BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME FROM THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF 1891 1. . B.^IifH - '/''Mj-.- 99S3 Cornell University Library LA128 .C68 Herbart and Froebel: an attempt at synth olin 3 1924 030 549 491 The original of tiiis bool< is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://archive.org/details/cu31924030549491 Columbia IDlnivetsitig Contributions to lEbucation Zcacbevs College Series mo. X4 HERBART AND FROEBEL: AN ATTEMPT AT SYNTHESIS Percival Richard Cole, Ph. D. PUBLISHED BY TEACHERS COLLEGE COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY NEW YORK 1907 J), BRANDOW PRINTING CO., ALBANY, N. Y. ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE. Introduction 3 Chapter I. The Philosophy of Froebel '7 I. A philosophy of nature 9 i. Nature as spirit visible 11 2. As objective 11 3. The unity of nature 12 4. Nature and man 14 5. Nature and development 14 6. Nature as symbol 15 II. A philosophy of man 18 1. The primacy of mind 18 2. Self-activity 20 3. The practical or moral life 21 4. The reign of law 25 5. Freedom 26 III. A theory of the absolute 33 1 . God as the ground of all things 33 2 . Pantheism 35 3. Teleology 36 Chapter II. The Philosophy of Herbart 41 I. The philosophical relations of Herbart 43 1. Herbart and Leibnitz 43 2. Ethical views 44 3. Herbart and Kant ^ 45 4. Spinoza and Leibnitz 48 5. Fichte and Schelling 50 II. The metaphysic of Herbart 52 1. The methodology of Herbart 52 2 . The ontology of Herbart 55 3. The cosmology of Herbart 61 4. The epistemology of Herbart 62 5.- Certain implications for education 63 III. The psychology of Herbart 65 I. The so-called faculties 65 , 72 . Ideas as dynamic 66 3. Reason and will 70 4. Another interpretation 71 Chapter III. The Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis 75 I. An attempt at a psychological synthesis 75 1. The soul and the concept 75 2. Mental forms and mental content 77 4 Analytical Table of Contents. PAGE. 3. Habit and attention 79 4. An evolutionary psychology 80 5. Mental structure and function 81 6. The self and the situation 84 II. Possibility of a metaphysical and ethical synthesis 85 1 . Freedom ' 85 2. Progress and equilibrium 86 3 . Possibility and actuality 87 4. Being and becoming 88 5. Intellect and will 90 6. The education of character 93 Chapter IV. An Attempt at an Educational Synthesis 95 I. Curriculum and method 95 1. Society and the curriculum 95 2. Educational values 97 3. Correlation and concentration 98 4. Formal steps 99 5. Epochs of culture loi 6. Technique 102 7. Instruction 103 8. Education for vocation 105 II. Nature and culture 107 1 . Nature and civilisation 107 2. Education by institutions 109 3. Individuality in 4. Interest 112 Summary 114 INTRODUCTION. The notion of a synthesis of Herbart and Froebel was first suggested to the writer by Professor John Adams, of London University, in 1905. Already the outline of a synthesis has aippeared in an article in the Educational Review, written by Professor Welton, and entitled A Synthesis of Herbart and Froebel.^ Dr. F. H. Hayward, himself an able Herbartian writer, has admitted that this phrase suggests the vision of a third educational " Secret," beyond the secrets that seem to him to have been disclosed in the respective works of Froebel and of Herbart.'' The article by Professor Welton is suggestive, and only too slight. A more inclusive comparative study has been made by Professor MacVannel, of Columbia University.* With the work of Professor Welton and of Professor MacVannel the present attempt at a synthesis is in general accord. Like both of these, it assumes the practical value of a philosophy of edu- cation. It is, however, widely differentiated, as to its aims, from the former by its scope, and from the latter by a less his- torical mode of approach. The writer is deeply indebted to Professor MacVannel, as well for his aid in the present under- taking as for his invaluable contributions to a philosophy of education. In the present dissertation, the term synthesis has been broadly interpreted. At the same time it has not been used to denote an aggregation of the educational principles of Froebel and of Herbart. Neither is it intended to imply that in cases where Herbart may be said to maintain a thesis, and Froebel an antithesis, anything like an equal validity need always be attrib- uted to the respective principles that may be emphasised by each. That which is sought is neither an aggregation of prin- ciples, nor an indifference to them, nor a forced equality of emphasis upon them, but a type of synthesis that may be called organic. The term organic may be opposed to mechanical, or to ^September, 1900. ^The Secret of Herbart. London, 1904. p. vii. ^The Educational Theories of Herbart and Froebel. Teachers College, New York. 1905. 6 Introduction. that piecemeal or mosaic type of eclecticism which is not uncom- mon in the literature of education. Perhaps an organic syn- thesis may be taken to imply at once an endeavour for approxi- mate consistency, and a repudiation of the attribute of finality. The value of the synthesis is likely to depend upon the breadth and depth of the interpretation of experience which it may con- vey. For the essential implication of a synthesis is a higher standpoint, a broader view, than those that are to be reconciled. Such a standpoint, such a view, should be possible in the light of a more recent philosophy. Probably there are those who may feel that in the following pages something is to a degree read into Herbart and Froebel; and that the result is more akin to an outline of a philosophy of education than to the more limited reconciliation of two his- toric systems of educational thought. Such criticism is not unwillingly accepted. In a sense, to read a fuller meaning into Herbart and Froebel is the very purpose and final cause of the synthesis. The problem is philosophical, and to a degree even metaphysical; but it is also eminently practical. For at present one of the chief practical difficulties in American education is the synthesis, or articulation, or reconciliation, of the primary school with the kindergarten. The primary school tends to be dominated by the ideas of Herbart, as the kindergarten is domi- nated by the ideas of Froebel ; so that there is apparently a need of a synthetic theory of education which may tend to the more amicable reconstruction of them both. Below are given the specific aims of the present attempt at a synthesis. 1. To review the educational theories of Herbart and Froebel in the light of the philosophies which they imply. 2. To compare and interpret those theories of Herbart and Froebel which concern reality, consciousness and character. 3. To adjust in a measure the emphasis of Herbart upon cul- ture, instruction and mental content with the emphasis of Froebel upon nature, self-activity and will. One can only set Froebel upon the philosophical plane of Herbart by crediting him with what is implied as well as what is expressed in his educational theory. This done, he is often found to be in close sympathy with modem thought. Froebel, indeed, was a man of wide and deep reading. He twice rejected Introdiiction. 7 the opportunity to become a university professor. He had read eagerly as a boy and a student; and his reading as a man included the Levana of Richter, the writings of Arndt and Novalis, the Bruno of Schelling, the works of Pestalozzi, and the Ideal of Humcmity and the Journal of Human Life of Krause.^ " The Sonntagsblatt" writes Eleonore Heerwart, " leads us to a further conclusion concerning Froebel : he was a man of wide reading. Not only does every number bear as a motto at the beginning expressions of famous men, but also ' voices ' and short biographical notices of such men as tended to ratify his views of education and of life."" Such evidence of culture, it is true, bears no comparison to the profound scholar- ship of Herbart. Its value is to indicate, with a greater degree of certainty, the source and spirit of many of the ideas of Froebel which in themselves are less comprehensible. ^Cf, Hanschmann. Friedrich Froebel. Eisenach, 1874. p. 27, p. 47, p. 41, p. 168, etc. ^Wilhelmine, Frobets erste Gattin. Eisenach, 1905. p. 219. ^Sd CHAPTER I. The Philosophy of Froebel. In his optimism, his will to believe, and his proclivity towards assumptions, Froebel had an entire school of contemporary thought to bear him company. For the appeal to faith as equal in authority to reason, the tendency to mysticism in expression, and symbolism in thought, and the supremacy of the synthetic over the analytic view, are to be regarded as marks not of Froe- bel only, but of romanticists generally, including the Schlegels, Tieck, Schleiermacher, Novalis, and Schelling. Science, art, religion and philosophy were all one to romanticism, for a com- mon feeling unified them and manifested them as aspects of a unitary and organic life. Thus Froebel would have none of the warning of an academic friend, that he should be guarded against philosophy which leads to doubt and darkness, but welcome art, the giver of life and joy.^ As to Schelling, so to Froebel, phil- osophy was an art, and art a philosophy, so that when either speaks as one who prophesieth, understanding nothing, he is apt to compensate for an occasional lack of lucidity by the certainty of his intuition.^ It is in vain to expect of either Froebel or Schelling a scholastic systematisation of his contributions to the life of the spirit. Froebel appears to draw his inspiration now from Schelling, now again from Fichte. In general, he follows Schelling when his discourse is of nature, or of symbolism, or when he takes an esthetic view of things; but Fichte, whenever he thinks in terms of morality, personality, will, duty, or citizenship. Among the philosophers contemporary with Froebel, Krause had already effected a similar synthesis. To Krause Froebel wrote a long autobiographical letter; and in return Krause sent Froebel his books. Between these two there existed certain personal affini- ties. Both were Thuringians, both sons of clergymen, both inured to a certain measure of poverty and hardship, both lovers of nature from their youth, both wanderers according to the standard of their period and nation, and both contemporaries ^Autobiography. Translated by Michaelis and Moore. Syracuse, N. Y. 1889. p. 40. 'Cf. Schelling, Clara. Stuttgart, 1865. p. 175. 10 Herbart and Froebel. save for Krause's advantage of a single year and for his com- paratively early death.^ Yet despite all these coincidences their lives as educators were by no means similar. For Froebel, although he had deep philosophical interests, a love of learning, and opportunities for advancement in the universities of Berlin and Sweden,* lay under an inner compulsion of which the con- scientious Krause knew nothing, to be a Menschenbildner.' Thus it was not Krause with his four daughters and eight sons, but the childless Froebel, who became the passionate lover and devoted teacher of children. Similarity of philosophical and religious convictions drew Froebel and Krause close together. In a review in Isis, which he wrote in 1823 upon Froebel's essay of the preceding year,* Krause attempted to call attention to the entire harmony of that essay with his own expressions of 181 1 in Das Urbild der Menschheit and Tagblatt des Menschheit Lebens. Indeed, quite in common with Krause," Froebel was convinced of the congru- ence of religion and science, the harmony of reason and art, the unity of mankind, the value of social service, theism as against pantheism, the dominance of the reUgious view in life, the might of love, the indivisibility of moral worth and beauty, and the freedom of the will as obeying only the law of its own idea. As with Krause, so with Froebel, God is permanent yet ever changing and working in all things as natura tiaturans, transcend- ent yet immanent, with even something of a special stress on the immanence. For them both, nature is through and through spiritual, and endowed with a tranquil constancy all her own. For them both, man for his part is essentially social, the sexes are spiritually and intellectually co-ordinate and equal, and the family is the chief institute of education, although by no means to the extent of the exclusion of education from the national con- cern. For the rest, Froebel had a more unitary conception of mind and body than Krause, who treated man as a triune bodily, mental, and spiritual being. Krause for his part had a univer- sality conceivably beyond even Froebel's, since he desired the name of the school of Froebel at Keilhau to be changed from Allge- 'Krause, b. 1781. d. 183J. Froebel. b. 1781, d. 1852. The University of Stockholm. ^Cf. Hanschmann, Friedrich Froebel. Eisenach. 1874. p. 101. *Ueber deutsche Eniehung, iiberhaupt. 'Cf. Ueber Krause und Froebel. Paul Hohlfeld. Dresden. 1873. pamm. Aiso Hanschmann, Friedrich Froebel. p. X48 sqq. Philosophy of Froebel. ii nieine deutsche Erziehungsaitstalt to the broader title, Reinmen- schliche Erziehungsanstalt fiir Deutsche. But this appeal of Krause to the catholicity of the ideals of the school of Rousseau perhaps lacks the happiness of the self-identification of Froebel with the surging forces of nationality. As a direct discipline of Krause and Schelling,^ Froebel devel- oped a world-view on the basis of a daring idealism. His own temperament inclined to the artistic, and was not averse even to mystic tendencies. His philosophy, then, is no cautious critique ; but neither need it be viewed as a closed system. It is, perhaps, none tlie less a philosophy because here and there it may lie open to ridicule, and oftener to misinterpretation. To adequately analyse his view of education is indeed to trace the ramifications of a wealth of overlapping categories. The problems of develop- ment, nature, spirit, will, society, and duty need to be examined and related in thought. At any rate as they are coming to be used in current educational literature, the well-worn categories of unity, development and self-activity seem to furnish an inade- quate clue by which to unravel such a labyrinth of fundamental questions as confronts us here. Let us rather borrow from Froebel the scheme of the Menschen Erziehung, to the extent merely of discussing in succession his philosophy of nature, his philosophy of man, and his philosophy of the absolute. It seemed to Kant, the philosopher of Konigsberg, that since, according to his analysis, the outer world can only produce sensa- tions, or the raw material of knowledge, whereas the mind is much more than sensations, or their sum or product, it should follow that mind must be possessed of an a priori s)Tithetic activity of its own. " If," he said, " intuition must conform to the nature of the objects, I do not see how we know anything a priori ; on the other hand if the object, as object of sense, conforms to the nature of our own capacity of intuition, I can very well con- ceive such a possibility."' This declaration of a revolution in thought, which was likened by Kant himself to the supersession of the Ptolemaic by the Copernican hypothesis of the revolution 'Especially through Middendorff, Langethal, and Krause, Froebel was also a disciple of Schleiermacher. Cf. Hanschmann. Friedrich Froebel. Eisenach, 1874. p. 94. ^Kritik der reinen Vemmtft. Berlin, 1889. p. 19. 12 Herbart and Fraebel. of the heavenly bodies, received independent confirmation from psychology and the religious consciousness. Fichte and Schel- ling built upon the Kantian principle a completer idealism, hav- ing in each case faults of its own, but transcending the dualism which, with a suspicion of the old Cartesian leaven, Kant had perpetuated in his system by the retention of an unknowable, mentally unconditioned, residuum of things-in-themselves. For his part Fichte, taking his departure from the Critique of Judg- ment rather than that of the Pure Reason, projected an idealism all too subjective, in which only the Ego exists. But for Fichte, since life is regarded as the reconquest, by the practical or moral Ego, of the field of self-limitation which the theoretical or know- ing Ego has set about itself, and which common sense calls the objective world, and since also the process of moral reconquest implies a universal moral order, the moral order was the one true self, the infinite will, the mediator between the self and the spiritual world, and the common source of both ; in a word, God.* To Schelling, nature was more than the self-set limit of Fichte, more than subjective, and more than moral ; for surely it is need- less or fantastic to morally reconquer, with Fichte, say the spots on the surface of the sun. The world had for Schelling an esthetic unity. Nature was spirit visible, spirit nature invisible. Through Krause and other channels the Absolute of Schelling, although in its final form too negative, too like a mere indiffer- ence,^ and too vulnerable to the satire of Hegel,' may have helped to reveal to Froebel the common ground and source of visible and invisible spirit in the unifying will of God.* This was a culmination of the romanticist tendency of thought, which, half poetic, more than half intuitive, and all inspired as it was, is in so many cases the key to the peculiarities of Froebelian education. The attitude of Froebel towards nature is definitely marked by the following positions: Nature is (a) spirit visible; (b) objec- tive; (c) a unity, such that every part is utterly in harmony with every part; (d) one with the mind of man, in the sense of involv- ing a necessary correspondence with his spirit, based upon a com- mon foundation in the absolute spirit, or in God ; (e) an harmoni- ous system developing according to its own inner laws, and as it 'C/. Fichte, Werke. Berlin, 1845. II. p. 399. 'Cjf. Schelling, Werke. Stuttgart und Augsburg. 1859. IV. p. 103, "V. Phdnomenolcgie des Geistes. Preface. *Cj. Menschen Erziehung, hrsg, Seidel. p. 144. Philosophy of Froebel. 13 were an organic whole; and finally (f) a type and symbol of the life of humanity. 1. Nature as spirit visible. Schelling, in reaction from the determination of nature according to Fichte as an abstract limit, held nature to be parallel to man and even larger and more real. He believed that there was no phenomenon in consciousness whose embodiment in nature he could not see. Such a doctrine may be interpreted in either of two ways. It may imply no more than the objectivity of nature, which Fichte in a way had denied. It may mean, again, that consciousness is a mere pro- duct ; and no ultimate process. If this be so, man is to be inter- preted from nature, rather than nature from man. But this is not the point of view of Froebel, highly though he valued the reality of nature. For him it may be said that nature at every point adumbrated spiritual relationships. Indeed, if the ethical meaning of idealism be no more mysterious than this, that it lies in seeking the explanations of things in their ideas, of lower forms in their higher possibilities, then it was a true idealism that moved Froebel, when the crux came of interpreting the given symbolic relation between consciousness and nature, to call nature the symbol, mind the reality. Herein is the philosophical basis of Froebel's symbolism, in itself not necessarily unsound, however ridiculous in a few of its applications.^ On the prin- ciples of Froebel, the educator need not go beyond symbolism to mysticism, if he will but teach nature not in its mere exter- nality, but in its life, beauty, spirit and meaning. There is little danger of reading spirit into nature if nature be visible spirit. The danger is only of misreading — corruptio optimi lit pessima. For only gradually are we differentiated from our environment, which therefore shares in our spiritual nature; and whether by the poetic process as with Wordsworth, or by school rambles as with Froebd,^ the growing mind is pledged by instinct, by kin- ship, and by utility, to cherish in relation to it a manner of sympathetic intercourse. 2. Nature as objective. Although they tended to regard nature as spiritual, or organic to consciousness, neither Schelling, nor Hegel, nor Froebel desired to detract from her objectivity, her reality, or her permanence. Nature to Schelling was the " com- '£.g. Der B-all ist ein Bild des All. Kindergartenwesen (Seidel) p. 40. ^Mtnschen Erziehung, h-sg. Seidel. p. 96. 14 Herbart and Froebel. plete real side in the eternal process of subject becoming object; " and the philosophy of nature was the " first and necessary side of philosophy itself."^ Froebel would have been willing to grant that nature is objectively given, but essentially as a means to conscious life, and subordinate to man, " a more beautiful ladder than Jacob's between earth and heaven."" An educational appli- cation by Froebel of the doctrine of the objectivity of nature is his agreement with the insistency of Pestalozzi upon things before words. Children are dejected by the inanities of a premature technical nomenclature. A text-book' has profaned the sancti- ties of the kindergarten with " tender violet voices " like this : " Do tell me," whispered a violet bud to a violet close by, " when will I be able to show my pretty blue dress ? It's non- sense my wearing my green pinafore so long ! " " If you were grown up enough to leave off your pinafore you would call your pinafore a calyx, and your blue dress a corolla. From your child- ish way of talking any one can see you are nothing but a baby." " I wonder if I've got those little stems inside me with gold tops like you have ? " went on the violet bud. The violet answered hastily, " Of course you have ; but don't call them stems — stamens is the right name for them. You're absurdly childish even for your age ! " One may leave such travesties with Froebel's patient comment that the words may wait,* only adding that he had every sympathy with the word in talk, and song, and story, if it were but the sym- bol of power. At the same time, contrary to a prevalent impres- sion, Froebel is distinctly for reality in education. Realising to a greater extent than Fichte, or than Herbart, that nature is real, and to a degree objective, Froebel took his material from the near at hand, developed occupations from contact with visible and tangible objects, and studied nature for what it is, as well as for what it may symbolise. 3. The unity of nature. Nature, which to Schelling was an Odyssey of the spirit," the spirit striving to return to its own true inwardness through the form of outwardness in which it is clad in nature, seemed to Herbart not deducible from a single principle, but to be the phenomenal manifestation of a plurality 'Schelling, Werke. 1859. V. p. 314- ^Menschtn Ertithung. hrsg. Seidel. 1883. p. 136. ^Tht Kindergarten Room.-' By F. A. Fistram. Blackie and Son. 1006. *lbid. p. 13 s. 'C/. HaffdinK. History of Modern Philosophy. II. p. 165. Philosophy of Froebel. 15 of independent reals. Yet if the unity be not conceived to be such as excludes difference, if it be as it seemed to Froebel, organic, then the unity of nature is an intelligible hypothesis. It is the point of departure from which Froebel endeavors to explain mind, nature, education, life and the absolute. His opening words in the Menschen Ersiehung read like the opening words of Krause in Das Urbild der Menschheit, and not unlike many expressions of Schelling. For instance : " Nature in its very essence," said Schelling,^ " is one ; there is one life in all things, and one power to be, the same regulative principle through ideas. There is no pure materiality in nature, but there is everywhere soul symbolically represented in body, with a preponderance of one or the other in phenomena. For the same reason there can be but one science in nature." Mr. Bradley and others repeat the same thing. " In reality there can be no mere physical nature. The world of physical science is not something inde- pendent, but is a mere element in one total experience."^ For Froebel as for so many of the metaphysicians of his day, the unity of the world was a consequence of its spirituality. In one sense man is a part of this unity, since his physical being is an atom in its immensity, and subject to all its laws ; in another he is a higher unity, capable of making the whole world his own, a bearer of its purposes for whom the stars fight in their courses. He is a member, yet also a whole; a part, yet all-inclusive; a Glied-ganzes. The desire to comprehend nature under intelli- gible laws is by Froebel set down to the galvanisation of this nature as a Glied-games by the fundamental instinct common throughout the world, for each individual man, animal or plant to actualise his own potentialities. The genuine boy, says Froe- bel, when you show him the objects of nature, will soon ask about their higher unity and causation.' There is a subtle distinction* between the master, who controls the elusive details of experi- ence by law, and the mere teacher who allows himself to be lost in a bewildering manifold of isolated incidents. Fragmentary study devitalises natural objects and militates against the vigor of the human mind.^ ^Werke, 1859- V. p. 32S. , ^ ^Appearance and Reahty. London, 1903. p. 2S3. ^Menschen Erziehung. p. 133- *Ibid. p. 81. ^Menschen Erziehung. p. 133. 1 6 Herbart and Froebel. 4. Nature and man. The unity of matter and mind, man and nature was for Froebel not sameness but a Divine immanent will ; intuitive perhaps, shot out of a pistol maybe, but not the night in which all cows are black. It has even an empirical basis so far as evolution is empirical. The nature that is akin to man cannot be spiritless.^ To Froebel the kinship was close, so close that the Christian, he who reads in nature her deepest sermons, is the only true naturalist.^ The spirit of nature and the soul of man are one, with the common ground and source, God.^ No differ- entiation, it is true, appears to go deeper than between mind and matter, but none is more surely confined within the limits of a system. The unity of man and nature, so close to the heart of poetry and romanticism, so dear to Froebel and Wordsworth, might easily lend itself to the gospel of Rousseau, education according to nature. Froebel seems to be at times a little too enamored of spontaneities, a trifle over-jealous of civilisation. We are prone, he says, to cover the divine source of life in all our hearts with rubbish, to dam it up with waste, to hedge it in with thorns.* Not that the defect as it appears in Froebel is serious, or much more than an aspect of the emphasis that he sets on self-activity. When the idea of membership, of the Glied-ganzes, or of organ- ism, prevails in Froebel, nature-worship in the Rousseau sense is quite transcended. 5. Nature and development. Granted that the mystical con- nections which Froebel postulated between the worlds of crystals, animals and vegetables will not stand the test of scientific inves- tigation, being at best a trespass of metaphysic upon fields that are not its own, the fact remains that Froebel's intuitions of evolution have endowed his educational theory with a certain permanence and validity which otherwise it could hardly have gotten, and in virtue of which it surpasses other systems, at least in the quality of anticipating views now current. It is true that since Darwin and Wallace we have a more definite idea of the nature of the inner laws of natural development; and that Froebel's deductions are subject to empirical revision, and occa- sionally, as in crystallography and the psychology of language, *C"f. Krause. Das Urbild der Menschheit. Dresden, 1811. p. 7. ^Menschen Ereiehung. p. 96. ^Menschen Brziehung. p. 144. *lbid. p. 163. Philosophy of Froebel. 17 may find their appropriate rest in the wastepaper basket. But among the truths that follow from the sanity of Froebel's main positions, that is to say, that nature develops by inner laws, and that these laws have a spiritual or teleological bearing, these which follow are of validity for education. Firstly, an accurate observation of natural laws in their evolution should lead up to a logical basis for the school curriculum; and secondly, if matter be really to us concrete spirit, this logical basis should tend to be psychological also. In the gifts and occupations Froebel endeavored to perfect such a logico-psychological sys- tem. The task was well done. But, since the situation contains a progressive factor, it involves a legacy of work, and is essen- tially a social undertaking. Since the plays and occupations of Froebel, admirable as is their tout ensemble, have no right Tithesis, or a transcendental-immanental reconciliation of his pantheistic leaningfs with the Hegelian notion that the Absolute is not substance but subject. For H^d, God was not so much an immanent Feeling, as for Schelling; but much more Will, a ^Man of war, a Spirit that is not only unity, but unit}" holding in itself all differences, and for ever active in their interpretation.* 2ilany have thought that Froebel failed to sufl&ciently discrim- inate his philosophy, reUgion, and education. Perhaps what at first sight seems to be confusion may reward the careful student by manifesting itself as an efficient harmony. Doubtless Froe- bel's bias was mystic, probably his syntheses were at times based on inadequate analyses; but of what constructive mind can this not be said, and is the word confusion applicable? At any rate it seems doubtful whether a few critical defects should be allowed to obscure the vigour and efficiency that are the fruits of a unitar}- organisation of the attitudes of the soul. In other words, Froebel may have been a better educator because he knew how to harmonise his jMosophy and his religion. And therefore, if the comparison may be made without odium, to whatever extent Froebel may have been weaker than Herbart on the side of the critical reason, it was much that he should have been the stronger in faith, feeling and intuition. Critically, philosophy and religion may lie far asunder; vitally they can- •Cf.TRovce. Sftrit of iloJem PhUosopky. Boston. 189J. p- i6». 'Sammtliikt RCT-fe*. Berlin. i54S. 11 p. 399. •"This Unity 13 God." See opening paragmihs of the EdwcaliOH of itax. •Compare the conclusion of Hegers Logic. Harris. C3iicagD, 1890. Philosophy of Froebel. 37 not. Philosophy, says H^d, only unfolds itself while it unfolds religion; and whfle unfolding itself it unfolds religion. Froebel's system of education was all bound up with religion. True, he had little concern with the problem of teaching children of diverse religious denominations, although few educators, per- haps, have passed through more bitter experiences of sectarian rancour. Yet this modem problem, delicate as it is, seems to have only an indirect bearing upon Froebel's thesis that religion should pervade the school curriculimi; nay, that it should begin at the mother's knee. Meaning by religion anything but dogma, Froebel entertained no fear that it might unduly perplex even the yoimgest child. On the contrary, he maintained, it is because we do not instruct on inner things that they might under- stand, but only on outer things that they do not understand, that the life and soul of older boys tend to be as empty as they are.^ " Inner "' things seem to mean things after which the soul him- gers, among them the love and the will of God. Rousseau would have kept Emile for many years ignorant of God's name. But for Froebel it was the task of instruction, in his own words, '" to bring into the consciousness of the scholar the unity of all things and the repose, being and life of all things in God, so that in time he may be able to act according to this consciousness.'- 2. Pantheism. Possibly for the purposes of the present analy- sis almost enough has already been said about the pantheistic leanings of Froebel.* He did not consider himself to be a pan- theist* It may none the less be true that in these matters the individual is not his own best critic, and that Froebel's categorical repudiation of the tenet a^-ails little in a dispassionate analysis of his creed. And yet perhaps it may serve, in conjtmction with the tenor of his teaching, to indicate that if his faith may have been pantheistic, it was not with the attenuated pantheism that societ}' hcJds in reproach. Froebel may have been pantheistic to the extent of an ample breadth of realisation of the divine immanence in nature, without sacrificing much of the intensitv" of the Christian notion of a personal God. He may have seen no more reason against a combined immanence and transcendence in the deity than in the nature of the human consciousness. If ^Menscken Eniektmg (Sddel 1883). pp. 169-jo. *Ibid. p. 80. 'See preceding section. *Erinnentngefi an Friedrich Froebel. Bulow. Kassd. 1S76. pp. 2S-9. 38 Herbart and Froebel. this were so, perhaps he may have had the right to emphasise immanence or transcendence at will. If it be possible to arrive at a narrower definition, it is not improbably this; that when Froebel thinks of humanity, God appeals to him rather as trans- cendent but sympathetic spirit; and when he thinks of nature, then God appeals to him chiefly as immanent spirit. It is in somewhat different terms that Froebel himself is reported to have repudiated the doctrine of pantheism. Pantheism, said he, practically views the world as God's body. Personally he dis- claimed such an opinion. God is not in the world, he maintained, but the world is in God.^ In a word, Froebel's position was that which Krause used to call panentheism. That the world is somehow in God does not seem gravely unorthodox; it may be a sort of reconciliation between pantheism and transcendentalism ; and if it be an essentially pantheistic position, it is also more than pantheistic. So fundamental is the notion of the divine immanence to Froebel's thought, and so vital to his educational theory, that it would have to be treated at much greater length had not this been already done in the section upon Froebel's theory of nature. But, as the case stands, it may suffice to recall by mere phrases certain educational implications to which attention has already been given. Perhaps these are especially (a) the culti- vation of a human sympathy with nature, (b) the recognition of the unity of her processes in all her kingdoms, (c) the sub- jection of nature to spiritual laws, and all that this involves for conduct and method, and (d) the partial justification of an emphasis upon universal laws, even in the kindergarten. Per- haps only the last of these points demands a more specific explanation. A divine immanence means at least that all things are related; that the Absolute, the whole, is somehow involved in every part; and that consequently there may be a certain philosophic basis for symbolism in education. 3. Teleology. Froebel's theory of the divine element in edu- cation, broadly viewed, presents another aspect for discussion, that of teleology. Teleology, perhaps, may fairly be identified with ethical idealism, and again with the Aristotelian concep- tion of final cause.- In a way it is the supreme factor in ideal- 'Erinnerungen, etc., v. 28 as above. , . _ , 'Aristotle, Physics. Books I and II. MetaphysKS. I. 111. i. Philosophy of Froebel. 39 ism, because of the bond which it establishes between the ideal and the real, between realised and struggling spirit, between the divine and human, between Plato's pattern laid up in heaven and the Aristotelian process of becoming on earth. Teleology ventures to affirm that it is only the end which can explain the process that moves toward it ; and that true cause is not so much the sum of pre-existing necessary and sufficient conditions as the purpose or end which calls forth the whole process. Accord- ing to Idealism one may even expect a necessary connection between the notions of efficient or scientific, and final or tele- ological, cause. For the efficient cause of any change, which is the sum of all the relevant pre-existing conditions, seems ulti- mately to become indistinguishable from the constitution of the universe at large. How many thousand factors in the universe enter into the constitution of man? But if then the universe be structurally the efficient cause, so also must it not be the effect? It would seem to follow, as the doctrine of the con- servation of energy more clearly indicates, that true change is less in matter than in meaning. But the notion that change, or if one may put upon the word change an optimistic interpre- tation, progress, is a growth in fulness of meaning, would appear to imply that explanations should come rather from ends than origins, simply because the ends or realisations manifest the major significance. And this again is teleology. The stuff, as possibility, remains; but progress is through new forms, ideas, meanings and relations.^ Teleology perhaps implies the postu- late of healthy optimism, that the best is the true. It will decline to interpret man by the brute that he may have sprung from, preferring to interpret the brute by a supplementary reflux of light from man. It will affirm that Rousseau was mistaken in his appeal to nature in the sense of origin, because man is more true, more real, more valid than nature, in the sense that he is relatively her most significant realisation. As against all appeals to primitivism, teleology involves an unequivocal faith in pro- gress and a dynamic theory of life." God, said Froebel, has not 'Cf. Bosanquet's characterisation of cause as "change in the permanent," in the concluding chapter of his "Essentials of Logic." 'Expressed by Schiller in his ;3oem, Hoffntmg: 'Es ist kein leerer, schmeichelnder Wahn, Erzeugt im Gehime des Thoren, Im Herzen ktindet es laut sich an: Zu was Besserm sind wir geboren; Und was die innere Stimme spricht, Das ta.uscht die hofEende Seele nicht." 40 Herbart and Froebel. placed man on the narrow path of imitation, but on the broad road of development.^ It may fairly be admitted that Froebel's theory of development is teleological throughout, both because, on the one hand, he is confident that the free unfolding of the activities of the self will tend to the realisation of ideal or divine purposes ; and also for this further reason, that he finds in these purposes a standard for the interpretation of the education pro- cess. Education aims at bringing the soul into conscious har- mony with the development in which it functions and lives. The well-educated man, it might be submitted, is literally the man who has entered as a conscious determining agent, or as a free co-operative partner, into this development; who has in a sense taken over his own evolution, and achieved personal freedom along with the recognition of personal responsibilities. Morality, as the endeavour to transform the is into the ought, may possibly be described as the practice of teleology. Theoretically accord- ing to teleology, practically according to morality, the end to which all things are relative is a spiritual, divine nature, con- sciously achieved and realised.^ According to the doctrine of teleology, men as self-conscious beings are no longer merely impelled from behind, but also attracted from before; and even though their ideals may be in a sense the products of a past, this is made possible because their past itself stood in an organic relation to spirit, and is only explicable in the light of a present and future. Teleology is almost in itself a philosophy of education. It connects, as education must, two terminal aspects of a unitary process. It indicates a vital relation between possibilities and realisations, between powers and values, between instincts and thoughts, between impulses and freedom. It shows dimly, per- haps, but still it shows, what the child is to man, what man to the child. As an aspect of evolution, it seems to reconcile the Pestalozzian standard of the development of given powers with more obviously social and vicarious ends. But teleology is not only the condition of the possibility of education ; it is also a ground of the activity of the teacher in the educative process. One may none the less freely grant a sense in which education is passive, following, because the natural impulses of the child, ^Menschtn Eniehung, krsg. Seidd. 1883. p. n. 'Menschen Eniehung, hrsg. Seidel. 1883. p. 23. Philosophy of Froebel. 41 possibly by their pre-natal education in the race and in the species, clamor on the whole for social satisfactions, and are only wayward in their marginal vagaries. And yet the principal message of teleology to education is to be positive. If conscious- ness have any pragmatic validity, any use, if it be more than a mere " epiphenomenon ; " then the teacher, representing the social consciousness, will have to interfere and keep on interfering rela- tively to a consciously conceived end. To the realisation of this end everything else, even development, is subordinate. Thus a teleological theory of education, to be rational, may be said to subordinate and subject development itself to the idea of devel- opment. This is precisely what Froebel would do in his attempt to make family education consciotts; and to raise it from the level of an instinctive process to that of scientific method. Indeed, the moment reflection comes into play, to make devel- opment itself the end is meaningless. For the question is at once asked, what is this development that is made the end, and the answer is necessarily in terms of an idea of it. Man cannot well escape from the use of his reason; he must think, and in thinking set up a standard of what he conceives the true nature of development to be. This is as true for a metaphysical realist like Herbart as for a metaphysical idealist like Froebel. Ethic- ally, Herbart is perhaps as good an idealist as Froebel, in aiming as he does at a many sided interest and a good will. But there are those who find a greater discrepancy between the metaphys- ical and ethical positions of Herbart than those of Froebel. For Froebel the origin is God, and the end God ; so that for him the whole process of life has a spiritual, and one may almost say a religious, character. For Herbart the origin is independent reality, and the end phenomenal morality — a difficult transition. The final word in this preliminary interpretation of Froebel is that his central tliought was guidance. Sometimes he seems to say with Rousseau, follow nature; sometimes with Hegel, con- trol nature. " Follow nature '' means witli Froebel not only to foreswear force and to remove hindrances; it means also that there is a positive social and " divine " tendency in instincts and impulses themselves. " Control nature " means tliat this mere tendency to the good is to be consciously cherished, guided, and improved. To follow nature is as it were to look at education from the side of origin, or genetically. But Froebel saw values 42 Herbart and Froebel. too, and set them above origins. " Without rational, conscious guidance," he is reported to have said, " the activity of the child degenerates into idle games (Spielerei) , instead of preparing for the tasks of life unto which it is destined."^ It would almost seem from the above analysis that, since Froebel, we have not so much to add to his teaching, or even to correct it, as to evolve from it a completed philosophy of educa- tion. Yet there is perhaps in his teaching at times an ambiguity, at times a hyper-symbolism, at times an imperfection. The way to escape the dangers of these and the Uke faults, which are in general rather tendencies than faults properly so called, is to study another philosophy of education, the philosophy of Her- bart. This will be found to be largely antithetic to Froebel's, and yet in such a way that the two philosophies are to a large extent the complements of one another. Before turning to Herbart, one may perhaps pay a final tribute to Froebel's contribution to a philosophy of education. His chief ideas, of self-activity as the force operative in education, of development as the process of education, of freedom as the path of education, and duty or service as the standard of values for education, these have all stood the test of time unchanged except in their development to a richer concreteness. Accordingly it is difficult for an idealist to read Froebel without feeling himself to be fundamentally a Froebelian. Let his philosophy savour as it will of eclecticism from Kant, Schelling, Fichte and Krause, let his practical recommendations fall short as they must of the counsel of perfection, still it is impossible not to perceive a fundamental unity in his philosophy and a fundamental truth in his practice. His voice is the voice of a prophet and a reformer. His theory may be said to center about that maxim of idealism, or rather if you will of teleology, the best is the true, as his prac- tice lives in his own motto. Come let us live for our children. ^Erinntrungen an Frtedrich Froehel. Bulow. Kassel, 1876. p. 45. CHAPTER II. The Philosophy of Herbart. It may be said of Herbart that, unlike Froebel, he stepped out of the line of development from Kant to Hegel in order to fashion a link in another and a divergent chain. For it is possible to distinguish two modes of the post-Kantian philosophical devel- opment. The idealism of Kant was developed by Fichte, Schel- ling, and Hegel ; and his realism by Herbart, Beneke, and Lotze. It may be indicated how logical and perhaps inevitable this bifur- cation was. To go back to the beginning, Kant had discovered a new mode of approach to the fundamental problem of reality. Instead of accepting the external or sensational as the basis of the interpretation of mind, he preferred as it were to reverse the problem; and, beginning with mind, to inquire how its a priori activities may be possible. He found that sensation can do no more than to furnish the raw material of thought, upon which in all knowledge the mind has to impose a contribution of its own. In this way, so far as the world of conceptions goes, Kant became an idealist. At the same time, he regarded his analysis as valid only for thought, and not for things as such. In this distinction lay the germ of a dualism which idealists have ever since endeav- oured to transcend and realists to make intelligible. There are those who would not think it unfair to maintain that in spirit Kant was an idealist, and only by reservation a realist. Others, among whom must be reckoned Herbart, held that the Kantian dualism between the real and the rational is fundamental and metaphysically irreducible. Ultimate reality consists for this school in a plurality of independent reals, unknowable, because ■other than the phenomena registered or capable of being regis- tered by consciousness. To this position Herbart stood faithful, unable to subscribe to the idealistic construction which Fichte based upon Kant's Critique of Judgment. " In one word," as Herbart declares in the preface to his Allgemeine Metaphysik, " the author is a Kantian ... if however of the year 1828, and not of the times of the Categories and the Critique of Judg- ment, as the diligent reader will soon observe."^ ^Allgemeine Metaphysik. Kfinigsberg. 1828. Vorrede, pp. xxvi. — xxviii. 44 Herbert and Froebel. The realism of Herbart has nothing in common with mate- rialism. The reals, the things-in-themselves, that for Herbart underlie the phenomenal world, may even be psychically inter- preted; Herbart leaves this indeterminate. Certainly Herbart is ethically an idealist, if idealism, ethically interpreted, mean the guidance of life by an idea. Further, even in the more onto- logical sense, Herbart is perhaps not wholly debarred by his realism from accepting spirit as a constitutive principle in the universe. For to Herbart as to Kant, time and space are sub- jectively determined rather than externally given. Again, Her- bart's reals, whether psychic or no, can by no means be materially conceived. Matter to Herbart is mere appearance ; and the reals behind it are according to Herbart's whole argument something heterogeneous to it, its unknown noumenal origin. The realist is then so far from being the materialist that he does not even hold matter to be real. In a sense only the idealist is a true believer in its reality. To put the matter in another way, the metaphysical question between idealism and realism may be said to center about the word merely, as employed in the follow- ing context. To the realist, the world as known is merely appearance. To the idealist also it is appearance; but not appearance merely, because to the idealist in a sense there is nothing else, save appearance and its potentiality. For idealism reality is nothing save as related to some consciousness ; and again, if anything does appear to any consciousness, it must have reality in some way and to some degree. For a realist a thing is flatly real or not real, for an idealist it is real to the extent of its relations, for a pragmatist it is real to the extent of its func- tions. An idealist would say that the fact that the existence of the world, for a thinking subject, can only be explained on the basis of the rationality of nature, is not to be interpreted as making the world unreal, but as making its reality conceivable. The world that is mere appearance to Herbart is to Froebel real appearance. This characterisation of the realism of Herbart, in contrast with the idealism of Froebel, is merely introductory. In the present chapter, the attempt will be made to treat, firstly, the philosophical relations of Herbart; secondly, the principles of his metaphysic ; and thirdly, the foundations and the fundamental implications of the Herbartian psycholog}-. Philosophy of Herbart. 45 I. I. Herbart and Leibnitz. In the Allgemeine Metaphysik, Herbart begins with the remark that if he were looking for a stately entrance to the realm of metaphysical speculation, he could find it nowhere more conveniently given than in the philosophy of Leibnitz. For to Leibnitz the world was a thoroughly inter- related whole, endlessly extended, without empty space, and in every smallest part infinitely full of monads or individual real existences. It may be held therefore to consist of an infinite number of real parts, each monad among which is possessed of an incessant activity, so that according to Leibnitz no substance can be perfectly at rest, and no soul utterly dormant. A kind of perception and striving goes on, even in unreasoning monads or reals. For Leibnitz, again, each monad has a capacity for reproducing the whole in detail. Each monad is in fact a mirror of the world, conformably to its own status. And yet, with all this fulness and greatness, the real world is not regarded as exhausting the law of possibilities. God chose it, thought Leib- nitz, as the best of all possible worlds. By a single undivided and indivisible fiat, He raised it into reality out of the realm of potentialities. This metaphysic has the merits of completeness and suggestiveness ; and, as Herbart remarks with a touch of mild satire, there remained for the school of Leibnitz only one arduous task, such a doctrine — to prove. Herbart considered that the school of Leibnitz had by no means succeeded in establishing the principles of the Monadology. Even Kant's reform did not satisfy him, much less the culmina- tion of that reform in the idealism of Reinhold, Fichte and Schel- ling. All this was to Herbart as it were a period of storm and exhaustion, duly to be followed by renewed efforts at rehabilita- tion. One such effort he himself inaugurated. He believed that in the rehabilitation, or reconstruction, of philosophy, monads might well reappear, but hardly following the method or views of Leibnitz. Rather must the monads be reinterpreted in the light of the " spiritualism "^ of the newer^ psychology and the atomism of the newer^ chemistry. Herbart adds that contempo- rary idealism has served its purpose as the embodiment of a ^Der Spir-itualismus. H. c. in 1828. 46 Herbert and Froebel. method of transition to clearer insight.^ Possibly this may be granted, and yet there may be no unanimity as to what consti- tutes the clearer insight; whether Herbart's solution, or that of Hegel. 2. Ethical views. It was Herbart's contention that the older metaphysic, for want of determinate bound and form, had sur- rendered to the comparatively external influences of the empi- rical detail of psychology, and the science of esthetics, " especially its most important part, ethics."" Ethics, as belonging to the world of appearance, had for Herbart no metaphysical validity, except in the looser sense in which the esthetic judgment may be called metaphysical. On the other hand with Fichte and Froebel, and in a sense Kant, ethics is fundamental to metaphysics, in that Fichte, Kant and Froebel explain and warrant that which is only by that which ought to be. Severing as he did the ethical from the metaphysical, Herbart could not consider the freedom of the will a strictly metaphysical problem, with the idealist. For Herbart, to attribute freedom or servitude to the will is a purely esthetic judgment; and to hold it to be more than this is to fall into the error of regarding the esthetic judgment, which concerns only the will, as if it indicated also the hidden ground of the will, with which it really has nothing to do. Herbart illustrated this so-called confusion from the controversy of Leibnitz and Clarke. Leibnitz said: "A will without motive is like the chance of Epicurus, a contra- dictory fiction, incompatible with the idea of will." Clarke replied : " The principle of action is quite separate from the motive." Herbart acutely pointed out that to deny motivation is to abolish the standard of moral worth, because the morality of an action could no longer be determined by the difference between good and evil.^ Again, Clarke insisted that nothing is worthy the name of action unless it may have proceeded from a power that was also a power not to act. To this Leibnitz responded that the mind that sets the weaker desire above the stronger is acting against itself. If Herbart inclines to one side or the other in this discussion, it is probably to the side of Leib- nitz ; but it is his feeling that Leibnitz and Clarke alike have failed to distinguish between the will itself, as esthetic judgment, ^Attgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 25. ^Alleemeine Metaphysik. Par. 30. 'Ibid. Par. 31. Philosophy of Herbart. 47 and its ultimate metaphysical ground. Herbart grants the will as it were an esthetic freedom, of the nature of a harmony between desire and satisfaction, but this freedom is for him noth- ing transcendental, nothing metaphy|Sical, nothing real. The relation of will to motive, which Leibnitz and Clarke disputed, was not a real problem to Herbart. His ethical problem was merely the relation of will to judgment. To Froebel, on the contrary, morality and freedom were real metaphysical problems centering about the question of motiva- tion. It may seem hardly fair to set Froebel, with his mere intuition, backed by a philosophical reading and training inferior to Herbart's, although not to be despised, over against one of the keenest and subtlest of metaphysicians in a discussion con- cerning freedom. Indeed it is not fair unless Froebel be sym- pathetically interpreted. This done, Froebel seems to say: yes, the will is motivated, but because it makes the motive its own through self-identification with one of its desires, one may say that it is free just because it is motivated. It is ruled in a way by desires, but the desires are also its own. It is impelled in a way by circumstances, but these circumstances are so far from external that in the process of being converted by the self from apparent masters to real servants they become instrumental to self-realisation. 3. The relation of Herbart to Kant. " The possible indicates the idea, but the real indicates the object and its position."^ This was the distinction by which, according to Herbart, Kant succeeded in effecting a revolution in metaphysic. In denying that the idea is the reality, Kant became the founder of modern realism, just as he is the founder of modern idealism by virtue of his demonstration that the idea is the real for us. Kant had held that the idea is the same, whether of a hundred real dollars or a hundred possible dollars, and yet the reality is different. An idealist might deny that the idea is the same ; but from this dis- tinction, such as it is, Herbart takes his departure. He believed it to involve a true theory of reality. But how, he asks, did Kant apply this theory ? What has Kant posited as being f This is a question to which the Kantian metaphysic is dumb ; and it is the question which Herbart devoted himself to answer. Herein Herbart would supplement Kant, he would analyse the true 'Kant. KriHk der reinen Vermmft. Par. 627. 48 Herbart and Froebel. nature of reality, of noumenal being, as opposed to mere appear- ance, or that which is changeable and phenomenal. Thus whereas idealism has no use for the Ding-an-sich, the imchange- able and unknowable kernel of reality beneath or behind the phenomenal world, it is to Herbart the principal feature of the Kantian dialectic. Herbart only regrets that Kant has not analysed or explained this " true " notion of being. It is not to be thought that Herbart would set things on one side, thought on the other ; and then try to get the things some- how into an alien mind. He did not sever objects from thought; he severed objects and thought alike from true being or reality. He was glad to think that Kant had done away with the older form of the metaphysical problem, so that the question was no longer, how do objects become intelligible to us? After the Kantian Critiques, says Herbart, it can no longer be held that things are just there, and admit of comprehension " by the onto- logical predicate."^ In future one may take ideas just in the same way as things, according as one finds them, since both the one and the other are for us, in us, and through us. After Kant, in short, the notion necessarily developed, that thought and things cannot except in an abstract way be separated; that they are not given the one without and the other within the self, but both in a unity, and this unity consciousness. This would have been a solution grateful to Leibnitz, for whom the soul appeared to bring forth all ideas from an inner activity subject only to the regulation of a pre-established harmony. So Herbart say^, and adds that the true difference between Kant and Leibnitz con- sisted in this, that the Kantian theory continued to admit the possibility of a sense-receptivity, without being impaled upon either horn of the dilemma of dualism. But Kant's work had been essentially critical, and had not essayed a theory of being. " Kant's work was intended to form a Critique, but not a sys- tem. He did not try to accomplish, what rightly forms the central task of metaphysics, namely to elucidate what is matter, and what spirit.''- That this is a fair characterisation is shown not only by Kant's usage of the word critique, but much more by the sjTithetic activity of both realists and idealists after his day, to whom he had at least as it were propounded a 'Allgtmtine Melaphysik. Par. 33. 'AUgemnnt Metophysik. 1838. Par. 30. Philosophy of Herbart. 49 set of questions that could only be adequately answered after decades, if ever. Herbart agrees that the theory of Kant offers two ostensible advantages, an explanation of matter and an account of the free- dom of the will. Passing reference has already been made in this chapter to Herbart's repudiation of transcendental freedom.^ Nor is he more content vAih Kant's opinion that the substantiality of matter is only a form of thought, which Herbart dismisses as a fallacy characteristic of Kantian demi-idealism. Here it may be clearer to quote Herbart's OAvn argument. " The whole difficulty of the idea of matter lies in this, that it should be real and in space.* As real, it must consist of monads; as in space, it must needs be a continuum. But these two demands are abso- lutely incompatible. Kant sacrificed the former; and he could do this easily, because according to his opinion the substantiality of matter is only a form of thought. The advantage of this ^^ew seemed very great; for now nothing stands in the way, we can throw ovusdves into the arms of geometrj' and mathematical idiysics without reserve, without closer criticism. How should anyone, who esteems mathematics aright, fail to be deeply rejoiced? . . And yet the advantage was nothing but an illusion; Kant's doctrine of nature is false from beginning to end."' Herbart admits the monads and denies the continuimi, which he none the less uses as a methodological postulate. As to the post-Kantian philosophers, it seemed to Herbart that they had only made confusion worse confounded. They had in his opinion inextricably and disastrously commingled ideas that to his mind were almost disparate, the ideas namely of the possible, the real and the necessary. Kant had done well, thought Herbart, to definitely sever the notions of being and duty ■* but only to have them confused over again in the systems of his idealistic followers. Herbart agreed that Kant had also done well to suggest the iration of a harmony between the law of dut}' and the activity' of the will. This very harmony is what Herbart calls inner freedom." So far as this definition goes, an idealist might agree to it, were it not that his characterisation ^Section a. ^Ikiss sie ein rjumiiches RttUts srin soil. \A.Ugcmsi9is yietaphysik. Par. 39. *S*in and SolUn, KAUifmrm* Metaphysik. Konigsberg, 1828. Par. 30 (I. p. 116) 50 Herbert and Froebel. of the activity of the will would differ materially from that of Herbart. Kant however probably never intended his distinction between Sein and Sollen to be ultimate. At any rate, having separated them in the Critique of Pure Reason, he brought them once more into a single teleological process in the more synthetic, more idealistic. Critique of Judgment. With the latter Critique, to Fichte the most inspiring of all Kant's works, Herbart had but little sympathy. " It refers to an ideal world wherein reality and duty coincide to such an extent that the first condition of all esthetic judgments, namely the entire severance of two members of a relation, and consequently the value of the harmony between insight and will to which reference has already been made, must vanish. But an ideal world, wherein moral values are reduced to nothing, is not for us."^ To the latter sentence an idealist might give in his adherence, but hardly either to the antithesis or rather divorce of reality and duty, or the identification of morality with an esthetic harmony. Meantime Herbart's argu- ment may perhaps be stated in the following terms. Morality consists in an " esthetic " harmony between knowledge and will ; but if the is and the ought in any sense coincide, then knowledge and will become identical and morality disappears. At the root of this reasoning seems to lie Herbart's inclination for rigid antitheses. For him the is and the ought are either one, or not one ; and he will not see with the idealist a unity in difference, or a good in error. Thus Herbart recognises in symbolism only a burden on education ; nor has he much of Froebel's faith that what is will naturally tend to become what ought to be. 4. The relation of Herbart to Spinoza and Leibnitz. Herbart looked for inspiration not only to Kant, but beyond him to Spinoza and Leibnitz, chiefly the latter. Spinoza had begun with the Cartesian view of substance, as that which exists uncon- ditioned by anything else. This substance is not only the cause of all finite things, it also is them; and to it Spinoza gives the name of God. It is defined as causa sui, because the essence of it involves existence. This divine substance then is invested by the human understanding with the two attributes of matter and spirit, which are however merely contingent. But what of the specific forms in which substance is particularised? These ^AHeemeini Metaphysik. Kcnigsberg. i8a8. Par. 39. Philosophy of Herbert. 51 Spinoza calls modi. Man is a modus. Modi are to Spinoza no more than temporary expressions of substance, even as waves of the sea. They have no freedom, and only a borrowed reality. Mere matter, as Herbart insists, is therefore no more real to Spinoza than to Leibnitz or Kant. " Leibnitz arrived at monads ; the merely extended was not to him the true. Spinoza explained substance as indivisible, therefore to him also that which is divisible is not the true. Both united thought to the true (reality) ; Leibnitz set it in every individual monad, Spinoza in the whole. Kant . . . explained matter as mere appearance."^ Whatever then the Herbartian metaphysic may seem to imply for education, it turns away from materialism. For Herbart as for Spinoza, Kant and Leibnitz, matter is not itself real. The Kantian metaphysic appealed to Herbart even more than that of Leibnitz or Spinoza ; for it was Herbart's belief that Kant alone had the true idea of being or reality, which the older school had constructed out of essence and existence. This theory of the older school, because it explained reality as though reality itself were constituted by something behind it, was inconsistent with Herbart's view of reality as mere position, that is to say, as something merely posited, although a form of the older theory was not without its contemporary champion in Jacobi. The meta- physic of Spinoza, which lends itself so readily to an idealistic construction that it became an invaluable source of inspiration to the post-Kantian idealists, admitted of varying degrees of reality. The more pregnant the potentiality, the richer the causa immanens, the greater would the fulness of reality be. " Everywhere one can see the notion peeping through, that reality primarily reveals itself in its manifestations, in its effects ; and therefore if it did not so show itself, it would be nothing ! "^ False as this Spinozistic theory may be to the principles of the Herbartian metaphysic, for which reality has neither degree nor quality, it may appear to the modern reader to anticipate in a remarkable way one of the fundamental positions of contemporary pragmatism. Herbart had more sympathy with Leibnitz than with Spinoza. Even what seemed to be errors in Leibnitz were attributed by ^AUgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 57. ^Allgemeine Metaphysik. Par, 72. 52 Herbart and Froebel. Herbart to the misfortune of the former in living before the development of a new chemistry and physics. Had Leibnitz but lived in post-Kantian times, he might have lost all desire to develop the germ of idealism, der Keim des Idealismus, that lay enveloped in his theory of a pre-established harmony. The ideal- ism of Leibnitz was hidden from himself, or at least so thought Herbart; and had Leibnitz lived in a later age, his own scientific sympathies might have at the least alienated him from the romanticist school. As against Spinoza, yet conformably to the view of Herbart, Leibnitz ventured to be a pluralist. For him reality did not cleave together in an indivisible substance; but consisted of independent monads following their own destinies.^ Powerfully influenced as he admitted himself to be in his pluralism and realism by the atomic theory which was then supreme in chem- istry, Herbart believed it to imply that the independence of the monads might be less absolute than Leibnitz had in his own day imagined. In that case the pre-established harmony might have been dispensed with, and a better understanding might have been reached on the subject of the relation of mind and body. Mind and body according to Herbart interact, but have not the parallel- ism suggested by the Leibnitzian pre-established harmony or the Spinozistic doctrine that the order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things.' 5. The relation of Herbart to Fichte and Schelling. To Fichte and Schelling the unknowable residuum of reality, or the thing in itself, which Kant had postulated in order to explain cognis- able phenomena, and which Herbart had welcomed as perhaps Kant's chief contribution to metaphysical theory, seemed little more than an aberration from a truer idealism. They belonged to a period of which it was said that metaphysic had died heir- less, and the things-in-themselves had been put to auction.* Fichte seems to have commanded Herbart's respect; but not his adherence. Of Fichte's Wissenschaftlehre Herbart writes : " It is a wild landscape, but the landscape is nature."* To intro- duce a new problem into metaphysic, this is no small achievement, and this in a way is what Fichte did. His new problem was that of the self or Ego. Fichte held the self to be absolute. For ^Allsemeine Metaphysik. Par. 70. ^Ordo el connexio idearum idem est ac ordo el conntxio rerum. 'Da die Metaphysik vor Kurzem unbeerbt abging, Werden die Dinge-an-sich jeta sub hasta verkauft. *Allgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 96. Philosophy of Herbart. S3 him there was no place for things-in-themselves, because the outer world was but a Nicht-Ich, a non-Ego, a self-set limitation. To Herbart on the contrary the Ego is not the whole problem of metaphysic. The Ego is given, is therefore possible; and the object of enquiry is merely its condition. " My whole impulse," wrote Fichte in the Wissenschaftlehre, " is derived from absolute independence and self-sufficiency; before I have recognised it as such I have not completely determined myself, nor, in contradistinction to myself, things."^ Fichte's meta- physical system mystically concludes in the complete annihila- tion of the individual, and his blending or merging in the pure absolute pattern of reason. Freedom may be said to be the cardinal principle of Fichte ; for if phenomena themselves be self-determined, it follows that determination by phenomena is only a veiled self-determination that in no wise may limit the transcendental self. Fichte spoke of the self as though no problem existed outside of it. The modern idealist is content to claim that no problem exists for the self which is unrelated to it. For Schelling, as a romanticist and almost a mystic, Herbart seems to feel less regard than for Fichte. Ever since Kant, he thought, philosophy had in a sense degenerated, but with Schel- ling came the deluge. " The most perverted counted now for the best, and Kant's authority served to fortify attempts that were as immature as they were visionary."^ Yet, admitting the diffi- culty of interpreting Schelling aright, admitting his trick of leaving the common paths of reason for the by-ways of romanti- cism, and even admitting the consequent barbarity of his scientific deductions, it remains true that not only does Schelling write as one inspired, but also that his doctrine of nature may be regarded as a wholesome corrective to Fichte's subjectivism. Those principles which Herbart called the Schellingian preju- dices, that philosophy must be monistic, and that the principle of knowledge must be the principle of reality, are not only vital to Froebel's educational theory; but probably, if rightly inter- preted, to idealism. Again, though to Herbart none of Schel- ling's principles was less welcome than unity in plurality, there are now few principles as assured, especially since the doctrine ^Cj. Herbart, Alleemeine Metaphysik. Konigsberg, 1828, Par. 96 (I. p. 282). ^Allgemeitie Metaphysik. Par. 39 (Vol. I. p. 122). 54 Herbart and Froebel. of organic evolution, as ideal unity in a manifold of parts. " One would think that with Schelling everything is possible. . Unity in the manifold is with Schelling by no means impossible ; since unity is postulated, and the manifold is given."^ This is for Herbart a contradiction. The unity itself would have to be manifold, and therefore no unity. It might however be replied that the contradiction is verbal and logical only; that, further, it is transcended even in thought in the category of organism. Here the educator needs to choose between Herbart and Schel- ling ; for the notion of the one in many, unintelligible to Herbart but vital to Schelling and Froebel, is the principle of symbolic education. The argument for symbolism, very briefly recapitu- lated, is that the world is a system, such that the whole is implied in each part, and in such a way that the implication is dis- cernible at least for the man of genius. Possibly one may set over against this theory, without destroying it, the guarded empiricism of Herbart's attitude towards nature. " The true nature-seeker," Herbart writes, " is accustomed to be anxious for fear that his notions may not be able to attain to the heights of nature. Schelling is anxious, for fear that nature may not reach up to his own notions. And he has reason to be so! For what particular attains to the whole? But, according to Schel- ling, what particular can fail to be the whole? Where, where is the unity of his bond, if nature will not obey, if it will not ful- fil the expectations of the man of genius ? "^ H. Having now an idea of the philosophical relations of Herbart, one may proceed to an analysis of his metaphysic. For the psy- chology and the educational theory of Herbart are not ultimately intelligible apart from his theory of reality and his theory of knowledge. The theory of knowledge, or epistemology, will be found to be connected not only with the theory of reality, or ontology; but also, and that in an intimate way, with the Her- bartian psychology and education. I. The methodology of Herbart. The terminology of the metaphysic of Herbart may require a brief word of explanation. ^Atleemeint Metaphysik. Par. 104. ^Jbid. Par. 107. Philosophy of Herbart. 55 The subject falls, he would say, into two classes, general meta- physics, and applied metaphysics. The scope of applied meta- physics includes cosmology, psychology, and natural theology. Ontology, in the large sense, involves the treatment of method- ology, ontology proper, synechology, and eidolology. Of these, methodology is the treatment of principles and methods. Ontol- ogy proper comprises the doctrines of being, becoming, substance, and cause. Synechology is literally the doctrine of the contin- uum, including space, time, motion, and the most general appli- cation of these ideas to life and nature. Finally eidolology, or the doctrine of phenomena as such, comprises attempts to dis- cern how far ideas may be able to furnish us with a true cogni- tion. Eidolology is the virtual equivalent of epistemology. Herbart begins the Methodology with the remark that the dif- ference between the scholar on the one hand, and the teacher or independent thinker on the other hand, is that the former is con- tent to see nature taken to pieces and put together again, like a machine, before his eyes; but not so the latter. He, the inde- pendent thinker, seeks to know how one may begin to find the real. First of all, then, he asks what is given. Is the unity of all things given? Yes, Froebel seems to say;^ but no, answers Herbart. " Neither the whole, nor the one, is given."^ But what then is given? Why, answers Herbart, that which is given is experience. Things are brought before the mind by the psy- chological mechanism natural to man. They appear as com- plexes of attributes,' apparently extended in space, changeable, doing and suffering things done. Metaphysic has to investigate the validity of these common sense views. To this investigation Herbart would attach almost a pragmatic significance. In other words, metaphysic is to be not only reflection ; but reflection with power, or comprehension. Philosophical reflection has at all times, says Herbart, seen the given, that is to say experience, as matter and form. What then are the matter and form of experience, and to what extent may they be subject to philosophical criticism? "The matter of the given is feeling. This was never an object of doubt, and can never become so."* But, adds Herbart, the form is an object of •As in the opening paragraphs o£ the Education of Man. ^Allgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 165. ^Complexiontn von Merkmalen. *AUgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 169. 56 tierbart and Froebel. doubt, because it is not immediately given in the way that feeling is immediately given. Kant therefore did well to criticise the forms or categories of experience ; and this, Kant's procedure, is also Herbart's. None the less would Herbart admit that ulti- mately the categories of experience are given, only not immedi- ately. It was his conviction that he who considers the series of ideas, the laws of their reproduction, and the results of their tendencies to complication and fusion, will come to think " that those systems overlook a great deal, which, bowing to idealism, would persuade him that the forms of experience must be deduced from original forms of the possibility of knowledge."^ Whether or no the forms or categories of the mind be an orig- inal factor in experience, Herbart was as convinced as Kant that they should be subjected to a critical investigation rather than be accepted at their face value. Space appears to be a merely relative limitation. Time is a measure of change. Causality itself can hardly be explained as the mere succession of ante- cedents and consequents. But if time, space and causation are not what they seem, may not this be equally true of reality ; and therefore, may not the current valuation of reality be subject to a similar discount? The idealists, as Herbart not unfairly suggests, must have reality in the soul, in consciousness. Here only, in self-con- sciousness, if anywhere at all, is certainty, reality and truth. Cogito, ergo sum. Yet, to Herbart's way of thinking, it is an error thus to posit one element of experience as the reality which explains it all. Everything that is given in experience counts originally for real, and its claim to reality is only suspended, not denied, when we find that we cannot think of it in the form in which it was first given. Accordingly all that is needful is that the notion of reality should be separated from the quality which is ascribed to it by the common-sense intuition. The question is no longer what is reality, but what sort of reality, and this is the problem of Herbart's Ontology.' In fairness to Herbart it may be repeated that he would begin with experience, and end with experience, and that his reals or monads are no more designed to express the meaning of the world than a scaffold the meaning of a building. 'Ibid. Par. 170. 'AUgemeint Metaphysik. KSnigbserg, i8»8. Par. loj. Philosophy of Herbart. 57 2. The ontology of Herbart. The Ontology opens with a logical criticism of the term real.^ A ship sails by the shore. From her deck the trees upon land seem to move, but their movement is not real, while the movement of the ship is real. Again, paper is different from flax. The diflference is real, and yet the paper is really one and the same with the flax, the linen, from which it is made. In these illustrations three realities are typified, those namely of a movement, and of a condition, and of a substarice. But again, one may differentiate between a thing being real and being reality. If a man discover new properties in a thing, is it correct to say that he has discovered more reality? According to Herbart, it is hardly so. All that can be said is that he has learned to know reality in a new way. The reality is the thing itself, and not its properties ; which are called indeed real, but not reality.'' Thus perhaps even the vulgar use and wont of speech, pressed into the service of philosophic argu- ment, might have exposed the " error " of Spinoza, that how many attributes a thing has, so much has it of reality.^ Only in appearance, thinks Herbart, do attributes measure reality. The so-called " real " movement of a ship, the " real " difference of paper and flax, and the " real " identity of both, for Herbart belong alike in the last analysis to the world of mere phenomena. Therefore for Herbart true reality has nothing in common with these ostensibly real happenings. The reality that is the ground and source of all phenomena must be sought outside of the phenomena themselves. It must exclude change, which as the specious concurrence of irreducible atoms cannot have meta- physical reality. It is true that this conclusion was favoured and probably suggested by an atomic theory of chemistry that is not so well accredited at the present day. But perhaps, if change be not real, there is nothing real. " Therefore we will utter the dictum ; Nothing is ! There is no reality,"* Yet not for long is this scepticism conceivable; it barely flits across the path of the Herbartian dialectic and reap- pears no more. " Let a man plunge into nothingness as he will, the course of the world goes steadily on. Now a man may very easily find the way from the world to nothing, but then he finds H. e. wirklich. 'Allgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 19S. ^Allgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 197. */6«o. Par. 190. 58 Herbart and Froebel. the path of return closed to him. He cannot return again from nothingness to the world! Of every thing, of every event it may be said, you are nothing, and you do nothing. But things go on appearing; and involve us in the question, whence then can the appearance come? For it is clear that if nothing is, then nothing must appear."^ So there is something real, and yet it is not appearance. " We have now the given, as the actual appearance, whether it be of things, or conditions, or movements, as opposed to the red, which lies at its foundation."* All that is so far ascertained of this real is that it is positive. An effectual appearance can- not be explained by a negative reality. " The quality of the real is entirely positive or affirmative, without admixture of nega- tion."^ Also the real must be einfach, simple. For suppose it to be manifold, and to contain two determinations, A and B. Then these cannot by our hypothesis be reducible to a unity, or else this unity, and not A and B, would be the true quality of the real. But then, A and B would each without the other be insuffi- cient to constitute the real; they would be merely relative, and reality would lose its absolute, positive character. Reality is then positive and simple. Unto these conclusions Herbart would add two others. " The quality of the real is absolutely inacces- sible to all ideas of quantity," for a manifold real would con- tradict simplicity. " How much, or how many, is, remains quite undetermined by the idea of the real."* In other words, though each real be necessarily simple, there may be many reals. The distinction is between manifold in reality and manifold of reality, of which the former only is forbidden, and the latter admissible. Having now arrived at a more definite notion of reality, as something made up of positive and simple reals, Herbart turns to the venerable problem of inherence. For him the common sense theory of reality as somewhat in which different attributes inhere is quite contradictory. Indeed the phenomenon of inher- ence is the indication of a plurality of reals. For suppose that a thing, A, have several attributes, a, b, c, etc. Then, according to the common sense view, A is their seat and substance, and is a real. But if a real, A is simple, and so must be equal to a, b, c, ^Allgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 190. ^Ibia, Par. aoo. >lbid. Par. 206. *Al!gemeint Mttaphysik. Par. ao8. Philosophy of Herbart. 59 etc., separately, rather than to a+h+c+etc, which would make A a complex. We have now this contradictory result, that A, which is absolute, is equal to a, to b, to c, etc., which are merely inherent in it. This is surely a contradiction, unless it be that a, b, c, etc., are as it were contingent aspects of A, just as the square root of 64, or 2 raised to the third power, are contingent aspects of 8. But this is evidently not the case. The only solu- tion of the difificulty is to posit several As. It does not neces- sarily follow that any one of these will be equal to a, or b, or c. All that can be said is that the attributes a, b, c, etc., arise out of the combination of several As ; or in other words, that sub- stance is the index or witness of a plurality of reals.^ And now the dilemma of inherence is circumvented. Sub- stance is for Herbart " not a thing with many attributes, and it alone does not lie at the root of these attributes, but a manifold of reals must be postulated for every one of them."" For the attribute a may be understood the combination of reals A.'+A'+A'-\-etc., for the attribute b, K"+K"+A."+etc., and so on, v/here the sign + is used to indicate mere connexion and not addition. It remains to account for the unity of attributes in one substance. This difficulty Herbart meets by the hypothesis of the identity of the first real in each combination. " It is understood of itself that the first term in all these series must be the same; and that the series should radiate as it were from the one center."' In conclusion, what now is the thing of com- mon sense? For Herbart it is not a sum or a system of attri- butes, as idealism tends to insist, but it has these attributes, only that which has these attributes is not the indivisible substance of a Spinozist metaphysic but the connection of a plurality of reals. It follows from Herbart's ontology that there is no real change. Education is not real, character is not real, life itself is not real if one has the will to believe Herbart. The horror of these thoughts is mitigated by the recollection that for Herbart the real is not the valuable. For him the real has no value; life, education, character, the highest. The common sense view of change is that a substance varies its attributes. A, that was once a, b, c, etc., is now a, b, d, etc. ^AUgemeine Meiaphysik. Par. 215. nbid. Par. 218. 'Allgemeine Meiaphysik. Par. 218. 6o Herbart and Froebel. On reflection this proves unthinkable. According to Herbart, the real situation is that a arises out of the connexion of reals A'+K'+K'+etc., b from the connection A"+A"+A"+etc., c from the connection A"'+A"'+A"'+ etc., and d from the con- nexion A""+A""+A""+etc. Then the apparent change of A, from a, b, c, etc., to a, b, d, etc., really means that A has no longer its original connexion with the series A"'-^A!"-\-A"'+etc., but has entered into a connexion with the series A""-l-A""+A""-l- etc. Reality is the same as before. But the question now arises, what is the nature of this mys- terious connexion^ of the reals? In other words, now that being has been explained, how is it possible to explain happening? It was from happenings, from experiential phenomena, that Her- bart took his departure, and it is these which he is vitally con- cerned to explain. What can happen to the qualities of simple reality, or what can happen beyond them? Or how does that which happens in connexion with them lend itself to an interpre- tation of experience? The answer to this question is the key to Herbart's epistemology and his psychology. Whatever happens when the reals come into connexion must be regarded as ultimate causation. Now let two reals A and B be represented b)'^ contingent aspects, as A by a+j8 + y and B by m+n—y. When A and B come into connexion, there will then be left only a+^+m+n as perceptible contingent aspects of A and B. The reals are unchanged ; but their contingent aspects are alterable. " But then nothing happens ! Everything stays just as it is ! How can anything happen, when the real merely remains like itself ? "" The only outlet is in the condition of the apparent happenings. In the illustration, the reals A and B may be regarded as differing in the quality of their contingent aspects to the extent y, so that on coming into connexion they tend to disturb one another to this extent y. But A and B as unchange- able reals must preserve themselves against the tendency to a disturbance. A has still to be equal to a+^ + y and B to m+n—y, in order that apparently A-l-B may be equal to a + p+m+n. Thus A and B have preserved themselves to the extent y. ^Zusammensein. 'Allgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 335. Lotze {Mttaphysics, Book I. Chapter II.) repeats this question and rejects the solution which Herbart has to offer. Philosophy of Herbart. 6i It is now possible to summarise the argument of Herbart con- cerning change. It is the resultant of the contact of two or more reals which differ in the quality of their contingent aspects. Acts of self-preservation are performed by the reals to the extent of their difiference in quality, and out of these self-preservations as manifested in the alteration of contingent aspects is generated the appearance of change. And now, how does man stand in relation to phenomena and to reality? Herbart is ready with the following answer: " Granted that a spectator should stand at such a point that he should not know the simple quality, but should be himself involved in the different relations of A to B, C, D, and so forth ; then all that remains visible to him is the peculiarity of the indi- vidual self-preservations, not the constant similarity of their origin and their result. This is the standpoint of Man.^ So Herbart comes to regard feelings as the self-preservations of the soul, which is ignorant at once of its own nature, and of the fact that its experiences, all-important as they are to itself, depend upon happenings in connection with reals outside of it, of whose own self-preservations it can know nothing. 3. The Cosmology of Herbart. In the Synechology or Cos^ mology Herbart reverses the analytic procedure by which in the Ontology he has arrived at the fundamental doctrines of his realism. Arduous is now the task before him, no less than to reconstruct from his reals, and from the theory of their self-preservations, the world of human experience. Few will maintain that Herbart has succeeded here. In order to explain the appearance of matter he introduced what he re- garded as a fictitious category, that of a continuum, or of partially overlapping points, precisely as the mathematician employs so imaginary a quantity as \/— i. The use which Herbart makes of this methodological device is ingenious. For although in the case of two reals A and B the reals must disturb one another to the extent of their difference in quality, yet, do we suppose three or more reals in con- nexion, we are obliged to conceive a preservation that appears no more than partial. In reality the preservation must be complete, because the reals, are unalterable, but it will appear to be incomplete. For B as against A and A' ^Allgemeine Mttaphysik. Konigsberg, i8s8. Par. 236. 62 Herbart and Froebel. must appear to preserve itself only in part or else to have a doubled self-preservation which is inconsistent with our hypothesis. The rest is easy. Out of a tendency to complete the self-preservation will arise the notion of attraction. Re- pulsion will arise from a tendency to hinder the complete- ness of the self-preservation.* Several As and Bs, armed with their specious attractions and repulsions, form aggre- gates that convey the idea of a corporeal mass. So matter has been reconstructed from the reals, if possibly with a certain disregard for concreteness. Like matter, time and motion may be explained by the fiction of a continuum, in which the reals appear to lie, although they do not. Changes in motion are not real, and yet they are the objective appearance of the contacts of reals; and, further, to the human observer they appear as in time, and even, because they partly overlap, as in con- tinuous time. Thus, although to the real in itself the cate- gories of space and motion do not apply ; yet for the observer, the real is to be regarded as at rest in its own space, but moving in the spaces of other reals.^ The real is timeless, yet out of its meetings with other reals there arises the notion of time. The real is immaterial, yet out of these meetings there comes also the notion of matter. In all this argument the objection perhaps holds, that the more ingenious, the more elaborate, the more mathematical it is, the more does it commend itself alike to our admira- tion and our unbelief. At least this tends to be true of persons of the concrete type of mind, whose feelings and will rebel against the abstractions of its intellectualism. 4. The epistemology of Herbart. That part of his meta- physic which Herbart calls the Eidolology deals with the epistemological problem of how man may be able to act as a spectator of the objective semblance of the interaction of reals. Its problem then is the problem of thg. self, and covers the determination .. of .the origin and_ possibility of ideas, the process of knowledge, and the general founda- tions of psychology. ^AUnemeine Metaphysik. Par. 270. ^AUgemHne Metaphysik. Par. 283. Philosophy of Herbart. 63 In general, idealistic solutions of the problem of the self have rested upon the assumption of an identity between the self as knower and the self as known; in more technical terms, of the subjective and objective Ego. As Spinoza expresses it, if any man know anything, then he also knows that he knows it, and he knows again his knowledge of the knowledge and so on to infinity. Yet between the sel f as knower and as known , though there may possibly not be a diiiference, there is clearly a valid distinction. For Herbart the distijactign_is_ absolute. "If the known be a certain A, then the knowledge of A is not A itself; and the sum, A plus the knowledge of A, is no Ego."^ What solution is offered by Herbart for the problem of the Ego? Whatever it be, it must affect his educational theory. For Herbart in the first place the Ego, being a subject and real, as such remains unknown like other reals. This however is only true of the metaphysical soul. The empirical Ego, or the Ego as object, is to be regarded as a CQ mglex.- ,Qf,,attri.bates. ~an3"~so~"falls under the catgggix_2f inherencf which Herbart has been at pains to analyse. Not the real Ego therefore, but the Ego as known, is a resultant of forces taking their rise in the self-preservations of reals. T he in v estigatio n of these forces is the task of 2§Z£!l2l°SiZ- " The soul is not originally a power of reflection, an impulse and the like. Neither is it constructed out of real and ideal activity, as Fichte would have it. Rather must its whole spiritual diversity be supposed to consist in an adequate number of determinations of a manifold connexion with other and again other reals. "^ But if man cannot know reality itself, and if thus the real soul be past his ken, he has the consolation of knowing actual happenings. His sensations, the material of all his knowledge, are themselves the preservations of his soul against other reals. Sensations, as the resultants of the meet- ings of reals, compel him to posit these reals. 5. Certain implications for education. Upon the metaphysic 4e£ends the psychology o f Herbart, and upon the psychology, the_ education.__^ But it is seldom remarked that the theory ^Allgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 323. ^AUgemeine Metaphysik. Par. 364. 64 Herbart and Froebel. of education of Herbart is dependent upon a metaphysic. One would imagine that its utmost genesis were in psychol- ogy as such. And yet on maturer consideration it may be doubted to what extent psychology, as descriptive and ex- perimental, may alone and unaided give even a tentative answer to any fundamental educational problem. In the case of the education al theory of Herbart, at least three of its rtiajor principles see m to merely filter through a psycholo gical medi um in the course of their derivation from a rarer meta- physical source. For methodological reasojis these principles may be stated in-uegative form. They are, that education i^ not real, that education is not free, and that it does not proceed by an organic or evolutionary unfolding of the human s pTfitT TTiis~Bald and negative formuTation, though in itself it may do Herbart less than justice, may temporarily sub- serve the antithetical method because of its almost absolute contrast with the foregoing analysis of the educational theory of Froebel. For Herbart education is not re al. Realitv is unchang e- able,_ and the educator can only manipulate the iridescent colors on its surface. It is true that forJHprbart jaforths are constitute d by these, cjaloxs and not by reality, as the worth of a diamond may be said to reside in its fires. Yet some will think it degrading that education should be mere appear- ance. It is not a satisfactory hypothesis for the educator that the essence of things is not amenable to moral predication, and can never be a whit the better or worse for all his efforts. And again, for Herbart ideas arise out of an interaction of reals over which the self has no power. Freedom exists as an externally produced harmony, but it is admitted that such freedom is only a specious pretence of moral autonomy, and is not real. It is not even in process of becoming trans- cendental. Finally, for Herbart education is strictly not a development. According to the fundamentals of his metaphysic it should be an aggregation of ideas, due to undirigible self-preserva- tions of reals. It is true that in the psychology Herbart gets far away from so untenable a position, that he introduces fusions and blendings of ideas, and subjects these processes to a mathematical regime. But ever at the root of these Philosophy of Herbert. 65 changes there lurks the atomism of the metaphysic. It seems to be a fundamental and consistent assumption of the mathe- matical psychology of Herbart that the ideational units remain true throughout every fusion to their isolation, inde- pendence, and mutual externality. But although he may sympathise with the Herbartian psychology, no modern educator will subscribe to the meta- physic of Herbart. For the crucial transition from a set of originally unrelated reals to a phenomenal world of rela- tions is too severely unintelligible to win permanent adher- ence even from sympathetic minds.^ If indeed it were really thinkable that all relations may be external to their terms, then surely it should follow that relations are pure illusion." But in the assumption of self-preserving activities among the reals Herbart has smuggled into his system as it were a core of idealism; and while it is true that his psychology and educational theory have never lost the impression of their pluralistic origin, it is conceivable that this core of idealism may be sponsor to some part of their validity. HI. I. The so-called faculties. It is now possible to turn to the psychology of Herbart. In the judgment of Beneke, the two chief advances of modern psychology were made respec- tively by Locke and Herbart, in that the former dealt a mortal blow to the theory of innate ideas, and the latter to the theory of innate faculties. Herbart found that the so-called faculties are no more than classifications of mental phenomena.*^ To make them prior to such phenomena is to lapse into the fallacy of the physician who argues that a certain draught produces sleep because it is possessed of a soporific faculty. Even as classifications, the faculties seemed to Herbart to be unreli^hlsjnjhe_absence of the^needful empirical data of psychology, although in'So^Tar ai present cdhditiohs are con- cerned, it would seem that the validity of this objection to the faculties has been diminished in proportion to the suc- cessful activity of the recent period of psychological research. 'Cf. Lotze, Metaphysics. Book I. Chapter I. 'Cf. A. E. Taylor, Elements of Metaphysics.' London, 1903. p. 148. 66 Herba/rt and Froebel. But a " faculty " psychology offers yet another difficulty. Its basis is in introspection, and introspection alters its own object. " Self-observation mutilates the facts of consciousness in the very act of seizing them."^ Upon these three grounds, then, Herbart would reject the psychology of the faculties. First, it offers an explanation which is no explanation; sec- ond, its forms are ill grounded in empirical fact; and third, of its own nature it deceives itself. Only one classification suggestive of the faculties retains the respect of Herbart. Usage compels him to adopt the terminology of conception, feeling and desire. Even these are unscientific terms, and to add to them other supposititious faculties, and to erect upon these a weighty superstructure, is to build an aerial castle on a mythology of the mind. As the destroyer of causal faculties Herbart reaches psychological greatness. But he may have harried them beyond necessity. Though there be no original cut-and-dried faculties, there may be original mental tendencies. Such tendencies, though they may do violence to the Herbartian metaphysic, are indicated by the a priori mental categories of Kant and the mental predispositions of heredity. Here in a sense is visible the fundamental psychological antithesis in Herbart and Froebel. For Herbart the mind is ideational content; for Froebel it has from the outset a unity of form. Only perhaps from an evolutionary point of view may the unity and polarity of the mind be duly co-ordinated and synthesised. 2. Ideas as dynamic. If there be no p rincipl es of unity in the mi nd, no faculties, no forms, and no original ^tendencies to faculties, principles of~ forms,- then the mm3 must be some sort of aggregate of isolated ideatrdrial forces. For Herbart, ideas are atomic foreesT^Tiich are false to their atomism only to the extent of fusions and blendings that mask their plurality without reducing it. In chemistry one is familiar with the notion of irreducible and disparate elements behind every compound. In like way Herbart, with the whole school of associationists, seems to assume that the most complex thought may be resolved in the limit into a plurality of un- related ideas. For Herbart in particular these ideas are con- 'Lehrbmh lur Psychologic. Kfinigsberg. 1834. Par. 3. Philosophy of Herba/rt. 6y stant enough, independent enough, self-identical enough to be amenable to mathematical treatment. But although it may be needless to follow him into a statics and dynamics^ of the mind that are based upon a vague analogy of mental tensions to physical forces, yet it may not be wasteful, and it may not be superfluous, to refer merely to the centraLtitUJU^ht of Herbart in this theory, the thoug ; -ht nf iHpag-ag-<3ynamiV For^ Her^bart_con£^.S_b£Ca3nie-foi«es-wben JJi^^ another. They are independent of original mental unities. The min£^self is a series of masses-oL-them, each mass rising or falling, from the„thresh.Qld_of consciousness ac cord- in g to its groupin g s and consequent train s nf association. It is true that in the most recent psychology the association of ideas is a less prominent category than stimulus and re- action. But the category of association, and-_tli£ _theory o f ideas as independent forces upon which it is built, retains a limited'~validit7: — FoF—a -moment, then, one may take the point of view of Herbart. What_happeris^ when concepts resist onp another? Experien ce finds t hat they are not dest"ro3rea",'""nQr'left— unchanged; they are s ubjec t~~to' "chlmge, but not'anmliilation. "fl he real concept is chaligecTTnto an effort to presenFTtself."^ Therefore only remove hindrances, and concepts will tena to reproduce themselves. Here is evidently the principle of involuntary memory. For Herbart the metaphor of tensions between concepts is a pretext for a statics and dynamics of the mind to treat respectively of equilibrated and disturbing concept-forces. On the aptness of this metaphor depends much of the validity of the educational system of Herbart. Let us attempt to subject the metaphorical theory of Herbart to an empirical verification. The mind is to be a product of independent forces called ideas. Now the phe- nomena of experience which seem to corroborate this view include especially dreams, reverie, the facts of abnormal psychology, habit and the feeling of inhibition in attention. In dreams, when the reference to ends in which the unity of consciousness perhaps consists is laid aside, it would seem that the mind is resolved into a chaos of irresponsible ^Lehrbuck eur Psyckologie. Konigsberg, 1834. Par. 13. ^Lthriuch zur Psychologie. Par. 11. 68 Herbart and Froebel. notions which rise and fall and make combinations by virtue of the arbitrary independence of each. And if there be a continuity in dreams, it is at best fantastic. It appears to be purely associative, and subject to no guiding process of discrimination. Yet it remains not only true that the inde- pendence of ideas in dreams is apt to be relative, and to this extent conditioned by some unity of purpose, however fan- ciful it may be ; but it also remains true that the large amount of independence which ideas may be said to possess is essen- tially of a secondary and derivative character. The ideas ot the dream consciousness, like those of habit, appear to have originated out of the stress and strain of a mental re- action upon specific stimuli. In that case the interaction of independent ideas is inadequate as a category for the explanation of dreams. The basis of association appears to be less one of subjective cohesion than objective teleological reference. As in dreams, so in reverie, the mind seems to function sometimes more by compartments than as a whole. The mind as will seems dormant, while concepts mass themselves as best they may. Yet reverie may hardly be more than a recapitulation and reorganisation of genuine teleological thought. Therefore ultimately it would appear to make less for an atomism of ideational forces than a purposeful mental unity. Most of all in hypnotic suggestion, and more generally in the facts of abnormal psychology, is there evidence for sup- posing the soul to be at the mercy of its states. Such evi- dence seems indisputable so far as it goes. But again, it would appear that the phenomena of suggestion in hyp- notism only point in a secondary way to an atomism of ideas. Primarily they are only made possible through a previous unitary experience belonging to the hypnotic subject. To illustrate, the hypnotic subject who is told to raise a finger can do so only because he knows what a finger is and how to raise it. The polarisation of his ideas is then made pos- sible by their previous organic relation, and hardly points to the original independence of conceptual forces. As in dreams, and reverie, and abnormal psychology, so in habit also is there evidence of the independence of ideas Philosophy of Herbart. 69 in relation to the unity of the normal mental process. It is probably fair t o say thjtt Ab£. HfiJbar-tiarL -^sa^chglo^ is befcJre all things a psychology of habit For it is in hlbit ,that-i4e a s- be camtr^xea in theiF'assDCiations,"and IFYs in hatit'that they appear to be moiFmciependent inTKeir activi- ti^'"ms true that there is something mcongruSns about the notion of an association of atoms. On the other hand, however incongruous it may be, it is not only fundamental to the Herbartian metaphysic, but it not unsuccessfully in- terprets the facts of psychology in so far as these are chosen from the realm of habit alone. /If consciousness were no more than habit the psychology of Herbart might be an acceptable account of its phenomena^ But habit is only the static side of consciousness, the primary nature of which is dynamic. Genetically and biolog- ically, the office of consciousness would appear to be the performance of imperative readjustments. Perhaps the early development of the human consciousness may have been cor- relative with the need of an increased wariness against ani- mals stronger than man, or with the necessity for an increased wisdom in the search for food. In any case, consciousness would be genetically and primarily not a number of clear ideas, but a subjective response and awakening to the stress and strain of critical situations. Itj§__out- of conflict and confusion, anjd— often_Qul.j)f haziness and^YSgueness. thai" ideas arise,.^-Apparently the cleariiess" and immediacy of ideas m habit, illustrated by the almost reflex obedience of a trained soldier to the command " attention " or " halt " even though he be off duty, may be explained by the cumu- lative effect of a recurrence of approximately the same solu- tions to approximately the same problems in experience. It is then out of the problematic situation that ideai~aiT5e. But the problematic situation qr_, crisis^Js.._a-£ase where the combine~d~energies-t>fHrhcr'self are brought into requisition for a single end. In other words, in the ultimate limit the being of ideas is evidence of a unitary, teleological, mental process. Concepts however may be forces, without being inde- pendent forces. The phenomenon of inhibition in attention 70 Herbart and Froebel. seems to point to an inner striving, and an inner striving should imply something to strive against. Ideas are at vsrar among themselves apparently in the spirit of the Herbartian psychology. And yet it is conceivable that the strife of ideas may be within and for a purposive self. Though the ideas be a divided and rebellious section of the self, yet they seem to be affiliated to the self in a sort of constitutionally indis- soluble union. 3. Reason and will. In the, p sychology of Herbart, Jhe em phasis i s on apperceived content and not apperceiving activity. More simply, it is upo n ideas and not will . Even desires are regarded as the appetitive tendencies of concepts and conceptual masses. And the will, t he apperceiving act iy- ity jyh j£h pl n y q p n large a par ^TInllEelpsycho logical theory of Wundt^s for H er b art only a kind of desire. " The facu lty of desir e, together with those of representation and feeling, should furnish an exhaustive classification oi th€ mental faculties."^ For Herbart the- wiH-is-JJi at kind of desire wit h which is cnupled the idea of the attaimnpnt of its object. But it is possible to discriminate the will diiterently, as the whole personality consciously functioning in a situation, and for such an activity desire is an unconvincing name. For Herbart the will is not free. It is not dependent upon the formal or categorical reason. "Reason is originally neither commanding nor law-giving; above all, it is not the source of willing. It is quite as little a source of knowledge. Nevertheless it is regarded as such; indeed it is thought to be the highest judge and authority, which is a very natural result.'"" But the reference of Herbart is to the forms of thought and not to mental content or ideas. According to the psychology of the tension of concept masses, the will cannot fail to be dependent upon presentations, concepts, ideas, if not upon reason formally as such. The will is not primary, not original. In Herbartian education it will not be evolved by constructive occupation and practical endeavour so much as erected by the intellectual reinforcement of satis- factory groups of concepts. Character will be constructed from without, to the disregard of those developmental forces ^Lehrbuch zur Psychologic. Kflnigsberg, 1834. Par. 107. 'Ibid. Par. 115. Philosophy of Herhart. 71 of spiritual evolution upon the cooperation of which Froebel for his part did not fear to rely. Little is said in this chapter of apperception and interest. It is true that these shibboleths in a way summarise the permanent contributions of Herbart to psychology, but for this very reason it seems unnecessary to afford them a pre- liminary analysis, so well-known are their chief implications. Interest and apperception will presently receive a compara- tive and synthetic treatment. 4. Another interpretation of the psychology of Herbart. A revolutionary interpretation of the psychology of Herbart has been recently advanced by Dr. Davidson of Edinburgh University.^ The psychology of Herbart, we are told, is founded on the metaphysic of Leibnitz, and its implications are those of the " functional " psychology of Professor Adam- son and Professor James.^ It is customary to regard the psychology of Herbart as obsolete in other fields than that of education. In education it is charged with the validity and invested with the authority of an empirical law. It is found to work fairly well, though to what extent its practical value may have been overrated or underrated by certain common sense departures of teachers from its implications, or possibly, by the rebellious workings of the minds of pupils according to unorthodox mental laws, is a question not easy ta decide. Still, the pragmatically minded will sympathise with the following argument of Dr. Davidson. " If the Herbartian theory of education ' works,' then^ this very fact implies that the practice of Herbartian education involves a psychological theory which must be true." The Herbartian psychology really seems to work too well not to have a quantum of validity. But our thesis as against Dr. Davidson is, that it is only valid for habit, and for mental phenomena allied to habit, that it gives no satis- factory account of attention, and that therefore it falls short of the relative completeness of a modern functional psychology. Incidentally, let it be remarked that there is a danger in deducing the psychology of Herbart from the phil- osophy of Leibnitz. Herbart not only knew Leibnitz but ^A new Interpretation of Herbart's Psychology and Educational Theory. Edinburgh'and London. 1906. ^Ibid., p. 41. 72 Herbart and Froebel. criticised him;^ and assuredly his own metaphysic, the obvious and acknowledged source of his psychology, is far from the mere result of a late recrudescence of the Leibnitzian school. There is also a danger of confusing interpretation with jus- tification. A metaphysic may interpret, but experience alone justifies. It is difficult to believe that either Leibnitz or Herbart had a psychology essentially functional. In Leibnitz the logical tendency is to a subjective idealism. For him reality is reducible to monads, simple, self-active, spiritual, independent beings, each a mirror of the universe, but each except God an imperfect mirror, each unfolding from within, and having no windows, and only controlled by a pre-established har- mony. Matter is for Leibnitz the confused perception by a monad of other monads. And, although the perceptions of the monads differ in quality, the monads enter into no relations, but the world appears by the unfolding of the monad itself. It is difficult to make more out of this than a subjective idealism. " When Professor James sums up by saying that ' the knowing of many things together is just as well accounted for when we call it a functioning of the soul state as when we call it a reaction of the soul,' he is only expressing in positive terms what we have tried to show is implicit in Herbart's theory of the reaction of soul."^ Let us examine this as a crucial passage. First of all, what is the gist of the quoted corroboration from Professor James? It is that for certain definite psychological purposes the substantial unity of the soul is superfluous. " Herbart, as we have tried to show, considered it superfluous ; and any theory of educa- tion that bases on such a principle is not entitled to rank as scientific."' In limitation of the validity of this argument at least four considerations may be taken into account. The nature of the soul is rather a metaphysical than a psycholog- ical question, and the soul may be as metaphysically necessary as perhaps it is psychologically irrelevant. The abstract science of psychology merely as such adopts ^Cf. Chapter 11. a. ^Davidson, A new Interpretation, etc.. p. 64. s/iirf. p. 66. Philosophy of Herbart. 73 an attitude of thorough-going .duaHsm^ which is ultimately almost unthinkable. In any case, the word substantial almost begs the question of a soul unity, for all real unity is prob- ably purposive rather than substantial, as the pragmatic philosophy of Professor James virtually asserts. Finally, Herbart himself did believe in a real metaphysical soul. This alone would suffice to end the matter, were it not true that the real soul of the Herbartian metaphysic is a barren ab- straction unrelated to the mind as known, and not an in- telligible principle of unification. Our general conclusion is that the psychology of Her- bart is not equivalent to a psychology of function, if only because the latter theory will have none of the traditional Locke-Humian permanence and independence of ideas. For this very reason Professor James has criticised Herbart as one of the victims of the " psydiologist^jfallacy." " The thought of the obiect's recun^gnt^id^JltJtXJ^ i^egar4ed- as the identity oT its recurrenT" thought; and the perce^JQns. of mulipircit'y7"of co-existence, ptsiiccession, are severally con- ceived to Jbe brought , about .,QtUx through a multiplicity, a co-existenipe, a succession, of perceptions. The continuous flow of the tneiital stream is .sacrificedj and in its place an atomism, a brick-bat plan of construction,- is preached, for the existence of which no good introspective grounds can be brought forward, and out of which presently grow all sorts of paradoxes and contradictions, the heritage of woe of stu- dents of the mind. These words are meant to impeach the entire English psychology derived from Locke and Hume, and the entire German psychology derived from Herbart, so far as they both treat ' ideas ' as separate subjective en- tities that come and go."^ In something like a functional psychology there is shadowed a certain synthesis of Herbart and Froebel, in that there is room both for the emphasis of Herbart upon mental con- tent and habit, and for the emphasis of Froebel upon will and progress. According to a psychology of function, habit and attention work into and out of one another as severally the retrospective and prospective sides of a dynamic process 'C/. James, Psychology. New York, 1890. I. pp. 21S-220. 'Psychology, 1890. I. p. 196- See also I. pp. 353-354. 74 Herbart and Froebel. in which the organism readjusts itself to imperative crises. But it is not to be imagined that such a concrete psychology is the only or the fundamental ground of a synthesis of the educational theories of Herbart and Froebel. It is pur- posed to indicate other such grounds, here novel and there familiar enough, in the hope that here and there they may support the educator more safely, more stably, and even on a higher level of interpretation than the more subjective opinions of individual reformers, however great. CHAPTER III. The Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis. The attempt has been made to analyse firstly the philosophy of Froebel, and secondly the philosophy of Herbart. It may now be possible to adopt a more synthetic standpoint, from which an estimate may be made of the relative validity of the theories of Herbart and Froebel. Accordingly the earlier part of the present chapter is devoted to an attempt at a psychological synthesis; and the latter part to an indication of the possibility of an ethical and metaphysical synthesis. I. The soul and the concept. It has been admitted that associationism may be one terminus of a valid psychology. In dreams, in habit, in reverie, and in the phenomena of abnormal psychology, ideas manifest a disconcerting self- sufficiency and independence. No doubt this independence, this self-sufficiency, are relative and iii a sense derivative from a unitary activity of the soul. And yet derivative may be too strong a word; for if there is no idea in vacuo, neither is there any soul known to experience without ideas. It would seem that the original activity of the soul may be conceived as a tendency at the same time to a spiritual unity and an ideational dififerentiation. If so, neither Herbart nor Froebel completely satisfies. Froebel thinks of the unity of the mind as something given, and in a sense from its origin fully mature; Herbart ascribes to the original soul no more power than an incomprehensible reaction to pre- serve itself, which changes its appearance without stirring the depth of its reality. For Herbart the unity of the mind is a product of apperceptive processes in which the forces are ideas. There would seem to be a sense in which the unity of the soul, the self or Ego if you will, is achieved ratWer than given; and yet also a sense in which it is implicit as a tendency from the first. Thus the category 76 Herbart and Froebel. of evolution offers a working psychological synthesis. The mind at birth may be regarded as the elementary germ both of a unified personality and differentiated ideas; and yet in such a way that the character and individuality of an adult are essentially things to be developed and achieved. While it is not pretended that such a synthesis is authori- tative, it has at least this value for a philosophy of education, that it suggests a reasonable theory of free will. Does the self function as a unity? Then it may be free. Is it swayed by independent wills called concepts? Then it is not free. For if mental activity be merely a phase of the tension of concepts, regarded as more or less independent, although capable of fusions and blendings, then the self is no more than a product of circumstances over which it has no control. Herbart is therefore a determinist, and education is for him wholly a matter of external stimuli to which mechanical responses are expected and assumed. But the logical corollary of the psychology of Froebel is transcendental freedom. Ideas are not taken seriously as independent activities; but the soul is looked upon as superior to any or all of them, and to any or all of the desires and actions that may be at the back of them. This dignified and happy view is not quite warranted by fact. The will appears to be not so transcen- dental but that it may be jeopardised, not so transcendental but that it may never be achieved. What light is thrown upon this antithesis by the recon- ciling category of human evolution? Essentially this, that freedom appears no more to be a static thing, given once for all, or once for all withheld. Freedom may be viewed as a potentiality becoming actualised. Man may not begin with transcendental freedom, but he moves toward it. He is not wholly superior to mundane circumstance, to time, place, and opportunity; and yet he may more and more become so, not in the sense of dispensing with them, but in the sense of making them instrumental to his purposes. If he is in a sense at the mercy of his concepts, still, they are his concepts. It would seem to be a very practical and inspiring notion, that freedom lies in a process of becoming, in which man gradually emancipates himself from the deter- Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis. 77 minations of external agencies, not by disregarding such determinations, but by giving them a value, and controlling them in relation to that value. The self is not concerned to suppress the activities of ideas, but to relate and guide them. Again, according to this view the self is not one thing, and the ideas another thing; but the self is the purposeful unity of its ideas, and the ideas are differentiated attitudes of the self. What is desired, is therefore not merely, as the Froebelian psychology might suggest, the conquest of ideas by the soul, and not merely, as Herbartianism implies, the formation of concept masses that are likely to combine to good effect; rather it is on the side of the unity of the soul, a will capable of controlling habitual ideas, and on the side of mental content, ideas at once ready to be precipitated into action and amenable to the guidance of the concrete self. The Froebelian psychology with its stress upon unity tends to be formal, the Herbartian, with its stress upon content, tends to be mechanical; and the truer psychology may be one in which form and content, soul activity and idea activity, come to be regarded as normal correlatives functioning to- gether. Then morality may be based on environment as to its origin, but on freedom as to its value and goal. 2. Mental forms and mental content. The emphasis which Herbart seems to set upon permanence and mental equilibrium is connected with the fundamental, and, as it stands, insuper- able difficulty of passing over from the soul as an independent and unchangeable real, without parts or diversity, and lack- ing even the activity which Leibnitz had ascribed to it, to the active mind of human experience. Between these two conceptions there is a gap that Herbart would none too suc- cessfully fill by the assumption of real happenings to the extent of self-preservations of the reals against one another. If there be some real happening, then why hold the reals to be unchangeable at all? If reality change at all, even in respect of happening and not in respect of being, then it is perhaps as well to hold the changing phenomena of our experience to partake of the nature of reality, as to invent an hypothetical occurrence equally irreconcilable with a hypothesis of pure being without becoming. 78 Herbart and Froebel. " The soul," says Herbart, " has no innate natural talents nor faculties whatever, either for the purpose of receiving or for the purpose of producing. It is, therefore, no tabula rasa in the sense that impressions foreign to itself may be made upon it; moreover, in the sense indicated by Leibnitz, it is not a substance which includes in itself original activity. It has originally neither concepts, nor feelings, nor desires. It knows nothing of itself, and nothing of other things; also in it lie no forms of perception and thought, no laws of willing and action, and not even a remote predisposition to any of these."^ This is not the soul as known, only Her- bart's theory of the metaphysical soul. The significance for life and education of such an hypothesis appears to be that the soul as a unity, or as natural tendency, in general the formal soul, is negligible though existent; only the content of the soul is an object of knowledge and a source of morality. The Herbartian psychology becomes consistently a polemic in favor of content; hence its value, and hence its formless- ness. According to the synthetic psychology already indicated in this chapter, no mental content that is merely content is competent to create the forms of mental action, any more than such forms could of themselves realise a content. Froe- bel approaches the other extreme from Herbart, and makes given mental unities hew out a content for themselves after the fashion of their own inwardness. A less abstract view is that form and content are inseparable aspects of the mental process, to such a degree that the question of priority may have to be abandoned. If it be true that Froebel tended more nearly to such a synthetic view than did Herbart, it may be attributed to the fact that he virtually adopted a category of evolution — development from within — as Herbart did not. "All human investigation," wrote Herbart, " must recognise the funda- mental source of vital forces by referring them to that provi- dence according to whose designs they were originated. No metaphysic and no experience reaches further. Every theory as to the probable creation of higher organisms from those of a lower order, can be refuted." To this Froebel might ^Lrhrbuch zur Psychologit. Konigsbersr, 1834. Par. 1S2. Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis. 79 have in part agreed, but he would have insisted upon some kind of unity and development throughout nature. Herbart did not conceive, with evolutionary idealism, that life may be evolutionary and yet divine; that the development of a higher from a lower order does not degrade the former but ennobles the latter; that even the conceivable derivation of organisms from comparatively inorganic matter need only show that matter is spiritual and significant in a way not hitherto suspected; and that things are to be adjudged less according to their origins than their worths, or ends, or satis- factions. It will now be apparent that the opposition of mental forms and mental content has resolved itself into the opposition of the soul and its ideas, and that the synthesis suggested is that of an evolutionary psychology, where the category of evolution is intended to carry genetic and biolog- ical interpretation up to the level of spirit, by orientating them to future possibilities. 3. Habit and attention. The antithesis between the psychol- ogy of Herbart and that of Froebel is manifested anew as a relative stress upon habit and attention. When Herbart makes the claim that the Ego, even should it exist as tran- scendental, could as such have no value for education,^ he appears to have in mind that the function of education is to cultivate habits of thought and character. When the school of Froebel, or rather of Kant, proclaims the soul to be transcendental, what is implied for education is the suprem- acy of will over habit, since the self is to be hailed as superior to any or all of its desires. In the synthesis, it may be possible to admit that the Herbartian cult of ideas may be a valuable account of the operations of habit, at the same time that progress may demand a Froebelian art of exercising the will in selfactivity, where selfactivity means action coupled with or hinged upon attention and initiative. For the Froe- belian psychology of selfactivity seems to strengthen the psychology of Herbart just at its weakest point, which is that it expects too much from ideas when it seems to imply that they alone and in their intellectual nature will induce morality. Froebel seems to remember better than Herbart that good or bad is to be predicated of our thoughts not 'Cf. e. g. Herbart, Pddagogische Schrifttn. hrsg. Sallwurk. I. p. aji. 8o Herbart and Froebel. after the matter but the manner of them. And yet Herbart has psychology so far on his side, that each idea tends somehow to be realised in motor activity, undirected or misdirected though the tendency may be. There is even a sense in which all effort is directed towards the supremacy of some idea. If ideas had no relative objectivity, or, what means the same thing, if habit had no force, then there would be no check upon the momentary vagaries of the self, and no truth better than a doubtful structure reared upon momentary subjective impulses. In a synthetic psychology, in a psychology of function, there is place then for the emphases of Herbart and Froebel alike. The mind in atten- tion goes out to an object as with Froebel, and the resultant idea returns upon the mind as with Herbart.^ And again, what becomes of the opposition of attention and habit, if habit be funded attention, and attention be accommodatory habit? The opposition no longer appears to inhere in the facts, but only in the point of view. 4. An evolutionary psychology. There are those whose func- tional psychology does not carry them the length of the category of evolution. These may accept a reconciliation of the psychology of Herbart with that of Froebel, so far as concerns the functioning of the habit and attention of an agent in a given situation. But those who would go further with mental evolution, and, without interpreting mind merely from a genetic standpoint, still find it an ever-developing factor in the experience of the child and the race, may take their point of departure with Mr. Bosanquet, from '' a con- tinuous presentation, to be described either as feeling, or as others would say, as having the three aspects of feeling, conation and sensation (or cognition)."- The original con- tinuous presentation is not to be viewed as mere form, a pure Ego; nor as content only, a mass of independent ideas. As it functions, form and ideas will develop together. The unity of the self may be regarded as original, but as capable of higher expression ; and ideas will be present as possibility, but their actualisation will be a gradual development. We are now as it were between Locke and James. For Locke, ^Cf. A Synifusts of Herbart ami Froebel. Welton. In Educational Review, Sept. 1900. ^Ps^-chohgy of the Moral Self. London, 1897. p. 33. Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis. 8i ideas may vary not at all ;^ for Professor James, no two ideas are ever the same.'' We are adopting a view^ of the mind quite reconcilable with the latter statement, as though its identity were a persistent ideal, or purposeful, unity in change. Such a view of identity seems necessary to an interpretation of the category of evolution. One is compelled to abandon a block unity, a mere sameness, for a unity of purposeful reference. But a unity of purpose and function is very real; and perhaps in the last resort no other unity remains in- telligible. Therefore it is only with a certain reservation that one affirms with Herbart, " every individual is and remains a chameleon." It is only possible to dismiss every form of mental unity from one's psychology, if one be pre- pared to dismiss with it the entire range of human purposes and values. The conception of the unity of the mind as purpose may perhaps involve a truer notion of the so-called transcendental will. Thus the will may be regarded as transcending circumstance not absolutely or with a given finality, but to the extent that the purposeful unity of the mind may be capable of subjugating side issues like the minor and subsidiary sensuous purposes. Transcendentalism is from this point of view less an endowment or even a possession of the will than a potentiality which may be starved or stifled as well as developed. Thus considered, the will is competent to regulate any presentation, or any train of ideas, only to the extent that it is exercised in doing so. Freedom exists more or less in proportion to the effort to guide rather than eradicate habitual and critical activities and ideas. The fugitive and cloistered will, unexercised and un- breathed, that never sallies out to meet its adversary, and that Milton cannot praise,* loses, or never wins, its " trans- cendental " efficacy. 5. Mental structure and mental function. Viewed structur- ally, the mind appears to consist of ideas ; viewed functionally, it seems to act as a unitary will. Will and ideas are then terminal aspects of a single process; and, as a matter of 'Essay on the Human Understanding, Book II. Chapter 17. ^Psycholo^y. Nevi^ork, 1890. I. p. 23s- ^Areopagttica. 82 Herbart and Froebel. methodology, there is little to be said against placing an emphasis upon either. Psychology perhaps has to choose between two modes of procedure. The one mode is static; the investigator analyses the mental " content " at a given time. By this method one attains a sort of science of mental anatomy, or one gets as it were a cross section of conscious- ness. The alternative method is dynamic; it emphasises processes, and seeks to retain a reference to concrete vital conditions which the static or anatomical procedure has rigidly and even deliberately excluded. It assumes that the " anatomical " procedure is as inadequate to explain the living mind as anatomy itself to explain the physiological organism. After all, anatomy has the artificiality of an abstraction, and its purpose is to subserve something more functional and concrete. In a sense then, over against an anatomical view of the mind, a figuratively physiological view may be given a certain kind of priority; or at the least, the notion of mind as a process, as a dynamic func- tional principle, is to be taken into account, even when a deliberate methodology pursues the static and cross-sectional treatment of mental content. It is indeed clear that process without content, or change without permanence, or func- tion without a structure that functions, is meaningless. Con- versely content without process appears to be a fictitious abstraction, and so permanence does without change, and a structure without function. In the case of the mind, while content, permanence and structure suggest habit as the mode, and ideas as the units of its life, it is equally true that the categories of process, change and function suggest atten- tion as mode, and character as unit. A view of the mind as essentially habit is the result of looking immediately at the structure of its content. It comes from a retrospective seeing, from looking at what is already there ; from admiring the organisation of consciousness, from the revelation of its miracles of harmony alread}' achieved and its record of already established control. One of the results for psychology of this emphasis upon organisation and habit is that ideas come to be expected to discharge all needful functions by virtue of a peculiar process of mutual association. In this Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis. 83 way the English associationists and Herbart accounted for the major part of the phenomena of conscious life. The psychology of Froebel, so far as it goes, has the con- trary emphasis. It is processive, dynamic, attentive, readjus- tive and readaptational. From its very origin the soul is active. " The newborn child, like a ripe kernel of seed-corn dropped from the mother plant, has life in itself."^ From the psychological standpoint, Froebel cares perhaps less for habit than will, and from the ethical standpoint, less for what has been achieved than what may yet be done. Froebel is ever preoccupied with processes, and with what alone make processes intelligible, purposes. It is not difficult to synthesise structure and function in theory, and to remark that they are mutually essential aspects of a life process. It is not difficult to add that habit and will react upon one another, and that what has been done becomes a datum for what there is to do. But it is not easy in practice to dynamically adjust the convenient post mortem investigation of the mind by Herbart to the attempt at a natural history of it which distinguishes Froebel. For the educator is asked to cease to think of an Herbartian psychology, or of a Froebelian psychology; and to think in their stead of an Herbartian contribution to psychology, or a Froebelian emphasis in it. To summarise, the Herbartian account of mental phe- nomena may be approximately valid for the past, for habit, and possibly for physiological psychology. This last is added because it is in the nervous system that habits are formed and perpetuated. On the other hand the Herbartian psychology suffers from its unduly structural emphasis; it is abstract, in so far as it ignores the functional, accommo- datory, and prospective view. It may be synthesised to advantage with what Hegel might have called its Other, its residual complement in psychological emphasis, that which insists with Froebel on a self-activity, or with Wundt on an apperception which partakes of the nature of an ultimate volitional function. Again, the Herbartian phase of psychol- ogy, as a psychology of the association of ideas and of habit, ^Fritdrich FroebeVs Kindergartenwesen. hrsg. Seidel, 1883. p. 33. Or Ptdagogics of tht Kindergarten, 189s, p. 23. 84 Herbart and Froebel. may be connected with physiological psychology and may therefore be suggestive, not to say valid, for the explanation of the primitive growth of consciousness; while Froebel's psychology, emphasising the forward tendency to ends, may seem to subordinate origin to value. But a synthetic or a functional psychology looks at the process of origin growing into value. 6. The self and the situation. What has been said of habits and attention, of origins and value, of stable and dynamic mental elements, and of the tensions of ideas and self-activity, implies a theory of the self and the situation. A theory like that of Herbart, which explains mental activity as a tension of concepts, appears to disregard the phenomenon of the consciousness of self, and to attribute an overweening influence to environment. Nay, it is rejoined, does your evolutionary interpretation of the mind complain of a stress on environment? What is evolution but the outcome of environment? Does the evolutionary pot call the associative kettle black? And yet the alleged inconsistency may not be real. Evolution seems to mean more than situations, for it is not easy to see how any amount of mere environment, lacking a principle of inner activity, could produce anything. So far as Froebel's educational system emphasises the self, and that of Herbart the situation, there is need of a synthesis. Modern psychology looks upon the agent and the situation as two sides of a process of experience. The self is a sort of focus of the situation, as the latter is in turn an objective manifestation of the agent self; and there is a sense in which each may be said to determine the other. Progress is the tale of a continuous struggle between their mutually deter- mining forces in which the self, as conscious spirit, gradually gains the upper hand. It needs to be added that the evolutionary psychology which has been suggested as a possible ground of synthesis may be interpreted from the side of idealism. Idealism inter- prets evolution, in the first place, as a process of possibility becoming realisation. The evolution is interpreted by its end, although it may not be necessary to conceive this end as perfect in the sense of static or finished. In the second place, idealism notices a modification in the methodology of Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis. 85 evolution. Man tends to take over the control of his own evolution from the hands of his mother nature, without deny- ing the fundamental wisdom of her "precepts." And finally, idealism interprets evolution as grounded in the absolute, although this phrase may be taken to imply the common travail in all things of an universal spirit, rather than the transformation of the universe into an ingenious mechanical toy. II. In turning from the attempt at a psychological synthesis to the suggestion of a metaphysical and ethical synthesis, it will be convenient to make the transition through a dis- cussion of the problem of freedom. I. Freedom. If action be prior to thought, then ethics may possibly be prior to metaphysic . At least, one cannot go far in philosophy without adopting some attitude to the ethical problem of freedom. On the one hand, as with Froe- bel, freedom may be a divine endowment, and real; on the other, as with Herbart, it may be an inner harmony of ideas, the creation of circumstance. . But there even seems to exist a possibility of reconciling these apparently diverse positions. That is to say, the quantum of truth in each may be mani- fested in a theory which will explain the facts better than either. For instance, the will may be neither free nor deter- mined, but struggling out of determinism into freedom. Herbart cannot reconcile himself to the notion of a transcen- dental freedom. How then does he include morality? For morality seems to stand or fall with responsibility, as re- sponsibility stands or falls with the freedom of the will. Nay, seems to be the rejoinder of Herbart, although man is | not free, he acts none the less under the consciousness of freedom. He therefore attributes to himself responsibility, as others attribute it to him and he to others. But responsi- bility stops with the actor, no matter what may be the ultimate causes or occasions of the will. " However, if it be found that the will had an earlier will as its source, the responsi- bility begins again anew. The depraved man, after he has become entirely bad, will be held to be completely responsible for his crimes, but these again may be laid as a burden 86 Herbart and Froebel. upon his corruptor, and so on backward as long as some- where a will may be pointed out as the originator of those crimes."^ This view appears to have the validity of origin, but not of end. The will is not what it was, it is not its own past causes and occasions, rather perhaps it is what it is becoming. Herbart makes freedom an illusion, because he finds causality behind it; but it may be regarded as a reality, because it has power of transcendence before it. Herbart agrees that there exists a self-control, in the sense of capacity to repress our desires in the light of considera- tions of good, and that this may be properly called freedom. The stronger a man's self-control, the freer he is. " But, whether such a strength can be increased ad infinitum, cannot be determined by existing cases, for these indicate only a limited power."^ Yet, it may be answered, if freedom as self-control be capable of ever greater advances, then it may be supposed to imply a leaven of the transcendental, or a tendency to overcome the limits of circumstance and time. 2. Progress and equilibrium. There would seem to be that in the temperament of the individual which afltects the mode of his metaphysical thought. He may gravitate towards notions of rest, being, and permanence; or again to becom- ing, progress and change. It would seem that a metaphysic of unchangeable being marches with a notion of mental equilibrium, and a metaphysic of becoming with the idea of mental progress and evolution. Herbartianism tends on the whole to the notion of mental equilibrium as the end. Many- sided interest means equilibration. Indeed, many-sided in- terest includes also an element of progress; but there is a difference between its equable expansiveness and the passion- ate self-activity of idealism. This difference is perhaps largely of emphasis. An idealist will admit the need of mental bal- ance, but will set greater store upon mental activity and the tendency to self-expression. On the other hand, the follow- ing description, by Herbart, of the normal condition of the mind, may serve to illustrate his emphasis upon equilibrium. "As the opposite of mental delusion and of passions, the 'Lehrbuch cur Psychologi*. Konigsbers, 1834. Par. 118. Note j. ^Lehrbuch tur Psychologic. 1834. Par. 119. Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis. 87 sound mind involves mutual determination of all concepts and desires through one another, or freedom from fixed ideas and fixed desires. As the opposite of madness and emotion, it involves repose and equanimity. As the opposite of dementia and distraction, it involves coherence and concen- tration of thought. As an opposite of idiocy and indolence, it involves excitability and sprightliness."^ Only the last sentence emphasises progress, and its terms are hardly satis- factory to the idealist. To Froebel, to idealism, a sound mind is an organised system of tendencies making for expression. If these have due freedom, an adequate equilibrium should follow of itself, but it will not be an all-sided equilibrium, the same for all. A synthesis seems to be requisite and conceivable. One may regard the mind as normally in equilibrium, but it must be a moving equilibrium; or one may regard it as a force, but it must be an equilibrated force. Perhaps a teacher may lean a little to the side of equilibrium, or of progress, according to the demands of his own disposition. 3. Possibility and actuality. If the notion of an equilibrated character be not static, perhaps it is comparatively so, over against the idea of character as a development in which inner potentialities are to realise their utmost value. The former, the notion of Herbart, is almost Platonic; the latter, the view of Froebel, distinctly Aristotelian." Consider for a moment the teleological theory of Aristotle. All develops from potentialities, which in themselves are neither non-being nor actuality. Origin is to be regarded as that which in actuality is not, but potentially is; its final cause is its validity, its form, spirit, or meaning. But, so far as present conditions are concerned, the development of potentialities to actualities is a process never complete. To us, therefore, potentialities are always in excess of actualities, though it is conceivable that they may not necessarily and eternally be so. For such a conception as that of God, as a Being in whom potentialities are realised, and in whom activity is not dead but equilibrated, may suggest a reconciliation be- tween being and becoming, permanence and activity, and ^Lehrbuch zur Psyckologie. i*34- Par. 140. „ , „, „, „», 'Aristotle. Metaphysics. Books VII. and VIII. and Book IV. Chap. XII. 88 Herbart and Froebel. ideals as static and dynamic. It might be argued that the Herbartian ideal of a manysided interest involves such a reconciliation. The teleological emphasis of Aristotle is in line with the thought of evolutionary idealism. Life is seen as a process of becomng, from the not-yet to the shall-be, and then from the shall-be, which in the act of realisation becomes ipso facto another not-yet, to the higher shall-be, and so forward. For Aristotle, potentiality is that which possesses a principle of development. It is that which under suitable conditions will of its own inner self become. Evidently, applied to education, the Aristotelian concept of becoming involves a dynamic principle, universal and endless for human experi- ence. And yet, the progressive ideal of the here and and now may have its perfect pattern viewed sub specie eternitatis. If so, there is no ultimate contradiction between the chang- ing and developing aim of Froebelian education, and the per- fectly equilibrated and all-sided ideal of Herbart. 4. Being and becoming. Though it be admitted that the educational theory of Froebel is primarily concerned with potentialities, and that of Herbart with actuality as such, it remains true that the distinction is largely one of emphasis, and the opposition to a degree abstract. Herbart is further than Froebel from a concrete principle, because he will endow the soul with no original potentialities. Possibly the view of Froebel may be so given the benefit of the doubt as to clear- ness and consistency as to be brought into line with the suggested Aristotelian synthesis. To this synthesis may be ascribed both a metaphysical and an ethical side. On the ethical side, one has potentialities making for actualities, which again become potentialities for progress. In such a way, with Froebel, do instincts and impulses rise to the level of the social mind. But progress may be a mere illusion, or according to the suggestion of Rousseau, a real retrogression, unless there be a summiim bonum conditioning it. Such a highest good, such a perfect ideal, may be held to pervade progressive ideals much as permanence pervades change in the physical world. Change is inconceivable without perma- nence, because if the result of change have no identity with the ground of it, then there could have been nothing to be Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis. 89 changed. Change then is logically necessary only for the finite. Physically, it seems to be within a self-identical system. There is according to science an ultimate ground of permanence in the universe, which becomes in all its parts. What changes, is not substance but meaning. So it may be held in the moral sphere, not unintelligibly, that the ulti- mate ground of progressive ideals is a permanent and perfect ideal. This ideal may conceivably be ours to the extent of the lights in which we learn to see it, and according to the meanings which we may become able to attribute to it. And again, the underlying permanence of the universe need not be dead, nor the summum bonutn motionless; but it may be coming towards realisation in the finite, and this realisation may be conceived less as dull satisfaction than perfected activity. From this point of view the perfect or Platonic idea, to which Herbartian educators may logically turn, may have an objective and real validity, and may be the standard to which concrete individuals approximate. The " concept " boy may be a real far oflE, divine event. Then the progressive ideals that are dear to the educator " by development " may be regarded as the filtrations of eternal truths, whose " white radiance " is in part disguised in the medium of life, as by " a dome of many-colored glass." And so this attempt at an ethical and educational synthesis may be offered, that although the immediate concern of the educator is with the " percept " or individual child of Froebel, he should cling to the belief that the " percept " child is a " concept " or universal child at heart. It may be added, that so far as class instruction in the schools is collective, it is addressed necessarily to the " concept " child. Herbartianism has con- tributed much that is valuable to the principles of class teaching,^ without recognising so fully as does the kinder- garten the worth of the individual. But the synthesis of collective and individual teaching is hardly to be summar- ised in an abstract phrase; it consists in the dynamic con- crete readjustment, by the teacher, of the emphasis in given situations. ^Cf. e. g. Findlay, Principles of Class Teaching, London, 1904. passim. 90 Herbart and Proebel. The ethical reconciliation of being and becoming, or of perfect and dynamic ideals, may suggest for those who are willing to accept it a similar modus vivendi in ontology. It may be argued that the fundamental problein in this branch of metaphysic is causation. Something is, and something happens; and causation, if it exist, is that which connects the thing that is and the thing that happens. But the pre- ceding discussion of being and becoming seems to suggest that evolution may be a more helpful category than causa- tion. For causation is a highly contradictory category. It must be continuous, and yet continuity appears to annihilate the distinction between cause and effect. Again, cause must be and yet cannot be prior in time to effect. It involves an indefinite regress from cause ^o cause ad inHnitum. Prac- tically, causes are treated as a plurality, and yet the notion of a plurality of causes is logically absurd.^ Apparently then the most tenable view of change and of causation is that in which the category of evolution is involved. In short, there is need of a permanence to give an aspect of con- tinuity, simultaneity, and unity to causation, as well as a new- ness which gives it an aspect of change, temporal sequence and plurality. Apparently it is the element of permanence in change and causation which lies at the root of the ontology of Herbartian realism. The other element, qualitative change, is, except in certain closed and dogmatic systems, a principle of idealistic ontology. It should follow that even the meta- physical theories of Herbart and Froebel need not be wholly excluded from the synthesis of an evolutionary theory of reality, teleologically interpreted. The permanent being of Herbart, and the becoming of Froebel, seem to be abstracted aspects of this more concrete principle. But the suggestions for a synthesis in this section are confessedly speculative. 5. Intellectualism and voluntarism. In the field of ethics, the opposition of Herbart and Froebel may be illustrated not only in relation to the problems of freedom and the ideal, but also in relation to the question of how to educate char- acter. It is true that Herbart no less than Froebel aims at the good will as the end of education. Since Kant, repeats 'Cf. The Elements of Metaphysics. A. E. Taylor. London, igoj. Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis. 91 Herbart, nothing else can be called good but the good will.^ Character then is the thing desired. Notwithstanding, within this consensus, it would appear that Herbart and Froebel respectively emphasise intellect and feeling. If now the in- tellect and feeling be set obstinately over against one another, or if the will be regarded as a third coordinate factor with them, and no more, then there does not seem to be a tenable ground for a synthesis. But it is perhaps preferable to regard feeling and intellect as the content of the mind at a given plane of intersection. Then the will is the mind in action, or in the exercise of its function of controlling experience. From this point of view, thought as distinguished from feeling will refer to the focus of mental strain; and the marginal element in consciousness will be present essen- tially as feeling. Such a psychological analysis may pave the way for a synthesis of the emphasis of Herbart upon thought with the emphasis laid by Froebel upon feeling. The psychological ground of the synthesis will be, that the mind is only concrete as will; that thinking is teleologically conditioned with reference to willing, or more simply, that it functions as a means to the control of activities; and that feeling may be regarded as a dynamo, which provides a " head " or motive power for thought and action. For Herbart the will depends upon ideas, which in turn are externally provided. Herbart experienced a difficulty in reconciling the determinism of this hypothesis with the moral sanction of personal responsibility. In order to escape from this dilemma he advanced a doctrine as it were of two wills. He distinguished sharply between character as objective and as subjective.^ The will before reflection differs from the will after reflection. In accordance with this change, educational methodology has to effect a transition from the appeal to external control to a reliance upon inner self- discipline.' In a word, the will before reflection is deter- mined; after reflection, free. The self before reflection is a product; after it, an agent. The distinction is not only significant; but within limits acceptable. But by what magic 'Herbart refers to Kant, Grundlegtmg tur Metaphysik der SiUen. Section i. ^Cf. Pad. Schirfl- hrsg. Willman. Leipzig, 1880. II. pp. 457-8. ^Ibid. II, p. 524. 92 Herbart and Froebel. can there be a transition from a purely objective to a sub- jective will? Can freedom and self-control rest upon a basis of mere determinism? Nay, one is compelled to answer, the objective will must have contained in itself the implicit principle of selfhood. But this is evolutionary idealism, and not the philosophy of Herbart. The contradiction that is involved in a rigid distinction between the subjective will and the objective will is reflected in Herbartian educational theory. Herbart himself attacked only transcendental freedom; and not inner freedom or freedom in general.^ But the educator qua educator is to be a determinist. " The freedom principle," writes Hayward, " sounds well in university class-rooms, and may, indeed, represent a fundamental philosophical truth; but as an edu- cational maxim it is useless if not pernicious." And again: " We must be, in so far as we are educators, determinists."" But for Froebel, education is a process of liberation, and even of the exercise of freedom or selfactivity. The notion that freedom may be a fundamental truth, and yet obnoxious in education, is worthy of a science of casuistry. But the Herbartian who is willing to admit, in the objective will, an implicit principle of conscious self-control, is virtually on the way to the suggested teleological and evolutionary synthesis. The relation of the will to thought and feeling was dif- ferently conceived by Herbart and by Froebel. Herbart as well as Froebel would have the child to be an active agent.* For Herbart: "Action generates the will out of desire."* Action, that is, is the immediate ancestor of the will; but action itself depends upon desire, which in the Herbartian psychology is essentially a product of ideas. Herbart adds: " But^ca£acity_ and opportunity are necessary to action."^ To this Froebel would have~agreed, though he might have wished to add that action is a factor even in the making of opportunities. For Herbart, thought is essentially prior to action ; for Froebel, action is rather prior to thought. Her- 'Piidagogische Schriften. (Sallwurk). II. p. aa?. Note. ^The Secret of Herbart. 1904. p. 30. ^Pddagogiiche Schrijten. iSallwiirk], I. pp. 233-4. Or see Felkin, The Science of Edu- cation, p. aiQ. *lbid. I. p. aaS. Possibility of a Philosophical Synthesis. 93 bart practically deduced the will out of thought through desire. Froebel, on the other hand, preceded from inner desire to thought by way of action and will. So far as Herbart may over-emphasise ideas, or Froebel feeling, in relation to will, a synthesis has already been suggested. For the will has been regarded as the concrete and dynamic mind of which intellect and feeling are sectional phases. From the point of view of an evolution interpreted in the light of ideals, the synthesis may be somewhat differently expressed. Feeling then appears to constitute the terminus of origin, and selfconscious activity to characterise the goal. Feeling and thought are then not opposites but co-laborers in personal activity. In the evolution from mere feeling to a higher form of self-consciousness, feeling, as motive power, is not lost ; but persists along with thought, the guid- ing hand. But evolutionary idealism may suggest a synthesis that runs deeper still. It may suggest, on the side of origin, that thought can only have arisen out of a feeling whose ultimate nature and basis is rational. And again, the thought that enters into the goal of feeling, while it does not eradi- cate sense, really does attempt to reorganise sense upon a higher plane. So the naturalness, the sympathy of Froebel may be reconciled with the clear mental vision of Herbart. If both reason and feeling function in activity, then reason is not for the elimination of feelings, or even of passions; but rather for their location, adaptation and control. 6. The education of character. The intellectualism of Her- bartian, the voluntarism of Froebelian education aim alike at the goal of character. But if there be any validity in the Aristotelian distinction between goodness of intellect and goodness of character, of which the former is declared to be of time and teaching, and the latter of habit, then Her- bart and Froebel may be said to respectively represent these abstract terms of the mental series. Herbart represents goodness of intellect, and the formative aspect of time and teaching upon such goodness. Froebel represents goodness of character, born of the habit of moral activity. This good- ness is equally amenable to education, so far as education is content with the guidance of inner activities, though it is of a kind liable to rebel against dogmatism. But the anti- 94 Herbart and Froebel. thesis is imperfect, and largely a tribute to emphasis. Per- haps so far as one may look at goodness in a quasi-Platonic way, that is to say, as an intellectual possession, it is Her- bart who indicates how education may promote it. But, when the question is of the good in use, or when one's attitude is Aristotelian, then Froebel may become the more helpful. Herbart, regarding the mind as it were in cross section, justly emphasises the ethical import of the mental content which a cross section appears to reveal; just as Froebel, seeing the mind as process, prefers to lay stress upon the tenor of its activities. Herbart may be right to the extent that even a transcendental will can hardly act without a content; Froebel to the degree that no content, which is merely a content, or merely objective, can possibly give birth to a subject mind. If indeed the case stand so, then Herbart and Froebel may correct one another where there is direst need of recti- fication. Herbart has contributed to moral teaching an emphasis upon the power of ideas in the making of char- acter.^ It may also be well that he should have treated morality as a thing not given, but produced in the process of living. And yet, each time that the educator would put into practice the recipe of Herbart for man-making, let Froebel remind him that he is dealing with a personality having potentialities as unfathomable as his own. If the educator can establish no sympathetic communion with this cognate will, his house of moral instruction is built on a foundation no better than sand. ^a. Padagogische SchrijUn. (Sallwurk). pp. 114-5. CHAPTER IV. An Attempt at an Educational Synthesis. In the course of the preceding chapters, attempts have been made to anticipate to a degree the synthesis of Her- bart and Froebel in the field of education. And chiefly, the problem of the education of character, the problem of freedom in education, and the problem of the nature and possibility of knowledge have received explicit attention. It now appears to be necessary to devote a chapter to the synthetic treat- ment of more technical educational categories. I. Society and the curriculum. Both for Herbart and for Froebel, the curriculum is a system of social values. By its agency, or rather by the agency of the pTocess of educa- tion to which it ministers, the individual is to be socialiagd. In a relatively static society, such as that of the Chinese tradition, the attempt may be made to promote an adjust- ment of the individual to his environment with a finality that is foreign to the spirit of western civilisation. But in a democracy, the curriculum will be formulated with the aim of adjusting individuals to social ideals rather than to any state of society that has been fully actualised. It will be in a manner sensitive to the progressive reorganisation of individual and social functions. Its value_j5dll_be to pro- niote_cooperation,— tb€~possifeili4y-ef— an— adequate-speciaHsa- tion.J3i-functions, ,aiid,jyie._due .relation of the theoretical to thf; practical life Its tendency is to divide into two sections, of which the sciences, industries, and sundry processes form one, and that the democratic section, while the humanities form the other section, which tends to be intellectual and aristocratic.___.TJie Herbartian ten4eft€y-'is~t«— eSpSasise^the latter aspect of the curriculum. The Froebelian bias, at least in the occupations and gifts, is rather towards processes. But a synthesis may be conceived, wherein the humanities may become practical, and science and the manual arts human. Indeed it would appear that for a synthetic educa- tional system art and industry, or rather the cultural and 96 Herbart and Froebel. the occupational side of the curriculum, represented in a way by Herbart and Froebel respectively, should go hand in hand. There are obvious anticipations of this view in Ruskin and Morris, and in the whole movement of the arts and crafts. Herbart appears to draw nearer than Froebel to the com- mon-sense view of education, as the attempt to get a curric- ulum of facts into the minds of the less mature members of society. The element of truth in this view may be the principle, that the curriculum is not accordinz to nature in _ any primitive or original sense; but rather according to culture,, or xSiniaSes7~or if you will, nature teleologically interpreted. The Herbartian analysis of the curriculum is distinctively cultural. Indeed, the followers of Herbart have relied so much upon the achievements of the race, that in their anxiety to recapitulate these achievements, in extreme cases they have almost closed their eyes to the necessity for further progress. For epochs of culture can tell of little more than historic fact, so far as even this is known; and value can only be attributed to such fact in the light of the needs and aspirations of the present day. Not only Herbart but Froebel also has the social ideal. It will be indicated that Froebel, for his part, may at times have wavered between the standards of civilisation and original nature, and so between the normative and genetic methods. He may have been justified in his many concessions to original nature, to the extent that education is a process of the liberation as well as the guidance of the human spirit. At least, so far as Froebel may have emphasised original activities, and Her- bart cultural values, the following adjustment of emphasis may be offered. Genetic method may criticise, illustrate, amplify, and interpret; but only out of civilisation are born the fundamental standards of the valuable. The genetic method is itself unintelligible apart from a supplementary reflux of light from the zone of adult achievement. It may be desirable to add, that to a certain degree both Herbart and Froebel attained to the reconciliation of a norma- tive with a genetic methodology. The method of Froebel may be said to have been the guidance of a .socialising process, by means of material drawn from what the child Attempt at an Educational Synthesis. 97 at each successive stage of his development may be able to see as at unity with himself. The criterion of Herbart may be even more normative, and less genetic; yet these two aspects may be discriminated also in it. It is the body of racial experience, therefore an ulterior end; and yet this end is to be attained by a sort of genetic process of the recapitulation of culture epochs. Thus both Herbart and Froebel have attempted, each in his own way, to reconcile genesis with aim. 2. Educational values. The school of Herbart represents to a degree a theory of the gradation of culture values. It sets for example the humanities above the study of nature. There appears to~be a species of validity in the stress upon culture, which man has achieved, over against such a nature, say, as Rousseau had posited in his curriculum for the educa- tion of Emile. Yet ultimately the sciences, which some have opposed to culture as if they were original and given truths of nature, are as truly human achievements as the humanities. With Froebel, nature might seem to be preferred above culture. But his standard of value in the occupations and gifts is social. And, even were this not so, his spiritual interpretation of nature would bestow a human significance upon the study of it. Thus the possibility of a reconciliation between Herbart and Froebel is suggested. But what form shall the synthesis take? Have all subjects of the curriculum, rightly methodised, an equal educational value? Not so, if equal means the same, and any other sense of the word is here unintelligible. Manual training, however treated, can hardly have the same educational value as poetry. Rather, for practical purposes, their values are not wholly commen- surable. But the following suggestion for a synthesis en- deavours to allow for what is valid in the views of both Herbart and Froebel. It seeks to preserve the theory of Herbart, that the subjects of the curriculum have different and graded values, without a denial of Froebel's principle of the essential unity of man and nature. The suggestion is this, that while there are subjects in the curriculum which possess specialised and to a degree graded values, yet the very existence of these subjects is determined by human 7 98 Herbart and Froebel. needs. Thus the values of the subjects of the curriculum are not the creation of independent compartments of original fact. They are indeed determined by the indispensableness of the relationships that may be established between the ideal set up by society, and the needs and aspirations of the indi- vidual life. Then, if this be so, the subjects of the school curriculum are logical divisions imposed by the social spirit upon the material of knowledge for the realisation of human purposes. The value of a school subject is essentially the extent to which it may be made to minister to those purposes. 3. Correlation and concentration. Just as the subjects of the curriculum are related as to their value by a common reference to human purposes, so it seems reasonable to correlate them as to their content in the process of teach- ing. Correlation is one of the practical recommendations of the school of Herbart. Froebel also related the activities of the child to a central object; but correlation is not the same conception with Froebel as with Herbart. For Her- bart, correlation is based upon a theory of associatr6n~of ideas j^n _th£jjidivM»;Ei^imn^^ life oljhought be not sporadic^ jdeas^mus^^^ accordiagL to, a pjocess directed by the teacher from .without. Without instruction to complete the organisation of ideas, the house of thought, and thence of will, might be divided against itself so that it could not stand. To Froebel, however, correlation is just the recognition of the fundamental oneness of the individual with society. For the curriculum is a systematised sum- mary of civilisation, held in the social medium. The indi- vidual, however, is in purpose and function social. Correla- tion, then, is from this point of view a process of carrying over the inward unity of the self to the field of its mani- festation or liberation. Froebel's is perhaps the truer notion of correlation, in that correlation is not of and among ex- ternals, but of social norms and the individual life. Even so, Herbart has done more than Froebel, on the technical side, for the recognition of correlation as a principle. To the extent of the validity of his psychology of the blendings and fusions of ideas he has given an invaluable account of its educational functions. It is not to be forgotten that the curriculum itself exists in a medium of thought, that thought Attempt at an Educational Synthesis. gg to be worthy of the name must be organised and vital, and that in the curriculum must be preserved at once the vitality, the reality of the outer world, and of the child also. The correlation which tends to externality, including that which forms the essence of the Herbartian methodology, has to be fitted together with the methodology of the little child. Probably indeed the feasibility of so delicate a task may hinge upon an hereditary harmony of the child with society. So far as concentration means technically a particular variety of correlation, it is opposed in principle to the co- ordination of a number of equivalent groups. In concentra- tiqn there is one m ain, tnpir. .abautjKhich others ai£gESBped. In co-ordination there.. may -hs^s. jnarobsr-jQi_.su£k_top,icSi. as with Dr. Harris, five.^ Froebel's correlation is of the con- centric type; now all centers about the ball, and anon about another and yet another gift or occupation. Perhaps there is something lacking about almost all formulations of the principle of correlation. Even that which relates the school to life,^ and reflects the life unity in the school curriculum, may be open to misinterpretation. For it would seem that the true life unity is an ideal or teleological unity; and that the true correlation is not after all a mere unity of reference to the life of the moment, so much as a unity of application in a system of ends. 4. The formal steps of method. Thus far, little has been said of method as such. At the same time, it has been suggested that curriculum and method are after all the same thing considered in different aspects. T he curriculum is an organisation o£-cldIisa.tijQii,,.an_.instit.utinnal .aSaJr^ Like_all instituiions,-.iJLisLibexrffire„iales.seiK;e_ajne^^^ are the meth ods throu gh ajid_i^ which society coiiyeys to indivi35als-its,. social-norms. The curriculum may be viewed as such a means pr„,iiielhod»- It seems to follow that the current distinction between curriculum and method can only refer to a given something viewed statically or habitually, and the same thing viewed dynamically^. _Method^_if_,you will, is dynamic curriculum.- Curriculum itself is crystallised method. ^Psychological Foundations of Education. In International Education Series, p. sas- 'Cf. The School and Society. Dewey, p. 107. 100 Herbart and Froebel. A' serious consequence of the stated relation of matter to method is that no formal method should aspire to uni- versal validity. For if method be the subject matter as dynamic, it cannot be uniform, unless the subject matter be so. Yet modern Herbartians tend to assume a uniformity of method in educational operations. For instance, they would begin each set recitation with a period of review, according to the routine engendered by the mechanical tendency of a psychology of mere associationism. It might be more scientific in principle to regulate reviews by the demands of the par- ticular situation. The function of reviews may be less to secure knowledge, or clearness, than power. In that case, the ultimate criterion of the necessity of reviews may be the need of energising an achieved mental content. This illustration may suggest a further argument against the uniformity of the method of the recitation. The first argument was, that method cannot be uniform, because it is dynamic subject matter, and subject matter is not uniform. Now by dynamic subject matter is meant, the curriculum as functioning with the mind of the child. Two causes evidently preclude the uniformity of this functioning. In the first place, as has been said, the subject matter varies; and in the second place the mind of the child varies. Method ought then to concede somewhat to individuality ; for to make it uniform is to explain away something of the concreteness of life. Finally, it is to be said of the five formal steps that ulti- mately they are not logical divisions of a lesson period so much as principles of a psychological process. Clearness, association, system and method^ are types of mental activity, although even as such it is difficult to regard them as at all uniform or final. It may not be clear that what has been said of the formal steps has much to do with a synthesis of Herbart and Froe- bel. But the individual psychology of Froebel, his endeavour to get at the inner life of each child, makes as decisively for diversity of method, as the more mechanical psychology of Herbart makes for uniformity. And something like a •Herbart, Pddagogische Schriflen. Sallwiirk. I. p. 157. Attempt at an Educational Synthesis. loi synthesis has been indicated, inasmuch as the formal steps of the school of Hcrbart are valid, to the extent that they may be seen to assist, in many concrete cases, the function- ing together of the curriculum and the child. But this will neither uniformly nor always be the case, according to the principles of the foregoing analysis. 5. The theory of culture epochs. What has been said of the formal stq^s of method may suggest some remarks upon the f ormal theo ry of epochs of culture. Apparently, the child comes to scFiooJ with a system of needs, conditioned by a genetic process through which he has inherited his civilised estate. This thought has led to such conclusions, as that the child is to run rapidly yet freely through recapitulatory stages about which hangs the aroma of a past of primitivism, perhaps even of arboreal and piscatorial life. Early child- hood has been regarded as a period in which these phases of origin may be worked out and worked oflf, especially in play. I'lay in this sense, as spontaneous, is opposed to work. This antithesis is at variance with Froebel's thought of play, that it is, or should be, an anticipation of social function. Without doubt the child mind is apt to behave in a manner that suggests many typical primitive activities. If this be an evolutionary recurrence, or any kind of atavistic phe- nomenon, it is probably more desirable to guide such mani- festations than to obstruct them. For recapitulatory activities that are in line with social evolution may be expected to be amenable to a measure of social control. The older Herbartians used to dogmatise about culture epochs, lacking either a standard of value for the alleged primitive activities, an analysis of what these may really be, a reasonable historical perspective of the order of their recurrence, or a notion of where to begin or end with them. Should one begin with, or educate for, the aquatic stage, if ever one existed? Or should education first take cog- nisance of simian activities, or those of primitive man; or if first of the latter, of what kind or stage of him? Accord- ing to Sallwurk, the error of Ziller, Staude and Rein is that they have omitted to establish a real correspondence between individual and racial development. " Lack of the historic 102 Herbart and Froebel. sense is above all a characteristic of the Zillerian school."^ But though the fact of correspondence be admitted, it affords no standard of educational values. It becomes for education a mere emphasis on the significance of impulses as such, apart from their quality, and apart from their desirability. Indeed, it may also be held to affect the order in which parts of the curriculum should be presented to the child. But the question of the priority of subject to subject in time appears to be in part determined by the interests appealed to and the methods employed. It might be possible for Herbart and Froebel to agree that genetic epochs of culture matter to education only at second hand. That is to say, even if the historic culture of the race were fully known and understood, its worth would have to be estimated in terms of the standards erected by modern intelligence. For example, the hunting instinct as such is not to be cultivated merely because at one time it may have been vital to human subsistence. It is only to be cultivated in so far as the hunting activity retains a value in the present constitution of society. And so, just as Froebel appreciated play not merely as impulse, but also as something implicitly social, Herbart may have really empha- sised the Odyssey less for its mere priority in human experi- ence than for its social value. Thus it does not seem im- possible to reconcile what is reasonable in a theory of epochs of culture, and the recapitulation of them, with twentieth century standards of worth. 6. Technique. The formal steps, and certain " culture epoch " curricula, are among the indications of the strength of Herbartianism on the side of technique. This does not appear to be accidental, but a natural consequence of the Herbartian tendency to centralise the education process rather as it were in the teacher than the child.^ Herbart himself, it is true, did not emphasise technicalities so much as his school has done. " I am not such a fool," he wrote, " as to imagine that the salvation of mankind depends on such trifling aids, which may more or less lighten the burden of instruction."' ^Sallwurk. Handel undWandelderPddagogischerSchitleHerbarts. Lan^nsalza, x885,p.39. ^Cf, Pddagogische Schriften. hrsg. SEulwiirk, 1. p. 183. Or Felkin, Science of Educa- tion. Boston 1902. 13. 159. ^Pddagogische Schriften. hrsg. Sallwurk. I. p. 183. Attempt at an Educational Synthesis. 103 Yet the mathematical and mechanical bias of the psychology of Herbart has lent itself to a high degree of technical elabora- tion. Froebel, for his part, seems to care less for technique than for the spirit of instruction. For him, the mother is the queen of teachers. It is quite a question whether indeed the teacher should rely more upon settled devices, or upon initiative, charged as it should perhaps be from the dynamo of feeling. The teacher of zeal and enthusiasm may make his curriculum dynamic, and therefore self-methodising. On the other hand, mere enthusiasm without technique is lack- ing in economy. If it be conceivable that the very science, the very technique, the very habit of education may be informed by passion, then in such a temper do I conceive the reconciliation of the spirit of Herbart and Froebel to lie. According to this view, formal devices, formal methods, are apt to be valuable in proportion as they are or become the teacher's own. They need to be energised and animated by an adequate force of will and feeling. 7. Instruction. For Froebel, the activities of the child ! appear to regulate the method of instruction. But, accord- ing to Herbart, it is better to leave method in the hands of the teacher. There is a sense in which one cannot but adopt the view of Herbart. The teacher, not the child, reflects upon the method of instruction; therefore the teacher, not the child, is able to control it' Moreover, Herbart believed as fully as Froebel that the teacher should defer in his instruction to psychological modes of activity. But Herbart conceived these modes differently from Froebel. For Herbart they were mathematical, for Froebel rather " divine ;" for Herbart typical, for Froebel individual ; for Herbart plas- tic, for Froebel to a degree elastic. Now if the mind be mathematical, uniform and plastic, it is clear that instruction will be for education, like motley for Jacques, " the only wear." " I admit," confessed Herbart, " having no notion of education without instruction, just as conversely I can imagine no instruction that does not educate."^ „ But_for_ FroebeL.edacatiorLJa-.as- mu£k_hy_a2ESti±ion as instruction^- Jt-4s--4J©tj--as-k-4s-with-JHerbaTt^^^_a^ of '■Alleemeine Padaeoeik. X. Par. ii. , _ . , „ ^Padagogische Scnnften. hrsg. Sallwurk. I. p. aio. Or Felkin, Sctence of Education. Boston, 1902. p. 192. I04 Herbart and Froebel. fillingthe mind from without. For the child cries_put^ for education. In a certain sense, and from a certain point of view, the child is his own instructor. It may not be difficult to reconcile in some measure this mode of emphasis upon inner activity with the emphasis of Herbart upon instruction. Writers like Linde have conceived a synthetic " developing- presentative method."^ The problem may resolve itself into this form: does the environment fashion the child, or the child the environment? If the former, then education is instruction merely; if the latter, it resembles the develop- ment of a Leibnitzian monad, as a process moving entirely from within outward. But in this extreme form neither hypothesis is tenable. If life be of the nature of an inter- action of organism with environment, then neither can be ultimately conceived as static. In fact, the environment unbends to the child, and so far as may be accommodates itself to him, from birth to maturity. Conceive education then as interaction; and the antithesis between instruction, and development from within, loses its absolute character. For the teacher will still instruct, without depriving the child of freedom. He will not create men according to his will, as Herbart would almost suggest,'' neither will he abstain from interference with " nature." But his function, in a word, will be guidance. The possibility of guidance may depend upon the communion which the teacher enjoys on the one hand with the child, and on the other hand with the environ- ment with which the child interacts. In any case, into guidance there enter two factors, whether we know them as nature and culture, or origin and value, or the child and the curri- culum, or the individual and society. To emphasise the former in each pair of categories is to emphasise freedom; to lay stress upon the latter in each case indicates pre- occupation with control. Freedom is perhaps the more Froe- belian principle; but into it enters social control. Control ■, is the message of Herbart; but freedom is smuggled into it , through the gate of interest. In a synthesis, what is needed appears to be a redistribution of the balance of emphasis. Such a redistribution may be suggested by the term guidance. ^Cf. Linde. Der darsttUende Unterricht. p. 49. *C/. p. g. Pddagogische Schriften, Sallwurk. L p. 173. Attempt at an Educational Synthesis. 105 It is true that guidance is interference ; but it is not so much interference with activities, as interference for activities. 8. Education for vocation. Herbart and Froebel are agreed that the purpose of instruction, is. to promote . character. B ut it J^s desirab le to give to characte r a v ery definite content. For instanceTls cEaracter a possession of the individual, or the mode of his functioning? In concrete cases this ques- tion generally takes a narrower form. Is education, in the narrower sense of the word, cultural; or is it essentially vocational? Thus on the one hand, some cu lture seems_ due to the^inrliviHiial as. th/?: hi'rthn'ght nf Viis map )if> oH J Fj^mati has a higher nature, higher possibi lities, it is ultima tely for these possibilities and f or this natu re that education is^ Her- bart there forg_feTt""nTat""education should prodijfce many-sid'ed and cultured m ^^I^^EdtfCatiuu, irtJ"5aid, du ea" not work f or the calling, the vocatio n, in "llfe.^ But everything depends upon the irTferpretatiorToT vocation so-called. With Froebel, edu- cation is for vocation, but not for any trade or superficial occupation merely. Vocation according to Froebel is a " divine " calling to make the best of one's possibilities. But vocation in this ethical sense is not inconsistent with the Herbartian definition of the end of education. The difference is perhaps this, that for Herbart it is an outer voice that calls ; an inner voice for Froebel. And again, the principles of Froebel, unlike those of Herbart, are not very definitely opposed to education for vocation in the more utilitarian sense. The soul, thought Froebel, can find freedom and realisation not only in history, and literature, and mathe* matics, but again in the trivial round of daily opportunity. Indeed, in a modern society there needs to be education for specialised function. For consider society as a member- ship, or as an organism, if " organism " be interpreted not merely on a biological plane, but psychically. Society then appears to be a " vicarious " system, an association of men to bear one another's burdens, an organisation of innumer- able functions, an attempt at an equilibration of many dif- ferentiated occupations and pursuits. This is the character of society in Plato's ideal republic, where men are to be counsellors, artists, soldiers, according to innate fitness and ^Pddagogischt Sckriften. (Sallwurk). I. p. 233. io6 Herbart and Froebel. public training. It persists not only in ideal communities, such as More's Utopia and the New Atlantis of Bacon; but in all historical societies and states, in republics, monarchies, oligarchies, and conspicuously in feudal organisations. In certain respects regard for the highly specialised organism of twentieth century society appears likely to swell the cry for an education for vocation to an irresistible clamor. Science has already been forced into the curriculum by social needs, so that the literae humaniores are no longer without a rival. Manual training is said to have many values; but perhaps ultimately it is in an industrial bias that its strength in public opinion lies. Indeed, the two facts that have done more than anything else to establish a vocational emphasis in education are probably the development of public opinion as a social force and the industrial character of the present age. Industry has strong claims upon the patience if not devotion of an educator. It has come to color the literature, the science, the art, the politics, and the whole life of the present. It has reorganised society on a commercial basis. It has made factories instead of families the units of work. It has made actual a broad culture and a high standard of luxury such as were previously only possible to the lim- ited few. It may soon afford to all workers an unprecedented margin of leisure. It would seem therefore to be a social duty to educate for the transmission and development of the processes of industry that have done so much for the higher values of life, and may do so much more. And, again, the case for industry is prima facie a case for vocational training, if only because specialised vocational functioning is the chief principle of the organisation of modem industrial development. Therefore, at the present day, one dare hardly sever edu- cation from vocation so sharply as did Herbart. Herbartians may be fundamentally right in attributing, say to the Odyssey, a greater culture value than to manual training. And yet, Greek is only for the few, and if manual training be culturally treated, it may be possible to atone for a conceivable loss in intensity by the wider extension of educational influence. Such a plea, did they stand in need of it, might also justify the place of nature study and science in the school cur- Attempt at an Educational Synthesis. 107 riculum. The vocational, the industrial, tends to be scientific and physical. The aim of the teacher then will be, to humanise science and to idealise nature. So far as this may be done, Herbart and Froebel at their best are reconciled. For now, first, in industrial training there will be a basis for ultimate vocational efficiency. Second, in its idealisation, there will be a foundation for reconciling the work with the personality. Third, in industrial training for all, there will be laid the groundwork of a social sympathy even between classes whose interests at present almost lack a point of contact. Fourth, the traditions of a democratic society will be so far respected, that without abandoning the notion that each man has a place, the set and rigid distinctions of a caste system may be avoided, and the opportunity be left to each individual to make a place for himself according to the potentialities of his nature and' the quality of his energies. II. Thus far, the attempt has been made in this chapter to indicate the possibility of a synthesis of Herbart and Froebel in the direction of curriculum and method. Without 'alto- gether forsaking these topics, the second part of the chapter will center about the traditional opposition of nature and culture. In a sense, Froebel stands for the emphasis upon nature; and Herb art f or_tha omptiagj;^ npnn mltiirp Is it possible to reconcile the principle of education according to nature with that of education for an institutional life? I. Nature and civilisation. Rousseau appears to have mis- taken the stagnancy of the institutions of his day for sheer degeneracy. He even came to consider civilisation as a fall from a better and happier state of nature. To him, then, it logically seemed better for education to follow nature rather than to follow civilisation. Thus for Emile, at least so far as common sense would tolerate such a doctrine, instincts and tendencies were to be everything, curriculum nothing. Back to nature lay the path of man. This note helped to stir Leasing and Herder, Kant and Pestalozzi, Goethe and Schiller, Froebel and Herbart. It tended to lib- erate thought and to emphasise feeling. With Pestalozzi io8 Herbart and Froebel. it found part and lot in educational theory and practice. Fol- lowing nature, becoming a child with the child, is one aspect of the doctrine of Froebel. But to Froebel and Pestalozzi there was no ultimate opposition between nature and culture. Herbart was even convinced that culture or civilisation is prior to nature in education. He may be said to have led a distinct reaction against the educational views of Rousseau. " To leave man to nature, or even to wish to lead him to, and train him up in, nature, is mere folly. . . . We know our aim, nature does much to aid us, and humanity has gathered much on the road she has already traversed; it is our task to pin them together."^ But before we proceed to pin them together, there is a question to be answered. What is nature? There is perhaps no other category so ambiguous. At the least, the following senses of the term are distinguishable and vital to the present topic. To the scientist, nature is an externality to be accurately described. To the poet, nature is a background to human emotion. To the idealist, nature is the expression of spirit or reason. To Rousseauists, nature is primitivism or origin. And to the moralist, nature is that which ought to be. To Froebel nature tends to mean a sort of combination of all of these. In the last analysis, as nature is to him something social and divine, he is not very far from Herbart. The opposition of nature and culture is sometimes expressed as an og£ositiqn of heredity an.dj£nYir.onjm£nt^_ofJjaiiiure.and nurture.. In Huxley and Matthew Arnold the antithesis, r\AU-ire. jierxux cilltnrp , leads tr> a respective emphasis upon the sciences-aad- -the -htmianities- as factors in— tb«~«d«€attonal curriculum^, " The distinctive character of our own times," said Huxley, " lies in the vast and constantly increasing part which is played by natural knowledge."" And again; "For all those who mean to make science their serious occupa- tion; or who intend to follow the profession of medicine; or who have to enter early upon the business of life; for all these, in my opinion, classical education is a mistake."' This reads not unlike a criticism of the type of curriculum suggested by Herbart. It raises the question, for instance, ^Pidagogische Schriften [Sallwurk], I. p. 164. 'Science and Culture. New York, 1888. p. 31. M^Ibid. p. 13. Attempt at cm Educational Synthesis. 109 whether the Odyssey is a suitable center for a modern curric- ulum. Its reality is not quite a modern reality. Froebel, for his part, preferred to begin with the near at hand.' He seemed to prefer, even in song and story, an idealised actuality to an imported mythology. But over against Huxley, Mat- thew Arnold has a word to add on behalf of culture. What, he asks, is a man advantaged, if he gain the whole world, and lose himself, forfeit himself?'' For nature is indeed what he works from and with, but dare he neglect art and litera- ture, or the wealth of emotional exercise in poetry and elo- quence? Even for the sake of science, it cannot be. Synthetically then, the educator will endeavour to find nature in culture, and culture in nature. He will seek to combine nature and culture, if not like Froebel in a poetic or romantic way, then like Herbar t in a reasona bl^co nfide nce that the achievements of the race, which constitute the objects of culture, are in the truest sense, natural. In education, natu?eTs to be civilised, humanised, idealised; and culture is not to be confounded with artificiality, or attributed merely to one selected kind of subject matter. The knowledge for the sake of knowledge of the scientist, the art for art's sake of the humanist, are for education, if taken alone and of themselves, equally inadequate categories. There could only be an ultimate antinomy between nature and culture if by some means an individual were born outside of society, and suddenly dragged within it. 2. Education by institutions. Although culture is ultimately an appeal to social values, mere literary culture is not socialisation. For this reas on Herb art, with all his appre- ciation of literature, conceived a less social process of educa- tion than did Froebel. He did not care primarily for educa- tional institutions ; but even _ retained a ~'pf efereHTig for individual tuition. "But for Froebel", the school was insti- tiifioMT." It wasan evolution out of the home and vocation. Especially in the Mother Plays are there many glimpses of an adapted institutionalism.' The institution.,. pX.. the kinder- garten was looked upon by Fjoehel-iess as a, private enter- prise than a permanent social factor contributinf'^o the 'Cf. t.e. Ptdatogies of thi Kindtrgarttn. New York, 1895, p. aa. 'Cf. Discoursts in America. London, 1889. LtUratw and ScuHce. Kf. •■ g. Dir kUint Ziichner. no Herbart and Froebel. higher li fe of the German _people. In a speech made in his old age at the opening of the first Burghers' Kindergarten in Hamburg, Froebel never once abandoned " the thought of a uniting education satisfying the individual in all his relations."* But with the Herbartians, and notably Ziller, there is n o such e m phajus upon thp needs of the social wiu^le^* And again, the desperate endeavours of Froebel to found educational institutions had no parallel with Herbart himself. From one point of view, the several basic institutions, including the home, the school, the state, the vocation and the church, are methods by which society convej's to indi- viduals an adaptative and controlling power in experience. Through institutions, again, individuals are admitted into partnership with larger social groups. But although insti- tutions have these general functions in common, their oflBces in the social economy are in a measure delimited. The state, indeed, has a station among them that is legally rather than actually unique. On paper the state is omnipotent. In a way it supervises the endeavours of its fellow institutions, and is the residuary legatee of such of their functions as remain unfulfilled. In this way certain states and cities are coming to employ the kindergarten to supplement the de- ficiencies of educational influences in the family. This is wholly in the spirit of Pestalozzi and Froebel. " You shall do for your children what their parents fail to do for them," are the words of Gertrude to the schocJmaster.' " The primary, indispensable requisite of education at this period," wrote Froebel, "is the union of the school and the family."* But unto Herbartians, for whom the teacher rathe r creates than trains the mind, the_family is a disturbinpr element. At-this'day7 many "scientific teachers, whose inclinations are Herbartian, look upon the parents of their pupils as inter- lopers in the work of education. Perhapg,. jf^d ucation w ere for culture merelj', or for the indiNndu al merely, t hen the teacher would be its absolute center, and the pedagogical works of Herbart might be its sufficient book of method. 'Cf. Th* Third Voltoiu of Froebtrs Ptdagogics. 1904- Translated by Josephine Jarvis. p. i8. Vf. Padagogisdi* Str.}mmiittn oh drr WrmU dts Jak-^inuUrts im GMtU drr VaftnctaUr. Hanschmann. Leipzig. 1806. p. j6, 'See Pestalozzi. Lnmard tt$id Gtrtmdt. In foacatwiKU Ciassia. p. 118. 'Kftnsdim Ertuhnrng. hrsf. Seidel. iSSj. p. i6t. Attempt at an Educational Synthesis. iii But if education be rather for socialisation than individual accomplishment, then the home, or the spirit of the home, is still as central as it was for Froebel. This distinction to a degree conveys a synthesis, if it should suggest that the educator may seek to guide the moving balance of schol- astic and domestic functions. 3. Individuality/ In_§Q_far.jas_it js^consistent with the psy- chology of Herbaft, education is wholly a plroc'e§iS'Of~T5ontrol. It cannot, ;bel' conceivjed- aparLJramJnsttUCtipn.- I£i s as i t were the man ipulation of c lay-l):K_-th£„hand of a sculptor -of-Hien. It is a process motiv ated from wit ^out^ It is the study-of'arpEilosopher or a scientist, rather than a mutual commerce of satisfactions, in which the child repays the adult in full measure for the boon of his own socialisation. Unlike Froebel, Herbart could not consistently value educa- tion as a reciprocal process in which the privilege is partly on the side of the adult. One result of this difference in attitude between Herbart and Froebel is that Froebel had a more vivid intuition of the worth of the individual. But it has been already urged that Herhartian pHiir.atinn tend s toJndividuaJism bx_v^irlaie-^^ leanings. Indi- vidualism, however, is not individuality. Individuality is a social matter. One cannot be individual without being social, inasmuch as it is only the process of socialisation which confers that harmony with environment which is the essential condition of freedom. Butjaccprding to an jlerbartian psy- chology, education makes not only for sociality but for uniformity. It makes for a set type of sociality, many- sidedness. The psychology of Froebel, on the other hand, by attributing to the soul an original character, admits of greater concessions to brotherly dissimilitudes and varying degrees of hereditary capacity. The social chord is to sound in harmony ; not in mere unison. But it may be that Froebel tends to overestimate the power of freedom which resides in the individual. For although, as Froebel in effect main^ tained, the individual is not to be regarded as the product of facts which are foreign to his own spirit, neither is he so far aloof from the facts of experience as to be utterly independent of laws of causation. Therefore, in the attempt to synthesise the views of Herbart and Froebel that concern 112 Herbart and Froebel. individuality, the educator will need to bring together the emphasis of Herbart upon causation in the sphere of mind, and the emphasis of Froebel upon freedom. With Herbart, education will construct and instruct; and with Froebel, it will at the same time endeavour to secure the co-operation of the will of the pupil as the indispensable condition of success. 4. Interest. Interest may be defined as the hedonic aspect of thought. There persists an emotional element in the background of the mind. Of course thought proper, which in its characteristic form partakes of the nature of a stress or crisis, holds the foreground. What is called interest seems to be the background of feeling which shades into the more critical phases of consciousness . Interest cannot be_said to be prior to att ention , as Hprhart hel d it to he., if it is the pleasure-pain aspect of attention. Yet, if it be regarded also as a background of which any part may upon occasion come into the focus of militant thought, interest would seem to play a part in motivation. It appears to assist the agent in securing a sufficiency of power to do something. According to this account of interest, it can hardly be as it was for Herbart a product of the blend and fusion of ideas. Interest is perhaps rather a true psychic activity, an aspect of self-expression, a part of the efficient cause of man's realisation of himself in a world of objects. As descriptive of a state of mind, it involves a two-fold ref- erence, to a natural tendency and an ideal for attainment. Usually pleasure is regarded as the end of interest. In so far as pleasure is a by-product of the realisation of the self in a world of objects, this may be dismissed as a psycholog- ical error. For if pleasure be a by-product, then to seek pleasure defeats its own end. Thus it seems to be an object rather than a feeling that is sought. Interest, then, would not seem to be something external which is set up as a standard to be achieved, so much as an original tendency accompanying activity. It is indeed the self-activity of Froe- bel regarded emotionally. The psychology of Herbart is a psychology of ideas. Froe- bel's is less so, than a voluntaristic psychology. If this Attempt at an Educational Synthesis. 113 broad distinction be maintained, a more synthetic statement may be made of the place of interest in a theory of educa- tion. Interest may be described as the hedonic aspect of the functioning of the self with a situation. This functioning is two-sided; it is conditioned by a past as with Herbart, and yet it is a primary impulse to realisation as with Froebel. Mental content is perhaps less the source than the aliment of interests. In the process of education, interests have less to be created than fed and controlled. It seems to follow that the ideal of a numy-sided interest should give way in a measure to best-sided interest. For, on the side of origin, interests are impulses of which neither good nor bad is to be predicated. How then should they be at all indiscrim- inately or even equally developed? They are rather to be developed for the sake of the social situation. However, since interests are in the first place unmoral rather than immoral or moral, it is possible to make their very existence an argument for their cultivation. For even original powers and tendencies bear the stamp of a previous endorsement by the race; and the presumption is that few if any of them are mere excrescences in the contemporary social situation. Over against education by interest has been set education by effort, or the disciplinary theory. Yet it is needless, and inconsistent with the facts, to oppose effort to interest. A synthetic attitude would only be debarred if effort implied distaste, or interest ease. But effort and interest are rather complementary. Perhaps there is no interest without effort. The prevalence of a contrary opinion may be due to a con- fusion of effort with the disagreeable. Probably, again, there is no effort without an interest, either mediated or imme- diate. It is commonly to be found that an interest at first external tends to become by effort more vital to the self. Thus if an Herbartian system of education pays too little attention to the developmental powers as such, a disciplinary system makes the error of disparaging mental content. But one does not train the will separately, nor the interests merely as such. Both are developed as related aspects of a unitary personality, and grow together as inseparably as control and freedom. 8 114 Herbart and Froebel. Finally, it may be well to summarise the conclusions which have been reached in the course of our attempt at a synthesis. The following tabulation may serve to recapitulate the line of thought that has been followed. But such is the nature of the present endeavour, that, taken of itself and apart from the previous context, a summary may prove to be neither intelligible nor convincing. Indeed, although at this stage, for the sake of greater clearness, the terminology of dog- matism may be employed, all that is said is intended only as the nucleus of a working hypothesis. 1. For Froebel, the mind is a unitary activity. For Her- bart, ideas are independent activities. But it is possible to regard the ideas as dynamic, yet normally subject to a unitary will. 2. The psychology of Froebel is a psychology of will and attention. That of Herbart is a psychology of habit. But habit is essentially funded attention; and attention is habit accommodating itself to a " crisis." 3. The emphasis of Froebel is upon mental forms or unities ; that of Herbart upon content. An evolutionary theory of the mind, which may be teleologically interpreted, may afford a synthetic interpretation of the unitary process from which these aspects have been abstracted. For, in the concrete, content and form are inseparable. 4. For Froebel, the Ego is a given principle or soul. For Herbart, the self is a construction. Froebel may be in the right to the extent that selfhood is implicitly given; and Herbart to the extent that it is not g^ven explicitly. 5. The educational theory of Froebel emphasises the self; and that of Herbart the situation. But the self is a focus of the environment; and again, the environment is an objec- tive manifestation of the agent self. 6. For Froebel, the will is free. For Herbart, the will is determined. But the synthetic hypothesis is tenable, that the self is in process of winning its way out of determination into freedom. 7. In his metaphysic, Herbart emphasises the unchange- able character of reality. On the other hand, the philosophy of Froebel assumes the reality of change. But for an ontology Attempt at an Edutational Synthesis. ii$ of evolutionary idealism, reality involves change in the perma- nent, and permanence in change. 8. For Froebel as well as Herbart, character is the end of education. But Froebel aims at character in progress and Herbart at character in equilibrium. The true aim in education, from the standpoint of the individual, is a char- acter of moving equilibrium or equilibrated progress. 9. The ideal of Herbart is a static perfection. That of Froebel is a progressive betterment. But while, from the standpoint of humanity, ideals are dynamic, yet viewed sub specie aeternitatis they may be perfect and complete. 10. Both Froebel and Herbart find that there is nothing good but the good will. But in the development of the good will, Herbart emphasises the intellect, and Froebel the emotions. The will, however, is the concrete mind, viewed as dynamic, of which feeling and intellect are the sectional phases. Emotion may be regarded as the periphery of thought, and thought as the focus of emotion. 11. For Herbart, ideas make the character. For Froebel, the development of potentialities makes the character. But character is less a product than a process; and potentialities and ideas are functional aspects of that process. 12. Herbart emphasises culture; Froebel, to a degree, nature. But nature, teleologically interpreted, is cultural. Nature, as origin, is not opposed to culture, as value; but these are terminal aspects of the education of man. 13. To a certain extent, Herbart emphasises curriculum the more; and Froebel method. But method is the curri- culum as dynamic. 14. Herbart to a degree emphasises the technique, and Froebel the spirit of instruction. Technique should be in- formed with an aspect of subjectivism, or made one's own. 15. Herbart would educate by instruction, Froebel by development. But development and instruction are simply the subjective and objective aspects of the educative process. 16. Herbart does not educate for vocation; Froebel edu- cates for " spiritual " vocation. Perhaps vocational training may be made both cultural and spiritual. ii6 Herbart and Froebel. 17. Herbart educates for indi vidual perfection; Froebel for religious and institutional lite. But a synthesis is possible, for true individuality implies institutionalism. 18. Froebel emphasises freedom in education; and Her- bart, control. But the only trustworthy control, and the only effectual freedom, are synthesised in self-control. 19. For Herbart, education moves towards a socially de- termined pattern. For Froebel, it attempts to liberate the divine element in the individual. But, pragmatically, social- isation and liberation are one and the same. 20. Herbart aims at many-sided interest as a mental type. Froebel is more concerned with best-sided interest. Syn- thetically there are reasons for regarding the existence of interests as an argument for their development; but not for their fortuitous or even equal development.