SI W33 PS €titm\\ SKniwrsitg Jttatg BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME FROM THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF Itenrg M. Sage ..^.'."^rfAtf^.' ^.f.mL.. 9963 -T^'—m-^—'r-^rrT-'' "" '- - , • ■."V3'),- The date showa when this volume was/tiiken. HOME USE RULES. nm^. Ur2 2l97[> - ^ :^^4a25^yiaw All Bosks subject to Recall. Books not used for instruction or research are returnable within 4 weeks. . Volumes of periodi- cals and of pamphlets are held in the library as much as possible. For special purposes they are given out for a limited time. Borrowers should not use their library privileges for the bene- fit of other persons. Books not \ needed during recess periods should be returned to the libr^y, or arrange- ments made for their lirn during borrow- r^bsence, i^anted. Books needed by J ^nrf^ than one person *" are held on the reserve list. Books of special value and gift books, when the giver wishes it, are not allowed to circulate. Readers are asked to report all cases of books marked or muti- jasi: ^Tjaaaj: Do not deface books by marks and writing. BL51.W33°P5" ""'^^^^"vLibrary ^^'S.?f?ff,te!,,.!?.^&,of., religion: a serie oljn 3 1924 029 208 232 The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924029208232 THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION PUBLISHED BV JAMES MACLEHOSE AND SONS, GLASGOW $ttbUeh£r£E to the Snibcrstt^. MACMILLAN AND Cfi., LTD., LONDON. NeTX) York, • The Macmillan Co. Toronto^ - • The Macmillan Co. of Canada London, • • Simpkin, Hamilton and Co. Cambridge^ - Bowes and Bowes, Edinburgh, - • Douglas and Foulis, Sydney, - Angus and Robertson, THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION A SERIES OF LECTURESWVA \ \ BY JOHN WATSON, M.A., LL.D. PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY IN QUEEN'S UNIVERSITY KINGSTON, CANADA GLASGOW JAMES MACLEHOSE AND SONS PUBLISHERS TO THE UNIVERSITY 1907 ■"^l, In 7 3 \ -y^^ ^i / ^ GLASGOW : PRINTED AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS BY ROBERT MACLEHOSE AND CO. LTD. PREFACE Six of the lectures contained in this volume — the third, fourth, fifth, seventh, sixteenth and seventeenth — were delivered in April of this year before the Brooklyn Institute of Arts and Sciences, Brooklyn, U.S.A.; the two first were composed at the same time, and were intended to be introductory to the course; while the substance of the sixth, together with the eighth, ninth, tenth, eleventh, twelfth, thirteenth, fourteenth and fifteenth were read some years ago to the Theological Alumni Association of the University with which 1 have the honour to be connected. The lectures which constitute the body of this work are mainly essays in the reconstruction and history of religious belief. The importance of the problem and the pressing need of its solution will hardly be denied by any one who realizes the significance of the unrest and confusion of ideas which have invaded our modern life. The appeal to external authority in any form does not in our day carry conviction even to those who make it. Nothing short of a complete revision of current theo- logical ideas, as I am convinced, can bring permanent satisfaction to our highly reflective age. I have vi PREFACE therefore endeavoured to set forth, as simply and clearly as I could, the conception of life which commends itself to my own mind after the most careful thought The conditions under which the lectures were delivered made it necessary that I should avoid as far as possible all merely technical terms, and at the same time should not assume intimate familiarity on the part of the audience with the history and problems of philosophy. Convinced as I was that the theology of the future must take the form of a philosophy of religion, it was therefore impossible, in writing the lectures, to avoid a certain amount of philosophical exposition ; while, on the other hand, I should have defeated the object I had at heart, if I had burdened my pages with an excess of historical detail. I have therefore tried to combine freedom of movement with definiteness of thought. The development of the religious consciousness in the past has been partly aided, and partly hindered, by its inevitable dependence upon external authority ; and, though the whole principle of authority was virtually overthrown at the beginning of the modern world with the Reformation and the Renaissance, there is now, as there always has been, a tendency to revive it, whenever a new movement of the secular conscious- ness seems to threaten the enfeeblement or extinction of traditional religious beliefs. In this way we may explain such ineffectual attempts to defend an obsolete point of view as that of Cardinal Newman, and in our own day of Mr. Balfour in his Foundations PREFACE vii of Belief, Therefore, in the two first lectures I have stated my reasons for dissatisfaction with the various attempts which have been made to base religion upon authority. Granting that religion can find no real support in external authority, we are obviously under compulsion either to abandon all systematic thought in this region, or to rebuild our theological beliefs on the basis of reason. I have therefore attempted to deal with this question, in a general way, in the third and fourth lectures, which consist of an exposition of the Critical solution of the problem and the outline of an Idealism developed out of it by a firm application of the principle that the world is rational and is capable of being comprehended by us in virtue of the rationality which is our deepest and truest nature. Having reached this point, we are met by two opposite philosophical schools of thought, which refuse to accept the solution of the problem thus advanced, or perhaps rather of what they mistakenly regard as that solution. In the fourth lecture will be found my reasons for rejecting both of these views, — the former because it virtually abolishes the rationality of the whole, the latter because it ignores the rationality of the parts. So far the discussion has proceeded on the principle that a philosophy of religion is possible. There is, how- ever, a very active school of thinkers who are averse to any philosophy of religion, or at least to any that claims to provide more than a working conception of life. viii PREFACE This is the topic dealt with in the sixth and seventh lectures, which endeavour to show that Professor James is led by his method to over-accentuate the per- sonal aspect of religion and to fall back upon an empty " subliminal consciousness/' while Professor Harnack misinterprets the history of Christianity by a mistaken identification of thought with abstract reflection, an identification which results in the exclusion of religious experience from the universal law of all experience. The lectures which immediately follow, from the eighth to the fifteenth inclusive, are critical studies in the historical evolution of religious thought, intended to cover its main movements, and to show, in a concrete way, the process by which the religious consciousness has been gradually purified and enriched. Incidentally these studies may be taken to confirm the view, tacitly or expressly maintained in the whole course of lectures, that philosophy is a systematic formulation of the rational principles underlying all experience, and the philosophy of religion a systematic formulation of the single rational principle which differentiates itself in all experience and makes it a coherent whole, not a thing of shreds and patches. This idea of a self-differentiating principle, which is the central thought of the whole course of lectures, is the special topic of the two last, in which an attempt is made to contrast the concrete idea of God, as the culmination of the whole enquiry, with the one-sided determination of His nature characteristic of Agnosticism, Mysticism and Pantheism, and to PREFACE ix show the bearing of the idea thus reached upon the interpretation of nature and of human life. My obligations to Dr. Edward Caird, late Master of Balliol, I shall not attempt to estimate or express. In the two last lectures especially I am very greatly indebted to his Evolution of Theology in the Greek Philosophers^ and, in a less degree, to his Evolution of Religion. For the use made of the material which he has supplied I am of course alone responsible. I have also found an article by Professor J. S. Mackenzie, in Mind for July, 1906, on "The New Realism and the Old Idealism," of great assistance in the preparation of Lecture Fifth. Of the books on Philo, mentioned in the Appendix, I owe most to Dr. Drummond's Philo-Judaeus, Maier's Des Juden Philo Buch von der Weltschopfung, and Jowett's St PauVs Epistles. Professor Harnack's Lehrbuch der Dogmengeschichte^ Flugel's Maniy seine Lehre und seine Schriften, Dorner's Augustinus, and Nourrisson's La Philosophie de Saint Augustin have been of great service to me in dealing with Augustine and his relations to Manichaeism and Neoplatonism. In the statement of the philosophy of Thomas Aquinas I have found Stockl's Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters an invaluable guide. To my colleague, Professor John Macnaughton, recent Croall Lecturer I owe the improvement of several passages in the translations from Philo, Irenaeus and Hippolytus. By the courtesy of Messrs. Houghton, Mifflin & Co. I am enabled to include the lecture on " Leibnitz X PREFACE and Protestant Theology," which originally appeared in the New World, To the other works cited in the Notes I am more or less indebted, while various articles in the Hibbert Journal have served as an index of current theological thought. I hope that the somewhat full analysis of the Contents may be useful. Queen's University, Canada, ibth October^ 1907. CONTENTS LECTURE FIRST RELIGION AND AUTHORITY PAGE Importance and difficulty of the Philosophy of Religion. Method followed is to examine typical ways of con- ceiving the world with a view to a higher synthesis, . i Religion at once a life, a creed and a ritual ; but, as any one of these constituents may be accentuated, there are three main types of religious philosophy. The lectures first consider that sub-division of the second type which bases religion on Authority, 3 Christian dogma inevitable, because Christianity had to satisfy men nourished on Greek philosophy, and was required as the unifying bond of the Church ; just as, conversely, the Church was needed to guarantee dogma. Hence the early view of Authority, which must now be modified to seem even plausible. Cardinal Newman the first to propound the modern view, ... 6 Newman's theory of development right in holding that there is an intellectual element in faith, and in denying that the religious consciousness is created by dogma ; wrong in not recognizing that reflection enriches faith ; as -also in viewing doctrine as a "symbol" of faith, and faith as a " symbol " of truth, .... 9 The problem of the comprehension of the Infinite must be faced. The solution does away with Newman^s plea for the Authority, of t)ie Church, ig xu CONTENTS LECTURE SECOND THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA PAGE Summary of Lecture First, . 22 Dr. Wilfrid Ward's new defence of Authority : (i) we recognize the authority of experts in science and history ; (2) the intuitions and reflections of men of religious genius have a peculiar authority ; (3) the Church does not originate, but merely sanctions, true ideas ; (4) as organic the human race requires a special organ of religion, 24 Weakness of the defence: (i) the authority of experts rests upon the rationality of the universe and the identity of reason in all men ; (2) the man of genius has no authority other than deeper insight ; (3) the authority of the Church is ultimately the authority of reason ; (4) the same principle is present in all . members of the human race, not confined to religious "experts"; hence the true Church is the ideal Church, not a special organisation, 26 Ahb6 Loisy, applying the results of modern science to scripture and dogma, opposes Harnack's reduction of Christianity to a few simple truths, but, ultimately, he falls back on Authority, on the ground that by reason man cannot attain to a knowledge of God, . . 40 Untenability of this view, 42 LECTURE THIRD SCIENCE. MORALITY AND RELIGION Summary of Lecture Second, . . . . . . 46 The rejection of Authority throws us back on Reason as the only basis of morality and reHgion, ... 48 Sketch of the development of thought from the Sixteenth Century till the age of Kant, 50 CONTENTS xiii Kant accepts . the inviolability of natural law, but seeks *'age to defend God, Freedom and Immortality. As the method of the sciences is constructive, so the mind constitutes the system of nature, and therefore is not subject to it. Nor is that system self-complete, as is^ proved by the contradictions which arise when nature is confused with ultimate reality. As our experience is only of phenomena, there is a possibility that in our inner or noumenal nature we may be free ; a possibility which is converted into certainty by our consciousness of moral law, which compels us to postulate freedom, immortality and God, ... 54 LECTURE FOURTH IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Summary of Lecture Third, 72 Kant has refuted the old dualism of subject and object, but has given occasion for a new dualism. His problem not psychological but speculative. He rightly holds the identity of intelligence, but destroys the force of his contention by opposing experience to reality. Origin and untenability of the opposition. The system of nature but a partial determination of a rational self-determinant and spiritual universe. The opposition of faith and knowledge not necessary in the defence of man's higher interests, and disappears when the higher side of the Critical Philosophy is developed, y^ LECTURE FIFTH PERSONAL IDEALISM AND THE NEW REALISM Summary of Lecture Fourth, . .... 100 Herbert Spencer's Philosophy of Religion unsatisfactory, . loi Personal Idealism opposes Monism, and insists upon Per- sonality as distinctive of man and God. In meeting objections, it admits God to be hmited in power, . 102 xiv CONTENTS Contrast of Personal and Speculative Idealism. The page former is self-contradictory in identifying knowledge with "ideas" in an individual mind and yet affirming the existence of other minds. The distinction of "idea" and "content" does not avoid the contradiction. God, as confined to his own "ideas," can neither know nor will anything, io8 The New Realism a protest against Personal Idealism. It maintains that "ideas" and "objects" are funda- mentally different: (i) the "idea'' of a sensible thing is not the thing itself ; (2) the feeling of hunger is not the state of hunger ; (3) the thought that 2 + 2=4 is not the truth that 2 + 2=4, 113 The New Realism right in opposing the reduction of >^-' reality to "ideas," wrong in opposing "ideas" and *■' objects " and thus endorsing the mistake of its opponent. Speculative Idealism maintains : (i) that the conditions of the existence of an external object are the same as the conditions of knowledge ; (2) that the feeling of hunger differs from the state of hunger as the sensitive to the non-sensitive ; (3) that mathematical judgments are not based on "ideas" as "images" but on " universals," which express true though limited aspects of reality. The realist over- looks the spiritual character of the universe. Answer to the difficulty that prior to life and intelligence inorganic nature existed. The absolute not a mere "ideal," 115 LECTURE SIXTH THE INTERPRETATION OF RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE Summary Statement of Speculative Idealism, . . .136 First Type of religious theory that which accentuates the personal aspect of religion. Professor James as the representative of the "psychological" subdivision of it. Great value of his "Varieties of Religious Experience" as a collection of psychological data, . . . . i37 CONTENTS XV Development of Philosophy since Kant in England : ^^^^ Herbert Spencer, T. H. Green, F. H. Bradley, . . 138 "Pragmatism" as a method of defending religion. It rests upon two untenable assumptions: (i) that nothing is verifiable except "scientific" fact; (2) that there is an absolute opposition of faith and knowledge, . . 141 James, in his philosophy of religion, falls back on the "subliminal consciousness," and reduces the object of religion to " something larger than ourselves," or perhaps a " collection " of finite selves. This concep- tion of religion results in an abstraction, and ignores the higher elements of religious experience. Thus St, Paul is admitted to be a rehgious genius because of his " visions " instead of his " prophecy." The "sub-conscious" life really lower than the conscious. The sense in which "experience" is the basis of religion, 149 Note on the Pragmatic conception of Truth, . . .158 LECTURE SEVENTH CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY First Type of religion, second subdivision : Professor Harnack the representative of the "historical" view. His kinship with Professor James. His doctrine con- nected with that of Ritschl, himself a follower of Schleiermacher, 165 The history of dogma is for Harnack an obscuration and "secularization" of the essence of religion, as found in Jesus Christ and his Gospel. Religion is a life, not a doctrine. Aim of the historian is to discover the kernel of religion by an examination of the facts of history. This kernel consists in the " Kingdom of God" as present here and now: of God the Father and the infinite value of the human soul ; of the higher righteousness and the New Commandment of love, 167 xvi CONTENTS While religion may exist without abstract conceptions, ^^^^ Harnack is wrong in assuming that it excludes all conceptions. Thought is only an element in the religious consciousness, but so also are feeling and will. Harnack virtually admits the function of thought when he makes religion imply "the reality of God the Father/* A purely historical investigation will not reveal the "essence'' of Christianityj but only a philo- sophical enquiry. Religion not an unchanging "kernel," but a living principle ; hence religious experience grows ever richer. Illustration from early, as compared with modem, Christianity, i68 LECTURE EIGHTH PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT Summary of Lecture Seventh, 190 Philo an eclectic in philosophy. Difficulty of determining his influence on New Testament writers, . . . 193 In his De Mundi Opificio Philo assumes that the Penta- teuch is a final revelation of truth, and contains a complete philosophy. By his use of the allegorical method he reconciles Moses and Plato. Origin and temporary value of the method, 196 Philo's theory of creation a transformation of the Jewish conception under the influence of Greek thought. He denies the eternity of the world, while maintaining the eternity of formless matter. He has a clear idea of the limits of the "design/' argument, but virtually assumes two opposite principles, God and "matter." Employs the " cosmological " argument. Interprets the Mosaic account of creation as implying a distinction between the ideal or archetypal world and the visible universe. The divine powers, ideas and reason are inseparable, but the visible universe only partially manifests God's goodness, not his whole nature. Philo extracts from scripture a theory of the order of rank in the parts of the ideal world, 200 CONTENTS xvii Three main ideas in Philo : (i) the absoluteness of God ; pa^e (2) the divine Logos ; (3) the visible creation, including man. God in his inner nature held to be for us incomprehensible, inexpressible and without qualities, because Finite and Infinite are incommensurable. Self-contradictory character of this doctrine, . . 215 LECTURE NINTH PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT (CONCLUDED) Summary of Lecture Eighth, . . . . .217 The Logos in Philo : its two-fold meaning. The macro- cosm and the microcosm. How Philo would reconcile the inscrutability of God with man's knowledge of Him. The Logos is (i) the Word, (2) the instrument of God in the creation of the world, (3) eternally begotten, not made, (4) the first-born Son, (5) the man of God, (6) the heavenly man, (7) the second God, (8) the Mediator, (9) the Intercessor, (10) the High Priest, (11) the bread from heaven, (12) the Hving stream, (13) the flaming sword, or "cutter," (14) the cloud at the Red Sea, (15) the Rock; all of which appear in the New Testament. The Logos in Philo is not a Person. It is identified with the Law, subjection to which is freedom, and which is the convincer of sin, 221 Philo holds the pre-existence and independence of the soul, and regards the body as the source of evil, though not in itself evil. As the soul has two parts, so there are men who live in the flesh and men who live in the spirit. Man being by nature corrupt, a virtuous life is of no avail without the grace of God. Besides the four cardinal virtues, there are the three graces of faith, hope and love. The Jewish ceremonial law is of perpetual obligation, 230 Philo, St, Paul and the author of the Epistle to the Hebrews partly agree in their method. There are also similarities of expression. But there seems to be no borrowing, and the whole spirit and outlook on life are different. Comparison of Philo with St. Paul and St. John, 233 h xviii CONTENTS LECTURE TENTH GNOSTIC THEOLOGY PAGE Summary of Lecture Ninth, . . ... 248 Irenaeus' characterisation of the Gnostics. They are less unchristian and irrational than he supposes : nor did they pervert the accepted doctrine, but made an honest attempt to defend Christianity. Encratites, Docetists and Carpocratians may be neglected, . . . .251 L Judaic Gnosticism claimed hidden wisdom, exclusive mysteries and special illumination ; attributed the work of creation to angels ; and advocated asceticism. How Cerinthus differs from the Ebionites, . . 258 IL Hellenic Gnosticism, under the influence of Greek ideas and the allegorical method, transformed Chris- tianity into a mystical philosophy. Starting from the preconception that God is absolutely complete in Him- self apart from the world, its results are unsatisfactory, . 264 Valentinus holds that before all created being there existed the Father or Depth ; alone, uncreated, without place or time, unrelated to any other being, at once indeter- minate and infinitely determinate, . . . 269 Basilides maintained that " the God that was not " willed to make a world ; at least so we must express ourselves, though no human language can really express the truth. How Basilides is led to deny thought, perception and will of God. Logical result of that denial, ... . ... 270 LECTURE ELEVENTH GNOSTIC THEOLOGY (Concluded) Hellenic Gnosticism solves the problem of evil by inter- posing a series of "aeons" or "powers" between God and the world. Valentinus makes them dual, Basilides single, and both distinguish the Pleroma from the visible universe, the latter being the product of the CONTENTS xix Demiurge. Basilides combines the two ideas of creation p*g^ and development in his doctrine of the " cosmical seed." He holds a threefold Sonship. His view of the relation between Judaism and Christianity. Evil he traces back to the spiritual Powers, and salvation he conceives as a special illumination or Gnosis. Jesus not the heavenly- Christ. The Church rightly rejected the separation of the human and divine. The ethics of Hellenic Gnosti- cism either ascetic or antinomian, .... 278 in. Syriac Gnosticism was unaffected by Greek philosophy and was of a practical character, 294 The Acts of Thomas unspeculative both in form and in content : it indicates a belief in angels, devils and demoniac possession, and in the magical virtue of the dust of St. Thomas ; inculcates asceticism on the ground of the evil nature of matter ; is infected with mysticism ; and denies the knowability of the spiritual world, 295 The treatise of Philip, a disciple of Bardaisan, though it is infected with dualism, shows some speculative power in its reconciliation of nature, fate and free- will, 297 LECTURE TWELFTH AUGUSTINE'S PHASES OF FAITH ^- Augustine's influence partly due to the process of religious experience through which he passed, .... 299 Cicero's Hortensius awakened him to a higher view of life, though it disappointed him by the absence* of Christian ideas, 300 Turning to Scripture, he was repelled by its anthropo- morphism, not having as yet found a solvent in the allegorical method, 300 His next phase was faith in Manichaeism. Relation of Manichaeism, Neoplatonism and Catholic Christianity. Source of the popularity of Manichaeism. It confuses &2 XX CONTENTS the natural and the spiritual, and sets up two page antagonistic kingdoms of good and evil, placing Satan at the head of the latter. Though he is made in the image of Satan man has elements of good in him. The prophets, including Jesus, St. Paul and Mani himself, descended into the world to save man. Manichaeism ascetic in its ethics. Orders of the Manichaean community. Augustine attracted by its denial of anthropomorphism, its apparent solution of the problem of evil and free will, its high estimate of reason, and its asceticism, 301 Augustine's misapplication of Aristotle's Categories the beginning of Scholasticism, 308 In an aesthetic treatise Augustine characterizes the beautiful as involving the contrast of opposites, and applies the distinction to the universe at large, .... 308 By his study of astronomy Augustine's belief in Mani- chaeism was weakened, and he fell back on a dogmatic scepticism, ......... 310 Influenced by Ambrose, he rejected Manichaeism, and adopted Neoplatonism, 311 Neoplatonism the euthanasia of Greek philosophy. Its historical phases. Plotinus seeks to answer two questions: (i) How does the Absolute reveal itself? (2) How does man apprehend the Absolute? To the first he answers, " through emanations" ; to the second, "in a divine ecstasy," 315 His five-fold division of Being. The Absolute indefinable. As a pure energy it produces that which is distinct from itself, but an "image" of itself. Grades of being determined by the degree of remoteness from it. The emanations are : (i) The Notjs, (2) the world soul, (3) the phenomenal world, (4) matter. Spiritual life the ascent to the Absolute, its ultimate stage consisting in absorption in it. Adaptation of Neoplatonism to popular religion ; especially by Amelius, Porphyry, and lamblichus, I 317 CONTENTS xxi Augustine attracted by the Neoplatonic idea of God as page spirit, by its doctrine of the Logos, by its high concep- tion of the soul, and by its apparent reconciHation of evil with the perfection of God, 3^3 Learning from experience that Neoplatonism did not destroy the power of the passions, Augustine turned to Scripture, and found in the doctrine of the Incar- nation the revelation of the inner nature of God and the desiderated means of transforming the whole nature, 326 Summary of Augustine's phases of faith, .... 327 LECTURE THIRTEENTH AUGUSTINE'S THEOLOGY Augustine gave Christian Theology a Neoplatonic colour- ing. His two main ideas are God and sin. . . 330 God essentially self-manifesting. Defence of the Trinity : each "person" expresses a special "function," just as the mind of man is one and yet has the three "functions" of memory, intelligence and will. God rather appre- hended by intuition, than comprehended by thought. Augustine insists upon the unity of God, as an answer to Manichaeism, almost at the expense of the distinction of the three " persons," 332 Creation according to a divine plan. Difficulty of Augus- tine's view. His defence of the idea of "creation out of nothing." No succession in the divine will, for God is unchangeable, and only the changeable is subject to time. Nor is God extended, for space is relative to body, 336 The creation and preservation of the world identical in essence. Two different views of providence in Augustine, 340 Relation of man to God : Adam originally good, but capable of sin, since he had the power to refuse the aid of God. Self-assertion connected with the xxii CONTENTS negative element in man. Adam's sin at once privatio page boni and superbia. Augustine's doctrine contrasted with that of Pelagius. The consequences of Adam's sin are : (i) that his posterity have lost the power to will the divine aid, and (2) participate in his guilt. Augustine's attempts to reconcile his view of human freedom with the divine sovereignty by the idea of harmony, 341 Augustine's doctrine of divine grace. The essence of faith is the consciousness of sin and grace. Christ frees man from sin, guilt and punishment, and restores him to his original state of purity, by giving His own blood as a ransom to the devil for man's guilt, . . 345 Augustine's doctrine of Predestination the logical result of his view of the Fall. He tries to reconcile it with human activity by saying that there are means of grace which are necessary to the realization of the divine will, though not from the divine point of view, 347 Great influence of Augustine on his age, especially through his conception of sin and grace. He first formulated the doctrine of the authority of the Church, but he also insisted upon the necessity of direct communion with God, 348 (i) In his doctrine of the Trinity Augustine expresses the fundamental principle of Christianity, but he fails to grasp the unity-in-distinction of God, .... 353 (2) In his doctrine of the divine purpose, Augustine does not succeed in reconciling the completeness of God's knowledge, apart from the idea of the world, with the necessity of the idea of the world to its complete- ness, 355 (3) Nor does his theory of creation explain how God can be complete prior to the existence of the world, while yet the world has its own reality, .... 356 His view of time and space leads to a similar difficulty, . 357 CONTENTS xxiii (4) Augustine's doctrine of Sin unsatisfactory, because ^''^^ it gives man the power to will evil but not good, and thus destroys moral responsibility, .... 35^ (5) Truth and error in the Augustinian doctrine of Pre- destination, ... 360 LECTURE FOURTEENTH MEDIEVAL THEOLOGY Medieval Christianity unfavourable to independent specula- tion. In its first stage largely devoted to the logical problem of universals ; in its second stage to the formulation of the medieval ideal of the universal sovereignty of the Church, 362 Thomas Aquinas seeks to reconcile faith in authority with reason. He opposes Reason and Revelation, Knowledge and Faith, Philosophy and Theology ; attempting to maintain their independence, while affirming their harmony. In explaining the grades of being he employs the Aristotelian distinction of " form " and " matter." He affirms the primacy of the intellect, and holds that the good is commanded by God because it is good, 367 The theology of Thomas follows the articles of faith. Intuition, Faith and Knowledge are different modes of apprehending God, whose existence is a truth at once of reason and of revelation. Thomas rejects the ontological argument, but employs the cosmological and physico-theological. The doctrine of the Trinity is a truth of revelation, not of reason ; but in the world, and especially in man, there are traces of the divine nature, which yield analogies to it ; the Son being the "procession" of God's thought of Himself, the Holy Spirit the "procession" of His love of Himself,. . 375 The fact of creation Thomas holds to be demonstrable, but the creation of the world out of nothing is an article of faith, though it admits of " probable " proof. He defends the providence of God, but denies that xxiv CONTENTS infinite goodness demands the creation of a perfect ^^ge world. He tries to reconcile evil and free-will with providence. His doctrine of the Fall and of redemp- tion, 380 Thomas' doctrine, that the Sacraments are the instruments of grace, is the strongest support of the Church, which he identifies with the mystical person of Christ, . . 389 The Papacy essential to the preservation of the unity of the faith, on which the unity of the Church depends. The Church may punish heretics and apostates with death, 390 Contrast of medieval and modern thought, . . . 395 LECTURE FIFTEENTH LEIBNITZ AND PROTESTANT THEOLOGY Luther and Descartes as representatives of the modern spirit. Spinoza substitutes Philosophy for Theology. Leibnitz seeks to reconcile them, ..... 398 The post-Reformation Theology : the Augsburg Confession, Socinus, Melanchthon and Calvin, .... 400 The Cartesian and Spinozistic conceptions of God, . . 402 The TModicSe of Leibnitz : Relations of Paganism, Judaism and Christianity. Truths of faith and truths of reason. The latter divide into necessary and contingent truths. Answer to Bayle's difficulties, 404 Natural Theology : Human freedom and divine sovereignty reconciled in the doctrine that God has created the best of all possible worlds. Distinction between permitting and willing evil. The principles of Contradiction and Determinant Reason. The pre-established harmony as reconciling freedom and providence. Physical evil the condition of greater good, 413 Untenability of the Leibnitzian oppositions of natural and revealed religion, necessary and contingent truth, possibility and actuality, 424 CONTENTS XXV LECTURE SIXTEENTH GOD AND THE WORLD ' PAGE Short summary of the idealistic view of the world. Result of the historical enquiry, 430 How Speculative Idealism is distinguished from Agnosti- cism and Personal Idealism,. . . . . .431 Mysticism separates God from the world and from man's ordinary consciousness, with the result that all positive knowledge of God is denied. Contrast of Mysticism and Agnosticism. Agreement and contrast of Mysticism and Idealism, . . 434 Pantheism essentially different from the ideahstic concep- tion of God, . 440 LECTURE SEVENTEENTH GOD AND MAN Mysticism, in separating the Finite from the Infinite, leads to a false conception of good and evil. PlotinUs regards evil as a perversion of the craving for unity with the Absolute, due to the animal appetites. Regeneration is possible by liberation from self, and the ascent, through the practice of virtue, first to pure contemplation and finally to "ecstasy," . , . 448 Logical consequences of Mysticism : degradation of the Infinite and an insuperable conflict of morality and religion. Plotinus wrongly identifies self-will with the pursuit of definite ends, and is therefore led to conceive of the highest life as immersion in an indefinable Absolute. Augustine perceived the fundamental defect of Neo-platonism, 44^ Pantheism denies the existence of evil, explaining it to be due to the illusory influence of imagination, which represents the part as if it were the whole. This doctrine is self-contradictory and untenable, . . 454 xxvi CONTENTS ^ Idealism maintains that evil is real, but is not absolute. ^^°^ The perfection of the whole is not incompatible with the freedom and imperfection of the parts. The process of evil is necessary in a spiritual universe. The regeneration of man implies the immanence of the divine spirit in him, together with the free response of his own spirit to its intimations ; which means, that evil is overcome in so far as the individual makes the guilt of all his own, and so appropriates the good of all. Christianity is the reconciliation of morality and religion, 457 APPENDIX I. Books on Philo, 467 II. Extracts from Philo, 468 III. Extract from the Septuagint, Gen. I. . . . 479 Index, 480 THE PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION LECTURE FIRST RELIGION AND AUTHORITY The attempt to deal in a short course of lectures with a problem so difficult and comprehensive as the philosophy of religion will appear, I am afraid, bold to the verge of rashness. Not only is there much dispute as to what constitutes religion, and an equally great variety of opinion in regard to the nature and the claims of philosophy, but these divergencies concern what the disputants feel to be so vital and funda- mental, that they find it almost impossible to maintain that attitude of impartiality which is necessary to the solution of the problem. We shall probably all agree that a man's religion, as the expression of his total attitude to life, is that which gives meaning and direction to all that he thinks and feels and does ; and that his philosophy, whether it assumes an articulate and systematic form or simply constitutes the spiritual atmosphere in which he lives, expresses his deepest and most cherished convictions. There is, therefore, always a danger that one may inadvertently stir up the ashes of former controversy and liberate the fierce fires which glow beneath. I can hardly expect to be so fortunate as not to say something which runs counter to some heartfelt conviction of 2 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION those who hear me, and my only defence must be that which Aristotle urged in explanation of his attack upon Plato, that truth must be held dearer than friendship. "If only we are resolved to know the truth, even if that should compel us to abandon or modify opinions that we have long held to be beyond dispute, it does not seem unreasonable to hope that we may at least come to a general agreement in regard to the greatest of all interests, the interest of our religious life. Though the problems dealt with in the philo- sophy of religion are in one sense harder of solution than ever before, in another sense their solution was never more simple. Their solution is harder, because of the very intensity with which men now throw themselves into some special pursuit, and the con- sequent difficulty they experience in estimating the claims of other pursuits ; it is easier, because, by the inevitable progress of science and historical criticism, the dogmatic attitude of an earlier age has been superseded, or at least modified, and thus the com- batants are in a better frame of mind for the construction of a more comprehensive doctrine. I propose, then, to ask what conclusions may be reached by a careful and impartial interpretation of the facts of religious experience. In attempting to carry out this programme, it will be advisable to pass in review various typical ways of conceiving the world, with the object of determining how far they can be regarded as satisfactory. In examining these views I hope to avoid the merely polemical spirit, a spirit which is fatal to the discovery of truth, and to have a single eye for whatever of permanent value they contain. No doubt I might have ignored all the views which I am unable to accept in their integrity, and simply set forth what I conceive to be RELIGION AND AUTHORITY 3 a true philosophy of religion. But, though much may- be said in favour of this method, it seems to me to have two main defects : in the first place, it does not sufficiently come home to those who have been accustomed to hold a different set of beliefs ; and, in the second place, it ignores the important truth, that the value of philosophy in all cases, and especi- ally the value of the philosophy of religion, lies to a large extent, on the one hand, in giving to the various elements of truth their due weight, and, on the other hand, in bringing them together in a more comprehensive whole. What is religion? However this question may be answered, it will hardly be denied that religion contains three elements, which may be distinguished from one another, but which yet are inseparable. In the first place, religion is not a mere theory, but a Ijfe : it is a living personal expression of what is believed to be the highest form of activity of which a man is capable. It must not be assumed that this distinctive note of the religious consciousness is necessarily in contradiction with the co-existence in the same individual of a theory or system of religion ; all that need be held is, that, whether such a theory is constructed or not, at least there must be a direct and effective consciousness which in some way trans- forms a man's whole nature. In the second place, religion implies a belief in something higher than any given object of sense, and higher than any finite subject. Whether this belief is ultimately justifiable, or has no higher guarantee than its power of lifting the life of the individual to a higher plane, I do not at present enquire ; but it will hardly be denied that, with the elimination of the belief in something that may be called divine, the whole influence of religion 4 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION would be gone. No man can look on the world with " other larger eyes/' or preserve his enthusiasm for higher things, after his faith in the divine has been destroyed. Lastly, religion expresses itself in certain peculiar acts, sometimes called religious, and these acts, as it may perhaps be fairly claimed, are at least of service as the external signs or symbols of religious emotion, even if they are not, as some contend, essential to the very existence and vitality of the religious life. Religion, then, to sum up, is at once a life, a creed, and a ritual. Now, while it will be generally, if not universally, conceded, that all three elements are essential to religion in its completeness, there may be very great variation in the degree of importance attached to each. To one who regards religion mainly as a life, creed and ritual will naturally seem of very subordinate value ; and he may even go so far as to say that any definitely formulated creed is not only unessential, but is positively prejudicial to the fulness and vitality of the religious life ; while to ritual he will either be indifferent, or will seek to reduce it to its barest and simplest form. The dislike of system is shown in many ways, ranging from the contention that the truths of religion may be all summed up in the Fatherhood of God and the Sonship of man, to the denial of all objective truth and the substitution of any belief that gives satisfaction to the individual who holds it ; but, whatever form it assumes, it is characteristic of this mode of thought, that it views religion almost entirely as the direct and spontaneous expression of the spirit. Very different is the conception of religion held by those who attach most importance to the content of faith. For them religion is no doubt a life, but it RELIGION AND AUTHORITY 5 is a life nourished and sustained by beliefs which are fundamentally true. No belief, as they contend, can have a permanent influence upon a rational being which does not correspond to the actual nature of things. The bare suggestion that its value is based upon, or at least is to be decided purely by, its influence upon the life and character of the individual, seems to them preposterous and immoral. What right, they ask, has any one to believe what cannot in some way be proved to be in harmony with the ultimate nature of things? and how can the belief in what is false by any possibility minister to the higher life, unless truth and goodness are in hopeless disharmony with each other ? To minds of this type, therefore, a clearly formulated system of ideas is a necessity. They do not deny that religion is personal, but they maintain that unless the beliefs of 'the individual are true, his life will not be that to which man is fitted, and was meant, to attain. Agreeing in this general contention, representatives of this view of religion may yet differ fundamentally in regard to the foundation of religious belief; some appealing to the authority of a church, or of scripture, others to the self-evidencing power of reason. In the one case, religious truth is conceived to be formulated in a definite creed or collection of dogmas, in the other to consist in a science or philosophy of religion. Still another attitude towards religion is assumed by those who lay great stress upon the rites and ceremonies in which religion is outwardly expressed. The representatives of this view do not deny that their tendency is to identify the religious life with the performance of so-called " religious " acts, and to value the creed less in itself than as the authoritative constitution imposed by the Church. 6 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION In these lectures I do not propose to deal with this last type of thought. It seems enough to say, that whatever value may be ascribed to ritual, there can be no vital religion which does not express itself in a life, or which cannot be formulated in a definite system of ideas. Nor would any high-minded sacer- dotalist deny the truth of the statement that " pure ritual and undefiled is to visit the fatherless and widows in their affliction, and to keep oneself un- spotted from the world," though he might add that it also included the performance of the religious acts enjoined by the Church. There remain to be con- sidered the other two types of thought : that which attaches predominant importance to religion as a life, and tends to minimize the value of doctrine, and that which insists upon the supreme importance of true belief as the indispensable condition of the re- ligious life. It will be convenient to begin with the latter, and first of all with the view which bases the truth of religious beliefs upon the authority of a particular Church. The special form of this doctrine which I propose to consider is that which was first clearly expressed by Cardinal Newman, and has since been endorsed by some of the most distinguished and enlightened exponents of the Roman Church ; but it is practically accepted by all those representatives of other churches, who seek to base the doctrines of religion on authority. I shall therefore endeavour to determine the element of truth which is contained in the appeal to an authority other than that of the individual consciousness. The Christian religion, as it finds expression in the New Testament, is not as yet a system of doctrine, though no doubt in the epistles of St Paul and in the fourth Gospel the beginning of the reflective RELIGION AND AUTHORITY 7 process is already apparent. When we consider, how- ever, that this reflective process was essential to the liberation of the principle of Christianity from the accidents of its Jewish origin and to its triumph over the pagan conception of life to which it was opposed, we can hardly accept the view of Renan and others, that the transition from its first intuitive form to its later reflective form was an inevitable but melancholy degradation. What leads these writers to look at all systematic thought about religion as doing violence to its original simplicity and power is mainly a confusion between dogma, in the sense of a number of propositions based upon external authority, and a reasoned doctrine which claims no other support than its own inherent truth. But these two forms of reflection are widely different from each other. In the former, the assumption is virtually made that truth is not self-evidencing, but depends for its validity upon the attestation of an external witness ; while the latter claims to be but the explicit formu- lation of the rational system already implicit in the intuition of its founder. That the rise of dogma was inevitable becomes apparent when we consider the antagonists that Christianity had to meet and overcome. The early community of Christians soon contained among its members men whose minds had been nourished on Greek philosophy ; and for such men it was a simple necessity to reconcile their faith with their intelligence. The fourth Gospel, by representing Christ as the Eternal Word, which yet manifested itself in an ordinary human life, gave rise to a problem which could only be solved for the intellect by the adaptation of ideas borrowed from Greek philosophy to the content of Christian faith ; and there was a certain want of harmony between the form and the 8 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION matter to which it was applied, that resulted in the conversion of the large intuitions of primitive Chris- tianity into " mysteries " ; which no doubt preserved the various elements of the original intuition, but at the same time held them together in a more or less arbitrary and mechanical way. Moreover, a certain amount of dogma was required to serve as the unifying principle of a society which found itself in an alien world, and which yet claimed to regulate the lives of men in their whole compass ; and, on the other hand, such a society was necessary to give authority to the dogmas. As a natural result we find in the fourth century a complete system of doctrine, implicit belief in which was held by the Church to be essential to salvation. The dogma, as it was held, expressed mainly what was contained in scripture, but the truth of scripture had itself to be guaranteed by the authority of the Church. " Ego vero evangelio non crederem" says Augustine, " nisi me catholicae ecclesiae cominoveret auctoritas!' And indeed this view was inevitable, for when the original intuition was no longer experienced in its over- whelming power and vividness, and as yet an indirect path back to it had not been found through free and untrammelled speculation, the truth half hidden in dogma must for the time either get its support from external authority or be lost to the world. This glance at the origin of Christian dogma may perhaps enable us to realize the form in which the principle of authority first presents itself That form is as yet naive and unsophisticated. It is assumed that the Church is but the divinely appointed instrument for the simple transmission of " the faith once delivered to the saints." No doubt conceptions borrowed from Greek philosophy are freely used, RELIGION AND AUTHORITY 9 but it is assumed that their apph'cation to the truths of religion in no way affects their sense. The principle of authority, however, obviously requires modification, if it is still to be maintained after nineteen centuries of progress. More particularly, it must be brought into harmony with the fact, that not only secular knowledge, but the dogmas of the Church themselves, have undergone development. The first thinker to recognize the necessity of reconciling the progress of theology with the principle of authority was Cardinal Newman, who, in his famous " Essay on the Development of Christian Doctrine,'' advanced a view which with a certain modification is still relied upon by the most advanced thinkers of the Romish Church, and indeed by all theologians who believe at once in authority and progress. The Bible, as Newman points out, is neither the repository of a definite system of doctrines, nor does it contain a single unchanging set of ideas. The former supposition is due to the natural but indefensible tendency to read into the words of scripture a meaning which they do not really bear, and the latter to ignorance of development within the Bible itself through the prophets to Jesus, whose words are in their turn developed by the Apostles. No doubt " the whole truth, or large portions of it, are told, yet only in their rudiments, or in miniature ; ' and they are expanded and finished in their parts as the course of revelation proceeds." Nor can it be held that this process of expansion and completion ends with the apostles ; for " in the apostolic teaching, no historical point can be found at which the growth of doctrine ceased."^ What, then, is dogma? (i) It is the reflective ^Cf. Mellone's Leaders of Religious Thought, pp. 64-67. 10 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION formulation of faith. Certainly dogma does not pro- duce faith, but the content of faith is expressed in dogma. And by "faith" must be understood, not merely an emotion, but also an intellectual comprehension of the object to which it is directed. Faith, as we may say, is a passionate belief that Christianity is a true revelation of the nature of God. (2) As dogma is merely the intellectual formulation of what is contained in faith, " the formulated dogmas are not essential to the genuineness or perfection of religion or religious belief." (3) There is another characteristic of dogma upon which Newman insists : it is not a complete expression of faith, but only a " symbol " or " sign " of it. (4) But, while dogma is merely the abstract formulation of faith — while it is, therefore, neither essential to the perfection of faith nor a complete expression of all that is contained in faith — it yet is a means, and indeed an indispensable means, of preserving and perpetuating faith. On the other hand, it would be a mistake to contrast faith as perfect with dogma as imperfect ; for, just as dogma is an inadequate expression of faith, so faith itself is an imperfect substitute for ultimate truth. A religious idea corresponds to its object as ectype to archetype. Faith holds God to be eternal, omnipotent, omniscient, omnipresent ; but all these predicates are but our poor human substitutes for the Divine verities — "metaphors" or "symbols'* employed to express the inexpressible, and indeed incomprehensible, approxima- tions to a truth which is for ever beyond our reach.^ The bare outline just given of Newman's theory of Development is sufficient to show the originality, and in a certain sense the comprehensiveness, of his ^Cf. Dr. Wilfrid Ward's article on "Newman and Sabatier,*' in the Fortnightly Review for May, 1901. RELIGION AND AUTHORITY ii thought Like all the higher minds of the nineteenth century, he instinctively seeks for a principle of reconciliation which shall lift us above such abstract opposites as faith and doctrine, revelation and reason, eternal truth and human fallibility ; and the lever which he employs is that distinctive idea of the nineteenth century, the idea of development. How far, then, can it be said that he has given us a solution that we can accept without reservation ? The conception of development which Newman applies in explanation of the relation between the original " deposit of faith," as he calls it, and the process by which it has been gradually transformed, seems to me to be inadequate. What he means by " development " is something analogous to its older biological use, in which it was employed to designate a theory of preformation, according to which the growth of a living being is " simply a process of enlarging and filling out a miniature organism, actual but invisible, because too inconspicuous," ^ as distinguished from a genuine evolution of new organic forms. Such a view is no more tenable in the realm of ideas than in the sphere of organic nature. The transition from the original intuition to dogma is not a mere expansion of what already exists " in miniature," to use Newman's own phrase ; it is the transformation of a principle into a form which is, at least reflectively, more specific and more complex than the germ from which it is developed. This defect in Newman's conception of development would now, as I think, be admitted by his recent followers, who maintain that there is a genuine development in the ideas of the Divine, as recorded in the Bible itself, and in the history of doctrine, as evolved from ^Wallace's Logic of Hegel, p. 424. 12 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION the apostolic teaching, that teaching being itself a development of the teaching of Jesus. And not only does Newman's contention, that there is no break in the continuity of religious life and thought, anticipate in a way the course of the best recent thought, but his assertion that faith includes an intellectual, as well as an emotional element, is of great importance at the present time, when there is a strong tendency to regard religion as purely subjective, and to deny that it is based upon universal principles which can be justified at the bar of reason. In protesting by anticipation against this view — a view which is at bottom sceptical of all truth — Newman did valuable service in the cause of a rational faith. When religion is emptied of its intellectual element, and reduced to an inarticulate feeling, nothing can save it from final extinction. For, feeling as such — feeling conceived in separation from every object — is a pure fiction, to which no real experience corresponds, and which only seems to exist because it is unwittingly invested with a rational element to which it has no rightful claim. Even Schleiermacher, who tended to eliminate its intellectual constituent, after defining religion as a " feeling of absolute dependence,*' goes on to identify this " feeling " with " the consciousness of God." In truth, if we eliminate the reference to a Being higher than self, all that is characteristic of religion vanishes away ; for a feeling which admits of no further definition has no meaning for human life, and in fact no habitation anywhere but in the confused imagination of the theorist. Religion, as Newman rightly maintains, involves more than mere feeling. If we speak of it as feeling at all, we must add that it is the feeling of a rational being, who recognizes his own finitude in contrast and relation to an Infinite RELIGION AND AUTHORITY 13 Being. What has led to the supposition that religion is purely a matter of feeling is the familiar experience that it exists, and not infrequently exists in great strength and purity, in those who are unable to analyze their belief, and set forth its constituent elements in reflective form. But the absence of reflection is not the same thing as the undivided sway of feeling. The religious consciousness involves the idea of the Infinite, though that idea may not be made an explicit and separate object of abstract thought ; and if that idea were not present as an informing spirit, giving meaning and direction to faith, the feeling of absolute rest in the Eternal, which is one of its marks, would be inexplicable. Newman is therefore right, as I believe, in main- taining that the religious consciousness contains an intellectual or rational element. And he is also right, I think, in affirming that this consciousness is not created by dogma. More hesitation will be felt in admitting that the genuineness and perfection of religion is entirely independent of formulated dogmas. Since faith precedes and is the condition of dogma, obviously it cannot depend for its existence upon dogma ; but it hardly follows that the development of faith into doctrine in no way contributes to the perfection of faith. The formulation by reason of what is implicit in religious intuition is not a work of supererogation ; it is an instance of a universal law of the human mind, and plays an important part in the development of the religious consciousness. Only by formulating his faith, and setting its contents clearly before his mind, does man come to understand what it really involves ; only thus does he learn to eliminate the accidental and self-contradictory ingredients that weaken its power, and to liberate it from its 14 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION sensuous and unspiritual setting. In this way- Christianity, at first swathed in the garments of the Jewish ceremonial law, was purified and univer- salized ; and a similar process has been going on in modern times, by which it has been stripped of the limitations imposed upon it by the application to it of forms of thought borrowed from the later Greek philosophy and by the confinement of its free spirit in the bonds of medieval dualism. Thus the primitive faith, though it contained a principle that, as I believe, can never die — the principle that only in unity with the Infinite can man realize himself — has come to an ever clearer comprehension of its true self By disengaging the principle which operates in simple faith, it is seen to have a wider and more intimate application, as when, to borrow the imagery of Goethe's fairy-tale, the shepherd's hut has expanded into the temple of humanity by the ever clearer realiza- tion of what is meant by love of one's neighbour. It cannot therefore be said that the process of formulating faith has nothing to do with its perfection ; for that process does minister to its perfection by revealing it to itself We may say of it what Shakespeare says of the eye : " Nor doth the eye itself, That most pure spirit of sense, behold itself, Not going from itself; but eye to eye opposed Salutes each other with each other's form. For speculation turns not to itself. Till it hath travelled and is mirrored there, Where it may see itself."^ No doubt the development of faith comes largely through the influence of men of religious genius, who raise it to a higher potency ; but even here the ^ Troiius and CressidUy act Hi., scene iii., U. 107-111. RELIGION AND AUTHORITY jS reformulation of faith is an indispensable element in its development. What Newman was mainly thinking of, when he declared that faith is independent of dogma, was no doubt the undeniable fact, that the individual man does not cease to be religious because he does not, and perhaps cannot, express his faith in definite propositions. But, true as this is, it by- no means shows that faith is not enriched by the process in which it is brought to a reflective conscious- ness of its own principle. " No man liveth to himself, no man dieth to himself"; and, though this or that man may live in a faith which he cannot make articulate, it must be remembered that he habitually dwells in an atmosphere of ideas prepared for him by the toil of his fellows, not excluding those who have provided him, without effort on his part, with an instrument of reason in the very words he uses to express what otherwise would be inexpressible. Newman, however, tells us that after all dogma is not really an expression of faith, but merely a " symbol" of what cannot be expressed. What he seems to mean is, that there is a fulness and concreteness in the imme- diate religious consciousness which defies all attempts at embodiment in abstract propositions. And no doubt we must admit that it is fatal to identify religion and theology, for such an identification will either destroy the warm and breathing intensity of faith, substituting a creed for a life, or it will convert a system of con- :eptions into a vague and ill-defined mass of feelings, impulses, and images. Religion and theology have sach their own form and their own law, and nothing 3Ut confusion can result from fusing together things >o disparate in their nature. The perfection of religion ;onsists in complete immersion of the whole man in ;he Eternal, the perfection of theology in the complete i6 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION comprehension of the Eternal by the intellect ; and, although, in the wide sense, religion is the source from which theology must draw its content, it is nevertheless true that a religion which never rises to self-conscious- ness in a theology will soon have no content from which theology can draw. Nor do I think that theology is merely the symbol of a reality contained only in religion, if this means that religion has a wealth of content which escapes formulation. In the sense already stated, theology cannot comprehend religion without becoming identical with it, and that would mean the destruction of both ; but this is in no way inconsistent with the view, that theology may bring to explicit consciousness ^^ principle of which religion is the personal consciousness. The notion that theology is merely symbolic seems to me to rest upon the false assumption that thought operates with mere abstrac- tions, whereas it really works with conceptions, which are ultimately distinctions within a single principle that admits of infinite applications. So far from taking this view of thought, Newman goes on to maintain that, just as dogma is an inade- quate expression of faith, so faith is itself an imperfect substitute for the apprehension of ultimate truth. And here, perhaps, we come clearly in sight of the funda- mental assumption which underlies the whole of New- man's reasoning, and indeed of the reasoning of all who ultimately fall back upon authority. If the faith of the individual is veritably life in the Eternal, there is no reason to seek for any tertium quid to unite man and God ; for they are, on that supposition, already united. But if faith is after all merely the aspirations of a weak and fallible mortal after an Infinite to which he can never reach, it is necessary to find some external medium by which the finite and. infinite may be RELIGION AND AUTHORITY 17 Drought together. That medium Newman finds in the authority of the Church, just as others have found It in a mystical intuition, or in some form of mind different from our ordinary consciousness. In referring the view of Newman to his hidden assumption of the Church as an external authority necessary to help out the weakness of faith, I do not mean that he in any way tampered with the facts as he read them ; but only that, seeing them as he did, no other solution seemed to him open. Newman saw, as every devout mind must see, that it is impossible to comprehend the Infinite in all its fulness and perfection, while we yet must in some sense know the Infinite, or we are for ever shut out from reality and truth. " Who can by searching find out God, who can find out the Almighty unto perfection ? " This difficulty he tried to solve by distinguishing between the " symbols " we employ to express the truth, and the " truth " they are meant to express. Now, there is great plausibility in the idea, that all our conceptions of the Divine are " symbols " of a Reality that we do not grasp in itself ; but, when it is pressed to its logical consequences, it results in the denial of all knowledge of any kind. Let us suppose, with Newman, that our highest ideas of the Divine are merely symbolic. Then, what we call our know- ledge of God cannot be the comprehension of God as He is, but must be merely the presentation of a mental construction of our own, which stands to us for God, but is in reality only a convenient fiction, which we assume to be in some way representative of a God whom in any proper sense we do not know. But, if, in thinking of God, we do not really comprehend Him, by what process is He brought within the range of our experience ? It is no answer to fall back upon the " imbecility of the human intelligence," for it is the 6 i8 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION religious consciousness as a personal experience whiclT is here in question, and if that consciousness does not bring us into the presence of God, we have no other organ by which to apprehend Him. And if Newman is precluded from urging the limitation of the intellect in this case, he cannot take refuge in a mystical intuition, for he does not admit that we possess any higher form of apprehension than that of the ordinary conscious- ness. Nor, again, can he urge that the religious consciousness is a form of feeling ; for he contends, and, as I think, rightly contends, that faith must have an object to which it is directed, and this object, as he admits, exists only for thought Now, if God is present neither in pure feeling, nor in pure thought, nor in the unity of the two, how can the human mind possibly come into contact with Him ? As Newman rejects the via negativa of a mystical union with God, maintaining that a rational faith is the highest form of human experience, we are forced to conclude that there is in his doctrine a fundamental discrepancy which vitiates his main conclusion. If we cannot compre- hend the nature of God, it is obvious that we cannot even comprehend that we cannot comprehend Him. A symbol is meaningless except in relation to that which it symbolizes, and if we are unable to reach out beyond the symbol, we can never know that it is a symbol of anything, much less the symbol of an Infinite which by hypothesis is hidden from us by the very constitution of our minds. We cannot, then, as I think, admit that the Divine lies beyond the reach of our consciousness. But, if we deny Newman's view of the symbolical character of our religious ideas, we are forced to face the problem of how a finite being can comprehend the Infinite. Can we know God without being God ? RELIGION AND AUTHORITY 19 This is a problem with which every philosophy of religion must grapple on pain of annihilation. I hope to do something in the sequel to solve it. Meantime, it may be pointed out that to claim knowledge of the Infinite is not to claim infinite knowledge. To say that 3 + 2 = 5 is certainly not to assume complete y knowledge, and yet, if the judgment is true at all, it is true for all intelligences and at all moments, and in that sense is a knowledge of the Infinite. So if I say that " God is one," I express what is true absolutely, if it is true at all, no matter what the character of the " oneness " may be. The judgment means, that whatever else God is, He is one. Now, if this is true, we reach a conception which no possible extension of experience can possibly overthrow, though, with the increase of knowledge, it will no doubt receive further definition and interpretation. If God is " one," He may still be " one " in many senses ; we may con- ceivably define His unity as the unity of a Substance, the unity of a Person, or the unity of Spirit ; but, whichever of these determinations we may ultimately adopt, our original proposition, that He is one and not many, will remain intact ; and, indeed, one test of the truth of different attempts to characterize His nature, will be, whether they are, or are not, consistent with the fundamental characterization of Him as one. No doubt, if we are challenged to prove the oneness of God, we shall have some difficulty in doing so ; a difficulty, however, which will not seem insuperable to any one who sees that, by its denial, the whole of our experience is made inexplicable. Starting, then, from the comprehension of God as one, we may pro- ceed to ask what further determinations are essential to the explanation of the facts of our experience. In this way we may, as I think, proceed step by step to define 20 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION God, ue, to state the fundamental determinations implied in the reality of the world we know. And if in the end we admit, as we must, that we cannot fully deter- mine God, that will in no way invalidate our claim to know what God in His essential nature truly is. Thus every step in our thought of God may be a real com- prehension of what He is, while yet our knowledge of Him is no doubt but poor and barren as compared with the unsearchable riches of His being. Why, then, does Newman deny our knowledge of God ? Why does he set up an impassable barrier between the consciousness of man and the reality of God ? Partly at least because, in his view, the human mind is not only incapable of itself of discovering ultimate reality, but even of really comprehending it when it is supernaturally revealed. The Church, as divinely appointed, must guarantee what reason can neither originate nor understand. But this doctrine cuts both ways. If the mind cannot comprehend God even when He is revealed to it, how can He be revealed at all ? To say that the Church stands sponsor for the existence and nature of God does not do away with the fundamental difficulty, that man, as a being who is unable to transcend his own limited consciousness, cannot be the recipient of even the certainty that God is, because he cannot form any idea of what this God of whom the Church speaks really is. Nor indeed can he have real knowledge of anything else, and therefore not even of the Church, nor of what the Church means. Nothing, in short, can be revealed to a being who is incapable of grasping reality. You cannot make a dog or a child understand a proposition in Euclid, because the faculty of working with universals is absent in the one and undeveloped in the other; and, similarly, if my so-called knowledge of God is never RELIGION AND AUTHORITY 21 really of God, but only of " symbols " that are inter- posed between my consciousness and reality, anything pretending to be a revelation of God will be to me as incomprehensible as the pons asinorum to the dog or the child. The fundamental weakness of this whole mode of thought was clearly brought to light, subse- quent to the time of Newman, by ManseFs self-contra- dictory attempt, in his Limits of Religious Thought^ to show that the Infinite is a self-contradictory concep- tion, being inconceivable by us because of the imbecility of our intelligence. As Newman urged the feebleness of our minds to attain to union with God, in order to force the admission of the divine authority of the Church, so Mansel, by an argument at bottom identical, sought to establish the authority of Scripture on the basis of the insuperable limitations of the human intellect. The logical result of both doctrines was soon seen in the philosophy of Herbert Spencer, who drew the inference that the term " God " is but a name for that ultimate Reality, the nature of which is by us unknowable and indefinable. When the idea of God has thus been emptied of all content, it cannot matter very much whether it stands for something or nothing ; one thing at least is certain, that it cannot serve as the foundation either of religion or of theology. LECTURE SECOND THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA At our last meeting we were occupied in considering the general nature of religion, the different elements which enter into it, and the relation of these elements to one another. Religion we agreed to regard as the consciousness of the divine, and its constituents as the response to the divine of the individual, its comprehension by his intelligence, and the outward expression of this rational emotion in certain acts of ritual. We further discovered that, in the attempt to understand the religious consciousness, different thinkers attach pre-eminent importance to one or other of these constituents, and thus reach widely different conclusions: some forcing the personal aspect into the foreground, while others attach almost exclusive importance to its intellectual or conceptual aspect To the latter class belong those theologians, whether Roman Catholic or Protestant, who hold that the truth of the Christian religion cannot be established by the exercise of private judgment, but requires for its security the authority of a church. A distinguished representative of this mode of thought we found in Cardinal Newman, whose " Essay on the Development of Christian Doctrine" struck the key-note with which the speculations of THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 23 more recent thinkers are in substantial harmony. That Essay we found to be so far in agreement with the reconciliatory spirit of the nineteenth century as to apply the idea of development in explanation of the permanence in change which has marked the history of religion, but to be defective to this extent, that development is conceived rather as a mere enlargement of features present from the first than as a genuine evolution. Newman, however, as we saw, rightly insists upon the presence in the religious consciousness of an intellectual as well as an emotional element, though he hardly does justice to the value of the explicit formulation of that element as a means of enriching faith by bringing to clear consciousness its permanent essence as distinguished from its evanescent form, and enabling it to gain a mastery over all the manifestations of the human spirit. Conceiving of dogma as merely a symbol of faith, Newman is forced to fall back on the external authority of the Church, a conclusion which seems to be confirmed by his view of faith, as itself but the " symbol " of a truth with which the individual mind, because of the limitations of human thought, never comes in direct contact. This whole mode of conception we ventured to reject, together with the corollary that religion must ultimately rest upon external authority ; main- taining that, if pressed to its logical conclusion, it results in absolute scepticism ; and in place of it we sought to commend what seemed the self-consistent doctrine, that in virtue of his rational nature man is not only capable of comprehending the Infinite and Eternal, but in truth only requires to bring into clear consciousness what is implied in his experience of the world and of himself to see that, as his true life consists in union with the Divine, so it is the 24 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION conception of the Divine which gives meaning to the whole of his experience. With this conclusion we might pass from the theory which appeals to external authority in support of faith, but it seems advisable first to consider what more recent exponents of it have to say in its favour. It is customary, as we are told by Dr. Wilfrid Ward,^ for those who attack the principle of Authority to give a false and misleading account of what it means, representing it as a claim upon men to accept certain religious dogmas as true, not because they admit of demonstration, but because they are vouched for by an infallible Church. No intelligent man would advance or submit to so preposterous a demand. What is really contended is that the living Church embodies the intuitions of the great saints, and the reflections of the great theologians, as exercised by them in the consideration and analysis of the Christian revelation. The function of the Church has been to proclaim formally through its official organs the conclusions derived in this way from scripture and tradition. St. Augustine, and not any infallible teacher, formed the theological intellect of Western Christen- dom, as Cardinal Newman reminds us, just as St. Thomas Aquinas was the master spirit in the age of Dante. It is individual genius within the Church which has for the most part suggested the successive developments of the primitive revelation and its intellectual illustration and setting. It is further contended that, not merely in matters of religious belief, but in the case of all beliefs, Authority plays an important and a necessary part. ( I ) No one would now press the right of private judgment to the extreme of claiming for it the privilege of holding any opinion, "^ Hibbert Journal^ i. 678 ff. THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 25 however absurd or immoral. We all recognize the corporate authority of experts in history, physical science, and other departments of knowledge; and we have no hesitation in saying that the mere layman should defer to their authority, devoting his own reasoning powers mainly to the correction and develop- ment of the corporate reason. The human race has justly been compared to a living organism, and if there is any force in the analogy there must be not only the same division of labour in the one as in the other, but also growth and development. The long experience of the race, in fact, is to a great extent the ground of the Authority exercised by the educated over the uneducated. (2) Besides the Authority of experts, a peculiar Authority is rightly claimed for those whose perceptions are either absolutely new or at least abnormally clear and distinct. These are the great spiritual pioneers of the race, whose conscience is supremely sensitive to the direct influence of the Divine. Here is a new Authority, whose intimations should be acted upon, tested, and developed. Of this nature is the Authority of Christ, the highest of all Authority because based upon an experience absolutely unique, in which the Unknown God, dimly present in the conscience of prophet and sage, is openly and unambiguously proclaimed. (3) Lastly comes the Authority of the Christian Church, which, resting upon the revelations of conscience and its development by Christ, may fairly be held to embody the highest spiritual perceptions known to man. And not only so, but it is the custodian of the conceptions elaborated by Christian theologians from conscience and revelation. Thus it contains at once the highest intuitions and the most comprehensive conceptions of Christendom, while the blending of spiritual perception and rational 26 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION analysis is secured by the rulers who preserve the organic unity of the Church, protect the revelation from rationalistic assaults, and seek to keep theology spiritual as well as rational. No one can fail to be struck by the moderate and reasonable tone of the modern exponents of Authority, as indicated by the theory of which a hasty summary has just been given. It is of good augury for the future of theology that the older idea of an absolutely fixed and unchanging body of doctrine has come to seem incredible to the more enlightened minds in the Romish Church, just as the view held for so long by Protestant theologians, that " all the books of the Bible contain the same rigid system of ideas with unessential variations," has been modified by recent advances in historical criticism. But, while we cannot but rejoice in the new and more sympathetic attitude of liberal theologians, we must ask whether, having gone so far, they are not in consistency under compulsion to go further. If there is no infallible system of doctrine, can we still retain the conception of an infallible Church? Is it possible to admit that dogma has undergone continual evolution, without granting that the Church has not always stood for the highest truth ? And if the Church has in some cases opposed what afterwards she accepted, are we not forced to say that the authority which she has exercised has sometimes been an obstacle to the truth, instead of being the condition of its development? These questions cannot be summarily dismissed, but must be candidly considered, and answered either positively or negatively. The Church, as it is claimed, has been the custodian of the intuitions of the great saints and the ratiocina- tions of the great theologians ; so that the revelations THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 27 of men of religious genius have been the main factor in determining the theology which official authority guards. Now, it is of course true that Christianity has developed under the influence of the new experiences and the reflections of men whose ideas have received the official sanction of the Church. But, while this is admitted, it does not follow that there was no truth in the intuitions and reflections of those who have not only failed to receive authoritative recognition, but who have even been condemned as heretics. There are, indeed, thinkers within the Church who are candid enough to admit, what in any case is undeniable, that there have been occasions in which the heretic was right and the official authority wrong; as when Marcion protested against the acceptance of the Old Testament as an absolute standard of Christian morals. It is hardly possible to reconcile such a lapse with the contention that the Church has always guarded the truth, except on the principle that even her mistakes have been advantageous in the long run ; a principle which may indeed be defended if we take a sufficiently comprehensive view, but only by a method which would equally establish the rationality of the wildest deviations from truth and the most atrocious crimes. Without entering into this subtle and difficult problem, I think we may fairly say, with a recent defender of the Romish Church, that by the condemnation of Marcion, the difficulty, which he sought to have solved, was "thereafter thrust into the background under the aegis of Church authority, only to become more prominent than ever when . . . Luther used the Old Testament to defend the polygamy of a Christian King and the Puritans to defend the murder of enemies whom the Lord had delivered into their hands." ^ "^ Hibbert Journal, ii. 218. 28 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION In the condemnation of Marcion, then, we have an instance in which the authority of the Church was admittedly exercised in withstanding the truth. Is it not evident from such a fact alone, that the progress of truth cannot be confined within any prescribed limits ? Beyond the sphere of ideas which official authority guards, lies a wider realm of truth, which it ignores or condemns, and this fact is in no way invalidated by the consideration that the Church has been enriched by the intuitions and the reasonings of her favoured sons. It is not denied that on the whole the Church for many centuries preserved truth which would otherwise have been lost to the world ; but this cannot be taken to mean that it never resisted the progress of truth, and certainly it does not entitle us to assert that, in these days when many organs, all working together and contributing towards the good of the whole, are essential to perfection, all truth is shut up within a single branch of the Christian Church, or even within all its branches in their totality. While the development of theology, as it is held, has been determined mainly by the intuitions and reflections of men of original genius, the Church is claimed to have exercised a controlling and selective influence, guarding the truth from the aberrations of an unsanctified reason. Obviously, therefore, a certain critical process, involving the exercise of reason, falls to be discharged by the Church. Its various councils weighed and adjudicated upon competing doctrines, determining how far the ideas suggested by men of genius were compatible with the essence of Christianity. And it must be admitted that, on the whole, the Church has shown a true instinct in refusing to endorse one- sided views of the divine nature. In this way it discharged an inestimable service in its earlier history, THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 29 rejecting dualistic views, which involved the absolute opposition of divine and human ; refusing to break with the past by discarding the Old Testament scrip- tures, which contain the records of a religious experience, of which Christianity is not the abrogation but the fulfilment; absorbing Greek Philosophy and employ- ing its categories in the construction of a Theology ; and, in our own day, using the discoveries of science and the fuller comprehension of philosophy to deepen and expand its conception of God, the world, and man. But, in all this process, we must discern the operation of that higher reason, which in other forms gives mean- ing to the intuitions of men of religious genius, informs the speculations of philosophy, and determines the discoveries of science. What gives force to the decisions of the Church is the reason immanent in it. Its authority springs from no external transmission of power, nor does it possess any special means of insight not open to the universal spirit of humanity; and its decrees have precisely that degree of value and no more that is imparted to them by their harmony with the truth. That the Church has in general stood for the truth, and has been thfe indispensable instrument in the preservation of a spiritual view of life, is but an instance of that fundamental reasonableness which lies deep in human nature. Nor can she claim to have been invariably free from aberration and error, for which humanity has had to suffer, and in some cases to suffer terribly. The Church, in short, like all human institutions, is neither infallible nor devoid of reason : she has undoubtedly been a witness for the truth, but it is an utterly untenable position that no truth has been developed beyond her pale. What, then, is the ultimate court of appeal ? There Is no ultimate court of appeal but reason, as interpreting 30 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION the growing experience of the race. Anything short of this must be more or less a distortion of the true nature of things. And reason can only do its perfect work, if it is left free and untrammelled. This does not mean that there are no eternal principles of truth and righteousness. The notion that the denial of all authority but reason is equivalent to the assertion that everyone has a right to raise his private judgment and his conscience to the rank of an absolute authority, irresponsible to any other tribunal, is a mere travesty of the so-called " right of private judgment." There is no right divine to reason wrong, any more than to govern wrong. Nothing absolves a man from the obligation to accept nothing but the truth. The justifi- cation of the right, or rather the duty, of private judgment is that, as truth is not revealed to man once for all, but is slowly evolved by immense patience and toil, any foreclosing of the pathway to truth — any assumption of an ultimate and intranscendible limit — puts an arbitrary stop to that free movement of the spirit, without which a new and deeper insight into reality is impossible. As Cardinal Newman pointed out, the theology of a given age is the expression of the stage of truth at which man has so far arrived, but it is not to be identified with absolute truth, truth in its full-orbed completeness. Nevertheless, as I believe, the truth of any age contains absolute truth within it, as the germ contains the developed organism ; for, at no time, not even in his primitive half-blind imaginings, is man entirely destitute of the consciousness of the divine, just as in his latest stage he cannot hope to find the universe absolutely trans- parent to his spiritual vision. The element of truth, then, in the contention that theology rests upon the authority of the Church, seems THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 31 to me to be this, that the Church has on the whole endorsed that higher view of life which is the most precious possession of the race, a view which has been mainly determined by the insight of its saints and thinkers ; i.e. by reason as interpreting the deepest experiences of the heart and coming to the conscious- ness of itself in the comprehension of a rational universe. What is called the authority of the Church is really the authority of reason or truth, and where the Church has been misled, or has been contented with a half-truth, to that extent it has no authority what- ever. Let us, however, consider the special reasons which are usually put forward in support of the con- tention that the authority of the Church is in all cases absolute and unquestionable. An argument is based, for one thing, on the analogy of science and religion. As the layman must acknow- ledge the authority of the expert in history, physical science, and other departments of thought, devoting his own reasoning powers to the correction and develop- ment of the corporate reason ; so, it is said, the individual ought to submit to the authority of the Church, reserving his independent activity for the enrichment of the truth announced by the Church. And of course no one is likely to deny that we shall all show our wisdom by deferring to the conclusions reached by those whose lives are devoted to the solution of a special problem. But we must not lightly assume that an acceptance of the conclusions reached by a body of experts is identical in principle with submission to an external authority. Why do we hesitate to dispute the statements of scientific men, especially if there is substantial agreement among them ? We do so, or should do so, because we have good grounds for believing that they have gone through 32 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION a process, and reached a result, which is identical with the process and result that we should ourselves have experienced had it been possible for us to devote our- selves with equal energy and ability to the same problem. Our assent, in fact, rests upon the tacit conviction that the human mind is in all men of the same fundamental texture, and that, however men may differ in the degree of their intelligence, all will ultimately draw the same conclusions from the same premises. Such a conviction is justifiable only on the supposition that the world in which we live is a rational world, and that in our own intelligence is to be found the principle by which it may be comprehended. Were the universe funda- mentally irrational, or were our intelligence incapable of comprehending it — and either supposition leads to the other — there would be no basis for our faith in the conclusions of science, and therefore no reason for ascribing to experts any more '' authority " than to others. In a company of the blind, it has been said, even the one-eyed man is king. But where all are equally blind there is no king. The so-called " authority " of the expert, then, is really conceived by us to flow from his greater power of rational insight Whenever we have reason to believe that he is swayed by prejudice or passion, we lose faith in his judgment, and he ceases to have " authority " over us. Nor can it be admitted without reserve that it is our duty to devote ourselves solely to the correction and develop- ment of the corporate reason. No doubt even genius of the highest order does not entitle its possessor to set aside the long toil of ages, as if it had borne no fruit ; but, true as this is, it in no way justifies blind submission to current ideas as if they were ultimate. What is the function of genius but to draw aside the veil of tradition which half-conceals and half- THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 33 eveals the fair form of Truth ? Whether a man is to ►ccupy himself with the application of ideas already istablished, or to transmute the whole mass of ideas :haracteristic of his age into a higher truth, must iepend upon his rank in the scale of intelligence. ?rom whatever point of view we look at it, we thus ind that no one is called upon to submit to any luthority but the authority of reason itself, a reason vhich is immanent in all men, and of which therefore 10 man or body of men can claim to be the privileged possessors. The scientific expert who should claim juperhuman powers of insight would only draw down apon himself a well-merited suspicion of intellectual irrogance or charlatanry. His real strength lies in his ippeal to the universal intelligence. If, therefore, the analogy suggested by the relation of the plain man to the scientific expert is to be valid, the authority :laimed for the Church must be placed in its superior rationality. The man of religious genius, like the man Df scientific, artistic, or philosophical genius, is endowed mth a free and penetrative vision which lifts him above :he confused and perplexed consciousness of the ordinary man ; but he is no dweller in a strange aniverse to which others are denied access ; what he sees, those of duller perception can be brought to see under his guidance and inspiration. Just as the poet 3r painter, by stripping off the accidents which hide it from us, directs our attention to a beauty, which we too may come to see, so the man of religious genius, dwelling habitually in the Eternal, of which we catch Dnly fitful glimpses, enables us in some measure to see with his purer and clearer eyes. The real analogy ivould therefore seem to be between the scientific expert ind the man of religious genius, while the plain man ivill be related to the former very much as the Church c 34 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION is held to be related to the latter. And just as the ordinary man can have no valid ground either for accepting or for rejecting the results of science but their harmony or their disharmony with reason, so the Church which endorses or disapproves of the intuitions of the religious genius can have no defensible ground for its deliverances other than their agreement with reason and truth. And obviously the comparison of the human race to an organism in no way invalidates this conclusion. It is perfectly true that there is, and must be, a division of labour. We cannot all be experts, any more than there can be a human organism which is all brain ; but it is just as true that the same life must permeate and vitalize every one of the organs, or there will be, not a single organic unity, but a mere assemblage of heterogeneous parts. The analogy will therefore lead us to maintain, that, diverse as are the functions of the layman and the expert in the social organism, it is the same universal reason which is present in both ; the only difference being, that in the former it is developed, while in the latter it is to a large extent only implicit. And similarly, when it is argued that, as organic, the human race grows in experience, and that " the long experience of the race is to a great extent the basis of the authority of the educated over the unedu- cated," we gladly assent ; only adding, that the " authority " thus resulting is due to the gradual development in the race of that rationality which constitutes in its self-conscious form the distinctive characteristic of man among all the beings known to us. We have " experience " at all, only because through the whole history of our race the same identical principle has been at work, embodying itself in language, customs, laws, and institutions, and in the THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 35 creation of knowledge, art, and religion ; and wherever we discover the inadequacy of the conceptions by means of which order and system have been partially introduced into human life, the impulse to accept nothing that is not perfectly rational compels us to seek for more adequate conceptions. The exponents of " authority " may paint in the most vivid colours the danger of spiritual shipwreck from the disintegrating power of unchecked reason, but the process of transmu- tation goes on. As Dante tells us : " Well I perceive that never sated is Our intellect unless the Truth illumine it. Beyond which nothing true expands itself. Therefore springs up, in fashion of a shoot, Doubt at the foot of truth ; and this is nature Which to the top from height to height impels us." ^ The principle that only the Truth can permanently satisfy a rational being is especially apparent in the sphere of religion. Men of religious genius, we are told, are endowed with a super-sensitive " conscience," which reveals to them in an intuitive or direct way the reality of God. Without stopping to enquire whether *' conscience " is the only guarantee of the divine, we may admit that at least a complete idea of God is impossible without the aid of the moral consciousness. And it is true that there are men whose spiritual insight is so swift and sure that it seems like a gift of nature. They do not slowly and laboriously move from point to point, making their footing secure as they advance, but seem rather to rise by a bound into the empyrean, and to dwell permanently in an atmosphere so rare that others can only breathe it in their best moments. But, while only the finer spirits of our race habitually live ^ Divina Commedia, Paradiso^ 123-132 (Longfellow's translation). 36 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION consciously in the Eternal, all men are capable of the same experience, and without it they would not be the self-conscious and rational beings that they are. Men of religious genius, therefore, but express in a vivid and convincing way what others only discern when the leaden weight of custom is lifted, and for a moment they " see things clear as Gods do." The " authority " of the man of genius flows purely from his higher insight, and is recognized by others in whom it is repeated in a less intense form. The ordinary man is not a blind follower of the religious pioneer ; or, at least so far as he is so, he does not participate in the spirit of religion. The truth of Christianity cannot be established by an appeal to any authority other than the response of man's spirit, and if it is not in its essence a revelation of the very nature of the Infinite, all attempts to perpetuate it must end in failure. So far, therefore, as the Church embodies this revelation in her teaching, she may confidently count on the response of the rational spirit of man to it ; but that response would be not less certain were the Church to discard it and teach the exact opposite. No authority can make falsehood truth or evil good. That which contradicts ■the eternal nature of things cannot be made true, that which is in opposition to morality cannot be made obligatory, even by the fiat of omnipotence, much less by the imprimatur of a fallible organization. There is, therefore, nothing in the so-called " authority " of the religious reformer to sanction the inference that the Church, or any other body of men, is the sole guide and guardian of the spiritual interests of humanity. The individual may indeed enter into the heritage won for him by the choice religious spirits of the race, but only because in himself he can verify the truth which they have first brought to clear consciousness. The THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 37 whole world may join together in a conspiracy to call truth falsehood, and evil good, and the individual may yet withstand its " authority," conscious that in himself he has a witness that cannot be silenced. But, in truth, except in the mouth of the rhetorician, there never has been a case of " Athanasius against the world." The new principle advocated by the religious reformer is never an absolute negation of the old, but rather the old freed from its obscurity and limitations, and become clearly conscious of itself. Christianity effected a revo- lution in the whole conception of the world, but, as its Founder Himself has told us, it is not the destruction of what it superseded, but its fulfilment ; it did not break up the spiritual organism in which man had dwelt for centuries, but merely poured into it new streams of life and energy. From what has been said, the true view of the authority of the Church may be readily inferred. In the technical sense " The Church " has come to mean a particular organization which claims to be based upon the acceptance of the Christian revelation. This organization, as is held by the exponents of "authority," blends the perceptions of men of religious genius with the reflections of theologians, and " protects the revela- tion from rationalistic assaults." Now, as we have already seen, it is undoubtedly true that on the whole the Church has been the consistent guardian of the higher interests of man. It is also true that for the discharge of this function an external organization, and during the tutelage of humanity even an authoritative body of doctrine, was a necessity. But these facts by no means entitle us to say that the intuitions and doctrines safeguarded by the Church derive their authority from the Church. They are, as I have contended, authoritative because they are true, not 38 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION true because they are authoritative. And when the claim to unique and absolute authority is made, not merely for the Church as a whole — including all its branches, Greek, Roman, and Protestant — but for a single branch of it, we can only answer that it is not given to any body of men to possess a monopoly of truth. This is partly admitted by a Romish writer whom I have already quoted, who, in a remarkable essay, protests against " the idea long held in the Catholic world, and still held by some, that Pro- testantism and all heathen religions are the work of the devil " ; adding, that " the good work of Protestantism is self-evident, and all positive religious conceptions, not only of Protestantism but of Heathen- ism, have a relative value." No doubt the writer implies that " the good work " of his own Church is not "relative" but ^'absolute"; but it is hardly necessary to say that this is but an amiable preconception, and that the legitimate conclusion from his admissions is that the whole truth can only be obtained by taking into account the elements contributed by all sections of the Christian Church. But, having gone so far, we are logicc^lly compelled to go farther. If the " authority " of the Church universal lies solely and entirely in the truth which it contains, we must be prepared to admit that the ideal Church has a far wider sweep than the whole visible Church of our day, or even the whole visible Church in the com- pleteness of its historical evolution. Whatever makes for the higher life, whether it is sheltered by the visible Church or not, has the self-evidencing authority of Truth. Moreover, the true Church is the Church as in idea it is, the Church in the plenitude of its spiritual power, or as it will be " when the years have passed away " ; in other words, it is the divine THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 39 spirit immanent in humanity and progressively working itself out to completion. In this sense of the term, the Church is the vicegerent of God, but only because it is the conscious realization of God in the soul of man. It is therefore s, mistake to think of the Church as externally controlling the free movement of humanity, and prescribing fixed limits within which the mind of man must move. There are no limits but those which the divine spirit working in man imposes upon itself No man, and no body of men, is wise enough to tell in advance by what strange and apparently devious paths reason will work out its own salvation. Such movements as Gnosticism and Neoplatonism in the early centuries of the Christian era, Dualism and Mysticism in the middle ages, and Agnosticism in our own day, are really indispensable steps in the process by which the mind of man rises to a comprehension of the world, the self, and God. It would not be difficult to show that these and other movements, antagonistic to truth as they ap- parently are, have really contributed to its fuller comprehension. As Emerson says : One accent of the Holy Ghost A careless world hath never lost. If it is asked how such a view can be reconciled with the fact that, but for the protecting care of the Church, the Christian religion must long ago have succumbed to the assaults of rationalism, my answer is, that not even the protection of the Church would have saved Christianity from destruction had it not been based on the Truth, and that, if it does rest upon this eternal foundation, we may apply to it in a much truer than its original sense, the great word of Stoicism : Si fractus illabatur orbis impavidum ferient ruinae : 40 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION it will retain its serenity in the shock and ruin of a world. If we follow out the implications of the theory of development on the basis of authority, as held by Newman and his recent followers, it is obvious that it provides a way of escape from the older view of the literal accuracy of the sacred writings. These are held to be but the records of early religious experience or belief, and though there is '* a deposit of faith," as Newman calls it, the form in which Christianity originally appeared belongs to the transient element, while its essence is eternal, and receives con- tinuous definition in the development of Christian faith and doctrine. Obviously, anyone who adopts this attitude will have no difficulty in accepting the most drastic results of modern biblical criticism, confident at once in the absolute truth of the primitive revelation and in the certainty with which it is preserved from pollution by the fostering care of an infallible Church. By no writer of our day has this doctrine been more boldly and persuasively advocated than by Abbe Loisy in his UEvangile et VEglise. Religion, our author tells us, is subject to the universal law of all things — the law of growth, development, change. The Monotheism of the Old Testament, while it is in essence identical with that of the New, differs in being less developed. And, just as the Jahveh of the old canticles and legends differs very widely from the God of Justice revealed by the Prophets, so the formulas of our day are not in all points identical with those of St. Paul or St. Augustine. As a matter of fact, Jesus announced the immediate approach of " The Kingdom of Heaven," which must not be conceived merely as a state of holiness or union with God, but as a THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 41 joyous and happy life on earth, in which the physical and moral nature of mar# should be developed to the full. In this apocalyptic sense it was understood by His immediate followers. Now, men who are looking forward to an awful and universal catastrophe, to come upon the world in their own day, cannot stop to lay down rules for the guidance of the ages which in their belief will never follow. Hence, to attribute to Jesus a deliberate system of social organization is as false historically as it would be to assign to Solomon the authorship of the Proverbs. The truth is, that the New Testament, like the Old, is permeated by a conception of the universe and of history which has little in common with ours. And this is true not only of the teachings which fall within the intellectual sphere, but of those which pertain to the religious domain as well. Our notion of God and His goodness, our view of the Atone- ment, and in general the whole body of doctrine dealing with Christology, Man, and the Church, are not truths dropped from heaven and hoarded up by religious tradition in the exact form in which they first appeared. No limit can be set to the process by which the traditional formulas are subjected to a never-ending interpretation, in which the letter which killeth is regulated by the spirit that giveth life. Nor is rigid unchangeability at all essential to the authority of belief, or compatible with the nature of the human intellect. For no everlasting edifice can be built up with the elements of human thought. Truth is changeless, but not its image as reflected in the uneven mirror of our minds. Often the formation and growth of dogma has been ruled by the most halting logic, as when the Fathers and theologians of the Church sought to prove the 42 PHILOSOPHIGAL BASIS OF RELIGION doctrine of the Trinity by an untenable interpretation of the words of Genesis : " Let us make man in our image, after our likeness." But, to the historian who looks upon the reasons assigned in support of a belief as a sign of its vitality, rather than as the veritable ground of its origin, such a self-mockery of logic is irrelevant. In the domain of things religious and moral, the striving towards the better outruns the arguments adduced in favour of it. What alone is important is that living faith which mocks at the logic employed in its defence, and turns towards the unchangeable Truth athwart the inadequate and therefore perpetually changing formulas in which it is sought to be confined.^ In this remarkable correction and application of Newman's theory of development, we can see the doctrine of authority in process of accomplishing its own euthanasia. It is true that the contrast is still retained between the Truth as it is for us, and Truth as it is in itself; between the unchangeability of the original revelation and the varying forms in which it is intellectually formulated from age to age; but, apart from this saving reservation, there is nothing to dis- tinguish the position of Abb6 Loisy from that of the most pronounced advocate of a rational Christianity. Development is for him a real evolution, and not, as with Newman, the mere enlargement of a primitive germ ; though, no doubt, he conceives of it as in no way affecting the essence or validity of the original revelation. On the other hand, he expresses the strongest objection to the view of such writers as Harnack and Sabatier, who seek to reduce religion to its simplest elements by ^C/. the article on "The Abb^ Loisy and the Catholic Reform Move- ment" in the Contemporary R&view for March, 1903, signed "Voces Catholicae." THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 43 maintaining that the whole history of dogma, however necessary it may be to the practical triumph of Christi- anity over opposing forces, is a perversion of its original simplicity. Such a view, discarding as it does the regulative function of the Church, and conceiving of religion purely as a condition of the individual soul, Abbe Loisy could not possibly accept. The " primitive Christianity " of these writers is, in his view, a fiction of their own creation, invented as a support for their subjective view of religion, but in palpable contradiction to the Christianity of Jesus and His immediate followers. A candid examination of the records proves beyond doubt, as he contends, that the Founder of Christianity, though He did not put forward a system of doctrine, had perfectly definite beliefs, not merely in regard to the Fatherhood of God, but in regard to men's duty, in prospect of the approaching end of the world, and to many other things besides ; and it is the primary task of the historian to set forth the ideas of the Saviour as they were manifested in words and deeds, not to recast them in view of a modern theory of religion. Starting with the facts as we find them in the New Testament, it cannot be doubted, as he contends, that the whole process by which Christian doctrine has been developed is essential to the life and energy of the Christian religion. Step by step that religion has shown its power of incorporating all the elements of truth contained in ancient philosophy and modern science, and of informing them with its own spirit. The contention of Abb6 Loisy, that the history of dogma is essential to the unfolding of all that is contained in the original principle of Christianity, must be regarded as an important truth to which the views of Harnack and Sabatier fail to do justice; though Abb^ Loisy, on his part, can hardly be said 44 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION to distinguish sufficiently between the " winged words " in which the Master expresses the very soul of all religion, and those sayings which are obviously of only temporary interest ; and, as is only natural in a son of the Church, he fails to allow due weight to that aspect of religion to which Harnack and Sabatier, with a kind of exaggerated Protestantism, tend to attach exclusive value.^ In a complete view of religion, as I have already suggested, the personal and the universal aspects must each receive due weight ; for, if it is true that a religion which is not founded upon truth is a contradiction in terms, it is not the less true, and for the individual man of much greater importance, that it is also a life. The truth, however, seems to me to be that the exaggerated emphasis placed by Abb6 Loisy on doctrine, results in the end in the same defect as that of which he accuses his opponents. For, though Harnack seeks to reduce Christianity to a simple faith in the Fatherhood of God and the brotherhood of man, while his critic insists that it was from the first a complex body of truth, if not of doctrine; the former removes the rational basis of faith by denying that it admits of intellectual comprehension, while the latter, though he affirms that it can be grasped by the intelligence, denies that the forms of intelligence are competent to comprehend Truth as it is in itself. Thus both thinkers in the end agree in holding that faith is something inexplicable, or at least something so simple as to be beyond the reach of clear definition. Nor is the reason for this meeting of extremes far to seek. Like other Ritschlians, Harnack denies that the Infinite is comprehensible in itself, and therefore he is forced to deny the absolute value of all reflection upon the content of religion, and to fall back upon an ^ Harnack's view is discussed more fully in Lecture Seventh. THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOGMA 45 immediate faith in God and goodness as the be-all and end-all of religion ; while Abb6 Loisy, like Newman, refuses to admit that man by the exercise of his reason can rise to the knowledge of God, and, therefore, falling back upon the authority of the Church to guarantee what is beyond the reach of reason, he is ultimately driven to the conception of faith as a belief in that which is for reason incomprehensible. There is no escape, as I believe, from the opposite inadequacies of these two exponents of the inconceivable but the clear recognition, that the only valid defence of the Christian religion must consist in showing that, while its history is not a merely superficial process which leaves its primitive germ untouched, but a genuine development, in which a living faith has come to ever clearer self-consciousness, its principle is indestructible, because it is the only rational interpretation of the facts of our experience in their totality. A great writer has said that " in the religious consciousness all nations realize that they possess the truth ; and they have therefore always found in their religion the secret of true dignity and peace. ... In this pure aether man beholds his own existence in a transfigured reflection, in which all the harsh lights and colours and shadows of the everyday world are softened into eternal peace under the beams of a spiritual sun."^ Such a peace, as I believe, can be found neither by falling back upon a simple nucleus of faith, which does little to satisfy the obstinate questionings of the intellect, nor in the elusive attempt to find rest in an external authority, but only by the exhaustion of scepticism and pessimism. ^ Hegel's Geschichte der Religion^ i. 5. LECTURE THIRD SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION In my last lecture I finished the consideration of the principle of authority, as the supposed basis of doctrine. Recent writers, as we saw, follow the lead of Newman in endeavouring to reconcile the claims of an infallible Church with the changes through which its creed has undoubtedly passed ; maintaining that the function of authority is, not to originate or even to develop religious truths, but to select, among the new ideas advanced by men of religious genius, those which are in accordance with the original revelation. Admitting that there has been a real evolution of doctrine, and in this respect occupying a more tenable position than Newman, these thinkers employ the idea of the organic unity of man in support of their view of authority ; arguing (i) that no one can claim the right to set up his individual opinion against the collective experience of the race in the region of science and history ; (2) that the intuitions and reflections of men of religious genius carry with them a peculiar authority; and (3) that the Church combines the perceptions of its saints with the conceptions of its theologians, and protects the truth from rationalistic assaults. While admitting SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 47 « that the Church has done an invaluable service in the past, it was pointed out that it has also at times retarded progress, and therefore cannot be fairly- claimed as the only custodian of truth. No doubt it has on the whole resisted one-sided views ; but the real explanation of this fact is, that, like all the institutions in which man expresses himself, the Church is an embodiment, though not a perfect embodiment, of reason, and only in so far as this is the case has it any authority. Nor does the assimilation of man- kind to an organism lend any countenance to the doctrine of authority ; the analogy rather confirms the view, that, just as we accept the conclusions of the scientific expert because we believe them to have a rational foundation, and endorse the higher intui- tions of the religious genius because they appeal to our own awakened consciousness ; so the only claim of the Church to our allegiance is the degree in which it stands for the truth. It follows that no Church can justly claim to be the only guardian of the spiritual interests of humanity ; and, in fact, that the ideal Church cannot be confined within any given organization, but operates through all the channels by which the divine spirit immanent in man diffuses itself This is almost explicitly recognized by Abbd Loisy, who has no difficulty in accepting the results of recent science, including its application to the historical criticism of the sacred writings ; main- taining that, while truth is changeless, human beliefs undergo continual metamorphosis. In thus insisting upon the development of doctrine as essential to the comprehension of the principle of Christianity, Abb6 Loisy accentuates an important aspect of truth ; but he fails to allow proper weight to that aspect of truth to which thinkers like Harnack and Sabatier attach 48 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION almost exaggerated importance, namely, the response of the individual soul. A complete view of religion involves the due recognition of both aspects ; main- taining that, as reason informs the religious life of the individual, so it is capable of being embodied in an articulated system. The conclusion to which we have been led obviously compels us, while doing justice to the long experience of the race, to discard all appeals to external authority, and to claim assent for nothing that cannot be shown to be a valid interpretation of that experience. Now, it cannot be denied that the burden thus thrust upon us is a heavy one ; so heavy, indeed, that many thinkers of repute tell us that it is beyond the limited strength of man to bear. " Never before," says Mr. Goldwin Smith, " has there been such a crisis in the history of belief. Never before has man, enlightened as he now is by science, faced with a free mind the problem of his origin and destiny." Nor does the writer think that any aid can come from philosophy. " A metaphysical book, it seems, has reached its eighth edition. This shows that a number of inquirers are still upon that track. Is there any hope in that direction ? Is it possible that mental introspection should lead us to objective truth ? Might we not as well look for scientific fact in the structure of a scientific instrument, as for objective truth in the structure of the mind ? Intellects of the highest order have been devoted to metaphysic ; and with what result? From the Greek philosophers to the schoolmen, from the schoolmen to the Germans, system succeeds system, without progress or practical outcome. Even the reputed discoveries of Berkeley have borne no practical fruit, and Hegel is already as dead as Pythagoras. Meantime, genuine science SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 49 wins a series of practical triumphs and is advanced even by practical errors. The datum assumed by metaphysic throughout is that reality must correspond to conception. No such assumption is involved in our belief in moral responsibility, or other spiritual phenomena of human nature, which are facts of mental experience and observation, though not of bodily sense." ^ We have here the forcible expression of a view that is current in some form or other among many representatives of literature, art, and science ; a view which, as I hope to show, is at bottom superficial and self-contradictory. Its significance lies mainly in the fact that, with the collapse of traditional ideas, the whole edifice of religion, within which for cen- turies men have dwelt secure, seems to have crashed down, and they can only sit sadly among the ruins, vainly trying to comfort themselves with the belief that at least morality is safe. I say "vainly," for once persuade men that " objective truth " is beyond their reach, and it will not be long before they draw the only logical inference, that even " moral respon- sibility" is a fiction. Had the distinguished writer from whom I have quoted clearly seen the conse- quences of his rejection of all aid from philosophy — which, after all, is but reflection made systematic and comprehensive — perhaps he would have hesitated to condemn it so unreservedly. Of this, however, I am not sure, for his condemnation seems to be based upon the false opposition of introspection and observation — an opposition which no metaphysician would now admit to be valid, any more than he would accept the view of George Henry Lewes, which the writer endorses, that the history of philosophy is but a record of the ^ Goldwin Smith, In Quest of Light, p. 46. D so PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION abortive efforts of men of the first rank to solve an insoluble problem — a view which, among other defects, involves the incredible hypothesis that rational beings have persistently wasted their strength on an intrin- sically irrational task. That a writer who has made for himself a name as a historian and publicist should labour under such extraordinary misconceptions is a sufficient justification, if any were needed, of the attempt to show that the reconstruction of religious belief on the basis of reason is not an insoluble pro- blem. As the first step towards the solution of that problem, I shall begin with a short statement and criticism of the philosophy of Immanuel Kant, who, more than any other thinker, has determined the course of speculation for over a century. This was largely due to the courage with which he faced the apparently irreconcilable claims of the head and the heart, doing full justice to the inviolability of natural law, and yet refusing to surrender that inextinguishable belief in a spiritual world which has survived the heaviest onslaughts. From the sixteenth century till the age of Kant, there had been very marked progress in the region of physical science as well as in the wider movements of philosophy and theology. The progress in science had consisted in the ever clearer apprehension of the reign of law, as exhibited in instance after instance, and the consequent denial of all breaks in the continuity of natural processes, by the intrusion into the realm of nature of any supernatural agency. The growth of this conviction, the conviction of the inviolability of natural law, raised a peculiar difficulty when men came to con- sider its bearing upon their own life. If all other things are under the dominion of natural law, is it not an arbitrary proceeding, showing prejudice rather SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 51 than clear thought, to exempt man from the sway of law as if he were a sort of lusus naturae ? The diffi- culty had been increased by the change in the general poir^t of view produced by the Copernican astronomy, the revival of learning, and the discovery of the new world. The Ptolemaic cosmogony had for centuries ruled the minds of men, for reasons that are not. diffi- cult to understand. It could apparently appeal to the testimony of facts : it agreed with the biblical cosmo- logy: it cohered with the tendency of thought in all ages to conceive of the Divine as raised above the world, with its perpetual process of birth and death, its struggle between evil and good, its strange admixture of beauty and ugliness. We must also remember that, while the mind of man is ever seeking for complete unity, and therefore can never be satisfied with any- thing short of a perfect reconciliation of his higher beliefs with his scientific knowledge, there is at certain periods, and in certain persons, a tendency to place exaggerated emphasis on one or other of these aspects. Now, the long struggle of the middle ages was a period when the barbarism of the Teutonic, and the worldli- ness of the Latin, races had to be modified by the higher impulse of religious faith ; and it was only natural that an antagonism, which still survives in a modified way— the antagonism between the secular and the sacred — should then assume an acute form, and that whatever seemed to be inconsistent with the letter of religion should be branded as impious. Neverthe- less, reason was not entirely without a witness. The scholastic philosophy, though it was primarily employed in the service of an authoritative creed, unconsciously prepared the way for the new cosmogony of Copernicus. The human mind cannot be long employed even upon dogmas, the truth of which it does not venture to doubt 52 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION without finding itself confronted with difficulties which it is unable to solve. By accustoming the mind to see the objections which might be raised to what at first sight seemed beyond doubt, Scholasticism prepared the way for the rejection of that sensuous view of the cosmos on which ancient and mediaeval astronomy was based. And men's minds were more ready to accept the new cosmogony, because such thinkers as Nicolaus Cusanus and Bernardino Telesio had already suggested doubts of the traditional view on general philosophical grounds. The former argued that "the world can have neither centre nor circumference, for it could only have these in relation to something external, by which it is limited, and would thus not be the whole world." The cosmos has, therefore, no definite figure. " Every point in the world may, with equal right, be called the centre, or be set in the periphery. And since the earth does not stand at the absolute centre of the world, it cannot be at rest." ^ Cusanus thus denied on general grounds that the earth is the central point of the world, though he did not teach that the earth moved round the sun. In doing so he had dealt a severe blow to the mediaeval cosmogony ; for, not only was the world set spinning in space, but the sharp contrast between the heavens and the earth was obliterated. Bernardino Telesio, again, was the representative of a philosophy that made a direct appeal to experience. His main contention was, that there are two forces at work in nature, which manifest themselves in two different modes of motion. " These two principles work on matter, which is never increased or decreased, but which under their influence assumes the most widely different forms, and which is everywhere uniform. There is, therefore, no need to assume a distinction ^ Hoffding's History of Modern Philosophy^ i. 90. SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 53 between heavenly and terrestrial matter."^ By the labours of these two thinkers the traditional concep- tion of the world was shaken ; but it was only by the promulgation of the new cosmogony of Copernicus that it fell into complete ruin. The earth was now seen to have no claim to be at the centre of the universe ; the exceptional character of the heavenly bodies had disappeared ; an infinite horizon was dis- closed; and henceforth the limited universe of mediaeval thought had vanished away for ever. The modern mind, pondering over these things, was forced to ask how this new view of the universe affects the old faith. If our earth is an infinitesimal speck in the universe, can we any longer attribute to man that perfection which the Hebrew psalmist expressed by saying that he " is made a little lower than God " ? If, so far as experience can tell us, all finite beings, from the lowest to the highest, are continually losing their individuality and giving place to new individuals — a law which applies to man as well as to other beings — and if there is no reason for supposing that, granting the existence of other conscious beings, in other parts of the universe, they are exempt from the same principle of decay — since so far as we know all bodies in space have the same fundamental constitution — must we not conclude that the immortality of man is a fairy dream, natural in the infancy of society, but now incredible ? Nay, is there any longer reason to suppose that the existence of God will withstand the shock of modern mechanical explanations? When Laplace said that the idea of God was a " hypothesis " for which he had no need, did he not express the only logical result of the new cosmogony ? Thus it would seem that if the new conception of the universe has vastly enlarged our '^IHd, i. 94. 54 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION ideas-^if it has, in Mr. Balfour's phrase, " glutted our imaginations with material infinities " — it has at the same time given a tremendous shock to those beliefs which we are so unwilling as men to surrender. Now, Kant accepted the new cosmogony in its entirety, and even made a further contribution to it by propounding the nebular hypothesis ; and yet he believed that he had discovered a way by which the higher interests of man may be conserved. He first asks whether the method and the principles of the physical sciences, the validity of which, at least within their own sphere, seems to be firmly established by their success in explaining the facts of experience, are the only method and principles by which truth can be discovered. The method of the physical sciences is observation and experiment, its results being reached by a careful consideration of particular facts and by inferences drawn from them. No doubt these sciences tacitly assume certain conceptions, the truth of which they make no attempt to prove ; but this is not evident to the scientific man as such, and therefore he naturally supposes that any other method of investiga- tion than that which in his special region has yielded such brilliant results, must be a false or a defective method. He is therefore disposed to protest, and even to sneer at, any a priori method, as he calls it, z>, any method which goes beyond the interpretation of particular facts. And if this is the method of the special, sciences, its fundamental principle is that of natural causation. The sole object of these sciences is to discover the causal connections of particular facts. It was therefore but natural, in the age of Kant, when the physical sciences had achieved such triumphant results, especially at the hands of Newton, that there should be a strong tendency to interpret all SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 55 things in the light of the law of natural causation. Now, when this law is extended to the life of man, it seems as if there were no room for freedom. If man, like other beings, is under the dominion of natural law, how can we suppose that his acts proceed from himself in any other sense than that in which we may speak of the movements of an animal or even the fall of a stone as spontaneous ? And if there is no law but natural causation : if the whole sphere of reality is limited to particular phenomena and their connection with one another : is it not obvious that the ideas of God or of any other supernatural being, together with the immor- tality of man, must be mere fictions ? But when, by what Carlyle calls " victorious analysis/' we have got rid of human freedom and immortality, and of God, we shall be forced to throw duty and morality after them. If there is no real agency in man : if his acts are just as much the result of certain external causes as any other phenomenon in nature : then it is obviously absurd to speak of what he ought or ought not to do, since what in any given case he does is what he must do, and cannot possibly help doing. With the disappearance of the belief in moral obligation will also disappear the belief in moral responsibility, at least for anyone who thinks consistently. What a man does not do, what does not proceed from himself, for that he cannot be held responsible. Hence those who attempt to apply to human action the same law as that which they apply to other phenomena, when they are consistent (which they seldom are), tell us that the whole question in i-egard to human conduct is simply a question, not of what men ought to do, but of what as a matter of fact we find them doing. We may enquire, eg,^ into the manner in which men behave under certain forms of society, and we may trace the growth of what are called 56 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION moral ideas from age to age ; but all this, while it enables us to understand the natural history of man, does not entitle us to speak of absolute right and wrong, or in any strict sense of moral responsibility. No doubt society, for its own protection, lays down certain laws, and punishes those who violate them ; but this does not mean that those laws are absolutely right ; it only means that they are the necessary instruments for the preservation of social order, and for the security of life and property. This whole mode of thought obviously raises a problem of a most difficult character. It implies that there is a fundamental antagonism between two ruling ideas, which in a certain sense have made their influence felt from the dawn of human history. On the one hand, knowledge seems to be based on particular experiences, and particular experiences seem to be limited to the sensible and phenomenal ; while, on the other hand, there is in man an aspiration after a higher and better life, an aspiration which for centuries has been bound up with the belief in human freedom, duty, and moral responsibility. With the lucidity of philoso- phical genius Kant saw, that unless the antagonism of the natural and spiritual could be overcome, the whole life of man was threatened with destruction. The desire for definite knowledge is as strong in man as his belief in the supersensible. He can surrender neither, and yet his life must be in perpetual conflict and dis- harmony with itself, unless he can find some means of reconciling the one with the other. This apparent opposition of necessity and freedom has sometimes been sought to be solved by making the things of nature absolutely different in kind from spiritual beings. Thus it may be said that, while inorganic things, and even the highest of the animals. SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 57 are absolutely subject to the law of mechanical causa- tion, all their movements taking place in response to the action upon them of the environment, man, on the other hand, as a spiritual, self-conscious, and moral being, is the originator of his own acts, and is therefore free. This solution of the problem Kant refused to accept To remove man in this way from the sphere of natural law seemed to him to be a defiance of the facts and to lead to the denial of all knowledge. So far as we know ourselves, we do not find that our desires and volitions are withdrawn from the influence of external causes. When a man seeks to satisfy any of his desires, is it not the case that the desire is excited by the idea of some object, which presents itself to his imagination as pleasurable ? Given the man's natural susceptibility for certain objects rather than for others, and the response which he makes, when placed mentally in the presence of a given object, is just as fixed as the movement of a stone under the influence of external forces. Therefore, Kant maintains that, so far at least as his whole sensitive nature is concerned, it cannot be shown that man is peculiar in being exempted from the law of mechanical causation. If you examine the series of conscious states which occur in the case of any action, you will find, as he contends, that every member of that series follows in as unalterable a way as any series of movements in an unconscious being. It would thus seem that man, like every other being, acts simply as he must act under the given conditions. But, if the desires which act upon a man operate in the same fixed and unchanging way as any other force of nature, how can it possibly be shown that he is free ? For many years this problem perplexed Kant, but at length he seemed to himself to have found a way of solving it which allowed the fullest weight to the laws of nature and yet 58 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION preserved the independence and freedom of man. From what has been said, it is plain that any attempt to weaken or overthrow the inviolability of natural law could not be endorsed by Kant ; and indeed it was his acceptance of that law, as established by the discoveries of science, and especially by the discoveries of Newton, that first impressed upon him the importance of the problem. But how can it be held, in any sense, that every change in the world, including our own actions, takes place in accordance with the law of mechanical causation, while yet it is affirmed that man is free and self-determined ? Perhaps, Kant answers, we shall be able to get at the root of the matter, if we begin by asking why it is that mathematics and physics have made such remarkable progress, and are now universally regarded as estab- lished sciences, while the systems which deal with the supersensible, including the spiritual nature of man, are apparently still as far as ever from the discovery of a solid foundation. No doubt the representatives of these sciences, when they have any theory at all, usually describe their method as one of simple observation ; but if we look more closely, we shall see that mathe- matics and physics have not advanced by allowing nature to act upon the mind, and Simply registering the impressions thus received; on the contrary, progress has been made by anticipating in the mind the meaning of nature and then going to her and asking questions. The mathematician does not simply find his triangles and circles, but constructs them ; and the strange thing is that these constructions, which seem to be made in entire independence of nature, yet somehow or other apply to nature ; so that the mathematician confidently affirms, that his conclusions hold good always and necessarily, no matter how sensible objects may otherwise differ. Similarly, the physicist has made SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 59 advances by putting questions to nature, as when Galileo proceeded to interrogate her by causing elastic balls to roll down an inclined plane. All this suggests to us that in some sense nature is the creation of the human mind. This no doubt must seem at first sight a preposterous view to take. How, it may be said, can any man in his senses say that his mind makes nature ? Does not all knowledge consist in apprehending things as they are, not as we imagine them, or would like them to be ? Kant's answer is to point out that it is a great mistake to assume that nature exists, and would be what it is, even if the whole activity of the intelligence which grasps it were absent. If that were so, nature for us would be npthing but the impressions arising in us from moment to moment, and these would never present to our minds even the appearance of an orderly system of objects and events, spread out in space, following one another in time, and connected in fixed and unchanging ways. It is quite true that the earliest phase of our experience as individuals may be described as a mere chaos of impressions of sense ; but anyone may see that a chaos of impressions of sense is not what we mean by " nature." Those impressions we do not " make " : they are "given" to us ; but their interpretation as " objects," or, what is the same thing, our knowledge of nature as a system of " experiences," is due to the character of our perceptive and intellectual faculties, which compel us to present our perceptions as objects in space and time, as belonging to a single system, and as connected together in the unity of a single self-consciousness. Perhaps we shall best understand what Kant means by contrasting this new view of knowledge with that of Hume. The explanation of causality given by Hume reduces it to a mere habitual sequence 6o PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION of impressions and copies of impressions. This doctrine seemed to Kant to show that Hume had not grasped the true principle of knowledge. If Hume is right, it is obvious that there can be for us no system of nature, because there are no universal and necessary judgments. The result of Hume's theory therefore is, not to explain knowledge, but to explain it away. But to Kant it seemed perfectly certain that the pure sciences at least, viz., pure mathematics and pure physics, contain universal and necessary judgments : judgments therefore which are true, not merely at a particular time and in a particular place, but at all times and in all places. What, then, he asks, must be the character of our knowledge, if we are to account for the fact that there are such judgments? Mathematics obviously rests upon the ideas of space and time, and these again are not something which we can perceive by our senses. From moment to moment there arise in us different sensations, but the perception of external objects or of internal events is not possible apart from space and time, and these are not given in sensation, but are pre-supposed as conditions without which we should have no consciousness of sensible objects. As permanent elements pre-supposed in all our experience, they are involved in all our experience of objects, and they could not be so involved, as Kant argues, were they not the inalienable forms bound up with the very existence of our perceptive faculty. That being so, the objects of our experience can have no existence except within our experience. No doubt our impressions of sense are due to things that exist independently of our knowledge, but these must not be identified with the objects of our experience. The objects of our perception exist SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 6i nowhere but for the percipient subject. And the same thing is true of these objects, viewed as connected together in the system of experience. The work of so connecting them is done by the under- standing ; which, like perception, has its own fixed and unchanging constitution, — a constitution which is expressed in the forms of thought that Kant calls the "categories." To the existence of " nature" — understand- ing by this " the cosmos of experience " — our faculties of knowledge are therefore indispensable, for " nature " is no independent thing — no reality existing apart from us — but that system of experiences which is constituted by our minds as combining the elements of perception into an ordered whole. It is thus made clear to us why the man of science assumes that nature is subject to inviolable law. It is so subject, because nature is itself constituted by our minds, which by their very character order all our experiences under those forms of perception and thought which belong to us as men. But, having thus confirmed the preconception of the sciences, that nature is an unchanging > system, it seems as if we had only made any solution of the problem of freedom more hopeless than ever. At this point Kant gives the discussion a subtle and unexpected turn. What is this inviolable system of nature, but the product of our own activity as conscious beings? As such is it not obvious that it cannot be used as an engine for the destruction of a being without which it would not exist at all ? If the system of nature existed apart from any activity on our part, no doubt it would be impossible to make room for any self-activity in knowledge ; but as it has no existence anywhere but in our consciousness, it cannot destroy the very activity 62 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION without which it would have no existence. Our minds, it is true, do not contribute the sensible differ- ences of things, but they do supply the bonds which con- nect those differences into the unity of self-consciousness. Thus it is at once suggested to us, that for the mind which imposes them they cannot be really bonds. Necessity can only mean dependence upon something foreign, whereas the law of natural causation is no foreign yoke to which the human mind must submit, but its own law. And this idea receives strong confirmation when we see the relation of the system of nature to the idea of absolute reality. If the objects of our experience were things in themselves, no doubt it would be impossible for us to maintain that man in his true nature is free from the law of external necessity. For, if things as they really exist are what we are compelled to represent them as being, all things, including our own actions, must be subject to the law of natural causation, and therefore we can by no possibility be free. But ultimate reality on the one hand, and nature, or the system of our experience on the other hand, are by no means the same, as may readily be seen when we contrast what we know with what reason demands. Whatever else may be said of it, ultimate reality must be a whole, a unity ; for beyond it there can be nothing. That is the plain and simple demand which reason makes upon anything that claims to be absolutely real. Is the system of nature, then, a whole ? Is it a closed sphere, beyond which nothing else can be? or does it bear on its face the marks of finitude and limitation ? That it is not a whole is at once apparent the moment we compare it with our idea of a whole. Take it, e.g.y from the point of view of Time. If SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 63 the world-events constitute an absolute totality, then we must hold, either that the world has existed from all eternity, or that it began to be at a certain moment of time. Now, no matter which of these suppositions we adopt, it may at once be shown that it is incompatible with the nature of our experience. If the world never began to be, then an eternity must have elapsed up to any given point of time — say, the present moment ; and, by the very form of our experience, we can only present before our minds events in time by passing in imaginatidn from the one event back to the other, But, obviously, an infinite series of moments of time will require an eternity to sum them up. Hence, an infinite series of moments of time is an impossible experience ; and, consequently, the supposition that the world is eternal is incompatible with the condi- tions of our experience. Now, if the world is not eternal, we are thrown back on the other horn of the dilemma, viz., that the world began at a certain point of time. But this alternative is just as incompatible with experience as the other. If the world began to be at a certain moment of time, then prior to that moment there was nothing but blank, empty time. Now, nothing can begin to be unless there is some reason for its beginning to be. But there is nothing in empty time to explain why anything should begin to be. Consequently, the supposition that the world began to be at a certain moment of time conflicts with the very conditions of our experience. We can experience nothing which absolutely begins to be : all the things that we experience are changes which presuppose some- thing prior on which they depend. Now, what is to be inferred from this peculiar fact, that we can neither experience, or rather can neither conceive the possibility of experiencing, the eternity of the world, nor the 64 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION absolute beginning of the world? Surely our reason cannot compel us to adopt either of two contradictory propositions. We cannot say that the world is eternal, because that seems incompatible with the conditions of our knowledge : we cannot say that the world abso- lutely began to be, for that contradicts the principle of causality. But, on the other hand, we cannot accept a flat contradiction. How, then, are we to escape from the dilemma? Kant's answer is: we escape from it the moment we perceive that Time is merely a form of our experience. When we speak of absolute reality, there is no question as to whether it absolutely began to be or never began to be, because there is no ques- tion of Time at all. The reason that our experience is never a complete whole arises from the peculiar character of Time. Time is an unending series, and there is no possibility of summing up an unending series. Whatever, then, is represented as in time is thereby precluded from being a whole. And as the same thing is true of space, the conclusion we had already reached, that space and time are merely the forms of our perception, is confirmed by the insoluble contradictions into which we fall when we assume space and time to be characteristics of ultimate reality. And the same thing applies to the principle of causality itself. Causality as a principle of experience we have already seen to involve a reference to time. What it asserts is, that all successive events as in time imply a fixed order of connection, such that A must precede and B follow. Now this principle will clearly never give us totality : for, since it implies that an effect had a precedent cause, while this cause again is itself an effect having another prior cause, and so on to infinity, it follows that a totality as a series of causes is an impossible experience. In short, the fact that the principle of SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 65 causality is specified or limited to time, involves that it can never give us a completely rounded system of reality ; the most that it can do is to suggest the existence of a reality which it is itself unable to characterize. We are now in a better position to understand how Kant solves the apparent contradiction of necessity and freedom. Man seems to be bound in the chains of necessity, because, like other objects of experience, his acts seem to proceed from a cause external to himself But Kant has shown, as he believes, that the principle of causality is itself in a sense the crea- tion of the human mind, and hence that there must be a point of view from which man can be shown to be free from the bonds of merely external causation. For, the totality of the objects of experience, or the system of nature, is after all phenomenal. The phenomenal character of all the objects of our knowledge is clearly indicated by the fact that our experience can never be an absolute whole. Even the category of causality, so far as it is specified and thereby limited by its relation to events in time, does not enable us to determine the world as a complete whole. The process by which we characterize and connect events in time is unending; which shows that the pure conception of causality Is not really satisfied by the objects that fall within the range of our knowledge. The truth is, that, by follow- ing events back along the chain of temporal causation, we do not even in the end reach what can in the strict sense be called a cause ; for a cause, if it is to be com- pletely explanatory of an effect, cannot itself be an effect dependent upon a prior cause. Our intelligence demands a cause that is not itself an effect, or, in other words, a self-cause or a self-active being. Does such a cause actually exist ? Obviously we shall never 66 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION find a cause of this kind — a cause that absolutely origi- nates or initiates effects — within the region of sensible experience ; for, as we have seen, the conditions of sensible experience are such that no object is known to undergo any change without being acted upon by an object external to it. But a self-active cause must be acted upon purely by itself, not by any other being. It follows that a self-active cause existing in time is a contradiction in terms. This conclusion has been forced upon us by the abortive character of the attempt to find a real cause within the realm of sen- sible experience. We can pass from effect to cause, from this cause to a prior cause, in our search for an unconditioned cause ; but so long as we are limited by the conditions of our experience, such a cause we shall never find. But why should there not be a self- active cause, which is free from the conditions of time? This at least is obvious, that unless there is such a cause there is no free cause. Let us, then, admit the possibility of there being, not merely a phenomenal cause of events, but a real or ideal, or, as Kant calls it, a " noumenal " cause of those events. By this supposi- tion we provide for the possibility that we are ourselves in our true nature such self-active causes, while admitting that our inner being can never be brought within the circle of our knowledge. As we have proved know- ledge or experience to be a limited sphere, there is nothing impossible in the supposition that our true being is hidden behind the veil of our phenomenal being, and that every act we do is self-originated, though from the point of view of our knowledge we must figure it as. falling within the system of nature, and therefore as subject to natural causation. Now, is there anything in our own nature which would lead us to affirm at least the possibility that we are SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 67 self-active or self-determinant beings ? Kant's answer is, that we have undoubted grounds for this idea. The whole system of experience is constituted by the activity of our minds as acting upon the sensible by means of the universal forms of space and time. No element can enter into the system of experience unless there is a single self-conscious subject, which combines it with other elements in one system. In other words, we are for ourselves not merely objects of experience ; we are also the subjects^ for which alone those objects exist. It is true that as objects for ourselves we must regard ourselves as we regard other objects, and so far we have no reason to believe in our own self-activity. But there is this fundamental difference between man and all other beings of which he has experience ; that, while they are exhaustively characterized when they are affirmed to be objects, man, in virtue of his intelli- gence, is conscious of himself as the subject for which all objects are, including himself as a phenomenon. This pure self-consciousness points beyond the phe- nomenal world, and so far is in harmony with the idea that man in his true self or inner nature is self- determinant or free. Now, suppose for a moment that this free subject actually exists : what would be its relation to the phenomenal self? in other words, how would man as subject be related to man as object? The relation would be somewhat of this character : — Every act which a man ascribes to himself would proceed from his own initiative ; no other being in the universe could, on this supposition, interfere with his freedom or self-activity. But, though as a matter of fact his acts would all flow from his own will, it would nevertheless be true that to himself, as a knowing being, they would appear to be necessitated. We can thus see how it is possible that an act which proceeds 6S PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION purely from the self-conscious subject, may yet present itself to that subject under the form of time, and there- fore as in conformity with the law of natural causality. So far freedom has not been proved, but has only been shown to be possible. Is there any way by which its reality may be established? Kant affirms that there is such a way. It is true that so far as theoretical reason is concerned, we can never get beyond the mere idea that freedom is possible, because of the limitations under which it operates. But it is different when we come to consider man, not as a knowing, but as an acting being ; in other words, when we consider him from the point of view of his practical reason or will. For man cannot act at all except under the idea of freedom ; in other words, action in a self-conscious being presupposes the power of rising in idea above the phenomenal. If man were nothing but a link in the chain of phenomena, he would obviously never have the idea of any reality higher than the phe- nomenal. But in every act that he does he holds more or less clearly before himself the idea of himself as capable of a higher form of existence than that in which he finds himself. Thus man can act at all only under the presupposition that he is not a mere object like other objects, but is a self-conscious subject. Even this, however, does not prove freedom. It no doubt shows us how highly probable it is that man is free ; but what it actually proves is only that man has the idea or thinks of himself as free. We must therefore have a more solid basis for freedom before we can regard it as established beyond cavil. Is there such a basis ? Again Kant answers in the affirmative : there is the immovable basis of the moral law. That law cannot for a moment be identified with merely natural law ; for the peculiarity of moral law is, that it SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 69 is essentially an ideal, expressing not what is or has been or will be, but what ought to be. There is no meaning in speaking of ought when we refer to a merely natural object. We cannot say that a stone ought to ■ fall to the ground, or that a dog ought to bark ; what we must say is that stones do fall to the ground ; dogs do bark. But a being who can say to himself, " I ought to do this," " I ought not to do that," lives in a world of pure ideas, a " world not realized," which can never have a local habitation, but exists only as an intelligible or spiritual or ideal realm. A man does not judge himself by what he has been or is or will be, but by what he ought to be. It may be pointed out to him, that every act he has done had a special cause in a preceding act, and yet his belief remains unshaken, that he could have acted otherwise, and if he has acted contrary to duty, that he ought to have acted otherwise. Here is something that differs toto coelo from anything that presents itself within the sphere of knowledge proper. A being who has the idea of moral obligation, who creates spon- taneously an intelligible world and judges himself by its standard, must from the very nature of the case be independent of the phenomenal world with its law of natural causation. If he were merely one object among others in the realm of nature, he would never have this idea of a moral or intelligible world at all ; and therefore we are entitled to reason back from the fact that man has this idea to what it presupposes ; and what it presupposes is a being liberated from the chain of natural necessity, a self-active or free being. I have dwelt at what may seem inordinate length on Kant's reconciliation of freedom and necessity, because only by comprehending the grounds of that reconcilia- tion is it possible to understand his moral proofs of the 70 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION existence of God and the immortality of man. These must seem arbitrary and baseless to anyone who does not see why Kant regards the denial of any knowledge of God and immortality as essential to faith in their existence. His reason for insisting so strongly on this point is that, in his view, we should otherwise be compelled to believe that there was nothing higher than the system of nature ; whereas, admitting to the fullest extent the limitation of knowledge to that system, we may go on to build on the place left vacant by theoretical reason a solid edifice of reality by an appeal to the moral consciousness. It is in this way, as we have seen, that freedom is established ; and by a similar line of thought Kant seeks to show that, though God and immortality cannot be theoretically proved, they are postulates which we as rational beings are entitled, and indeed compelled, to make. For there are, as Kant contends, certain beliefs and hopes which are inextricably bound up with the moral consciousness. It is perfectly true that there is nothing in the world of nature affording the least support to them ; on the contrary, if we had no other source of illumination than that which is afforded by the natural sciences, we should never even dream of God, freedom, or immor- tality. But, as we have already seen, the system of nature is after all simply the manner in which we, as intelligent beings, interpret our sensible experiences ; and as we must therefore in a sense be beyond nature, we must impose upon ourselves a higher law or principle. Nor is it any objection to the ideal of reason that it can never be completely realized in any actual community ; for it yet remains the absolute standard by which we judge ourselves and others. It may, however, be objected that it is illegitimate to base reality upon our desires. Granting that a belief SCIENCE, MORALITY AND RELIGION 71 in God and a sure hope of immortality can alone bring permanent satisfaction, is it not a fallacy to take the strength of our longing as a guarantee that it is directed to what really exists? Kant's answer is, that while our ordinary wishes are in no way prophetic of their realization, it is different in the case of those desires which have their source in our rational and moral nature. The one class, as peculiar to this or that individual, and arising from his special disposition and circumstances, may never be realized ; the other, as springing from reason, receives the sanction of reason. Of this latter class is the will to believe in God, freedom, and immortality. As rational beings we demand their existence. For reason demands that conformity with the moral law should ultimately result in happiness ; and if we postulate the union of virtue and happiness, we must also postulate the existence of an Infinite Being to ensure the possibility of that union, and immortality as the condition of its realization. With perfect conviction we may affirm the objective reality of the three Ideas of reason ; and there- fore God, freedom, and immortality have the absolute guarantee of a rational faith. How far this method of defending the higher interests of man can be regarded as satisfactory must be left over for consideration at our next meeting. LECTURE FOURTH IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION At our last meeting we were engaged in the attempt to get an insight into the manner in which Kant, while discarding all external authority and accepting without reservation the inviolability of natural law, yet attempts to save the belief in freedom and moral responsibility, and to establish the existence of God and the immor- tality of man, by means of what he calls " postulates of practical reason/' Knowledge, as he holds, never extends beyond the realm of nature, and, therefore, it is precisely coincident with the sphere of the special sciences. Kant, however, points out that nature is not a reality which exists in separation from conscious beings : it is the product of the activity by which those beings, in virtue of the universal and necessary forms of perception and thought, which belong to them as men, construct for themselves an ordered system of experi- ence. While all objects and events take their appointed place in the one system of nature, that system does not itself form a complete whole ; for no such whole can be obtained consistently with the inclusion of all objects and events in space and time, and their external con- nection with one another through the principle of reciprocal causation. And as nothing can satisfy our IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 73 intelligence short of an absolutely complete whole, while the conditions of our experience preclude us from ever reaching it, we are forced to conclude that we never come face to face with reality as it is in itself, and must content ourselves with that distorted or blurred image of it which alone is possible for us. This limitation applies not only to inanimate things and the animals, but also to ourselves so far as we are objects for ourselves ; and, therefore, we do not, strictly speaking, know ourselves as we are, but only as we appear under the limitations imposed upon us by the character of our knowledge. But upon this very limitation Kant bases his main defence of our moral and religious interests. As we do not really know ourselves as we are, there is nothing in the character of our knowledge, as he argues, to show that in our true nature we are not free moral agents, and thus the way is left open for the defence of freedom and immortality on the basis of the moral consciousness. Moreover, the rational demand for unity can only be satisfied by the discovery of a principle comprehending both nature and man, object and subject ; and therefore the Idea of God inevitably arises in the search for that complete unity which alone can give satisfaction to reason. It is true that such a unity we can never know ; but here, as in the case of the Idea of freedom, we find that there is nothing in the conclusions of science to preclude the existence of God, if there are good grounds in another direction for believing in it. That such grounds do exist in the moral consciousness Kant contends, arguing that here is a case where our desires and hopes are the perfect guarantee of the reality of their objects. In the consciousness of moral obligation we come upon a principle which lifts us above all the desires that aim at merely individual happiness. So far as I hold myself bound to act in 74 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION conformity with the ideal of a perfectly moralized com- munity, of which every man recognizes himself to be a member, I refuse to make the very smallest concession to the clamours of natural inclination. If duty demands even the sacrifice of my life, and with it the loss of all possible satisfaction of my sensuous nature, reason tells me that I must obey. The solicitations of my lower nature are hard to withstand, especially when they are reinforced by a sort of moral cunning, which whispers that this is an exceptional case, or that it is justifiable because of the beneficial consequences to flow from it ; but we all know that the moral law admits of no paltering with its absolute commands, but must be obeyed absolutely and unconditionally. Thus we frame for ourselves the ideal of a community of rational beings, each of whom places himself and others under a universal system of moral laws, and this ideal we regard as expressing, and alone expressing, the true nature of man. It will not be denied that a society in which every one should at all times will the moral law, would be infinitely higher than any that has appeared on earth. Nor will Kant admit that morality may be merely a beautiful illusion, drawing man on by a sort of noble craft to seek the good of all. The moral con- sciousness, as he maintains, is the deepest thing in us. It is the point at which we are united to all possible rational beings, finite or infinite, and upon it depend the whole of our spiritual interests. If we had no other source of illumination than that which is afforded by the natural sciences, those interests would certainly vanish away as empty dreams. In a purely mechanical system there is no place for spirit, and if we were ourselves but links in an endless chain of causation, we should have no guarantee of freedom or immortality or God. But the system of nature is our own construction, IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 75 and therefore cannot be for us an absolute limit. When, therefore, we find in ourselves aspirations which have in them no taint of selfishness, but which are endorsed by reason, as essential to the realization of our moral nature, we are entitled to regard them as based upon reality. " The righteous man," says Kant, " may say : I will that there should be a God ; I will that, though in this world of natural necessity, I should not be of it, but should also belong to a purely intelligible world of freedom ; finally, I will that my duration should be endless. On this faith I insist and will not let it be taken from me." ^ The philosophy of Kant, as even the rapid outline just drawn may have suggested, lifts us above the old dualism of matter and mind, object and subject, and has made it impossible for anyone who has mastered its principle to suppose that reality can be revealed either in the immediacy of sensation and impulse, or in any mere process of abstract reflection. For, just as matter is never given in our experience as constituting a separate and independent realm of its own, but always as in conjunction with mind ; so there is no such thing as an experience which consists of isolated sensations and impulses, and just as certainly none composed entirely of " bloodless categories." Since Kant the problem must necessarily be, whether the whole world of our experience, within which matter and mind are subor- dinate distinctions, is identical with reality, and whether morality and religion can be demonstrated, or have only the warrant of faith. But while Kant has shown that the old antagonisms of the sensible and the intellectual, the material and the spiritual, spring from natural but untenable preconceptions, it cannot be denied that he has given occasion for his successors to fall back into ^Quoted in E. Caird's Evolution of Religion^ i. 339. 76 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION new forms of dualism, which are only less fatal than the old, because they put the problem in a way that brings us nearer to its solution. It is with the object of aiding in that solution that I propose to bring before you what seem to me to be certain inadequacies in the doctrine of Kant which prevent it from being entirely satisfactory. When Kant took up the problem of philosophy, it was tacitly assumed either that the world as known to us is complete in itself prior to, and independently of, our apprehension of it, or that the only reality of which / we have direct knowledge consists of our own ideas or states of consciousness. In the one case knowledge was supposed to consist in the passive apprehension of what already exists ; in the other, it was denied that we have any experience, or at least any direct experi- ence, of a world lying beyond consciousness. Now, Kant began by challenging this whole point of view. We cannot, he said, legitimately start with the assump- tion of a world lying beyond our minds, which yet is of the same essential character as the world of our experi- ence ; nor, again, can the position be defended, that we are directly conscious only of ideas in our own minds. If we take the former view, it is inconceivable how we can construct a science of nature ; for, on the assump- tion of the pure passivity of the mind, our judgments about nature can never have any wider application than to the limited number of objects that have fallen within our experience, whereas a science of nature must consist in judgments that are true unjversally and necessarily. If, again, we take the latter view, we can say nothing about the nature of the world ; for that which is assumed to be beyond the confines of our consciousness cannot even be known to exist. We must therefore revise our whole way of looking at things. Nature, or the so-called " external " world, is not external to mind, IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 77 but only " external " in the sense that it consists, of objects outside of one another spatially, or of events external to one another in the sense of being discrete and " marching single in an endless file." We are, therefore, just as directly conscious of matter as of mind. Moreover, the external or material world is not given to us in our sensations ; for sensations in their singleness are not knowledge : only when they are ordered and combined under the forms of perception and thought have we any experience of nature. Now, these forms do not, like sensation, vary with each individual and change upon us from moment to moment ; they are identical in all men. Thus, we all construct an external world which, vary as it may in its sensible aspects, is fundamentally the same in this sense, that it consists of objects in space and events in time, all of which are connected together by the bond of natural causation. This is the world which it is the business of the sciences to survey and reduce to specific laws. It is obvious from this account that Kant never for a moment supposed that the problem of knowledge is to explain the steps by which the individual gradually advances in knowledge, by the interpretation of his particular sensible experiences; what he sought to account for was that orderly world of faq;ts \x\ which every man lives, though it is only expressly conceived as a system by those who have learned the lesson of modern science. The development of knowledge in the individual is a question which^'^Talls to be answered by the psychologist, whereas the task of the critical philosopher is to determine what are the conditions under which every one comes to the consciousness af a system of experience, and acquiesces in the universal and necessary judgments by which it is constituted. 78 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION Kant assumed, as a basis for his investigation, the principle that all men are of the same essential nature, and therefore that the fundamental features in the experience of one man are identical in kind with the fundamental features in the experience of all men. Of course each of us has his own individual experi- ence, for which the experience of another cannot be a substitute ; but, differ as we may in particulars, we all organize our experience into a system in virtue of the inalienable birthright of our intelligence, and indeed into a system which is identical for all men, however they may differ in respect of the data so organized. Were it not so, as Kant maintains, our intelligence would not be a principle of unity, but a principle of contradiction. So far as he contends for the identity of intelligence in all men, Kant seems to me to insist upon a principle which is of supreme importance, a principle which is rejected or denied by those who seek, with what seems manifest inconsistency, to commend for our acceptance the doctrine that in the end what we call knowledge is nothing but the " working conceptions " by which we are enabled to reduce to order the confused mass of impressions ever crowding upon us. But, although he would have rejected without hesitation this recent development of his philosophy, maintaining as he does that the system of nature is necessarily the same for all men, Kant's theory of knowledge rests upon an assumption which logically leads to the conclusion that reality cannot be a rational and self-consistent whole. That assumption is, that the data furnished to us by our sensible experiences are infected by certain funda- mental and insuperable limitations, with the result that what we call knowledge is not really the comprehension of that which ts^ but only of that which appears. We IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 79 can have no experience, as Kant contends, except under the forms of space and time ;. and these forms prove themselves not to be determinations of reality in its ultimate nature by the fact that reason, compelled to operate with sensible data, cannot reach the unity for which it is its very nature to seek, and is thus forced to recognize that the system of nature, which alone falls within knowledge, is at the most but a poor analogue and adumbration of the true nature of things. Here, as I think, we come upon the vulnerable spot in the Critical theory of knowledge. It is no doubt true that our experience is never complete, and that the scientific view of the world is far from final ; but we cannot infer from either of these facts that reality lies beyond the sphere of our knowledge. This point is so fundamental, and has so important a bearing upon the philosophy of religion, that it seems necessary to devote special attention to it. Why does Kant hold that the objects of human experience are fundamentally different from things in themselves, so that we can only define the latter by negative predicates ? One reason seems to be, that he has not entirely freed himself from the individualistic point of view against which his whole philosophy is in one sense a protest. If we ask how the individual man comes to have the consciousness of a sensible object, it is natural to say that his knowledge results from the action upon him of that object And there is no doubt that this explanation is correct enough, so far as the only question asked is in regard to the condi- tions under which a certain sensation arises. Thus, e.g.^ the sensation which I experience from the heat of a fire can be determined in the same way, and on the same principle, as any other event ; in other words, it can be brought within the inviolable system of nature So PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION by the application of the principle of causality. So long as we remain at this point of view, therefore, we must say, that between the sensations of the individual and the external object which acts as a stimulus, there is a causal relation the same in kind as that which subsists between any two external objects — say, the heat of the sun and the heat of a stone, or, more precisely, the molecular vibrations in each. It does not follow, however, that we can apply the same principle of explanation to the relation between the external world and the knowledge by the individual of that world. For that knowledge is not the effect of the action upon consciousness of an object which exists independently of that consciousness. We are very apt to think of the matter in that way, because we are usually interested, not in the problem of know- ledge, but in the characteristics of the objects known ; and, therefore, we almost inevitably overlook the fact that for us there are no objects but those which fall within the sphere of our knowledge. When we say that the sensation of heat is due to the action of a fire, we are moving within a world that could not exist for us at all but for the complex activity implied in the interpretation of our sensation as a fact which takes its place in the orderly system of experience — a system which, as Kant himself has shown, has its being for us only because of the unifying activity of our minds. Overlooking this activity, and fixing our attention upon the sensation of the moment, we refer it to an external object as its cause, and imagine that no further explanation is needed, or can be given. In reality we have in this way explained nothing, but have simply assumed the knowledge of a system of experience, and pointed out that the sensation in question falls within it, and IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY Si is relative to a particular external object which also falls within it. But the question of knowledge is not in regard to the connection of one thing with another within a world assumed to be already known, but how we come to have the knowledge of a world of objects at all. To say that this world acts upon our minds is the same as saying that a world which exists only by the activity of our minds is the cause of that activity. The world is not the cause of our knowledge ; for, without knowledge, there is no cause. The principle of causality cannot be explained as the result of the relation between object and subject, because apart from the subject as interpreting his experiences there is no ' object. When, therefore, any attempt is made so to explain it, the so-called explanation must necessarily presuppose the very principle which is sought to be explained. If the validity of the principle of causality is admitted, there is no difficulty in accounting for the origination of a given sensation ; for all that in that case is necessary is to assign the conditions under which it arises ; but obviously we cannot account for the origination of the principle of causation by appealing to the very principle which is to be accounted for. Now, no one has pointed this out more clearly than Kant himself; but, while he contends with irresistible force that the principle of causality cannot be derived from the particular experiences which it makes possible, he never gets rid of the idea that the sensible element in experience is the result of the action on the knowing subject of an object that exists prior to the activity of the object. And as the object of experience is analysed into that sensible element in conjunction with the forms of perception and thought, Kant is precluded from identifying the object which causes the sensation with the object as known ; so that the former lapses into F 82 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION a thing-in-itself, of which we can say nothing but that it is, while the latter is regarded as the appearance of an object which does not itself appear, but falls beyond the sphere of knowledge. It cannot be denied that there is much plausibility in Kanfs reference to things-in-then)selves as the source of the sensations which we as individuals experience. Obviously, we do not make sensations for ourselves, but must take them as they come, and they stubbornly resist all our efforts to spirit them away. Naturally enough, therefore, we come to look upon ourselves as the passive recipients of impressions coming from without ; and when, with Kant, we recognize that the objects of our experience are con- stituted by the combining activity of our own minds, we inevitably think of the impressions themselves as somehow related to a real object which does not fall within knowledge, and therefore must be distinguished from the object as known to us. But, if we consider the matter more carefully, it becomes evident that we are the victims of a confusion of ideas. My sensations I certainly cannot make or unmake ; but it by no means follows that they are produced in me by a cause which lies beyond the circle of my knowledge. If I ask what place they have in my experience as a whole, I can trace out and assign the elements in it which are necessary as the condition of their existence, but by so doing I do not by any means explain their ultimate source. The only explanation which can give final satisfaction is one that assigns, not merely the particular conditions under which my sensations arise, but the conditions of my total consciousness ; and not merely of my consciousness, but of all consciousness, actual or possible ; and obviously such an explanation lifts us above the system of nature altogether. It is this IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 83 ultimate reality, in fact, which Kant faj6ely identifies with the unknown thing-in-itself, and thus is led to hold that the totality of our experience is confined within the sphere of phenomena. Seeing clearly that the system of nature is not a " closed sphere,!* he sets up the idea of a reality which escapes from its limits, and infers that this reality, as falling beyond experience, is not an object of knowledge. What he should really have inferred is, that, to prevent the system of nature from falling to pieces as a mere arbitrary construction of our finite minds, we must seek to carry back our knowledge of that system to its ultimate presupposi- tions. If this can be done, what Kant calls the thing-in-itself will no longer baffle our efforts to comprehend it. Now, when we have got rid of the illusory thing-in- itself, and grasped the principle that the only reality which has any meaning for us is that which falls within the circle of our experience, we begin to see that we can no longer accept the arbitrary limits assigned to knowledge. Kant assumes that knowledge is coincident with the mechanical system within which the natural sciences voluntarily confine themselves. Taking this view, he is led to hold that we can have experience only of objects in space and time, as acting and reacting on each other, and that any other conception of the world, though it may not be false, at any rate cannot be regarded as knowledge. One of the con- sequences of this assumption is, that as our own desires and volitions are events, they come under the same inviolable law of causation as other events ; and, therefore, we have no '' experience " or knowledge of ourselves as free agents, nor as a consequence of ourselves as moral beings. No doubt Kant would restore, under the name of " faith," what he denies as 84 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION " knowledge " ; but, at least in the first instance, he seems to place freedom and morality on a very precarious footing. Is there, then, any valid reason for limiting knowledge, in the way Kant has done, to objects and events which fall within the " system of nature " ? Not only does the limitation seem to be indefensible in itself, but it may be shown, as I think, that it is not consistent with the " new way of ideas " opened up by Kant himself. What is the " system of nature " ? It is the real world as it exists for us in virtue of our intelligence. No doubt that system is no arbitrary creation of ours, but it exists for us only because we are capable of comprehending the indissoluble con- nection of objects, a connection without which the world would fall to pieces, like a house when its supports are withdrawn. In other words, the world is transparent to us just in so far as it is rational or intelligible ; and, therefore, it can be no mere aggregate or collection of isolated atoms, but must be a whole, all the parts of which imply one another. Now, if this is so, we begin to see that the " system of nature," as it is viewed by the special sciences, is after all only a partial and inadequate representation of the world as it really is. The real world is a mechanical system, or, rather, with the object of attaining a clear and definite grasp of its elements, it may be viewed as a mechanical system ; but it is so much more, that any one who regards that mode of conception as ultimate will find himself landed in contradiction. For that "system," taken by itself, is very far from being self-supporting or self-complete. It exists only for a rational or intelligent subject ; and if this subject is left out of account, it vanishes away. The only foundation, there- fore, upon which a real science of nature can be based, is reason, and if the system of nature does not pre- IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 85 suppose a rational and intelligible whole, it can at the most be nothing but a well-ordered fiction. Now, a collection of objects and events, externally related to one another, but not expressing a single self-differ- entiating principle, cannot possibly satisfy the rational demand for a whole which needs nothing else for its presupposition. As Kant himself points out, there is no completeness or individuality in any accumulation of objects in space and time, because no magnitude, extensive or intensive, can even be conceived which is complete in itself In truth, the illimitable extension and the infinite divisibility of the extended universe exist at all only as abstractions of a thinking consciousness. Now, we are surely entitled to reason back from our experience to all that is necessary to make it possible, unless we adopt the self-contradictory attitude of the pure sceptic, and maintain that we cannot even be sure that we experience what we experience. And Kant, above all men, is bound to admit the validity of this method, for it is that which he has himself applied in justification of the special sciences. The system of experience, then, as we may fairly argue, presupposes a thinking intelligence as its correlate, or rather as the condition without which it could not exist at all. But if so, is it not evident that we must include within the sphere of knowledge the intelligence without which the system of ^ nature is impossible ? And not only so, but we must affirm of that system all that is necessary to account for its intelligibility. When, therefore, we find, as Kant himself shows we do find, that a world which is> conceived simply as an aggregate of objects, acting and reacting on one another, is not a complete whole, because it is not self-explaining, must we not go on to seek for a higher and more satisfactory way of S6 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION regarding it? An interminable chain of events, hanging suspended in the air at both ends, is obviously the mere fragment of a real universe, not the universe in its totality. For, after all, mind exists, and in any ultimate theory must have at least as much reality as the objects contrasted with and yet related to it. In mind, therefore, we must seek for the complement to the system of nature which is required to round it off. On the other hand, we cannot regard mind simply as another sphere, or hemisphere, externally attached to matter ; for, as we have seen, the system of nature must be so far akin to the intelligence for which it exists as to be compre- hensible by it. The universe, then, is a universe in which nature and mind imply each other, but in such a way that, while nature must be intelligible, mind is that for which nature exists. Now, when we ask what must be the character of an intelligible nature, the answer must be, that it is a universe every element of which is inseparable from the whole; in other words, a universe in which there is nothing which could exist were the whole not what it is. And there can be no doubt^ I think, that such a whole must contain within itself the principle of its own differentia- tion ; and must therefore be a free, self-determinant, rational whole, which expresses itself in every part, or employs every part as the means of its own self- realization. If this is true, we must conceive of the universe, not merely as organic, but also as spiritual, i.e, as the manifestation of an infinite intelligence. Should it be objected that we have no " knowledge " of such a principle, even granting that we are entitled to claim that it has a firm basis in " faith," I venture to reply, that the objection rests upon some such arbitrary limitation of knowledge as that upon which Kant's IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 87 separation of phenomena from things-in-themselves is based, — a limitation which, as I have tried to show, is not based upon anything in the nature of things. Knowledge, in any proper sense of the term, must include all that the total nature of our experience compels us to affirm; and the total nature of our experience, as I have argued, is incomprehensible unless there is presupposed in it the all-pervasive activity of an infinite Spirit. If it is still objected that the Infinite can never be an object of experience, I answer that while from the nature of the case the source of all reality cannot be identified with any one of its own phases, that does not prevent it from being cortiprehended by us in so far as we are capable of interpreting what we experience. If any one prefers to call this com- prehension of the ultimate principle of the universe faith rather than knowledge^ we need not dispute about words : at any rate, it is a " faith " based upon the insight of reason, and therefore a faith which can only be distinguished from "knowledge," because it is know- ledge come to complete self-consciousness. If, on the other hand, by " faith " is meant the blind acceptance of what cannot be established on rational grounds, we must answer, that such a faith is not above, but below, knowledge; or, at least, it can only be held to be higher than knowledge, if it implicitly contains the principle by which alone knowledge can be explained and defended. We cannot, then, admit with Kant that " knowledge " is limited to the "system of nature" without committing ourselves to the self-contradictory doctrine, that, while nature has no reality apart from intelligence, we can know nature but cannot know the intelligence without which it could not be. If the knowledge of nature is explicable only by showing that it presupposes principles, 88 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION and ultimately a single principle, which exist only for a rational subject, it is absurd to hold that we can know nothing of the rational subject, but only of its object. The contrary rather is true; for, if mind is the key to nature, it would be more reasonable to say that we know nothing but mind, nature being simply the object of mind. But neither of these extreme views is true to the facts. We know the system of nature just because it is intelligible, and we know mind just because it comprehends nature. To limit knowledge to either, or to assign one region to knowledge and another to faith, is to split up the universe into two separate halves, with the result that we have in the one a world which is unintelligible, and in the other an intelligence which is intelligent of nothing. Why, then, does Kant maintain with such energy that God, freedom, and immortality are based, not upon knowledge, but upon faith? and why does he seek to exalt the practical reason or moral consciousness above the theoretical reason ? And if these oppositions must be denied, what transformation of his philosophy results from the vindication of the latter as co-ordinate in value with the former ? Kanfs ostensible reason for denying knowledge of anything beyond the system of nature is, as we have seen, his conviction that in no other way can the higher interests and hopes of man be defended. Freedom, as it seemed to him, cannot be saved, consistently with the maintenance of the inviolability of natural law, unless we provide a way of escape from the realm of nature by opening up a supersensible region of which man may be shown from the moral consciousness to be a denizen. Immortality is a dream, if the whole nature of man is exhausted in our knowledge of him as an object like other objects, and therefore as IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 89 subject to the process of decay and death, which is the destiny of all that lives. Nor is there any reason for holding the existence of God, on the basis of experience, since experience can never carry us beyond the dead mechanism of nature. On the other hand, morality and religion demand that we should be free and immortal, and that God should exist as the source of that harmony between the ideal world of morality and the world of our experience. As a means of escape from this intolerable dilemma, Kant insists upon the distinction of the phenomenal from the noumenal world, and the limitation of positive knowledge to the former. Now, if we break down the middle wall of partition between the sensible and the supersensible, as we have insisted upon doing, do we not surrender all the advantages which Kant believed himself to have secured by its erection ? If man lives in the same world of experience as other beings, how can he be free? If he is subject to the universal law of nature, how can he be immortal? And if God is but a name for the system of nature, is there SLUy real basis for religion ? The problem thus raised does not seem to me to be so formidable as it appears at first sight, thanks largely to the new outlook opened up by Kant himself. Freedom, as he contends, is not capable of being proved by theoretical reason, though theoretical reason shows that its reality is possible ; but, what for knowledge is a vain effort, is a necessary ** postulate" of practical reason, which lays down an absolute moral law, and therefore must be held to guarantee the possibility of its fulfilment. This doctrine is obviously incom- patible with our contention, that nothing can be justly maintained which cannot be shown to be bound up with the nature of our knowledge ; and, therefore, that 90 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION unless we know ourselves to be free, we have no right to assert that we are free. But, with the denial of the critical solution of the apparent union in man of necessity and freedom by the distinction between man as he appears and man as he /j, are we not compelled to surrender freedom altogether, or to fall back upon the old device of seeking for breaks in the continuity of natural law ? It does not seem to me that we are impaled on either horn of this dilemma. No doubt we cannot maintain at once that our actions are free and that they are subject to necessity. For Kant this did not involve a flat contradiction, because, while man is in his view really free, he is only in appearance subject to necessity ; but for us, who have discarded what we regard as a dangerous and illusory method of defence, no such device is possible. Nor can we adopt the tactics of those who try to show that the laws of nature are after all not so very inviolable as they seem, being in fact merely empirical generalizations, which may be outgrown at any time by an extension of know- ledge. This essentially sceptical solution, of which I shall say something more in a later lecture, I believe to be on fundamentally false lines ; and I therefore assume, with Kant, that there are no breaks in the system of nature, and, in fact, that any relaxation of its rigidity will logically lead to the dissolution of the universe by its reduction to a mere assemblage of accidental particulars. Nature, as the sciences assume, is so welded and compacted together, that, as Hegel said on one occasion, it is at bottom an identical proposition to say, that the annihilation of a single atom of matter would destroy the whole universe. No doubt what are called " laws of nature " are not absolute, in the sense that they can never be super- seded ; for the history of science is, from one point IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 91 of view, nothing but the record of the supersession of laws previously regarded as absolute ; but it still remains true, that the world is ruled by inviolable law, however imperfectly that law may be grasped in its manifold variations, and that a new law always arises in the effort to explain the difficulties which confront the discoverer who assumes that nature must always be consistent with itself Are we, then, forced to deny freedom, immortality, and God? Are these objects of our moral and religious faith swept away by the irresistible might of science with its inexorable law? No such shipwreck of our higher interests need be feared, if we only follow out and interpret in its spirit the truth which Kant has done so much to bring home to us, namely, that the system of nature has in itself neither independence nor completeness. It has no independence, because, when it is separated from the rational whole, of which it is merely a phase or aspect, it becomes unintelligible ; and it has no completeness, since no assemblage of objects in space and time will account for_ the undoubted fact of our experience of ourselves. To urge that nature is governed by in- violable law, does not in the least degree imply that there is no room for freedom. For inviolable law, if we are right in maintaining that the universe is in every part subject to reason, is not a blind necessity, but simply the absolutely rational, and therefore un- varying, expression of a perfect intelligence. If it could be shown that nature is not subject to law — that it admits of an arbitrary interference with its uniformity there would then be the strongest reason for denying the possibility of freedom ; for, in the absence of all rational prevision, it would obviously be impossible to foresee what a day or an hour might bring forth, 92 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION and therefore impossible to realize our ideals, however high they might be/ (The more conclusively it is proved that the system of nature admits of no violation, the more assured we ought to be that it is compact of reason. If nature is, so to speak, the body of which reason is the soul ; if it is, in Goethe's phrase, " the visible garment of God " ; there can be no great difficulty in showing that the freedom of man is not only compatible with the inviolability of natural law, but is inconceivable on any other supposition.) For, natural law exists for man, not simply as some- thing to which he must submit, but as something which he can comprehend, and therefore something by reference to which he can organize his life. It is no doubt true, that in his first or natural state man finds himself in a world which seems to be hostile to him ; a world in which he has to struggle for existence against forces that seem to be expressly formed to crush him ; but, at the heart of this seeming antagonism lies a divine principle of unification, which the whole process of his life brings to ever clearer consciousness. In times of doubt or despair we may feel inclined to endorse the hopeless creed expressed by Tennyson : " The stars," she whispers, " blindly run ; A web is wov*n across the sky ; From out waste places comes a cry. And murmurs from the dying sun : And all the phantom, Nature, stands, With all the music in her tone, A hollow echo of my own, — A hollow form with empty hands." But deeper comprehension will bring us to the nobler and truer faith, expressed by the same poet, that there is roEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 93 " One God, one law, one element, And one far-off divine event To which the whole creation moves." If nature were intrinsically hostile to man, there would be no possibility of reconciliation with it In truth the long toil of ages is the method by which man learns to comprehend the inner meaning of nature, and thus to make it the means of his own development. The general answer, then, to Kant's dilemma of necessity and freedom is, that what is called necessity is no external compulsion by which freedom is destroyed, but the very condition by which it is realized. The system of nature cannot be a bar to the realization of freedom, since it is simply the immediate form in which the divine reason is expressed. This may be seen more clearly if we look for a moment at the method by which Kant first sets up nature and freedom as opposites, and . then attempts to reconcile them. Freedom, according to Kant, is proved, not directly, but indirectly. We cannot know ourselves to be free, because we cannot come in immediate contact with our real inner self, on account of the limitations in the constitution of our minds. But, though we are thus shut out from a direct consciousness of ourselves, there is no doubt of the fact that we have the conception of an intelligible or moral world, and are therefore in idea raised above the world of sensible experience. No being can have such a conception that is not more than a part of nature ; therefore, as Kant argues, the fact that we have the conception of an absolute moral law points back to our real freedom or self-determination. Now, this argument obviously depends for its whole force upon the idea that only a free being can have the consciousness of 94 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION an absolute moral law. " In other words, a free being is one that shows its freedom by submitting voluntarily to a law which it recognizes as the true law of its being. If therefore we find that man does not always submit to this absolute law, it would seem to follow that, in so far as he violates it, to that extent he is not free. But, if freedom and morality are strictly correlative, a man must either be always moral or he is not always free.^ Kant is not unaware of the difficulty, and indeed it was partly a perception of it which led him to distinguish between man as a natural, and man as a rational, being. Man, he contends, is a free being, who originates an absolute moral law as the law of his own nature ; but, on the other hand, he is a phenomenal being, affected by certain natural desires or inclinations or passions, which he does not originate, but simply finds in himself. So far as he is a natural being, man is not free. There the law of natural necessity reigns as absolutely as in the case of the inorganic thing or the " mere animal." But this raises a very great difficulty. So far as man is a merely natural being, there is no question of will or action proper at all. I will or act only in so far as I will or act under the idea of myself as the subject to be realized. But the natural desires or passions do not involve the consciousness of oneself as an active subject ; and, therefore, as it would seem, they have as little to do with the man himself, the man as a free or rational being, as if they belonged to some other being altogether. Apparently, then, we are left, on Kant's view, with the curious result, that man wills only the moral law ; all the " activities," so-called, which arise from the natural inclinations or passions being in no way attributable to himself. Now, Kant, seeing this difficulty, attempts to evade it. It is quite IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 95 true, he says, that man as a merely natural being must be regarded as simply one of the objects of nature, and therefore as subject to purely natural desires, which, like his sensations, he can neither make nor unmake ; but, on the other hand, he is capable of taking up these natural desires into himself and willing them, and when he does so, he voluntarily and freely violates the absoluteness of the moral law. This, then, is Kant's solution of the difficulty, that a free being apparently must be determined solely by the moral law. . His view is, that, while man sets up the idea of moral law, and regards it as absolutely binding upon himself, he yet is capable of being influenced by the natural desires, in so far as he takes these up into his will. But this only raises a new difficulty. How should a free being, who is defined as one that is independent of the sensible world as a whole, and therefore inde- pendent of natural inclination or passion, be acted upon by the sensible ? Is it not the very character of a free being, on Kant's own showing, to be independent of natural desire ? If so, how can natural desird act upon him ? Such a conception of the influence of natural desire would seem to bring this supposed free being back into the realm of phenomena ; for now, apparently, his will is acted upon by something external to himself. The difficulty, therefore, is to understand how a free being, defined as Kant defines it, viz, as a supersensible being, should in any way be affected by the sensible. To this objection Kant's answer would be, that the apparent action of sensible desire upon the free subject arises from the limitation of our knowledge. We can only know anything by connecting elements through the principle of causality, and this principle is of such a character that it necessarily represents these elements as externally connected and influenced by one another. 96 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION Hence, when we come to consider the relation of the free subject to the natural desires, we have no other way of representing that relation than by viewing it as an instance of cause and effect. We are therefore compelled to conceive of the relation between the desires and the free subject as the action of the former upon the latter, though in strict truth a free subject cannot be acted upon by anything else. It is not, therefore, correct to say that desire influences man: what we must rather say is, that man wills freely to act from sensuous desire. This is the final form of the solution, so far as Kant gives it. It does not, however, remove the fundamental difficulty. Why should a free being will to enslave himself? Why should a being whose very nature it is to be free from desire, voluntarily bring himself under the yoke of desire? Kant is forced to confess that this is an ultimate and in- explicable fact. We do find that man somehow is influenced by natural desire, or rather voluntarily submits to its influence ; but how a free being should thus fall into this practical contradiction, we are unable to explain. Now, whenever a system takes refuge in an inexplicable fact, it is pretty certain that it contains some fundamental defect. We have, therefore, to ask what is the fundamental defect in Kant's ethical doctrine that prevents him from giving a perfectly satisfactory solution of the problem which he raised. The fundamental defect in the ethics of Kant is similar to that which besets his theory of knowledge. Kant confuses two very different things ; the limitation of the human mind at a certain stage and its absolute limitation. He assumes that there is a complete opposition between reason and desire, and therefore that no one who acts from desire can act ratronally. But that opposition is based upon the false assumption IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 97 that the affections of a self-conscious subject are not implicitly rational ; while in truth every such affection implies the unreflective operation of reason. The "tender charities of husband, son, and brother" take the form of immediate feeling, but they are possible only because they carry with them a rational end. ( The truth is, that the mere affections of a sensitive subject are not desires at all, in the sense in which we speak of the desire for wealth, or knowledge, or the good of others, but only become so when they enter into the self-determinant life of man ; and then, when carried out into action, or willed, they are rational motives relative to rational ends. There is, therefore, no difficulty in understanding how a free being may determine himself by desire, for desire is just the manner in which the free subject does determine himself in any given case.J When Kant speaks as if man, in seeking the satisfaction of desire, is necessarily violating the rational law of duty, he overlooks the fact, which on occasion he is constrained to admit, that a rational being never acts except under the idea of the good, and never ascribes to himself an action which he does not will. No doubt, in seeking the satisfaction of his desires, he may act contrary to reason, but he could neither act contrary to nor in accordance with reason were his effective desires not the expression of his will. The freedom of man is therefore no mere "postulate," but a truth* of which the whole self-conscious life of man is the clearest evidence. To be a self and to be free are the same thing; for no being can be self-conscious without being beyond the influence of purely external causes. Nor is the existence of God a " postulate.*' As we have seen, the system of nature is unintelligible G 98 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION unless as the outward form of a perfect intelligence. For, nature exists only for us as intelligent beings, and our existence again is inconceivable apart from an ultimate principle from which our rational as well as our sensitive nature proceeds. Kant argues that the existence of God is merely a " postulate," which we are compelled to make because reason demands that the world should not by its very nature be incompatible with the union of virtue and happiness. But, such a " postulate " can have no validity, unless our experience is inexplicable on any other supposition ; and if that is so, we have ample ground for claiming that the existence of the Infinite is a principle of knowledge. (Thus the system of nature, the freedom of man and the existence of God are but different aspects of the same truth, the truth that we live in a rational universe. There is, therefore, no need to bring back, under the name of " faith," what is denied under the name of " knowledge," or to oppose theoretical reason and practical reason, assigning the " primacy " to the latter. What is called " faith " is really reason, which is not aware of itself as reason, just because it has unwittingly built up for itself the world of nature and the higher world of morality, art, and religion, and thus seems to find before it a creation foreign to itself. ; " Theoretical reason," again, is not a separate and independent faculty, but simply that aspect of the single self-conscious intelligence in which it contemplates its own unconscious work; while " practical reason " is the same intelligence, when it contemplates itself in the actual process of expressing itself in particular acts. To set up the one against the other, assigning a superiority to either, is to set up the intelligence against itself What sort of theoretical reason would that be, which did not IDEALISM AS A PHILOSOPHY 99 express itself in an objective world, but remained for ever self-enclosed ? and what sort of practical reason could there be, which did not comprehend the objective world, but ruled itself by fictions of its own creation ? The former would have nothing real '■ to know, and the latter nothing real to will. Reason is a seamless whole, and as such it must be conceived as knowing in its action and active in its knowledge. From what has been said it follows that there is no need to seek for God afar off; He is "in our mouths and in our hearts." When, therefore, the religious consciousness lifts us above the divisions of our ordinary prosaic view of life, it does not transport us into a realm which is foreign to reason, but simply reveals to us the truth of which in our ordinary mood we are only vaguely conscious ; the truth, that here and now we live in a spiritual realm, and may hold communion with the Eternal Spirit. Were it not so, religion would be impotent to elevate and idealize life. A God who is fabled to dwell in a region beyond the " flaming walls " of the universe, is not only impossible of demonstration, but would be for us nothing even if his existence could be demonstrated. ( The only God in whom we can believe is a God who constitutes the rational structure of nature, and is most clearly revealed to us in our own hearts and minds ; a God whose infinite perfection our intelligence comprehends in principle, to whom our aspirations go out, who forms the ever-growing ideal which we can never completely realize, and " in whose will," as Dante says, " is our peace " : zn la sua volontade e nostra pace, \ LECTURE FIFTH PERSONAL IDEALISM AND THE NEW REALISM In our last lecture an attempt was made to show- that the true elements contained in the Critical Philosophy of Kant can only be preserved, if that philosophy is developed into a Speculative or Con- structive Idealism. The main distinction between these two modes of thought is that, while both maintain that the universe is rational and that reason is self-harmonious, the former denies that either of these propositions can be established on the basis of knowledge, while the latter contends that the opposition of the theoretical and the practical reason is fatal to both propositions. Hence, while the Criti- cal Philosophy falls back upon certain "postulates" of the moral consciousness in support of ** faith," Speculative Idealism refuses to accept the antithesis of faith and knowledge, theoretical and practical reason, maintaining that a faith which is not identical with reason, a theoretical reason which is not in harmony with practical- reason, is beset by an inherent weakness, which is sure to betray itself under the most searching of all tests, the test of self-criticism. Under this test, as we contended, Kant's doctrine of a faith that from its very nature cannot be developed into knowledge PERSONAL IDEALISM loi is seen to be fatal to all our higher interests ; and we endeavoured, by working in the higher spirit of the Critical Philosophy, to show that those interests are vouched for by a rational interpretation of our experience as a whole. The system of nature, as we held, is no limit to human freedom or to the perfection of God, since it has no independent reality of its own, but is simply a certain aspect of reality as a whole — that aspect in which, for the limited purpose of the special sciences, the external world is viewed as if it were complete in itself. When this artificial limitation of reality to a collection of objects, all of which are reciprocally dependent, is taken at its proper value, we see that there is nothing in the nature of the sciences to prevent us from affirming the freedom of man and the absolute- ness of God, and basing both upon the character of our experience in its completeness. The form of Idealism thus outlined attempts to combine the truth of Materialism and Spiritualism in a theory which affirms that the universe is an intelligible whole, and that as such it implies as its correlate an Infinite Intelligence. Within this whole, and expressive of this Intelligence, is contained every form of existence, including that of man. But man, as it is further held, not only falls into his place in the whole, but within him and coming to consciousness in him operates the same identical principle as that which operates in the whole and characterizes the Infinite Intelligence. And it is also maintained that, on any other supposition, freedom in any rational sense is impossible. Partly through the influence of Lotze, and partly from the surviving influence of Empiricism, a number of writers, English and American, have preferred I02 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION various compromises to the thorough-going Idealism thus outlined. The doctrine which found most favour for many years, after the inadequacy of the older Empiricism, as represented by James Mill and John Stuart Mill, was perceived, was that of the late Herbert Spencer, who sought to reach beyond the opposition of Materialism and Subjective Idealism by maintaining that both are true phenomenally, while Reality in its ultimate nature differs from both, though from the necessary limitations of our thought it can never be an object of knowledge. This unknown and even unknowable Reality must be presupposed as the ultimate basis of both science and religion. The history of religion, as he thinks, has consisted in an ever clearer recognition of the impossibility on our part of a definite comprehension of the Power hidden behind the veil of the phenomenal ; so that at last it is openly confessed that " to think that God is, as we can think Him to be, is blasphemy." Nor is science any more successful than religion in enabling us to comprehend the Absolute. Such conceptions as time and space, motion and force, consciousness and personality, break down in contra^ diction the moment we attempt to transfer them to the Absolute ; the reason being, as Hamilton and Mansel have shown, that from the very nature of our knowledge we can only comprehend the finite and relative. It was not to be expected that this attempt to show that the whole of our experience is fundamen- tally discrepant could givQ permanent satisfaction ; and I think one may safely say that the only attack upon Speculative Idealism which is at present worthy of consideration comes from those who call themselves Personal Idealists, and from those who represent the PERSONAL IDEALISM 103 New Realism. While they are both agreed in their antagonism to Speculative Idealism, as they understand it, they are equally opposed to each other. I think it will be possible to show that neither of them can be regarded as a self-consistent and adequate explana- tion of the world in which we live, of our own nature, or of the ultimate principle of the uni- verse. Personal Idealism contends that it is impossible to preserve the freedom of man and the existence of God in a theory which abolishes individuality and leaves room for no reality but the Absolute. It may be regarded as proved that what are commonly called " things " have no independent existence, but exist only for mind. This being admitted, it follows that there exist souls, spirits, or selves, which know or experience things. Such beings are in some sense persons. Now, a person is, in the first place, a thinking, as distinguished from a merely feeling consciousness ; secondly, he is in some degree permanent, or brings different experiences into relation with one another ; thirdly, he distinguishes himself from the objects of his thought, though these have no existence except in his or some other consciousness ; fourthly, among the objects are other selves, which are known as beings, that, like himself, exist for themselves ; and lastly, he is not only a thinking and feeling, but a willing consciousness. To sum up, " a person is a conscious, permanent, self-distinguishing, individual, active being." These essential characteristics of per- sonality do not . seem to be found in any form of consciousness below the human, nor are they found in their perfection in the most developed human consciousness ; and, indeed, so far as our knowledge goes, they are found only in God. The world must I04 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION exist in a mind ; and as it existed before the origin o( any human mind, we must hold the existence of a Universal Thinker, to whom must be attributed in perfection all those characteristics which are implied by Personality, and which yet no human person ever completely realizes. It may be concluded, then, that God " is a being who thinks, who persists throughout his successive experiences, who knows those past experiences as well as the present, who distinguishes Himself from the objects of His thought, who in particular distinguishes Himself from all other con- sciousnesses, and, finally, who wills, and wills in accordance with the conception of an ideal end or good." If it is asked wka^ God wills, it may be answered, that He must at least will everything that is not willed by some lesser will ; in other words, He must will the object of His own thought, z,e, the world. To this view it may be objected : ( i ) that, just as the human self knows itself only by the same act in which it knows the not-self ; so the world is as necessary to God as God is to the world ; (2) that the Absolute must be both subject and object ; and (3) that wzi/ cannot be attributed to God. The answer to these objections is: (i) that, while the world must be an object for God, it does not follow that it is anything but His experiences, and these experiences must be conceived as willed, no less than thought ; (2) that, while subject and object are inseparable, it does not follow that they are indistinguishable ; and (3) that, while there is much in our experience of volition which belongs to our limitations, yet "our volition (as we know it) is the only experience which enables us to give concrete embodiment to the purely a priori concep- tion of Causality, which includes both final cause Wl PERSONAL IDEALIS'jt 105 * and efficient cause." And "even r^'part from this argument from Causality, the mere feet that mind, as we know it, is always will as ^11 as thought, would be a sufficient ground iir inferring by analogy that, if God be the sy^^eme source of being or Mind, He too must be^Will no less than Thought." (L The general conclusion is, that *4j all reality lies in souls and their experiences." What, then, is the relation between these souls c/ spirits? God, as omniscient and eternal, must b^egarded as '* causing those experiences of the other 5 |uls of which their own wills are not the cause, and ^nce no human will is ever the whole cause of anytning) as co-operating in some sense with whatever causality is exercised by human wills." Rejecting " the hypothesis of many independent, underived intelligences, co-eternal and uncreated," we must hold that " the human mind, like all minds, is derived from the one supreme Mind," Nevertheless, we must maintain " the sepa- rateness and distinctness of the individual self- consciousness from God when once in existence and so long as it exists." The fallacy of Monism is " the assumption that what constitutes existence for others is the same as what constitutes existence for self. A ^km£^ is as it is known : its esse is to be known : what it is for the experience of spirits, is its whole reality : it is that and nothing more. But the esse of a person is to know himself, to be for himself, to feel and think for himself, to act on his own knowledge, and to know that he acts. In dealing with persons, therefore, there is an unfathom- able gulf between knowledge and reality. What a person is for himself is entirely unaffected by what he is for any other. . . . The essence of a person is not io6 PHILOSC*>HICAL BASIS OF RELIGION what he is foi knother, but what he is for himself. , . . All the fallafes of our anti-individualist thinkers come from tak'Sng as though the essence of a person lay in what caA be known about him, and not in his own knowl "ige, his own experience of himself" And " God must 'know the self as a self which has a consciousness, a 4 experience, a will which is its own — that is, as ^^^ being which is not identical with the knowledge tl, ib, He has of it." No doubt God "must have an i^^finitely deeper and completer knowledge of every ^ne of us than any one has of another." " God's thdbght can as little be exactly what our thought is "^s our joys and sorrows can be exactly what His are*^ "God must, it would seem, know other selves by^ the analogy of what He is Himself . . . His knowledge of other selves may be perfect knowledge without his ever being or becoming the selves which He knows." Is God, then, finite? Well, " everything that is real is in that sense finite. God is certainly limited by all other beings in the Universe, that is to say, by other selves, in so far as He is not those selves. He is not limited . . . by anything which does not ultimately proceed from his own Nature or Will or Power. That power is doubtless limited, and in the frank recognition of this limitation of power lies the only solution of the problem of Evil which does not either destroy the goodness of God or destroy moral distinctions alto- gether. He is limited by His own eternal . . . nature — a nature which wills eternally the best which that nature has in it to create. . . . The truth of the world is then neither Monism, in the pantheizing sense of the word, nor Pluralism: the world is neither a single Being, nor many co-ordinate and independent Beings, but a One Mind who gives PERSONAL IDEALISM '\ 107 \ rise to many." The Reality is "a commur^ty of Persons." ^ The doctrine which has just been summarized obviously, owes its motive power - mainly g^ the dssure. to preserve the iadependeat personality .f ideas in this or that individual, while the latterfj claims that the whole conception of individuals as cvhat I have attempted to show is that personality in any ^ proper sense cannot^-Jae identified 4vith. abstract individuality, or defended by the methpcL of subjective .id.ealis^ The only, basis of personality is that which takes proper accouoL.xif the inseparable connection of all forms of existence iij the whole, while maintaining that the consciousness of this inseparable connection and of the unity of all forms of existence in the whoLe. is grasped . by JtOiuj THE NEW REALISM 113 iiu^virtue, of .his. participation in the reason vduch constitutes, th^. true.,, nature of the whole. Personality, whether in man or, God, .therefare. presupposes the ta1;aJ manifestation of a single self-determining principle. Xh^^iJal^ defensible-- conception. -x>f- God is that.whicb §fi£a,in„ Him „the self-manifestation and. s^lf-knowledga qL absolulfijceasaa, — a self-manifestation, and^self-inow- Jedge „„wludx.-.are™.unintelligible on any theory .that divides, up Jiie-Oioiverse into a number of self-enclosed individuals. It is through the consciousness of .what is-not-oneself that the consciousness of self is possible aL.^U» and the limitation of a finite being exactly corresponds to the defect in its relations, in the way of knowledge, feeling, and will, to the totality of other beings and to the whole. Complete personality will therefore consist, not in a perfect image of all things, 4)ut in a perfect comprehension of, and manifestation in, all things ; in other words, God can be shown to be a person only if it is established that He is not shut up within Himself, but completely expresses. Himself in the universe, and Jn,. that., expression reaches . perfect ^jalfrcomprehension. The fundamental defect in Personal Idealism, which I have endeavoured to point out, has given occasion for a theory which is vitiated by the opposite defect. When reality is reduced to states of consciousness in this or that individual, it is naturally pointed out that such a doctrine is based upon an arbitrary abstraction, which sets at defiance the actual nature of our experience. This is the attitude of the exponents of the New Realism. The objects of our knowledge, as they contend, cannot be identified with ideas in the individual mind, even if those ideas are regarded as sensations reduced to order and coherence by concep- tions. Nor can the time-honoured distinction of 114 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION primary and secondary qualities be accepted, at least if the former are attributed to things, while the latter are regarded as merely sensations with nothing objective corresponding to them. There is in all cases a sharp distinction between consciousness and its objects. My consciousness of an external object, such as a tree, ■cannot be identified with the existence of that object : the object exists whether I am conscious of it or not And the same thing applies to what occurs in my organism. My feeling of hunger is one thing, the state of being hungry is another and a totally different thing. Similarly, my thought that 2 + 2 = 4 is not the same thing as the truth that 2 + 2 = 4. Thus, no matter whether I have a perception, feeling, or conception, there is always a distinction between my idea and the object of which it is the idea. It is a mere confusion of thought, it is said, first to identify real objects with subjective states of consciousness, as Idealism does, and then to infer that there is no real world other than those states. Nor does it make any essential difference to say that reality is not given in immediate perception, but is the product of the conceptual activity of thought ; for this modification of the doctrine does not get rid of the fundamental defect, that the objective world is regarded as having no existence apart from the individual mind which constructs or constitutes it. Is it not perfectly plain, argues the realist, that every idea has a character of its own which distinguishes it from its object ? Thus, space as an object is essen- tially extension or outwardness-of-parts ; but my idea of space has no extension or outwardness-of-parts. Weight as an object implies the attraction of extended particles, whereas it is absurd to speak of my conscious- ness of weight as made up of extended particles attracting each other in proportion to their mass and THE NEW REALISM nS inversely as the square of the distance. Green is a, colour; but my idea, of green is not itself green, pleasure is always pleasant, but not so my Mea qC pleasure. How, then, can anyone doubt that there is " a, .r,^a,lity,qilite. distinct from Jjip , s.ubject,iv.e world of oujc.. direct experience?".. Idealiaax Js,.Jfch£i:gfexe_. an utterly untenable theory of existence. Now, iL is obvious, from the whole character of the attack, that ^a,t,. the New :-Realism. means.. by Idealism is the doctrine which we have discussed under the name of Personal Idealism, or at least. is 5Q,me form of Subjective Idealism kindred in. nature to it The gist of the whole argument is, that reality cannot be resolved into states of consciousness, or ideas which arise in the mind of this or that individual. In this contention the New Realism is not only in harmony with common sense, but it may count upon the support of Speculative Idealism, which differs from Subjective Idealism in almost everything but name. ]g^ality is certainly not reducible to ideas of the individual mind ; so far we must agree with the realist. Does it follow, as he contends,, that there is an absolute distinction between ideas and objects ? Let us begin with the case of an external object, say a tree. The position of the realist is that my idea of the tree is one thing, and the existing tree \s another and a different thing. The tree does not cease to exist when I lose consciousness of it, or come into existence when I again have an idea of it. And the same thing is true of all other conscious subjects, human or divine : nothing can obliterate the fundamental distinction between the idea^of a thing and the existence of that .thing. Now, there is of course no possible doubt that my consciousness of a tree or any other external J^IL^ ii6 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION object does not bring it into existence. But the., real Qiiestip^, is, not whether .the tree "exists," but what is meant by its " existence." To answer this question we must ask what is involved in our knowledge of the tree ; for the only tree of which we can say anything is one that falls within our knowledge.V^) Ji is-^ said that, the idea of the tree is independent, of the tree .as .it- exists^ If this statement is taken seriously, it must mean that my^^ide^'' is a certain fact, arising within my ,mindr and arising without 4n any . way coming into, contact, with- the .existing tree. What is the character of this "id£a''?(^As it. J^ purely mental^, it must, as I suppose, be held to. be inextended and immaterial, whereas the tree. is extended and ..material.- V But, even so, if I have a knowledge., of the. tree, I, must obtain, that knowledge in some way .through my " idl^^^gtSft**' 5'As these -are excluded .fram the tj^^e, they /nu^t in some.sensQ be images, or representations of. the tree, not ,the.. tj:e& itself WThus . I .have., no direct knowledge of Jiie tee, at all. But if not, how . can . I know that my image or idea of the. tree is .9., correct representatipjj of it? nay, how do I know that there is any treeil If I am limited to my ideas, ..how ..shall l. get beyond thegi.? Evidently the realist is after all only a less logical, subjective ideaUgf. And the reason why he lies open to the same criticism as the sub- jective idealist is, that Hke him .he has _set , up .tfag; pure fictioo of a mind . which j>ossesses idt3,s^ .^n^ as a man may possess a piece of property, -these ideas being figured after the pattern of images refleQl;ed in a mirror. But there are no such "ide^.^." Wb.eiJ J perceiye a tree, my perception is no image in my mind, while the tree is beyond my mind, but I gs^U^Uy perceive a real object, which ., I - name -a-tree. THE NEW REALISM 117 It may be objected that the tree exists when I do not perceive it, and therefore is independent of my perception of it. But " exists " in what sense ? It is natural to suppose that the tree is a single individual thing, which would exist and be what it is even if all other things were annihilated. But it requires very little reflection to see that a tree of this character is a pure fiction. Every tree has begun to be, and none has originated from itself ^pr is there any tree which will exist for ever, or,- which could exist at all but for the totality of forces, which operate in the universe. If we trace our tree back to its conditions, we are led to see that its existence is involved in the existence of the whole universe, .and that unless the whole universe conspired jio support it, it would shrivel into nothingness. When, therefore, we speak of the existence of the tree, we ^re tacitly affirming the existence of the whole universe. The subjective idealist would have us believe that the universe means for us the ideas which arise in our individual minds. Against this doctrine the realist rightly protests, but unfortunately he bases his protest on wrong grounds. He claims that ideas in the individual mind are incommensurable with objects beyond the individual mind ; overlooking the fact that, in admitting the existence of purely subjective ideas, he is tacitly affirming that objects beyond the mind are unknowable. In point of fact there are no "ideas" such as he assumes. What, then, gives plausibility to his contention that there is a distinction between the ideas of this or that man and the objects of which they are ideas? The existence. ^pf. an. objeqt [s made possible only by the whole universe of which jt is, but a jrelatively ins^ificant aspect. To identify tha.. object witb-^..the. perception of it on the part of ii8 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION this or that iiidividiial would thexefore be equivalent to ^saying ..that the transient activity of a particuiaj; individual was identical with the total activity of the universe* But, though it is not dependent for its .existence upon the perception of the individual, the pbjact. would not be what it is were it not capable of being presented to the individuaL^-Jjo-^thac^jacatds, i^,- existence is , bouod^ up with .its., possible xeidXiw to the perceiving subject. For the character of his perceptions, like the properties of the object, is deter- mined by the total nature of the universe ; and were it not so, the object would be no object for him. And as the relations of the object to his perceptions are constant and invariable, he rightly concludes, when his perceptions are the same, that the object is the same. Thus his knowledge of the existence of the object is the comprehension on his part of the immuta- bility of the object under the same conditions. Its " existence " consists in its permanence under the same conditions, and among those conditions the most significant for the perceiving subject is identity in his successive perceptions. From wh3i- has bpen said the inadequacy of ihe realistic account of reality is manifest. . Rightly insisting. 4iiat.„ihe,. world, cannol be ^reduced, to .ideas in the individual mind, .it plays into the hapdsof the en^rr^y by granting^. to_ hijn;i that our knowledge of things ja^y he re^oly.ed..Jfita...suc:h . ideals. Speculative Idealism denies this assumption, jnaintaioing that the conditions of the existence of anything whatever are the same as the conditions of knowledge : that just as no object can exist except in so far as its existence is guaranteed by the whole universe, so pp knowledge iS—PQ35ihls^. except Jn.^ so^ Jar. as it- is made., possible by the organic unity of na^ture^ and mind^^^IiJs Jxue. THE NEW REALISM 119 tbat—this—organic-- unity is never completely knjDwn Yjy .„ua ; but. that...in_ no way invalidates., the ^incipk, that^it Js...Just -in. so far as the organic unity ,xif alL-the. .phases of oui:. experience zs known, that we comp££hfia(i.-J:he- real- nature-- of ,.the..world,™and,..of jajirs£ly£S. Thus we come JaaGk^to^ the conclusion at ^ hich w e had previously arrived, that every , step ia ,th£_ .development of our experience is a farther j:evdatiaQ.J3lJiie self-determinant Spirit which, enfolds jji.jiiQ^g^QLexist§ace from the lowest to the highest. If I have succeeded in making plain the form of Idealism which seems to me defensible, there can be no great difficulty in disposing of the other instances given by the realist in support of his contention that ideas and objects have an existence quite independent of each other. That this is not true in the case of the perception of external objects we have seen ; for these ^ould not be- what they are, were they. „45LQt,..rd^^d to. perception in certain fi,5^.(i„ and.^ micbanging ways. The realist, however, also contends that even in the case of what is usually regarded as a purely subjective affection, there is a distinction between the subjective idea and the object of which it is an idea. Thus, my feeling of hunger is an idea in my mind, whereas the hunger is an objective state of my organism. Now, there can be no difficulty in dealing with such an instance as this. My feeling of hunger, it is said, is distinct from the actual condition of hunger ; in other words, the feeling is a mode of my individual consciousness, the hunger is not. One reason given for this contention is, that the existence of the hunger in me may be known by others while no one but myself can experience the feeling. And of course this is perfectly true. But the question is, whether I20 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION the feeling of hunger and the actual hunger are independent in the sense claimed by the realist If the feeling is separable fronn the actual state, it must have a subjective object distinct from that which it represents ; otherwise it would not be the feeling of hunger. How, then, can the transition be made from this internal object to the external state? It must be because the content of the feeling stands for, or represents, the external state. But if the individual is thus limited to his feeling, how does he know that there is any external state corresponding to it? Is it not plain that, by interposing an image between .the subject and the supposed object, the avenue out- wards. is„ blocked? Thus, once more, we see „that realism is. merely an arrested solipsism. Whaty. then, in the present instance misleads the realist? Why does his assertion of the distinction between the feeling of hunger and the actual state of hunger sound so reasonable? The answer is not far to seek. Hungej:^,^^ .3.n actual condition of the .organism cannot be identified^ with the feeling jq£, hungerj because by Jhe ..former „. is meant _a certain effect .XDJiditioned „by^ non-sensitive . processes, while by Jthej^itsrjs. meant. tke response of the. organi.sia AaJar as it ^is^. aensitive. To. identify the one wjth the other is manifestly impossible. But while this is true, it must be added that the feeling of hunger as such gives no knowledge of hunger as a state of the organism. The knowledge of hunger consists in the interpretation of the feeling by reference to all that is known of the organism. Now, such know- ledge implies a very considerable advance in the comprehension of the real world, since it means that the real world is grasped, n ot only as a physical system, but as a system comprehending within it THE NEW REALISM 121 organized as well as unorganized beings. To. reduce the knowledge of hunger tp , the passing, state of the individual-would therefore he even more absurd than to explain the existence of such an external object .aa a tree by immediate^- -sensatiofk^- for, as that Jcnowledge implies the comprehension of organic, as. w^^as iQorganic things,, it marks a further stage^„ijX the comprehension of the universe as a whole. Hunger cannot be reduced to the feeling of hunger, because it is the state of a living being, which could not exist were not the world not only a system, but a system making possible the existence of living beings, and therefore of the feeling of this particular living being, as. occurring under these and no other Gonditions. The reality of hunger as a fact therefore means the reality of a universe containing organized beings which respond to stimuli in certain fixed ^' ways ; and it is the knowledge of this fact which guarantees for us the reality of hunger as something that is not made by our feeling, but of which our feeling is the sign. If therefore we eliminate all that is implied in such knowledge, we destroy at the same time the basis upon which our judgment of hunger, as an object, rests ; for no feeling, taken in its abstraction, is the guarantee of anything. The remaining case of arithmetical or geometrical judgments is easily disposed of The realist contends that the truth of two and two making four is distinct from my consciousness of it. So far as this means that the truth in this case is not merely an ^ idea in my head, he is undoubtedly right Two and two are four, whether I think so or not. But on what ground do we base this objective truth? In the first place, we have to observe that such judgments take us beyond our immediate sensible experiences. 122 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION Two and two are not things that we can perceive with our eyes, or touch with our fingers : they are conceptions, which we grasp with our intellect. Now it is the character of every conception that it is not ^ mere individual, but is universal in the sense that it is potentially infinite, i.e. is applicable to all pDjssible instances. When I think of two, I mean, as Aristotle long ago pointed out,^ not this two, but every possible two ; and when I judge that 2 4-2 = 4, I mean that every possible two added to other two - makes four. On the other hand, this particular truth is ..not one-, which is true in its _ isolation, J t- implies ^ .an arithmetical system, apart from which it would not be true. The basis of that system is the absolute identity of every unit in the system of units, the equality of any sum of units with the synthesis of all the units taken individually. Not only, there- fore, does the judgment, 2 + 2 = 4, imply that any possible two added to any other possible two is four, but that any possible number of units added to any other possible number is equal to any possible number of units taken individually. The truth,, then, pf any sum of numbers, and indeed of the whole of the arithmetical and algebraic operations, presupposes the unchangeable identity of units in a system., of units ; and this, again, presupposes that every in- telligent subject who is capable of comprehending what is meant by a unit must agree in accepting the arithmetical judgments which express, what -,is implied, in a system of units. The conception of a unit, though it is not the express comprehension of an arithmetical system, really presupposes it ; so that, if the system is denied, the unit ceases to have any meaning. It is thus obvious .tbc^t,. the truth, of '^ Posterior Analytics J 'Jla, 30 ff. THE NEW REALISM 123 the simplest arithmetical judgment implies an arith- pietical system capable of being grasped by every jrational being. Now, when it is recognized that there is a fixed system of units, and a corresponding identity in the thought of every rational being, it would plainly be absurd to affirm that the truth of an arithmetical judgment is dependent upon its acceptance or rejection by this or that individual. The., judgment is one that must be accepted by every thinking being who understands what it means, and .that- because it is the expression of an element in a self-consistent whole,, the denial of which would make ^every arithmetical judgment unmeaning. j^The in- dividual, in making a particular arithmetical judgment, tacitly accepts the whole system of such judgments ; and unless he does so, he virtually falls into the contradiction of at once affirming and denying the truth of the particular judgment which he makesj The realist, however, affirms more than this : he maintains that the truth of our arithmetical judg- ments is one thing, and our arithmetical judgments another thing. Now, this can only mean that when I make a particular arithmetical judgment, I have before my mind an idea of, say, two units, together with the idea that they are to be added to other two units, and that I then pass to another idea, viz. the judgment, 2 + 2 = 4. The realist - is evidently under the illusion that I can frame an image of two. groups of „ units, which are to be combined, and that my mirid may then make the transition to a more complex image, in which the two groups are presented aa.. united, in a larger group. But this, view is based upon the untenable assumption, that units are images. No doubt there are images in many cases, but these are ^OTply... signs .of what is, not, and cannot be, 124 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION imaged, namely,, abstract units, grasped by thought a,s„,TOJyersals or infinite^ possibilities. Now, since the true units cannot be imaged at all, there are no ideas of units such as the realist supposes : in making the judgment, the mind is stating what holds good for every mind and holds good under all possible conditions. If the realist were right in supposing that " ideas," in the sense of " images," were the sole pbject with which the mind operates, it is easy tQ, show that no true judgment could possibly be made. An Image is necessarily particular and transitory, and therefore cannot have a universal applicatioja. But, when we judge that two and two are four, we do not mean that the images of two and two and the image of four are the same image (which is obviously yntrue): what our judgment means is, that these or any other two units added to other two are four; and thi^ judgment presupposes the comprehension by thought of an absolute or unchangeable arithmetical system. Perhaps it may be objected, that while this view explains the universality of arithmetical judgments, it does not show that this system is applicable to the actual world. For, it may be said, the whole arithmetical system, consistent as it is in itself, may merely have the consistency of an arbitrary fiction. In nature, as Mill argued, there are no objects corresponding to the units of arithmetic ; and hence, even if that system is admitted by every rational being who admits the reality of the unit, this only proves that a self-consistent hypothesis is not self-contradictory : it does not show that arithmetical judgments are true of real objects. Now, there is a certain amount of force in this objection, but I do not think that it casts any real doubt upon the objective truth of our mathematical THE NEW REALISM 125 judgments. What these judgments affirm is that, in whatever other and more complex ways it may be determined, the world in its aspect as an external > system has a fixed and unchangeable constitution. The world, in other words, is not merely an extended being, but it is extended ; and were it not so, it could not be the rational organism which it can be shown to be. For, if it were not extended, not only could it not be numbered, but all motion and change must be denied, and with these all intellectual and moral process. What the mathematical sciences do is to state the unchangeable conditions involved in there being an extended universe ; and though their judg- ments are inadequate when applied to the higher aspects of the universe, they never cease to be true of the universe in its aspect of an extended reality. The limitation of mathematical judgments to the outer manifestation of the spiritual universe therefore in no way casts doubt upon their objective truth. A world of pure externality is, no doubt, impossible ; but a world without externality, and therefore without motion or change of any kind, is equally impossible. While iL is right to protest against the part being taken fcr..tke_ whole, it must not be' forgotten that without the parts there is no whole. This is the sense, as it seems to me, in which mathematics may rightly claim to formulate what is objectively true. TJ:ie,.r£aliat, on the* other hand, affirms objective truth in a seji^e that \ CaoiUOJt- but regard as indefensible and ultimately jinthinkable. He virtually claims that objects, which ^£ist independently of this or that rational subject, |iave characteristics that belong to them in themselves entirely apart from their relatiai;! to any arational subject.. Now, if this contention, were, sound, there >K9WldcJtie. no basis, for the claim to a real knowledge of 126 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION the world, and no basis therefore for maintaining that the world is the outward form of a self-determia^tiii: reason. For, th^ ground upon which we legitimately jplaim to know the real world is, that, it falls within th^ sphere of our consciousness ; and the ground upoo .which we affirm the reality of a self-determinant. re^goQ js, that no other hypothesis is. compatible with .the .character of the world as . known by ys. Enough has been said on the former point, but it may be profitable to add a few words on the latter point. What is claimed by the realist Js_ that tlje:, mathe- matical determination of the world is an adequate characterization of the real world, which by its very nature is independent of all relation to conscious subjects. If this were true, we must suppose that the world is capable of existing, and would be what it is, even if the totality of living and rational beings were annihilated. Now, it is of course true that the world does not depend for its existence upon any finite rational being, and that we can imagine all these annihilated without contradiction. But the question is, whether nature can exist by itself, on the assumption that it is defined simply as an extended being. In answer to this question we must begin by pointing out fhat we have no knowledge of nature as so defined. Our experience presents us with a nature which contains external things of a definite and specific character, and it is only by an effort of abstraction that we are able to strip this many-coloured world of its covering and reduce it to the bare skeleton with which mathematics operates. So far therefore as the world with which mathematics deals is concerned, it is not true that it has any independent reality ; in fact, it exists nowhere but in the minds of the individuals who make it an object of their thought. But, though THE NEW REALISM 127 it thus originates in an act of abstraction, we cannot say that there is nothing in the world corresponding to the product of this act; on the contrary, this product is based upon the character of the world of experience. But while this is true, it is also true that the ultimate foundation for our mathematical judgments is the conviction that the world is in- telligible, and therefore that what our intelligence demands must be ; in other words, Jhe constructions Qf,.^the mathematician are true objectively only under the presupposition that the actual world involves a Tatipijal system. I To assume, therefore, as the realist does, that the world as external exists, and has a definite nature, apart from a creative reason, is to assume that the world can exist even when it has been separated from the principle upon which its existence and definite nature are absolutely dependent.' Even if we supposed it possible that there should exist a world which is unintelligible, at any rate it would be for us a " book with seven seals." The claim to {rue or objective mathematical judgments is therefore a claim to the comprehension of a world which constitutes an external system, but which is compre- hensible at all only because that external system, is. iJie true, but incomplete, expression of a universe whkh ?> fi^^pni-ially spixituaL , Tixe, ,ig.alist-takes^ the world., as-4)artially . determined, and then, identifying it-with -this torso of itsel^he claims the ultimate truth oLJbhe,-«GharaGteristics -^expressed, in our mathematical jildgments ;,..ixat-aeeij]ig. that these are. true only on pcesjipposition ,thaL.we- live in. an intelligible universe, ^audJiave in our intelligence the principle manifested in theuiiniMerse, There is an objection to the view which I have tried to express which is almost sure to be made. If 128 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION external nature has no reality apart from a creative intelligence, how, it may be asked, are we to explain the fact that prior to the advent of life and intelligence upon the earth, there was, if we are to believe the majority of scientific men, nothing but inorganic nature ? An answer to this difficult problem can only be in- dicated. The changes which take place in the world imply the consciousness of time or succession ; without which, indeed, they are inconceivable. Nor is there any valid mode of escape from the difficulty now under consideration in a theory, such as that of Kant, which regards time as merely the form in which we are compelled to order our experiences, because of the finite and sensible character of our knowledge. The objection to this mode of explanation is, that, if pressed to its consequences, it converts the whole of our knowledge into an illusion. Yet there is an underlying truth in Kant's doctrine, which, when it is brought to light and thought out into perfect consistency, may at least help us to solve our problem. There is, as we have admitted, such a thing as succession, i.e. events do follow one another. This does not mean that we have experience of events merely as successive : ^)^. we actually, experience is, that changes take, place, in the world, as. known to us, such that, when we compare one experience with another, .we find that. a new determination of things has. -taken, the place of the. old, And^this, again, implies that the series of events of which we have experience is not a mere series, i.e.'is not an absolute transition from one state to another, but is reaUy a succession of what is not successi)^. The changes in -the world,, in .other .words, are not absolute .jtsapgi- lions. There is , no break in the porit^nuity of the THE NEW REALISM 129 y\ror-ld-process^ __.It.ia-.-the. sajjie moxld -.whiojx. persists through, all the chan^ea^- ani.were_it-.jaot so there >vould- be no,- changes- If this ,is , admitted, it.Jis phyipus- that- there can be no- absolute origination or 4e&e?LSfi* To suppose that either is possible is to maintain that something may arise from nothing, or pass into nothing ; a supposition which ultimately leads to the conclusion that the whole of reality, as it has come out of nothingness, so it may vanish away into nothingness and literally " leave not a rack behind." Granting, then, as I think we must, that tit^.. universe, has. not sprung out of nothing and cannot pass Jnto nothing, we must regard the changes which go on i,ti_the -World, not as the absolute origination pr destruction of being, but as transformations of an imperishable realitjjv— These^-transformatians^Jio daubt iMQlx&-xhanges. in the. unchangeable.^^ , but not changes \vhich can. be regarded as., qreatipos.^ or. destruqtiQO.^ J^or have-we ^^ any experience of such creations or destructions-;- what we experience ate changes of form which Jeajje*..the. reality unchanged. What, then, is to be said of those great cosmic fihanges, which, if we are to believe our men of science, have resulted in — the__ibrmation of . our . sojar syatemi Whatever view we take of them, I think we shall agree that there has been jux-_jahsDhxte-.QriginatLoja^ but , only a transformation. Therefare, the^appearance of life. and ponsciousness uponuthe earth cannot have been their absolute -.Drigination ; in other , words, the primitive pebular matter must be conceived as involving, foi; 9ne who grasped what it implied, all that comes put of it. But as knowledge is in us a process, in which we pass from one phase of reality to another, we naturally fix our attention upon that aspect of the universe in which it presents itself to us as a I I30 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION series of events ; and as we thus observe the series of events, without reflecting upon the permanence which is its correlate, we are wont to speak of a cause as an antecedent, an effect as a consequent. " tfl reality, however, 5..j:a.ug£™iS--.JQ£iver-.an..-antecedeiii:, b ut thQ ^^Xotalit^^ai^ cO'.existeni;^.xonditians,...an£LJie only, .ultiucnate or xeal.. cause , is.. the^- whole, universe. As... the. ..changes -which, occur ,are never originations, thfiL emergence of iifa. and consciousness on our easth is only the- comprehension on the part of finite beings pf the.., unchangeable principle of all reality, which has .not,*,itselC origiaatsd- Siace._Jthe-.iuiiversfi.--.as— a »diQle.-.xaanot come into Jaeingj the ^..process through which it passes is self-evolved, and .therefore the events .which, from the. point, of , view of > time, we distinguish jas new .states, of the world, are but the expression of its self-activity^r«a Jhi a^ conception of the.- universe as self-cpnipletei.-and..jsjduEreyolving is, ..hQWfiy.er,. incoa- ceivable on the ... supposition that any jiew mode_^ jexistence is an, .absolute origination; and therefore, Jbs. ^ise of life .in the organic ,v^prld and of intelligence 113 man is bi;»t tlie gradua.1 niojaifestation and compxehension on their part of .j;hs,„ulj;ilU^^, principle which. givs§ ^meaning .to, .^11.. that is, and without „which nothing ifeai.k.c9Uld^. At this point it may be argued that, if all that ever comes to be is already contained in the universe before it comes to be, a complete knowledge of the universe would show it to be absolutely changeless and immovable. That being so, must we not regard the temporal process as not a real process, but as merely our imperfect representation, in the form of process, of that which is devoid of all process ? How, then, it may be demanded, can we escape from the conclusion that individuality and freedom are a mere THE NEW REALISM 131 dream ? Are we not forced to say with Spinoza that the only real being is God, and that all apparently real finite beings are but modes of his infinite attributes? In seeking to escape from Subjective Idealism have we not fallen into Absolutism of the most uncompromising kind ? Now, there is a specious way of escape from this difficulty, of which Speculative Idealism, as I under- stand it, cannot avail itself The conception of an eternal or infinite self-evolving rational universe, it may be said, is merely an ideal, valuable as presenting us with the goal towards which all things are ever ifnoving, but having no other validity or value. The ideal of knowledge is that of an organic whole in which every element is inseparable from every other, and the ideal of action is that of a universe in which every being, in completely realizing its own nature, fulfils its special function as a member of the whole. The value of this ideal in its two aspects is inestimable as the incentive and goal of all our efforts towards completeness of knowledge and of action ; but it cannot be assumed to be already realized in God. What we mean by God, the Absolute, or whatever term we use, is merely our own ideal, projected as a reality, while in truth it has no existence beyond our own minds. It is, in Kant's terminology, a regulative^ not a constitutive^ Idea. Now, it is not to be denied that this solution seems at first sight to provide a way of escape from some of the difficulties connected with the doctrine, that God is a real or objective existence. If God is but the ideal of unrealized possibilities, which we as men set before ourselves as the indefinable goal towards which we are ever moving, 132 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION we are not called upon to explain how there can be any process in that which is already perfect ; nor does there seem to be any special difficulty in maintaining our own freedom and moral responsibility. We know that our knowledge grows from more to more, and we believe that moral progress is con- tinually going on ; and, certain of these two facts, we have, it may be said, all that is necessary for the conduct of our individual life and the progressive organization of society. Why, then, should we gratuitously puzzle ourselves with the self-contradictory doctrine of a universe in which all possibilities are already realized, while yet it is undergoing a process of development? Is it not far simpler to keep strictly , to what we can prove from experience, viz. that the human race continually grows in knowledge and morality, leaving insoluble enigmas alone? Why can we not be contented to accept the conception of God as an ideal, without maintaining His objective existence ? What is here meant by an " ideal " ? If I con- struct the fiction of a city in the heavens, inhabited by immortals of human shape, and with the limitations of ordinary humanity, it may be admitted that, though it does not rest upon any solid basis of fact, it yet has distinct value as a picture which helps to bring to light the great spiritual forces which give meaning to our own life. But, if the whole conception of life underlying my fiction is challenged ; if it is maintained that I have not only constructed a mere fairy tale, but one which is in fundamental disharmony with the whole nature of man ; is it not manifest that I must either show that the objection is baseless, or admit that I have constructed a fiction which cannot serve as an ideal because it is essentially THE NEW REALISM 133 false to the nature of things? Now, it is the same with the ideal of God. J f -that. ideaLis to serve as-«. the standard by Which our lives may..he. regulated, it must be what our ,4i5;;ea~.- would be if. .aJJ- our possibilities were^ealizedfc-^ -An JdeaL.cannat-be purely gaegative^- we-Giust in . some - sense- be able to^^coxor prehend what completedr.- knowledge would be, or we xaMaU-jbaoac. t>hat - our-^Jeni^wledge is not con^pleta 3yt- there can be no meaning in calling knowledge incomplete, unless we are able to comprehend what the txuP^Mb^^^^Pl things |^, (Eliminate., the relation ,^aa* ^Lj3WX- ideas to reality, and the distinction betweeo toSb-^^aaad^Jsk^baod,, ^disapp Therefore, if there jg no reality corresponding to our ideal, that ideal will not ^be an ideal of, knowledge, but merely the fiction^^hat beyond what we call knowledge there .is a,,pnfiQih1f> form rvf rnnqrinn<;npqq whirfi^ as we believe, ^£>ii1d bring gatigfartinn tn us. But, if that were' really the case, our satisfaction would be placed, not in the realization of completed knowledge, but on the contrary in the effort to realize what from the nature of the case could not be realized. The ideal pf completed .knowledge then, Qiust be. the ideal of tllg,cpnipleted.„kaQwLedge of reality orjt, is an empty fictioa. It would thus seem that unless.- the. ideal of knowledge i3 based upon the existence, of a reality J^C5^£Sadiflg^Jta«.Jt. ^tifc^. Jd^l becomes a mere iHjl^^ji,^ But a reality corresponding tO- the. ideal can have no -existence, apart from a perfect intelligence, tecause, as .we have seen above, a reality which, falls beyond intelligence is unthinkable^ Applying the jsame -method to the question of the.- ideal of .action, SKe-.ind. that we- cannot escape from „.the conviction i]iL-an, infinite-- Reason without destroying at ^ouce, fkaovdedge-^and^ morality^- Thus we are thrown back 134 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION upon* the problem of reconciling the objective existence pf the Infinite with the process oL the ..finite, .«and especially of our own- life..-. Is., any solution „pQ§^ib]£? It is well to remind ourselves that, as self-conscious intelligences, we already in a sense possess a know- ledge of the whole. Our life as individuals is no doubt subject to insuperable limitations, but these can be made an object of consciousness, and therefore we can in idea rise above them. The fact that, we are able ..to reconstruct the history of our., solar system,,, while as .individuals our .existence does,, not extend beyond a few decades^ shows that, in the ^ealm of the mind, time and space are not absolute Jimits,. but limits that we transcend in every .thought a;ew>hayfM There is therefore nothing in the con- ception of an Infinite Being which we need regard as unthinkable. Now, the limits of our individual life arise mainly from our ignorance or uncertainty of details. The large outlines of our life we know, though the exact result of every act we learn only from experience. Nevertheless, the result must in all cases be such as the whole nature of the universe demands. At first sight this may seem to bring us within the iron law of necessity; but, as we have already seen, the world is not a mechanical system, but a rational or spiritual organism, and therefore the influences which urge us to action do not operate irrespective of our intelligence and will. Progress in knowledge and morality can therefore only mean tji^ progressive comprehension and realization on our part of what the true nature of things is, or, in theological language, it consists in communion with God.. This, participation in the nature of the Divine is certainly the coming to consciousness on our part of what w^, ceally are; or, other wise, expressed, , it. is the realizar THE NEW REALISM 135 tian-*of -the unity of our, spirit with the universal Spirit ; a unity which is not created, by our cpur ^ciousness qt it, but is. based, upon the absolute nature ptf things. Thus we may maintain,, as I think, that smx progress in knowledge and^ morality is „.^QlbiSi& Juit the experience of what we reallj^^aas* The view which I am trying to express must not be confused with the absorption of all the finite in the abyss of an absolute Being. It abolished no idistinction : what it does is to maintain that every., distinction, even the most minute, if only we could jtrace it out ^to its ultimate source, would be found Jo be inseparable from the whole spiritual reality, ^nd even in its immediate forni reveals, though in a yague jind. indefinite way, the principle pf the wb.plp« Hence, as we ascend in the scale of being there is an ever clearer manifestation and realization of the divine unity; and in man, of all the finite beings jve know, that unity is most clearly manifested and post . definitely apprehended. The whole movement of human history, in ,/act, is nothing but the in- creasing comprehension of what nature and man are, when brought .into connection with the principle immanent -in all things. If at first man seems to live in a world that is foreign to him, it yet is true -that the whole -development of civilization-^ .is.- the process by which the rationality of the universe is ever more clearly ^disclosed . to him, as he obtains an ever fuller knc>wledge of the Spirit in whom he "l,i y;gs and moves and has his ^b-^ing^" LECTURE SIXTH THE INTERPRETATION OF RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE With the last lecture we concluded the consideration of those views which recognize the importance of a connected system of ideas to the complete formulation of religion. The most satisfactory attempt to construct such a system, as we contended, is that which may be called Speculative or Constructive Idealism, which seeks to unite the elements of truth contained in the opposite doctrines of Personal Idealism and the New Realism, while avoiding the elements of error with which they are infected. Personal Idealism accentuates the important truth that the higher interests of man can only be defended by the recognition of his free- dom and personality ; but it falls into the mistake of affirming the separation of the individual in his existence from all other individuals, and even from God, and thus makes any real knowledge on his part impossible ; while at the same time, in maintaining the isolation of God from all other beings, it is forced to deny His infinity. The New Realism rightly denies that reality can be reduced to individual experiences, but it errs in affirming the separate and independent existence of individual objects, and thus lies open to the objection that, as knowledge is supposed to consist RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 137 in subjective states of consciousness, we can have no real knowledge of anything, not even of ourselves. Speculative Idealism, endeavouring to avoid these opposite pitfalls, claims that the personality of man presupposes the process by which the subject knows and realizes himself, not in separation from the world and God, but in the comprehension of both as in- separably bound up with the consciousness of himself. Man is capable of overcoming the world, because in it he discerns the operation of the principle of reason which constitutes his own true self, and because in realizing that self he is in harmony with the universal reason ; he is capable of union with God, because there is no aspect of the universe which is not the more or less explicit expression of the Divine Reason. Now, it was pointed out in our opening lecture, that besides the doctrines which seek to build up a system of ideas, there is another view, which attaches supreme importance to the religious consciousness of the individual, and either minimizes the value of all doctrinal systems, or even denies that any such system can be constructed at all. Various modifications of this general theory have found favour in our own day ; the main line of cleavage being between that which treats the religious consciousness as an object of psychological consideration, to be studied in the same way as any other phenomenon, and that which starts from the basis of historical Christianity, As a representative of the former, I propose to consider the view advanced by Mr. William James in his recent brilliant work, The Varieties of Religious Experience; and of the latter, the principle underlying Professor H'arnack's Das Wesen des Christentums, familiar to English-speaking readers under the title, What is Christianity ? 138 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION Whatever conclusion we may reach in regard to the value of Professor James* philosophy, or want of philosophy, there can be no doubt as to the great debt which we owe him for his zeal in the collection and interpretation of psychological material, and for the marvellous skill and sympathy with which he has presented the most divergent types of religious experience. We find in his book a graphic picture of the inner consciousness of " all sorts and conditions of men," including Christian scientists, rationalists, mystics, and others ; and it is impossible to avoid being touched, and not unfrequently painfully touched, by the pungent records of religious experience which he has brought together. Whether injustice is not done to religion by the selection of confessions, which, as our author admits, are saturated with sentiment, we shall afterwards consider ; meantime, it will help us to a final estimate of the value of his work if we first consider the general method which it at once presupposes and illustrates. That method is one which is now familiar to us all, under the name of Pragmatism. If it has not been directly affected by the Critical Philosophy, Pragmatism at least exhibits a certain analogy to one phase of it — that in which supreme importance is attached to the practical as distinguished from the theoretical reason. The abrupt contrast of these two forms of consciousness in Kant naturally led to divergent views in his successors. One class of thinkers, representing what has been called " natural- ism," cut the knot by denying in toto that we can determine anything in regard to the region lying beyond the sphere of sensible experience. At the same time the influence of Kant upon them is so far evident that they admit the existence of a reality RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 139 lying beyond experience, while they claim that of it we can say nothing except that it is. This is the attitude of thinkers like Huxley and Tyndall, who found a philosophic exponent in the late Herbert Spencer, For all thinkers of this school the sole knowable forms of being are those that can be brought within the mechanical system of nature, and though they claim that what we thus know is the relative and phenomenal, they deny that we can extend our knowledge beyond this limited region, A second class of thinkers attack the problem left by Kant in an entirely different way. They maintain that the abstract opposition of the theoretical and practical reason is untenable, and therefore they deny that ultimately there is any fundamental opposition between faith and knowledge. This is the attitude of Hegel and the English Idealists of the older type, Hegel makes two main criticisms of Kant. In the first place, he denies the abstract opposition of faith and knowledge, and therefore the abstract opposition of theoretical and practical reason upon which it is based. In the second place, he maintains that this false contrast is due to the unwarranted assumption that the highest conception involved in experience is that of a mechanical system of individual things. This is the general line of thought that has been followed by English Idealists. The first repre- sentative of this point of view was the late T, H, Green, who endeavoured to develop the positive part of the Kantian doctrine, while refusing to accept the principle of the primacy of practical reason. Green maintained with Kant that our ordinary experience of things presupposes the operation of the distinguishing and combining activity of thought. This being so, 140 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION he claimed that, as the world of experience exists only for a self-conscious being, we must interpret reality as a spiritual, not as a mechanical, system. On the other hand, Green holds that it is only by a gradual process that the spiritual system which constitutes reality comes into existence for us. The world is the manifestation of a spiritual being, but this being must be conceived as an *' eternally complete consciousness,*' which is in no way affected by the process of experience in us. This contrast between the world of experience, as arising for us only in the process by which we gradually come to know it, and the world as it is for the eternally complete consciousness, leads Green to deny that we can be said to know God in an absolute sense. We do indeed know that " the world in its truth or full reality is spiritual," because nothing less will explain the fact of our experience, but *'such a knowledge of the spiritual unity of the world as would be a knowledge of God " is impossible for us, or, as Green roundly puts it, " to know God we must be God." It is evident that Green has failed to justify adequately his contention that there is no opposition between knowable reality and reality as it absolutely is. In another way he restores the dualism between knowledge and faith which he inherited from Kant. Now, Mr. Bradley, in his Appearance and Reality^ has attempted in his own way to go beyond the guarded attitude of Green and to define the Absolute or God. No one has emphasized more strongly than he the infinite complexity of the world, the manifest want of harmony and consistency in our ordinary experience and the impossibility of regarding it as an ultimate determination of reality. Nevertheless, he maintains that we are able in general to define RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 141 the nature of the Absolute. For, as he argues, our very inability to accept the contradictions which we find in our ordinary experience proves that, real as that experience is, it cannot be regarded as coincident with reality in its ultimate nature. Now, why do we condemn our ordinary experience ? Is it not because it is inconsistent or self-contradictory? But this implies that we always presuppose true reality to be self-consistent. Moreover, as nothing can exist that falls entirely beyond all possible experience, the Absolute must be not only self-consistent, but a single or total experience. This, however, is as far as we can go. Ultimate reality is undoubtedly a harmonious whole, an absolute spiritual unity, and if we could put ourselves at the point of view of the Absolute, we should certainly find that the whole complexity of our experience — including science, morality, art, and religion — would be perceived as a single harmonious whole. Mr. Bradley, however, though he grants that there are "degrees of reality" within our experience, refuses to admit that even the highest form of reality known to us is an adequate characterization of the Absolute. It can hardly be denied that in this doctrine of Mr. Bradley the opposition between knowledge and faith still survives, and hence it is perhaps not to be wondered at that Professor James should find this form of Idealism unsatisfactory and self-contradictory. He therefore in a sense recurs to the point of view of Kant, so far at least as to maintain that, while we cannot comprehend the true nature of reality by the exercise of the intellect we yet can discover how far the world as experienced by us responds to the claims of our fundamental needs. This view was partly indicated by Lotze, and it has also 142 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION been adopted to a certain extent by Mr. Balfour and others. Our special interest, however, lies in the form which it assumes under the hands of Professor James. The main object Mr. James has in view is to "defend the legitimacy of religious faith"; that is, to show that we are in certain cases justified in believing that for which no definite evidence, in the ordinary sense of the term, can be advanced. This doctrine is the precise opposite of that which claims that nothing should be accepted as true which cannot justify itself at the bar of reason. Now, of course, Mr. James does not mean that we are in all cases to take as true what it suits us personally to believe. It may, for example, suit a political leader to believe that every member of his party is scrupulously honest, but he is not justified in taking his wish as equivalent to fact. Again, it would be very pleasant if a man who is roaring with rheumatism in bed could by believing that he was well at once become well, or if a man who has only a dollar in his pocket could convert it by his wish into a hundred dollars ; but it is obvious that in such cases the talk of believing by our volition is simply silly. Indeed, from another point of view it is worse than silly, it is vile. " When one turns to the magnificent edifice of the physical sciences, and sees how it was reared ; what thousands of disinterested moral lives of men lie buried in its mere foundations ; what patience and postponement, what choking down of preference, what submission to the icy laws of outer fact are wrought into its very stones and mortar ; how abso- lutely impersonal it stands in its vast augustness, — then how besotted and contemptible seems every little sentimentalist who comes blowing his voluntary smoke- wreaths, and pretending to decide things from out of RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 143 his private dream ! Can we wonder if those bred in the rugged and manly school of science should feel like spewing such subjectivism out of their mouths ? The whole system of loyalties which grow up in the schools of science go dead against its toleration ; so that it is only natural that those who have caught the scientific fever should pass over to the opposite extreme, and write sometimes as if the incorruptibly truthful intellect ought positively to prefer bitterness and unacceptable- ness to the heart in its cup. * It fortifies my soul to know That, though I perish. Truth is so' — sings Clough, while Huxley exclaims : ' My only consolation lies in the reflection that, however bad our posterity may become, so far as they hold by the plain rule of not pretending to believe what they have no reason to believe, because it may be to their advantage so to pretend, they will not have reached the lowest depth of immorality/ And that delicious enfant terrible Cliiffbrd writes : ' Belief is desecrated when given to unproved and unquestioned statements for the solace and private pleasure of the believer. . . . Whoso would deserve well of his fellows in this matter will guard the purity of his belief with a very fanaticism of jealous care, lest at any time it should rest on an unworthy object, and catch a stain which can never be wiped away. ... If a belief has been accepted on insufficient evidence (even though the belief be true, as Clifford in the same page explains), the pleasure is a stolen one. ... It is sinful because it is stolen in defiance of our duty to mankind. That duty is to guard ourselves from such beliefs as from a pestilence which may shortly master our own body and then spread to the rest of the town. ... It is wrong always. 144 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION everywhere, and for every one, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence/ " ^ Are we then to conclude that all beliefs are deter- mined by pure reason ? To do so would be to fly directly in the teeth of the facts. In truth we find ourselves believing we hardly know how or why. " Here in this room," says Mr. James, addressing a group of Harvard students, " we all of us believe in molecules and the conservation of energy, in democracy and necessary progress, in Protestant Christianity and the duty of fighting for ' the doctrine of the immortal Munroe,' all for no reasons worthy of the name. . . . Our reason is quite satisfied, in nine hundred and ninety-nine cases out of every thousand of us, if it can find a few arguments that will do to recite in case our credulity is criticised by some one else. Our faith is faith in some one else's faith, and in the greatest matters this is most the case.' " ^ Now, in what circumstances are we justified in exercising the "will to believe"? Under what condi- tions does a hypothesis presented to us for acceptance become a belief or conviction ? In the first place, it must be living, not dead ; that is, it must awaken a responsive interest in us, so that we do not at once set it aside as incredible. An hypothesis which has no relation to the individual thinker is dead, and therefore never passes into belief If, for example, we are asked to believe that the Mahdi is a prophet of God, we are presented with an hypothesis which finds no response in us, and which is therefore instantly rejected. In the second place, no hypothesis ever becomes a belief unless the option of believing or rejecting it is forced upon us ; in other words, it must be presented with an absolute alternative. Such an ^ James' Will to Believe, pp. 7-8. "^Ibid,, p. 9. RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 14S hypothesis is Christianity and Agnosticism. We must accept either the one alternative or the other. And lastly, the hypothesis presented must be momentous^ not trivial. In what cases, then, are hypotheses presented to us which are at once livings forced and momentous ? In the first place, such an hypothesis is the belief in the truth itself, the belief that there is truth and that our minds and it are made for each other. "What is this," asks Mr. James, "but a passionate affirmation of desire, in which our social system backs us up ? We want to have a truth ; we want to believe that our experiments and studies and discussions must put us in a continually better and better position towards it ; and on this line we agree to fight out our thinking lives. But if a pyrrhonistic sceptic asks us how we know all this, can our logic find a reply? No! certainly it cannot. It is just one volition against another, — we willing to go in for life upon a trust or assumption which he, for his part, does not care to make." ^ Nor is the matter different when we pass from the theoretical to the practical sphere. " Moral scepticism can no more be refuted or proved by logic than intellectual scepticism can.'' Moral questions cannot wait for solution upon sensible proof. Science can tell us what exists, but it cannot tell us what ought to exist. Thus "the question of having moral beliefs at all or not having them is decided by our will. ... If your heart does not want a world of moral reality your head will assuredly never make you believe in one." ^ Not only in the general belief in truth and good- ness, but in more concrete problems, we are forced to adopt an alternative for which no preponderating evidence can be adduced, and this choice is forced ^ James* Will to Believe, p. lo. '^Ibid., pp. 22-23. K 146 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION upon us just in those cases that are most momentous for us. In scientific questions we are not thus driven to the wall, because " the option between losing truth and gaining it is not momentous/' and therefore we can afford to miss the chance of gaining truth, and " at any rate save ourselves from any chance of believing falsehoods^ by not making up our minds at all till objective evidence has come." " In our dealings with objective nature we obviously are recorders, not makers, of the truth. . . . Throughout the breadth of physical nature facts are what they are quite in- dependently of us." What difference does it make to most of us whether we have or have not a theory of the X-rays? Here there is no forced option, and there- fore it is better to go on weighing the reasons pro and contra with an indifferent hand.^ But are there not options from which we cannot escape ? Mr. James answers that there are. Such options we have in the case of all moral principles. Here in the absence of proof our " passional nature " must decide. It is the heart and not the head that makes us believe in moral laws. Thus we obtain the general thesis, that " our passional nature not only lawfully may, but must, decide an option between propositions, when- ever it is a genuine option that cannot by its nature be decided on intellectual grounds." ^ Again, while it is true that even in human affairs in general the need of acting is seldom so urgent that a false belief to act on is better than no belief at all, yet there are cases in which our principle applies. Healthy relations between persons demand trust and ex- pectation, and indeed the desire for a certain kind of truth here brings about that special truth's existence. If you assume the nobility of a man, even where you 1 James' Will to Believe, p. 20. '^Ihid., p. il. RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 147 have no objective evidence for your belief, you are likely to create in him that quality even if he did not originally possess it. So a social organism of any sort is possible only on the basis of mutual trust. " Wherever a desired result is achieved by the co-operation of many independent persons, its existence as a fact is a pure consequence of the precursive faith in one another of those immediately concerned. A government, an army, a commercial system, a ship, a college, an athletic team, all exist on this condition, without which not only is nothing achieved, but nothing is attempted." " There are, then, cases where a fact cannot come at all unless a preliminary faith exists in its coming."^ There is still another case, and that the most important of all, to which our principle applies, viz., religious faith. Whatever form religion assumes, it at least presup- poses eternal perfection, and yet it is impossible to verify this belief scientifically. Now, here we must presuppose that we have an instance of a living hypothesis. If for any one religion is a hypothesis that cannot by any possibility be true, there is no way of convincing him of its truth ; but where it is regarded as a real possibility, there can be no doubt that religion offers itself as a " momentous " option ; and not only so, but it is a " forced " option, since we cannot escape the issue by remaining sceptical and waiting for more light, because if it is true we lose the good dependent upon it. Hence we are not justified in refusing to make our choice between belief and disbelief We have here the right to believe " at our own risk." " When I look at the religious question," says Mr. James, " as it really puts itself to concrete men, and when I think of all the ^ James' Will to Believe^ pp. 24-25. 148 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION possibilities which both practically and theoretically it involves, then this command that we shall put a stopper on our heart, instincts, and courage, and wait — acting of course meanwhile more or less as if religion were not true — till doomsday, or till such time as our intellect and senses working together may have raked in evidence enough, — this command, I say, seems to me the queerest idol ever manufactured in the philosophic cave."^ Without attempting anything like a detailed criticism of the doctrine of Mr. James, it may be pointed out that it rests throughout on two assumptions : — Firstly, that nothing can be verified except that which belongs to the sphere of external nature, and, secondly, that there is an absolute opposition between faith and knowledge. Now, it is rather curious that, although Mr. James has described Kant as a " curio," his own doctrine, so far as these two assumptions are concerned, coincides with that of Kant. For it is one of the main positions of the Critical Philosophy^ as we have seen, that knowledge is coterminous with sensible experience ; in other words, with the con- nected system of individual objects which constitutes the world of nature. Holding this view, Kant naturally went on to maintain that all the distinctively human interests, including morality and religion, must be based upon faith. Now, it was pointed out by Kant's immediate successors, and especially by Hegel, that the limitation of knowledge to the system of nature is a purely arbitrary assumption, resting upon the untenable hypothesis that the highest category con- stitutive of knowable objects is that of reciprocal action. Mr. James is involved in the same criticism. His main reason for denying that morality and ^ James* Will to Believe^ pp. 29-30. RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 149 religion can be proved is his tacit assumption that nothing can satisfy the intellect except that which can be expressed in terms of mechanical causation. He seems to forget that the whole sphere of life, not to speak of consciousness, is inexplicable except from a teleological point of view, and that the system of nature itself is ultimately unintelligible unless it is interpreted from the same point of view. A similar remark applies to the opposition between faith and knowledge. Even the proposition that there is truth and that it is obtainable by us is held to be beyond all rational evidence. Now, it is of course true that there is no way of proving the possibility of a true judgment by going beyond the whole sphere of knowledge. We can show the falsity of a particular or limited judgment by pointing out that it is inconsistent with some principle, the truth of which is admitted, but we cannot bring truth itself to the test of any higher principle. What we can do, however, is to show that even the denial of truth, since it is a judgment made by us, at least pre- supposes its own truth as a denial. Thus we may fairly argue, that the possibility of truth only seems to be lacking in evidence because it is the source of all evidence."^ This preliminary discussion of the pragmatic method will enable us to deal very shortly with Professor James* philosophy of religion. It is not possible, nor is it advisable, that I should attempt to reproduce the rich psychological or biographical material which he has supplied in his eloquent and instructive work. His treatment of the various types of religious ^Some remarks on the most recent form of Pragmatism, as expressed in Mr. James' Pragmatism^ will be found in the note at the end of this lecture. ISO PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION consciousness, and his estimate of their relative value for life, is broad, sane, and sympathetic ; while nothing could well be more fascinating than the vividness and charm of his literary style. What we are specially concerned with, however, is the measure in which he has contributed to the solution of our special problem. This part of his work is as disappointing as the other is satisfactory. At bottom his speculative doctrine comes ultimately to this : that as the intellectual method of philosophy, as ordinarily understood, is abstract and ineffective, the source of religion must be sought for, not in the normal processes of the self-conscious life, but in the obscure regions of the " subliminal consciousness.'' Now, " it is one of the peculiarities of invasions from the sub-conscious region to take on objective appearances, and to suggest to the Subject an external control. In the religious life the control is felt as ' higher ' ; but since it is primarily the higher faculties of our own hidden mind which are controlling, the sense of union with the power beyond us is a sense of something, not merely apparently, but literally true." ^ " We have in the fact that the con- scious person is continuous with a wider self through which saving experiences come, a positive content of religious experience which is literally and objectively true as far as it goes." ^ But what is the positive content of this experience? "The only thing that it unequivocally testifies to is that we can experience union with something larger than ourselves and in that union find our greatest peace. ... All that the facts require is that the power should be both other and larger than our conscious selves. Anything larger will do, if only it be large enough to trust for the next step. It ^ James, The Varieties of Religious Experience, pp. 512-513. "^ Ibid,, -p. 515. RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 151 need not be infinite, it need not be solitary. It might conceivably even be only a larger and more godlike self, of which the present self would then be but a mutilated expression, and the universe might conceivably be a collection of such selves, of different degrees of inclusiveness, with no absolute unity realized in it at all." ' The fundamental vice of Mr. James' method of interpreting the religious consciousness seems to me to be its abstractness. No one is more emphatic than he in affirming that a theory of religion must be based upon " experience," and no one, as a matter of fact, has made so little use of it. The problem, as he puts it, is to ascertain whether there is any solid foundation for the belief in the " supernatural," i.e. as our author conceives it, in a universe or sphere of being which differs in kind from the world of order and law recognized by science. It is obvious that it is useless to appeal, in support of the existence of such a universe, to those who deny that a realm of caprice and arbitrariness can possibly be real. Hence the scientific man, with his invincible belief in inviolable law, is ruled out of court. Next, the theologian who postulates the existence of an Infinite Spirit is convicted of dogmatism. And, lastly, the philosopher who main- tains that the universe is essentially rational and intelligible is condemned on the ground of his appeal to the ordinary processes of the conscious life. By this ingenious method of exclusion, the appeal to " experience " comes to mean an appeal either to those who have no scientific acquaintance with the world in which they live, or who regard the results of science as contradictory of religion. What is this but to limit "experience" to the intellectually weak and ^ James, The Varieties of Religious Experience, p. 525, IS2 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION unreasonable ? Nor is this all ; for a still further limitation must be made. Even those who, like Professor James himself, are familiar with the world of science, must be excluded on the ground that they are destitute of a ** leaky consciousness." Thus, in the end, it turns out that the only "experience" to which a valid appeal can be made, is the " experience " of those who are of a highly emotional, not to say hysterical, temperament. Such a method, as it seems to me, cannot possibly yield satisfactory results. Nevertheless, our author is not satisfied even yet. Visionaries, like other people, have a wide-awake consciousness, into which distinctly intellectual elements enter ; and, there- fore, they too must be liberated from the too great clarity of their ordinary experience, in order that the "subliminal consciousness" may be allowed the floor. Unfortunately, the " subliminal consciousness " gives forth a very confused and uncertain sound, for no two representatives of it agree in their testimony. We must therefore eliminate the discrepancies. What remains after this repeated process of elimination ? Nothing but the vaguest presentiment that there is something — we know not what — which re-enforces life and brings comfort to its possessor. Perhaps the " something " may be God ; perhaps it may be only a larger and more godlike self; and indeed it is difficult to understand why it should be anything more than an arbitrary product of the mysterious " subliminal " self — if indeed there is any " self," either sub-conscious, conscious, or super-conscious. This whole method seems to me unsound. An appeal is made to " experience,*' but, instead of taking it as a whole, it is arbitrarily limited and re-limited until it fades away into the barest and vaguest of abstractions. Mr. James has appealed to Caesar, and RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 153 to Caesar he must go. If religion is veritably to be based upon " experience," no one is justified in citing only the partial and fragmentary consciousness of this or that individual. A genuine inductive method must fix its eyes upon the whole wealth of experience, refusing to generalize from a mere fragment of it. Virtually to ignore the religious experience of the great majority of mankind, including all the scientific men, theologians and philosophers of our race, is a strange way of seeking for truth. Our author rightly blames those who rashly assume that nothing is real but that which can be compressed within the framework of mechanical law ; but, is it any more defensible first to separate the individual from all that gives meaning to his conscious life, and then to go behind even the conscious life, searching for the key to the riddle of existence in the dark abyss of the " sub-conscious " ? A philosophy of religion which cannot find a place for the whole wealth of experience, including the results of science and philosophical speculation, seems to me to be self-condemned. If religion is a principle of unification, it must unify, not isolate ; whereas the method of Mr. James, instead of seeing in religion a further and higher synthesis than that of ordinary experience and of the special sciences, turns its back upon both, and tries to find in the aberrations of unbalanced emotion the secret of life. No doubt religion is emotional, but why should it be assumed that the emotion must be irrational, if it is to find a place in a true theory of religion ? Our author himself admits that many of the " saints " whose experience he narrates were deficient in intellectual power ; but, instead of drawing the plain inference, that the highest form of the religious consciousness is to be found only in those who have the firmest grasp, intellectually as 1 54 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION well as emotionally, of the facts of life, he rules them out as unworthy to bear testimony at all. The inadequacy of the method may be seen from a single instance. St. Paul is admitted to the com- pany of the truly religious, not because of the general sanity of his whole conception of life, but because of his visions ; in virtue of which he takes rank with the crowd of visionaries, whose testimony is relied on as witnesses for the reality of a spiritual world. Surely this is to prefer the accidental to the essential. It is no doubt true that, in men of intense emotional quality, truth tends to project itself in sensible and palpable images, to which they themselves and others are apt to attach undue importance. As a matter of fact, St Paul was too sane to invert values in this irrational way ; what he insisted upon was not his visions but his " prophecy/' Le. his whole view of the meaning of life ; and even the lesser visionaries, to whose experiences Mr. James attaches inordinate value, owed their main influence, not to the erratic forms in which their beliefs were cast, but to the witness of their life and the essential truth embodied in it. We are told that there is a sub-conscious con- tinuation of the conscious life, and that there are persons in whom invasions from the sub-conscious life take on an objective appearance, and suggest to the subject of them an external control, which they feel as higher. Now, one may fairly ask in what sense the sub-conscious life is a " continuation " of the conscious life? The conscious life of a man is a " continuation " of the conscious life of a child, but it is the former, and not the latter, which is higher. Is the sub-conscious life, then, higher than the conscious? and if so, why? As Mr. James RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 155 admits that a great deal which comes out of the sub-conscious life is of the poorest possible character, it is obvious that we cannot conclude that a thing is higher merely because it emerges from the sub- conscious. To me it seems undeniable that the main difference between the sub-conscious and the conscious life consists in the vagueness and inde- finiteness of the former as compared with the latter. The nearest approach to the sub-conscious is when the current of conscious life is at its lowest ebb, as in the case of the temporary exhaustion of the higher nerve-centres, or just before dropping off to sleep. And it is significant that, in either case, what possesses consciousness is a large, vague, fluctuating, indeter- minate " something," with no clearly marked features, — exactly what Mr. James regards as the deliverance of the subliminal consciousness, except that in the latter even the poor minimum of definiteness which still survives has vanished away. It is hard to believe that this invertebrate state of mind is its highest form. Only those who identify the sublime with the indefinite can accept such an inversion of values. To me it seems almost self-evident that mind reaches its highest form in the unity of thought, emotion, and will ; a unity in which there is a perfectly clear, if not always a consciously articulated^ system of ideas. To seek for truth in the dark regions of the sub-conscious is to seek for the living among the dead. Those who, like the late Frederic Myers and Mr. James, try to persuade us that " God gives wisdom to his beloved in sleep," may be reminded of Hegel's sarcastic comment, that whcit we get in sleep is merely empty dreams. We are assured that there are persons in whom " invasions " from the sub-conscious life take on an IS6 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION objective form, and suggest external control. Is this psychological fact to be taken as a valid proof that there actually is *' external control " ? How is the transition made from the belief of these persons — admittedly not the clearest-headed of the race — to the objective reality of their belief? Is every belief which proceeds from the sub-conscious region to be taken as self-evidencing? And if not, by what criterion are we to distinguish beliefs that are true from those that are false? Mr. James does not accept the testimony of the sub-conscious as such, and that for the very sufficient reason, that it is by no means either self- consistent or free from ambiguity. It is very doubtful, in his opinion, whether the " objective reality," to which it seems to bear witness, is a God ; our author rather thinks it is something very much less specific. Now, if the testimony of a witness is found hesitating and doubtful on such a fundamental point, how can we have any faith in it? I can understand the attitude of one who claims that the testimony of the sub- conscious must be accepted implicitly, on the ground that the lower cannot set aside the authority of the higher ; but when it is admitted that this child-like attitude leads to confusion and self-contradiction, we seem forced to seek a way of escape out of an untenable position by falling back upon the con- scious life, and invoking the aid of that very reason which Mr. James finds to be essentially imbecile and irreligious. It may not be superfluous to close with a word or two on the question of " experience " as the basis of religion. In the widest sense of the term, a true theory of religion must be based upon religious ex- perience ; for what does not fall within our experience can have for us no meaning. But experience must .^ -M RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE 157 be taken in the widest possible sense. We cannot get any fruitful Results by simply describing the '* experience " of this or that individual, in its isolation. To interpret the experience of the individual we have to consider the spiritual medium in which he lives, and the stage in the process of experience as a whole which he represents. For experience is essentially a process. To understand the experience of a St. Paul we must first estimate the experience of the prophets who preceded him and made his experience possible. No doubt the man of religious genius has an unique experience, and adds a new dimension to human life ; but what gives his higher experience its convincing force is that it gathers up into itself the essence of all previous experiences and re-interprets them in the light of a new and more fruitful belief. To adopt the method of Mr. James — to disregard the stage in religious experience represented by the individual, and thus to look upon it as something that cannot be repeated in others — is a vicious method. Nor can the process of religious experience be rightly interpreted except by one who is able to view it in its relations to the total experience of the age in which it appears. The new religious experience transforms men's whole view of life, not merely a part of it, though its total bearing is never fully visible even to the man of genius, but requires, it may be, centuries to unfold in the fulness of its implications. It is here that philosophy is of such eminent service. No philosophy can take the place of experience : it is not life, but a theory of life ; but it can discover wherein the advance to a higher stage consists, and what bearing the new truth has upon other spheres of life. Moreover, philosophy sums up the results of experience, and prepares the way for a IS8 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION further advance. To set aside the patient labours of reflective thought, as embodied in theologies and philosophies, is a blind and unreasonable proceeding. Surely we may admit that philosophy cannot be a substitute for religious experience without denying it its function in helping to give order and system to the organic process of human evolution. Nor must we forget that clearness of thought is essential to the full development of experience, and therefore is an essential factor in the religious consciousness itself. Take this away, and there is no safeguard against the extravagances and aberrations of religious emotion, which, like all emotion, tends to over-balance itself. It is a gross mistake to suppose that emotion dis- appears, or loses its power, when it is purified by intelligence ; on the contrary, it gains in effectiveness, at least in the long run. I think we are safe in saying that no religious genius of the first rank has ever lived whose insight was not equal to the strength of his emotion. It is the grasp of reality which is the source and measure at once of power of thought and depth of emotion. NOTE ON THE PRAGMATIC CONCEPTION OF TRUTH. As originally set forth in his Will to Believe^ Pragmatism was in Mr. James' hands little more than a working conception — it might almost be called a " dodge " — by which, in default of scien- tific evidence, one may contrive to live and to turn nature to one's own ends. We cannot, as it is there held, refute the sceptic on theoretical grounds, but we can at least get the better of him in practice ; for, though we have no way of knowing whether we have even partially apprehended the world, not even the sceptic can show that we have not truly apprehended it j and we have always PRAGMATIC CONCEPTION OF TRUTH 159 the inestimable advantage over him, that the beliefs on which we act prove or disprove themselves practically in this way, that they either do or do not give satisfaction to our whole nature. The pragmatic method, as thus understood, is " primarily a method of settling metaphysical disputes that otherwise might be inter- minable."^ At the same time it "does not stand for any special results. It is a method only."^ After maintaining this guarded attitude for a number of years, Professor James seems at last to have convinced himself that Pragmatism is not merely a method, useful in exceptional cases, but a certain theory of truth ; and it is to the defence of this theory that his recent interesting and suggestive book is mainly devoted. My reasons for regarding this more ambitious form of Pragmatism as unsatisfactory I can only indicate in the shortest way. It is now maintained without qualification that an idea is true only in so far as it leads to satisfying and successful experiences. This is the only legitimate sense, as we are assured, in which it can be said that an idea is in " agreement " with *' reality.'' " True ideas are those that we can assimilate, validate, corroborate and verify." 3 Pragmatism therefore denies, firstly, that there is any distinction between the truth of an idea and the proof of its truth ; - the truth of an idea consists in its verification. It also denies, secondly, that there is any distinction between the truth of an idea and its practical usefulness in guiding towards desirable issues ; so that we can say either that an idea is useful because it is true, or that it is true because it is useful. I. An idea, as it is argued, is not true because it conforms to reality, but only because it leads to a satisfying experience. Now, it must be admitted, I think, that truth is not a property which attaches to an idea in its isolation. Simply to entertain an idea is not to have a true idea, even if it should turn out that the idea so entertained is afterwards verified. When the idea that Mars moved in an elliptical orbit presented itself to the mind of Kepler, his idea was not true ; it only became true when it was found to ^ be corroborated by the actual facts. Truth, in other words, exists only in judgments, and judgments are true only when they are based upon convincing evidence. So far we must agree with the pragmatist. Truth, as he rightly maintains, cannot be separated from the process of ^Jamas' Pragmatism, p. 45, '^Ibid., p. 51. ^ Ibid,, p. 201. i6o PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION verification. But, not contented with this conditional statement, the pragmatist contends that truth has no other meaning than its power of leading to a satisfying experience. With this contention I am unable to agree. There is no doubt a sense in which the object of experience grows or is made^ but it is not a sense which justifies the reduction of truth to verifiability. Since the " object " is the "experienced" object — the total " situation," as the prag- matist puts it — the object of the " idea," as entertained prior to the proof of its truth, and the object of the "judgment" differ as undeveloped and developed " object." The ordinary account of a true idea as a "copy "of the real object is obviously untenable, for the so-called " real object " exists only in the " true idea," and an idea cannot be a copy of itself. The developed idea, or judgment, is not different from the developed object, but is simply the developed object looked at from the side of the subject. But, while this is true, it does not follow that the truth of a judgment consists in its verification. When is a tentative idea capable of verifi- cation ? Only when it is in harmony with the conditions of experience, general and special. ( A given judgment is true which expresses what is compatible with the total system of experience ; by which we must not understand either a mere succession of impressions, or what we call " Nature," but the complex of con- ditions, external and internal, without which a given experience could not be. ) The pragmatist, tacitly assuming that we cannot comprehend reality as it is, is led to identify truth with what gives satisfaction. And obviously some such view must be advanced by anyone who denies that we can know the real world to be a single system. If, on the other hand, it is admitted that there is only one self-consistent reality, however various its particular manifestations may be, then the only true judgments will be those which are compatible with the total system of things. From this point of view we can understand how there may be a transition from a tentative idea, or hypothesis, to a judgment, and how a judgment may be true without being a " copy " of a real object lying beyond experience. » Nor does this conception of truth imply that in the real world there are no changes ; what it implies is that those changes are not arbitrary, but proceed upon a fixed principle. Truth, in short, presupposes a rational universe, which we, as rational, may comprehend./ 2. From what has been said it follows that the second denial of PRAGMATIC CONCEPTION OF TRUTH i6i the pragmatist is equally fallacious. An idea is not '* made true " by its satisfactory consequences, but it has these consequences because it is true. It would be passing strange if in a rational universe our fundamental needs were incapable of satisfaction ; ^ and as the desire for truth is one of those needs, and admittedly one which is essential to the satisfaction of the others, it is not surprising that when we hit upon an idea which agrees with the totality of our experience, we should experience the joy of a fulfilled desire. And as our experience is continually growing, we can also understand how it comes about that a partial truth, taken as the whole, should lead to dissatisfaction when it is found to be incom- patible with our wider experience. /In a sense, therefore, no single judgment is absolutely true ; nevertheless, judgments are true in so far as they involve and conform to the principle of the whole ; and when a judgment which has been accepted as final and complete is seen to be only a partial determination of reality, it does not follow that it loses all its truth, but only that it is absorbed ) in a wider truth. 3. Holding that truth is what leads to a successful and satisfying experience, the pragmatist naturally regards the various categories by which we systematize our experience as simply " postulates," or *' hypotheses,'^ which owe their validity to their success. " Our fundamental ways of thinking about things are discoveries of exceedingly remote ancestors, which have been able to preserve themselves throughout the experience of all subsequent time."^ These common-sense conceptions, as we are told, by the prescriptive right of immemorial custom, have come to seem axiomatic and absolutely indubitable ; but there is nothing to hinder us from supposing that quite different categories " could have proved on the whole as serviceable for handling our experiences mentally as those which we actually use. . . . All our conceptions are what the Germans call Denkmittel^ means by which we handle facts by thinking them."^ Nor is it different with the categories employed by the special sciences and by philosophy. " There are, then, at least three well-characterized levels, stages or types of thought about the world we live in, and the notions of one stage have one kind of merit, those of another stage another kind. It is impossible, however, to say that any stage as yet in sight is absolutely more true than another."^ '^]d,mts' Pragmatism, p. 170. '^Ibid., p. 171, ^ Ibid.t p. 188. L i62 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION It seems to be assumed that, if the categories by which we organize our experience have been developed in the process of experience, we thereby deprive them of any claim to truth in any other sense than that of their enabUng us to find our way through what would otherwise be an impassable jungle. Now, while it is certain that such categories as "thing," "identity," "atom,'' " reality,*' are not rigid and unchanging forms, belonging to our intelligence by its original constitution, it seems to me no less certain that they are not mere "working-conceptions.'' The presupposition of an intelligible reality is that it should be a self-determined and self-consistent whole, and therefore any less comprehensive conception will inevitably reveal its limitations if it is treated as ultimate. On the other hand, no category of a purely fictitious character can help us to organize our experiences, because such a category must be in fundamental antagonism to the real universe. If this is admitted, it cannot be conceded that there are other categories which might have "proved as serviceable for handling our experiences as those which we actually use." On such a view the development of experience, in any intelligible sense of the term, is unmeaning. For, if the supposed categories should not only differ from ours, but actually contradict them, we must be living in an irrational universe, in which "to be'' and "not to be " mean the same thing ; while, if they should be merely a variation of ours, they would be in essence the same, and therefore distinguishable only in form. It seems to me entirely fallacious to refer to the different geometries of Euclid and Descartes in defence of the merely instrumental character of our categories ; for those geometries are not contradictory of each other, but are related as less and more comprehensive formulations of the external world in its quantitative aspect. On this analogy, therefore, the categories by which we escape from the chaos of sensible impressions cannot be viewed as merely convenient instruments ; they must be, each in its degree, a veritable, though inadequate, comprehension of reality. They do actually bring to light certain characteristics of the real world, and only become false when they are viewed as if they were exhaustive definitions of it. For there can only be one completely exhaustive definition of reahty, a definition which must include within itself the whole truth, as embodied, dispersedly and more or less confusedly, in the various categories of common sense, science and philosophy. PRAGMATIC CONCEPTION OF TRUTH 163 We must, therefore, deny that the three grades of categories stand upon the same level : they are related as successively more comprehensive determinations of the real universe. No doubt we cannot escape from the pragmatic doctrine if we admit its view of truth. If " it is impossible to say that any stage as yet in sight is absolutely more true than another " : if we can say no more than that " common sense is better for one sphere of life, science for another, philosophical criticism for a third " : then we must indeed give up the quest for a rational view of the world. We must do so, because with the admission that we do not comprehend reality itself, but only succeed in organizing our individual experiences for our own limited ends, we have made it impossible to say anything whatever about reality ; for aught we can show, every category we use may not only be inadequate to characterize it, but may distort it into its precise opposite. 4. That this is the inevitable result of the pragmatic reduction of truth to expediency is shown clearly in the conclusion to which it leads. If truth is merely " satisfying experience," certainly we " cannot reject any hypothesis if consequences useful to life flow from it."^ Whatever we find useful is to that extent true, and true solely because it is useful. The idea of the Absolute, we are told, has been proved of use "by the whole course of men's religious history.'' But, as we may fairly object, if this category, like all others, is true only in the sense that it has helped to introduce order into our experience, there is nothing to show that its opposite might not have been equally useful ; while, on pragmatic premises, neither may be in agreement with the real nature of things. We are told that it is Pluralism which " agrees with the pragmatic temper best."^ If so, must we not accept it, as the idea which best makes for satisfaction ? Monism is practically held to be but a pis alter ; and it is hardly the part of good sense to accept a worse, when we have a better, way of organizing our experiences. We are expressly told that " the rational unity of things " really means "their possible ^rci^vaczS. unification^^ The " world's perfection," as we are assured, is only "a possible terminus ad quem^^^ But is the '* world's perfection" for the pragmatist even " possible" ? If our categories are not determinations of reaUty, but only (?«rways of organizing the Gewiihl of our impressions, it is difficult to see how, by any extension of experience, we come one whit ^ James' Pragmatism, p. 273. '^Ibid., p. 278. ^ Ibid.^ p. 280. i64 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION nearer to reality, and therefore difficult to understand how the " world's perfection " can be declared even " possible.'' The " possible " cannot contradict the essential nature of the "'' real," and as we never come in contact with reality at all, what may, or may not, be " possible " lies entirely beyond our ken. No wonder we are told that " it is our faith and not our logic ^' which decides ultimate questions ! LECTURE SEVENTH CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY In the present lecture I propose to complete the consideration of those views which accentuate the personal side of religion, by a somewhat careful examination of Professor Harnack's Das Wesen des ChrisientumSj a work which deservedly enjoys a very high reputation and has had a marked influence^ especially upon popular liberal theology. This work differs from Mr. James' Varieties of Religious Experience in basing its conclusions on historical Christianity, not upon psychological data. The absence, indeed, of any theory of historical evolution in Mr. James' work is one of the things which at once strikes a reader in these days when the idea of development is almost assumed as axiomatic and is applied as a matter of course in all departments of thought. At first sight this seems to put the historian of dogma and the psychologist in an entirely different class ; but, if the criticism of last lecture is at all sound, there is less divergence between the two thinkers than may at first sight appear ; for, while it is true that Professor James arranges his specific material without any reference to its place in the history of thought, Professor i66 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION Harnack, as I shall try to show, virtually ignores all development in Christian doctrine and in the Christian consciousness. Nor is this agreement a matter of accident ; for both writers either deny the possibility of a philosophy of religion, or at least seek to reduce it to the simplest possible elements. Ever since the days of Schleiermacher there has been in Germany an influential school of theologians who have sought to free religion from what they regard as the cramping and benumbing effects of the traditional creed. The starting-point of this move- ment was in one way simply a fresh appeal, in the spirit of the Reformation, to the immediate conscious- ness of the divine ; but in the hands of Schleiermacher it was exaggerated into an emotional mysticism, which set the heart at war with the head, and was only prevented from degenerating into a wild carnival of feeling by the unrecognized presence and restraining influence of reason. The pathway opened up by Schleiermacher was followed later by Ritschl, who makes use of the phenomenalistic side of the Critical Philosophy, as modified by Lotze, in support of a sceptical doctrine of knowledge, maintaining that the sole ground and value of our belief in God is its influence on our own higher life. God is love, and all statements as to the absoluteness and self-existence of God are but " heathenish metaphysics " ; though Ritschl, with obvious inconsistency, refuses to surrender the independent reality of God. Corresponding to the love of God is the kingdom of God, i.e. the union of men for mutual and common action from the motive of love ; a love which, as Ritschl in his later views affirms, derives its origin from the revelation of God in Christ Jesus he regards as the representative of the perfect spiritual religion, and his life as a permanent rule for us. CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY 167 This is the school of thought in which Professor Harnack has been trained, and its impress is visible in his conception of the religious life. The history of dogma, as he conceives it, is a record of the progressive obscuration of the truth by the action upon the simple faith of Jesus and his immediate disciples of Hellenic philosophy and other " secularizing " influences. " The Christian religion is something simple and sublime ; it means one thing and one thing only: Eternal life in the midst of time, by the strength and under the eyes of God." This essence of all religion is to be found in Jesus Christ and his Gospel, though we must also listen to what the first generation of his disciples tell us of the effect which he had upon their lives ; and we must also take account of the rekindling again and again of the spiritual life which burned in them. " It is not a question of a * doctrine ' being handed down by uniform repetition or arbitrarily distorted, but a question of a h/e " ; and ^' life cannot be spanned by general concep- tions " ; for " there is no general conception of religion to which actual religions are related simply and solely as species to genus." The business of the historian is, therefore, not to seek for a system of doctrine in the Christian records, but to determine what is of per- manent value in those records ; and this can only be done by finding out what is common to all the forms which the Christian idea has taken, corrected by reference to history. Thus we may recover the divine lineaments of Christianity, and find in it nourishment for our higher life. The message of Jesus and its influence upon the soul is the essence of Christianity, not the marvels by which it has been embellished, the dogmas in which it has been formulated, or the institu- tions in which it has been embodied. The Gospel may be said to consist in the glad tidings of the kingdom of 1 68 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION God as present here and now ; of God the Father and the infinite value of the human soul to Him and to itself; of the higher righteousness and the new com- mandment of love, as dependent for realization on humanity or openness to the love of God. In these truths is contained the whole of Christianity.^ It cannot be denied that there is much in this view of Harnack which commends itself to the educated man of to-day. The dogmas of the Church, in their traditional form, he has outgrown, and he is apt to look with suspicion on the attempts of recent thinkers to reconstruct them in the light of modern thought. It is therefore with peculiar satisfaction that he hears a scholar of the first rank, who has written one of the best histories of Christian dogma, say that no matter what the results of Biblical criticism and historical investigation may be, or in what vagaries of speculation metaphysicians may indulge, Christianity, as essentially life in the Eternal, cannot be affected by the changing fashions of an age. How far can we reconcile this simplification of religion with the just claims of our intellect? Can we admit that "life cannot be spanned by general conceptions," and that religion is simply and solely a thing of the heart ? So far as a distinction is meant to be drawn between religion as the personal experience of the individual, and theology, or the philosophy of religion, as a systematic statement of the truth which that experience presupposes, Harnack is no doubt right; though it may be added that it would be hard to find any representa- tive thinker who would not admit the distinction and even emphasize its importance. But, when it is admitted that religion is not philosophy, it does not follow either that religion can exist in absolute separa- ^ Harnack's Wkat is Christianity ? pp. 8 fF. CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY 169 tion from all " general conceptions/' or that by its very nature every philosophy must necessarily distort or annihilate it. As I have already argued, religion is possible only for a being who is possessed of reason, and indeed of reason as the intellectual comprehension of reality. No doubt a being of pure intellect is an impossible monster of abstraction, but a purely sentient being who lives in the realm of the spirit is not less fictitious. Whatever else religion may be, it involves, as Harnack himself admits, the consciousness of something higher than man ; and the Christian religion, on his own showing, involves the consciousness of God as Father, And surely it is almost a truism to say, that only a being who is conscious of himself can be conscious of something higher than himself But the consciousness of self, with the correlative consciousness of the higher- than-self, is impossible in any being that is destitute of the power to frame " general con- ceptions/' and indeed, in any being who has not already in some sense framed that most " general " of all conceptions, the conception of a single all- comprehensive principle to which all things are somehow related. It may be said, however, that the consciousness of some unifying principle higher than man is not the same thing as the abstract conception of such a principle ; for, while the former is a concrete experience, involving the response of the whole nature to the divine, the latter sets aside and discounts that vivid and living experience, and thus falls into an unreal abstraction. This objection really rests upon a mis- apprehension of the true character of conception. It is perfectly true that the personal consciousness of the divine can exist, and does often exist, in individuals who display very little power of theoretical reflection ; I70 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION for this is only to say that philosophy is a special enquiry, like other branches of knowledge, and demands in those who prosecute it a certain power of raising their individual experiences into universal forms. For them the conception of self or God is in one sense more abstract, and in another sense more concrete, than for the *' plain man " who is not given to reflection. It is more abstract, in so far as the idea of self or God has been made an object of exclusive and concentrated attention ; it is more concrete, because this act of abstraction has brought to light the infinity which is involved in this as in every other conception. It is the marvellous power of thought that it is able to comprehend the absolutely universal — that which applies not only to the given instance, but to every possible instance. Thus, the conception of self applies to every possible self that ever has been, is, or will be ; just as the conception of God involves the idea of a unity which embraces all possible objects, however various in their characteristics they may be. Without the activity of thought there obviously can be no philo- sophy of religion, for philosophy lives in the medium of thought. But, what is more important for our immediate purpose, without thought there can be no religion ; for, though religion cannot be resolved into thought, it necessarily includes thought ; since, whether or not it is recognized by the subject, there is no religion apart from the idea of the divine. That idea, it is true, does not in the first instance present itself in the form of a conception or universal ; but, though it may not be made an explicit object of reflection, its presence as informing the whole being is essential to the existence of the religious consciousness. Why, then, does Harnack speak as if the religious consciousness were possible without thought ? He does CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY 171 so, as I think, because he assumes that the absence of explicit conception is the same thing as the absence of conception in any sense. He sees that a man may be religious without having any definite theory of religion, and he therefore concludes that religion is possible independently of all conception. But one is entitled to ask, how there can be any consciousness of that which is higher than self for a being that is not conscious of self; and how there can be any consciousness of self without the comprehension of self as the subject of an infinite variety of possible experiences. If from the religious consciousness we eliminate all universals, and reduce it to pure feeling, there can be no consciousness of a universal self, or of God as the principle of all reality. If, on the other hand, it is admitted that the religious consciousness lives in the medium of uni- versals, to deny that religion involves conception is to remove from it that without which it cannot exist. We must, then, as it seems to me, refuse to admit that the personal experience of religion is possible apart from the universalizing and unifying activity of thought. On the other hand, the activity of thought cannot be identified with the religious consciousness in its fulness and complexity ; and it is this fact which gives force to the contention that " life is more than thought," and to the false inference that there is " life " without " thought." If we take a cross section of our personal experience at any moment, we shall find that it contains three distinguishable but inseparable elements : thought, feeling, and will. This is true of all experience, and therefore of religious experience. Hence, to identify religion with the intellectual com- prehension of the divine, thus isolating thought from feeling and will, is like breaking up an organism into parts and declaring that the disjecta membra are still 172 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION alive. Religion is the response of the whole man to what is higher than himself, and therefore it implies not only the conception of the divine, but love of it and self-surrender to it. The attempt to suppress any- one of these elements must therefore be fatal to the integrity of the whole. Harnack is especially impressed by the complex character of the religious consciousness, seeing clearly that its reduction to a mere conception destroys its essential character by removing that feeling of reverence and that active willing of the divine which are indispensable to it ; but, in his eagerness to liberate the lives of men from the burden of a "creed out- worn/' or rather overgrown, he forgets that feeling and will are just as impossible without thought as is thought without feeling and will. Wlien he contends for the independence of religion on dogma, he is so far right that religion can exist in the individual even in the absence of a definitely formulated creed ; but when he assumes that religion may exist without implying any intellectual element, he virtually affirms that it cannot be formulated, and therefore is essentially irrational. If his view were sound, it would be possible to preserve the religious consciousness while removing from it everything in the way of universal ideas ; and indeed the only legitimate conclusion would seem to be, that, as religion is altogether independent of such ideas, their removal must purge it of an adscititious element which tends to destroy its purity and power. Now, before we commit ourselves to this question- able doctrine, it is important to distinguish between what a man believes that he believes, and what he really believes. As Jowett once said, speaking of the belief in Christianity : " As there are many who say they are and are not, so may we not also say that there are many who say they are not and yet are ? " CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY 173 Socrates was condemned to death, among other things for " denying the gods of his country " ; but we should now say that for the charge of atheism should be substituted the commendation of theism. A man in our day may reject the traditional conception of the divine, because he regards it as subversive of religion, and his denial may be really equivalent to the assertion of a purified conception of it. But, while this is true, it hardly affects the problem at present under discussion, namely, whether it is possible, after penetrating behind the words in which a man's real thought may be veiled, to have a religion which does not, at least implicitly, rest upon belief in the divine. Now, it seems to me undeniable, that we cannot properly speak of religion except where there is the consciousness of something higher than the actual. It is true that in the earliest form of religion of which we have any knowledge, the belief in the divine is at once vague and fluctuating. But this only shows that the religious consciousness is at first hardly aware of what it really involves. Remove the belief in something in some sense divine, and with it the religious feeling of which it is the support dies, so that it ceases to have any influence upon me-n's lives. When primitive man's belief in the mysterious sanctity and divinity of his totem dies, he no longer worships it, but discards it as a detected sham. And at a more developed stage, with the conclusion that the gods of his fathers were creatures of his own imagination, the faith of the Greek in his national religion vanished away, and for the gods who had come to seem incredible to him he substituted a single deity, or at least a Fate, which subjected all things to its sway. Similarly, the scientific man of our own day, who is convinced that there is no such 174 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION thing as chance or supernatural interference with the inviolability of natural law, cannot believe in or worship a Being who is declared to be arbitrary and capricious, and he is therefore apt to speak of Nature, when at the basis of his faith lies the conception of a Principle in which is embodied all that may most fitly be called divine. I think, therefore, we may fairly assert that the religious consciousness, in its lowest as in its highest form, implies the belief in God. Nor is Buddhism or Comtism any real ex- ception to this law, for in both what is reverenced is not any mere assemblage of individual men, but an ideal of humanity which differs only in words from what other faiths characterize as divine. The only thing that is fatal to a religion is the conviction that it has no basis in the nature of things. The conclusion to which we have been brought is virtually endorsed by Harnack, inconsistent as it is with his attempt to reduce religion to a form of feeling ; for, though he insists, and in a certain sense rightly insists, that " the Gospel is no theoretical system of doctrine or philosophy," he yet admits that the Christian religion involves " the reality of God the Father " ; and by this admission he practically maintains that without the consciousness of the divine religion is impossible. Harnack would hardly contend that " the reality of God the Father " is in any sense doubtful ; on the contrary, it is for him the one truth upon which all religion, or at least the Christian religion, is based. Here, then, is one absolutely true judgment. But, unless we are to base this judgment upon mere authority — and I do not understand that our author takes that vitw — we must admit that in this case we have a conception which is consistent with the religious consciousness. Now, once admit CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY i75 the principle that there may be harmony between religion and theology, and we can no longer oppose the one to the other. The "Gospel," no doubt, is not a " theoretical system of doctrine or philosophy of the universe," but the record of a living personal experience ; nevertheless it must contain, in an immediate or unreflective form, ideas that may be expressed in a system ; — ideas, moreover, which in their totality must be consistent with one another, and must therefore form an organic unity. It is these ideas that a philosophy of religion has to express ; and to say that they cannot be identified with the religious experience which they seek to formulate, in no way detracts from their truth or their importance. Harnack himself reaches what he regards as the " essence " of Christianity, not by taking the Christian consciousness at any stage, even the earliest, as absolutely free from error, but only by conceiving it to contain an imperishable " kernel " of truth ; and this is at bottom identical with the aim of the philosophy of religion, as I understand it, widely as the content of that philosophy may differ from the bare residuum with which he identifies it. It would thus seem that if we follow out to its logical consequences the admission, almost inadvertently made by our author, that Christianity presupposes the truth of the doctrine that " God is Father," we cannot assent to his thesis, that the Gospel and Theology are inharmonious ; rather we must grant that in a sense Theology, or the Philosophy of Religion, is the inevitable development of the Gospel. This point is so important that it will repay us to consider some- what more closely what is involved in the assertion that " the reality of God the Father " is the " essence " of " the Gospel." 176 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION It can hardly be maintained that the predicate " Father," as applied to God, is to be taken in a baldly- literal sense. Like much of our language, the term involves a metaphor, though no doubt a metaphor which has the large suggestiveness of all apt literary expression. It must of course be admitted that, in its direct or immediate form, the religious consciousness shrinks from any attempt to enquire too curiously into the precise meaning of such a term, as if it were a sort of profanation ; but, natural as this feeling is, the more reflective minds of our age are simply unable to remain permanently satisfied with terms that have not been precisely defined. What, then, are we to understand by the proposition that " God is Father " ? After the somewhat laborious investigations of former lectures we may assume that by the term " God " is meant at least the Being from whom all proceeds and to whom all tends ; and that the predicate " Father " implies that we are related to this Being as free self-conscious spirits to the universal Spirit, in union with whom alone our nature is capable of being realized. This con- ception of God may be, and has been, denied ; but it cannot be consistently denied by one who, like Professor Harnack, regards the reality of God as inseparable from the religious consciousness. Now, if it is admitted that religion involves the objective existence of God, it is impossible at the same time to deny that it implicitly contains a " theoretical system of doctrine or philosophy of the universe." If we are to give any precise meaning to what is called the belief in " the reality of God the Father," we must grant that the ultimate principle of the universe is a self-manifesting Spirit, and that man is identical in nature with God ; and it is merely playing with words to deny that this involves a " theoretical CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY 177 system of doctrine or philosophy of the universe." No doubt it may still be denied that reason can evolve such a " system " out of itself, and on this ground it may be argued that we must base the reality of God upon a supernatural revelation. But the supposition that reason can evolve anything " out of itself,"^ i.e, in absolute independence of experience, is a fallacy hardly worthy of refutation ; while the attempt to base religion upon authority is, as we have seen, essentially suicidal, besides being inconsistent with Harnack's own view of the self-evidencing character of the religious conscious- ness. Human experience is essentially rational, and may be shown to be such ; but any attempt to derive its content from abstract conceptions must end in failure, just as no revelation is possible that does not appeal to the experience of the race. What we must hold then is, that the religious consciousness, in its most com- prehensive sense, involves a rational system ; which, when it is expressly formulated by reason, yields a philosophy of religion ; or, to keep more closely to Harnack's point of view, that in the Christian con- sciousness is imbedded a conception of the universe which may be developed into a Christian philosophy of religion. Perhaps enough has been said to show that Harnack cannot consistently admit the "doctrine" of the "reality of God the Father" without abandoning his thesis, that theology does not deal with the " essence '' of Christianity, but only with the temporary and evanescent forms assumed by it in self-defence. The more closely we examine into the reasons he advances for setting up an opposition between religion and philosophy, the more does it become manifest that he is continually contradicting himself. Nor is this due to any want of skill on his part, but to the 178 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION fundamental contradiction inseparable from his main thesis. The task he has set himself, as he tells us, is to solve the problem, What is the Christian religion? and to solve it from purely historical data. At first sight it may seem, as he goes on to say, that the Christian religion is the religion announced by its Founder, and thus the problem apparently narrows itself down to an enquiry into the life and sayings of Jesus Christ, as recorded in the Gospels, together with a few items gathered from the writings of St. Paul and other sources. And when we speak of the Gospels in this connection, we mean only the synoptic Gospels ; for " the fourth Gospel was not written, nor does it claim to be written, by the Apostle John." We cannot, however, really confine ourselves to Jesus and his Gospel, " because every great and powerful personality reveals a part of what it is only when seen in those whom it influences." Nor can we stop even " with the first generation of Jesus' disciples " ; but " we must include all the later products of its spirit." Our author denies, however, that " the question is of a 'doctrine' being handed down by uniform tradition or arbitrarily distorted : it is a question of a life^ again and again kindled afresh, and now burning with a flame of its own." The business of the historian is to " determine what is of permanent value " ; so that he " must not cleave to words," but " find out what is essential." " What is common to all the forms which the Christian idea has taken, corrected by reference to the Gospel, and, conversely, the chief features of the Gospel, corrected by reference to history, will . . . bring us to the kernel of the matter."^ Now, there is one obvious objection to this position. Not to insist upon the difficulty of separating what ^Hamack's What is Christianity? pp. 10-15. CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY 179 may with certainty be attributed to Jesus himself from what is due to the interpretation, or misinterpretation, of his disciples, it is hard to see how, by a purely historical investigation, we are to determine wherein the " essence " of Christianity consists. Suppose it to be granted, in the most unequivocal way, that we know precisely what was held by Jesus, and what was introduced by his followers ; how can we in this way reach the "kernel of the matter"? If indeed our author held that the Gospel was identical with what was taught by Jesus himself, and that all changes in it are to be viewed as distortions of its purity, one might admit that the problem was a " purely historical " one. But Harnack does not take that view. " Jesus Christ and his disciples," as he tells us, "were situated in their day just as we are situated in ours ; that is to say, their feelings, their thoughts, their judgments and their efforts were bounded by the horizon and the framework in which their own nation was set and by its condition at the time."^ For example, " there can be no doubt about the fact that the idea of the two kingdoms, of God and of the devil, and their conflicts, was an idea which Jesus simply shared with his contemporaries."^ Hence "the historian's task of dis- tinguishing between what is traditional and what is peculiar, between kernel and husk, in Jesus* message of the kingdom of God is a difficult and responsible one."^ How, then, one naturally asks, is the historian to accomplish this " difficult and responsible " task ? Without insisting upon the literal meaning of the term, may we not say that it is the business of the historian to tell us in this case, what, as a matter of fact, Jesus actually taught, not to determine how much of his ^ Harnack*s What is Christianity? p. 12. •^Ibid., p. 54. ^Ibid,, p. 55. i8o PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION teaching is permanent ? When we go on to ask how much is permanent and how much transitory, we enter upon an investigation that leads us very far beyond the proper problem of the historian. If with Harnack we regard all doctrine as excluded from the "essence" of Christianity, we shall no doubt limit Christianity as he does ; but, on the other hand, if we hold that Christianity is not merely a personal faith, but contains a revelation of the ultimate nature of things, our view of what is " essential " will differ very much from his. On what ground does Harnack exclude that part of Jesus' teaching which he claims to have been common to Jesus with others of his age and country? Is it not on the ground that the subsequent history of the race proved that this part was not consistent with fact ? The kingdom of heaven did not come in a few years, and indeed our author would not admit that it will ever come, in the literal sense which he ascribes to Jesus and his disciples. Is it not obvious, then, that his real reason for reject- ing this part of what he regards as the teaching of Jesus is that the subsequent development of knowledge has made it incredible? If, therefore, a distinction is to be drawn between the permanent and the temporary element in the teaching of Jesus, as Harnack main- tains, must it not be on the ground that the former is in harmony with the nature of things, while the latter is not ? In other words, the permanent element in the teaching of Jesus must be held to command our assent, not because it has the impress of his authority — for if so, all that he taught would be equally authoritative — but because it is true. The point I wish to make, as you will observe, is not that we are to identify Christianity with the form in which it is maintained to have been originally CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY i8i expressed, but that a purely historical investigation can bring us no further. So far as the historian goes, his task is done when he has told us what he believes Jesus as a matter of fact to have actually held : as a historian he cannot tell us whether the teaching of Jesus, as a whole or in part, was true or false. The moment we ask whether, or how far, the teaching is true, we enter upon an enquiry which can only be solved by a complete philosophy of religion. There is another point. Harnack seeks for the " essence " of religion in a permanent nucleus of reli- gious feeling, first experienced by Jesus, and subse- quently reproduced in the experience of every one of his followers. Now, as has been already pointed out, it may be admitted that, if we are speaking of religion, as distinguished from theology, there is a certain amount of truth in this contention. Every religious man experi- ences the uplifting power of the divine, and in that sense it may be said that religion is unchangeable. But, after all, this is a partial or abstract view. For, though there is an identical element in the religious consciousness of all Christians, in none, as Harnack himself admits, is it absolutely the same. Even the least reflective man has some way of construing life, and his religious experience is not separable from this construction. But what is of main importance here, each man participates in the ideas of his time, and as these again are only made possible by the whole previous experience of the race, he may well be under the influence of ideas of which he can give no definite account. Such ideas have not fallen from heaven : they first arose in the consciousness of some man of genius, or they have been won by the long and severe toil of many. It is impossible, for example, that a religious man, who at the same time shares in the main 1 82 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION ideas of our age, should believe in religious cataclysms ; for our whole view of things is so permeated by the idea of development, that even when we can give no account of our religious beliefs, or at best a slip-shod and confused account, we instinctively reject any expla- nation of their origin which cuts them off from the past. Now, it is curious that Professor Harnack should virtu- ally ignore this side of things. He regards religion, almost from the point of view of a pre-evolutionist age, as a permanent and unchanging kernel, enclosed in an external husk of doctrines, the value of which consists, not in its truth, but in its fitness to preserve the truth from injury or destruction. The husk is perpetually changing and decaying, while the kernel remains always the same. Such a view cannot be r^arded as final. If it were true, we should have to maintain that there is an imperishable and unchanging nucleus of religion which is common to the lowest and the highest forms of the religious consciousness. Thus Christianity would in no way differ on its personal side from the crassest animism. The real truth is that both religion and theology have developed, and on the whole developed pari passu. Man does not stand still in part and in part develop : when he changes his whole being changes. No doubt this or that element of his nature may receive temporary emphasis, but, in the long course of history, all the elements advance together. It is, therefore, a mistake to look for the " essence " of Christianity in any unchanging " kernel " : its real " essence " is to be sought in its living power of self-development. It is a natural parallax which leads us to imagine that we can discover the real nature of Christianity by enquiring into its primitive form, and comparing this form with its latest expression. The element of truth in this view is, that we are often enabled to separate the CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY 183 adventitious elements which attach to a principle by going back to its beginnings and tracing the process by which it has developed, A principle, on its first enunciation, may be said to embrace in confused fulness more than can be formulated at any stage short of the last ; which virtually means more than can ever be worked out into absolute clearness and definiteness. The truth, however, is that this fulness is to the origi- nator of the idea merely implicit, and that without the subsequent development it would not have for us the significance which it actually has. The meaning of Christianity is best discovered by asking what influence it has had in successive periods of human history, and what is its influence to-day. Every age has its own problems ; and though in a sense we inherit all the problems of the past, yet the process of evolution has prepared for us the special problem which it is our task to solve. Our problem seems to me to be this : to deter- mine the form which the principle of Christianity must take in view of the present state of science, art, morality, and social organization. To evade the complexity of the problem, as Harnack does, by setting up a half- mythical " essence " of Christianity, will not satisfy a critical age like ours. At the same time, I should not for a moment undervalue the important work which our author has done in throwing light upon the history of religious thought : what I deprecate is his attempt, under the guise of a historical problem, to withdraw religion from the realm of philosophical criticism. It is vain to deny the force of Kant's remark, that *' when religion seeks to shelter itself behind its sanctity, it justly awakens suspicion against itself, and loses its claim to the sincere respect which reason yields only to that which has been able to bear the test of its free and open scrutiny." 1 84 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION Pefhaps the view I have been trying to indicate may- be made clearer by a consideration of Harnack's picture of the early history of Christianity. In a passage already quoted he tells us that " Jesus Christ and his disciples were situated in their day just as we are situated in ours ; that is to say, their feelings, their thoughts, their judgments, and their efforts were bounded by the horizon and the framework in which their own nation was set and by its condition at the time," The " Kingdom of God " was for Jesus, on the one hand, a future Apocalyptic reign of God on earth, and, on the other hand, a purely spiritual regeneration, already begun in the hearts of believers ; and between these two poles his thoughts and feelings revolved. "Jesus, like all those of his own nation who were really in earnest, was profoundly conscious of the great anti- thesis between the kingdom of God and that kingdom of the world in which he saw the reign of evil and the evil one. . . . He was certain that the kingdom of the world must perish and be destroyed." There must, therefore, be a battle. But the triumph of the kingdom of God was assured and imminent, and when it should come Jesus saw himself " seated at the right hand of his Father, and his twelve disciples on thrones judging the twelve tribes of Israel ; so objective was this picture to him, so completely in harmony with the ideas of his time." But while Jesus undoubtedly shared with his contemporaries this idea of the two kingdoms of God and the devil, of their conflicts and of the future last conflict, in which the devil, after having long before been driven out of heaven, will be finally overcome on earth, it is a great mistake to look upon this idea as the main import of his teaching : what was really characteristic was the other view, that the kingdom of God " cometh not with observation," that it is CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY 185 already here. The parables show that " the kingdom of God comes by coming to the individual, by entering into his soul and laying hold of it True, the kingdom of God is the rule of God ; but it is the rule of the holy God in the hearts of individuals : it is God him- self in his power. From this point of v'l^v^ everything that is dramatic in the external and historical sense has vanished."^ This view of the consciousness of Jesus is shared by critics who do not sympathize with Harnack's con- ception of theology. Thus his colleague, Professor Pfleiderer, says : ** Jesus undeniably shared the Apo- calyptic belief of his time of the near end of the present age of the world, aind the dawn of a new supernatural age (a/a)i/ o^to^^ amv /neWoov) ; and to this eschatological supernaturalism logically corresponded his ethical super- naturalism — that is, the ascetic requirement of the not merely internal, but also external, renunciation of all that belongs to the present age, of goods and chattels, of family and calling, of friendship and fatherland."* Without attempting to determine upon the historical accuracy of the contention that Jesus presented his gospel in the form of the Apocalyptic belief of his time, we have to ask whether this belief must be regarded as inseparable from Christianity. Harnack, as we have seen, answers in the negative, maintaining that Christianity consists in what was characteristic of the teaching of Jesus, not in what he shared in common with his contemporaries. Now, while we must grant that Christianity cannot be identified with what is held by some thinkers to have been its first form, in which it included the belief in "a new supernatural age" (to use Pfleiderer's words), ^Harnack's What is Christianity? pp. 53-56. ^Pfleiderer's Philosophy and Development of Religion, ii. pp. 101-2. 1 86 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION we cannot admit that it may be identified with an immediate feeling in the soul of the individual. We can no longer accept the idea of *' a new supernatural age," because the actual course of history has shown that the belief in the near end of the world and the dawn of " a new supernatural age " was not realized ; and, still more, just because the recognition of the spiritual nature of the kingdom of God is one of the most assured results of the long toil of the Chris- tian centuries. But while this is true, it seems to me none the less true, that Christianity cannot be separated from the total conception of things which experience and reflection compel us to adopt. If its truth were dependent upon the form in which it is believed by Harnack to have been first enunciated, there would be no alternative for us of these latter days but to reject it as obsolete and incredible. For, nothing is more certain than that no form of religion which is based upon an interruption of the regular course of nature is now credible. Hence Christianity, if it is to survive, must be compatible with the fullest recognition of the reign of law. It is thus obvious that the form which it assumes in our day cannot possibly be identical with what is maintained to have been its primitive form : in other words, that it must be regarded as participating in that process of evolution which applies to the whole history of man. On the other hand, the history of religion cannot be a mere succession of disconnected changes ; there must be some permanent element which guarantees its con- tinuity. Nor can this element be viewed as simply something which in all changes remains the same : a dead cold identity with no principle of life in it ; it must be that which maintains itself in and through change. Now, if we wish to tell what in any case CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY 187 a living principle is, we must look to the end as well as to the beginning. " The child is father of the man/' as Wordsworth says ; but what the child is can only be learned by looking at the man, and viewing the child in the light of what is thus revealed. Similarly, if we wish to learn what Christianity is, we must ask what it is now, after the lapse of nineteen centuries, and only th^i can we tell what was wrapped up in its first form. Moreover, the Christianity of our day must be consistent with the highest products of reflection. We cannot now adopt in reference to it a view of history which has been exploded in other spheres ; we cannot believe that there are cataclysms in the realm of spirit, any more than in the realm of nature. There are no breaks in the life of humanity any more than in the external world. Therefore, the kingdom of heaven must consist in the development of goodness in and through the ordinary processes by which man is ever realizing his ideals. And this spiritual development is not some- thing which goes on in isolation, having no relation to the other phases of human life, but must be the higher spirit of the whole process. Hence, just as there was a primitive view of human history and of nature, so there is a modern view which Christianity must incorporate on pain of extinction. Is such an incorporation possible? I believe it is, if we only distinguish, as we ought to do, between a set of specific beliefs and a living principle. The specific beliefs of the first age of Christianity have necessarily passed away, and become incredible ; and they have done so, because they represented an early phase in the history of humanity. But, though they are no longer credible in their original form, the principle which animated them is not dead. Religion is not something accidental to man, but something 1 88 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION inseparable from his rational life. It is that undying and. inextinguishable faith in the divine, the denial of which is ultimately the destruction of all other beliefs. The Christian religion must therefore base its claim to acceptance upon its power of inspiring and satisfying this fundamental need of humanity. Now, when we direct our attention to the teaching' of Jesus as set forth in the Gospels, we find in it, besides the Apocalyptic belief in the dawn of a supernatural age, a belief in God as love and in the principle that the key to all conduct is, " Die to live." These two beliefs are inseparably intertwined, so that to deny either is to deny both. But surely we may admit, that, fundamental and absolute as they are, they yet stand in need of further definition. The teaching of Jesus was based upon his direct intuitions, not upon a process of scientific ratiocination ; and while these may fairly claim to rest upon a foundation that cannot be shaken, it is only by the whole teaching of experience, and by the combined labours - of the race, that they can yield up the whole of their meaning. In this process there is no doubt a certain danger : the danger that the reflective formulation should miss their full meaning, or should be regarded as a substitute for personal experience of their power. This, however, is a danger which not only cannot be avoided, but the avoidance of which would impoverish religious experience itself. Hence, instead of taking refuge from doubt in the undeveloped intuitions of Jesus, as Harnack does, we must in these days, if we are to place our faith in Christianity on impregnable grounds, develop them in the light of the best thought of our day into a full and complete system, which shall ignore no established result of science and no lesson of history. CHRISTIANITY AND HISTORY 189 For the Apocalyptic view, which critics tell us Jesus shared with his contemporaries, we must substitute a fully reasoned system or philosophy of religion. So only can we hope to retain our faith without doing violence to our reason, and our reason without sacrifice of our faith. LECTURE EIGHTH PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT In my last lecture, Harnack's "What is Christianity?" was taken as an instance of the doctrine which attaches pre-eminent importance to the personal aspect of religion. Since the days of Schleiermacher there has been an influential school of theologians who have sought to escape from the cramping influence of the traditional creed by making a fresh appeal to the religious experience of the individual. To this school belonged Ritschl, who may be regarded as the teacher of Harnack. It is held by the latter that " the Christian religion is something simple and sublime ; it means one thing and one thing only : Eternal life in the midst of time by the strength and under the eyes of God." The essence of all religion is to be found in Jesus Christ and his Gospel, though we must also listen to the first generation of his disciples, and take account of the rekindling again and again of the spiritual life which has burned in all his followers. Religion is not a matter of doctrine, but a life ; and " life cannot be spanned by general conceptions." The business of the historian is to find out what is common to all the forms which the Christian ideas have taken, corrected by reference to the Gospel, and conversely the chief PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT 191 features of the Gospel, corrected by reference to history. Thus we may recover the divine lineaments of Christianity, and find in it nourishment for our higher life. The Gospel consists in the glad tidings of the Kingdom of God as present here and now ; of God the Father and the infinite value of the human soul to Him and to itself; of the higher righteousness and the new commandment of love. In those truths is contained the whole of Christianity, while the history of Dogma is a record of the progressive obscuration of the truth by Hellenic philosophy and other " secu- larizing" influences. What lends force to this view of Harnack is the undeniable distinction between religion and theology or the philosophy of religion. But though religion is not philosophy, it does not follow either that it can exist without all "general conceptions" or that philosophy must distort or annihilate it. A being of pure intellect is no doubt a fiction, but so also is a religious being who is merely sentient. If it is said that the consciousness of God as Father is a concrete experience, while thought works with abstractions, the answer is that in one sense the conception of God is more concrete than the ordinary consciousness of God, because the former explicitly embraces all possible reality within itself, whereas the latter represents Him in a pictorial way and therefore as finite. Harnack's mistake is to identify the absence of explicit conception in the religious consciousness with the absence of all con- ception. On the other hand, religion cannot be identified with the intellectual comprehension of the divine, because, as a response of the whole man, it involves the indissoluble union of thought, feeling, and will. This is what gives plausibility to the conten- tion that religion may exist independently of all 192 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION conceptions ; a view which, if it were sound, would put the lowest form of religion on the same level as the highest When we penetrate to man's real beliefs, it becomes evident that the minimum of religion is faith in the divine, and such a faith is possible only to one who conceives of the universe as rational. This is virtually admitted by Harnack himself when he holds that belief in the Fatherhood of God and the sonship of man is the essence of Christianity. We cannot, however, grant that there is an unr changeable " kernel " of religion : for, as man develops, his whole nature develops, and therefore the religious consciousness becomes ever more complex. While its principle is no doubt ever the same, it is not a dead unchanging identity, but continually grows by the very energy which enables it to assimilate new forms of experience. In order to exhibit this process in its actual operation, I propose, in the present and the following lecture, to consider the relation of Philo to the writers of the New Testament, and in two subsequent lectures to indicate the struggle of the principle of Christianity with Greek philosophy, as represented by the Gnostics ; following up these studies with a statement of the phases of faith through which Augustine passed and a critical estimate of his theology ; continuing with a short consideration of medieval theology, as embodied in the teachings of Thomas Aquinas ; and ending with a statement and criticism of Leibnitz as an exponent of Protestant Theology. This historical course will bring us back to the point from which we started in our third lecture, and prepare the way for a final determination, in the two last lectures, of the relations of God, the world and man, as conceived by the form of Idealism advocated in these pages. PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT 193 How far, if at all, can the method and the ideas of Philo be said to have influenced the New Testament ? Both of these questions are surrounded with difficulty. Philo is not a pure philosopher of the type of Plato and Aristotle : he does not attempt to construct a system of thought on the basis of reason, but starts from certain preconceptions, which determine the character of his thought. Nor has he elaborated a philosophical system of his own, after a critical in- vestigation of the doctrines of his predecessors, but has taken from them whatever ideas seemed to fit in with his general conception of things. The result is that he presents us with an eclectic philosophy, which rather contains a number of suggestions that, after much critical labour, might be developed into a system, . than what can be called a philosophy. It might, perhaps, be said that Philo, in thus sitting loose to any hard and fast system, is only exhibiting the true philosophical temper, which refuses to admit that any given doctrine sums up the whole body of truth, and that he is to be commended, instead of condepined, for his contempt of system-mongering. The defence seems to me to be based upon a misunderstanding of the true function of philosophy. If we compare the method of Philo with one of the great masters of speculation, we shall see that his eclecticism is a mark, not of strength, but of weakness. Aristotle, for example, everywhere shows an accurate acquaintance with the thought of his predecessors and contem- poraries. It is his custom to begin the discussion of any topic by citing the current views in regard to it, and then going on to consider the doctrines of the philosophers. This method he follows under the conviction that no belief has been held by man that does not contain some rational element which has 194 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION commended it to the minds of those who held it. But Aristotle is also convinced that those views are only partial aspects of a more comprehensive truth ; and therefore he makes it his main point to discover what that truth is. This is not the method of Philo. He starts with the assumption that Moses, whom he assumes to have been the author of the Pentateuch, was the possessor of all truth ; and, under this preconception, he proceeds to find in the words of Moses whatever truth he seems to have discovered from any source. The result of course is that he is forced to read into scripture a meaning which it does not possess, so that its plain and simple sense is overlaid with the ideas of his own time. Similarly, he reads the Greek philosophers, not with the object of finding out what they really meant, or of discovering the element of truth which they had grasped, but as witnesses for ideas which belonged to the age in which he lived. Thus, Philo never comes into direct contact with the minds of sacred or profane writers at all, but approaches them with a priori conceptions of what they ought to have said. Of course this criticism is not meant as a charge against Philo : he was simply following the method of his time, and could not do otherwise ; but, in attempting to determine his personal value and influence, we have to bear in mind the character of his mind and the limitations of his age. Especially, in attempting to estimate his influence upon Christian thought, we must have a perfectly clear idea of the fundamental defect of his method. Christian writers of the early centuries borrowed the method of Philo, and even in our own day there are theologians who have not shaken off its influence. When we come to enquire whether Philo has PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT 195 influenced the writers of the New Testament, a problem of great difficulty immediately presents itself The influence of one writer upon another cannot be directly inferred from the use of common terms, or a similarity of ideas or expressions. For, two writers may be entirely independent of each other, and may yet express themselves in an almost identical way. Thera are terms and ideas which belong to the atmosphere of an age ; they have come, no one knows whence, and have become the symbols of current modes of thought. We do not, for example, prove that the writer of the fourth Gospel borrowed from Philo, because both speak of the Aoyo? as a manifestation of God. We are safe in saying that the term belonged to the age, but not that the one writer borrowed from the other. For- tunately, the question is of less importance than some writers seem to imagine. Suppose it were proved that St. John adopted the term Aoyo? from Philo, and was even influenced by Philo's doctrine of the Aoyos, the main point is whether both writers attach the same meaning to the term. As we shall see^ this is by no means the case ; and, though historical curiosity would fain be satisfied, in the development of ideas the question is of very subordinate interest. No one will now maintain that the truth of the A6yo9 doctrine as held by St. John is dependent upon the writer not having been influenced by Philo ; for, however he may have been influenced, he employed it to formulate a new idea, which came into the world only with Christianity. I have mentioned two difficulties which confront any one who seeks to explain the doctrine of Philo and to estimate his influence. There is another difficulty, which arises from the general character of human progress, Philo presupposes two independent lines of 196 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION development, the Jewish and the Greek. He is thus connected, on the one hand with Jewish, and on the other hand with Greek thought, and it is impossible to understand him fully without some reference to both. Now, it is obviously impossible to treat fully of either ; and the most that I can pretend to do is to indicate, as we proceed, the relation of particular ideas to these two lines of development Without more preamble, I shall attempt to convey some idea of part of Philo's De Mundi Opificio^ as the handiest way of getting an insight into the circle of ideas within which this expositor of Hellenistic Judaism lived and moved.^ Philo begins his treatise on the " Creation of the World " by drawing a strong contrast between Moses and other legislators. The first thing to be observed is Philo's belief that the Mosaic writings contain a complete revelation of God, and are absolutely true even in the most minute particular. The Law of Moses is therefore unchangeable and eternal, and will remain as long as the sun and moon and the universe endure. Nor is it merely the Hebrew scriptures which are thus inspired, but the same authority attaches to the Septuagint. No scribe of the straitest sect of the Pharisees had a more implicit faith than Philo in the inspiration of every word and even letter of scripture. Since the Mosaic writings, on his view, contain a final revelation of the nature of God and His relation to the world, it follows that they contain all truth, and hence that whatever is true can be extracted from a careful consideration of what they affirm. The distinction between religious and scientific truth, which ^The exposition which follows should be compared with the ''Extracts from Philo " contained in the Appendix at the end of the volume. PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT 197 many liberal theologians now make, was one which did not occur to Philo, and which, if it had been presented to him, he would have summarily rejected as impious. As the passage just referred to shows, it is precisely the " philosophical " character of the Mosaic writings which, in his view, constitutes their superiority to all other writings. For Philo the Pentateuch is not merely an expression of the religious consciousness, but a philosophical system, in which each part is set forth with a view to the other parts ; in other words, the Bible is not merely a record of religious experience, but a theology. In Philo's hands, in fact, it becomes almost entirely a theology, even the narrative parts being regarded as part of a system of general con- ceptions. With this method of dealing with Scripture we are only too familiar, and it was mainly through Philo's example and influence that it became the favourite method of Christian writers, and has survived down to our own day. The first class of legislators contrasted with Moses are those who simply state ethical principles without showing the basis upon which they depend. We may express Philo's meaning by saying that morality must be based upon religion. When moral precepts are laid down without being shown to flow from the relation of God to the world, and especially to man, it is not seen that the rational nature of man demands something more than external commands. It is for this reason, he holds, that Moses begins by revealing the nature of God, and thus prepares the minds of men for a joyous obedience to the laws. The second class of lawgivers are those who do, indeed, attempt to exhibit the divine nature, but distort it by the invention of myths, which give a false idea of God. To Philo a myth is simply a deliberate attempt 198 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION to impose upon the credulous masses. It is significant that Philo, while he here supposes that he is following his favourite philosopher, Plato, in reality .displays a different spirit. To Plato, and even more to Aristotle, a myth was a " noble lie " : it was the first attempt of the human mind to grasp the divine nature; and though Plato criticises the myths of his country, he is willing to allow that myths may be made an important in- strument in the education of the young. Aristotle, again, finds in mythology an implicit philosophy ; so that the mythologist, as he says, is in a sense a philosopher.^ Philo has not this wide range of sympathy. As a Jew he can see in the myths of polytheistic religions nothing but a false representation of the one invisible God. If it is asked how Philo, familiar as he was with the anthropomorphic repre- sentation of God found in the Pentateuch, was not able to find an element of truth in Greek and Oriental mythologies, the answer is that he spiritualized these sayings, and thus eliminated from them the obnoxious element. He therefore distinguishes between allegory and mythology. He admits that, in the Pentateuch, there are things " more incredible than myths " [De Mose, iii. 691); but the incredibility arises from inter- preting literally what was meant by the writer to be understood in an allegorical sense. To suppose that God really planted fruit trees in Paradise, when no one was allowed to live there, and when it would be impious to fancy that He required them for Himself, is " great and incurable silliness." The reference must, therefore, be to the paradise of virtues, with their appro- priate actions, implanted by God in the soul [De Plan. NoCy 8. 9). The objections of cavillers are set aside by a similar process. There are those who sneer "^ Metaphysics f A 2, 982* 18 : 6 199jj3 Xq p9;B9JD 9j9qdsoiu;B |Bn;tJids gq; 9q;B9jq :^U91iib;s9jl M9^ gq:^ jo sj9;iJM 9qjL -sSupuAV ;u9uib:js9J^ av9^ |Bdpuud 9q:^ jo JOU pdsof) 9q; jo uopisoddns9jd gq; lujoj J9q;pu sBgpi 5J99JQ o'lfpdfs ;Bq4 *;u9piAg SB ;snf si '\\ *puBq jgq;o gq; uo *;ng '9DU9n0UT uSpjoj Xub Xq pg^Dg^B Xbm ou ui si qoiqM uisTBpnf jo pnpojd gAisnpxg ub sb :ji pjBSgj 9m SB %v.o\ OS *giqiSttp;uiun X[|BOTJo;siq si jps^i pdsog gq; ;Bq; 'Xbs ugAg Xbui g^ -^uguiB^sgjL PIO ^H^ J° "o?^ -BisuBj; jfggjr) gq; jo gsn gq; Xq uMoqs si siq; ^pggpuj '4SB3 gqa JO SuTZTugipfj gq; uiojj pg;|nsgj -qoiqM gjni^pD IBjgugS puB ;qSnoq; jo gpoui gq; jo gougnyui gq; XBj;gq NOionsH ^o sisva ^VOIHJOSOTIHJ 9^^ PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT 237 it was a conscious rejection of the Philonic con- ception of the \6yo^. But, in other writings, as e,g. the epistles of St. Paul and St, James and the epistle to the Hebrews, the antagonism is none the less marked because it is less conscious. The really important result of a comparison of Philo and the New Testament is, therefore, that it enables us to see more clearly the unique character of Christianity, and to separate from it the accidents of its expression, whether these were due to modes of thought predominantly Jewish or predominantly Greek. The spirit of Chris- tianity is certainly not dependent upon the earthen vessel in which it was contained. On the other hand, it would be a grave mistake to assume that we can remove from Christianity all the elements which may be called theological, and narrow it down to simple faith in the Lord Jesus. Simple faith in the Lord Jesus is no doubt all that is essential to individual salvation ; but it is not all that is essential to the regeneration of the world. The teaching of our Lord contained implicitly a complete system of theology ; and when St. Paul and the New Testament writers sought to set forth this system explicitly, they were only seeking to supply a fundamental need of the human spirit. The question rather is, whether the first form in which the system of ideas which the Master expressed in all their freshness and living force was not unduly narrowed by the want of categories adequate to express it. There is, indeed, no opposition between the New Testament writers and the Master, but there is undoubtedly a difference in the mode of statement; and it is a very narrow and indefensible view which would insist that we are bound by the form of the disciples and may neglect the larger truth of the Master. Let us, then, begin by a comparison of St. Paul and Philo. 238 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION " The centre of all St. Paul's life and thought," as Harnack says, " was his absolute faith that Christ had revealed himself to him, that the Gospel was the revelation of the crucified and risen Christ, and that God had called him to proclaim this Gospel to the world. Those three ideas were in the consciousness of the Apostle absolutely inseparable from one another. If Christ had not revealed himself to him, there was no foundation for his faith ; if the Gospel was not the revelation of the crucified and risen Christ, there was no new revelation ; and if he had not himself become the medium of this new revelation he had no call to pro- claim the Gospel to others. In this new consciousness consisted his conversion, and his whole life was deter- mined by it. In this faith he was conscious of having undergone a complete revolution in his whole being. His attitude towards others was therefore completely changed. He was no longer a Jew, but a ' new man in Christ Jesus,' and therefore all men, Jews and Gentiles alike, were related to one another and to God in an identical way. That being so, his mission was to lead the Jew beyond the limits of Judaism, and to bring the Gentile to a consciousness of his true relation to God and his fellow-men. The crucified and risen Christ was not only the central principle of his theology, but the ruling principle in his hfe and thought. The Christ was not the man, Jesus of Nazareth, who had been exalted by God to a position beyond that of ordinary humanity, but the mighty personal spiritual being, who had humiliated Himself for a time, and had destroyed the world of the Law, of sin and of death, and who as spirit worked in the souls of believers. Hence for him theology was the doctrine of the liberating power of the spirit of Christ, operative in all the concrete relations of human life and of human need. The Christ PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT 239 who has overcome the law, sin and death, lives as spirit and through His spirit in believers, who therefore do not know Him according to the flesh. He is a creative power of life for those who from faith in His saving death on the cross allow Him to work in their souls, i.e. to be justified. Life in the spirit, which is the result of union with Christ, will at last reveal itself also in the body, not in the flesh. Looking back at the past, St. Paul regarded theology as the doctrine of the abolition of the Law. He therefore views the old in the light of the Gospel, maintaining that it has been done away by Christ. Hence the proofs from scripture are merely introduced in support of his inner convictions. These revolve around the idea, that the true meaning of the Law, of sin and of death is only revealed in their abolition. By the Law the Law is destroyed, in sinful flesh sin is overcome, through death death is conquered. " The historical view of St. Paul is set forth in the relation of Christ to Adam and Abraham, and to the Law of Moses ; it looks forward to the time, when God shall be all in all, after Christ has * put all things under his feet ' ; and to a time when the prophecies given to the Jewish people shall be fulfilled in the salvation of all Israel. The doctrine of Christ in St. Paul starts from the confession of the primitive church, that Christ as a heavenly being and as Lord of the living and the dead is with the Father. His theology does not rest upon the historical Christ, but upon the pre-existent Christ, the ' man from heaven,' who in self-denying love made Himself flesh, in order to destroy the power of nature and death ; but he refers to the works and the life of the historical Christ as the pattern for all men of life in the spirit. "In controverting Christian opponents^ who sought to 240 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION combine the gospel of the crucified Christ with the belief in * righteousness by works/ St. Paul makes use of argu- ments and even of ideas borrowed from the Pharisaic theology; and he employs the exegetical method practised by Pharisaic theologians, as well as by Alexandrian writers. But the dialectic in regard to the law, cir- cumcision and sacrifice does not form the central source of his inspiration, but is merely the outer body of his doctrine. St Paul is the highest product of the Jewish spirit as transformed by the creative power of the spirit of Christ Pharisaism had fulfilled its mission in producing a man of this type, and was henceforth dead. In a measure St Paul shares the Hellenic spirit, but this spirit he imbibed, not from the direct influence of Hellenic writers, but from his Phari- saic training. In his mission to the Gentiles he had the advantage of an intimate acquaintance with the Greek translation of the Old Testament, considerable skill in handling the Greek tongue, and an insight into the spiritual life of the Greeks. His great power, how- ever, lay in his gospel of the spiritual Christ This gospel he could express in modes of thought compre- hensible by the Greek mind. In his Apologetics he even turns to his purposes the philosophical doctrines of the Greeks, though it cannot be shown that he had a direct acquaintance with Greek literature and philo- sophy. Thus he prepares the way for the diffusion of the Gospel in the Greek and Roman world. But this in no way affects his central doctrine of salvation, which was neither Jewish nor Gentile, but universal." ^ Now, when we consider that the centre of all St Paul's ideas is faith in the crucified and risen Christ, we see at once that his whole conception of life differs from that of Philo. Both, indeed, speak of the ^Harnack's Dogmengesckichte, i. 89-91. PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT 241 ^* heavenly man," but their point of view is diametri- cally opposite. The " heavenly man " of Philo is not a person, but an abstract archetype: it is the divine pattern in the divine mind after which individual men are formed. But this archetype could never possibly be realised in any individual man. St Paul, on the other hand, finds in the crucified and risen Christ, the manifestation of the Son of God. Whereas Philo's ^* Son of God " is merely the divine mind in operation, St. Paul finds in Christ the true Son of God, who humbled himself by appearing in the flesh, and who thereby revealed the innermost nature of God. Whereas in Philo God remains in His own nature absolutely inscrutable, St. Paul sees in the crucified and risen Christ the manifestation of the infinite love of God. This is no mere superficial distinction : it is the funda- mental note of Christianity, which distinguishes it from all other religions. And as St. Paul's conception of the Son of God differs toto coelo from Philo's, so his conception of salvation is fundamentally different. The salvation of man for Philo was conceived to lie in the illumination of the mind by a philosophical conception of God, and obedience to the law of reason. Thus, it was the narrow way open only to the cultured few. St. Paul's way of salvation was open to all. No distinction of Jew or Gentile, cultured or uncul- tured, free man or slave, could separate a man from union with God through the indwelling of the Spirit of Christ in him. Philo no doubt liberated himself from the prepossession that only the Jew was capable of salvation, but he only got rid of this national limit to fall into the Greek idea of a limit in human nature arising from an intellectual defect. And further, while Philo conceives of all men as capable of goodness, he also regards the Law of Moses as binding upon Q 242 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION all men. Thus he is limited in two ways : on the one hand, the man of culture alone is capable of salvation^ and, on the other hand, the Jewish ceremonial law is not temporary, but eternal. St. Paul, on the other hand, bases his doctrine upon a faith of which all men are capable, and sweeps away the whole ceremonial law, which he regards as merely temporary. The universalism of Philo was no true universalism ; that of Paul was based upon the fundamental sinfulness of all men, and the possibility of salvation through faith in the love of God. We can thus understand how Philo's doctrine had no influence beyond the schools, while Christianity turned the world upside down. The more we reflect upon the doctrine of Philo, the more clearly we see that it was impotent to regenerate the race. And even as an abstract creed, it was merely a com- bination of discrepant ideas. There is, in his theory, no real manifestation of God. The inscrutable Being, who cannot be in any way defined, is little better than the deification of Nothing. His \6yo9i viewed on its higher side, is but the hypostatizing of abstract ideas ; and, on its lower side, it does not take us beyond the idea of an abstract law which operates beyond, but not in, the spirit of man. Thus, from either point of view, it has no more potency than an abstract law of nature. St. Paul, on the other hand, has grasped the principle of the self-manifestation of God, and the possibility of the regenerated man living in the Spirit of the Son of God. Thus, in his doctrine, we are dealing with the actual manifestation of God, and with the living principle operative in the souls of men. When we compare Philo with the writer of the Fourth Gospel we find the same superficial resemblance, and the same fundamental opposition. (i) We have seen how Philo affirms the absolute PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT 243 incomprehensibility of God. " Though God is by- nature visible, no man has seen Him." This lan- guage naturally suggests the similar statement in the Fourth Gospel (i. 18), *' No man hath seen God at any time." By the false method of assuming that simi- larity of statement is a proof of borrowing, it may be argued that St. John was indebted to Philo for his conception of the invisibility of God. Now, not to mention that Philo's conception of the incompre- hensibility and invisibility of God had taken a firm hold both of Palestinian and Alexandrian writers before Philo, it is easy to see that, in words which are almost identical, the two writers are expressing a totally different idea. In the passage where Philo speaks of the invisibility of God, he goes on to say that " the cause lies in the weakness of the creature," i,e. in the " imbecility of the human intellect," to use the phraseology of Sir William Hamilton. It is thus a limit in the human intelligence which, in Philo's view, prevents us from comprehending the nature of God ; and he adds that " we must become God — which is impossible — before we can comprehend God." But no such doctrine is suggested by the Gospel writer. After saying that " no man hath seen God at any time," he adds : " the only-begotten Son, which is in the bosom of the Father, he hath declared him." What the writer has in his mind is that, prior to the revelation of God by Jesus Christ, the Father was in His full nature unknown to man, but is now revealed as He truly is. That this is his meaning is evident from the words immediately preceding : " For the Law was given by Moses, but grace and truth came by Jesus Christ." The contrast is therefore between the Law and the Gospel ; and the fundamental thought is, that God, whose true nature had been hidden, is 244 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION now revealed as a God of love. No doubt the Gospel writer holds by the thought of the spirituality of God, but in his view God is not hidden but revealed. There is, in truth, nothing in the New Testament to cou ntenance the doctrine of the absolute incompre- hensibility of God, and theologians who interpret such passages in an agnostic sense do violence to its whole spirit. " Blessed are the pure in heart, for they shall see God," is the utterance of the living Christian consciousness, not a dogmatic proposition; but it is incompatible with any theology which sets up an impassable barrier between God and man. If theology is to remain Christian, it must discard this fiction of an absolutely incomprehensible God by providing a com- pletely reasoned basis for the Christian consciousness of a self-manifesting God. Fhilo then, as we see, so far from anticipating the Christian idea of God, merely expresses the conception current in his day among his countrymen. And it is significant that, in defending his preconception of the inscrutability of God, he employs the dualistic modes of thought which he had learned from his Greek teachers. The false abstraction of an incomprehensible God on the one side, has as its complement the equally false abstraction of formless matter on the other side ; so that God is not the creative source of all things, but merely the Architect who fashions the world. Thus the very writer who imagines that he exalts God by declaring Him to be incomprehensible, falls back upon the analogy of a human artist when he attempts to explain the creation of the world. This defect still permeates much of our current speculation. It is still supposed that God in respect of His relation to the world may be conceived as a kind of external artificer ; a view which rests upon the blasphemous PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT 245 notion of the independent existence of the material world, (2) The Xoyop is conceived by Philo as, on the one hand, the Thought of God, and, on the other, the expression of this Thought in the visible universe ; and this Word is represented as the "instrument" by which the cosmos is formed. When we turn to the Fourth Gospel we read : " In the beginning was the \6y09, and the \6y09 was with God, and the \6yo^ was God. The same was in the beginning with God. All things were by Him (St avTov), and without Him was not anything made thac hath been made." The two modes of statement have undoubtedly the strongest resemblance. But there are fundamental differences. According to Philo the \6yo^ is not identical with God, but is a product of His self-activity. Thus the \6yo^ is not a complete counterpart of the infinite energy of God ; nor, strictly speaking, is it an expres- sion of what God in His inner nature is, but only an effect, distinct and separate from Him. Philo, in short, applies the conception of external causation to express the relation between God and the \6y09. On the basis of his dualism, the Xoyog cannot be identical with God, because God is absolutely self-contained and therefore cannot be expressed. Now, St. John gives us a very different view. Holding that God is essen- tially self- manifesting, he employs the current term Xoyo^ to express this idea. The \6yog is said to be at once " with God " and to " be God." Thus the absolute identity of God and the X6yo9 is affirmed, while yet the Xoyos is distinguished from God. This can only mean that God manifests himself as He is in the \6yo%. It is, then, in this sense that he speaks of the \6yo^ or Word, There can be no doubt that he makes use of the current Hellenistic metaphor 246 PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS OF RELIGION implied in the double meaning of the term Xoyog^ but he adapts it to the expression of the new concep- tion of God as self-manifesting. Thus his conception of the \6yo9 has an entirely different meaning from that of Philo. God's inner nature is fully manifested in the XoyoSy who is not the product of God, but is God Himself. The mechanical conception of God as a cause distinct from the Xoyog is set aside, and for it is substituted the conception of God as the eternal self-manifesting God, or, in a word, of God as Spirit. Philo holds that the Xoyog was the " instrument " by which the visible world was created ; and he ex- pressly compares the world to a vast temple or city, explaining that the \6yos was the instrument by which the four elements and their various compounds have been formed. St. John also speaks of the Xoyo^ as that through which the world has been made, and so far he seems to be expressing the same idea as Philo. But there is this important difference : that as the X6yo9 is identical with God, it is God as the Xoyog who has " made the world." Further, the world is not " made " in the sense of being " formed " out of a " matter " already existing, but is brought into being absolutely. (3) In Philo, the X6yo9 conceived as the Thought of God is distinct from the Xoyos as the Word. The latter is the order and harmony of creation and pro- vidence. There is no such distinction in St. John. For him the Word is the expression of God Himself, arfd it is to the direct agency of God as the Xoyo^ that all created things owe their existence. Thus, from whatever point of view we compare them, we find that Philo and St. John, while using the same term, give to it an entirely different meaning. Nor PHILO AND THE NEW TESTAMENT 247 tnust we forget that the metaphor of the Word is only a metaphor, and that the fundamental idea which it is employed to express is that God has revealed Himself as He is in the knowable universe, or rather in His Son. LECTURE TENTH GNOSTIC THEOLOGY In my last lecture I endeavoured to show that the resemblances between the New Testament writers and Philo are no proof of direct obligation on the part of the latter, and that, when we go beneath the surface, we find in each a totally different conception of life. The first point of resemblance is in the doctrine of the Logos. In ordinary usage the term Xoyog means either (a) thought, or (d) speech. Philo makes use of this double meaning to explain the relation between the intelligible and the sensible world. Thought and speech in man are related to each other as the Divine Thought to its Expression in the visible universe. Thus the \6y09 is the Word of God, z,e. the order impressed upon the sensible world. Therefore man, in grasping by his intelligence the order exhibited in the visible universe, may attain to truths or to a symbolical apprehension of the Divine Thought. The Xoyo^ is the " instrument " of creation, while God is its " cause." Hence the visible world is represented as a vast temple or city, the form of which is impressed upon it by the ^070?, just as the architect embodies his thought in his work. The Xoyo^ is therefore intermediate between God and man ; it is " neither unbegotten as God, nor GNOSTIC THEOLOGY 249 begotten as man," but is eternally begotten. As the expressed Thought or Word of God, it is called the " eldest " or " first-born Son of God." It is the " bond " of all things, i.e. the principle which constitutes the world an ordered system. The Ao'yo? or Word is also the law which determines the course of human life. Hence the \6yof5 is called the " man of God " or the " heavenly man," who is distinguished from Adam, the " earthly man." Philo also speaks of the Xofyo^s as the " second God/' because it is not God as He is in Himself, but the product or " image " of God. There are other ways in which the \6yo