PF 7 7 ■ URIS LIBRARY DATE DUE ^^^-a^***^ ^^"'"^Mnnn ^TT^ GAYLORD PRINTED INU.S. A. social IHe in Greeee f iwro" l|liiW.3 Cornell University Library The original of tliis book is in tlie Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31 92401 1 52291 3 THE SOCIAL LIFE OF THE GREEKS, I SOCIAL LIFE IN GREECE FROM HOMER TO MENANDER SOCIAL LIFE IN GREECE FROM HOMER TO MENANDER J. P. MAHAFFY FELLOW ETC. OF TRINITY COLLEGE, DUBLIN; HON. FELLOW OP QU£EN*S COLLEGE, OXFORD ; KNIGHT OP THE ORDER OF THE REDEEMER ; CORRESPONDING MEMBER OF THE ACADEMY OF VIENNA; AUTHOR OF 'PROLEGOMENA OF ANCIENT HISTORY*; ' KANT's PHILOSOPHY FOR ENGLISH READERS': 'creek life and THOUGHT, FROM THE AGE OF ALEXANDER TO THE ROMAN conquest'; 'the greek world under ROMAN sway'; 'rambles AND STUDIES IN GREECE*; 'a HISTORY OF CLASSICAL GREEK literature'; 'the empire of the ptolemies*; £dit0r of the petrie papyri, etc. ILflntton MACMILLAN AND CO., Limited NEW YORK : THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 1902 rights reserved]. "\%A^- First Editiomij^. Second xSjs. TAt'rd lijj. FouriA iSjg. Fi/lk iS Sixth xSSS. Seventh liga. Jie^rinted jSg4, iSgS, igoi. WILSONO KING PIGNUS AMICITLE PREFACE TO THE 1898 EDITION. This book had already in the fourth edition as- sumed its final form, nor was it my intention hereafter to enlarge it, but rather to add companion volumes upon the later portions of old Greek life. Indeed, maturer study has led me to reject some chang-es which I had introduced in deference to the censure of professional critics, and I added in the fourth edition some considerations concerning the moral standard of Greek politics in Demosthenes' day, which seem to me of much importance, and which have been generally accepted among later Greek historians, though likely to increase the displeasure with which certain scholars regard my estimate of old Greek civilisation. It is too homely for them ; it detracts too much from the ideal they have framed for themselves ; it asserts the weaker and commoner side of the nation in the face of their unreal speculations. Nor is it true that homely views imply a grudging appreciation of the perfections of Greek literature and art. What they really imply is only this, that the greatest poets and the greatest artists were not the average repre- sentatives of the nation at large, and that the social life of the people was not of that extraordinary perfection which the men of books had imagined. I had long felt that the extremely learned often miss the practical infer- viii PREFACE. ences which may be drawn from our classics by plain common sense, and itoccured to me to seek the materials for sketching the Social Life of the Greeks, not in pre- vious commentators, but in the Greek books them- selves, which I re-read one by one specially, with par- ticular attention to the social points they contained. This was the method which led me to draw a picture of the Greeks from their ancient books correspond- ing in many points to the Greeks of to-day, nor do I know of any attempt to dispute the accuracy of my statements, except some vague assertions put forward without evidence. On a few details I at first sur- rendered my own opinion too readily ; but these points are not worth discussing here. So far as they turn upon the internal evidence for spuriousness in extant orations and other documents I have said all that is necessary in my History of Greek Classical Litera- ture, a work which treats of the literary aspects of the life portrayed in the following pages, and is there- fore an important supplement for all those who desire to get a general view of Greek civilisation in its various phases. Thus objections have been answered and a want supplied, so that the present volume may maintain the favour with which the general p"ublic has honoured it. And now, when I am saying the last word about it, and in some sense taking leave of it, I may be excused for dwelling on the circum- stances which gave it a peculiar interest, and have obtained for it a longer life and a better name than I could have hoped. The same favour has been extend to my Rambles PREFACE. IX and Studies in Greece {^td ed. 1887, Macmillan), which give my impressions of modern Hfe among the suc- cessors of the old Hellenes, and in the land which produced so many centuries of splendid civilization. To this study I had appended a chapter on Greek Music and Painting, which was rightly considered to belong to the present volume. I have therefore added it to this edition, to make way for new matter upon mediaeval Greece in future editions of my Rambles. I have since been enabled to complete two new volumes, covering part of the huge gap between clas- sical and modern Greece, and have given in my Greek Life and Thought from the death of Alexander to the Roman Conquest, and in The Greek World under Roman Sway, the evidence culled from the Greek authors between Menander and Plutarch, as well as some estimate of that literature. These volumes were therefore strictly a sequel to the present one, worked out in the same way from the texts themselves, and will answer the objection that I had paused in the middle of my great subject. There yet remains the appreciation of Greek Life under the Roman Empire ; from the days when Christianity became a social force. I trust I may yet be able to complete this task. Trinity College, Dublin, ' May, 1898. TABLE OF CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. Introduction. Modern complexion of Greek life, page i. Defects in the current literature on the subject, 3. Plan of the present volume, 4. Political lessons to be drawn from Greek culture, 5. Gradual development of Greek morals and society, 6. Contrasts vifith modern life, 8. CHAPTER II. The Greeks of the Homeric Age. The Homeric controversy not here in question, 9. Exceptional atti- tude of Hesiod, 10. His evidence is truer than Homer's ideal pictures, II. Improbabilities in Homer, 12. Mr. Grote's estimate criticised, 13. Difficulties about Hesiod — chiefly textual, 14. Fragments of pre- Homeric history, 15. Homer describes the close of an epoch, 18. Modern English Homerists criticised, 19. Analysis of the Homeric ideal, 20; as regards — Courage, 21; Truth, 27; Compassion, 29; Loyalty, 36. Causes of these features, 39. Homer's Pallas Athene, as an ideal character, 41. CHAPTER III. The Greeks of the Homeric Age (continued). Homer's society an exclusive caste society, 44 ; which was refined and courteous, 45 — in feasting, 46 ; and conversation, 47 ; but showing slight decay in hospitality, 48. Examples of Menelaus and Alcinous, 51. Treatment of women, 5 2 ; of servants, 56 ; of domestic animals, 62; of those beyond the caste, and its dependents, 65. Evidence of Hesiod, 66. Love of money — universal in Greek life, 70. Hesiod's domestic rude- ness, 71. General results, 74. xii CONTENTS. CHAPTER IV. The Greeks of the Lyrio Age. Contrasts to Homer's idealism; Lyric realism, 77. Assertions of cowardice in the fragments, 78. Thucydidean features of the lyric poets, 82. They sustain the attitude of Hesiod, 82. Unjust estimates of the tyrants by modern critics, 83. Example at Athens ; Solon and Peisistratus, 85. Classification of the lyric poets ; free aristocrats, and court poets, 90 j their religion, 9 2 ; ethics, 94 ; Violent party feelings, 97 ; Modem parallel in Ireland, 98. General estimate, 100. CHAPTER V. The Greeks of the Lyrio Age (continued). ■Advance in social refinement, 102. Wine drinking and feasting, 103. Attitude of women in — Simonides- of Ceos, :o8 ; Sappho, 109; and Simonides of Amorgos, no. Strong sentiment of love, 113. Points of direct succession to Homeric Greece, 115. Hatred of old age, 119; causes of this feeling, 1 20. Selfishness, 122. Hospitahty, 124. Points of contrast with Homeric Greece; the feeling of love; the objects of love, 126. Religious progress, 129. CHAPTER VI. The Greeks of the Attic Age. Division of subject : authorities, 133. Attic patriotism, 135. Coarse- ness of Attic relaxations, 136. General decay of letters throughout Greece, 137; Causes of the exception at Athens, 138; Estimate of Pericles, 140. Position of women, 142 ; its causes, 145. Examination of our authorities, viz. .lEschylus, his characters, 149; Herodotus, his characters, 155; their meanness, 157; justice, 160; benevolence, 163; sociality, 168; sadness, 171. CONTENTS. xiii CHAPTER VII. 'STa.e Greeks of the Attic Age (continued). Thucydides, 173; cruelty described in his history, 175 1 strictures on his pictures of Greek life, 177; ^^'s mistake rectified on psychological grounds, 179. Sophocles and ^schylus: inferiority of Sophocles, 182. Euripides, his attitude, 185; his contrast to Sophocles, 187; his philo- sophy, 188 ; example in his Electro, 191 ; his great female characters— Alcestis, Macaria, Iphigenia, 198 ; injustice of the critics, 205. CHAPTER VIII. The Oreeks of the Attic Age (concluded). The Attic comedy, 207. Variance of type in the characters of the Attic drama, 208. Historic value of the comedy, 209. Possible reli- gious cause of Aristophanes' ribaldry, 210. Evidence about Aspasia and the Hetairai, especially of Corinth, 212; the charges against her examined, 214. Conversation at this epoch, 219. Excesses of young aristocrats: Alcibiades, Callias, 220. Contrast of the lower classes, 235. Exceptional cruelties, 226. General estimate of the Periclean Greeks, 228. Cruelties in war, 234; at home, and in private life, 237; in the law-courts, 239. Hard treatment of old age, 244; palliation of this harshness, 247 ; examples from the tragedians, 249. CHAPTER IX. A-ttic Culture. Limited size of Athens: its results on Greek culture, 252. Bad cha- racter of the Peirseus, 255. Slaves to perform menial work, 258. General refinement, 260; exemplified in executions, 262 ; disposal of the bodies after the sentence, 266. High character of jailors, 268. Abatement of cruelty in war, 270 ; effect of mercenaries on this question, 271 ; qualifi- cations and exceptions, 272. Social position of women, 274; evidence of Xenophon's (Economics, 275 ; the rights of women coming into notice, 281. The Hetairai, 284. Difficulty of estimating the evidence of tragic poets, 286, Abuse of marriage, 287. xiv CONTENTS. CHAPTER X, Attic Culture. — Certain Trades and Professions. Medical practice : its social side, 290 ; state physicians and their salaries, 292; persuasive treatment, 293; Doric prescriptions, 296; quackery — private, 297; public, 298. Cooks — their general character, 2Q9 ; Doric bills of fare, 301 ; impertinence, 302 ; grandiloquence, 303 ; slave cooks of later days, 306. The fishmongers, 306 ; their audadty, 307- CHAPTER XI. Attio Culture. — Entertainments and Conversation. — Tie Education of Boys. — Th.e Streets in Athens. Philosophical objections to music in society, 312. General hints on conversation, 314. Drinking of weak mixtures of wine, 317. Plato's Symposium, 319. Xenophon's Symposium, 323. Absence of ladies at Greek feasts, 325. Male beauty, 326. The education of boys, 330. Controversies on education, 332. Defects of Socrates' teaching, 334. Sound objections to athletics, as compared with field sports, 336. Homely features in the streets of Athens, 339. Street brawls, 340. Narrovraess of Attic culture, 342. The Hellenism of Isocrates, 343; of Plato, 346. CHAPTER XII. Beligious Feeling in the Attio Ago. Gradual decay of belief, 348. Immoralities of the Epic theology: the explanation of the comparative mythologers examined, 349 ; the true explanation, 353. The Bible of the Greeks, 353. Supposed moral object of the Epos, 354. Greek theory of inspiration : the Ion of Plato, 357. Over-estimate of Greek scepticism : Thucydides, 361. The his- toric dignity of Greek mythology, 363. The waxing and waning of belief, 363. Orthodoxy of the Athenians, 366 ; evidence of the orators, 367; of Xenophon, 3O8. Sceptical tendencies of the new comedy, 372. CONTENTS. XV Contrasts to modem faith: (o) love of mystery, 374 ; the Greek myste- ries, 376 ; (/3) union of art and religion, 378 ; (7) of pleasure and devo- tion, 379. Religion urged against morals, 383. CHAPTER XIII, The Business Habits of the Attio Greeks. Importance of trade : commercial wars, 385. Complicated legal system, 387. Stringent laws against vPpis or assault, 390. Division of judicial functions, 391. Delays of Attic law ; trial by jury, 392. De- fects in estimation of evidence, 393. Criticisms of Aristophanes, 398. Sycophancy, 398. Inferiority of Greek to Roman legal oratory, 399. Begging for mercy in court, 400. Shabbiness of Greek commerce, 402. Peculiarity of Greek protective laws, 404. Aristotle's blunders about money, 406. Contrasts to modem trade : stock exchange, 407. Bad methods of taxation : axTiSoais, 409. Hiding of money, 411. Banks and banking, 41a. Position of Pasion, 414. Family quarrels, 415. Case of Calippus, 417. Comparison with othernations, 419. Illustra- tions from politics, 432, Case of Demosthenes' public profits, 423. CHAPTER XIV. The Social Aspects of Oreek Art. Common notions of the diffusion of, Greelj art, 429. Contrast with their every day life, 430. Art due to the tyrants and the Attic period, 430. ^Esthetic sense of the Greeks, 431. Beauty of the country, 432. Absurd stress laid on Adamantius, 433. Real state of the facts, 435. Retarding circumstances, 436. Professional poetry, 437. Contempt of amateurs, 439. , Low social position of artists, 440. The Greek leisure, 441. Secular and religious incentives to art, 443. False view of Greek perfection, 444. Genius exceptional, 445. Coldness of Greek art, 447. xvi CONTENTS. CHAPTER XV. Greek Musio and Fainting. Contrast between the objective and subjective arts, 449. Remains of painting and music, 450. Morality iii Greek music, 451 ; in modern, 453; Professional, 455. Greek instruments, 456. Extant tunes, 457; scales, 462 ; harmony, 466 ; results, 469. Greek painting, 470. Polygnotns, 472. Agatharchus and perspective, 474. Landscape painting, 476. The picturesque, 477. Theocritus, 479. Personification of landscape, 481. Sculptural landscape, 483. Comparison with Italian republics, 485. With modem states, 4S8. Conclusion, 489. Inpex ^91 CHAPTER I. INTRODUCTION. Among the nations which stand out in the course of history as having done most to promote human knowledge, human art, and human culture, the Greeks are first in the judgment of all competent observers. The hold which Greek literature retains on our modern education is not the mere result of prece- dent or fashion. Every thinking man who becomes acquainted with the masterpieces of Greek writing, must see plainly that they stand to us in a far closer relation than the other remains of antiquity. They are not mere objects of curiosity to the archaeologist, not mere treasure-houses of roots and forms to be sought out by comparative grammarians. They are the writings of men of like culture with ourselves, who argue with the same logic, who reflect with kindred feelings. They have worked out social and moral problems like ourselves ; they have expressed them in such language as we should desire to use. In a word, they are thoroughly modern, more modern even than the epochs quite proximate to our own. The disjointed sentences of the Egyptian moralist, 1 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. the confused metaphors of the Hebrew prophet, show that were they transplanted into our life, and taught our language, they would still be completely at a loss to follow the reasoning of our modern literature. Ptah-hotep or Ezechiel could not move in modern society. Aristotle or Menander, on the other hand, would only need to understand the names invented for our modern discoveries. In all moral and social questions they would at once find their way, and enjoy even our poetry and our fiction. But what is more striking, even the mediaeval baron and the mediaeval saint would feel vastly more out of place among us than the intelligent Greek. The satire and scepticism of our modern society, the decay of fixed belief, the omnipotence of free discussion as shown by press and platform, the rule of private interest over patriotism and self-sacrifice — all these features would be very congenial to the Greek, while they would shock and perplex the Crusader. Commerce and speculation, debate and diplomacy, would delight the clever Athenian. He would recognise the teach- ing of his nation in poetry, architecture, and paint- ing ; and the manifest superiority of the old models would save him from feeling inferior in the face of pur other progress. Let us invert the whole case, and the result would be very analogous. If one of us were transported to Periclean Athens, provided he were a man of high culture, he would find life and manners strangely like our own, strangely modern, as he might term it. The thoughts and feelings' of modern life would be there without the appliances, I.] INTRODUCTION. 3 and the high standard of general culture would more than counterbalance sundry wants in material com- fort. For these reasons Greek social life must be far more interesting to general readers than any other phase of ancient history. Some of the problems which are still agitating our minds were settled by the Greeks, others, if not settled, were at least dis- cussed with a freedom and an acuteness now unat- tainable. Others, again, were solved in strange violation of our notions of morals and good taste ; and when such a people as the Greeks stand opposed to us, even in vital principles, we cannot reject their verdict without weighing their reasons. The social life of the Greeks has often been handled, especially by German and French authors. But the ponderous minuteness and luxury of cita- tion in the works of the former have obscured the general effect, and leave the ordinary reader with no distinct impression on his mind. The crushing weapon of modern criticism has in Germany shivered classical philology into splinters, and each man is intent on gathering up, and claiming as his own a fragment or two, which he analyses with wearying accuracy. The French essays on Greek life are of an opposite description. They usually aim at bril- liancy and esprit alone, and gain these qualities at the frequent sacrifice of accuracy and critical re- search. Their authors are often ready to uphold, for example, a spurious treatise against all critical ob- jections, however sound, provided it affords them a striking trait to complete their social picture. In SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. fact, a sound knowledge of Greek has not yet been diffused among the French, and so their isolated Hellenists, brilliant as they are, do not write in an atmosphere of correcting friends and carping critics. In spite, therefore, of the abundance of materials at hand, and the abundance of theories based upon them, there is still room for attempts to select salient features, and to bring before the modern public an accurate picture of Greek life,' not in its trivial details, but in its large and enduring features. A more than incidental notice of the peculiarities of food and dress, and of the plan and arrangement of houses, is but weariness and idle labour. We want to know how they reasoned, and felt, and loved ; why they laughed and why they wept; how they taught and what they learned. But alas ! to these questions we can only find full answers from one city, and from one brief epoch. Athenian culture under the Athenian democracy may indeed be regarded as the highest type and outcome of the Greek mind. But there, and there only, can we find sufficient materials to discuss the principal social question in separate essays. The earlier ages are only known to us through the scanty remains of epic and lyric poetry, which afford many hints and suggestions, and in the case of the simpler epic age even allow us to draw a general sketch of life and manners ; but in the far more interesting lyric age — the transition from the old to the new life — they fail us utterly, and allow little more than scattered reflections often inconsistent I.] INTRODUCTION. 5 and scanty inferences always uncertain. The essays therefore on the Greeks of the epic and lyric ages may be regarded as introductory to those in which Athenian life is more amply described. However unsatisfactory, these earlier chapters seem necessary in an historical work, where the later stages cannot be regarded as born in full armour, like the goddess Athene, but as growing insensibly from long sown seed and in long prepared soil. In connection, more particularly, with such theories as those of Mr. Froude, which endeavour to get rid of the refinements of philosophers and politicians, and to reduce the motives of society to rude violence and successful force — in relation to such theories I cannot but think that the best possible antidote is to study the various phases through which the society and the morals of such a people as the Greeks passed. It will be seen how they began with rude notions, how in the Homeric days the now fashionable theory that 'Might is Right' was practically carried out — of this the present essay will give ample proofs. Even deli- cacy of feeling and chivalry of sentiment will be very inadequate, if the check of sound laws, based upon pure moral feeling diffused throughout a society, be not ever there to repress and to educate. We may then see, in succeeding ages, this social and moral force contending, and in the end contending success- fully, against the disintegrating and barbarising forces opposed to it — the party struggles and social hatreds so prominent in Greece. And so we arrive at the Attic period, in which the free citizen could boast SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. that the state protected him both from violence and injustice, so that men learned to postpone wounded feelings and outraged honour to the majesty of the law, that forbad all violence, even in the vindication of personal injury. And so the refinement of Greek manners culminated in the gentle Menander, who brings his philosophy to aid the dictates of the law, and warns us that controversy and disputes are dis- agreeable and inconsistent with true comfort, and that a true gentleman would rather lose advantages and even submit to annoyance than ruffle his temper, and agitate himself with either wrangling or retalia- tion ^. Unfortunately these developments within single states were not accompanied by similar im- provements in their external relations. The Greeks never attained the higher condition of subjecting their public disputes to a system of international law or public arbitration. But we may well excuse it in them, seeing that in our nineteenth century this wise and civilised method of avoiding war is but seldom invoked, and only submitted to with discontent and with grumbling. I think it will farther be shown that ' See his Vtoiff&&, frag. 3 (ed. Meineke), ' He is the best man, Gorgias, who knows best how to control himself when injured (oittis aSiKaaOu TiKiim' iTriffTor' i-yKpaTois), for this hot temper and extreme bitterness is clear evidence to all of smallness of mind.' This sentiment, so different from those of Euripides, is repeated in other fragments ; see frag, incert. 25, and yviii^ai 47. The latter passage is almost Christian in tone : ' Prefer to be injured rather than to injure, for (in so doing) you will blame others, and you will escape censure.' If he had not promised us the luxury of blaming others, the sentiment would be thoroughly Christian. I.] INTRODUCTION. 7 the general public of ancient Greece did not approach so nearly to the enlightenment of its intellectual leaders, as our modern public does. We find, for example, in the ordinary life of Athens, cruelties and barbarities so violently in conflict with the humanity of a Socrates, a Euripides, or a Plato, as to astonish us, and make us doubt our estimate of Attic culture. These harsh contrasts would, I think, exist now among us, but for two great differences in our society — one of them the direct result of Christianity. They are the invention of printing, and the abolition of slavery. The former has brought the leaders of public opinion into a close contact with the masses, quite unattainable in ancient days. In its modern develop- ment, the newspaper press, with all its faults, certainly brings home to the public mind all cases of cruelty and injustice with a promptness impossible even in busy and gossipping Athens, and so the public conscience is not only made sensitive, but has ob- tained a powerful organ for uttering its immediate censure. The latter has weaned the dominant classes from that contempt of human rights and human emotions which, even in our own day, is manifest in those who live as masters or rulers over degraded populations. Nothing, for example, is more frequent in our Co- lonial Official, and still more in his wife, than their impatience of the rights and feelings of the lower classes at home, which they are obliged to respect, after their habit of lording it over inferior races. 8 SOCIAL GREECE. I suppose the planters of the slave states in America would exhibit similar feelings. If these things be true, it will appear that the points of superiority in our condition to that of the Greeks were partly due to an accident in our civilisation — the discovery of a rapid means of multiplying books, but partly to a higher and better religion. This latter is of course the great contrast, and the great advantage which we have gained. But I confess that when I compare the religion of Christ with that of Zeus, Apollo, and Aphrodite, and consider the enormous, the unspeak- able contrasts, I wonder not at the greatness, but at the smallness of the advance in public morality which has been attained. It is accordingly here, where the difference ought to be greatest, that we are led to wonder most at the superiority of Greek genius which, in spite of an immoral and worthless theology, worked out in its higher manifestations a morality approaching in many points the best type of modern Christianity. Socrates and Plato are far superior to the Jewish moralist, they are far superior to the average Christian moralist ; it is only in the matchless teaching of Christ himself that we find them surpassed. So then the social life of the Greeks is more than a matter of antiquarian curiosity, it is of practical value and interest to us all. CHAPTER II. THE GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. The great vexed question of the origin and com- position of the Homeric poems Ues happily beyond our present scope'. To those who desire to study the social indications in these great epics, it is a rnatter of small importance to know whether they were composed by one poet, by two, or by many ; whether they grew up gradually in a school of rhapsodists, or whether they sprang complete from a single genius. Even the ultra-sceptical theory, which holds that the Iliad and Odyssey, as we have them, did not acquire their present form till late in the Attic age, — even this theory, supposing it were shown not impossible, would little affect us. Two facts alone we demand, and these will doubtless be conceded by critics of every description ; first, that whenever or wherever the Homeric poems were arranged or produced,' the great result was accom- plished by building with pre-existing materials, by assimilating or embodying older and shorter lays : secondly, that whatever may be the exact age of these older materials, at least this is certain, that they describe a state of society different from and ' My views will be found in Macmillan's Magazine for October, 1878, and February, 1879. lo SOCIAL GREECE. [cil. more primitive than that implied in any other relic of Greek literature. A qualified exception, as to antiquity, may perhaps be made in favour of Hesiod, but the social state described by him, if contemporaneous, yet belongs to a different part of Greece and to a different rank in society. So far then as he is contemporaneous, we may call in his assistance as affording a contrast, and possibly as completing the picture left us by Homer. For the social attitude of Hesiod seems to differ curiously from that of all the rest of the earlier Greek poets, except perhaps Hipponax. It has hardly been remarked, how intensely aristocratic was their tone, and how they uniformly addressed themselves to the powers that be, often in pointed exclusion of all inferior classes. The Rhapsodists addressed kings and princes, and sang at courts. The Lyric poets addressed either the gods, the ty- rants, or those close aristocratic circles that swayed the Greek cities on the abolition of monarchies. Even the Gnomic poets were aristocrats, and spoke their wisdom to their compeers only. No Greek poet ad- dressed the Demos till it too became the sovereign Demos, and till the distinction of higher and lower classes became as it were inverted by the radical spirit of the times. Apart, then, from the scanty fragments of popular songs, no voice directly ad- dressed to the lower classes has reached us, save the plain shrewdness of Hesiod, whose ' Works and Days' (unlike the Georgics of his Roman imitator, written in the interests of the rulers) gives us some n.] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. it evidence of the poor and shady side of Greek life in early days. It is even possible that he describes the Homeric society from a widely diverse point of view '. And if it be the same society, there can be little doubt that the genuine Hesiod's picture must be in many respects truer than Homer's. It is almost painful to say anything in the least derogatory to the Iliad or Odyssey, especially when they are almost our only authority for the earliest phase of Greek society. But I am convinced that all the critics, even Grote and the sceptical Germans, have overrated the accuracy of the pictures of life given in these poems. They have been persuaded by the intense reality and the natural simplicity which have made these scenes unapproachable in their charm, and they have thought that such qualities could only coexist with a simple and faithful reproduction of the circumstances actually surrounding the poet's life. But surely this argument, irresistible up to a certain point, has been carried too far. A poet of genius may surely be capable of modifying and colouring, even when he is observing and copying nature. Moreover, he must even endeavour to do so, if he sets himself to describe an ideal state of things, or if he desires to please a rich patron, to whom actual surroundings are in many respects unpleasant. Now these were the very conditions under which the epic poets composed. Their poems ' Cp. Horn. 8 490. I quote the Books of the Odyssey by small Greek letters, those of the Iliad by capitals, according to a convenient German habit. 13 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. were certainly intended foir recitation at the courts of kings and chiefs. They were intended to honour these chiefs by extolling the deeds and lives of their ancestors. And so an ideal state must be described — a state evidently differing only in degree from the poet's own experience, else the truth and reality of his picture must have suffered — but yet differing from it in the greater interference of the gods, in the larger size and strength of the heroes, and in the greater valour of their deeds. These differences are acknowledged by the poets themselves, but are we sure that they confined them- selves to these .'' Are we sure that they did not ac- commodate other matters to the wishes or the regrets of their noble hearers ? Thus, for example, the rank and file of the army are there to be marshalled by the kings, and to raise the shout of battle, but then they disappear from the action, and leave the field perfectly clear for the chiefs to perform their deeds of valour. There is not, I think, an example in all the Iliad of the chief falling, or even being wounded, by an ignoble hand. Such a misfortune was too shocking to the sensibilities of an aristocratic au- dience. Amid the cloud of missiles that were flying on the plains of Troy, amid the crowd of chiefs and kings that were marshalled on either side, we never hear how a ' certain man drew a bow at a venture, and smote a king between the joints of the harness.' Yet this must surely have occurred in any prolonged combats such as those about the walls of Troy. Here, then, is a plain departure from truth, and II.] GREEKS. OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 13 even from reasonable probability. It is indeed a mere omission which does not offend the reader; but such inaccuracies suggest serious reflections. If the epic poets ignore the importance of the masses on the battlefield, is it not likely that they underrate it in the agora} Is it not possible that here, too, to please their patrons, they describe the glorious ages of the past as the days when the assembled people would not question the superior wisdom of their betters, but merely came together to be taught and to applaud? I cannot, therefore, as Mr. Grote does, accept the political condition of things in the Homeric poems, especially in the Iliad, as a safe guide to the political life of Greece in the poet's own day. The figure of Thersites seems drawn with special spite and venom, as a satire upon the first critics that rose up among the people, and questioned the divine right of kings to do wrong. We may be sure the real Thersites, from whom the poet drew his picture, was a very different and a far more serious power in debate, than the mis- shapen buffoon of the Iliad. But the king who had been thwarted and exposed by him in the day would over his evening cups enjoy the poet's tra- vesty, and long for the good old times, when he could put down all impertinent criticism by the stroke of his knotty sceptre. Indeed the Homeric agora could hardly have existed had it been so idle a form as the poets represent. As the lower classes were carefully marshalled on the battlefield from a full sense of the importance which the poet denies 14 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. them, so they were marshalled in the public assem- bly, where we may be sure their weight told with equal effect, though the poet neglected it for the greater glory of the counselling chiefs. Would that we had fuller sketches from the tamer Hesiod ! He, at least, does not sing in the interest of courts and kings, and he moreover gives us a glimpse into the sorrows and severities which encompassed the lower classes while the courts may have revelled in luxury and splendour. Yet even his wisdom, as we have it, is not without suspicion from a very different cause, for his works have suffered more than most Greek poems from in- terpolations and additions. Their moral and didactic tone, as well as their fragmentary character, made them at an early period a favourite handbook of education, especially as the moral advices of later Gnomic poets could be foisted in, and taught under the venerable name of the older Hesiod. Though I am not here concerned with critical questions, it were not right to begin a social sketch based upon such evidence, without at once telling the reader the nature and the imperfections of that evidence. More especially when I intend making considerable use of Grote's remarkable chapter on the ' Manners of the Heroic Age,' it is necessary to warn the reader against the too ready faith here shown by a great writer, sometimes imbued with a very sceptical spirit. Other points of difference will disclose themselves in the sequel. But I cannot pass on without supplementing briefly IL] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE, 15 a large defect in the attitude of Grote and other English authors on the Homeric age. They lay- aside all inquiry into the previous conditions of Greece as impossible and useless. The very civil- ised life of the Greek and Trojan heroes is assumed as a starting-point, having developed itself, we know not how, from the rude barbarism which Thucydides rightly considers to have been the really primitive state, the v&x\ti}o\& juventus of Hellenism. Yet surely the wonder of Aristotle is justified, when he expreses himself at a loss to explain how a monarchy such as that of Agamemnon could spring from such con- ditions. I cannot but think that the consistent voice of the older Greek legends, coupled with what we know of early Phoenician and Egyptian history, wellnigh solves the difficulty. The remains of the stone age found lately under the lava at TherasiaS are too remote and isolated to admit of any safe inferences. But the older Semitic histories, the Egyptian in- scriptions, and the traditions of the Greeks them- ' Cp. Revue ArchSologiqiie, vol. xvi. pp. 141-7. The islands of Santorin and Therasia in the Mgean Sea are the sides of a gigantic volcano, of which the crater is now a deep sea basin, surrounded by precipitous cliffs, which slope gradually outward to the open sea. Deep under these lava slopes there have been found buried the remains of what the French call an ante-historic Pompeii. Stone implements, some rude gold ornaments, pottery with ornamental patterns, a rude house, and some skeletons have been disinterred. Our oldest Greek authorities on Thera, such as Pindar, make no allusion to its having been a volcano, so that even the tradition of this great irruption had died away in his- torical Greece. I mention these facts here, as not sufficiently known ; to discuss them would be irrelevant. 1 6 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH, selves, agree that the Phoenicians certainly, and perhaps the Egyptians, sailed with powerful fleets through the ^gean, and traded at enormous advan- tage with the rude inhabitants of the coasts and islands, by means of their imposing wealth and cul- ture. They settled also in the Greek waters, partly for commercial and mining purposes, as for example at Thasos, — where Herodotus saw a whole mountain disembowelled by their operations \ — but partly also from the desire of forming new empires. Just as distinguished Athenians, like Miltiades or Iphicrates, became great princes among the ' butter - eating Thracians,' so we may suspect that the legends of Minos, of Cadmus, and of Danaus indicate sovereign- ties set up by these civilised foreigners in prehistoric days among the Greeks. They possessed the requi- sites which Aristotle sought in vain among the chiefs of his own nation, and gained their power by intro- ducing great public benefits to the ruder Greeks, as well as by the splendour of their circumstances, and the superior arms of their followers. The legend of Minos "^ seems to us the echo of the most important of these sovereignties, but the prehistoric ruins at Argos, Mycenae, and Orchomenus, show that Crete was not the only seat of culture. Gradually the national spirit was roused against * ovpos fiiya avarerpaiJLfiivov kv ry ^TjT-qir^t. vi. 47. ' I agree rather with Holm, who considers Minos to represent a purely Phoenician power, than with E. Curtius, who thinks it was an Hellenic, or semi-Hellenic power. All the legends point to Phoenician sources, and to Phoenician mythology, in connection with this king, nor do I see any Greek feature in his rule, so far as we know it. 11.] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 17 these foreigners. As the legends tell us of Theseus conquering the Amazon worshippers of Astarte, and refusing his tribute to the servants of Moloch, so I suppose Greek, perhaps at first semi-Greek, chiefs, the offspring of connections between the invaders and the natives, began gradually to dispossess and supplant the Semitic forerunners of Greek culture. But the splendour of their rule was too attractive to be abolished. The native chiefs seem therefore to have succeeded to the power and wealth already centred at Argos, Mycenae, Crete, Orchomenus, and other such favourable positions. The great Cyclo- pean ruins are found on the very sites indicated in Homer, as the seats of the greatest monarchs. Ac- cordingly, I conceive Agamemnon, Menelaus, Nestor, and other of the richer chiefs, but especially the Atreidae, to have rather inherited a power and wealth established originally by the enlightened despotism of Semitic merchant princes, and not gradually ac- quired by the extension of a local patriarchal sway. The legends are with me, and so is Aristotle, who cannot conceive monarchies arising in Greece gra-i dually, but rather in consequence of some special circumstance, such as some great public benefit conferred by a prominent individual. The splendour of the palaces of Menelaus and of Alcinous, who had their walls covered with a profusion of bright metal, seems to point to a kind of decoration essentially Eastern and not Hellenic. Even in late times, the only old hereditary monarchy in Greece, that of Sparta, retained, in the public mourning for the c i8 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. kings, features so strikingly foreign and Asiatic, that they called for special notice from Herodotus \ If therefore Agamemnon inherited his splendour from such predecessors, it will follow that the earliest form of the monarchy was not patriarchal but despotic, and that the Homeric King of men succeeded to a power with great pretensions, but practically limited in all directions by the rise of petty chieftains, more or less independent. The general tone of the Iliad and Odyssey implies then, not a nascent, but a decaying order of things ; subordinate chiefs rebelling against their suzerains; nobles violating the rights of their absent chiefs. The fierce spirit of independence in the Greek already stood opposed to the idea of a monarchy hallowed by precedent and tradition ; and it was even then plain to thinking men (like Hesiod) that this profound antagonism could only be solved by such a change in the order of things as would give the majority an interest in maintaining the govern- ment. This majority, at first, only included the aristocracy, and so, when the Dorian invasion had dislocated Greece, aristocratical types of government resulted. But with the development of commerce, and with the depression of the nobles by the tjTrantf^ ^ vi. 58. ' The custom of the Lacedsemonians upon tiie-death of their kings is the same as that of the barbarians in AsiarTbTmost of the bar- barians now practise the same custom when their kings die.' He describes these customs in detail. The public lament over the deceased king, ' affirming that the last king is always the best,' is very like the 'Irish cry' still practised in the mountainous regions of Kerry and Connemara. '• II.] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 19 who rose up among them, the lower classes awoke to a sense of their rights, and so, upon a second dis- location of Greece (the Persian wars) democracies re- sulted as an equally natural development. These later stages are beyond my present scope. I wish merely to indicate how the Homeric poems represent to me the close of an epoch — almost a state of decay preceding a newer order of things — and that I, therefore, estimate the society and the morals of the Iliad and Odyssey quite differently from those writers who have compared them with primitive conditions in other nations. Of course primitive features remained, as they do in every na- tion ; but they were combined with vices which betray the decadence of culture, and with virtues rather springing from mature reflection and long experience than from the spontaneous impulse of a generous instinct. Mr. Grote, Mr. Gladstone, and others, have made the Homeric age more familiar than any other phase of Greek life to English readers. They have accepted the descriptions of the rhapsodists as a literal account of a real contemporaneous society; they have moreover deduced, with exceeding subtlety, all the inferences which can be extracted from the poems in favour of Homeric honour and purity. Every casual utterance is weighted with the deepest possible meaning ; every ordinary piece of good-nature attributed to profound and self-denying benevolence. We are told that morals in historic Greece had decayed ; that a social state of real refinement and purity had passed away, to make c a 20 SOCIAL GREECE. *_ [CH. way for cold calculation and selfish aggrandisement. How far this picture is real we shall see in the sequel. But the labours of these ingenious authors have ref. lieved me of the task of minutely describing all thej details of Homeric life. The great masterpieces them- selves are accessible to all in the translations which have of late years poured from the press. I shall, therefore, confine myself to the features in which the Homeric Greek was the parent of the historical Greek, noticing incidentally such contrasts as must naturally suggest themselves in the inquiry. The mediaeval knights, with whom it is fashionable to compare the princes of the Iliad and Odyssey, were wont to sum up the moral perfection which they es^ t;eemed under one complex term — a term for which there is no equivalent in Greek — the term HONOUR. It may be easily and sufficiently analysed into four component ideas, those of cotirage, truth, compassion, and loyalty. No man could approach the ideal of chivalry, or rank himself among gentlemen and men of honour, who was not ready to contend, when occasion arose, against any odds, and thus to en- counter death rather than yield one inch from his post. He must feel himself absolutely free from the stain of a single lie, or even of an equivocatien.™ He must be ever ready to help the weak and the distressed, whether they be so by nature, as in the case of women and children, or by circumstances, .as in the case of men overpowered by numbers. He must with his heart, and not with mere eye-servjce, obey God and. the king, or even such other authority II. J GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 21 as he voluntarily pledged himself to obey. A knight who violated any of these conditions, even if he es- caped detection at the hands of his fellows, felt liimself degraded, and untrue to the oath taken before God, and the obligation which he had bound himself to fulfil. This, I conceive, was the ideal of knight- hood. Let us now turn to the Homeric poems to obtain information on these four points, remembering that, as the real knight may have fallen short of the ideal we have just sketched, so doubtless the real Homeric Greeks were considerably worse than the ideal cha- racters depicted by the rhapsodists. I believe I shall run counter to an old-established belief when I say that the courage of the Homeric chiefs — in this types of their historical descendants — was of a second-rate order. It was like the courage of the modern French, dependent upon excitement, and vanishing quickly before depression and delay. No doubt the Greeks were a warlike nation, like the French, fond of glory, and revelling in excitement ; but they did not possess that stubborn valour which was the duty of the medieval knight, and which is the physical characteristic of the English and German soldier. With the exception of Achilles and of Dio- mede, all the chiefs in the Iliad are subject to panics, and fly before the enemy. Of course, the flattering bard ascribes these disgraceful scenes to the special interference of the gods, but as he equally attributes special feats of valour to a like interference, we may discount the marvellous element, and regard these 23 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. men, as we do a French army, to be capable of splendid acts of daring and of courage, but liable to sudden relapse into dismay and craven flight ^. Even Achilles flies in fear from the pursuit of the river Scamander, but this is rather the dread of an ignoble death, as he himself says, than proper, cowardice. Ajax, who approaches nearest of the ordinary men in the poem to our notions of a stubborn soldier — even he is surprised by panic, and makes for the ships. There are farther indications of the same thing in the Odyssey. When Ulysses hears from Circe (k 496) what sufferings he has yet to undergo, he tells us himself : ' So she spake, but my spirit was broken within me, and I sat crying on the bed, and I felt no more desire to live and see the light of the sun.' This was natural enough, but very diflferent from the courage, not only of the mediaeval knight, but of the modern gentleman. Still worse, when the hero is telling Achilles among the Shades of the valour of his son Neoptolemus, he says that as the chiefs en- tered the wooden horse, though they were the best of the Greeks, yet 'the other leaders of the Danai wiped tears from their eyes, and the limbs of each trembled beneath him, but Neoptolemus alone neither grew pale nor wept ^.' ""^^ ■ The courtly Pindar maintains the Homeric doctrine {Nem. ix. 27) when he says : iv -j&p Sat/iovlotai ipS^ois (pevyovn xal ircuSes SeSiv ' in panics even sons of the gods run away'— a sentiment which no trouba- dour would have ventured to utter. ' Cp. X 524 sq. IvO' &\\oi Aavauv ^y^Topea ^Si /USovTfs ddKpvi t' ii/iSpyvwTo rpiiiOv ff brth fvia ixiaTOV II.] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 33 These hints in an ideal description, professing to tell of the highest possible heroism, indicate plainly that the Greeks of the heroic age were no extraor- dinary heroes, and that they were not superior in the quality of courage to the Greeks of history. In this respect, then, the Achaean chiefs were indeed but the forerunners of their descendants. The same combination of warlike ardour, but of alternating valour, meets us all through Greek history'. The Athenians, the brave people who first ventured to look the barbarians in the face, whether at Sardis, or at Marathon, as Herodotus says — these brave Athenians are frequently seized with panics and run for their lives. The same may be said of all the Greeks, except the Spartans, who succeeded in curing their national defect by a very strict and complete discipline. ^ But this discipline controlled all their lives, Ravov S' ouiroTt ird/iwav iyaiv tSov IxpBaKiioiaiv oiJt' SjxpTicavTa XP^^ H&WifLov ovre •napuSiv SaKfiv d/iopianevov. See also « 198 sq., where the weeping of Ulysses and his men is almost ludicrous. I may as well here cite an historical parallel to show the unity of Greek sentiment at every epoch. At the conclusion of the 21st oration in our remains of Lysias (the diroXoyia StopoSoKias) the speaker says, ' whenever I was about to risk my life in the naval battles, I never lamented or wept, or kept talking about my wife and children, and saying how dreadful it would be, if I dying for my country were to leave them orphans and desolate." Thus the speaker takes special credit to himself as an exception to the general rule. ' Thus in a curious passage of Plato's Gorgias (Jowett, iii. 94), Cal- licles, in answer to Socrates, tells us that brave men and cowards are equally pained at the approach of the enemy, and equally pleased at their departure. He does not contemplate that bravery which delights in danger, and seeks it out. 24 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. and sacrificed all higher objects to that of making them stand firm in their ranks. I conclude this discipline to have been unnatural and strained, from the fact that no other Greek city, much as they all admired Spartan Organisation, ever attempted to imitate it. When we now-a-days see the German armies better disciplined than our own, we forth- with propose to reform ourselves on their model. No such attempt ever occurs in Greek history. This could hardly have been so, but for the reason just assigned. The Spartan training was so oppressive that not even the certainty of victory in battle could induce other Greek politicians to recommend it, or other Greek citizens to adopt it. Thucydides hints at this very plainly, and, in the mouth of Pericles, shows that, even with inferior military training, the real advantages are on the side of wider culture. Aristotle supports the same view in stronger and more explicit terms. I cite these authorities to show how artificial and factitious a thing the Spartan valour was, and how different from the spirit of the Viking, the Baron, and the Yeoman. We know too how even the Spartan valour collapsed as soon as Epaminondas met it with superior tactics, and how little idea there was, either at Leuctra or Sphacteria, of resisting to the death. The Greeks, then, though a very warlike were not a very courageous people, and we may affirm of them, in a lesser degree indeed, what Tacitus says of the Britons : ' In deposcendis periculis eadem audacia, et ubi advenere, in detrectandis eadem formido.' II.] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. a5 The reasons of this curious combination are obvious enough, and worth a moment's digression. In the first place, the Greeks, from Homer's day downward, were an exceedingly sensitive people. Evidences of this feature crowd upon us in the Iliad and Odyssey. The delicate tact with which unpleasant subjects are avoided in conversation shows how easily men were hurt by them, and how perfectly the speaker could foretell it by his own feelings. In fact, so keenly alive are the Homeric Greeks to this great principle of politeness, that it seriously interferes with their truth- fulness, just as in the present day the Irish peasant, with the same lively imagination and the same sen- sitivenesSj will instinctively avoid disagreeable things, even if true, and ' prophesy smooth things ' when he desires especially to please. He is not less reluctant to be the bearer of bad news than the typical messenger in Greek tragedy, who complains, in regular stock phrases, of the hard and ungrateful duty thrust upon him by untoward circumstances. To this mental sensitiveness there was doubtless joined a corresponding bodily sensitiveness. An acute sense of pain and of pleasure, delicate nerves of taste and touch — these gifts were essential for the artistic products in which the Greeks excelled. We know how important a place was held in historical times by cooks, and how keenly the Greeks enjoyed the more refined pleasures of the table. So we may find Plato's contemporaries disputing in music on the difference of notes almost identical, showing that they appre- ciated dissonances which we consider unimportant. 26 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. I cannot parallel these facts in Homer, except by a curious case of sensitiveness in smell. When Menelaus is windbound off the coast of Egypt, and at his wit's end, a goddess (Eidothea) explains to him how to catch and interrogate Proteus, and engages to place him in ambush, which she does by concealing him with three comrades under fresh sealskins (8 440 sqq.). These men were in danger of their lives, and were engaged on the perilous errand of doing violence to a marine god. Yet the point which left its mark most strongly on Menelaus' mind was the bad smell of the sealskins! 'That would have been a most dreadful ambush ; for a most deadly stench of sea- bred seals distressed us sore. For who would lie down beside a sea-monster ? But the goddess saved us, and devised a great boon. She brought and put very sweet-smelling ambrosia under our nostrils, and it destroyed (counteracted) the smell of the seal.' If we combine with this great delicacy of sensibility the gloomy and hopeless views which the Homeric Greeks held concerning a future life, we shall see good reason for their dread of death. For although Homer distinctly admits an after life, and even in- troduces us to it in the Odyssey, he represents the greatest kings and heroes in weakness and in misery, without hope or enjoyment, save in hearing the vague and scanty rumours that reached them from the world of mortal men. The blessed islands of the West were indeed even then a home for the dead (6 564 sqq.), but they had not yet been opened to 11 ] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 27 moral worth, as in the days of Pindar ^ They were reserved for those who, like Menelaus, had the good fortune of being nearly related to the gods by marriage or family connections. From this aristocratic heaven therefore even Agamemnon, Achilles, and Ajax were excluded, and wandered forlorn in the doleful meadow of asphodel. There will be less controversy as to the low sense of truth among Homeric Greeks. At no period did the nation ever attain that high standard which is the great feature in Germanic civilisation. Even the Romans, with all their coarseness, stood higher in this respect. But neither in Iliad nor Odyssey is there, except in phrases, any reprobation of deceit as such. To deceive an enemy is meritorious, to deceive a stranger innocent, to deceive even a friend perfectly unobjectionable, if any object is to be gained. So it is remarked of Menelaus, as it were exceptionally, that he will tell the truth, if you press him, for he is very considerate (Treirvvixivos). This was said to Telemachus, who was expecting melancholy news, and in such a case I have already observed that the Greeks would almost certainly avoid the truth. But the really leading characters (except Achilles) in the Odyssey and Iliad do not hesitate at all manner of lying. Ulysses is perpetually inventing, and so is his patroness, Pallas Athene, and she actually mentions this quality of wily deceit as her special ground of love and affection for him (v 328). Zeus deceives both gods and men, the other gods deceive Zeus ; in ' Cp. 01. ii. 57 sqq., and the famous frag, of his Bpijvoi. 28 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. fact the whole Homeric society is full of guile and falsehood. There is indeed as yet a check upon men, which is often ignored in later Greek society. There is still a belief in the gods, and an expectation that if they are called to witness a transaction by means of an oath, that they will punish deceit. This belief, ap- parently surviving from an earlier and simpler state of society, must have been rudely shaken in Homeric times, when we consider the morality of Olympus in the epic poetry. The poets clearly held tliat the gods, if they were under no restraint, or fear of punishment from Zeus, were at liberty to deceive as they liked. One safeguard as yet remained, the oath by the Styx, the penalties of violating which are enumerated in Hesiod's Theogony, and consist of nine years' transportation, with solitary confinement and hard labour\ As for other oaths, the Hymn to Hermes shows that in succeeding generations their solemnity was openly ridiculed. Among the Homeric gods, as well as among the heroes, there were indeed old-fashioned characters who adhered to probity. The character of Apollo is unstained by deceit. So is that of Menelaus. But Apollo fails in defendmg his favourite against the reckless party politics of Here and Pallas ; he gives way in battle before Poseidon ; he is like Menelaus among men, an emi- nently respectable, but second-rate personage. The experience of Homeric men was aged enough to know that probity secured no man from the troubles 1 Cp. his Theog. 793 sqq. II.] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 29 of life and the reverses of fortune. The gods were often ungrateful and thankless, and so the weight of public opinion inclined decidedly to the belief that honesty was indeed respectable, and of better repute than deceit, but that it was not safe to practise it without the help of superior forced So Achilles was master of the situation, and to him lying was useless to attain ends that might be better attained by force. This subject will naturally recur when we come to compare the Homeric with later Greeks^. We pass to the third element in chivalrous honour,, a sense of compassion for the weak, and an obliga- tion to assist the oppressed. Unfortunately this duty appears to have been delegated to Zeus, whose amours and other amusements often prevented him from at- tending to his business. How badly he performed it in this respect is plain from the very pathetic passages ' As similar states of society produce similar philosophies, so we find the very same attitude in Machiavelli's Principe, especially in his celebrated i8th chapter, entitled ' In che modo i principi debbiano osservare la fede.' He begins by praising good faith, but observing that history shows great princes to have succeeded by the. opposite principle. In fact the prince must be partly a fox, to detect snares, and partly a lion, to terrify the wolves. ' Non puo pertanto un signer prudente nfe debbe osservar la fede, quando tale osservanzia gli torni contro, e che sono spente le cagioni . che la feciono promettere.' He adds the usual excuse : ' E se gli uomini fossero tutti buoni, questo precetto non saria buono, ma perchfe son tristi, e non 1' osserverebbono a te, tu ancora non 1' hai da osservare a loro.' He goes on to show that the virtues of honour, probity, and good faith must be simulated, or else men will not be deceived, though he observes that men are so silly, or so bound by present necessities, that there is little difficulty in deceiving them. The whole chapter is the most characteristic in a very characteristic treatise. ' Ct. below, p. 115. 30 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. in which the condition of the decrepit father, the for- lorn widow, and the helpless orphan are described. We must not for a moment imagine that the Homeric age was wanting in sympathy for children. On the contrary, Herodotus alone, of later Greek authors, shows this sympathy as strongly as we find it in the Iliad. The Homeric similes— and no similes are more thoroughly realistic and drawn from actual experience — constantly imply it. ' As a mother drives away the fly from her child when it lies in sweet sleep.' ' Why do you weep like an infant girl, who running along by her mother, begs to be carried, and holding on by her dress delays the hurrying woman, but looks up at her with her eyes full of tears in order that she may be taken up and carried.' Apollo destroys the earth- works of the Greeks ' very easily, as a child treats the shingle by the sea-side, who, when he has heaped it up in his childish sport, in his sport again levels it all with his hands and feet ^.' These comparisons are evidently drawn from the same society which suggested the de- lightful picture (in Z) of Andromache with her nurse and darling son, coming to bid farewell to Hector as he was hurrying to the battle. The whole picture — the child ' fair as a star,' his terror at Hector's helmet and nodding crest, the strong love of the parents sorrowing at the very prospect of misfortune for their child ; — this picture, which I dare not abridge, and which is too long for quotation, shows no ordinary feeling for help- less innocence. But all this sympathy in the poet, and doubtless in the society which he described, did ' Cf. A 130 ; O 361 ; and n 7. II.] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 51 not save little children from cruelty and from neglect. There is no passage in the two poems, if we except that on the dog Argus, which will bring more tears into hard modern eyes than the lament of Andro- mache over Hector (X 482 sqq. Lord Derby's transl.), ' Now thou beneath the depths of earth art gone, Gone to the viewless shades; and me has left A widow in thy house, in deepest woe, Our child an infant still, thy child and mine. Ill-fated parents both 1 nor thou to him. Hector, shalt be a guard, nor he to thee; For though he 'scape this tearful war with Greece, Yet nought for him remains but ceaseless woe. And strangers on his heritage shall seize. No yoimg companions own the orphan boy. With downcast eyes, and cheeks bedewed with tears. His father's friends approaching, pinched with want, He hangs upon the skirt of one, of one He plucks the cloak ; perchance in pity some May at their tables let him sip the cup. Moisten his lips, but scarce his palate touch : While youths with both surviving parents blest May drive him from their feast with blows and taunts : Begone, thy father sits not at our board! Then weeping to his widowed mother's arms He flies, that orphan boy, Astyanax,' etc. It is here the lamentable condition of the orphan that strikes us so forcibly. 'Qui a vu la misere des hommes n'a rien vu, il faut voir la misere des femmes ; qui a vu la misere des femmes, n'a rien vu, il faut voir la misere des enfants.' How different, for example, do we find the Irish peasants, with whom I have already compared the Greeks, where the neighbours divide among them without complaint 33 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. the children left destitute by the death or emigration of the parents, and extend their scanty fare and their wretched homestead to the orphan as to their own children. The Homeric gentleman, of whose refinement and delicate politeness we hear so much, was far removed from such generosity. We feel almost painfully the beauty of the simile, by which the poet pictures the joy of Ulysses, when, after two nights and two days in the deep, he sees land from the summit of the great rocking wave (e 394) : ' As when a father on the point to die. Who for long time in sore disease hath lain, By the strong fates tormented heavily Till the pulse faileth for exceeding pain. Feels the life stirring in his bones again, While glad at heart his children smile around; He also smiles^the gods have loosed his chain- So vifelcome seemed the land, with forest crowned, And he rejoicing swam, and yearned to feel the ground'.' And again {& 533) : ' As when a woman weeps fall- ing upon the body of her dear lord, who has fallen before his city, and commanding his people, in de- fending the town and his children from the pitiless day [of slavery]. She then, seeing him gasping in death, casts her arms about him with shrill cries. But they (the enemy) striking her with spears on the back and shoulders, bring her into slavery, to have sorrow and misery, and her cheeks waste with piteous woe.' Little, indeed, need be said about the respect for ' Worsley's transl. II] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 33 the rights of women. As is well known, when a town was captured, the noblest and fairest ladies, whether married or not, became the property of the victors as their concubines. But a still more signifi- cant fact has not been adequately noted — that such a fate, though felt as a lamentable misfortune, was in no sense a dishonour to the Greek lady, of which she need afterwards be ashamed. In spite of all the courtliness with which ladies are treated in the Ho- meric poems, in spite of the refinement of their characters and the politeness of their ordinary life, the hard fact remains that they were the property of the stronger, and that they submitted to this fate without being compromised in society. Neither Briseis nor Chryseis seem the least disgraced by their residence in the Greek camp ; and still worse, Helen, after living for years with Paris, is then handed over to Deiphobus, and finally taken back by Menelaus without scruple or difficulty. If we weigh carefully her appearance in the Odyssey, we shall see that her regrets are chiefly for the turmoil she has caused, and for the tears and blood wasted upon her recovery; her dignity has suffered no great shock, nor does she avoid (except in words) the eyes of men ^, These facts show with great clearness how com- ' Xenophon, in a passage which will hereafter be discussed, announces this principle distinctly. ' If such an accident,' he says, ' happen to a woman without her own fault, she is not the less honoured among men' He would not of course agree with the courtly rhapsodist, in admitting an adulteress to this class, even though she alleged compulsion on the part of Aphrodite. D 34 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH, pletely the law of force prevailed over the weak, and how the Homeric lady was so constrained by its iron necessity, that all delicate feeling, however orna- mental to the surface of society, vanished in stern practice. The case of Penelope corroborates this view. It was hateful to her to marry one of the rude and ungentlemanly suitors, who thrust their attentions upon her in her grief. Yet if Ulysses were surely dead, there was no help, she must pass into their hands, whether she choose it or not. Stranger and not less characteristic is the treat- ment of old age. The king or chief, as soon as his bodily vigour passed away, was apparently pushed aside by younger and stronger men. He might either maintain himself by extraordinary usefulness, like Nestor, or be supported by his children, if they chanced to be affectionate and dutiful ; but except in these cases his lot was sad indeed. We hear Achilles (A 492 sq.) lamenting that doubtless in his absence the neighbouring chiefs are ill-treating the aged Peleus, and he longs to dye his spear in their blood. We see Laertes, the father of Ulysses, exiled, apparently by grief and disgust, to a barren farm in the country, and spending the close of his life, not in honour and comfort, but in poverty and hardship. When these princes, who had sons that might return any day to avenge them, were treated in such a way, it is surely no strained inference to say that unpro- tected old age commanded very little veneration or respect among the Homeric Greeks. While therefore we find here, too, much courtliness of manner, and II.] GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 35 respectfulness of address toward the aged from their younger relations, the facts indicate that helpless women and children and .worn-out men received scanty justice and little consideration. Among friends and neighbours, at peace and in good humour, they were treated with delicacy and refinement, but with the first clash of conflicting inter-ests such con- siderations vanished. The age was no longer, as I have said, a believing age ; the interference of the gods to protect the weak was no longer the object of a simple faith, and Greek chivalry rested on no firmer basis. I may add, by anticipation, that at no period of Greek history can we find old age commanding that respect and reverence which has been accorded it in modern Europe. We hear, indeed, that at Sparta the strictest regulations were made as to the conduct of young men towards elders, but this seems an ex- ceptional case, like most things at Sparta. There is a hackneyed story of an old man coming into the crowded theatre at Athens, and looking in vain for a seat, till he came near the Spartan embassy, who at once stood up and made room for him. Though the whole theatre applauded this act of courtesy, I am sure they did not habitually imitate it. The lyric and tragic poets, as I shall show by ample quotations in future chapters, were perpetually cursing the miseries of old age, and blessing youth, fair in poverty, fairer still in riches. Probably old Athenian gentlemen were for these reasons like old Frenchmen, who are very prone to prolong their youth by artificial means, D 2 36 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. and strive to maintain a place among their fellows which they will lose when they are confessedly of the past generation. And so in Greece, as in France, old age may have come to lack that dignity and that importance which it obtains in the British army, on our Governing Boards, and in Chinese society. The comic features in Euripides' old men, and their ridiculous attempts to dance and to fight ^, show the popular feeling about them to have recognised this weakness. But apart from these peculiarities of race, the feverish and agitated condition of Greek politics, the perpetual wars and civil conflicts must have made prompt action and quick decision all-important, and so the citizens could not brook the slowness and caution of old age, which often mistakes hesitation for deliberation, and brands prompt vigour as rash- ness. There yet remains the idea of loyalty — I mean hearty and unflinching allegiance to superior author- ity, or to the obligations taken by oath or promise. The idea is not unknown to Homer's men and women. Achilles and Penelope (more especially the latter) are in the highest sense loyal, the one to his friend Patroclus, the other to her husband Ulysses. But in the Greek camp the chiefs in general are wofully deficient in that chivalrous quality. I will not lay stress on their want of conjugal loyalty, a point in which Menelaus, according to the scholiasts, formed an honourable, but solitary exception. In those days, as in the times of the Mosaic law, ' In Euripides' Heradida and Baccha. II.J GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 37 absolute fidelity was expected from women, but not from men. In their own homes, indeed, scandals of this kind were avoided as the cause of ill-will and domestic discomfort. It is specially observed (a 433), that Laertes avoided these relations with Euryclea from respect for his wife's feelings, and the misconduct of the suitors in the same direction is specially repro- bated ; but when the chiefs were away at their wars, or travelling, the bard seems to expect no continence whatever. The model Ulysses may serve as an example, instar omnium. But it is in their treatment of Agamemnon that tl\e want of loyalty is specially prominent. Achilles is quite ready to insult him, and but for the prompt- ings of Athene (that is, of prudence), who suggests that he may play a more lucrative game by confining himself to sulkiness and bad language, is ready even to kill him. The poet, too, clearly sympathises with Achilles. He paints Agamemnon as a weak and inferior man, succeeding by fortune to a great king- dom, but quite unfit to govern or lead the turbulent princes whose oath had bound them to follow him to Troy. It is in fact Ulysses, Diomede, and Nestor who direct him what to do. It may be said that we might expect such insubordination in the case of an armament collected for a special purpose, and that even the mediaeval knights did not escape this disgrace in the very parallel case of the Crusades. I will not, then, press the point, though Agamemnon's title to supremacy is far different from that of God- frey de Bouillon. Take the case of Peleus, which 38 SOCIAL GREECE. [cii. I have already mentioned (p. 32). Take the case of Ithaca in the absence of its king. We are told repeatedly that he treated his people like a father, and yet only a few old servants seem to side with him against the worthless aspirants to the throne. The experimentum crucis, however, is the picture of the gods in Olympus. We have here Zeus, a sort of easy-going but all-powerful Agamemnon, ruling over a number of turbulent self-willed lesser gods, who are perpetually trying to evade and thwart his commands. At intervals he wakes up and terrifies them into submission by threats, but it is evident that he can count on no higher principle. Her^, Poseidon, Ares, Aphrodite, Pallas, all are thoroughly insubor- dinate, and loyal to one thing only, that is, their /«r^. Faction, as among the Greeks of Thucydides, had clearly usurped the place of principle, and we are actually presented with the strange picture of a city of gods more immoral, more faithless, and more de- praved, than the world of men. This curious feature has much exercised critics, and caused many conjectures as to the real moral attitude of the epic poets. I think the most natural explana- tion is based upon the notorious levity and reck- lessness of the Ionic character, as developed in Asia Minor ^. We know from the lyric poets, we know ' We have ample evidence that the more serious of the Greeks re- garded the matter in tlie same light. Xenophanes, for example, was known as a severe critic of Hesiod's Tkeogony, as well as of Homer, and Sextus Empiricns has preserved for us his bitter utterance : vavTo. Qiots dviGijKav "OpiTjpos 6' 'Kaiob6s re Satja Trap' SivOpdbwotffiv dvdSca teal ip6yos iartv II.J GREEKS OF THE HOMERIC AGE. 39 from the course of history, how the pleasure-loving lonians of Asia Minor seem to have lost all the stronger fibre that marked the Greeks of Hellas. Revelling in plenty, associating with Asiatic splen- dour and luxury, they very soon lost those sterner features — love of liberty, self-denying heroism, humble submission to the gods — which still survived in Greece ; and thus I conceive the courts at which the bards sang enjoyed a very free and even profane handling of the gods as a racy and piquant entertainment, so that presently it was extended even to the so- called Homeric hymns, which, of all Greek poetry, treat the gods in the most homely and even sensual way. The Hymn to Aphrodite, detailing her amour with Anchises, and that to Hermes, detailing his theft and perjury, are exact counterparts to the lay of Demodocus, which treats both Ares and Aphrodite in the same way. This bold and familiar attitude was narrowly con- nected with another leading feature in the Greeks — ■ their realism in art. There is nothing vague, or ex- aggerated, or incomprehensible, tolerated by their chaste judgment and their correct taste. The figures of dogs or men, cast by Hephaestus, are specially remarked for being life-like throughout the Homeric ot ir\erv apirrj jula yii/erai ^'Se TtXOVTflV. III.] THE HOMERIC AGE. 71 sees Penelope drawing gifts from the suitors : but his lofty and varied sphere of action forces it back into a subordinate place. Yet I would have the reader note this feature carefully, as we shall meet it again in many forms throughout later Greek society. There is another point on which Hesiod is vastly inferior in social attitude to Homer; I mean in his estimate of women. But the plain-spoken bard was not singing at courts, where queens sat by and longed to hear of worthies of their own sex ; nor did he contemplate the important duties of the house-mother in the absence of her husband in wars and on the service of his state. Hence it was that .iEschylus, though living in a democracy where women fared badly enough, yet found and felt in the epic poets such characters as his Clytemnestra, a reigning queen, invested with full powers in the king's absence — free to discuss public affairs, to re- ceive embassies, and act as her judgment directed her. All these things were foreign to Hesiod's at- titude ; yet surely it is strange that in describing farm life and farm duties, he should not have thought more of the important duties of the house- wife — duties which throughout all Greek and Roman history raised the position of the country - woman above that of the towns-woman, whose duties were less important, and whom the jealousy of city life compelled to live in fear and darkness^. Yet the first allusion in the 'Works and Days' is rude • eWiaiiivov StSotKos Kai aieoTeiviv f^" is Plato's expresi'ion. 72 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. enough: 'You must start with a house, a wife, and an ox to plough, and have your farming implements ready in the housed' There is, I believe, no farther notice of the woman till the short advice concerning marriage ; and here too nothing is stranger than the brevity with which the subject is noticed, and the total silence concerning the all - important duties which even Homer's princesses performed, and which were certainly in the hands of the women of Hesiod's acquaintance. We might almost imagine that some sour Attic editor had expunged the advice which Hesiod owes us on the point, and had justified him- self with the famous apophthegm of Pericles (or rather of Thucydides), that ' that woman is best who is least spoken of among men, either for good or for evil.' Hesiod implies, indeed, that a man may know something of the young women in the neigh- bourhood, and this supposes some freedom of inter- course; yet he seems to consider the worst feature of a bad wife her desire to sit at ineals with her husband, an opinion which in his-age, and his plain and poor society, seems very harsh indeed^. However, then, I may be accused of having drawn Homeric society in darker colours than it deserves, though I have given authority for every charge, yet ' Of course Aristotle's authority is decisive for the meaning of the verse (375\ oIkov /ilv -npimaTa, •ywcuit& Tf, 0ovv t* opoT^pa, as well as for the spuriousness of the false commentary added in the next line. * I am not satisfied with the epithet Seiirvo\6xov (649), or with the rendering of the old Commentators, and think some corruption must have crept into the text, though the MSS. do not vary except in the termination, and the editors seem satisfied. in.J THE HOMERIC AGE. 73 on the Hesiodic society all intelligent students of the 'Works and Days' are pretty well agreed. It pictures a hopeless and miserable existence, in which care, and the despair of better things, tended to make men hard and selfish, and to blot out those fairer features which cannot be denied to the courts and palaces of the Iliad and Odyssey. So great, in- deed, is the contrast, that most critics have assumed a change of things between . the states described in Homer and in Hesiod ; they have imagined that the gaiety and splendour of the epic bard could not have coexisted with the sorrows and the mean- ness of the moral teacher. But both tradition and internal evidence should convince us that these poems, if not strictly contemporaneous, are yet proximate enough in date to be considered socially pictures of the same times, differing, as I have explained, in the attitude of the poets, but not in the men and the manners which gave them birth '. If so, Hesiod has told us what the poor man thought • The usual theory makes the authors of the Iliad and Odyssey Asiatic Greeks, living among the lonians, though of ^olian extraction. If this were so, the contrasts of Asiatic luxury and Greek poverty might be brought in to explain the striking differences between the two poets. For we know that the Asiatic Greeks attained to wealth and luxury long before their brethren in Greece. Mr. Gladstone, however, in the Contemporary Review for June 1874, contends earnestly that Homer composed his poems in Greece, and both Sengebusch and Professor Geddes assert it of the earliest part of the poems. To any who may adopt this theory, my argument in the text will be even more pointed, and the contrast more remarkable, between the refinement of the noble and the rudeness of the peasant, in immediate contact throughout the same, or adjoining, distiicts. 74 SOCIAL GREECE. [_CH. and felt, while the Homeric poet pictured how kings and ladies ought, in his opinion, to have lived and loved. And with all the contrasts, I think we can see conclusively that the fundamental features were the same, and that they were the legitimate seed from which sprang the Greeks of historic times. I may add, in conclusion, that this great contrast between the fair exterior and the misery and injustice within, though it has been now put very strongly in the case of the Greeks, was not peculiar to them, but has probably existed in all history where a favoured caste has ruled in its own interest, and to the ex- clusion of the general mass of the people. It was so in ancient Egypt, it was so in ancient India — indeed, in India at all times, — and it was so in mediaeval Europe. But in most of these cases the stronger classes write their own history and sing their own praises, while the wrongs and troubles of the poor transpire but rarely and by accident. So, the miseries of the old Egyptian poor are only transmitted to us by the boasts of reckless kings, who so loved their own glory, and to magnify their deeds, that they confessed the ruthless waste of human life with which they completed their eternal monuments. And again, the letter of a scribe has reached us, calling on a friend to embrace a literary life, and contrasting the poverty and the oppression under which the farming class suf- fered, with the comforts of his own calling \ These chance pieces of evidence lay open to us great social • Cf. my Prolegom. to Aiu. Hist., p. 327. I I III.] THE HOMERIC AGE. ']^ — . ,i__ sores, great sorrows of humanity covered with a s^^j.. face of unjust and heartless splendour. Can we ii^^a- gine that in the Middle Ages, in the days of tro/^]-,^. jiours and tournaments, of moated castles and j-j^-j^ abbeys, when the rude baron and the wily ,'abbot divided the spoil — that the lower strata of Society fared in proportion? and can we imagine ther^j shar- ing the splendour and the refinement told j^ qJj romances and ballads? I need not speak Qf pgj.. secuted races like the Jews, who were so br^j-j^j^j-Q^gj^ treated that injustice towards them lost its^^gj.^ mean- ing to their oppressors, who have vauntej^ their own rapine and murder as the execution of X^j^jj^g com- mands, and as the spreading of the gogngl of mercy through the world. But even in the c^g of the poor and the unprotected, the orphan andy^hg ^j^ow, the sick ancf \^e destitute, it is but too- certain that all the earth w|s full of violence; and/ that hearts were broken and>?nour trampled in th^ j^st with little compassion, wljkn^no law was foun^ ^ punish trans- ression. \ ' Feudal times m^ both sen«ment and hT^ ^rchilochu^ron ; to the boor they are days of turmo«r^^.^ ^^ J ^f uncertain and scanty comfort, of certain ^.^/gggj^^ ^^^ ^ What are the social pictures dra-.^ ^f t^ese times in the novels of Sir Walter Scott-^^ooks which contain more and truer history than nv^st of the dry annals professing to be such? Cons^yg^ Ivanhoe, or Queniin Durward, or the Fazr Maid .f p.^^f,, are they not all darkened with the cry of ^.^e poor for justice and gression. \ "" >plain truth. WfY may produce 76 SOCIAL GREECE. mercy, while the rich and powerful are made by the nov;elist only to suffer the punishments which they esca'^ed in real life ? These things should moderate, our Contempt for the Homeric Greelts, even though I have \sttipped off the husk, and shown the bitterness of th^ fruit within. They were unjust and cruel and coarse I'lelow the surface ; but so were our ancestors, ay, wit&in a century of to-day. After all it is the democratic spirit — vulgar, unsentimental, litigious spirit thaCj it is — which first overthrew this feudalism in the worfid ; and which, in ancient Greece, in Rome, and in the^' Europe of to-day, has redressed social grievances, f^brbidden injustice, and punished violence and wrong, o CHAPTER IV. THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. When we pass the great gap that separates Ho- tneric from historical Greece we find ourselves in presence of a very different type of literary men. The tooth of time has eaten their works into frag- ments. We can find no continuous picture, no com- plete sketch of life, in these scanty remnants ; but still there is a something in the briefest of them that speaks to us in a different tone from that of the smooth and courtly rhapsodists. The lyric poets had lost interest in old kings and byegone glories ; they wrote about the present, they told about themselves, they spoke out the plain truth. We can see in the earliest of them, such as Archilochusj a clear reaction against the perpetual singing of antique glory, and the false palliation of heroic crimes. 'Had not the poet himself told us,' says an old writer', 'we should never have known that he was the son of a slave, and that he was driven from his country (Paros) by poverty and want, to Thasos, where he became • Critias, quoted by ^lian, in Bergk, Fragg. Lyric. Grac. p. 724, from which I quote throughout. 78 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. very unpopular ; nor should we have known that he abused friends and foes alike, nor that he was an adulterer, except from his own words, nor that he was sensual and insolent, nor, worst of all\ that he threw away his shield. Archilochus, therefore, was no good witness concerning himself.' And yet this poet was unanimously placed by the Greeks next to Homer in popularity. We are, there- fore, no longer in the presence of Greek Spensers and Miltons, who forgot themselves and their age to sing about gods and heroes, but in the presence of a Greek Byron, who not only applied his transcendent genius to satirise the men and the social laws of his own time, but who flaunted before the world the worst passages of an evil life, and, as a fatifaron de vices, gloried in violating the holiest obligations which restrain ordi- nary men in every civilised community. The same outspokenness, though it did not reach the same extremes, marks the fragments of Alcaeus, of Sappho, of Theognis, and of Solon. They stand totally apart in spirit from the old rhapsodists, and in contact with the moderns. They were strict realists in their art, not approaching the ideal save in the hymns they composed for the public worship of the gods. The self-assertion of cowardice in so many of these poets is a feature well worth noticing more particu- larly. Not only have we the evidence just quoted about Archilochus, but Herodotus (v. 95), and after- wards Strabo (xiii. 600), tell us a similar story of Alcaeus, who actually wrote a poem to a friend, and ' Observe this Greek gradation of crimes. IV.] THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. 79 published it, detailing how he had thrown away his shield in battle, and how the Athenians, with whom he had fought, had hung it up as a trophy in Sigeum. We are not surprigjgd, when such statements were made by turbulent and warHke poets, to find allusions in the fragments of Anacreon which seem to point to some similar story {frags. 29, 30). I argued above (p. 21) that the Greeks were not a courageous nation, in the sense now accepted, and I think these ad- ditional pieces of evidence, from a later age, cor- roborate what I have said. The attitude of Pindar towards war is quite similar to that of other Greek poets. His style and subject-matter do not admit of confessions like those of Archilochus and Alcsus. He says {frag. 74) that only the inexperienced love war ; a sentiment likely enough to be strongly felt in the days of the disastrous, though glorious, Persian invasion, just as we often heard it expressed by German soldiers and ofScers after the late war in France. But still it is evidence of a feeling in Pindar different from, and more modern than, the valour of the knight-errant and the crusader. Plato, in his Laws^, has a very Greek theory to account for the decay of valour in modern times, as compared with the valour of the ideal Homeric hero and the old Spartan citizen. He notices that the Athenians were subject to Minos ^ and obliged to pay him a tribute of human lives, because he pos- ' Jowett, vol. iv. p. 227. " This is probably the mythical account of the old Phoenician supre- macy in the Greek waters. Cf. above, p. 16. 8o SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. sessed a naval power, and they did not. ' Better for them,' he adds, ' to have lost many times over the seven youths, than that heavy-armed and stationary troops should have been turned into sailors, and ac- customed to leap quickly on shore, and again to hurry back to their ships ' ; or should have fancied that there was no disgrace in not awaiting the attack of an enemy and dying boldly ; and that there were good reasons, and many of them, for a man throwing away his arms, and betaking himself to flight, which is affirmed upon occasion not to be dishonourable. This is the language of naval warfare, and is anything but worthy of extraordinary praise. For we should not teach bad habits, least of all to the best part of the citizens. You may learn the evil of such a prac- tice from Homer, by whom Odysseus is introduced, rebuking Agamemnon, because he desires to draw down the ships to the sea at a time when the Achaeans are hard pressed. ' For,' says he, ' the Achaeans will not maintain the battle, when the shijjs are drawn into the sea, but they will look behind and cease from strife.' You see that be quite knew triremes on the sea, in the neighbourhood of fighting men, to be an evil j lions might be trained in that way to fly from a herd of deer. Moreover, naval powers, which owe their safety to ships, do not honour that sort of warlike excellence which is most deserving of honour. For he who owes his safety to the pilot, and the cap- tain, and the oarsman, and all sorts of rather good- for-nothing persons, cannot rightly give honour to whom honour is due. IV.] THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. 8i Plato has not the smallest notion of real sailor courage, such as .we have inherited from the Norse- men ; he does not know that such courage may be higher than that of any landsman, for he only had before him the wretched coasting and plundering sea warfare of the Greeks, His evidence, however, on the small valour of the Greek marine is most valuable. But to return ; there are ample historical reasons to account for the blunt realism of the lyric poets. The main interests of the Hellenic nation, after the wars and adventures occasioned by their colonising epoch had passed away, were centred not on foreign affairs, or external wars, but on the internal conflicts of their cities. The great social struggle between the higher and lower classes had commenced, and so the aristocracy became naturally separated in most of the cities into close factions, with common interests and common principles of action. The early lyric poets, as a class, were members of this society, and spoke as equals to intimate equals, not as paid in- feriors to please their employers, till the epoch of the tyrants came, when a few of the later lyrists fell back socially into a position somewhat analogous to the rhapsodists. Since these things are so, the scanty and dislocated lyric fragments are worth far more, historically, than the more consecutive but more imaginary pictures of the epic poems. They disclose to us a society of men of like passions with the later Greeks, but more reckless and violent, inasmuch as men whose old privileges are for the first time G 82 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. attacked are more bitter than those who have become accustomed to this ungrateful reform. When Thucydides tells us that the moral depravity so graphically described in his third book came in with the civil war, it is surprising that this assertion has been adopted by historians without large quali- fications. It may possibly be true that democracies, being more thoroughly organised and firmer in their claims, began to develope these vices more mani- festly at this time, but ii is plainly false to say that the Greek aristocrats did not openly act on all the principles indicated by Thucydides long before his day. As I have already shown, even Homer's Gods and Hesiod's Iron Age possess all these disagreeable features. Were we to seek an historical illustration of the same thing, it would rather be found in the poems of Theognis (v. 1182) or Alcaeus than in any other portion of Greek literature. But we must look more to Hesiod than to Homer for the antecedents of the moral darkness of lyric Greece. We now see, not the oppressed farmer suffering from injustice and violence, yet still in awe of the divine right of his princes, but these very hcapo(pdyoi ^ao-tATJes quarrelling, as we might expect, over their ill-used privileges, and over the booty ^ey had plundered from their people. Greek history, too, makes it plain that the lower classes did not awake spontaneously to their rights, and put forth one of themselves to vindicate and lead them ; but that the noble who failed in the struggle with his brother aristocrats — this was he who taught the brjuos their IV.] THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. 83 rights, and offered to lead them against their former oppressors. The Hesiodic boor was thiis awakened to his claims, and entered into the conflict with the vigour of his race. But of course he was duped by his leader, who only wanted hini as a tool, not as a friend, and who reduced both his former equals and his former supporters to one level, as soon as he was able to, establish his tyranny. Thus there arose a certain phase of Greek society, called the age of the Tyrants, which has hardly re- ceived fair treatment at the hands of historians. Politically, indeed, as regards the development of written laws, and the habits of public debate, it must be regarded as an epoch of stagnation, or of retro- gression in Greece ; but socially and aesthetically, nay even morally, in spite of the vices of many Greek despots, I hold it to have been not only an age of progress in Greece, but even a necessary prelude to the higher life which was to follow. For if we regard carefully the attitude of Hesiod, Theognis, Alcaeus, and other such poets, we shall find that in the aris^ tocratic stage, in which the proper history of Greece opens, the degradation of the lower classes and the un- disguised violence of the nobles made all approach to a proper constitution impossible. The Boeotian farmer thought that he must suffer for the sins of his princes, and never thought it possible that he should reject the responsibility. He regarded this Jove-sprung pestilence as a sort of iron necessity that brought him unavoidable suffering. In like manner the aris- tocrats could never endure to see the men who lived 84 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. like wild beasts' in skins, and- were timid as deer', claiming privileges, and discussing rights with their noble selves. ' Between us and you there is a great gulf fixed ' — this was the watchword of their policy. And so the nobles in Athens, in Megara, in Lesbos, and probably in Sparta, quarrelled among themselves with great violence, but never thought for one moment of bettering the condition of the hr]jj.os. When the tyrants arose, they forced these widely separated classes into the same subjection. There is ample evidence that they systematically raised the common people, and lowered the nobles. There is equally ample evidence that they enforced order, and in some cases put down with a strong hand open immorality'*, so that cities which had been racked with revolution and violence for generations, first came to feel the blessings of a strong government, and the benefits of a peace to which they had been total strangers. This gave them time to develope commerce and to cultivate art — the latter specially encouraged by the tyrants as a class. I hold, then, that Greece, when the tyrants passed away, was in a condition vastly superior to its aristocratic age— in fact, in a condition fit to develope political life. This ' I quote this from Theognis, v. 55. ^ This is certain from the evidence we have in the fragments of Theoporapus {cf. frag. 252) about the tyrants of Mitylene. Curtius has an ingenious theory that the tyrants were the evidence of a mercantile Ionic reaction against the aristocratic Doric ascendancy brought about by the greatness of Sparta. This theory, if proved, does not contradict what is said in the text, but concerns the pohtical side of a question, which I am regarding from a social point of view. IV.J THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. 85 would have been impossible but for the fusion of classes and the development of culture produced by the tyrants. One memorable example will suffice by way of illustration. What was the state of Athens when Solon arose ? It had been torn by factions for years. The country was languishing. Men were weary of turmoil and confusion. At last this great genius was entrusted with the regulation of public affairs. He tells us plainly enough in extant poems that he endeavoured to lay down a fair constitution, raising the lower classes gradually, curbing the violence of the nobles, tempering all the extremes into a great whole in which all should have an interest. Here, then, was a fair and just constitution offered to a city in the pre-despotic stage. What was the re- sult ? In spite of all his efforts, in spite of his self- imposed absence, and the oath taken to avoid changes, the aristocrats could not be restrained. They openly ridiculed Solon, as he tells us, for not grasping the tyranny, in fact they could not con- ceive his declining to do so ; even the lower classes seem not to have understood his great benefits, for the noble legislator complains, in language which still touches us across the great gulf of centuries, how he stands alone without friend or support in the state'. ' The ridicule of his aristocratic friends appears in quotations from Solon's own poems by Plutarch in chap. xvl. of his precious Life of Solon. ' But his intimates more particularly depreciated him, because he thought ill of monarchy on account of its name, as if it did not forth- 86 SOCIAL GREECE. [cH. It is to be observed, farther, that the lessons which he taught, and the ideas which he strove to instil into the Athenian mind, were no obscure metaphy- sics, no lofty flights of fancy, but the plainest home- spun morality, so plain indeed that his practical lessons appear to us mere truisms. His moral atti- tude differs toto ccelo from that of ^schylus, and stands so close to that of Hesiod and Theognis, that they dispute with him the authorship of sundry re- flections. This very plain teaching, and this great moral and political pre-eminence of Solon, were nevertheless to all appearance useless. No sooner had he completed his work and left Athens, than the old strife of parties revived. His return made no change in this wretched state of things. His laws were powerless, his lessons were unheeded. He had cast his pearls before swine, and they were ready to turn again and rend him. His solution of the problem was no with become a kingship [instead of a tyranny?] by the merit of the holder, and as they had the precedents of Tynnondas in Euboea and PittaciTS in Mitylene. None of these things made Solon to swerve from his policy, but he said to his friends that a tyranny was a fair position with no escape from it. ..." He has thus described the ridicule of those who derided him for avoiding the tyranny : ' Solon is no man of sound sense or counsel, for when God gave him a fine chance he himself would not take it ; but when he had made a miraculous draught, in amazement he did not haul in the great net, through want both of spirit and of sense. 'He should have been well content, having got power and abundant wealth, to be tyrant of Athens for a single day, even were he then flayed ^live and his race destroyed.' It is with reference to such friends that Solon speaks of himself (/raj*. 37) as a wolf worried by dogs crowding about him. , . IV.] THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. 87 doubt theoretically excellent, but practically it was a decided failure. Peisistratus, a man of inferior genius, but of greater vigour and boldness, saw better how to solve it. Of course Peisistratus had private ends, like Julius Csesar, like Alexander, like Napo- leon. But when a great man's private ends happen to coincide with the good of the state, he ought not to lose all credit because he happens to benefit him- self. There is ample evidence that Peisistratus was not only a wise but a humane and orderly ruler. Despite the violent opposition of the aged Solon, he treated him with respect, and is said to have strictly obseived his laws. This shows his esti- mate of Solon's theory. But if he did approve of Solon's laws, he introduced the new element in which Solon was wanting. After all, the aristocrats who had ridiculed the lawgiver for not turning tyrant, had some wisdom in their taunts. Laws must not only be made, they must be enforced. Peisistratus en- forced Solon's laws \ He was not content with laws punishing neutrality during insurrections. He in- sisted on peace and order in the city. He stopped by main force the perpetual political agitation which is the ruin of any commonwealth. He developed the tastes of the lower classes, giving them intellectual and social pleasures to compensate for the loss of higher but more dangerous excitement. The reading • See the remarkable passage in Plato's Laws, iv. 711, in which he shows how rapidly a tyrant was able, even by merely selling the fashion, to alter the laws and customs of a state. He is distinctly of opinion that there is no other means at all so rapid and complete. 88 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. of Homer, the feasts of Dionysus, the newest lyric poems, attracted the attention of the public, and weaned them from the wild fever of conflicting rights and opposing privileges. Of course the great nobles found the change intolerable. They retired, like Miltiades, to their country mansions. Thfey gladly left the country to found colonies, and regain as foreign princes the importance they had lost at home. Athens stood still in political training, but she gained immensely in culture. Let the reader remember that without sound intellectual culture all political train- ing is and must be simply mischievous. A free con- stitution is perfectly absurd, if the opinion of the majority is incompetent. Until men are educated, they want a strong hand over them — a fact which very few in this country will be disposed to dispute. I fear it is almost hopeless to persuade English minds that a despotism may in some cases be better for a nation than a more advanced constitution. And yet no students of history can fail to observe that eveii now very few nations in the world are fit for diffused political privileges. These nations are so manifestly the greatest and best, and consequently the most prosperous^ that inferior races keep imitating their institutions, instead of feeling that these institutions are the result and not the cause of true national greatness. Of course the result reacts upon the cause, and becomes itself a cause in due time, but only Avhere it has grown up naturally, not where it has been superinduced artificially. Thus the attempts at democracy of the Spaniards, of the American IV.] THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. 89 negroes, and of all such non-political races, must for generations to come end in failure. The case of the Irish is still more remarkable. The English nation has in vain given them its laws, and even done something to enforce them. The nation will not thrive, because this is the very constitution not fit for it. I believe even a harsh despotism would be more successful, and perhaps in the end more humane. When the Greek tyrants had done their work, the day of liberty came, and with it a great struggle, which nerved and braced the people's energies against an outward foe. The literature of free Athens shows us a perfectly new attitude. Of course it were absurd to attribute this memorable national development — the most miraculous the world has ever seen — to any single cause. A con- current number of great causes could alone have produced such an effect. But I claim as one cause the literary culture which Athens received at the hands of Peisistratus and his sons. The hearers of j^schylus were intellectually men widely different from the hearers of Solon, nay even from the early hearers of later lyric poets, like Pindar and Simonides. There is a depth and a condensation of thought in .^schylus which would have made him, perfectly unintelligible to men who appreciated the stupid saws of Hesiod and Solon, even when obscured or polished by Pindar and Simonides. The fact that .^schylus was appreciated proves that Athens had attained the intellectual culture fit for a great demo- 90 SOCIAL GREECE. [CO.. cracy. I believe that she owed this culture mainly to her tyrants '. But of course the tyrants had their bad effect on literary men, even while they promoted culture. For their position and their policy led them to encourage smoothness and elegance rather than originality and vigour. Archilochus and Aristo- phanes could not have been tolerated among them, and there were certain species of poetry, like the comedy of the latter, which though born, lay dor- mant till their control had passed away. . So then the lyric poets, who have been divided in numerous cross divisions, as regards dialect, metre, country, and subjects, may be divided for our present pur- pose into the poets of free states, and the poets at the courts of tyrants. The characteristics of the former and the value of the evidence they afford us are sufficiently ob- vious from the foregoing remarks. I shall only here call attention among the latter to the attitude of Pindar, who appears from his poems to have been more a courtier than an honest man. I take his moral reflections, and those of Simonides, to be far less sincere than those of Solon or Theognis. But unfortunately, the high popularity of the earlier gnomists made it impossible to keep their works ' In corroboration nf this view of the literary influence of the tyrants, I may quote the curious case of Magna Grsecia, where the AchEean con- federation.which excluded tyrants.also exhibited no literary genius, though Tarentum and Rhegium and the Sicilian cities bore their full share, often under tyrants. Cf. Mommsen's Ram. Hist. i. 143, Eng. Trans. IV.] THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. 91 pure and undefiled. Later moral teachers added to the older reflections various new saws and maxims, and these, especially when they were of high merit \ took refuge under the name of Hesiod, or of Solon, or of Theognis, even where they seem to us in direct contradiction to these authors' opinions. Accordingly there is no more hopeless task than the critical expurgating of such texts. The interpolations are often as old as the circulation of the poems, and usually of equal merit as to thought and diction. These additions are flagrantly obvious in our extant remains of Theognis, and have been there since the fourth century B.C., at all events, for Plato criticises them in his Meno ^ as part of the received text. The curious saltus from subject to subject, the constant and direct in- consistencies, the total absence of continuity in the fragments, tell but too plainly the history of their text. It is beyond the scope of a general sketch to attempt a notice of all the individual peculiarities ' This consideration shows the folly of a very common procedure among the German critics, of determining by their own taste (generally a very capricious one) what lines are of inferior merit, and excluding them as unworthy of the genuine poet. The supposed defect in the suspected passage often arises from a want of comprehension on the part of the critic. Choice specimens of this sort of restitution may be seen in Steitz' othem-ise valuable book on Hesiod, and still better in Lucian MuUer's papers on some of Ovid's Heroides in the twenty- third vol. of the Rhein. Mus. In proverbial poetry at all events, neither commonplace nor disconnection are sufficient proof of spuriousness, and again no line is more liktly to be foisted in than a really good and striking line. There is indeed no reason why the interpolated lines should not be superior to the original poem. ' Jowett, vol. i. p. 286. 93 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. scattered through the widely severed fragments of the lyric poets. Where the germ was developed in later Greek society we shall notice it in our more special consideration of the Attic age. But there are a few general features, repeated in many of the fragments, despite of contrasts in time and place, in metre and in dialect. These must here occupy us a brief space. There is, for example, a peculiar uniformity in many of them as to their religious views — I mean their views of Divine Justice and Benevolence, of Providence and of Fate. Solon and Theognis, Ar- chilochus and the earlier Simonides, the later Simon- ides and his contemporary Pindar, all agree in their general theory of life. They were led by bitter ex- perience to assert, what had never been dared by Homer and only hinted by Hesiod, that goodness and justice among men were often without reward, and that the wicked did flourish as a green bay tree ; and yet, for all that, they never advanced even to the most distant hint of atheism, or to a denial that the gods could and did interfere in human affairs. Had such a notion been within their horizon, it must have come into sight when we find such almost comic appeals as this of Theognis : — ' Dear Zeus, I wonder at thee : for thou rulest over all, having in thine own hands honour and great power and of men thou knowest well the heart and mind of each, and thy strength is over all, O king ! How is it then that thy mind can tolerate to hold transgressors and the just in the same lot .■' ' And so the conclusion appears briefly in the succeeding lines, ' there is nothing de- IV.] THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. 93 cided for mortals as regards the Deity, nor what path he must tread to please the immortal gods.' This is their common attitude. They feel the pre- sence of the Deity ; they believe that human hap- piness and misery are bestowed by him ; but though their deepest instinct tells them that virtue must be his law, and justice his principle, they cannot reconcile with it the facts of common life. They con- clude, therefore, that the ways of God are inscrutable, and his paths past finding out. Thus Solon, in the most famous of his ■ fragments (No. 13, ed. Bergk), where he tells us the results of his deepest reflections on human life, after asserting in the strongest terms a ruling Providence, which though often tardy, yet never fails to seek out and punish vice, it may be in the sinner himself, it may be by visitations upon the third and fourth generation — after this dogmatic teaching, Solon goes on to show how men are car- ried about, each by his own vanity and his peculiar ambition, and how not one of them can see what dangers and what successes are before him. In the words of another fragment (17) irwrTj 8' hBavLTOiv a^avT]^ voos avOpairoLcriv. The lines of Theognis (vv. 133 sq.) are still stronger : — ' No one, Cyrnus, is himself the cause of his misfortune or his gain, but the gods are the givers of them both ; nor does any man work with a sure knowledge whether the result will be good cr evil. For often when he thinks he is producing evil, he produces good, and again thinking to pro- duce good he produces evil. Nor does any man 94 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. attain his expectations, for the Hmits of stern ina- bility restrain him (tuxet yap \a.\i-nr\^ lidpixT a\vi]xav'jr\i). For we men form idle opinions, knowing nothing, but the gods accomplish all according to their mind,' It must be observed that, by way of antidote, the succeeding lines tell that he who deceives a stranger, or a suppliant, never escapes the immortal gods. The gloomy lines of Archilochus {fr. 56), and Si- monides of Amorgos {fr. l), of Simonides of Ceos (/''■ ,5)j ^'^^ of Pindar's twelfth Olympian Ode, repeat the same disappointment and the same de- spair ; nay, their very language is so similar to that of Solon and Theognis, that they seem but evident repetitions of the • common wisdom of the day, couched in the tritest and most homely words ^ It is worthy of remark that these poets were far too philosophic to account for their difficulties, as Homer would do, by the conflicting passions of in- dependent deities. This vulgar polytheism had long passed away from educated minds, and the poets speak of the Deity, for the most part, impersonally, or as one almighty Zeus. The vague and negative attitude of their religion ' I quote the words of Pindar instar omnium : — av\i^6Kov 8' ov irij tis emxOoviouv marbv dfi^l irpi^tos iaaoixivas etpev 9e66ev rwv S^ iJLe\K6vT03y Tcn^tf^ouvTcu tppdSal. TToAXcl S' dvOpiinoLS trapci yv^ptav Hireaev, €fina\iv fXiV Teptpios, ol 5' dviapaXs &iiriKipaavT(s (/6,\aii iaXbv fiaOi) irqimros iv puKp^ iteSifunlay Xpivtji. 01. xii. 7-12. These poets add but little to Hesiod, "Epy. 83 sqq. IV.] THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. 95 naturally coloured their practical ethics, and so we here find many conflicting apophthegms, as is wont to be the case in all proverbial philosophy. According to the writer's momentary attitude, according to the subject in hand, the preacher frames his parable, without regard to consistency. This peculiarity is indeed so salient in the extant works of Theognis, that it seems impossible to deny extensive interpo- lations ; and there can be little doubt that here, as in Hesiod, the use of the author as a schoolbook induced men to smuggle in foreign morality under the shelter of a great name. It is of course impos- sible to gather such teaching under general heads, or present it as a connected system. But there are some points on which lyric poets as widely apart as Tyrta;us and Pindar agree, and this because they have both inherited them from the Ionic and Boeotian Epos. They both think, for example, that the best way of inculcating heroism is not by sentimental appeals, but by showing the solid ad- vantages to be derived from it. It is far better, says Tyrtseus {fr. lo), to die in battle, than to be driven from one's city and rich fields and have to beg, going about with one's aged father, one's wife and little children. For a man is hateful to those whom he visits in his poverty and dire distress, and dis- graces his race and his own respectability. ' If then,' the poet proceeds, ' there is no regard for a wan- dering man, nor respect, nor consideration, nor pity, let us fight with courage, and not spare our lives.' This picture of the contempt in which a vagrant 96 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. beggar is held, even if sprung from gentle blood, reminds us of the anxious hurrying of Ulysses to the asylum of the hearth, it literally repeats Hesiod's advice to Perses (v. 367), and reminds us of the sad words of Andromache, in describing the lot of her orphan child (above, p. 41). Pindar, whose evidence is not quite so valuable, inasmuch as he wrote in the interest of his pro- fession, repeatedly tells us that the satisfaction of doing great things is nothing, if the glory of being publicly praised does not attend it. We saw above that this worship of success was quite Homeric^ being the counterpart of the contempt of failure, and equally prominent in the Greek mind. To the pas- sages already quoted I may add one in Pindar, which shocks us in comparison with the gentleness and sympathy of Achilles towards the vanquished at the games. He says that the Deity has given to the four lads, whom Alcimedon conquered, a most hateful return from the arena, a cowed voice, and a sneaking along unfrequented paths ^. The same idea is found in one of his fragments (150). A very remark- able historical parallel is to be read in Herodotus (vi. 6"]), where the new king of Sparta sends a mes- senger to ask his deposed rival, out of insolence and derison, how he liked being a magistrate after being a king. I think, therefore, that in this respect^ the Greeks of the lyric age were hardly gentlemen in our sense. Another feature may, perhaps, be regarded * v6 vv. 279, 847, 853. * This antipathy sometimes assumes a very grotesque form. ' How are you getting on, James ?' said a friend of mine to one of these Orange- men. ' Badly enough, your honour ; sure the country is gone to the divil.' ' Why do you say that ? I see your farm in good order, with plenty of stock on it.' ' What matter about that, doesn't your honour know that if you shot a Papist now you'd be tried for it?' When my friend looked amused, the Orangeman added with much warmth : ' Well, with the blesiiti n' God, I'll have one day's fowlin' among them before I die.' Another was known to object vehemently to controversial sermons, whereby the Papists might be converted. 'Till hell with them,' he exclaimed, ' I wouldn't convert them.' Such anecdotes might be multiplied ad libitum. The Roman Catholic party have just as strong \5entiments, but do not express them so boldly, II 2 100 SOCIAL GREECE. [CH. and relations. Thus any thoughtful man who has lived in Ireland comes to understand Greek political hate with peculiar clearness. Theognis has various theories to explain the mean- ness and falseness of the lower classes, all of them more or less true, and all of them verified by the modern parallel I have cited. He says (v. 279) that these people have to live from hand to mouth, and therefore are trained to disregard and forget just requital, if future. He says (v. 305) that they are not all bad from the mother's womb, but are brought up in bad society, and so all degenerate to a low level. Crush them under your heel, and drive them with a sharp goad (v. 847), for they are slavish. Finally (vv. 383, 899), he speaks very strongly on the .de- grading effects ^-^-novert v.. which ^drag, even ^«(*S,ne and noble mind into meanness and cowardice ; for strong necessity compels him to look to his daily bread, and not to endanger it by pride and inde- ' pendence. If we weigh the evidence on these great problems in the lyric fragments, as compared with the epic poems, we shall say that while on the question of religion men had begun to see and appreciate diffi- culties, and to repudiate low and childish views about the gods,. in morals there was neither much advance nor marked retrogression. The collapse of the popular religion, which was even then in process, ought to have made men more reckless, for many are totally unhinged when old beliefs fall away from them ; they have bound together all their morals with their IV.] THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE. loi dogmas, and cannot sustain the one without the other. But a deeper sense of moral obHgation, and a sounder and stronger conviction of the duties each man owes to society — these counterbalancing forces saved the higher and purer minds, and gave them a surer and better reason for honesty and goodness than the wrath of Athene or Apollo ; and so in some minds, and those the highest, a better and nobler morality took the place of the religion of olden days. This development would doubtless have borne good fruit, and shown us the lyric age far superior to Homer's, had not the almost universal and chronic civil wars in the Greek cities embittered every relation of life, and sown the growing mind of Greece with hate and with revenge. It is to this melancholy social state — a state first checked by the tyrants — that we must ascribe the smallness of the moral progress among the Greeks of this age. I pass to kindred, but lighter topics. CHAPTER V. THE GREEKS OF THE LYRIC AGE {continued). Social intercourse appears to have stood far apart from the older times, and in close relation to the manners of the later Greeks, as we shall have ample occasion to notice hereafter. In feasting especially, moderate eating and drinking, combined with good conversation, had assumed in the minds of educated Greeks the prominence which they now have in in- tellectual society. Of course all noise and clamour, such as is the fashion among our students, were in- tolerable to Greek refinement^. ' Come, now,' says ' Tennyson has well contrasted (7b Mem. Ixxxvi.) ' the noise Of songs, and clapping hands, and boys That crashed the glass and beat the floor,' with that higher society which Xenophanes and Plato enjoyed ages before him. Even the reckless suitors of Penelope (