, can entertain any other sentiments and feelings toward the devil, or 80 306 SYSTEMATIC THBOLOGY. wicked men, but those of disapprobation, distrust, disrespect, and often of loathing and abhorrence. The intellectual sentiment will be uniform. Disapprobation, distrust, condemnation, will always necessarily possess the minds of all who know wicked men and devils. And often, as occa- sions arise, wherein their characters are clearly revealed, and under cir- cumstances favorable to such a result, the deepest feelings of disgust, of loathing, of indignation, and abhorrence of their wickedness, will mani- fest themselves alike among saints and sinners. 11. Saints and sinners may be equally honorable and fair in business transactions, so far as the outward act is concerned. They have diflfer- ent reasons for their conduct, but outwardly it may be the same. This leads to the remark, — 12. That selfishness in the sinner, and benevolence in the saint, may, and often do, produce, in many respects, the same results or manifesta- tions. For example : benevolence in the saint, and selfishness in the sinner, may beget the same class of desires, to wit, as we have seen, de- sire for their own sanctification, and for that of others, to be useful, and to have others so ; desires for the conversion of sinners, and many such like desires. 13. This leads to the remark, that, when the desires of an impenitent person for these objects become strong enough to influence the will, he may take the same outward course, substantially, that the saint takes in obedience to his intelligence. That is, the sinner is constrained by his feelings to do what the saint does from principle, or from obedience to the law of his intelligence. In this, however, although the outward manifestations be the same for the time being, yet the sinner is entirely selfish, and the fiaint benevolent. The saint is controlled by principle, and the sinner by impulse. In this case, time is needed to distinguish between them. The sinner not having the root of the matter in him, will return to his former course of life, in proportion as his convictions of the truth and importance of religion subside, and his former feelings return ; while the saint will evince his heavenly birth, by manifesting his sympathy with God, and the strength of principle that has taken pos- session of his heart. That is, he will manifest that his intelligence, and not his feelings, controls his will. REMARKS. 1. For want of these and such like discriminations, many have stum- bled. Hypocrites have held on to a false hope, and lived upon mere con- stitutional desires and spasmodic turns of giving up the will, during sea- sons of special excitement, to the control of these desires and feelings. These spasms they call their waking up. But no sooner does their ex- citement subside, than selfishness again assumes its wonted forms. It is EVIDENCES OF REGENERATION. 307 truly wonderful and appalling to see to what an extent tliis is true. Be- cause, in seasons of special excitement they feel deeply, and are conscious of feeling, as they say, and acting, and of being entirely sincere in fol- lowing their impulses, they have the fullest confidence in their good estate. They say they cannot doubt their conversion. They felt so and so, and gave themselves up to their feelings, and gave much time and money to promote the cause of Christ. Now this is a deep delusion, and one of the most common in Christendom, or at least one of the most common that is to be found among what are called revival Christians. This class of deluded souls do not see that they are, in such cases, gov- erned by their feelings, and that if their feelings were changed, their conduct would be so, of course ; that as soon as the excitement subsides, they will go back to their former ways, as a thing of course. When the state of feeling that now controls them has given place to their former feelings, they will of course appear as they used to do. This is, in few words, the history of thousands of professors of religion. 2. This has greatly stumbled the openly impenitent. Not knowing how to account for what they often witness of this kind among professors of religion, they are led to doubt whether there is any such thing as true religion. Again : many sinners have been deceived just in the way I have pointed out, and have afterwards discovered that they had been deluded, but could not understand how. They have come to the conclusion that everybody is deluded, and that all professors are as much deceived as they are. This leads them to reject and despise all religion. 3. Some exercises of impenitent sinners, and of which they are con- scious, have been denied for fear of denying total depravity. They have been represented as necessarily hating God and all good men ; and this hatred has been represented as a feeling of malice and enmity towards God. Many impenitent sinners are conscious of having no such feelings ; but, on the contrary, they are conscious of having at times feelings of respect, veneration, awe, gratitude, and affection towards God and good men. To this class of sinners, it is a snare and a stumbling-block to tell them, and insist, that they only hate God, and Christians, and ministers, and revivals ; and to represent their moral depravity to be such, that they crave sin as they crave food, and that they necessarily have none but feelings of mortal enmity against God. Such representations either drive them into infidelity on the one hand, or to think themselves Christians on the other. But those theologians who hold the views of constitu- tional depravity of which we have spoken, cannot, consistently with their theory, admit to these sinners the real truth, and then show them con- clusively that in all their feelings which they call good, and in all their yielding to be influenced by them, there is no virtue ; that their desires 308 StSTEMATtC THEOLOGY. and feelings have in themselves no moral character, and that when they yield the will to their control, it is only selfishness. The thing needed is a philosophy and a theology that will admit and explain ^,11 the phenomena of experience, and not deny human conscious- ness. A theology that denies human consciousness is only a curse and a stumbling-block. But such is the doctrine of universal constitutional moral depravity. It is frequently true, that the feelings of sinners become exceedingly rebellious and exasperated, even to the most intense opposition of feeling toward God, and Christ, and ministers, and revivals, and toward every- thing of good report. If this class of sinners are converted, they are very apt to suppose, and to represent all sinners as having just such feelings as they had. But this is a mistake, for many sinners never had those feelings. Nevertheless, they are no less selfish and guilty than the class who have the rebellious and blasphemous feelings which I have mentioned. This is what they need to know. They need to under- stand definitely what sin is, and what it is not ; that sin is selfishness ; that selfishness is the yielding of the will to the control of feeling, and that it matters not at all what the particular class of feelings is, if feelings control the will, and not intelligence. Admit their good feelings, aa they call them, and take pains to show them, that these feelings are merely constitutional, and have in themselves no moral character. 4. The ideas of depravity and of regeneration, to which I have often alluded, are fraught with great mischief in another respect. Great numbers, it is to be feared, both of private professors of religion and of ministers, have mistaken the class of feelings of which I have spoken, as common among certain impenitent sinners, for religion. They have heard the usual representations of the natural depravity of sinners, and also have heard certain desires and feelings represented as religion. They are conscious of these desires and feelings, and also, sometimes, when they are very strong, of being influenced in their conduct by them. They assume, therefore, that they are regenerate, and elected, and heirs of salvation. These views lull them asleep. The philosophy and theol- ogy that misrepresent moral depravity and regeneration thus, must, if consistent, also misrepresent true religion ; and oh I the many thousands that have mistaken the mere constitutional desires and feelings, and the selfish yielding of the will to their control; for true religion, and have gone to the bar of God with a lie in their right hand ! 5, Another great evil has arisen out of the false views I have been exposing, namely : — Many true Christians have been much stumbled and kept in bondage, and their comfort and their usefulness much abridged, by finding tliem- Belves, from time to time, very languid and unfeeling. Supposing reli- EVIDENCES OF REGENERATION. 309 jpon to consist in feeling, if at any time the sensibility becomes ex- nausted, and their feelings subside, they are immediately thrown into unbelief and bondage. Satan reproaches them for their want of feeling, and they have nothing to say, only to admit the truth of his accusations. Having a false philosophy of religion, they judge of the state of their hearts by the state of their feelings. They confound their hearts with their feelings, and are in almost constant perplexity to keep their hearts right, by which they mean their feelings, in a state of great excitement. Again : they are not only sometimes languid, and have no pious feel- ings and desires, but at others they are conscious of classes of emotions ■which they call sin. These they resist, but still blame themselves for having them in their hearts, as they say. Thus they are brought into bondage again, although they are certain that these feelings are hated, and not at all indulged, by them. Oh, how much all classes of persons need to have clearly defined ideas of what really constitutes sin and holiness ! A false philosophy of the mind, especially of the will, and of moral depravity, has covered the world with gross darkness on the subject of sin and holiness, of regenera- tion, and of the evidences of regeneration, until the true saints, on the one hand, are kept in a continual bondage to their false notions ; and on the other, the church swarms with unconverted professors, and is cursed with many self-deceived ministers. LECTURE XXX. EVIDENCES OF REGENERATION. III. Wherein saints and sinners must differ. 1. Let it be distinctly remembered, that all unregenerate persons, without exception, have one heart, that is, they are selfish. This is their whole character. They are universally and only devoted to self-gratifica- tion. Their unregenerate heart consists in this selfish disposition, or in this selfish choice. This choice is the foundation of, and the reason for, all their activity. One and the same ultimate reason actuates them in all they do, and in all they omit, and that reason is either presently or re- motely, directly or indirectly, to gratify themselves. 2. The regenerate heart is disinterested henevolence. In other words, it is love to God and our neighbor. All regenerate hearts are precisely limilar. All true saints, whenever they have truly the heart of the 310 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. saints of God, are actuated by one and the same motive. They hare only one ultimate reason for all they do, and suffer, or omit. They have one ultimate intention, one end. They live for one and the same object, and that is the same end for which God lives. 3. The saint is governed by reason, the law of God, or the moral law ; in other words still, the law of disinterested and universal benevo- lence is his law. This law is not only revealed and developed in his in- telligence, but it is written in his heart. So that the law of his intellect is the law of his heart. He not only sees and acknowledges what he ought to do and be, but he is conscious to himself, and gives evidence to others, whether they receive it and are convinced by it or not, that his heart, his will, or intention, is conformed to his convictions of duty. He sees the path of duty, and follows it. He knows what he ought to will, intend, and do, and does it. Of this he is conscious. And of this others may be satisfied, if they are observing, charitable, and candid. 4. The sinner is contrasted with this, in the most important and fundamental, respects. He is not governed by reason and principle, but by feeling, desire, and impulse. Sometimes his feelings coincide with the intelligence, and sometimes they do not. But when they do so coincide, the will does not pursue its course out of respect or in obedience to the law of the intelligence, but in obedience to the impulse of the sensibility, which, for the time being, impels in the same direction as does the law of the reason. But for the most part the impulses of the sensibility incline him to worldly gratifications, and in an opposite direc- tion to that which the intelligence points out. This leads him to a course of life that is too manifestly the opposite of reason, to leave any room for doubt as to what his true character is. 5. The saint is justified, and he has the evidence of it in the peace of his own mind. He is conscious of obeying the law of reason and of love. Consequently he naturally has that kind and degree of peace that flows from the harmony of his will with the law of his inteUigeuce. He some- times has conflicts with the impulses of feeling and desire. But unless he is overcome, these conflicts, though they may cause him inwardly, aind, perhaps audibly, to groan, do not interrupt his peace. There are still the elements of peace within him. His heart and conscience are at one, and while this is so, he has thus far the evidence of justification iu himself. That is, he knows that God cannot condemn his present state. Conscious as he is of conformity of heart to the moral law, he cannot but affirm to himself, that the Lawgiver is pleased with his present attitude. But further, he has also within the Spirit of God witnessing with his spirit, that he is a child of God, forgiven, accepted, adopted. He feels the filial spirit di'awing his heart to exclaim, Father, Father. He is con- scious that he pleases God, and has God's smile of approbation. EVIDENCES OP REGENERATION. 311 He is at peace with himself, because he affirms his heart to be in uni- son with the law of love. His conscience does not upbraid, but smile. The harmony of his own being is a witness to himself, that this is the state in which he was made to exist. He is at peace wibh God, because he and God are pursuing precisely the same end, and by the same means. There can be no collision, no controversy between them. He is at peace with the universe, in the sense, that he has no ill-will, and no malicious feelings or wish to gratify, in the injury of any one of the creatures of God. He has no fear, but to sin against God. He is not influenced on the one hand by the fear of hell, nor on the other by the hope of reward. He is not anxious about his own salvation, but prayerfully and calmly leaves that question in the hands of God, and concerns himself only to promote the highest glory of God, and the good of being. " Being justified by faith, he has peace with God through our Lord Jesus Christ." "There is now no condemnation to them that are in Christ Jesus, who walk not after the flesh, but after the Spirit." 6. The sinner's experience is the opposite of this. He is under con- demnation, and seldom can so far deceive himself, even in his most reli- gious moods, as to imagine that he has a consciousness of acceptance either with his own conscience or with God. There is almost never a time in which he has not a greater or less degree of restlessness and misgiving within. Even when he is most engaged in religion, as he supposes, he flnds himself dissatisfied with himself. Something is wrong. There is a struggle and a pang. He may not exactly see where and what the difficulty is. He does not, after all, obey reason and con- science, and is not governed by the law and will of God. Not having the consciousness of this obedience, his conscience does not smile. He sometimes feels deeply, and acts as he feels, and is conscious of being sincere in the sense of feeling what he says, and acting in obedience to deep feeling. But this does not satisfy conscience. He is more or less wretched after all. He has not true peace. Sometimes he has a self- righteous quiet and enjoyment. But this is neither peace of conscience nor peace with God. He, after all, feels uneasy and condemned, not- withstanding all his feeling, and zeal, and activity. They are not of the right kind. Hence they do not satisfy the conscience. They do not meet the demands of his intelligence. Conscience does not approve. He has not, after all, true peace. He is not justified ; he cannot be fully and permanently satisfied that he is. 7. Saints are interested in, and sympathize with, every effort to reform mankind, and promote the interests of truth and righteousness in the earth. The good of being is the end for which the saint really and truly lives. This is not merely held by him as a theory, as an opinion, as a 312 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY, theological or philosophical speculation. It is in his heart, and precisely tor this reason he is a saint. He is a saint just because the theory, which is lodged in the head of both saint and sinner, has also a lodgment and reigning power in his heart, and consequently in his life. As saints supremely value the highest good of being, they will, and must, take a deep interest in whatever is promotive of that end. Hence, their spirit is necessarily that of the reformer. To the universal reforma- tion of the world they stand committed. To this end they are devoted. For this end they live, and move, and have their being. Every proposed reform interests them, and naturally leads them to examine its claims. The fact is, they are studying and devising ways and means to convert, sanctify, reform mankind. Being in this state of mind, they are predis- posed to lay hold on whatever gives promise of good to man. True saints love reform. It is their business, their profession, their life to promote it ; consequently they are ready to examine the claims of any proposed reform ; candid and self-denying, and ready to be convinced, however much self-denial it may call them to. They have actually re- jected self-indulgence, as the end for which they live, and are ready to sacrifice any form of self-indulgence, for the sake of promoting the good of men and the glory of God. The saint is truly and greatly desirous and in earnest, to reform all sin out of the world, and just for this reason is ready to hail with joy, and to try whatever reform seems, from the best light he can get, to bid fair to put down sin, and the evils that are in the world. Even mistaken men, who are honestly endeavoring to re- form mankind, and denying their appetites, as many have done in dietetic reform, are deserving of the respect of their fellow men. Sup- pose their philosophy to be incorrect, yet they have intended well. They have manifested a disposition to deny themselves, for the purpose of promoting the good of others. They have been honest and zealous in this. Now no true saint can feel or express contempt for such re- formers, however much mistaken they may be. No : his natural senti- ments and feelings will be, and must be, the reverse of contempt or censoriousness in respect to them. If their mistake has been injurious, he may mourn over the evil, but will not, cannot, severely judge the honest reformer. War, slavery, licentiousness, and all such like evils and abominations, are necessarily regarded by the saint as great and sore evils, and he longs for their complete and final overthrow. It is impos- sible that a truly benevolent mind should not thus regard these abomina- tions of desolation. The saints in all ages have been reformers. I know it is said, that neither prophets, Christ, nor apostles, nor primitive saints and martyrs declaimed against war and slavery, etc. But they did. The entire in- structions of Christ, and of apostles and prophets, were directly opposed EVIDENCES OF KEGENEEATION. 313 to these and all other evils. If they did not come out against certain legalized forms of sin, and denounce them by name, and endeavor to array public sentiment against them, it is plainly because they were, for the most part, employed in a preliminary work. To introduce the gospel as a divine revelation ; to set up and organize the visible kingdom of God on earth ; to lay a foundation for universal reform, was rather their business, than the pushing forward of particular branches of reform. The overthrow of state idolatry, the great and universal sin of the world in that age ; the labor of getting the world and the governments of earth to tolerate and receive the gospel as a revelation from the one only living and true God ; the controversy with the Jews, to overthrow their objections to Christianity ; in short, the great and indispensable and pre- liminary work of gaining for Christ and his gospel a hearing, and an ac- knowledgment of its divinity, was rather their work, the pushing of particular precepts and doctrines of the gospel to their legitimate results and logical consequences. This work once done, has left it for later saints to bring the particular truths, precepts, and doctrines of the blessed gospel to bear down every form of sin. Prophets, Christ, and his apostles, have left on the pages of inspiration no dubious testimony against every form of sin. The spirit of the whole Bible breathes from every page blasting and annihilation upon every unholy abomination, while it smiles upon everything of good report that promises blessings to man and glory to God. The saint is not merely sometimes a re- former ; he is always so. 8. The sinner is never a reformer in any proper sense of the word. He is selfish and never opposed to sin, or to any evil whatever, from any such motive as renders him worthy the name of reformer. He some- times selfishly advocates and pushes certain outward reforms ; but as certain as it is that he is an unregenerate sinner, so certain is it, that he is not endeavoring to reform sin out of the world from any disinterested love to God or to man. Many considerations of a selfish nature may en- gage him at times in certain branches of reform. Eegard to his reputa- tion may excite his zeal in such an enterprise. Self-righteous considera- tions may also lead him to enMst in the army of reformers. His relation to particular forms of vice may infiuence him to set his face against them. Constitutional temperament and tendencies may lead to his en- gaging in certain reforms. For example, his constitutional benevolence, as phrenologists call it, may be such that from natural compassion he may engage in reforms. But this is only giving way to an impulse of the sensibility, and it is not principle that governs him. His natural conscientiousness may modify his outward character, and lead him to take hold of some branches of reform. But whatever other motives he piay have, sure it is that he is not a reformer j for lie is a siiiuerj apd it 3M SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. is absurd to say that a sinner is truly engaged in opposing sin as sin. No, it is not sin that he is opposing, but he is seeking to gratify an am- bitious, a self-righteous, or some other spirit, the gratification of which is selfishness. But as a general thing, it is easy to distinguish sinners, or deceived professors from saints by looking steadfastly at their temper and deport- ment in their relations to reform. They are self-indulgent, and just for the reason that they are devoted to self-indulgence. Sometimes their self-indulgent spirit takes on one type, and sometimes another. Of course they need not be expected to ridicule or oppose every branch of reform, just because it is not every reformer that will rebuke their favorite indul- gences, and call them to I'eform their lives. But as every sinner has one or more particular form of indulgence to which he is wedded, and as saints are devising and pushing reforms in all directions, it is natural that some sinners should manifest particular hostility to one reform, and some to another. Whenever a reform is proposed that would reform them out of their favorite indulgences, they will either ridicule it, and those that propose it, or storm and rail, or in some way oppose or wholly neglect it. Not so, and so it cannot be, with a true saint. He has no indulgence that he values when put in competition with the good of being. Nay, he holds his all and his life at the disposal of the highest good. Has he, in ignorance of the evils growing out of his course, used ardent spirits, wine, tobacco, ale, or porter ? Has he held slaves ; been engaged in any traflic that is found to be injurious ; has he favored war through ignorance ; or, in short, has he committed any mistake what- ever ? Let but a reformer come forth and propose to discuss the tendency of such things ; let the reformer bring forth his strong reasons ; and, from the very nature of true religion, the saint will listen with attention, weigh with candor, and suffer himself to be carried by truth, heart, and hand, and influence with the proposed reform, if it be worthy of support, how much soever it conflict with his former habits. This must be true, if he has a single eye to the g6od of being, which is the very character- istic of a saint. 9. The true saint denies himself. Self-denial must be his character- istic, just for the reason that regeneration implies this. Regeneration, as we have seen, consists in turning away the heart or will from the supreme choice of self-gratiflcation, to a choice of the highest well-being of God and of the universe. This is denying self. This is abandoning self-indulgence, and pursuing or committing the will, and the whole being to an opposite end. This is the dethroning of self, and the en- throning of God in the heart. Self-denial does not consist, as some seem to imagine, in acts of outward austerity, in an ascetic and penance-doing course of starvation, and mere legal and outward rctrenchroeut, in wear- EVIDENCES OF KEGENBRATION. 315 ing a coat with one button, and in similar acts of " will worship and voluntary humility, and neglecting the body ;" but self-denial consists in the actual and total renunciation of selfishness in the heart. It con- sists in ceasing wholly to live for self, and can be exercised just as truly upon a throne, surrounded with the paraphernalia of royalty, as in a cot- tage of logs, or as in rags, and in caves and dens of the earth. The king upon his throne may live and reign to please himself. He may surround himself with all that can minister to his pleasure, his ambition, his pride, his lusts, and his power. He may live to and for himself. Self-pleasing, self-gratification, self-aggrandizement, may be the end for which he lives. This is selfishness. But he may also live and. reign for God, and for his people. That is, he may be as really devoted to God, and render this as a service to God, as well as anything else. Ko doubt his temptation is great ; but, nevertheless, he may be perfectly self-denying in all this. He may not do what he does for his own sake, nor be what he is, nor possess what he possesses for his own sake, but, accommodating his state and equipage to his relations, he may be as truly self-denying as others in the humbler walks of life. This is not an impossible, though, in all probability, a rare case. A man may as truly be rich for God as poor for him, if his relations and circumstances make it essential to his highest usefulness that he should possess a large capital. He is in the way of great temptation ; but if this is plainly his duty, and submitted to for God and the world, he may have grace to be entirely self-denying in these circumstances, and all the more commendable, for standing fast under these circumstances. So a poor man may be poor from principle, or from necessity. He i may be submissive and happy in his poverty. He may deny himself even the comforts of life, and do all this to promote the good of being, or he may do it to promote his own interest, temporal or eternal, to secure a reputation for piety, to appease a morbid conscience, to appease his fears, or to secure the favor of God. In all things he may be selfish. He may be happy in this, because it may be real self-denial : or he may be murmuring at his poverty, may complain, and be envious at others who are not poor. He may be censorious, and think everybody proud and selfish who dresses better, or possesses a better house and equipage than he does. He may set up bis views as a standard, and denounce as proud and selfish all who do not square their lives by his rule. This is selfishness, and these manifestations demonstrate the fact. A man may forego the use of a coat, or a cloak, or a horse, or a carriage, or any and every comfort and convenience of life, and all this may proceed from either a benevolent or a selfish state of mind. If it be benevolence and true self-denial, it will be cheerfully and happily submitted to, with- out murmuring and repining, without censofiousness, and without envy 316 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOOT. towards others, without insisting that others shall do and be, just what he does and is. He will allow the judge his ermine, the king his robes of state, and the merchant his capital, and the husbandman his fields and his flocks, and will see the reasonableness and propriety of all this. But if it be selfishness and the spirit of self-gratification instead of self-denial, he will be ascetic, caustic, sour, ill-natured, unhappy, severe, censorious, envious, and disposed to complain of, and pick at, the extravagance and self-indulgence of others. Especially does the true saint deny his appetites and passions. His artificial appetites he denies absolutely, whenever his attention is called to the fact and the nature of the indulgence. The Christian is such just because he has become the master of his appetites and passions, has denied them, and consecrated himself to God. The sinner is a sinner just because his appetites and passions and the impulses of his desires are his masters, and he bows down to them, and serves them. They are his masters instead of his servants, as they are made to be. He is consecrated to them and not to God. But the saint has ceased to live to gratify his lusts. Has he been a drunkard, a rake, a tobacco user ? Has he been in self-indulgent habits of any kind ? He is reformed : old things are past away, and behold all things are become new. Has he still any habit the character of which he has either mistaken or not consid- ered ; such as smoking, chewing, or snuffing tobacco, using injurious stimulants of any kind, high and unwholesome living, extravagant dress- ing or equipage, retiring late at night and rising late in the morning, eating too much, or between meals, or in short, has there been any form of self-indulgence about him whatever ? Only let his attention be called to it, he will listen with candor, be convinced by reasonable evidence, and renounce his evil habits without conferring with flesh and blood. All this is implied in regeneration, and must follow from its very nature. This also the Bible everywhere affirms to be true of the saints. " They have crucified the flesh with its affections and lusts." It should be forever remembered, that a self-indulgent Christian is a contradiction. Self-indulgence and Christianity are terms of opposition. 10. The sinner does not deny himself. He may not gratify all his desires, because the desires are often contradict(jry, and he must deny one for the sake of indulging another. Avarice may be so strong as to forbid his indulging in extravagance in eating, drinking, dressing, or equipage. His love of reputation maybe so strong as to prevent his engaging in any- thing disgraceful, and so on. But self-indulgence is his law notwith- standing. The fear of hell, or his desire to be saved, may forbid his out- ward indulgence in any known sin. But still he lives, and moves, and has his being only for the sake of indulging himself. He may be a miser, and statrvp and freege himself, and deny himself the necessaries of life j EVIDENCES OP EEGENERATION. 317 yet self-indulgence is his law. Some lusts he may and must control, aa they may be inconsistent with others. But others he does not control. He is a slave. He bows down to his lusts and serves them. He is en- slaved by his propensities, so that he cannot overcome them. Thia demonstrates that he is a sinner and nnregenerate, whatever his station and profession may be. One who cannot, because he will not, conquer himself and his lusts — this is the definition of an nnregenerate sinner. He is one over whom some form of desire, or lust, or appetite, or passion has dominion. He cannot, or rather will not, overcome it. This one is just as certainly in sin, as that sin is sin. 11. The truly regenerate soul overcomes sin. Let the Bible be heard upon this subject. " And hereby we do know 'hat we know him, if we keep his commandments. He that saith I know him, and keepeth not his commandments, is a liar, and the truth is not in him." — 1 John ii. 3, 4. •' And every man that hath this hop» in him purifieth himself, even as he is pure. Whosoever committeth sin transgresseth also the law : for sin is the transgression of the law. And ye know that he was manifested to take away our sins : and in him is no sin. Whosoever abideth in him sinneth not : whosoever sinneth hath not seen him, neither known him. Little children, let no man deceive you : he that doeth righteousness is righteous, even as he is righteous. He that committeth sin, is of the devil ; for the devil sinneth from the beginning. For this purpose the Son of God was manifested, that he might destroy the works of the devil. Whosoever is born of God doth not commit sin ; for his seed remaineth in him : and he cannot sin, be- cause he is born of God. In this the children of God are manifest, and the children of the devil ; whosoever doth not righteousness is not of God, neither he that loveth not his brother." — 1 John iii. 3-10. " Whosoever helieveth that Jesus is the Christ, is born of God, and every one that loveth him that begat, loveth him also that is begotten of him. By this we know that we love the children of God, when we love God and keep his commandments. For this is the love of God, that we keep his com- mandments ; and his commandments are not grievous. For whatsoever is bom of God overcometh the world : and this is the victory that over- cometh the world, even our faith." — 1 John v. 1-4. These passages, understood and pressed to the letter, would not only teach, that all regenerate souls overcome and live without sin, but also that sin is impossible to them. This last circumstance, as well as other parts of scripture, forbid us to press this strong language to the letter. But this much must be understood and admitted, that to overcome sin is the rule with every one who is born of God, and that sin is only the ex- ception ; that the regenerate habitually live without sin, and fall into sin only at intervals, so few and far between,that in strong language it may 318 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. be said in truth they do not sin. This is surely the least which can be meant by the spirit of these texts, not to press them to the letter. And this is precisely consistent with many other passages of scripture, several of which I have quoted ; such as these : — " Therefore, if any man be in Christ, he is a new creature : old things are passed away ; behold, all things are become new." — 3 Cor. v. 17. "For in Jesus Christ, neither circumcision availeth anything nor uncircumcision ; but faith which worketh by love." — Gal. v. 6. "For in Christ Jesus neither circumcis- ion availeth anything, nor uncircumcision, but a new creature." — Gal. vi. 15. " There is therefore now no condemnation to them which are in Christ Jesus, who walk not after the flesh, but after the Spirit. For the law of the Spirit of life in Christ Jesus hath made me free from the law of sin and death. For what the law could not do, in that it was weak through the flesh, God sending his own Son in the likeness of sinful flesh, and for sin, condemned sin in the flesh : that the righteousness of the law might be fulfilled in us, who walk not after the flesh, but after the Spirit." — Kom. viii. 1-4. " What shall we say then ? Shall we con- tinue in sin, that grace may abound ? God forbid. How shall we that are dead to sin, live any longer therein ? Know ye not, that so many of us as were baptized into Jesus Christ were baptized into his death ? Therefore we are buried with him by baptism into death : that like as Christ was raised up from the dead by the glory of the Father, even so we also should walk in newness of life. For if we have been planted to- gether in the likeness of his death, we shall be also in the likeness of his resurrection : knowing this, that our old man is crucified with him, that the body of sin might be destroyed, that henceforth we should not serve sin. For he that is dead is freed from sin. Now if we be dead with Christ, we believe that we shall also live with him ; knowing that Christ being raised from the dead, dieth no more ; death hath no more domin- ion over him. For in that he died, he died unto sin once : but in that he liveth, he liveth unto God. Likewise reckon ye also yourselves to be dead indeed unto sin, but alive unto God, through Jesus Christ our Lord. Let not sin therefore reign in your mortal body, that ye should obey it in the lusts thereof. Neither yield ye your members as instru- ments of unrighteousness unto sin : but yield yourselves unto God, as those that are alive from the dead, and your members as instruments of righteousness unto God. For sin shall not have dominion over you : for ye are not under the law, but under grace." — Eom. vi. 1-14. The fact is, if God is true, and the Bible is true, the truly regenerate soul has overcome the world, the flesh, and Satan, and sin, and is a con- queror, and more than a conqueror. He triumphs over temptation as a general thing, and the triumphs of temptation over him are so far be- tween, that it is said of him in the living oracles, that he does not, can- EVIDENCES OF REGENERATION. 319 not 8111. He is not a sinner, but a saint. He is sanctified ; a holy per- son ; a child and son of God. If at any time he is overcome, it is only to rise again, and soon return like the weeping prodigal. " The steps of a good man are ordered by the Lord : and he delighteth in his way. Though he fall he shall not be utterly cast down : for the Lord uphold- eth him with his hand." — Psalm xxxvii. 23, 24. 12. The sinner is the slave of sin. The seventh of Eomans is his ex- perience in his best estate. When he has the most hope of himself, and others have the most hope of his good estate, he goes no further than to make and break resolutions. His life is but a death in sin. He has not the victory. He sees the right, but does it not. Sin is his master, to whom he yields himself a servant to obey. He only tries, as he says, to forsake sin, but does not in fact forsake it, in his heart. And yet be- cause he is convicted, and has desires, and forms resolutions of amend- ment, he hopes he is regenerated. 0, what a horrible delusion ! Stop short with convicljon, with the hope that he is already a Christian ! Alas I how many are already in hell who have stumbled at this stum- bling stone ! 13. The subject of regeneration may know, and if honest he must know, for what end he lives. There is, perhaps, nothing of which he inay be more certain than of his regenerate or unregenerate state ; and if he will keep in mind what regeneration is, it would seem that he can hardly mistake his own character, so far as to imagine himself to be re- generate when he is not. The great diflBculty that has been in the way of the regenerate soul's knowing his regeneration, and has led to so much doubt and embarrassment upon this subject, is that regeneration has been regarded as belonging to the sensibility, and hence the attention has been directed to the ever-fluctuating feelings for evidence of the change. No wonder that this has led conscientious souls into doubt and embar- rassment. But let the subject of regeneration be disenthralled from a false philosophy, and let it be known that the new heart consists in su- preme disinterested benevolence, or in entire consecration to God, and then who cannot know for what end he lives, or what is the supremo preference or intention of his soul ? If men can settle any question whatever beyond all doubt by an appeal to consciousness, it would seem that this must be the question. Hence the Bible enjoins it as an im- perative duty to know ourselves, whether we are Christians. We are to know each other by our fruits. This is expressly given in the Bible as the rule of judgment in the case. The question is not so much. What are the man's opinions ? as, What does he live for ? Does he manifest a charitable state of mind ? Does he manifest the attributes of benevo- lence in the various circumstances in which he is placed ? 0, when shall the folly of judging men more by their opinions and feelings, than 320 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. bv the tenor of their lives cease ? It seems difficult to rid men of the prejudice that religion consists in feelings and in ejcperiences in which they are altogether passive. Hence they are continually prone to delu- sion upon the most momentous of all questions. Nothing can break this spell but the steady and thorough inculcation of the truth, in legard to the nature of regeneration. LECTURE XXXI. NATURAL ABILITY. We next proceed to the examination of the question of man's ability or inability to obey the commandments of God. This certainly must be a fundamental question in morals and religion ; and as our views are upon this subject, so, if we are consistent, must be our views of God, of his moral government, and of every practical doctrine of morals and re- ligion. This is too obvious to require proof. The question of ability has truly been a vexed question. In the discussion of it, I shall consider the elder President Edwards as the representative of the common Calvinistio view of this subject, because he has stated it more clearly than any other Calvinistio author with whom I am acquainted. "When, therefore, I speak of the Edwardean doctrine of ability and inability, you will under- stand me to speak of the common view of Calvinistio theological writers, as stated, summed up, and defended by Edwards. In discussing this subject I will endeavor to show, — 1. President Edwards's notion of natural ability. Edwards considers freedom and ability as identical. He defines free- dom or liberty to consist in the power, opportunity, or advantage, that any one has, to do as he pleases. " Or, in other words, his being free from hindrance or impediment in the way of doing or conducting in any respect as he wills." — Works, vol. ii., page 38. Again, page 39, he says, " One thing more I should observe concern- ing what is vulgarly called liberty ; namely, that power and opportunity for one to do and conduct as he will, or according to his choice, is aU that is meant by it ; without taking into the meaning of the word any- thing of the cause of that choice ; or at all considering how the person came to have such a volition ; whether it was caused by some external motive, or internal habitual bias ; whether it was determined by some in- ternal antecedent volition, or whether it happened without a cause ; whether it was necessarily connected with something foregoing, or not connected. Let the person come by his choice anyhow, yet if he is able, NATURAL ABILITY. 321 and there is nothing in the way to hinder his pursuing and exerting his will, the man is perfectly free, according to the primary and common notion of freedom." In the preceding paragraph, he says, " There are two things contrary to what is called liberty in common speech. One is, constraint ; which is a person's being necessitated to do a thing contrary to his will ; the other is, restraint, which is his being hindered, and not having power to do according to his will." Power, ability, liberty, to do as you will, are synonymous with this writer. The foregoing quotations, with many like passages that might be quoted from the same author, show that natural liberty, or natural ability, according to him, consists in the natural and established connec- tion between volition and its effects. Thus he says in another place, *' Men are justly said to be able to do what they can do, if they will." His definition of natural ability^ or natural liberty, as he frequently calls it, wholly excludes the power to will, and includes only the power or ability to execute our volitions. Thus it is evident, that natural ability, according to him, respects external action only, and has nothing to do with willing. When there is no restraint or hindrance to the execution of volition, when there is nothing interposed to disturb and prevent the natural and established result of our volitions, there is natural ability ac- cording to this school. It should be distinctly understood, that Edwards, and those of his school, hold that choices, volitions, and all acts of will, are determined, not by the sovereign power of the agent, but are caused by the objective motive, and that there is the same connection, or a con- nection as certain and as unavoidable between motive and choice, as between any physical cause and its effect : " the difference being," ac- cording to him, " not in the nature of the connection, but in the terms connected." Hence, according to his view, natural liberty or ability cannot consist in the power of willing or of choice, but must consist in the power to execute our choices or volitions. Consequently, this class of philosophers define free or moral agency to consist in the power to do as one wUls, or power to execute one's purposes, choices, or volitions. That this is a fundamentally false definition of natural liberty or ability, and of free or moral agency, we shall see in due time. It is also plain, that the natural ability or liberty of Edwards and his school, has nothing to do with morality or immorality. Sin and holiness, as we have seen in a former lecture, are attributes of acts of will only. But this natural ability respects, as has been said, outward or muscular action only. Let this be distinctly borne in mind as we proceed. II. This natural ability is no ability at all. We know from consciousness that the will is the executive faculty, and that we can do absolutely nothing without willing. The power or 21 822 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOaY ability to will is indispensable to our acting at all. If we bave not the power to will, we bave not power or ability to do anything. All ability or power to do resides in the will, and power to will is the necessary con- dition of ability to do. In morals and religion, as we shall soon see, the willing is the doing. The power to will is the condition of obligation to do. Let us hear Edwards himself upon this subject. Vol. ii. p. 156, he says, " The will itself, and not only those actions which are the effects of the will, is the proper object of precept or command. That is, such a state or acts of men's wills, are in many cases properly required of them by commands ; and not only those alterations in the atate of their bodies or minds that are the consequences of volition. This is most manifest ; for it is the mind only that is properly and directly the subject of pre- cepts or commands ; that only being capable of receiving or perceiving commands. The motions of the body are matters of command only as they are subject to the soul, and connected with its acts. But the soul has no other faculty whereby it can, in the most direct and proper sense, consent, yield to, or comply with any command, but the faculty of the will ; and it is by this faculty only that the soul can directly disobey or refuse compliance ; for the very notions of consenting, yielding, accept- ing, complying, refusing, rejecting, etc., are, according to the meaning of terms, nothing but certain acts of will." Thus we see that Edwards himself held, that the will is the executive faculty, and that the soul can do nothing except as it wills to do it, and that for this reason a command to do is strictly a command to will. We shall see by and by, that he held also that the willing and the doing are identical, so far as moral obligation, morals, and religion are concerned. For the present, it is enough to say, whether Edwards or anybody else ever held it or not, that it is absurd and sheer nonsense to talk of an ability to do when there is no ability to will. Every one knows with intuitive certainty that he has no ability to do what he is unable to will to do. It is, therefore, the veriest folly to talk of a natural ability to do anything whatever, when we exclude from this ability the power to will. If there is no ability to will, there is, and can be no ability to do ; therefore the natural ability of the Edwardean school is no ability at all. Let it be distinctly understood, that whatever Edwards held in respect to the ability of man to do, ability to will entered not at all into his idea and definition of natural ability or liberby. But according to him, natural ability respects only the connection that is established by a law of nature between volition and its sequents, excluding altogether the in- quiry how the volition comes to exist. This the foregoing quotations abundantly show. Let the impression, then, be distinct, that the Edwardean natural ability is no ability at all, and nothing but an empty name, a metaphysico-theological fiction. NATURAL ABILITY. 323 III, What constitutes natural inability according to this school. Edwards, vol. ii. p. 35, says, " We are said to be naturally unable tc do a thing when we cannot do it if we will, because what is most com- monly called nature, does not allow of it ; or because of some impeding defect or obstacle that is extrinsic to the will ; either in the faculty of understanding, constitution of body, or external objects." This quota- tion, together with much that might be quoted from this author to the same effect, shows that natural inability, according to him, consists in a want of power to execute our volitions. In the absence of power to do as we will, if the willing exists and the effect does not follow, it is only because we are unable to do as we will, and this is natural inability. We are naturally nnablci according to him, to do what does not follow by a natural law from our volitions. If I will to move my arm, and the mus- cles do not obey volition, I am naturally unable to move my arm. So with anything else. Here let it be distinctly observed, that natural in- ability, as well as natural ability, respects and belongs only to outward action or doing. It has nothing to do with ability to will. Whatever Edwards held respecting ability to will, which will be shown in its proper place, I wish it to be distinctly understood that his natural inability had nothing to do with willing, but only with the effects of willing. When the natural effect of willing does not follow volition, its cause, here is a proper natural inability. IV. This natural inability is no inability at all. By this is intended that, so far as morals and religion are concerned, the willing is the doing, and therefore where the willing actually takes place, the real thing required or prohibited is already done. Let us hear Edwards upon this subject. Vol. ii. p. 164, he says, " If the will fully complies and the proposed effect does not prove, according to the laws of nature, to be connected with his volition, the man is perfectly excused ; he has a natural inability to do the thing required. For the will itself, as has been observed, is all that can be directly and immediately required by command, and other things only indirectly, as connected with the will. If, therefore, there be a full compliance of will, the per- son has done his duty : and if other things do not prove to be connected with his volition, that is not criminally owing to him." Here, then, it is manifest, that the Edwardean notions of natural ability and inability have no connection with moral law or moral government, and, of course, with morals and religion. That the Bible everywhere accounts the' willing as the deed, is most manifest. Both as it respects sin and holi- ness, if the required or prohibited act of the will takes place, the moral law and the lawgiver regard the deed as having been done, or the sin 324 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. committed, whatever impediment may have prevented the natural effect from following. Here, then, let it be distinctly understood and remem- bered that Edwards's natural inability is, so far as morals and religion are concerned, no inability at all. An inability to execute our volitions, is in no case an inability to do our whole duty, since moral obligation, and of course, duty, respect strictly only acts of will. A natural inabil- ity must consist, as we shall see, in an inability to will. It is truly amazing that Edwards could have written the paragraph just quoted, and others to the same effect, without perceiving the fallacy and absurd- ity of his speculation — without seeing that the ability or inability about which he was writing, had no connection with morals or religion. How could he insist so largely that moral obligation respects aots of will only, and yet spend so much time in writing about an ability or inability to comply with moral obligation that respects outward action exclusively ? This, on the face of it, was wholly irrelevant to the subject of morals and religion, upon which subjects he was professedly writing. V. Natural ability is identical with freedom or liberty of will. It has been, I trust, abundantly shown in a former lecture, and is admitted and insisted on by Edwards, — 1. That moral obligation respects strictly only acts of will. 2. That the whole of moral obligation resolves itself into an obliga- tion to be disinterestedly benevolent, that is, to will the highest good of being for its own sake. 3. That willing is the doing required by the true spirit of the moral law. Ability, therefore, to will in accordance with the moral law, must be natural ability to obey God. But, — 4. This is and must be the only proper freedom of the will, so far as morals and religion, or so far as moral law is concerned. That must constitute true liberty of will that consists in the ability or power to will, either in accordance with, or in opposition to the requirements of moral law. Or in other words, true freedom or liberty of will must consist in the power or ability to will in every instance either in accordance with, or in opposition to, moral obligation. Observe, moral obligation respects acts of will. What freedom or liberty of will can there be in relation to moral obligation, unless the will or the agent has power or ability to act in conformity with moral obligation ? To talk of a man's being free to will, or having liberty to will, when he has not the power or ability, is to talk nonsense. Edwards himself holds that ability to do, is indispensa- ble to liberty to do. But if ability to do be a sine qud non of liberty to do, must not the same be true of willing ? That is, must not ability to will be essential to liberty to will ? Natural ability and natural liberty to will, must then be identical. Let this be distinctly remembered, since NATURAL ABILITY. 325 many have scouted the doctrine of natural ability to obey God, who have nevertheless been great sticklers for the freedom of the will. In this they are greatly inconsistent. This ability is called a natural ability, because it belongs to man as a moral agent, in such a sense that without it he could not be a proper subject of command, of reward or punish- ment. That is, without this liberty or ability he could not be a moral agent, and a proper subject of moral government. He must then either possess this power in himself as essential to his own nature, or must possess power, or be able to avail himself of power to will in every in- stance in accordance with moral obligation. Whatever he can do, he can do only by willing ; he must therefore either possess the power in himself directly to will as God commands, or he must be able by willing it to avail himself of power, and to make himself willing. If he has power by nature to will directly as God requires, or by willing to avail himself of power so to will, he is naturally free and able to obey the commandments of God. Then let it be borne distinctly in mind, that natural ability, about which so much has been said, is nothing more nor less than the freedom or liberty of the will of a moral agent. No man knows what he says or whereof he affirms, who holds to the one and denies the other, for they are truly and properly identical. VI. The human will is free, therefore men have power or ability to do all their duty. 1. The moral government of God everywhere assumes and implies the liberty of the human will, and the natural ability of men to obey God. Every command, every threatening, every expostulation and de- nunciation in the Bible implies and assumes this. Nor does the Bible do violence to the human intelligence in this assumption ; for, — %. The human mind necessarily assumes the freedom of the human will as a first truth. First truths, let it be remembered, are those that are necessarily as- sumed by every moral agent. They are assumed always and necessarily by a law of the intelligence, although they may seldom be the direct ob- jects of thought or attention. It is a universal law of the intelligence, to assume the truths of causality, the existence and the infinity of space, the existence and infinity of duration, and many other truths. These assumptions every moral agent always and necessarily takes with him, whether these things are matters of attention or not. And even should he deny any one or all of these first truths, he knows them to be true notwithstanding, and cannot but assume their truth in all his practical judgments. Thus, should any one deny the law and the doctrine of causality, as some in theory have done, he knows, and cannot but know, — he assumes, and cannot but assume, its truth at every moment. With- 326 • SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGtY. out this assumption he could not so much as intend, or think of doing, or of any one else doing anything whatever. But a great part of his time, he may not, and does not, make this law a distinct object of thought or attention. Nor is he directly conscious of the assumption that there is such a law. He acts always upon the assumption, and a great part of his time is insensible of it. His whole activity is only the exercise of his own causality, and a practical acknowledgment of the truth, which in theory he may deny. Now just so it is with the freedom of the will, and with natural ability. Did we not assume our own liberty and ability, we should never think of attempting to do anything. We should not so much as think of moral obligation, either as it respects ourselves or others, unless we assumed the liberty of the human will. In all our judgments respecting our own moral character and that of others, we always and necessarily assume the liberty of the human will, or natural ability to obey God. Although we may not be distinctly conscious of this assumption, though we may seldom make the liberty of the human will the subject of direct thought or attention, and even though we may deny its reality, and strenuously endeavor to maintain the opposite, we, nevertheless, in this very denial and endeavor, assume that we are free. This truth never was, and never can be rejected in our practical judgments. All men assume it. All men must assume it. Whenever they choose in one di- rection, they always assume, whether conscious of the assumption or not, and cannot but assume, that they have power to will in the opposite direction. Did they not assume this, such a thing as election between two ways or objects would not be, and could not be, so much as thought of. The very ideas of right and wrong, of the praiseworthiness, and blameworthiness of human beings, imply the assumption, on the part of those who have these ideas, of the universal freedom of the human will, or of the natural ability of men as moral agents to obey God. Were not this assumption in the mind, it were impossible from its own nature and laws that it should affirm moral obligation, right or wrong, praiseworthi- ness or blameworthiness of men. I know that philosophers and theolo- gians have in theory denied the doctrine of natural ability or liberty, in the sense in which I have defined it ; and I know, too, that with all their theorizing, they did assume, in common with all other men, that man is free in the sense that he has liberty or power to will as God commands. I know that, but for this assumption, the human mind could no more predicate praiseworthiness or blameworthiness, right or wrong of man, than it could of the motions of a windmill. Men have often made the assumption in question without being aware of it, have affirmed right and wrong of human willing without seeing and understanding the conditions of this affirmation. But the fact is, that in all cases the assumption has lain deep in the mind as a first truth, that men are free in the NATURAL ABILITY. 327 sense of being naturally able to obey God : and this assumption is a neces- sary condition of the aflSrmation that moral character belongs to man. VII. What constitutes moral inability, according to Edwards and those who hold with him. I examine their views of moral inability first in order, because from their views of moral inability we ascertain more clearly what are their views of moral ability. Edwards regards moral ability and inability as identical with moral necessity. Concerning moral necessity, he says, vol. ii. pp. 32, 33, " And sometimes by moral necessity is meant that neces- sity of connection and consequence which arises from such moral causes as the strength of inclination or motives, and the connection which there is in many cases between these and such certain volitions and actions. And it is in this sense that I shall nse the phrase moral necessity in the following discourse. By natural necessity, as applied to men, I mean such necessity as men are under through the force of natural causes, as distinguished from what are called moral causes, such as habits and dis- positions of the heart, and moral motives and inducements. Thus men placed in certain circumstances are the subjects of particular sensations by necessity. They feel pain when their bodies are wounded ; they see the objects presented before them in a clear light when their eyes are open : so they assent to the truth of certain propositions as soon as the terms are understood ; as that two and two make four, that black is not white, that two parallel lines can never cross one another ; so by a natural necessity men's bodies move downwards when there is nothing to support them. But here several things may be noted concerning these two kinds of necessity. 1. Moral necessity may be as absolute as natural necessity. That is, the effect may be as perfectly connected with its moral cause, as a natural effect is with its natural cause. Whether the will is in every case necessarily determined by the strongest motive, or whether the will ever makes any resistance to such a motive, or can ever oppose the strongest present inclination or not ; if that matter should be controverted, yet I suppose none will deny, but that, in some cases, a previous bias and inclina- tion, or the motive presented may be so powerful, that the act of the will may be certainly and indissolubly connected therewith. When motives or previous bias are very strong, all will allow that there is some difficulty in going against them. And if they were yet stronger, the difficulty would be still greater. And therefore if more were still added to their strength up to a certain degree, it might make the difficulty so great that it would be wholly impossible to surmount it, for this plain reason, be- cause whatever power men may be supposed to have to surmount diffi- culties, yet that power is not infinite, and so goes not beyond certain limits. If a certain man can surmount ten degrees of difficulty of this 328 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. kiud, witli twenty degrees of strength, because the degrees of strength are beyond the degrees of difficulty, yet if the difficulty be increased to thirty, or a hundred, or to a thousand degrees, and his strength not also increased, his strength will be wholly insufficient to surmount the diffi- culty. As therefore it must be allowed that there may be such a thing as a sure and perfect connection between moral causes and effects ; so this only is what I call by the name of moral necessity." Page 35, he says : " What has been said of natural and moral necessity may serve to explain what is intended by natural and moral inability. "We are said to be nat- urally unable to do a thing when we cannot do it if we will, because of some impeding defect or obstacle that is extrinsic to the will, either in the faculty of understanding, constitution of body, or external objects. Moral inability consists not in any of these things, but either in a want of inclination, or the want of sufficient motives in view, to induce and excite the act of the will, or the strength of apparent motives to the con- trary. Or both these may be resolved into one, and it may be said in one word that moral inability consists in the opposition or want of inclina- tion. For when a person is unable to will or choose such a thing, through a defect of motives or prevalence of contrary motives, it is the same thing as his being unable through the want of an inclination, or the prevalence of a contrary inclination in such circumstances, and under the influence of such views." From these quotations, and much more that might be quoted to the same purpose, it is plain that Edwards, as the representative of his school, holds moral inability to consist, either in an existing choice or attitude of the will opposed to that which is required by the law of God, which inclination or choice is necessitated by motives in view of the mind, or in the absence of such motives as are necessary to cause or necessitate the state of choice required by the moral law, or to overcome an opposing choice. Indeed he holds these two to be identical. Observe, his words are, " Or these may be resolved into one, and it may be said in one word, that moral inability consists in opposition or want of inclination. For when a person is unable to will or choose such a thing, through a defect of motives, it is the same thing as his being unable through the want of an inclination, or the prevalence of a contrary inclination, in such cir- cumstances and under the influence of such views," that is, in the pres- ence of such motives. If there is a present prevalent contrary inclina- tion, it is, according to him : 1. Because there are present certain rea- sons that necessitate this contrary inclination ; and 2. Because there are not sufficient motives present to the mind to overcome these opposing motives and inclination, and to necessitate the will to determine or choose in the direction of the law of God. By inclination Edwards means choice or volition, as is abundantly evident from what he all along savs in this NATURAL ABILITY. 329 connection. This no one will deny who is at all familiar with his writings. It was the object of the treatise from which the above quotations have been made, to maintain that the choice invariably is as the great- est apparent good is. And by the greatest apparent good he means, a sense of the most agreeable. By which he means, as he says, that the sense of the most agreeable, and choice or volition, are identical. Vol. ii., page 30, he says, "And therefore it must be true in some sense, that the will always is as the greatest apparent good is." "It must be observed in what sense I use the term 'good,' namely, as of the same im- port with agreeable. To appear good to the mind, as I use the phrase, is the same as to appear agreeable, or seem pleasing to the mind." Again, pp. 31, 23, he says : " I have rather chosen to express myself thus, that the will always is as the greatest apparent good is, or as what appears most agreeable, than to say that the will is determined by the greatest apparent good, or by what seems most agreeable ; because an appearing most agreeable to the mind and the mind's preferring, seem scarcely dis- tinct. If strict propriety of speech be insisted on, it may more properly be said, that the voluntary action, which is the immediate consequence of the mind's choice, is determined by that which appears most agree- able, than the choice itself." Thus it appears that the sense of the most agreeable, and choice or volition, according to Edwards, are the same things. Indeed, Edwards throughout confounds desire and volition, making them the same thing. Edwards regarded the mind as possessing but two primary faculties — the will and the understanding. He eon- founded all the states of the sensibility with acts of will. The strongest desire is with him always identical with volition or choice, and not merely that which determines choice. When there is a want of inclination or desire, or the sense of the most agreeable, there is a moral inability ac- cording to the Edwardean philosophy. This want of the strongest de- sire, inclination, or sense of the most agreeable, is always owing ; 1. To the presence of such motives as to necessitate an opposite desire, choice, etc. ; and 3. To the want of such objective motives as shall awaken this required desire, or necessitate this inclination or sense of the most agree- able. In other words, when volition or choice, in consistency with the law of God, does not exist, it is, 1. Because an opposite choice exists, and is necessitated by the presence of some motive ; and 3. Eor want of suflBciently strong objective motives to necessitate the required choice or volition. Let it be distinctly understood and remembered, that Edwards held that motive, and not the agent, is the cause of all actions of the will. Will, with him, is always determined in its choice by motives as really as physical effects are produced by their causes. The differ- e»pe with him in the connection of moral and phys}pp,l parses and 330 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. effects "lies not in the nature of the connection, but in the terma connected." "That every act of the will has some cause, and consequently (by what has already been proved) has a necessary connection with its cause, and so is necessary by a necessity of connection and consequence, is evident by this, that every act of the will whatsoever is excited by some motive, which is manifest ; because, if the mind, in willing after the manner it does, is excited by no motive or inducement, then it has no end which it proposes to itself, or pursues in so doing ; it aims at nothing, and seeks nothing. And if it seeks nothing, then it does not go after anything, or exert any inclination or preference towards anything ; which brings the matter to a contradiction ; because for the mind to will some- thing, and for it to go after something by an act jof preference and in- clination, are the same thing. " But if every act of the will is excited by a motive, then that motive is the cause of the act. If the acts of the will are excited by motives, then motives are the causes of their being excited ; or, which is the same thing, the cause of their existence. And if so, the existence of the acts of the will is properly the effect of their motives. Motives do nothing, as motives or inducements, but by their influence ; and so much as is done by their influence is the effect of them. For that is the notion of an effect, something that is brought to pass by the influence of something "And if volitions are properly the effects of their motives, then they are necessarily connected with their motives ; every effect and event being, as was proved before, necessarily connected with that which is the proper ground and reason of its existence. Thus it is manifest that voli- tion is necessary, and is not from any self-determining power in the will."— Vol. ii., pp. 86,87. Moral inability, then, according to this school, consists in a want of inclination, desire, or sense of the most agreeable, or the strength of an opposite desire or sense of the most agreeable. This want of inclination, etc., or this opposing inclination, etc., are identical with an opposing choice or volition. This opposing choice or inclination, or this want of the required choice, inclination, or sense of the most agreeable is owing, according to Edwards, 1. To the presence of such motives as to necessi- tate the opposing choice ; and 2. To the absence of suflScient motives to beget or necessitate them. Here then we have the philosophy of this school. The will or agent is unable to choose as God requires in all cases, when, 1. There are present such motives as to necessitate an oppo- site choice ; and, 2. "When there is not such a motive or such motives in the view of the mind, as to determine or necessitate the required choice pr volition 5 that is^ to awaken a desjre, or tq create £|,n inclination or NATURAL ABILITY. 331 sense of the agreeable stronger tlian any existing and opposing desire, inclination, or sense of agreeable. This is the moral inability of the Edwardeans. VIII. Their moral inability to oiey God consists in real disoiedience and a natural inability to obey. 1. If we understand Edwardeans to mean that moral inability con- sists,— (1.) In the presence of such motives as to necessitate an opposite choice ; and, — (3.) In the want or absence of suflBcient motives to necessitate choice or volition, or, which is the same thing, a sense of the most agreeable, or an inclination, then their moral inability is a proper natural inability. Edwards says, he " calls it a moral inability, because it is an inability of will." But by his own showing, the will is the only executive faculty. Whatever a man can do at all, he can accomplish by willing, and what- ever he cannot accomplish by willing he cannot accomplish at all. An inability to will then must be a natural inability. We are, by nature, unable to do what we are unable to will to do. Besides, according to Edwards, moral obligation respects strictly only acts of will, and willing is the doing that is prohibited or required by the moral law. To be un- able to will then, is to be unable to do. To be unable to will as God re- quires, is to be unable to do what he requires, and this surely is a proper, and the only proper natural inability. 2. But if we are to understand this school, as maintaining that moral inability to obey God, consists in a want of the inclination, choice, de- sire, or sense of the most agreeable that God requires, or in an inclination or existing choice, volition, or sense of the most agreeable, which is opposed to the requirement of God, this surely is really identical with disobedience, and their moral inability to obey consists in disobedience. For, be it distinctly remembered, that Edwards holds, as we have seen, that obedience and disobedience, properly speaking, can be predicated only of acts of will. If the required state of the will exists, there is obedience. If it does not exist, there is disobedience. Therefore, by his own admission and express holding, if by moral inability we are to understand a state of the will not conformed, or, which is the same thing, opposed to the law and will of God, this moral inability is nothing else than disobedience to God. A moral inability to obey is identical with disobedience. It is not merely the cause of future or present dis- obedience, but really constitutes the whole of present disobedience. 3. But suppose that we understand his moral inability to consist both in the want of an inclination, choice, volition, etc., or in the existence of an opposing state of the will, and also, — 332 SYSTEMATIC IxlBOLOGY. (1.) In the presence of such motives as to necessitate an opposite choice, and, — (2.) In the want of suflBcient motives to overcome the opposing state, and necessitate the requii-ed choice, Tolition, etc., then his views stand thus : moral inability to choose as God commands, consists in the want of this choice, or in the existence of an opposite choice, which want of choice, or, which is the same thing with him, which opposite choice is caused : — (i.) By the presence of such motives as to necessitate the opposite choice, and, — (ii.) By the absence of such motives as would necessitate the required choice. Understand him which way you will, his moral inability is real disobedience, and is in the highest sense a proper natural inability to obey. The cause of choice or volition he always seeks, and thinks or as- sumes that he finds, in the objective motive, and never for once ascribes it to the sovereignty or freedom of the agent. Choice or volition is an event, and must have some cause. He assumes that the objective motive was the cause, when, as consciousness testifies, the agent is himself the cause. Here is the great error of Edwards. Edwards assumed that no agent whatever, not even God himself, possesses a power of self-determi- nation, that the will of God and of all moral agents is determined, not by themselves, but by an objective motive. If they will in one direction or another, it is not from any free and sovereign self-determjnation in view of motives, but because the motives or inducements present to the mind, inevitably produce or necessitate the sense of the most agreeable, or choice. If this is not fatalism or natural necessity, what is ? IX. This pretended distinction between natural and moral indbility is nonsensical. What does it amount to ? Why this : — 1. This natural inability is an inability to do as we will, or to execute our volitions. 2. This moral inability is an inability to will. 3. This moral inability is the only natural inability that has, or can have, anything to do with duty, or with morality and religion ; or^ as ha? been shown, — 4. It consists in disobedience itself. Present moral inability to obey is iflentical with present disobedience, with a natural inability to obey ! It is amazing to see how so great and good a man could involve himself in a metaphysical fog, and bewilder himself and his readers to such a degree, that an absolutely senseless distinction should pass into the current phraseology, philosophy, and theology of the church, and a score of theo- logical dogmas be built upon the assumption of its truth. This nonsen- sical djstinctioij hs.s been in the mouth of the Edwardean scljoo} of th^Q' NATURAL ABILITY. 333 logians, from Edwards's day to the present. Both saints and sinners have been bewildered, and, I must say, abused by it. Men have been told that they are as really unable to will as God directs, as they were to create themselves ; and when it is replied that this inability excuses the sinner, we are directly silenced by the assertion, that this is only a moral inability, or an inability of will, and therefore, that it is so far from ex- cusing the sinner, that it constitutes the very ground, and substance, and whole of his guilt. Indeed ! Men arc under moral obligation only to will as God directs. But an inability thus to will, consisting in the absence of such motives as would necessitate the required choice, or the presence of such motives as to necessitate an opposite choice, is a moral inability, and really constitutes the sinner worthy of an " exceeding great and eternal weight " of damnation 1 Eidiculous I Edwards I revere ; his blunders I deplore. I speak thus of this Treatise on the Will, be- cause, while it abounds with unwarrantable assumptions, distinctions without a difference, and metaphysical subtleties, it has been adopted as the text-book of a multitude of what are called Calvinistic divines for scores of years. It has bewildered the head, and greatly embarrassed the heart and the action of the church of God. It is time, high time, that its errors should be exposed, and so exploded, that such phraseology should be laid aside, and the ideas which these words represent should cease to be entertained. X. What constitutes moral ability according to this school? It is of course the opposite of moral inability. Moral ability, according to them, consists in willingness, with the cause of it. That is, moral ability to obey God consists in that inclination, desire, choice, volition, or sense of the most agreeable, which God requires together with its cause. Or it consists in the presence of such motives as do actually necessitate the above-named state or determination of the will. Or, more strictly, it consists in this state caused by the presence of these motives. This is as exact a statement of their views as I can make. According to this, a man is morally able to do as he does, and is necessitated to do, or, he is morally able to will as he does will, and as he cannot help willing. He is morally able to will in this manner, simply and only because he is caused thus to will by the presence of such motives as are, according to them, " indissolubly connected " with such a willing by a law of nature and necessity. But this conducts us to the conclusion, — ■ XL Their moral ahility to oiey God is nothing else than real obedience and a natural inability to disobey. Strictly, this moral ability includes both the state of will required by the law of God, and also the cause of this state, to wit, the presence of 334 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. such motives as necessitate the inclination, choice, volition, or sense of the most agreeable, that God requires. The agent is able thus to will because he is caused thus to will. Or more strictly, his ability, and his inclinaijion or willing, are identical. Or still furbher, according to Ed- wards, his moral ability thus to will and his thus willing, and the pres- ence of the motives that cause this willing, are identical. This is a sub- lime discovery in philosophy ; a most transcendental speculation ! I would not treat these notions as ridiculous, were they not truly so, or if I could treat them in any other manner, and still do them anything like justice. If, where the theory is plainly stated, it appears ridiculous, the fault is not in me, but in the theory itself. I know it is trying to you, as it is to me, to connect anything ridiculous with so great and so revered a name as that of President Edwards. But if a blunder of his has en- tailed perplexity and error on the church, surely his great and good soul would now thank the hand that should blot out the error from under heaven. Thus, when closely examined, this long established and venerated fog-bank vanishes away ; and this famed distinction between moral and natural ability and inability, is found to be " a thing of nought." XII. I will state what I consider to ie the fundamental errors of midwords and his school upon the subject of ability. 1. He denied that moral agents are the causes of their own actions. He started, of course, with the just assumption, that every event is an effect, and must have some cause. The choices and volitions of moral agents are effects of some cause. What is that cause ? He assumed that every act of will must have been caused by a preceding one, or by the objective motive. By the reductio ad absurdum, he easily showed the absurdity of the first hypothesis, and consequently assumed the truth of the last. But how does he know that the sovereign power of the agent is not the cause ? His argument against self-determination amounts to nothing ; for it is, in fact, only a begging of the whole question. If we are conscious of anything, we are of the affirmation that we do, in fact, originate our own choices and volitions. Edwards, as really as any other man, believed himself to originate and be the proper cause of his own volitions. In his practical judgment he assumed his own cau- sality, and the proper causality of all moral agents, or he never could have had so much as a conception of moral agency and accountability. But in theory, he adopted the capital error of denying the proper causality of moral agents. This error is fundamental. Every definition of a moral agent that denies or overlooks, his proper causality is radically defective. It drops out of the definition the very element that we necessarily aflBrm to be essential to liberty and accountability. Denying, as he did, the NATURAL ABILITY. 335 proper causality of moral agents, he was driven to give a false deiinition of free agency, as has been shown. Edwards rightly regarded the choices and volitions of moral agents aa effects, but he looks in the wrong direction for the cause. Instead of heeding the affirmation of his own mind that causality, or the power of self-determination, is a sine qud non of moral agency, he assumed, in theorizing, the direct opposite, and sought for the cause of choice and volition out of the agent, and in the objective motive ; thus, in fact, denying the validity of the testi- mony of the pure reason, and reducing moral agents to mere machines. No wonder that so capital an error, and defended with so much ability, should have led one of his own sons into scepticism. But the piety of the president was stronger than even his powerful logic. Assuming a false major premise, his straightforward logic conducted him to the dggma of a universal necessity. But his well-developed reason, and deep piety of heart, controlled his practical judgment, so that few men have practically held the doctrines of accountability and retribution with a firmer grasp. 2. Edwards adopted the Lockean philosophy. He regarded the mind as possessing but two primary faculties, the understanding and the will. He considered all the desires, emotions, affections, appetites, and passions as voluntary, and as really consisting in acts of will. This confounding of the states of the sensibility with acts of the will, I regard as another fundamental error of his whole system of philosophy, so far as it respects the liberty of the will, or the doctrine of ability. Being conscious that the emotions, which he calls affections, the desires, the appetites and passions, were so correlated to their appropriate objects, that they are excited by the presence or contemplation of them, and assuming them to be voluntary states of mind, or actions of the will, he very naturally, and with this assumption, necessarily and justly, concluded, that the will was governed or decided by the objective motive. Assuming as he did that the mind has but two faculties, understanding and will, and that every state of feeling and of mind that did not belong to the under- standing, must be a voluntary state or act of will, and being conscious that his feelings, desires, affections, appetites and passions, were excited by the contemplation of their correlated objects, he could consistently come to no other conclusion than that the will is determined by motives, and that choice always is as the most agreeable is. XIII. 1 will now present another scheme of inability and its philosophy. 1. This philosophy properly distinguishes between the will and the sensibility. It regards the mind as possessing three primary departments, powers, or susceptibilities, the intellect, the sensibility, and the will. It does not always call these departments or susceptibilities by these names. 836 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. but if I understand them, the abetters of this philosophy hold to their existence, by whatever name they may call them. 3. This philosophy also holds, that the states of the intellect and of the sensibility are passive and involuntary. 3. It holds that freedom of will is a condition of moral agency. 4. It also teaches that the will is free, and consequently that man is a free moral agent. 5. It teaches that the will controls the outward life and the attention of the intellect, directly, and many of the emotions, desires, affections, appetites, and passions, or many states of the sensibility, indirectly. 6. It teaches that men have ability to obey God so far as acts of will are concerned, and also so far as those acts and states of mind are con- cerned that are under the direct or indirect control of the will. 7. But it holds that moral obligation may, and in the case of man at least, does extend beyond moral agency and beyond the sphere of ability ; that ability or freedom of will is essential to moral agency, but that free- dom of will or moral agency does not limit moral obligation ; that moral agency and moral obligation are not co-extensive ; consequently that moral obligation is not limited by ability or by moral agency. 8. This philosophy asserts that moral obligation extends to those states of mind that lie wholly beyond or without the sphere or control of the will ; that it extends not merely to voluntary acts and states, together with all acts and states that come within the direct or indirect control of the will, but, as was said, it insists that those mental states that lie wholly beyond the will's direct or indirect control, come within the pale of moral legislation and obligation : and that therefore obligation is not limited by ability. 9. This philosophy seems to have been invented to reconcile the doc- trine of original sin, in the sense of a sinful nature, or of constitutional moral depravity, with moral obligation. Assuming that original sin in this sense is a doctrine of divine revelation, it takes the bold and uncom- promising ground already stated, namely, that moral obligation is not merely co-extensive with moral agency and ability, but extends beyond both into the region of those mental states that lie entirely without the will's direct or indirect control. 10. This bold assertion the abetters of this philosophy attempt to support by an appeal to the necessary convictions of men and to the au- thority of the Bible. They allege that the instinctive judgments of men, as well as the Bible, everywhere assume and aflSrm moral obligation and mo'ral character of the class of mental states in question. 11. They admit that a physical inability is a bar to or inconsistent with moral obligation : but they of course deny that the inability to which they hold is physical. NATURAL ABILITY. . 337 XIV. This brings us to a brief consideration of the claims of this philosophy of inability. 1. It is based upon a petitio prindpii, or a begging of the question. >It assumes that the instinctive or irresistible and universal judgments of men, together with the Bible, assert and assume that moral obligation and moral character extend to the states of mind in question. It is ad- mitted that the teachings of the Bible are to be relied upon. It is also admitted that the first truths of reason, or what this philosophy calls the instinctive and necessary judgments of all men, must be true. But it is not admitted that the assertion in question is a doctrine of the Bible or a first truth of reason. On the contrary both are denied. It is denied, at least by me, that either reason or divine revelation affirms moral obliga- tion or moral character of any state of mind, that lies wholly beyond both the direct and the indirect control of the will. Now this philosophy must not be allowed to beg the question in debate. Let it be shown, if it can be, that the alleged truth is either a doctrine of the Bible or a first truth of reason. Both reason and revelation do assert and assume, that moral obligation and moral character extend to acts of will, and to all those outward acts or mental states that lie within its direct or indirect control. "But further these deponents say not." Men are conscious of moral obligation in respect to these acts and states of mii^d, and of guilt when they fail, in these respects, to comply with moral obhgation. But who ever blamed himself for pain, when, without his fault, he received a blow, or was seized with the tooth-ache, or a fit of bilious colic ? 2. Let us inquire into the nature of this inability. Observe, it is ad- mitted by this school that a physical inability is inconsistent with moral obligation — ^in other words, that physical ability is a condition of moral obligation. But what is a physical inability ? The primary definition of the adjective physical, given by Webster, is, "pertaining to nature, or natural objects." A physical inability then, in the primary sense of the term physical, is an inability of nature. It may be either a material or a mental inability ; that is, it may be either an inability of body or mind. It is admitted by the school whose views we are canvassing, that all hu- man causality or ability resides in the will, and therefore that there is a proper inability of nature to perform anything that does not come within the sphere of the direct or indirect causality of, or control of the will. It is plain, therefore, that the inability for which they contend must be a proper natural inability, or inability of nature. This they fully admit and maintain. But this they do not call a physical inability. But why do they not ? Why, simply because it would, by their own admissions, overthrow their favorite position. They seem to assume that a physical inability must be a material inabihty. But where is the authority for 88 338 STSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. such an assumption ? There is no authority for it. A proper inability of nature must be a physical inability, as opposed to moral inability, or there is no meaning in language. It matters not at all whether the ina- bility belongs to the material organism, or to the mind. If it be consti- tutional, and properly an inability of nature, it is nonsense to deny that this is a physical inability, or to maintain that it can be consistent with moral obligation. It is in vain to reply that this inability, though a real inability of nature, is not physical but moral, because a sinful inability. This is another begging of the question. The school whose views I am examining, maintain, that this inability is founded in the first sin of Adam. His first sin plunged himself and his posterity, descending from him by a natural law, into a total inability of nature to render any obedience to God. This first sin of Adam en- tailed a nature on all his posterity " wholly sinful in every faculty and part of soul and body." This constitutional sinfulness that belongs to every faculty and part of soul and body, constitutes the inability of which we are treating. But mark, it is not physical inability, because it is a sinful inability ! Important theological distinction ! — as truly wonderful, surely, as any of the subtleties of the Jesuits. But if this inability is sinful, it is important to inquire. Whose sin is it ? Who is to blame for it ? Why to be sure, we are told that it is the sin of him np"on whom it is thus entailed by the natural law of descent from parent to child with- out his knowledge or consent. This sinfulness of nature, entirely irre- spective of, and previous to any actual transgression, renders its possessor worthy of and exposed to the wrath and curse of God for ever. This sin- fulness, observe, is transmitted by a natural or physical law from Adam, but it is not a physical inability. It is something that inheres in, and belongs to every faculty and part of soul and body. It is transmitted by a physical law from parent to child. It is, therefore, and must be a phys- ical thing. But yet we are told that it cannot be a physical inability, because first, it is sinful, or sin itself ; and, secondly, because a physical inability is a bar to, or inconsistent with, moral obhgation. Here, then, we have their reasons for not admitting this to be a physical inability. It would in this case render moral obligation an impossibility ; and, be- sides, if a bar to moral obligation, it could not be sinful. But it is sinful, it is said, therefore it cannot be physical. But how do we know that it is sinful ? Why, we are told, that the instinctive judgments of men, and the Bible everywhere aflSrm and assume it. We are told, that both the instinctive judgments of men and the Bible affirm and assume, both the inability in question and the sinfulness of it ; " that we ought to be able, but are not ;" that is, that we are so much to blame for this inability of nature entailed upon us without our knowledge or consent, by a physical necessity, as to deserve the wrath and curse of God for ever. We are NATURAL ABILITY. 339 under a moral obligation not to have this sinful nature. We deserve damnation for having it. To be sure, we are entirely unable to put it away, and had no agency whatever in its existence. But what of that ? We are told, that " moral obligation is not limited by ability ;" that our being as unable to change our nature as we are to create a world, is no reason why we should not be under obligation to do it, since " moral ob- ligation does not imply ability of any kind to do what we are under obli- gation to do ! "... , I was about to expose the folly and absurdity of these assertions, but hush 1 It is not allowable, we are told, to reason on this subject. We shall deceive ourselves if we listen to the " miserable logic of our understandings." We must fall back, then, upon the intui- tive affirmations of reason and the Bible. Here, then, we are willing to lodge our appeal. The Bible defines sin to be a transgression of the law. What law have we violated in inheriting this nature ? What law requires us to have a different nature from that which we possess ? Does reason affirm that we are deserving of the wrath and curse of God for ever, for inheriting from Adam a sinful nature ? What law of reason have we transgressed in inheriting this nature ? Reason cannot condemn us, unless we have violated some law which it can recognize as such. Season indignantly rebukes such nonsense. Does the Bible hold us responsible for impossibilities ? Does it require of us what we cannot do by willing to do it ? Nay, verily ; but it expressly affirms, that " if there be first a willing mind, it is accepted according to that a man hath, and not according to that he hath not." The plain meaning of this passage is, that if one wills as God directs, he has thereby met all his obligation ; that he has done all that is naturally possible to him, and therefore nothing more is required. In this passage, the Bible expressly limits obligation by ability. This we have repeatedly seen in former lectures. The law also, as we have formerly seen, limits obliga- tion by ability. It requires only that we should love the Lord with all our strength, that is, with all our ability, and our neighbor as ourselves. Does reason hold us responsible for impossibilities, or affirm our obli- gation to do, or be, what it is impossible for us to do and be ? No in- deed I Eeason never did and never can condemn us for our nature, and hold us worthy of the wrath and curse of God for possessing it. Nothing is more shocking and revolting to reason, than such assumptions as are made by the philosophy in question. This every man's consciousness must testify. But is it not true that some, at least, do intelligently condemn them- selves for their nature, and adjudge themselves to be worthy of the wrath and curse of God for ever for its sinfulness ? The framers of the West- minster Confession of Faith made this affirmation in words, at least ; whether intelligently or unintelligently, we are left to inquire. The 'M6 STSTEMAtlC THEOLOGY. reason of a moral agent condemning himself, and adjudging hitoSelf worthy of the wrath and curse of God for ever, for possessing a nature entailed on him by a natural law, without his knowledge or consent ! This can nerer be. But is it not true, as is aflBrmed, that men instinctively and neces- sarily aflfirm their obligation to be able to obey God, while they at the same time affirm that they are not able ? I answer, no. They affirm themselves to be under obligation simply, and only, because deeply in their inward being lies the assumption that they are able to comply with the requirements of God. They are conscious of ability to will, and of power to control their outward life directly, and the states of the intel- lect and of their sensibility, either directly or indirectly, by willing. Upon this consciousness they found the affirmation of obligation, and of praise-worthiness and blame- worthiness in respect to these acts and states of mind. But for the consciousness of ability, no affirmation of moral obligation, or of praise-worthiness or blame-worthiness, were possible. But do not those who affirm both their inability and their obligation, deceive themselves ? I answer, yes. It is common for persons to over- look assumptions that lie, so to speak, at the bottom of their minds. This has been noticed in former lectures, and need not be here repeated. It is true indeed that God requires of men, especially under the gospel, what they are unable to do directly in their own strength. Or more strictly speaking, he requires them to lay hold on his strength, or to avail themselves of his grace, as the condition of being what he re- quires them to be. With strict propriety, it cannot be said that in this, or in any case, he requires directly any more than we are able directly to do. The direct requirement in the case under consideration, is to avail ourselves of, or to lay hold upon his strength. This we have power to do. He requires us to lay hold upon his grace and strength, and thereby to rise to a higher knowledge of himself, and to a consequent higher state of holiness than would be otherwise possible to us. The direct requirement is to believe, or to lay hold upon his strength, or to receive the Holy Spirit, or Christ, who stands at the door, and knocks, and waits for admission. The indirect requirement is to rise to a degree of knowledge of God, and to spiritual attainments that are impossible to us in our own strength. We have ability to obey the direct command directly, and the indirect command indirectly. That is, we are able by virtue of our nature, together with the proffered grace of the Holy Spirit, to comply with all the requirements of God. So that in fact there is no proper inability about it. But are not men often conscious of there being much difficulty in the way of rendering to God all that we affirm ourselves under obligation to render ? I answer, yes. But strictly speaking, they must admit their GRACIOUS ABILITY. 341 direct or indirect ability, as a condition of aflBrming their obligation. This difficulty, arising out of their physical depravity, and the power of temptation from without, is the foundation or cause of the spiritual war- fare of which the Scriptures speak, and of which all Christians are con- scious. But the Bible abundantly teaches, that through grace we are able to be more than conquerors. If we are able to be this through grace, we are able to arail ourselves of the provisions of grace, so that :here is no proper inability in the case. However great the difficulties may be, we are able through Christ to overcome them all. This we must and do assume as the condition of the affirmation of obligation. LECTURE XXXII. GRACIOUS ABILITY. Grace is unmerited favor. Its exercise consists in bestowing that which, without a violation of justice, might be withheld. Ability to obey God, as we have seen, is the possession of power adequate to the performance of that which is required. If, then, the terms are used in the proper sense, by a gracious ability must be intended that the power which men at present possess to obey the commands of God, is a gift of grace relatively to the command ; that is, the bestow- ment of power adequate to the performance of the thing required, is a matter of grace as opposed to justice. I. / will show what is intended by the term gracious ability. The abettors of this scheme hold that by the first sin of Adam, he, together with all his posterity, lost all natural power and all ability of every kind to obey God ; that therefore they were, as a race, wholly unable to obey the moral law, or to render to God any acceptable service whatever ; that is, that they became, as a consequence of the sin of Adam, wholly unable to use the powers of nature in any other way than to sin. They were able to sin or to disobey God, but entirely unable to obey him ; that they did not lose all power to act, but that they had power to act only m on^ direction, that is, in opposition to the vrill and law of God. By a gracious ability they intend, that in consequence of the atonement of Christ, God has graciously restored to man ability to accept the terms of mercy, or to fulfil the conditions of acceptance with God ; in other words, that by the gracious aid of the Holy Spirit which, upon condition of the atonement, God has given to every member of the 342 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. human family, all men are endowed with a gracious ability to obey God. By a gracious ability is intended, then, that ability or power to obey God, which all men now possess, not by virtue of their own nature or constitutional powers, but by virtue of the indwelling and gracious influence of the Holy Spirit, gratuitously bestowed upon man in conse- quence of the atonement of Christ. The inability, or total loss of all natural power to obey God into which men as a race fell by the first Bin of Adam, they call original sin ; perhaps more strictly, this inability is a consequence of that original sin into which man fell ; which original sin itself consisted in the total corruption of man's whole nature. They hold, that by the atonement Christ made satisfaction for original sin, in such a sense that the inability resulting from it is removed, and that now men are by gracious aid able to obey and accept the terms of salva- tion. That is, they are able to repent and believe the gospel. In short, they are able, by virtue of this gracious ability, to do their duty, or to obey God. This, if I understand these theologians, is a fair statement of their doctrine of gracious ability. II. This doctrine of a gracious ahility is an absurdity. The question is not whether, as a matter of fact, men ever do obey God without the gracious influence of the Holy Spirit. I hold that they do not. So the fact of the Holy Spirit's gracious influence being exerted in every case of human obedience, is not a question in debate between those who maintain, and those who deny the doctrine of gracious ability, in the sense above explained. The question in debate is not whether men do, in any case, use the powers of nature in the manner that God re- quires, without the gracious influence of the Holy Spirit, but whether they are naturally able so to use them. Is the fact, that they never do so use them without a gracious divine influence, to be ascribed to absolute inability, or to the fact that, from the beginning, they univer- sally and voluntarily consecrate their powers to the gratification of self, and that therefore they will not, unless they are divinely persuaded, by the gracious influence of the Holy Spirit, in any case turn and conse- crate their powers to the service of God ? If this doctrine of natural inability and of gracious ability be true, it inevitably follows : — 1. That but for the atonement of Christ, and the consequent bestow- ment of a gracious ability, no one of Adam's race could ever have been capable of sinning. For in this case the whole race would have been wholly destitute of any kind or degree of ability to obey God. Conse- quently they could not have been subjects of moral government, and of course their actions could have had no moral character. It is a first- truth of reason, a truth everywhere and by all men necessarily assumed in their practical judgments, that a subject of moral government must GRACIOUS ABILITY. 843 be a moral agent, or that moral agency is a necessary condition of any one's being a subject of a moral government. And in the practical judgment of men, it matters not at all whether a being ever was a moral agent, or not. If by any means whatever he has ceased to be a moral agent, men universally and necessarily assume, that it is impossible for him to be a subject of moral government any more than a horse can be such a subject. Suppose he has by his own faalt made himself an idiot or a lunatic ; all men know absolutely, and in their practical judgment assume, that in this state he is not, and cannot be a subject of moral government. They know that in this state, moral character cannot justly be predicated of his actions. His guilt in thus depriving himself of moral agency may be exceeding great, and his guilt in thus depriving himsef of moral agency may equal the sum of all the default of which it is the cause, — but be a moral agent, be under moral obliga- tion, in this state of dementation or insanity, he cannot. This is a first- truth of reason, irresistibly and universally assumed by all men. If therefore Adam's posterity had by their own personal act cast away and deprived themselves of all ability to obey God, in this state they would have ceased to be moral agents, and consequently they could have sinned no more. But the case under consideration is not the one just supposed, but is one where moral agency was not cast away by the agent himself. It is one where moral agency was never, and never could have been possessed. In the case under consideration, Adam's posterity, had he ever had any, would never have possessed any power to obey God, or to do anything acceptable to him. Consequently, they never could have sustained to God the relation of subjects of his moral government. Of course they never could have had moral character ; right or wrong, in a moral sense, never could have been predicated of their actions. 2. It must follow from this doctrine of gracious ability and natural inability, that mankind lost their freedom, or the liberty of will in the first sin of Adam ; that both Adam himself, and all his posterity would and could have sustained to God only the relation of necessary, as opposed to free, agents, had not God bestowed upon them a gracious ability. But that either Adam or his posterity lost their freedom or free agency by the first sin of Adam, is not only a sheer but an absurd as- sumption. To be sure Adam fell into a state of total alienation from the law of God, and lapsed into a state of supreme selfishness. His posterity have unanimously followed his example. He and they have become dead in trespasses and sins. Now that this death in sin either consists in, or implies, the loss of free agency, is the very thing to be proved. But this cannot be proved. I have so fully discussed the subject of human moral depravity or sinfulness on a former occasion, as to render it unnecessary to enlarge upon it here. 344 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. 3. Again, if it be true, as these theologians affirm, that men have only a gracious ability to obey God, and that this gracious ability con- sists in the presence and gracious agency of the Holy Spirit, it follows that, when the Holy Spirit is withdrawn from man, he is no longer a free agent, and from that moment he is incapable of moral action and of course can sin no more. Hence, should he live any number of years ^fter this withdrawal, neither sin nor holiness, virtue nor vice, praise- worthiness nor blameworthiness could be predicated of his conduct. The same will and must be true of all his future eternity. 4. If the doctrine in question be true, it follows, that from the mo- ment of the withdrawal of the gracious influence of the Holy Spirit, man is no longer a subject of moral obligation. It is from that moment absurd and unjust to require the performance of any duty of him. Nay to con- ceive of him as being any longer a subject of duty ; to think or speak of duty as belonging to him, is as absurd as to think or speak of the duty of a mere machine. He has, from the moment of the withholding of a gra- cious ability, ceased to be a free and become a necessaiy agent, having power to act but in one direction. Such a being can by no possibility be capable of sin or holiness. Suppose he still possesses power to act con- trary to the letter of the law of God ; what then ? This action can have no moral character, because, act in some way he must, and he can act in no other way. It is nonsense to affirm that such action can be sinful in the sense of blameworthy. To affirm that it can, is to contradict a first truth of reason. Sinners, then, who have quenched the Holy Spirit, and from whom he is wholly withdrawn, are no longer to be blamed for their enmity against God, and for all their opposition to him. They are, ac- cording to this doctrine, as free from blame as are the motions of a mere machine. 5. Again, if the doctrine in question be true, there is no reason to believe that the angels that fell from their allegiance to God ever sinned but once. If Adam lost his free agency by the fall, or by his first sin, there can be no doubt that the angels did so too. If a gracious ability had not been bestowed upon Adam, it is certain, according to the doc- trine in question, that he never could have been the subject of moral obligation from the moment of his first sin, and consequently, could never again have sinned. The same must be true of devDs. If by their first sin they fell into the condition of necessary agents, having lost their free agency, they have never sinned since. That is, moral character cannot have been predicable of their conduct since that event, unless a gracious ability has been bestowed upon them. That this has been done cannot, with even a show of reason, be pretended. The devils, then, ac- cording to this doctrine, are not now to blame for all they do to oppose God and to ruin souls. Upon the supposition in question, they cannot GEACIOUS ABILITY. 34:5 help it ; and you might as well blame the winds and the waves for the evils which they sometimes do, as blame Satan for what he does. fi. If this doctrine be true, there is not, and never will be, any sin in hell, for the plain reason, that there are no moral agents there. They are necessary agents, unless it be true, that the Holy Spirit and a gra- cious ability be continued there. This is not, I believe, contended for by the abettors of this scheme. But if they deny to the inhabitants of hell freedom of the will, or, which is the same thing, natural ability to obey God, they must admit, or be grossly inconsistent, that there is no sin in hell, either in men or devils. But is this admission agreeable either to reason or revelation ? I know that the abettors of this scheme maintain, that God may justly hold both men, from whom a gracious ability is withdrawn, and devils, responsible for their conduct, upon the ground that they have destroyed their own ability. But suppose this were true — that they had rendered themselves idiots, lunatics, or necessary as op- posed to free agents, could God justly, could enlightened reason still re- gard them as moral agents, and as morally responsible for their conduct ? No, indeed ! God and reason may justly blame, and render them miser- able, for annihilating their freedom or their moral agency, but to hold them still responsible for present obedience, were absurd. 7. We have seen that the ability of all men of sane mind to obey God, is necessarily assumed as a first truth, and that this assumption is from the very laws of mind, the indispensable condition of the aflBrmation, or even the conception, that they are subjects of moral obligation ; that, but for this assumption, men could not so much as conceive the possibility of moral responsibility, and of praiseworthiness and blameworthiness. If the laws of mind remain unaltered, this is and always will be so. In the eternal world and in hell, men and devils must necessarily assume their own freedom or ability to obey God, as the condition of their obligation to do so, and, consequently of their being capable of sin or holiness. Since revelation informs us that men and devils continue to sin in hell, we know that there also it must be assumed as a first truth of reason, that they are free agents, or that they have natural ability to obey God, 8. But that a gracious ability to do duty or to obey God is an ab- surdity, will further appear, if we consider that it is a first truth of rea- son, that moral obligation implies moral agency, and that moral agency implies freedom of will ; or in other words, it implies a natural ability to comply with obligation'. This ability is necessarily regarded by the in- telligence as the sine qud non of moral obligation, on the ground of natural and immutable justice. A just command always implies an ability to obey it. A command to perform a natural impossibility would not, and could not, impose obligation. Suppose God should command human beings to fly without giving them power ; could Pfic^ » cofiiipapd 346 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. impose moral obligation ? No, indeed I But suppose he should givf them power, or promise them power, upon the performance of a condi- tion within their reach ; then he might in justice require them to fly, and a command to do so would be obligatory. But relatively to the require- ment, the bestowment of power would not be grace, but justice. Eela- tively to the results or the pleasure of flying, the bestowment of power might be gracious. That is, it might be grace in God to give me power to fly, that I might have the pleasure and profit of flying ; so that relar tively to the results of flying, the giving of power might be regarded as an act of grace. But, if God requires me to fly as a matter of duty, he must in justice supply the power or ability to fly. This would in justice be a necessary condition of the command imposing moral obligation. Nor would it at all vary the case if I had ever possessed wings, and by the abuse of them had lost the power to fly. In this case, considered relatively to the pleasure, and profit, and results of flying, the restoring of the power to fly might and would be an act of grace. But if God would still command m§ to fly, he must, as a condition of my obligation, restore the power. It is vain and absurd to say, as has been said, that in such a case, although I might lose the power of obedience, this could not alter the right of God to claim obedience. This assertion proceeds upon the absurd assumption that the will of God makes or creates law, instead of merely declaring and enforcing the law of nature. We have seen in former lectures, that the only law or rule of action that is, or can be obligatory on a moral agent, is the law of nature, or just that course of willing and acting, which is for the time being, suitable to his nature and relations. We have seen that God's will never makes or creates law, that it only declares and enforces it. If therefore, by any means whatever, the nature of a moral agent should be so changed that his will is no longer free to act in conformity with, or in opposition to, the law of nature, if God would hold him still obligated to obey, he must in justice, relatively to his requirement, restore his liberty or ability. Suppose one had by the abuse of his intellect lost the use of it, and become a perfect idiot, could he by any possibility be still required to understand and obey God ? Certainly not. So neither could he be re- quired to perform anything else that had become naturally impossible to, him. Viewed relatively to the pleasure and results of obedience, the restor- ing of power would be an act of grace. But viewed relatively to his duty or to God's command, the restoring of power to obey is an act of justice and not of grace. To call this grace were to abuse language, and confound terms. III. In what sense is a gracious ability possible ? 1. Not, as we have just seen, in the sense that the bestowment of power to render obedience to a command possible, can be properly a t^ift GRACIOUS ABILITY. 8i7 of grace. Grace is undeserved favor, something not demanded by jus- tice, that which under the circumstances might be withholden without injustice. It never can be just in any being to require that which under the circumstances is impossible. As has been said, relatively to the re- quirement and as a condition of its justice, the bestowment of power adequate to the performance of that which is commanded, is an unaltera- ble condition of the justice of the command. This I say is a first truth of reason, a truth everywhere by all meii necessarily assumed and known. A gracious ability to obey a command, is an absurdity and an im- possibility. 2. But a gracious ability considered relatively to the advantages to result from obedience is possible. Suppose, for example, that a servant who supports himself and his family by his wages, should by his own fault render himself unable to labor and to earn his wages. His master may justly dismiss him, and let him go with his family to the poor-house. But in this disabled state his master cannot justly exact labor of him. Nor could he do so if he absolutely owned the servant. Now suppose the master to be able to restore to the servant his former strength. If he would require service of him, as a condition of the justice of this re- quirement, he must restore his strength so far at least as to render obe- dience possible. This would be mere justice. But suppose he restored the ability of the servant to gain support for himself and his family by labor. This, viewed relatively to the good of the servant, to the results of the restoration of his ability to himself and to his family, is a matter of grace. Relatively to the right of the master in requiring the labor of the servant, the restoration of ability to obey is an act of justice. But relatively to the good of the servant, and the benefits that result to him from this restoration of ability, and making it once more possible for him to support himself and his family, the giving of ability is properly an act of grace. Let this be applied to the case under consideration. Suppose the race of Adam to have lost their free agency by the first sin of Adam, and thus to have come into a state in which holiness and consequent salva- tion were impossible. Now, if God would still require obedience of them, he must in justice restore their ability. And viewed relatively to his right to command, and their duty to obey, this restoration is properly a matter of justice. But suppose he would again place them in circum- stances to render holiness and consequent salvation possible to them : — viewed relatively to their good and profit, this restoration of ability is properly a matter of grace. A gracious ability to obey, viewed relatively to the command to be obeyed, is impossible and absurd. But a gracious ability to be saved, viewed relatively to salvation, is possible. There is no proof that mam SiS SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. kind ever lost their ability to obey, either by the first sin of Adam, or by their own sin. For this would imply, as we have seen, that they had ceased to be free, and had become necessary agents. But if they had, and God had restored their ability to obey, all that can be justly said in this case, is, that so far as his right to command is concerned, the resto- ration of their ability was an act of justice. But so far as the rendering of salvation possible to them is concerned, it was an act of grace. 3. But it is asserted, or rather assumed by the defenders of the dogma under consideration, that the Bible teaches the doctrine of a natural in- ability, and of a gracious ability in man to obey the commands of God. 1 admit, indeed, that if we interpret scripture vidthout regard to any just rules of interpretation, this assumption may find countenance in the word of God, just as almost any absurdity whatever may do, and has done. But a moderate share of attention to one of the simplest and most uni- versal and most important rixles of interpreting language, whether in the Bible or out of it, will strip this absurd dogma of the least appearance of support from the word of God. The rule to which I refer is this, " That language is always to be interpreted in accordance with the subject- matter of discourse." When used of acts of will, the term " cannot," interpreted by this rule, must not be understood to mean a proper impossibility. K I say, I cannot take five dollars for my watch, when it is ofEered to me, every one knows that I do not and cannot mean to affirm a proper impossibility. So when the angel said to Lot, " Haste thee, for I cannot do anything until thou be come thither," who ever understood him as aflBrming a natural or any proper impossibility ? All that he could have meant was, that he was not willing to do anything until Lot was in a place of safety. Just so when the Bible speaks of our inability to comply with the com-- mands of God, all that can be intended is, that we are so unwilling that, without divine persuasion, we, as a matter of fact, shall not and will not obey. This certainly is the sense in which such language is used in com- mon life. And in common parlance, we never think of such language, ■ when used of acts of will, as meaning anything more than unwillingness, a state in which the will is strongly committed in an opposite direction. When Joshua said to the children of Israel, " Ye cannot serve the Lord, for he is a holy God," the whole context, as well as the nature of the case, shows that he did not mean to affirm a natural, nor indeed any kind of impossibility. In the same connection, he requires them to serve the Lord, and leads them solemnly to pledge themselves to serve him. He undoubtedly intended to say, that with wicked hearts they could not render him an acceptable service, and therefore insisted on their putting away the wickedness of their hearts, by immediately and voluntarily con- secrating themselves to the service of the Lord. So it must be in all cases eRACIOUS ABILITY. 349 where the term " cannot," and such-like expressions which, when applied to muscular action, would imply a proper impossibility, are used in ref- erence to acts of will ; they cannot, when thus used, be understood as im- plying a proper impossibility, without doing violence to every sober rule of interpreting language. What would be thought of a judge or an ad- vocate at the bar of an earthly tribunal, who should interpret the lan- guage of a witness without any regard to the rule, " That language is to be understood according to the subject-matter of discourse." Should an advocate in his argument to the court or jury, attempt to interpret the language of a witness in a manner that made " cannot," when spoken of an act of will, mean a proper impossibility, the judge would soon rebuke his stupidity, and remind him that he must not talk nonsense in a court of justice ; and might possibly add, that such nonsensical assertions were allowable only in the pulpit. I say again, that it is an utter abuse and perversion of the laws of language, so to interpret the Bible as to make it teach a proper inability in man to will as God directs. The essence of obedience to God consists in willing. Language, then, used in reference to obedience must, when properly understood, be interpreted in accord- ance with the subject-matter of discourse. Consequently, when used in reference to acts of will, such expressions as "cannot," and the like, can absolutely mean nothing more than a choice in an opposite direction. But it may be asked. Is there no grace in all that is done by the Holy Spirit to make man wise unto salvation ? Yes, indeed, I answer. And it is grace, and great grace, just because the doctrine of a natural inability in man to obey God is not true. It is just because man is well able to render obedience, and unjustly refuses to do so, that all the influence that God brings to bear upon him to make him willing, is a gift and an influ- ence of grace. The grace is great, just in proportion to the sinner's ability to comply with God's requirements, and the strength of his voluntary opposition to his duty. If man were properly unable to obey, there could be no grace in giving him ability to obey, when the bestowment of ability is considered relatively to the command. But lot man be regarded as free, as possessing natural ability to obey all the requirements of God, and aU his difficulty as consisting in a w'icked heart, or, which is the same thing, in an unwillingness to obey, then an influence on the part of God designed and tending to make him willing, is grace indeed. But strip man of his freedom, render him naturally unable to obey, and you ren- der grace impossible, so far as his obligation to obedience is concerned. But it is urged in support of the dogma of natural inability and of a gracious ability, that the Bible everywhere represents man as dependent on the gracious influence of the Holy Spirit for all holiness, and conse- quently for eternal life. I answer, it is admitted that this is the repre- sentation of the Bible, but the question is, in what sense is he depend- 350 SYSTKMATIC THEOLOGY. ent ? Does his dependence consist in a natural inability to embrace the gospel and be saved ? or does it consist in a voluntary selfishness — in an unwillingness to comply with the terms of salvation ? Is man depend- ent on the Holy Spirit to give him a proper ability to obey God ? or is he dependent only in such a sense that, as a matter of fact, he will not em- brace the gospel unless the Holy Spirit makes him willing ? The latter, beyond reasonable question, is the truth. This is the universal repre- sentation of scripture. The difficulty to be overcome is everywhere in the Bible represented to be the sinner's unwillingness alone. It cannot possibly be anything else ; for the willingness is the doing required by God. " If there is first a willing mind, it is accepted according to that a man hath, and not according to that he hath not." But it is said, if man can be willing of himself, what need of divine persuasion or influence to make him willing ? I might ask, suppose a man is able but unwilling to pay his debts, what need of any influence to make him willing ? Why, divine influence is needed to make a sinner willing, or to induce him to will as God directs, just for the same reason that persuasion, entreaty, argument, or the rod, is needed to make our children submit their wills to ours. The fact therefore that the Bible represents the sinner as in some sense dependent upon divine influence for a right heart, no more implies a proper inability in the sinner, than the fact that children are dependent for their good behavior, oftentimes, upon the thorough and timely discipline of their parents, implies a prop- er inability in them to obey their parents without chastisement. The Bible everywhere, and in every way, assumes the freedom of the will. This fact stands out in strong relief upon every page of divine in- spiration. But this is only the assumption necessarily made by the uni- versal intelligence of man. The strong language often found in scripture upon the subject of man's inability to obey God, is designed only to rep- resent the strength of his voluntary selfishness and enmity against God, and never to imply a proper natural inability. It is, therefore, a gross and most injurious perversion of scripture, as well as a contradiction of human reason, to deny the natural ability, or which is the same thing, the natural free agency of man, and to maintain a proper natural inabil- ity to obey God, and the absurd dogma of a gracious ability to do our duty. BEMABES. 1. The question of ability is one of great practical importance. To deny the ability of man to obey the commandments of God, is to repre- sent God as a hard master, as requiring a natural impossibility of his creatures on pain of eternal damnation. This necessarily begets in the mind that believes it hard thoughts of God. The intelligence cannot be GRACIOUS ABILITY. 351 satisfied with the justice of such a requisition. In fact, so far as this error gets possession of the mind and gains assent, just so far it natu- rally and necessarily excuses itself for disobedience, or for not complying with the commandments of God. 2. The moral inability of Edwards is a real natural inability, and so it has been understood by sinners and professors of religion. When I entered the ministry, I found the persuasion of an absolute inability on the part of sinners to repent and believe the gospel, almost universal. When I urged sinners and professors of religion to do their duty without delay, I frequently met with stern opposition from sinners, professors of rehgion, and ministers. They desired me to say to sinners, that they could not repent, and that they must wait God's time, that is, for God to help them. It was common for the classes of persons just named to ask me, if I thought sinners could be Christians whenever they pleased, and whether I thought that any class of persons could repent, believe, and obey God without the strivings and new-creating power of the Holy Spirit. The church was almost universally settled down in the belief of a physical moral depravity, and, of course, in a belief in the necessity of a physical regeneration, and also of course in the belief, that sinners must wait to be regenerated by divine power while they were passive. Professors also must wait to be revived, until God, in mysterious sove- reignty, came and revived them. As to revivals of religion, they were settled down in the belief to a great extent, that man had no more agency in producing them than in producing showers of rain. To attempt to effect the conversion of a sinner, or to promote a revival, was an attempt to take the work out of the hands of God, to go to work in your own strength, and to set sinners and professors to do the same. The vigor- ous use of means and measures to promote a work of grace, was regarded by many as impious. It was getting np an excitement of animal feeling, and wickedly interfering with the prerogative of God. The abominable dogmas of physical moral depravity, or a sinful constitution, with a con- sequent natural, falsely called moral, inability, and the necessity of a physical and passive regeneration, had chilled the heart of the church, and lulled sinners into a fatal sleep. This is the natural tendency of such doctrines. 3. Let it be distinctly understood before we close this subject, that we do not deny, but strenuously maintain, that the whole plan of salva- tion, and all the influences, both providential and spiritual, which God exerts in the conversion, sanctification, and salvation, of sinners, is grace from first to last, and that I deny the dogma of a gracious ability, be- cause it robs God of his glory. It really denies the grace of the gospel. The abettors of this scheme, in contending for the grace of the gospel, really deny it. What grace can there be, that should surprise h^^iv^p 352 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. and earth, and cause " the angels to desire to look into it," in bestowing ability on those who never had any, and, of course, who never cast away their ability — to obey the requirements of God ? According to them all men lost their ability in Adam, and not by their own act. God still re- quired obedience of them upon pain of eternal death. Now he might, according to this view of the subject, just as reasonably command all men, on pain of eternal death, to fly, or to undo all that Adam had done, or perform any other natural impossibility, as to command them to be holy, to repent and believe the gospel. Now, I ask again, what possible grace was there, or could there be, in his giving them power to obey him ? To have required the obedience without giving the power had been infinitely unjust. To admit the assumption, that men had really lost their ability to obey in Adam, and call this bestowment of ability for which they con- tend, grace, is an abuse of language, an absurdity, and a denial of the true grace of the gospel not to be tolerated. I reject the dogma of a gracious ability, because it involves a denial of the true grace of the gos- pel. I maintain that the gospel, with all its influences, including the gift of the Holy Spirit, to convict, convert, and sanctify the soul, is a "■ system of grace throughout. But to maintain this, I must also maintain, that God might justly have required obedience of men without making these provisions for them. And to maintain the justice of God in re- quiring obedience, I must admit and maintain that obedience was pos- sible to man. Let it not be said then, that we deny the grace of the glorious gospel of the blessed God, nor that we deny the reality and necessity of the influences of the Holy Spirit to convert and sanctify the soul, nor that this influence is a gracious one ; for all these we most strenuously main- tain. But I maintain this upon the ground, that men are able to do their duty, and that the difiSculty does not lie in a proper inability, but in a voluntary selflshness, in an unwillingness to obey the blessed gospel. I say again, that I reject the dogma of a gracious ability, as I understand its abettors to hold it, not because I deny, but solely because it denies the grace of the gospel. The denial of ability is really a denial of the possibility of grace in the affair of man's salvation. I admit the ability of man, and hold that he is able, but utterly unwilling to obey God. Therefore I consistently hold that all the influences exerted by God to make him willing, are of free grace abounding through Christ Jesus. THE NOTION OP INABILITY. 353 LECTURE XXXIII. THE NOTION OF INABILITY. PBOPEB METHOD OF ACCOUNTING FOE IT. I HAVE represented ability, or the freedom of the will, as a first- truth of consciousness, a truth necessarily known to all moral agents. The inquiry may naturally arise, How then is it to be accounted for, that so many men have denied the liberty of the will, or ability to obey God ? A recent writer thinks this denial a sufiBcient refutation of the afiBrma- tion, that ability is a first-truth of consciousness. It is important that this denial should be accounted for. That mankind affirm their obliga- tion upon the real, though often latent and unperceived assumption of ability, there is no reasonable ground of doubt. I have said that first-truths are frequently assumed, and certainly known without being always the direct object of thought or attention ; and also that these truths are universally held in the practical judgments of men, while they sometimes in theory deny them. They know them to be true, and in all their practical judgments assume their truth, while they reasoa against them, think they prove them untrue, and not nnfrequently affirm, that they are conscious of an opposite affirmation. For example, men have denied, in theory, the law of causality, while they have at every moment of their lives acted upon the assumption of its truth. Others have denied the freedom of the will, who have, every hour of their lives, assumed, and acted, and judged, upon the assumption that the will is free. The same is true of ability, which, in respect to the commandments of God, is identical with freedom. Men have often denied the ability of man to obey the commandments of God, while they have always, in their practical judgments of themselves and of others, assumed their ability, in respect to those things that are really com- manded by God. Now, how is this to be accounted for ? 1. Multitudes have denied the freedom of the will, because they have loosely confounded the will with the involuntary powers — with the intel- lect and the sensibility. Locke, as is well known, regarded the mind as possessing but two primary faculties, the understanding and the will. President Edwards, as was said in a former lecture, followed Locke, and regarded all the states of the sensibility as acts of the will. Multitudes, nay the great mass of Calvinistic divines, with their hearers, have held the same views. This confounding of the sensibility with the will has oeen common for a long time. Now everybody is conscious, that the 23 354 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. states of the sensibility, or mere feelings, cannot be produced or changed by a direct efEort to feel thus or thus. Everybody knows from conscious- ness that the feelings come and go, wax and wane, as motives are pre- sented to excite them. And they know also that these feelings are under the law of necessity and not of liberty ; that is, that necessity is an attribute of these feelings, in such a sense, that under the circumstances, they will exist in spite of ourselves, and that they cannot be controlled by a direct efEort to control them. Everybody knows that our feelings, or the states of our sensibility can be controlled only indirectly, that is, by the direction of our thoughts. By directing our thoughts to an object calculated to excite certain feelings, we know that, when the excitability is not exhausted, feelings correlated to that object will come into play, of course and of necessity. So when any class of feelings exist, we all know that by diverting the attention from the object that excites them, they subside of course, and give place to a class correlated to the new object that at present occupies the attention. Now, it is- very manifest how the freedom of the will has come to be denied by those who confound the will proper with the sensibility. These same persons have always known and assumed, that the actions of the will proper were free. Their error has consisted in not distinguishing in theory between the action of the proper will, and the involuntary states of the sensibility. In their practical judgments, and in their conduct, they have recognized the distinction which they have failed to recognize in their speculations and theories. They have every hour been exerting their own freedom, have been controlling directly their attention and their outward life, by the free exercise of their proper will. They have also, by the free exer- cise of the same faculty, been indirectly controlling the states of their sensibility. They have all along assumed the absolute freedom of the will proper, and have always acted upon the assumption, or they would not have acted at all, or even attempted to act. But since they did not in theory distinguish between the sensibility and the will proper, they denied in theory the freedom of the will. If the actions of the will be confounded with desires and emotions, as President Edwards confounded them, and as has been common, the result must be a theoretical denial of the freedom of the will. In this way we are to account for the doc- trine of inability, as it has been generally held. It has not been clearly understood that moral law legislates directly, and, with strict propriety of speech, only over the will proper, and over the involuntary powers only indirectly through the will. It has been common to regard the law and the gospel of God, as directly extending their claims to the involuntary powers and states of mind ; and, as was shown in a former lecture, many have regarded, in theory, the law as extending its claims to those states that lie wholly beyond, either the direct or indirect control of the will. THE NOTION OP INABILITY. 355 Kow, of course, with these views of the claims of God, ability is and must be deuied. I trust we have seen in past lectures, that, strictly and properly speaking, the moral law restricts its claims to the actions of the will proper, in such a sense that, if there be a willing mind, it is accepted as obedience ; that the moral law and the lawgiver legislate over invol- untary states only indirectly, that is, through the will ; and that the whole of virtue, strictly speaking, consists in good-will or disinterested benevolence. Sane minds never practically deny, or can deny, the free- dom of the will proper, or the doctrine of ability, when they make the proper discriminations between the will and the sensibility, and properly regard moral law as legislating directly only over the will. It is worthy of all consideration, that those who have denied ability, have almost always confounded the will and the sensibility ; and that those who have denied ability, have always extended the claims of moral law beyond the pale of proper voluntariness ; and many of them even beyond the limits of either the direct or the indirect control of the will. But the inquiry may arise, how it comes to pass that men have so ex- tensively entertained the impression, that the moral law legislates directly over those feelings, and over those states of mind which they know to be involuntary ? I answer, that this mistake has arisen out of a want of just discj'imination between the direct and indirect legislation of the law, and of the lawgiver. It is true that men are conscious of being respon- sible for their feelings and for their outward actions, and even for their thoughts. And it is really true that they are responsible for them, in so far as they are under either the direct or indirect control of the wilL And they know that these acts and states of mind are possible to them, that is, that they have an indirect ability to produce them. They, how- ever, loosely confound the direct and indirect ability and responsibility. The thing required by the law directly and presently is benevolence or good-will. This is what, and all that, the law strictly, presently or di- rectly requires. It indirectly requires all those outward and inward acta and states that are connected directly and indirectly with this required act of will, by a law of necessity ; that is, that those acts and states should follow as soon as by a natural and necessary law they will follow from a right action of the will. When these feelings, and states, and acts do not exist, they blame themselves, generally with propriety, because the absence of them is in fact owing to a want of the required act of the will. Sometimes, no doubt, they blame themselves unjustly, not considering that, although the will is right, of which they are con- scious, the involuntary state or act does not follow, because of exhaus- tion, or because of some disturbance in the established and natural con- nection between the acts of the will and its ordinary sequents. Wheo this exhaustion or disturbance exists, men are apt, loosely and unjustly, U6 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. to write bitter things against themselves. They often do the same in hours of temptation, when Satan casts his fiery darts at them, lodging them in the thoughts and involuntary feelings. The will repels them, but they take effect, for the time being, in spite of one's self, in the intel- lect and sensibility. Blasphemous thoughts are suggested to the mind, unkind thoughts of God are suggested, and in spite of one's self, these abominable thoughts awaken their correlated feelings. The will abhors them and struggles to suppress them, but for the time being, finds itself unable to do anything more than to fight and resist. Now, it is very common for souls in this state to write the most bitter accusations against themselves. But should it be hence inferred that they really are as much in fault as they assume themselves to be ? No, indeed ! But why do ministers, of all schools, unite in telling such tempted souls. You are mistaken, my dear brother or sister, these thoughts and feelings, though exercises of your own mind, are not yours in such a sense that you are responsible for them ? The thoughts are suggested by Satan, and the feelings are a necessary consequence. Your will resists them, and this proves that you are unable, for the time being, to avoid them. You are therefore not responsible for them while yon resist them with all the power of your will, any more than you would be guilty of murder should a giant overpower your strength, and use your hand against your will to shoot a man. In such cases it is, so far as I know, universally true, that all schools admit that the tempted soul is not responsible or guilty for those things which it cannot help. The in- ability is here allowed to be a bar to obligation ; and such souls are justly told by ministers. You are mistaken in supposing yourself guilty in this case. It is just as absurd, in the one case as in the other, to infer real responsibility from a feeling or persuasion of responsibility. To hold that men are always responsible, because they loosely think themselves to be so, is absurd. In cases of temptation, such as that just supposed, as soon as the attention is directed to the fact of inability to avoid those thoughts and feelings, and the mind is conscious of the will's resisting them, and of being unable to banish them, it readily rests in the assurance that it is not responsible for them. Its own irresponsi- bility in such cases appears self-evident to the mind, the moment the proper inability is considered, and the aflBrmation of irresponsibility attended to. Now if the soul naturally and truly regarded itself as re- sponsible, when there is a proper inability and impossibility, the in- structions above referred to could not relieve the mind. It would say. To be sure I know that I cannot avoid having these thoughts and feel- ings, any more than I can cease to be the subject of consciousness, yet I know I am responsible notwithstanding. These thoughts and feelings are states of my own mind, and no matter how I come by them, oi THE NOTION OF INABILITY. 357 whether I can control or prevent them or not. Inability, you know, is no bar to obligation ; therefore, my obligation and my guilt remain. Woe is me, for I am undone. The idea, then, of responsibility, when there is in fact real inability, is a prejudice of education, a mistake. The mistake, unless strong prejudice of education has taken posses- sion of the mind, lies in overlooking the fact of a real and proper in- ability. Unless the judgment has been^ strongly biased by education, it never judges itself bound to perfo2-m impossibilities, nor even conceives of juch a thing. Who ever held himself bound to undo what is past, to recall past time, or to substitute holy acts and states of mind in the place of past sinful ones ? No one ever held himself bound to do this ; first, because he knows it to be impossible ; and secondly, because no one that I have heard of ever taught or asserted any such obligation ; and therefore none have received so strong a bias from education as loosely to hold such an opinion. But sometimes the bias of education is so great, that the subjects of it seem capable of believing almost anything, however in- consistent with the intuitions of the reason, and consequently in the face of the most certain knowledge. For example, President Edwards relates of a young woman in his congregation, that she was deeply convicted of being guilty for Adam's first sin, and deeply repented of it. Now sup- pose that this and like cases should be regarded as conclusive proof that men are guilty of that sin, and deserve the wrath and curse of God for ever for that sin ; and that all men will suffer the pains of hell forever, except they become convinced of their personal guilt for that sin, and re- pent of it in dust and ashes I President Edwards's teaching on the sub- ject of the relation of all men to Adam's first sin, it is well known, was calculated in a high degree to pervert the judgment upon that subject ; and this sufficiently accounts for the fact above alluded to. But apart from education, no human being ever held himself responsible for, or guilty of, the first or any other sin of Adam, or of any other being, who existed and died before he himself existed. The reason is that all moral agents naturally know, that inability or a proper impossibility is a bar to moral obligation and responsibility ; and they never conceive to the con- trary, unless biased by a mystifying education that casts a fog over their primitive and constitutional convictions. 2. Some have denied ability because they have strangely held, that the moral law requires sinners to be, in all respects, what they might have been had they never sinned. That is, they maintain that God re- quires of them just as high and perfect a service as if their powers had never been abused by sin ; as if they had always been developed by the perfectly right use of them. This they admit to be a natural impossi- bility ; nevertheless they hold that God may justly require it, and that ginners are justly bound to perform this impossible service, and that they 858 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Bin continually in coming short of it. To this sentiment I answer, that it might be maintained with as much show of reason, and as much authority from the Bible, that God might and does require of all sinners to undo all their acts of sin, and to substitute holy ones in their places, and that he holds them as sinning every moment by the neglect to do this. Why may not God as well require one as the other ? They are alike impossibilities originating in the sinner's own act or fault. If the sinner's rendering himself unalile to obey in one case does not set aside the right of God to command, so does it not for the same reason in the other. If an inability resulting from the sinner's own act cannot bar the right of God to make the requisition in the one case, neither can it for . the same reason in the other. But every one can see that God cannot justly require the sinner to recall past time, and to undo past acts. But why ? No other reason can be assigned than that it is impossible. But the same reason, it is admitted, exists in its full extent in the other case. It is admitted that sinners, who have long indulged in sin, or who have sinned at all, are really as unable to render as high a degree of service as they might have done had they never sinned, as they are to recall past * time, or to undo all their past acts of sin. On what ground, then, of reason or revelation does the assertion rest, that in one case an impossi- bility is a bar to obligation, and not in the other ? I answer, there is no ground whatever for the assertion in question. It is a sheer and an absurd assumption, unsupported by any aflBrmation of reason, or any truth or principle of revelation. But to this assumption I reply again, as I have done on a former occasion, that if it be true, it must follow, that no one on earth or in heaven who has ever sinned will be able to render as perfect a service as the law demands ; for there is no reason to believe, that any being who has abused his powers by sin will ever in time or eternity be able to render as high a service as he might have done had he at every moment duly developed them by perfect obedience. If this theory is true, I see not why it does not follow that the saints will be guilty in heaven of the sin of omission. A sentiment based upon an absurdity in the outset, and resulting in such consequences as this, must be rejected without hesitation. 3. A consciousness of the force of habit, in respect to all the acts and states of body and mind, has contributed to the loose holding of the doctrine of inability. Every one who is at all in the habit of observation and self -reflection is aware, that for some reason we acquire a greater and greater facility in doing anything by practice or repetition. We find this to be true in respect to acts of will as really as in respect to the involuntary states of mind. When the will has been long committed to the indulgence of the propensities, and in the habit of submitting THE NOTION OP INABILITY. 359 itself to their impulse, there is a real diflBculty of some sort in the way of changing its action. This diflBculty cannot really impair the liberty of the will. If it could, it would destroy, or so far impair, moral agency and accountability. But habit may, and, as every one knows, does interpose an obstacle of some sort in the way of right willing, or, on the other hand, in the way of wrong willing. That is, men both obey and disobey with greatest facility from habit. Habit strongly favora the accustomed action of the will in any direction. This, as I said, never does or can properly impair the freedom of the will, or render it impossible to act in a contrary direction : for if it could and should, the actions of the will, in that case, being determined by a law of neces- sity in one direction, would have no moral character. If benevolence became a habit so strong that it were utterly impossible to will in an opposite direction, or not to will benevolently, benevolence would cease to be virtuous. So, on the other hand, with selfishness. If the will came to be determined in that direction by habit grown into a law of necessity, such action would and must cease to have moral character. But, as I said, there is a real conscious diflBculty of some sort in the way of obedience, when the will has been long accustomed to sin. This is strongly recognized in the language of inspiration and in devotional hymns, as well as in the language of experience by all men. The lan- guage of scripture is often so strong upon this point, that, but for a regard to the subject-matter of discourse, we might justly infer a proper inability. For example, Jer. xiii. 23 : " Can the Ethiopian change his skin, or the leopard his spots ? then may ye also do good, that are accustomed to do evil." This and similar passages recognize the influ- ence of habit. " Then may ye who are accustomed to do evil ;" cus- tom or habit is to be overcome, and, in the strong language of the prophet, this is like changing the Ethiop's skin or the leopard's spots. But to understand the prophet as here aflBrming a proper inability were to disregard one of the fundamental rules of interpreting language, namely, that it is to be understood by reference to the subject of discourse. The latter part of the seventh chapter of Eomans affords a striking instance and an illustration of this. It is, as has just been said, a sound and most important rule of interpreting all language, that due regard be had to the subject-matter of discourse. When "cannot," and such like terms, that express an inability are applied to physical or involuntary actions or states of mind, they express a proper natural inability ; but when they are used in reference to actions of free will, they express not a proper impossibility, but only a diflBculty arising out of the existence of a contrary choice, or the law of habit, or both. Much question has been made about the seventh of Eomans in its relation to the subject of ability and inability. Let us, therefore, look a 360 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. little Into this passage, Romans vii. 15-23 : " For that which I do, I allow not ; for what I would, that do I not ; but what I hate, that do I. If then I do that which I would not, I consent unto the law that it is good. Now then it is no more I that do it, but sin that dwelleth in me. Tor I know that in me (that is in my flesh) dwelleth no good thing ; for to will is present with me ; but how to perform that which is good I find not. For the good that I would I do not ; but the evil which I would not, that I do. Now if I do that I would not, it is no more I that do it, but sin that dwelleth in me. I find then a law, that when I would do good, evil is present with me. For I delight in the law of God after the inward man. But I see another law in my mem- bers, warring against the law of my mind, and bringing me into cap- tivity to the law of sin which is in my members." Now what did the apostle mean by this language ? Did he use language here in the popu- lar sense, or with strictly philosophical propriety .'' He says he finds himself able to will, but not able to do. Is he then speaking of a mere outward or physical inability ? Does he mean merely to say, that the established connection between volition and its sequents was disturbed, so that he could not execute his volitions ? This his language, literally interpreted, and without reference to the subject-matter of discourse, and without regard to the manifest scope and design of the writer, would lead us to conclude. But who ever contended for such an inter- pretation ? The apostle used popular language, and was describing a very common experience. Convicted sinners and backslidden saints often make legal resolutions, and resolve upon obedience under the influ- ence of legal motives, and without really becoming benevolent, and changing the attitude of their wills. They, under the influence of con- viction, purpose selfishly to do their duty to God and man, and, in the presence of temptation, they constantly fail of keeping their resolutions. It is true, that with their selfish hearts, or in the selfish attitude of their willS; they cannot keep their resolutions to abstain from those inward thoughts and emotions, nor from those outward actions that result by a law of necessity from a selfish state or attitude of the wiU. These legal resolutions the apostle popularly calls willings. " To will is pres- ent with me, but how to do good I find not. When I would do good, evil is present with me, so that the good I would I do not, and the evil I would not, that I do. If then I do the evil I would not, it is no longer I that do it, but sin that dwelleth in me. I delight in the law of God after the inner man. But I see another law in my members warring against the law of my mind, and bringing me into captivity to the law f)f sin which is in my members," etc. Now, this appears to me to be descriptive of a very familiar experience of every deeply convicted sinner oi back- glider. The will is committed to the propensities, to the law la the THE NOTION OF INABILITf. 361 members, or to the gratification of the impulses of the sensibility. Hence, the outward life is selfish. Conviction of sin leads to the forma- tion of resolutions of amendment, while the will does not submit to God. These resolutions constantly fail of securing the result contemplated. The will still abides in a state of committal to self-gratification ; and hence resolutions to amend in feeling or the outward life, fail of securing those results. Nothing was more foreign from the apostle's purpose, it seems to me, than to affirm a proper inability of will to yield to the claims of God, Indeed, he affirms and assumes the freedom of his will. " To will," he says, " is present with me ;" that is, to resolve. But resolution is an act of will. It is a purpose, a design. He purposed, designed to amend. To form resolutions was present with him, but how to do good he found not. The reason why he did not execute his purposes was, that they were selfishly made ; that is, he resolved upon reformation without giving his heart to God, without submitting his will to God, without actually be- coming benevolent. This caused his perpetual failure. This language, construed strictly to the letter, would lead to the conclusion, that the apostle was representing a case where the will is right, but where the es- tablished and natural connection between volition and its sequents is destroyed, so that the outward act did not follow the action of the will. In this case all schools would agree that the act of the will constitutes real obedience. The whole passage, apart from the subject-matter of discourse, and from the manifest design and scope of the writer, might lead us to conclude, that the apostle was speaking of a proper inability, and that he did not therefore regard the failure as his own fault. " It is no more I, but sin that dwelleth in me. wretched man that I am," etc. Those who maintain that the apostle meant to assert a proper ina- bility to obey, must also admit that he represented this inabihty as a bar to obligation, and regarded his state as calamitous, rather than as properly sinful. But the fact is, he was portraying a legal experience, and spoke of finding himself unable to keep selfish resolutions of amendment in the presence of temptation. His will was in a state of committal to the in- dulgence of the propensities. In the absence of temptation, his convic- tions, and fears, and feelings were the strongest impulses, and under their influence he would form resolutions to do his duty, to abstain from fleshly indulgences, etc. But as some other appetite or desire came to be more strongly excited, he yielded to that of course, and broke his former reso- lution. Paul writes as if speaking of himself, but was doubtless speaking as the representative of a class of persons already named. He found the law of selfish habit exceedingly strong, and so strong as to lead him to cry out, " wretched man," etc. But this is not affirming a proper iniv- biUty of will to submit to God. S62 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. 4. All men who seriously undertake their own reformation find them- Bclves in great need of help and support from the Holy Spirit, in conse- qnenoe of the physical depravity of which I have formerly spoken, and because of the great strength of their habit of self-indulgence. They are prone, as is natural, to express their sense of dependence on the Divine Spirit in strong language, and to speak of this dependence as if it consisted in a real inability, when, in fact, they do not really consider it as a proper inability. They speak upon this subject just as they do upon any and every other subject, when they are conscious of a strong inclina- tion to a given course. They say in respect to many things, "I cannot," when they mean only " I will not," and never think of being understood as afiSrming a proper inability. The inspired writers expressed them- selves in the common language of men upon such subjects, and are doubtless to be understood in the same way. In common parlance, " can- not" often means " will not," and perhaps is used as often in this sense as it is to express a proper inability. Men do not misinterpret this lan- guage, and suppose it to aflBrm a proper inability, when used in reference to acts of will, except on the subject of obedience to God ; and why should they assign a meaning to language when used upon this subject which they do not assign to it anywhere else ? But, as I said in a former lecture, under the light of the gospel, and with the promises in our hands, God does require of us what we should be unable to do and be, but for these promises and this proffered assistance. Here is a real inability to do directly in our own strength all that is re- quired of us, upon consideration of the proffered aid. We can only do it by strength imparted by the Holy Spirit. That is, we cannot know Christ, and avail ourselves of his offices and relations, and appropriate to our own souls his fulness, except as we are taught by the Holy Spirit. The thing immediately and directly required, is to receive the Holy Spirit by faith to be our teacher and guide, to take of Christ's and show it to us. This confidence we are able to exercise. Who ever really and intel- ligently affirmed that he had not power or ability to trust or confide in the promise and oat^ of God ? Much that is said of inability in poetry, and in the common language of the saints, respects not the subjection of the will to God, but those ex- periences, and states of feeling that depend on the illuminations of the Spirit just referred to. The language that is so common in prayer and in the devotional dialect of the church, respects general^ our dependence upon the Holy Spirit for such divine discoveries of Christ, as to charm the soul into a steadfast abiding in him. We feel our dependence upon the Holy Spirit so to enlighten ns, as to break up for ever the power of Blnful habit, and draw us away from our idols entirely and for ever. In future lepturps I shall h»ve opcasion to enlarge much upon the THE NOTION OF INABILITY. 363 subject of our dependence upon Christ and the Holy Spirit. But this dependence does not consist in a proper inability to will as God directs, but, as I have said, partly in the power of sinful habit, and partly in the great darkness of our souls in respect to Christ and his mediatorial work and relations. All these together do not constitute a proper inability, for the plain reason, that through the right action of our will which is always possible to us, these diflSculties can all be directly or indirectly overcome. Whatever we can do or be, directly or indirectly, by willing, is possible to us. But there is no degree of spiritual attainment required of us, that may not be reached directly or indirectly by right willing. Therefore these attainments are possible. " If any man," says Christ, " will do his will," that is, has an obedient will, '■ he shall know of the doctrine whether it be of God." "If thine eye be single," that is, if the intention or will is right, " thy whole body shall be full of light." " If any man love me, he will keep my words, and my Father will love him, and we will come and make our abode with him." The scriptures abound with assurances of light and instruction, and of all needed grace and help, upon condition of a right will or heart, that is, upon condition of our being really willing to obey the light, when and as fast as we receive it. I have abundantly ^hown on former occasions, that a right state of the will constitutes, for the time being, all that, strictly speak- ing, the moral law requires. But I said, that it also, though in a less strict and proper sense, requires all those acts and states of the intellect and sensibility which are connected by a law of necessity with the right action of the will. Of course, it also requires that cleansing of the sen- sibility, and all those higher forms of Christian experience that result from the indwelling of the Holy Spirit. That is, the law of God re- quires that these attainments shall be made when the means are pro- vided and enjoyed, and as soon as, in the nature of the case, these at- tainments are possible. But it requires no more than this. For the law of God can never require absolute impossibilities. That which requires absolute impossibilities, is not and cannot be moral law. For, as was formerly said, moral law is the law of nature, and what law of nature would that be that should require absolute impossibilities ? This would be a mockery of a law of nature. What 1 a law of nature requiring that which is impossible to nature, both directly and indirectly ! Impossible. 864 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. LECTURE XXXIV. REPENTANCE AND IMPENITENCE. Ik the discussion of this subject I shall show,— I. What repentance is not. 1. The Bible everywhere represents repentance as a virtue, and as constituting a change of moral character ; consequently, it cannot be a phenomenon of the intelligence : that is, it cannot consist in conviction of sin, nor in any intellectual apprehension of our guilt or ill-desert. All the states or phenomena of the intelligence are purely passive states of mind, and of course moral character, strictly speaking, cannot be pre- dicated of them. 2. Repentance is not a phenomenon of the sensibility : that is, it does not consist in a feeling of regret or remorse, of compunction or sor- row for sin, or of sorrow in view of the consequences of sin to self or to others, nor in any feelings or emotions whatever. All feelings or emo- tions belong to the sensibility, and are, of course, purely passive states of mind, and consequently can have no moral character in themselves. It should be distinctly understood, and always borne in mind, that repentance cannot consist in any involuntary state of mind, for it is im- possible that moral character, strictly speaking, should pertain to passive states. II. What repentance is. There are two Greek words which are translated by the English word, repent. 1. Metamelomai, " to care for," or to be concerned for one's self ; hence to change one's course. This term seems generally to be used to express a state of the sensibility, as regret, remorse, sorrow for sin, etc. But sometimes it also expresses a change of purpose as a consequence of regret, or remorse, or sorrow ; as in Matt. xxi. 29, " He answered and said, I will not ; but afterwards he repented and went." It is used to represent the repentance of Judas, which evidently consisted of remorse and despair. 2. Metanoeo, " to take an after view ;" or more strictly, to change one's mind as a consequence of, and in conformity with, a second and more rational view of the subject. This word evidently expresses a change of choice, purpose, intention, in conformity with the dictates of the intelligence. REPENTANCE AND IMPENITENCE. 365 This is no doubt the idea of evangelical repentance. It is a phenom- enon of will, and consists in the turning or change of the ultimate in- tention from seMshness to benevolence. The term expresses the act of turning ; the changing of the heart, or of the ruling preference of the soul. It might with propriety be rendered by the terms " changing the heart." The English word "repentance " is often used to express regret, remorse, sorrow, etc., and is used in so loose a sense as not to convey a distinct idea, to the common mind, of the true nature of evangelical re- pentance. A turning from sin to holiness, or more strictly, from a state of consecration to self to a state of consecration to God, is and must be the turning, the change of mind, or the repentance that is required of all sinners. Nothing less can constitute a virtuous repentance, and nothing more can be required. III. What is implied in repentance. 1. Such is the correlation of the will to the intellect, that repentance must imply reconsideration or after thought. It must imply self-reflec- tion, and such an apprehension of one's guilt as to produce self-condemna- tion. That selfishness is sin, and that it is right and duty to consecrate the whole being to God and his service, are first truths, necessarily as- sumed by all moral agents. They are, however, often unthought of, not reflected upon, Eepentance implies the giving up of the attention to the consideration and self-application of these first truths, and consequently implies conviction of sin, and guilt, and ill-desert, and a sense of shame and self-condemnation. It implies an intellectual and a hearty justifica- tion of God, of his law, of his moral and providential government, and of all his works and ways. It implies an apprehension of the nature of sin, that it belongs to the heart, and does not essentially consist in, though it leads to, outward conduct ; that it is an utterly unreasonable state of mind, and that it justly deserves the wrath and curse of God forever. It implies an apprehension of the reasonableness of the law and com- mands of God, and of the folly and madness of sin. It implies an in- tellectual and a hearty giving up of all controversy with God upon all and every point. It implies a conviction, that God is wholly right, and the sinner wholly wrong, and a thorough and hearty abandonment of all excuses and apolo- gies for sin. It implies an entire and universal acquittal of God from every shade and degree of blame, a thorough taking of the entire blame of sin to self. It implies a deep and thorough abasement of self in the dust, a crying out of soul against self, and a most sincere and universal, intellectual, and hearty exaltation of God, 2. Such, also, is the connection of the will and the sensibility, that 866 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGt. the turning of the will, or evangelical repentance, implies sorrow for sin as necessarily resulting from the turning of the will, together with the intellectual views of sin which are implied in repentance. Neither con- viction of sin, nor sorrow for it, constitutes repentance. Yet from the correlation which is established between the intelligence, the sensibility, and the will, both conviction of sin, and sorrow for it, are implied in evangelical repentance, the one as necessarily preceding, and the other as often preceding, and always and necessarily resulting from repentance. During the process of conviction, it often happens, that the sensibility is hardened and unfeeling ; or, if there is much feeling, it is often only re- gret, remorse, agony, and despair. But when the heart has given away, and the evangelical turning has taken place, it often happens that the fountain of the great deep in the sensibility is broken up, the sorrows of the soul are stirred to the very bottom, and the sensibility pours forth its gushing tides like an irresistible torrent. But it frequently happens, too, in minds less subject to deep emotion, that the sorrows do not im- mediately flow in deep and broad channels, but are mild, melting, ten- der, tearful, silent, subdued. Self-loathing is another state of the sensibility implied in evangelical repentance. This state of mind may and often does, exist where repent- ance is not, just as outward morality does. But, like outward morality, it must exist where true repentance is. Self-loathing is a natural and a necessary consequence of those intellectual views of self that are implied in repentance. While the intelligence apprehends the utter, shameful guilt of self, and the heart yields to the conviction, the sensibility neces- sarily sympathizes, and a feeling of self-loathing and abhorrence is the inevitable consequence. It implies a loathing and abhorrence of the sins of others, a most deep and thorough feeling of opposition to sin — to all sin, in self and everybody else. Sin has become, to the penitent soul, the abominable thing which it hates. It implies a holy indignation toward all sin and all sinners, and a manifest opposition to every form of iniquity. 3. Repentance also implies peace of mind. The soul that has full confidence in the infinite wisdom and love of God, in the atonement of Christ, and in his universal providence, cannot but have peace. And further, the soul that has abandoned all sin, and turned to God, is no longer in a state of warfare with itself and with God. It must have peace of conscience, and peace with God. It implies heart-complacency in God, and in all the holy. This must follow from the very nature of repentance. It implies confession of sin to God and to man, as far as sin has been committed against men. If the heart has thoroughly renounced sin, it hoe become benevolent, and is of course disposed, as far as possible, to REPENTANCE AND IMPENITENCE. 367 undo the wrong it has committed, to confess sin, and humhle self on ac- count of it, before God and our neighbor, whom we have injured. Ee- pentance implies humility, or a willingness to be known and estimated according to our real character. It implies a disposition to do right, and to confess our faults to God and man, as far as man has a right to know them. Let no one who has refused, and still refuses or neglects to confess his> sins to God, and those sins to men that have been committed against them, profess repentance unto salvation ; but let him remember that God has said, " He that covereth his sins shall not prosper ; but whoso confesseth and forsaketh them shall find mercy:" and again, " Confess your faults one to another, and pray one for another, that ye may be healed." Kepentance implies a willingness to make restitution, and the actual making of it as far as ability goes. He is not just, and of course is not penitent, who has injured his neighbor in his person, reputation, proji- erty, or in anything, and is unwilling to make restitution. And he is unwilling to make restitution who neglects to do so whenever he is able. It is impossible that a soul truly penitent should neglect to make all practicable restitution, for the plain reason that penitence implies a be- nevolent and just attitude of the will, and the will controls the conduct by a law of necessity. Eepentance implies reformation of outward life. This follows from reformation of heart by a law of necessity. It is naturally impossible that a penitent soul, remaining penitent, should indulge in any known sin. If the heart be reformed, the life must be as the heart is. It implies a universal reformation of life, that is, a reformation ex- tending to all outward sin. The penitent does not, and remaining peni- tent, cannot, reform in respect to some sins only. If penitent at all, ho must have repented of sin as sin, and of course of all sin. If he has turned to God, and consecrated himself to God, he has of course ceased from sin, from all sin as such. Sin, as we have seen on a former occasion, is a unit, and so is holiness. Sin consists in selfishness, and holiness in disinterested benevolence : it is therefore sheer nonsense to say that re- pentance can consist with indulgence in some sins. What are generally termed little, as well as what are termed great sins, are alike rejected and abhorred by the truly penitent soul, and this from a law of necessity, he being truly penitent, 4. It implies faith or confidence in God in all things. It implies, not only the conviction that God is wholly right in all his controversy with sinners, but also that the heart has yielded to this conviction, and has come fully over to confide most implicitly in him in all respects, so that it can readily commit all interests for time and eternity to his hands. Repentance is a state of mind that implies the fullest confidence in all th« 3C8 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. promises and threateuings of God, and in the atonement and grace of Christ. IV. What impenitence is not. 1. It is not a negation, or the mere absence of repentance. Some «eem to regard impenitence as a nonentity, as the mere absence of repent- ance ; but this is a great mistake. 2. It is not mere apathy in the sensibility in regard to sin, and a mere want of sorrow for it. 3. It is not the absence of conviction of sin, nor the consequent care- lessness of the sinner in respect to the commandments of God. 4. It is not an intellectual self-justification, nor does it consist in a disposition to cavil at truth and the claims of God. These may and often do result from impenitence, but are not identical with it. 5. It does not consist in the spirit of excuse-making, so often mani- fested by sinners. This spirit is a result of impenitence, but does not constitute it. 6. Nor does it consist in the love of sin for its own sake, nor in the love of sin in any sense. It is not a constitutional appetite, relish, or craving for sin. If this constitutional craving for sin existed, it could have no moral character, inasmuch as it would be a wholly involuntary state of mind. It could not be the crime of impenitence. V. What impenitence is. 1. It is everywhere in the Bible represented as a heinous sin, as in Matt. xi. 20-24 : " Then began he to upbraid the cities wherein most of his mighty works were done, because they repented not. "Woe unto thee, Chorazin ! woe unto thee, Bethsaida ! for if the mighty works which were done in you, had been done in Tyre and Sidon, they would have repented long ago in sackcloth and ashes. But I say unJ;o you, it shall be more tolerable for Tyre and Sidon at the day of judgment than for you. And thou Capernaum, which art exalted unto heaven, shalt be brought down to hell ; for if the mighty works which have been done in thee, had been done in Sodom, it would have remained until this day. But I say unto you, that it shall be more tolerable for the land of Sodom, in the day of judgment, than for thee." Here, as elsewhere, impenitence is represented as most aggravated wickedness. 2. Impenitence is a phenomenon of the will, and consists in the will's cleaving to self-indulgence under light. It consists in the will's pertina- cious adherence to the gi-atification of self, in despite of all the light with which the sinner is surrounded. It is not, as has been said, a passive state nor a mere negation, nor the love of sin for its own sake ; but it is an active and obstinate state of the will, a determined holding on to that bepentance and impenitence. 369 course of self-seeking which constitutes sin, not from a love to sin, but for the sake of the gratification. This, under light, is of course, aggra- vated wickedness. Considered in this view, it is easy to account for all the woes and denunciations that the Saviour uttered against it. When the claims of God are revealed to the mind, it must necessarily yield to them, or strengthen itself in sin. It must, as it were, girJ itself up, and struggle to resist the claims of duty. This strengthening self in sin under light is the particular form of sin which we call impenitence. All sin- ners are guilty of it, because all have some light, but some are vastly more guilty of it than others. VI. Notice some things that are implied in impenitence. As it essentially consists in a cleaving to self-indulgence under light, it implies, — 1. That the impenitent sinner obstinately prefers his own petty and momentary gi-atification to all the other and higher interests of God and the universe ; that because these gratifications are his own, or the gi-ati- fication of self, he therefore gives them the preference over all the infinite interests of all other beings. 3. It implies the deliberate and actual setting at naught, not only of the interests of God and of the universe, as of no value, but it implies also a total disregard, and even contempt, of the rights of all other beings. It is a practical denial that they have any rights or interests to be promoted. 3. It implies a rejection of the authority of God, and contempt for it, as well as a spurning of his law and gospel. 4 It implies a present justification of all past sin. The sinner who holds on to his self-indulgence, in the presence of the light of the gospel, really in heart justifies all his past rebellion. 5. Consequently present impenitence, especially under the light of the glorious gospel, is a heart-justification of all sin. It is taking sides deliberately with sinners against God, and is a virtual endorsing of all sins of earth and hell. This principle is clearly implied in Christ's teaching. Matt, xxiii, 34-36 : "Wherefore, behold, I send unto you prophets, and wise men, and scribes ; and some of them ye shall kill and crucify ; and some of them shall ye scourge in your synagogues, and persecute them from city to city ; that upon you may come all the right- eous blood shed upon the earth, from the blood of righteous Abel unto the blood of Zacharias, son of Barachias, whoui ye slew between the temple and the altar. Verily, I say unto you. All these things shall come upon this generation." 6. Present impenitence, under all the light and experience which the linner now has, involves the guilt of all his past sin. If he still holds on 84 S?0 8ts*rteMAtic TriEoLOGf. to it, he in heart justifies it. If he in heart justifies it, he virtually M- commits it. If in the presence of accumulated light, he still persists in sin, he virtually endorses, recommits, and is again guilty of all past sin. It implies a total want of confidence in God ; want of confidence in his character and government ; in his works and ways. It virtually charges G-od with usurpation, falsehood, and selfishness in all their odious forms. It is a making war on every moral attribute of God, and is utter enmity against him. It is mortal enmity, and would of course always manifest itself in sinners, as it did when Christ was upon the earth. When he poured the light upon them, they hardened themselves until they were ripe for murdering him. This is the true nature of im- penitence. It involves the guilt of a mortal enmity against God. VII. Notice some of the characteristics or evidences of impenitence. 1. A manifested indifference to the sins of men is evidence of an im- penitent and sin- justifying state of mind. It is impossible that a peni- tent soul should not be deeply and heartily opposed to all sin ; and if heartily opposed to it, it is impossible that he should not manifest this opposition, for the heart controls the life by a law of necessity. 2. Of course a manifest heart-oomplacency in sin or in sinners is sure evidence of an impenitent state of mind. " He that will be the friend of the world is the enemy of God." Heart-complacency in sin- ners is that friendship with the world that is enmity against God. 3. A manifest want of zeal in opposing sin and in promoting reforma- tion, is a sure indication of an impenitent state of mind. The soul that has been truly convinced of sin, and turned from sin to the love and service of God, cannot but manifest a deep interest in every effort to ex- pel sin out of the world. Such a soul cannot but be zealous in opposing sin, and in building up and establishing righteousness in the earth. 4. A manifest want of sympathy with God in respect to his govern- ment, providential and moral, is an evidence of impenitence of heart A penitent soul, as has been said, will and must of course justify God in all his ways. This is implied in genuine repentance. A disposition to complain of the strictness and rigor of God's commandments — to speak of the providence of God in a complaining manner, to murmur at its allotments, and repine at the circumstances in which it has placed a soul, is to evince an impenitent and rebellious state of mind. 5. A manifest want of confidence in the character, faithfulness, and promises of God, is also sure evidence of an impenitent state of mind. A distrust of God in any respect cannot consist with a penitent state of heart. 6. The absence of peace of mind is sure eridence of an impenitent state. The penitent soul must have peace of conscience, because peni- tence is a state of conscious rectitude. It also must have peace with God, in view of, and through confidence in, the atonement of Christ. Eepentance is the turning from an attitude of rebellion against God, to a state of universal submission to his will, and approbation of it as wise and good. This must of course bring peace to the soul. When therefore there is a manifest want of peace, there is evidence of impenitence of heart. 7. Every unequivocal manifestation of selfishness is a conclusive evidence of present impenitence. Eepentance, as we have seen, consists in the turning of the soul from selfishness to benevolence. It follows of course that the presence of selfishness, or a spirit of self-indulgence, ia conclusive evidence of an impenitent state of mind. Repentance implies the denial of self ; the denial or subjection of all the appetites, passions, and propensities to the law of the intelligence. Therefore a manifest spirit of self-indulgence, a disposition to seek the gratification of the appetites and passions, such as the subjection of the will to the use of tobacco, of alcohol, or to any of the natural or artificial appetites, under light, and in opposition to the law of the reason, is conclusive evidence of present impenitence. I say, " under light, and in opposition to the law of the reason." Such articles as those just named, are sometimes used medicinally, and because they are regarded as useful, and even in- dispensable to health under certain circumstances. In such cases their ase may be a duty. But they are more frequently used merely to gratify appetite, and in the face of a secret conviction that they are not only un- necessary, but absolutely injurious. This is indulgence that constitutes sin. It is impossible that such indulgence should consist with repen- tance. Such a mind must be in impenitence, or there is no such thing as impenitence. 8. A spirit of self-justification is another evidence of impenitence. This manifestation must be directly the opposite of that which the truly penitent soul will make. 9. A spirit of excuse-making for neglect of duty is also a conclusive evidence of an impenitent heart. Eepentance implies the giving up of all excuses for disobedience, and a hearty obedience in all things. Of course, where there is a manifest disposition to make excuses for not being what and all God requires us to be, it is certain that there is, and must be an impenitent state of mind. It is war with God. 10. A want of candor upon any moral subject relating to self, also betrays an impenitent heart. A penitent state of the will is committed to know and to embrace all truth. Therefore a prejudiced, uncandid stai^e of mind must be inconsistent with penitence, and a manifestation of prejudice must evince present impenitence. An unwillingness to be searched, and to have all our words and ways brought into the light of truth, and to be reproved when we are in error, is a sure indication 372 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. of an impenitent state of mind. " Every one that doeth evil hateth the light, neither cometh to the light, lest his deeds should be reproved. But he that doeth truth cometh to the light, that his deeds may be made manifest, that they are wrought in God." 11. Only partial reformation of life, also indicates that the heart has not embraced the whole will of God. When there is a disposition manifested to indulge in some sin, no matter how little, it is sure evi- dence of impenitence of heart. The penitent soul rejects sin as sin ; of course every kind or degree of iniquity is put away, loathed, and abhorred. "Whoso keepeth the whole law and yet offends in one point, is guilty of ' all ;" that is, if a man in one point unequivocally sins or disobeys God, it is certain that he truly from the heart obeys him in nothing. He has not an obedient state of mind. If he really had supreme respect to God's authority, he could not but obey him in all things. If therefore it be found, that a professor of penitence does not manifest the spirit of universal obedience ; if in some things he is manifestly self-indulgent, it may be known that he is altogether yet in sin, and that he is still " in the gall of bitterness and in the bond of iniquity." 13. Neglect or refusal to confess and make restitution, so far as opportunity and ability are enjoyed, is also a sure indication of an unjust and impenitent state of mind. It would seem impossible for a penitent soul not at once to see and be impressed with the duty of making confes- sion and restitution to those who have been injured by him. When this is refused or neglected, there must be impenitence. The heart controls the life by a law of necessity ; when, therefore, there is a heart that confesses and forsakes sin, it is impossible that this should not appear in outward confession and restitution. 13. A spirit of covetousness, or grasping after the world, is a sure indication of impenitence. " Covetousness is idolatry." It is a hunger- ing and thirsting after, and devotion to this world. Acquisitiveness indulged must be positive proof of an impenitent state of mind. If any man love the world, how dwelleth the love of God in him ? 14. A want of interest in, and compassion for, sinners, is a sure indication of impenitence. If one has seen his own guilt and ruin, and has found himself sunk in the horrible pit and miry clay of his own abominations, and has found the way of escape, to feel deeply for sinners, to manifest a great compassion and concern for them, and a zeal for their salvation, is as natural as to breathe. If this sympathy and zeal are not manifested, we may rely upon it that there is still impenitence. There is a total want of that love to God and souls that is always implied in repentance. Seest thou a professed convert to Christ whose compas- sions are not stirred, and whose zeal for the salvation of souls is not awakened ? Be assured that you behold a hypocrite. FAITH AND UNBELIEF. 373 15. Spiritual sloth or indolence is another evidence of an impenitent heart. The soul that thoroughly turns to God, and consecrates itself to him, and wholly commits itself to promote his glory in the building up of his kingdom, will be, must be, anything but slothful. A disposition to spiritual idleness, or to lounging or indolence of any kind, is an evi- dence that the heart is impenitent. I might pursue this subject to an indefinite length ; but what has been said must suffice for this course of Instruction, and is sufficient to give you the clue by which you may de- tect the windings and delusions of the impenitent heart. LECTURE XXXV. FAITH AND UNBELIEF. I. What evangelical faith is not. 1. The term faith, like most other words, has diverse significations, and is manifestly used in the Bible sometimes to designate a state of the intellect, in which case it means an undoubting persuasion, a firm con- viction, an unhesitating intellectual assent. This, however, is not its evangelical sense. Evangelical faith cannot be a phenomenon of the in- tellect, for the plain reason that, when used in an evangelical sense, it is always regarded as a virtue. But virtue cannot be predicated of intel- lectual states, because these are involuntary, or passive states of mind. Faith is a condition of salvation. It is something which we are com- manded to do upon pain of eternal death. But if it be something to be done — a solemn duty, it cannot be a merely passive state, a mere intel- lectual conviction. The Bible distinguishes between intellectual and saving faith. There is a faith of devils, and there is a faith of saints. James clearly distinguishes between them, and also between an antino- mian and a saving faith. " Even so faith, if it hath not works, is dead, being alone. Yea, a man may say, thou hast faith, and I have works : show me thy faith without thy works, and I will show thee my faith by my works. Thou believest that there is one God ; thou doest well : the devils also believe, and tremble. But wilt thou know, vain man, that faith without works is dead ? Was not Abraham our father justified by works, when he had offered Isaac his son upon the altar ? Seest thou how faith wrought with his works, and by works was faith made perfect ? And the scripture was fulfilled which saith, Abraham believed God, and it was imputed unto him for righteousness ; and he was called the friend of God. Ye see then how that by works a man is justified, and not by 374: SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. faith only. Likewise also was not Eahab the harlot justified by works, when she had received the messengers, and had sent them out another way ? For as the body without the spirit is dead, so faith without works is dead also." — James ii. 17-36, The distinction is here clearly marked, as it is elsewhere in the Bible, between intellectual and saving faith. One produces good works or a holy life ; the other is unproductive. This shows that one is a phenomenon of the intellect merely, and does not of course control the conduct. The other must be a phenomenon of the will, because it manifests itself in the outward life. Evangelical faith, then, is not a conviction, a perception of truth. It does not belong to the intellect, though it implies intellectual conviction, yet the evangelical or virtuous element does not consist in it. 2. It is not a feeling of any kind ; that is, it does not belong to, and is not a phenomenon of, the sensibility. The phenomena of the sensibility are passive states of mind, and therefore have no moral character in themselves. Faith, regarded as a virtue, cannot consist in any involun- tary state of mind whatever. It is represented in the Bible as an active and most eflScient state of mind. It works, and " works by love." It produces " the obedience of faith." Christians are said to be sanctified by the faith that is in Christ. Indeed the Bible, in a great variety of instances and ways, represents faith in God and in Christ as a cardinal form of virtue, and as the mainspring of an outwardly holy life. Hence, it cannot consist in any involuntary state or exercise of mind whatever. IL What evangelical faith is. Since the Bible uniformly represents saving or evangelical faith as a virtue, we know that it must be a phenomenon of the will. It is an eflBcient state of mind, and therefore it must consist in the embracing of the truth by the heart or will. It is the will's closing in with the truths of the gospel. It is the soul's act of yielding itself up, or committing itself to the truths of the evangelical system. It is a trusting in Christ, a committing of the soul and the whole being to him, in his various offices and relations to men. It is a confiding in him, and in what is revealed of him, in his word and providence, and by his Spirit. The same word that is so often rendered faith in the New Testament is also rendered commit ; as in John ii. 24, " But Jesus did not commit himself unto them, because he knew all men." Luke xvi. 11, " If, there- fore, ye have not been faithful in the unrighteous mammon, who will commit to your trust the true riches ? " In these passages the word ren- dered commit is the same word as that which is rendered faith. It is a confiding in God and in Christ, as revealed in the Bible and in reason. It is a receiving of the testimony of God concerning himself, and con- corning all things of which he has spoken. It is a receiving of Christ for FAITH AND DNBKLIEF. 37£ just what he is represented to be in his gospel, and an unqualified sur- render of the will, and of the whole being to him. III. What is implied in evangelical faith f 1. It implies an intellectual perception of the things, facts, and truths believed. No one can believe that which he does not understand. It is impossible to believe that which is not so revealed to the mind, that the mind understands it. It has been erroneously assumed, that faith did not need light, that is, that it is not essential to faith that we under- stand the doctrines or facts that we are called upon to believe. This is a false assumption ; for how can we believe, trust, confide, in what we do not understand ? I must first understand what a proposition, a fact, a doctrine, or a thing is, before I can say whether I believe, or whether I ought to believe, or not. Should you state a proposition to me in an unknown tongue, and ask me if I believe it, I must reply, I do not, for I do not understand the terms of the proposition. Perhaps I should be- lieve the truth expressed, and pei'haps I should not ; I cannot tell, until I understand the proposition. Any fact or doctrine not understood is like a proposition in an unknown tongue ; it is impossible that the mind should receive or reject it, should believe or disbelieve it, until it is undelrstood. We can receive or believe a truth, or fact, or doctrine no further than we understand it. So far as we do understand it, so far we may believe it, although we may not understand all about it. For example : I can be- lieve in both the proper divinity and humanity of Jesus Christ. That he is both God and man, is a fact that I can understand. Thus far I can believe. But how his divinity and humanity are united I cannot under- stand. Therefore, I only believe the fact that they are united ; the quo modo of their union I know nothing about, and I believe no more than I know. So I can understand that the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are one God. That the Father is God, that the Son is God, that the Holy Spirit is God ; that these three are Divine persons, I can understand as a fact. I can also understand that there is no contradiction or impossi- bility in the declared fact, that these three are one in their substratum of being ; that is that they are one in a different sense from that in which they are three ; that they are three in one sense, and one in another. I understand that this may be a fact, and therefore I can believe it. But the quo modo of their union I neither understand nor believe : that is, I have no theory, no idea, no data on the subject, have no opinion, and consequently no faith, as to the manner in which they are united. Faith, then, in any fact or doctrine, implies that the intellect has an idea, or that the soul has an understanding, an opinion of that which the heart embraces or believes. 2. Evangelical faith implies the appropriation of the truths of the 376 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. gospel to ourselves. It implies an acceptance of Christ as our wisdom, righteousness, sanctification, and redemption. The soul that truly be- lieves, believes that Christ tasted death for every man, and of course for it. It apprehends Christ as the Saviour of the world, as oflEered to allj and embraces and receives him for itself. It appropriates his atonement, and his resurrection, and his intercession, and his promises to itself. Christ is thus presented in the gospel, not only as the Saviour of the world, but also to the individual acceptance of men. He is embraced by the world no further than he is embraced by individuals. He saves the world no further than he saves individuals. He died for the world, be- cause he died for the individuals that compose the race. Evangelical faith, then, implies the belief of the truths of the Bible, the apprehension of the truths just named, and a reception of them, and a personal accept- ance and appropriation of Christ to meet the necessities of the individual Boul. 3. Evangelical faith implies an evangelical life. This would not be true if faith were merely an intellectual state or exercise. But since, as we have seen, faith is of the heart, since it consists in the committal of the will to Christ, it follows, by a law of necessity, that the life will cor- respond with the faith. Let this be kept in perpetual remembrance. 4. Evangelical faith implies repentance towards God. Evangelical faith particularly respects Jesus Christ and his salvation. It is an em- bracing of Christ and his salvation. Of course it implies repentance to- wards God, that is, a turning from sin to God. The will cannot be sub- mitted to Christ, it cannot receive him as he is presented in the gospel, while it neglects repentance toward God ; while it rejects the authority of the Father, it cannot embrace and submit to the Son. 5. Disinterested benevolence, or a state of good-will to being, is im- plied in evangelical faith ; for that is the committal of the soul to God and to Christ in all obedience. It must, therefore, imply fellowship or sympathy with him in regard to the great end upon which his heart is set, and for which he lives. A yielding up of the will and the soul to him, must imply the embracing of the same end" that he embraces. 6. It implies a state of the sensibility corresponding to the truths be- lieved. It implies this, because this state of the sensibility is a result of faith by a law of necessity, and this result follows necessarily upon the acceptance of Christ and his gospel by the heart. 7. Of course it implies peace of mind. In Christ the soul finds its full and present salvation. It finds justification, which produces a sense of pardon and acceptance. It finds sanctification, or grace to deliver from the reigning power of sin. It finds all its wants met, and all needed grace proffered for its assistance. It sees no cause for disturbance, noth- ing to ask or desire that is uot treasured up in Christ. It has ceased to FAITH AND UNBELIEF. 377 war with God — ^with itself. It has found its resting-place in Christ, and rests in profound peace under the shadow of the, Almighty, 8. It must imply the existence iu the soul of every virtue, because it is a yielding up of the whole being to the will of God. Oonsequentlyj all the phases of virtue required by the gospel must be implied as exist- ing, either in a developed or in an undeveloped state, in every heart that truly receives Christ by faith. Certain forms or modifications of virtue may not in all cases have found the occasions of their development, but certain it is, that every modification of virtue will manifest itself as its occasion shall arise, if there be a true and a living faith in Christ. This follows from the very nature of faith. 9. Present evangelical faith implies a state of present sinlessness. Observe, faith is the yielding and committal of the whole will, and of the whole being to Christ. This, and nothing short of this, is evangelical faith. But this comprehends and implies the whole of present, true obedience to Christ. This is the reason why faith is spoken of as the condition, and as it were, the only condition, of salvation. It really implies all virtue. Taith may be contemplated either as a distinct form of virtue, and as an attribute of love, or as comprehensive of all virtue. When contemplated as an attribute of love, it is only a branch of sancti- fication. When contemplated in the wider sense of universal conformity of will to the will of God, it is then synonymous with entire present sanctification. Contemplated in either light, its existence in the heart must be inconsistent with present sin there. Faith is an attitude of the will, and is wholly incompatible with present rebellion of will against Christ. This must be true, or what is faith ? 10. Faith implies the reception and the practice of all known or per- ceived truth. The heart that embraces and receives truth as truth, and because it is truth, must of course receive all known truth. For it is plainly impossible that the will should embrace some truth perceived for a benev- olent reason, and reject other truth perceived. All truth is harmonious. One truth is always consistent with every other truth. The heart that truly embraces one, will, for the same reason, embrace all truth known. If out of regard to the highest good of being, any one revealed truth is truly received, that state of mind continuing, it is impossible that all truth should not be received as soon as known. IV. What unbelief is not. - 1. It is not ignorance of truth. Ignorance is a blank ; it is the negation or absence of knowledge. This certainly cannot be the unbe- lief everywhere represented in the Bible as a heinous sin. Ignorance may be a consequence of unbelief, but cannot be identical with it. We may be ignorant of certain truths as a consequence of rejecting others, bvit this ignorance is not, and, we shall see, cannot be unbelief. 378 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. 2. Unbelief is not the negation or absence of faith. This were a mere nothing — a nonentity. But a mere nothing is not that abominable thing which the scriptures represent as a great and a damning sin. 3. It cannot be a phenomenon of the intellect, or an intellectual scepticism. This state of the intellect may result from the state of mind properly denominated unbelief, but it cannot be identical with it. Intel- lectual doubt or unbelief often results from unbelief properly so called, but unbelief, when contemplated as a sin, should never be confounded with theoretic or intellectual infidelity. They are as entirely distinct aa any two phenomena of mind whatever. 4. It cannot consist in feelings or emotions of incredulity, doubt, or opposition to truth. In other words, unbelief as a sin cannot be a phe- nomenon of the sensibility. The term unbelief is sometimes used to express or designate a state of the intellect, and sometimes of the sensi- bility. It sometimes is used to designate a state of intellectual incredu- lity, doubt, distrust, scepticism. But when used in this sense, moral character is not justly predicable of the state of mind which the term unbelief represents. Sometimes the term expresses a mere feeling of incredulity in regard to truth. But neither has this state of mind moral character ; nor can it have, for the very good reason that it is involuntary. In short, the unbelief that is so sorely denounced in the Bible, as a most aggravated abomination, cannot consist in any involuntary state of mind whatever. V. What unbelief is. The term, as used in the Bible, in those passages that represent it as a sin, must designate a phenomenon of will. It must be a voluntary state of mind. It must be the opposite of evangelical faith. Faith is the will's reception, and unbelief is the will's rejection, of truth. Faith is the soul's confiding in truth and in the God of truth. Unbelief is the soul's withholding confidence from truth and the God of truth. It is the heart's rejection of evidence, and refusal to be influenced by it It is the will in the attitude of opposition to truth perceived, or evidence presented. Intellectual scepticism or unbelief, where light is proffered, always implies the unbelief of the will or heart. For if the mind knows, or supposes, that light may be had, on any question of duty, and does not make honest efforts to obtain it, this can be accounted for only by ascribing it to the will's reluctance to know the path of duty. In this case light is rejected. The mind has light so far as to know that more is proffered, but this proffered light is rejected. This is the sin of unbelief. All infidelity is unbelief in this sense, and infidels are so, not for want of light, but, in general, they have taken much pains to shut their eyes against it. Unbelief must be a voluntary state or attitude FAITH AND UNBELIEF. 379 of the will, as distinguished from a mere volition, or executive act of the will. Volition may, and often does, give forth, through words and deeds, expressions and manifestations of unbelief. But the volition is only a result of unbelief, and not identical with it. Unbelief is a deeper and more eflBcient and more permanent state of mind than mere volition. It is the will in its profoundest opposition to the truth and will of God. VI. Conditions of both faith and unbelief, 1. A revelation in some way to the mind, of the truth and will of God, must be a condition of faith and of unbelief. Be it remembered, that neither faith nor unbelief is consistent with total ignorance. There can be unbelief no further than there is light. 2. In respect to that class of truths which are discerned only upon condition of divine illumination, such illumination must be a condition both of faith and unbelief. It should be remarked, that when a truth has been once revealed by the Holy Spirit to the soul, the continuance of the divine light is not essential to the continuance of unbelief. The truth, once known and lodged in the memory, may continue to be re- sisted, when the agent that revealed it is withdrawn. 3. Intellectual perception is a condition of the heart's unbelief. The intellect must have evidence of truth as the condition of a virtuous belief of it. So the intellect must have evidence of the truth, as a con- dition of a wicked rejection of it. Therefore, intellectual light is the condition, both of the heart's faith and unbelief. By the assertion, that intellectual light is a condition of unbelief is intended, not that the in- tellect should at all times admit the truth in theory ; but that the evi- dence must be such, that by virtue of its own laws, the mind or intellect could justly admit the truth rejected by the heart. It is a very common case, that the unbeliever denies in words, and endeavors to refute in theory, that which he nevertheless assumes as true, in all his practical judgments. VII. The guilt and ill-desert of unbelief. "We have seen, on a former occasion, that the guilt of sin is condition- ated upon, and graduated by, the light under which it is committed. The amount of light is the measure of guilt, in every case of sin. This is true of all sin. But it is peculiarly manifest in the sin of unbelief ; for unbelief is the rejection of light ; it is selfishness in the attitude of re- jecting truth. Of course, the amount of light rejected, and the degree of guilt in rejecting it, are equal. This is everywhere assumed and taught in the Bible, and is plainly the doctrine of reason. The guilt of unbelief under the light of the gospel must be indefl- 380 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. nitely greater, than when merely the light of nature is rejected. The guilt of unbelief, in cases where special divine illumination has been en joyed, must be vastly and incalculably greater, than where the mere light of the gospel has been enjoyed, without a special enlightening of tho Holy Spirit. The guilt of unbelief in one who has been converted, and has known the love of God, must be greater beyond comparison, than that of an ordinary sinner. Those things that are implied in unbelief show that it must be one of the most provoking abominations to God in the universe, lb is the perfection of all that is unreasonable, unjust, ruinous. It is infinitely slanderous and dishonorable to God, and destructive to man, and to all the interests of the kingdom of God. VIII. Natural and govermnental consequences of loth faith and un- belief. By natural consequences are intended consequences that flow from the constitution and laws of mind, by a natural necessity. By govern- mental consequences are intended those that result from the constitution, laws, and administration of moral government. 1. One of the natural consequences of faith is peace of conscience. When the will receives the truth, and yields itself up to conformity with it, the conscience is satisfied with its present attitude, and the man becomes at peace with himself. The soul is then in a state to really respect itself, and can, as it were, behold its own face without a blush. But faith in truth perceived is the unalterable condition of a man's being at peace with himself. A governmental consequence of faith is peace with God : — (1.) la the sense that God is satisfied with the present obedience o: the soul. It is given up to be influenced by all truth, and this is com- prehensive of all duty. Of course God is at peace with the soul, so far as its present obedience is concerned. (2.) Faith governmentally results in peace with God, in the sense ">! being a condition of pardon and acceptance. That is, the penalty of the law for past sins is remitted upon condition of true faith in Christ The soul not only needs present and future obedience, as a necessary condition of peace with self ; but it also needs pardon and acceptance on the part of the government for past sins, as a condition of peace with God. But since the subject of justification or acceptance with God is to coma up as a distinct subject for consideration, I will not enlarge upoi- it here. 2. Self-condemnation is one of the natural consequences of unbelief. Such are the constitution and laws of mind, that it is naturally impossi- |)Je for the mind to justify the heart's rejection of truth. On the con- FAITH AND UNBELIEF. 381 trary, the conscience necessarily condeinns such rejection, and pro- nounces judgment against it. Legal condemnatioti is a necessary governmental consequence of un- belief. No just government can justify the rejection of known truth. But, on the contrary, all just governments must utterly abhor and con- demn the rejection of truths, and especially those truths that relate to the obedience of the subject, and the highest well-being of the rulers and ruled. The government of God must condemn and utterly abhor all unbelief, as a rejection of those truths that are indispensable to the highest well-being of the universe. 3. A holy or obedient life results from faith by a natural or necessary law. Faith is an act of will which controls the life by a law of necessity. It follows of course that, when the heart receives or obeys the truth, the outward life must be conformed to it. 4. A disobedient and unholy life results from unbelief also by a law of necessity. If the heart rejects the truth, of course the life will not be conformed to it. 5. Faith will develop every form of virtue in the heart and life, as their occasions shall arise. It consists in the committing of the will to truth and to the God of truth. Of course as different occasions arise, faith will secure conformity to all truth on all subjects, and then every modification of virtue will exist in the heart, and appear in the life, as circumstances in the providence of God shall develop them. 6. Unbelief may be expected to develop resistance to all truth upon all subjects that conflict with selfishness ; and hence nothing but selfish- ness in some form can restrain its appearing in any other and every other form possible or conceivable. It consists, be it remembered, in the heart's rejection of truth, and of course implies the cleaving to error. The natural result of this must be the development in the heart, and the appearance in the life, of every form of selfishness that is not prevented by some other form. For example, avarice may restrain amativeness, intemperance, and many other forms of selfishness. 7. Faith, governmentally results in obtaining help of God. God may and does gratuitously help those who have no faith. But this is not a governmental result or act in God. But to the obedient he extends his governmental protection and aid. 8. Faith lets God into the soul to dwell and reign there. Faith re- ceives, not only the atonement and mediatorial work of Christ as a redeemer from punishment, but it also receives Christ as king to set up his throne, and reign in the heart. Faith secures to the soul communion with God. 9. Unbelief shuts God out of the soul, in the sense of refusing his reign in the heart. It also shuts the soul out from an interest in Christ's 382 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. mediatorial work. This results not from an arbitrary appointment, but is a natural Consequence. Unbelief shuts the soul out from communion with God. These are hints at some of the natural and governmental consequences of faith and unbelief. They are designed not to exhaust the subject, but merely to call attention to topics which any one who desires may pursue at his pleasure. It should be here remarked, that none of the ways, com- mandments, or appointments of God are arbitrary. Faith is a naturally indispensable condition of salvation, which is the reason of its being made a governmental condition. Unbelief renders salvation naturally impos- sible : it must, therefore, render it governmentally impossible. LECTURE XXXVI. JUSTIFICATION. Ghbist is represented in the gospel as sustaining to men three classefl of relations. 1. Those which are purely governmental. 2. Those which are purely spiritual. 3. Those which unite both these. We shall at present consider him as Christ our justification. I shall show, — I. What gospel justification is not. There is scarcely any question in theology that has been encumbered with more injurious and technical mysticism than that of justification. Justification is the pronouncing of one just. It may be done in words, or, practically, by treatment. Justification must be, in some sense, a governmental act ; and it is of importance to a right understanding of gospel justification, to inquire whether it be an act of the judicial, the executive, or the legislative department of government ; that is, whether gospel justification consists in a strictly judicial or forensic proceeding, or whether it consists in pardon, or setting aside the execution of an in- curred penalty, and is therefore properly either an executive or a legis- lative act. We shall see that the settling of this question is of great im- portance in theology ; and as we view this subject, so, if consistent, we must view many important and highly practical questions in theology. This leads me to say, — That gospel justification is not to be regarded as a forensic or judicial proceeding. Dr. Chalmers and those of his school hold that it is. But JUSTIFICATION. 383 this is certainly a great mistake, as wo shall see. The term forensic is from, forum, "a court." A forensic proceeding belongs to the judicial department of government, whose business it is to ascertain the facts and declare the sentence of the law. This department has no power over the law, but to pronounce judgment, in accordance with its true spirit and meaning. Courts never pardon, or set aside the execution of penalties. This does not belong to them, but either to the executive or to the law- Making department. Oftentimes, this power in human governments is lodged in the head of the executive department, who is, generally at least, a branch of the legislative power of government. But never is the power to pardon exercised by the judicial department. The ground of a judicial or forensic justification invariably is, and must be, universal obedience to law. If but one crime or breach of law is alleged and proved, the court must inevitably condemn, and can in no such case justify, or pronounce the convicted just. Gospel justification is the justification of sinners ; it is, therefore, naturally impossible, and a most palpable con- tradiction, to aflBrm that the justification of a sinner, or of one who has violated the law, is a forensic or judicial justification. That only is or can be a legal or forensic justification, that proceeds upon the ground of its appearing that the justified person is guiltless, or, in other words, that he has not violated the law, that he has done only what he had a legal right to do. Now it is certainly nonsense to afiirm, that a sinnet can be pronounced just in the eye of law ; that he can be justified by deeds of law, or by the law at all. The law condemns him. But to be justified judicially or forensically, is to be pronounced just in the judgment of law. This certainly is an impossibility in respect to sinners. The Bible is as express as possible on this point. Eomans iii. 30, — " Therefore by the deeds of the law there shall no flesh be justified in his sight : for by the law is the knowledge of sin." It is proper to say here, that Dr. Chalmers and those of his school do not intend that sinners are justified by their own obedience to law, but by the perfect and imputed obedience of Jesus Christ. They maintain that, by reason of the obedience to law which Christ rendered when on earth, being set down to the credit of elect sinners, and imputed to them, the law regards them as having rendered perfect obedience in him, or regards them as having perfectly obeyed by proxy, and therefore pro- nounces them just, upon condition of faith in Christ. This they insist is properly a forensic or judicial justification. But this subject will come up more appropriately under another head, IL What is gospel justification ? It consists not in the law pronouncing the sinner just, but in his be- ing ultimately governmentally treated as if he were just ; that is, it cor.- 384 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. sists in a governmental decree of pardon or amnesty — in arresting and setting aside the execution of the incurred penalty of law — ^in pardoning and restoring to favor those who have sinned, and those whom the law had pronounced guilty, and upon whom it had passed the sentence of eternal death, and rewarding them as if they had been righteous. In proof of this position, I remark, — 1. That this is most unequivocally taught in the Old Testament scrip- tures. The whole system of sacrifices taught the doctrine of pardon upon the conditions of atonement, repentance, and faith. This, under the old dispensation, is constantly represented as a merciful acceptance of the penitents, and never as a forensic or judicial acquittal or justifica- tion of them. The mercy-seat covered the law in the ark of the cove- nant. Paul informs us what justification was in the sense in which the Old Testament saints understood it, in Kom. iv. 6-8 : — " Even also as David describeth the blessedness of the man to whom God imputeth righteousness without works, saying. Blessed are they whose iniquities are forgiven, and whose sins are covered. Blessed is the man to whom the Lord will not impute sin." This quotation from David shows both what David and what Paul understood by justification, to wit, the pardon and acceptance of the penitent sinner. 2. The Xew Testament fully justifies and establishes this view of the subject, as we shall abundantly see under another head. 3. Sinners cannot possibly be just in any other sense. Upon certain conditions they may be pardoned and treated as just But for sinners to be forensically pronounced just, is impossible and absurd. III. Conditions of justification. In this discussion I use the term condition in the sense of a sine qud non, a " not without which." This is its philosophical sense. A con- dition as distinct from a ground of justification, is anything without which sinners cannot be justified, which, nevertheless, is not the procur- ing cause or fundamental reason of their justification. As we shall see, there are many conditions, while there is but one ground, of the justifi- cation of sinners. The application and importance of this distinction we shall perceive as we proceed. As has been already said, there can be no justification in a legal or forensic sense, but upon the ground of universal, perfect, and uninter- rupted obedience to law. This is of course denied by those who hold that gospel justification, or the justification of penitent sinners, is of the nature of a forensic or judicial justification. They hold to the legal maxim, that what a man does by another he does by himself, and there- fore the law regards Christ's obedience as ours, on the ground that he obeyed for us. To this I reply, — JtrSTIplCATlON. 385 1. The legal maxim just repeated does not apply, except in cases where one acts in behalf of another by his own appointment, which was not the case with the obedience of Christ ; and, — 2. The doctrine of an imputed righteousness, or that Christ's obedi- ence to the law was accounted as our obedience, is founded on a most false and nonsensical assumption ; to wit, that Christ owed no obedience to the law in his own person, and that therefore his obedience was alto- gether a work of supererogation, and might be made a substitute for our own obedience ; that it might be set down to our credit, because he did not need to obey for himself. I must here remark, that Justification respects the moral law; and that it must be intended that Christ owed no obedience to the moral law, and therefore his obedience to this law, being wholly a work of superero- gation, is set down to our account as the ground of our justification upon condition of faith in him. But surely this is an obvious mistake. We have seen, that the spirit of the moral law requires good-will to God and the universe. Was Christ under no obligation to do this ? Nay, was he not rather under infinite obligation to be perfectly benevolent ? Was it possible for him to be more benevolent than the law requires God and all beings to be? Did he not owe entire consecration of heart and life to the highest good of universal being? If not, then benevolence in him were no virtue, for it would not be a compliance with moral obligation. It was naturally impossible for him, and is naturally impossible for any being, to perform a work of supererogation; that is, to be more benevo- lent than the moral law requires him to be. This is and must be as true of God as it is of any other being. Would not Christ have sinned had he not been perfectly benevolent ? If he would, it follows that he owed obe- dience to the law, as really as any other being. Indeed, a being that owed no obedience to the moral law must be whoUy incapable of virtue, for what is virtue but obedience to the moral law? But if Christ owed personal obedience to the moral law, then his obe- dience could no more than justify himself. It can never be imputed to us. He was bound for himself to love God with all his heart, and soul, and mind, and strength, and his neighbor as himself. He did no more than this. He could do no more. It was naturally impossible, then, for him to obey in our behalf. There are, however, valid grounds and valid conditions of justification. 1. The vicarious suffering or atonement of Christ is a condition of Justification, or of the pardon and acceptance of penitent sinners. It has been common either to confound the conditions with the ground of jus- tification, or purposely to represent the atonement and work of Christ aa the ground, as distinct from and opposed to a condition of justification. In treating this subject, I find it important to distinguish between the 25 ^80 S-^STfiMATlc TfiEoLo&lf. ground and conditiois of justification and to regard the atonement and work of Christ not as a ground, but only as a condition of gospel justifi- cation. By the ground I mean the moving, procuring cause ; that in which the plan of redemption originated as its source, and which was the fundamental reason or ground of the whole movement. This was the benevolence and merciful disposition of the whole Godhead, Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. This love made the atonement, but the atonement did not beget this love. The Godhead desired to save sinners, but could not safely do so without^fianger to the universe, unless something was done to satisfy public, not retributive justice. The atonement was resorted to as a means of reconciling forgiveness with the wholesome administration of justice. A merciful disposition in the Godhead was the source, ground, mainspring, of the whole movement, while the atonement was only a con- dition or means, or that without which the love of God could not safely manifest itself in justifying and saving sinners. Failing to make this distinction, and representing the atonement as the ground of the sinner's justification, has been a sad occasion of stum- bling to many. Indeed, the whole questions of the nature, design, extent, and bearings of the atonement turn upon, and are involved in, this dis- tinction. Some represent the atonement as not demanded by, nor as proceeding from the love or merciful disposition, but from the inexora- ble wrath of the Father, leaving the impression that Christ was more merciful, and more the friend of sinners than the Father. Many have received this impression from pulpit ^rnd written representations, as I well know. Others, regarding the atonement as the ground as opposed to a con- dition of justification, have held the atonement to be the literal payment of the debt of sinners, and of the nature of a commercial transaction : a quid pro quo, a valuable consideration paid down by Christ, by suffering the same amount as was deserved by the whole number of the elect ; thus negativing the idea of a merciful disposition in the Father, and repre- senting him as demanding pay for discharging and saving sinners. Some of this class have held, that since Christ has died, the elect sinner has a right to demand his justification, on the ground of justice, that he may present the atonement and work of Christ, and say to the Father, " Here is the price ; I demand the commodity." This class, of course, must hold to the limited nature of the atonement, or be universalists. While others again, assuming that the atonement was the ground of justification in the sense of the literal payment of the debt of sinners, and that the scriptures represent the atonement as made for all men, have very consistently become universalists. Otheij again have given up, or never held the view that the atonement was of the nature of the literal payment of a debt, and hold that it was g JOSTrt'IdA'TION. 38? governmental expedient td reconcile the pardon of sin with a wholesome administration of justice : that it was snfiflcient for all as for a part of mankind : that it does not entitle those for whom it was made to a par- don on the score of justice, but that men are justified freely by grace through the redemption that is in Christ Jesus, and yet they inconsis- tently persist in representing the atonement as the ground, and not merely as a condition of justification. Those who hold that the atonement and obedience of Christ were and are the ground of the justification of sinners, in the sense of the pay- ment of their debt, regard all the grace in the transaction as consisting in the atonement and obedience of Christ, and exclude grace from the act of justification. Justification they regard as a forensic act. I regard the atonement of Christ as the necessary condition of safely manifesting the benevolence of God in the justification and salvation of sinners. A merciful disposition in the whole Godhead was the ground, and the atonement a condition of justification. Mercy would have saved without au atonement, had it been possible to do so. That Christ's sufEerings, and especially his death, were vicarious, has been abundantly shown in treating the subject of atonement. I need not repeat here what I said there. Although Christ owed perfect obe- dience to the moral law for himself, and could not therefore obey as our substitute, yet since he perfectly obeyed, he owed no suffering to the law or to the Divine government on his own account. He could therefore suffer for us. That is, he could, to answer governmental purposes, sub- stitute-his death for the itffliction of the penalty of the law on us. He could not perform works of supererogation, but he could endure sufEer- ings of supererogation, in the sense that he did not owe them for him- self. The doctrine of substitution, in the sense just named, appears everywhere in both Testaments. It is the leading idea, the prominent thought, lying upon the face of the whole scriptures. Let the few pas- sages that follow serve as specimens of the class that teach this doctrine ; Lev. xvii. 11. " For the life of the flesh is in the blood ; and I have given it to you upon the altar, to make an atonement for your souls ; for it is the blood that maketh an atonement for the soul." Isa. liii. 5, 6, 11. " But he was wounded for our transgressions, he was bruised for our iniquities ; the chastisement of our peace was upon him, and with his stripes we are healed. All we like sheep have gone astray ; we have turned every one to his own way, and the Lord hath laid on him the iniquity of us all. He shall see of the travail of his soul, and shall be satisfied ; by his knowledge shall my righteous servant jus- tify many ; for he shall bear their iniquities." Matt. XX. 18. "Even as the Son of man came not to be ministered nuto, but to minister, and to give his life a ransom for mauy," 388 SYSTEMATIC THteoLOGtir. Matt, xxvl 38. " For this is my blood of the New Testament, which is shed for many for the remission of sins." John iii. 14. " And as Moses lifted up the serpent in the wilderness, even so must the Son of man be lifted up : 15. That whosoever be- lieveth in him should not perish, but have eternal life." John vi. 51. " I am the living bread which came down from heaven ; if any man eat of this bread, he shall live for ever ; and the bread that I will give is my flesh, which I will give for the life of the world." Acts XX. 28. " Take heed therefore unto yourselves, and to all the flock over the which the Holy Ghost hath made you overseers, to feed the churcli of God,, which he hath purchased with his own blood." Eom. iii. 34. " Being justified freely by his grace, through the re- demption that is in Christ Jesus. 35. Whom God hath set forth to be a propitiation, through faith in his blood, to declare his righteousness for the remission of sins that are past, through the forbearance of God. 26. To declare, I say at this time his righteousness ; that he might be just, and the justifier of him which believeth in Jesus." Eom. V. 6. " For when we were yet without strength, in due time Christ died for the ungodly. 7. For scarcely for a righteous man will one die ; yet peradventure for a good man some would even dare to die. 8. But God commendeth his love toward us, in that while we were yet sinners, Christ died for us. 9. Being now justified by his blood, we shall be saved from wrath through him. 11. And not only so, but we also joy in God, through our Lord Jesus Christ, by whom we have now received the atonement. 18. Therefore, as by the offence of one judg- ment came upon all men to condemnation, even so by the righteousness of one the free gift came upon all men unto justification of life. 19. For as by one man's disobedience many were made sinners, so by the obe- dience of one shall many be made righteous." 1 Cor. V. 7. "For even Christ our passover is sacrificed for us." 1 Cor. XV. 3. " Christ died for our sins according to the scriptures." Gal. iii. 13. " Christ hath redeemed us from the curse of the law, being made a curse for us ; for it is written. Cursed is every one that hangeth on a tree. 14. That the blessing of Abraham might come on the Gentiles through Jesus Christ ; that we might receive the promise of the Spirit through faith." Eph. ii. 13. " But now, in Christ Jesus, ye who sometimes were far off, are made nigh by the blood of Christ." Heb. ix. 13. "Neither by the blood of goats and calves, but by his own blood, he entered in once into the holy place, having obtainet. eternal redemption for us. 13. For if the blood of bulls and of goata and the ashes of an heifer sprinkling the unclean, sanctifieth to the pur fying of the flesh ; 14. How much more shall the blood of Christ, who JUSTIFICATION. 389 throngh the eternal Spirit offered himself without spot to God, purge your coascience from dead works to serve the living God ? 33. And almost all things are by the law purged with blood ; and without shed- ding of blood is no remission. 23. It was therefore necessary that the patterns of things in the heavens should be purified with these ; but the heavenly things themselves with better sacrifices than these. 34. For Christ is not entered into the holy places made with hands, which are the figures of the true : but into heaven itself, now to appear in the presence of God for us ; 25. Nor yet that he should offer himself often, as the high priest entereth into the holy place every year with blood of others ; 36. For then must he often have suffered since the foundation of the world ; but now once in the end of the world hath he appeared to put away sin by the sacrifice of himself. 27. And as it is appointed unto men once to die, but after this the judgment ; 38. So Christ was once offered to bear the sins of many." 1 Pet. i. 18. " Forasmuch as ye know that ye were not redeemed vith corruptible things, as silver and gold, from your vain conversation i«ceived by tradition from your fathers : 19. But with the precious blood of Christ." 1 Pet. ii. 24. " Who his own self bare our sins in his own body on the tree, that we being dead to sins, should live unto righteousness ; by whose stripes ye are healed." 1 John i. 7. " But if we walk in the light, we have fellowship one with another, and the blood of Jesus Christ his Son cleanseth us from all sin." 1 John iv. 9. " In this was manifested the love of God toward us, because that God sent his only-begotten Son into the world, that we might live through him. 10. Herein is love, not that we loved God, but that he loved us, and sent his Son to be the propitiation for our sins." These and many such like passages establish the fact beyond question, that the vicarious atonement of Christ is a condition of our pardon and acceptance with God. 2. Eepentance is also a condition of our justification. Observe, I liere also use the term condition, in the sense of a " not without which," and not in the sense of &" that for the sake of which" tha sam&v is justified. It must be certain that the government of God cannot pardon Bin without repentance. This is as truly a doctrine of natural as of revealed religion. It is self-evident that, until the sinner breaks off from sins by repentance or turning to God, he cannot be justified in any sense. This is everywhere assumed, implied, and taught in the Bible. No reader of the Bible can call this in question, and it were a useless occupation of time to qiiote more passages. 8.. Faith in Christ is, in the same sense, another condition of justifi- SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. cation. We have already examined into the nature and necessity of faith. I fear that there has been much of error in the conceptions of many upon this subject. They have talked of justification by faith, as if they supposed that, by an arbitrary appointment of God, faith was the condition, and the only condition of justification. This seems to be the antinomian view. The class of persons alluded to speak of justification by faith ; as if it were by faith, and not by Christ through faith, that the penitent sinner is justified ; as if faith, and not Christ, were our justification. They seem to regard faith not as a natural, but merely as a mystical condition of justification ; as bringing us into a covenant and mystical relation to Christ, in consequence of which his righteousness or personal obedience is imputed to us. It should never be forgotten that the faith that is the condition of justification, is the faith that works by love. It is the faith through and by which Christ sanctifies the soul. A sanctifying faith unites the believer to Christ as his justification ; but be it always remembered, that no faith receives Christ as a justification, that does not receive him as a sanctification, to reign within the heart. We have seen that repentance, as well as faith, is a condition of justification. We shall see that perseverance in obedience to the end of life is also a condition of justification. Faith is often spoken of in scripture as if it were the sole condition of salva- tion, because, as we have seen, from its very nature it implies repentance and every virtue. That faith is a naturally necessary condition of justification, we have seen. Let the following passages of scripture serve as examples of the manner in which the scriptures speak upon this subject. Mark xiv. 15. '-'And he said unto them. Go ye into all the world, and preach the gospel to every creature. 16. He that believeth and is baptized, shall be saved ; but he that believeth not, shall be damned." John i. 12. " As many as received him, to them gave he power to become the sons of God, even to them that believe on his name." John iii. 16. "For God so loved the world, that he gave his only- begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him should not perish, but have everlasting life. 36. He that believeth on the Son hath everlast- ing life ; and he that believeth not the Son shall not see life, but the wrath of God abideth on him." John vi. 38. " Then said they unto him. What shall we do, that we might work the works of God ? 29. Jesus answered and said unto them, This is the work of God, that ye believe on him whom he hath sent. 40. This is the will of him that sent me, that every one which seeth the Son, and believeth on him, may have everlasting life ; and I will raise him up at the last day." * John viii. 24. " If ye believe not that I am he, ye shall die in youi JUSTIFICATION. 391 Bins. 44. Ye ai-e of your father the idevil, and the lusts of your fathet . ye -will do ; he was a murderer from the beginning, and abode not in the truth ; because there is no truth in him. 47. He that is of God, heareth God's words ; ye therefore hear them not, because ye are not of God." John xi. 25. "Jesus said unto her, I am the resurrection and the life ; he that believeth in me, though he were dead, yet shall he live ; 26. And whosoever liveth, and believeth in me, shall never die." Acts X. 43. " To him give all the prophets witness, that through his name, whosoever believeth in him shall receive remission of sins." Acts xvi. 31. "Believe on the Lord Jesus Christ, and thou shalt be saved, and thy house." Eom. iv. 5. " But to him that worketh not, but believeth on him that justifieth the ungodly, his faith is counted for righteousness." Eom. X. 4. " For Christ is the end of the law for righteousness to every one that believeth." Gal. ii. 16. " Knowing that a man is not justified by the works of the law, but by the faith of Jesus Christ, even we have believed in Jesus Christ, that we might be justified by the faith of Christ, and not by the works of the law ; for by the works of the law shall no flesh be justi fied." Heb. ii. 6. " Without faith it is impossible to please him ; for he that Cometh to God must believe that he is, and that he is a rewarder of them that diligently seek him." 1 John V. 10. " He that believeth on the Son of God hath the witness in himself ; he that believeth not God hath made him a liar, because he believeth not the record that God gave of his Son. 11. And this is the record, that God hath given to us eternal life ; and this life is in his Son. 12. He that hath the Son hath life ; and he that hath not the Son of God, hath not life. 13. These things have I written unto you that be- lieve on the name of the Son of God ; that ye may know that ye have eternal life, and that ye may believe on the name of the Son of God." 4. Present sanctification, in the sense of present full consecration to God, is another condition, not ground, of justification. Some theologians have made justification a condition of sanctification, instead of making sanctification a condition of justification. But this we shall see is an erroneous view of the subject. The mistake is founded in a misapprehen- sion of the nature both of justification and of sanctification. To sanctify is to set apart, to consecrate to a particular use. To sanctify anything to God is to set apart to his service, to consecrate it to him. To sanctify one's self is voluntarily to set one's self apart, to consecrate one's self to God. To be sanctified is to be set apart, to be consecrated to God. Sanctification is an act or state of being sanctified, or set apart to the service of God. It is a state of consecration to him. This is present 392 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. obedience to the moral law. It is the whole of present duty, and is im- plied in repentance, faith, regeneration, as we have abundantly seen. Sanctlflcation is sometimes used to express a permanent state of obedience to God, or of consecration. In this sense it is not a condition of present justification, or of pardon and acceptance. But it is a condition of con- tinued and permanent acceptance with God. It certainly cannot be true, that God accepts and justifies the sinner in his sins. The Bible every- where represents justified persons as sanctified, and always expressly, or impliedly, conditionates justification upon sanctification, in the sense of present obedience to God. 1 Cor. vi. 11 ; "And such were some of you : but ye are washed, but ye are sanctified, but ye are justified, in the name of the Lord Jesus, and by the Spirit of our God." This is but a specimen of the manner in which justified persons are spoken of in the Bible. Also, Eom. viii. 1 ; "There is therefore now no condemnation to them which are in Christ Jesus, who walk not after the flesh, but after the Spirit." They only are justified who walk after the Spirit. Should it be objected, as it may be, that the scripture often speaks of saints, or truly regenerate persons, as needing sanctification, and of sanctification as something that comes after regeneration, and as that which the saints are to aim at attaining, I answer, that when sanctification is thus spoken of, it is doubtless used in the higher sense already noticed ; to wit, to denote a state of being settled, established in faith, rooted and grounded in love, being so confirmed in the faith and obedience of the gospel, as to hold on in the way steadfastly, unmovably, always abounding in the work of the Lord. This is doubtless a condition of permanent justifica- tion, as has been said, but not a condition of present justification. By sanctification being a condition of justification, the following things are intended : (1.) That present, full, and entire consecration of heart and life to God and his service, is an unalterable condition of present pardon of past sin, and of present acceptance with God. (2.) That the penitent soul remains justified no longer than this full- hearted consecration continues. If he falls from his first love into the spirit of self-pleasing, he falls again into bondage to sin and to the law, is condemned, and must repent and do his " first work," must return to Christ, and renew his faith and love, as a condition of his salvation. This is the most express teaching of the Bible, as we shall fully see. 5. Perseverance in faith and obedience, or in consecration to God, is also an unalterable condition of justification, or of pardon and acceptance with God. By this language in this connection, you will of course un- derstand me to mean, that perseverance in faith and obedience is a con- dition, not of present, but of final or ultimate acceptance and salvation. Those who hold that justification by imputed righteousness is a foren- JUSTIFICATION. 393 Bic pi'oceeding, take a view of final or ultimate justification, according with their view of the nature of the transaction. With them, faith re- ceives an imputed righteousness, and a judicial justification. The first act of faith, according to them, introduces the sinner into this relation, and obtains for him a perpetual justification. They maintain that after this first act of faith it is impossible for the sinner to come into condem- nation ; that, being once justified, he is always thereafter justified, what- ever he may do ; indeed that he is never justified by grace, as to sins that are past, upon condition that he ceases to sin ; that Christ's righteousness is the ground, and that his own present obedience is not even a condition of his justification, so that, in fact, his own present or future obedience to the law of God is, in no case, and in no sense, a sine qud non of his justification, present or ultimate. Now this is certainly another gospel from the one I am inculcating. It is not a difference merely upon some speculative or theoretic point. It is a point fundamental to the gospel and to salvation, if any one can be. Let us therefore see which of these is the true gospel. I object to this view of justification : — 1. That it is antinomianism. Observe, they hold that upon the first exercise of faith, the soul enters into such a relation to Christ, that with respect to it the penalty of the divine law is for ever set aside, not only as it respects all past, but also as it respects all future acts of disobedience; BO that sin does not thereafter bring the soul under the condemning sen- tence of the law of God. But a precept without a penalty is no law. Therefore, if the penalty is in their case permanently set aside or repealed, this is, and must be, a virtual repeal of the precept, for without a penalty it is only counsel, or advice, and no law. 2. But again : it is impossible that this view of justification should be true ; for the moral law did not originate in the arbitrary will of God, and he cannot abrogate it either as to its precept or its penalty. He may for good and sufiBcient reasons dispense in certain cases with the execu- tion of the penalty. But set it aside in such a sease, that sin would not incur it, or that the soul that sins shall not be condemned by it, he can- not — it is naturally impossible ! The law is as unalterable and unre- pealable, both as to its precept and its penalty, as the nature of God. It cannot but be, in the very nature of things, that sin in any being, in any world, and at any time, will and must incur the penalty of the moral law. God may pardon as often as the soul sins, repents and believes, but to prevent real condemnation where there is sin, is not at the option of any being. 3. But again ; I object to the view of justification in question, that it is of course inconsistent with forgiveness or pardon. If justified by imputed righteousness, why pai'don him whom the law accounts as 394 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOOr. already and perpetually, and perfectly righteous ? Certainly it wera absurd and impossible for the law and the law-giver judicially to justify a person on the ground of the perfect obedience of his substitute, and at the same time pardon him who is thus regarded as perfectly righteous. Especially must this be true of all sin committed subsequently to the first and justifying act of faith. If when once the soul has believed, it can no more come into condemnation, it certainly can no more be for- given. Forgiveness implies previous condemnation, and consists iu setting aside the execution of an incurred penalty. 4. If the view of justification I am opposing be true, it is altogether out of place for one who has once believed, to ask for the pardon of sin. It is a downright insult to God, and apostacy from Christ. It amounts according to their view of justification, to a denial of perpetual justifica- tion by imputed righteousness, and to an acknowledgment of being con- demned. It must therefore imply a falling from grace, to pray for pardon after the soul has once believed. 5. But this view of justification is at war with the whole Bible. This everywhere represents Christians as condemned when they sin — teaches them to repent, confess, and pray for pardon — to betake themselves afresh to Christ as their only hope. The Bible, in almost every variety or manner, represents perseverance in faith, and obedience to the end, as a condition of ultimate justification and final salvation. Let the follow- ing passages serve as examples of the manner in which the Bible repre- sents this subject : — Ezek. xviii. 24. " But when the righteous turneth away from his righteousness, and committeth iniquity, and doeth according to all the abominations that the wicked man doeth, shall he live ? All his right- eousness that he hath done shall not be mentioned ; in his trespass that he hath trespassed, and in his sin that he hath sinned, in them shall he die." Ezek. xxxiii. 13. " When I shall say to the righteous, that he shall surely live ; if he trust to his own righteousness, and commit iniquity, all his righteousness shall not be remembered ; but for his iniquity that he hath committed, he shall die for it." Matt. X. 23. " And ye shall be hated of all men for my name's sake ; but he that endureth to the end shall be saved." [Matt. xxiv. 13.] 1 Cor. ix. 27. " But I keep under my body, and bring it into sub- jection ; lest that by any means when I have preached to others, I myse. ehould be a castaway." 1 Cor. X. 12. " Wherefore let him that thinketh he standeth, take heed lest he fall." 2 Cor. vi. 1. " We then, as workers together with hinj, beseech you ftlso tbat ye receive pot the grace of God in vain," JUSTIFICATION. 395 IfCiI. i. JJ3. " If ye contiuue in the faith gronuded and settled, and 'it tot moved away from the hope of the gospel, which ye have heard, and which was preached to every creature which is under heaven ; where- of I Paul am made a minister." Heb. iv. 1. " Let us therefore fear, lest a promise being left us of ntering into his rest, any of you should seem to come short of it. 11. Let us labor therefore to enter into that rest, lest any man fall after the 'jame example of unbelief." 2 Pet. i. 10. " Wherefore the rather, brethren, give diligence to make your calling and election sure; for if ye do these things, ye shall never fall." Eev. ii. 10. " Fear none of those things which thou shalt suffer. Behold, the devil shall cast some of you into prison, that ye may be tried ; and ye shall have tribulation ten days. Be thou faithful unto death, and I will give thee a crown of life. 11. He that hath an ear, let him hear what the Spirit saith unto the churches ; He that overcom- eth, shall not be hurt of the second death. 17. To him that overcometh will I give to eat of the hidden manna, and will give him a white stone, and in the stone a new name written, which no man knoweth, saving he that receiveth it. 26. And he that overcometh, and keepeth my words unto the end, to him will I give power over the nations ; 27. And he shall rule them with a rod of iron ; as the vessels of a potter shall they be broken to shivers ; even as I received of my Father." Observe, I am not here calling in question the fact, that all truo saints do persevere in faith and obedience to the end ; but am showing that such perseverance is a condition of salvation, or ultimate justifica- tion. The subject of the perseverance of the saints will come under consideration in its proper place. 6. The view of justification which I am opposing is contradicted by the consciousness of the saints. I think I may safely aflBrm that the saints in all time are very conscious of condemnation when they fall into sin. This sense of condemnation may not subject them to the same kind and degree of fear which they experienced before regeneration, because of the confidence they have that God will pardon their sin. Nevertheless, until they repent, and by a renewed act of faith lay hold on pardon and fresh justification, their remorse, shame, and conscious- ness of condemnation, do in fact, if I am not much deceived, greatly exceed, as a general thing, the remorse, shame, and sense of condemna- tion experienced by the impenitent. But if it be true, that the first act of faith brings the soul into a state of perpetual justification, so that it cannot fall into condemnation thereafter, do what it will, the experi- ence of the saints contradicts facts, or, more strictly, their consciousness of condemnation is a delusion. They are not in fact condemned by the moral J*w as they conceive themselves to be. 896 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOait. 1. If I understand the framers of the Westminster Confession oS Faith, they regarded justification as a state resulting from the relation of Bn adopted child of God, which state is entered into by faith alone, and held that justification is not conditionated upon obedience for the time being, but that a person in this state may, as they hold that all in this life in fact do, sin daily, and even continually, yet without con- demnation by the law, their sin bringing them only under his fatherly displeasure, and subjecting them to the necessity of repentance, as a condition of his fatherly favor, but not as a condition of pardon or of ultimate salvation. They seem to have regarded the child of God as no longer under moral government, in such a sense that sin was imputed M him, this having been imputed to Christ, and Christ's righteousness so literally imputed to him that, do what he may, after the first act of iiulh he is accounted and treated in his person as wholly righteous. If this a not antinomianism, I know not what is ; since they hold that all who once believe will certainly be saved, yet that their perseverance in ho'y obedience to the end is, in no case, a condition of final justification, but that this is conditionated upon the first act of faith alone. They support their positions with quotations from scripture about as much in point as is common for them. They often rely on proof-texts that, in their meaning and spirit, have not the remotest allusion to the point in support of which they are quoted. I have tried to understand the subject of justification as it is taught in the Bible, without going into labored speculations or to theological technicalities. If I have succeeded in understanding it, the following is a succinct and a true account of the matter : The Godhead, in the exercise of his adorable love and compassion, sought the salvation of sinners, through and by means of the media- torial death and work of Christ. This death and work of Christ were resorted to, not to create, but, as a result of, the merciful disposition of God and as a means of securing the universe against a misapprehen- sion of the character and design of God in forgiving and saving sinners. To Christ, as Mediator between the Godhead and man, the work of justifying and saving sinners is committed. He is made unto sinners " wisdom, righteousness, sanctification, and redemption." In considera- tion of Christ's having by his death for sinners secured the subjects of the divine government against a misconception of his character and designs, God does, upon the further conditions of a repentance and faith that imply a renunciation of their rebellion and a return to obedience to his laws, freely pardon past sin, and restore the penitent and believing sinner to favor, as if he had not sinned, while he remains penitent and believing, subject however to condemnation and eternal death, unless he holds the beginning of his confidence steadfast unto the JUSTIFICATION. 397 end. The doctrine of a literal imputation of Adam's sin to all his pos- terity, of the literal imputation of all the sins of the elect to Christ, and of his suffering for them the exact amount due to the transgiiBssors, of the literal imputation, of Christ's righteousness or obedience to tlfe elect, and the consequent perpetual justification of all that are converted from the first exercise of faith, whatever their subsequent life may be — I say I regard these dogmas as fabulous, and better befitting a romance than a system of theology. But it is said, that the Bible speaks of the righteousness of faith. " What shall we say then ? That the Gentiles, which followed not aftei righteousness, have attained to righteousness, even the righteousness which is of faith." — Eom. ix. 30. "And be found in him, not having mine own righteousness, which is of the law, but that which is through the faith of Christ, the righteousness which is of God by faith." — Phil, iii. 9. These and similar passages are relied upon, as teaching the doc- trine of an imputed righteousness ; and such as these : " The Lord our righteousness ;" " Surely, shall one say, in the Lord have I righteousness and strength." By "the Lord our righteousness," we may understand, either that we are Justified, that is, that our sins are atoned for, and that we are pardoned and accepted by, or on account of the Lord, that is Jesus Christ ; or we may understand that the Lord makes us righteous, that is, that he is our sanctiflcation, or working in us to will and to do of his good pleasure ; or both, that is, he atones for our sins, brings us to repentance and faith, works sanctiflcation or righteousness in us, and then pardons our past sins, and accepts us. By the righteousness of faith, or of God by faith, I understand the method of making smners holy, and of securing their justification or acceptance by faith, as op- posed to mere works of law or self-righteousness. Dihaiosune, rendered righteousness, may be with equal propriety, and often is, rendered justi fication. So undoubtedly it should be rendered in 1 Cor. i. 30. " But of him are ye in Christ Jesus, who of God is made unto us wisdom, and righteousness, and sanctification, and redemption." The meaning here doubtless is, that he is the author and finisher of that scheme of redemp- tion, whereby we are justified by faith, as opposed to justification by our own works. " Christ our righteousness " is Christ the author or pro- curer of our justification. But this does not imply that he procures o\\l- justification by imputing his obedience to us. The doctrine of a literal imputation of Christ's obedience or right- eousness is supported by those who hold it, by such passages as the fol- lowing : Rom. IV. 5-8. " But to him that worketh not, but believeth on him that justifieth the ungodly, his faith is counted for righteousness. Even as David also describeth the blessedness of the man, unto whom God imputeth righteousness without works, saying. Blessed aj.e they whose 398 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. iniquities are forgiven, and whose sins are covered. Blessed is the tnaii to whom the Lord will not impute sin." But here justification is represented only as consisting in forgiveness of sin, or in pardon and acceptance. Again,. 2 Cor. v. 19, 31. "To wit, that God was in Christ, reconciling the world unto himself, not imputing their trespasses unto them ; and hath committed unto us the word of reconciliation. For he hath made him to be sin for us who knew no sin ; that we might be made the Righteousness of God in him." Here again the apostle is teaching only his much loved doctrine of justification by faith, in the sense that upon condition or in consideration of the death and mediatorial interference and work of Christ, penitent believers in Christ are forgiven and rewarded as ii laey were righteous. IV. Foundation of the justification of penitent believers in Christ What is the ultimate ground or reason of their justification ? 1. It is not founded in Christ's literally suffering the exact penalty of the law for them, and in this sense literally purchasing their justification and eternal salvation. The Westminster Confession of Faith affirms as follows : chapter on Justification section 3 — " Christ by his obedience and death, did fully discharge the debt of all those that are thus justified, and did make a proper, real, and full satisfaction to his Father's justice in their behalf. Yet, inasmuch as he was given by the Father for them, and his obedience and satisfaction accepted in their stead, and both freely, not for anything in them, their justification is only of free grace, that both the exact justice and rich grace of God might be glorified in the justification of sinners." If the framers of this confession had made the distinction between the grounds and conditions of justification, so as to represent the gracious disposition that gave the Son, and that accepted his obedience and satisfaction in their stead, as the ground or moving cause, and the death and work of Christ as a condition or a means, as '•' that without which " the benevolence of God could not wisely justify sinners, their iitatement had been much improved. As it stands, the transaction is represented as a proper quid pro quo, a proper full payment of the debt of the justified. All the grace con- sisted in giving his Son, and consenting to the substitution. But they deny that there is grace in the act of justification itself. This proceeds upon the ground of "exact justice." There is then according to this, no grace in the act of pardon and accepting the sinner as righteous. This is " exact justice," because the debt is fully cancelled by Christ. Indeed, " Christian, what do you think of this ?" God has, in the act of giving his Son and in consenting to the substitution, exercised all the grace he ever will. Now your forgiveness and justification are, accord- ing to this teaching, placed on the ground of "exact justice." You have JUSTIFICATION. 399 now onlj to believe and demand "exact justice." One act of faith places vour salvation on the ground of " exact justice." Talk no more of the j,Tace of God in forgiveness ! But stop, let us see. What is to be under- stood here by exact justice, and by a real, full satisfaction to his Fathelf's justice ? I suppose all orthodox Christians to hold, that every sinner and every sin, strictly on the score of justice, deserves eternal death or end- less suffering. Did the framers of this confession hold that Christ boi-e the literal penalty of the law for each of the saints ? Or did they hold that by virtue of his nature and relations, his suffering, though indefi- nitely less in amount than was deserved by the transgressors, was a full equivalent to public justice, or govern mentally considered, for the exe- cution of the literal penalty upon the transgressors ? If they meant this latter, I see no objection to it. But if they meant the former, namely, that Christ suffered in his own person the full amount strictly due to a^l the elect, I say, (1.) That it was naturally impossible. (2.) That his nature and relation to the government of God was such as to render it wholly unnecessary to the safe forgiveness of sin, that ho should suffer precisely the same amount deserved by sinners. (3.) That if, as their substitute, Christ suffered for them the fiill amount deserved by them, then justice has no claim upon them, sinCe their debt is fully paid by the surety, and of course the principal is, in justice, discharged. And since it is undeniable that the atonement was made for the whole posterity of Adam, it must follow that the salvation of all men is secured upon the ground of " exact justice." This is the conclusion to which Huntington and his followers came. This doctrine of literal imputation, is one of the strongholds of universalism, and while this view of atonement and justification is held they cannot be driven from it. (4.) If he satisfied justice for them, in the sense of literally and exactly ob^ng for them, why should his suffering be imputed to them as a con- dition of their salvation ? Surely they could not need both the imputa^ tion of his perfect obedience to them, so as to be accounted in law as perfectly righteous, and also the imputation of his sufferings to them, as if he had not obeyed for them. Is God unrighteous ? Does he exact of the surety, first, the literal and full payment of the debt, and secondly, perfect personal obedience for and in behalf of the sinner ? Does he first exact full and perfect obedience, and then the same amount of suf- fering as if there had been no obedience ? And this, too, of his beloved Son? (5.) What Christian ever felt, or can feel in the presence of God, that he haa a right to demand justification in the name of Christ, as due to him on the ground of " exact justice ?" Observe, the framers of the Con 400 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOOY. fession just quoted, studiously represent all the grace exercised in the justification of sinners, as confined to the two acts of giving his Son and accepting the substitution. This done, Christ fully pays the debt, fully and exactly satisfies his Father's justice. You now need not, must not conceive of the pardon of sin as grace or favor. To do this is, according to the teaching of this Confession, to dishonor Christ. It is to reject his righteousness and salvation. What think you of this ? One act oi grace in giving his Son, and consenting to the substitution, and all for- giveness, all accepting and trusting as righteous, is not grace, but " ex- act justice." To pray for forgiveness, as an act of grace, is apostacy from Christ. Christian ! Can you believe this ? No ; in your closet, smarting under the sting of a recently committed sin, or broken down and bathed in tears, you cannot find it in your heart to demand " exact justice " at the hand of God, on the ground that Christ has fully and literally paid your debt. To represent the work and death of Christ as the ground of justification in this sense, is a snare and a stumbling-block. This view that I have just examined, contradicts the necessary convic- tions of every saint on earth. For the truth of this assertion I appeal to the universal consciousness of saints. 2. Our own works, or obedience to the law or to the gospel, are not the ground or foundation of our justification. That is, neither our faith, nor repentance, nor love, nor life, nor anything done by us or wrought in us, is the ground of our justification. These are conditions of our justification, in the sense of a " not without which," but not the ground of it. We are justified upon condition of our faith, but not for our faith ; upon condition of our repentance, love, obedience, perseverance to the end, but not for these things. These are the conditions, but not the reason, ground, or procuring cause of our justification. We cannot be justified without them, neither are we or can we be justified by them. None of these things must be omitted on pain of eternal damnation. Nor must they be put in the place of Christ, upon the same penalty. Faith is so much insisted on in the gospel as the sine qud non of our jus- tification, that some seem disposed, or at least to be in danger of substi- tuting faith in the place of Christ ; of making faith instead of Christ the Savior. 3. Neither is the atonement, nor anything in the mediatorial work of Christ, the foundation of our justification, in the sense of the source, moving, or procuring cause. This, that is the ground of our justifica- tion, lies deep in the heart of infinite love. We owe all to that merciful disposition that performed the mediatorial work, and died the accursed death to supply an indispensable condition of our justification and salva- tion. To stop short in the act which supplied the condition, instead of finding the depths of a compassion as fathomless as infinity, as the source of the whole movement, is to fail in discrimination. The work, and death, and resurrection, and advocacy of Christ are indispensable condi- tions, are all-important, but not the fundamental reason of our justi- fication. 4. Nor is the work of the Holy Spirit in converting and sanctifying the soul, the foundation of our justification. This is only a condition, or means of bringing it about, but is not the fundamental reason. 5. But the disinterested and infinite love of God, the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit, is the true and only foundation of the justification and salvation of sinners. God is love, that is, he is infinitely benevolent. AH he does, or says, or suffers, permits or omits, is for one and the same ultimate reason, namely, to promote the highest good of universal being. 6. Christ, the second person in the glorious Trinity, is represented in scripture, as taking so prominent a part in this work^ that the number of offices and relations which he sustains to God and man in it are truly wonderful. For example, he is represented as being, — King — Judge — Mediator — Advocate — Redeemer — surety — wisdom — righteousness — sanctification — redemption — Prophet — Priest — passover, or Lamb of God — the bread and water of life — true God and eternal life — our life — our all in all — as the repairer of the breach — as dying for our sins — as rising for our justification — as the resurrection and the life — as bearing our griefs and carrying our sorrows — as he, by whose stripes we are healed — as the head of his people — as the bridegroom or husband of his church — as the shepherd of his flock — as the door by which they enter — as the way to salvation — as our salvation — as the truth — as being made sin for sin — ^that we are made the righteousness of God in him — ^that in him dwells all the fulness of the Godhead — that in him all fulness dwells — all power in heaven and earth are said to be given to him — the true light that lighteth every man that cometh into the world — Christ in us the hope of glory — the true vine of which we are the branches —our brother— Wonderful — Counsellor — the mighty God — the everlastmg Father — ^the prince of peace — the captain of salvation — the captain of the Lord's host.. These are among, the official relations of Christ to his people, and to the great work of our justification.! I shall have frequent occasion to con- sider him in some of these relations, as we proceed in the course of study. Indeed, the offices, relations, and works of Christy are among the most important topies. of Christian theology. Christ is, our Justification,, in the sense that he carries into execution the whole scheme of redemption devised by the adorable Godhead. To him the scriptures everywhere direct the eyes of our faith and of our in- .teUigpnoe also. The Holy Spirit is represented not as glorifying himself, but as speaking of Jesus, as taking of the things of Christ and showing 26 402 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. them to his people, as glorifying Christ Jesus, as being sent by Christ, as being the Spirit of Christ, as being Christ himself dwelling in the hearts of his people. But I must forbear at present. This subject of Christ's relations needs elucidation in future lectures. REMABE. The relations of the old school view of justification to their view of depravity is obvious. They hold, as we have seen, that the constitution in every faculty and part is sinful. Of course, a return to personal, pres- ent holiness, in the sense of entire conformity to the law, cannot with them be a condition of justification. They must have a justification while yet at least in some degree of sin. This must be brought about by im- puted righteousness. The intellect revolts at a justification in sin. So a scheme is devised to divert the eye of the law and of the lawgiver from the sinner to his substitute, who has perfectly obeyed the law. But in order to make out the possibility of his obedience ' being imputed to them, it must be assumed, that he owed no obedience for himself ; than which a greater absurdity cannot be conceived. Constitutional depravity or sinfulness being once assumed, physical regeneration, physical sanctifica- tion, physical divine influence, imputed righteousness and justification, while personally in the commission of sin, follow of course. LECTURE XXXVII. SANCTIPICATION. I. I mill remind you of some points that have been settled in this course of study. 1. The true intent and meaning of the law of God has been, as I trust, ascertained in the lectures on moral government. Let this point, if need be, be examined by reference to those lectures. 2. We have also seen, in those lectures, what is not, and what is im- plied in entire obedience to the moral law. 3. In those lectures, and also in the lectures on justification and re- pentance, it has been shown that nothing is acceptable to God, as a con- dition of justification, and of consequent salvation, but a repentance that implies a return to full obedience to the moral law. 4. It has also been shown, that nothing is holiness short of full obe- dience, for the time being, to the moral law. SANCTIFICATIOM. 403 5. It has also been shown, that regeneration and repentance consist in the heart's return to full obedience, for the time being, to this law. 6. We have also examined the doctrine of depravity, and seen, that moral depravity, or sin, consists in selfishness, and not at all in the con- stitution of men ; that selfishness does not consist in the involuntary ap- petites, passions, and propensities, but that it consists alone in the com- mittal of the wiU to the gratification of the propensities. 7. We have seen that holiness consists, not at aU in the constitution of body or mind ; but that it belongs, strictly, only to the will or heart, and consists in obedience of will to the law of God, as it lies revealed in the intellect ; that it is expressed in one word, love ; that this love is identical with the entire consecration of the whole being to the glory of God, and to the highest well-being of the imiverse ; or in other words, that it consists in disinterested benevolence. 8. We have seen that all true saints, while in a state of acceptance with God, do actually render, for the time being, fuU obedience to all the known requirements of God ; that is, that they do for the time being their whole duty — all that God, at this time, requires of them. 9. We have seen that this obedience is not rendered independent of the grace of God, but is induced by the indwelling spirit of Christ received by faith, and reigning in the heart. This fact will be more fully elucidated In this discussion than it has been in fbrmer lectures. A former lecture was devoted to it ; but a fuller Consideration of it remains to be entered upon hereafter. II. Define the principal terms to be used in this discussion. Here 'let me remark, that a definition of terms, in all discussions, is of prime importance. Especially is this true of this subject. I have ob- served that almost without an exception, those who have written on this subject dissenting from the views entertained here, do so upon the groxmd that they understand and define the terms sanctification and Christian perfection differently from what we do. Every one gives his own defini- tion, varying materially from others, and from what we understand by the terms ; and then he goes on professedly opposing the doctrine as in- culcated here. Now thi^ is not only utterly unfair, but palpably absurd. If I oppose a doctrine inculcated by another man, I am boimd to oppose what he really holds. If I misrepresent his sentiments, "I fight as one that beateth the air." I have been amazed at the diversity of definitions that have been given to the terms Christian perfection, sanctification, etc. ; and to witness the diversity of opinion as to what is, and what is not, implied m these terms. One objects wholly to the use of the term Christian perfection, because, in his estimation, it implies this, and that, and the other thing, which I do not suppose are at aU implied in it. »04 SYSTEMATIC THfiOLOQT. Another objects to our nsing the term sanctification, because tbatimpliea according to his understanding of it, certain things that render its use improper. Now it is no part of my design to dispute about the use of words. I must however use some terms ; and I ought to be allowed to use Bible language in itt. scriptural sense, as I understand it. And if I should suflSciently explain my meaning, and define the sense in which I use the terms, and the sense in which the Bible manifestly uses them, this ought to sufiice. And I beg, that nothing more or less may be un- derstood by the language I use, than I profess to mean by it. Others may, if they please, use the same terms, and give a different definition of them. But I have a right to hope and expect, if they feel called upon to oppose what I say, that they will bear in mind my definition of the terms, and not pretend, as some have done, to oppose my views, while they have only differed from me in their definition of the terms used, giving their own definition varying materially and, I might say, infinitely from the sense in which I use the same terms, and then arraying their arguments to prove, that according to their definition of it, sanctification is not really attainable in this life, when no one here or anywhere else, that I ever heard of pretended that, in their sense of the term, it ever was or ever will be, attainable in this life, and I might add, or in that which is to come. Sanctification is a term of freqnent use in the Bible. Its simple and primary meaning is a state of consecration to God. To sanctify is to set apart to a holy use — to consecrate a thing to the service of G-od, This is plainly both the Old and the New Testament use of the term. The Greek word hagiazo means to sanctify, to consecrate, or devote a person or thing to a particular, especially to a sacred, use. This word is syn- onymous with the Hebrew kaudasTi. This last word is used in the Old Testament to express the same thing that is intended by the Greek hag- iaeo, namely, to consecrate, devote, set apart, sanctify, purify, make clean or pure. Sagiasmos, a substantive from hagiazo, means sanctification, devotion, consecration, purity, holiness. Prom the Bible use of these terms it is most manifest, — 1. That sanctification does not imply any constitutional change, eitfaei of Boul or body. It consists in the consecration or devotion of the con stitutional powers of body and soul to God, and not in any change wrought in the constitution itself. 2. It is also evident from the scriptural use of the term, that sancti fication is not a phenomenon, or state of the intellect. It belongs neithe. to the reason, conscience, nor understanding. In short, it cannot con slai in any state of the intellect whatever. All the states of this faonltj Vb purely passive states of mind ; and of course, as we have abnndantl} * tainable in this life, is as absolutely to take the part of sin against God, as it would be to insist upon repentance in theory, and then avow that in practice it is not attainable. And here let me ask Christians what they expect ministers to preach ? Do you think they have a right to connive at any sin in you, or to insist upon any thing else as a practicable fact, than that you should abandon every iniquity ? I ask, by what authority 27 '418 SYSTEMAflCi 1SE6L0GY.. can a minister preach any thing less ? And how shall any minister dare to inculcate the duty as a theory, and yet not insist upon it as a practical matter, as something to be expected of every subject of God's kingdom? 9. A denial of this doctrine has the natural tendency to beget the very apathy witnessed in the church. Professors of religion go on in sin, with- out much conviction of its wickedness. Sin unblushingly stalks abroad even in the church of God, and does not fiU Christians with horror, be- cause they expect its existence as a thing of course. Tell a yoimg con- vert that he must expect to backslide, and he will do so of course, and with coniparatively little remorse, because he looks upon it as a kind of necessity. And being led to expect it, you find him, in a few months after his conversion, away from God, and not at all horrified with his state. Just so, inculcate the idea among Christians, that they are not expected to abandon all sin, and they will of course go on in sin with comparative indifference. Reprove them for their sin, and they wiU say, "O, we are imperfect creatures ; we do not pretend to be perfect, nor do we expect we ever shall be in this world." Many such answers as these will show you at once the God-dishonoring and soul-ruining tendency of a denial of this doctrine. 10. A denial of this doctrine prepares the minds of ministers to tem- porize, and wink at great iniquity in their churches. Feeling, as they certainly must, if they disbeUeve this doctrine, that a great amount of sin in all believers is to be expected as a thing of course, their whole preach- ing, and spirit, and demeanor, will be such as to beget a great degree of apathy among Christians, in regard to their abominable sins. 11. If this doctrine is not true, how profane and blasphemous is the covenant of every church of every evangelical denomination. Every church requires its members to make a solemn covenant with God and with the church, in the presence of God and angels, and with their hands upon the emblems of the broken body and shed blood of the blessed Jesus, "to abstain from all ungodliness and every worldly lust, to live soberly, righteously, and godly, in this present world." Now, if the doctrine of the attainability of entire sanctification in this life is not true, what pro- fane mockery is this covenant ! It is a covenant to live in a state of en- tire sanctification, made under the most solemn circumstances, enforced by the most awful sanctions, and insisted upon by the minister of God distributing the bread and wine. Now what right h^ any minister on earth to require less than this ? And again, what right has any minister on earth to require this, unless it is a practicable thing, and imless it is expected of him who makes the vow ? Suppose, when this covenant was proposed to a convert about to unite with the church, he should take it to his closet, and spread it before the Lord, and inquire whether it would be right for him to make such a cove- SANCTIFtCATlON. 41^ nant, and whether the grace of the gospel can enable him to fulfil it ? Do you suppose the Lord Jesus would reply, that if he made that cove- nant, he certainly would, and must, as a matter of course, live in the habitual violation of it as long as he hves, and that his grace was not sufficient to enable him to keep it ? Would he, in such a case, have any right to take upon himself this covenant ? No, no more than he would have a right to lie to the Holy Ghost. It has long been maintained by orthodox divines, that a person is not a Christian who does not aim at living without sin — that unless he aims at perfection, he manifestly consents to live in sin ; and is therefore im- penitent. It has been said, and I think truly, that if a man does not, in the fixed purpose of his heart, aim at total abstinence from sin, and at being wholly conformed to the wiU of God, he is not yet regenerated, and does not so much as mean to cease from abusing God. In Barnes' Notes upon 2 Cor. viii. 1, we have the following : — "The unceasing and steady aim of every Christian should be perfec- tion — ^perfection in all things — in the love of God, of Christ, of mai/; perfection of heart, and feeling, and emotion ; perfection in his words, and plans, and dealings with men ; perfection in his prayers, and in his submission to the will of God. No man can be a Christian who does not sincerely desire it, and who does not constantly aim at it. No man is a friend of God who can acquiesce in a state of sin, and who is satisfied and contented that he is not as holy as God is holy. And any man who has no desire to be perfect as God is, and who does not make it his daily and constant aim to be as perfect as God, may set it down as demonstrably certain that he has no true religion." Now if this is so, I would ask how a person can aim at, and intend to do, what he knows to be impossible. Is it not a contradiction to say that a man can intend to do what he knows he cannot do 7 To this it has been objected, that if true, it proves too much^— that it would prove that no man ever was a Christian who did not believe in this doctrine. To this I reply : — A man may believe in what is really a state of entire sanctification, and aim at attaining it, although he may not call it by that name. This I believe to be the real fact with Christians ; and they would much more frequently attain what they aim at, did they know how to appropriate the grace of Christ to their own circumstances. Mrs. President Edwards, for example, firmly believed that she could attain a state of entire conse- cration. She aimed at, and manifestly attained it, and yet, such were her views of constitutional depravity, that she did not call her state one of entire sanctification. It has been common for Christians to suppose, that a state of entire consecration is attainable ; but while they believe in the sinfulness of their natures, they would not of course call even en- 420 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. tire consecration, entire sanctification. Mrs. Edwards believed in, aimed at, and attained, entire consecration. She aimed at what she believed to be attainable, and she could aim at nothing more. She called it by the same name with her husband, who was opposed to the doctrine of Christian perfection, as held by the Wesleyan Methodists, manifestly on the ground of his notions of physical depravity. I care not what this state is called, if the thing be fully explained and insisted upon, together with the conditions of attaining it. Call it what you please. Christian perfection, heavenly mindedness, the fuU assurance of faith or hope, or a state of entire consecration ; by all these I understand the same thing. And it is certain, that by whatever name it is called, the thing must be aimed at to be attained. The practicability of its attainment must be admitted, or it cannot be aimed at. And now I would humbly inquire, whether to preach any thing short of this is not to give coxmtenance to sin? 12. Another argument in favor of this doctrine is, that the gospel, as a matter of fact, has often, not only temporarily, but permanently and perfectly, overcome every form of sin, in different individuals. Who has not seen the most beastly lusts, drunkenness, lasciviousness, and every kind of abomination, long indulged and fully ripe, entirely and forever slain by the power of the grace of God ? Now how was this done ? Only by bringing this sin fuUy into the light of the gospel, and showing the in- dividual the relation which the death of Christ sustained to that sin. Nothing is wanting to slay any and every form of sin, but for the mind to be fully baptized into the death of Christ, and to see the bearings of one's own sins upon the sufferings, and agonies, and death of the blessed Jesus. Let me state a fact to illustrate my meaning. An habitual and most inveterate smoker of tobacco, of my acquaintance, after having been plied with almost every argument to induce him to break the power of the habit and relinquish its use, in vain, on a certain occasion lighted his pipe, and was abqut to put it to his mouth, when the inquiry was started, Did Christ die to purchase this vile indulgence for me ? The perceived relation of the death of Christ to this sin instantly broke the power of the habit, and from that day he has been free. I could relate many other facts more striking than this, where a similar view of the relation of a particular sin to the atonement of Christ, has, in a moment, not only broken the power of the habit, but destroyed entirely and forever, the appetite for similar indulgences. And in multitudes of cases when the appetite has not been entirely slain, the will has been endowed with abundant and abiding efficiency effectually to control it. If the most in- veterate habits of sin, and even those that involve physical consequences, and have deeply debased the physical constitution, and rendered it a source of overpowering temptation to the mind, can be, and often have SANCTIFICATION. [421 been, utterly broken up, and forever slain by the grace of God, why should it be doubted, that by the same grace a man can triumph over all sin, and that forever ? 13. If this doctrine is not true, what is true upon the subject ? It is certainly of great importance that ministers should be definite in their instructions ; and if Christians are not expected to be wholly conformed to the will of God in this life, how much is expected of them ? Who can say. Hitherto canst thou, must thou come, but no further ? It is certainly absurd, not to say ridiculous, for ministers to be forever press- ing Christians up to higher and higher attainments, saying at every step, you can and must go higher, and yet all along informing them, that they are expected to fall short of their whole duty, that they can as a matter of fact, be better than they are, far better, indefinitely better ; but stiU it is not expected that they will do their whole duty. I have often been pained to hear men preach, who were afraid to commit them- selves in favor of the whole truth ; and who were yet evidently afraid of falling short in their instructions, of insisting that men should stand "perfect and complete in all the will of God." To be consistent they are evidently perplexed, and well they may be ; for in truth there is no consist- ency in their views and teachings. If they do not inculcate, as a matter of fact, that men ought to do, and are expected to do, their whole duty, they are sadly at a loss to know what to inculcate. They have evidently many misgivings about insisting upon less than this, and stUl they fear . to go to the full extent of apostolic teaching on this subject. And in their attempts to throw in qualifying terms and caveats, to avoid the impression, that they believe in the doctrine of entire sanctification, they place themselves in a truly awkward position. Cases have occurred in which ministers have been asked, how far we may go, must go, and are expected to go, in dependence upon the grace of Christ, and how holy men may be, and are expected to be, and must be, in this life. They could give no other answer to this, than that they can be a great deal better than they are. Now this indefiniteness is a great stumbling- block to the church. It cannot be according to the teachings of the Holy Ghost. 14. The tendency of a denial of this doctrine is, to my mind, conclu- sive proof that the doctrine itself must be true. Many developments in the recent history of the church throw light upon this subject. Who does not see that the facts developed in the temperance reformation have a direct and powerful bearing upon this question ? It has been ascer- tained, that there is no possibility of completing the temperance refor- mation, except by adopting the principle of total abstinence from all intoxicating drinks. Let a temperance lecturer go forth as an evangel- ist, to promote revivals on the subject of temperance-^let him inveigh 422 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. against drunkenness, while he admits and defends the moderate use of alcohol, or insinuates, at least, that total abstinence is not expected or practicable. In this stage of the temperance reformation, every one can see that such a man can make no progress ; that he would be employed like a child in building dams of sand to obstruct the rushing of mighty waters. It is as certain as that causes produce their effects, that no per- manent reformation could be effected, without adopting and insisting on the total abstinence principle. And now, if this is true, as it respects the temperance reformation, how much more so when applied to the subjects of holiness and sin. A man might, by some possibility, even in his own strength, overcome his habits of drunkenness, and retain what might be called the temperate use of alcohol. But no such thing is possible in a reformation from sin. There is no temperate indulgence in sin. Sin, as a matter of fact, is never overcome by any man in his own strength. If he admits into his creed the necessity of any degree of sin, or if he allows in practice any degree of sin, he becomes impenitent, consents to live in sin, and of course grieves the Holy Spirit, the certain result of which is a relapsing into a state of legal - bondage to sin. And this is probably a true history of many professed Christians in' the church. It is just what might be expected from the views and practice of the church upon this subject. The secret of backsliding is, that reformations are not carried deep enough. Christians are not set with all their hearts to aim at a speedy deliverance from all sin, but on the contrary are left, and in many in- stances taught, to indulge the expectation that they shall sin as long as they live. I probably never shall forget the effect produced on my mind by reading, when a yoimg convert, in the diary of David Brainerd, that he never expected to make any considerable attainments in holiness in this life. I can now easily see that this was a natural inference from the theory of physical sinfulness which he held. But not perceiving this at the time, I doubt not that this expression of his views had a very in- jurious effect upon me for many years. It led me to reason thus : if such a man as David Brainerd did not expect to make much advancement in holiness in this life, it is vain for me to expect such a thuig. The fact is, if there be anything that is important to high attainments in holiness, and to the progress of the work of sanctification in this life, it is the adoption of the principle of total abstinence from sin. Total abstinence from sin must be every man's motto, or sin will certainly sweep him away as with a flood. That cannot possibly be a true princi- ple in temperance, that leaves the causes which produce drunkenness to operate in their full strength. Nor can that be true in regard to holiness which leaves the root unextracted, and the certain causes of spiritual decUne and backsliding at work in the very heart of the church. And I SANCTIFICATION. 423 am fully convinced that until evangelists and pastors adopt, and carry out in practice, the principle of total abstinence from all sin, they will as certainly find themselves, every few months, called to do their work over again, as a temperance lecturer would who should admit the moder- ate use of alcohol. Again, who does not know that to call upon sinners to repent, and at the same time to inform them that they will not, and cannot, and are not expected to repent, would for ever prevent their repentance ? Sup- pose you say to a sumer, "You are naturally able to repent ; but it is certain that you never will repent in this hfe, either with or without the Holy Spirit." Who does not see that such teaching would prevent his repentance as surely as he believed it ? To say to a professor of religion, "You are naturally able to be wholly conformed to the wiU of God ; but it is certain that you never will be, in this life, either in your own strength, or by the grace of God ;" if this teaching be believed, it will just as certainly prevent his sanctification, as the other teaching would the repentance of the sinner. I can speak from experience on this subject. While I inculcated the common views, I was often instrumental in bringing Christians under great conviction, and into a state of temporary repentance and faith. But falling short of urging them up to a point where they would become so acquainted with Christ as to abide in him, they would of course soon relapse again into their former state. I seldom saw, and can now understand that I had no reason to expect to see, under the instructions which I then gave, such a state of religious principle, such steady and confirmed walking with God among Christians, as I have seen since the change in my views and instructions. LECTURE XXXVIII. SANCTIFICATION. PAUL ENTIBELT SANCTIFIED. L Might urge a great many other considerations, and as I have said, fill a book with scriptures, and arguments, and demonstrations, of the attainability of entire sanctification in this life. But I forbear, and will present only one more consideration — a con- sideration which has great weight in some minds. It is a question of great importance, whether any actually ever did attain this state. Some who believe it attainable, do not consider it of much importance to show 424 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. that it has actually been attained. Now I freely admit, that it may be attainable, even if it never has been attained. Yet it appears to me that as a source of encouragement to the church, it is of great importance whether, as a matter of fact, a state of entire and continued holiness has been attained in this life. This question covers much ground. But for the sake of brevity, I design to examine but one case, and see whether there is not reason to believe that, in one instance at least, it has been at- tained. The case to which I allude is that of the apostle Paul. And I propose to take up and examine the passages that speak of him, for the purpose of ascertaining whether there is evidence that he ever attained to this state in this life. And here let me say that, to my own mind, it seems plain, that Paul and John, to say nothing of the other apostles, designed and expected the church to understand them as speaking from experience, and as hav- ing received of that fulness which they taught to be in Christ and in his gospel. And I wish to say again and more expressly, that I do not rest the practicability of attaining a state of entire and continued holiness at all upon the question, whether any ever have attained it, any more than I would rest the question, whether the world ever will be converted, upon the fact whether it ever has been converted. I have been surprised, when the fact that a state of entire holiness has been attained, is urged as one argument among a great many to prove its attainability, and that too, merely as an encouragement to Christians to lay hold upon this blessing — ^that objectors and reviewers fasten upon this, as the doctrine of sanctification, as if by calling this particular question into doubt, they could overthrow all the other proof of its attainability. Now this is utterly absurd. When, then, I examine the character of Paul with this object in view, if it should not appear clear to you that he did attain this state, you are not to overlook the fact, that its attainability is settled by other arguments, on grounds entirely independent of the question, whether it has been attained or not ; and that I merely use this as an argument, simply because to me it appears forcible, and fitted to afford great en- couragement to Christians to press after this state. I wiU first make some remarks in regard to the manner in which the language of Paul, when speaking of himself, should be understood ; and then proceed to an examination of the passages which speak of his Chris- tian character. His character, as revealed in his life, demands that we should imder- stand him to mean all that he says, when speaking in his own favor. The Spirit of inspiration would guard him against speaking too highly of himself. No man ever seemed to possess greater modesty, and to feel more unwilling to exalt his own attainments. K he considered himself SANCTIFICATION. 425 as not having attained a state of entire sanctification, and as often, if not in all things, falling short of his duty, we may expect to find him ac- knowledging this in the deepest self-abasement. If he is charged with living in sin, and with being wicked in anything, we may expect him, when speaking under inspiration, not to justify, but unequivocally to condemn himself in those things, if he was really guilty. Now, in view of these facts, let us examine those scriptures in which he speaks of himself, and is spoken of by others. 1 Thess. ii. 10 : "Ye are witnesses, and God also, how holily, and justly, and unblamably, we behaved ourselves among you that believe." Here he unquaUfiedly asserts his own holiness. This language is very strong, "How hoUly, justly, and unblamably." If to be holy, just, and unblamable, be not entire sanctification, what is ? He appeals to the heart-searching God for the truth of what he says, and to their own ob- servation, caUing on God and on them also to bear witness, that he had been holy and without blame. Here we have the testimony of an inspired apostle, in the most unquaUfied language, asserting his own entire sanc- tification. Was he deceived ? Can it be that he knew himself all the time to have been living in sin ? If such language as this does not amount to an unquaUfied assertion, that he had lived among them without sin, what can be known by the use of human language ? 2 Cor. vi. 3-7 : "Giving no offence in anything, that the ministry be not blamed ; but in all things approving ourselves as the ministers of God, in much patience, in afifictions, in necessity, in distresses, in stripes, in imprisonments, in tumults, in labors, in watchings, in fastings ; by pureness, by knowledge, by long-suffering, by kindness, by the Holy Ghost, by love unfeigned, by the word of truth, by the power of God, by the armor of righteousness on the right hand and on the left." Upon these verses I remark : Paul asserts that he gave no offence in anything, but in all things approved himself as a minister of God. Among other things, he did this "by pureness, by the Holy Ghost, by love unfeigned," and "by the armor of righteousness on the right hand and on the left." How could so modest a man as Paul speak of himself in this manner, unless he knew himself to be in a state of entire sanctification, and thought it of great importance that the church should know it ? 2 Cor. i. 12 : " For our rejoicing is this, the testimony of our con- science, that in simplicity and godly sincerity, not with fleshly wisdom, but by the grace of God, we have had our conversation in the world, and more abundantly to youward." This passage plainly implies the same thing, and was manifestly said for the same purpose — ^to declare the great- ness of the grace of God as manifested in himself. Acts xxiv. 16 : "And herein do I exercise myself to have always a conscieiice yoi^ pf offence toward God, and tows^yd men/' Paul doubtr 426 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. leas at this time had an enlightened conscience. If an inspired apostle could afltan, that he "exercised himself to have always a conscience void of offence toward God and toward men," must he not have been in a state of entire sanctification ? 2 Tim. i. 3 : "I thank God, whom I serve from my forefathers with a pure conscience, that without ceasing I have remembrance of thee in my prayers night and day." Here again he affirms that he serves God with a pure conscience. Could this be, if he was often, and perhaps every day, as some suppose, violating his conscience ? Gal. ii. 20 : "I am crucified with Christ ; nevertheless I live ; yet not I, but Christ liveth in me ; and the life which I now live in the flesh, I live by the faith of the Son of God, who loved me, and gave himself for me." This does not assert, but strongly implies, that he lived without sin, and also that he regarded himself as dead to sin in the sense of being permanently sanctified. Gal. vi. 14 : "But God forbid that I should glory, save in the cross of our Lord Jesus Christ, by whom the world is crucified imto me, and I imto the world." This text also affords the same inference as above. Phil. i. 21 : "For me to live is Christ, and to die is gain." Here the apostle afiErms that for him to live was as if Christ lived in the church, that is, by his doctrine illustrated by his life, it was as if Christ lived again and preached his own gospel to sinners and to the church ; or for him to live was to make Christ known as if Christ lived to make himself known. How could he say this, unless his example, and doctrine, and spirit, were those of Christ ? Acts XX. 26 : "Wherefore I take you to record this day, that I am piu-e from the blood of all men." This passage, taken in its connection, shows clearly the impression that Paul desired to make upon the minds of those to whom he spake. It is certain that he could in no proper sense be "pure from the blood of all men," imless he had done his whole duty. If he had been sinfully lacking in any grace, or virtue, or labor, could he have said this 7 Certainly not. • 1 Cor. ii. 16, 17 : "Wherefore, I beseech you, be ye followers of me. For this cause have I sent unto you Timotheus, who is my beloved son, and faithful in the Lord, who shall bring you into remembrance of my ways which be in Christ, as I teach everywhere in every church." Here Paul manifestly sets himself up as an example to the chiu-ch. How could he do this if he were living in sin ? He sent Timotheus to them to refresh their memories in regard to his doctrine and practice ; implying that what he taught in every church he himself practiced. 1 Cor. xi. 1 : "Be ye followers of me, even as I also am of Christ." Here Paul commands them to follow him "as he followed Christ •" not so far as he followed Christ, as some seem to understand it, but to follow SANCTIFICATION. 427' him because he followed Christ. How could he, in this unqualified manner, command the church to copy his example, unless he knew himself to be blameless'? Phil. iii. 17, 20 : "Brethren, be followers together of me, and mark them which walk so as ye have us for an ensample. For our conversa- tion is in heaven, from whence we also look for the Saviour, the Lord Jesus Christ." Here again, Paul calls upon the church to follow him, and par- ticularly to notice those that copied his example, and assigns as the reason, "for our conversation is in heaven." Phil. iii. 9 : "Those things, which ye have both learned and received, and heard, and seen in me, do ; and the God of peace shall be with you." The Philippians were commanded to "do those things which they had learned, and received, and seen in him." And then he adds, that if they do those things, the God of peace shall be with them. Now can it be, that he meant that they should tmderstand anything less, than that he lived without sin among them ? I will next examine those passages which are supposed by some to imply that Paul was not in a state of entire sanctification. Acts XV. 36-40 : "And some days after, Paul said unto Barnabas; Let us go again and visit our brethren in every city where we have preached the word of the Lord, and see how they do. And Barnabas determined to take with them John whose surname was Mark. But Paul thought not good to take him with them, who departed from them from Pamphylia, and went not with them to the work. And the con- tention was so sharp between them, that they departed asunder one from the other ; and so Barnabas took Mark, and sailed to Cyprus ; and Paul chose Silas, and departed, being recommended by the brethren unto the grace of God." t This contention between Paul and Barnabas arose out of the fact, that John, who was a nephew of Barnabas, had once abruptly left them in their travels, it would seem, without any justiuable reason, and had re- turned home. It appears that the confidence of Barnabas in his nephew was restored. But Paul was not as yet satisfied ol the stability of his character, and thought it dangerous to trust him as a traveUing com- panion and fellow laborer. It is not intimated, nor can it fairly be in- ferred, that either of them sinned in this contention. If either was to be blamed, it seems that Barnabas was in fault, rather than Paul, inas- much as he determined to take John with him, without having consulted Paul. And he persisted in this determination until he met with such firm resbtance on the part of Paul, that he took John and sailed abruptly for Cyprus ; while Paul choosing Silas as his companion, was recom- mended by the brethren to the grace of God, and departed. Now cer- tainly there is nothing that we can discover in this transaction, that Paul, 428 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. or any good man, or an angel, under the circumstances, needs to have been ashamed of. It does not appear, that Paul ever acted more from a regard to the glory of God and the good of religion, than in thi^ transac- tion. And I would humbly inquire, what spirit is that which finds suf- ficient evidence in this case to charge an inspired apostle with rebellion' against God ? Acts xxiii. 1-5 : "And Paul, earnestly beholding the council, said. Men and brethren, I have lived in aU good conscience before God imtil this day. And the high priest Ananias commanded them that stood by him to smite him on the mouth. Then said Paul unto him, God shall smite thee, thou whited wall : for sittest thou to judge me after the law, and commandest me to be smitten contrary to the law ? And they that stood by said, RevUest thou God's high priest ? Then said Paul, I wist not, brethren, that he was the high priest : for it is written, Thou shalt not speak evil of the ruler of thy people." In this case sinful anger has been imputed to Paul ; but, so far as I can see, without any just reason. To my mind it seems plain, that the contrary is to be inferred. It ap- pears, that Paul was not personally acquainted with the then officiating high priest. And he manifested the utmost regard to the authority of God in quoting from the Old Testament, "Thou shalt not speak evil of the ruler of thy people ;" implying, that notwithstanding the abuse he had received, he should not have made the reply, had he known him to be the high priest. Rom. vii. from the fourteenth to the twenty-fifth verse, has by many been supposed to be an epitome of Paul's experience at the time he wrote the epistle. Upon this I remark : — 1. The connection and drift of Paul's reasoning show, that the case of which he was speaking, whether his own or the case of some one else, was adduced by him to illustrate the influence of the law upon the carnal mind. This is a case in which sin had the entire dominion, and overcame all his resolutions of obedience. ! 2. That his use of the singular pronoun, and in the first person, proves nothing in regard to the point, whether or not he was speaking of himself, for this is common with him, and with other writers, when using illustrations. He keeps up the personal pronoun, and passes into the eighth chapter ; at the beginning of which, he represents himself, or the person of whom he is speaking, as being not only in a different, but in an exactly opposite state of mind. Now, if the seventh chapter contains Paul's experience, whose experience is this in the eighth chapter ? Are we to understand them both as the experience of Paul ? If so, we must understand him as first speaking of his experience before, and then after he was sanctified. He begins the eighth chapter by saying, "There is therefore now no condemnation to them who are in Christ Jesus, who SANCTIFICATION, 429 walk not after the flesh, but after the Spirit ;" and assigns as a reason, that "The law of the Spirit of life in Christ Jesus hath made me free from the law of sin and death." The law of sin and death was that law in his members, or the influence of the flesh, of which he had so bitterly com- plained in the seventh chapter. But now, it appears, that he has passed into a state in which he is made free from this influence of the flesh, — is emancipated and dead to the world and to the flesh, and in a state in which "there is no condemnation." Now, if there was no condemnation in the state in which he then was, it must have been, either because he did not sin, or, if he did sin, because the law did not condemn him ; or because the law of God was repealed or abrogated. Now, if the penalty of the law was so set aside in his case, that he could sin without condem- nation, this is a real abrogation of the law. But as the law was not, and could not be set aside, its penalty was not and could not be so abrogated, as not to condemn every sin. If Paul lived without condemnation, it must be because he lived without sin. To me it does not appear that Paul speaks of his own experience in the seventh chapter of Romans, but that he merely supposes a case by way of illustration, and speaks in the flrst person, and in the present tense, simply because it was convenient and suitable to his purpose. His object manifestly was, in this and in the beginning of the eighth chapter, to contrast the influence of the law and of the gospel — to de- scribe in the seventh chapter the state of a man who was living in sin, and every day condemned by the law, convicted and constantly struggling with his own corruptions, but continually overcome, — and in the eighth chapter to exhibit a person in the enjoyment of gospel Uberty, where the righteousness of the law was fulflUed in the heart by the grace of Christ. The seventh chapter may well apply either to a person in a backslidden state, or to a convicted person who had never been converted. The eighth chapter can clearly be applicable to none but to those who are in a state of entire sanctification. I have abeady said, that the seventh chapter contains the history of one over whom sin has dominion. Now, to suppose that this was the experience of Paul when he wrote the epistle, or of any one who was in the Uberty of the gospel, is absurd and contrary to the experience of every person who ever enjoyed gospel liberty. And further, this is as expressly contradicted in the sixth chapter as -it can be. As I said, the seventh chapter exhibits one over whom sin has dominion : but God says, in the sixth chapter and fourteenth verse, "For sin shall not have dominion over you ; for ye are not under the law, but under grace." I remark finally upon this passage, that if Paul was speaking of himself in the seventh chapter of Romans, and really giving a history of his own experience, it proves nothing at all in regard to his subsequent sanctifica- 430 'STSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. tion ; for the eighth chapter shows conclusively, that it was not his experience at the time he wrote the epistle. The fact that the seventh and eighth chapters have been separated since the translation was made, as I have before said, has led to much error in the understanding of this passage. Nothing is more certain, than that the two chapters were designed to describe not only different experiences, but experiences opposite to each other. And that both these experiences should belong to the same person at the same time, is manifestly impossible. If there- fore Paul is speaking in this connection of his own experience, we are bound to understand the eighth chapter as describing his experience at the time he wrote the epistle ; and the seventh chapter as descriptive of a former experience. Now, therefore, if any one understands the seventh chapter as describing a Christian experience, he must understand it as giving the exercises of one in a very imperfect state ; and the eighth chapter as descriptive of a soul in a state of entire sanctification. So that this epistle, instead of militating against the idea of Paul's entire sanctifica- tion, upon the supposition that he was speaking of himself, fuUy estab- lishes the fact that he was in that state. What do those brethren mean who take the latter part of the seventh chapter as entirely disconnected from that which precedes and follows it, and make it tell a sad story on the subject of the legal and sinful bondage of an inspired apostle ? What cannot be proved from the Bible in this way ? Is it not a soimd and indispensable rule of biblical interpretation, that a passage is to be taken in its connection, and that the scope and leading intention of the writer is to be continually borne in mind, in deciding upon the meaning of any passage ? Why then, I pray, are the verses that precede, and those that immediately follow in the eighth chapter, entirely overlooked in the examination of this important passage ? Phil. iii. 10-15. "That I may know him, and the power of his res- urrection, and the feUowship of his sufferings, being made conformable unto his death ; if by any means I might attain unto the resurrection of the dead. Not as though I had already attained, either were already per- fect ; but I follow after, if that I may apprehend that for which also I am apprehended of Christ Jesus. Brethren, I count not myself to have apprehended ; but this one thing I do, forgetting those things which are behind, and reaching forth unto those things which are before, I press toward the mark for the prize of the high calling of God in Christ Jesus. Let us therefore as many as be perfect, be thus minded : and if in any- thing ye be otherwise minded, God shall reveal even this unto you." Here is a plain allusion to the Olympic games, in which men ran for a prize, and were not crowned until the end of the race, however well they might run. Paul speaks of two kinds of perfection here, one of SANCTIFICATION. 431 which he claims to have attained, and the other he had not. The perfec- tion which he had not attained, was that which he did not expect to attain until the end of his race, nor indeed until he had attained the resur- rection from the dead. Until then he was not, and did not expect to be, perfect, in the sense that he should "apprehend all that for which he was apprehended of Christ Jesus." But all this does not imply that he was not living without sin, any more than it implies that Christ was living in sin when he said, "I must walk to-day and to-morrow, and the third day I shall be perfected." Here Christ speaks of a perfection which he had not attained. Now it is manifest, that it was the glorified state to which Paul had not attained, and which perfection Tie was pressing after. But in the fifteenth verse, he speaks of another kind of perfection, which he pro- fessed to have attained. "Let us therefore," he says, "as many as be perfect, be thus minded ;" that is, let us be pressing after this high state of perfection in glory, "if by any means we may attain unto the resur- rection of the dead." The figure of the game should be kept continually in mind in the interpretation of this passage. The prize in those races was the crown. This was given only at the end of the race. And besides, a man was not crowned except he ran lawfully, that is, accord- ing to rule. Paul was running for the prize, that is the crown ; not, as some suppose, for entire sanctification, but for a crown of glory. This he did not expect until he had completed his rac?. He exhorts those who were perfect, that is, those who were ruiiTiing lawfully or according to rule, to forget the things that were behind, and press to the mark, that is, the goal, for the prize, or the crown of glory, which the Lord the righteous judge, who was witnessing his race to award the crown to the victor, would give him at that day. Now it is manifest to my mind, that Paul does not in this passage, teach expressly nor impliedly, that he was living in sin, but the direct opposite — ^that he meant to say, as he had said in many other places, that he was unblamable in respect to sin, but that he was aspiring after higher attainments, and meant to be satisfied with nothing short of eternal glory. Again, Phil. iv. 11-13 : "Not that I speak in respect of want : for I have learned, in whatsoever state I am, therewith to be content. I know both how to be abased, and I know how to abound : everyTvhere, and in all things, I am instructed, both to be full and to be hungry, both to abound and to suffer need. I can do all things through Christ which strengtheneth me." Here Paul undoubtedly meant to affirm, not merely his abstract ability to do all his duty, but that he had learned by experience, that as a matter of fact and reality, he found himself able to do all things required of him. In relation to the character of Paul, let me say : — If Paul was not sin- 432 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. less, he was an extravagant boaster, and such language used by any min- ister in these days would be considered as the language of an extravagant boaster. This setting himself up as an example so frequently and fully, without any caution or qualification, was highly dangerous to the interests of the church, if he was not in a state of entire sanctification. His language in appealing to God, that in life and heart he was blame- less, was blasphemous, unless he was really what he professed to be ; and if he was what he professed to be, he was in a state of entire sanctifica- tion. It is doing dishonor to God, to maintain, under these circumstan- ces, that Paul had not attained the blessing of entire sanctification. He nowhere confesses sin after he becan^e an apostle, but invariably justifies himself, appealing to man and to God, for his entire integrity and blame- lessness of heart and life. To maintain the sinfulness of this apostle, is to deny the grace of the gospel, and charge God foolishly. And I cannot but inquire, why is this great effort in the church to maintain that Paul lived in sin, and was never wholly sanctified till death ? Two things have appeared wonderful to me : 1. That so many professed Christians should seem to think themselves highly honoring God in extending the claims of the law, and yet denying that the grace of the gospel is equal to the demands of the law. 2. That so many persons seem to have an entirely self-righteous view of the subject of sanctification. With respect to the first of these opin- ions, much pains has been taken to extend to the utmost the claims of the law of God. Much has been said of its exceeding and infinite strict- ness, and the great length, and breadth, and height, and depth of its claims. Multitudes are engaged in defending the claims of the law, as if they greatly feared that the purity of the law would be defiled, its strictness and spirituality overlooked, and its high and holy claims set aside, or frittered down somehow to the level of human passion and self- ishness. But while engaged in their zeal to defend the law, they talk and preach, and write, as if they supposed it indispensable, in order to sustain the high claims of the law, to deny the grace and power of the gospel, and its suflBlciency to enable human beings to comply with the re- quisitions of the law. Thus they seem to me, imwittingly, to enter the lists against the grace of Christ, and with the utmost earnestness and even vehemence, to deny that the grace of Christ is sufficient to overcome sin, and to fulfil in us the righteousness of the law. Yes, in their zeal for the law they appear to me either to overlook, or flatly to deny, the grace of the gospel. Now let the law be exalted. Let it be magnified and made honorable. Let it be shown to be strict, and pure, and perfect, as its Author ; spread its claims over flie whole field of human and angelic accountability ; carry it like a blaze of fire to the deepest recess of every human heart ; exalt it BANCTIPICATION. 4^3 aa high as heaven ; and thunder its authority and claims to the depths c.f heil ; stretch out its line upon the universe of mind ; and let it, as it well may, and as it ought, thunder death and terrible damnation against every kind and degree of iniquity. Yet let it be remembered for ever, that the grace of the gospel is co-extensive with the claims of the law. Let no man, therefore, in his strife to maintain the authority of the law, insult the Saviour, exercise unbelief himself, or fritter away and drown the faith of the church, by holding out the profane idea, that the glori- ous gospel of the blessed G-od, sent home and rendered powerful by the efficacious application of the Holy Spirit, is not sufficient to fulfil in us " the righteousness of the law," and cause us " to stand perfect and com- plete in all the will of God." With I'espect to the second thing which appears wonderful to me, namely, that so many seem to have an entirely self-righteous view of the doctrine of sanctification, let me say, that they seem afraid to admit, that any are entirely and perfectly sanctified in this life, lest they should - flatter human pride, seeming to take it for granted, that, if any are en- tirely sanctified, they have whereof to glory, as if they had done some- thing, and were in themselves better than others. Whereas, the doctrine of entire sanctification utterly abhors the idea of human merit, disclaims and repudiates it as altogether an abomination to God, and to the sanc- tified soul. This doctrine, as taught in the Bible, aud as I understand it, is as far as possible from conniving in the least degree at the idea of anything naturally good in saints or sinners. It ascribes the whole of salvation and sanctification from first to last, not only till the soul is sanctified, but at every moment while it remains in that state, to the in- dwelling Spirit, and influence, and grace of Christ. LECTURE XXXIX. SANCTIFICATION. V. The conditions of this attainment. 1. A state of entire sanctification can never be attained by an indiffer- ent waiting of God's time. 2. N"or by any works of law, or works of any kind, performed in your own strength, irrespective of the grace of God. By this I do not mean, thatj were you disposed to exert your natural powers aright, you could not at once obey the law in the exercise of your natural strength, and continue to do so. But I do mean, that as you are whollv indisposed to iSi SYSTEMATIC THEOLOQT. use your natural powers aright, without the grace of God, no efforts that you will actually make in your own strength, or independent of his grace, will ever result in your entire sanctification. 3. Not by any direct efforts to feel right. Many spend their time in vain efforts to force themselves into a right state of feeling. Now, it should be for ever understood, that religion does not consist in a mere feeling, emotion, or involuntary affection of any kind. Feelings do not result from a direct effort to feel. But, on the contrary, they are the spontaneous actings of the mind, when it has under its direct and deep consideration the objects, truths, facts, or reahties, that are correlated to these involuntary emotions. They are the most easy and natural state of mind possible under such circumstances. So far from its requiring an effort to put them forth, it would rather, require an effort to prevent them, when the mind is intensely considering those objects and consider- ations which have a natural tendency to produce them. This is so true, that when persons are in the exercise of such affections, they feel no diffi- culty at all in their exercise, but wonder how any one can help feeling as they do. It seems to them so natural, so easy, and, I may say, so almost unavoidable, that they often feel and express astonishment, that any one should find it diflBcult to exercise the feelings of which they are conscious. The course that many persons take on the subject of religion, has often appeared wonderful to me. They make themselves, their own state and interests, the central point, around which their own minds are continu- ally revolving. Their selfishness is so great, that their own interests, happiness, and salvation, fill their whole field of vision. And with their thoughts and anxieties, and whole souls, clustering around their own sal- vation, they complain of a hard heart, that they cannot love God, that they do not repent, and cannot believe. They manifestly regard love to God, repentance, faith, and all religion, as consisting in mere feelings. Being conscious that they do not feel right, as they express it, they are the more concerned about themselves, which concern but increases their embarrassment, and the diflSculty of exercising what they call right affec- tions. The less they feel, the more they try to feel — the greater efforts they make to feel right without success, the more are they confirmed in their selfishness, and the more are their thoughts glued to their own in- terests ; and they are, of course, at a greater and greater distance from any right state of mind. And thus their selfish anxieties beget in- effectual efforts, and these efforts but deepen their anxieties. And if in this state, death should appear in a visible form before them, or the last trumpet sound^, and they should be summoned to the solemn judg- ment, it would but increase their distraction, confirm, and almost give omnipotence to their selfishness, and render their sanctification morally impossible. It should never be forgotten, that all true religion conBidti SANCtmOATlON. 435 in voluntary states of mind, and that the true and only way to attain to true religion, is to look at and understand the exact thing to be done, and then to put forth at once the voluntary exercise required. 4. Not by any efforts to obtain grace by works of law. Should the question be proposed to a Jew, " What shall I do that I may work the work of God ? " he would answer, Keep the law, both moral and ceremonial ; that is, keep the commandments. To the same inquiry an Arminian would answer, Improve common grace, and you will obtam converting grace ; that ii, aae the means oi grace according to the best light you have, and you will obtain the grace of salvation. In this answer it is not supposed, that the inquirer already has faith ; but that he is in a state of unbelief, and is inquiring after converting grace. The answer, therefore, amounts to this ; you must get converting grace by your impenitent works ; you must become holy by your hypocrisy ; you must work out sanctification by sin. To this question, most professed Calvinists would make in substance the same reply. They would reject the language, while they retained the idea. Their direction wouid imply, either that the inquirer already has faith, or that he must perform some works to obtain it, that is, that he must obtain grace by works of law. A late Calvinistic writer admits that entire and permanent sanctifica- tion is attainable!, although he rejects the idea of the actual attainniom of such a state in this life. He supposes the condition of attaining this state or the way to attain it, is by a diligent use of the means of grace, and that the saints are sanctified just so far as they make a diligent use of the means of sanctification. But as he denies, that any saints ever did or will use all the means with suitable diligence, he denies also, of course, that entire sanctification ever is attained in this life. The way of attaining it, according to his teaching, is by the diligent use of means. If then this writer were asked, " what shall I do that I may work the works of God ?" — or in other words what shall I do to obtain entire and permanent sanctiiication ? his answer, it seems, would be : "Use dili- gently all the means of grace ;" that is, you must get grace by works, or, with the Arminian, improve common grace, and you will secure sanctify- ing grace. Neither an Arminian, nor a Calvinist, would formally direct the inquirer to the law, as thp jround of justification. But nearly th« whole church would give directions that would amount to the same thing. Their answer would be a legal and not a gospel answer. For whatevei answer is given to this question, that does not distinctly recognize faith as the condition of abiding holiness in Christians, is legal. Unless the inquirer is made to understand, that this is the first, grand, fundamental duty, without the performance of which all virtue, all giving up of sin, til acceptable obedience, is impossible, he is misdirected. He is led to 436 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. believe that it is possible to please God without faith, and to obtain grace by works of law. There are but two kinds of works — works of law, and works of faith. Now, if the inquirer has not the " faith that works by love," to set him upon any course of works to get it, is certainly to set him to get faith by works of law. Whatever is said to him that does not clearly convey the truth, that both justification and sanctifleation are by faith, without works of law, is law, and not gospel. Nothing before or without faith, can possibly be done by any one, but works of law. His first duty, therefore, is faith ; and every attempt to obtain faith by un- believing works, is to lay works at the foundation, and make grace a re- sult. It is the direct opposite of gospel truth. Take facts as they arise in every day's experience to show that what I have stated is true of almost all professors and non-professors. When- ever a sinner begins in good earnest to agitate the question, " What shall I do to be saved ?" he resolves as a first duty, to break off from his sins, that is, in unbelief. Of course, his reformation is only outward. He determines to do better — to reform in this, that, and the other thing, and thus prepare himself to be converted. He does not expect to be saved without grace and faith, but he attempts to get grace by works of law. The same is true of multitudes of anxious Christians, who are in- quiring what they shall do to overcome the world, the flesh, and the devil. They overlook the fact, that " this is the victory that overcometh the world, even our faith," that it is with "the shield of faith " they are "to quench all the fiery darts of the wicked." They ask. Why am lover- some by sin ? Why can I not get above its power ? Why am I thus the slave of my appetites and passions, and the sport of the devil ? They cast about for the cause of all this spiritual wretchedness and death. At one time, they think they have discovered it in the neglect of one duty ; and at another time in the neglect of another. Sometimes they imagine they have found the cause to lie in yielding to one temptation, and sometimes in yielding to another. They put forth efforts in this direction, and in that direction, and patch up their righteousness on one side, while they make a rent in the other side. Thus they spend years in running round in a circle, and making dams of sand across the current of their own habitudes and tendencies. Instead of at once purifying their hearts by faith, they are engaged in trying to arrest the overflowing of the bitter waters of their own propensities. Why do I sin ? they inquire ; and casting about for the cause, they come to the sage conclusion. It is be- cause I neglect such a duty, that is, because I do sin. But how shall I get rid of sin ? Answer : By doing my duty, that is, by ceasing from sin. Now the real inquiry is, Why do they neglect their duty ? Why do they commit sin at all ? Where is the foundation of all this mischief? Will it be replied, the foundation of all this wickedness is the force of SANCTIFICATION. 437 temptation — in the weakness of our hearts — in the strength of our evil propensities and habits ? But all this only brings us back to the real inquiry again, How are these things to be overcome ? I answer, by faith alone. No works of law have the least tendency to overcome our sins ; but rather to confirm the soul in self-righteousness and unbelief. The great and fundamental sin, which is at the foundation of all ithcr sin, is unbelief. The first thing is, to give up that — to believe the vrord of God. There is no breaking off from one sin without this. "Whatsoever is not of faith is sin." "Without faith it is impossible to please God." Thus we see, that the backslider and convicted sinner, when agonizing to overcome sin, will almost always betake themselves to works of law to obtain faith. They will fast, and pray, and read, and struggle, and outwardly reform, and thus endeavor to obtain grace. Now all this is vain and wrong. Do you ask, shall we not fast, and pray, and read, and struggle ? Shall we do nothing but sit down in antino- miau secKrity and inaction ? I answer, you must do all that God com- mands you to do ; but begin where he tells you to begin, and do it in the manner in which he commands you to do it ; that is, in the exercise of that faith that works by love. Purify your hearts by faith. Believe in the Son of God. And say not in your heart, " Who shall ascend into heaven, that is to bring Christ down from above ; or who shall descend into the deep, that is, to bring up Christ again from the dead. But what saith it ? The word is nigh thee, even in thy mouth, and in thy heart, that is, the word of faith which we preach." Now these facts show, that even under the gospel, almost all professors of religion, while they reject the Jewish notion of justification by works of law, have after all adopted a ruinous substitute for it, and suppose, that in some way they are to obtain grace by their works. 5. A state of entire sanctification cannot be attained by attempting to copy the experience of others. It is very common for convicted sinners, or for Christians inquiring after entire sanctification, in their blindness, to ask others to relate their experience, to mark minutely the detail of all their exercises, and then set themselves to pray for, and make direct efforts to attain the same class o-f exercises, not seeming to understand, that they can no more exorcise feelings in the detail like others, than they can look like others. Human experiences differ as human countenances differ. The whole history of a man's former state of mind, comes in of course to modify his present and future experience ; so that the precise train of feelings which may be requisite in your case, and which will act- aaliy occur, if you are ever sanctified, will not in all its details coincide with the exercises of any other human being. It is of vast importance for you to understand, that you can be no copyist in any true religious experience ; and that you are in great danger of being deceived by Satan. *38 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. whenever yon attempt to copy the experience of others. I beseech you therefore to cease from praying for, or trying to obtain, the precise experience of any person whatever. All truly Christian experiences are, like human countenances, in their outline so much alike as to be readily known as the lineaments of the religion of Jesus Christ. But no further than this are they alike, any more than human countenances are alike. But here let it be remembered, that sanctification does not consist in the various affections or emotions of which Christians speak, and which are often mistaken for, or confounded with, true religion ; but that sanctification consists in entire consecration, and consequently it is all out of place for any one to attempt to copy the feelings of another, inas- much as feelings do not constitute religion. The feelings of which Christians speak do not constitute true religion, but often result from a state of heart. These feelings may properly enough be spoken of as Christian experience, for although involuntary states of mind, they are experienced by true Christians. The only way to secure them is to set the will right, and the emotions will be a natural result. 6. Not by waiting to make preparations before you come into this state. Observe, that the thing about which you are inquiring, is a state of entire consecration to God. Now do not imagine that this state of mind must be prefaced by a long introduction of preparatory exercises. It is common for persons, when inquiring upon this subject with earnestness, to think themselves hindered in this progress by a want of this, or that, or the other exercise or state of mind. They look everywhere else but at the real difficulty. They assign any other, and every other but the true reason, for their not being already in a state of sanctification. The true difficulty is voluntary selfishness, or voluntary consecration to self- interest and self-gratification. This is the difficulty, and the only difficulty, to be overcome. 7. Not by attending meetings, asking the prayers of other Chris- tians, or depending in any way upon the means of getting into this state. By this I do not intend to say, that means are unnecessary, or that it is not through the instrumentality of truth, that this state of mind is induced. But I do mean, that while you are depending upon any instrumentality whatever, your mind is diverted from the real point before you, and you are never likely to make this attainment. 8. Not by waiting for any particular views of Christ. When persons in the state of mind of which I have been speaking, hear those who live in faith describe their views of Christ, they say, Oh, if I had such views, I could believe ; I must have these before I can believe. Now you should understand, that these views are the result and effect of faith in the promise of the Spirit, to take of the things of Christ and show them to you. Lay hold of this class of promises, and the Holy Spirit will reveal SANCTIFICATION. 439 Christ to you, in the relations in which you need him from time to time. Take hold, then, on the simple promise of God. Take God at his word. Believe that he means just what he says ; and this will at once bring you into the state of mind after which you inquire. 9. Not in any way which you may mark out for yourself. Persons in an inquiring state are very apt, without seeming to be aware of it, to send imagination on before them, to stake out the way, and set up a flag where they intend to come out. They expect to be thus and thus exer- cised — to have such and such peculiar views and feelings when they have attained their object. Now, there probably never was a person who did not find himself disappointed in these respects. God says, " I will bring the blind by a way that they know not. I will lead them in paths that they have not known : I will make darkness light before them, and crooked things straight. These things will I do unto them, and not forsake them." This suffering your imagination to mark out your path is a great hindrance to you, as it sets you upon making many fruitless, and worse than fruitless attempts to attain this imaginary state of mind, wastes much of your time, and greatly wearies the patience and grieves the Spirit of God. While he is trying to lead you right to the point, you are hauling off from the course, and insisting, that this which your imagination has marked out is the way, instead of that in which he is trying to lead you. And thus in your pride and ignorance you are causing much delay, and abusing the long-suffering of God. He says, " This is the way, walk ye in it." But you say, no — this is the way. And thus you stand and parley and banter, while you are every mo- ment in danger of grieving the Spirit of God away from you, and of losing your soul. If there is anything in your imagination that has fixed definitely upon any particular manner, time, or place, or circumstance, you will, in all probability, either be deceived by the devil, or be entirely disappointed in the result. You will find, in all these particular items on which you had laid any stress, that the wisdom of man is foolishness with God — that your ways are not his ways, nor your thoughts his thoughts. " For as the heavens are higher than the earth, so are his ways higher than your ways and his thoughts higher than your thoughts." But, — 10. This state is to be attained by faith alone. Let it be for ever re- membered, that "without faith it is impossible to please God," and " whatsoever is not of faith, is sin." Both justification and sanctification are by faith alone. Kom. iii. 30 : " Seeing it is one God who shall justify the circumcision by faith, and the uncircumcision through faith ;" and ch. v. 1 : " Therefore, being justified by faith, we have peace with God, through our Lord Jesus Christ." Also, ch. ix. 30, 31 ; " What shall we Bay then ? That the Gentiles, who followed not after righteousness, have 4:40 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. attained to righteousness, even the righteousness which is of faith. Bat Israel, who followed after the law of righteousness, hath not attained to the law of righteousness. Wherefore ? Because they sought it not by faith, but, as it were, by the works of the law." But let me by no means be understood as teaching sanctiflcation by faith, as distinct from and opposed to sanctiflcation by the Holy Spirit, or Spirit of Christ, or which is the same thing, by Christ our sanctiflca- tion, living and reigning in the heart. Faith is rather the instrument or condition, than the efiBcient agent that induces a state of present and permanent sanctiflcation. Faith simply receives Christ, as king, to live and reign in the soul. It is Christ, in the exercise of his different offices, and appropriated in his different relations to the wants of the soul, by faith, who secures our sanctiflcation. This he does by Divine discoveries to the soul of his Divine perfections and fulness. The condition of these discoveries is faith and obedience. He says, John xiv. 21-23 : "He that hath my commandments, and keepeth them, he it is that loveth me ; and he that loveth me shall be loved of my Father, and I wiU love him, and will manifest myself to him. Judas saith unto him, (not Iscariot,) Lord, how is it that thou wilt manifest thyself unto us, and not unto the world ? Jesus answered and said unto him. If a man love me, he will keep my words : and my Father will love him, and we will come unto him, and make our abode with him." To ascertain the conditions of entire sanctiflcation in this life, we must consider what the temptations are that overcome us. When first converted, we have seen, that the heart or will consecrates itself and the whole being to God. We have also seen, that this is a state of disinter- ested benevolence, or a committal of the whole being to the promotion of the highest good. We have also seen, that all sin is selfishness, or that all sin consists in the will's seeking the indulgence or gratification of self ; that it consists in the will's yielding obedience to the propensities, instead of obeying God, as his law is revealed in the reason. Now, who cannot see what needs to be done to break the power of temptation, and let the soul go free ? The fact is, that the department of our sensibility that is related to objects of time and sense, has received an enormous develop- ment, and is tremblingly alive to all its correlated objects, while, by reason of the blindness of the mind to spiritual objects, it is scarcely developed at all in its relations to them. Those objects are seldom thought of by the carnal mind, and when they are, they are only thought of. They are not clearly seen, and of course they are not felt. The thought of God, of Christ, of sin, of holiness, of heaven, and hell,excites little or no emotion in the carnal mind. The carnal mind is alive and awake to earthly and sensible objects, but dead to spiritual realities. The spiritual world needs to be revealed to the souL The SANCTIFICATION 441 soul needs to see and clearly apprehend its own spiritual condition, rela- tions, wants. It needs to become acquainted with God and Christ, to have spiritual and eternal realities made plain, and present, and all-absorbing realities to the soul. It needs such discoveries of the eternal world, of the nature and guilt of sin, and of Christ, the remedy of the soul, as to kill or greatly mortify lust, or the appetites and passions in their relations to objects of time and sense, and thoroughly to develop the sensibility, in its relations to sin and to God, and to the whole circle of spiritual realities. This will greatly abate the frequency and power of temptation to self-gratification, and break up the voluntary slavery of the will. The developments of the sensibility need to be thoroughly corrected. This can only be done by the revelation to the inward man, by the Holy Spirit, of those great, and solemn, and overpowering realities of the " spirit land," that lie concealed from the eye of flesh. We often see those around us whose sensibility is so developed, in some one direction, that they are led captive by appetite and passion in that direction, in spite of reason and of God. The inebriate is an exam- ple of this. The glutton, the licentious, the avaricious man, are exam- ples of this kind. We sometimes, on the other hand, see, by some striking providence, such a counter development of the sensibility pro- duced, as to slay and put down those particular tendencies, and the whole direction of the man's life seems to be changed ; and outwardly, at least, it is so. Prom being a perfect slave to his appetite for strong drink, he cannot, without the utmost loathing and disgust, so much as hear the name of his once loved beverage mentioned. From being a most avari- cious man he becomes deeply disgusted with wealth, and spurns and despises it. Now, this has been effected by a counter development of the sensibility ; for, in the case supposed, religion has nothing to do with it. Eeligion does not consist in the states of the sensibility, nor in the will's being influenced by the sensibility ; but sin consists in the will's being thus influenced. One great thing that needs to be done, to confirm and settle the will in the attitude of entire consecration to God, is to bring about a counter development of the sensibility. Bo that it will not draw the will away from God. It needs to be mortified or crucified to the world, to objects of time and sense, by so deep and clear, and powerful a revela- tion of self to self, and of Christ to the soul, as to awaken and develop all its susceptibilities in their relations to him, and to spiritual and divine realities. This can easily be done through and by the Holy Spirit, who takes of the things of Christ and shows them to us. He so reveals Christ, that the soul receives him to the throne • of the heart, to i-eign throughout the whole being. When the will, the intellect, and the sensi- bility are yielded to him, he develops the intelligence, and the sensibil- itjjr by plesr revpjstiops pf bimsejf, iii all Ijis ofl^ces a.nd relations to the 442 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Bou], confirms the will, mellows and chastens the sensibility, by these divine revelations to the intelligence. We need the light of the Holy Spirit to teach ns the character of God, the nature of his government, the purity of his law, the necessity and fact of atonement — to teach us our need of Christ in all his oflSces and relations, governmental, spiritual, and mixed. We need the revelation of Christ to our souls, in such power as to induce in us that appropriat- ing faith, without which Christ is not, and cannot be, our salvation. We need to know Christ, for example, in such relations as the following : — 1. As King, to set up his government and write his law in our hearts ; to establish his kingdom within us ; to sway his sceptre over our whole being. As King he must be spiritually revealed and received. 2. As our Mediator, to stand between the offended justice of God and our guilty souls, to bring about a reconciliation between our souls and God. As Mediator he must be known and received. 3. Ab our Advocate or Paracleios, our next or best friend, to plead our cause with the Father, our righteous and all prevailing advocate to secure the triumph of our cause at the bar of God. In this relation he must be apprehended and embraced. 4. As our Kedeemer, to redeem us from the curse of the law, and from the power and dominion of sin ; to pay the price demanded by pub- lic justice for our release, and to overcome and break up forever our spiritual bondage. In this relation also we must know and appreciate him by faith. 5. As the propitiation for our sins, to offer himself as a propitiatory or offering for our sins. The apprehension of Christ as making an atone- ment for our sins seems to be indispensable to the entertaining of a healthy hope of eternal life. It certainly is not healthy for the sonl to apprehend the mercy of God, without regarding the conditions of its exercise. It does not sufficiently impress the soul with a sense of the justice and holiness of God, with the guilt and desert of sin. It does not sufficiently awe the soul and humble it in the deepest dust, to regard God as extending pardon, without regard to the sternness of his justice, as evinced in requiring that sin should be recognized in the universe, as worthy of the wrath and curse of God, as a condition of its forgiveness. It is remarkable, and well worthy of all consideration, that those who deny the atonement make sin a comparative trifle, and seem to regard God's benevolence or love as good nature, rather than, as it is, " a con- suming fire " to all the workers of iniquity. Nothing does or can pro- dace that awe of God, that fear and holy dread of sin, that self-abasing, God-justifying spirit, that a thorough apprehension of the atonement of Christ will do. Nothing like this can beget that spirit of self-renuncia- tion, of cleaving to Christ, of taking refuge in his blood. Ip these r?la- SANCTIFICATION. 443 tiona Christ must be revealed to us, and apprehended and embraced by us, as the condition of our entire sanctification. It is the work of the Holy Spirit thus to reveal his death in its rela- tions to our individual sins, and as related to our sins as individuals. The soul needs to apprehend Christ as crucified for us. It is one thing for the soul to regard the death of Christ merely as the death of a martyr, and an infinitely different thing, as every one knows, who has had the experience, to apprehend his death as a real and veritable vica- rious sacrifice for our sins, as being truly a substitute for our death. The soul needs to apprehend Christ as suffering on the cross for it, or as its substitute ; so that it can say. That sacrifice is for me, that suffering and that death are for my sins ; that blessed Lamb is slain for my sins. If thus fully to apprehend and to appropriate Christ cannot kill sin in us, what can ? 6. We also need to know Christ as risen for our justification. He arose and lives to procure our certain acquittal, or our complete pardon and acceptance with God. That he lives, and is our justification we need to know, to break the bondage of legal motives, and to sJay all selfish fear ; to break and destroy the power of temptation from this source. The clearly convinced soul is often tempted to despondency and unbelief, to despair of its own acceptance with God, and it would surely fall into the bondage of fear, were it not for the faith of Christ as a risen, living, jus- tifying Saviour. In this relation, the soul needs clearly to apprehend and fully to appropriate Christ in his completeness, as a condition of abiding in a state of disinterested consecration to God. 7. We need also to have Christ revealed to us as bearing our griefs ' and as carrying our sorrows. The clear apprehension of Christ, as being made sorrowful for us, and as bending under sorrows and griefs which in justice belonged to us, tends at once to render sin unspeakably odious, and Christ infinitely precious to our souls. The idea of Christ our sub- stitute, needs to be thoroughly developed in our minds. And this rela- tion of Christ needs to be so clearly revealed to us, as to become an everywhere present reality to us. We need to have Christ so revealed as to so completely ravish and engross our affections, that we would sooner die at once than sin against him. Is such a thing impossible ? Indeed it is not. Is not the Holy Spirit able, and willing, and ready thus, to reveal him, upon condition of our asking it in faith ? Surely he is. We need to apprehend Christ as the one by whose stripes we are healed. We need to know him as relieving our pains and sufferings by his own, as preventing our death by his own, as sorrowing that we might eternally rejoice, as grieving that we might be unspeakably and eternally glad, as dying in unspeakable agony that wo might die in deep peace ni^^ 'm unspeakable triumph. 444 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. 8. "As being made sin for us." We need to apprehend him as being treated as a sinner, and even as the chief of sinners on our account, or for us. This is the representation of scripture, that Christ on our ac- count was treated as if he were a sinner. He was made sin for us, that is, he was treated as a sinner, or rather as being the representative, or as it were the embodiment of sin for us. I this the soul needs to appre- hend — the holy Jesus treated as a sinner, and as if all sin were concen- trated in him, on our account ! We procured this treatment of him. He consented to take our place in such a sense as to endure the cross, and the curse of the law for us. When the soul apprehends this, it is ready to die with grief and love. 0, how infinitely it loathes self under such an apprehension as this ! In this relation he must not only be ap- prehended, but appropriated by faith. We also need to apprehend the fact that " he was made sin for us, that we might be made the righteousness of God in him ;" that Christ was treated as a sinner, that we might be treated as righteous ; that we might also be made personally righteous by faith in him ; that we might inherit and be made partakers of God's righteousness, as that righteous- ness exists and is revealed in Christ ; that we might in and by him be made righteous as God is righteous. It needs to embrace and lay hold by faith upon that righteousness of God, which is brought home to saints in Christ, through the atonement and indwelling Spirit. 9. We also need Christ revealed to the inward being, as " head over all things to the church." All these relations are of no avail to our sanctiBcation, only in so far forth as they are directly, and inwardly, and personally revealed to the soul by the Holy Spirit. It is one thing to have thoughts, and ideas, and opinions concerning Christ, and an entirely different thing to know Christ, as he is revealed by the Holy Spirit. All the relations of Christ imply corresponding necessities in us. When the Holy Spirit has revealed to us the necessity, and Christ as exactly suited to fully meet that necessity, and urged his acceptance in that relation, until we have appropriated him by faith, a great work is done. But until we are thus revealed to ourselves, and Christ is thus revealed to us and accepted by us, nothing is done more than to store our heads with notions or opinions and theories, while our hearts are becoming more and more, at every moment, like an adamant stone. I have often feared, that many professed Christians knew Christ only after the flesh ; that is, they have no other knowledge of Christ than what they obtain by reading and hearing about him, without any special rev- elation of him to the inward being by the Holy Spirit. I do not won- der, that such professors and ministers should be totally in the dark, upon the subject of entire sauctification in this life. They regard sane- tiflcation as brought about by the fornjation of holy habits, in8J;ea4 of SANCTIFICATION. 445 reBulting from the revelation of Christ to the soul in all his fulness and relations, and the soul's renunciation of self and appropriation of Christ in these relations. Christ is represented in the Bible as the head of the church. The church is represented as his body. He is to the church what the head is to the body. The head is the seat of the intel- lect, the will, and in short, of the living soul. Consider what the body would be without the head, and you may understand what the church would be without Christ. But as the church would be without. Christ, so each believer would be without Christ. But we need to have our necessities in this respect clearly revealed to us by the Holy Spirit,- and this relation of Christ made plain to our apprehension. The utter dark- ness of the human mind in regard to its own spiritual state and wants, and in regard to the relations and fulness of Christ, is truly wonderful. His relations, as mentioned in the Bible, are overlooked almost entirely until our wants are discovered. When these are made known, and the soul begins in earnest to inquire after a remedy, it needs not inquire in vain. " Say not in thine heart, who shall ascend up to heaven ? that is, to bring Christ down from above ; or who shall descend into the deep ? that is, to bring Christ again from the dead. But what saith it ? The word is nigh thee, even in thy mouth, and in thy heart." how infinitely blind he is to the fulness and glory of Christ, who does not know himself and Christ as both are revealed by the Holy Spirit. When we are led by the Holy Spirit to look down into the abyss of our own emptiness — to behold the horrible pit and miry clay of our own habits, and fleshly, and worldly, and infernal entanglements ; when we see in the light of God, that our emptiness and necessities are infinite ; then, and not till then, are we prepared wholly to cast off self, and to put on Christ. The glory and fulness of Christ are not discovered to the soul, until it discovers its need of him. But when self, in all its loathsomeness and helplessness, is fully revealed, until hope is utterly extinct, as it respects every kind and degree of help in ourselves ; and when Christ, the all and in all, is revealed to the soul as its all-sufiioient portion and salvation, then, and not until then, does the soul know its salvation. This knowledge is the indispensable condition of appropriat- ing faith, or of that act of receiving Christ, or that committal of all to him, that takes Christ home to dwell in the heart by faith, and to pre- side over all its states and actions. 0, such a knowledge and such a re- ception and putting on of Christ is blessed. Happy is he who knows it by his own experience. It is indispensable to a steady and implicit faith, that the soul should have a spiritual apprehension of what is implied in the saying of Christ, that all power was delivered unto him. The ability of Christ to do all, and even exceeding abundantly above all that we ask oi think, is what iiQ SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. the soul needs clearly to apprehend, in a spiritual sense that is, \o appre- hend it, not merely as a theory or as a proposition, but to see the true spiritual import of this saying. This is also equally true of all that is said in the Bible about Christ, of all his oflBces and relations. It is one thing to theorize, and speculate, and opine, about Christ, and an in- finitely different thing to know him as he is revealed by the Holy Spirit, When Christ is fully revealed to the soul by the Comforter, it -will never again doubt the attainability and reality of entire sanctification in this life. When we sin, it is because of our ignorance of Christ. That is, whenever temptation overcomes us, it is because we do not know and avail ourselves of the relation of Christ that would meet our necessities. One great thing that needs to be done is, to correct the developments of our sensibility. The appetites and passions are enormously developed in their relations to earthly objects. In relation to things of time and sense, our propensities are greatly developed and are alive ; but in rela- tion to spiritual truths and objects, and eternal realities, we are naturally as dead as stones. When first converted, if we knew enough of our- selves and of Christ thoroughly to develop and correct the action of the sensibility, and confirm our wills in a state of entire consecration, we should not fall. In proportion as the law- work preceding conversion has been thorough, and the revelation of Christ at, or immediately subse- quent to, conversion, full and clear, just in that proportion do we wit- ness stability in converts. In most, if not in all instances, however, the convert is too ignorant of himself, and of course knows too little about Christ, to be established in permanent obedience. He needs renewed conviction of sin, to be revealed to himself, and to have Christ revealed to him, and be formed in him the hope of glory, before he will be stead- fast, always abounding in the work of the Lord. It must not be inferred, that the knowledge of Christ in all these re- lations is a condition of our coming into a state of entire consecration to God, or of present sanctification. The thing insisted on is. that the soul will abide in this state in the hour of temptation only so far forth as it betakes itself to Christ in such circumstances of trial, and apprehends and appropriates him by faith from time to time in those relations that meet the present and pressing necessities of the soul. The temptation is the occasion of revealing the necessity, and the Holy Spirit is always ' ready to reveal Christ in the particular relation suited to the newly- developed necessity. The perception and appropriation of him in this relation, under these circumstances of trial, is the sine qud non of our remaining in the state of entire consecration. The foregoing are some of the relations which Christ sustains to us as to our salvation. I could have enlarged greatly, as you perceive, upon SANCTIPICATION. 447 « each of these, and easily haye swelled this part of our course of study to a large volume. I have only touched upon these relations, as specimens of the manner in which he is presented for our acceptance in the Bible, and by the Holy Spirit. Do not understand me as teaching, that we must first know Christ in all these relations, before we can be sanctified. The thing intended is, that coming to know Christ in these relations is a condition, or is the indispensable means, of our steadfastness or persever- ance in holiness under temptation — that, when we are tempted, from time to time nothing can secure us against a fall, but the revelation of Christ to the soul in these relations one after another, and our appropriation of him to ourselves by faith. The gospel has directly promised, in every temptation to open a way of escape, so that we shall be able to bear it. The spirit of this promise pledges to us such a revelation of Christ, as to secure our standing, if we will lay hold upon him by faith, as revealed. Our circumstances of temptation render it necessary, that at one time we should apprehend Christ in one relation, and at another time in another. For example, at one time we are tempted to despair by Satan's accusing us of sin, and suggesting that our sins are too great to be forgiven. In this case we need a revelation and an appropriation of Christ, as having been made sin for us ; that is, as having atoned for our sins — as being our justification or righteousness. This will sustain the soul's confidence and preserve its peace. At another time we are tempted to despair of ever overcoming our tendencies to sin, and to give up our sanctification as a hopeless thing. Now we need a revelation of Christ as our sanctification, etc. At another time the soul is harassed with the view of the great sub- tlety and sagacity of its spiritual enemies, and greatly tempted to despair on that account. Now it needs to know Christ as its wisdom. Again, it is tempted to discouragement on account of the great num- ber and strength of its adversaries. On such occasions it needs Christ revealed as the Mighty God, as its strong tower, its hiding place, its munition of rocks. Again, the soul is oppressed with a sense of the infinite holiness of God, and the infinite distance there is between us and God, on account of our sinfulness and his infinite holiness, and on account of his infinite abhorrence of sin and sinners. Now the soul needs to know Christ as its righteousness, and as a mediator between God and man. Again, the Christian's month is closed with a sense of guilt, so that he oannot look up, nor speak to God of pardon and acceptance. He trembles and is confounded before God. He lies along on his face, and despairing thoughts roll a tide of agony through his soul. He is speech- less, and can only groan out his self-accusations before the Lord. Now as a condition of rising above this temptation to despair, he needs a 448 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. revelation of Christ as his advocate, as his high priest, as ever liring tc make intercession for him. This view of Christ will enable the soul to commit all to him in this relation, and maintain its peace and hold on to its steadfastness. Again, the soul is led to tremble in view of its constant exposedness to besetments on every side, oppressed with such a sense of its own utter helplessness in the presence of its enemies, as almost to despair. Now it needs to know Christ as the good shepherd, who keeps a constant watch over the sheep, and carries the lambs in his bosom. He needs to know him as a watchman and a keeper. Again, it is oppressed with the sense of its own utter emptiness, and is forced to exclaim, I know that in me, that is, in my flesh, dwelleth no good thing. It sees that it has no life, or unction, or power, or spiritual- ity in itself. Now it needs to know Christ as the true vine, from which it may receive constant and abundant spiritual nourishment. It needs to know him as the fountain of the water of life, and in those relations that will meet its necessities in this direction. Let these suflSce, as specimens to illustrate what is intended by entire or permanent sanctification being conditioned on the revelation and appropriation of Christ in aU the ful- ness of his official relations. LECTURE XL. SANCTIFICATION. VI. Objections answered. I will consider those passages of scripture which are by some supposed to contradict the doctrine we have been considering. 1 Kings viii. 46 : "If they sin against thee, (for there is no man that sinneth not,) and thou be angry with them, and deliver them to the enemy, so that they carry them away captives unto the land of the enemy, far or near," etc. On this passage, I remark : — 1. That this sentiment in nearly the same language, is repeated in 2 Chron. vi. 26, and in Eccl. vii. 20, where the same original word in the same form is used. 3. These are the strongest passages I know of in the Old Testament, and the same remarks are applicable to the three. 3. I will quote, for the satisfaction of the reader, the note of Dr. Adam Clarke upon this passage, and also that of Barclay, the celebrated and highly spiritual author of " An Apology for the True Christian Di- SANCTIPICATION. *4y tinity." And let me say, that they appear to me to be satisfactotji answers to the objection founded upon these passages. Clakke : " ' If they sin against thee.' — This must refer to some gen- eral defection from truth ; to some species of false worship, idolatry, or corruption of the truth and ordinances of the Most High ; as for it, they are here stated to be delivered into the hands of their enemies, and car- ried away captive, which was the general punishment of idolatry, and what is called, [verse 47,] acting perversely and committing wickedness. "'If they sin against thee, for there is no man that sinneth not.' The second clause, as it is here translated, renders the supposition in the first clause, entirely nugatory ; for, if there be no man that sinneth not, it is useless to say, if they sin ; but this contradiction is taken away, by reference to the original ki yechetau lah, which should be translated, if they shall sin against th'ee ; or should they sin against thee,,fo" ein adam asher lo yechetaj 'for there is no man that may not sin ; ' that is, there is no man impeccable, none infallible j none that is not liable to trans- gress. This is the true meaning of the phrase in various parts of the Bible, and so our translators have understood the original, for even in the thirty-first verse of this chapter, they have translated yecheta, if a man trespass ; which certainly implies he might or might not do it ; and in this way they have translated the same word, if a soul sin, in Lev. v. 1, and vi. 3 ; 1 Sam. ii. 25 ; 3 Ohron. iv. 22 ; and in several other places. The truth is, the Hebrew has no mood to express words in the permissive or optative way, but to express this sense it uses the future tense of the conjugation kal. " This text has been a wonderful strong-hold for all who believe that there is no redemption from sin in this life ; that no man can live with- out committing sin ; and that we cannot be entirely freed from it till we die. " 1. The text speaks no such doctrine ; it only speaks of the possibility of every man's sinning ; and this must be true of a state ol probation. "2. There is not another text in the divine records that is more to the purpose than this. " 3. The doctrine is flatly in opposition to the design of the gospel ; for Jesus came to save his people from their sins, and to destroy the works of the devil. " 4. It is a dangerous and destructive doctrine, and should be blotted out of every Christian's creed. There are too many who are seeking to excuse their crimes by all means in their power ; and we need not embody their excuses in a creed, to complete their deception, by stating that their sins are unavoidable." Baeclat : " Secondly, — Another objection is from two passages of ecripture, much of one signification. The one is 1 Kings viii. 46 : * For 29 ^ 450 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOaY. there is no man that sinneth not.' The other is Eccl. vii. 20 : ' For there is not a just man upon earth, that doeth good and sinneth not.' " I answer, — " 1. These aflBrm nothing of a daily and continual sinning, so as ncYer to he redeemed from it ; but only that all have sinned, that there is none that doth not sin, though not, always so as never to cease to sin ; and in this lies the question. Yea, in that place of the Kings he speaks within two verses of the returning of such with all their souls and hearts, which implies a possibility of leaving off sin. " 2. There is a respect to be had to the seasons and dispensations ; for if it should be granted that in Solomon's time there were none that sinned not, it will not follow that there are none such now, or that it is a thing not now attainable by the grace of God under the gospeL " 3. And lastly, this whole objection hangs upot a false interpretation ; for the original Hebrew word may be read in the potential mood, thus, — There is no man who may not sin, as well as in the indicative ; so both the old Latin, Junius, and Tremellius, and Vatablus have it, and the same word is so used, Ps. cxix, 11 : ' Thy word have I hid in my heart, that I might not sin against thee ' — in the potential mood, and not in the indicative : which being more answerable to the universal scope of the scriptures, the testimony of the truth, and the sense of almost all interpreters, doubtless ought to be so understood, and the other interpre- tation rejected as spurious." Whatever may be thought of the views of these authors, to me it is a plain and satisfactory answer to the objection founded upon these passa- ges, that the objection might be strictly true under the Old Testament dispensation, and prove nothing in regard to the attainability of a state of entire sanctification under the New. "What ! does the New Testament dispensation differ nothing from the Old in its advantages for the acqui- sition of holiness ? If it be true, that no one under the comparatively dark dispensation of Judaism, attained a state of permanent sanctifica- tion, does that prove such a state is not attainable under the gospel ? It is expressly stated in the Epistle to the Hebrews, that " the old covenant made nothing perfect, but the bringing in of abetter hope did." Under the old covenant, God expressly promised that he would make a new one with the house of Israel, in "writing the law in their hearts," and in " engraving it in their inward parts." And this new covenant was to be made with the house of Israel, under the Christian dispensation. What then do all such passages in the Old Testament prove, in relation to the privileges and holiness of Christians under the new dispensation ? Whether any of the Old Testament saints did so far receive the new Covenant by way of anticipation, as to enter upon a state of permanent sanctification, it is not my present purpose to inquire. Nor will I in SANCTIPICATION. 451 quire, whether, admitting that Solomou said in his day, that there was not a just man upon the earth that liveth and sinneth not, the same could with equal truth have been asserted of every generation under the Jewish dispensation. It is expressly asserted of Abraham, and multi- tudes of the Old Testament saints, that they " died in faith, not having received the promises." Now what can this mean ? It cannot be, that they did not know the promises ; for to them the promises were made. It cannot mean, that they did not receive Christ, for the Bible expressly asserts that they did — that " Abraham rejoiced to see Christ's day " — that Moses, and indeed all the Old Testament saints, had so much knowledge of Christ as a Saviour to be revealed, as to bring them into a state of salvation. But still they did not receive the promise of the Spirit, as it is poured out under the Christian dispensation. This was the great thing all along promised, first to Abraham, or to his seed, which is Christ. Gal. iii. 14, 16 : "That the blessing of Abraham might come on the Gentiles through Jesus Christ ; that we might receive the prom- ise of the Spirit through faith." " Now to Abraham and his seed were the promises made. He saith not. And to seeds, as of many ; but as of one, and to thy seed, which is Christ ;" and afterwards to the Christian church, by all the prophets. Acts ii. 16-21 : " But this is that which was spoken by the prophet Joel ; And it shall come to pass in the last days (saith God,) I will pour out of my Spirit upon all fiesh, and your sons and your daughters shall prophesy, and your young men shall see visions, and your old men shall dream dreams ; and on my servants, and on my handmaidens, I will pour out in those days of my Spirit ; and they shall prophesy ; and I will show wonders in heaven above and signs in the earth beneath ; blood, and fire and vapor of smoke ; the sun shall be turned into darkness, and the moon into blood, before the great and notable day of the Lord come ; and it shall come to pass, that whosoever shall call on the name of the Lord shall be saved." Acts ii. 38, 39 : " Then Peter said unto them, Repent, and be baptized every one of you in the name of Jesus Christ for the remission of sins, and ye shall re- ceive the gift of the Holy Ghost. For the promise is unto you, and to your children, and to all that are afar off, even as many as the Lord our God shall call." Acts iii. 24, 26 : "Yea, and all the prophets from Samuel, and those that follow after, as many as have spoken, have likewise fore- told of these days." " Unto you first, God having raised up his Son Jesus, sent him to bless you, in turning away every one of you from his iniqui- ties;" and lastly, by Christ himself, which he expressly styles "the promise" of the Father. Acts i. 4, 5 : "And being assembled together with them, commanded them that they should not depart from Jerusa- lem, but wait for the promise of the Father, which, saith he, ye have heard of me. For John truly baptized with water ; but ye shall be ■'■■•4 462 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. baptized with the Holy Ghost not many days hence." They did not re- ceive the light and the glory of the Christian dispensation, nor the fal- ness of the Holy Spirit. And it is asserted in the Bible, " they without us," that is, without our privileges, "could not be made perfect." The next objection is founded upon the Lord's Prayer. In this Christ has taught us to pray, "Forgive us our trespasses as we forgive those who trespass against us." Here it is objected, that if a person should become entirely sanctified, he could no longer use this clause of this prayer, which, it is said, was manifestly designed to be used by the church to the end of time. Upon this prayer I remark : — 1. Christ has taught us to pray for entire, in the sense of perpetual sanctification. "Thy will be done on earth, as it is done in heaven." 2. He designed, that we should expect this prayer to be answered, or that we should mock him by asking what we do not believe is agreeable to his will, and that too which we know could not consistently be granted ; and that we are to repeat this insult to God as often as we pray. 3. The petition for forgiveness of our trespasses, it is plain, must apply to past sins, and not to sins we are committing at the time we make the prayer ; for it would be absurd and abominable to pray for the forgiveness of a sin which we are then in the act of committing. 4. This prayer cannot properly be made in respect to any sin of which we have not repented ; for it would be highly abominable in the sight of God, to pray for the forgiveness of a sin of which we did not repent. 5. If there be any hour or day in which a man has committed no actual sin, he could not consistently make this prayer in reference to that hour or that day. 6. But at the very time, it would be highly proper for him to make this prayer in relation to all his past sins, and that too, although he may have repented of, and confessed them, and prayed for their forgiveness, a thousand times before. This does not imply a doubt, whether God has forgiven the sins of which we have repented ; but it is only a renewal of our grief and humiliation for our sins, and a fresh acknowledgment of, and casting ourselves upon, his mercy. God may forgive when we re- pent, before we ask him, and while we abhor ourselves so much as to have no heart to ask for forgiveness ; but his having forgiven us does not ren- der the petition improper. 7. And although his sins may be forgiven, he ought still to confess them, to repent of them, both in this world and in the world to come. And it is perfectly suitable, so long as he lives in the world, to say the least, to continue to repent, and repeat the request for forgiveness. For myself, I am unable to see why this pd,ssage should be made a stumblings block ; for if it be improper to pray for the forgiveness of sins of which we have repented, then it is improper to pray for forgiveness at all. And 8ANCTIPICATI0N. iSS if this prayer cannot be used with propriety in reference to past sins of which we have already repented, it cannot properly be used at all, except upon the absurd supposition, that we are to pray for the forgiveness of sins which we are now committing, ^.nd of which we have not repented. And if it be improper to use this form of prayer in reference to all past sins of which we have repented, it is just as improper to use it in refer- ence to sins committed to-day or yesterday, of which we have repented. Another objection is founded on James iii, 1, 2 : " My brethren, be not many masters, knowing that we shall receive the greater condemna- tion. For in many things we offend all. If any man offend not in word, the same is a perfect man, and able also to bridle the whole body." Upon this passage I remark : — 1. The term rendered masters here, may be rendered teachers, critics, or censors, and be understood either in a good or bad sense. The apostle exhorts the brethren not to be many masters, because if they are so, they will incur the greater condemnation ; "for," says he, "in many things we offend all." The fact that we all offend is here urged as a reason why we should not be many masters ; which shows that the term masters is here used in a bad sense. " Be not many mas- ters," for if we are masters, " we shall receive the greater condemnation," because we are all great offenders. Now I understand this to be the simple meaning of this passage ; do not many (or any) of you become censors, or critibs, and set yourselves up to judge and condemn others. Tor inasmuch as you have all sinned yourselves, and we are all great offenders, we shall receive the greater condemnation, if we set ourselves up as censors. "For with what judgment ye judge, ye shall be judged, and with what measure ye mete, it shall be measured to you again." 2. It does not appear to me that the apostle designs to afBrm any- thing at all of the present character of himself, or of those to whom he wrote ; nor to have had the remotest allusion to the doctrine of entire sanctiflcation, but simply to affirm a well-established truth in its applica- tion to a particular sin ; that if they became censors, and injuriously condemned others, inasmuch as they had all committed many sins, they should receive the greater condemnation. 3. That the apostle did not design to deny the doctrine of Christian perfection or entire sanctiflcation, as maintained in these lectures, seems evident from the fact, that he immediately subjoins, " If any man offend not in word, the same is a perfect man, and able also to bridle the whole body." Another objection is founded on 1 John, i. 8 : " If we say we have no sin, we deceive ourselves, and the truth is not in us." Upon this I remark : — 1. Those who make this passage an objection to the doctrine of entire 454 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. sanctification in this life, assume that the apostle is here speaking of sanctification instead of justification ; whereas an honest examination of the passage, if I mistake not, will render it evident that the apostle makes no allusion here to sanctification, but is speaking solely of justifi- cation. A little attention to the connection in which this verse stands will, I think, render this evident. But before I proceed to state what I understand to be the meaning of this passage, let us consider it in the connection in which it stands, in the sense in which they understand it who quote it for the purpose of opposing the sentiment advocated in these lectures. They understand the apostle as aflBrming, that, if wo say we are in a state of entire sanctification and do not sin, we deceive ourselves, and the truth is not in us. Now if this were the apostle's meaning, he involves himself, in this connection, in two flat contradictions. 2. This verse is immediately preceded by the assertion that the " blood of Jesus Christ cleanseth us from all sin." Now it would be very remarkable, if immediately after this assertion the apostle should meau to say that it does not cleanse us from all sin, and if we say it does, we deceive ourselves ; for he had just asserted, that the blood of Jesus Christ does cleanse us from all sin. If this were his meaning, it involves him in as palpable a contradiction as could be expressed. 3. This view of the subject then represents the apostle in the conclu- sion of the seventh verse, as saying, the blood of Jesus Christ his Son cleanseth us from all sin ; and in the eighth verse, as saying, that if we suppose ourselves to be cleansed from all sin, we deceive ourselves, thus flatly contradicting what he had just said. And in the ninth verse he goes on to say, that " He is faithful and just to forgive us our sins, and to cleanse us from all unrighteonsness ;" that is, the blood of Jesus cleanseth us from all sin ; but if we say it does, we deceive ourselves. " But if we confess our sins, he is faithful and just to forgive us our sins, and to cleanse us from all unrighteousness." Now, all unrighteous- ness is sin. If we are cleansed from all unrighteousness, we are cleansed from sin. And now suppose a man should confess his sin, and God should in faithfulness and justice forgive his sin, and cleanse him from all unrighteousness, and then he should confess and profess that God had done this ; are we to understand, that the apostle would then affirm that he deceives himself, in supposing that the blood of Jesus Christ cleanseth from all sin ? But, as I have already said, I do not understand the apostle as affirming anything in respect to the present moral charac- ter of any one, but as speaking of the doctrine of justification. This then appears to me to be the meaning of the whole passage. If we say that we are not sinners, that is, have no sin to need the blood of Christ ; that we have never sinned, and consequently need no Saviour, we deceive ourselves. For we have sinned, and nothing but the blood SANCTIFICATION. 455 of Christ cleanseth from sin, or procures our pardon and justification. And now, if wt will not deny, but confess that we have sinned, " He is faithful and just to forgive us our sins, and to cleanse us from all un- righteousness." " But if we say we have not sinned, we make Him a liar, and his word is not in us." These are the principal passages that occur to my mind, and those I believe upon which the principal stress has been laid, by the opposers of this doctrine. And as I do not wish to protract the discussion, I shall omit the examination of other passages. There are many objections to the doctrine of entire sanctification, besides those derived from the passages of scripture which I have con- sidered. Some of these objections are doubtless honestly felt, and de- serve to be considered. I will therefore proceed to notice such of them as now occur to my mind. 1. It is objected, that the doctrine of entire and permanent sanctifi- cation in this life, tends to the errors of modern perfectionism. This objection has been urged by some good men, and I doubt not, honestly urged. But still I cannot believe that they have duly considered the matter. It seems to me, that one fact will set aside this objection. It is well known that the Wesleyan Methodists have, as a denomination, from the earliest period of their history, maintained this doctrine in all its length and breadth. Now if such is the tendency of the doctrine, it is passing strange that this tendency has never developed itself in that denomination. So far as I can learn, the Methodists have been in a great measure, if not entirely, exempt from the errors held by modern perfectionists. Perfectionists, as a body, and I believe with very few exceptions, have arisen out of those denominations that deny the doc- trine of entire sanctification in this life. Now the reason of this is obvious to my mind. When professors of religion, who have been all their life subject to bondage, begin to inquire earnestly for deliverance from their sins, they have found neither sym- pathy nor instruction, in regard to the prospect of getting rid of them in this life. Then they have gone to the Bible, and there found, in almost every part of it, Christ presented as a Saviour from their sins. But 'when they proclaim this truth, they are at once treated as heretics and fanatics by their brethren, until, being overcome of evil, they fall into censoriousness ; and finding the church so decidedly and utterly wrong, in her opposition to this one great important truth, they lose confidence in their ministers and the church, and being influenced by a wrong spirit, Satan takes the advantage of them, and drives them to the ex- treme of error and delusion. This I believe to be the true history of many of the most pious members of the Calvinistic churches. On the contrary, the Methodists are very much secured against these errors. 456 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOQl. Tliey are taught that Jesus Christ is a Saviour from all sin in this world. And when they inquire for deliverance, they are pointed to Jesus Christ as a present and all-suflScient Redeemer. Finding sympathy and in- struction on this great and agonizing point, their confidence in their ministers and their brethren remains, and they walk quietly with them. It seems to me impossible that the tendency of this doctrine should be to the peculiar errors of the modern perfectionists, and yet not an in- stance occur among all the Methodist ministers, or the thousands of their members, for one hundred years. And here let me say, it is my full conviction, that there are but two ways in which ministers of the present day can prevent members of their churches from becoming perfectionists. One is, to suffer them to live so far from God, that they will not inquire after holiness of heart ; and the other is, most fully to inculcate the glorious doctrine of entire consecra- tion ; and that it is the high privilege as well as the duty of Christians, to live in a state of entire consecration to God. I have many additional things to say upon the tendency of this doctrine, but at present this must suffice. By some it is said to be identical with perfectionism ; and attempts are made to show in what particulars antinomian perfectionism and our views are the same. On this I remark : — (1.) It seems to have been a favorite policy of certain controversial writers for a long time, instead of meeting a proposition in the open field of fair and Christian argument, to give it a bad name, and attempt to put it down, not by force of argument, but by showing that it is identi- cal with, or sustains a near relation to Pelagianism, Antinomianism, Calvinism, or some other ism, against which certain classes of minds are deeply prejudiced. In the recent controversy between what are called old and new school divines, who has not witnessed with pain the frequent attempts that have been made to put down the new school divinity, as it is called, by calling it Pelagianism, and quoting certain passages from Pelagius and other writers, to show the identity of sentiment that exists between them. This is a very unsatisfactory method of attacking or defending any doctrine. There are no doubt, many points of agreement between Pela- gius and all truly orthodox divines, and so there are many points of dis- agreement between them. There are also many points of agreement between modern perfectionists and all evangelical Christians, and so there are many points of disagreement between them and the Christian church in general. That there are some points of agreement between their views and my own, is no doubt true. And that we totally disagree in regard to those points that constitute their great peculiarities is, if I nuder^tand them, also true. But did I really agree in all points with SANCTIFIOATION. 457 Augustine, or Edwards, or Pelagius, or the modem perfectionists, neither the good nor the ill name of any of these would prove my senti- ments to be either right or wrong. It would remain, after all, to show that those with whom I agreed were either right or wrong, in order, on the one hand, to establish that for which I contend, or on the other, to overthrow that which I maintain. It is often mot-e convenient to give a doctrine or an argument a bad name, than it is soberly and satisfactorily to reply to it. (3.) It is not a little curious, that we should be charged with holding the same sentiments with the perfectionists ; while yet they seem to be more violently opposed to our views, since they have come to understand them, than almost any other persons whatever. I have been informed by one of their leaders, that he regards me as one of the master-builders of Babylon. With respect to the uiodern perfectionists, those who have been ac- quainted with their writings, know that some of them have gone much farther from the truth than others. Some of their leading men, who commenced with them, and adopted their name, stopped far short of adopting some of their most abominable errors ; still maintaining the authority and perpetual obligation of the moral law ; and thus have been saved from going into many of the most objectionable and destructive notions of the sect. There are many more points of agreement between that class of perfectionists and the orthodox church, than between the church and any other class of them. And there are still a number of important points of difference, as every one knows who is possessed of correct information upon this subject. I abhor the practice of denouncing whole classes of men for the errors of some of that name. I am well aware, that there are many of those who are termed perfectionists, who as truly abhor the extremes of error into which many of that name have fallen, as perhaps do any persons living. 2. Another objection is, that persons could not live in this world, if they were entirely sanctified. Strange I Does holiness injure a man Does perfect conformity to all the laws of life and health, both physical and moral, render it impossible for a man to live ? If a man break off from rebellion against God, will it kill him ? Does there appear to haVe been anything in Christ's holiness inconsistent with life and health ? The fact is, that this objection is founded in a gross mistake, in regard to what constitutes entire sanctification. It is supposed by those who hold this objection, that this state implies a continual and most intense degree of excitement, and many things which are not at all implied in it. I have thought, that it is gather a glorified than a sanctified state, that most m^n have before their miiids, whenever tljey consider this subject, B 458 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. When Christ was upon earth, he was in a sanctified but not in a glorified state. " It is enough for the disciple that he be as his Master." Now, what is there in the moral character of Jesus Christ, as represented in his history, that may not and ought not to be fully copied into the life of every Christian ? I speak not of his knowledge, but of his spirit and temper. Ponder well every circumstance of his life that has come down to us, and say, beloved, what is there in it that may not, by the grace of God, be copied into your own ? And think you, that a full imitation of him, in all that relates to his moral character, would render it impossible for you to live in the world ? 3. Again, it is objected, that should we become entirely, in the sense of permanently, sanctified, we could not know it, and should not be able intelligently to profess it. I answer : All that a sanctified soul needs to know or profess is, that the grace of God in Christ Jesus is sufficient for him, so that he finds it to be true, as Paul did, that he can do all things through Christ who strengtheneth him, and that he does not expect to sin, but that on the contrary, he is enabled through grace " to reckon himself dead indeed unto sin, and alive unto God through Jesus Christ our Lord." A saint may not know that he shall never sin again ; he may expect to sin no more, because of his confidence, not in his own reso- lutions, or strength, or attainments, but simply in the infinite grace and faithfulness of Christ. He may come to look upon, to regard, account, reckon himself, as being dead in deed and in fact unto sin, and as hav- ing done with it, and as being alive unto God, and to expect henceforth to live wholly to God, as much as he expects to live at all ; and it may be true that he will thus live, without his being able to say that he knows that he is entirely, in the sense of permanently, sanctified. This he need not know, but this he may believe upon the strength of such prom- ises as 1 Thess. v. 23, 24 : " And the very God of peace sanctify you wholly : and I pray God your whole spirit, and soul, and body, be pre- served blameless unto the coming of our Lord Jesus Christ. Faithful is he that calleth you, who also will do it." It is also true, that a Christian may attain a state in which he will really fall no more into sin, as a matter of fact, while, at the same time, he may not be able to express even a thorough persuasion that he shall never fall again. All he may be able intelligently to say is : " God knoweth I hope to sin no more, but the event will show. May the Lord keep me ; I trust that he will." 4. Another objection is, that the doctrine tends to spiritual pride. And is it true, indeed, that to become perfectly humble tends to pride ? But entire humility is implied in entire sanctification. Is it true, that you must remain in sin, and of course cherish pride, in order to avoid pride ? Is your humility more safe in yovy own hands, and are you ipore secure against spiritual pride, in refusing to receive Christ ^ SANCTIFICATION. 459 yonr helper, than yon would be in at once embracing him as a full Sariour ? I have seen several remarks in the papers of late, and have heard several suggestions from various quarters, which have but increased the fear which I have for some time entertained, that multitudes of Cliristians, and indeed many ministers, have radically defective views of salvation by faith in Jesus Christ. To the doctrine of entire sanctification in this life, as believed and taught by some of us, it has been frequently of late objected, that prayers offered in accordance with this belief, and by a sanctified soul, would savor strongly of spiritual pride and self-righteona- ness. I have seen this objection stated in its full force of late, in a re- ligious periodical, in the form of a supposed prayer of a sanctified soul, the object of which was manifestly to expose the shocking absurdity, self-righteousness, and spiritual pride, of a prayer, or rather thanksgiv- ing, made in accordance with a belief that one is entirely sanctified. Now, I must confess, that that prayer, together with objections and re- marks which suggest the same idea, have created in my mind no small degree of alarm. I fear much that many of our divines, in contending for the doctrines of grace, have entirely lost sight of the meaning of the language they use, and have in reality but very little practical understand- ing of what is intended by salvation by grace, in opposition to salvation by works. If this is not the case, I know not how to account for their feeling, and for their stating such an objection as this to the doctrine Oi. entire sanctification. Now, if I understand the doctrine of salvation by grace, both sanctifi- cation and justification are wrought by the grace of God, and not by any works or merits of our own, irrespective of the grace of Christ through faith. If this is the real doctrine of the Bible, what earthly objection can there be to our confessing, professing, and thanking God for our sanctification, any more than for our justification ? It is true, indeed, that in our justification our own agency is not concerned, while in our sanctification it is. Yet I understand the doctrine of the Bible to be, that both are brought about by grace through faith, and that we should no sooner be sanctified without the grace of Christ, than we should be justi- fied without it. Now, who pretends to deny this ? And yet if it is true, of what weight is that class of objections to which I have alluded ? These objections manifestly turn upon the idea, no doubt latent and deep seated in the mind, that the real holiness of Christians, in whatever degree it exists, is, in some way, to be ascribed to some goodness originating in themselves, and not in the grace of Christ. But do let me ask, how is it possible that men who entertain, really and practically, right views upon this subject, can by any possibility feel, as if it must be proof conclusive (^ lplf-righteons|iese and Pharisaism, to profess a^d thank God for sane- 460 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. tiflcation ? Is it not understood on all hands, that sanctificatioh is by grace, and that the gospel has made abundant provision for the sanctifl- cation of all men ? This certainly is admitted by those who have stated this objection. Now, if this is so, which is the most honorable to God, to confess and complain that our sins triumph and gain dominion over us, or to be able truly and honestly to thank him for having given ub the victory over our sins ? God has said, " Sin shall not have dominion over you, for ye are not under the law, but under grace." Now, in view of this and multitudes of kindred promises, suppose we come to God, and say : " Lord, thou hast made these great and pre- cious promises, but, as a matter of fact, they do not accord with our own experience. For sin does continually have dominion over us. Thy grace is not suflBcient for us. We are continually overcome by tempta- tion, notwithstanding thy promise, that in every temptation thou wilt make a way for us to escape. Thou hast said, the truth shall make us free, but we are not free. We are still the slaves of our appetites and lusts." Now, which, I inquire, is the most honorable to God, to go on with a string of confessions and self-accusations, that are in flat contradiction to the promises of God, and almost, to say the least, a burlesque upon the grace of the gospel, or to be able, through grace, to confess that we have found it true in our own experience, that his grace is sufficient for us — that as our day is so our strength is, and that sin does not have dominion over us, because we are not under the law, but under grace ? To this I know it will be answered, that in this confessing of our sins we do not impeach the grace or faithfulness of God, inasmuch as all these promises are conditioned upon faith, and consequently, that the reason of our remaining in sin is to be ascribed to our unbelief, and is therefore no disparagement to the grace of Christ. But I beg that it may be duly considered, that faith itself is of the operation of God — is itself produced by grace ; and therefore the fact of our being obliged to confess our unbelief is a dishonor to the grace of Christ Is it honorable or dishonorable to God, that we should be able to confess that even our unbelief is overcome, and that we are able to testify from our own ex- perience, that the grace of the gospel is sufficient for our present salva- tion and sanctification ? There is no doubt a vast amount of self-right- eousness in the church, which, while it talks of grace, really means noth- ing by it. For a man to go any farther than to hope thdt he is con- verted, seems to many minds to savor of self-righteousness. Now, why is this, unless they themselves entertain self-righteous notions in regard to conversion ? Many persons would feel shocked to hear a man in prayer unqualifiedly thank God that he had been converted and justi- fied, And they might just as \yell feel shocke4 at this, and upon pre- SANCTIKICATION. 461 cisely the samo principle, as to feel shocked^ if he should unqualifiedly thank God that he had been sanctified by his grace. But again, I say, that the very fact that a man feels shocked to hear a converted or a sanctified soul unqualifiedly thank God for the grace received, shows that down deep in his heart lies concealed a self-right, eous view of the way of salvation, and that in his mind all holiness in Christians is a ground of boasting ; and that, if persons have become truly and fully sanctified, they really have a ground of boasting before God, I know not how else to account for this wonderful prejudice. For my own part, I do not conceive it to be the least evidence of self- righteousness, when I hear a man sincerely and heartily thank God for converting and justifying him by his grace. Nor should I feel either shocked, horrified, or disgusted, to hear a man thank God that he had sanctified him wholly by his grace. If in either or both cases I had the corroborative evidence of an apparently holy life, I should bless God, take courage, and feel like calling on all around to glorify God for such an instance of his glorious and excellent grace. The feeling seems to be very general, that such a prayer or thanks- giving is similar, in fact, and in the principle upon which it rests, with that of the Pharisee noticed by our Saviour. But what reason is there for this assumption ? We are expressly informed, that that was the prayer of a Pharisee. But the Pharisees were self-righteous, and ex- pressly and openly rejected the grace of Christ. The Pharisee then boasted of his own righteousness, originated in and consummated by, his own goodness, and not in the grace of Christ. Hence he did not thank God, that the grace of Christ had made him unlike other men. Now, this prayer was designed to teach us the abominable folly of any - man's putting in a claim to righteousness and true holiness, irrespective of the grace of God by Jesus Christ. But certainly this is an infinitely different thing from the thanksgiving of a soul, who fully recognizes the grace of Christ, and attributes his sanctification entirely to that grace. And I cannot see how a man, who has entirely divested himself of Pharisaical notions in respect to the doctrine' of sanctification, can (appose these two prayers to be analogous in their principle and spirit 462 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. LECTURE XLI. SANCTIFICATION. FUKTHEB OBJECTIONS ANSWEBBD. 5. Again it is objected, that many who have embraced this dootrinet really are spiritually proud. To this I answer : (1.) So have many who believed the doctrine of regeneration been deceived and amazingly puffed up with the idea that they have been regenerated when they have not been. But is this a good reason for abandoning the doctrine of regeneration, or any reason why the doctrine should not be preached ? (2.) Let me inquire, whether a simple declaration of what God has done for their souls, has not been assumed as of itself sufficient evidence of spiritual pride, on the part of those who embrace this doctrine, while there was in reality no spiritual pride at all ? It seems next to impossi- ble, with the present views of the church, that an indi\ndual should really attain this state, and profess to live without known sin in a manner so humble, as not, of course, to be suspected of enormous spiritual pride. This consideration has been a snare to some, who have hesitated and even neglected to declare what God had done for their souls, lest they should be accused of spiritual pride. And this has been a serious injury to their piety. 6. But again it is objected, that this doctrine tends to censoriousness. To this I reply : — (1.) It is not denied, that some who have professed to believe this doctrine have become censorious. But this no more condemns this doctrine than it condemns that of regeneration. And that it tends to censoriousness, might just as well be urged against every acknowledged doctrine of the Bible, as against this doctrine. (2.) Let any Christian do his whole duty to the church and the world in their present state, let him speak to them and of them as they really are, and he would of course incur the charge of censoriousness. It is therefore the most unreasonable thing in the world, to suppose that the church in its present state, would not accuse any perfect Christian of censoriousness. Entire sanctification implies the doing of all our duty. But to do all our duty, we must rebuke sin in high places and in low places. Can this be done with all needed severity, without in many cases giving offence, and incurring the charge of censoriousness ? No, it is impossible ; and to maintain the contrary would be to impeach the wisdom iind holiness of Jesus Christ himself. SANCTIFICATION. 463 7. It is objected that the believers in this doctrine lower the standard of holiness to a level with their own experience. To this I reply, that it has been common to set up a false standard, and to overlook the true spirit and meaning of the law, and to represent it as requiring something else than what it does require ; but this notion is not confined to those who believe in this doctrine. The moral law requires one and the same thing of all moral agents, namely, that they shall be universally and disinterestedly benevolent ; in other words, that they shall love the Lord their God with all their heart, and their neighbor as themselves. This is all that it does require of any. Whoever has understood the law as requiring less or more than this, has misunderstood it. Love is the fulfilling of the law. But I must refer the reader to what I have said upon this subject when treating of moral government. The law, as we have seen on a former occasion, levels its claims to us as we are, and a just exposition of it, as I have already said, must take into consideration all the present circumstances of our being. This is indispensable to a right apprehension of what constitutes entire sanctifi- cation. There may be, as facts show, danger of misapprehension in regard to the true spirit and meaning of the law, in the sense that, by theorizing and adopting a false philosophy, one may lose sight of the deepest affirmations of his reason, in regard to the true spirit and mean- ing of the law ; and I would humbly inquire, whether the error has not been in giving such an interpretation of the law, as naturally to beget the idea so prevalent, that, if a man should become holy, he could not live in this world ? In a letter lately received from a beloved, and use- ful, and venerated minister of the gospel, while the writer expressed the greatest attachment to the doctrine of entire consecratibn to God, and said that he preached the same doctrine which we hold to his people every Sabbath, but by another name, still he added, that it was revolting to his feelings to hear any mere man set up the claim of obedience to the law of God. Now let me inquire, why should this be revolting to the feelings of piety ? Must it not be because the law of God is supposed to require something of human beings in our state, which it does not and cannot require ? Why should such a claim be thought extravagant, unless the claims of the living God be thought extravagant ? If the law of God really requires no more of men than what is reasonable and possi- ble, why should it be revolting to any mind to hear an individual profess to have attained to entire obedience ? I know that the brother to whom I allude, would be almost the last man deliberately and knowingly to give any strained interpretation to the law of God ; and yet, I cannot but feel that much of the difficulty that good men have upon this sub- ject, has arisen out of a comparison of the lives of saints with a standard entirely above that which the law of God does or can demand of persons i64 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. in all respects in our circumstances, or indeed of any moral agent whaterer. 8. Another objection is, that, as a matter of fact, the grace of God is not sufiBcient to secure the entire sanctification of saints in this life. It is maintained, that the question of the attainability of entire sanctifica- tion in this life, resolves itself after all into the question, whether Chris- tians are sanctified in this life ? The objectors say, that nothing is suffi- cient grace that does not, as a matter of fact, secure the faith, and obedience, and perfection of the saints ; and therefore that the provisions of the gospel are to be measured by the results ; and that the experience of the church decides both the meaning of the promises, and the extent of the provisions of grace. Now to this I answer : — If this objection be good for anything in regard to entire sanctification, it is equally true in ];egard to the spiritual state of every person in the world. If the fdct that men are not perfect, proves that no provision is made for their per- fection, their being no better than they are proves, that there is no pro- vision for their being any better than they are, or that they might not have aimed at being any better, with any rational hope of success. But who, except a fatalist, will admit any such conclusion as this ? And yet I do not see but this conclusion is inevitable from such premises. As well might an impenitent sinner urge, that the grace of the gospel is not, as a matter of fact, sufficient for him, because it does not convert him : as well might he resolve everything into the sovereignty of God, and say, the sovereignty of God must convert me, or I shall not be con- verted ; and since I am not converted, it is because the grace of God has not proved itself sufficient to convert me. But who will excuse the sinner, and admit his plea, that the grace and provisions of the gospel are not sufficient for him ? Let ministers urge upon both saints and sinners the claims of God. Let them insist that sinners may, and can, and ought, immediately to become Christians, and that Christians can, and may, and ought to live wholly to God. Let them urge Christians to live without sin, and hold out the same urgency of command, and the same encouragement that the new school holds out to sinners ; and we shall soon find that Chris- tians are entering into the liberty of perfect love, as sinners have found pardon and acceptance. Let ministers hold forth the same gospel to all, and insist that the grace of the gospel is as sufficient to save from all sin as from a part of it ; and we shall soon see whether the difficulty has not been, that the gospel has been hid and denied, until the' churches have been kept weak through unbelief. The church has been taught not to expect the fulfilment of the promises to them ; that it is danger- ous error to expect the fulfilment to them, for example, of the promise ill 1 Thess, v. 33, 34 : " And the very God of peace sanctify yon wholly ; SANCI'IPICATION. 4G5 and I pray God your whole spirit, and soul, and body, be preserved blameless unto the coming of our Lord Jesus Christ. Faithful is he that calleth yoa, who also will do it." When God says he will sanctify us wholly, and preserve us blameless unto the coming of the Lord, masters in Israel tell us that to expect this is dangerous error. 9. Another objection to this doctrine is, that it is contrary to the views of some of the greatest and best men in the church : that such men as Augustine, Calvin, Doddridge, Edwards etc., were of a difEerent opinion. To this I answer : — (1.) Suppose they were ; we are to call no man father, in such a sense as to yield up to him the determination of our views of Christian doctrine. (2.) This objection comes with a very ill grace from those who wholly reject the opinions of these divines on some of the most important points of Christian doctrine. (3.) Those men all held the doctrine of physical moral depravity, which was manifestly the ground of their rejecting the doctrine of entire sanctification in this life. Maintaining, as they seem to have done, that the constitutional susceptibilities of body and mind were sinfully de- praved, consistency of course led them to reject the idea, that persons could be entirely sanctified while in the body. Now, I would ask what consistency is there in quoting them as rejecting the doctrine of entire sanctification in this life, while the reason of this rejection in their minds, was founded in the doctrine of physical moral depravity, which notion is entirely denied by those who quote their authority ? 10. But again ; it is objected, that, if we should attain this state of continual consecration or sanctification, we could not know it until the day of judgment ; and that to maintain its attainability is vain, inas- much as no one can know whether he has attained it or not. To this I reply :— (1.) A man's consciousness is the highest and best evidence of the present state of his own mind. I understand consciousness to be the mind's recognition of its own existence and exercises, and that it is the highest possible evidence to our own minds of what passes within us. Consciousness can of course testify only to our present sanctification ; but, (2.) With the law of God before us as our standard, the testimony of consciousness, in regard to whether the mind is conformed to that standard or not, is the highest evidence which the mind can have of a present state of conformity to that rule. (3.) It is a testimony which we cannot doubt, any more than we can doubt our existence. How do we know that we exist ? I answer, by our consciousness. How go Tkntm tliat I breathe, or love, or hate, or 466 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. sit, or stand, or lie down, or rise up, that I am joyful or sorrowful ? In short, that I exercise any emotion, or volition, or affection of mind ? How do I know that I sin, or repent, or believe ? I answer, by my own consciousness. No testimony can be " so direct and convincing as this." Now, in order to know that my repentance is genuine, I must know what genuine repentance is. So if I would know whether my love to God and man, or obedience to the law is genuine, I must have clearly before my mind the real spirit, and meaning, and bearing of the law of God. Having the rule before my mind, my own consciousness affords " the most direct and convincing evidence possible," whether my present state of mind is conformed to the rule. The Spirit of God is never employed in testifying to what my consciousness teaches, but in setting in a strong light before my mind the rnle to which I am to conform my life. It is his province to make me understand, to induce me to love and obey the truth ; and it is the province of consciousness to testify to my own mind whether I do or do not obey the truth, when I apprehend it. When God so presents the truth, as to give the mind assurance, that it understands his mind and will npon any subject, the mind's consciousness of its own state in view of that truth, is " the highest and most direct possible " evidence of whether it obeys or disobeys. (4.) If a man cannot be conscious of the character of his own supreme or ultimate choice, in which choice his moral character consists, how can he know when, and of what, he is to repent ? If he has committed sin of which he is not conscious, how is he to repent of it ? And if he has a holiness of which he is not conscious, how could he feel that he has peace with God ? But it is said, that a man may violate the law, not knowing it, and consequently have no consciousness that he sinned, but that, afterwards, a knowledge of the law may convict him of sin. To this I reply, that if there was absolutely no knowledge that the thing in question was wrong, the doing of that thing was not sin, inasmuch as some degree of knowl- edge of what is right or wrong is indispensable to the moral character of , any act. In such a case, there may be a sinful ignorance, which may in- volve all the guilt of those actions that were done in consequence of it ; but that blameworthiness lies in that state of heart that has induced this, and not at all in the violation of the rule of which the mind was, at the time, entirely ignorant (5.) The Bible everywhere assumes, that we are able to know, and unqualifiedly requires us to know, what the moral state of our mind is. It commands us to examine ourselves, to know and to prove our own selves. Now, how can this be done, but by bringing our hearts into the light of the law of God, and then taking the testimony of our own con- Bciousness, whether we are, or are not, in a state of conformity to the SANCTIFICATION. 467 law ? But if we are not to receive the testimony of our own conscious- ness, in regard to our present sanctification, are we to receive it in re- spect to our repentance, or any other exercise of our mind whatever ? The fact is, that we may deceive ourselves, by neglecting to compare our- selves with the right standard. But when our views of the standard are right, and our consciousness bears witness of a felt, decided, unequivocal state of mind, we cannot be deceived any more than we can be deceived in regard to our own existence. (6.) But it is said, our consciousness does not teach us what the power and capacities of our minds are, and that therefore if consciousness could teach us in respect to the kind of our exercises, it cannot teach us in regard to their degree, whether they are equal to the present capacity of our mind. To this I reply : — Consciousness does as unequivocally testify whether we do or do not love God with all our heart, as it does whether we love him at all. How does a man know that he lifts as much as he can, or runs, or walks as fast as he is able ? I answer, by his own consciousness. How does he know that he repents or loves with all his heart ? I answer, by his own consciousness. This is the only possible way in which he can know it. The objection implies that God has put within our reach no possible means of knowing whether we obey him or not. The Bible does not di- rectly reveal the fact to any man, whether he obeys God or not. It reveals his duty, but does not reveal the fact whether he obeys. It refers for this testimony to his own consciousness. The Spirit of God sets our duty before us, but does not directly reveal to us whether we do it or not ; for this would imply that every man is under constant inspiration. But it is said, the Bible directs our attention to the fact, whether we outwardly obey or disobey, as evidence whether we are in a right state of mind or not. But I would inquire. How do we know whether we obey or disobey ? How do we know anything of our conduct but by our con- sciousness ? Our conduct, as observed by others, is to them evidence of the state of our hearts. But, I repeat it, our consciousness of obedience to God is to us the highest, and indeed the only, evidence of our true character. If a man's own consciousness is not to be a witness, either for or against him, other testimony can never satisfy him of the propriety of God's dealing with him in the final judgment. There are cases of com- mon occurrence, where the witnesses testify to the guilt or innocence of a man, contrary to the testimony of his own consciousness. In all such cases, from the very laws of his being, he rejects all other testimony : and let me add, that he would reject the testimony of God, and from the very laws of his being must reject it, if it contradicted his own consciousness. When God convicts a man of sin, it is not by contradicting his con- 468 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Bciousness ; but by placing the consciousness which he had at the time, in the clear strong light of his memory, causing him to discover clearly, and to remember distinctly what light he had, what thoughts, what con- victions, what intention or design ; in other words, what consciousness he had at the time. And this, let me add, is t'he way, and the only way, in which the Spirit of Grod can convict a man of sin, thus bringing him to condemn himself. Now, suppose that God should bear testimony against a man, that at such a time he did such a thing, that such and such were all the circumstances of the case ; and suppose that at the same time the individual's consciousness unequivocally contradicts him. The testimpny of God in this case could not satisfy the man's mind, nor lead him into a state of self-condemnation. The only possible way in which this state of mind could be induced, would be to annihilate his opposing consciousness, and to convict him simply upon the testimony of God. (7.) Men may overlook what consciousness is. They may mistake the rule of duty, they may confound consciousness with a mere negative state of mind, or that in which a man is not conscious of a state of opposition to the truth. Yet it must forever remain true that, to our own minds, " consciousness must be the highest possible evidence " of what passes within us. And if a man does not by his own conscious- ness know whether he does the best that he can, under the circumstances — whether he has a single eye to the glory of God — and whether he is in a state of entire consecration to God — he cannot know it in any way whatever. And no testimony whatever, either of God or man, could, according to the laws of his being, satisfy him either as to conviction of guilt on the one hand, or self-approbation on the other. (8.) Let me ask, how those who make this objection know that they are not in a sanctified state ? Has God revealed it to them ? Has he revealed it in the Bible ? Does the Bible say to A. B. , by name, You are not in a sanctified state ? Or does it lay down a rule, in the light of which his own consciousness bears this testimony against him ? Has God revealed directly by his Spirit, that he is not in a sanctified state, or does he hold the rule of duty strongly before the mind, and thus awaken the testimony of consciousness that he is not in this state ? Now just in the same way consciousness testifies of those that are sanctified, that they are in this state. Neither the Bible nor the Spirit of God makes any new or particular revelation to them by name. But the Spirit of God bears witness to their spirits by setting the rule in a strong light before them. He induces that state of mind which conscience pronounces to be conformity to the rule. This is as far as possible from setting aside the judgment of God in the case ; for conscience, under these circum- gtances^ is the testimony of God, and the way in which he convinces of BANCTIFICATION. 469 sin on tlie one hand, and of entire consecration on the other ; and the decision of conscience is given to us in consciousness. By some it is still objected, that consciousness alone is not evidence even to ourselves of our being, or not being, in a state of entire sanctifioa- tion ; that the judgment of the mind is also employed in deciding the true intent and meaning of the law, and is therefore as absolutely a ■witness in the case as consciousness is. "Consciousness," it is said, "gives us the exercises of our own mind, and the judgment decides whether these exercises are in accordance with the law of God." So then it is the judgment rather than the consciousness, that decides whether we are, or are not, in a state of entire sanctification ; and there- fore if, in our judgment of the law, we happen to be mistaken, than which nothing is more common, in such case we are utterly deceived if we think ourselves in a state of entire sanctification. To this I answer : — • It is indeed our judgment that decides upon the intent and meaning of the law. We may be mistaken in regard to its true application in cer- tain cases, as it respects outward conduct, but let it be remembered, that neither sin nor holiness is to be found in the outward act. They both belong only to the ultimate intention. No man, as was formerly shown, can mistake his real duty. Every one knows, and cannot but know, that disinterested benevolence is his duty. This is, and nothing else is, his duty. This he can know, and about this he need not mistake. And sure it is, that if man can be certain of anything, he can be certain in respect to the end for which he lives, or in respect to his supreme ultimate intention. I deny that it is the judgment which is to us the witness, in respect to the state of our own minds. There are several powers of the mind called into exercise, in deciding upon the meaning of, and in obeying, the law of God ; but it is consciousness alone that gives us these exer- cises. Nothing but consciousness can possibly give us any exercise of our own minds ; that is, we have no knowledge of any exercise but by our own consciousness. Suppose then the judgment is exercised, the will is exercised, and all the involuntary powers are exercised. These exer- cises are revealed to us only and simply by consciousness ; so that it remains an invariable truth, that consciousness is to us the only possible witness of what our exercises are, and consequently of the state of our own minds. When, therefore, I say, that by consciousness a man may know whether he is in a state of sanctification, I mean, that conscious- ness is the real and only evidence that we can have of being in this state. This objection is based upon a misapprehension of that which consti- tutes entire or continued sanctification. It consists, as has been shown, in abiding consecration to God, and not as the objection assumes, in in- voluntary affections and feelings. When it is considered, that entire 4:70 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. sanctifioation consists in an abiding good will to God and to being in general, in living to one end, what real impossibility can there be in knowing whether we are supremely devoted to this end, or supremely devoted to our own interest ? 11. Again, it is objected, that if this state were attained in this life, it would be the end of our probation. To this I reply, that probation since the fall of Adam, or those points on which we are in a state of probation or trial, are — (1. ) Whether we will repent and believe the gospel. (2.) Whether we will persevere in holiness to the end of life. Some suppose, that the doctrine of the perseverance of the saints sets aside the idea of being at all in a state of probation after conversion. They reason thus : If it is certain that the saints will persevere, then their probation is ended ; because the question is already settled, not only that they are converted, but that they will persevere to the end ; and the contingency, in regard to the event, is indispensable to the idea of pro- bation. To this I reply, that a thing may be contingent with man that is not at all so with God. With God, there is not, and never was any contingency, in the sense of uncertainty, with regard to the final destiny of any being. But with men almost all things are contingent. God knows with absolute certainty whether a man will be converted, and whether he will persevere. A man may know that he is converted, and may believe that by the grace of God he shall persevere. He may have an assurance of this in proportion to the strength of his faith. But the knowledge of this fact is not at all inconsistent with his idea of his con- tinuance in a state of trial till the day of his death, inasmuch as his per- severance depends upon the exercise of his own voluntary agency ; and also, because his perseverance is the condition of his final salvation. In the same way some say, that if we have attained a state of entire or permanent sanctifioation, we can no longer be in a state of probation. I answer, that perseverance in this depends upon the promises and grace of God, just as the final perseverance of the saints does. In neither case can we have any other assurance of our perseverance, than that of faith in the promise and grace of God ; nor any other knowledge that we shall continue in this state, than that which arises out of a belief in the testi- mony of God, that he will preserve us blameless until the coming of our Lord Jesus Christ. If this be inconsistent with our probation, I see not why the doctrine of the saint's perseverance is not equally inconsistent with it. If any one is disposed to maintain, that for us to have any judgment or belief grounded on the pi'omises of God, in regard to our final perseverance, is inconsistent with a state of probation, all I can say is, that his views of probation are very different from my own, and so far as I understand, from those of the church of God. 8ANCTIPICATI0N. 471 Again : there is a very high and important sense in which every moral being will remain on probation to all eternity. While under the moral government of God, obedience must for ever remain a condition of the favor of God. And continued obedience will for ever depend on the' faithfulness and grace of God ; and the only confidence we can ever have, either in heaven, or on earth, that we shall continue to obey, must be founded upon the faithfulness and truth of God. Again : if it were true, that entering upon a state of permanent sanc- tification in this life, were, in some sense, an end of our probation, that would be no objection to the doctrine ; for there is a sense in which pro- bation often ends long before the termination of this life. Where, for example, for any cause God has left sinners to fill up the measure of their iniquity, withdrawing forever his Holy Spirit from them, and sealing them over to eternal death : this, in a very important sense, is the end of their probation, and they are as sure of hell as if they were already there. So on the other hand, when a person has received, after believ- ing, the sealing of the Spirit unto the day of redemption, as an earnest of his inheritance, he may regard, and is bound to regard this as a solemn pledge on the part of God, of his final perseverance and salvation, and as no longer leaving the final question of his destiny in doubt. Now it should be remembered, that in both these cases the result de- pends upon the exercise of the agency of the creature. In the case of the sinner given up of God, it is certain that he will not repent, though his impenitence is voluntary, and by no means a thing naturally neces- sary. So, on the other hand, the perseverance of the saints is certain, though not necessary. If in either case there should be a radical change of character, the result would differ accordingly. 12. Again : while it is admitted by some, that entire sanctification in this life is attainable, yet it is denied, that there is any certainty that it will be attained by any one before death ; for it is said, that as all the promises of entire sanctification are conditioned upon faith, they therefore secure the entire sanctification of no one. To this I reply, that all the promises of salvation in the Bible are conditioned upon faith and repent- ance ; and therefore it does not follow on this principle, that any person ever will be saved. What does all this arguing prove ? The fact is, that while the promises of both salvation and sanctification, are conditioned upon faith, yet the promises that God will convert and sanctify the elect, spirit, soul and body, and preserve and save them, must be fulfilled, and will be fulfilled, by free grace drawing and securing the concurrence of free- will. With respect to the salvation of sinners, it is promised that Christ shall have a seed to serve him, and the Bible abounds with promises to Christ that secure the salvation of great multitudes of sinners. So the promises, that the church, as a body, at some period of her earthly history. 472 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. ehall be entirely sanctified, are, as it regards the church, unconditional, in the sense that they will assuredly be accomplished. But, as I have already shown, as it respects individuals, the fulfilment of these promises must depend upon the exercise of faith. Both in respect to the salvation of sinners and the sanctification of Christians, God is abundantly pledged to bring about the salvation of the one and the sanctification of the other, to the extent of his promise to Christ. 13. It is also objected, that the sanctification of the saints depends upon the sovereignty of God. To this I reply, that both the sanctifica- tion of the saints and the conversion of sinners is, in some sense depen- dent upon the sovereign grace of God. But who except an antinomian would, for this reason, hesitate to urge it upon sinners to repent imme- diately and believe the gospel ? Would any one think of objecting to the doctrine or the fact of repentance, that repentance and the conver- sion of sinners were dependent upon the sovereignty of God ? And yet, if the sovereignty of God can be justly urged as a bar to the doctrine of entire sanctification, it may, for aught I see, with equal propriety be urged as a bar to the doctrine and fact of repentance. "We have no con- troversy with any one upon the subject of entire sanctification, who will as fully and as firmly hold out the duty and the possibility, and the practical attainability, of entire sanctification, as of repentance and sal- vation. Let them both be put where the Bible puts them, upon the same ground, so far as the duty and the practicability of both are con- cerned. Suppose any one should assert, that it*were irrational and dan- gerous for sinners to hojDe or expect to be converted, and sanctified, and saved, because all this depends upon the sovereignty of God, and ttiey do not know what God will do. Who would say this ? But why not as well say it, as make the objection to sanctification which we are now considering ? LECTURE XLII. SANCTIFICATION. REMARKS. 1. There is an importance to be attached to the sanctification of the lody, of which very few persons appear to be aware. Indeed, unless the bodily appetites and powers be consecrated to the service of God — unless we learn to eat, and drink, and sleep, and wake, and labor, and rest, for the glory of God, permanent sanctification as a practical thing is out of the question. It is plain, that very few persons are aware of the great SANCTIFICATION. 47b influence which their bodies have over their minds, and of the indispen- sable necessity of bringing their bodies under, and keeping thein in subjection. Few people seem to keep the fact steadily in view, that unless their bodies be rightly managed, they will be so fierce and overpowering a source of temptation to the mind, as inevitably to lead it into sin. If they indulge themselves in a stimulating diet, and in the use of those condiments that irritate and rasp the nervous system, their bodies will 'be, of course and of necessity, the source of powerful and incessant temptation to evil tempers and vile affections. If persons were aware of the great influence which the body has over the mind, they would realize, that they cannot be too careful to preserve the nervous system from the influence of every improper article of food or drink, and preserve that system as they would the apple of their eye, from every influence that could impair its functions. No one who has opportunity to acquire in- formation in regard to the laws of life and health, and the best means of sanctifying the whole spirit, soul, and body, can be guiltless if he neglects these means of knowledge. Every man is bound to make the structure and laws of both body and mind the subject of as thorough investigation as his circumstances will permit, to inform himself in regard to what are the true principles of perfect temperance, and in what way the most can be made of all his powers of body and mind for the glory of God. ■ 2. From what has been said in these lectures, the reason why the church has not been entirely sanctified is very obvious. As a body the church has not believed that such a state was attainable until neai* the close of life. And this is a sufficient reason, and indeed the most weighty of all reasons, for her not having attained it. 3. From what has been said, it is easy to see, that the true question in regard to entire sanctification in this life is : Is it attainable as a matter of fact ? Some have thought the proper question to be : Are Christians entirely sanctified in this life ? Now certainly this is not the question that needs to be discussed. Suppose it to be fully granted that they are not ; this fact is sufficiently accounted for, by the consideration that they do not know or believe it to be attainable until the close of life. If they believed it to be attainable, it might no longer be true that they do not attain it. But if provision really is made for this attainment, it amounts to nothing, unless it be recognized and believed. The thing needed then is, to bring the church to see and believe, that this is her high privilege and her duty. It is not enough, as has been shown, to say that it is attainable, simply on the ground of natural ability. This is as true of the devil, and the lost in hell, as of men in this world. Bat unless grace has put this attainment so within our reach, as that it may be aimed ,a,t witjh t^ie r^as^jnable j^rospeeit of success,, there is, ,?is a mattei 474 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. of fact, no more provision for our entire sanctification in this life, than for the devil's. As has been said, it seems to be trifling with mankind, merely to maintain the attainability of this state, on the ground of natural ability only, and at the same time to tell them, that they cer- tainly never will exercise this ability unless disposed to do so by the grace of God ; and furthermore, that it is a dangerous error for us to expect to receive grace from God to secure this result ; that we might by natural possibility make this attainment, but it is irrational and danger- ous error to expect or hope to make it, or hope to receive sufficient grace to secure it. The real question is. Has grace brought this attainment so within our reach, that we may reasonably expect, by aiming at it, to experience it in this life ? It is admitted, that on the ground of natural ability, both wicked men and devils have the power to be entirely holy. But it is also admitted that their indisposition to use this power aright is so complete, that as a matter of fact, they never will, unless influenced to do so by the grace of God. I insist therefore that the real question is, whether the provisions of the gospel are such, that did the church fully under- stand and lay hold upon the proffered grace, she might attain this state ? Are we as fully authorized to offer this grace to Christiana, as we are the grace of repentance and pardon to sinners ? May we as consistently urge Christians to lay hold on sanctifying grace sufficient to keep them from all sin, as to urge sinners to lay hold of Christ for justification ? May we insist upon the one as really and as honestly as the other ? 4. We see how irrelevant and absurd the objection is, that as a matter of fact the church has not attained this state, and therefore it is not at- tainable. Why, if they have not understood it to be attainable, it no more disproves its attainableness, than the fact that the heathen have not embraced the gospel, proves that they will not when they know it. Within my memory it was thought to be dangerous to call sinners to re- pent and believe the gospel ; and on the contrary, they were told by Cal- vinists, that they could not repent, that they must wait God's time ; and it was regarded as a dangerous error for a sinner to think that he could repent. But who does not know, that the thorough inculcation of an opposite doctrine haa brought scores of thousands to repentance ? Now the same course needs to be pursued with Christians. Instead of being told, that it is dangerous to expect to be entirely sanctified in this life, they ought to be taught to believe at once, and take hold on the promises of perfect love and faith. 5. You see the necessity of fully preaching and insisting upon this doctrine, and of calling it by its true scriptural name. It is astonishing to see to what an extent there is a tendency among men to avoid the use of scriptural language, and to cleave to the language of such men as BANCTIFICATION. 475 Edwards, and other great and good divines. They object to the terms perfection and entire sanctification, and prefer to nso the temu entire consecration, and such other terms as have been common in the church. Now, I would by no means contend about the use of words ; but still it does appear to me to be of great importance, that we use scripture lan- guage, and insist upon men being " perfect as their Father in Heaven is perfect," and being "sanctified wholly, body, soul and spirit." This appears to me to be the more important for this reason, that if we use the language to which the church has been accustomed upon this subject, she will, as she has done, misunderstand us, and will not get before her mind that which we really mean. That this is so, is manifest from the fact, that the great mass of the church will express alarm at the use of the terms perfection and entire sanctification, who will neither express nor feel any such alarm, if we speak of entire consecration. This de- monstrates, that they do not by any means understand these terms as meaning the same thing. And although I understand them as meaning precisely the same thing, yet I find myself obliged to use the terms per fection and entire sanctification to possess their minds of their real mean- ing. This is Bible language. It is unobjectionable language. And in- asmuch as the church understands entire consecration to mean something less than entire sanctification or Christian perfection, it does seem to me of great importance, that ministers should use a phraseology which will call the attention of the church to the real doctrine of the Bible upon this subject. With great humility, I would submit the question to my be- loved brethren in the ministry, whether they are not aware, that Chris- tians have entirely too low an idea of what is implied in entire consecra- tion, and whether it is not useful and best to adopt a phraseology in ad- dressing them, that shall call their attention to the real meaning of the words which they use ? 6. Young converts have not been allowed so much as to indulge the thought that they could live even for a day wholly without sin. They have as a general thing no more been taught to expect to live even for a day without sin, than they have been taught to expect immediate trans- lation, soul and body, to heaven. Of course, they have not known that there was any other way than to go on in sin ; and however shocking and distressing the necessity has appeared to them, in the ardor of their first love, still they have looked upon it as an unalterable fact, that to be in a great measure in bondage to sin is a thing of course while they live in this world. Now, with such an orthodoxy as this, with the conviction in the church and ministry so ripe, settled and universal, that the utmost that the grace of God can do for men in this world is to bring them to repentance, and to leave them to live »nd die in n, state of sinning and 476 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGr. repenting, is it at all wonderful, that the state of religion should be aae it really has been ? In looking over the results to Christians, of preaching the doctrine in question, I feel compelled to say, that so far as all observation can go, I have the same evidence that it is truth, and as such is owned and blessed of Uod to the elevation of the holiness of Christians, as I have, that those are truths which I have so often preached to sinnere, and which have been blessed of God to their conversion. This doctrine seems as naturally calculated to elevate the piety of Christians, and as actually to result in the elevation of their piety, under the blessing of God, as those truths that I have preached to sinners were to their conversion. 7. Christ has been in a great measure lost sight of in some of his most important relations to mankind. He has been known and preached as a pardoning and. justifying Saviour; but as an actually indwelling and ■reigning Saviour in the heart, he has been but little known. I was struck with a remark a few years since, of a brother whom I have from that time greatly loved, who had been for a time in a desponding state of mind, borne down with a great sense of his own vileness, but seeing no way of escape. At an evening meeting the Lord so revealed himself to him, as entirely to overcome the strength of his body, and his brethren were obliged to carry him home. The next time I saw him, he exclaimed to me with a pathos I shall never forget, " Brother Finney, the church have buried the Saviour." Now it is no doubt true, that the church have be- come awfully alienated from Christ — ^have in a great measure lost a knowl- edge of what he is, and ought to be, to her ; and a great many of her members, I have good reason to know, in different parts of the country, are saying with deep and overpowering emotion, " They have taken away my Lord, and I know not where they have laid him." 8. With all her orthodoxy, the church has been for a long time much nearer to Unitarianism than she has imagined. This remark may shock some of my readers, and you may think it savors of censoriousness. But, beloved, I am sure it is said in no such spirit. These are " the words of truth and soberness." So little has been known of Christ, that, if I am not entirely mistaken, there are multitudes in the orthodox churches, who do not know Christ, and who in heart are Unitarians, while in theory they are orthodox. They have never known Christ, in the sense of which I have spoken of him in these lectures. I have been, for some years, deeply impressed with the fact, that so many professors of religion are coming to the ripe conviction that they never knew Christ. There have been in this place almost continual de- velopments of this fact ; and I doubt, whether there is a minister in the Jand who will present Christ as the gospel presents him, in all the ful- ness of his oflBcial relations .to mankind, who y^ll jiot be .st^ck mA BANCTIFICATlON. 477 agonized with developments that will assure him, that the great mass of professors of religion do not know the Sa,viour. It has been to my mind a painful and serious question, what I ought to think of the spiritual state of those who know so little of the blessed Jesus. That none of them have been converted, I dare not say. And yet, that they have been con- verted, I am afraid to say, I would not for the world "quench the smoking flax, or break the bruised reed," or say anything to stumble, or weaken the feeblest lamb of Christ ; and yet my heart is sore pained my soul is sick ; my bowels of compassion yearn over, the church of the blessed God. 0, the dear church of Christ I What does she in her present state know of the gospel-rest, of that " great and perfect peace " which they have whose minds are stayed on God ? The church in this place is composed, to a great extent, of professors of religion from difEerent parts of the world, who have come hither for educational pur- poses, and from religious considerations. And as I said, I have some- times been appalled at the disclosures which the Spirit of God has made of the real spiritual state of many who have come here, and were con- sidered by others before they came, and by themselves, as truly converted ;to God. 9. If I am not misbaken, there is an extensive feeling among Chris- tians and ministers, that much that ought to be known and may be known of the Saviour, is not known. Many are beginning to find tha,t the Saviour is to them "as a root out of a dry ground, having neither form nor comeliness ;" that the gospel which they preach or hear is not to them "the power of God unto salvation " from sin ; that it is not to them " glad tidings of great joy;" that it is not to them a peace-giving gospel ; and many are feeling that if Christ has done for them all that his grace is able to do in this life, the plan of salvation is sadly defective ; that Christ is not after all a Saviour suited to their necessities ; that the religion which they have is not suited to the world in which they live ; that it does not, cannot make them free, but leaves them in a state of perpetual bondage. Their souls are agonized, and tossed to and fro with- out a resting-place. Multitudes also are beginning to see, that there are many passages, both in the Old and the New Testament, which they do not understand ; that the promises seem to mean much more than they have ever realized ; and that the gospel and the plan of salvation, as a whole, must be something very difEerent from that which they have as yet ap- prehended. There are, if I mistake not, great multitudes all over the country, who are inquiring more earnestly than ever before, after a knowledge of that Jesus who is to save his people from their sins. 10. If the doctrine of these lectures is true, you see the immense im- portance of preaching it clearly and fully, in revivals of religion. When the hearts of converts are warm with their first love, then is the time to 478 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. make them fully acquainted with their Saviour, to hold him up in all hia oflBces and relations, so as to break the power of every sin — to lead them to break ofE forever from all self-dependence, and to receive Christ as a present, perfect, everlasting Saviour, so far as this can possibly be done with their limited experience. 11. Unless this course be taken, their backsliding is inevitable. You might as well expect to roll back the waters of Niagara with your hand, as to stay the tide of their former habitudes of mind, surrounded as they are with temptation, without a deep, and thorough, and experimental acquaintance with the Saviour. And if they are thrown upon their own watchfulness and resources, for strength against temptation, instead of being directed to the Saviour, they are certain to become discouraged, and fall into dismal bondage. 12. But, before I conclude these remarks, I must not omit to notice the indispensable necessity of a willingness to do the will of God, in order rightly to understand this doctrine. If a man is unwilling to give up his sins, to deny himself all ungodliness and every worldly lust, if he is iinwilling to be set apart wholly and forever to the service of the Lord, he will either reject this doctrine altogether, or only intellectually admit it, without receiving it into his heart. It is an eminently dangerous state of mind to assent to this, or any other doctrine of the gospel, and not reduce it to practice. 13. Much evil has been done by those who have professedly embraced this doctrine in theory, and rejected it in practice. Their spirit and temper have been such as to lead those who saw them to infer, that the tendency of the doctrine itself was bad. And it is not to be doubted that some who have professed to have experienced the power of this doctrine in their hearts, have greatly disgraced religion, by exhibiting a very different spirit from that of an entirely sanctified one. But why in a Christian land should this be a stumbling block ? When the heathen see persons from Christian nations who professedly adopt the Christian system, exhibit on their shores, and in their countries, the spirit which many of them do, they infer that this is the tendency of the Christian religion. To this our missionaries reply, that they are only nominal Christians, only speculative, not real believers. Should thousands of our church members go among them, they would have the same reason to complain ; and might reply to the missionaries, these are not only nominal believers, but profess to have experienced the Christian religion in their own hearts. Now what would the missionaries reply ? Why, to be sure, that they were professors of religion ; but that they really did not know Christ, that they were deceiving themselves with a name to live, while in fact they were dead in trespasses and sins. It has often been a matter of astonishment to me, that in a Christian SANCTIPICATION. 479 land, it should be a stumbling-block to any, that some, or if you please, a majority of those who profess to receive and to have experienced the truth of this doctrine, should exhibit an unchristian spirit. What if the same objection should be brought against the Christian religion ; against any and every doctrine of the gospel, that the great majority of all the professed belierers and receivers of those doctrines were proud, worldly, selfish, and exhibited anything but a right spirit ? This objec- tion might be made with truth to the professed Christian church. But would the conclusiveness of such an objection be admitted in Christian lands ? Who does not know the ready answer to all such objections as these, that the doctrines of Christianity do not sanction such con- duct, and that it is not the real belief of them that begets any such spirit or conduct ; that the Christian religion abhors all these objectionable things. And now suppose it should be replied to this, that a tree is known by its fruits, and that so great a majority of the professors of religion could not exhibit such a spirit, unless it were the tendency of Christianity itself to beget it. Who would not reply to this, that this state of mind and course of conduct of which they complain, is the natural state ot man uninfluenced by the gospel of Christ ; that, in these instances, on account of unbelief, the gospel has failed to correct what was already wrong, and that it needed not the influence of any corrupt doctrine to produce that state of mind ? It appears to me, that these objectors against this doctrine, on account of the fact that some and perhaps many who have professed to receive it, have exhibited a wrong spirit, take it for granted that the doctrine produces this spirit, instead of considering that a wrong spirit is natural to men, and that the diflBculty is that through unbelief, the gospel has failed to correct what was before wrong. They reason as if they supposed the human heart needed some- thing to beget within it a bad spirit, and as if they supposed, that a belief in this doctrine had made men wicked ; instead of recognizing the fact, that they were before wicked, and that through unbelief the gospel has failed to make them holy. 14 But let it not be understood, that I suppose or admit, that the great mass who have professed to have received this doctrine into their hearts, have exhibited a bad spirit. I must say, that it has been emi- nently otherwise, so far as my own observation extends. And I am fully convinced, that if I have ever seen Christianity and the spirit of Christ in the world, it has been exhibited by those, as a general thing, who have professed to receive this doctrine into their heart. 15. How amazingly important it is, that the ministry and the church should come fully to a right understanding and embracing of this doc- trine. 0, it will be like life from the dead 1 The proclamation of it ifl now regarded by multitudes as "good tidings of great joy." From *80 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. every quarter, we get the gladsome intelligence, that souls are entenng into the deep rest and peace of the gospel, that they are awaking to a life of faith and love — and that, instead of sinking down into antino- mianism, they are eminently more benevolent, active, holy and useful than ever before ; that they are eminently more prayerful, watchful, diligent, meek, sober-minded, and heavenly in all their lives. This is the character of those, to a very great extent, at least, with whom I have been acquainted, who have embraced this doctrine, and professed to have experienced its power. I say this for no other reason, than to relieve the anxieties of those who have heard very strange reports, and whose honest fears have been awakened in regard to the tendency of - this doctrine. 16. Much pains have been taken to demonstrate, that our views of this subject are wrong. But in all the arguing to this end hitherto, there has been one grand defect. None of the opponents of this doctrine have yet showed us " a more excellent way, and told us what is right." It is certainly impossible to ascertain what is wrong, on any moral sub- ject, unless we have before us the standard of right. The mind must ■■ certainly be acquainted with the rule of right, before it can reasonably pronounce anything wrong ; "for by the law is the knowledge of sin." It is therefore certainly absurd, for the opponents of the doctrine of en- tire sanctification in this life, to pronounce this doctrine wrong without being able to show us what is right. To what purpose, then, I pray, do they argue, who insist upon this view of the subject as wrong, while they do not so much as attempt to tell us wh^.t is right ? It cannot be pre- tended, that the scriptures teach nothing upon this subject. And the question is, what do they teach ? We therefore call upon the denouncers of this doctrine, and we think the demand reasonable, to inform us defi- nitely, how holy Christians may be, and are expected to be in this life. And it should be distinctly understood, that until they bring forward the rule laid down in the scripture upon this subject, it is but arrogance to pronounce anything wrong ; just as if they should pronounce any- thing to be sin without comparing it with the standard of right. Until they inform us what the scriptures do teach, we must beg leave to be excused from supposing ourselves obliged to believe, that what is taught in these lectures is wrong, or contrary to the language and spirit of in- spiration. This is certainly a question that ought not to be thrown loosely aside, without being settled. The thing at which we aim is, to establish a definite rule, or to explain what we suppose to be the real and explicit teachings of the Bible upon this point. And y^e do think it absurd, that the opponents of this view should attempt to convince us of error, without so much as attempting to show what the truth upon this mbject is. As if we "ould. easily enough decide what is contrary to ELECTION. 481 right, without possessing any knowledge of right. We therefore beseech our brethren, in discussing this subject, to show us what is right. And if this is not the truth, to show us a more excellent way, and convince us that we are wrong, by showing us what is right. Por we have no hope of ever seeing that we are wrong, until we can see that something else than what is advocated in this discussion, is right. 17. But before I close my remarks upon this subject, I must not fail to state what I regard as the present duty of Christians. It is to hold their will in a state of consecration to God, and to lay hold on the promises for the blessing promised in such passages as 1 Thess. v. 33, 24 : — ",And the very God of peace sanctify you wholly, and I pray God your whole spirit, and soul, and body, be preserved blameless unto the coming of our Lord Jesus Christ ; faithful is he that calleth you, who also wi|l do it." This is present duty. Let them wait on the Lord in faith, for that cleansing of the whole being which they need, to confirm, strengthen, settle them. All they can do, and all that God requires them to do, is to obey him from moment to moment, and to lay hold of him for the blessing of which we have been speaking ; and to be assured, that God will bring forth the answer in the best time and in the best manner. If you believe, the anointing that abideth will surely be secured in due time. LECTURE XLIIL ELECTION. In discussing this subject, I. I shall notice some points in which there is a general agreement among all denominations of Christians respecting the natural and moral attributes of God. 1. It is agi'eed that eternity is a natural attribute of God in the sense that he grows no older. He was just as old before the world or universe was made, as he is now, or as he will be at the day of judgment. 3. It is agreed that omniscience is an attribute of God, in the sense that he knows from a necessity of his infinite nature all things that are objects of knowledge. 3. That he has necessarily and eternally possessed this knowledge, so that he never has, and never can have, any accession to his knowledge. Every possible thing that ever was, or will be, or can be an object of knowledge, has been necessarily and eternally known to God. If this were not true, God would be neither infinite nor omniscient, 31 482 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. 4. It is agreed also that God exercises an universal providence, em- bracing all events that ever did or ever will occur in all worlds. Some of these events he secures by his own agency, and others occur under his providence, in the sense that he permits or suffers them to occur rather than interpose to prevent them. They may be truly said to occur under his providence, because his plan of government in some sense embraces them all. He made provision to secure those that are good, that is, the holy intentions of moral agents, and to overrule for good those that are evil, that is, the selfish intentions of moral agents. These intentions are events, and may be said to occur under Divine Providence, because all events that do, or ever will, occur, are and must be foreseen results of God's own agency, or of the work of creation. 5. It is agreed that infinite benevolence is the sum of the moral at- tributes of God. 6. That God is both naturally and morally immutable ; that in his natural attributes he is necessarily so, and in his moral attributes is certainly so. 7. It is agreed that all who are converted, sanctified and saved, are converted, sanctified, and saved by God's own agency ; that is, God saves them by securing, by his own agency, their personal and individual holi- ness. II. WJiai the Bible doctrine of election is not. 1. The Bible doctrine of election is not that any are chosen to salva- tion, in such a sense, that they will or can be saved without repentance, faith, and sanctification. 2. l^OT is it that some are chosen to salvation, in such a sense, that they will be saved irrespective of their being regenerated, and persever- ing in holiness to the end of life. The Bible most plainly teaches, that these are naturally indispensable conditions of salvation, and of course election cannot dispense with them. 3. Nor is it that any are chosen to salvation for, or on account of their own foreseen merits, or good works. 2 Tim. i. 9 : " Who hath saved us, and called us with a holy calling, not according to our works, but according to his own purpose and grace, which was given us in Christ Jesus before the world began." The foreseen fact, that by the wisest gov- ernmental arrangement God could convert and sanctify and fit them for heaven, must have been a condition in the sense of a sine qud non, of their election to salvation, but could not have been the fundamental rea- son for it, as we shall see. God did not elect them to salvation, for or on account of their foreseen good works, but upon condition of their fore- seen repentance, faith and perseverance. 4. The Bible doctrine of election is not that God elected some to stir ELECTION. 483 fation, upon such conditions that it is really uncertain whether they will comply with those conditions, and be finally saved. The Bible does not leave the question of the final salvation of the elect as a matter of real uncertainty. This we shall see in its place. The elect were chosen to salvation, upon condition that God foresaw that he could secure their re- pentance, faith, and final perseverance. III. What the Bible doctrine of election is. It is, that all of Adam's race, who are or ever will be saved, were from eternity chosen by God to eternal salvation, through the sanctiflcation of their hearts by faith in Christ. In other words, they are chosen to sal- vation by means of sanctiflcation. Their salvation is ithe end — their sanctiflcation is a means. Both the end and the means are elected, ap- pointed, chosen ; the means as really as the end, and for the sake of the end. The election of some individuals and nations to certain privileges, and to do certain things, is not the kind of election of which I treat at this time ; but I am to consider the doctrine of election as it respects election unto salvation, as just explained. IV. I am to prove the doctrine as I have stated it to be true. 1. It is plainly implied in the teaching of the Bible : the Bible every- where assumes and implies the truth of this doctrine just as might be expected, since it so irresistibly follows from the known and admitted attributes of God. Instead of formally revealing it as a truth unknown to, or unknowable by, the human reason, the scriptures in a great vari- ety of ways speak of the elect, of election, etc., as a truth known by irresistible inference from his known attributes. To deny it involves a denial of the attributes of God. I have been surprised at the labored and learned efEorts to show that this doctrine is not expressly taught in the Bible. Suppose it were not, what then ? Other truths are taught and reason irresistibly afi&rms truths, from which the doctrine of election, as I have stated it, must follow. It is common for the inspired writers to treat truths of this class in the same manner in which this is, for the most part, treated. Suppose it were possible so to explain every passage of scripture as that no one of them should unequivocally assert the doctrine in question, this would be to no purpose ; the doctrine would still be irresistibly inferrible from the attributes of God. It would still be true, that the Bible assumes the truth of the doctrine, and incidentally speaks of it as a truth of reason, and as following of course from the attributes of God. It is thus treated throughout the entire scriptures. The Bible as really assumes the truth of this doctrine, as it does the existence of God. It asserts it just as it does the attributes of God. The learned »Dd labored efEorts to show that this doctrine is not expressly asserted in iSi SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. the Bible, are of no value, since it would follow as a certain truth from the attributes of God, and from the revealed facts, that some will be saved, and that God will save them, even had the Bible been silent on the subject. I shall therefore only introduce a few passages for the pur- pose of showing that the inspired writers repeatedly recognize the truth of this doctrine, and thus preserve their own consistency. But I shall not attempt by labored criticism to prove it from scripture, for reasons just mentioned. Matt. XX. 16 : " So the last shall be first, and the first last, for many be called, but few chosen." Matt. xxiv. 22 : " And except those days should be shortened, there should no flesh be saved ; but for the elect's sake those days shall be shortened." John xiii. 18 : "I speak not of you all ; I know whom I have chosen." John XV. 16 : "Ye have not chosen me, but I have chosen you, and ordained you, that ye should go and bring forth fruit, and that your fruit should remain ; that whatsoever ye shall ask of the Father in my name, he may give it you. 19. If ye were of the world, the world would love his own ; but because ye are not of the world, but I have chosen you out of the world, therefore the world hateth yon." Bom. viii. 28 : " And we know that all things work together for good to them that love God, to them who are the called according to his pur- pose. 29. For whom he did foreknow, he also did predestinate to be conformed to the image of his Son, that he might be the first-born among many brethren." Rom. ix. 10 : " And not only this, but when Eebecca had conceived by one, even by our father Isaac; 11. (For the children being not yet born, neither having done any good or evil, that the purpose of God according to election might stand, not of works, but of him that calleth.) 12. It was said unto her, The elder shall serve the younger. 13. As it is written, Jacob have I loved, but Esau have I hated. 14. What shall we say then ? Is there unrighteousness with God ? God forbid. 15. For he saith to Moses, I will have mercy on whom I will have mercy, and I will have compassion on whom I wiU have compassion." Rom. xi. 5 : " Even so at this present time also there is a remnant according to the election of grace. 7.. What then ? Israel hath not ob- tained that which he seeketh for, but the election hath obtained it, and the rest were blinded." Eph. i. 4 : " According as he hath chosen us in him before the foun- dation of the world, that we should be holy and without blame before him in love. 11. In whom also we have obtained an inheritance, being predestinated according to the purpose of him who worketh all things after the counsel of his own will." KLECTION. 485 1 Thess. i. 4 : " Knowing, brethren beloved, your election of God." 1 Thess. V. 9 : " For God hath not appointed us to wrath, but to ob- tain salvation by our Lord Jesus Christ." 2 Thess. ii. 13 : " But we are bound to give thanks alway to God for you, brethren beloved of the Lord, because God hath from the beginning chosen you to salvation through sanctification of the Spirit, and belief of the truth." 1 Pet. i. 2 : " Elect according to the foreknowledge of God the Father, through sanctification of the Spirit, unto obedience and sprinkling of the blood of Jesus Christ." Eev. xvii. 8 : " The beast that thou sawest was, and is not ; and shall ascend out of the bottomless pit, and go into perdition : and they that dwell on the earth shall wonder, (whose names were not written in the book of life from the foundation of the world,) when they behold the beast that was, and is not, and yet is." This doctrine is expressly as- serted, or indirectly assumed and implied in every part of the Bible, and in ways and instances too numerous to be quoted in these lectures. The above are only specimens of the scripture treatment of this subject. 2. It is plainly the doctrine of reason. (1.) It is admitted that God by his own agency secures the conversion, sanctification, and salvation of all that ever were or will be saved. (3.) Whatever volitions or actions God puts forth to convert and save men, he puts forth designing to secure that end ; that is, he does it in accordance with a previous design to do as and what he does. This must be an universal truth, to wit, that whatever God does for the sal- vation of men, he does with the design to secure the salvation of all who ever will be saved, or of all whose salvation he foresees that he can secure, and with the certain knowledge that he shall secure their sal- vation. He also does much for the non-elect, in the sense of using such means with them as might secure, and ought to secure, their salvation. But as he knows he shall not succeed in securing their salvation, on ac- count of their voluntary and persevering wickedness, it cannot be truly said, that he uses these means with design to save them, but for other, and good, and wise reasons. Although he foresees, that he cannot se- cure their salvation, because of their wilful and persevering unbelief, yet he sees it important under his government to manifest a readiness to save them, and to use such means as he wisely can to save them, and such as will ultimately be seen to leave them wholly without excuse. But with respect to those whom he foresees that he can and shall save, it must be true, since he is a good being, that he uses means for their salvation, with the design to save them. And since, as we have seen, he is an omniscient being, he must use these means, not only with a design to save them, but also with the certainty that he shall sav? them. With 486 BYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. respect to tbem, lie uses these means for the sake of this eud ; that is, for the sake of their salvation. (3.) But if God ever chooses to save any human beings, he must always have chosen to do so, or else he has changed. If he now has, or ever will have, any design about it, he must always have had this design ; for he never has, and never can have, any new design. If he ever does, or will, elect any human being to salvation, he must always have chosen or elected him, or he has, or will form some new purpose, which is in- consistent with his immutability. (4.) If he will ever know who will be saved, he must always have known it, or he will obtain some new knowledge, which is contrary to his omniscience. (5.) We are told by Christ, that at the day of judgment he will say to the righteous, "'Come, ye blessed of my Father, inherit the kingdom prepared for you from the foundation of the world j" that is, from eternity. Now, has the Judge at that time any new knowledge or design respecting those individuals ? Certainly not. (6.) Since God of necessity eternally knew all about the elect that* will ever be true, he must of necessity have chosen something in respect to them ; for it is naturally impossible, that he should have had no choice about, or in respect to, them and their salvation. (7.) Since God must of necessity from eternity have had some choice in respect to their salvation, it follows, that he must have chosen that they should be saved, or that he would not use such means as he foresaw would save them. If he chose not to use those means that he foresaw would save them, but afterwards saves them, he has changed, which is contrary to his immutability. If he always chose that they should be saved, this is the very thing for which we are contending. (8.) It must therefore be true, that all whom God will ever save wore from eternity chosen to salvation by him ; and since he saves them by means of sanctification, and does this designedly, it must be that this also was eternally designed or intended by him. To deny the doctrine of election, therefore, involves a denial of the attributes of God. (9.) It must also be true, that God foreknew all that ever will be true of the non-elect, and must have eternally had some design respecting their final destiny. And also that he has from eternity had the same, and the only design that he ever will have in respect to them. But this will come up for consideration in its place. v. What could not have been the reasons for election. 1. It is admitted that God is infinitely benevolent and wise. It must follow that election is founded in some reason or reasons ; and that these ELECTION. 487 reasons are good and sufficient ; reasons that rendered it obligatory upon God to choose just as he did, in election. Assuming, as we must, that God is wise and good, we are safe in affirming that he could have had none but benevolent reasons for his election of some to eternal life in preference to others. Hence we are bound to affirm, that election was not based upon, nor does it imply partiality in God, in any bad sense of that term. Partiality in any being, consists in preferring one to another without any good or sufficient reason, or in opposition to good and suffi- cient reasons. It being admitted that God is infinitely wise and good, it follows, that he cannot be partial ; that he cannot have elected some to eternal salvation and passed others by, without some good and sufficient reason. That is, he cannot have done it arbitrarily. The great objec- tion that is felt and urged by opposers of this doctrine is, that it implies partiality in God, and represents him as deciding the eternal destiny of moral agents by an arbitrary sovereignty. But this objection is a sheer and altogether unwarrantable assumption. It assumes, that God could have had no good and sufficient reasons for the election. It has been settled, that good is the end upon which God set his heart ; that is, the highest well being of himself and the universe of creatures. This end must be accomplished by means. If God is infinitely wise and good, he must have chosen the best practicable means. But he has chosen the best means for that end, and there can be no partiality in that. In support of the assumption, that election implies partiality, and the exercise of an arbitrary sovereignty in God, it has been affirmed, that there might have been divers systems of means for securing the same end in every respect equal to each other ; that is, that no reason existed for preferring any one, to many others ; that therefore in choosing the present, God must have been partial, or must have exercised an arbitrary sovereignty. To this I answer : — (1.) There is no ground for the assumption, that there are or can be divers systems of means of precisely equal value in all respects, in such a sense, that there could have been no good reason for preferring one to the other. (3.) I reply, that if there were divers such systems, choosing the one, and not any other, would not imply preference. Choice of any one in such case must have proceeded upon the following ground ; to wit, the value of the end demanded, that one should be chosen. There being no difference between the various systems of means, God chooses one without reference to the other, and makes no choice respecting it, any more than if it did not exist. He must choose one, he has no reason for preference, and consequently he cannot prefer one to the other. His benevolence leads him to choose one because the end demands it. He therefore takes any one of many exact equals, indifferently, without preferring it to any 488 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. of the others. This im])lies no partiality in God in any had sense of the term. For upon the supposition, he was shut up to the necessity of choosing one among many exact equals. If he is partial in choosing the one he does, he would have been equally so had he chosen any other. If this is partiality, it is a partiality arising out of the necessity of the case, and cannot imply anything objectionable in God. That there is no preference in this case is plain, because there is no ground or reason for preference whatever, according to the supposition. But there can be no choice or preference, when there is absolutely no reason for the choice or preference. We have seen on a former occasion, ^that the reason that determines choice, or the reason in view of which, or in obedience to which, or for the sake of which, the mind chooses, and the object or end chosen, are identical. When there is absolutely no rea- son for a choice, there is absolutely no object of choice, nothing to choose, and of course there can be no choice. Choice must have an object ; that is, choice must terminate upon something. If choice exists, something must be chosen. If there are divers systems of means, between which there is no possible ground of preference, there can absolutely be no such thing as preferring one to the other, for this would be the same as to choose without any object of choice, or without choosing anything, which is a contradiction. If it be said, that there may be absolutely no difference in the system of means, so far as the accomplishment of the end is concerned, but that one may be preferred or preferable to another, on some other account, I ask on what other account ? According to the supposition, it is only valued or regarded as an object of choice at all, because of its relation to the end. God can absolutely choose it only as a means, a condition, or an end ; for all choice must respect these. The inquiry now respects means. Now, if as a means, there is absolutely no difference between diverse systems in their relation to'the end, and the value of the end is the sole reason for choosing them, it follows, that to prefer one to another is a natural impossibility. But one must be chosen for the sake of the end, it matters not which ; any one is taken indifferently so far as others are concerned. This is no partiality, and no exercise of arbitrary sove- reignty in any objectionable sense. But as I said, there is no ground for the assumption, that there are various systems of means for accomplishing the great end of benevolence in all respects equal. There must have been a best way, a best system, and if God is infinitely wise and good, he must have chosen that for that reason ; and this is as far as possible from partiality. Neither we, nor any other creature may be able now to discover any good reasons for pre- ferring the present to any other system, or for electing those who are elected, in preference to any other. Nevertheless, such reasons must ELECTION. 489 have been apparent to the Divine mind, or no such election could have taken place. 2. Election was not an exercise of arbitrary sovereignty. By arbitrary sovereignty is intended the choosing and acting from mere will, without consulting moral obligation or the public good. It is admitted that God is infinitely wise and good. It is therefore impossible that he should choose or act arbitrarily in any case whatever. He musb have good and BuflBcient reasons for every choice and every act. Some seem to have represented God, in the purpose or act of election, as electing some and not others, merely because he could or would, or in other words,' to exhibit his own sovereignty, without any other reasons than because so he would have it. But it is impossible for God to act arbitrarily, or from any but a good and sufficient reason ; that is, it is impossible for him to do so, and continue to be benevolent. We have said that God has one, and but one end in view ; that is, he does, and says, and suffers all for one and the same reason, namely, to promote the highest good of being. He has but one ultimate end, and all his volitions are only efforts to secure that end. The highest well being of the uni- verse, including his own, is the end on which his supreme and ultimate choice terminates. All his volitions are designed to secure this end, and in all things he is and must be directed by his infinite intelligence, in respect not only to his ultimate end, but also in the choice and use of the means of accomplishing this end. It is impossible that this should not be true, if he is good. In election then he cannot possibly have exercised any arbitrary sovereignty, but must have had the best of reasons for the election. His intelligence must have had'^good reasons for the choice of some and not of others to salvation, and have affirmed his obligation in view of those reasons to elect just as and whom he did. So good must the reasons have been, that to have done otherwise, would have been sin in him ; that is, to have done otherwise would not have been wise and good. 3. Election was not based on a foreseen difference in the moral char- acter of the elect and the non-elect, previous to regeneration. The Bible everywhere affirms, that, previous to regeneration, all men have precisely the same character, and possess one common heart or disposition, that this character is that of total moral depravity. God did not choose some to salvation because he foresaw that they would be less depraved and guilty, previous to regeneration, than the non-elect. Paul was one of the elect, yet he affirms himself to have been the chief of sinners. We often see, and this has been common in every age, the most outwardly aban- doned and profligate converted and saved. The reason of election is not found in the fact, that God foresaw that some would be more readily converted than others. We oftep see those 490 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. who are converted hold out for a long time in great obstinacy and rebel- lion, while God brings to bear upon them a great variety of means and influences, and takes much more apparent pains to convert them than he does to convert many others who are, as well as those who are not, con- verted. There is reason to believe, that if the same means were used with those who are not converted that are used with those who are, many who are not converted would be. It may not be wise in God to use the same means for the non-elect, and if he should, they might, or might not be saved by them. God often uses means that to us seem more powerful to convert the non- elect than are used to convert many of the elect. This is fully implied in Matt. xi. 20-34. The fact is, he mast have some reason aside from their characters for stubbornness or otherwise, for elect- ing them to salvation, VI. What must have been the reasons for election. 1. We have seen that God is infinitely wise and good. From the wisdom and goodness of God, it follows, that he must have chosen some good end, and must have had some plan, or system of means, to secure it. The end, we know, is the good of being. The means, we know from reason and revelation, include election in the sense explained. It fol- lows, that the fundamental reason for election was the highest good of the universe. That is, the best system of means for securing the great end of benevolence, included the election of just those who were elected, and no others. This has been done by the wisdom and benevolence of God. It follows, that the highest good demanded it. All choice must respect ends, or conditions and means. God has, and can have, but one ultimate end. All other choices or volitions must respect means. The choice or election of certain persons to eternal salvation, etc., must have- been founded in the reason, that the great end of benevolence de- manded it. 2. It is very easy to see, that under a moral government, it might be impossible so to administer law, as to secure the perpetual and universal obedience of all. It is also easy to see, that under a remedial system, or system of grace, it might be impossible to secure the repentance and salvation of all. God must have foreseen all possible and actual results. He must have fore- seen how many, and whom he could save by the wisest and best possible arrangement, all things considered. The perfect wisdom and benevo- lence of God being granted, it follows, that we are bound to regard the present system of means as the best, all things considered, that he could adopt for the promotion ol the great end of his government, or the great end of benevolence. The fact, that the wisest and best system of govern- ment would secure the salvation of those who are elected, must have ELECTION. 491 been a condition of their being elected. As God does everything for the same ultimate reason, it follows, that the intrinsic value of their salva- tion was his ultimate end, and that their salvation in particular must have been of greater relative value in promoting the highest good of the universe at large, and the glory of God, than would have been that of others ; so that the intrinsic value of the salvation of those elected in particular, the fact that by the wisest arrangement he could save them in particular, and the paramount good to be promoted by it, must have been the reasons for election. VII. When the election was made. 1. Not when the elect are converted. It is admitted, that God is omniscient, and has known all things from eternity as really and as perfectly as he ever will. It is also admitted, that God is unchangeable, and consequently has no new plans, designs, or choices. He must have had all the reasons he ever will have for election, from eternity, because he always has had all the knowledge of all events that he ever will have ; consequently he always or from eternity chose in respect to all events just as he always will. There never can be any reason for change in the Divine mind, for he never will have any new views of any subject. The choice which constitutes election, then, must be an eternal choice. 2. Thus the scriptures represent it. Eph. i. 4 : " According as he hath chosen us in him before the foun- dation of the world, that we should be holy and without blame before him in love." Eph. ii. 10 : "For we are his workmanship, created in Christ Jesus unto good works, which God hath before ordained that we should walk in them." 3 Tim. i. 9 : " Who hath saved us, and called us with a holy calling, not according to our works, but according to his own purpose and grace, which was given us in Christ Jesus before the world began." Eev. xvii. 8 : " The beast that thou sawest was, and is not, and shall ascend out of the bottomless pit, and go into perdition : and they that dwell on the earth shall wonder, (whose names were not written in the book of life from the foundation of the world,) when they behold the beast that was, and is not, and yet is." This language means from eternity, beyond question. 3. But the question will arise, was election in the order of nature subsequent to, or did it precede the Divine foreknowledge. The answer to this plainly is, that in the order of nature what could be wisely done must have been foreseen before it was determined what should be done. And what should be done must, in the order of nature, have preceded the kr owledge of what would be done. So that in the order of nature 492 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. foreknowledge of what could be wisely done preceded election, and fore- knowledge of what would be done, followed or was subsequent to elec- tion.* In other words, God must have known whom he could wisely save, prior, in the order of nature, to his determination to save them. But his knowing who would be saved must have been, in the order of nature, subsequent to his election or determination to save them, and dependent upon that determination. VIII. Election does not render means for the salvation of the elect unnecessary. We have seen that the elect are chosen to salvation through the use of means. Since they are chosen to be saved by means, they cannot be saved in any other way or without them, IX. Election is the only ground of hope in the success of means. 1. No means are of any avail unless God gives them efficiency. 2. If God gives them efficiency in any case, it is, and will be, in accordance with, and in execution of, his election. 3. It follows that election is the only ground of rational hope in the use of means to efEect the salvation of any. X. Election does not oppose any obstacle to the salvation of the non- elect. 1. God has taken care to bring salvation within the reach of all, and to make it possible to all. 2. He sincerely offers to save all, and does all to save all that he wisely can. 3. His saving some is no discouragement to others, but should rather encourage them to lay hold on eternal life. 4. The election of some is no bar to the salvation of others. 5. Those who are not elected may be saved, if they will but comply with the conditions, which they are able to do. 6. God sincerely calls, and ministers may sincerely call on the non elect to lay hold on salvation. 7. There is no injury or injustice done to the non-elect by the elec- tion of others. Has not God " a right to do what he will with his own ?" If he offers salvation to all upon terms the most reasonable, and • I Bay, in the order of nature. With God all duration or time is present. In the order of time, therefore, all the divine ideas and purposes are cotemporaneons. But the divine ideas mast sustain to each other a logical relation. In the above para- graph I have stated what must have been the logical order of the Divine ideas in re gard to election. By the order of nature, is intended that connection and relatioB of ideas that must result from the nature of intellect. ELECTION. 493 if he does all he wisely can for the salvation of all, shall some complain if God, in doing for all what he wisely can, secures the salvation of some and not of others ? XI. There is no injustice in election. God was nnder obligation to no one — he might in perfect justice have sent all mankind to hell. The doctrine of election will damn no one : by treating the non-elect according to their deserts, he does them no injustice ; and surely his exercising grace in the salvation of the elect, is no act of injustice to the non-elect ; and especially will this appear to be true, if we take into consideration the fact, that the only reason why the non-elect will not be saved is, because they pertinaciously refuse salvation. He offers mercy to all. The atonement is sufficient for all. All may come, and are under an obligation to be saved. He strongly desires their salvation, and does all that he wisely can to save them. Why then should the doctrine of election be thought unjust ? * * To this paragraph it has been objected as follows : — " Can it be said, that the only reason why the non-elect are not saved is their rejection of salvation, etc 1 la there not a reason back of this 1 God does not give that gracious influence in their case, which he does in the case of the elect. If the only reason why the non-elect are not saved is their pertinacious refusal, then it would follow that the only reason why the elect are saved, is their acceptance of salvation. If these two points are so, thCin why all this discussion about election to salvation, and the means to that end, and God's reason for electing V The whole matter would resolve itself into free- will, and God would stand quite independent of the issue in every case. Then would there be no such thing as election." The objection contains a non sequitur. I say, the only reason why the non-elect are not saved, is because they pertina- ciously refuse salvation. But if this is true, he says, " it will follow that the only reason why the elect are saved, is their acceptance of salvation. But this does not follow. The non-elept fail of salvation only because they resist all the grace that God can wisely bestow upon them. This grace they resist, and fail of salvation. It is no more reasonable to say, that God's not giving them more divine influence to convert them " is a reason back of this," than it would be to say that his not having by a gracious influence, restrained them from sin altogether, is " a reason back of " their pertinacious resistance of grace. If the non-elect are lost, or fail of salvation only because they resist all the grace that God can wisely bestow, it would not fol- low that the only reason why the elect are saved, is because they accept, or yield to the same measure of gracious influence as that bestowed upon the non-elect, for it may be, and in many cases the fact is, that God does bestow more gracious influence on the elect, than on the non-elect, because he can wisely do so. Here then is a plain non sequitur. Observe, I am writing in the paragraph in question upon the justice of the divine proceeding. I say, that so far as this is concerned, he fails of salvation, not because God withholds the grace that he could wisely bestow, but only because he rejects the grace profiered, and all that can be wisely proffered. If I understand this objector, there is another non sequitur in his objection. I naderstand him to sa/, that upon the supposition that the elect and the non-elect 494 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. XII. 77m is the best that could be done for the inhabitants of this world. It is reasonable to infer from the infinite benevolence of God, that his present government will secure a greater amount of good than could have been secured under any other mode of administration. This is as certain as that infinite benevolence must prefer a greater to a less good. have the same measure of gracious influence, and that the reason why the elect are saved, and the non-elect not saved is, that the elect yield to, and the non-elect resist this influence ; the whole question resolves into free-will, and there is no election about it. If this is his meaning, as I think it must be, it is a plain non tequitur. Suppose God foresaw that this would be so, and in view of this foreseen fact elected those who he foresaw would yield both to the privileges and gracious influence to which he foresaw they would yield, and to salvation as a consequence of this influence and yielding. And suppose he foresaw that the non-elect, although ordained or elected to enjoy the same measure of gracious influence, would resist and reject salvation, and for this cause rejected or reprobated them in his eternal purpose. Would not this be election ? To be sure, in this case the different results would turn upon the fact that the elect yielded, and the non-elect did not yield, to the same measure of gracious influence. But there would be an election of the one to eternal life, and a rejection of the other. I cannot see how this objector can say, that in this case there coald be no election, unless in his idea of election there is the exercise of an arbitrary sovereignty. I suppose that God bestows on men une- qual measures of gracious influence, but that in this there is nothing arbitrary ; that, on the contrary, he sees the wisest and best reasons for this ; that being in justice under obligation to none, he exercises his own benevolent discretion, in bestowing on all as much gracious Inflaence as he sees to be upon the whole wise and good, and enough to throw the entire responsibility of their damnation upon them if they are lost. But upon some he foresaw that he could wisely bestow a sufficient measure of gracious influence to secure their voluntary yielding, and upon others he could not bestow enough in fact to secure this result, In accord- ance with this foreknowledge, he chose the elect to both the gracious influence and its results, eternal life. In all this there was nothing arbitrary or unjust. He does all for all that he wisely can. He does enough for all to leave them without ex- cuse. If the non-elect would yield to that measure of gracious influence which he can and does bestow upon them, which is the best he can do without acting unwisely, and of course wickedly, they would be saved. To this they might yield. To this they ought to yield. God has no right to do more than he does for them, all thidgs considered ; and there is no reason of which they can j ustly complain why they are not saved. They can with no more reason complain of his not giving them more gracious influence than that he created them, or that he made them free agents, or that he did not restrain them from sin altogether, or do anything else which it had been unwise, and therefore wrong to have done. Nor is the fact that God does not bestow on them suflacient grace to secure their yielding and salvation, a, " reason back of their obstinacy to which their not being saved is to be ascribed," any more than any one of the above-named things is such a reason. This objection proceeds upon the assumption, that election must be uncondi- tional to be election at all — that election must be so defined, as to be the eauie of thn difference in the eternal state of the elect and non-elect. But I see out why ELECTION. 495 To suppose that God would prefer a mode of administration that would secure a less good than could have been secured under some other mode, would manifestly be to accuse him of a want of beneyolence. Jt is doubt- less true that he could so vary the course of events as to save other indi- viduals than those he does ; to convert more in one particular neighbor- hood, or family, or nation, or at one particular time ; or it may be a greater number upon the whole than he does. It would not follow that be does not secure the greater good upon the whole. Suppose there is a man in this town, who has so strongly intrenched himself in error, that there is but one man in all the land who is so ac- quainted with his refuge of lies as to be able to answer his objections, and drive him from his hiding-places. Now, it is possible, that if this individual could be brought in contact with him, he might be converted ; yet if he is employed in some distant part of the vineyard, his removal from that field of labor to this town, might not, upon the whole, be most for the glory of God's kingdom ; and more might fail of salvation through his removal here, than would be converted by such removal. God has in view the good of his whole kingdom. He works upon a vast and com- prehensive scale. He has no partialities for individuals, but moves forward in the administration of his government with his eye upon the general good, designing to secure the greatest amount of happiness with- in his kingdom that can be secured by the wisest possible arrangement, and administration of his government. XIII. How we may ascertain our own election. Those of the elect that are already converted, are known by their character and conduct. They have evidence of their election in their obedience to God, Those that are unconverted may settle the question each one for himself, whether he is elected or not, so as to have the most satisfactory evidence whether he is of that happy number. If you will now submit yourselves to God, you may have evidence that you are elected. But every hour you put off submission, increases the evidence that you are not elected. Every sinner under the gospel has it within his power to accept or reject salvation. The elect can know their election only by accepting the offered gift. The non-elect can know their non-election only by the consciousness of a voluntary rejection of offered life. If any one fears election ma^ not be conditioned upon the foreseen fact, that the wisest possible administration of moral government would secure the free concurrence of some, and not of others. What could be wisely done being foreseen, the purpose that so it should be done would be election. No man has a right to define the terms election and reprobation in such a, sense, as to exclude all conditions, and then insist that conditional election is no election at all. 496 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. that he is one of the non-elect, let him at once renounce his unbelief, and cease to reject salvation, and the ground of fear and complaint in- stantly falls away. INFERENCES AND EBMARK3. 1. Foreknowledge and election are not inconsistent with free agency. The elect were chosen to eternal life, upon condition that God foresaw that in the perfect exercise of their freedom, they could be induced to repent and embrace the gospel. 2. You see why many persons are opposed to the doctrine of election, and try to explain it away ; 1st., they misunderstand it, and 2nd, they deduce unwarrantable inferences from it. They suppose it to mean, that the elect will be saved at all events, whatever their conduct may be ; and again, they infer from the doctrine that there is no possibility of the sal- vation of the non-elect. The doctrine, as they understand it, would be an encouragement to the elect to persevere in sin, knowing that their salvation was sure, and their inference would drive the non-elect to des- peration, on the ground that for them to make efforts to be saved would be of no avail. But both the doctrine, as they understand it, and the inference, are false. For election does not secure the salvation of the elect irrespective of their character and conduct ; nor, as we have seen, does it throw any obstacle in the way of the salvation of the non-elect. 3. This view of the subject affords no ground for presumption on the one hand, nor for despair upon the other. No one can justly say, If I am to be saved I shall be saved, do what I will. Nor can any one say. If I am to be damned I shall be damned, do what I will. But the question is left, so far as they are concerned, as a matter of entire contingency. Sinners, your salvation or damnation is as absolutely suspended upon your own choice, as if God neither knew nor designed anything about it. 4. This doctrine lays no foundation for a controversy with God. But on the other hand, it does lay a broad foundation for gratitude, both on the part of the elect and non-elect. The elect certainly have great reason for thankfulness, that they are thus distinguished. Oh, what a thought, to have your name written in the book of life, to be chosen of God an heir of eternal salvation, to be adopted into his family, to be destined to enjoy his presence, and to bathe your soul in the boundless ocean of his love for ever and ever ! Nor are the non-elect without obligations of thankfulness. You ought to be grateful, if any of your brethren of the human family are saved. If all were lost, God would be just. And if any of this dying world receive the gift of eternal life, you ought to be grateful, and render everlasting thanks to God. 5. The non-elect often enjoy as great or greater privileges than the •lect. Many men have lived and died under the sound of the gospel ELECTION. 497 have enjoyed all the means of salvation during a long life, and have at last died in their sins, while others have been converted upon their first hearing the gospel of God. Nor is this difference owing to the fact, that the elect always have more of the strivings of the Spirit than the non- elect. Many who die in their sins, appear to have had conviction for a great part of their lives ; have often been deeply impressed with a strong sense of their sins and the value of their souls, but have strongly in- trenched themselves under refuges of lies, have loved the world and hated God, and fought their way through all the obstacles that were thrown around them to hedge up their way to death, and have literally forced their passage to the gates of hell. Sin was their voluntary choice. 6. Why should the doctrine of election be made a stumbling-block in the way of sinners ? In nothing else do they make the same use of the purposes and designs of God, as they do on the subject of religion ; and yet, in everything else, God's purposes and designs are as much settled, and have as absolute an influence. God has as certainly designed the day and circumstances of your death, as whether your soul shall be saved. It is not only expressly declared in the Bible, but is plainly the doctrine of reason. What would you say if you should be called in to see a neigh- bor who was sick ; and, on inquiry, you should find he would neither eat nor drink, and that he was verily starving himself to death. On expos- tulating with him upon his conduct, suppose he should calmly reply, that he believed in the sovereignty of God, in foreknowledge, election and decrees ; that his days were numbered, that the time and circumstances of his death were settled, that he could not die before his time, and that all efforts he could make would not enable him to live a moment beyond his time ; and if you attempted to remonstrate against his inference, and such an abuse and perversion of the doctrine of decrees, he should accuse yon of being a heretic, of not believing in divine sovereignty. Now, should you see a man on worldly subjects reasoning and acting thus, you would pronounce him insane. Should farmers, mechanics, and mer- chants, reason in this way in regard to their worldly business, they would be considered fit subjects for bedlam. t. How forcibly the perversion and abuse of this doctrine illustrate the madness of the human heart, and its utter opposition to the terms of salvation 1 The fact that God foreknows, and has designs in regard to every other event, is not made an excuse for remaining idle, or worse than idle, on these subjects. But where men's duty to God is concerned, and here alone, they seize these scriptures, and wrest them to their own destruction. How impressively does this fact bring out the demonstra- tion, that sinners want an excuse for disobeying God ; that they desire an apology fbr living in sin ; that they seek an occasion for making wai npon their Maker. 33 498 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOQT. 8. I have said, that the question is as much open for your decision, that you are left as perfectly to the exercise of your freedom, as if God neither knew or designed anything in regard to your salvation. Suppose there was a great famine in New York city, and that John Jacob Astor alone had provisions in great abundance ; that he was a benevolent and liberal-minded man, and willing to supply the whole city with provisions, free of expense ; and suppose there existed a universal and most unrea- sonable prejudice against him, insomuch that when he advertised in the daily papers that his store-houses were open, that whosoever jvould, might come and receive provisions, without money and without price, they all, with one accord, began to make excuse, and obstinately refused to accept the offers. Now, suppose that he should employ all the cartmen to carry provisions around the city, and stop at every door. But still they strengthened each other's hands, and would rather die than be indebted to him for food. Many had said so much against him, that they were utterly ashamed to feel and acknowledge their dependence upon him. Others were so much under their influence as to be unwilling to offend them ; and so strong was the tide of public sentiment, that no one had the moral courage to break loose from the multitude and accept of life. Now, suppose that Mr. Astor knew beforehand the state of the public mind, and that all the citizens hated him, and had rather die than be indebted to him for food. Suppose he also knew, from the beginning, that there were certain arguments that he could bring to bear upon cer- tain individuals, that would change their minds, and that he should pro- ceed to press them with these considerations, until they had given up their opposition, had most thankfully accepted his provisions, and were saved from death. Suppose he used all the arguments and means that he wisely could to persuade the rest, but that, notwithstanding all his benevolent efforts, they adhered to the resolution, and preferred death to submission to his proposals. Suppose, further, he had perfect knowledge from the beginning, of the issue of this whole matter, would not the question of life and death be as entirely open for the decision of every individual as if he knew nothing about it ? 9. Some may ask. Why does God use means with the non-elect, which he is certain they will not accept ? I answer, because he designs that they shall be without excuse. He will demonstrate his willingness and their obstinacy before the universe. He will stop their mouths effectu- ally in judgment by a full offer of salvation ; and although he knows that their rejection of the offer will only enhance their guilt, and aggra- vate their deep damnation, still he will make the offer, as there is no other way in which to illustrate his infinite willingness to save them, and their perverse rejection of his grace. 10. Lastly, God requires you to give all diligence to make your call' REPROBATION. 499 ing and election sure. In choosing his elect, you must understand that he has thrown the responsibility of their being saved upon them • that the whole is suspended upon their consent to the terms ; you are all per- fectly able to give your consent and this moment to lay hold on eternal life. Irrespective of your own choice, no election could save you, and no reprobation can damn you. The " Spirit and the Bride say Come : let him that heareth say. Come ; let him that is athirst come ; and who- soever will, let him take the water of life freely." The responsibility is yours. God does all that he wisely can, and challenges yon to show what more he could do that he has not done. If yon go to hell, you must go stained with your own blood. God is clear, angels are clear. To your own Master you stand or fall ; mercy waits ; the Spirit strives ; Jesus stands at the door and knocks. Do not then pervert this doctrine, and make it an occasion of stumbling, till you are in the depths of hell. LECTURE XLIV. REPROBATION. Ik discussing this subject I shall endeavor to show, I. What the true doctrine of reprobation is not. 1. It is not that the ultimate end of God in the creation of any was their damnation. Neither reason nor revelation confirms, bat both con- tradict the assumption, that God has created or can create any being for the purpose of rendering him miserable as an ultimate end. God is love, or he is benevolent, and cannot therefore will the misery of any being as an ultimate end, or for its own sake. It is little less than blasphemy to represent God as creating any being for the sake of rendering him miser- able, as an ultimate end of his creation. 2. The doctrine is not, that any will be lost or miserable to all eter- nity, do what they can to be saved, or in spite of themselves. It is not only a libel upon the character of God, but a gross misrepresentation of the true doctrine of reprobation, to exhibit God as deciding to send sin- ners to hell in spite of themselves, or notwithstanding their endeavors to please God and obtain salvation. 3. Nor is this the true doctrine of reprobation, to wit : that the pur- pose or decree of reprobation is the procuring cause of the destruction of reprobates. God may design to destroy a soul because of his foreseen 500 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. ■wickedness ; but his design to destroy him for this reason does not cause his wickedness, and consequently does not prove his destruction. 4 The doctrine is not, that any decree or purpose of reprobation throws any obstacles in the way of the salvation of any one. It is not that God has purposed the damnation of any one in such sense as that the decree opposes any obstacle to the salvation of any soul under heaven. 5. Nor is it that any one is sent to hell, except for his own voluntary wickedness and ill-desert. 6. Nor is it that any one will be lost who can be induced, by all the means that can be wisely used, to accept salvation, or to repent and be- lieve the gospel. 7. Nor is it, nor does it imply, that all the reprobates might not be saved, if they would but comply with the indispensable conditions of sal- vation. 8. Nor does it imply, that the decree of reprobation presents or opposes any obstacle to their compliance with the necessary conditions of salvation. 9. Nor does it imply, that anything hinders or prevents the salvation of the reprobate, but their perverse perseverance in sin and rebellion against God, and their wilful resistance of all the means that can be wisely used for their salvation. II, What the true doctrine of reprobation is. The term reprobation, both in the Old and the New Testament, sig- nifies refuse, cast away. Jer. vi. 30 : " Reprobate silver shall men call them, because the Lord hath rejected them." The doctrine is, that cer- tain individuals of mankind are, in the fixed purpose of God, cast away, rejected and finally lost. III. This is a doctrine of reason. By this is intended, that since the Bible reveals the fact, that some will be finally cast away and lost, reason aflBrms that if God casts them off, it must be in accordance with a fixed purpose on his part to do so, for their foreseen wickedness. If, as a matter of fact, they will be cast away and lost, it must be that God both knows and designs it. That is, he both knows that they will be cast away, and designs to cast them off for their foreseen wickedness. God can certainly never possess any new knowledge respecting their character and deserts, and since he is un- changeable, he can never have any new purpose respecting them. Again, it follows from the doctrine of election. If God designs to save the elect, and the elect only, as has been shown, not for the reason, but upon condition of their foreseen repentance and faith in Christ, it must be that he designs, or purposes to cast away the wicked, for their foreseen wickedness. He purposes to do something with those whom he REPROBATION. 501 foresees will finally be impenitent. He certainly does not purpose to save them. What he will ever do with them, he now knows that he shall do with them. What he will intend to do with them he now intends to do with them, or he were not unchangeable. But we have seen that im- mutability or unchangeableness is an attribute of God. Therefore the present reprobation of those who will be finally cast away or lost, is a doctrine of reason. The doctrine of reprobation is not the election of a part of mankind to damnation, in the same sense that the elect unto salvation are elected to be saved. The latter are chosen or elected, not only to salvation, but to holiness. Election, with those who are saved, extends not only to the end, salvation, but also to the conditions or means ; to wit, the sanctifi- cation of the Spirit, and the belief of the truth. This has been shown. God has not only chosen them to salvation, but to be conformed to the image of his Son. Accordingly, he uses means with them, with the design to sanctify and save them. But he has not elected the reprobate to wickedness, and does not use means to make them wicked, with the ultimate design to destroy them. He knows, indeed, that his creating them, together with his providential dispensations, will be the occasion, not the cause, of their sin and consequent destruction. But their sin and consequent destruction are not the ultimate end God had in view in their creation, and in the train of providences that thus result. His ulti- mate end must in all cases be benevolent, or must be the promotion of good. Their sin and damnation are only an incidental result, and not a thing intended as an end, or for its own sake. God can have no pleas- ure, in either their sin or consequent misery for its own sake ; but on the contrary, he must regard both as in themselves evils of enormous magni- tude. He does not, and cannot therefore elect the reprobate to sin and damnation, in the same sense in which he elects the saints to holiness and salvation. The elect unto salvation he chooses to this end, from regard to, or delight in the end. But the reprobate he chooses to destroy, not for the sake of their destruction as an end, or from delight in it for its own sake ; but he has determined to destroy them for the public good, since their foreseen sinfulness demanded it. He does not use means to make them sinful, or with this design ; but his providence is directed to another end, which end is good ; and the destruction of the reprobate is, as has been said, only an incidental and an unavoidable result. That is, God cannot wisely prevent this result. IV. This is the doctrine of revelation. That this view of the subject is sustained by divine revelation, will appear from a consideration of the following passages : — Ex. ix. 16 : " And in very deed for this cause have I raised thee up, 502 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. for to shew in thee my power, and that my name may be declared throughout all the earth." Prov. xvi. 5 : " Every one that is proud in heart is an abomination to the Lord ; though hand join in hand, he shall not be unpunished." Mark iv. 11 : " And he said unto them, unto you it is given to know the mystery of the kingdom of God, but unto them that are without, all these things are done in parables : 13. That seeing they may see, and not perceive, and hearing they may hear and not understand, lest at any time they should be converted, and their sins should be forgiven them." Kom. ix. 17 : " For the scripture saith unto Pharaoh, even for this same purpose have I raised thee up, that I might shew my power in thee, and that my name might be declared throughout all the earth. 23. What if God, willing to shew his wrath, and to make his power known, endured with much long-suffering the vessels of wrath fitted to destruc- tion. 33. And that he might make known the riches of his glory on the vessels of mercy, which he had afore prepared unto glory. 34. Even us, whom he hath called, not of the Jews only, but also of the Gentiles ? " 2 Oor. xiii. 56 : " Examine yourselves, whether ye be in the faith ; prove your own selves ; know ye not your own selves, how that Jesus Christ is in you, except ye be reprobates? But I trust that ye' shall know that we are not reprobates." 3 Peter ii. 13 : " But these as natural brute beasts, made to be taken and destroyed, speak evil of the things that they understand not ; and shall utterly perish in their own corruption." Ezek. xviii. 33 : " Have I any pleasure at all that the wicked should die ? saith the Lord God ; and not that he should return from his ways, and live ? 33. For I have no pleasure in the death of him that dieth, saith the Lord God, wherefore turn yourselves, and live ye ? " Ezek. xxxiii. 11 : " Say unto them, as I live, saith the Lord God, I have no pleasure in the death of the wicked, but that the wicked turu from his way and live ; turn ye, turn ye, from your evil ways ; for why will ye die, house of Israel ? " 3 Peter iii. 9 : " The Lord is not slack concerning his promise, i« some men count slackness, but is long-suffering to usward, not willing that any should perish, but that all should come to repentance." These passages when duly considered are seen to teach : 1. That some men are reprobates, in the sense that God does not design to save, but to destroy them, and, — 3. That he does not delight in their destruction for its own sake ; but would prefer their salvation, if under the circumstances in which his wisdom has placed them, they could be induced to obey him. 3. But that he regards their destruction as a less evil to the universe, than would be such a change in the administration and arrangements of REPROBATION. 503 his government as would secure their salvation. Therefore, for their foreseen wickedness and perseverance in rebellion, under circumstances the most favorable to their virtue and salvation, in which he can wisely place them, he is resolved upon their destruction ; and has already m purpose cast them off for ever. V. Why sinners are reprobated or rejected. This has been already substantially answered. But to avoid misap- prehension upon a subject so open to cavil, I repeat : ^ 1. That the reprobation and destruction of the sinner is not an end, in the sense that God delights in misery, and destroys sinners to gratify a thirst for destruction. Since God is benevolent, it is impossible that this should be. 3. It is not because of any partiality in God, or because he loves the elect, and hates the reprobate, in any sense implying partiality. His benevolence is disinterested, and cannot of course be partial. 3. It is not from any want of interest in, and desire to save them, on the part of God. This he often afiBrms, and abundantly attests by his dealings with them, and the provision he has made for their salvation. 4. But the reprobates are reprobated for their foreseen iniquities : — Rom. i. 28 : "And even as they did not like to retain God in their knowledge, God gave them over to a reprobate mind, to do those things which are not convenient." Eora. ii. 6 : " Who will render to every man according to his deeds : 7. To them who, by patient continuance in well-doing, seek for glory, honor, and immortality, eternal life ; 8. But unto them that are conten- tious, and do not obey the truth, but obey unrighteousness, indignation and wrath ; 9. Tribulation and anguish, upon every soul of man that doeth evil, of the Jew first, and also of the Gentile; 10. But glory, honor, and peace, to every man that worketh good ; to the Jew first, and also to the Gentile : 11. For there is no respect of persons with God." Ezek. xviii. 4 : "Behold all souls are mine ; as the soul of the father, so also the soul of the son is mine : the soul that sinneth, it shall die. 19. Yet say ye. Why ? Doth not the son bear the iniquity of the father ? When the son hath done that which is lawful and right, and hath kept all my statutes, and hath done them, he shall surely live. 20. The soul that sinneth, it shall die. The son shall not bear the iniquity of the father, neither shall the father bear the iniquity of the son : the right- eousness of the righteous shall be upon him, and the wickedness of the wicked shall be upon him." a Cor. V. 10 : " For we must all appear before the judgment-seat of Christ, that every one may receive the things done in the body, accord- ing to that he hath done, whether it be good or bad," S04 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOaY. Gal. vi. 7 : "Be not deceived, God is not mocked : for whatsoever « man soweth, that shall he also reap." Eph. vi. 8 : " Knowing that whatsoever good thing any man doeth, the same shall he receive of the Lord, whether he be bond or free." Col. iii. 34 : "Knowing that of the Lord ye shall receive the reward of the inheritance : for ye serve the Lord Christ." Eev. xxii. 12 : " And, behold, I come quickly ; and my reward is with me, to give every man according as his work shall be." Jer. vi. 30 : " Keprobate silver shall men call them, because the Lord hath rejected them." These passages show the teachings of inspiration on this subject. Be it remembered, then, that the reason why any are reprobated, is because they are unwilling to be saved ; that is, they are unwilling to be saved on the terms upon which alone God can consistently save them. Ask sin- ners whether they are willing to be saved, and they all say, yes ; and with perfect sincerity they may say this, if they can be saved upon their own terms. But when you propose to them the terms of salvation upon which the gospel proposes to save them ; when they are required to repent and believe the gospel, to forsake their sins, and give themselves up to the service of God, they will with one consent begin to make excuse. Now, to accept these terms, is heartily and practically to consent to them. For them to say, that they are willing to accept salvation, while they actually do not accept it, is either to deceive themselves, or to utter an infamous falsehood. To be willing is to accept it ; and the fact, that they do not heartily consent to, and embrace the terms of salvation, is demonstration absolute, that they are unwilling. Yes, sinners, the only terms on which you can possibly be saved, you reject. Is it not then an insult to God for you to pretend that you are willing ? The only true reason why all of you are not Christians, is that you are unwilling. You are not made unwilling by any act of God, or because you are reprobate ; but if you are reprobate, it is because you are unwilling. * But do any of you object and say, why does not God make us will- ing ? Is it not because he has reprobated us, that he does not change our hearts and make us willing ? Ko, sinner, it is not because he has reprobated you ; but because you are so obstinate that he cannot, wisely, and in consistency with the public good, take such measures as will con- vert you. Here you are waiting for God to make you willing to go to heaven, and all the while you are diligently using the means to get to hell — yes, exerting yourself with greater diligence to get to hell, than it would cost to insure your salvation, if applied with equal zeal in the ser- vice of your God. You tempt God, and then turn round and ask him why he does not make you willing ? Now, sinner, let me ask you, do you think you are a reprobate ? IE so, what do you think the reason is BEPBOBATION. 505 that has led the infinitely benevolent God to reprobate you ? There must be some reason ; what do you suppose it is ? Did you ever seri- ously ask yourself, what is the reason that a wise and infinitely benevo- lent God has never made me willing to accept salvation ? It must be for one of the following reasons : either — (1.) He is a malevolent being, and wills your damnation for its own sake ; or — (2.) He cannot make you willing if he would ; or — (3.) You behave in such a manner in the circumstances in which you are, that, to his infinitely benevolent mind it appears unwise to take such a course as would bring you to repentance. Such a change in the admin- istration of his government as would make you willing, would not, upon the whole, be wise. Now, which of these do you think it is ? You will not probably take the ground that he is malevolent, and desires your damnation because he delights in misery ; nor will you, I suppose, take the ground that he could not convert you if he would, that is, if he thought it wise to do so. The other, then, must be the reason, to wit : that your heart, and conduct, and stubbornness, are so abominable in his sight, that, every thing considered, he sees that to use such further means with you as to secure your conversion, would, on the whole, do more hurt than good to his kingdom. I have not time at present to agitate the question whether you, as a moral agent, could not resist any possible amount of moral in- fluence that could be brought to bear upon you, consistently with your moral freedom. Do you ask how I know that the reason why God does not make you willing is, that he sees that it would be unwise in him to do so ? I an- swer, that it is an irresistible inference, from these two facts, that he is infinitely benevolent, and that he does not actually make you wilhng. I do not believe that God would neglect anything that he saw to be wise and benevolent, in the great matter of man's salvation. Who can believe that he could give his only-begotten and well-beloved Son to die for sin- ners, and then neglect any wise and benevolent means for their salvation ? No, sinner, if you are a reprobate, it is because God foresaw that you would do just as you are doing ; that you would be so wicked as to defeat all the efforts that he could wisely make for your salvation. What a variety of means he has used with you. At one time he has thrown you into the furnace of affliction ; and when this has not softened you, he has turned round and loaded you with favors. He has sent you his word, he has striven by his Spirit, he has allured you by the cross ; he has tried to melt you by the groanings of Calvary ; and tried to drive you back from the way to death, by rolling in your ears the thunders of damnation. 4t oi;e time clpudp an4 darl^ness h£^ve beep round about you ; the hpay- 506 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. ens have thundered over your head ; divine vengeance has hung out, all around your horizon, the portentous clouds of coming wrath. At another time mei'cy has smiled upon you from above like the noon-day sun, breaking through an ocean of storms. He urges every motive ; he lays heaven, earth and hell, under perpetual contributions for considerations to move your stony heart. But you deafen your ears, and close your eyes, and harden your heart, and say, " Cause the holy one of Israel to cease from before us." And what is the inference from all this ? How must all this end ? " Eeprobate silver shall men call them, because the Lord has rejected them." VI. When sinners are reprobated. 1. In respect to the act of casting them off, they are cast away only when, and not until, the cup of their iniquity is full. 2. In respect to the purpose of reprobation, they are in the purpose of God reprobated or rejected from eternity. This follows irresistibly from the omniscience and immutability of God. He has certainly and neces- sarily had from eternity all the knowledge he ever can or will have of the character of all men, and must have designed from all eternity all things respecting them which he ever will design. This follows from his un- changeableness. If he ever does cast off sinners, he must do it designedly or undesignedly. He cannot do it without any design. He must there- fore do it designedly. But if he does it designedly, it must be either that he eternally entertained this design, or that he has changed. But change of purpose or design is inconsistent with the moral immutability of God. Therefore the purpose of reprobation is eternal ; or the reprobates were in the fixed purpose of God cast off and rejected from eternity. VII. Reprobation is just. Is it not just in God to let men have their own choice, especially when the highest possible motives are held out to them as inducements to choose eternal life. What ! Is it not just to reprobate men when they obstinately refuse salvation — when every thing has been done that is con- sistent with infinite wisdom and benevolence to save them ? Shall not men be willing to be either saved or lost ? What shall God do with you ? You are unwilling to be saved ; why then should you object to being damned ? If reprobation under these circumstances is not just, I chal- lenge you, sinner, to tell what is just. VIII. Reprobation is benevolent. It was benevolent in God to create men, though he foresaw that they would sin and become reprobate. If he foresaw that, upon the whole, he could secure such an amount of virtue and happiness by means of moral BEPROBATION. 507 gOTemment, as to more than counterbalance the sin and misery of those who would be lost, then certainly it was a dictate of benevolence to cre- ate them. The question was, whether moral beings should be creatbd, and moral government established, when it was foreseen that a great evil would be the incidental consequence. Whether this would be benevolent or not, must turn upon the question, whether a good might be secured that would more than counterbalance the evil. If the virtue and happi- ness that could be secured by the administration of moral government, would greatly outmeasure the incidental evils arising out of a defection of a part of the subjects of this government, it is manifest that a truly be- nevolent mind would choose to establish the government, the attendant evils to the contrary notwithstanding. Now, if those who are lost de- serve their misery, and bring it upon themselves by their own choice, when they might have been saved, then certainly in their damnation there can be nothing inconsistent with justice or benevolence. God must have a moral government, or there can be no such thing as holiness in the created universe. For holiness in a creature is nothing else than a voluntary conformity to the government of God. Since the penalty of the law, although infinite, under the wisest possible administration of moral government, could not secure universal obedience ; and since multitudes of sinners will not be reclaimed and saved by the gospel, one of three things must be done ; either moral government must be given up ; or the wicked must be annihilated, or they must be reprobated and sent to hell. Now, that moral government should be given up, will not be pretended ; annihilation would not be just, inasmuch as it would not be an adequate expression of the abhor- rence with which the divine ruler regards the violation of his law, and consequently it would not meet the demands of public justice. Now, as sinners really deserve eternal death, and as their punishment may be of real value to the universe, in creating a respect for the authority of God, and thus strengthening his government, it is plain that their reprobation and damnation is, for the general good, making the best use of the wicked that can be made. Doubtless God views the loss of the soul as a great evil, and he always will look upon it as such, and would gladly avoid the loss of any soul, if it were consistent with the wisest administration of his government. How slanderous, injurious, and ofEensive to God it must be, then, to say, that he created sinners on purpose to damn them. He pours forth all the tender yearnings of a father over those whom he is obliged to destroy— "How shall I give thee up, Ephraim ? How shall I deliver thee, Israel ? How shall I make thee as Admah ? How shall I set thee as Zeboim ? My heart is turned within me, my repentings are kindled together." And now, sinner, can ^ou find it in your heart to accuse 608 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. the blessed God of a want of benevolence ? " ye serpents ! ye genera- tion of vipers I how can you escape the damnation of hell ?" IX. How it may he known who are reprobates. It may be diflBcult for us to ascertain with certainty in this world, who are reprobates ; but there are so many marks of reprobation given in the Bible, that by a sober and judicious investigation, we may form a pretty correct opinion, whether we or those around us are reprobates or not. 1. One evidence of reprobation is a long course of prosperity in sin. The Psalmist lays it down as such in Psa. xcii. 7 : " When the wicked spring as the grass, and when all the workers of iniquity do flourish, it is that they shall be destroyed forever." God often gives the wicked their portion in this world, and lets them prosper and wax fat like a stalled ox, and then brings them forth to the slaughter. " The wicked are reserved unto the day of wrath." When therefore you see an indi- vidual for a long time prospering in his sins, there is great reason to fear that man is a reprobate. In this passage inspiration assumes the truth of the distinction between evidence and proof. The Psalmist does not mean to be understood as aflBrming a universal truth. He did not intend, that prosperity in sin was proof conclusive that the prosperous sinner is a reprobate. But the least that could have been intended was, that such prosperity in sin afEords alarming evidence of reprobation. It may be called presumptive evidence. 2. Habitual neglect of the means of grace is a mark of reprobation. If men are to be saved at all, it is through the sanctification of the Spirit and belief of the truth ; and it will probably be found to be true, that not one in ten thousand is saved of those who habitually absent themselves from places where God presents his claims. Sometimes, I know, a tract, or the conversation or prayer of some friend, may awaken an individual, and lead him to the house of God ; but, as a general fact, if a man stays away from the means of grace, and neglects his Bible, it is a fearful sign of reprobation, and that he will die in his sins. He is vol- untary in it, and he does not neglect the means of grace because he is reprobated, but was reprobated because God foresaw that he would take this course. Suppose a pestilence were prevailing, that was certain to prove fatal in every instance where the appropriate remedy was not applied. Kow, if you wished to know whose days were numbered and finished, and who among the sick were certain to die with the disease, if you found any among them neglecting and despising the only appropri- ate remedy, you would know that they were the persons. 3. Those who have grown old in sin, are probably reprobates. It is a golemu and alarming fact, thg,t a vast majority of those who give REPROBATION. 509 evidence of piety, are converted under twenty-five years of age. Look at the history of revivals, and see, even in those that have manifested the greatest power, how few aged persons have been converted. The men who are set upon the attainment of some worldly object, and de- termined to secure that before they will attend to religion, and yield to the claims of their Maker, expecting afterwards to be converted, are almost always disappointed. Such a cold calculation is odious in the sight of God. What ! Take advantage of his forbearance, and say, that because he is merciful you will venture to continue in sin, till you have secured your worldly objects, and worn yourself out in the service of the devil, and thus turn your Maker ofE with the jaded remnant of your abused mortality ! Yon need not expect God to set his seal of approba- tion upon such a calculation as this, and suffer you at last to triumph, and say, that you had served the devil as long as you pleased, and got to heaven at last. 4. Absence of chastisements is a sign of reprobation. God says in the epistle to the Hebrews : " My son, despise not thou the chastening of the Lord, nor faint when thou art rebuked of him ; for whom the Lord loveth he chasteneth, and sconrgeth every son whom he receiveth ; if ye endure chastening, God dealeth with you as with sons ; for what son is he whom the Father chasteneth not ; but if ye be without chas- tisement, whereof all are partakers, then are ye bastards, and not sons." 5. When men are chastened and not reformed by it, it is a mark of reprobation. A poet has said, " When pain can't bless, heaven quits us in despair." God says of such, " Why should ye be stricken any more ? Ye will revolt more and more." When your afiB.ictions are unsanctifled, when you harden yourselves under his stripes, why should he not leave you to fill up the measure of your iniquity ? 6. Embracing damnable heresies, is another mark of reprobation. Where persons seem to be given up to believe a lie, there is solemn reason for fearing that they are among that number upon whom God sends strong delusions, that they may believe a lie, and be damned, because they obey not the truth, but have pleasure in unrighteousness. Where you see persons giving themselves up to such delusions, the more certainly they believe them, the greater reason there is for believing that they are reprobates. The truth is so plain, that with the Bible in your hands, it is next to impossible to believe a fundamental heresy, without being given up to the judicial curse of God. It is so hard to believe a lie, with the truth of the Bible before you, that the devil cannot do it. If therefore you reject your Bible, and embrace a fundamental false- hood, yon are more stupid and benighted than the devil is. When a man professes to believe a lie, almost the only hope of his salvation that remains, is, that he does not cordially believe it. Sinner, beware how 510 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. yon trifle with God's truth. How often have individuals begun to argue in favor of heresy, for the sake of argument, and because they loved debate, until they have finally come to believe their own lie, and are lost for ever. X. Objections. 1. To the idea that God rejected the reprobate for their foreseen wickedness, it is replied that, Prov. xvi. 4 : " The Lord hath made all things for himself ; yea, even the wicked for the day of evil," teaches another doctrine ; that this passage teaches, that God made the repro- bates for the day of evil, or for the purpose of destroying them. To this I reply, that if he did create them to destroy them, or with a design when he created them to destroy them, it does not foUow that their destruction was an ultimate end, or a thing in which he delighted for its own sake. It must be true, as has been said, that he designed from eternity to destroy them, in view, and in consequence, of their foreseen wickedness ; and of course, he designed their destruction when he created them. In one sense then, it was true, that he created them for the day of evil, that is, in the sense that he knew how they would behave, and designed as a consequence to destroy them when, and before, he created them. But this is not the same as his creating them for the sake of their destruction as an ultimate end. He had another and a higher ultimate end, which end was a benevolent one. He says "I have created all things for myself, even the wicked for the day of evil ;" that is, he had some great and good end to accomplish by them, and by their destruction. He foresaw that he could use them for some good purpose, notwithstanding their foreseen wickedness ; and even that he could over- rule their sin and destruction to manifest his justice, and thus show forth his glory, and thereby strengthen his government. He must have fore- seen that the good that might thus, from his overruling providence, result to himself and to the universe, would more than compensate for the evil of their rebellion and destruction ; and therefore, and upon this condition, he created them, knowing that he should destroy and intend- ing to destroy them. That destruction was not the ultimate end of their creation, must follow from such scriptures as the following : — Bzek. xxxiii. 11 : " Say unto them, As I live, saith the Lord God, I have no pleasure in the death of the wicked ; but that the wicked turn from his way and live : turn ye, turn ye, from your evil ways ; for why will ye die, house of Israel ? " Ezek. xviii. 23 : Have I any pleasure at all that the wicked should die ; saith the Lord God ; and not that he should return from his ways and live ? " 2 Peter iii. 9 : " The Lord is not slack concerning his promise, as REPROBATION. 511 Bome men count slackness, but is long-suffering to usward, not willing that any should perish, but that all should come to repentance," 1 John iv. 8 : "He thatloveth not, knoweth not God, for God is love. 16. And we have known and believed the love that God hath to us. God is love ; and he that dwelleth in love dwelleth in God, and God in him. " Heb. ii. 9 : " But we see Jesus, who was made a little lower than the angels for the suffering of death, crowned with glory and honor ; that he by the grace of God should taste death for every man." 2. Another objection to the doctrine of this lecture is founded on Kom. ix. 20-33 : " Nay, but man, who art thou that repliest against God ? Shall the thing formed say to him that formed it. Why hast thou made me thus ? Hath not the potter power over the clay, of the same lump to make one vessel unto honor, and another unto dishonor ? What if God, willing to shew his wrath, and make his power known, endured with much long-suffering the vessels of wrath fitted to destruction ; and that he might make known the riches of his glory on the vessels of mercy, which he had afore prepared unto glory ?" From this passage it has been inferred, that God creates the character and disposes of the destinies of both saints and sinners with as absolute and as irresistible a sovereignty as that exercised by the potter over his clay ; that he creates the elect for salvation, and the reprobate for dam- nation, and forms the character of both so as to fit them for their re- spective destinies, with an absolutely irresistible and efficient sovereignty ; that his ultimate end was in both cases his own glory, and that the value of the end justifies the use of the means, that is, of such means. To this I reply :— (1.) That it is absurd and nonsensical, as we have abundantly seen, to talk of creating moral character, either good or bad, by an irresistible efficient sovereignty. This is naturally impossible, as it implies a con- tradiction. Moral character must be the result of proper, voluntary action, and the moral character of the vessels of wrath or of mercy neither is, nor can be, formed by any irresistible influence whatever. (2.) It is not said nor implied in the passage under consideration, that the character of the vessels of wrath was created, or that God had any such agency in procuring their character, as he has in forming the char- acter of the vessels of mercy. Of the vessels of wrath it is only said they are " fitted to destruction," that is, that their characters are adapted for hell ; while of the vessels of mercy it is said " which he had afore pre- pared unto glory." The vessels of wrath are fitted, or had fitted them- selves to destruction, under the light and influence that should have made them holy. The vessels of mercy God had, by the special grace and in- fluence of the Holy Spirit, engaging and directing their voluntary agency, afore prepared for glory. 512 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. (3.) But the lump spoken of in the text contemplates, not the origi- nal creation of men, nor the forming or creating in them of a wicked character. But it manifestly contemplates them as already existing as the potter's clay exists ; and not only as existing, but also as being sinners. God may reasonably proceed to form out of this lump vessels of wrath or of mercy, as seems wise and good unto him. He may appoint one por- tion to honor and another to dishonor, as is seen by him to be demanded by the highest good. (4.) The passage under consideration cannot, in any event, be pressed into the service of those who would insist, that the destruction of the reprobate is chosen for its own sake, and therefore implies malevolence in God. Hear what it says : " What if God, willing to show his wrath, and make his power known, endured with much long-suffering the ves- sels of wrath fitted to destruction ; and that he might make known the riches of his glory on the vessels of mercy, which he had afore prepared unto glory ?" Here it appears, that he designed to show and make known his attributes. This cannot have been an ultimate, but must have been a proximate, end. The ultimate end must have been the highest glory of himself, and the highest good of the universe, as a whole. If God willed thus to make known his holiness and his mercy, for the purpose of securing the highest good of the universe, who has a right to say. What doest thou ? or Why doest thou thus ? 3. Another objection is, if God knew that they would be reprobate or lost, why did he create them ? If he knew that such would be the result, and yet created them, it follows that he created them to destroy them. I reply : — This objection has been already answered, but for the sake of per- spicuity I choose here to answer it again. From the admitted fact, that God knew when he created them jnsl what their destiny would be, it does not follow that their destruction was the end for which he created them. He created them, not for their sin and destruction as an ultimate end, but for another and a good end, not- withstanding his foreknowledge of their sin and ultimate ruin. 4 It is further objected, that if God designed to make known his at- tributes, in the salvation of the vessels of mercy, and in the destruction of the vessels of wrath, he must have designed their characters as well as their end, inasmuch as their characters are indispensable conditions of this result. I reply, that it is true, that the characters of both the vessels of wrath and of mercy must have been in some sense purposed or designed by God. But it does not follow that he designed them both in the same sense. The character of the righteous he designed to beget, or induce by his own agency ; the character of the wicked he designed to suffer BEPROBATlOtT. 513 him to form for himself. He doubtless designed to suffer the one rather than to interfere, in such manner and tovva. as would prevent sin, seeing as he did, that, hateful as it was in itself, it could be overruled for good. The other he designed to produce, or rather induce, both ona.ccount of the pleasure he has in holiness, and also for the sake of its bearings on the subject of it, and upon the universe. 5. To the doctrine of this lecture it is further objected, that if one is a reprobate it is of no use for him to try to be saved. If God knows what he will be in character, and designs his destruction, it is impossible that it should be otherwise than as God knows and designs, and there- fore one may as well give up in despair first as last. (1.) To such an objector I would say, you do not know that you are a reprobate, and therefore you need not despair. (3.) If God designs to cast you off, though you cannot know this, it is only because he foresees that you will not repent and believe the gospel ; or in other words, for your voluntary wickedness. He foreknows that yon will be wicked simply becaiise you will be, and not because his fore- knowledge makes you so. Neither his foreknowledge respecting your character, nor his design to cast you off, in consequence of your charac- ter, has any agency in making you wicked. You are therefore perfectly free to obey and be saved, and the fact that you will not, is no reason why you should not. (3.) You might just as reasonably make the same objection to every thing that takes place in the universe. Everything that did, or will, or can occur, is as infallibly knpwn to God, as the fact of your wickedness and destruction is. He also has a fixed and eternal design about every- thing that ever did or will occur. He knows how longtyou will live, where you will live, and when and where you will die. His purposes re- specting these and all other events are fixed, eternal, and unchangeable. Why, then, do you not live without food and say, I cannot make one hair black or white ; I cannot die before my time, nor can I prolong my days beyond the appointed time, do what I will ; therefore, I will take no care of my health ? No ; this would be unreasonable. Why not also apply this objection to everything, and settle down in despair of ever doing or being anything, but what an irresistible fate makes you ? The fact is, that the true doctrine, whether of election or reprobation, affords not the least countenance to such a conclusion. The foreknowledge and designs of God respecting our conduct or our destiny, do not in the least degree interfere with our free agency. We, in every case, act just as freely as if God neither knew nor designed anything about our conduct. Suppose the farmer should make the same objection to sowing' his seed, and to doing anything to secure a crop ; what would be thought of him ? And yet he might with as much reason, since he 33 514 SrSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. can plead the foreknowledge and designs of God, as an excuse for doing nothing to secure his saltation. God as really knows now whetnei you will sow and whether you will have a crop, and has from eternity known this, as perfectly as he ever will. He has either designed that you shall, or that you shall not, have a crop this year, from all eternity ; and it will infallibly come to pass just as he has foreseen and designed. Yet yoa are really just as free to raise a crop, or to neglect to do so, as if he neither knew nor designed anything about it. The man who will stumble either at the doctrine of election or repro- bation, as defined and maintained in these lectures, should, to be consis- tent, stumble at everything that takes place, and never try to accomplish anything whatever^; because the designs and the foreknowledge of God extend equally to everything ; and unless he has expressly revealed how it will be, we are left in the dark, in respect to any event, and are left to use means to accomplish what we desire, or to prevent what we dread, as if God knew and designed nothing about it. 6. But it is objected, that this is a discouraging doctrine, and liable to be a stumbling-block, and therefore should not be inculcated. I an- swer — (1. ) It is taught in the Bible, and plainly follows also from the at- tributes of God, as revealed in the reason. The scriptures that teach it are not less likely to be a snare and a stumbling-block, than are the definition and explanation of the doctrine. (2.) The proper statement, explanation, and defence of the doctrines of election and reprobation, are important to a proper understanding of the nature and attributes of God. (3.) The scriptures that teach these doctrines are often subjects of cavil, and sometimes of real diflficulty. Religious teachers should, there- fore, state these doctrines and explain them, so as to aid the inquirer after truth, and stop the mouths of gainsayers. (4.) Again, these doctrines have often been so mis-stated and per- verted as to make them amount to an iron system of fatalism. Many Bouls have heard or read these perversions, and greatly need to be en- lightened upon the subject. It is therefore all the more important, that these truths should find a place in religious instruction. Let them be understood, properly stated, explained, and defended, and they can no more be a stumbling-block, than the fact of God's omniscience can be so. DIVINE SOVEREIGNTY, 515 LECTURE XLV. DIVINE SOVEREIGNTY. br this disoussion I shall endeavor to show,— I. What is not intended by the term " sovereignty " when applied to Ood. It is not intended, at least by me, that God, in any instance, wills or acts arbitrarily, or without good reasons ; reasons so good and so weighty, that he could in no case act otherwise than he does, without violating the law of his own intelligence and conscience, and consequently without sin. Any view of divine sovereignty that implies arbitrariness on the part, of the divine will, is not only contrary to scripture, but is revolting to reason, and blasphemous. God cannot act arbitrarily, in the sense of unreasonably, without infinite wickedness. For him to be arbitrary, in the sense of unreasonable, would be a wickedness as much greater than any creature is capable of committing, as his reason or knowledge is greater than theirs. This must be self-evident. God should therefore never be represented as a sovereign, in the sense that implies that he is actuated by self or arbitrary will, rather than by his infinite intelligence. Many seem to me to represent the sovereignty of God as consisting in a perfectly arbitrary disposal of events. They seem to conceive of God as being wholly above and without any law or rule of action guiding his will by his infinite reason and conscience. They appear shocked at the idea of God himself being the subject of moral law, and are ready to inquire, Who gives law to God ? They seem never to have considered that God is, and must be, a law unto himself ; that he is necessarily omniscient, and that the divine reason must impose law on, or prescribe law to, the divine will. They seem to regard God as living wholly above law, and as disposed to have his own will at any rate, reasonable or unreasonable ; to set up his own arbitrary pleasure as his only rule of action, and to impose this rule upon all his subjects. This sovereignty they seem to conceive of as controlling and disposing of all events, with an iron or adamantine fatality, inflexible, irresistible, omnipotent. " Who worketh all things after the counsel of his own will." This text they dwell much upon, as teaching that Ood disposes all events absolutely, not according to his own infinite wisdom and discretion, but simply accord- ing to his own will ; and, as their language would often seem to imply, without reference at all to the universal law of benevolence. I will not say,' that such is the view as it lies in their own mind ; but only that from the language they use, such would seem to be their idea of divine 516 StSTEitATiC THEOLOGt. Bovereignty. Such, however, is not the view of this subject which I shall state and defend on the present occasion. II. What is intended ly divine sovereignty^ The sovereignty of God consists in the independence of his will, in consulting his own intelligence and discretion, in the selection of his end, and the means of accomplishing it. In other words, the sovereignty of God is nothing else than infinite benevolence directed by infinite knowledge. God consults no one in respect to what shall be done by him. He asks no leave to do and require what his own wisdom dictates. He consults only himself ; that is, his own infinite intelligence. So far is he from being arbitrary in his sovereignty, in the sense of unreasona- ble, that he is invariably guided by infinite reason. He consults his own intelligence only, not from any arbitrary disposition, but because his knowledge is perfect and infinite, and therefore it is safe and wise to take counsel nowhere else. It were infinitely unreasonable, and weak, and wicked in God to ask leave of any being to act in conformity with his own judgment. He must make his own reason his rule of action, God is a sovereign, not in the sense that he is not under law, or that he is above all law, but in the sense that he is a law to himself ; that he knows no law but what is given him by his own reason. In other words still, the sovereignty of God consists in such a disposal of all things and events, as to meet the ideas of his own reason, or the demands of his own intelligence. " He works all things after the counsel of his own will," in the sense that he formed and executes his own designs inde- pendently ; in the sense that he consults his own infinite discretion ; that is, he acts according to his own views of propriety and fitness. This he does, be it distinctly understood, without at all setting aside the freedom of moral agents. His infinite knowledge enabled him to select an end and means, that should consist with and include the perfect freedom of moral agents. The subjects of his moral government are free to obey or disobey, and take the consequences. But foreseeing precisely in all cases how they would act, he has laid his plan accordi ingly, so as to bring out the contemplated and desired results. In aU his plans he consulted none but himself. But this leads me to say, — HI. That God is and ought to he an absolute and a universal sove- reign. By absolute, I mean, that his expressed will, in obedience to hia reason, is law. It is not law because it proceeds from his arbitrary will, but because it is the revelation or declaration of the affirmations and demands of his infinite reason. His expressed will is law, because it is an infallible declaration of what is intrinsically fit, suitable, right. Hia DIVINE SOVEBBIQNTT. 517 will does not make the things that he commands, right, fit, proper, ob- ligatory, in the sense, that should he require it, the opposite of what he now requires would be fit, proper, suitable, obligatory ; but in the sense that we need no other evidence of what is in itself intrinsically proper, fit, obligatory, than the expression of his will. Our reason aflBrms, that /fha,t he wills must be right ; not because he wills it, but that he wills it because it is right, or obligatory in the nature of things ; that is, our reason afiBrms that he wills as he does, only upon condition, that his infinite intelligence affirms that such willing is intrinsically right, and therefore he ought to will or command just what he does. He is a sovereign in the sense that his will is law, whether we are ible to see the reason for his commands or not, because our reason affirms that he has and must have good and sufficient reasons for every com- mand ; so good and sufficient, that he could not do otherwise than re-, quire what he does, under the circumstances, without violating the law of his own intelligence. We therefore need no other reason for affirm- ing our obligation to will and to do, than that God requires it ; because we always and necessarily assume, that what God requires must be right, not because he arbitrarily wills it, but because he does not arbitrarily will it : on the contrary that he has, and must have in every instance, infinitely good and wise reasons for every requirement. Some persons represent God as a sovereign, in the sense, that his arbitrary will is the foundation of obligation. But if this is so, he could in every instance render the directly opposite course from what he now requires, obligatory. But this is absurd. The persons just mentioned eeem to think, that unless it be admitted that God's will is the founda- tion of obligation, it will follow that it does not impose obligation, un- less he discloses the reasons for his requirements. But this is a great mistake. Our own reason affirms that God's expressed will is always law, in the sense that it invariably declares the law of nature, or dis- closes the decisions of his own reason. God must and ought to be an absolute sovereign in the sense just de- fined. This will appear if we consider : — 1. That his end was chosen and means decided upon, when no being but himself existed, and of course, there was no one to consult but himself. 3. Creation and providence are only the results, and the carrying out of his plans settled from eternity. 3. The law of benevolence, as it existed in the divine reason, must have eternally demanded of him the very course he has taken. 4. His highest glory and the highest good of universal being demand that he should consult his own discretion, and exercise an absolute and a universal sovereignty, in the sense explained. Infinite wisdom and 518 STSTEMA.TIC THEOLOGY. goodness ought of course to act independently in the promotion of their end. If infinite wisdom or knowledge is not to give law, what or who shall ? If infinite benevolence shall not declare and enforce law, what or who shall ? God's attributes and relations render it obligatory upon him to exercise just that holy sovereignty we have ascribed to him. (1.) This sovereignty, and no other, he claims for himself. Ps. cxv. 3 : "But our God is in the heavens ; he hath done what- soever he hath pleased," Ps. cxxxv. 6 : " Whatsoever the Lord pleased, that did he in heaven, and in earth, in the seas, and all deep places." Isa. Iv. 10 : "For as the rain cometh down, and the snow from heaven, and returneth not thither, but watereth the earth, and maketh it bring forth and bud, that it may give seed to the sower, and bread to the eater ; 11. So shall my word be that goeth forth out of my mouth ; it shall not return unto me void, but it shall accomplish that which I please, and it shall prosper in the thing whereto I sent it." Matt. xi. 25 : " At that time Jesus answered and said, I thank thee, Father, Lord of heaven and earth, because thou hast hid these things from the wise and prudent, and hast revealed them unto babes. 36. Even so, Father, for so it seemed good in thy sight." Bom. ix. 15 : " For he saith to Moses, I will have mercy on whom I will have mercy, and I will have compassion on whom I will have com- passion. 16. So then it is not of him that willeth, nor of him that runneth, but of God that showeth mercy. 17. For the scripture saith unto Pharaoh, Even for this same purpose have I raised thee up, that I might show my power in thee, and that my name might be declared throughout all the earth. 18. Therefore hath he mercy on whom he will have mercy, and whom he will he hardeneth." Eph. i. 11 : " In whom also we have obtained an inheritance, being predestinated according to the purpose of him who worketh all things after the counsel of his own will." (3. ) Again : God claims for himself all the prerogatives of an abso- lute and a universal sovereign, in the sense already explained. For ex- ample, he claims to be the rightful and sole proprietor of the universe, 1 Chron. xxix. 11 : " Thine, Lord, is the greatness, and the power, and the glory, and the victory, and the majesty ; for all that is in the heaven and in the earth is thine ; thine is the kingdom, Lord, and thou art exalted as head above all." Ps. 1. 10 : " For every beast of the forest is mine, and the cattle upon a thousand hills ; 11. I know all the fowls of the mountains ; and. the wild beasts of the field are mine. 12. If I were hungry, I would not teU thee, for the world is mine, and the fulness thereof." Ps. xcv. 5 : "The sea is his, and he made it, and his hands formed DIVINE SOVEEEIGNTY. 619 the dry land. 6. come, let us worship, and bow down, let us kneel before the Lord our Maker ; 7. For he is our God, and we are the people of his pasture, and the sheep of his hand." Ps. Tj. 3 : "Know ye that the Lord he is God, it is he that hath made us, and not we ourselves ; we are his people, and the sheep of his pasture." Ezek. ZYiii. 4 : " Behold, all souls are mine ; as the soul of the father, so also the soul of the son is mine ; the soul that sinneth it shall die." Bom. xiv. 8 : " For whether we lire, we live unto the Lord ; and whether we die, we die unto the Lord ; whether we live therefore, or die, we are the Lord's." (3.) Again : God claims to have established the natural or physical laws of the universe. Ps. cxix. 90 : " Thy faithfulness is unto all generations, thou hast established the earth, and it abideth. 91. They continue this day ac- cording to thine ordinances, for all are thy servants." Prov. iii. 19 : " The Lord by wisdom hath founded the earth, by understanding hath he established the heavens. 20. By his knowledge the depths are broken up, and the clouds drop down the dew." Jer. xxxi. 35 : "Thus saith the Lord, which giveth the sun for a light by day, and the stars for a light by night, which divideth the sea when the waves thereof roar ; the Lord of hosts is his name." Jer. xxxiii. 25 : "Thus saith the Lord, if my covenant be not with day and night, and if I have not appointed the ordinances of heaven and earth ; 26. Then ' will I cast away the seed of Jacob, and David my servant, so that I will not take any of his seed to be rulers over the seed of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob ; for I will cause their captivity to return, and have mercy on them." (4.) God claims the right to exercise supreme authority. 1 Chron. xxix. 11 : " Thine, Lord, is the greatness and the power, and the glory, and the victory, and the majesty ; for all that is in the heaven and the earth is thine ; thine is the kingdom, Lord, and thou art exalted as head above all." Ps. xlvii. 7 : " For God is the king of all the earth, sing ye praises with understanding." Isa. xxxiii. 22 : " For the Lord is our judge, the Lord is our law- giver, the Lord is our king ; he will save us." (5.) God claims the right to exercise his own discretion in using such means, and in exerting such an agency as will secure the regeneration of men, or not, as it appears wise to him. Deut. xxix. 4 : " Yet the Lord hath not given you an heart to per- ceive, and eyes to see, and ears to hear, unto this day." Jer. T. 14 : " Wherefore thus saith the Lord God of hosts, Because 520 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. ye speak this word, behold, I will make my words in thy mouth fire, and this people wood, and it shall devour them." Matt. xiii. 10 : " And the disciples came, and said unto him. Why speakest thou to them in parables ? He answered and said unto them, Because it is given unto you to know the mysteries of the kingdom of heaven, but to them it is not given." Rom. ix. 22 : " What if God, willing to show his wrath, and to make his power known, endured with much long-suffering the vessels of wrath fitted to destruction. 33. And that he might make known the riches of his glory on the vessels of mercy, which he had afore, prepared unto glory." 2 Tim. ii. 35 : "In meekness instructing those that oppose them- selves ; if God peradventure will give them repentance to the acknowl- edging of the truth." (6.) God claims the right to try his creatures by means of temptation. Deut. xiii. 1 : "If there arise among you a prophet, or a dreamer of dreams, and giveth thee a sign or a wonder, 2. And the sign or the won- der come to pass, whereof he spake unto thee, saying, let us go after other gods, which thou hast not known, and let us serve them ; 3. " Thou shalt not hearken unto the words of that prophet, or that dreamer of dreams ; for the Lord your God proveth you, to know whether ye love the Lord your God with all your heart and with all your soul." 1 Kings xxii. 30 : " And the Lord said. Who shall persuade Ahab, that he may go up and fall at Eamoth-gilead ? And one said on this manner, and another said on that manner. 31. And there came forth a spirit, and stood before the Lord, and said, I will persuade him. 33. And the Lord said unto him. Wherewith ? And he said, I will go forth, and I will be a lying spirit in the mouth of all his prophets. ^And he said. Thou shalt persuade him, and prevail also ; go forth, and do so." Job ii. 3. " And the Lord said unto Satan, Hast thou considered my servant Job, that there is none like him in the earth, a perfect and an upright man, one that feareth God, and escheweth evil ? And still he holdeth fast his integrity, although thou movedst me against him, to de- stroy him without cause. 7. So went Satan forth from the presence of the Lord, and smote Job with sore boils, from the sole of his foot unto his crown." Matt. iv. 1 : " Then was Jesus led up of the spirit into the wilder- ness to be tempted of the devil." (7.) God also claims the right to use all creatures, and to dispose of all creatures and events, so as to fulfil his own designs. 3 Sam. vii. 14 : "I will be his father, and he shall be my son ; if he commit iniquity, I will chasten him with the rod of men, and with the stripes of the children of men." DIVINE SOVEREIGNTY. 521 2 Kings V. 1 : " Now Naaman, captain of the host of the king of Syria, was a great man with his master, and honorable, because by him the Lord had given deliverance unto Syria ; he was also a mighty man in valor, but he was a leper." Job i. 15 : " And the Sabeans fell upon them, and took them away ; yea, they have slain the servants with the edge of the sword ; and I am escaped alone to tell thee. 17. While he was yet speaking, there came also another, and said. The Chaldeans made out three bands, and fell upon the camels, and have carried them away ; yea, and slain the servants with the edge of the sword ; and I only am escaped to tell thee. And Job said, Naked came I out of my mother's womb, and naked shall I return thither ; the Lord gave, and the Lord hath taken away ; blessed be the name of the Lord." Isa. X. 5 : "0 Assyrian, the rod of mine anger, and the staff in their hand is mine indignation : 6. I will send him against an hypocritical na- tion, and against the people of mywrath will I give him a charge, to take the spoil, and to take the prey, and to tread them down like the mire of the streets. 7. Howbeit he meaneth not so, neither doth his heart think so ; but it is in his heart to destroy and cut off nations not a few. 13. Wherefore it shall come to pass, that when the Lord hath performed his whole work upon Mount Zion and on Jerusalem, I will punish the fruit of the stout heart of the king of Assyria, and the glory of his high looks. 15. Shall the axe boast itself against him that heweth therewith ? or shall the saw magnify itself against him that shake th it ? as if the rod should shake itself against them that lift it up, or as if the staff should lift up itself, as if it were no wood." Ezek. xxiv. 14 : " And I will lay my vengeance upon Edom by the hand of my people Israel ; and they shall do in Edom according to mine anger, and according to my fury ; and they shall know my vengeance, saith the Lord God." Hab. i. 6 : "For, lo, I raise up the Chaldeans, that bitter and hasty nation, which shall march through the breadth of the land, to possess the dwelling-places that are not theirs. 13. Art thou not from everlast- ing, Lord, my God, mine Holy One ? We shall not die, Lord, thou hast ordained them for judgment ; and mighty God, thou hast estab- lished them for correction." (8.) God claims the right to take the life of his sinful subjects at his own discretion. Gen. xxii. 2 : "And he said. Take now thy son, thine only son Isaac, whom thou lovest, and get thee into the land of Moriah, and offer him there for a burnt-offering upon one of the mountains^ which I will tell thee of." Pput. ?x, 16 : " Put of the cities of these people, which the Lord thy 522 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. God doth give thee for an inheritance, thou shalt save alive nothing that breatheth. 17. But thou shalt utterly destroy them ; namely, the Hit- tites, and the Amoritee, the Canaanites, and the Perizzites, the Hivites, and the Jebusites, as the Lord thy God hath commanded thee : 18. That they teach you jiot to do after all their abominations, which they have done unto their gods ; so should ye sin against the Lord your God." 1 Sam. XV. 3 : " Now go and smite Amalek, and utterly destroy all that they have, and spare them not ; but slay both man and woman, in- fant and suckling, ox and sheep, camel and ass." (9.) God declares that he will maintain his own sovereignty. Isa. xlii. 8 : "I am the Lord ; that is my name : and my glory will I not give to another, neither my praise to graven images." Isa. xlviii. 11 : " For mine own sake, even for mine own sake, will I do it : for how should my name be polluted ? and I will not give my glory unto another." These passages will disclose the general tenor of scripture upon thia subject. BEMABKS. 1. The Sovereignty of God is an infinitely amiable, sweet, holy, and desirable sovereignty. Some seem to conceive of it as if it were revolting and tyrannical. But it is the infinite opposite of this, and is the perfec- tion of all that is reasonable, kind and good. Isa. Ivii. 15 : " For thus saith the high and lofty One that inhabiteth eternity, whose name is holy : I dwell in the high and holy place, with him also that is of a contrite and humble spirit, to revive the spirit of the humble, and to revive the heart of the contrite ones. 16. For I will not contend for ever, neither will I be always wroth : for the spirit should fail before me, and the souls which I have made. 17. For the iniquity of his covetousness was I wroth, and smote him : I hid me, and was wroth, and he went on frowardly in the way of his heart. 18. I have seen his ways, and will heal him ; I will lead him also, and restore com- forts unto him, and to his mourners. 19. I create the fruit of the lips ; Peace, peace to him that is far off, and to him that is near, saith the Lord ; and I will heal him." 2. Many seem afraid to think or speak of God's sovereignty, and even pass over, with a very slight reading, those passages of scripture that so fully declare it. They think it unwise and dangerous to preach upon the subject, especially unless it be to deny or explain away the sove- reignty of God. This fear in pious minds has no doubt originated in a misconception of the nature of this sovereignty. They have been led either by false teaching, or in some way, to conceive of the divine sove- reignty as an iron p,nd unreasopable despotism, T^at is, they have uft- DIVINE SOVEKEIGNITY. 633 derstood the doctrine of divine sovereignty to so represent God. Thej therefore fear and reject it. But let it be remembered and for ever ur'- derstood, to the eternal joy and unspeakable consolation of all holy beings, that God's sovereignty is nothing else than infinite love directed by infi- nite knowledge, in such a disposal of events as to secure the highest well- being of the universe ; that, in the whole details of creation, providence and grace, there is not a solitary measure of his that is not infinitely wise and good. 3. A proper understanding of God's universal agency and sovereignty, of the perfect wisdom and benevolence of every measure of his govern- ment, providential and moral, is essential to the best improvement of all his dispensations toward us, and to those around us. When it is under- stood, that God's hand is directly or indirectly in everything that occurs, and that he is infinitely wise and good, and equally wise and good in every single dispensation — that he has one end steadily and always, in view — that he does all for one and the same ultimate end — and that this end is the highest good of himself and of universal being ; — I say, when these things are understood and considered, there is a divine sweetness in all his dispensations. There is then a divine reasonableness, and amiableness, and kindness, thrown like a broad mantle of infinite love over all his character, works and ways. The soul, in contemplating such a sacred, universal, holy sovereignty, takes on a sweet smile of delightful complacency, and feels secure, and reposes in perfect peace, surrounded and supported by the everlasting arms. 4. Many entertain most ruinous conceptions of divine sovereignty. They manifestly conceive of it as proceeding wholly independent of law, and of second causes, or means. They often are heard to use language that implies this. They say, "if it is God's will, you cannot hinder it. If God has begun the work, he will accomplish it." In fact, their lan- guage means nothing, unless they assume that in the dispensation of grace all is miracle. They often represent a thing as manifestly from God, or as providential, because it was, or appeared to be, so disconnected with appropriate means and instrumentalities. In other words it was quite miraculous. Now, I suppose, that God's sovereignty manifests itself through and by means, or second causes, and appropriate instrumentalities. God is as much a sovereign in the kingdom of nature as of grace. Suppose farmers, mechanics, and shopkeepers should adopt, in practice, this absurd view of divine sovereignty of which I am speaking ? Why, they would succeed about as well in raising crops and in transacting business, as those Christians and ministers who apply their views of sovereignty to spiritnal matters, do in saving souls. 624 SrSTEMATlC THEOLOGY. LECTURE XLVI. PURPOSES OP GOD. In discussing this subject I shall endeavor to show, I. What I understand hy the purposes of God. Purposes, in this discussion, I shall use as synonymous with design, intention. The purposes of God must be ultimate and proximate. That is, God has and must have an ultimate end. He must purpose to accom- plish something by his works and providence, which he regards as a good in itself, or as valuable to himself, and to being in general This I call his ultimate end. That God has such an end or purpose, follows from the already established facts, that God is a moral agent, and that he is infinitely wise and good. For surely he could not be justly considered as either wise or good, had he no intrinsically valuable end which he aims to realize, by his works of creation and providence. His purpose to secure his great and ultimate end, I call his ultimate purpose. His proximate purposes respect the means by which he aims to secure his end. If he purposes to realize an end, he must of course purpose the necessary means for its accomplishment. The purposes that respect the means are what I call in this discussion, his proximate purposes. II. Distinction between purpose and decree. Pui-pose has just been defined, and the definition need not be re- peated. The term decree is used in a variety of senses. The term is used in the Bible as synonymous — 1. With fore-ordination or determination, appointment. Job xxviii. 10 : " He putteth forth his hand upon the rock ; he bver- turneth the mountains by the roots. 26. When he made a decree for the rain, and a way for the lightning of the thunder." Ps. xi. 2 : "I will declare the decree, the Lord hath said unto me. Thou art my son ; this day have I begotten thee." Ps. cxlviii. 6 : " He hath also established them for ever and ever ; he hath made a decree which shall not pass." Prov. viii. 29 : " When he gave to the sea his decree, that the waters should not pass his commandment ; when he appointed the foundations of the earth." Jer. V. 22 : " Pear ye not me ? saith the Lord : will ye not tremble at my presence, which have placed the sand for the bound of the sea, by a perpetnq,! decree t})a|; it cannot pass it, and though the waves thereof tosp PURPOSES OP aoD. 525 themselves, yet can they not prevail ; though they roar, yet can they not pass over it ? " Dan. iv. 34 : " This is the interpretation, king, and this is the de- cree of the Most High, which is come upon my lord the king." 2. It is used as synonymous with ordinance, statute, law. Dan. vi. 7 : " All the presidents of the kingdom, the governors, and the princes, the counsellors,, and the captains, have consulted together to establish a royal statute, and to make a firm decree, that whosoever shall ask a petition of any god or man for thirty days, save of thee, king, he shall be cast into the den of lions. 8. Now, king, establish the decree, and sign the ■writing, that it be not changed, according to the law of the Medes and Persians, which altereth not. 26. I make a decree, that in every dominion of my kingdom men tremble and fear before the God of Daniel ; for he is the living God, and steadfast for ever, and his kingdom that which shall not be destroyed, and his dominion shall be even unto the end." This term has been generally used by theological writers as synony- mous with fore-ordination, appointment. To decree, with these writers, is to appoint, ordain, establish, settle, fix, render certain. This class of writers also often confound decree with purpose, and use the word as meaning the same thing. I see no objection to using the term decree, in respect to a certain class of physical events, as synonymous with appoint- ment, fore-ordination, fixing, rendering certain. But I think this use of it, applied, as it has been, to the actions of moral agents, is highly ob- jectionable, and calculated to countenance the idea of fatality and neces- sity, in respect to the actions of men. It seems inadmissible to speak of God's decreeing the free actions of moral agents, in the sense of fixing, settling, determining fore-ordaining them as he fixes, settles, renders cer- tain all physical events. The latter he has fixed or rendered certain by a law of necessity. The former, that is, free acts, although they may be, and are certain, yet they are not rendered so by a law of fate or necessity ; or by an ordinance or decree that fixes them so, that it is not possible they should be otherwise. In respect to the government of God, I prefer to use the term purpose, as I have said, to signify the design of God, both in respect to the end at which he aims, and the means he intends or purposes to use to accomplish it. The term decree I use as synonymous with command, law, or ordi- nance. The former I use as expressive of what God purposes or designs to do himself, and by his own agency, and also what he purposes or de- signs to accomplish by others. The latter I use as expressive of God's will, command, or law. He regulates his own conduct and agency in accordance with the former, that is, with his purposes. He requires his creatures to conform to the latter, that is, to his decrees or laws. We 526 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. shall see, in its proper place, that both his purposes and his a<3tion8 are conformed to the spirit of his decrees, or laws ; that is, that he is benevo- lent in his purposes and conduct, as he requires his creatures to be. I distinguish what God purposes or designs to accomplish by others, and what they design. God's end or purpose is always benevolent. He always designs good. His creatures are often selfish, and their designs are often the direct opposite to the purpose of God, even iu the same events. For example, see the following cases : — Gen, xlv. 4 : " And Joseph said unto his brethren, Come near to me, I pray you ; and they came near. And he said, I am Joseph your brother, whom ye sold into Egypt, 5. Now therefore, be not grieved, nor angry with yourselves that ye sold me hither ; for God did send me before you, to preserve life, 6, For these two years hath the famine been in the land, and yet there are five years, in the which there shall neither be earing nor harvest." Gen. 1. 19 : " And Joseph said unto them, Fear not ; for am I in the place of God ? 20. But as for you, ye thought evil against me, but God meant it unto good, to bring to pass, as it is this day, to save much peo- ple alive." Isa. X. 5 : "0 Assyrian, the rod of mine anger, and the stafE in their hand is mine indignation, 6. I will send him against a hypocritical nation, and against the people of my wrath will I give him a charge, to take the spoil, and to take the prey, and to tread them down like the mire of the streets. 7, Howbeit he meaneth not so, but it is in his heart to destroy, and cut ofE nations not a few, 12. Wherefore it shall come to pass, that when the Lord hath performed his whole work upon Mount Zion and on Jerusalem, I will punish the fruit of the stout heart of the king of Assyria, and the glory of his high looks," Mark xv, 9 : " But Pilate answered them, saying. Will ye that I re- lease unto you the king of the Jews ? 10, (For he knew that the chief priests had delivered him for envy)." John iii. 16 : " For God so loved the world, that he gave his only- begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him should not perish, but have everlasting life," Acts ii. 23 : " Him, being delivered by the determinate-counsel and fore-knowledge of God, ye have taken, and by wicked hands have cru- cified and slain." Ill, There must be some sense in which God's purposes extend to all tvents. 1. This is evident from reason. His plans must, in some sense, include bU actual events. He must foreknow all events by a law of necessity. This is implied in his omniscience. He must have matured and adopted PURPOSES OF GOD. 627 hii plan in view of, and with reference to, all events. He must have had some purpose or design respecting all events that he foresaw. All events transpire in consequence of his own creating agency ; that is, they all result in some way directly or indirectly, either by his design or sufferance, from his own agency. He either designedly brings them to pass, or suffers them to come to pass without interposing to prevent them. He must have known that they would occur. He must have either positively designed that they should, or, knowing that they would result from the mistakes or selfishness of his creatures, negatively de- signed not to prevent them, or, he had no purpose or design about them. The last hypothesis is plainly impossible. He cannot be indifferent to any event. He knows all events, and must have some purpose or design respecting them. 2. The Bible abundantly represents God's purposes as in some sense extending to all events. For example ; — Deut. xxxii. 4 : "He is the Rock, his work is perfect ; for all his ways are judgment ; a God of truth, and without iniquity ; just and right is he." Ps. civ. 24 : "0 Lord, how wonderful are thy works ; in wisdom hast thou made them all ; the earth is full of thy riches." Job xiv. 5 : " Seeing his days are determined, the number of his months are with thee ; thou hast appointed his bounds that he cannot Isa. xiv. 26 : " This is the purpose that is purposed upon the whole earth ; and this is the hand that is stretched out upon all the nations." Acts xvii. 26 : " And hath made of one blood all nations of men for to dwell on all the face of the earth, and hath determined the times before appointed, and the bounds of their habitation." Eph. i. 11 : " In whom also we have obtained an inheritance, being predestinated according to the purpose of him who worketh all things after the counsel of his own will." Acts ii. 23 : " Him, being delivered by the determinate counsel and fore-knowledge of God, ye have taken, and by wicked hands have cruci- fied and slain." Acts iv. 27 : " For of a truth against thy holy child Jesus, whom thou hast anointed, both Herod and Pontius Pilate, with the Gentiles, and the people of Israel, were gathered together, 28. For to do whatso- ever thy hand and thy counsel determined before to be done." Acts xiii. 29 : " And when they had fulfilled all that was written of him, they took him down from the tree, and laid him in a sepulchre." Jude 4 : " For there are certain men crept in unawares, who were before of old ordained to this condemnation, ungodly men, turning the 528 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. grace of our God, into lasciviousness, and denying the only Lord iSod, and our Lord Jesus Christ." Rev. xvii. 17 : " For God hath put in their hearts to fulfil his will, and to agree, and give their kingdom unto the beast, until the words of God shall be fulfilled." Acts xxxvii. 22 : " And now I exhort you to be of good cheer ; for there shall be no loss of any man's life among you, but of the ship. 23. For there stood by me this night the angel of God, whose I am, and whom I serve, 24. Saying, Pear not Paul, thou must be brought before Caesar ; and, lo, God hath given thee all them that sail with thee. 30. And as the shipmen were about to flee out of the ship, when they had let down the boat into the sea, under color as though they would have cast anchors out of the foreship, 31. Paul said to the centurion and to the soldiers, except these abide in the ship, ye cannot be saved." 2 Thess. ii. 13 : " But we are bound to give thanks alway to God for you, brethren, beloved of the Lord, because God hath from the begin- ning chosen you to salvation through sanctification of the Spirit, and belief of the truth." 1 Pet. i. 2 : " Elect according to the foreknowledge of God the Pather, through sanctification of the Spirit, unto obedience and sprink- ling of the blood of Jesus Christ." Ps. cxlvii. 8 : " Who covereth the heaven with clouds, who prepar- eth rain for the earth, who maketh grass to grow upon the mountains. 9. He giveth to the beast his food, and to the young ravens which cry. 15. He sendeth forth his commandment upon earth ; his word runneth very swiftly. 16. He giveth snow like wool ; he scattereth the hoar-frost like ashes. 17. He casteth forth his ice like morsels ; who can stand before his cold ? 18. He sendeth out his word and melteth them, he causeth his winds to blow, and the waters flow." Isa. xlv. 7 : " I form the light, and create darkness ; I make peace and create evil. I the Lord do all these things." Dan. iv. 36 : "And all the inhabitants of the earth are reputed aa nothing ; and he doeth according to his will in the army of heaven, and among the inhabitants of the earth, and none can stay his hand, or say unto him. What doest thou ? " Amos. iii. 6 : " Shall a trumpet be blown in the city, and the people not be afraid ? Shall there be evil in a city, and the Lord hath not done it?" Matt. X. 29 : " Are not two sparrows sold for a farthing ? and one of them shall not fall on the ground without your Pather." Rom. xi. 36 : Por of him, and through him, and to him, are all things. " Eph. i. 11 : " In whom also we have obtained an inheritance, being t'URi*o^Es OP Qob. 6^9 predestinated according to the purpose of him who worketh all things after the counsel of his own will." Matt. V. 45 : " That ye may be the children of your Father which is in heaven ; for he maketh his sun to rise on the evil and on the good, and sendeth rain on the just and on the unjust." Matt. vi. 26 : " Behold the fowls of the air, for they sow not, neither do they reap, nor gather into barns ; yet your heavenly Father feedeth them. Are ye not much better than they ? 38. And why take ye thought for raiment ? Consider the lilies of the field, how they grow ; they toil not, neither do they spin. 19. And yet I say unto you, that even Solomon in all his glory, was not arrayed like one of these. 30. Wherefore, if God so clothe the grass of the field, which to-day is, and to-morrow is cast into the oven, shall he not much more clothe you, ye of little faith ?" Jer. X. 23 : "0 Lord, I know that the way Df man is not in himself ; it is not in man that walketh to direct his steps." Jer. xviii. 6 : " house of Israel, cannot I do with you as this pot- ter ? saith the Lord. Behold, as the clay is in the potter's hand, so are ye in mine hand, house of Israel." 2 Cor. iii. 5 : " Not that we are suflBcient of ourselves to think any- thing, as of ourselves, but our sufficiency is of God." Neh. ix. 5: "Thou, even thou, art Lord alone: thou hast made heaven, the heaven of heavens, with all their host, the earth, and all things that are therein, the seas, and all that is therein, and thou pre- servest them all ; and the host of heaven worshippeth thee." Ezek. xiv. 6 : " And if the prophet be deceived when he hath spoken a thing, I the Lord have deceived that prophet ; and I will stretch out my hand upon him, and will destroy him from the midst of my people Israel." Luke X. 21 : " In that hour Jesus rejoiced in spirit, and said, I thank thee, Father, Lord of heaven and earth, that thou hast hid these things from the wise and prudent, and hast revealed them unto babes : even so. Father ; for so it seemed good in thy sight." John xii. 32 : " Therefore they could not believe, because that Esaias said again, 40. He hath blinded their eyes, and hardened their heart ; that they should not see with their eyes, nor understand with their heart, and be converted, and I should heal them. 41. These thing said Esaias, when he saw his glory, and spake of him." Rom. ix. 18 : " Therefore hath he mercy on whom he will have mercy, and whom he will he hardeneth." 2 Thess. ii. 10 : " And with all deceivableness of unrighteousness in them that perish ; because they received not the love of the truth, that they might be saved. 11. And for this cause God shall send them 34 530 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. strong delasions, that they should believe a lie ; 12. That they all might be darnucd who believed not the truth, but had pleasure in unrighteousness." These passages will show the general tenor of scripture upon this subject. IV. Different sense in which God purposes different events. 1. The great end of all his works and ways he must have purposed positively, that is, absolutely. This end, namely his own good and the highest good of the universe, he set his heart upon securing. This end he no doubt properly intended, or purposed to secure. This must have been his ultimate intention or purpose. This end was no doubt a direct object of choice. 2. God must no doubt also, in some sense, have purposed all the necessary means to this result. Such actions as tended naturally, or on account of their own nature, to this result, he must have purposed posi- tively, in the sense that he delighted in them, and chose them because of their own nature, or of their natural relation to the great end he proposed to accomplish by them. Observe, the end was an ultimate end, delighted in and chosen for its own sake. This end was the highest good or weU-being of himself and the universe of sentient existences. This has been suflBciently shown in former lectures ; and besides it follows of necessity from the nature and attributes of God. If this were not so, he would be neither wise nor good. Since he delighted in and chose the end for its own sake or value, and purposed it with a positive purpose, he must also have chosen and delighted in the necessary means. He must have created the universe, both of matter and of mind, and established its laws, with direct reference to, and for the sake of, the end he purposed to accomplish. The end was valuable in itself, and chosen for that reason. The necessary means were as really valuable as the end which depended upon them. This value, though real, because of their tendency and natural results, is not ultimate, but relative ; that is, they are not, in the same sense that the end is, valuable in themselves; but they being the necessary means to this end, are as really valuable as the end that depends upon them. Thus our necessary food is not valua- ble in itself, but is the necessary means of prolonging our lives. There- fore, though not an ultimate good, yet it is a real good of as great value, as the end that naturally depends upon it. The naturally necessary means of securing a valuable end we justly esteem as equally valuable with the end, although this value is not absolute but relative. We are so accustomed to set a value on the means, equal to the estimated impor- tance of the end to which they sustain the relation of necessary means, that we come loosely to regard and to speak of them as valuable in them- selves, when in fact their value is not absolute but relative. PtTRPOSfiS OB* QOC. 531 }od must have purposed to secure, so far as he wisely could, obe- diewje to the laws of the universe. These laws were established for the sake of the end to which they tended, and obedience to them must have been regarded by God as of real, 'though not ultimate, value, equal to that of the end, for the accomplishmen,t of which they were ordained. He must have delighted in obedience to these laws for the sake of the end, and must have purposed to secure this obedience so far as he could in the nature of things ; that is, in\so far as he wisely could. Since moral law is a rule for the government of free moral agents, it is con- ceivable, that, in some cases, this law might be violated by the subjects of it, unless God resorted to means to prevent it, that might introduce an evil of greater magnitude than the violation of the law in the in- stances under consideration would be. It is conceivable, that, in some cases, God might be able so to overrule a violation of his laws, as upon the whole to secure a greater good than could be secured, by introducing such a change into the policy and measures of his administration, or so framing his administration, as to prevent altogether the violation of any law. In this case, he might regard the violation as the less of two evils, and suffer it rather than change the arrangements of his government. He might sincerely deplore and abhor these violations of law, and yet might see it not wise to prevent them, because the measures necessary to prevent them might result in an evil of still greater magnitude. He might purpose to suffer these violations, and take the trouble to overrule them, so far as was possible, for the promotion of the end he had in view, rather than interpose for their prevention. These violations he might not have purposed in any other sense than that he foresaw them, and purposed not to prevent them, but on the contrary to suffer them to occur, and to overrule them for good, so far as this was practicable. These events, or violations of law, have no natural tendency to promote ' the highest well-being of God and of the universe, but have in themselves a directly opposite tendency. Nevertheless, God could so overrule them as that these occurrences would be a less evil than that change would be that could have prevented them. Violations of law then, he might have purposed only to suffer, while obedience to law he might have designed to produce or secure. 3. We have seen, that God and men may have different motives ia the same event, as in the case of the brethren of Joseph, already alluded to:— Gen. xlv. 4 : " And Joseph sijid unto his brethren. Come near to me, I pray you. And they came near. And he said, I am Joseph your brother, whom ye sold into Egypt. Now therefore be not grieved nor angry with yourselves that ye sold me hither ; for God did send me before you to preserve life. 6. For these two years hath the famine been in tho 632 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. land ; and yet there are five years, in the which there shall neither be earing nor harvest ! " As also in the case of the king of Assyria : Is. x. 5 : "0 Assyrian, the rod of mine anger, and the stafE in their hand is mine indignation. 6. I will send him against a hypocritical nation, and against the people of my wrath will I give him a charge, to take the spoil, and to take the prey, and to tread them down like the mire of the streets. 7. Howbeit he meaneth not so, neither doth his heart think so ; but it is in his heart to destroy and cut off nations not a few. 13. Wherefore it shall come to pass, that when the Lord hath performed his whole work upon mount Zion, and on Jerusalem, I will punish the fruit of the stout heart of the king of Assyria, and the glory of his high looks." ' Also, John iii. 16 : "For God so loved the world, that he gave his only begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him should not perish, but have everlasting life." Acts ii. 23. " Him being delivered by the determinate counsel and foreknowledge of God, ye have taken, and by wicked hands have crucified and slain." These, and such like instances, show that wicked agents may, and often do, and when wicked always do, entertain a very different reason for their conduct from what God entertains in suffering it. They have a selfish end in view, or do what they do for a selfish reason. God, on the contrary, has a benevolent end in view in not interposing to prevent their sin ; that is, he hates their sin as tending in itself, to destroy, or defeat the great end of benevolence. But foreseeing that the sin, not- withstanding its natural evil tendency, may be so overruled, as upon the whole to result in a less evil than the changes requisite to prevent it would, he benevolently prefers to suffer it rather than interpose to prevent it. He would, no doubt, prefer their perfect obedience, under the circum- stances in which they are, but would sooner suffer them to sin, than so change the circumstances as to prevent it ; the latter being, all things con- sidered, the greater of two evils. God then always suffers his laws to be violated, because he cannot benevolently prevent it under the circum- stances. He suffers it for benevolent reasons. But the sinner always has selfish reasons. 4. The Bible informs us, that God brings good out of evil, in the sense that he overrules sin to promote his own glory, and the good of being : — Ps. Ixxvi. 10. " Surely the wrath of man shall praise thee ; the re- mainder of wrath shalt thou restrain." Kom. iii. 5 : " But if our unrighteousness commend the righteous- ness of God, what shall we say ? Is God unrighteous who taketh ven- geance ? (I speak as a man.) 7. For if the truth of God hath more PURPOSES OF GOD. 533 abounded through my lie unto his glory ; why yet am I judged as a sin- ner ? And not rather (as we be slanderously reported, and as some a£Brm that we say,) Let us do evil, that good may come ? whose damnation ia just." Eom. V. 20 : " Moreover, the law entered, that the ofPence might abound ; but where sin abounded, grace did much more abound." Eom. viii. 28 : " And we know that all things work together for good to them that love God, to them who are the called according to his pur- pose." 5. The Bible also informs us that God does not aim at producing sin in creation and providence ; that is, that he does not purpose the exist- ence of sin in such a sense as to design to secure and promote it, in the administration of his government. In other words still, sin is not the object of a positive purpose on the part of God. It exists only by suf- ferance, and not as a thing which naturally tends to secure his great end, and which therefore he values on that account and endeavors to promote, as he does obedience to the law. Jer. vii. 9. " Will ye steal, murder, and commit adultery, and swear falsely, and burn incense unto Baal, and walk after other gods whom ye know not ? 10. And come and stand before me in this house, which is called by my name, and say. We are delivered to do all these abomina- tions ?" 1 Cor. xiv. 33 : " For God is not the author of confusion, but of peace, as in all churches of the saints." James i. 13 : " Let no man say when he is tempted, I am tempted of God ; for God cannot be tempted with evil, neither tempteth he any man ; 14. But every man is tempted, when he is drawn away of his own lust, and enticed. 15. Then when lust hath conceived, it bringeth forth sin ; and sin when it is finished, bringeth forth death. 16. Do not err, my beloved brethren. 17. Every good gift and every perfect gift is from above, and cometh down from the Father of lights, with whom is no va- riableness, neither shadow of turning." James iii. 14 : " But if ye have bitter envying and strife in your hearts, glory not, and lie not against the truth. 15. This wisdom de- scendeth not from above, but is earthly, sensaal, devilish. 16. For where envying and strife is, there is confusion, and every evil work. 17. But the wisdom that is from above is first pure, then peaceable, and gentle, and easy to be entreated, full of mercy and good fruits, without partiality and hypocrisy." 1 John ii. 16 : " For all that is in the world, the lust of the flesh, and the lust of the eyes, and the pride of life, is not of the Father, but is of the world." Obedience to law is an object of positive purpose. God purposes to 534 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. promote it, aad uses means with that design. Sin occurs incidentally, so far as the purpose of God is concerned. It need not be, and doubtless is not, the object of positive design or purpose, but comes to pass because it cannot wisely be prevented. God uses means to promote obedience. But moral agents, in the exercise of their free agency, often disobey in spite of all the inducements to the contrary which God can wisely set be- fore them. God never sets aside the freedom of moral agents to prevent their sinning, nor to secure their obedience. The Bible everywhere rep- resents men as acting freely under the government and universal provi- dence of God, and it represents sin as the result of, or as consisting in, an abuse of their freedom. Gen. xlii. 31 : "And they said one to another. We are verily guilty concerning our brother, in that we saw the anguish of his soul, when he besought us, and we would not hear ; therefore is this distress come upon us." Ex. viii. 32 : " And Pharaoh hardened his heart at this time also, neither would he let the people go." Ex. ix. 27 : " And Pharaoh sent, and called for Moses and Aaron, and said unto them, I have sinned this time : the Lord is righteous, and I and my people are wicked." Ex. X. 16 : " Then Pharaoh called for Moses and Aaron in haste ; and he said, I have sinned against the Lord your God, and against you. 17. Now therefore forgive, I pray thee, my sin only this once, and entreat the Lord your God, that he may take away from me this death only." Deut. XXX. 19 : "I call heaven and earth to record this day against you, that I have set before you life and death, blessing and cursing : therefore choose life, that both thou and thy seed may live." Josh. xxiv. 15 : " And if it seem evil unto you to serve the Lord, choose ye this day whom ye will serve ; whether the gods which your fathers served that were on the other side of the flood, or the gods of the Amorites, in whose land ye dwell ; but as for me and my bouse, we will serve the Lord." 2 Sam. xxiv. 1 : "And again the anger of the Lord was kindled against Israel, and he moved David against them to say. Go, number Israel and Judah. 10. And David's heart smote him after that he had numbered the people. And David said unto the Lord, I have sinned greatly in that I have done : and now, I beseech thee, Lord, take away the iniquity of thy servant ; for I have done very foolishly.'.' Prov. i. 10 : " My son, if sinners entice thee, consent thou not. 29. For that they hated knowledge, and did not choose the fear of the Lord; 30. They would none of my counsel ; they despised all my reproof ; 3L Therefore shall they eat of the fruit of their own way, and be filled with their own devices." PURPOSES OP GOD. 535 Prov. XTi. 9 : " A man's heart deviseth his way, but the Lord directeth his steps." The following things appear to be true in respect to the purposes of God, as taught both by reason and revelation : — (1.) That God's purposes extend in some sense to all events. (2.) That he positively purposes the highest good of being, as a whole as his end. (3.) That he has ordained wise and wholesome laws as the necessary means of securing this end. (4.) That he positively purposes to secure obedience to these laws in so far as he wisely can, and uses means with this design. (5.) That he does not positively purpose to secure disobedience to his laws in any case, and use means with that design ; but that he only purposes to suffer violations of his law rather than prevent them, because he foresees that, by his overruling power, he can prevent the violation from resulting in so great an evil as the change necessary to prevent it would do. Or in other words, he sees that he can secure a greater good upon the whole, by suffering the violation under the circumstances in which it occurs, than he could by interposing to prevent it. This is not the same thing as to say, that sin is the necessary means of the greatest good. For should all moral agents perfectly obey, under the identical circumstances in which they disobey, this might, and doubtless would result in the highest possible good. But God, foreseeing that it were more conducive to the highest good of being to suffer some to sin, rather than so change the circumstances as to prevent it, purposed to suffer their sin, and overrule it for good ; but he did not aim at producing it, and use means with that intent. V. Qod^s revealed will is never inconsistent with his secret purpose. It has been common to represent sin as the necessary occasion, condi- tion, or means of the greatest good, in such a sense, that upon the whole God secretly, but really prefers sin to holiness in every case where it exists ; that while he has forbidden sin under all circumstances, upon pain of eternal death, yet because it is the necessary occasion, condition, or means of the greatest good, God really prefers its existence to holiness in every instance in which it exists. It has been said, sin exists. God does not therefore prevent it. But he could and would prevent it, if he did not upon the whole prefer it to holiness, in the circumstances in which it occurs. Its existence, then, it has been said, is proof conclusive that God secretly prefers its existence to holiness, in every case in which it occurs. But this is a non sequitur. It does not follow from the existence of sin, that God prefers sin to holiness in the circumstances in which it occurs ; but it may be that he only prefers sin to such a 836 SrSTiSMATlC THEOLOGY. change of circumst.auces as would prevent it. Suppose I require my son to do a certain thing. I know that he will do it, if I remain at home and see to it. But I know also, that if I go from home he will not do it. Now I might prefer that he should do as I command, and con- sider his disobedience as a great evil-5 still I might regard it as a less evil than for me to remain at home, and keep my eye upon him. I might have just reasons for supposing that, under the circumstances, a greater good could be secured upon the whole by my going from home, although his disobedience might be the consequence, than by remaining at home, and preventing his disobedience. Benevolence therefore might require me to go. But should my son infer from my leaving him, under these circum- stances, that I really, though secretly, preferred his disobedience to his obedience, under the identical circumstances in which I gave the com- mand, would his inference be legitimate ? No, indeed. All that he could justly infer from my leaving him, with the knowledge that he would disobey me if I did, would be, that although I regarded his diso- bedience as a great evil, yet I regarded remaining at home a greater. Just so, it may be when sin exists. God is sincere in prohibiting it. He would greatly prefer that it should not exist. All that can be justly inferred from his not preventing it is, that, although he regards its existence as a great and real evil, yet upon the whole he regards it as a less evil, than would result from so great a change in the administra- tion of his government as would prevent it. He is therefore entirely and iniinitely sincere in requiring obedience, and in prohibiting disobe- dience, and his secret purpose is in strict keeping with his revealed will. Were the moral law universally obeyed, under the circumstances in which all moral agents exist, no one can say, that this would not be better for the universe, and more pleasing to God than disobedience is in the same circumstances. Nor is it fair to infer, that upon the whole, God must prefer sin to holiness, where it occurs, from the fact that he does not prevent it. As has been said, all that can justly be inferred from his not preventing it is, that under the circumstances he prefers not sin to holiness, but prefers to suffer the agent to sin and take the consequences, rather than introduce such changes in the policy and ad- ministration of his government as would prevent it. Or it may be said, thai, the present system is the best that infinite wisdom could devise and execute, not because of sin, but in spite of it, and notwithstanding sin , is a real though incidental evil. It is a palpable contradiction and an absurdity to affirm, that any being can sin, intending thereby to promote the greatest good. Thif will appear if we consider : — 1. That it is admitted on all hands, that benevolence is virtue. PURPOSES OF GOD. 537 3. That benevolence consists in willing good, or the highest good of being as an end. 3. That it is duty to will both the end and the necessary means to promote it. 4. That right and benevolence are always at one, that is, that which is benevolent must always be right, and can in no case be wrong. 5. That consequently it can never be sin to choose the highest good of being, with all the necessary occasions, conditions, and means of pro- moting it. 6. It is impossible therefore for a being to sin, or to consent to sin, as an occasion, condition, or means, or designing thereby to promote the highest good of being ; for this design would be virtue, and not sin. Whether all virtue consists in benevolence, or not, still it must be ad- mitted, that all forms of virtue must be consistent with benevolence, un- less it be admitted, that there can be a law of right inconsistent with, and opposed to, the law of benevolence. But this would be to admit, that two moral laws might be opposed to each other ; which would be to admit, that a moral agent might be under an obligation to obey two op- posing laws at the same time, which is a contradiction. Thus it appears, that there can be no law of right opposed to, or separate from, the law of benevolence. Benevolence and right must then always be at one. If this be so, it follows, that whatever benevolence demands, cannot be wrong, but must be right. But the law of benevolence demands not only the choice of the highest good of being as an end, but also demands the choice of all the known necessary occasions, conditions, and means with a design to promote that end. It is naturally impossible to sin, in using means designed and known to be necessary to the promotion of the end of benevolence. It is there- fore naturally impossible to do evil, or to sin, that good may come, or with the design to promote good thereby. Let those who hold that right and benevolence may be opposed to each other, and that a moral agent can sin with a benevolent intention, see what their doctrine amounts to, and get out of the absurdity as best they can. The fact is, if willing the highest good of being is always vir- tuous, it must always be right to will all the necessary occasions, condi- tions, and means to that end. It is therefore a contradiction to say that sin can be among the necessary and intended occasions, conditions, and means ; that is, that any one could sin intending thereby to promote the highest good. But it is not pretended by those who hold this dogma, that sin sustains to the highest good the same relations that holiness does. Holiness has a natural tendency to promote the highest good ; but the supposition now iinder consideration is, that sin is Ijateful in itsejf, apd tha^t it therefore 538 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. must dissatisfy and disgust all moral agents, and that its namrsii tend- ency is to defeat the end of moral government, and to prevent rather than promote the highest good ; but that God foresees that, notwith- standing its intrinsically odious and injurious nature, he can so overrule it as to make it the condition, occasion, or instrument of the highest good of himself and of his universe, and that for this reason he really upon the whole is pleased that it should occur, and prefers its existence in every instance in which it does exist, to holiness in its stead. The supposition is, that sin is in its own nature infinitely odious and abomi- nable to God, and perfectly odious to all holy moral agents, yet it is the occasion of calling into development and exercise such emotions and feel- ings in God and in holy beings, and such modifications of benevolence, as do really more than compensate for all the disgust and painful emo- tions that result to holy beings, and for all the remorse, agony, despair, and endless sufEering, that result to sinners. It is not supposed by any one that I know of, that sin naturally tends to promote the highest good at all, but only that God can, and does, so overrule and counteract its natural tendency, as to make it the occasion or condition of a greater good, than holiness would be in its stead. Now in reply to this, I would say, that I pretend not to determine to what extent God can, and will, overrule and counteract the naturally evil and injurious tendency of sin. It surely is enough to say that God prohibits it and that it is impossible for creatures to know that sin is the neces- sary occasion, or condition, or means of the highest good. * * If sin is known by God to be the necessary occasion, condition, or means of the highest good of himself and of the universe, whatever it may be in itself, yet viewed in its relations, it must be regarded by him as of infinite value, since it is the indispensable condition of infinite good.' According to this theory, sin in every instance in which it exists, is and must be regarded by God as of infinitely greater value than holi- ness would be in its stead. He must then, upon the whole, have infinite complacency in it. But this leads me to attend to the principal argu- ments by which it is supposed this theory is maintained. It is said, for example : — (1.) That the highest good of the universe of moral agents is condi- tionated upon the revelation of the attributes and character of God to them ; that but for sin these attributes, at least some of them, could never have been revealed, inasmuch as without sin there would have been no occasion for their display or manifestation ; that neither justice nor mercy, nor forbearance, nor self denial, nor meekness, could have found the occasions of their exercise or manifestation, had sin never existed. To this I reply, that sin has indeed furnished the occasion for a glori- ous manifestation of the moral perfections of God, From this we see PURPOSES OP GOD. 539 that God's perfections enable him greatly to overrule sin, and to bring good out of evil : but from this we are not authorized to infer, that God could not have revealed these attributes to his creatures without the exist- ence of sin. Nor can we say, that these revelations would have been necessary to the highest perfection and happiness of the universe, had all moral agents perfectly and uniformly obeyed. When we consider what the moral attributes of God are, it is easy to see that there may be myriads of moral attributes in God of which no creature has, or ever will have, any knowledge ; and the knowledge of which is not at all essential to the highest perfection and happiness of the universe of creatures. God's moral attributes are only his benevolence, existing and contemplated in its various relations to the universe of beings. Benevolence in any being must possess as many attributes as there are possible relations under which it can be contemplated, and should their occasions arise, these attributes would stand forth in exercise. It is not at all probable, that all of the attributes of benevolence, either in the Creator or in creat- ures, have yet found the occasions of their exercise, nor, perhaps, will they ever. As new occasions rise to all eternity, benevolence will develop new and striking attributes, and manifest itself under endless forms and varieties of loveliness. There can be no such thing as exhausting its capabilities of development. In God benevolence is infinite. Creatures can never know all its at- tributes, nor approach any nearer to knowing all of them than they now are. There can be no end to its capabilities of developing in exercise new forms of beauty and loveliness. It is true, that God has taken oc- casion to show forth the glory of his benevolence through the existence of sin. He has seized the occasion, though mournful in itself, to mani- fest some of the attributes of his benevolence by the exercise of them. It is also true, that we cannot know how or by what means God could have revealed these attributes, if sin had not existed ; and it is also true, that we cannot know that such a revelation was impossible without the exist- ence of sin ; nor that, but for sin, the revelation would have been neces- sary to the highest good of the universe. God forbids sin, and requires universal holiness. He must be sincere in this. But sin exists. Shall we say that he secretly chooses that it should, and really, though secretly, prefers its existence to holiness, in the circumstances in which it occurs ? Or shall we assume, that it is an evil, that God regards it as such, but that he cannot wisely prevent it • that is, to prevent it would introduce a still greater evil ? It is an evil and a great evil, but still the less of two evils ; that is, to suffer it to occur, under the circumstances, is a less evil than such a change of cir- cumstances, as would prevent it, would be. This is all we can justly infer from its existeace, This leq,ves the sincerity of God unimpeached, and 540 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOSY. sustains his consistency, and the consistency and integrity of his law. The opposite supposition represents God and the law as infinitely de- ceitful. (2.) It has been said, that the Bible sustains the supposition, that sin is the necessary means of the highest good. I trust the passages that have been quoted, disprove this saying. (3.) It is said, that to represent sin as not the means of the highest good, and God as unable to pre\ient it, is to represent God as unable to accomplish all his will ; whereas he says, he will do all his pleasure, and that nothing is too hard for him. I answer : God pleases to do only what is naturally possible, and he is well pleased to do that and nothing more. This he is able to do. This he will do. This he does. This is all he claims to be able to do ; and this is all that in fact infinite wisdom and power can do. (4.) But it is said, that if sin is an evil, and God can neither prevent nor overrule it, so as to make it a means of greater good than could be secured without it, he must be unhappy in view of this fact, because he cannot prevent it, and secure a higher good without it. I answer : God neither desires nor wills to perform natural impossi- bilities. God is a reasonable being, and does not aim at nor desire im- possibilities. He is well content to do as well as, in the nature of the case, is possible, and has no unreasonable regrets because he is not more than infinite, and that he cannot accomplish what is impossible to in- finity itself. His good pleasure is, to secure all the good that is possible to infinity : with this he is infinitely well pleased. Again : does not the objection, that the view of the subject here pre- sented limits the divine power, lie with all its force against those who make this objection ? To hold that sin is the necessary means or condi-- tion of the highest good, is to hold that God was unable to promote the highest good without resorting to such vile means as sin. Sin is an abomination in itself ; and do not they, as really and as much limit the power of God, who maintain his inability to promote the highest good without it, as they do who hold, that he could not wisely so interfere with the free actions of moral agents as to prevent it ? Sin exists. God abhors it. How is its existence to be accounted for ? I suppose it to be an evil unavoidably incidental to that system of moral government which, notwithstanding the evil, was upon the whole the best that could be adopted. Others suppose that sin is the necessary means or condition of the greatest good ; and account for its existence in this way : — that is, they suppose that God admits or permits its existence as a necessary oc- casion, condition, or means of the highest good ; that he was not able to secure the highest good without it. The two explanations of the ad- inittpd ifact that pip exists, differ in this ; — PURPOSES OP GOD. 541 One method of explanation holds, that sin is the necessary occasion, condition, or means of the highest good ; and that God actually, upon the whole, prefers the existence of sin to holiness, in every instance in which it exists ; because, in those circumstances, it is a condition or means of greater good than could have been secured by holiness in its stead. This theory represents God as unable to secure his end by other means, or upon other conditions, than sin. The other theory holds, that God really prefers holiness to sin in every instance in which it occurs ; that he regards sin as an evil, but that while he regards it as an evil, he suffers its existence as a less evil than such a change .in the ad- ministration of his government as would prevent it, would be. Both theories must admit, that in some sense God could not wisely prevent it. Explain the fact of its existence as you will, it must be admitted, that in some sense God was not able to prevent it, and secure his end. If it be said, that God could neither wisely prevent it, nor so overrule it as to make it the means or condition of the highest good, he must be rendered unhappy by its existence ; I reply, that this must be equally true upon the other hypothesis. Sin is hateful, and its consequences are a great evil. These consequences will be eternal and indefinitely great. God must disapprove these consequences. If sin is the necessary condi- tion or means of the greatest good, must not God lament that he cannot secure the good without a resort to such loathsome, and such horrible means ? If his inability wisely to prevent it will interfere with and di- minish his happiness, must not the same be true of his inability to secure the highest good, without such means as will prove the eternal destruc- tion of millions ? VI. Wisdom and benevolence of the purposes of God. We have seen that God is both wise and benevolent. This is the doc- trine both of reason and of revelation. The reason intuitively aflSrms that God is, and is perfect. The Bible assumes that he is, and declares that he is perfect. Both wisdom and benevolence must be attributes of the infinite and perfect God. These attributes enter into the reason's idea of God. The reason could not recognize any being as God to whom these attributes did not belong. But if infinite wisdom and benevolence are moral attributes of God, it follows of course that all his designs or purposes are both perfectly wise and benevolent. God has chosen the best possible end,^and pursues it in the use of the best practicable means. His purposes embrace the end and the means necessary to secure it, to- gether with the best practicable disposal of the sin, which is the inciden- tal result of his choosing this end and using these means ; and they extend BO further ; they are all therefore perfectly wise and good. 542 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. VII. The immutability of the divine purposes. We have seen that immutability is not only a natural, but also a moral attribute of God. The reason affirms, that the self-existent and infinitely perfect God is unchangeable in all his attributes. The ground of this affirmation it is not my purpose here to inquire into. It is sufficient here to say, what every one knows, that such is the affirmation of the reason. This is also everywhere assumed and taught in the Bible. God's moral attributes are not immutable in the sense of necessity, but only in the sense of certainty. Although God is not necessarily benevolent, yet he ie as immutably so, as if he were necessarily so. If his benevolence were necessary, it would not be virtuous, for the simple reason that it would not be free. But being free, its immutability renders it all the more praiseworthy. VIII. The purposes of God are a ground of eternal and joyful confi- That is, they may reasonably be a source of eternal comfort, joy, and peace. Selfish beings will not of course rejoice in them, but benevolent beings will and must. If they are infinitely wise and good, and sure to be accomplished, they must form a rational ground of unfailing confi- dence and joy. God says : — Isa. xlvi. 10 : " Declaring the end from the beginning, and from ancient times the things that are not yet done, saying. My counsel shall stand, and I will do all my pleasure." Psa. xxxiii. 11 : " The counsel of the Lord standeth for ever, the thoughts of his heart to all generations." Prov. xix. 31 : " There are many devices in a man's heart, neverthe- less, the counsel of the Lord, that shall stand." Acts V. 39 : " But if it be of God, ye cannot overthrow it, lest haply ye be found even to fight against God." These, and many parallel passages are reasonably the source of per- petual confidence and joy to those who love God, and sympathize with him. IX. The relation of God's purposes to his prescience or foreknowledge. We have seen that God is omniscient, that is, that he necessarily and eternally knows whatever is, or can be, an object of knowledge. His purposes must also be eternal and immutable, as we have seen. In the order of time, therefore, his purposes and his foreknowledge must be coeval, that is, they must be co-eternal. But in the order of nature, God's knowledge of what he could do, and what could be done, must have preceded his purposes : that is, he could not, so to speak, in the order of nature, have formed his purpose and PURPOSES OF QOD. 543 made up his mind what to do, until he had considered what could be done, and what was best to be done. Until all possible ends, and ways, and means, were weighed and understood, it was of course impossible to make a selection, and settle upon the end with all the necessary means ; and also settle upon the ways and means of overruling any evil, natural or moral, that might be seen to be unavoidably incidental to any system. Thus it appears, that, in the order of nature, fore-knowledge of what could be done, and what he could do, must have preceded the purpose to do. The purpose resulted from the prescience or fore-knowledge. He knew what he could do, before he decided what he would do. But, on the other hand, the purpose to do must, in the order of nature, have pre- ceded the knowledge of what he should do, or of what would be done, or would come to pass as a result of his purpose. Viewed relatively to what he could do, and what could be done, the Divine prescience must in the order of nature have preceded the Divine purposes. But viewed rela- tively to what he would do, and what would be done, and would come to pass, the Divine purposes must, in the order of nature, have preceded the Divine prescience. But I say again, as fore-knowledge was necessarily eternal with God, his purposes must also have been eternal, arid there- fore, in the order of time, neither his prescience could have preceded his purposes, nor his purposes have preceded his prescience. They must have been cotemporaneous and co-eternal. X. God's purposes are not inconsistent with, hut demand the use 0/ means loth on Ms part, and on our part, to accomplish them. The great end upon which he has set his heart necessarily depends upon the use of means, both moral and physical, to accomplish it. The highest well-being of the whole universe is his end. This end can be secured only by securing conformity to the laws of matter and of mind. Mind is influenced by motives, and hence moral and physical government are naturally necessary means of securing the great end proposed by the Divine mind. Hence also results the necessity of a vast and complicated system of means and influences, such as we see spread around us on every hand. The history of the universe is but the history of creation, and of the means which God is using to secure his end, with their natural and inci- dental results. It has already been shown, that the Bible teaches that the purposes of God include and respect both means and ends. I will only add, that God's purposes do not render any event, dependent upon the acts of a moral agent, necessarily certain, or certain with a certainty of necessity. Although, as was before said, all events are certain with some kind of certainty, and would be and must be, if they are ever to come to pass, whether God purposes them, or whether he foreknows them or not j yet 6*4 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. no event, depending upon the will of a free agent, is, or can be, certain with a certainty of necessity. The agent could by natural possibility do otherwise than he will do, or than God purposes to suffer him to do, or wills that he shall do. God's purposes, let it be understood, are not a system of fatality. They leave every moral agent entirely free to choose and act freely. God knows infallibly how every creature will act, and has made all his arrangements accordingly, to overrule the wicked actions of moral agents on the one hand, and to produce or induce, the holy actions of others on the other hand. But be it remembered, that neither the Divine fore-knowledge nor the Divine purpose, in any in- stance, sets aside the free agency of the creature. He, in every instance, . acts as freely and as responsibly, as if God neither knew nor purposed anything respecting his conduct, or his destiny. God's purposes extend to all events in some sense, as has been shown. They extend as really to the most common events of life as to the most rare. But in respect to the every day transactions of life, men are not wont to stumble, and cavil, and say. Why, if I am to live, I shall live, whatever I may do to destroy my health and life ; and if I am to die, I * cannot liVe, do what I will. No, in these events they will not throw off responsibility, and cast themselves upon the purposes of God ; but on the contrary, they are as much engaged to secure the end they have in view, as if God neither knew nor purposed anything about it. Why then should they do as they often do, in regard to the salvation of their souls, cast ofE responsibility, and settle down in listless inactivity, as if the purposes of God in respect to salvation were but a system of iron fatality, from which there is no escape ? Surely " madness is in their hearts while they live." But let them understand, that, in thus doing, they sin against the Lord, and be sure their sin will find them out. LECTURE XLVII. PERSEVEEANCE OF SAINTa In discussing this subject, I will, I. Notice the different hinds of certainty. Every thing must be certain with some kind of certainty. There is a way in which all things and events either have been, are, or will be. All events that ever did or will occur, were and are as really certain before as after their occurrence. To an omniscient mind their real certainty PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. 546 might and must have been known, as really before as after their occur- rence. All future events, for example, will occur in some way, and there is no real uncertainty in fact, nor can there be any real uncertainty in the knowledge of God respecting them. They are really as certain before they come to pass as they will ever be, and they are as truly and perfectly known as certain by God as they ever will be. They are as truly present to the Divine fore-knowledge as they ever will be. What- ever of contingency and uncertainty there may be respecting them in some respects, yet, in point of fact, all events are certain, and there is no real uncertainty in respect to any event that ever did or will occur. This would be equally true, whether God or any other being knew how they would be or not. The fore-knowledge of God does not make them certain. He knows them to be certain simply because they are so. Omniscience is the necessary knowledge of all objects of knowledge, past, present, and future. But omniscience does not create objects of knowl- edge. It does not render events certain, but only knows how they cer- tainly will be, because it is certain, not only that they will be, but how and when they will be. All the free actions of moral agents are as really certain before they occur, as they ever will be. And God must as truly know how they will be before they occur, as he does after they have occurred. 1. The first kind of certainty that I shall notice, is that of absolute necessity ; that is, a certainty depending on no conditions whatever. This is the highest kind of certainty. It belongs to the absolute and the infinite, to the existence of space, duration, and to the existence of God ; and in short to everything that is self-existent, infinite, and im- mutable in a natural sense j that is, to everything infinite that does not imply voluntariness. The natural attributes of God are certain ]py this kind of certainty, but his moral attributes, consisting as they do in a voluntary state of mind, though infinite and eternal, do not belong to this class. 2. A second kind of certainty is that of physical, but conditional necessity. To this class belong all those events that come to pass under the operation of physical law. These belong properly to the chain of cause and effect. The cause existing, the efEect must exist. The event is rendered certain and necessary by the existence of its cause. Its certainty is conditionated upon its cause. The cause existing, the event must follow by a law of necessity, and the events would not occur of course, did not their causes exist. The causes being what they are, the events must be what they are. This class of events are as really certain as the fo:egoing class. By speaking of one of them as certain in a higher sense than the other, it is not intended, that one class is any more certain than the other, but only that the certainty is of a difEerent kiiid, Foi 35 546 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. example, the first class are certain by a kind of certainty ttat does not, and never did depend on the will of any being whatever. There never was any possibility that these things should be otherwise than they are. This, it will be seen, must be true of space and duration, and of the existence and the natural attributes of God. But all other things except the self-existent, the naturally immutable and eternal, are certain only as they are conditionated directly or indi- rectly upon the will of some being. For example, all the events of the physical universe were rendered certain by creation, and the establishing and upholding of those physical and necessary laws that cause these events. These are, therefore, certain by a conditioned, though physical necessity. There is no freedom or liberty in the events themselves ; they occur necessarily, when their causes or conditions are supplied. 3. A third kind of certainty is that of a moral certainty. I call it a moral certainty, not because the class of events which belong to it are less certain than the foregoing, but because they consist in, or are conditionated upon, the free actions of moral agents. This class do not occur under the operation of a law of necessity, though they occur with certainty. There is no contingency predicable of the absolutely certain in the sense of absolute certainty above defined. The second class of certainties are contingent only in respect to their causes. Upon condi- tion that the causes are certain, the events depending upon them are certain, without or beyond any contingency. This third class, though no less certain than the former two, are nevertheless contingent in the highest sense in which anything can be contingent. They occur under the operation of free will, and consequently there is not one of them that might not by natural possibility fail, or be otherwise than it is or will in fact be. This kind of certainty I call a moral certainty, as opposed to a physical certainty, that is, it is not a certainty of neces- sity in any sense ; it is only a mere certainty, or a voluntaiy certainty, a free certainty, a certainty that might, by natural possibility in every case, be no certainty at all. But, on the contrary, the opposite might in every instance be certain by a natural possibility. God in every instance, knows how these events will be, as I'eally as if they occurred by necessity ; but his foreknowledge does not affect their certainty one way or the other. They might in every instance by natural possibility be no certainties at all, or be the opposite of what they are or will be, God's foreknowledge in anywise notwithstanding. God knows them to be certain, not because his knowledge has any infiuence of itself to necessi- tate them, but because they are certain in themselves. Because it is certain in itself that they will be, God knows that they will be. To this class of events belong all the free actions of moral agents. All events may be traced ultimately to the action of God's free will ; that is, God's PERSEVERANCE OP SAINTS. 547 free actions gave existence to the universe, with all its physical agencies and laws, so that all physical events are in some sense owing to, and result from the actions of free will. But physical events occur neverthe- less under the immediate operation of a law of necessity. The class now under consideration depend not upon the operation of physical law as their cause. They are caused by the free agent himself. They find the occasions of their occurrence in the providential events with which moral agents are surrounded, and therefore may be traced indirectly, and more or less remotely, to the actions of the Divine will. Concerning this class of events, I would further remark that they are not only contingent in such a sense, that they might in every case by natural possibility be other than they are, but there may be, humanly speaking, the utmost danger that they will be otherwise than they really will be, that is, there may be danger, and the utmost danger, in the only sense in which there can be in fact any danger that any event will be otherwise than what it turns out to be. All events being really certain, there is in fact no danger that any event whatever will turn out differ- ently from what it does, in the sense that it is not certain how it will be. But since all acts of free will, and all events dependent on those acts, are contingent in the highest sense in which any event can in the nature of things be contingent ; and in the sense that, humanly speaking, there may be millions of chances to one that they will be otherwise than they will in fact turn out to be, — we say of all this class of events, that there is danger that they may or may not occur. Again : I remark in respect to this class of events, that God may foresee that so intricate is the labyrinth, and so complicated are the occasions of failure, that nothing but the utmost watchfulness and dili- gent use of means on his part, and on our part, can secure the occurrence of the event. Everything revealed in the Bible concerning the perse- verance and final salvation of the saints, and everything that is true, and that God knows of the free actions and destinies of the saints, may be of this class. These events are nevertheless certain, and are known to God as certainties. Not one of them will, in fact, turn out difEerently from what he foresees that they will ; and yet by natural possibility, they might every one of them turn out differently ; and there may, in the only sense in which danger is predicable of anything, be the utmost danger that some or all of them will turn out differently from what they in fact will. These events are contingent in such a sense, that should the means fail to be used, or should any event in the whole chain of influences connected with their occurrence, be otherwise than it isj the end or event resulting, would or might be otherwise, than in fact it will be. They are, nevertheless, certain, every one of them, together with all the influences upon which each free act depends. Nothing is uncertain 548 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. in respect to whether it will occur or not ; and yet no free act, or event depending upon a free act, is certain, in the sense that it cannot by natural possibility be otherwise, nor in the sense that there may not be great danger, or, humanly speaking, a probability that it will be other- wise, and that, humanly speaking, there may not be many chances to one that it will be otherwise. When I say, that any event may, by natural possibility, be otherwise than what it will in fact be, I mean, that the free agent has natural power in every instance to choose otherwise than he does or actually will choose. As an illustration of both the contingency and the certainty of this class of events, suppose a man about to attempt to cross Lake Erie on a wire, or to pass down the falls of Niagara in a bark canoe. The result of this attempt is really certain. Gofl must know how it will be. But this result, though certain, is conditionated upon a multitude of things, each of which the agent has natural power to make otherwise than in fact he will. To secure his safe crossing, every volition must be just what and as it will be ; but there is not one among them that might not, by natural possibility, be the opposite of what it will be. Again, the case may be such, and the danger of failure so great, that nothing could secure the safe crossing, but a revelation from God that would inspire confidence, that the adventurer should in fact cross the lake, or venture down the falls safely : I say, this revelation of God might be indispensable to his safe crossing. Suppose it were revealed to a man under such circumstances, that he should actually arrive in safety; but the revelation was accompanied with the emphatic assurance, that the end depended upon the most diligent, cautious, and persevering use of means on his part, and that any failure in these would defeat the end. Both the revelation of the certainty of success, and the emphatic warn- ing, might be indispensable to the securing of the end. Now, if the adventurer had confidence in the promise of success, he would have con- fidence in the caution not to neglect the necessary means, and his confi- dence in both might secure the desired result. But take an example .from scripture : — Acts xxvii. 21 : " But after long abstinence, Paul stood forth in the midst of them, and said. Sirs, ye should have hearkened unto me, and not have loosed from Crete, and to have gained this harm and loss. 22. And now I exhort you to be of good cheer : for there shall be no loss of any man's life among you, but of the ship. For there stood by me this night the angel of God, whose I am, and whom I serve, 24. Saying, Fear not, Paul : thou must be brought before Caesar : and lo, God hath given thee all them that sail with thee. 25. Wherefore, sirs, be of good cheer : for I believe God, that it shall be even as it was told me. 36. Howbeit we must be cast upon a certain island. 27. But when the four- PERSEVEEANCE OF SAINTS. 549 teenth night was come, as we were driven up and down in Adria, about midnight the ship-men deemed that they drew near to some country ; 28. And sounded, and found it twenty fathoms : and when they had gone a little further, they sojinded again, and found it fifteen fathoms. 29. Then fearing lest we should have fallen upon rocks, they cast anchors out of the stern, and wished for the day. 30. And as the ship-men were about to flee out of the ship, when they had let down the boat into the sea, under color as though they would have cast anchors out of the fore- ship, 31. Paul said to the centurion and to the soldiers. Except these abide in the ship, ye cannot be saved." Here the end was foreknown and expressly foretold at first, without any condition expressed, though they plainly understood that the end was to be secured by means. Paul after- wards informed them, that if they neglected the means, the end would fail. Both the means and the end were certain in fact, and God there- fore expressly revealed the certainty of the result, and afterwards by a subsequent revelation secured the use of the necessary means. Here was no uncertainty, in the sense that the thing might, in fact, turn out other- wise than it did, and yet it was uncertain in the sense that, by natural possibility, both the means and the end might fail. I remark, again, in respect to events that are morally certain, that if they are greatly desired, they are not the more, but all the less, in dan- ger of failing, by how much stronger the confidence is that they will occur, provided it be understood, that they are certain only by a moral certainty ; that is, provided it be understood, that the event is conditioned upon the free acts of the agent himself. Again : it is generally admitted, that hope is a condition of success in any enterprise ; and if this is so, assurance of success, upon the proper conditions, cannot tend to defeat the end. I remark, again, that there is a difEerence between real danger, and a knowledge or sense of danger. There may be as great and as real dan- ger when we have no sense or knowledge of it, as when we have. And on the other hand, when we have the highest and the keenest sense of dan- ger, there may be, in fact, no real danger ; and indeed, as has been said, there never is any danger in the sense that anything will, as a mat- ter of fact, turn out differently from what God foresees it will be. Again : the fact that anything is revealed as certain, does not make it certain ; that is, the revelation does not make it certain. It had been certain, had not this certainty been revealed, unless it be in cases where the revelation is a condition or means of the certainty revealed. An event may be really certain, and may be revealed as certain, and yet, humanly speaking, there may be millions of chances to one, that it will not be as it is revealed ; that is, so far as human foresight can go, the probabilities may all be against it. 650 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGT. II. State what is not intended hy the perseverance of the saints, as 1 hold the doctrine. 1. It is not intended that any sinner will be saved without complying with the conditions of salvation ; that is, without regeneration, and per- severing in obedience to the end of life, in a sense to be hereafter ex- plained. 2. It is not intended that saints, or the truly regenerate, cannot fall from grace, and be finally lost, by natural possibility. It must be natu- rally possible for all moral agents to sin at any time. Saints on earth and in heaven can by natural possibility apostatize and fall, and be lost. Were not this naturally possible, there would be no virtue in perseverance. 3. It is not intended, that the true saints are in no danger of apostacy and ultimate damnation. For, humanly speaking, there may be, and doubtless is, the greatest danger in respect to many, if not of all of them, in the only sense in which danger is predicable of any event whatever, that they will apostatize, and be ultimately lost. 4. It is not intended, that there may not be, humanly speaking, myr-- iads of chances to one, that some, or that many of them will fall and be lost. This may be, as we say, highly probable ; that is, it may be proba- ble in the only sense in which it is probable, that any event whatever may be different from what it will turn out to be. 5. It is not intended, that the salvation of the saints is possible, ex- cept upon condition of great watchfulness and effort, and perseverance on their part, and great grace on the part of God. 6. It is not intended, that their salvation is certain, in any higher sense than all their future free actions are. The result is conditioned upon their free actions, and the end can be no more certain than its means or conditions. If the ultimate salvation of the saints is certain, it is certain only upon condition, that their perseverance in obedience to the end of life is certain. Every act of this obedience is free and contin- gent in the highest sense in which contingency can be predicated of any thing whatever. It is also uncertain by the highest kind of uncertainty that can be predicated of any event whatever. Therefore there is and must be, as much real danger of the saints failing of ultimate salvation, as there is that any event whatever will be different from what it turns out to be. But here it should be distinctly remembered, as was said, that there is a difference between a certainty and a knowledge of it. It is one thing for an event to be really certain, and another thing for us to have a knowledge of it as certain; Everything is really equally certain, but many things are not revealed to us as certain. Those that are revealed as certain, are no more really so than others, but with respect to future PERSEVERANCE OP SAINTS. 551 things, not in some way revealed to us, we know not how they will prove to be. The fact that a thing is revealed to us as certain does not make it certain, nor is it really any the less uncertain because it is revealed to us as certain, unless the revelation tends to secure the certainty. Sup- pose the ultimate salvation of all the saints is certain, and that this cer- tainty is revealed to us ; unless this revelation is the means of securing their salvation, they are in just as much real danger of ultimately failing of eternal life, as if no such revelation had been made. Notwithstand- ing the certainty of their salvation, and the fact that this certainty is re- vealed to them, there is just as much real, though unknown, certainty or uncertainty, in respect to any future event whatever, as there is in re- spect to this. All events are certain with some kind of certainty, and would be whether any being whatever knew the certainty or not. So all events, consisting in or depending upon the free acts of free agents, are really as uncertain as any event can be, and this is true whether the cer- tainty is revealed or not. The salvation of the saints then, is not certain with any higher certainty than belongs to all future events that consist in, or are conditionated upon, the free acts of free will, though this cer- tainty may be revealed to us in one case, and not in the other. 7. Of course ^the salvation of the saints is not certain by any kind or degree of certainty that affords the least ground of hope of impunity in a course of sin. " For if they are to be saved, they are to be saved upon condition of continuing in faith and obedience to the end of life." Moreover, their salvation is no more certain than their future free obedience is. The certainty of future free obedience, and a knowledge of this certainty, cannot be a reason for not obeying, or afford encour- agement to live in sin. So no more can the knowledge of the conditional and moral certainty of our salvation afford a ground for hope of impunity m a life of sin. 8. The salvation of the saints is not certain by any kind or degree of certainty that renders their salvation or their damnation any more im- possible, than it renders impossible any future acts of sin or obedience. Consequently, it is not certain in such a sense as to afford the least en- couragement for hope of salvation in sin, any more than a certainty that a farmer would raise a crop upon condition of his diligent, and timely, and persevering use of the appropriate means, would encourage him to neglect those means. If the farmer had a knowledge of the certainty with its conditions, it would be no temptation to neglect the means ; but, on the other hand, this knowledge would operate as a powerful incentive to the required use of them. So neither can the knowledge of the cer- tainty of the salvation of the saints, with the condition of it, be to them a temptation to live in sin ; but, on the contrary, this knowledge must act as a powerful incentive to the exercise of confidence in God, and per- 552 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. severance in holiness unto the end. So neither can the certainty that the necessary means will be used, afford any encouragement to neglect the use of them in the cas6 of man's salvation, any more than the revealed certainty that a farmer will sow his field and have a crop, would encour- age him to neglect to sow. The known certainty of both the means and the end, with an understanding of the moral nature of the certainty, has no natural tendency to beget presumption and neglect ; but, on the con- trary, to beget a diligent, and cheerful, and confident use of the neces- sary means. III. Show what is intended by the doctrine in question. It is intended, that all who are at any time true saints of God, are preserved by his grace and Spirit through faith, in the sense that subse- quently to regeneration, obedience is their rule, and disobedience only the exception ; and that being thus kept, they will certainly be saved with an everlasting salvation. Before I proceed to the direct proof of the doctrine, a few remarks may be desirable. 1. I would remark, that I have felt greater hesitancy in forming and expressing my views upon this, than upon almost any other question in theology. I have read whatever I could find upon both sides of this question, and have uniformly found myself dissatisfied with the argu- ments on both sides. After very full and repeated discussion, I feel better able to make up and express an opinion upon the subject than formerly. I have at some periods of my ministry been nearly on the point of coming to the conclusion that the doctrine is not true. But I could never find myself able to give a satisfactory reason for the rejection of the doctrine. Apparent facts that have come under my observation have sometimes led me seriously to doubt the soundness of the doctrine ; but I cannot see, and the more I examine the more unable I find myself to see, how a denial of it can be reconciled with the scriptures. I shall give the substance of what I regard as the scripture proof of this doctrine, and beg the reader to make up his opinion for himself by a careful examination. Perhaps what has been satisfactory to my mind may not be so to the minds of others. Let no one believe this, or any other doctrine upon my authority, but " prove all things and hold fast that which is good." 2. I observe, that its truth cannot be inferred from the nature of re- generation. It is true, as was said, and as will be farther shown, that perseverance is an attribute or characteristic of Christian character ; but this does not necessarily result from the nature of regeneration, but from the indwelling Spirit of Christ. It has been common for that class of writers and theologians, who hold what is called the Taste Scheme of PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. 653 regeneration, to infer the truth of this doctrine from the nature of the change that constitutes the new birth. In this they have been entirely consistent. If, as they suppose, regeneration consists in a change in the constitution of the mind, in the implanting or infusion of a new consti- tutional taste, relish, or appetite ; if it consists in or implies a change back of all voluntary action, and such a change as to secure and necessi- tate a change of voluntary action ; why, then it is consistent, to infer from such a change the perseverance of the saints, unless it can be made to appear that either God, or Satan, or voluntary sin, can change the- nature back again. If, in regeneration, the nature is really changed, if there be some new appetite or taste implanted, some holy principle im- planted or infused into the constitution, why, then it must follow, that they will persevere by a physical law of the new nature or constitution. I see not how, in this case, they could even be the subjects of temporary backsliding, unless the new appetite should temporarily fail, as does sometimes our appetite for food. But if this may be, yet if regeneration consists in or implies a new creation of something that is not voluntary, a creation of a new nature, instead of a new character, I admit, that perseverance might be reasonably inferred from the fact of such a change. But since I reject wholly this theory of regeneration, and maintain that it is wholly a voluntary change, I cannot consistently infer the final salvation of the saints from the nature of the change that occurs in regeneration. I have been struck with the inconsistency of those who hold the Taste Scheme of regeneration, and yet contend, not only for falling from a regenerate state, but also that the regenerate may and do fall into a state of entire depravity, every time they sin ; that they fall from this state of physical or constitutional regeneration every time they commit sin, and must be regenerated or converted anew, or be lost. Now this is not reconcilable with the idea of the physical regeneration. 3. Nor can we infer the perseverance of the saints, with any justice, from their being, at their conversion, brought into a state of justifi- cation. By perseverance some seem to mean, not that the saints do persevere or continue in obedience, but that they will be saved at any rate, whether they persevere in obedience or not. It was against this idea that such ' men as the Wesleys, and Fletcher, and their coadjutors fought so val- iantly. They resisted justly and successfully the doctrine of perpetual justification, upon condition of one act of faith, and maintained that the saints as well as sinners are condemned whenever they sin. They also contended that there is no kind of certainty that all true saints will be saved. Since I have endeavored to refute the doctrine of a perpetual justification, conditioned upon the first act of faith, I cannot of course infer the final salvation of the saints from the nature of justification, 564 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Those who hold, that the first act of faith introduces the soul into a new relation of such a nature that, from thenceforth, it is not con- demned by the law, do what it will, may justly infer from the nature of such a Justification, that all who ever exercise faith will escape the pen- alty of the Divine law. But we have seen, that this is not the nature of gospel justification, and therefore we must not infer that all saints will be saved, from the mere fact that they have once believed and been justified. LECTURE XLVIII PERSEVEKANCE OF THE SAINTS PROVED. The following considerations, taken together, seem to me to estab- lish the truth of the doctrine in question beyond reasonable doubt. 1. God has from eternity resolved upon the salvation of all the elect. This we have seen. No one of this number will ever be lost. These are given to Christ from eternity, as a seed to serve him. The con- version, perseverance, and final salvation of the elect, we have seen to be secured. Their conversion, perseverance, and salvation, are secured by means of the grace of God in Christ Jesus, prevailing through the gospel, so to influence their free-will as to bring about this result. The instruc- tions, promises, threatenings, warnings, expostulations of the Bible, with all the influences with which they are surrounded, are the instrumentali- ties by means of which the Holy Spirit converts, sanctifies, and saves them. At every step, as Fletcher acknowledges, "grace is beforehand - with free will." God first comes to, and moves upon, the sinner; but the sinner does not come to and move, or attempt to move, God. God first draws, and the sinner yields. God calls and the sinner answers. The sinner would never approach God, did not God draw him. Again : God calls effectually, but not irresistibly, before the sinner yields. He does not yield and answer to a slight call. Some indeed wait to be drawn harder, and to be called louder and longer than others ; but no one, in fact, comes to God until effectually persuaded to do so ; that is, until he is effectually hunted from his refuges of lies, and drawn with so great and powerful a drawing, as not to force, but to overcome, his reluctance or voluntary selfishness, and as to induce him to turn to God and to believe in Christ. That the sinner is wholly disinclined to obey, up to the very moment in which he is persuaded and induced to yield, there can be no doubt. His turning, as we have seen, is an act of his own, but he is induced to turn by the drawings of the Holy Spirit, PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. 555 Every person who was ever truly converted knows, that his conver- sion is not to be ascribed to himself, in any other sense, than that ho finally consented, being drawn and peTsuaded by the Holy Spirit. The glory belongs to God, for the sinner only yielded after, perhaps, pro- tracted resistance, and never until after he was so convinced as to have no further excuse or apology for sin, nor until the Spirit,vby means of truth, and argument, and persuasion, fairly overcame him, and con- strained, not forced him to submit. This is a brief statement of the facts connected with the conversion of every soul that was ever converted to God. This is true of the conversion of all the elect of God ; and if others besides the elect are ever converted, this is a true; account of their con- version. Again : the same is true of their perseverance in holiness, in every instance, in every act. The saints persevere, not by virtue of a constitu- tional change, but as a result of the abiding and indwelling influence of the Holy Spirit. " Free grace is always beforehand with free-will ;" that is, the will never obeys, in any instance, nor for one moment, except as it is persuaded to do so as really as at the first. The work begun by the Holy Spirit is not carried on, except as the same Spirit continues to work in the saints to will and to do of his good pleasure. Saints do not begin in the Spirit, and then become perfect through or by the flesh. There is no holy exercise that is not as really to be ascribed to the grace and to the influence of the Holy Spirit, as is conversion itself. The saints convert not themselves, in the sense that they turn or yield, until persuaded by the Holy Spirit. God converts them in the sense, that he effectually draws or persuades them. They turn themselves, in the sense that their turning is their own act. God turns them, in the sense that he induces or produces their turning. The same is true of their whole course of obedience in this life. The saints keep themselves, in the sense, that all obedience is their own ; all their piety consists in their own voluntary obedience ; but God keeps them, in the sense, that in every instance, and at every moment of obedience, he persuades, and enlightens, and draws them, insomuch, that he secures their voluntary obedience ; that is, he draws and they. follow. He persuades, and they yield to his persuasions. He works in them to will and to do, and they will and do. God always anticipates all their holy exercises, and per- suades the saints to put them forth. This is so abundantly taught in the Bible, that to quote scripture to prove it were but to waste your time. The saints are not only said to be converted, but also sanctified, and kept by the power of God. No saint then keeps himself, except in so far as he is kept by the grace, and Spirit, and power of God. There is therefore no hope for any gf^int, and no reason to palcul^te upon the s^lvatioij of any one, unlpsg o56 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. God prevails to keep him from falling away and perishing. All who evei are saved, or ever will be, are saved by and through free grace, prevailing over free will, that is, by free grace securing the voluntary concurrence of free will. This God does, and is sure to do, with all the elect. It was upon condition of the foreseen fact, that God could by the wisest admin- istration of his government, secure this result, they were elected to eter- nal salvation, through sanctification of the Spirit, and belief of the truth. Now observe how the elect are saved. All the threatenings, warnings, and teachings of the Bible are addressed to them, as to all others. If there are any saints, at any time, who are not of the elect, the Bible no- where notices any such persons, or speaks of them, as any less or more secure than the elect. Again : the Bible nowhere represents or implies, that any but the elect are converted. It does not represent any but the elect as at any time coming in heart to Christ — as at any time regenerated or born of God. The Bible nowhere acknowledges two classes of saints, elect and non- elect. But, if there were two such classes, and the salvation of the elect was certain, as it really is, and that of the non-elect not certain, it is in- credible that the Bible should not reveal this fact. Again : so far is the Bible from recognizing or implying any such distinction, that it every- where implies the contrary. It divides mankind into two, and but two classes, and these it sets one over against the other. These are con- trasted by the names, saint and sinner ; people of God, and people of this world ; children of God, and children of this world, or children of the devil ; the elect and the reprobate, that is, the chosen and the rejected ; the sanctified and the unsanctifled ; the regenerated and the unregener- ated ; the penitent and the impenitent. By whatever names they are called, it is manifest that the same classes and none others are meant. The elect of God is a common name for the saints or people of God. I cannot find in the Bible any evidence, that any were converted at any time, but the elect, or those whose salvation is sure. The elect are, or will be, every one of them certainly converted and saved. If any one chooses to contend that any other are ever converted, the burden of proof is upon him ; let him prove it, if he can. But this he must prove, in order to establish the fact, that any truly regenerated persons are ever lost, for sure it is, that no one of the elect will ever be lost. But, since I am to take the affirmative, I must take the burden of showing, that none but the elect are recognized in the scriptures as saints ; and as I am speaking only of the salvation of the saints, I shall take it for granted, that all those who were from eternity chosen to eternal salvation, through sanctification of the Spirit and belief of the truth, will certainly be saved. Now, if it can be shown, that some saints have been really lost, it will pbesevebance OS* Saints. 657 follow, that some have been converted who were not of the elect. And, on the other hand, .if it can be shown that no saint has been, or will be, finally lost ; but, on the contrary, that all the true saints are, and will be, saved, it will follow that none but the elect are converted. For all who are, or will be, saved, are saved by God, and saved by design, and in accordance with an eternal design, and of course they were elected to sal- vation from eternity. 1 have already said, that it is incredible that the Bible should read as it does, and that it should nowhere distinguish between elect and non- elect saints, if there is any such distinction. It cannot be said with jus- tice, that the Bible purposely conceals from all saints the fact of their election, lest it should be a stumbling-block to them. This we have seen is not the fact, but on the contrary, that the elect, at least in some in- stances, have known that they were elect. But it is said, that Peter exhorts the saints to " give all diligence to make their calhng and election sure ;" from which it is inferred, that they did not know that they were elect ; and furthermore, that it might be that, although they were real saints, nevertheless they were not, at least all of them, of the elect. The words here referred to stand in the following connection : — 2 Pet. i. 1 : " Simon Peter, a servant and an apostle of Jesus Christ, to them that have obtained like precious faith with us, through the righteousness of God and our Saviour Jesus Christ : 2. Grace and peace be multiplied unto you through the knowledge of God, and of Jesus our Lord ; 3. According as his divine power has given unto us all things that pertain unto life and godliness, through the knowledge of him that hath called us to glory and virtue : 4. Whereby are given unto us exceeding great and precious promises ; that by these ye might be partakers of the divine nature, having escaped the corruption that is in the world through lust. 5. And beside this, giving all diligence, add to your faith, virtue ; and to virtue, knowledge ; 6. And to knowledge, temperance ; and to temperance, patience ; and to patience, godliness ; 7. And to godliness, brotherly kindness ; and to brotherly kindness, charity. 8. For if these things be in you and abound, they make you that ye shall neither be bar- ren nor unfruitful in the knowledge of our Lord Jesus Christ. 9, But he that lacketh these things is blind, and cannot see afar off, and hath forgotten that he was purged from his old sins. 10, Wherefore the rather, brethren, give diligence to make your calling and election sure : for if ye do these things, ye shall never fall." Upon this passage, I re- mark, — That Peter addressed this epistle to all who had faith, that is, to all true Christians, as appears from the first verse. He addressed no one by name, but left it for every one to be sure that he had faith. He then 5S8 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. proceeds to exhort them to grow in grace, assuring them that, if any one did not do so, he had forgotten that he was purged from his former sins ; that is, if any one lacked that which he enjoined, it would prove that he had not true faith, or that he had backslidden. Then he adds, as in the 10th verse : " Wherefore the rather, brethren, give diligence to make your calling and election sure : for if ye do these things, ye shall never fall." The apostle plainly assumes : — (1.) That the called and elected will be saved ; to make their calling and election sure, was to make their salvation sure : and, (2.) That none others are saved but the called and elected, for if others are saved, it were of no consequence whether they were of the called and elected or not, provided they were saved ; (3. ) That he regarded none as Christians, or as at any time having true faith, but the called and elected ; for he was not exhorting supposed impenitent sinners to become Christians, but supposed Christians to be sure of their calling and election. This shows that he regarded all Christians as of the called and elected. To be sure of their calling and election was to be sure of their salvation. The apostle did not certainly mean to exhort them to become of the number of the elect, for this num- ber we have, seen was settled from eternity ; but by diligence and growth in grace to secure their salvation, or thus to prove or demonstrate their calling and election. He meant also to admonish them that, although called and elected, still their ultimate salvation was conditionated upon their diligent growth in grace, and perseverance in holiness to the end of life. He therefore exhorts them to make their calling and election sure, which is the same as to secure their salvation. He speaks of calling and election as indissolubly connected. Effectual calling either results from election, or election from calling. We have seen that election is eternal ; therefore election cannot result from calling, but calling must result from election. Again : Christians and saints, and the children and people of God, the disciples of Christ, and the elect, are to all appearance regarded throughout the Bible as the same class. Again : Christ says, John vi. 37 : " All that the Father giveth me shall come to me ; and him that cometh to me I will in no wise cast out. 39. And this is the Father's will which hath sent me, that of all which he hath given me I should lose nothing, but should raise it up again at the last day." Here Jesus says, that all who are given to him by the Father shall come to him, and that of those that come to him, it is his Father's will that he should lose none, but that he should raise them up, (that is, to eternal life,) at the last day. He does not say here, that none do come to him who are not given to him by the Father, but this is plainly PERSEVERANCE OP SAINTS. 559 implied, for he says, 37th. " All that the Father giveth me shall come to me ; and him that cometh to me I will in no wise cast out." What he means by not casting them out, is plain from verse 39. That is, " It is the Father's will that of all that shall come to me I should lose nothing." By not casting them out, then, he intended that he should surely save them, that is, all that came to him. But if he saves them, they must have been given to Christ and have been elected, or they were not. If they were not elected, or given to Christ by the Father, they will never be saved, unless some are saved without God's designing or choosing to save them. If any are saved, God saves them, through or by Chiist. If he saves them, he does it designedly, and not without design. But if he ever does, or will design it, he has from eternity designed it. So then, it appears, that all who come to Christ were given to him of the Father ; and that he will lose none of them, but will raise them up at the last day. My object at present, however, is not to insist that no one that comes to Christ will be lost, but only that all who come to Christ are of the number that were given to him of the Father, or are of the elect. Again : compare verses 37, 39, ii, 45. He says : John vi. 37 : "All that the Father giveth me shall come to me, and him that cometh to me I will in no wise cast out. 39. And this is the Father's will which hath sent me, that of all which he hath given me I should lose nothing, but should raise it up again at the last day. 44. No man can come to me except the Father which hath sent me, draw him, and I will raise him up at the last day. 45. It is written in the Prophets, And they shall be all taught of God. Every man therefore that hath heard, and hath learned of the Father, cometh unto me." Here it appears that no one can come to Christ except he be drawn of the Father. Every one who is drawn by the Father with an efEectual drawing, or every one who hears and learns of the Father comes to Christ, and no other. The Father draws none to Christ, but those whom he has given to Christ ; for these, and these only, are the children of God. Isa. liv. 13 : " And all thy children shall be taught of the Lord ; and great shall be the peace of thy children." From these passages it appears that none come to Christ but those who are drawn by the Father, and that none are drawn by the Father but those whom he has given to his Son, or the elect ; and that of those who are thus drawn to Christ, it is the Father's will that he should lose none, but that he should raise them up at the last day ; that is, that he should save them. But observe, it is my particular object just now to establish the fact, that none come to Christ but those who are of the number that are given to Christ, and also that every one who is given to him shall come to him. These, and these only are efiectually called or drawn of the Father. All are called in the sense of being earnestly and honestly invited, and all the divine 660 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. persuasion is addressed to them that can wisely be addressed to them. But others, besides those given to the Son, are not, as a matter of fact, persuaded and effectually drawn, in a sense that secures the "concur- rence of free will with free grace." The same truth is strongly implied in many other passages in the teachings of Christ; For example, he says, — John X. 1 : "Verily, verily, I say unto you, he that entereth not by the door into the sheep-fold, but climbeth up some other way, the same is a thief and a robber. 3. But he that entereth in by the door is the shepherd of the sheep. 3. To him the porter openeth : and the sheep hear his voice ; and he calleth his own sheep by name, and leadeth them out. 4. And when he putteth forth his own sheep, he goeth before them, and the sheep follow him : for they know his voice. 5. And a stranger will they not follow, but will flee from him : for they know not the voice of strangers. 6. This parable spake Jesus unto them : but they understood not what things they were which he spake unto them." He then proceeds to expound the parable. He is the good shepherd having the care of his Father's sheep. He says : — 7. " Then said Jesus unto them again. Verily, verily, I say unto you, I am the door of the sheep. 8. All that ever came before me are thieves and robbers : but the sheep did not hear them. 9. I am the door ; by me if any man enter in, he shall be saved, and go in and out, and find pasture. 10. The thief cometh not, but for to steal, and to kill, and to destroy : I am come that they might have life, and that they might have it more abundantly. 11. I am the good shepherd : the good shepherd giveth his life for the sheep. 13. But he that is a hireling, and not the shepherd, whose own the sheep are not, seeth the wolf coming, and leaveth the sheep, and fleeth, and the wolf catcheth them, and scatter- eth the sheep. 13. The hireling fleeth, because he is a hireling, and careth not for the sheep. 14. I am the good shepherd, and know my sheep, and am known of mine. 15. As the Father knoweth me, even so know I the Father : and I lay down my life for the sheep. 16. And other sheep I have, which are not of this fold : them also I must bring, and they shall hear my voice ; and there shall be one fold, and one shepherd. 1. Therefore doth my Father love me, because I lay down my life, that I might take it again." He had other sheep which were not yet called — they were not of this fold — that is, they were not Jews, but Gentiles ; these he must bring. To the unbelieving and cavilling Jews he said : — John X. 36 : " But ye believe not, because ye are not of my sheep, as I said unto you. 37. My sheep hear my voice, and I know them, and they follow me. 28. And I give unto them eternal life ; and they shall never perish, neither shall any pluck them out of my hand. 29. Mj PEBSEVEEANCE OP SAINTS. 561 Father which gave them me, is greater than all ; and none is able to pluck them out of my Father's hand." Here it is plainly implied, that all those were sheep who were given to him by the Father, and that all such would surely hear and know his voice and follow him, but those that were not of his sheep, or were not given him by the Father, would not believe. He says, verse 26 : But ye beheve not, because ye are not of my sheep, as I said unto you. What he here says amounts to this : all those are sheep. who are given to me of my Father. All my sheep thus given, shall and will hear my voice, and fol- low me, and none others will. I do not notice in this place what he says of the certainty of their salvation, because my present object is only to show that those and those only come to Christ who are given to him of the Father, or are of the elect. This same truth is either expressly taught, or strongly im'plied in a great many passages, and indeed it seems to me to be the doctrine of the whole Bible. Eom. viii. 28 : " And we know that all things work to- gether for good to them that love God, to them who are the called ac-^ cording to his purpose." Here they that love God are represented as identical with those "who are the called according to his purpose." In other words, they who love God are the called according to, or in conse- quence of their election. All that love God do so because they have been effectually called, according to the purpose or election of God. This passage seems to settle the question, especially when viewed in its con- nection, that all who ever love God are of the elect, and that they are prevailed upon to love God in conformity with their election. "We shall have occasion, by and by, to examine the connection in which this passage is found, for the purpose of showing that all who at any time truly come to love God, will be saved. I have only quoted this twenty-eighth verse here for the purpose of showing, not directly, that all that love God at any time will be saved, but that they are of the num- ber of the elect, from which fact their ultimate salvation must be inferred. It is plain that the apostles regarded regeneration as conclusive evi- dence of election. The manner in which they address Christians seems to me to put this beyond a doubt. Paul, in writing to the Thessalonians, 2 Thes. ii. 13, says, " But we are bound to give thanks alway to God for you, brethren beloved of the Lord, because God hath from the be- ginning chosen you to salvation through sanctification of the Spirit, and belief of the truth:" Here the apostle speaks of all the brethren at Thes- salonica as beloved of the Lord, and as being from eternity chosen to sal- vation. He felt called upon to give thanks to God for this reason, that God had chosen them to salvation from eternity. This he represents as true of the whole church : that is, doubtless, of all true Christians in the church. Indeed, the apostles ever3nvhere speak as if they regarded all 36 562 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. true saints as of the elect, and their saintship as evidence of their elec- tion. Peter, in writing to the Christians in his first letter, says : 1 Pet. i. 1 : " Peter, an apostle of Jesus Christ, to the strangers scat- tered throughout Pontus, Galatia, Cappadocia, Asia, and Bithynia^ 2. Elect according to the foreknowledge of God the Father, through sanc- tification of the Spirit unto obedience and sprinkling of the blood of Jesus Christ : Grace unto you, and peace, he multiplied. 3. Blessed be the God and Father of our Lord Jesus Christ, which, according to his abundant mercy, hath begotten us again unto a lively hope by the resur- rection of Jesus Christ from the dead. 4. To an inheritance incorrupti- ble, and nndeflled, and that fadeth not away, reserved in heaven for you, 5. Who are kept by tlje power of God through faith unto salvation, ready to he revealed in the last time : 6. Wherein ye greatly rejoice, though now for a season, if need be, ye are in heaviness through manifold temp- tations ; 7. That the trial of your faith, being much more precious than that of gold that perisheth, though it be tried with fire, might be found unto praise, and honor, and glory, at the appearing of Jesus Christ : 8. Whom having not seen ye love ; in whom, though now ye see him not, yet believing, ye rejoice with joy unspeakable, and full of glory : 9. Ke- eeiving the end of your faith, even the salvation of your souls." Here it is plain that Peter regarded all who had been born again to a lively hope, or who were regenerated, as elected, or as chosen to salvation. I might pursue this argument to an indefinite length, but I must attend to other considerations in support of the doctrine in question. I will for the present close what I have to say under this particular branch of the argument, by reminding you that Christ has expressly as- serted that no man can or does come to him except the Father draw him, and that the Father draws to him those — and by fair inference those only — whom he has given to Christ ; and further, that it is the Father's will, that of those whom the Father had given to Christ, and drawn to him, Christ should lose none, but should raise them up at the last day. It is, I think, evident, that when Christ asserts it to be his Father's will, that of those whom the Father had given him he should lose none, but should raise them up at the last day, he intended to say, that his Father not merely desired and willed this, but that such was his design. That the Father designed to secure their salvation. This we shall more fully see in its proper place. PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. 563 LECTURE XLIX. PERSEVERANCE PROVED. t. I EBMABK, that God is able to preserve and keep the true saints from apostacy, in consistency with their liberty : 2 Tim. i. 13 : " For the which cause I also suffer these things ; nevertheless, I am not ashamed ; for I know whom I have believed, and am persuaded that he is able to keep that which I have committed unto him against that day." Here the apostle expresses the fullest confidence in the ability of Christ to keep him : and indeed, as has been said, it is most manifest that the apostles expected to persevere and be saved only because they believed in the ability and willingness of God to keep them from falling. Again : Eom. xiv. 4 : " Who art thou that judgest another man's servant ; to his own master he standeth or falleth ; yea, he shall be holden up, for God is able to make him stand." Again, Phil. iii. 31 : " Who shall change our vile body, that it may be fashioned like unto his glorious body, according to the working whereby he is able even to subdue all things unto himself." Again, Eph. iii. 30 : " Now unto him that is able to do exceeding abundantly above all that we ask or think, according to the power that worketh in us." Again, Jude 34 : " Now unto him that is able to keep you from falling, and to present you faultless before the presence of his glory with exceeding joy." Again, 3 Cor. ix. 8 : "And God is able to make all grace abound towards you ; that ye, always having all sufficiency in all things, may abound to every good work." Eph. i. 18 : The eyes of your understandftig being enlightened ; that ye may know what is the hope of his calling, and what the riches of the glory of his inheritance in the saints. 19. And what is the exceeding greatness of his power to usward who believe, according to the working of his mighty power, 30. Which he wrought in Christ, when he raised him from the dead, and set him at his own right hand in the heavenly places." Again, Heb. vii. 35 : " Wherefore he is able to save them to the uttermost that come unto God by him, seeing he ever liveth to make intercession for them." These and many other passages prove beyond a doubt that God is able to preserve his saints. 3. God is not only able to keep all that come to Christ, or all true Christians, but he is also willing. But Christ has settled this question, as we have seen. John vi. 37 : " All that the Father giveth me shall come to me, and him that cometh to me I will in no wise cast out. 38. For I came down from heaven, not to do my own will, but the will of him that sent me ; 564 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. 39. And this is the Father's will which hath sent me, that of all which he hath given me I should lose nothing, but should raise it up again at the last day. 40. And this is the will of him that sent me, that every one which seeth the Son, and believeth on him, may have everlasting life ; and I will raise him up at the last day." Here, then, we have just seen these two points settled, namely, that God is able to save all saints, or all who at any time truly believe and come to Christ ; and, that he is willing, or wills to do it. Now if he is both able and willing to keep and save all the saints, he certainly will do it. But here I know it will be objected, that by this course of argument, the doctrine of universal salvation may be established. The Bible, it is said, represents God as both able and willing to save all men, and if his being both able and willing to save the saints, proves that they will all be saved, it follows that his being able and willing to save all men proves that all men will be saved. But the cases are not parallel ; for God no- where professes ability to save all men, but on the contrary, disclaims such ability, and professes to be unable to save all men ; that is, he can- not, under the circumstances, wisely save them, nor can he wisely do any more for saints or sinners than he does. No passage can be found in the Bible, in which God asserts his ability to save all men. The pas- sages that affirm that "God can do all things," and that "nothing is too hard for the Lord," and the like, cannot be understood as affirming God's ability to save all men. They do imply, that he has power to do whatever is an object of physical omnipotence ; but to save sinners is not an object of physical power. Their salvation, if accomplished at all, must be brought about by a moral and persuasive influence, and not by the exercise of physical* omnipotence. In the sense in which we can justly apply the terms ability and inability to this subject, God is really unable to do what it is unwise for him to do. He has an end in view. This end is the highest good and blessedness of universal being. This end can be accomplished only by the appropriate means, or upon certain conditions. These conditions include the perfect holiness of moral agents. If God cannot wisely use such means as will secure the conversion and sanctification of sinners, he cannot save them. That is, he is unable to save them. This he repeatedly professes to be unable to do. Ezek. xviii. 23 : " Have I any pleasure at all that the wicked should die, saith the Lord God ; and not that he should return from his ways, and live ? 33. For I have no pleasure in the death of him that dieth, saith the Lord God ; wherefore turn yourselves, and live ye." Ezek. xxxiii. 11, " Say unto them, As I live, saith the Lord God, I have no pleasure in the death of the wicked ; but that the wicked turn PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. 565 from his way and live : turn ye, turn ye, from your evil ways ; for why will ye die, house of Israel ? " Isa. v. 4 : " What could have been done more to my vineyard that I have not done ip it ? Wherefore, when I looked that it should bring forth grapes, brought it forth wild grapes ? " Hos. xi. 8 : " How shall I give thee up, Ephraim ? How shall I deliver thee, Israel ? How shall I make thee as Admah ? How shall I set thee as Zeboini ? My heart is turned within me, my repen tings are kindled together." These are only specimens of the manner in which God speaks of his ability to save sinners, and to do more for the church or the world than he does. From such professions on the part of God, we are to under- stand him, as disclaiming ability to do more or otherwise than he does, in consistency with the highest good of being in general, ^ince the highest good of being in general is the end which he is aiming to secure, he " may justly be said to be unable to do whatever he cannot do in con- sistency with the use of those means that will secure this end." God, therefore, does not afi&rm his ability to save all men, but fully disclaims any such ability, and professes to do, and to be doing, all that he can to save them. He professes to be perfectly benevolent and infinitely wise, and to be doing all that infinite wisdom and benevolence can do for sin- ners and for all men, and complains, that all he can do does not save, and will not save many of them. But with respect to the saints, he does expressly aflBrm his ability to keep them, in a sense that will secure their salvation. This we have seen. He does for them all that he wisely can, and does enough, as he expressly aflQrms, to secure their salvation. No one can attentively read and consider the passages relating to God's ability to save all men, and his ability to save his people, without perceiving, that the two cases are not parallel, but that in fact they are contrasts. He expressly affirms his ability to keep, to sanctify, and to save his elect children, whilst he repeatedly, either expressly, or by implication, disclaims ability to save all men. Again : the Bible nowhere represents God as willing the salvation of all men, in the same sense in which it represents him as willing the sal- vation of Christians, or of his elect. Such passages as the following are specimens of God's professions of willingness to save all men. 1 Tim. ii. 4 : " Who will have all men to be saved, and to come unto the knowledge of the truth." John iii. 16. " For God so loved the world, that he gave his only-be- gotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him should not perish, but have everlasting life. 17. For God sent not his Son into the world to con- demn the world ; but that the world through him might be saved." 566 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. 3 Peter iii. 9 : "The Lord is not slack concerning his promise, as some men count slackness ; but is long-sufEering to usward, not willing that any should perish, but that all should come to repentance." These and similar passages teach that God wills the salvation of all men, only in the sense of desiring it. This we know from the fact, that he nowhere intimates a willingness, in the sense of a design or intention, to save all men ; but on the contrary, plainly reveals an opposite purpose or design ; that is, he reveals the fact, that he cannot, shall not, and of course, does not, expect or design to save all men. By the profession of a willingness to save all men, we can therefore justly understand him to mean, only that he desires the salvation of all men, and that he would secure their salvation if he wisely could. This is all that we can under- stand him as afBrming, unless we would accuse him of self-contradic tion. But he professes a willingness to save his elect, or in other words, all regenerate persons, or all believers in Christ, and all whoever will trulj believe in him, in the sense of purposing or designing to save them. This is most manifest from the scriptures we have already examined, and this will still further appear from the passages to be examined. "We have seen that the Father has given a certain number to Christ, with express design to secure their salvation ; that he has committed to him all the requisite power and influences to save them, and that they will actually be saved. Nothing like this can be found in the Bible, respect- ing any other class of men whatever. This objection, then, is without foundation, and the argument from the ability and willingness of God to save his saints, remains in full force and conclusiveness. 4. Again : Christ expressly prayed for all believers, and in a manner that secures their being kept and saved : — , John xvii. 2 : "As thou hast given him power over all flesh, that he should give eternal life to as many as thou hast given him. 6. I have manifested thy name unto the men which thou gavest me out of the world ; thine they were, and thou gavest them me ; and they have kept thy word. 7. Now they have known that all things whatsoever thou hast given me are of thee ; 8. For I have given unto them the words which thou gavest me ; and they have received them, and have known surely that I came out from thee, and they have believed that thou didst send me. 9. I pray for them ; I pray not for the world, but for them which thou hast given me, for they are thine. 10. And all mine are thine, and thine are mine ; and I am glorified in them. 11. And now I am no more in the world, but these are in the world, and I come to thee. Holy Father, keep through thine own name those whom thou hast given me, that they may be one, as we are. 12. While I was with them in the world, I kept them in thy name : those that thou gavest me I have PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. 567 kept, and none of them is lost, but the son of perdition, that the scrip- ture might be fulfilled. 13. And now come I to thee ; and these things I speak in the world, that they might have my joy fulfilled in them- selves, 14. I have given them thy word ; and the world hath hated them, because they are not of the world, even as I am not of the world. 30. Neither pray I for these alone, but for them also which shall believe on me through their word. 21. That they all may be one ; as thou. Father, art in me, and I in thee, that they also may be one in us ; that the world may believe that thou hast sent me. 22. And the glory which thou gavest me, I have given them ; that they may be one, even as we are one. 23. I in them, and thou in me, that they may be made perfect in one, and that the world may know that thou hast sent me, and hast loved them as thou hast loved me. 24. Father, I will that they also whom thou hast given me, be with me where I am ; that they may behold my glory, which thou hast given me ; for thou lovedst me before the founda- tion of the world." Now observe, that in this most afEecting prayer Christ says, — (1.) Verse 2. " As thou hast given him power over all flesh, that he should give eternal life to as many as thou hast given him." We have seen, that, in the 6th chapter of this book Christ expressly teaches, that all are given to him that come to him by the Father. (2.) He proceeds to aflBrm, that he had in the exercise of this power kept in his Father's name all who had been given, and had come to him, and had lost none. (3.) He asks the Father henceforth to keep them in his own name, as he was about to leave them, as to his bodily presence. He says, verse 15, " I pray not that thou shouldest take them out of the world, but that thou shouldest keep them from the evil." Again, he says, 20-24 : " Neither pray I for these alone, but for them also which shall believe on me through their word. That they all may be one ; as thou. Father, art in me, and I in thee, that they also may be one in us ; that the world may believe that thou hast sent me. And the glory which thou gavest me I have given them ; that they may be one, even as we are one. I in them, and thou in me, that they may be made perfect in one ; and that the world may know that thou hast sent me, and hast loved them as thou hast loved me. Father, I will that they also whom thou hast given me be with me where I am ; that they may behold my glory, which thou hast given me ; for thou lovedst me before the foundation of the world." Now, as surely as Christ's prayer is answered, all believers will be saved ; that is, at least all who ever have believed, or ever will believe, subsequent to the offering of this prayer. But Christ's prayers are always answered. 568 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. To this it is objected, that a part of this same prayer is not answered, and of course never will be. It is said, for example, that in the 21st verse he prays for the union of all believers, which has been far enough from having been answered. The verse reads, " That they all may be one ; as thou. Father, art in me, and I in thee, that they also may be one in us ; that the world may believe that thou hast sent me." Here he explains the sense ia which he prays that all believers may be one, not that they should be all of one denomination or creed, but that they should possess one and the same spirit ; that the same spirit that united the Father and the Son, that is, the Holy Spirit, who is in the Father and the Son, might also be in all Christians. This is plainly his meaning ; and that this is true of all real Christians, that they possess the Holy Spirit, or the Spirit that dwells in the Father and the Son, no one can doubt who understands and believes his Bible. But it is objected again, that Christ prayed to be delivered from crucifixion, and his prayer was not answered. I reply, that he did not pray for this, if at all, unqualifiedly. He says, if it be possible, nevertheless, not as I will, but as thou wilt." If it were the pains of the cross from which his soul shrunk in the garden, and from which he desired, if possible, to be excused, it is plain that he did not pray unqualifiedly to be delivered ; but, on the contrary, sub- mitted the question to the will of his Father. But in the prayer, in John 17, he made no such condition. He knew that in this case it was his Father's will to grant his request. Of this he had expressly informed his disciples, as we have seen ; that is, that it was his Father's will to keep and save all who were given to Christ, and had been drawn by the Father to Christ. The Spirit of this petition accords precisely with his teaching upon the subject. He had taught before that all believers would be kept and saved, and that this was his Father's will ; now, could he, either expressly or impliedly, in this prayer, put in the condi- tion that was in the prayer just referred to, namely, "If it be thy will ?" But, although what has been said is a full answer to the assertion that Christ's prayers were not always answered, it may be, for some minds, important to say, that it is far from being certain that Christ prayed to be delivered from crucifixion. But be this as it may, we are to remember that Christ expressly affirms, that his Father always hears, that is, answers his prayers. John. xi. 43 : " And I knew that thou hearest me always : but because of the people which stand by I said it, that they may believe that thou hast sent me." Again, Paul says of Christ, Heb. vii. 25 : " Wherefore he is able also to save them to the uttermost that come unto God by him, seeing he ever liveth to make intercession for them." PERSEVERANCE OP SAINTS. 569 Here he asserts, that Christ is able to save unto the uttermost all that come unto God by him, seeing he always lives to make intercession for them. This, as plainly as possible, implies that his intercessions are all- prevailing. Indeed, as he is the mediator, they must be. Now let us consider how far we have advanced in establishing the perseverance and final salvation of all believers. (1.) We have seen, that all the elect to salvation will be saved. (2.) That all true believers are of this number, (3.) That God and Christ are able to keep them from apostasy, and save them. (4.) That he is willing or wills to do it. (5.) That Christ expressly prayed for the perseverance and final sal- vation of all believers. (6.) That he prayed in express accordance with the revealed will of his Father ; and — (7.) That his prayers always prevail and are answered. In Christ's prayer in John, chap, xvii., he expressly afiSrms that he did not pray for the world, that is, for all men. He prayed only for those whom the Father had given him. For these he prayed, not merely that God would save them upon condition of their perseverance, but that God would keep them from the evil that is in the world, and save them, and make them one, in the sense, that one Spirit should be in them all. He asked manifestly the same things for all that in future believe, that he asked for those who had already believed. Should I proceed no further the argument is complete, and the proof conclusive. But since this doctrine is so abundantly taught, either ex- pressly or impliedly, in the Bible, I proceed to the consideration of a num- ber of other passages which will throw still further light on the subject. 5. Christ expressly and designedly teaches this doctrine. John vi. 39 : " And this is the Father's will which hath sent me, that of all which he hath given me, I should lose nothing, but should raise it up again at the last day. 40. And this is the will of him that sent me, that every one which seeth the Son, and believeth on him, may have everlasting life : and I will raise him up at the last day. 47. Verily, verily, I say unto you. He that believeth on me hath everlasting life. 51. I am the living bread which came down from heaven. If any man eat of this bread, he shall live forever : and the bread that I will give is my flesh, which I will give for the life of the world." Here he expressly teaches, as we have before seen, that it is hia Father's will, that all believers, or all who at any time believe, (for this is plainly his meaning,) shall be saved ; that he should lose none of them, but as we have seen, John xvii. 2, should give them eternal life, ^ben hP claims ability to ieep and save them agreeably to his Faft^r'^ 670 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. will. This, remember, respects all belieyers, or all who are given to Christ, who, we have learned, are the same persons. Again : John x. 27 : " My sheep hear my voice, and I know them, and they follow me : 38. And I give unto them eternal life , and they shall never perish, neither shall any pluck them out of my hand. 29. My Father which gave them me, is greater than all ; and none is able to pluck them out of my Father's hand." The whole connection shows, that Christ intended to teach the cer- tainty of the salvation of all his sheep, or of all the elect, or, which is the same, of all true believers. But, to this it is objected, that none are sheep any longer than they remain obedient, and therefore the assertion that he will save the sheep, does not secure those who at any time sin. But I reply, that Christ recognizes all the elect as his sheep, whether converted, or whether in a state of temporary backsliding, or not. He represents his sheep as hearing his voice, and as following him, and those who are not of his sheep as not hearing his voice, and as not fol- lowing him, John x. 16 : "And other sheep I have which are not of this fold : them also I must bring, and they shall hear my voice ; and there shall be one fold, and one shepherd. 26. But ye believe not, because ye are not of my sheep, as I said unto you." Again, Matt, xviii. 12 : " How think ye ? If a man have a hundred sheep, and one of them be gone astray, doth he not leave the ninety and nine, and goeth into the mountains, and seeketh that which is gone astray ? 13. And if so be that he find it, verily I say unto you, he re- joiceth more of that sheep, than of the ninety and nine which went not astray. 14. Even so it is not the will of your Father which is in heaven, that one of these little ones should perish." The design of this parable is to teach the doctrine I am defending; If not, what is its design ? This is a full answer to the objection, that no one is recognized as a sheep who has gone astray. But again, it is said, that although no one else can pluck the sheep out of the Father's hand, yet we can do it ourselves. I grant that we can by natural possibility ; but this objection is good for nothing, for Christ expressly says, John x. 27 : " My sheep hear my voice, and I know them, and they follow me : 28. And I give unto them eternal life ; and they shall never perish, neither shall any pluck them out of my hand. 29. My Father, which gave them me, is greater than all ; and none is able to pluck them out of my Father's hand." Not only is no one able to pluck them out of his Father's hand, but Christ gives unto them eternal life, and they shall never perish. This implies, that while they might or are able to apostatize and be lost, yet, as a matter of fact, they never will. What could be made out of all he says of himself as a shepherd in this passage, if, after all, PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. Ill ho loses some of his sheep ? Let any one ponder the whole chap- ter and see. 6. Another argument, in support of the doctrine under consideratiow, I deduce from the fact, that Paul, an inspired apostle, believed it. Phil. i. 1 : " Paul and Timotheus, the servants of Jesus Christ, to all the saints in Christ Jesus which are at Philippi, with the bishops and ■ deacons ; 2. Grace be unto you, and peace, from God our Father, and from the Lord Jesus Christ. 3. I thank my God upon every remem- brance of you, 4. (Always in every prayer of mine for yon all making re- quest with joy,) 5. For your fellowship in the gospel, from the first day until now. 6. Being confident of this very thing, that he which hath begun a good work in you will perform it until the day of Jesus Christ. Here the apostle represents himself as giving thanks for all the saints at Philippi, upon the ground of his confidence that he who had begun a good work in them would perform, or perfect it, until the day of Christ. His confidence did not rest in them, but in the faithfulness of Christ. He did not express a confidence, that they would of themselves persevere, but that he who had begun a good work in them, would carry it on : that is, that he would so work in them as to keep them, and as to secure their perseverance to the end. This he expected with respect to all the saints at Philippi. But if he believed this of all the saints at that place, it is plainly and fairly inferable that he believed it, simply because he expected this, as to all true saints. He does not intimate, that he ex- pected this because of any peculiarity in their case, — that is, not because they were better than other saints, or that God would do more for them than for others. He seems plainly to have expressed this confidence, ' upon the ground of his expectation, that he who begins a good work in any saint, will carry it on and perfect it until the day of Christ. Should it be said, that Paul intended merely to express the conviction or opinion of a good man, that the Philippian saints would be saved, but that he did not intend to utter this as the voice of inspiration ; I reply, that Paul plainly expresses a confidence that they would all be saved, and that God would perfect the work which he had begun. Now, how came he by this confidence ? He was an inspired man. If inspiration had taught him that real saints do fall away and are lost, how could he consistently express so thorough a persuasion, that all the saints at Philippi would be saved ? If Paul believed in the perseverance of the saints, it must be true, or he was deceived in respect to this important doctrine. But is it not safe to trust Paul's opinion of this doctrine ? If any one is disposed to contend, that we cannot with strict justice infer that Paul believed the same in respect to God's perfecting the work in all saints, that hfl beHeved in respecting the Phihppians, I will not contend with him with respect to this, Jt is, however, clear, that Paul no wh^rp in th?-3 573 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. epistle, nor elsewhere, intimates that he had higher expectations in re- gard to the salvation of the Philippians, than he had in respect to the salvation of all true saints. In writing to the churches, the apostles ap- pear to have regarded and spoken of all true saints as the elect-children of God. They seem to represent the salvation of all such persons as cer- tain, but alwg,ys keeping in mind and holding forth, either expressly or by way of implication, the nature of this certainty, that it was condi- tioned upon the right and persevering use of their own agency. They consequently constantly endeavor to guard the churches against delusion, in regard to their being real saints, and admonish them to prove them- selves in this respect, and also warn them against the supposition, that they can be saved, without actual perseverance in faith and obedience to the end of life. 7. The apostles seemed to regard the conversion of sinners as an evidence that God designed to save them, or that they were of the olect : — Acts ii. 47 : " Praising God, and having favor with all the people. A.nd the Lord added to the church daily such as should be saved." Acts xiii. 48. " And when the Gentiles heard this, they were glad and glorified the word of the Lord ; and as many as were ordained to eternal life, believed." In these passages as elsewhere, the conversion of sinners is spoken of as settling the question of their salvation. But if true saints do fall from grace and perish, why should the inspired writers so often express themselves, as if they regarded the regeneration of a person as an indi- cation that he is one of the elect, and as securing his salvation ? So common is it for Christ and the apostles to speak of regeneration as settling the question of the salvation of those who are regenerated, that great multitudes have overlooked the fact, that there was any other condition of salvation insisted on in the Bible. When the jailor de- manded of Paul and Silas what he should do to be saved, Paul replied to him, " Believe in the Lord Jesus Christ, and thou shalt be saved, and thy house." Here, as is common in the Bible, faith is spoken of as if it were the Bole condition of salvation. Eepentance, faith, regeneration, etc., are often, as every student of the Bible knows, spoken of as if they were the only conditions of salvation. Now, it seems to me, that this could not, and ought not to be, if there is not a certain connection of some sort between real conversion and eternal salvation. It is true, the necessity of perseverance to the end is often mentioned and insisted upon in the Bible as a condition of salvation, just as might be expected when we con- rider the nature of the certainty in question. If there is not, however, A ofc|-tpft ppnj^pptipn betireefl t^rije regpftefafcjpn, pr faith, or repentance PERSEVERANCE OP SAINTS. 573 and salvation, it seems to me incredible, that we should so often find faith, and repentance, and conversion spoken of as if they secured salvation. Those who believe are represented as already having eternal life, as not coming into condemnation, but as having passed from death unto life. The following passages are specimens of the manner in which the scriptures speak upon this subject. John i. 13 : " But as many as received him, to them gave he power to become the sons of God, even to them that believe on his name ; 13. Which were born, not of blood, nor of the will of the flesh, nor of the will of man, but of God." John iii. 36 : " He that believeth on the Son hath everlasting life, and he that believeth not the Son shall not see life ; but the wrath of God abideth on him. 16. For God so loved the world, that he gave his only begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him should not perish, but have everlasting life. 18. He that believeth on him is not con- demned ; but he that believeth not is condemned already, because he hath not believed in the name of the only begotten Son of God." John iv. 14 : " But whosoever drinketh of the water that I shall give him, shall never thirst : but the water .that I shall give him shall be in him a well of water springing up into everlasting life." John V. 24 : " Verily, verily, I say unto you. He that heareth my word, and believeth on him that sent me, hath everlasting life, and shall not come into condemnation ; but is passed from death unto life." John vi. 37 : " All that the Father giveth me shall come to me ; and him that cometh to me I will in no wise cast out. 40. And this is the will of him that sent me. That every one which seeth the Son, and be- lieveth on him, may have everlasting life ; and I will raise him up at the last day. 45. It is written in the prophets. And they shall be all taught of God. Every man therefore that hath heard, and hath learned of the Father, cometh unto me. 47. Verily, verily, I say unto you. He that believeth on me hath everlasting life." Acts ii. 38 : " Then Peter said unto them, Eepent, and be baptized every one of you in the name of Jesus Christ, for the remission of sins ; and ye shall receive the gift of the Holy Ghost." Mark xvi. 15 : " And he said unto them. Go ye into all the world, and preach the gospel to every creature. 16. He that believeth and is baptized shall be saved ; but he that beheveth not shall be damned." Now it seems to me, that this numerous class of passages strongly im- ply that there is a certain connection of some sort between coming to Christ, receiving Christ, etc., and eternal life. Observe, I do not con- tend that perseverance in faith and obedience is not also a condition of salvation, but on the contrary, that it actually is. Nor do I contend 674 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. that such like representations as the above, settle the question that all who at any time repent, believe, or come to Christ, will be saved. The thing which I here intend is, that this class of texts is just what we might expect, if the fact of regeneration were certainly connected with salvation, and just what it seems they ought not to be, in case this were not true. To this it is objected, that many who attended on Christ's ministry are represented from time to time as believing, of whom it is almost im- mediately said, that they turned back and walked no more with him. I answer, that the Bible manifestly recognizes different kinds of faith, such as an intellectual faith, a faith of miracles, and the faith of the heart. The following are specimens of the Bible treatment of this subject : Acts viii. 13 : " Then Simon himself believed also : and when he was baptized, he continued with Philip, and wondered, beholding the mira- cles and signs which were done. 31. Thou hast neither part nor lot in this matter : for thy heart is not right in the sight of God." James ii. 19 : " Thou believest that there is one God ; thou doest well : the devils also believe and ijremble." These and many other passages manifestly speak of an intellectual faith, or of a simple conviction of the truth. Matt. vii. 33, 33 ; 1 Cor. xiii. 1, 3, are specimens of the manner in which the faith of miracles is represented. See Eom. x. 9, 10, 11 ; Acts viii. 37 ; Gal. v. 6. These and such like passages speak of evangelical faith, or the faith of the heart. When the multitude are spoken of as believing under Christ's instruction, or in view of his miracles, and then as going back and walking no more with him, we are doubtless to understand those passages as teaching simply, that they were at the time convinced of his Messiahship, and that they intellectually believed that he was what he professed to be. But their history seems to forbid the conclusion that they were truly regenerated, or that they had the true faith of the gospel. Again : John speaks of those who openly apostatized as if they had not been true Christians : 1 John ii. 19 : " They went out from us, but they were not of us ; for if they had been of us, they would no doubt have continued with us : but they went out, that they might be made man- ifest that they were not all of us." Observe the force of the expressions, " They went out from us, but they were not of us ;" that is, were not truly Christians. Why does he say so ? He assigns the reason for this assertion : "for if they had been of us, they would have continued with us, but they went out that they might be made manifest that they were not all of us." That is, a part of the professed disciples went out from the rest and returned to the world, that it might be made PERSEVERANCE OP SAINTS. o73 manifest who were and who were not Christians. I do not say, however, that this is indubitably taught in this passage ; but it cannot be denied, that this is its most natural construction. 8. The inhabitants of heaven seem to believe that there is a certain connection between repentance and salvation. Luke XV. 7 : "I say unto you, that liliewise joy shall be in heaven over one sinner that repenteth, more than over ninety and nine just persons which need no repentance." Now surely this joy is premature, unless they expect the penitent to be saved. If, after all, there is an uncertainty about the result, in their estimation, and if it may be, or there is a probability, that the penitent will fall, and sufEer a vastly more aggravated damnation than if he had never been enlightened, one would think that they would at least suspend their triumph until the result was known. To be sure they might rejoice, if the sinner broke ofE temporarily from his sin, and rejoice at the bare prospect of his salvation ; but to me this passage reads just as it might be expected to read, if they regarded repentance as certainly connected with ultimate salvation. Again : there are several parables that seem to take the perseverance of the saints for granted, or to assume its truth. The one immediately preceding the verse upon which I have just remarked is one of them. Luke xv. 3 : " And he spake this parable unto them saying : 4. What man of you, having a hundred sheep, if he lose one of them, doth not leave the ninety and nine in the wilderness, and go after that which is lost, until he find it ? 5. And when he hath found it, he layeth it on his shoulders, rejoicing. 6. And when he cometh home, he calleth together his friends and neighbors, saying unto them, Kejoice with me ; for I have found my sheep which was lost. 7. I say unto you, that likewise joy shall be in heaven over one sinner that repenteth, more than over ninety and nine just persons which need no repentance." Now, why this joy at the return of a strayed or lost sheep, if there is no certainty, or scarcely any probability, that he will not stray again, and be finally lost with an aggravated destruction ? Immediately follow- ing this is another parable of the same import. Luke XV. 8 : " Either what woman, having ten pieces of silver, if she lose one piece, doth not light a candle, and sweep the house, and seek diligently till she find it ? 9, And when she hath found it, she calleth her friends and her neighbors together, saying, Rejoice with me ; for I have found that which was lost. 10. Likewise, I say unto you, there is joy in the presence of the angels of God over one sinner that repenteth." —. Here again it may be asked, why this great joy at finding the sinner^ ^unless his conversion is to result in his salvation ? fi76 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. I do not quote these passages as proving the doctrine in question, bnl only as specimens of the class of passages that seem to assume the truth of the doctrine, and as being just what might be expected, if the doctrine is true, and just what might not be expected if the doctrine is not true. To this it may be, and has been replied, that there are many passages that are just what we could not expect, if the perseverance of the saints were true. The following are relied upon as expmples of this class : — Heb. vi. 1 : " Therefore, leaving the principles of the doctrine of Christ, let us go on unto perfection ; not laying again the foundation of repentance from dead works, and of faith toward God ; 2. Of the doc- t-rine of baptisms, and of laying on of hands, anrd of resurrection of the dead, and of eternal judgment. 3. And this will we do if God permit. 4. For it is impossible for those who were once enlightened, and have tasted of the heavenly gift, and were made partakers of the Holy Ghost ; 5. And have tasted of the good word of God, and the powers of the world to come ; 6. If they shall fall away, to renew them again unto repentance ; seeing they crucify to themselves the son of God afresh, and put him to an open shame." Ez. xviii. 34 : " But when the righteous tumeth away from his righteousness, and committeth iniquity, and doeth according to all the abominations that the wicked man doeth, shall he live ? All his right- eousness that he hath done shall not be mentioned ; in his trespass that he hath trespassed, and in his sin that he hath sinned, in them shall he die." Ezek. xxxiii. 13 : " When I shall say to the righteous, that he shall surely live ; if he trust to his own righteousness and commit iniquity, all his righteousness shall not be remembered ; but for his iniquity that he hath committed, he shall die for it." Matt. X. 22 : " And ye shall be hated of all men for my name's sake ; but he that endureth to the end shall be saved." John XV. 6 : " If a man abide not in me, he is cast forth as a branch, and is withered ; and men gather them, and cast them into the fire, and they are burned." 1 Cor. X. 12 : " Wherefore let him that thinketh he standeth take heed lest he fall." Heb. iii. 6 : " But Christ as a Son over his own house ; whose house are we, if we hold fast the confidence and the rejoicing of the hope firm unto the end. 12. Take heed, brethren, lest there be in any of you an evil heart of unbelief, in departing from the living God. 13. But exhort one another daily, while it is called to-day ; lest any of you be hardened through the deceitfulness of sin. 14. For we are made partakers of Christ, if we hold the beginning of our confidence steadfast unto the end." fleb. iV. 1 : " Let us therefore fear, lest a promise being left us of entering into his rest, any of you should seem to come short of it. 11. Let us labor therefore to enter into that rest, lest any man fall after the same example of unbelief." 3 Peter i. 10 : " Wherefore the rather, brethren, give diligence to make your calling and election sure : for if ye do these things, ye shall never fall." In reply to this objection I remark, that instead of these passages be- ing otherwise than might be expected if the doctrine in question were true, and therefore implying that the doctrine is not true, they are pre- cisely what might be expected, if the doctrine as I have stated it, were true. If the certainty be but a moral certainty, even when the fact of conversion is settled beyond all doubt, or possibility of mistake, if the final salvation of the truly regenerate be as really conditioned upon per- severance as if there was no certainty about it ; and if, moreover, the fact of conversion is seldom settled in this life beyond the possibility of mis- take, then these passages, instead of implying any real uncertainty in re- gard to the final salvation of the saints, are just as and what might be expected, because they are just what is needed, upon the supposition, that the doctrine in question is true. They do not affirm that any true saints are, or will be, lost. They do imply the natural possibility, and, humanly speaking, the danger of such an event. They further imply, that without watchfulness and perseverance salvation is impossible. They also imply, that caution, warning, and threatening, are needed. They also imply, that some men, to say the least, are not certain of their own salvation, and that they do not certainly know that they are saints, be- yond all possibility of mistake. Now, these things that are fairly implied in this class of passages are really true : hence these passages just meet the necessities of the church, and are therefore just what might be expected when all the facts in the case are considered. I do not intend that this class of passages imply the truth of the doctrine under consideration, but that they are consist- ent with it, and might be expected, if the doctrine, as I have stated it, be true. 9. Eegeneration is represented as securing perseverance in obedi- ence : — First, In those passages that make it the condition of salvation. Secondly, In those passages that expressly affirm, that the truly re- generated do not, and cannot, live in sin. 1 John iii. 9 : " Whosoever is born of God doth not commit sin; for his seed remaineth in him : and he cannot sin, because he is born of God." 1 John iv. 7 : " Beloved, let us love one another : for love is of God ; and every one that loveth is born of God, and knoweth God." 37 578 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY, 1 John V. 1 : " Whosoever believeth that Jesus is the Christ is born of God: and everyone that loveth him that begat, loveth him also that is be- gotten of him. 4. For whatsoever is born of God overcometh the world: and this is the victory that overcometh the world, even our faith. 18. We know that whosoever is born of God sinneth not : but he that is be- gotten of God keepeth himself, and that wicked one toucheth him not." These and similar passages expressly teach the persevering nature of true religion, through the indwelling of the Holy Spirit : in other words, they teach that the truly regenerate do not sin, in the sense at least of living in anything like habitual sin. They teach, that with all truly re- generate souls, holiness is at least the rule, and sin only the exception ; that instead of its being true, that the regenerate souls live a great ma- jority of their days subsequent to regeneration in sin, it is true that they so seldom sin, that in strong language it may be said in truth, they do not sin. This language so strongly and expressly teaches that persever- ance is an unfailing attribute of Christian character, that but for the fact that other passages constrain us to understand these passages as strong language used in a qualified sense, we should naturally understand them as affirming that no truly regenerate soul does at any time sin. But since it is a sound rule of interpreting the language of an author, that he is, if possible, to be made consistent with himself ; and since John, in other passages in this same epistle and elsewhere, represents that Christians, or truly regenerate persons, do sometimes sin ; and since this is frequently taught in the Bible, we must underststnd these passages just quoted as only affirming a general and not a universal truth ; that is, that truly re- generate persons do not sin anything like habitually, but that holiness is the rule with them, and sin only the exception. Certainly these pas- sages cannot be reasonably understood as affirming and meaning less than this. I know that it has been said, that being born of God is used by John in these cases in a higher sense, and as meaning more than simple conversion or regeneration, as representing a higher state than can be predicated of all true Christians. But observe, he especially affirms that all who truly believe are born of God. Again : Christ speaks as if he regarded those only as having truly be- lieved who persevere in obedience. John viii. 31 : " Then said Jesus to those Jews which believed on him, if ye continue in my word, then are ye my disciples indeed." The parable of the sower appears to have been designed expressly to teach the persevering nature of true religion. Luke viii. 5 : " A sower went out to sow his seed : and as he sowed, some fell by the way side, and it was trodden down, and the fowls of the air devoured it. 6. And some fell upon a rock ; and as soon as it was sprung up, it withered awiy, because it lacked moisture. 7. And some fell among thorns; PERSEVERANCE OP SAINTS. 579 and the thorns sprang up with it, and choked it. 8. And other fell on good ground, and sprang up, and bare fruit a hundred fold. And when he had said these things, he cried. He that hath ears to hear, let him hear. 11. Now the parable is this : The seed is the word of God. 13. Those by the way side are they that hear ; then cometh the devil, and taketh away the word out of their hearts, lest they should believe and be saved. 13. They on the rock are they, which, when they hear, receive the word with joy ; and these have no root, which for a while believe, and in time of temptation fall away. 14. And that which fell among thorns are they, which when they have heard, go forth, and are choked with cares, and riches, and pleasures of this life, and bring no fruit to per- fection. 15. But that on the good ground are they, which, in an honest and good heart, having heard the word, keep it, and bring forth fruit with patience." If this parable was not designed to distinguish true religion from its counterfeits, and to illustrate the persevering nature of true religion, I do not know, and cannot conceive, what was its design. I need not en- large upon it. Let any one read and consider the parable for himself. Again : the parable of the leaven seems designed also to teach the progressive and persevering nature of true religion. Matt. xiii. 33 : " Another parable spake he unto them : the kingdom of heaven is like unto leaven, which a woman took and hid in three meas- ures of meal, till the whole was leavened." This parable I understand to represent or teach the aggressive nature of true faith and piety, as it exhibits itself both in the hearts and lives of individual Christians, and also as it progresses and extends itself in the world. It is in its nature persevering and aggressive, and when it once truly exists, it will through grace triumph. When I speak of the perse- vering nature of true religion, I do not mean, that religion as it exists in the hearts of the saints in this life would of itself, if unsupported by the grace and indwelling Spirit of God, prevail and triumph over its enemies ; but the thing intended is, that through the faithfulness of God, he that has begun or shall begin a good work in any heart, will perfect it until the day of Jesus Christ. The persevering character of true religion is ] I owing to the indwelling Spirit of God. This leads me to remark again, that repentance is made the condition of receiving the Holy Spirit ; and when this Spirit is received, it is with the express promise and pledge that he shall abide in the heart for ever. John vii. 37 : " In the last day, that great day of the feast, Jesus ■tood and cried, saying. If any man thirst let him come unto me and drink. He that believeth on me, as the Scripture hath said, out of his j I belly shall flow rivers of living water. 39. (But this spake he of the 680 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. Spirit, which they that believe on him should receive ; for the Holy Ghost ■was not yet given ; because that Jesus was not yet glorified.") Here we learn that water represents the Holy Spirit. This is abund- antly taught in the Bible. Now let us hear what Christ said to the woman of Samaria. John iv. 13 : " Jesus answered and said unto her. Whosoever drinketh of this water shall thirst again. 14. But whosoever drinketh of the water that I shall give him, shall never thirst : but the water that I shall give him shall be in him a well of water springing up into everlasting life." The prominent truth taught in this text is, that whosoever shall drink of this water shall never thirst. In this particular respect the Saviour contrasts it with the water of Jacob's well, and says, 13, 14 : " Jesus an-, swered and said unto her, Whosoever drinketh of this water shall thirst again : but whosoever drinketh of the water that I shall give him, shall never thirst ; but the water that I shall give him shall be in him a well of water springing up into everlasting life." This Christ plainly states as a fact. That is, he shall never perish for lack of this Spirit or water, but it shall abide in him, and spring up into eternal life. The Spirit shall remain in him, and secure him against falling and perishing. The fact that the Spirit shall abide with and in all who ever receive him, and shall prevail to secure their salvation, seems to be plainly taught in this passage. Again, Rom. viii. 9 : " But ye are not in the flesh, but in the Spirit, if so be that the Spirit of God dwell in you. Now if any man have not the Spirit of Christ, he is none of his. 10. And if Christ be in you, the body is dead because of sin ; but the Spirit is life because of righteous- ness. 11. But if the Spirit of him that raised up Jesus from the dead dwell in you, he that raised up Christ from the dead shall also quicken your mortal bodies by his Spirit that dwelleth in you. " Here it is expressly declared, that none are Christians who have not the Holy Spirit, or Spirit of Christ, and that they who are Christ's do not walk after the flesh, but after the Spirit ; that they who are Christ's have crucified, that is killed, the lusts of the flesh. This is the real char- acter of all true saints. Suchlike passages, observe, are designed to dis- tinguish true religion from its counterfeits, and to teach that perseverance in true obedience is a characteristic of all real saints. 10. Christ represents it as impossible to deceive the elect. Matt, xxiv. 24 : We have seen that the elect unto salvation include all true Christians ; that is, that all Christians are the elect children of God. They have come to Christ. Observe, the Saviour himself teaches, as we have seen : (1.) That no one can come to, or believe in him, unless the Father draw him. PEESEVERANCE OP SAINTS. 581 (2.) That the Father draws those, and only those'to Christ, whom he has given to him. (3.) That all whom the Father has given to him shall come to him, and of those that come to him he will lose none, but will raise them up at the last day. John vi. 44 : "No man can come to me except the Father which hath sent me, draw him ; and I will raise him up at the last day. 45. It is written in the prophets, And they shall be all taught of God. Every man therefore that hath heard, and hath learned of the Father, Cometh unto me. 39. All that the Father giveth me shall come to me ; and him that cometh to me I will in no wise cast out. 38. For I came down from heaven not to do mine own will, but the will of him that sent me. 37. And this is the father's will which hath sent me, that of all which he hath given me I should lose nothing, but should raise it up again at the last day. 40. And this is the will of him that sent me, that every one which seeth the Son and believeth on him may have everlasting life ; and I will raise him up at the last day." False theories are represented as permitted to test the piety of true and false professors. 1 Cor. xi. 19 : " For there must be also heresies among you, that they which are approved may be made manifest among you." Those that are of the elect, or are true children of God, will not follow heresies. Christ says, John x. 4, 6 : " And when he putteth forth his own sheep, he goeth before them, and the sheep follow him ; for they know his voice. 9. And a stranger will they not follow, but will flee from him : for they know not the voice of strangers. 27. My sheep hear my voice, and I know them, and they follow me. 28. And I give unto them eternal life ; and they shall never perish, neither shall any pluck them out of my hand." But those who are not true believers will not, and do not hear and know his voice, and follow him. John x. 26 : " But ye believe not, because ye are not of my sheep, as I said unto you." 11. The eighth chapter of Romans seems to settle the question, or rather is of itself a clear proof of the doctrine we are examining. We need to read and ponder prayerfully the whole chapter, to apprehend distinctly the scope of the apostle's teaching upon this subject. He had in the seventh chapter been dwelling upon and portraying a legal ex- perience. He begins this eighth chapter by asserting, Rom. viii. 1 : "There is therefore now no condemnation to them which ai'e in Christ Jesus, who walk not after the flesh, but after the Spirit. 3. For the law of the Spirit of life in Christ Jesus hath made me free from the law of sin and death. 3. For what the law could not do, in that it was weak through the flesh, God sending his own Son in the likeness of sin- ful flesh, and for sin, condemned sin in the flesh ; 4. That the right- 582 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. eousness of the lafrtuight be fulfilled in us, who walk not after the flesh but after the Spirit. 5. For they that are after the flesh do mind the things of the flesh ; but they that are after the Spirit, the things of the Spirit. 6. For to be carnally minded is death; but to be spiritually minded is life and peace. 7. Because the carnal mind is enmity against God ; for it is not subject to the law of God, neither indeed can be. 8. So then they that are in the flesh cannot please God. 9. But ye are not in the flesh, but in the Spirit, if so be that the Spirit of God dwell in you. Now, if any man have not the Spirit of Christ, he is none of his. 10. And if Christ be in you, the body is dead because of sin ; but the Spirit is life, because of righteousness. 11. But if the Spirit of him that raised up Jesus from the dead dwell in you, he that raised up Christ from the dead shall also quicken your mortal bodies by his Spirit that dwelleth in you. 12. Therefore, brethren, we are debtors, not to the flesh, to live after the flesh. 13. For if ye live after the flesh, ye shall die ; but if ye through the Spirit do mortify the deeds of the body, ye shall live. 14. For as many as are led by the Spirit of God, they are the sons of God. 15. For ye have not received the spirit of bondage again to fear ; but ye have received the Spirit of adoption, whereby we cry, Abba, Father. 16. The Spirit itself beareth witness with our spirit, that we are the children of God : 17. And if children, then heirs ; heirs of God and joint heirs with Jesus Christ : if so be that we suffer with him, that we may be also glorified together. 18. For I reckon, that the sufferings of this present time are not worthy to be compared with the glory which shall be revealed in us." Here he describes the character of true believers as distinguished from mere legalists, of whom he had been speaking. True believers, he here asserts, are justified ; they are in Christ Jesus ; they walk not after the flesh, but after the Spirit ; the righteousness of the law is fulfilled in them, that is, the law is written in their hearts ; they have the Spirit of Christ, the Spirit of adoption ; the Spirit witnesses with their spirit that they are the adopted children of God ; " If children, then heirs, heirs of God and joint heirs with Christ ;" the sufferings of this present time are not worthy to be compared to the glory that shall be revealed in them. Verse 24, he says : "For we are saved by hope ; but hope that is seen, is not hope ; for what a man seeth, why doth he yet hope for ?" He then proceeds to notice the ground of this hope : verses 26 and 27. " Likewise the Spirit also helpeth our infirmities ; for we know not what we should pray for as we ought ; but the Spirit itself maketh in- tercession for us with groanings which cannot be uttered. And he that eearcheth the hearts knoweth what is the mind of the Spirit, because he maketh intercession for the saints according to the will of God." This, observe, he aflBrms to be true of all who are Christ's, or who are PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. 583 true believers. Of this Spirit he aflSrms the following things: (1.) That all Christians possess this Spirit. (3.) That this Spirit bears witness with the spirits of Christians that they are the children of God. (3.) That he makes intercession for the saints according to the will of God; that is, that he prays in them or excites them to pray, and to pray aright, for those things which it is the will of God to grant to them. He then in the 28th verse says, "And we know that all things work together for good to them that love God, to them who are the called according to his purpose." Here he represents those who love God, and those who are the called according to his purpose, as the same persons ; and affirms, that we know that all things shall work together for their good. This he notices as a second ground of hope. Ho next proceeds to state, how we know that all things work together for the good of those that love God : or, which he regards as the same thing, to those who are the elect, called according to the election or purpose of God. He says, verse 29, "For whom he did foreknow, he also did predestinate to be conformed to the image of his Son, that he might be the first-born among many brethren :" that is, we know it, because they are predesti- nated to be conformed to the image of his Son. Not if they will be, but to be, and therefore, all things must directly or indirectly contribute to this result. He then says, " Moreover, whom he did predestinate, them he also called ; and whom he called, them he also justified ; and whom he justified, them he also glorified." That is, furthermore, we know this, and have good ground of hope from the fact, that whom he did predestinate to be conformed to the image of his Son, them, that is the same persons, he also called ; and whom, that is, the same persons whom he had predestinated to be conformed to the image of his Son and had called, them he also justified ; and whom he predestinated, and called, and justified, them, that is, the same persons, he also glorified. Here then, he concludes, is a firm foundation for the hope of which he had spoken, the grounds of which he had been pointing out. He ac- cordingly proceeds to say in a spirit of triumph : — Rom. viii. 31 : " What shall we then say to these things ? If God be for us, who can be against us ? 32. He that spared not his own Son, but delivered him up for us all, how shall he not with him also freely give us all things ? 33. Who shall lay anything to the charge of God's elect ? It is God that justifieth. 34. Who is he that condemneth ? It is Christ that died, yea rather, that is risen again, who is even at the right hand of God, who also maketh intercession for us." Here he says, "if God be for us, who cati be against us ? " and then proceeds to point out several other considerations that enter into this ground of confidence. All who love God are his elect. God justifies them, and who is he that condemns them ? God is for them, and who 684 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. shall be against them ? God freely gave his Son for all of them, how much more shall he freely give them all things ? If he did not withhold his Son, surely he would withhold nothing else from them that was neces- sary to secure their salvation. Furthermore, it was Christ that died, and still more and rather, that had risen again, and maketh intercession for them. If these things are so, we may well inquire : — Kom. viii. 35 : " Who shall separate us from the love of Christ ? Shall tribulation, or distress, or persecution, or famine, or nakedness, or peril, or sword ? 36. (As it is written. For thy sake we are killed all the day long ; we are accounted as sheep for the slaughter.)" He then triumphantly afiBrms, verses 37-39 : " Nay, in all these things we are more than conquerors, through him that loved us. For I am per- suaded, that neither death, nor life, nor angels, nor principalities, nor powers, nor things present, nor things to come, nor height, nor depth, nor any other creature, shall be able to separate us from the love of God, which is in Christ Jesus our Lord." If Paul in the eighth of Komans does not settle the question, that all true saints will be saved, how could it be settled ? Let us in few words sum up the argument, as he here presents it : — We are saved already in anticipation, or in hope ; and only by hope, for as yet we have not received our crown. ^ The grounds of this hope are, that we are in Christ Jesus, have the Spirit of Christ, Spirit of adop- tion. We walk not after the flesh, but after the Spirit. This Spirit wit- nesses that we are children and heirs of God. He makes intercession for us according to the will of God. We also know, that all things work to- gether for good to them who love God, for they are the called according to his purpose. They who are called, that is, efEectually called, are called in conformity with their predestination to be conformed to the image of God. Hence those who are thus predestinated are called, and justified, and glorified. Therefore, no one can lay anything to the charge of God's elect. God justifies, and who shall condemn them ? Christ died for them, yea rather, has risen and makes intercession for them. God with- held not his Son, and of course will withhold from Christians nothing that is essential to secure their salvation. Wherefore he concludes, that nothing shall be able to separate us from the love of God. I know that to this it has been replied, that although nothing else can separate us from the love of God, yet we may separate ourselves from hia love. To this I answer, true ; we may, or can do so ; but the question is, shall we, or will any of the 'elected and called do so ? No, indeed ; for this is the thing which the apostle intended to afiBrm, namely, the cer- tainty of the salvation of all true saints. The apostle manifestly in this passage assumes, or affirms, that all who ever truly loved God are elect, PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. 585 or are chosen to be conformed to the image of his Son ; and are called, and sanctified, and justified, in conformity with such predestination. If this is not his meaning, what is ? If this is not his meaning, what ground of hope do we, after all, find in what he says ? The apostle seems to have had the same thought in his mind in writing to the Hebrews. Heb. vi. 17 : "Wherein God willing more abundantly to show unto the heirs of promise the immutability of his counsel, confirmed it by an oath; 18. That by two immutable things, in which it was impossible for God to lie, we might have a strong consolation, who have fled for refuge to lay hold upon the hope set before us ; 19. Which hope we have as an anchor of the soul, both sure and steadfast, and which entereth into that within the veil ; 30. Whither the forerunner is for us entered, even Jesus, made a high-priest forever, after the order of Melchisedec." There are a great many other passages of scripture, of the same Import as those I have quoted in support of this doctrine, as every one knows who has taken the trouble to examine for himself. But I have pursued this investigation far enough. If what has been said fails to satisfy any mind, it is presumed that nothing which might be added would produce conviction. I will therefore, after replying to some further objections, conclude the discussion of this subject. LECTURE L. PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. OBJECTION'S AKSWBRBD. 1. It is said that the natural tendency of this doctrine condemns it ; that it tends to beget and foster a carnal presumption in a life of sin, on the part of those who think themselves saints. There is, I reply, a broad and obvious distinction between the abuse of a good thing or doctrine, and its natural tendency. The legitimate tendency of a thing or doctrine may be good, and yet it may be abused and perverted. This is true of the atonement, and the offer of pardon through Christ. These doctrines have been, and are, greatly objected to by TJniversalists and Unitarians, as having a tendency to encourage the hope of impunity in sin. It is said by them, that to hold out the idea that Christ has made an atonement for sin, and that the oldest and vilest sinners may be forgiven and saved, tends directly to immorality, and to encourage the hope of ultimate impunity in a life of sin — the hope that, after a sinful life, the siiinej: may at }.ast repent and be saved. 586 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOQT. Now, there is bo much plausibility in this objection to the doctrine of pardon and atonement, that many sensible men hare rejected those doctrines because of this objection. They have regarded the objection as unanswerable. But a close examination will show, that the objection against those doctrines is entirely without foundation ; and not only so, but that the real natural tendency of those doctrines affords a strong presumptive argument in their favor. The telling of a convinced and self-condemned sinner, that Christ has died for his sins, and offers freely and at once to forgive all the past, has no natural tendency to beget a spirit of perseverance in rebellion ; but is on the contrary the readiest, and safest, and I may add, the only effectual method of subduing him, and bringing him to immediate repentance. But suppose, on the other hand, you tell him there is no forgiveness, that he must be punished for his sins at all events, what tendency has this to bring him to immediate and genuine repentance ; to beget within him the love required by the law of God ? Assuring him of punishment for all his sins, might serve to restrain outward mani- festations of a sinful heart, but certainly it tends not to subdue selfish- ness, and to cleanse the heart ; whereas the offer of mercy through the death of Christ, has a most sin-subduing tendency. It is such a mani- festation to the sinner of God's great love to him, his real pity for him, and readiness to overlook and blot out the past, as tends to break down the stubborn heart into genuine repentance, and to beget the sincerest love to God and Christ, together with the deepest self-loathing and self- abasement on account of sin. Thus the doctrines of the atonement and pardon through a crucified Eedeemer, instead of being condemned by their legitimate tendency, are greatly confirmed thereby. These doc- trines are no doubt liable to abuse, and so is every good thing ; but is this a good reason for rejecting them ? Our necessary food and drink may be abused, and often are, and so are all the most essential blessings of life. Should we reject them on this account ? It is admitted that the doctrines of atonement and forgiveness through Christ, are greatly abused by careless sinners and hypocrites ; but is this a good reason for denying and withholding them from the convicted sinner, who is earnestly inquiring what he shall do to be saved ? No indeed I It is also admitted, that the doctrine of the perseverance of the saints is liable to abuse, and often is abused by the carnal and deceived professor ; but is this a good reason for rejecting it, and for withholding its consolations from the tempted, tempest-tossed saint ? By no means. Such are the circumstances of temptation from within and without, in which the saints are placed in this life, that when they are made really ac(juainted with tbemselvesj and are brought to a proper appreci^ PERSEVERANCE OF SAINTS. 587 tion of the circumstances in which they are, they have but little rational ground of hope, except what is found in this doctrine. The natural tendency and inevitable consequence of a thorough revelation of them- selves to themselves, would be to beget despair, but for the covenanted grace and faithfulness of God. What saint who has ever been revealed to himself by the Holy Spirit, has not seen what Paul saw when he said, " In me, that is, in my flesh, dwelleth no good thing ?" Who that has been made acquainted with himself, does not know that he never did, and never will take one step towards heaven, except as he is antici- pated and drawn by the grace of God in Christ Jesus ? Who that knows himself does not understand that he never would have been converted, but for the grace of God anticipating and exciting the first motions of his mind in a right direction ? And what true saint does not know, that such are his former habitudes, and such the circumstances of trial under which he is placed, and such the downward tendency of his own soul that although converted, he shall not persevere for an hour, except the indwelling grace and Spirit of God shall hold him up, and quicken him in the path of holiness ? Where, I would ask, is the ground of hope for the saints as they exist in this world ? Not in the fact that they have been physically regen- erated, so that to fall is naturally impossible. Not in the fact that they have passed through any such change of nature as to secure their perse- verance for an hour, if left to themselves. Not in the fact that they can or will sustain themselves for a day or a moment by their resolutions. Where then is their hope ? There is not even a ground of probability, that any one of them will ever be saved, unless the doctrine in question be true, that is, unless the promised grace and faithfulness of God in Christ Jesus goes before, and from step to step secures their perseverance. But if this grace is promised to any saint, as his only ground of confi- dence, or even hope that he shall be saved, it is equally, and upon the same conditions, promised to all the saints. No one more than another can place the least reasonable dependence on anything, except the grace equally promised and vouchsafed to all. What does a man know of him- self who hopes to be saved, and who yet does not depend wholly on promises of grace in Christ Jesus ? The natural tendency of true and thorough conviction of sin, and of such a knowledge of ourselves, as is essential to salvation, is to beget and foster despondency and despair ; and, as I said, the soul in this condition has absolutely little or no ground of hope of ultimate salvation, except that which this doctrine, when rightly understood, affords. However far he may have progressed in the way of life, he sees, when he thoroughly knows the truth, that he has progressed not a step, except as he has been tirawn ^o4 ioclined by the indwelling grace and Spirit of Christ ; and 588 SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY. that he shall absolutely go no further in the way to heaven, unless tho same gracious influence is continued, in such a sense, and to such an ex- tent, as to overcome all the temptations with which he is beset. His only hope is in the fact, that God has promised to keep and preserve him. Nothing but God's faithfulness to his Son procured the conversion of any saint. Nothing but this same faithfulness has procured his perseverance for a day, and nothing else can render the salvation of any soul at all probable. What can a man be thinking about, or what can he know of himself, who does not know this ? Unless the same grace that secures the conversion of the saints, secures their perseverance to the end, there is no hope for them. It is true, that the promises to sinners and to saints are conditioned upon their faith, and upon the right exercise of their own agency ; and it is also true, that grace secures the fulfilment of the conditions of the promises, in every instance in which they are fulfilled, or they never would be fulfilled. We have seen that the promises of the Father to the Son secure the bestowment upon the saints of all grace to ensure their final salvation. It shocks and distresses me to hear professed Christians talk of being saved at all, except upon the ground of the anticipating, and persevering, and sin-overcoming, and hell-subduing grace of God in Christ Jesus. Why, I should as soon expect the devil to be saved, as that any saint on earth will be, if left, with all the promises of God in his hands, to stand and persevere without the drawings, and inward teachings, and over-per- suading influences of the Holy Spirit. Shame on a theology that sus- pends the ultimate salvation of the saints upon the broken reed of their own resolutions in their best estate ! Their firmest resolutions are noth- ing unless they are formed and supported by the influence of the Spirit of grace, going before, and exciting, and persuading to their formation and their continuance. This is everywhere taught in the Bible ; and who that has considered the matter does not know, that this is the ex^ perience of every saint ? Where, then, is the ground of hope, if the doctrine in question be denied ? " If the foundation be destroyed, what shall the righteous do ? " Where, then, is the evil tendency of this doc- trine ? It has naturally no evil tendency. Can the assurance of eternal salvation through the blood, and love, and grace of Christ, have a natural tendency to harden the heart of a child of God against his Father and his Saviour ? Can the revealed fact, that he shall be more than a con- queror through Christ, beget in him a disposition to sin against Christ ? Impossible ! This doctrine, though liable to abuse by hypocrites, is nev- ertheless the sheet anchor of the saints in hours of conflict. And shall the children be deprived of the bread of life, because sinners will pervert the use of it to their own destruction ? This doctrine is absolutely need- ful to preyent despair, wjien conviction is