M3iE25i™" ■jy ji.ifii i;^., ::^^:^s„,.i BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME OP^ THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF HENRY W. SAGE 1891 Cornell University Library B393 .B88 Plato's studies and criticisms of the po oiin 3 1924 028 975 139 Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924028975139 PLATO'S STUDIES AND CRITICISMS OF THE POETS BY CARLETON LEWIS BROWNSON Head of the Classical Department and Dean of the College of the City of New York BOSTON RICHARD G. BADGER THE GORHAM PRESS COFYBIGET, 1920, BY CaELETON LEWIS BrOWNSON All Rights Reserved Made in the United States of America The Gorham Press, Boston, U. S. A. PREFACE There is hardly any subject which the Platonic Soc- rates finds more interesting than poetry, hardly any class of people to whom he refers more frequently than to the poets. And it seems clear that in this respect Plato is fairly representing the historic Socrates. In both the Memorabilia and the Symposium of Xenophon Socrates appears as one fully versed in literature. He tells Antiphon"^ that he is wont to peruse with his friends the writings of the wise men of old and to make excerpts therefrom. First among these "wise men of old" was Homer. Socrates not only refers often^ to characters and episodes of the Iliad and the Odyssey but quotes' freely from both poems. He also quotes more than once from Hesiod,* as well as from Theognis^ and Epi- charmus.* He does not mention by name nor quote any Athenian dramatist, but it is evident from allusions' to things theatrical, which he introduces, as Plato fre- quently does, for purposes of illustration, that he was an observing play-goer. He has also listened to the re- citals of rhapsodes, but thinks* with Plato that they fail to understand the meaning of what they say. 'Mem. I. 6. 14. 2 Mem. I. 3. 7, II. 6. 31, Symp. IV, 20, VIII. 23 and 31. 'Mem. II. 6. 11, III. 1.4, 2. 1 and 2, IV. 6. 15, Symp. VIII. 30. * Mem. I. 3. 3, II. I. 20. 'Symp. II. 4. « Mem. II. I. 20. 'Mem. II. 2. 9, III. 4. 3, s. 6. 8 Symp. III. 6. 3 4 Preface Xenophon tells us further' — and his statement is im- portant for the present purpose — that Socrates was accused of selecting the worst passages from the most famous poets and making them a basis for harmful teachings.^" Several verses from the Iliad^^ and one from Hesiod^^ are then cited which Socrates was charged with perverting. It appears, then, that Socrates was a lover and a student especially of Homer but also of the other poets. All this we might of course fairly expect of a seeker after wisdom who lived in the age of Pericles and numbered among his acquaintance a Nicer'atus,^' who knew by heart both the Iliad and the Odyssey. Socrates found in Plato a follower whose tastes cor- responded with his own in this as in other respects. It is a well-known and altogether probable story that Plato in his youth was himself a- poet and wrote dithyrambs, lyric verse and tragedies." We learn further from Diogenes Laertius'^ that Plato at the age of twenty was just about to present a tragedy, when he first heard Socrates; thereupon he committed his poems to the flames with the words, "H<^ato'T6 7rp6)LcoX 'dJ5e, nXdrwi' v\J Tt, aelo xarifei." This anecdote may or may not be true; it seems to me worth telling be- cause it illustrates truly Plato's feeling in regard to poetry. Even as he renounces the art, he does so in the words of the great poet of Greecevfso ' Mem. I. 2. 56. " vid. infra p. 124. " B 188-191, 198-202. ^ W. and D. 311. '^ Symp. III. j. " Diog. Laert. Vitae Philosophorum, III. 5. Olympiodorus, Vita, 3. Aelian, Var. Hist. II. 30. '^ 1. c. 1° Cf. Iliad, 2 392. Pr^ace 5 the philosophy which led him to condemn and banish the poets is adorned in his writings with all the graces of poetrjy Plato does, indeed, abandon poetry as a calling but he is far from giving up the study of the poets. According to tradition^' he was especially fond of Epicharmus and Sophron. Those who were jealous of his fame charged him with having copied the latter's mimes in his dialogues.^' On the other hand Diogenes states^' that he was greatly as- sisted by Epicharmus, the greater part of whose works he transcribed. Indeed he was said to have kept a copy of the comedian always under his pillow.^" An- other story of the same sort is that the works of Sophron and Aristophanes were found in his bed after his death.^^ Such in brief is the external evidence re- garding Plato's literary tastes and studies. Needless to say that it is of extremely slight importance, first, because it is meager and rests upon poor authority, and second, because the internal evidence is so entirely adequate that it could hardly be strengthened by the fullest and most trustworthy information from other sources. It is the aim of the present dissertation to collect and analyse this internal evidence and to that end all the dialogues which Christ^^ classes as ' i- doubtedly genuine have been examined. " Diog. III. 9, lo, i8. Olymp. 3. Val. Max. V. 7. 18 Diog. III. 18. "Id. III. 9, 10. 20 Olymp. 3. Val. Max. V. 7. 21 Diog. III. 18. Olymp. 1. c. ^ Gesch. der Griech. Litt. p. 376 ff. CONTENTS PART I— PLATO'S STUDIES OF THE POETS AND OF POETRY FACE Introduction ii I Plato's References to the Poets As a Class and to Poetry 13 General Comments 13 Definition of the various types of poetry ... 17 Remarks upon the subject of harmonies and rhythms 1 8 References to the externals of dramatic representa- tion 19 II Plato's References to Individual Poets and Quota- tions FROM Their Works 22 Prehistoric bards 22 Elegiac poets 25 Iambic poets 29 Lyric poets 30 Dramatic poets 35 a. The Comedians 3S b. The Tragedians 37 Epic poets 46 General conclusions 68 PART II— PLATO'S CRITICISMS OF THE POETS AND POETRY Introduction 77 I Review of Plato's Condemnatory Utterances . . 81 In the Republic 81 In the Laws ■. . . . 98 In other dialogues lOj 7 8 Contents FAGS II The Study of the Poets in the Greek System of Education io8 III The Shortcomings of the Poets as Educators . ii8 IV The Ancient Quarrel between Poetry and Phi- losophy 132 V Minor Reasons for Plato's Hostility to the Poets 139 VI General Considerations and Conclusions . . . 144 Bibliography 155 Tables 159 PART I Plato's studies of the poets and of poetry INTRODUCTION The influence of Plato's early training as a poet, or rather the natural bent of his genius toward the poetic, is shown in three ways : first, by the dramatic and poetic element in his dialogues; second, by his comments upon poetry and the poets; third, by his wonderfully wide acquaintance with the works of poets of his own age and of the earlier centuries. With regard to the first point little need be said. We feel, as did Aristotle,^ that Plato's style is midway between poetry and prose, but we do not care to undertake a demonstration of the fact by means of quotations and abstracts. We accept the statement of Longinus' that Plato was 'O/ii/ptKOJTa- Tos iravTOiv, but we can more fully appreciate the influence of Homer and the other poets upon Plato's habits of thought and expression by reading the Phae- drus, the Phaedo, the Symposium, or any one of many other dialogues than by studying the opinions of critics or collecting examples of poetic imagination and dic- tion in the philosopher's works. I shall consider, therefore, only the second and third of the points men- tioned, and in dealing with them shall disregard for the present the few famous passages in which Plato treats of the poets as the "educators of Hellas" and con- demns many of their teachings so sternly. ' Diogenes III. 37. " De Sublimitate, XIII. p. 56. II Plato's Studies and Criticisms of the Poets CHAPTER I Plato's references to the poets as a class and to POETRY I. General Comments. — Plato is at one with his coun- trymen in regarding the poets as the earliest sages of Greece, divinely endowed with superior wisdom. In the Lysis' he speaks of them as "our fathers and leaders in wisdom," and in the Laws,* a dialogue as far as possible removed from the Lysis, they are said to be delov ykvos and to attain to truth with the help of the Muses and Graces. Again we find them de- scribed in the Republic^ as TratSes d^wv, though these words are put in the mouth of Adimantus and are probably not to be taken seriously. A similar irony is evident in the Timaeus,* where the poets are said to call themselves descendants of the gods. Their posi- tion and mission in ancient times corresponded with that of the philosophers and sophists in later days. For Protagoras, Heraclitus, and Empedocles are said in the Theaetetus'' to be their lineal descendants; and Protagoras, in the dialogue which is called by his name,* affirms his belief that they were simply sophists who termed their art poetry in order to escape odium. It ' 214 A. * 682 A. » 366 B. 8 40 D. ' 152 C, 160 D., 179 E. 8316 D. 13 14 Plato's Studies and Criticisms of the- Poets is from the poets also that we must learn with regard to the science of names, as Socrates urges in the Cratylus.' The poets, however, differ from the philosophers in that "they do what they do, not by wisdom but by a sort of natural genius and inspiration."^" There is nothing of which Plato is more thoroughly convinced than of this. He reiterates the statement in the Ion,*' the Meno,'^ the Phaedrus,'' and the Laws." The poet is a light and winged and holy thing, and is not able to compose poetry until he becomes inspired and out of his mind.*" He is frequently compared, as in the passage quoted from the Apology, with the seers and soothsayers.*' Like them he is a servant of the gods, who speaks not of himself.*' How else can one explain the fact that Tynnichus, the Chalcidian, wrote one magnificent paean but nothing else worth reading?** The poet, then, is not eiJ,