CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME OF THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND GIVEN IN 1 89 1 BY HENRY WILEIAMS SAGE Cornell University Library arW994 Aristotle: a chapter from the history of 3 1924 031 899 978 olin.anx IP IP Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924031899978 ARISTOTLE. WORKS BY THE SAME AUTHOR. THE LIFE OF GOETHE. New Edition, partly rewritten. 1863. STUDIES IN ANIMAL LIFE. With Coloured Frontispiece and other Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 5s. THE PHYSIOLOGY OF COMMON LIFE. With Illustrations. 2 vols. 1859. SEASIDE STUDIES AT ILFRACOMBE, TENBY, SOLLY ISLES, AND JERSEY. With Illustrations. Second Edition. 1860. THE BIOGRAPHICAL HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY -. from Thales to the Present Day. Library Edition. 1857. ARISTOTLE: A CHAPTER FROM THE HISTORY OF SCIENCE, INCLUDING* ANALYSES OF AKISTOTLE'S SCIENTIFIC WEITINGS. BT GEORGE HENRY LEWES. LONDON: SMITH, ELDEE AND CO., 65, COENHILL. M.DCCC.LXIV. [ The right of Translation is reserved, - ] A< HH^33 Nam de famosis philosophus solus Aristoteles cum sua familia voeatus est judieio omnium sapientum, quoniam ipse omnes partes philosophise digessit secundum possibilitatem sui temporis, sed tamen ad finem sapiento non per- venit. — Bogeb Bacon: Opus Majus, p. 4, Venet., 1750. Noi siamo qui tra noi discorrendo familiarmente per investigar qualche verita ; io non avro mai per male, che yoi mi palesiate i miei errori, e quando io non avro conseguita la mente d'Aristotile, riprendetemi pur liberamente, che io ve ne avrd buon grado. — Galileo Galilei : Dialoghi, XL, 128, Opere, Milano, 1811. Bur. — Volete che Platone sia un ignorante, Aristotile sia un asino, e quei che l'hanno seguitati sieno insensati, stupidi, e fanatichi ? Fra. — Figlio mio, non dico che questi sieno li pulledri, e quelli gli asini, come voi volete ch'io dica ; ma come vi dissi da principio, li stimo eroi de la terra, ma che non voglio credergli senza causa, ne ammetterli quelle proposi- zione de le quali le contradittorie come possete aver compreso, se non siete a fatto cieco e sordo, sono tanto espressamente vere. — Giobdano Bboto : De I'infinito Universo, Op. Ital., II., 67, Leipzig, 1830. PE E F AC E, The conception of evolution as the law of life, and conse- quently as the law of Humanity, a conception which links the Present indissolubly with the whole Past, and gives to the study of history a new and deeper significance, is the creation of our age. By a venial, yet fatal error, Catholicism separated itself from the traditions of ancient thought ; with equal exclusiveness, Protestantism opposed the great labours of the Middle Ages ; and the philosophy of the 18th century in turn rejected both, shouting the watchwords of Progress and Enlightenment, as if these words were then heard for the first time. All piety towards the Past was gone. With clearer vision the leading minds of the 19th century have attempted a reconciliation by accepting the positive, and rejecting the negative tendencies of all schools. History has consequently been studied with increasing ardour, and with ever-widening aims. Nor is it only the development of national life which History is summoned to investigate. Everywhere questions of origin and develop- ment have become paramount. The history of our globe, and the development of animal life, are debated with a fervour which would have been incomprehensible a century •yiii PREFACE. ago. Even the anatomist is no longer contented to display what the tissues are ; he must also trace their origin, and show how they became what they are. The origin and development of Science are questions of high interest, and fortunately admit of being handled even by those who would shrink from the gigantic difficulties of a History of the Sciences. I have been for many years pre- paring myself to attempt a sketch of the Embryology of Science, so to speak, — an exposition of the great momenta in scientific development ; and the present volume is the first portion of such an exposition, which I publish separately because in itself it forms a monograph, and because I may never live to com- plete the larger scheme. As a monograph it has not, I believe, been forestalled. Numerous and exhaustive as are the works devoted to Aristotle's moral and metaphysical writings, there is not one which attempts to display, with any fulness, his scientific researches. The only considerable treatise which touches on this ground,* is strictly confined within the limits of Natural History. Although Aristotle mainly represents the science of twenty centuries, his scientific writings are almost unknown in England. Casual citations, mostly at secondhand, and vague eulogies, often betraying great misconception, are abundant ; but rare indeed is the indication of any accurate appreciation extending beyond two works, the De Animd, and the History of Animals. The absence of translations is at once a cause and a sign of this neglect. Of the 15 treatises analyzed in the present volume, only the two just named have been translated, * J. B. Meter: Aristoteles Thierlamde, Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der Zoologie, Physiologie, und alien Philosophic. Berlin, 1855. PREFACE. IX and one of these appeared after my work was written.* Nor would translations be of much help to the ordinary student, unless illuminated by an ample commentary, such as would place him at the requisite point of view for appreciating these ancient monuments of scientific labour. I have endeavoured to furnish such a point of view, as far as the limits and the object of my work permitted. Instead of following the usual plan of weaving together various passages scattered through widely different works, which thus presents a succinct, systematic, and often false outline of the doctrines, I have analyzed the separate treatises, given the doctrines precisely as Aristotle gave them (illuminating them when necessary and possible from other sources), and have never distorted them into modern formulae, nor eliminated from them their essential or incidental absurdities. This latter point is of some importance. Most expositions of Aristotle's doctrines, when they have not been dictated by a spirit of viru- lent detraction, or unsympathetic indifference, have carefully suppressed all, or nearly all, the absurdities, and only retained what seemed plausible and consistent. But in this procedure their historical significance disappears. Writing as an his- torian, not as a partisan, I have allowed the errors and the crudities to take their rightful place beside the plausibilities and truths ; thus preserving, as far as may be, the historical colouring derived from the inherent weakness of early Science, and the individual weakness of Aristotle. * There is, indeed, a version of all Aristotle's works, by Thomas Taylor, in 10 vols. 4to. But there are two reasons for considering this as practically non- existent: first, its rarity, only a very few copies having been printed ; secondly, and chiefly, the translator's imperfect knowledge of science. I speak of the work only from report ; but from what I have seen quoted, I believe the report does him substantial justice. X PREFACE. That I have not been unmindful of what my predecessors in all ages have done towards the elucidation of various points, will be apparent from the notes, of which it_ is only needful to say, that all citations made at secondhand have been scrupu- lously acknowledged, and all references not thus acknowledged may be accepted as the results of my own research. It is eminently desirable that the growing practice of secondhand citation should be discouraged ; since our native infirmity renders us all sufficiently liable to error, without our taking on ourselves the responsibility of other men's carelessness or of their misrepresentations. Headers who have but small interest in the details of Biology, may perhaps object to my having sometimes — espe- cially in the notes — wandered from the broad path, into the windings and obscure alleys whither only a certain class will care to follow. Let me plead in anticipation, that although my own predilections have seduced me into adding details for the sake of a class, I have not sacrificed any general interest to such predilections, but merely given these details in addition. The first draught of this volume was completed in February, 1862. The rewriting was finished in July, 1862 ; but fresh researches, and many revisions, have retarded its publication. The Priory, January, 1864. CONTENTS. CHAPTER PAGE I. The Life op Aristotle 1 II. The Dawn of Science 24 HE. Ancient Science 45 IV. The Metaphysical and Scientific Methods 65 V. Plato's Method 101 VI. Aeistotle's Method 108 VII. Aristotle's Physics, Meteorology, and Mechanics 122 VHI. Aristotle's Anatomy 154 IX. Aristotle's Physiology 171 X. General Principles of Biology.. 182 XI. ANTICIPATIOSL.PJ~MeBERN DISCOVERIES 197 XII. Life and Mind : Be AnimI 221 XIII. On the Senses 246 XIV. On Memory, Sleep, Dreams, and Longevity 256 XV. " The History of Animals " 269 XVI. "On the Pabts of Animals" 292 XVLL On Generation and Development 325 XVIII. Conclusion 376 Index 383 ARISTOTLE. CHAPTEE I. THE LIFE OP ARISTOTLE. § 1. It is difficult to speak of Aristotle .without exaggera- tion : he is felt to be so mighty, and is known to be so wrong. History, surveying the whole scope of his pretensions, gazes on him with wonder. Science, challenging these separate pretensions, and testing their results, regards them with in- difference ; an indifference easily exasperated into antagonism by the clamorous urgency of unauthenticated praise. It is dif- ficult to direct the opposing streams of criticism into the broad equable current of a calm appreciation ; because the splendour of his fame perpetuates the memory of his failure ; and to be just we must appreciate both. His intellect was piercing and comprehensive; his attainments surpassed those of every known philosopher ; his influence has only been exceeded by the great founders of Eeligions; nevertheless, if we now estimate the product of his labours in the discovery of posi- tive truths, it appears insignificant, when not erroneous. None of the great germinal discoveries in science are due to him, or to his disciples. His vast and active intellect gave an impulse to philosophy, and for twenty centuries held the 1 2 THE LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. [CHAP. I. world in awe. Then came a change; the long-murmuring spirit of rebellion grew strong enough to dethrone him. Ages of servility had raised him to an unexampled eminence ; in the tumult of revolution this pedestal became a pillory. "When the Arabs kill a lion, their released terror vents itself in insults on the harmless corpse : they kick, and spit upon, and apostrophize in sarcasms the helpless image of their former dread. It was thus with the great lion of Stagira. Men who a few years before would have burned a presumptuous critic for daring to think that the great teacher could be wrong, were now laughing to scorn the method and conclusions of the rejected sophist. 1 Our task is twofold : we shall constantly have to bear in mind the relative (or historical) and the absolute (or scientific) aspect which his achievements present ; never permitting our natural and justifiable admiration for the effort, to disguise our appreciation of its result ; nor, conversely, permitting our contempt or disregard of the result, to mislead us into an unjust depreciation of the effort. " It is the destiny and glory 1 The virulence with which some of the reformers attacked him is at times amusing. A good example is Ramus : Scholarum Physicarum libri octo, 1565 (which I only know at second hand). Less virulent, but not less decided, is the antagonism of Nizolids : De veris Principiis et vera Ratione Philosophandi contra pseudo Philosophos, Parma, 1553. He complains indignantly of the Greeks being followed, " perinde ac si essent oracula qusedam Delphica, aut arcana divinitus revelata, qua? nullo pacto falsa esse possent," and he compares Aristotle to the cuttlefish escaping in a cloud of ink — perhaps the earliest example of this now threadbare comparison. Leibnitz thought this treatise worth republishing, and wrote a preface to it ; see Tiraboschi : Storia della Litteratura Italiana, 1812,, VH. 44, where he truly says that if Nizolius is right in combating the Peripatetics, he is less happy in the attempt to replace them. A more formidable antagonist is Telesio, whose work, De Natura Iterumjuxta propria Principia libri novem, Naples, 1586, 1 shall have to quote hereafter. Even more virulent is Patrizio (see Note 9). Giordano Bruno, though relentless towards the peripatetics of his day, is more respectful to Aristotle. The same must be said of Galileo and Descartes ; and notably of Taurellus, in his attack on C^esalpinus, punningly entitled Alpes Casce, hoc est A. Casalpini monstrosa et superba Dogmata discussa et excussa, Frank- fort, 1650. No longer worthy of more than a passing glance is Basso : Phi- losophies Naturalis adversus Aristotelem libri XII., Elzevir, 1649, though once CHAP. I.] THE LIFE OE ARISTOTLE. 3 of the anatomist of Stagira," says Isidore St. Hilaiee, 2 "to have had before him simply precursors and after him only disciples." In yielding our most ample tribute, we must be careful to make that tribute generously just : we must hold the balance fairly, weighing the failures with the successes. In an attempt so delicate, I cannot pre- tend to have preserved the balance; but I can affirm that it has been my constant aim; and I wish that I could be certain of so expressing myself as to prevent readers from misconstruing either the praise or the blame which will have to be pronounced. The risk must be run; both praise and blame must be expressed without reticence. Piety towards the Past demands of us to be ready with our gratitude for all good work ; and an equal piety towards the Present commands us to beware of an exaggeration which would convert panegyric of the departed into insults against the living. It is the glory of Science to be constantly progressive. After the lapse of a century, the greatest teacher, on reappearing among men, would have to assume the attitude of a learner. His point of view would no longer command the whole field of knowledge. The very seed sown by himself would have sprung up into a forest to obscure the view. But we who rejoice in the grandeur of the forest must not forget by whom the seeds were sown. His heritors, we are richer, but not greater than he. " The similitude which many have fancied between the superiority of the moderns to the ancients, and the elevation of a dwarf on the back of a giant, is altogether false and puerile. Neither were they giants nor are we dwarfs ; but all of us men of the same standard, and we the taller of the two highly prized. Campanella I have not read. Gassexdi is an uncompro- mising adversary (see Note 18). If we except the two great luminous intellects Galileo and Descartes, the inferiority of these adversaries to the man they attack is so conspicuous that nothing but sympathy with their revolutionary fervour can make them tolerable. 2 Isidobe Geoitboy St. Hilaire: Histoire Glnhak des Begnes Organiques, Paris, 1854, 1. 19. 1-2 4 THE LITE OE ARISTOTLE. [CHAP. I. by adding their height to our own : provided always that we do not yield to them in study, attention, vigilance and love of truth, for if these qualities be wanting, so far from mounting on the giant's shoulders, we throw away the advantage of our own stature by remaining prostrate on the ground." 3 § 2. The ancient biographies of Aristotle have been gathered by Buhle into the first volume of his valuable but unfinished edition of the Opera Omnia. Meagre in detail, and of suspicious authenticity, these are all that moderns have to rely on for the facts of Aristotle's career. And as I was aware, from previous experience, that the whole race of compilers is far from trustworthy, and that little con- fidence is to be placed in an ancient compiler (though to moderns it generally seems as if anything written in Greek must have a peculiar authenticity, even nonsense wearing an august air in that language), it occurred to me that perhaps the mere registration of the dates at which these several biographies were compiled, might amply justify scepticism as to their accuracy. All ancient writers, except, perhaps, Thucydides, are uncritical in their reception of facts. ' Even in our own critical age, as it is rashly called, we find it extremely difficult to ascertain the truth respecting celebrated persons ; so powerful is the mythical tendency, and so fungus- like the rapidity with which lies are propagated. But the ancients had not risen to the conception of what constitutes evidence ; they were as credulous as children ; and accepted almost any marvel which was narrated gravely. What then are the dates, or thereabouts ? Aristotle was born b.c. 384. Diogenes Laektius, whose narrative is the fullest, the best, and the most generally followed, was born, at the earliest, nearly six centuries later — i.e. a.d. 200 ; and it is even supposed that he was as late as Constantino. The next on our list is Ammonius (if the work be really his), who comes 8 This fine passage is quoted from Ludoviocs Vives by Dugald Stewaet. CHAP. I.] THE LIFE OP ARISTOTLE. 5 eight centuries after his hero, in a.d. 460; and that these eight centuries have not been profitably employed in sifting tradition, and bringing it nearer to accuracy, may be gathered from a single detail noticed by Btjhle, 4 that Aristotle is made a pupil of Socrates, who died just fifteen years before the Stagirite was born. The nearest biographer, in point of time, is Dionysius of Halicarnassus (b.c. 50), and this gives a gap of three centuries ; moreover, one meagre page comprises all he has to say. Hesychius was born a.d. 500 — nearly nine centuries too late ; the date of Suidas is uncertain, but pro- bably not earlier than the eleventh century of our era. These writers contradict each other on separate points. What means have we for deciding between them ? They may have had contemporary documents as their authorities ; but what guarantee have we for the accuracy of these docu- ments ? It is but just three hundred years since Shakspbaeb was born ; throughout this period he has been prized, and written about ; compilers have done their worst upon this subject ; yet what do we authentically know of his life ? above all, what value do we attach to the earliest biography, that by Eowb ? If, therefore, modern scholars have pieced together the various details traditionally preserved about Aristotle, we 4 " Quis enim Ammonium credat tain absurdum, ut Aristotelem per tres annos Socratis, qui diu ante mortuus esset, discipulum, eundemque Alexandri in itinere per Asiam usque ad Indos comitem fuisse, temere asseruerit ? " Buhle : Arist. Opera, I., 51. It has been suggested that instead of Socrates we should read the school of Socrates; but there was no such school. Mr. Blakesley, by a plausible emendation, suggests Xenockates as the name which by corruption has become Sockates. This, however, ill accords with the statement of Ammonius ; nor have we any evidence that Xenocrates taught till many years afterwards. During the revision of this chapter there has fallen in my way a copy of the Greek text of Ammonius, from the Library of St. Mark's at Venice, now first published by Dr. Robbe : Vita Aristotelis ex codice Marciano Grace nunc primum edita, Lugd.-Batav., 1861, which gives the same reading as the old Latin translation, previously our only guide. Here is the passage: krUtv Si yevopevog eirra nal dixa, tov HvGoi Qtov , xpi\aavTOZ avTif fAouoipuv irap' 'ASijvatoic, 0oir$ XuiKpam, xal avvijv tov, p-ixP l Tt\evTtjg abrov xpovov okiyov ovra. 6 THE LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. [CHAP. I. may accept their narrative as the best which is now pro- curable, though with no firm reliance on any side when separate points are under discussion. I shall not, there- fore, occupy the reader's time with discussions, where decisive evidence is necessarily deficient ; but tell the story, by using at my own discretion the narratives given in the latest and most authoritative treatises, 5 leaving the unprofit- able task of weighing imponderable evidence to those who delight in such ingenuities. § 3. Stagira — which, Boeckh says, should correctly be written Stageiros — was a town in Northern Greece, on the western coast of the Strymonic Gulf (now called the Gulf of Contezza) just where the coast begins to take a southerly bend. Its situation has been compared with the southern part of the Bay of Naples. Immediately south, a promontory, like the Punta della Campanella, and nearly in the same lati- tude, runs out in an easterly direction, thus effectually screen- ing the little town and its harbour, Capros, from the stormy squalls of the iEgean. Stagira is said to resemble Sorrento, not only in the general disposition of its coast lines, but also in the terraced windings of its multitudinous orange and lemon groves. 6 § 4. In this picturesque seaport, Aristotle was born, B.C. 384, that is, exactly one century after the birth of Herodotus ; one century before the foundation of the Alexandrian library, and the execution of the Septuagint version of the Scriptures ; and two centuries before the death of Philopcemen, " the last of the Greeks," when the Achaean league dissolved before the Boman power, and Greece merged her splendid existence in the dependence of a Boman province. 6 Buhle, I, 80-104. Eittee : History of Philosophy, trans, by Morrison, 1839, III. Blakesley : Life of Aristotle, 1839. Stahr, art. Arist. in Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography, 1844. Brandis : Aristoteles seine Academischen Zeitgenossen und ndclisten Nachfolger, 1853. Zeller : Die Philosophie der Griechen, 1 860, II. 6 Blakeslet : Op. eft., p. 12. CHAP. I.] THE LIFE 01? ARISTOTLE. 7 His father, Nicomachus, was a physician and an Ascle- piad; but whether he had any better claim to the honour of descent from iEsculapius than so many others who usurped the title, 7 or simply belonged to the famous guild, cannot now be determined. It is certain that he was a physician of repute, attached to Amyntas II., the father of the Macedonian Philip. The fact of his profession, coupled with the fact of Stagira being on the sea-coast, may have been of moment in determining his son's studies in the direction of physiology and marine zoology. There is indeed a .passage in Galen, often quoted, which affirms that among the Asclepiads chil- dren were taught dissection, just as they were taught reading and writing, thus becoming as familiar with anatomy as with the alphabet. But this must be accepted with a large handful of salt ; for, as we shall see presently, the Asclepiads, and Aristotle himself, were very imperfectly acquainted with anatomy. The statement, however, even in its exaggeration, points to the important fact that anatomy was not neglected, but formed one part of the boy's education ; and this isolated fact sums up all we know of that education. § 5. It is unknown how long he remained at Stagira before accompanying his father to the court of Amyntas, at Pella, where he learned to know and ingratiate himself with Philip, who was hereafter to befriend him. Everything at this epoch is conjecture, and conjecture may amuse, but cannot instruct. § 6. At the age of seventeen he lost his father. This is the next isolated fact which has been recorded, and it is important. He thus became his own master, with the com- mand of a large fortune ; a perilous condition to most youths the temptation to squander his fortune in frivolous dissipation must have been great, and could only be withstood by an unusual seriousness of mind, or unusual felicity in his social connections. So plausible is the supposition that a youth 7 See Hakless: De Medicis Veteribus " Aschpiades" dictis, a work only known to me at second hand. 8 THE LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. [CHAP. I. thus circumstanced will be ruined, that idle gossip, which always flits about a celebrated name, invented a story of his having wasted his means, and having been reduced to sell drugs for a subsistence ; a story which, however, found refutation even among the ancients, and is wholly irreconcilable with the known facts of his subsequent career. He was young, ardent, ambitious, rich. Athens, the glory of the world, though her political sun was setting, the luminous centre of Philosophy and Art, beckoned to him, as Rome and Florence beckon to the students of our day. Plato taught there, and might admit him to the groves of the Academy. To listen to this " old man eloquent," was a rare attraction, and naturally it drew him to Athens. Arrived there, he found that Plato was absent. Awaiting the great teacher's return, he qualified himself for discipleship Joy three years of arduous study. Had he squandered his wealth in dissipa- tion, as the babblers reported, he could not have collected the treasure of books which he is known to have bought; for in those days it was almost as costly to create a library of books as in our own to create a gallery of pictures. 8 To collect books and to read them are not always the same thing. "With him they were one; and Plato, alluding to the extraordinary passion he displayed, called him " the reader." His writings show how diligently he had studied all accessible literature ; and it is to his punctilious quotation 8 According to Gellius, he paid for the works of Speusippus alone three Attic talents, that is about 700A of our money, a sum not to be spared out of the profits of drug-selling unless by a merchant prince. In our own days 1,0007. has been paid for a rare edition of an Italian poet ; but that was merely the avidity of a collector's furor backed by the wealth of an English noble- man. Curious details on the price of books in the Middle Ages may be read in Muratori : Dissertazione sopra Vantichitd, Italiane, Diss. XLIII. Com- pare also Heeken : Gesckichte der Classischen Litteratur im Mittelalter, Werke, 1822, IV. In our days of cheap literature— cheap, because we have cheap paper, and that because we wear linen instead of woollen clothes —these details seem to render the darkness of the dark ages more in- telligible. CHAP. I.] THE LIFE OE ARISTOTLE. 9 of his predecessors that we are greatly indebted for the preservation of many fragments of ancient thought. So little justice is there in Bacon's sarcasm, that like an Eastern despot he strangled his rivals in order to reign peaceably. 9 § 7. When Aristotle came to Athens the splendour of her life was fast departing, and near at hand was the towering greatness of Macedon, so soon to overshadow her on the plains of Chseroneia. The sun was setting on the Age of Pericles, and was rising on the Age of Alexander. For sixty years Pericles had ceased to thunder from the bema ; had ceased to communicate his agitating stimulus to art and politics ; had ceased to adorn the beautiful city with 9 Aristotle's precepts, no less than his practice, answer this accusation. See Metaph., II., 1, 995; De Colo, I., 10, 279 ; and De Anima, I., 1. Bacon simply echoed Patkizio, whose enmity was virulent and avowed, and who de- clares that one cause of this hatred was the abuse which Aristotle heaps on the writers from whom his best ideas are stolen. Patkitii: Discussionum Peripa- teticarum tomi quatuor, Bale, 1581, from which learned but untrustworthy work some moderns have largely drawn. The first volume contains a life and a list of the extant works, with an account of all the Peripatetics. In the third book there is a valuable collection of the passages in which A. refers to his own writings ; a collection subsequently used and expanded by Bitter, but without the acknowledgment due in such a case. The second volume gives an exposition of the points of agreement between the doctrines of A. and Plato, and the older writers. In the third volume the points of difference are noted. In the preface he complains of the insults to philosophers (p. 291-2), and sarcastically adds that there is no mention of Hippocrates. (Some moderns, coupling this supposed silence with the silence of Thucydides, have argued that Hippocrates lived after Aristotle ; but the fact is that Hippocrates is mentioned, and in the Politics there is a sketch of his views on climate.) In the fourth volume Patkizio gives full expression to his antagonism. Giordano Bruno, in spite of his own opposition to the peripatetic system, speaks with measureless con- tempt of Patrizio as " un stereo di pedante Italiano che ha imbrattati tanti quinterni con le sue discussione peripatetiche," and vows that he has not under- stood th$ Stagirite, but only read and reread him " cucito, scucito e confeiito con mill* altri greci autori amici e nemici di quello, et al fine fatta una grandis- sima fatica non sola senza profitto alcuno, ma etiam con un grandissimo sproposito." De la Causa Principio et Una {Opere ltd., Leipzig, 1830), I., 250. Patrizio had many admirers and imitators; a notable one is Basso (see Note 1). I have not had the courage to extend my wanderings further through this rubbish of denunciation and criticism heaped up by the iconoclasts, 10 THE LIFE OP ARISTOTLE. [CHAP. I. his munificence and taste. Sophocles and Eueipides were gone ; and the grand and pathetic drama they had unfolded to applauding thousands, had fallen into the hands of ChjEEemon, Cleophon, and Theodeotes (the last the friend of Aristotle), whose efforts to make rhetoric supply the place of poetry pointed unmistakably towards decline. Aristo- phanes no longer laughed at the absurdities, and scourged the corruptions of his time, in riotous and reckless farces, which too often wilfully misrepresented persons and ideas essentially wise and noble. No great prose writer except Xenophon remained ; not one poet of eminence. But if a sunset, it was still a glorious sunset, with some splendour of the after-glow. Great memories swelled ambitious minds. Powerful vibrations were still felt from Salamis, Marathon, and Platsea. Isoobates upheld the renown of Athenian eloquence ; and the greater Demosthenes was preparing for his matchless displays. Peaxiteles was at work upon statues, the very copies of which were for centuries to be the despair of artists. Scopas, the' sculptor of the immortal Niobe and the Venus of Milo, had enchanted the Athenians with his Furies. Diogenes, with drastic energy, despised the citizens from his tub. The schools were crowded with listeners to many teachers. In every direction there was intellectual activity and social ferment. A young, keen intellect would find there abundant stimulus. § 8. As years ripened his intelligence, and free intercourse with eminent men procured him the advantages and oppor- tunity of display, Aristotle gradually won for himself a foremost position. He came there a raw ambitious youth, not only with the disadvantages of inexperience, but with those disadvantages of accent and manner which, in the eyes of supercilious Athenians — the Frenchmen of antiquity — made him seem almost a barbarian. These, however, he soon modified. One fact recorded of him — that he was some- CHAP. I.] THE LIFE OE ARISTOTLE. 11 what given to foppery in costume — implies an eager sensitive- ness to approbation, which would have directed his attention to anything provincial in his air. Keen, witty, logical, and learned, he was a brilliant talker, and in that city of talkers could hold his own with the best ; not even refraining from controversy with his great master. Without pretending to decide the much vexed question of his ingratitude towards Plato, I must express my own disbelief in the accusation ; although it is very credible, and by no means derogatory to him, that, differing from his master in cast of mind, as well as on certain fundamental points of philosophy, he should often, during the seventeen years they were together, have been seduced into warm, and sometimes irritating, discussion with one whom, on the whole, he considered as the noblest of thinkers. All opposition is apt to be construed as an offence ; and if Aristotle's criticisms and allusions to Plato are not always remarkable for their judicial calmness, they have never any approach to irreverence. Often in antagonism — how could this sincerely be avoided? — he is never in hostility to Plato. Indeed, in the Ethics, he complains of the necessity of attacking doctrines held by " dear friends," adding — "It is our duty to slay our own flesh and blood where the cause of Truth is at stake, especially as we are philo- sophers; loving both, it is our sacred duty to give the preference to Truth." It is a timidity unworthy of a noble mind to shrink from intellectual opposition as an offence against friendship, and to suppress convictions for fear of misconstruction . § 9. Aristotle remained twenty years at Athens. During seventeen of these years, Plato was first his master, and then his friend. His health was, like that of most ardent brain- workers, delicate. He was short and slender in person ; he had small eyes, and an affected lisp. Somewhat given to sarcasm in conversation, he made, of course, many enemies. On hearing that some one had vituperated him in his absence 12 THE LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. [CHAP. I. he humourously said, " If he pleases, he may heat me too — in my absence." His heart was kind, as was manifest in certain acts, and is expressed in this saying, " He who has many friends has no friends," which profoundly touches the very core of the subject, and may he paired off with this other saying of his, " A friend is one soul in two bodies." When asked how we should behave towards friends, he said, " As we should wish them to behave towards us." Advancing age and development, no less than the decidedly scientific bias impressed upon his studies, necessarily caused him to take up an independent position with respect to Plato, who had little taste for physical science, and whose intellect naturally withdrew from those very subjects to which his young rival was, by nature and early bias, strongly determined. With- out absolutely opening a rival school, Aristotle gradually gathered round him a circle of admirers, and began, during the last years of his Athenian residence, to give lectures. 10 § 10. Among the listeners was Heemias, the tyrant (or ruler) of Atarneus, and to him, by invitation, Aristotle went, on quitting Athens, after Plato's death. His companion on this journey was Xenoceates, the best loved of Plato's disciples. What was the object of their visit ? It has been conjectured that Heemias invited them to frame a political constitution. The scheme, if such it were, was frustrated by the assassina- tion of Hermias, and the fall of Atarneus into Persian hands. The two philosophers escaped to Mytilene, carrying with them Pythias, the adopted daughter of their friend and patron ; and Aristotle subsequently married her, out of compassion for her defenceless position, and respect for the memory of his murdered friend. Worthy of special reprobation, as indicating the peculiar infelicity with which calumny often selects its 10 The story of his haying practised medicine at this time, which is founded on his interest in that art, is refuted by his express statement in the work, De Divinatione, I., 468, that in medicine he was only one of the laity, though accustomed to philosophize upon it. CHAP. I.] THE LIFE OP ARISTOTLE. 13 points of attack, is the fact that his friendship for Heemias, and generosity towards Pythias, furnished the cruel thought- lessness of scandal with its bitterest accusations. Here once more may be seen how in this life men are punished for their virtues ; as a set-off, perhaps, to the rewards which often crown their vices. So little reliance can be placed on these ancient scandals, that some call Pythias the daughter, and others the concubine, of Hebmias. It is, perhaps, a slight objection to both these assertions that Heemias was an eunuch. § 11. To the memory of Hermias he raised a statue at Delphi, with an inscription ; on which act was founded a charge of impiety. Nor was the memory of Pythias, who died after giving birth to a daughter, less honoured by the grateful husband. In his will he enjoined that her bones should be- laid beside his own. § 12. He had not long been at Mytilene before he received from Philip of Macedon the magnificent offer to undertake the charge of the young Alexandee. From this it is evident that his reputation, while at Athens, must have been consider- able. To Macedon he went. His princely pupil was then fourteen : young enough to receive a determining bias, old enough to revere the intellectual force which impressed that bias. The respectful love which men of fine intellect and generous sympathies so gladly give to their first instructors is well expressed in the saying of Alexandee, that he honoured Aristotle no less than his own father ; for if to the one he owed life, to the other he owed that which made life valuable. That the tutor and pupil might promenade in the cool shade during the hours of instruction, Philip caused a gym- nasium to be built in a grove.; and even so late as the days of Plutarch, the traveller might still see the shady walks (7T£ptVarot) with their stone seats for resting-places. Aristotle remained seven years in Macedon ; but only four of these were given to the education of the prince,* who at eighteen 14 THE LITE OE ARISTOTLE. [CHAP. I. became Eegent. Thus while Demosthenes was thundering against the ambition of Philip, who claimed for Macedon the hegemony of Greece, Aristotle was stimulating and enlarging the mind of Alexander, who was soon to carry the silver shields of Macedon from Syria to Egypt, from Candahar to the Indus, and from the Indus to the Persian Gulf. Popular fiction makes the great teacher accompany the great conqueror on this splendid expedition; and one regrets that this is a fiction. There was, indeed, other work for Aristotle to do, which the life of camps would hardly have advanced. Still the expedition would have been a vast experience for him ; and his observing mind could not have beheld that varied, shifting panorama without great result. To have passed with the conquering hosts to Tyre ; to have witnessed the foundation of Alexandria ; to have lived through the agitations of the day at Arbela, when the countless hosts of Darius were assembled on the plain beneath the Koordish mountains, and there were slaughtered like sheep ; to have witnessed the suc- cessive subjection of Babylon and Susa, of Persepolis and Ecbatana ; and finally to see the young Dionysus, maddened with the insolence of success, cut off suddenly in his youth ; these were grand experiences which one regrets to think were lost to Aristotle. § 13. Although, as I said, the relation between master and pupil lasted only four years, the relation of friendly counsel on the one side, and magnificent gratitude on the other con- tinued. Had it not been for Alexander's princely aid, Aris- totle's enormous collections could not have been made. The aid is unexampled. It is said, but not on trustworthy authority, that Alexander presented him with the sum of eight hundred talents, which represents nearly two hundred thousand pounds of our money. Few critical readers will believe that ; and Schneider, in his edition of the Historia Animalium, quotes with approbation the estimate of a prede- cessor, who calculates that the whole revenue of Macedon CHAP. I.] THE LIFE OE AKISTOTLE. 15 would not have furnished such a sum. Still if we make liberal deductions, and strike off two thirds of this sum, it leaves a splendid surplus. The enormity of the exaggeration points to an enormous sum. Add to this the statement of Pliny, that Alexander gave orders to his hunters, game- keepers, fishermen, and bird-catchers to furnish the philo- sopher with all the material he might desire — an order which at once placed several thousand men at his service. 11 But at the same time remember it is Pliny who makes the state- ment, and for untrustworthiness of statement he cannot easily be surpassed ; so that even here an immense exaggera- tion may be suspected ; and to sum up, remember that although Aristotle must have had a large collection of materials before he could have written his work on animals, Humboldt declares j that there is no trace in that work of any acquaintance with < animals first known through Alexander's expedition.-^ § 14. After an absence of twelve years, B.pj_35i>, Aristotle reappeared in Athens. He found the Academy already occu- pied by his friend Xenoceates ; so that some other place had to be sought where he might open a school. This he found at the Lyceum, a gymnasium in the vicinity of the temple of Apollo Lykeios, founded by Pisistratus, and embellished by Pericles. It was the most splendid of the Athenian gymnasia, consisting of a mass of edifices surrounded with gardens, avenues, and a sacred grove. It had its spacious courts with porticos, theatres for professors, covered promenades, baths, an arena for wrestling matches, and a stadium for foot- races. The walls were adorned with paintings ; the gardens and walks were furnished with seats. But we must not sup- pose, as many suppose, that this establishment was placed 11 Alexandre) Magno rege inflammato cupidine animalium naturas noscendi, delegataque hac commentatione Aristoteli, summo in omni doctrina viro, aliquot millia hominum intotius Asja? Grseciaeque tractu parere jussa, omnium quos venatus, aucupia, piscatusque alebant ; quibusque vivaria, armenta, alvearia, piscinae, aviaria in cura erant ; ne quid usquam genitum ignoraretur ab eo."— Pliny : Hist. Nat., VHL, 16. 16 THE LIFE OP ARISTOTLE. [OHAP. I. under the direction of Aristotle, or that he had any voice in its affairs. He simply received permission to teach in the morning and evening at the peripatos, 12 a permission which was the more acceptable because the shady walks offered facilities to his accustomed habit of walking to and fro during the delivery of lectures. The name of Peripatetics is commonly supposed to have been given to his disciples on account of this habit ; but as, according to the testimony of Theopheastus and Ltcon, the lecture-place itself was named o irtpnrarog, the locality probably gave ,the title to his school. This suggestion is countenanced by the practice in other cases ; for we find the schools designated by the places where they were founded, unless when some peculiarity in doctrine gave the title : thus the Academy, the Porch, the Garden, Megara, and Cyrene, severally gave names to schools ; but never was a name borrowed from some casual peculiarity in the mode of lecturing. Moreover, Aristotle was by no means singular in this practice of promenading while he taught. § 15. For thirteen years he continued teaching, and composing his immortal treatises ; powerfully impressing the crowd of eager disciples, but probably regarded with angry suspicion by the patriots, owing to his connection with Auexandek. And now came the electric shock, shaking Athens to her foundations, and agitating her with tumultuary hopes : the Great Conqueror was no more ! At once, and with exultant energy, the anti-Macedonian party took the lead in public affairs. Aristotle necessarily was in peril ; for although, in truth, his life had been blameless of political intrigue, and no colourable accusation could be raised against him on that score, if only because he was excluded from political influence ; 13 yet as a foreigner, a philosopher, and a friend of Macedon, he was trebly odious to the political 12 Maiteb: Hist, de I' (cole d'Alexandrie, Paris, 1840, 1., 30. 13 This political attitude is conspicuously set forth in Mr. Congebve's intro- duction to his edition of the Politics, London, 1855. CHAP. I.J THE LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. 17 leaders ; and a pretext for accusation was raised on a ground where such pretexts are always easily raised and are always dangerous — irreligion. He was accused of blasphemy, and of paying divine honours to mortals. And who were these mortals he had honoured ? His friend and his wife. The charge may seem frivolous ; but too well he knew the temper of the multitude to hope that the absurdity of the charge would be a guarantee for his safety. Mobs seldom reason, rarely examine. The blameless life and lofty soul of Socrates had been no defence against the charges of Mblittjs ; and Aristotle quitted Athens, "not to give the Athenians a second opportunity of committing a sacrilege against philosophy." § 16. He retired to Chalcis in Eubcea.. There he wrote an elaborate defence of his conduct, and exposed the calum- nies circulated about him. But his health,, always delicate, and severely tasked by unremitting study, rapidly gave way. The Athenians, on his refusal to appear in answer to the summons of the Areopagus, deprived him of citizenship, and all the honours that had been conferred upon him. An idle sentence of death was passed ; but nature had already written that sentence in terms that were not idle. He died in the sixty-third year of his age, B.C.. 322, only a few months before the great orator, Demosthenes, also an exile. § 17. His will, which maybe read in Diogenes Laeetius, tells of his thoughtful kindness. His daughter Pythias, his son Nicomachtjs, his adopted son Nicanoe, and his concubine Herpyllis, are all duly provided for, and some of his slaves are emancipated, others rewarded. § 18. The purposes of this History render it unnecessary to enter upon the vexed question of the authenticity of the various writings which have passed under his name, had I the scholarship which could justify such a digression. The curious reader will easily find abundant material on this and all cognate points. "We have here rather to consider the nature of his ' achievements. The first thing which must 2 18 THE LIFE OS ARISTOTLE. [CHAP. I. strike every one is their encyclopedic extent, unrivalled in the history of literature. In all branches of science then cultivated he was proficient. He wrote on Politics, giving the outlines of two hundred and fifty-five constitutions-; even the little treatise on that subject, which is still extant, is thought to be one of the very best works yet written, and Dr. Aknold, who knew it by heart, declared that he found it of daily service in its application to our own time. His Ethics, Ehetoric, and Logic are still by many held to be authoritative and unsurpassed. His Metaphysics would of itself suffice to found a great renown. His fragments on Poetics is perhaps the most valuable of all ancient critical writings. And as if these were not titles enough, we must now add the several scientific works which form the special object of this volume; these embrace Physics, Astronomy, Zoology, Comparative Anatomy, and Psychology. With Sir W. Hamilton, we may say: "His seal is upon all the sciences, and his speculations have mediately or immediately determined those of all subsequent thinkers." Hegel, though of a less fervid temperament, expresses himself with greater emphasis : " He penetrated into the whole universe of things, and subjected its scattered wealth to intelligence; and to him the greater number of the philosophical sciences owe their origin and distinction." 14 § 19. Such an intellectual phenomenon must always excite astonishment. Let us form what opinion we may of his philosophy, we cannot withhold our admiration of the vigour and comprehensiveness of his mind. Nor is this his only claim. Hq is admirable for the intense urgency of his mind in seeking scientific explanations of phenomena, at a period when such explanations were novelties ; and for the dominant induc- tive tendency which led him on all subjects to collect the facts before reasoning on them. The contrast he presents to Plato 14 Hegbl ; Vorhiiingen iiber die Gesch. der Philos., 18S8, II., 298. CHAP. I.] THE LIFE OE ARISTOTLE. 19 in this respect is as much to his advantage as the contrast in respect of literary power is to his disadvantage. 15 Plato was the most artistic of philosophers, and, among men of great eminence, one of the worst of investigators; not, assuredly, from deficient power, but from his disastrous miscon- ception of Method. In spite of a certain loitering diffuseness of style, and an oppressive circumstantiality in refuting trivial considerations, no one before Plato, no one since, has managed the extremely difficult art of dramatic debate on philosophic topics with such commanding success; and in consequence of this fascinating art, aided by the union of dialectical subtlety with mystical yearnings, a subtlety which seems to give a hope to mysticism, and a warrant to transcendentalism, no one has exercised a more pernicious influence on culture. The charm of the artist has immor- talized the vices of the thinker. 16 With Aristotle the case is different. His Method although imperfect, as we shall shortly see, was not utterly wrong, but wrong only in one important particular ; in direction it was wholly right. It was a Method which required development, and was not like that of Plato, one upon which rational philo- sophy was impossible. But as an artist, Aristotle is simply 15 The contrast is felicitously presented by Matjkice in the following passage: " The student passing from the works of Plato to those of Aristotle is struck first of all with the entire absence of that dramatic form and that dramatic feeling with which he has become familiar. The living human beings with whom he has conversed have -passed away. Prodicus, Protagoras, and Hippias, are no longer lounging upon their couches amidst groups of admiring pupils ; we have no walks along the walls of the city, no readings beside the Hissus, no lively symposia giving occasion to high discourses about love, no Critias re- calling the stories he had heard in the days of his youth, before he became a tyrant, of ancient and glorious republics ; above all, no Socrates forming a centre to those various groups. Some little sorrow for the loss of so many clear and beautiful pictures will be felt, perhaps, by every one, but by far the greater portion of readers will believe that they have ample compensation in the pre- cision and philosophical dignity of the treatise for the richness and variety of the dialogue." — Moral and Metaphysical Philosophy, 1850, L, 162. 16 See Chap. V., "Plato's Method.'' 2—2 20 THE LIFE OE AKISTOTLE. [CHAP. I. without rank ; and as a writer, with submission be it said, he is many degrees removed from excellence. This opinion will probably excite surprise ; let it be, therefore, more circumstan- tially explained. In works like the Politics, Poetics, Ethics, and Ehetoric, — works which from their subject do not severely task the writer's powers of composition, in the artful dis- tribution of materials, — he is intelligible, and sometimes epigrammatic, although without charm. But where more severely tasked, and where he is called upon to marshal numerous facts and ideas for effective presentation, so as to shape arguments into culminating sequence, his composition is rambling, scattered, and confused. There is little illus- tration, and no side-lights of suggestion. The want of artistic composition renders this absence of illustration a serious defect. "When a writer's composition is good there is less need of illustration, or (to use a favourite word with the Florentine Platonists) collustration. But there are few writers who understand this art; and Aristotle understood it not at all. In studying his works, and especially in attempting to reproduce their arguments, this defect has been painfully forced upon my notice ; and when we read praises of his style, supported by the great authority of Ciceeo, we must admit the inference that he referred to works which are no longer extant, and that moderns are awed by the majesty of Greek type. Whatever may be the excellencies of Aristotle's dic- tion (and these. few moderns can pretend to appreciate), the defects of his composition are not matters of opinion, but of demonstration. § 20. It is not consistent with my design to follow the course of Aristotelian influence through the commentaries of Alexandee of Aphrodisias,' Porphyry, Iamblichus, Peoclus, Themistius, Simplicius 01} Philoponus — which I only know through extracts liberally given by scholars ; and this know- ledge has excited in me thelliyeliest desire not to read more. Nor can we follow the splendid train of the Benaissance in CHAP. I.] THE LIFE OE ARISTOTLE. 21 which figure Argyropyltjs, Gaza, Philelphus, George of Tre- bizond, Politian, Hermolaus Barbarus, Latjrentitjs Valla and Keuchlin, some of whom will be laid under contribution as we proceed. The history of Aristotle is for many centuries the history of learning. In the 17th century the tide com- pletely turned. It is true that at the close of the 16th Casaubon (1590) and at the opening of the 17th Du Val (1619) published complete editions of the works, which, to judge by the reprints, 17 must have been rapidly sold. But these were the last efforts of expiring energy. The revolt against Authority which characterized that century, was neces- sarily directed against the thinker whose authority had been most servilely accepted. 18 Nor can I find mention of a single edition after that by Du Val. During the whole of the 18th century there was no edition of the complete works, not even a reprint; and only an occasional edition of the Poetics and Ethics. Btjhle's undertaking (1791-1800) was thwarted by the burning of Moscow, in which all his collected materials were destroyed. § 21. A' reaction began at the close of the 18th which has gained strength in the 19th century. Lessing called attention to the Poetics by his own luminous comments. Schneider by his edition of the History of Animals (1812) — which, alas ! is even yet the only tolerable edition for the use of naturalists, and is very defective — gave an impulse to the 17 Buhle, I, 229-30. 18 Hegel : Gesch. der Philos., II., 416. It is worthy of remark that in 1624 appeared the work o£ Gassendi : Exercitationum paradoxicarum adversus Aristoteleos libri VII., in which, among other propositions, he maintains these four : quod apud A. innumera deficiant — immensa superfluant — immensa fallant — innumera contradicant. In the September of the same year the Par- liament of Paris, which in the 13th century had declared some of A.'s works to he heretical (See Roger Bacon's indignant protest, Opus Majus, Venet. 1750, p. 10 ; compare also Jourdain : JRecherches sur les anciennes traductions Latines d'Aristote, Paris, 1843), issued an edict that on pain of death no oppo- sition against the approved doctrines of the ancients should publicly be taught. The struggle had become a death struggle. 22 THE LIFE OE ARISTOTLE. [CHAP. I. study of the biological works. Fulleborn, Buhle, and Tennemaxn, in their histories of philosophy, began to assign him his legitimate position; but it was Hegel who first spoke of him with enthusiasm and commanding authority. 19 From this time he began once more to be considered as the profoundest of thinkers, whose works emphatically challenged the attention of philosophers. Sir "W. Hamilton, in this country, also lent his powerful aid in the revival, and Eos- mini, in Italy, with more reserve, called attention to his significance. 20 Meanwhile scholars have not been idle. Bkandis and Bekker were commissioned by the Berlin Academy to pro- duce a complete edition. For three years these patient scholars courageously toiled over the manuscripts in Italy, France, and England, and the result appeared in Bekker's edition (Berlin, 1831-40, since reprinted at Oxford), and in the work by Bbandis already cited (Note 5). A complete edition was printed in 1832 by Tauchnitz in sixteen volumes, and in 1843 by Weisse in one volume, neither of them highly esteemed ; and in 1847 Didot began an excellent edition in four volumes, edited by Bussemakee, still incomplete. 21 Of separate treatises the editions have been too numerous to be specified here. § 22. Activity so energetic, after so long a period of neglect, was naturally prompted and accompanied by a ten- dency to over-estimate the works ; and the danger now is lest the reaction go too far. Hegel and Sir W. Hamilton have 19 Lord Mokboddo in his Ancient Metaphysics ; Harris in bis Philosophical Arrangements; and Thomas Taylor in various works, were enthusiastic enough, but they spoke with no authority. 20 Eosmini : Aristotele esposto ed esaminato. " Poiche le questioni che giaccino nella filosofia aristotelica sono vitali per 1' uman genere, e la grandezza e l'importanza di queste restituira sempre ad Aristotele un gran peso d'autorita.'' — p. 14 of the Milan edition, 1855. 21 This, and Buhle's, are the editions I hare used ; but for general conveni- ence in reference I have given Bekker's pagination as nearly as possible CHAP. I.] THE LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. 23 done their best to impress on fluctuating public opinion the conviction that not only was Aristotle a thinker of vast power, but of present worth : not only great in his own time, but anticipating the truths of all time. Cuvier, Isidoee St. Hilaire, De Blainville, and Johannes Muller, draw- ing after them crowds of obedient disciples, have spoken of his scientific works as if they were on a level with the science of our day, claiming for him some of the most curious dis- coveries of modern research. Certes il ne meritait Ni cet excSs d'honneur, ni cette indignite ; and it will be the task of the following chapters to show that / both the past neglect and the modern deification need revi- < sion. One point only requires to be noticed at present. It is, that among his modern eulogists will be found biologists, politicians, and metaphysicians, but no astronomer, no physi- cist, no chemist. In other words, in those sciences which have advanced to the positive stage, and in which the rigour of proof reduces Authority to its just position, his opinions are altogether disregarded; whereas in those sciences in which, from their complexity and immaturity, the influence of Authority and the delusive promises of the Subjective Method still gain acceptance, his dicta are cited as those of a puissant investigator. ( 24 ) CHAPTER II. THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. § 23. In one sense, the dawn of Science is coeval with the dawn of human intelligence. Introduced to this mysterious universe naked and helpless, man is early forced to gain some understanding of its relations to him. At first all is dim sensation. To this succeeds a slowly organized classification of elementary experiences. The great forces of Nature are everywhere at work, everywhere manifesting themselves in manifold and intermingling motions, which he must appreciate, and intellectually disentangle, as far as they directly concern him. This is simple knowledge. Science, which is a higher sublimation of this knowledge, begins when the forces of Nature are appreciated in their relations to each other; and in its highest flights all personal relations are merged in a grand disinterestedness. At first man stands before " the roaring loom of Time," gazing in helpless perplexity at the movements of the infinite shuttles, ignorant of the move- ments which may be beneficent, and of those which may be destructive to him. But he cannot remain thus. His necessities soon change this attitude of wonder into an attitude of inquiry. The objects which he sees are of pressing importance ; he must observe them attentively that he may adapt their powers to his purposes. The preservation CHAP. II.] THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. 25 of his daily existence depends on the accuracy with which he observes, classifies, and infers the properties of objects — their order of co-existence and succession. He has to find his friends and his foes amid the multitude of forces which surround him. None immediately announce their qualities ; each has to be carefully watched and tested; the dearest friend suddenly proving the direst foe under very trifling changes of conditions. Then come intellectual needs ; above all, the imperious desire for an explanation. The spontaneous activity of his growing intellect urges him to make out some scheme by which the various phenomena may be bound together. He begins to link the known and acces- sible on to the unknown and inaccessible ; he animates the universe ; interprets all he sees by all he feels. Thus Philosophy emerged from Knowledge. As civiliza tion advanced, Knowledge became more extensive and precise, Philosophy more ambitious in its sweep. Arts arose, which preserved and extended the common fund of Knowledge, transmitting it as a priceless heirloom. Those great nations which duly cherished this heirloom, and increased its store, magnified their existence, and became the glory of our race. Those nations which neglected it, perished, or continued barbarous — that is, comparatively helpless and miserable. § 24. Although in this sense Science may be said to be coeval with man, the sense in which moderns employ the word carries a more restricted meaning. To measure the ground ; to measure the seasons and the length of days ; to cure a disease or dress a wound ; to plough the soil and garner the harvest ; to guide a fragile bark along a perilous coast by the aid of the Pleiades, or " sailing stars;" to know that fire burns, liquids evaporate, and metals fuse — these are among the early experiences of the race, but they are not Science. They are the preparatory materials — items of that Common Knowledge which the energy of man, as he advances 26 THE DAWN Or SCIENCE. [CHAP. II. to maturity, developes into Science. 1 Science, as we now understand the word, is of later birth. If its germinal origin may be traced to the early period when Observation, Induc- tion, and Deduction were first employed, its birth must be referred to that comparatively recent period when the mind, — rejecting the primitive tendency to seek in supernatural agencies for an explanation of all external phenomena, — endeavoured, by a systematic investigation of the phenomena themselves to discover their invariable order and connection. The separation of Science from Knowledge was effected step by step as the Subjective Method was replaced by the Objective Method : i. e., when in each inquiry the phenomena of external nature ceased to be interpreted on premisses suggested by the analogies of human nature. We shall presently state more explicitly the character of these Methods (§ 31) ; to . prepare the way for a thorough appreciation of them, is the purpose of the ensuing paragraphs. § 25. The history of human development shows that there are three modes by which we conceive phenomena ; and there are only three. The second being a transition from the first to the third, we might, in strictness, admit of only two distinct modes of conception. The first of these supposes that the order and succession observed in phenomena, is due to the influence of outlying agencies — powers which are super natural, above the objects, not belonging to them. The second supposes that the order of phenomena is due simply to properties inherent in the objects themselves, which properties are realities, and form part of the nature of the objects. Obviously, things must either be conceived as, by nature, passive or active; if passive, they can only be moved by superior powers, independent of them ; if active, they possess in themselves the conditions of their activity. Thus on one 1 To make clear the distinction between Science and Common Knowledge would carry us too far ; it will be discussed in the Prolegomena to the History of which the present volume forms a chapter. CHAP. II. J THE DAWN OE SCIENCE. 27 of two fundamental assumptions, respecting the activity of objects, rests every possible explanation we can frame of the mysteries around us. § 26. The attitude of mind which is based on the first of these assumptions is that which is common to all primitive theories. It characterizes what Auguste Comte names the Theological Stage in human development. On this assump- tion, all phenomena not of the simplest and most familiar kind are referred to the agency of invisible powers, spirits, deities, or demons. To these powers, and not to any activity inherent in the objects themselves, the changes in phenomena are assigned. It is the will of some spirit which moves the objects. As this idea of will originates in the analogies of human volitions influencing human actions, the same caprici- ousness and variability which characterize human actions are supposed to characterize external phenomena. Much more caprice would be attributed to the gods, because we do know something of human motives — greed, anger, and love ; hut we do not know why Zeus sends a storm in harvest-time, or burns his own temple with lightning, or kills a pious man by the side of a blasphemer. Variableness is predicated of all successions of phenomena, save those of such frequent occurrence, that expectation of their being found to vary is finally extirpated. § 27. In direct contrast to this is the scientific attitude, based upon the second of the two assumptions just rehearsed. It never could have obtained acceptance in the early stages of our development. It implies a certain advance of culture and great familiarity with the orderliness of Nature. Before men could refer the changes they observed to the influence of properties inherent in the objects, a strong conviction must have arisen that the order of succession in phenomena was not variable, but fixed. Invariableness would inevitably lead to the conception of all changes being due to the relations between the various properties of objects — first, by discrediting 28 THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. [CHAP. II. the interference of an external will, which is essentially incalculable ; next, by disclosing that there was really no need of anything but the recognized or recognizable pro- perties of objects to account for all changes. The conviction that objects are not by nature inert, passive, acted on only by outlying, supernatural agencies, grew up slowly with the slowly-growing perception of the essential invariableness of phenomena whenever the conditions are the same. In our day, reliance on the stability of created things is unshakeable. The idea of variability is banished from ex- ternal phenomena, and admitted only by one school with refer- ence to internal phenomena. "Whenever a change does not take place in accordance with our previsions, we never suppose the failure to be owing to the caprice of Nature, or to some out- lying power; we at once conclude the presence of some inter- fering condition, some relation which we have overlooked. Not only is the primitive conception of variability banished for ever, but in its banishment is included that of externality. Causation is now assumed to lie within, and not without, the circle of phenomena. Science, withdrawing from all specula- tion where it can find no adequate evidence, and where its methods are inoperative, refrains from inquiry as to ultimate causes, and says nothing respecting the mystery of creation ; in dealing with created objects, and with natural phenomena, it presupposes no variableness in their order of succession and co-existence. Thus the clergyman who told the farmer that it was useless to pray for rain till the wind changed, had embraced the scientific view, and had learned to distrust appeals against the order of Nature, because that was not a variable order. In earlier days this man would have considered the direction of the wind quite insignificant, and would have believed that prayer was likely to determine a change in the weather by de- termining a change in the will which regulated it. To the mind of men in the primitive, theological stage, the sun was a god driving a chariot of fire, the moon a goddess CHAP, n.] THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. 29 and a huntress. So difficult was it to escape these personifi- cations that we find remnants of this Polytheism even in the teaching of the Christian Church, which assigned to every planet its tutelary angel. 2 The scientific mind replaces these gods and angels by laws of nature, according to which the planets move by forces similar, and under conditions similar to those observed in all other moving bodies. It having been discovered that the orbit of the planets is an ellipse, Newton demonstrated on dynamical principles that a body could only move in such an orbit in virtue of two forces, the variations of which are in a reciprocal ratio with the vector — the one force being centrifugal, the other centripetal. Thus the law of gravi- tation dethroned the arbitrary agencies. Though in itself not more intelligible than the action of the gods, this law has the supreme advantage of linking astronomical and terrestrial phenomena into general harmony, and admitting of a syste- matic co-ordination of all observed facts. Besides this, it gets rid of the presumed variability in the agency, and leads to the careful study of the inevitable order ; instead of encouraging attempts, by prayers, supplications, invocations, or the sacri- fices of animal life, to persuade the inevitable order to alter its course. § 28. These two sharply opposed modes of conceiving phenomena, one of which aims at penetrating the mysteries of existence, and explaining the external order by knowledge of the ultimate causes, the other of which aims only at detect- ing the exact relations of co-existence and succession which determine that order, without any hope of knowing the ulti- mate causes : these two modes require some intermediate transitional mode which will enable the mind to pass from the one to the other. Such a transition is effected in the Meta- physical stage, which agrees with the theological inasmuch as it 2 " Le Pere Schot, jesuite, a ecrit qu'en 1660 on voyait a. Rome la Basilique des Sept Anges Gubernateurs des Planetes." — Savekibn : Hist, des Progres de I'Esprit Humain, Paris, 1775, p. 222. 80 THE DAWN OP SCIENCE. [CHAP. II. also assumes a knowledge of the ultimate causes, and assumes that these causes are in essence independent of the objects.' But it differs from the theological in discarding the idea of these agencies being variable ; by this it forms the passage to a scientific conception. In the place of deities it assumes abstract entities. Thus by gradual modifications the personal agency becomes an impersonal agency, the deity an abstraction, and this in turn becomes more and more material, as we see in the succession of 1, Spirit; 2, Entity; and 3, Fluid or Ether. Although the entities which are assumed as the ultimate causes of change are neither the objects themselves, nor properties of the objects, they are assumed to be inseparable from the objects and invariable in their agency. It is thus they form an easy transition to the more purely objective conception of laws. For example, the Veg'etal Soul, which is supposed to be the cause of all the phenomena observed in plants, is not a plant, nor a property of the plant, nor the resultant of the plant's many properties ; it is an existence sui generis, in virtue of which the plant is. At the same time this Vegetal Soul is exclusively limited to the plant ; it has no other form of existence ; it exists only under the con- ditions of plant-life. And when the biologist patiently traces out these conditions, the metaphysician willingly accepts them, simply protesting against the supposition that the life of the plant is due to nothing more than the mutual action and reaction of the properties inherent in the molecules com- posing the plant ; he asserts that, over and above these, there is the Vegetal Soul, arranging the molecules and directing their forces. § 29. Such are the three modes of conceiving the course 3 " Le caractere fondamental des conceptions mfitaphysiques est d'envisager les phSnomenes independamment des corps qui nous les mauifestent, d'attribuer aux proprietfis de chaque substance uno existence distincte de la sienne." — Comte: Cows de Philosophie Positive, 1835, II., 446. CHAP. II.] THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. 31 of nature which will everywhere be found curiously interwoven amid the web of human history. Each has been predominant at certain epochs. Each has had a potent influence on our culture. But it is obvious that after the mind has passed through its earlier stages of development, progress is seriously impeded by theological and metaphysical explanations of natural phenomena. Whether such explanations are now desirable in any other department of inquiry, is a question which need not here be agitated ; it is certain that they are obstacles to the progress of science. The theological explanation is an obstacle, because instead of stimulating the mind to a close and reverent study of the truths revealed in Nature, it directs the attention to whatever has been assumed respecting the will and purpose of deities, supposed to be manifested in phenomena. The metaphysical explanation is an obstacle, because it withdraws attention from the close scrutiny of facts,' and deludes the mind with unverified, unverifiable assumptions. 4 When an epidemic fever wasted the Grecian camp, the cause was at once assumed to be Apollo's wrath. Had not the Deity been angered, the people would not have been punished. What had angered him ? Surely it must have been the insult offered to his priest ? Acting on this natural inference, the Greeks bethought them how to appease this wrath. In the Crimea our troops also suffered from fever ; we bethought ourselves of the ventilation and drainage : an idea which to the Greeks would have appeared not only inefficacious, but impious. On the Palatine Hill, the Romans erected a Temple to the Goddess of Fever. We build fever-hospitals, and our form of prayer is a dose of quinine. 5 4 " Nous devons examiner la nature par tous les moyens que foumissent l'observation et l'experience ; et non leur supposer des principes sur lesquels l'esprit se repose et croit avoir tout fait lorsqu'il lui reste tout a, faire." — VlCQ d'Aztk: Discours sur I'Anatomie. CEuvres, 1305, IV., 15. s To a mind even moderately trained in the use of evidence and logical connection, ancient superstitions are absolutely inconceivable. What, for 32 THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. [CHAP. II. So long as diseases were conceived to be the products of supernatural agency, their cure was properly sought in invoca- tions, sacrifices, prayers and charms, rather than in the study of the organism, and an accurate acquaintance with the pro- perties of objects. And although it is true that reliance on supernatural appeals never wholly excluded reliance on all natural means that were known, the quinine being administered as well as the prayer, yet the mere fact that men conceived the order of phenomena to depend upon a mutable will, was an obstacle to the thorough and patient study of natural means. No sooner was it understood that diseases were the results inseparable from certain conditions of organic sub- stances, and that under similar conditions the action of these substances was invariable, than the mind recognized the necessity of relinquishing a vain reliance on invocation, and gave its severe attention to the study of objects, and the con- ditions of health and disease. § 30. The theological, metaphysical, and scientific ex- planations have three different criteria, or guarantees. The guarantee of the first is sacerdotal. A conclusion is held to be certain, if it is conformable with the doctrines of which the priesthood is the interpreter. Those doctrines, being received as indisputable, form the standard of all truth. The guarantee of the second is somewhat less absolute ; it admits of question, because it is based on reason, not on faith ; nevertheless, any conclusion which can be logically deduced from general doctrines accepted by metaphysicians is held by them to be demonstrated. To the theologian it is enough if he can adduce a text. To the metaphysician it is enough example, can we suspect to have been the grounds on which the Druids believed that in any perilous juncture they could be guided Ivy the writhings of a dying man ? They seized some innocent wretch, plunged a knife in his breast, " a ce coup mortel ce miserable tombant a la renverse, on augurait de l'evenement a veniv en observant les circonstnnces de sa chute, les convulsions de diffeientes parties de son corps, et le rejaillissement de son sang." — Histoire LitUraire de la France, by the Benedictines of St. Maur, 1733, 1., 28. CHAP. II.] THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. 33 if he can deduce his proposition from " clear and distinct ideas." The guarantee of science is in the verification of expe- rience, direct or indirect (§ 64). It distrusts the validity of a priori conclusions, or of any explanations drawn solely from general ideas of Nature's order, unless those general ideas have themselves been rigorously demonstrated to be necessities of thought, or to represent the observed order, (§ 63 a). What must be, or may be, has to give place to what is. The general doctrines of Science are never, like those of Theology and Metaphysics, conceived to be final. However firmly fixed at present, they may be shaken to- morrow by a new discovery. Moreover, in the general doctrines of Science, while one portion is understood as beyond dispute until the horizon of knowledge is enlarged, another portion is admitted to be more or less hypothetical and approximative. In every case Science welcomes scrutiny and scepticism; its final guarantee is conformity with fact. Its general doctrines have been slowly elaborated, verified step by step, and therefore, to a considerable extent, they represent the actual facts, and are not arbitrary assumptions founded on slight analogies, or conclusions deduced from unverified premisses. 6 The contrast between the metaphysical and scientific guarantee is that the verification which both need is by the one disregarded and by the other emphatically put forward. While both the metaphysicist and the physicist draw conclu- sions from their general doctrines, the one is contented with logical symmetry, the other demands the confrontation with fact. The ancient astronomers believed in the uniformity of the celestial revolutions, and in the circularity of their orbit. 6 " Expliquer un phenomene se reduit toujours a faire voir que les faits qu'il presente se suivent dans un ordre analogue a l'ordre de succession d'autres faits qui sont plus familiers, et qui des lors semblent etre plus connus." — Babthez : Nouveaux Element de la Science de I'Homme, Paris, 1816, 1., 8. 3 84 THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. [CHAP. II. On subjective grounds this belief is not only logical, but irresistible. How, as M. Biot remarks, 7 could men imagine these movements to be variable, which were seen to be performed in perfect freedom, and in periods rigorously constant, no obstacle being suspected? How could such movements be accelerated or retarded, > being, as they were, eternal, and due to neither impact nor resistance ? From this assumption of uniformity, the circularity of the orbit was a necessary conclusion. The logical chain was perfect. It so completely fettered the mind as almost. to bar the way against the admission of the truth. Kepleb had difficulty in accepting his own discovery, when indubitable proofs revealed that the orbit of Mars was not circular, and con- sequently that its velocity was not uniform, but subject to periodical variations. Thus nothing could be more plausible, considered a priori, than the ancient theory; nevertheless, no sooner were adequate means of Verification applied to the theory than the whole fabric tumbled down like a house of cards. § 31. I have thus endeavoured to characterize the three modes of speculative inquiry by which in all ages men have explained the facts of nature ; these modes, as Auguste Comxe profoundly saw, constitute the necessary evolu- tion of speculative thought. To get rid of the equivoque which lies in the phrases theological and metaphysical, we may group all three under the Subjective and Objective Methods, their tendencies being thus characterized : the Subjective draws all explanations of external phenomena from premisses directly suggested by consciousness ; it identifies the external order with the internal order. Obviously, this is the primitive method. When in the early days of our de- velopment we find ourselves face to face with phenomena, the order of which we do not understand, we satisfy the irresistible impatience which demands an immediate explanation, by 7 Biot : Eludes sur VAstronomie Indienne et Chinoise, 1862, p. 58. CHAP. II.] THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. 35 assuming that the objects are moved as we are moved. We feel that our own actions are determined by our volitions, by the mysterious something within us; and we assign a similar cause to the motions of external objects. Quite other- wise is it with the Objective Method. This arises out of a more extensive and precise knowledge of the objects, fami- liarity with which gradually reveals something of their order of co-existence and succession. As such knowledge accumu- lates, it irresistibly pushes aside the interpretation which was originally drawn from consciousness. It reveals the cosmical order more and more as a system not measurable by the analogies of human personality. Under the light of this knowledge men cease to suppose anger behind the violence of a storm, or prophecy in the gloom of an eclipse. The savage who thinks the watch is alive, can only be made to relinquish this subjective hypothesis by acquiring positive knowledge of the properties of steel springs and the actions of a mechanism ; but no sooner is this objective knowledge acquired than he ceases to have recourse to the analogies of his own nature for an explanation. 8 The Subjective Method claims direct knowledge of the nature of things and the ultimate causes of all changes. The Objective Method by looking at things, assuming the position of simple spectator, renounces all hope of ever penetrating the mysteries of existence, of ever knowing the intimate essence of things, and only hopes to detect the invariable order of co-existence and succession. The one claims a knowledge of " noumena," the other a knowledge of the laws of phenomena. 8 The influence of the Subjective Method is constantly traceable in com- mercial and other enterprises rashly undertaken by men in the confidence that facts will bend to their desires. A man sees great advantage to himself (/"events take a certain direction ; and he believes that this direction will be taken because he greatly desires it. The more objective mind sets aside its wishes and tries to calculate the chances of the direction from a knowledge of the ex- ternal conditions. 3—2 86 THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. [CHAP. II. § 31 a. It is evident, therefore, that since the Subjective Method arises from our ignorance, and the Objective from our positive knowledge, there can have been no period in the history of our race in which either Method obtained exclusive acceptance. Even the earliest and most ignorant tribes must have so far familiarized themselves with certain phenomena as to have explained them without reference to the deities spontaneously invoked in less familiar cases. The observed properties of the things themselves were deemed sufficient for the immediate production of the changes, so that by availing himself of these properties man was often able to modify the course of phenomena according to his needs. After learning that unless the wood were dry even his fetish could not make it burn, he soon came to fix attention on the dryness, and to cease invoking his fetish. On the other hand, the most advanced European nations, although they have frankly assumed the scientific attitude with re- spect to most cosmical phenomena, still retain in their systems a large admixture of theological and metaphysical conceptions. The rise of the Objective or Scientific Method is a late event in the history of man, if we consider it not in isolated fragmen- tary efforts, but as a systematic and conscious attitude of mind. A late and glorious event, of which no trace is visible in the early civilizations. The dawn of this new era in which Nature was investigated without reference to supernatural agencies, but solely with the view of deciphering her alphabet, and reading her own sacred writing, is to be sought in Italy. It was the Greeks, and especially the Italian Greeks who commenced this revolution. In saying this I am not unmindful of the opinion, held by many learned scholars, that the East was the cradle of Science. It is not a subject that can be adequately discussed here ; nor can I pretend to the erudition requisite for its dis- cussion. But leaving the subject in worthier hands, there is one general consideration which to my mind carries conviction. CHAP. II.] THE DAWN OP SCIENCE. 37 We have no evidence whatever that the Egyptians, Assyrians, Persians, or Hindoos, conceived the true scientific Method ; and there is positive evidence that they could not have had the scientific knowledge often attributed to them, simply because they had not the Instruments by which such knowledge is attained. They had not the requisite Mathematics ; they had not the Instruments. Unless facts are accurately known, laws must remain obscure. But accuracy in the knowledge of facts, that is to say, scientific accuracy, depends on instruments of measurement and calculation. Science is pre-eminently quan- titative, i. e., dependent on exact appreciations of quantities of time, space, and force ; and hence its progress is intimately connected with the perfection and application of Instruments of measurement and calculation. Wanting these, the East necessarily wanted scientific knowledge. Not only am I compelled to follow those scholars who dis- credit the claims of the East to any initiation of the era of science, but I should also question the claim, more commonly allowed, of the Egyptians as astronomers. That they made numerous observations, and amassed some of the preparatory material, is admissible, without involving any assent to their scientific claim. It would be difficult to show that they had mastered any of the initial conceptions. We read, indeed, of priests, relieved from toil, devoting their leisure to study ; but what was the nature of that study ? We hear of their careful observations and their enormous annals, on which point exaggeration is traditional : Hippakchus speaks of the Assyrians having continuous records for 270,000 years ; Diodoeus says the Chaldeans claim for their observations an antiquity of myriads of years ; and " Maetianus Capella adopts a statement that astronomy had been practised in secret by the Egyptians for 40,000 years before it was divulged to the rest of the world." 9 If this were true it would only the 9 Lewis : Historical Survey of the Astronomy of the Ancients, 1862, p. 264. 38 THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. [CHAP. II. more decisively refute their pretensions ; since to have observed the heavens for forty thousand years, and not discern a single astronomical law, proves them to have been without the rudiments of exact Science. Indeed, when we reflect that they had not discovered one of the fundamental laws of motion, and were unacquainted with trigonometry, it is obvious that they were without exact knowledge, and without the means of obtaining it. 10 The Egyptians made observations which were sufficiently accurate for many of their needs, but not for science. And no sooner do we pass from Astronomy to the other sciences than discussion ceases. No one thinks of assigning the origin of Dynamics, Optics, Acoustics, Anatomy, &c., to the East. It is undoubtedly to the Greeks that we must look for these ; as it is to them that we must look for the systematic adoption of Method. The researches of the Pythagoreans on the vibrations of bodies are the earliest researches in Physics which were conceived in a scientific spirit. 11 By the development of the mighty instrument of calculation, and by their stedfast constancy in investigating the causes of phenomena irrespective of theological bias, this wonderful people began that intellectual movement which in 10 " A la reserve du gnomon, tous les instrumens astronomiquea sont des inventions des Grecs. Nul autre people n'a produit aucune observation qui meritat ce nom." — Delambre: Hist.de V Astronomic Ancienne, 1817, 1., p. 20. Compare also Montucla : Histoire des Mathematiques, 1768 ; and Mbssen- bhoeck : Cours de Physique ExpCrimentale, par Sigatjd de la Fond, Leyden, 1769, I., p. 28. On the astronomy of the Hindoos see Biot : Etudes sur V Astronomie Indienne et Chinoise, 1862, p. 47, where it is proved that the Greeks were the parents of Hindoo science. 11 " Pendant que les Etrusques torturaicnt et d6figuraient la Nature pour faire coincider les phenom&ies qu'ils obscrvaient avec leurs idees mytholo- giques, et que les Grecs tournaient leurs plus grands efforts vers les problSmes metaphysiques qui surpassent les forces humaines, les habitans du Midi de l'ltalie cultivjrent les sciences de l'observation, suivaient la methodo experi- mentale, et contribuaient aux progres de la geometric et de l'arithmetique. Les recherches des Pythagoriciens sur les vibrations des corps sont les plus anciennes experiences de physique qui soient parvenues jusqu' a nous." — Libbi : Histoire des Sciences Mathlmaiiques en Italic, Paris, 1888, 1., 28. CHAP. II.] THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. 39 modern times has achieved conquests more glorious than the dreams of poets. § 32. Observe the significance of the fact that the Greeks gave us Mathematics. Of all sciences this is the one which most rigorously typifies the true Method. In it there is no place for the supernatural. It admits no outlying agencies. It fixes the mind on relations, and only on relations. By so doing it coerces the mind to maintain the strictly scientific attitude, namely, the most watchful solicitude respect- ing accuracy, both in data and conclusions. Much has been written about the superior certainty of Mathematics ; but this does not, I conceive, result from the simplicity of its symbols, nor from the simplicity of the ideas involved; since it is obvious that we may employ very simple symbols and very clear ideas, yet arrive at very uncertain and very absurd con- clusions. 12 The superior exactness and certainty of Mathe- matics are due to the fact that no hypothesis is allowed to stand for more than an hypothesis ; no deduction takes its place as a datam until it has been demonstrated. Whereas in all other sciences the mind has great difficulty in restraining its impatience, and is thus induced to employ un- verified data, and to rely on unverified deductions ; but when- ever the data and the deductions have been rigorously verified, the truths of Physics and Chemistry are as certain as those of Mathematics. There is a second important element in scientific research for which we are indebted to the Greeks : the systematic employment of Scepticism ; without which, indeed, research would be vain, and a true Method impossible. The Greeks, unwilling longer to acquiesce in traditional dogmas, 12 " Une propositiqn tout a fait absurde pent etre extr&nement precise, comme si Ton disait que la somme des angles d'un triangle est egale a trois angles droits ; et une proposition tres certaine peut ne comporter qu'une pre- cision fort mediocre, comme lorsqu'on affirme que tout homme mourra." — Comte: Cours de Philosophie Positive, 1830, 1., 103. 40 THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. [CHAP. n . early saw that if Observation and Reason were to be the guides in investigation, these guides, being fallible, required perpetual vigilance. "Men who desire to learn," said Abis- totle, " must first learn to doubt ; for science is only the solution of doubts : " l3 an aphorism, novel in those days, in our own a truism. That the Greeks imperfectly practised the scepticism which they inculcated, will be seen by and by. In their eagerness to explain phenomena they were far too ready to accept observations which had not been controlled, and deduc- tions which had not been verified. Nevertheless it is their immortal glory to have recognized the necessity of proof; and this recognition was itself consequent upon their ceasing to interpret phenomena as the direct results of supernatural agencies. Hippocbates, amid much that is preposterous in the eyes of modern science, exhibits the new spirit which was then guiding inquiry. Let us cite an example. Speaking of a disease which was attributed to a god, he remarks, " For my part I think this disease comes from a god just as others do ; and that there are no diseases more divine or more human than others. Each disease comes according to natural laws ; none has any other origin." w § 33. A fortunate union of temperament with culture enabled this wonderful people to range through Nature in pursuit of the true relations of things, without perplexing themselves by fictions imagined respecting outlying agencies, essentially mysterious. The mysteriousness was not denied ; it was simply set aside, removed from the sphere of scientific thought. The Greek had a free, independent spirit, adven- turous, rebellious, curious ; and boldly doubting, sought a 13 Metaph., III., 1. Compare Phys., I., 2. l X u yap fi\oao(ptav i) irictyic. 14 Hipfocrates : De ASre, Aquis, et Locis. CV1I., Ed. Coray, Paris, 1800, I., 100. Iptol Si Kal airl<(j Sokiu Tama ra iraQta Oela tlvat, Kal t aXXa irdvTa, Kal ovSiv ^rlpov iripov Qiionpov, oiSi avtiptumviimpov, a\\a iravra fata' tKaarov Si tft" fyvoiv twv toiovtswv, KOt oiSiv &viv fyvaioQ yiyvtrat. CHAP. II. J THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. 41 solution of his doubts in his own way. He refused sub- mission to established doctrines. He would accept neither priest nor philosopher as his oracle. Without directly con- tradicting the priest, he boldly erected his own Academy beside the Temple. Both their weakness and their strength aided the Greeks in this new enterprise. For it was a weakness in them that they had little sympathy with that sense of the Infinite which characterizes some other eminent nations. This is visible in their Art : an Art matchless in clearness and pro- portion, in the beauty of arrested lines, and the repose of symmetrical simplicity; but having none of those finer issues which escape into the sublimity of Christian Art. Greek Art is a lute, not an organ. Abistotle is a striking illustration of this excellence and this defect. He seems utterly destitute of any sense of the Ineffable. There is no quality more noticeable in him than his unhesitating confidence in the adequacy of the human mind to comprehend the universe; a quality obviously con- nected with the defect just mentioned. He never seems to be visited by misgivings as to the compass of human faculty, because his unhesitating mind is destitute of awe. He has no abiding consciousness of the fact deeply impressed on other minds, that the circle of the Knowable is extremely limited ; and that beyond it lies a vast mystery, dimly recog- nized as lying there, but also recognized as impenetrable. Hence the existence of Evil is no perplexity to his soul ; it is accepted as a simple fact. Instead of being troubled by it, saddened by it, he quietly explains it as the consequence of Nature not having correctly written her meaning. This mystery which has darkened so many sensitive meditative minds with anguish, he considered to be only bad orthography (§107). Although ready enough to recognize the fallibility of men, he nowhere, that I remember, expresses a conviction of 42 THE DAWN OE SCIENCE. [CHAP. II. the inherent fallibility of reason. His contemporary, the author of Ecclesiastes, passionately declared that all science was vanity. Nor was this merely the dejected expression of his own sense of miserable failure ; it was the serious conviction of human infirmity. Not only had his efforts failed, all men would fail, because the task was greater than human strength. Such doubts never assailed the Greek. Great as his failure was, he had little suspicion of it, and no suspicion of human frailty. Where he knew that his insight fell short, he was assured that the gaze of his successors would penetrate. For the race, if not for himself, he had regal pretensions. § 34. This royal confidence powerfully aided the develop- ment of Science. It gave the stimulus to research, and made inquiry adventurous. Yet it also exercised in one respect a retarding influence. It prevented due circumspection. It caused scepticism to stop half-way. It relied too securely on logical deduction ; and accepted evidence without cross-exami- nation. A little more distrust, a more modest hesitation, might have prevented that precipitancy to which alone many errors were due. But if this confidence had its drawbacks, it had also its incitements. It led to the laborious study of Nature, merely with a view to knowledge for the sake of knowledge, and not with a view to Eeligion, nor the interests of Commerce. Science acquires her dignity, and her supreme power, from her noble disinterestedness. Although her researches even in the remotest regions are always finally beneficent among our daily uses, although the abstract speculations of geometers de- termine the satisfaction of our vulgar needs, it is not with this view that researches are undertaken. Use is seoondary and derivative; the primary objeot is elucidation of the Truth. All Truth is beneficent ; but her seekers desire to behold the serene splendour of her face, and not themselves to reap the benefits which spring up on her track. §85. This attitude was first assumed by the Greeks. Their CHAP. II.] THE DAWN OF SCIENCE. 43 philosophers were content to seek wisdom as the one great object, without directly subordinating their search to Eeligion or to Use. In doing so they incurred serious peril. They were assailed by the ridicule and persecution which await all inno- vators. Abistophanes only gives expression to public hatred and to public scorn, in ridiculing and misrepresenting the physical inquirers of his day — men said to occupy them- selves in Walking on air and contemplating the sun. The attempt to explain Nature, without reference to the gods, very generally drew on philosophers the accusation of impiety. Nor was this prejudice confined to the vulgar and unthinking ; it was shared and avowed by Sooeates. The repugnance which, in early life, caused him to relinquish physical inquiries, was, as we learn from Xenophon, repugnance at the idea of excluding the constant agency of the gods, and the consequent destruction of moral feelings connected with this agency. The same thought has, in all ages, roused the bitter hostility of theologians, against the scientific attitude, as one essentially irreligious. 13 This hostility has gradually grown feebler, and is now entirely restricted to narrow or imperfectly culti- vated minds. The change has been effected partly by the irresistible progress of Science with her triumphant demon- strations, and partly by a deeper philosophy, which has disclosed that Science can only destroy false explanations, which it is for our welfare to have destroyed. No single truth can be shaken by Science. If in her own path she detects certain truths, these must necessarily be harmonious with all other truths. We must learn to welcome all, and to prove all. Even those bigoted minds which still regard with alarm the steady advance of Science, must admit the fact of its 15 " Mos onmes Deum aut saltern Dei providentiam tollere putant, qui res et miracula per cansas naturales explicant aut intelligere student." — Spinoza : Traetatus Theolog.-Politicus, vi. Opera, III., 86. Ed. Bkuder, Leipzig, 1846. 44 THE DAWN OE SCIENCE. [CHAP. II. advance, the greatness of its victories, the triumph of its Method, and the certainty of its continuing to extend its empire. In minds of larger culture, or of less jealous narrow- ness, there is a complete cessation of the old antagonism ; a gradual approximation is being made between theology and science, and a more candid recognition of their mutual claims in regard to the grand religious and moral ideas which must ever determine the movement of society. § 36. The object of this chapter has been to show why the Greeks are to be regarded as the originators of Science, strictly so-called, and why this History takes note of no earlier people. Other peoples amassed details of knowledge, manifested intellectual activity, invented useful arts ; but it is in the Greek writers that we must seek the inauguration of the scientific epoch. It is in them that, for the first time, appears the systematic effort to ascertain the relations of things objectively, to detect the causes of all changes as in- herent in the things themselves, and to reject all supernatural or outlying agencies. The Greeks began, but only began, this revolution. They carried it but a little way. Their explanations were generally inaccurate, owing to causes which will be set forth in the next chapter ; and the eclipse which for several centuries darkened the day that had thus brightly dawned, was owing chiefly to the energetic revival of that very theological spirit from which the illustrious Greeks had emancipated themselves. ( 45 ) CHAPTEE m. ANCIENT SCIENCE. § 37. Two thousand two hundred years have passed since Aristotle began his scientific investigation of Nature, and during two thousand of these years his writings were regarded as the purest and most copious fount of knowledge. Then came a revolution ; and during the two hundred years which succeeded that revolution, almost everything we now dignify by the name of scientific truth, saw the light. The earlier discoveries were but as preludes to the great achieve- ments of modern research; nor do those early discoveries form more than an insignificant item in the mass of ancient science. How can this failure of twenty centuries be accounted for ? And why were the ancients so strikingly eclipsed by the moderns ? § 38. In subsequent pages of this History we shall have to enumerate the causes which prolonged the infancy of Science from the days of Aristotle and Archimedes to those of Kepler and Galileo. At present we have to consider how it was that the Greeks and Eomans, in spite of the splendour of their genius, made such slight progress in the discovery of physical laws. In Art, Literature, and Philosophy they have legislated for the world. In Science, they are without authority. Vainly have scholars struggled against this verdict ; vainly have they striven to keep up a supersti- 46 ANCIENT SCIENCE. [CHAP. III. tious reverence for the profundity of ancient writings by audacious announcements of " anticipations of modern dis- coveries." 1 The candid student is quickly disabused ; he learns that this profundity is indistinctness, the anticipa- tion purely verbal. Interesting these ancient writings must ever be : not as surpassing, or even approaching, the depth and grandeur of some modern works ; not as anticipating the results of modern labour ; but as brilliant points in the dimness of the Past, by which the story of human develop- ment may be deciphered; and as lessons, wherein may be read the results of yielding to that natural impatience which urges us to outstrip by guesses the tardy conclusions of experience. The failure of ancient efforts thus assumes an impressive interest, far exceeding the interest excited by a discovery of accordance between the old thought and the new. It suddenly lights up the study of ancient writings, rescuing them from the dilettantism of scholarship, and placing them among the serious archives of progress. , § 39. There is tolerable unanimity as to the fact of the ancient failure, but uncertainty and indistinctness as to its cause. The failure is generally assigned to a complete dis- 1 See, for example, Ideler: He Meteorohgia veterum Gracorum et Roma- norum, Berlin, 1832. He considers that Aristotle originated the undulatory theory of light, because the generation of light by motion is compared with the generation of sound 1 Schweigger maintains that in the ancient myths were embodied the shattered and misunderstood fragments of a science which existed in a remote antiquity. In the myth of the Dioscuri, for example, he reads a perfect appreciation of the two electricities. Ueber die alteste Physik und den Ursprung des Heidenthums aus einer misverstandenen JVaturweisheit, 1823. These views, of which Bacon gave a fanciful anticipation in his New Atlantis, and Baillt a more elaborate sketch in his Lettres sur I'Origine des Sciences, Paris, 1777, have been further developed by Karl Fischer : Beitraye zur Urgeschichte der Physik, 1833. The notion is not more extravagant than that of Democritus and Aristotle having anticipated modern physical dis- coveries, which is not unfrequently put forward. See especially Dctens : Origines des Dteouvertes attributes aux Modernes, 1796. The hardiest of recent assertors of the profundity and accuracy of Aristotle's physics is M. Barthk- lemt St. Hilaire, to whom the public is deeply indebted for several free and vigorous translations. See the Introduction to his La Physique d'Aristote, 1862. CHAP. III.] ANCIENT SCIENCE. 47 regard of Observation and Experiment, together with a "fondness for abstract reasoning." The amount of truth in this charge depends upon the sense in which it is interpreted. Taken absolutely it might be impugned by a defender of the old philosophy on two different counts. He might reply that i men may amass great wealth of observation, perform numer- ous experiments, and carefully abstain from abstract reasoning (if that be a merit), without reaching the explanation of a simple physical law. He might affirm, and affirm truly, that the ancients did observe, did perform experiments, and did employ the Inductive Method, which indeed was systematically proclaimed by Aristotle with a precision and an emphasis unsurpassed by Bacon himself. •§ 40. The cause commonly assigned, therefore, lends no illumination. As a general statement, it is too vague in its truth, and may be so erroneously interpreted as to pass from a truism into a falsism. Let us seek something more precise. A survey at once close and comprehensive detects the exist- ence of two causes : a psychological and an historical cause. The first lies in the nature of the Method pursued ; the second lies in the condition of knowledge at the period. On the Method pursued by the ancients, no satisfactory issues could have been reached, even had it been backed by the stored-up wealth of modern research : on such a Method failure inevitably followed, precisely as it follows the efforts of moderns whenever they employ it. Nor, on the other hand, is it less certain that had the ancients clearly conceived and rigidly adhered to that Method which alone issues in fruitful results, their achievements, splendid in comparison with what actually was achieved, would still necessarily have been slight, because there was no stored-up material to form the basis of extensive discovery. Science is a growth. The future must issue from seeds sown in the past. The bare and herbless granite must first be covered with mosses and lichens, if from their decay is to be formed the nidus of a higher life. 48 ANCIENT SCIENCE. [CHAP. in. No magnificent vegetation springs up at once ; it emerges gradually from the accumulated stores of former epochs. From the small beginnings and successive growths of know- ledge there emerges a more comprehensive and more complex Science. The advance is not simply one of addition, but of new development — a development rendered possible by the addition ; just as the addition of a new tissue raises the organism to a higher possibility of functional power. The truth sought in one age as a goal becomes a starting-point to the age which follows; the discovery which was the passionate aim of one man, and conferred on him lasting glory, becomes to his successors a mere instrument of new research. No one who reflects on the actual condition of any science, will fail to notice the complicated connection of all the sciences. The perfection of one demands illumination from all. Not only are the movements of the stars in- comprehensible before the laws of Mechanics are established, but even a fact so simple as the transit of a star cannot be ascertained until after it has been illuminated by optios, barology, and thermology. The position of a star has to be estimated with reference to the laws of aberration and refraction of light, which in turn are affected by the laws of atmospheric density, which again depend on laws of ^temperature. The very telescope with which the star is r observed is. itself the product of advanced science. This connection of the sciences points to a simultaneous growth, and a slow growth. Therefore in the early ages, before a large mass of established truth had been accumulated, before instruments had been invented, and when discoveries which were to be the instruments of research were still unsus- pected, it almost was impossible for any mind, however great, to give a scientific explanation of any class of phenomena ; all that could be done was to suggest some happy hypothesis, or to work out some small point of special value. Some few minds CHAP. III.] ANCIENT SCIENCE. 49 were contented with this humble effort ; but the majority, especially of philosophers, were too impatient ; and unable to rest without some explanation, trusted confidently to the Sub- jective Method, because the Objective Method could not then have been constantly applied, so as to satisfy their intel- lectual cravings. § 41. Before we can explain the failure of the ancients we must rightly appreciate the influence of two different and concurrent causes, methodological and historical. Those writers who, to my knowledge, have treated this subject ex professo, have entirely overlooked the historical cause, confining themselves to a specification of the defects in the ancient Method. Nor does it seem to me that they have been successful in very distinctly marking the sources of failure, even with respect to Method. They have felt the defects rather than assigned a philosophical explanation of them. An exception must be made in favour of Dr. Whewell, who has brought his views on the philosophy of science to elucidate this very question ; with what success we will presently inquire. The general mode of viewing the failure is typified in Pt.awatr's celebrated Dissertation prefixed to the Encyclopedia Bri- tannica, and we may content ourselves with a scrutiny of its arguments. § 42. After comparing ancient with modern physics, Playfair thus delivers his verdict : " Extreme credulity disgraced the speculations of men who, however ingenious, were little acquainted with the laws of nature." Why were they so ignorant? Because "unprovided with the great criterion by which the evidence of testimony can alone be examined. Though observations were sometimes made, experiments were never instituted; and philosophers, who were little attentive to the facts which spontaneously offered, did not seek to increase their number by artificial combina- tions." Playtaib is inaccurate in saving that no experiments 4 50 ANCIENT SCIENCE. [OHAP. in. were instituted, and that observations were only occasional ; but this historical error is insignificant beside the methodo- logical error of assuming that the chief source of the ancient failure was the absence of experiment. What is Experiment ? what its function ? Its function obviously is to supplement Observation, or rather to direct it, by making it definite, precise, in cases where to the unassisted observer the facts are indefinite and confused. Experiment, by varying the circumstances which usually accompany the phenomena, endeavours to disengage the conditions which are coincident from the conditions which are causally related. Hence it has been happily defined "une observation provoquee." Instead of contenting itself with the ordinary course of pheno- mena, it produces a definite disturbance of that course by artificial means. Observation tells us in the gross that atmospheric air which has been inspired by an animal, and then expired, is more or less damaged for further respiration. Experiment tells us definitely what have been the changes undergone by the gaseous constituents of air. Observation gives us the fact with great certainty, but without precision j Experiment adds nothing to the certainty, but renders the fact precise, and quantitatively appreciable. Although Experi- ment is an instrument of immense importance, it is one which derives all its value from the mind directing it. Used at haphazard, its results are fortuitous. The example of the alchemists should teach us how little it effects in incom- petent hands ; that example discloses experimental investiga- tions wandering into paths more eccentric, and arriving at conclusions more preposterous than ever seduced an Aristotle or an Abohimedes. Experiment is an art, and demands an artist. § 43. Moreover Playpaie's misconception may be answered on other grounds. He would not deny that Astronomy, Anatomy, Zoology, and Botany are sciences ; he would not deny that the ancients failed to discover the laws of these CHAP. III.] ANCIENT SCIENCE. 51 sciences ; yet he: would be forced to admit that in these sciences his " grand criterion," Experiment, has scarcely any place, however humble. The astronomer cannot disturb the ordinary course of the stars ; he must observe and calcu- late. The anatomist and zoologist must likewise observe and describe. These operations were performed by the ancients ; yet they failed. Immense stores of observation were accu- mulated, but they were of little, value. If it be said that the Greeks may have observed and experimented, yet did not observe correctly, nor experiment skilfully, the statement is true, but unenlighiening.. Our inquiry is, ; Why was this so ? § 44- As if imperfectly satisfied with his explanation, Platfair next tries thev effect of rhetoric- " Experience in those days was' a light which darted a few tremulous and uncertain rays on some small portions of the field of science ; but men had not acquired the power over that light which now enables them to concentrate, iis : beams,, and to fix; them steadily on whatever subject they wish to examine. This power," he adds r as if he were speaking of something definite, " is 1 what distinguishes modern physics, and is the cause why later philosophers*, without being more ingenious than their predecessors,, have been, infinitely more successful in the study of nature." Stripped of all metaphor thiff means that the ancients failed because they did not bring the results of their research in many directions to elucidate each special inquiry. But unless those results had been truths, their concentration, would have only been a complication^ of error. And our inquiry is, Why were these results imperfect ? Why were the: separate sciences so barren? To thisPLAVflAnt gives no answer. If, indeed, we place ourselves at that elevation which brings twenty centuries under our eye, from, which point, of view all details are merged in a general mist, and only the broad failure becomes visible?, we may say. with truth^. that deficient 4—2 52 ANCIENT SCIENCE. [CHAP. in. Observation was the origin of the failure. But such a truth is barren of instruction. To make it fruitful we must rear it in the soil of History ; we must trace the actual struggles of Science, and learn there what were the causes of this imper- fection. Had the Greeks observed truly, they must have succeeded ; the fact of their failure proves that some radical defect existed: a defect of completeness, or a defect of Method. Can we discover that defect ? § 45. It is the exceptional merit of Dr. Whewell to have seen the necessity of a distinct answer to this question, and to have proposed an answer which claims to be at once definite and philosophical. It is given in the section on the " Cause of the failure of the Greek Philosophy " in his History. 8 He first points out the common error of supposing that this cause lay in neglect of facts. The Greeks, he assures us, did not disregard experience, did not spin their philosophy purely from their own minds. " The disregard of experience is a phrase which may be so interpreted as to express almost any defect of philosophic method, since coincidence with experience is requisite to all theory." He adds that Aristotle not only insisted on experience as the foundation of science, but " also stated in language much resembling the habitual phraseology of modern schools that particular facts must be collected; that from these, general principles must be obtained by in- duction ; and that these principles, when of the most general kind, are axioms " — an assertion we shall see amply justified in our sixth chapter. After referring to the large collection of facts, and the ingenuity of their classification, to be found in Aristotle, he remarks : " Since, as we have before said, two things are requisite to science — Facts and Ideas ; and since, as we have seen, Facts were not wanting, we are naturally led to ask, were the ancients deficient in Ideas ? was there a want among * Whewell : History of the Inductive Sciences, 3rd ed., 1857, 1, 54. CHAP. III.] ANCIENT SCIENCE. 53 them of mental activity, and logical connexion of thought?" The answer is foreseen. Undue mental activity is the standing reproach against them. § 46. Having thus surveyed the elements of the question, and having found that the defect sought could be neither owing to absence of Pacts, as is commonly alleged, nor to absence of Ideas, Dr. "Whewell concludes that " the defect was that though they had in their possession Facts and Ideas, the Ideas were not distinct and appropriate to the Facts." § 47. An obvious answer to this solution is that it merely restates, in other words, the case of failure. In saying that the Ideas were not distinct and appropriate to the Facts, he simply says that the Facts were wrongly interpreted, not why they were so. Answering this criticism, he affirms that his explanation, over and above the case of failure, points out the one special direction, out of several, in which the Greeks went wrong. " They did not fail because they neglected to, observe facts ; they did not fail because they had not ideas to reason from ; but they failed because they had not the right ideas in each case. And as long as they were wrong in this point, no industry in collecting facts, or ingenuity in classing them and reasoning about them, could lead them to solid truth." § 48. It is many years since this explanation was first propounded, but I find myself still unable, after long medita- tion, to see either the precision it claims, or accuracy in the premisses from which it is deduced. I must venture therefore to consider it under both aspects. With respect to the first it should be observed that "distinct and appro- priate Ideas " have a peculiar position in the author's philo- sophy, which may be appreciated through the following "The Greeks in their physical speculations fixed their attention upon the wrong aspects and relations of phenomena ; 54 ANCIENT SCIENCE. [CHAP. III. and the aspects and relations in which the phenomena are to be -viewed in order to arrive at scientific truths, may be ranged under certain heads, which I have termed Ideas;: such as Space, Time, Number, Cause, Likeness. In every case there is an Idea to which the phenomenon may be referred so as to bring into view the Laws by which they are governed ; this Idea, I term the appropriate Idea in such a case ; and in order that the reference of the phenomena to the Law may be clearly seen, the Idea must be distinctly possessed. Thus the reason of Aristotle's failure in his attempts at mechanical science is that he did not refer the Facts to the appropriate Idea, namely Force, the Cause of Motion, but to relations of Space, and the like ; that is, he introduced geometrical instead of mechanical Ideas." § 49. That many special errors may be referred to such a cause is admissible. A writer so conversant with science and its history as Dr. Whewell, would not propound an explanation which was destitute of confirmatory examples; but he will admit that, unless the explanation be generally applicable, it will not serve our purpose ; and it would be easy to cite abundant examples of unequivocal failure which cannot be referred to the indistinctness or inappropriateness of the Ideas. When the orbit of the planets was held to be circular, and their motion uniform, the appropriate and distinct Ideas of Space and Time were not less . vividly present to the mind of Aristotle, than they were to the mind of Kepleb, when he held the orbit to be elliptical, and the motion variable. Again, Aristotle's failure in Biology is not less conspicuous than his failure in Mechanics ; yet the ideas of Final Cause, Likeness, and Vitality, which are said to be the ideas appro- priate to this science, were assuredly possessed by him with a distinctness unsurpassed in modern times. In the course of the ensuing pages many glaring errors of the Greeks will have to be noticed ; and the reader will see how few of them can be referred to the cause assigned by Dr. Whewell. CHAP, m.] ANCIENT SCIENCE. 55 § 50. Instead of conceiving that the Greeks failed to detect the laws of equilibrium and motion because their Ideas of pressure, resistance, momentum, &c, were indistinct, it seems to me more consonant with History to conceive that these Ideas were gradually evolved from the precise appreciation of the Facts of equilibrium and motion. Thus, what Dr. Whewell considers to be primary, fundamental, I hold to be secondary and derivative. The appropriate Ideas said to determine the progress of discovery are, I conceive, them- selves perfected — brought into distinctness — during the progress of discovery, and cannot properly be applied as Instruments until some progress has been achieved. To use the very illustration of our author — " The Idea of Likeness could not be applied so as to give rise to a scientific classifica- tion of plants till considerable progress was made in studying the general relations of vegetable form and life." 3 However, as this is a point in which our views on science are widely at variance, I shall not further moot it here. § 51. If it were admitted that the one determining cause of the failure was the absence of distinctness and appropriateness in the Ideas, a philosophic historian would still be called upon to, explain this absence. The reason why the Greeks viewed phenomena under wrong relations, and why the moderns viewed them under right relations, would stand in need of explanation. Thus Dr. Whewell's reply to the question, Why did the Greeks fail ? is wanting in precision, to say the very least ; and we may now proceed to consider the want of accuracy in the premisses on which his conclusion is founded. § 52. He affirms that the Greeks were not wanting in Facts, nor deficient in Ideas. The statement is delusively equivocal. In strict language, neglect of facts was the cause of failure ; and it is inaccurate to say that the Greeks were * 3 History of Scientific Ideas, 1858, IL, 115. 56 ANCIENT SCIENCE. [CHAP. III. not strikingly deficient in them. Anatomy, for example, is a science which consists in the accurate appreciation of visible facts. It demands nothing but patience in dissection and correctness in description. This science the Greeks professed ; they expounded the facts of animal organization, and their failure was extensive, minute, surprising. Can we say there was not neglect of facts here ? § 53. Although it may be justifiable to answer vague allegations respecting the ancient contempt of observation, by pointing out the large accumulation of facts from which the Greeks drew their data, and by quoting their emphatic recog- nition of the Inductive Method, it is equivocal to claim for them such an appreciation of facts as warrants the assertion that their failure did not arise from deficient observation. It is true that they observed ; it is not true that they observed adequately. It is true that they invoked experience; it is not true that they invoked it sufficiently. They very im- perfectly appreciated the nature of evidence ; they were careless both as to the quantity and quality of the facts. § 54. Nor is the assertion that they were fully possessed with Ideas less equivocal. Undoubtedly, they exhibited immense intellectual energy, but their Ideas were for the most part inductions carelessly obtained from facts which had never been verified ; consequently the ingenuity and activity of their theories only exhibit mental energy, careless whether its constructions rest on granite or on shifting sand. It will be seen hereafter that they were not less regardless of Verification in the region of ideas than in facts ; and therefore, although we cannot say that they were deficient in facts or ideas, meaning by deficiency entire absence, we must avow them to have been deficient in both, meaning by it, insufficiency. This was not due to want of power, but to want of Method. They observed and reasoned, but observed badly, and reasoned precipitately. § 55. There are three modes of investigation : Obser- CHAP. HI.] ANCIENT SCIENCE. 57 vation, Induction, Deduction. To be fruitful, these must all be rigorously subordinated to Verification. Before each new step can be safely taken, the facts must be verified, the induction verified, and the deduction verified. At any one of these stages error may creep in ; unless these doors are securely barred, no success is certain. Imperfectly observed facts, im- perfect inductions and deductions, constantly betray men of science in our own day ; and more constantly betrayed the Greeks, because the Greeks were less alive to the dangers. Our sole superiority consists in this : we have an ampler basis of demonstrated and colligated truths, and a keener sense of the sources of error. They were careless and credulous, where we are circumspect and sceptical. They were confi- dent and precipitate in induction ; and when an argument was verbally consistent it had an excellent chance of being accepted as an accurate representation of the order of nature. § 56. Abundant illustrations will present themselves in the course of the following pages ; meanwhile let this example suffice. The ancients maintained that the velocity of a falling body is proportional to its weight. This is an opinion natu- rally suggested by an unverified survey of the phenomena ; and in those days no -one thought of verifying what was prima facie plausible ; no one thought of ascertaining whether a heavy body did fall more rapidly than a lighter body. The fact was assumed on the faith of such experiences as the fall of a stone and a feather. When Galileo denied the fact, he was ridiculed by the Aristotelians. When he sought to bring it within the range of Verification, by dropping bodies of different weights from the leaning tower of Pisa, so powerful was the old prejudice that it was unshaken even by the simul- taneous sound of these bodies ringing on the pavement. The Aristotelians, from having so long neglected Verification, had come to disbelieve in its teaching. § 57. To affirm that the Greeks wanted neither Facts nor 58 AWCIENT SCIENCE. [CHAP. HI. Ideas is therefore manifestly equivocal. Tor the purposes of Science they wanted both ; that is, they wanted true facts and true ideas. Such facts as they had, seldom sufficed for their inductions, and their deductions were seldom confronted with reality. In a word, they failed because they had not a clear conception of the true Method, and wanted the aid of the proper Instruments. The true Method came into use only after the baffled ingenuity of many generations had dis- closed the futility of every other, and partial success had cheered men on the difficult but certain path. Each step on that path made it easier for followers. The Greeks had no predecessors. With the impatience of active intellects they attempted to build before the accumulation of building materials had furnished the means, and before Architecture had furnished a Method. " The ancients," says Bacon, " proved themselves, in everything that turns on wit and abstraction, wonderful men. But as in former ages, when men sailed only by observation of the stars, they could indeed coast along the shores of the old continent, or cross a few of the Mediterranean seas; but before the ocean could be traversed, and the new world discovered, the use of the mariner's needle, as a more faithful and certain guide, had to be found out." * Unhappily the ancients were ill-content to creep along the coasts, and slowly collect the wealth to be found there. They hoped to traverse the great ocean without the guide of a compass. That guide is Verification. § 58. In the absence of this important principle, the inter- pretation of nature can be but mere guesswork, sometimes right and sometimes wrong, but without a standard of right or wrong. The complexity of phenomena is that of a labyrinth, the paths of which cross and recross each other ; one wrong turn causes the wanderer infinite perplexity. Verification is the Ariadne-thread by which the real issues may be found. Un- 4 Bacon: Works, by Spedmng and Ellis, 1858, IV., 18. CHAP. III.] ANCIENT SCIENCE. 59 happily, the process of Verification is slow, tedious, often difficult and deceptive ; and we are by nature lazy and im- patient, hating labour, eager to obtain. Hence credulity. We accept facts without scrutiny, inductions without proof ; and we yield to our disposition to believe that the order of phenomena must correspond with our conceptions. Verification, the alpha and omega of research, of which Experiment is the potent handmaid, was so little understood by the ancients, that it found neither employment in their practice, nor recognition in their philosophy. I do not, of course, mean that they never verified their facts or conclusions ; only thus could they have acquired any accurate knowledge. I mean that they rarely set about Verification with a distinct consciousness that such a proeess was an indispensable part of true investigation. The great Hippaechtjs and the illus- trious Archimedes are individual examples of true scientific inquiry, and their success was their reward. But few ancients can be named beside these. Even in a science founded so much on calculation as Astronomy we see a deplorable defi- ciency of any due recognition of Verification. Thus when Eeatosthenes conceived the felicitous idea of measuring an arc of the meridian by the sun's distance from the zenith of Alexandria on the solstitial day, conceiving that on the same day the sun was exactly in the zenith of Syene, he never thought of verifying his basis, never ascertained whether Alexandria and Syene were, in fact, due north and south of one another. Yet this is what no modern astronomer would neglect. Had Eeatosthenes taken this preliminary trouble he would have found that Syene is to the east of Alexandria, and must have measured his arc by other points. In future chapters we shall notice Aristotle framing theories, more or less ingenious, upon premisses which a very moderate scrutiny would have detected to be utterly erroneous ; and we may compare this facile acquiescence in unverified facts with the laborious solicitude of ft Hallee, sacrificing one hundred and 60 ANCIENT SCIENCE. [CHAP, m. ninety animals to establish the basis of his theory of Irri- tability, 5 or with the patience of a Mullee, devoting two years of almost daily observation to the generative organs of reptiles and birds. 6 These great investigators knew the futility of theorizing so long as facts remained unverified. They knew the perpetuity of error and disputation when unchecked by peremptory fact. 7 § 59. We have thus gradually disclosed the psychological cause of the ancient failure. It was this defect of Method which prevented successful research. The ancients flagrantly disregarded the principle of Verification, both in the region of facts and the region of ideas; neither recognizing its necessity as a matter of teaching, nor employing it with any rigour and system in practice. To this source every one of their errors may be traced. Every error may be shown to have arisen from reliance on unproved facts, pre- cipitate inductions, or mere phrases reasoned from as if they 5 Haller : MSmoires sur la Nature sensible et irritable des parties du corps animal, Lausanne, 1761, 1., 4. He complains of his contemporaries for not taking due precautions. " Us ne font que peu, ou point, d' experiences, et ce qui est plus dangereux encore, ils lour substituent des analogies auxquclles ils donnent la meme force." In the preface to the 8th vol. of his Elementa Phy- siologic, he finely says : " Lsetus exitum video immensi operis : qui ab annis retro triginta et sex majorem partem vitae mese in id unum impendi. Numerosos libros eo fine legi: animalia pene innumera incidi, et mortua et imprimis viva, ut motus animales eorumque causas perciperem. . . . Longum id tempus non suffecit tamen ut omnia ipse, et satis accurate, et satis repetito viderem ; fuerunt quae nunquam, fuerunt qum nou satis itcrato viderim." This was the spirit which made him one of the great legislators of science in his day. 6 Muixer : Bildungsgeschichte der Genitalien, 1830. Comp. also Vr/LPIAN et Philipeaux : Hecherches ExpSrimentales sur la regeneration des nerfs in the Memoires de la Societe de Biologie, Paris, 1859, I., 382, where, noticing the small amount of facts they adduce after so many experiments, they add, " on en trouvera les raisons dans le controle rigoreux auquel nous avons souniis nos observations, parceque, nous defiant de nous memes, et soulevant apropos de chaque fait des objections, nous n'acceptions comme reellement demonstratives que les experiences qui ne pouvaient laisser place a aucun doute." No ancient would have understood such scruples ; all moderns will applaud, if they have not the patience to imitate them. 7 Por example, the disputes of physicians continued through oenturies re- specting the share in diseases due to an acid state of the blood, before any one had ascertained the fact of free acid existing in the blood at all. CHAP. III.] ANCIENT SCIENCE. 61 were demonstrated truths. And' to this source, likewise, may all the errors of moderns be traced. The last sentence seems to raise a doubt as to the propriety of bringing against the ancients a charge to which the moderns are confessedly open. But it is with steady purpose that I identify the psychological cause in both cases. The human mind has not changed. The cause of error is everywhere the same. In modern times this cause must be very active, since we see unequivocal evidence of its effects. The superiority we have over the ancients arises from our having learned in the study of science to distrust the facile pro- cedure of the mind when left to its native impulses. We have learned the art of investigation. Often failing in its applica- tion, we, at any rate, recognize its methods. The ancients imperfectly understood that art ; and since the art could only have emerged gradually in the growth of Science, we are brought to the second or historical cause of the ancient failure. The psychological cause lies deep in human nature, and is not less operative in our days than of old, whenever it is disengaged from the influences of the historical cause ; that is, whenever the mind acts free from the control of acquired knowledge and acquired tendencies. A long training of the mind in scientific investigation has induced a firm reliance on scientific Method. This represses the spontaneous im- patience and credulity natural to the untrained intellect. We have acquired the habit of Verification in a long experience of the dangers incurred by its neglect. We have learned to view Metaphysics with such distrust as not unfrequently to misconceive the value of abstract principles. § 60. It thus appears that if we can explain the failure of the ancients by their disregard of Verification, we have still to explain why they disregarded so important a principle, and why moderns have both recognized and employed it. The explanation is simple and has already been sketched (§ 40). Science is the attempt to interpret the phenomena 62 ANCIENT SCIENCE. [CHAP, m. of nature; and this interpretation borrows light from the general illumination of discovery. But men cannot, or at least, they will not, await the tardy results of discovery; they will not sit down in avowed ignorance. Imagination supplies the deficiencies of Observation. A theoretic arch is thrown across the chasm, because men are unwilling to wait till a solid bridge be constructed. The mind, as Bacon says, " has a yearning which makes it dart forth to generali- ties that it may have something to rest in ; and after a little dalliance with experience becomes weary of it." The early thinkers, by reason of the very splendour of their capacities, were not less incompetent to follow the slow processes of scientific investigation, than a tribe of martial savages to adopt the strategy and discipline of modern armies. No accumulated laws, no well-tried methods existed for their aid. The elementary laws in each department were mostly unde- tected. And with this poverty in material, with this absence of acquired skill, and this native precipitancy of judgment"; acting on the ambition to interpret nature, it is not wonder^ ful if they chose the a priori road, neglecting the laborious Inductive road which had not then been proved to lead to great results. History tells how the theories established in one generation become the starting-points of successors. The laws, so difficult to discover, become, when discovered; familiar facts ready for the tyro's use. Newton, with all his genius, would not have detected the law of gravitation had not Kepler and Galileo preceded him;, nor could they have made their discoveries had not Greek mathemati- cians supplied the means. It was by the bold and happy identification of celestial with terrestrial physics that the great thinkers of the seventeenth century made physical Astronomy an exact science, making it a part of Mechanics, explaining its' phenomena by those very Laws of Motion which were proved to regulate the phenomena of terrestrial bodies. CHAP. III.] ANCIENT SCIENCE. 63 The growth of discovery is slow, and man is naturally impatient. Herein, as before hinted, lies the explanation of the preference for the Subjective Method. Not until that method had been tried by successive generations, and found to lead to no discovery, was it relinquished for the more modest and difficult method which experience proved to be the true one. And this relinquishment was gradual. The. great results obtained in the 17th century naturally fixed attention on the method by which they were reached. From that time to the present there has been an ever-increasing extension of the method. And that this has been determined by the accumulations of Knowledge is evident when we reflect that the Subjective Method is co-extensive with our ignor- ance. It is the tendency of all positive knowledge of objects gradually to displace the subjective fictions by which the blank of ignorance was at first filled up. Thus with the growth of knowledge Metaphysics, which once reigned supreme, has given place to Science in all but a few depart- ments of inquiry. It will be the task of this History to set forth the various stages of this progress and their causes. For the present it is enough to note how the existence of a mass of accurately-appreciated facts has determined the general acceptance of that Method on which alone the mass may be largely increased, and the true laws of phenomena discovered. The amazing rapidity of scientific progress in the last half century, compared with the slowness of its progress in early times, is clearly due to the facilities afforded by what may be called the historical conditions — the state of knowledge out of which the progress issued. To resume : The cause of the ancient failure was primarily a defect of Method ; and the continuance of this cause, which lies deep in human nature, was due to the imperfect con- dition of Knowledge. At no time was the right Method wholly disregarded, but the predominance of the false Method kept it in a state of feeble subjection. As know- 64 ANCIENT SCIENCE. [CHAP. HI, ledge slowly advanced, this predominance slowly diminished ; and at the present time the relative positions are changed; the false Method is still employed, and in certain inquiries preserves its supremacy; but the existence of a vast body of scientific doctrine, and the rapidly increasing extension of the scientific spirit, prove that the true Method is at length predominant. ( 65 ) CHAPTEK IV. THE METAPHYSICAL AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. § 61. The conclusion arrived at in the preceding chapter requires that some specific account should be given of the two rival Methods, Subjective and Objective, which for so many centuries have struggled for mastery. I shall here confine myself to the metaphysical phase of the Subjective Method. Since the days of Bacon it has been a standing reproach against the Greeks and the Schoolmen that they wasted fine intellects in metaphysical disputes, prolonged the infancy of philosophy by forsaking the plain paths of observation for the wilderness of abstract speculation, and failed to make any considerable advances towards true knowledge, because they engaged in the hopeless endeavour to solve problems insoluble by man. There is a sense in which this reproach is just. There is also a sense in which it is profoundly unjust. Those who perceive only the former, cannot understand why those who perceive the latter should still persist in relying on their bafiled pretensions, and should declare that the historical fact of incessant failure is no convincing reason for ultimate despair. •- — The great battles of Humanity are never fought in vain. Supposing it to be granted that energy and ingenuity have been flung away upon problems essentially insoluble, the 5 66 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. efforts of Metaphysics have not been without fruit. Apart from the valuable experience gained respecting the nature of the problems attacked, there has been the far greater gain of clear insight into the true Method, which discloses what problems are insoluble, and why they are so. For it is a great, though frequent error, to suppose that all metaphysical problems are beyond our power, and that many physical problems are not so. The vanity of Metaphysics lies in its Method, not in its aims. The same Method is no less disastrous in Physics. How little force there is in the de- clamations against that "fondness for abstract reasonings" supposed to have led the ancients astray from the path of observation, may be appreciated on remembering that the Chaldeans observed the heavens for centuries without learning more astronomy than would equip an old almanack-maker; and that many modern astronomers, instead of confining them- selves to observation, are exclusively occupied in calculation and abstract reasoning, some of them being scarcely able to recognize a star in the heavens. § 62. The fundamental ideas of modern science are as transcendental as any of the axioms in ancient philosophy. Who will say that the Law of Causation, or the Laws of Motion, although suggested by experience, and found to be con- formable with it, do not transcend it? These are to ustu ra voiica. Take the formula : " Motion is necessarily rec- tilinear and uniform." This is purely ideal. Our experience, when closely examined, is never of uniform and rectilinear mo- tions, but always of motions accelerated or retarded, and more or less divergent. But the curve of a projectile is explained as the resultant of the resistance of the ah-, and the attraction of the earth acting upon a body which is conceived to be in uniform and rectilinear motion ; and this conception itself is derived from the law of inertia, in other words from the law of causation, that no change (of velocity or direction) can take place without a cause. Thus the uniformity of undisturbed rectilinear motion CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 67 is an abstraction. But it is gained objectively — it is abstracted from facts accurately observed, and is verified by undeviating conformity with facts. In like manner the Law of Inertia is an abstraction ; it so far transcends all experience as to seem in flagrant contradiction to daily experience which shows us that bodies in motion gradually cease to move, without any cause of the cessation being apparent. The law asserts that a body in motion will move for ever with undiminished velocity, unless acted upon by some external cause. This assertion obviously goes beyond the possibilities of experience. We know no body that is not acted upon. The thing does not exist. Nevertheless the law is irresistible. No sooner is it understood than it is accepted without qualification. And the reason of this is that it rigorously fulfils every condition of Verification. Considered in its ideal aspect — (as a mere abstraction) — it is seen to be in conformity with what may be termed the Ideal test, namely, that its negative is unthinkable. I mean, of course, unthink- able by us, not by the ancients, who held that bodies moved and ceased to move from internal causes. Considered in its phenomenal aspect — (as an expression of observed facts) — it is seen to be in conformity with the Real test, namely, that by experimentally diminishing all the known causes of resistance to a body we proportionately diminish its retardation; from whence we conclude that if all resistance were abolished all retardation would disappear ; and thus we establish by experi- ment a truth which transcends the limits of experience. § 63. It is not a difference in \ the problems so much as a difference in the Methods, which distinguishes ancient from modern investigation. Compare the Physics of Abis- totle with the Principia of Newton, and this becomes immediately apparent. In the latter we find metaphysical abstractions, but not the metaphysical Method. The formulas are gained objectively, not subjectively : they are accurate descriptions of the observed order in phenomena ; they are moulded on realities ; they were abstracted from objects, and 5—2 68 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. have been rigorously verified according to the Ideal and Real tests. The formulas of Aeistotle are not more transcen- dental, but they want the guarantee of Verification. On confronting them with the accurately observed order of phe- nomena we find them to be at variance with that order, or unrelated to it. Formed upon incomplete or unverified data, often upon slight analogies and verbal resemblances, they are inaccurate as descriptions. When he deduces his theorems of circular movement from the idea of the circle as the most perfect form, he has neither the justification of conformity with observed phenomena, nor of conformity with the ideal criterion. The two ideas of perfection and motion are not co-ordinates ; they admit of no equation. If an a priori proposition conforms to the Ideal Test, that is to say, if its negative is unthinkable, or absurd, we accept it as subjectively true. When we say that under similar con- ditions similar causes will be followed by similar effects, the truth of the proposition is irresistible, although its absolute conformity with fact can never be established, being, as it is, a proposition respecting the future. Its negation being really unthinkable, its positive truth is irresistible. On the other hand, when Galileo supposed, with the ancients, that the velo- city acquired by a falling body, at any point, must be propor- tional to the space through which it had fallen ; this a priori idea, though very distinct and plausible, did not withstand the Ideal Test, since its negation was thinkable, and there was the equally distinct idea of the velocity being proportional to the time by which to oppose it. Then came the necessity for Verification ; and the criterion in this case was obviously that which we have named the Real Test. By this criterion he learned that his first conception was erroneous, and, although the conception which replaced it was not more intelligible, it had the supreme advantage of being a more accurate descrip- tion of the order of nature. The Ideal Test was recognized by Abistotle and Des- CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 69 cartes, when they advanced it as a principle of the logic of Science, that on passing beyond the region of sense we are to rely on what is possible. 1 In all verifiable cases we dare not be confident that an explanation is true because its truth seems possible. Our conceptions of possibility are too contingent to form a secure ground of deduction. Thus, to Galileo, it seemed possible that velocity must be proportional to space, because, in so conceiving it, he had not distinctly visible to his mind all the elements of the problem ; in other words, all the possibilities. On the application of the Eeal Test he found that the seeming possibility was a fiction. He might have suspected this on the application of the Ideal Test, for the negation of the proposition, "velocity is proportional to space," is perfectly conceivable. Indeed, in such cases Possi- bility requires to be submitted to the twofold verification, and cannot therefore of itself furnish an ultimate test. § 63 a. We are thus brought round to the simple rule which Science inscribes on the pediment of her temple :— No formula admissible unless verifiable; none admitted, except as an hypothesis, until verified ; the Verification having two different criteria : one, conformity with the positive laws of thought; the other, conformity with the observed order of phenomena. This rule at once distinguishes the soluble from the insolu- ble problems, by furnishing the tests to which they must con- 1 Meteor, I., vii., 343. " Concerning things which escape the perception of our senses, we consider them to be sufficiently demonstrated when we have shown them to be possible: irepi rdv dipavTwv ry aia&fiaa vo\uZ,ojiiv Uavuig diroScdelxdai Kara rbv Xoyov, idv tig rb dvvarov dvaydyujfuv.'' Descaktes refers to this as representing his own views : Principia Philosophies, Pars quarta, § cciv. ; he adds the important qualification : " quod equidem verum esse libentissime concedo, satisque a me prsestitum esse putabo, si tantum ea quae scripsi talia sint ut omnibus naturae phenomenis accurate respondeant." This is in accordance with Kant's excellent remark that, "Irrthiimer entspringen nicht allein daher weil man gewisse Dinge nicht weiss, sondern weil man sich zu urtheilen unternimmt ob man gleich nicht Alles weiss was dazu erfordert wird." — Untersuchungen vher die Deutlichkeit der Grundsatze. Werke, 1838, 1., 100. 70 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. form. In transcendental questions the test is ideal. No question within the sphere of natural phenomena is too vast for human capacity, or too subtle for human ingenuity, if it can be brought within the range of Verification, direct or in- direct ; and all questions are insoluble so long as they remain outside this range. A year ago (1860) it would have been as idle to speculate respecting the metals which now exist in the sun's atmosphere, as respecting the change of a luminiferous vibration into a sensation of light — both questions were hopelessly insoluble because both lay outside the sphere of Verification. No sooner did the brilliant discoveries of Kibchoff and Bunsen 2 disclose a means of Verification (Spectrum analysis), than the question became strictly scientific. In like manner, if ever the means of establishing an equation between motion and sensation be detected, we shall be able to recognize the sensation of light to be the correlated form of the force previously existing as vibrations of the luminiferous medium ; and we shall trace the re-appearance of this force in the motion of muscular contraction, just as in physics we see motion passing into heat, and heat re-passing into motion, or into electricity. § 68 b. That the ancients and the schoolmen spent them- selves on insoluble problems, is true ; but it is not the capital charge against them. Their grand mistake was the employ- ment of a Method on which all problems were insoluble, and 2 " Nos connaissances positives par rapport aux astres sont necessairement limitees a leurs phenomenes ggometriques et mccaniques, sans pouvoir nulle- ment embrasser les autres recherches physiques, chimiques, physiologiques et meme sociales que component les etres accessibles a. tous nos divers moyens d'observation." — Comte : Cours de Philos. Positive, 1835, II., 9. Compare also pp. 11, 13, This seemed justifiable at the time it was written, although perhaps there was even then an unphilosophical absoluteness in asserting the necessary limitation of knowledge, since Woixaston and Fraunhofer had discovered the "lines " which form the basis of the new means of verification. It is quite possible that we shall one day indirectly verify physical, chemical, and even biological propositions concerning the planets, as we have already verified their magnitudes, distances, orbits, and times of revolution. But until the means of Verification are detected, such problems are insoluble. CHAP. IT.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 71 which rendered their explanations of ordinary phenomena as fruitless as their speculations about noumena and efficient causes. Instead, therefore, of indulging in declamations against their verbal quibbles and pursuit of metaphysical abstractions, we may inquire why verbal quibbles should so long have deluded them, and why the pursuit of metaphysical abstractions seemed to them the pursuit of noblest wisdom. To ascertain this we must appreciate their Method, in contrast with the Method of Science. § 64. Science is that co-ordination of facts which describes the order of co-existence and succession in phenomena. It classifies facts, bringing the particular facts under general heads, co-ordinating them into theories which have all the exactitude compatible with our means. § 64 a. What is the meaning of Fact ? Nothing seems easier to define, until we try ; on trial, the task is perplexing because of the ambiguities of language. In philosophical and in vernacular usage, an antithesis is implied between Fact and Idea (or Theory), which fades into vagueness on exami- nation. Facts are commonly understood to relate exclusively to sense — to the objective world — to phenomena existing externally, and per se. Ideas, on the contrary, relate to con- sciousness — to the conceptions we form of external things. The sweetness of an apple is a fact when the quality on which it depends is considered apart from our sensation ; an idea when considered as a part of our experience. Facts might thus be defined the order of phenomena ; Ideas, or Theories, our conceptions of that order. In this sense there can be no false facts, but only false ideas. Could such distinctions be consistently maintained it might be well. But they cannot. The psychologist knows how shadowy and artificial are these pretended limits. His analy- sis discloses that facts are indissolubly ideal — the appearances of things to us, not the things per se, and that so far from any fact being the unadulterated image of its object, the con- 72 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. ditions of our consciousness are necessarily mingled with it. Moreover his analysis shows in the simplest fact an inextricable blending of inference with sensation. A fact may be defined as a bundle of inferences tied together by one or more sensations. Take a case so simple as the sight of an apple on the table. All that is here directly certified by consciousness is the sen- sation of a coloured surface ; with this are linked certain ideas of roundness, firmness, sweetness, and fragrance, which were once sensations, and are now recalled by this of colour, and the whole group of actual and inferred sensations clusters into the fact which is expressed in " there is an apple." Yet any one of these inferences may be erroneous. The coloured object may be the imitation of an apple in wood or stone ; the inferences of roundness and solidity would then be correct, those of sweetness and fragrance erroneous ; the statement of fact would be false. Or the object seen may be another kind of fruit, resembling an apple, yet in important particulars differing from it. Or the object may not exist, and our per- ception may be an hallucination. Thus a case seemingly so simple may furnish us with the evidence that Facts express our conception of the order in external things, and not the unadulterated order itself. Should the accuracy of any par- ticular fact happen to be of importance — and in Science all facts are important — we must verify it, before accepting it. How is it verified ? By submitting each of its constituent in- ferences to the primordial test of Consciousness. The test with regard to objects within range of sense is obviously the reduction of inference to sensation. The test with regard to axioms, or general principles transcending sense, is con- formity with the laws of thought (§ 62) ; when we have thus verified a fact we have attained the highest degree of certitude. § 65. The mental vision by which in Perception we see the unapparent details — i. e. by which sensations formerly co-existing with the one now affecting us are reinstated under the form of ideas, which represent the objects — is a process CHAP. IV. j AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 73 closely allied to Ratiocination, which also presents an ideal series such as, if the objects were before us, would be a series of sensations, or perceptions. A chain of reasoning is a chain of inferences, which are ideal presentations of the details now unapparent to sense. Could we realize all the links in this chain, by placing the objects in their actual order as a visible series, the chain of reasoning would be a succession of percep- tions, and would cease to be called reasoning. The path of the planets is seen by reason to be an ellipse ; it would be perceived as a fact if we were in a proper position, and endowed with the requisite instruments to enable us to follow the planet in its course. Not having this advantage, we infer the unapparent points in its course, from those which are apparent. We see them mentally. In like manner, suppose a human body is discovered under conditions which suggest that it has been burned, but without sufficient indication of the cause, i. e. the facts antecedent to the burning. Some one suggests that these unapparent facts are those of Spon- taneous Combustion. Our greater familiarity with the facts of combustion in general, and with the facts of the animal organism, enables us to see that this explanation is absurd; we mentally range the supposed objects before us, and see that such an order of co-existences and successions is in contradic- tion to all experience ; we cannot see what the actual order was, but see clearly that it was not that. Correct reasoning is the ideal assemblage of objects in their true relations of co-existence and succession. It is see- ing with the mind's eye. Bad reasoning results from over- looking either some of the objects, or their relations ; some links are dropped, and the gap is filled up from another series. Thus the traveller sees a highwayman, where there is truly no more than a sign-post in the twilight ; and a philosopher, in the twilight of knowledge, sees a pestilence foreshadowed by an eclipse. These considerations may elucidate the real meaning to be 74 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. assigned to Facts, which are sometimes taken to express the order of external things, and sometimes our conception of that order —our description of it ; just as sound means hoth the vibrations of the air, and our sensation of them. There is a general tendency to use the word Fact for a final truth. " This is a fact not a theory " means, " this is an indis- putable truth, riot a disputable view of the truth." But if, as we have seen, Facts are inextricably mingled with Inferences, and if both Perception and Seasoning, are processes of mental vision reinstating unapparent fatails, and liable to error in the inferences, it is clear that the radical antithesis is not between Fact and Theory, but between verified and unverified Inferences. § 66. The antithesis between Fact and Theory is un- tenable, for the same statement may be either a fact or a theory, without any change in its evidence. It is a fact that the earth is globular. It is a fact that this globe is an oblate spheroid. It is a fact that its orbit is elliptical. No one doubts that these are facts, no one doubts that they are theories. Shall we say that they were theories until they were verified, when they became facts ? This will not extricate us; since all facts require verification before they are admitted as truths; up to that point they are not less inferential than theories. I see an apple now falling, and I see an apple which has fallen. These are two facts which ordinary language will not suffer us to call theories. Now consider two theories which ordinary language suffers us to call facts : namely, that all apples when unsupported will fall, and that the spaces fallen through will be as the squares of the times. These are two theories of extreme generality, which are far more indisputable than the facts we have contrasted them with. They carry such certainty that no mind having the requisite preparation can for a moment hesitate in assenting to them. They are inferences which are necessities. Whereas the inferences in- CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 75 volved in the facts before named may very easily be erroneous. The falling object may not be an apple ; the apple found at the foot of the tree may not have fallen, but have been plucked and placed there. Thus doubt is permissible ; and if the facts carried any importance we should be bound to verify the accuracy of our inferences. No doubt is permissible in respect to the two theories, because the inferences on which they rest have already been rigorously verified. They carry none of those possibilities of error which we know may be carried by individual experiences ; all such possibilities have been eliminated in the establishment of the general truth. Should any individual experience seem in contradiction with a thoroughly verified theory, should a hundred individual experi- ences contradict it, our confidence would suffer no disturbance ; we should at once assign them to the interference of some condition not included in the formula. That condition might be wholly undiscoverable, but we should be certain that the laws of nature were invariable; and our experience of disturbing influences is sufficiently extensive to invoke them in every apparent exception to a law. If it happened that two magnets placed side by side impressed on a particle of iron a velocity greater, or less, than the sum of the velocity due to each magnet acting separately, and if this were to occur a thousand times, we should not doubt the truth of the law that the velocity is proportional to the force, but should attribute this exception to some exceptional condition, such as the influence of one magnet on the other. The reason is simple : the law has been rigorously verified ; the absence of any exceptional condi- tion has not been verified, whereas the presence of such a con- dition is suggested by manifold experiences in analogous cases. § 67. Failing thus to discover any valid antithesis between Fact and Theory, we must look upon the ordinary distinction as simply verbal. Shall we express it by the terms Descrip- tion and Explanation, implying that a Fact describes the order of phenomena, and a Theory interprets that order? For 76 the Metaphysical [chap. iv. many purposes this would suffice. Yet on examination we shall find that an Explanation is only a fuller Description : more details are introduced, greater precision is given, the links in the chain which are unapparent to sense, are made apparent to reason ; but the essential mystery is untouched ; successions are enumerated, but causation escapes. Thus in the description of falling bodies, greater fulness and precision of detail are given when the unapparent links are added, and the law of attraction is introduced as the explanation. In like manner the description of an event, say the destruction of a house by a fire, acquires greater fulness and precision of detail when the apparent details are completed by some eye- witness who saw the fire break out, and explains it by this enumeration of details. In each case the objects are ranged in their order, and are seen thus ; but in each case many objects are not seen, many intermediate links are overlooked, or are undiscoverable ; and the causal nexus is for ever undis- coverable. Thus it is that explanations are descriptions, and descriptions are explanations, facts are theories, and theories facts. Science is the explanation of nature ; the systematic co-ordination of the facts of co-existence and succession. § 68. It is beyond the purpose of this chapter to specify the means by which facts and theories are verified. Enough that whether they be simple or complex, particular or general facts, they only amount to descriptions of the external order. What is termed the explanation of a phenomenon by the discovery of its cause, is simply the completion of its descrip- tion by the disclosure of some intermediate details which had escaped observation. The phenomenon is viewed under new relations. It is classed. It is no longer isolated, but linked on to known facts : as when the ascent of a flame, and the descent of an apple are seen to be particulars of one general fact. We learn that chlorine is a gas having a strong " ten- CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 77 dency" to unite with hydrogen; that is to say, we have discovered this among its several relations. But the ten- dency is only manifested in sunlight. The two gases may he mingled together in darkness, and will not there unite if they are left together. Admit a ray of light, and the gases rush together with a loud explosion. So far we can describe. If we desire to explain, we must seek the intermediates ; we must bring the particular facts under some general fact, and thereby detect the unapparent antecedent named cause. Shall we seek this intermediate in a " repul- sive force," which we assign to the darkness, and which would forcibly separate the two gases ? On the Metaphysical Method this would be legitimate, and metaphysicists might accept the explanation. On the Scientific Method it would at once be condemned, because it does not bring the unknown into visible relation with the known, but into imaginary relation with an imagined fact. Darkness is itself a negation, and its repulsive force a fiction without basis. Let us turn to Light, which is more or less known. Do we know any- thing of it which enables us to class this effect on the two gases under the same head as other effects ? We believe that it is ethereal undulation of a specific velocity, and we may infer that the transference of this velocity to the atoms of the gases causes them to rush together. "We cannot produce this combination by any other known velocity, consequently we are not able rigorously, to assert that it is motion and no other cause which effects the change ; but we have so many evidences of chemical change produced by motion, i. e. by heat and light and electricity, that it is difficult to assign any other cause. Now let us suppose this proved. What has been done ? The obvious order has received an addition to its description by the recognition of an unapparent detail. If our senses were sufficiently acute we might see the vibra- tion of light transferred to the gaseous atoms, we might see them quivering and rushing together; we might see them 78 THE METAPHYSICAL [OHAP. IV. liberated from the ethereal vibrations (heat), which had kept them in a more expanded condition, and which now produce the explosion. But that is all we should see; the mystery of their new union, the nature of the forces, would be veiled from us, and our explanation would still be no more than a description of the order in phenomena. § 68 a. To this illustration from science let one be added from ordinary life. A man stumbles on the prostrate body- of a girl. There is blood on the ground; a gash in her throat ; a razor lies on the trampled mud. These appearances suggest unapparent details. He sees that the girl has been murdered ; recognizes the razor as belonging to her brutal stepfatber; and at once explains the presence of the corpse by inferring that the girl was murdered by her stepfather. This description of the order of events, this mental vision of unseen occurrences, may be correct. Another man looking from a distant window may have seen the murder committed ; seeing the facts which the other only inferred. But both are describing an order of events in which there is large inference, and both may be in error. The first witness infers that the girl was murdered ; she may have committed suicide. The second witness verifies the truth of the infer- ence respecting the murder ; but the inference respecting the identity of the stepfather needs confirmation. One relies on the fact that the razor belongs to the stepfather, and that this man has frequently maltreated the girl : but the razor may be the property of another man, or may have been used by another purposely to mislead suspicion. The eye-witness, again, infers that the man seen from the window was the stepfather, and no other : infers this from certain visual sensations ; but the murderer may have resembled in general aspect the stepfather. Suppose that the accused is able to prove on unexceptionable evidence, that at the very hour named, he was many miles away from the spot ; this would at once set aside all the criminating evidence founded on the CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 79 inferences of the eye-witness. By thus sifting the facts, confronting inferences with the actual order of things, justice and science arrive at their verdicts. The digression we have just made discloses that whatever may he the convenience of language, Fact and Theory, Description and Explanation, admit of no essential separation. The only vital antithesis is between verified and unverified inferences. We are thus once again brought to the iteration of the important principle that Verification is the alpha and omega of philosophy ; and that it is by the vigilant solicitude for Verification, and the comprehensive delicacy of the means employed in it, that Science asserts her superiority over Metaphysics. § 69. The metaphysician and metaphysicist pretend to co-ordinate facts with all the rigour of a physicist ; but they admit facts which have not withstood the preliminary test, and facts which are not amenable to that test. This disregard and misapprehension of the test are due to overweening confidence in the validity of reason. Ideas are accepted, .unchallenged, as the correct representatives of the external order. " There is one basis of science," says Descaktes, " one test and rule of truth, namely, that whatever is clearly and distinctly conceived is true." 3 A profound psychological mistake. It is true only of formal logic, wherein the. mind never quits the sphere of its first assumptions to pass out into the sphere of real existences ; no sooner does the mind pass from the internal order to the external order, than the necessity of verifying the strict correspondence between the two becomes absolute. The Ideal Test must be supplemented 3 " Hac igitur detecta veritate simul etiam invenit omnium scientiarum fanda- mentum: ac etiam omnium aliarum veritatem, mensuram ac regulam ; scilicet, quicquid tam clarS ac distinct^ percipitur quam istud verum est." He after- wards qualifies this by adding " when the idea involves existence." Spinoza, Implicitly in the Ethics, and explicitly in his letter to Oldenbukg, assumes the iame criterion. Compare, also, his tract, De emendatione intellectus, § 108. Indeed, it is the only ground on which Metaphysics can be justified. 80 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. by the Real Test, to suit the new conditions of the problem. "Reason is the Absolute," says Schilling, "and all the objections against this proposition spring from our tendency to regard things, not as they are in Reason, but as they appear."* Again : " It is a fundamental belief that not only do things exist independently of us, but that our Ideas so com- pletely correspond with them that there is nothing in the things which is not in our Ideas." Hegel, in the introduction to his Logic, comes upon the question, " What is truth ? In ordinary language we name the concordance of an object with our conception of it, truth. In philosophical language, on the contrary, truth is the concordance of the meaning with itself (iibereinstimmung eines Inhalts mit sich selbst). And this sense has also penetrated our vernacular, for we speak of a true friend, meaning thereby one whose actions correspond with the idea of friendship." 5 And he scornfully characterizes Empiricism as seeking truth in Experience instead of in Thought (statt in dem Gedanken selbst das Wahre zu suchen.) 6 It is on such principles that the modern German Philosophy has reproduced the ambitious but inane attempts of Scholas- ticism. Hegel's disciples avow that " since the Whole is ideally in the Mind, the I has only to yield itself to its I-hood, in order to see the Absolute in itself as there im- mediately given." 7 The curious results of yielding to the I-hood are familiar to all those who have toiled through modern German philosophy. Let us for one moment pause to consider how Hegel applies this method to the elucidation of Matter and Spirit. * Sohellino : Zeitschrift far speculative Physik, IX., Heft. II, 3, s Hegel's Philosophie in wSrtlichen Ausziigen. Von Ekanz und Hillekt: Berlin, 1843, p. 27. 'Hegel: Encyclopadie der philos. Wissenschaften, § 37, Heidelberg, 1830, p. 44. 'Ekanz und Hilleut: Op. cit. XII. The original must be added: " Denn da im Geiste idealiter das Ganze ist, so hat sich das Ich nur seiner Ichheit zu begeben, urn in sieh selbst das Absolute anzuschauen welches sich unmittelbar darbietet." CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 81 The substance or essence (substanp) of Matter, he says, is Gravity ; that of Spirit is Freedom. But Matter is only heavy inasmuch as it tends to a centre. It is composite ; its very existence is external to itself — sie besteht ausser einander. Thus the essence of matter consists in the search for an unity which would be its destruction." 8 Now, supposing we accepted these strange propositions, does not the inquirer at once perceive that such subjective manipulations can be of no assistance in the search for external relations ? § 69 a. But the errors of a Descabtes or a Hegel, not to mention the thousand broad and subtle intellects which have pursued similar paths, are not to be disposed of by a sentence. History reveals the completeness of the failure; but Philosophy demands an exposition of its cause. I have already indicated that cause in general terms, and will endeavour to complete that indication. First, let us consider the futility of deciding upon the external order, by subjective scrutiny — of passing from formal logic into the sphere of concrete objects — without being care- ful to apply the Real Test. Oxygen and nitrogen are two colourless gases ; abstract Logic assures us that out of two negatives we cannot educe a positive ; out of two colourless gases, therefore, Logic tells us that we can get no colour by their union. But what is the fact ? We pass from the sub- ject to the object ; we bring the two gases into union ; and the nitrous acid which results has a deep orange colour. The application of the Eeal Test, the verification of our deduction by the confrontation with reality, discloses an imperfection in that deduction, which, subjectively, could not have been sus- pected. And if, in so simple a case, the objective facts are not in accordance with the subjective deduction, how much more urgent is the demand for Verification in highly complex 8 Hegel: Philos. der Geschichte, 1849, p. 22. Comp. also Encyclop. der philos. Wissen., § 262. 6 82 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. cases, physiological or psychological, not to mention the favourite themes of Metaphysics ? And yet it is obvious that the truths of formal logic are unimpeachable. But they lose their guarantee in passing beyond their sphere. The laws of Kational Mechanics are none the less certain, because in Practical Mechanics the effects of friction and the inevitable imperfection of materials cause us to modify our calculations. But the results of apply- ing the laws of Bational Mechanics without due consideration for the disturbing causes would be disastrous. It is the same in speculation. No sooner do we pass beyond the region of abstractions, than we must at every step assure ourselves of the truth of our inferences by the confirmation of reality. This necessity metaphysicians have overlooked. Logical dependence was the sole test they sought. A conclusion was pronounced valid if it could be shown to be " involved in the idea " which was formed of the facts ; but how that idea itself had been formed, or how far it was verifiable, was disregarded. The uniform velocity of the planets was involved in the idea of their circular orbit, which again was involved in the idea of the circle as the most perfect form. The variable velocity of the planets is equally involved in the idea of their orbit being elliptical ; but this idea was not gained by deduction from the idea of perfection ; it was gained by an abstraction from the observed order of phenomena : it was a verifiable and verified inference. The one conclusion was purely metaphysical, the other purely scientific. 9 § 70. Unless we adopt the Platonic conception of Ideas, and suppose that our d priori notions are independent of 9 Roger Bacon is worth quoting here : " Duo enim sunt modi cognoscendi, scilicet per argumentum et experimentum. Argumentum concludit et facit nos concludere qussstionem, sed non certificat neque removet dubitationem, ut quiescat animus in intuitu veritatis, nisi earn inveniat via experientia? • " and comparing the man who argues about the properties of fire with the man who tests them, he adds, " sed assumpta experientia combustionis certificatur ani- mus et quiescit in/ulgore veritatis." — Opus Majus, Venet., 1750 p. 336 CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 83 experience, it is obvious thai the Metaphysical Method violates the first principles of research. If experience is the basis of even abstract knowledge— the abstract notions being elicited from concrete facts— experience will be the test of all know- ledge. This is not the place to re-open the discussion respect- ing the origin of knowledge. Those who hold that the mind is furnished with ideas derived from a source independent of experience, and not therefore amenable to it, must neverthe- less confine themselves strictly within the sphere of such ideas, and not include in it the facts only given by experience. Descabtes, who started from universal doubt, refusing to admit anything but what was demonstrably true, very soon wandered into error, because his criterion of truth was simply subjective ; whereas another criterion was no less indispensa- ble directly he passed from the region of ideas to the region of facts. Thus, in assigning the pineal gland as the seat of the soul, he says, " The reason which persuades me that the soul can have no other seat is that I consider all the other parts of the brain are double, and that thought is single ; and one can easily conceive that the images are collected in this gland by means of the animal spirits." 10 What he can easily conceive, he at once unsuspectingly accepts to be the truth ; any con- firmation of this view by the application of the Eeal Test he deems superfluous. Here, as throughout, he falls into the common mistake of metaphysicians. Kant truly says " it is the fate of human reason in speculation to build as rapidly as possible, and only when the edifice is completed to examine the solidity of its foundations." 11 And the source of such carelessness he finds in this, that knowledge often consisting in the analysis of our conceptions, we are led to pay exclusive attention to them, rather than to their prigin. § 71. That the vital distinction between Metaphysics and 10 Descartes: Traite des Passions, art. 32. (Euvres, ed. Simon: Paris, 1844, p. 519. 11 Kant : Kritik. Einleitung, § III., p. 9. 6 — 2 84 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. Science is less the nature of their problems than the nature of their Method, which finally determines what problems are soluble and how they can be solved, may be shown from two sides. Many of the fundamental principles of Science are, as we have already seen, principles which transcend experience, although rigorously conformable with it. They are necessary truths, in the sense that the mind having once understood the terms of their enunciation cannot conceive the proposi- tions otherwise ; they conform to the Ideal Test, and cannot be made matters of direct observation. The law of causation, and the law of inertia, are not measurable and demonstrable in the same way as the law of refraction is measurable and demonstrable. No physicist ever thought of proving the former by experiment ; no physicist would accept the latter unless it had been experimentally verified. Hence Kant has proposed to form a separate science, physica pura or rationalis, of those propositions which usually form the introduction to Physics. 12 But the reason which most imperatively forces us to regard Method as the primary and cardinal distinction, I take to be this : a theory may be transferred from Metaphysics to Science, or from Science to Metaphysics, simply by the addition or the withdrawal of its verifiable element. Thus the law of universal attraction becomes pure Metaphysics if we withdraw from it the verifiable specification of its mode of operation. Withdraw the formula " inversely as the square of the distance and directly as the mass," and Attraction is left standing a mere " occult quality." Indeed the Cartesians reproached it with being such an occult quality, and stigmatized it as a revival of Aristoteliauism. On the other hand, add this verifiable formula to the " inherent virtue " of the old meta- physicists, and the result is a strictly scientific proposition. 12 Kaht : Kritik. Einleitung, and compare also his very remarkable treatise Metaphysische Anfangsgriinde der Naturwissenschaft. Werke. V., where these propositions are elucidated. CHAP. IV.J AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 85 § 72. And how is this transference from Metaphysics to Science effected ? Obviously by the precision of our descrip- tion, the intercalation of facts in their proper order, facts which previously had been unsuspected, or had not been seen in that order. It is a common mistake to suppose that Science deals solely with facts, and Metaphysics with ideas. Both deal largely with both.' The difference lies in the authenticity of the Method by which the facts are collected, and co- ordinated. There is abundance of well authenticated facts which nevertheless form no Science because their co-ordination has not been effected ; they are bricks awaiting the architect. It is certain, for example, that the cervical vertebra of all mammals (with two or three exceptions) are seven in number ; the long-necked giraffe has the same number as the short- necked hog, or mole. The same uniformity, however, is not found in other vertebrae. The giraffe has 14 dorsal and 20 caudal vertebras ; the mole has 13 dorsal and 10 caudal. Indeed, the varieties are no less striking in the other portions of the spinal column, than the uniformity is in the neck; and these varieties suffice to refute the suggestion which has been propounded respecting the mystic influence of the number seven ; a suggestion not only metaphysical in its principle, but faulty in its disregard of the fact that in some mammals the cervical vertebras are not seven in number, in the sloth, for example, they are nine. Although we are at present without a reason, without an explanation, we carefully preserve the facts ; they are not science yet ; they may become science by co-ordination with other facts. If we attempt to co-ordinate them, we class them first under the general fact of Type. All the mammals are related : probably by kinship, remote ancestry ; certainly by those organic resemblances which con- stitute Type. Passing to more special considerations, and asking why the cervical vertebras have varied so little from the ancestral type, and why the dorsal, lumbar, and caudal have varied so much, we are led to seek the conditions of variation ; 86 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. when these have been ascertained, we may be able to co- ordinate them, and then we shall have a scientific explanation why mammals have seven cervical vertebrae, neither more nor less. The metaphysician instead of waiting for such facts proceeds to solve the difficulty by invoking the influence of Number, or perhaps of Final Causes, § 72 a. The spontaneous tendency to invoke a Final Cause in explanation of every difficulty is characteristic of meta- physical, philosophy. It arises from a general tendency towards the impersonation of abstractions which is visible throughout History. We animate Nature with intentions like our own. We derive our ideas of Cause, and Force, from our own experience of effort ; and the changes we observe are interpreted as similar in origin to the changes we effect. This leads to the Fetichism of savages and children ; to the Polytheism of more advanced intelligence ; and, by a gradual refinement in abstraction, to the Metaphysics and Transcendental Physics of later days. We first impersonate the causes as Deities ; we next eliminate more and more of the personal elements, leaving only abstract Entities ; we finally reduce these Entities to Forces, as the general expres- sion of Properties or Eelations ; e. g., the Force of gravity is only the abstract expression of the fundamental relation which matter universally manifests. All matter is heavy ; all masses attract other masses ; this property is as universal and funda- mental as that of impenetrability ; we abstract it as gravita- tion or attraction (§ 74 c). In this gradation the Will first disappears ; next the independent Existence ; leaving finally, an abstract expression of observed order. In the final stage we recognize that what was assumed to be an independent something, regulating phenomena, moulding them according to its nature, is only an impersonation of the order in pheno- mena, the statement in abstract terms of the very facts them- selves. Thus, observing the facts of organic growth and development, physiologists have attributed them to the agency CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 87 of a Plastic Force (vis formativa, Bildungstrieh), which moulds the heterogeneous materials into definite shapes. If, however, we seriously consider what this Plastic Force can be, apart from the phenomena, we are quickly led to perceive that it is only a name assigned to the observed order, a generalized expression of the facts, which has been personified, according to a well-known tendency. § 72 b. Of this kind is the impersonation of a Vital Prin- ciple, which has played so conspicuous a part in speculation, and which has been endowed with many imaginary attributes, among them that of controlling chemical agency. What is it, in a last analysis ? All the visible facts of life are generalized in an abstract expression ; this abstract expression is personified ; this personification is endowed with attributes ; and we then believe firmly that over and above the facts observed there is an independent Principle regulating these facts, calling them into existence, and impressing on them a definite direction ; in other words, besides the organism and its functions, the organs and their acts, we believe in the existence of a mysterious something, an Entity inhabiting the organism, fashioning its organs, and direct- ing its acts. Did we not know that the mechanism of a watch was arranged by man, and that its activities depended on the properties of matter, placed in certain relations of interdependence, we should believe in the existence of a Watch-principle, fashioning springs, wheels, and escapements, and regulating their activities. But knowing the fact, we recognize the purely ideal existence of such a Principle ; and in like manner we can conceive that what we imagine to be a Vital Principle, anterior and independent in the organism, is really nothing but our generalized expression, abstracted from the mutually-dependent facts. § 72 c. It is the same with all the other numerous imper- sonations of abstract ideas. They are collected from the observed order, and interpreted according to the analogies of 88 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. our personality ; then the facts from which they were abstracted are gradually dropped out of sight, until only the abstraction remains. When this has been done, we have great difficulty in not believing that they exist independently of the facts — that our subjective separation corresponds with an objective separation — and we therefore make them the starting-points of investigation without reference to the facts. This is the basis of Metaphysics. § 73. Having thus endeavoured to understand the nature of Metaphysics, and the reason why it necessarily formed the first explanations of philosophy, we may now glance at the influence of Language in abetting the spontaneous tendency. " All the first attempts to comprehend nature led to the introduction of abstract conceptions, often vague, indeed, but not therefore unmeaning, such as motion and velocity, force and pressure, impetus and momentum (jootttj). And the next step in philosophizing necessarily was to endeavour to make these vague abstractions more clear and fixed, so that the logical faculty should be able to employ them securely and coherently. But there were two ways of making this attempt ; the one by examining the words only and the thoughts which they call up ; the other by attending to the facts and things which bring these abstract terms into use. The latter, the method of real inquiry, was the way to success; but the Greeks followed the former, the verbal or notional course, and failed." 13 Not the Greeks alone, but all metaphysicians, metaphysicists, and metaphysiologists, have followed this course, and consistently followed it, when they have once adopted the belief that the order in ideas necessarily repre- sents the order in external things. The pivot of Science is precisely the Verification of this assumed correspondence. Moreover, aiding and abetting this tendency in the mind to accept ideas as exact representations of things, there is the tendency to assume that distinct names represent distinct 13 Whewell : History of the Inductive Sciences, 1857, I., 27. CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 89 facts, so that to analyse the meaning of words is held equivalent to analysis of the things represented. Psychology has made a great advance when it has learned to question these primitive assumptions, an advance which was scarcely suspected in ancient philosophy. The theory of Language was little understood, and nations familiar with no language but their own could hardly have been on their guard against verbal fallacies. When Aristotle commences an investigation he is careful to enumerate what other men have said on the subject, and the meanings which are attached to certain words. In this he is imitated by most moderns, but with a difference : while they display even greater servility to the mere opinion of authoritative writers, they own no servility to the current meanings of words ; if they are careful in defining their expressions, it is in order to be understood; whereas Aristotle defined them in order to expound the facts they resumed. " The propensity to seek for principles in the common usages of language," says Dr. Whewell, " may be discovered at a very early period. Thus we have an example of it in the saying of Thales, when he was asked, What is the greatest thing ? He replied Place ; for all things are in the world, and the world is in it. In Aristotle we have the consummation of this mode of speculation. The usual point from which he starts is that we say thus or thus, in common language. Thus, when he has to discuss the question whether there be in any part of the universe a Void, or space in which there is nothing, he first inquires in how many senses we say that one thing is in another. He enumerates many of these : we say the part is in the whole, as the finger is in the hand ; again, we say the species is in the genus, as man is included in animal ; again, the government of Greece is in the king ; and various other senses are described, but of all these the most proper is when we say a thing is in a vessel, and generally, in place." 14 14 Op. cit., p. 29. 90 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. § 74. The Method which has led to success in every department of inquiry, and a success proportional to the rigour of its employment, does not, as many suppose, lead us to rely solely or mainly on ohservation, to the neglect of ideas, but to rely solely on those facts and ideas which have with- stood the tests of Verification, and have received their " Hall mark " from the Goldsmith's Company (§ 62). This Method at once eliminates many of the objects of metaphysical research, rejecting them because not verifiable. The primary requisi- tion of Science is that, apart from the hypothesis which colligates the facts, and is understood to be only an hypothesis (§ 74 a), every detail in its Descriptions (Explanations) shall have been confronted with the observed order in things. It thereby renounces, as beyond its scope, all inquiry into noumena, or essences, confining itself to phenomena and their order of co-existence and succession. Metaphysics, believing that what we think necessarily corresponds with what Nature is, endeavours, by analysis of the ideas of existence and cause, to gain a clear understanding of them. Its Method demands only the one criterion of logical depen- dence ; and so long as it keeps within transcendental limits, this criterion is the only possible one. In passing from formal logic to physical inquiry, a new set of conditions is entered upon, and the test of conformity with fact becomes imperative. Owing to the impatience excited by metaphysical preten- sions, there has of late years arisen a desire to banish the word " cause " from inductive philosophy ; but the word is useful, and it cannot be banished. All that can be done is to mark out clearly the meaning assigned to it in science, namely, that of unconditional antecedence. The metaphysical conception of a cause, the producer of effect, needs limitation. "We can know nothing of the final nexus. When we say that heat produces expansion, we simply express the observed facts, that one heated body brought near a colder body begins to con- CHAP, IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 91 tract, and the colder simultaneously begins to expand; nothing new has been produced ; a mutual change in the condition of the two bodies has resulted in the transference of so much motion (heat, expansion) from one body to another. Hence, rigorously speaking, we must limit even the con- ception of necessary sequence, which is held to express all that is known of causation. There is no following of effects from causes ; but, as Sir John Herschel more truly says, the causes and effects are simultaneous. If a bar of antimony and bismuth, in contact, be heated, a current of electricity is said to be produced ; yet if a fine wire be introduced between the extremities, the wire becomes heated, and no electricity is manifested. Is the heat a cause of electricity in the metals, and this electricity a cause of heat in the wire ? Which is cause, and which effect ? Both or neither. Again : bring a magnet within a certain distance of a needle and the needle rushes towards it. Here the magnet is said to produce motion by its attraction, which is the cause — antecedent — of the effect. Our minds demand such artifices : we abstract one detail from a complex description, that is, we abstract the attrac- tion and view it by itself, considering it as the cause or antecedent of the motion which succeeds it in our conception ; and similarly we abstract the motion, viewing it by itself, and consider it as the effect, or consequent of the attraction. But however indispensable, such language is merely an artifice. No separation actually exists. There is not first attraction, and subsequently motion ; the two are simultaneous. In like manner, we say the earth's attraction causes the weight of the apple ; but the weight is the attraction : they are two aspects of one unknown reality. § 74 a. Although admitting the utility of the word Cause, thus explained, Science disclaims all attempts to penetrate the secrets of causation. It seeks only the phenomenal and relative. It recognizes the constant presence of the Un- 92 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. knowable, as something real though inaccessible ; but while admitting the mystery it makes no effort to transcend the already vast limits of the Knowable. So readily does it restrict itself within the relative and phenomenal that it accepts hypotheses which are themselves unverifiable and which even seem absurd if in any way they facilitate the more accurate co-ordination of facts. This is a paradox ; but it is significant. The first person who grasped its significance I believe to be Copernicus. In the preface to his immortal work he says of the heliocentric hypothesis, " It is by no means necessary that hypotheses should be true, nor even seem true, it is enough if they reconcile calculation with observation." 15 The hypotheses of geometry are manifestly of this kind ; no one believes in the existence or possibility of a line without breadth. The hypotheses of atoms, and of an attractive force inherent in molecules, are beyond all reach of proof. They are metaphysical ideas, and find a place in Science simply because they facilitate calculations and the exposition of facts. The metaphysical Method would employ them as bases for the deduction of facts, would argue from them as if their nature were known and their truth indisputable. But Science, which concerns itself only with facts and their observed order, in its indifference to the undiscoverable nexus binding the facts into this order, allows any hypothesis respecting that nexus, pro- vided some convenience of colligation or exposition belongs to it. Nay it even adopts contradictory hypotheses when they suit convenience. For example, we adopt the hypothesis that the gravity of bodies above the superficies of the earth is inversely as the squares of their distances from the earth's centre. It is because this hypothesis reconciles calculation 15 Copernicus : De Revolutionibus Orbium cvelestium. " Neque enim necesse est eas hypotheses esse veras, imo ne verisimile quidem, sed sufficit hoc unum, si calculum obsei'vationibus congruentem cxhibeant." I do not remember where I found this striking passage. To a similar effect, though less explicit, Descabtbs : Principia, pars IV., § 1 and 204. CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 93 with observation that we accept it, knowing all the while that the absolute relation may possibly be different. But in the theorem of falling bodies we adopt a contradictory hypothesis, that is, we assume the action of gravity to be the same at all distances ; because the heights to which bodies can be carried above the surface of the earth are so trifling compared with the length of the earth's semi-diameter, as to be disregarded in our calculation. If we never had occasion to pass beyond ter- restrial phenomena this theorem would perfectly satisfy all our needs ; yet we know that it is false ; but it has the relative truth demanded for our purposes; and we have no better assurance of the truth of universal attraction. So indifferent is Science to the absolute truth of ideas ; so anxious about their relative truth ! The reverse is the case with Meta- physics. It cannot be indifferent to absolute truth; if its ideas are false, all deductions drawn from them are vitiated. See the contrast in an example : whether comets be said to make their appearance in consequence of the anger of a deity, or in consequence of the law of gravitation, the explanation in either case rests on the assumption of an ultimate cause acting in the manner described; but in the one case the truth of the assumption is all important, in the other it is indifferent. Unless the anger of a deity be actually in opera- tion, the first explanation is wholly irrelevant and must lead to irrelevant conclusions; but the second explanation pre- serves all its value provided that the path of the comet be observed to be precisely the curve which accords with the assumption of a gravitating force. Let this curve be verified, according to the known law, and we are supremely indifferent respecting the truth or error of our ideas as to the force of which the law is known. How clearly Newton saw this appears in the following declaration : "What I call attraction may be performed by impulse, or by some other means un- known to me. I use that word here to signify only in general my force by which bodies tend towards one another, whatever 94 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. be the cause." In truth the cause is in itself unknowable, and it is solely the law of its action with which Science is concerned. Given the law — i.e. the verifiable statement of the observed order — and the cause is known in all the fulness possible or desirable for human needs. Suppose that an angel were discovered in the centre of the sun drawing the planets ; this discovery would at once displace our hypothesis of attractive force inherent in the molecules of matter; but it would make no alteration in our formula of the law; the drawing would still take place with an inverse quadratic power, and all our calculations would remain unshaken. A new band would tie our facts together, but the facts would present an unchanged order. § 74 b. One other aspect of causation, rarely appreciated, remains to be noticed. While it is important to understand that causes — in the metaphysical sense — cannot be known, and that all inquiry into their ultimate nature is waste of ingenuity, not less important is it to understand that our limitations in this direction are no greater than those placed by our necessary ignorance of matter, and of all noumena. All knowledge is phenomenal. Apart from the phenomena, we know no more of Matter than we know of Force. But phenomena we know ; and we are also said to know their laws, when we have rigorously ascertained the exact order of their co-existence and sequence. Observing falling bodies with the requisite precision, we find that the space fallen through is invariably proportional to the square of the time. This is a law ; and other laws are known as accurately as the properties of the bodies themselves. But we are not content with these laws ; we desire to know the cause. What is it which forces bodies to fall, and to fall in this order? We name it the force of gravity ; but the name brings no exten- sion of knowledge. In itself the cause remains unknown; but we already know it in its positive characters, or modes of action, as fully as we can know Matter. Both Force and CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 95 Matter are abstractions. They stand on similar ground : as essences equally inaccessible, as phenomena equally acces- sible. Considered solely in reference to falling bodies, the general fact (law), that they fall through spaces proportional to the squares of the times, gains no additional illumination from an ascription of the cause, since all we know of this cause is the law of its action. But although the cause, named gravity, is merely an abstraction, yet it enables us to class under the same head, to interpret by the same laws, many phenomena besides those of falling bodies. By this force we explain the figure of our globe and its flattened poles, the orbit of the moon, the movements of all planetary masses, the precession of the equinoxes, and the ebb and flow of the tides. Thus, although causes, or forces, are abstractions, the great and obvious advantage to philosophy of such abstractions needs not be emphasized. Their danger lies in our tendency to forget that they are introduced into our calculations solely as unknown agents acting through known laws ; a forgetful- ness which leads us to postulate more of them than has been disclosed through the laws. If once anything is assumed of Force, which has not already been verified in fact, we incur the same danger as when we assume properties in a substance which have never been recognized in it. An immense gain to philosophy, and the dissipation of an incalculable amount of vague theorizing, must result when men have firmly fixed in their minds the true conception of Force as a mere abstraction which only has reality for us through its demonstrated Laws. People will cease to talk glibly of nerve-force, vital-force, &c, in explanation of phenomena not yet reduced to law ; they will understand that only such effects as can be deduced from the known laws may be predicated of the unknown forces. Without being called upon to give up the advantages of having such abstractions as that of Force, they will escape the 96 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. danger of metaphysical reliance on such generalized expres- sions. Thus once again the principle of Verification shows itself as our firmest guide and our best consolation. Knowledge may be limited to phenomena, causes may be hidden from us, as all ultimate existence is hidden, for the ground of existence must transcend knowledge so long as Being and Knowing are not one ; but within the sphere of positive knowledge a sufficient basis may be laid, resting on three separate stages : 1st, the observation of phenomena (facts) ; 2nd, the observation of their order of co-existence and suc- cession (laws) ; 3rd, the determination of the abstract forces from which the order results as a calculable consequent (causes). § 74 c. In the foregoing section no notice has been taken of the great question mooted in philosophy respecting the existence of Force as an Entity independent of Matter ; for in truth whether we believe in two distinct existences (Force an Ens, and Matter an Ens), or believe that Force is only the abstract expression for the dynamical relations of Matter (§72 a), in either case the principles are equally valid; since the realist must admit that Force can only be in- vestigated in its positive characters, or laws ; and the nominalist holds that beyond these laws there is nothing to investigate. In each case the limitation to phenomena imperatively calls for Verification and condemns Meta- physics. § 75. Metaphysics is the co-ordination of unverified facts. Science is the co-ordination of verified facts. That confirma- tion which the one sees in Logic, the other sees in Observa- tion. The metaphysical tendency is the spontaneous tendency ; the scientific caution is an acquired caution. Hence not only is the metaphysical tendency active in all the early epochs of speculation, both of the race and the individual, but is with great difficulty repressed even in the highly-trained CHAP. IV.] AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 97 intellect of an advanced period. It may be traced in the speculations of philosophers whom we should never think of classing among metaphysicians. Lamarck abounds in illustrations. For instance, he argues that a Polype cannot have Sensibility, because that "would be contrary to the laws of organization, and to the plan which Nature is obliged to follow in all her works." l6 No ancient speculator was ever more adventurous; to deduce a fact from the idea of "a plan which nature is obliged to follow," in lieu of ascer- taining what the fact is, what plan she does follow, is pure metaphysics. Elsewhere he explains the variety in organisms as due to two causes : one of these is the metaphysical pouvoir propre de la vie, which tends incessantly to form complex organisms, and to perfect them ; the other is the modifying influence of external circumstances. 17 Nay, even Newton, the exalted type of the scientific intellect, occasionally yields to the metaphysical tendency, as may be seen in his account of the Vis Inertia, or in the following query at the close of the Optics : 1B " It seems probable to me that God in the beginning formed matter in solid, massy, hard, impenetrable, moveable particles, of such size and figures, and with such properties and in such proportions to space, as most conduced to the end for which He formed them; and that the primitive particles being solids are incomparably harder than any porous bodies com- pounded of them, even so very hard as never to wear or break in pieces : no ordinary power being able to divide what God made one in the first creation." It is noticeable how Newton, with his usual caution, advances this as what to him seems probable ; an ancient would have advanced it as a fact beyond dispute. Yet why probable ? "What proof can there be, except such metaphysical proof as is to be found in the easiest 16 Lamarck : Histoire des Animaux sans Vertebres, Paris, 1835, 1., 105. "Ibid., I., 114. 18 Newton : Works, ed. Hoksley, 1782, IV., 260. 98 THE METAPHYSICAL [CHAP. IV. mode of conceiving an order of things wholly removed from any possible knowledge ? Newton's query is, however, simply an hypothesis, and is made to prove nothing. This cannot he said of many hypotheses now current, especially those in what Berzelius sarcastically calls the " physiology of probabilities." No one who scrutinizes the science of our day can fail to perceive how ready men still are to accept phrases for explanations, and guesses for facts. Long before these pages are yellow with age, men will have learned to look upon much that is now taught in the schools respecting the oxidation of the tissues, and the like, with a pity akin to that which is bestowed on the physiology of Aristotle or Van Helmont. It will then be noted that this explanation — the oxidation of tissues — was presented without the guarantee of a single direct observation, that it was based on inferences, none of which were verified, and that it was a phrase used to cloak our ignorance, much as the " nervous fluid " was used a few years ago. 19 § 76. Let it be noted, on the other hand, that many objec- tions are raised against ideas and expressions, which though metaphysical are perfectly justifiable. For example, Laplace in stating the first law of motion says that a body at rest does not contain within itself any reason for moving in one direc- tion rather than in another. 20 This seems to Auguste Comte a metaphysical, and therefore vicious, conception, 21 the prin- ciple of " sufficient reason " being odious to him. How, he asks, could we be assured that " there was no reason " for the deviation ? what can we know of it except from experience ? In this criticism, it seems to me that his antagonism against 10 Cuvier said he could not believe in the existence of a fluid which no one had demonstrated j instead of acknowledging the propriety of this caution, Lamarck scornfully retorted that, on similar grounds, physicists would be forced to abandon the magnetic fluid (Hist, des Animaux sans Vertebres, I., 189). Not long afterwards they did abandon it. 10 Laplace: Exposition du Systeme du Monde, 6th ed., 1836, 1., 275. 21 Comte: Cours de Philosophie Positive, 1830, 1., 557. CHAP. IV. 1 AND SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 99 metaphysics has led him too far. If we replace the word "reason" by the word "condition," the formula will run thus, " a body remains at rest, because there is no condition present which would cause it to move ; " and such a formula is every way unexceptionable. If we are asked how we can be assured of this, we reply, The axiom of general causation, founded on universal experience, assures us that no change can take place unless the conditions of change be present. I cannot agree in the assertion that "all these pretended explanations resolve themselves into nothing but repeating in abstract terms the very fact itself, and saying that bodies have a natural tendency to move in a right line, which was precisely the proposition to be proved." What is here called the fact itself is never a matter of experience; there are no motions in a straight line absolutely perceived by us ; the "natural tendency" is an abstraction, an idea, guaranteed by observation and calculation (§ 62), but deduced a priori from the law of causation. The " principle of sufficient reason " fulfils all the requisites of the a priori method. It conforms to the Ideal Test, namely, that its negation is inconceivable, or absurd. Whereas the principle of "per- fection" by which Aeistotle infers that all movements are naturally circular — a principle by Comte placed on a level with that of the " sufficient reason " — does not conform to this test. We can as readily conceive its negation as its affirmation; in other words, the laws of thought, which represent universal experience, do not force' us to conceive undisturbed motion as circular, but they do force us to con- ceive it as uniform and rectilinear. I have thus endeavoured to make clear the characteristics and defects of the Metaphysical Method in contrast with the characteristics of the Scientific Method, and shall have frequent opportunities. in the course of this History of invoking and illustrating what may be called the supreme law of all research —the principle of Verification. No one familiar T^h History 7^2 100 THE TWO METHODS. [CHAP. IV. will consider that too much importance is here assigned to Method ; few will consider that its true characteristics have hitherto been adequately expounded even by those who have specially treated of it. The principles of Inductive and Syllogistic Logic have indeed been amply expounded ; but the supreme law (with its two criteria, Ideal and Real), has been taken for granted, rather than articulately expressed, and has very often been wholly overlooked. Hence the iterated in- sistance on it in these pages, "car les hommes ont encore plus besoin de m^thode que de doctrine, d'^ducation que destruction." 22 22 Comte : Cours de Pkilosophie Positive, 1835, II., 225. ( 101 ) CHAPTEE V. PLATO'S METHOD. § 77. Having chosen Aristotle as the representative of Ancient Science, it is unnecessary for me to expound the doc- trines of his various precursors ; yet on many accounts it is desirable to sketch the outlines of the Method adopted by his great master and rival Plato, indicating how far it was meta- physical, and how far scientific j not only that we may thereby gain clearer insight into the condition of ancient thought, but also that we may be more just to the Stagirite, by esti- mating the kind of science which satisfied the mind of his illustrious teacher. The name of Plato is still surrounded witn the respect due to a great genius and a great renown. It is true that this respect often degenerates into servility, because here, as else- where, the admiration of the few becomes the exaggeration of the many, and genuine enthusiasm is echoed in loud lip- homage. But no amount of exaggeration, or of insincerity, ought to make us unjust to the noble faculties which inspired these excesses. I do not myself pretend to share the sym- pathy and admiration for Plato's philosophy, which has un- doubtedly been felt in all ages by many wise and beautiful souls. He had great qualities, and has greatly influenced men; but our admiration for his dramatic power, dialectical 102 PLATO'S METHOD. [CHAP. V. skill, and moral elevation ought not to blind us to the defects of his teaching, and above all to the disastrous tendency of his method. A general estimate of Plato is not within the scope and purpose of this History ; and in the present chapter we have to consider him solely with reference to Science ; an aspect, it must be confessed, in which he is seen to great disadvantage. § 78. In the Phcedo he has sketched the history of his studies. He tells us how in youth he was eager to learn all about the causes of things, but found to his disappointment that his efforts left him no wiser. One day he heard a person reading from a book of Anaxagoeas, in which it was declared that " Mind was the cause and orderer of all things." This filled him with delight. He at once accepted its truth. " And I considered with myself that Mind orders all things and disposes each as it will be best for it. If any one, then, desire to discover the cause of any phenomenon, how it is produced, and how it perishes, he must ascertain in what way it is best for it to exist or act. From this it follows that a man should consider only what is most excellent and best." With such a clue to the mysteries of nature Anaxagoeas, he thought, could enlighten him not only as to whether the earth were flat or globular, but also as to the cause of its being so, showing that it is better for it to be what it is ; and, " if he should say it is in the centre, he would explain why it is better in the centre." To his great disappointment, he found Anaxagohas adducing simple physical reasons, instead of the teleological reasons which he had expected. Such a teacher could no longer allure him. A new course opened. Wearied with contemplating things as they are, he bethought him that men in studying an eclipse of the sun look at its image reflected in the water, lest they should become blind by gazing directly at the sun. " It seemed to me, therefore, that I ought to have recourse to reasons, and in them to contemplate the truth of things. Thus always adducing the reason which CBfAP. V.] PLATO'S METHOD. 103 I judge to be strongest, I pronouce that to be true which appears to me to accord with it ; those which .do not accord with it I deny to be true." 1 In this frank avowal of the Subjective Method he takes no precautions and offers no guarantee for the solidity of the grounds upon which he judges one reason to be stronger than another. Between the caprices of imagination and the rigours of demonstration he offers no criterion. And the disastrous consequences of this oversight are visible in every page of the Timmus, where the idea of a Best, to which Nature is made to conform, leads him into extravagances such as would be incredible unless their origin were known. § 79. Above the world of fleeting phenomena, he conceived a world of permanent existences. These were Ideas. With these, and these only, was Science properly concerned. The visible phenomena are diagrams for the convenience of reason. The great value of Science consists in its withdrawal of the soul from the contemplation of phenomena, and its insistance on the contemplation of pure essences. " If geometry com- pels the soul to contemplate real existence it does concern us ; but if it only forces the changeful and perishing upon our notice it does not concern us. . . . Science is pursued solely for the sake of knowledge." 2 He ridicules the notion of Astronomy, as practised by astronomers, being capable of making the soul look upwards ; and says it positively makes the soul look downwards. " I 1 Plato : Phtsedo, p. 90, ed. Bekker, Berlin, 1817: 'i$o%e St) poi XPV VCCI tl S t6vq \6yovg Kuratpvyovra Iv ikuvoiq gkottuv tSjv ovtidv tt)v akifiuav .... Kai vTrodtjiivos kicaoTOTE Aoyov '6v av Kpivui i^piniuvkaraTOV clvai, a fdv av pot SoKy Toi>T<$ %vitfojviiv TiQrifii a>£ AXrjdrj ovtcl . . . & S'dv /it), a>g oiiK a\r)9fj. He overlooks the fact so felicitously expressed by Bacon that the mind may be an unequal mirror to the rays of things—" instar speculi inasijualis ad radios rerum, qui suam naturam naturae rerum immiseet, eamque distorquet et inficit." 2 Plato : Republic. Translated by Davies and Vaughan, Cambridge, 1852. One of the rare translations from the Greek which may be used with confidence. 104 PLATO'S METHOD. [CHAP. V. cannot conceive that any science makes the soul look upwards unless it has to do with the real and invisible. It makes no difference whether a person stares stupidly at the sky, or looks with half-shut eyes upon the ground ; so long as he is trying to study any sensible object I deny that he can be said to have learned anything, because no object of sense admits of scientific treatment. Since this fretted sky is still a part of the visible world we are bound to regard it, though the most beautiful of visible things, as far inferior, nevertheless, to those true revolutions which real velocity and real slowness, existing in true number and in all true forms, accomplish relatively to each other, carrying with them all that they contain : which are verily apprehended by reason and thought, but not by sight. Therefore we must employ that fretted sky as a pattern or plan to forward the study which aims at those higher objects." Further on, he says, " Whenever a person strives by the help of Dialectics to start in pursuit of every reality by a simple process of reason independent of all sensuous informa- tion, never flinching until by an act of pure intelligence he has grasped the real nature of good, he arrives at the very end of the intellectual world." There is more of the same kind in this 7th book of the Republic, but no more need be cited here. § 80. Let us now glance at a few of the results to which this Method led him. We open the Timceus, and learn that the Universe was generated as an animal, with a soul, because that was best. 3 Whatever is generated must necessarily have body, and be visible no less than tangible. Nothing can be visible without Fire, nothing tangible without a Solid, nothing solid without Earth. Thus the first step in creation was the production of two elements. But it is impossible for two things to cohere without the intervention of a third. A bond 1 Plato : Timaus, ed. Bek., p. 27. CHAP. V.] PLATO'S METHOD. 105 is necessary, and of all bonds the most beautiful is that which as nearly as possible unites into one both itself and the things bound. 4 Had the substance of the universe been a superficies without depth, one medium or bond would have sufficed ; but as it was a solid, and solids are never one only, but always joined by two bonds, therefore the Creator placed Water and Air between Fire and Earth. These are the Four Elements, and the reason has been given why they are only four. The elements are fashioned into a perfect sphere, because the sphere is the most perfect of figures, and most resembles itself. Although this universe was made an animal, it was made becoming and congruous ; hence it had neither eyes nor ears, there being nothing external for it to see and hear ; no lungs, for it needed not respiration ; no digestive organs ; no secretory organs ; no feet, for its motion is peculiar, namely, circular, and circular motion requires no feet, since it is not progression. § 81. The mathematicians having discovered the five regular solids, Plato naturally made great use of them in his cosmology. Four of them were represented by the four elements — the Earth was a Cube, Fire a Tetrahedron, Water an Octahedron, and Air an Icosahedron. This left the fifth, the Dodecahedron, without a representative, accordingly it was assigned to the universe as a whole. The Creator, having thus shaped the visible universe, and distributed souls over the earth, the moon, and other unnamed places, — and having commissioned the younger gods (dii minores) to construct man, — retired to his repose. It is needless to add that Plato never thinks of offering any better reason for these propositions than that they are by him judged sufficient. If one of his hearers had asked him why water might not be a cube, and air an octahedron — or 4 deapGiv 8k KaMtoroc 8$ av avrov Kal to. ZvpSoifteva on fuxkurra iv icovg. 106 PLATO'S METHOD. [CHAP. V. what proof there was of either being one or the other — he would have replied : " It is thus I conceive it. This is best." § 82. Let us proceed. The universe, we learn, has a soul which moves in perpetual circles. Man also has a soul which is but a portion thereof, consequently it also moves in circles. To make the resemblance more complete, man's soul is also enclosed in a spherical body — namely the head. But the gods foresaw that this head, being spherical, would roll down the hills and could not ascend steep places ; to prevent this, a body with limbs was added, that it might be a loco- motive for the head. And as the foreparts are more honour- able and regal than the hind parts, the gods made man's locomotion chiefly progressive. § 83. As may be anticipated, the anatomical and physio- logical conclusions to which such a Method leads are not in strict agreement with inductive science. Thus we find the liver described 3 as " compact and smooth, shining and sweet, though somewhat bitter ; and the reason is that the thoughts falling on it from the intellect, as on a mirror, might terrify it by employing a bitterness akin to its nature ; and threaten- ingly mingle this bitterness with the whole liver, so as to give it the black colour of bile; or, when images of a different kind are reflected, sweetening its bitterness, and giving peace to that part of the soul which lies near the liver, giving it rest at night, with the power of divination in dreams. Although the liver was constructed for divination, it is only during life that its predictions are clear ; after death its oracles become obscure, for it becomes blind." Even more surprising is the description of the intestines. They are, he says, on the left side for the purpose of acting like a sponge to keep the surface of the liver bright and clear, and capable of reflecting the images of the soul. § 84. In a modern such ideas would not appear profound. ' Op. cit., p. 100. CHAP. V.] ; PLATO'S METHOD. 107 I have not cited them for % the poor pleasure of holding up a great name in the light of ridicule ; but to show how even a great intellect may unsuspectingly wander into absurdities, when it quits the "firm though laborious path of inductive inquiry. " The dove cleaving the thin air," to use the happy illustra- tion of Kant, " and feeling its resistance, might suppose that in airless space her movements would be more rapid. Pre- cisely in this way Plato thought that by abandoning the sensuous world, because of the limits it placed to his under- standing, he might more successfully venture into the void space of pure intellect." 6 It is not in Science only that Plato is misled by his Method. The same confidence in deduction from unverified premisses vitiates his teaching in every other department of inquiry, moral and political; but in Science his errors are more patent, because his statements admit of a readier, and less equivocal, confrontation with fact. 6 Kant : Kritih. Einleitung, § III., 1790, p. 8. ( 108 ) CHAPTER VI. ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. § 85. The contrast between the Master and the Pupil is no- where more emphatic than in Method. Aristotle may he truly styled the father of the Inductive Philosophy, since he first announced its leading principles ; and announced them with a completeness and precision not surpassed by Bacon himself. There is, indeed, a radical defect in his conception of Method, but it is a defect not less visible in the Novum Organwm, and is common to all the systematic expositions of Method that have yet been published. This defect is the absence of the due recognition of Verification. All writers implicitly recognize Verification as the inseparable attendant of Observation, Induction, and Deduction ; but they do not explicitly, and emphatically, assign to it the primary import- ance it should have ; they do not trace in its neglect the cause of every failure. Overlooking this defect, men have expressed surprise at the unquestionable fact that Aeistotle and Bacon failed egregiously in scientific research, in spite of their i conception of scientific Method; and this failure has some-' times been made a ground for denying the value claimed for! Method. But the seeming contradiction disappears on close examination. The failure is then traced to a radical imperfec- tion in the Method. A discrepancy is disclosed between the principles which Aristotle and Bacon implicitly taught, and the principles they actually employed. CJ5AP. VI.] ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. 109 § 86. We will first inquire what those principles were. In direct opposition to Plato, who, denying the validity of the senses, made intuitions the ground of all true knowledge, Aristotle sought his basis in sensuous perception. Antici- pating Bacon, he affirmed that it was wiser to dissect the "complex phenomena of sense than to resolve them into abstractions — "melius est naturam secare quam abstrahere." * His reliance was on Experience and Induction : the one furnishing the particular facts, from which the other found a pathway to general facts— or laws. 2 "Without sensation thought is impossible. 3 Plato held that the deceptions of sense justified scepticism of all sense-knowledge (airarris jUEffTj) fi Bia rwv ofi/j,a.TO)v aKsxpig). Aristotle, more correctly, taught that error did not arise from the senses being false media, but from the wrong interpretations we put on their testimony. Manifold deceptions may thence arise ; but each sense speaks truly so far as it speaks at all. 4 It is from sense we gain the knowledge of particulars. It is from Induction we gain the knowledge of universals. Agreeing with Plato that Science is only concerned with universals, he affirmed that these could only be reached through Experience. § 87. This is the corner-stone of the experience-philo- sophy or " Empiricism," so often urged as a reproach against Aristotle. 5 Hegel boldly denies the charge. Science regards the accusation as an eulogy. Unhappily, even by Aristotle, experience was too frequently neglected and too carelessly in- terrogated. The vigilance of scientific scepticism was wanting. Yet at times he seems thoroughly impressed with the necessity 1 Bacon: Nov. Org., 41. 8 kirayiayri Srj r) d.irb twv KaQkicaara kiri ra Kadokov ItpoSog. Topic, L, 10. See also Anal. Post. I., 31 ; Hist. Animal. I., 6. 3 ovSk vou 6 vovq ra Ikto£ pr) per ala8r]iTeo)Q ovra. Be Sensu, VL, 445 ; Be Anima, III., 8, 432. 4 Be Anima, III., 3; Metaph., TV., 5; and elsewhere. s Even so late as Schleieemaokeb, who urges it in his History of Philosophy. 110 ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. [CHAP. VI. of securing his basis before attempting to build. " Let us first understand the facts, and then we may seek for their causes." 6 There are many passages in which he distinctly disapproves of the fatal tendency to eke out deficiencies of observation by mere guesses, and to rely on those guesses as on observations. Of such passages four may here be given : — I. Speaking of the parthenogenesis of bees, he says, " There are not facts enough to warrant a conclusion, and more dependence must be placed on facts than on reasonings, which must agree with facts." r »#^ II. Speaking of Hybridity, after noticing*- the opinions of his predecessors, and even suggesting an a priori argument himself, he says, "But such a proof is far too abstract and empty (/c6V(>e). For reasons not drawn from the inherent principles of things (rdiv oikeiojv ap-^uiv) are empty, and only seem to explain them, just as only those are geometrical proofs which are deduced from geometrical principles ; so also in all other sciences. The empty argument seems potent, but is powerless." 8 III. Speaking of those who held a certain astronomical view, he says, they did so because their thoughts were not directed to the phenomena and the discovery of the causes, but they endeavoured to make the phenomena correspond with their opinions. 9 And still more strongly in this passage : " These philosophers, treating of phenomena, say things which by no means correspond with the phenomena, the cause of this being that they have not rightly conceived first principles, but reduce everything to certain prescribed notions (irpog rivag $o£o.q dipi(T / u£i>ae) , and they persist in these in spite of all contra- diction, as if they were in possession of true principles, as if these ought not rather to be educed from the phenomena." 10 6 De Part, I., 1, 639. 7 De Gener. Animal, III., 10, 760. 8 Ibid., II., 8, 748. 9 De Casio, II., 13, 293. Compare also ibid., p. 294. 10 Ibid., IH.,1, 306. CHAP. VI.] ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. HI IV. " The reason why men do not sufficiently attend to the facts is their want of experience. Hence those accustomed to physical inquiries are more competent to lay down the principles which have an extensive application; whereas others who have been accustomed to many assumptions without the confrontation of reality, easily lay down principles, because they take few things into consideration. It is easy to distinguish those who argue from facts and those who argue from notions." u § 88. Instea^gf distrusting knowledge derived through the senses, and-^lacing unhesitating reliance on knowledge derived from intuitions, he declared that ideas are nothing but the products of reason. Eeason separates, by abstraction, the particular objects from their general relations, i. e. those relations which these objects have in common. Anticipating modern Psychology, he taught, confusedly indeed, and not always consistently, that intelligence is a late development. The understanding is built up from sensuous materials. Each particular sensation gives rise to a sensuous state, and the permanence of this state is Memory. From memory arise, first, distinctions ; and finally, after many repetitions, experi- ence ; from experience a pathway leads to Science, that path- way being Induction. Plato taught that all knowledge was reminiscence — a revival of pre-existent Ideas. From any one Idea we can arrive at all others, owing to the logical connexion existing between them. In direct contradiction to this, Aristotle maintained that complete knowledge could only arise out of complete experience ; and he significantly points out the danger of the Platonic Method, which neglects facts, and rashly concludes a general proposition from a few par- ticulars. 12 § 89. In indicating the way we are to arrive at general 11 De Gen. et Corr., I., 2, 316. Compare also De Partibus, IV., 5, 679. 12 De Gen. et Corr., I., 2. 112 ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. [CHAP. VI. truths, he expresses himself with a precision unsurpassed by moderns. " We must not," he says, " accept a general principle from logic only, but must prove its application to each fact, for it is in facts that we must seek general prin- ciples, and these must always accord with the facts." 13 Nor, while thus insisting on Observation, was he wholly without a perception of the value of that aid to inquiry, which is usually supposed to be a modern invention, I mean Experiment. He did not, indeed, see its importance as moderns have seen it ; for, not rightly apprehending the necessity of Verification, he failed to apprehend the true purpose of Experiment, which is simply a means of verifying the accuracy of data, and conclu- sions hypothetical or theoretical. But he refers to it, and even to vivisection, often enough to mislead a modem wor- shipper into the belief that this great instrument of scientific research was distinctly recognized by him. Here are a few of the passages I have noticed. 14 He refers to the experiment of tying or removing the right testis of the male, previous to congress, in disproof of the hypothesis that the sexes are derived from the right and left testes. 15 He refers to the experiment of removing the eyes from young birds, to show that these organs are capable of being reproduced, a capability not observed in adult birds. 16 Although he places the seat of motive power in the heart, yet he refers to the experiment of removing the heart from tortoises, after which they still continue for some time to move ; 17 and to prove that the nutritive soul is contained in the centre, he refers to the insects whose heads and limbs 13 De Animal, motione, I., 698. Aci Sh tovto /u) povov 7-<£ \6yip Ka86\ov \afSitv, dXKa Kal iirl t&v KaOsKaara Kal tSiv aiaBrjrwv, Si dVtp Kal roie kcc96\ov faroi/iev \6yovg, Kal krneld as a mere thread, which for convenience sake may tie the facts together until a better be discovered. It must never form a basis of deduc- tion. This Aristotle did not distinctly understand, although he is said to have invented the theory of proof. Let us see what that theory was. § 92. Science is the co-ordination of facts (§ 64), the reduction of particular facts to general facts. " As this can only take place through an induction of universals from particulars, proof must first lie in the correctness of the induction; and when these universals have been attained, and a deduction is made from them to some new particulars, proof lies in the correctness of this deduction. There is, however, an initial difficulty : all knowledge rests upon ante- cedent knowledge. We see this in induction and in demon- stration; the one arriving at a conclusion from particulars already known ; the other starting from a conclusion already CHAP. VI.j ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. 115 known." Plato evades this difficulty by referring all know- ledge to reminiscence. This explanation Aristotle rejects. He affirms that demonstration rests upon universals which are in their nature better known 19 (or, let us say, more cer- tainly apprehended) ; whereas induction rests on particulars, which are better known to us. The basis of Science is therefore an Inductive Syllogism. It is necessary to appreciate clearly this distinction between knowledge of universals and knowledge of particulars. He affirms that, although sensation is the origin of all knowledge, the first ideas awakened in the soul consist of general ideas. Thus a man seeing a body at a distance has at first only the general idea of substance ; on approaching nearer, and observing that it moves spontaneously, he has the less general idea of an animal. On approaching still nearer, he recognizes the kind of animal, by recognizing many of the particulars which distinguish it as kind ; and he thus gains a particular idea, in lieu of his first general idea. In this way the mind advances from the universal to the particular. The infant at first calls every man papa, and every woman mamma; afterwards it learns to discriminate individuals. The fallacy here is patent. It confounds an indefinite with a generalized conception. It is a fallacy which leavens ancient speculation. § 93. Since proof rests on universals, perception, which is concerned only with particulars, can give no science. Nay, if we could perceive that a triangle has the sum of its angles equal to two right angles, we should still be forced to seek for a proof of it (IforoujUEv av airoSti^iv), otherwise we should have no knowledge of it. 19 This very important distinction in his philosophy was completely misun- derstood by the schoolmen, who, as Mr. Ellis pointed out, were misled by- the ambiguity of the Greek dative, notius naturd, to suppose that notius natura was meant, as if Aristotle contrasted Nature's knowledge with our own. Bacon fell into this error : Works by Ellis and Spedding, 1857, 1., 137. The same mistake is made by Roger Bacon : Opus Majus, Venet., 1750, p. 46. 8—2 116 ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. [CHAP. VI. If the question be asked why we must seek this proof of what has already been perceived, Aristotle answers : "Because only particulars can be perceived, and science is of universals." In another work (for hitherto I have been drawing from the Analytics), he judiciously remarks that it is absurd to seek for a proof of that which is clearly known, and for which all the conditions of a correct perception are present. 20 But even the universal must be obtained through induction from perceptions. He says that if we were in the moon, and the earth, coming between us and the sun, deprived us of light, we should have no knowledge of the cause of darkness ; we should see that the moon was dark, but not why it was dark. It is true that, from frequent observation, we might find out the cause by detecting the universal ; since out of numerous particulars the universal becomes evident (e/c yap tHiv KaOsKaara irXtiovwv to tcaOoXov StjXov). But, he adds, the universal has the preference, because it makes evident the cause. We do not understand a phenomenon until we can demonstrate its cause by a syllogism, showing that it necessarily follows from some general principle. Hence syllo- gism is the true scientific instrument ; and as the syllogism proceeds from the general to the particular, it must be better known in its nature than the particulars it has to prove. There is no need to enter more minutely here into Aristotle's Logic. The reader may find it analysed with great care by Biese, 21 and more briefly in most histories of philo- sophy. The foregoing paragraphs contain all that is essential as regards Method. § 94. It is clear that this conception of proof is one which inevitably tends to make investigation metaphysical and a priori. In spite of his recognition of the importance of observation and induction, he conceived universals as better 20 Phys., VIII., 3. Compare Metaph., IV., 4. 21 Biese : Die Phihsophie des Aristoteles in ihren inneren Zusammenhange, Berlin, 1835-42. CHAP. VI.] ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. 117 , r known than particulars. It was therefore inevitahle that he should practically rely on universals to the neglect of par- ticulars, care more about syllogisms than observations ; and whenever the universals (general ideas) happened to be true, the reliance was secure. Unfortunately these universals were very often false, still oftener irrelevant ; and as no criterion of their truth or relevancy was furnished by the syllogism, the reliance proved disastrous. By his theory of proof he placed the Ideal Test above the Real Test : this is metaphysical. Hence in his writings we see little of the patient circum- spection of Verification ; we see only the impatient facility of Deduction from assumptions which have not been confronted with reality. § 95. It was this which led him and all the ancients to waste so much effort in the pursuit of causes. Science was supposed to be the knowledge of causes; not the knowledge of laws, or the order of succession and co-existence, but of causes which were knowable'entities. He recognized four different kinds : the formal, or sub- stantial; the material ; the motor, or efficient ; and the final. A word of explanation on each of these may be of service. I. The formal cause, or essence, known under the scholastic titles of " quiddity " and " substantial form," is what may be called the raison d'etre of a thing. Although form cannot be disjoined from substance in fact, it can in thought, — and that was enough for the ancients. We still preserve the idea in such phrases as, the essence of good government consists in reconciling order with progress ; or, the essence of a circle consists in the equi-distance of every point in the periphery from the centre. 22 The substantial form, in short, is that a " En contemplant les choses nous voyons qu'elles sont differentes entr'elles, et que chacune a quelque chose de particulier qui la distingue des autres : c'est ce qu'on appelle Pessenee d'une chose, qu'on definit ce qui fait qu'une chose est ce qu'elle est." — S'Gkavesande : Intro, a la Philosophic, Leyden, 1737, p. 5. This is strictly Aristotelian, and explains the phrase by which Aristotle defines the formal cause:— ») ovaia icai rb n rp>' tlvai. The phrase is not gramma- 118 ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. [CHAP. VI. which makes a thing to be what it is. N.B.— The distinction between the essence of a thing and the essence of our concep- tion of a thing had not then been admitted into philosophy. II. The material cause— causa materialis—v «Xj? kqi to Woicetfuvov — is the matter itself, conceived apart from its form. Under all the varieties of things we recognize something which exists as the subject of these varieties ; for example, the sub- stance of the soul is something distinct from its phenomena. III. The motor cause — efficient cause — h apyj\ tx\q Kivi'iatwg — which plays so great a part in scholasticism, is a conception necessarily added to the two first-named causes, since these alone will not explain movement or change. But inasmuch as change is incessant, there must be some principle of change. Nature is not self-moved ; we must, therefore, assume a Prime Mover, himself immoveable. But even thus we fail to account for the phenomena of this changing universe. What is it which determines each par- ticular movement to be that and not another ? What is it which causes the harmony, regularity and beauty of the world ? Obviously a fourth cause : — ■ IV. The final cause — to o5 ivaca Kai rayadov. This gives to every movement an aim, and a benevolent aim. The good of each and the good of all is the final cause of every change. 23 tically explicable. See Trendelenberg's edition of the De Anima, 1833, pp. 192-471 ; or Zeller: Pliilosophie der Griechen, 1860,11., 147. 23 " Finis vero est, quo res tendit. Finium alii praeoptati, alii consequentes. Prseoptati ejus generis sunt, ut valitudo qua? medicamentis et deambulatione comparatur. Consequentes vero ejus generis sunt, ut medicatio et deambulatio: primum enim valetudinem, doinde ea quse valitudini faeiunt quserimus." — Hermolaos Barbarus : Compendium scientice naturalis ex Aristotele, 1547, Lib. I., p. 6. I cannot quote from this once renowned and now forgotten scholar, without remarking that, although he occupies a prominent place in the correspondence of scholars during the latter part of the 15th century, and was thought by Erasmbs to be a " divine man," whose name could never die, he has so completely passed out of sight that most Encyclopaedias and Biographical Dictionaries do not. even mention him. The notices in Tirabosohi: Storia delta Litt. ItaL, 1807, VI. ; in HeerenT Gesehichte der classischen Litteratur CHAP. VI.] AKISTOTLE'S METHOD. 119 § 96. It is apparent, on the most casual inspection, that no one of these causes can be verifiable ; no one of them is susceptible of any stronger guarantee than that of a certain logical concordance in the assumptions we make respecting them ; but inasmuch as they pass beyond the sphere of ideas, and claim to represent external realities, the Eeal Test is indis- pensable; yet it cannot be applied. Such conceptions are, therefore, utterly unscientific. Nevertheless the slow evolu- tion of Science has not altogether disengaged itself from their trammels. Even in the present day there are not wanting men of eminence who firmly uphold the validity of final causes, and believe teleological argument to be an instrument of research. This is owing to the lingering influence of the Subjective Method, and is seldom met with in astronomy, physics, or chemistry. The Objective Method teaches that it is idle to assign a final cause, unless we believe that we have, or can have, authoritative knowledge of what actually were the Creator's intentions ; and such knowledge Science modestly disclaims. It endeavours to co-ordinate facts ; assumptions respecting the intentions of the Creator are not verifiable ; if we accept them as we accept other transcendental conceptions, they can only be an unknown quantity in our calculation. The futility of the teleological argument may be seen in this, that until we have discovered the law of succession, until the facts are co-ordinated, the assumption of a final cause brings with it no illumination ; and when the law has been discovered, the addition of the final cause brings no increase of knowledge. § 97. By the imperfection of his Method, no less than by the condition of culture at the time, Aristotle was, therefore, practically a metaphysician, assuming, without misgiving, the im Mittelalter, II. (Werhe, 1821-8, V.); and in Corniani : / secoli della Litt. Itoi., 1818, III., are all obviously at second hand, drawn probably from that marvellous torso of Italian erudition, Mazzuchelli: Gli scrittori cT Italia, 1758, vol. II., parte I., 256. A good account of him is given in Johnson : Life of Linacre, 1835. Scaligek speaks of him as " incomparabilis doctrinae, divinas probitatis." — Contra Cardanum, 1557, Exerc. clvii. 120 ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. [CHAP. VI. validity of all principles that were clear and logically consistent, no matter if they were merely verbal propositions, wholly without correspondence in fact. He argued from these prin- ciples, and only scrutinized the logical dependence of his deduction, instead of scrutinizing the principles themselves, and the verification of his conclusions. Thus, from the assumption that the circle is the most perfect form, he deduced the conclusion that the motion of the planets must be circular. From the assumption that the centre is the " noblest place," he deduced the conclusion that the heart, being central, must be the seat of the noblest faculty — the soul. And in this path his disciples unhesitatingly followed. Although History is bound to record the disastrous results which issued from the imperfect conception and imperfect practice of the Objective Method, not less is it bound to testify to the greatness of the revolution which that Method inaugurated. Aristotle's claim to our veneration is that he produced an organon of science. It was a gigantic creation ; and for centuries was regarded as the perfect organon. This book it was which opened the subject, and which for centuries was thought to have closed it. We, instructed by a fuller wisdom, may point out its deficiencies, and perceive how they hampered as much as they aided true investigation. The errors and excesses of his followers threw strong light on his defects. But we must not suffer these defects to obscure the real greatness of his achievement. His noblest title is that of Father of the Inductive Method. He first made men aware of the paramount importance of Fact, and taught them to seek explanations of phenomena on the Objective Method. His followers were fascinated by his defects. Hence the revival of Science was accompanied by the most energetic protests against Aristotelianism, as being the despotic obstacle to all true research; and Eogeb Bacon expressed a feeling which afterwards moved many minds, when he said that if he had the power he would burn all the works CHAP. VI.] ARISTOTLE'S METHOD. 121 of the Stagirite, since the study of them was not simply loss of time' but multiplication of ignorance. 24 24 Si haberem potestatem supra libros Aristotelis, ego facerem omnes cremari ; quia non est nisi temporis amissio studere in illis, et causa erroris, et multiplicatio ignorantise. — Roger Bacon: Opus Majus, Jebb's preface, p. v. Yet in spite of this outbreak every page is studded with citations from Aristotle, of whom he everywhere speaks in the highest admiration. After writing this note I found Jourdain in his erudite work, Recherches sur les anciennes traductions latiiies d'Aristote, 1843, p. 386, giving a rational explana- tion of Roger Bacon's words: " En s'exprimant ainsi, il ne voulait sans doute pasparler des ouvrages dAristote ainsi que Jebb parait le croire, mais simplement des versions latines sur lesquelles la fonle des etudiants s'exercait." The virulent style in which Bacon speaks of these translations renders this explanation highly probable. And indeed on referring again to Jebb's preface I think this was his interpretation also, although Roger Bacon's latest biographer, Charles : Roger Bacon, sa vie, ses ouvrages, et ses doctrines, d'apres des textes ine"dits, 1861, p. 103, and Milman: History of Latin Christianity, 1855, VI., 477, have understood the passage as I have given it in the text. 122 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. CHAPTEE VII. ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. § 98. Although modern Science includes ideas not less transcendental than those included in ancient Science, and employs the a priori or deductive Method with almost equal confidence, the resemblance is only superficial. If similar ideas are invoked they are ideas reached by a different route, having a different guarantee, and occupying a different position in the system of thought. In modern science they are the highest generalities of accurate, quantitative research. Often transcending the limits of actual experience, they are always founded on experience, and are strictly conformable with all we know or can think. As abstract expressions of the observed order of nature they are liable at any moment to be displaced in favour of expressions more accurate. They serve as guides and starting-points in research. They are not believed in as absolute existences. In ancient science they were held to be absolute existences, which it was the primary object of research to find, and which, when disclosed to the imagination, required no confrontation with reality. The ancients studied phenomena to discover the realities under- lying phenomena ; the moderns study phenomena to detect the order of their co-existences and successions. § 99. It is deeply significant of the importance of Method that, although Aristotle and his followers were in the main metaphysical in their researches, they failed in their attempts to establish the transcendental ideas of Physics, not less CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 123 signally than in their attempts to discover special laws. The reason is that their Method was subjective; whereas even the laws of transcendental physics are discoverable solely by the objective Method. It is also noticeable that, although the ancients had formed the conception of the Indestructibility of Matter, they failed to take the step which now seems so easy, the Indestructibility of Force. Ex nihilo nihil fit was an axiom applied only to Matter. While no one thought that new matter could be produced, every one believed that force could be produced where no force pre-existed. The idea had not arisen that each manifestation of force was a devolutidn from some other already in existence. The conception of the Indestructibility of Force — with its consequence "the Correlation of Forces" (or, more accurately, the correlations of Force), is modern. It is now so obvious that no physicist disputes it, whatever may be his views of the nature of Force — whether he believes it to be an Entity, or a Kelation (§ 72 a). There is indeed some difficulty in keeping this conception steadily before the mind, and this arises from the two conditions under which Force is apprehended, conditions which are antagonistic to Sense, though transcendentally identical. These are the statical and dynamical conditions — i.e., Force as tension, and Force as vis viva. According to sensuous perception, these are antagonistic, and mutually exclusive; and correspond with the two fundamental conditions of matter, namely, Eest and Motion. According to transcendental ideas, they are iden- tical: as tension disappears, vis viva reappears; and what seems lost as vis viva is found to be restored in tension. Tension is not the less force because of its equilibrium; matter is not the less active because it is at rest. What is called the passive, or static, condition of bodies is a pure abstraction, a fiction framed for our convenience, a necessary fiction, but directly at variance with what is disclosed by objective inquiry. The idea of absolute inertness— inac- 124 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. tivity — is a figment; it is correlative with the idea of all activity being due to some outlying agency, some existence apart from, and controlling bodies. It arose from the metaphysical view of Nature which interpreted subjective distinctions as objective realities, and thus separated Motion from the Moving Body, because such abstractions were possible in thought, and convenient in speech. The abstrac- tion became personified as an independent Force (§ 72 a). In Mechanics we also make this abstraction, and conceive bodies as passive; nor is there any impropriety in doing so, for Mechanics deal only with abstractions. Elsewhere we recognize the fiction, and we conceive Motion not as a thing, but as a relation: "a change of situation in reference to bodies con- ceived as at rest," 1 though the bodies are known not to be at rest. Thus in a moving ship, only those bodies are said to move which change their position in the ship. But this ship, thus conceived to be at rest, is moving through the sea ; the sea moves with the earth round its axis ; the earth moves round the sun ; the sun moves through space. Thus we pass on in our analysis, till finally we arrive at fixed points, from which absolute motion may be considered. "We imagine space without limit, motionless, penetrable by matter. It is to the parts of this imaginary space that we refer the positions of bodies, and conceive those bodies to be in motion when they correspond with successive portions of this space. This is the ultimate effort of abstraction. All we know of motion is change of position ; such changes are necessarily relative ; absolute motion is therefore unknown ; and consequently Best must be equally unknown. § 100. To cite another example : — The transcendental idea of uniformity in Nature, which is so completely interwoven 1 Laplace : Exposition du Si/slhne du Monde, I., 269. On the relativity of our conceptions of Motion and Rest, compare Kant : Neuer Lehrbegriff der Sewegung und Mute, Werke, 1839, V., 279. Compare also his Anfangsgriinde der Naturwissenchaft, erstes Hauptstiick, V., 320. CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 125 with modern speculations, was by no means clearly conceived by Aristotle. We shall presently find him maintaining that action and reaction are not always equal. We shall find him satisfied with the conclusion, based on extremely superficial ob- servation, that some male animals have teats, others not ; that lions have only one cervical vertebra, although dogs, in all other respects so similar in structure, have several. Hebschel has noticed how the Stagirite. obstructed the progress of astronomy by not identifying celestial with terrestrial me- chanics, but laying down the principle that celestial motions were regulated by peculiar laws, thus placing them entirely without the pale of experimental research, while at the same time the progress of mechanics was impeded by the assump- tion of natural and unnatural motions. 2 The remark is just, and yet, although a clear conception of the principle of uniformity would have prevented such an , error, we must not forget that the principle itself was really disclosed by vast experiences of uniformity ; that is to say, the ^ idea was obtained inductively. In our day the principle is so < familiar that we imagine it must have been an easy step to generalize from terrestrial to celestial mechanics. Yet neither Kepler, the bold, nor Galileo, the far-seeing, had the courage to make such a generalization. Kepler assumed that there was some distinct force operating in planetary motions ; and it was for the same purpose that Descartes invented his vortices. Even Newton, as will be seen hereafter, was very timid in extending terrestrial to celestial laws ; and Auguste Comte goes so far as to consider the extension of gravitation beyond our solar system to be very rash, unless understood to be simply a conjecture founded on analogy. 3 This seems to me ultra-scepticism. It is true that we have at present no proof that gravitation extends beyond our own system ; but neither have we the shadow of an indi- 2 Hekschel : Discourse on Natural Philosophy, 1830 (294). 3 Comte :, Corns de Philos. Positive, 1835, III., 254. 126 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. cation to the contrary, and gravity is so indissolubly bound up with our conception of matter that we cannot think of the stars being material without at the same time thinking of them in relations of gravity. Direct proof to the contrary would, of course, rectify this belief, but until that is fur- nished, the idea of matter without gravity is unthinkable. § 101. He who is ignorant of Motion, says Aristotle, is necessarily ignorant of all natural things. Much as he has written about Motion, it is very significant that he should not have contributed the smallest item even to what we now call the metaphysics of the subject. 4 Not only was he entirely in the dark respecting the Laws, he was completely wrong in his conception of the nature of Motion. He thought it was a something superadded ; an " energy" which was opposed to that of Best. He thought that every body in motion naturally tends to rest. We have learned to identify the two ; we have learned that Rest is not a mere privation, not a mere negation, but one aspect of the positive energy of Force {tension, not vis viva) ; for we have learned that Eest is only Equilibrium, and that is the action of equal and opposing forces, i. e., tension. The ancients all conceived Rest as something essentially different from Motion, different in nature, not simply in quan- titative amount. They believed the earth to be at rest ; we no longer believe this of the sun. We have measured the velocity of the earth which seems to be at rest, and have learned to regard motion simply as a change of relation. In justice to Aristotle, however, we should remember that these ideas are of late development. Even Mtjssenbeoek could only conceive Motion and Rest as two attributes or pro- perties of bodies. He thought that Motion was by no means 4 In writing this I was little prepared to find a modern contradictor ; yet M. Baeth&emt St. Hilaikb asserts that he knows no work in the whole range of philosophy wherein the theory of motion has been treated " avec plus d'etendue ni plus de solidite."— La Physique d'Aristote, 1862, 1., p. Ixiv. His idolatry leads hhn to make many such surprising assertions. CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 127 necessary to bodies, since a body might rest eternally in the place once given it by the Creator. 5 § 102. Aristotle has been compared with Newton on the ground that both make a theory of motion the basis of Physics. But the comparison is unjust ; the reaction it provokes against Aristotle leads to a misconception of his real greatness by the application of a false standard. While it is true that both deliver a theory of motion, it is certain that Aristotle had mastered none of the elements out of which a true theory could be constructed, whereas Newton had not only mastered the elements, but also the laws, which constitute a theory as mag- nificent in reach as it is fruitful in result. § 103. The physical writings of Aristotle still extant are the eight books of Physics, the four books On the Heavens, the two books on Generation and Corruption, with the Meteorology, and the Mechanical Problems. The contents of these works very slightly correspond with their titles, according to modern conceptions. The sciences which we class under the heads of Physics and Astronomy are in no sense repre- sented in them. There is no attempt to sketch the laws of Statics, Dynamics, Optics, Acoustics, Thermotics, or Elec- tricity. There is nothing beyond metaphysical disquisitions suggested by certain physical phenomena ; wearisome disputes about motion, space, infinity, and the like ; verbal distinc- tions, loose analogies, unhesitating assumptions, inexpressibly fatiguing and unfruitful. They have furnished matter for centuries of idle speculation, but few beams of steady light to aid the groping endeavours of science. We cannot say that on every point he is altogether wrong ; on some points he was assuredly right ; but these are few, isolated, without bear- s Mussenbroek : Cours de Physique Exptr. et Mathematique, 1769, 1., 71. His predecessor Rohatot had a clearer view, and defined Motion as " the suc- cessive application of a body to the different parts of those bodies which are immediately about it." Rest, therefore, became " the continual application of that body to the same parts of those bodies which are about it and immediately touch it." — System of Natural Philos., by Clarke, 1735, 1., 39. 128 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. ing on the rest of his speculations, and without influence on research. I shall therefore analyse these works much more rapidly and briefly than the works on Biology. I. — The Work on Physics. 6 § 104. In Book I., after briefly laying down the rules of Method, he examines the opinions of his predecessors. This has an historical interest, but science nowadays is some- what indifferent to criticisms on Being, or the various meanings which may be attached to the word. Nor will any but metaphysicians trouble themselves with the celebrated principle of Contraries, once so fruitful in disputation. He says truly enough (Chap. II.) that the early speculators erred because insufficient experience led them into a wrong path ; but his own conception of the right path turns out not a whit less misleading. There are, he says, three principles : Matter, Form, and Privation. In every phenomenon we can distinguish the sub- stance and its form ; but as the form can only be one of two Contraries, and as only one of these two can exist at each moment, we are forced to admit the existence of a third prin- ciple — Privation — to account for the contrary which is absent. Thus a man must be either a musician or a non-musician ; he cannot be both at the same time ; and that which prevents his being one of these is the privation of the form. 7 Another conclusion reached, after some difficulty, is that Motion really exists. 6 Pranti, has added a German translation and useful notes to his edition of the text. Leipzig, 1854. And during the revision of these sheets there has appeared a French version by Barthelemy St. Hilaire : La Physique d'Aristote, Paris, 1862, in two volumes, with a long preface and a paraphrase. The version seems excellent. ' " "Voila, cette theorie fameuse de la matiere et de la forme si souvent reprochee a Aristote, et que l'on critique™ sans doute plus d'une fois encore. Pour moi, je la trouve simple et vraie." — Barthelemy St. Hilaire, I., p. xxviii. CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 129 § 105. In Book II. he presents his definition of Nature. After some confused and vacillating explanation, he arrives at the conclusion that Nature is the principle of Motion and Best. Those things are called natural which are self-moved. He then enters upon .the four causes, which we have already expounded (§ 95). These comprise Nature : for everything has substance, everything has form, everything has motion, everything has an end or aim. § 106. In the eighth chapter of this Book there is a dis- cussion on final causes, which is too interesting to be passed over. He first argues against those who hold Chance to be a cause of phenomena. " What, it has been said, is to prevent nature from acting without an aim, and without any refer- ence to the Best (fir\ 'ivaca tov iroiuv juryS' on (5s\riov) ? Why should not Zeus rain from necessity (e$ avayfoje), and not to make the corn grow? Since the vapour, rising upwards, must become cold, and vapour chilled is water, which would descend as rain ; and, because this has happened, the corn has grown. Again, if the corn in a granary is ruined by the rain, we cannot say that the final cause of the rain was the ruin of the corn, but that this ruin was accidental (tovto ovfifiefinicEv). What, then, prevents the organs of animals from being formed in a similar way ? The teeth are produced necessarily ; those in front are sharp and capable of tearing the food ; those behind are broad, and capable of grinding it. They are not there for these ends, but these ends simply coincide with their existence (av/nireaeiv). And so of all other organs. Thus, those things which happen to be constituted as if they were made for an express purpose persist, and are preserved because the conditions permit ; but those of, which this is not the case have perished, or will perish." 8 Having thus stated the argument with great impartiality, 8 oirov fihi ovv Uiravra avvifiri tioirtg «av d ivaca tov iyiviro, Tama fiiv la&Bri diro tov ccvto/jAtov avaravra lmrti$eiw£' oca Si fir) ovnig diriiXcro icai diraXKvrat. 9 130 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. Til. he proceeds to answer it as follows : — " That this should be the case is impossible, and for this reason : these things, and all things naturally generated, are always, or mostly, so generated. On the contrary, this is never seen in spontaneous or accidental cases. Thus, it does not seem to be accidental, or coincidental, when much rain falls in winter; but it does' seem so when it occurs in the dog- days. Nor is it accidental when great heat occurs during the dog-days; but it is so during winter. If, therefore, such occur, either as an accident or with a view to some purpose, and if it is impossible to say the phenomena are accidental, it is clear they must occur with some end in view. But since all things are thus in nature — as even those admit who speak of these things — there must neces- sarily be a final cause of these things which in nature exist, or are produced." Considering the reputation of Aristotle as a logician, this is, perhaps, one of the feeblest arguments ever put forth on this subject, which has elicited many. 9 Had he confined him- self to the proposition first announced, namely, that constant uniformity of adaptation to an end implies a design, whereas accidental adaptations are only occasional, there would have been some force in the argument ; but his illustrations betray the confusion of his ideas. § 107. He goes on to specify the obvious illustrations used by the advocates of final causes, in the acts of animals, and in the structure of plants, concluding that " there must be some cause for everything which exists, or is produced." But Nature is to be considered under two aspects — Matter and Form. Now form being an end, and all the rest being arranged with reference to it, we may call the form the final 9 Opinions differ. M. Bakth^lemy St. Hilatke, always ready with his enthusiasm, thinks this argument " une magnifique apologie de la nature." Aristotle himself, on one occasion, sees through the absurdity of always seek- ing final causes (§ 401). CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 131 cause. Error is, however, possible both in Nature and in Art. A grammarian may be betrayed into an error of spelling, a physician into administering a wrong potion. Similar errors may exist in Nature. Monstrosities are Nature's faults in orthography. § 108. In Book III. we have his celebrated definition of Motion as the passage from potential existence to actual exist- ence. " Motion is the energy of what exists in power, so far as existing. It is the act of a moveable which belongs to its power of moving." Before studying motion it is necessary to come to a clear understanding of Infinity, since motion is continuity, and as such infinitely divisible ; therefore the Infinite must first be studied. Then again as Motion implies both Space and Time, these also must be studied. What Aristotle has to say on these transcendental questions the curious reader must find out for himself; it would occupy too much space, and too unprofitably, to reproduce it here. I will rather call attention to the long persistence of the metaphysical fallacy which kept up discussions on such subjects as the existence of space as anything more than a relation. The fallacy (§ 69) is, that whenever man can form clear ideas, not in themselves con- tradictory, these ideas must of necessity represent truths of nature. 10 Hence when we conceive body, we conceive it as existing in something, which contains it (i. e. body as filling space), we are led to believe that this all-container must itself have an objective existence. The idea will not withstand criticism. An equal necessity can be shown for something to contain the container. As we cannot pursue this reduction ad infinitum, we must stop somewhere ; why not, therefore, 10 " Jusqu' a present nous n'avons traite que de l'idee du vuide ; il faut main- tenant que nous fassions voir qu'il n'est pas impossible qu'il existe dans le monde un vuide etendu ; ce qu'on peut demontrer facilement d'apres l'idee que chacun peut se former du vuide; car en peut supposer que tout ce qui se concoit clairement etqui n'emporte aueune contradiction avec soi, existe.' ' — Mussenbkoek : Cours de Physique, I., 82. 9—2 132 AEISTOTLE'S physics, [CHAP. VII. stop at Substance, of which we know something, rather than, go on to Space, of which we know nothing ? The argument of J. Beenouilli, cited by Mussenbeoek with approval, is a specimen of metaphysical trifling quite worthy of Aristotle. " Before the creation of the world there was nothing existing, except God. If this universal vacuity was not repugnant to Creative "Wisdom, we cannot suppose it repugnant to his Wisdom if there are now many vacant spaces between existing bodies." Out of similar " suppositions " and "clear ideas," metaphysicians have built many systems ; systems, but no science. § 109. Instead of wearying the reader with discussions about Space, let me detach from Aristotle's fourth book the theory of projectiles, interesting in itself, and also because it gives us the first glimpse of a conception of Inertia. He argues that in vacuo, Motion is impossible. In a void there can be no difference of place ; and motion implies differ- ence of place. He then adds that projectiles continue moving after the original motor ceases to be in contact with them, " either, as some say, by reaction (Si avriirtpiaTaaiv), or by the motion of the moved air, which is more rapid than that of the natural tendency of the body to its proper place." 11 " In vacuo, on the contrary, there will be nothing of the kind, no body can have motion there unless it be carried and supported as in a chariot." How the chariot is to be moved in vacuo, he does not explain ; yet he started from the position that no motion was possible in vacuo. " Moreover," he adds, "no one can say why in vacuo a body once set in motion should ever stop ; since why rather here than there ? Con- sequently it must either remain in necessary rest, or — if in motion — in endless motion, unless some stronger interferes." " Compare also lib. VIII., chap. X., 267, where the same explanation is given. Galileo's masterly refutation of this may be seen in his Dicdoghi, Giornata Seconda (Opera, Milan, 1811, XI., 344). CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 133 § 110. On many accounts this is an interesting passage. He had by no means overlooked the fact of the resistance of air, since he compares it with the resistance of water. Yet the air is made to keep up rather than destroy the motion of a projectile. He had, also, as we see, got a glimpse of Inertia— at least, as regards bodies in vacuo. But it never occurred to him to connect the two ideas, and make inertia keep up the continuity of motion, and resistance of the air destroy the motion. 12 He was forced to seek for some continuous external motor to account for continuous motion; "the pulses of the moved air " was the first cause which presented itself, and was accepted at once. Whereas had he (and succeeding philoso- ; phers) steadily conceived the so-called Law of Inertia— that is ' to say, the transcendental Law of Causation, that every change demands a cause,— he would have perceived that continuous motion was motion unchanged — would have perceived that no - external cause was needed for such continuity, but was only '> needed to arrest, deflect, accelerate, in a word change the motion. The pulses of air might thus have been conceived as retarding the motion, deflecting it, or* accelerating it — and by Verification he would have ascertained which of these conceptions was correct. But in no sense could the pulses of air have been conceived as causing the simple continuance of motion, since continuance implied that there was nothing to cause change. \ 111. The succeeding Books (V. — VIII.) are mainly devoted to Motion. It is divided into absolute, partial, and accidental motions — phrases much cherished by scholasticism, which fed on phrases as the fabled chamaeleon fed on air. By accidental motion is not meant motion occurring without a known cause, but motion which has reference to the "acci- dent" or attribute of a thing. Thus when we say "a musician walks " we speak of an accidental motion ; since it is not the a As Des Cabtes did. See his Principia Philos., pars II., c. xxxviii. 134 ABISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. musician which walks, but the man in whom being a musician is the "accident." Partial motion is when we say of a sick man that he is cured. In truth this motion of cure concerns only his diseased organ, and not the whole man himself. Absolute motion is that in which the object moves entirely, as when we say "a man walks" because his whole body changes its place. In the theory of motion five elements are involved : the motor, the moved, the direction of movement, the starting- point, and the goal. It is from the last that motion receives its special designation. Thus the corruption of a body is its movement towards non-existence, although it must neces- sarily start from existence. In like manner the movement of generation is a movement towards existence, though starting from non-existence. § 112. A little of this kind of philosophy will doubtless suffice for all readers. They can easily imagine how fertile such principles must have been in verbal disputation, how sterile in any other result. Yet this is the system which has been compared with Newton's ! There are three Categories of Motion laid down : — 1. Quantity; 2. Quality; 3. Place. On these he rings the changes. When a body increases or diminishes, there is the " motion of quantity." When the body changes its quality without changing its quantity — as in becoming hot or cold — there is "the motion of quality." When a body merely changes its place, there is locomotion, or the " motion of place." 13 § 113. Motion in space, from an external motor, is of four 12 Hekmolaus Barbarus thus compendiously Btates it: " Motus autem est ejus rei, quae movetur, fluens atque inchoata perfectio. Qusecunque ver6 moventur, aut spatium percurrunt (ut ea qute loco mutantur), aut quantitatem transferuiit (ut ea qua? auctantur minuunturque), aut qualitatem (ut ea quae calefiunt fiigefiuntque), aut aliquid hujuscemodi nanciscuntur." — Compendium Scientia Naturalis ex Aristotele, 1547, Lib. I., p. 8. CHAP. VII.] METEOKOLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 135 kinds : — Traction, Impulsion, Translation, and Rotation. To these all changes may be referred. Thus Compulsion (eV&wc) is an Impulsion (oxnc) in which the motor accompanies the body which it moves ; and Repulsion (avwaic) is an Impul- sion which does not accompany the moved body. Projection is the impress of a more violent movement than the body would naturally have, and lasts until this "natural motion" regains the upperhand. Expansion is repulsion, Contraction is traction. This analysis may be carried further ; we may reduce both translation and rotation under the heads of traction and impulsion. Thus the body may be accidentally moved, or be in some body which is moved, or be on that body ; that which carries may itself be carried, either because it is drawn, or pushed, or rolled. Rotation is obviously constituted by traction and impulsion. § 114. There are two great classes of movements — 1st, the natural; and 2nd, the violent, or unnatural. These belong to all bodies. Fire ascends, and a stone descends, by natural movement. A stone may be made to ascend, but this is owing to violence ; some external motor causes it to ascend ; by its natural movement the stone would never rise, but always fall. For a similar reason fire may be made to descend ; but left to its natural movement it will only ascend. § 115. Translation being the first of movements, and being reducible to circular, linear, and mixed, the question arises : Which of these is the most perfect ? which represents the infinite, continuous, uniform motion of the First Mover ? Not the mixed, since that is a combination of the two others. Not the linear, since a straight line is necessarily finite, and if a body were to move eternally along it, there must be a return, which would produce contrary movements, and moments of repose, which would be solutions of continuity. The circular therefore alone remains : in the circle there is no solution of continuity : the motion may be eternal in it. 136 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. This demonstration of circular movement as the most perfect, played a conspicuous part in peripatetic philosophy. Yet the reader sees at once how entirely it is removed from , reality, how purely verbal its basis, how utterly unscientific. The same may be said of all the ideas expounded in the Physics ; and we need bestow no more time upon them. II. — The work on the Heavens. 1 * § 116. The title of this work, De Goelo, was not given by its author. It raises in the modern reader an expectation which will not be fulfilled of finding in it astronomical views. Its subject-matter is very much that of the Physics; indeed, the two works may be considered as parts of one treatise. § 117. In Book I. substance is treated as a continuity of three dimensions, divisible on all sides. Bodies are deter- mined by motion; but every motion is either straight or circular, or else a compound of the two. Circular motion is movement round a centre ; straight motion is either upwards or downwards. That is named upwards which goes from the centre ; that is named downwards which goes to the centre. The qualities of bodies which correspond to these forms of Up and Down are Levity and Gravity. These are not relative but absolute ; they belong to the bodies themselves. In .a subsequent passage (Book IV.) Aristotle objects to the early philosophers that they conceived these contraries of Up and Down as simple relations, without determining what Levity and Gravity were in themselves. He maintains that Earth by nature tends downwards, and has absolute gravity ; Fire, on the contrary, tends upwards, and has absolute levity. The former underlies the firm and solid; the latter rises above, and swims over the elements. Those bodies which move in circles can be neither heavy nor light, since they 14 Pbantl has given an edition of this also, with a German translation, fol- lowed by the little treatise On Generation and Corruption. Leipzig, 1857. CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 137 cannot be moved from or to a centre, either by natural, or unnatural motions. § 117 a. The profound difference between such ideas and the ideas of modern science must be obvious. Instead of trying to ascertain the law of gravitation, that is to say, its proportional relations, a verbal definition of the nature of gravitation is given, without any guarantee for the accuracy of the definition. No illumination can issue from such a source, nor from the subsequent demonstration that an infinite body is impossible, consequently there can be no infinite gravity, no infinite levity. § 118. We have learned that the weight of bodies is not an absolute quality inherent in the particles, but the relation existing between the particles and the centre of the earth, a relation which varies with the variation of the distance. But this conception could not have been formed until it had been disclosed in the phenomena of celestial mechanics. It was otherwise with the conception of positive levity The ordinary phenomena of terrestrial physics might have disclosed to Aristotle the error of supposing bodies to have positive levity. Epictjkus clearly saw through the fallacy of imagining that Fire ascended in virtue of its levity. " No body," says Lucretius, 15 " can by its own force tend upwards ; flame descends when left to its own nature, as we see in lightning, falling stars, and the descending beams of the sun which reach the earth." § 119. In Book II. there is much profitless discussion of the Contraries in Space, Eight and Left, and the like. It is to be observed that he regards these not as relative, but as positive ; thus in Book IV. he distinctly says that Up and Down, Eight and Left, are fixed by nature, and are not 15 Luchetius : II., v., 184, seq. " Nullani rem posse sua vi corpoream sur- snm ferri, sursumque meare." The idea of a positive Levity continued to reign so long that even in 1755 we find Dr. Samuel Clarke elaborately refuting it. See notes to Rohault's System of Natural Philosophy, I., 99. 138 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. simply relations to us : ov ftovov 7r s ooc ij/iae. After this dis- cussion he advances the proposition that whatever exists exists for its own end. The energy of God is immortality : this is eternal life. The Godlike must consequently have eternal motion, and as the Heaven is Godlike it must contain bodies eternally moving in circles. Why are not all bodies of this nature ? Because it is necessary, when a body moves in a circle, that there should be a fixed and motionless centre ; such a centre is the earth. By a similar course of argument, it is proved that there must be a contrary to this earth; namely fire. But the positive is prior to the privative, and heat is prior to cold. Now, Kest and Gravity are said to be privations of Motion and Levity. The apparent contra- diction in thus making fire prior to earth is reconciled by Peantl somewhat more Germanico. He sees in it a deep ontological meaning, that out of the co-existence of two contraries a deeper metaphysical priority for one of the two may be- evolved, and precisely for this of fire. 16 Leaving this dainty morsel to the palates of metaphysi- cians, we may consider the important detail that when Aristotle speaks of Best and Cold as privations, he is not to be understood as meaning negations. In his system priva- tives are positives (§ 104). Hence the solid earth is conceived as privative in respect of fire ; gravity is privative in respect of levity. § 120. " The necessary form of the Heaven," he says, " is a circle; for this form is the most suitable to its substance, and is the first in nature : tovto yap oi/ceiorarov te ry ovoia. Kai Ty vaei Trpurov." Substance can be known, then ? Yes, but you must not ask how the knowledge is acquired. He pro- ceeds to demonstrate his proposition at length ; but we need not follow. The stars attract us. " It is most rational to con- ceive the stars as constituted of that substance in which they 16 See Phantl : ad locum, p. 298. CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 139 have their orbit." Why ? The answer is intensely signifi- cant. " Because we have said already that there was some- thing which by its very nature was moved in a circle : £7m§77 ifafxiv ti e'tvai b kvkAoj ipiaOai irtyvictv." Should any doubt arise respecting the high rationality of such a conclusion, the doubt will be silenced by the axiom that " everything neces- sarily arises from that in which it is." Thus as the stars move in circles they must be formed out of circles. § 121. The dynamical theory of heat, which in our day has received something approaching to a demonstration, and has led to the questionable hypothesis that the heat of the sun is produced and constantly renewed by the shock of planetary masses against it, gives a curious interest to the following passage, which an uncritical admirer might regard as an anticipation. " The heat and light of the stars are evolved from the friction of their bodies against the air ; for motion naturally produces heat, even in wood and stones ; and still more must this be the case with bodies which are nearer to fire ; and air is nearer to fire, as may be concluded from the heat of arrows which become so heated that some- times their lead is melted; and when they are heated the air surrounding them must be heated also. Motion through the air generates heat. Of the Upper bodies, each is moved in its own circle, so that it does not become hot, but the air surrounding it is made hot, and there hottest where the sun is. We must conclude, therefore, that the stars are neither made of fire nor moved in fire." § 122. Anything like a connected view ofJiis astronomical opinions must be deferred until we come to the early history of astronomy ; here we may content ourselves with one more characteristic detail, namely, his proof of the stars being spherical. " They are by nature incapable of being self- moved; and as nature never does anything irrational or purposeless (ov&v a'Aoywe ovSs parr/v), it follows that to the body incapable of self-movement she would give the 140 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. Til. form which is the least moveable; now the sphere is the least moveable, since it has no instruments by which to move : Sia to firi§iv e\uv opyavov irpog rr)v Kivrjaiv. § 123. In Book III. he gives expression to the famous conception of four elements. He defines an element to be that which exists potentially, or actually, in bodies, and cannot be resolved into any other elements. Fire and earth are potentially in flesh and wood ; otherwise they could never come out of flesh and wood. But in fire there is neither actual nor potential flesh or wood ; otherwise we should see them produced out of it. Peantl thinks it is a striking illustration of the Grecian tendency to neglect facts for ideas that not one among these early speculators ever attempted to ascertain what earth and fire really are. The reproach is scarcely just, for it is difficult to conceive how such an attempt could have been made at that period. The energetic protests against the a priori Method which escape from Aristotle in this very book, warrant us in saying that he would have escaped from it had the other Method been open with any prospect of result. He accepted the idea of the elements because it was plausible. There was no suspicion of its accuracy, no known means of verifying it. Although only four elements are enumerated here, and generally also elsewhere, yet a fifth is often named, the Ether, and a great part assigned to it in his speculations. Critics, however, are far from agreement respecting it. Hitter, Henri Martin and Meyer, for example, maintain the Ether to be a distinct element. Biese, Humboldt, and Zeller argue that it wants the cardinal character of an element, the principle of contraries. It is neither heavy, nor light ; neither hot nor cold ; therefore it has no linear, but only circular movement, and is destitute of up and down. One cannot but see that Aristotle's language must be very vacillating or obscure when there can be two opinions on such a point. I think that CHAP. 711.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 141 although his language is lax, his meaning is consistently preserved. There are some unequivocal passages in which Ether is included generally among the elements, though it is always marked off from the other four, as standing by itself; the four elements are commonly spoken of because they are the four mundane principles; from them all bodies on our earth and in our atmosphere are derived ; whereas the Ether begins where our world ends, and fills the whole of the supra- mundane space. This view is clearly expressed in the apochry- phal treatise De Mimdo, v < which may be cited as collateral evidence, showing how Aristotle was understood by the Alexandrians : " Ether is the substance of the heavens and the stars ; so named not because it is of fire, but because of its eternal circular movement. It is an element differing from the four others, not to be confounded with them, because divine." There is, therefore, good reason why the principle of contraries which characterizes the other four should be absent from this element. § 124. In Book IV. he returns to Gravity and Levity, which are conceived to be at once absolute and relative. " Heavy and light we call that which by nature has the power of being moved ; for the two energies there is no name unless it be velocity. Some things are called absolutely heavy, or absolutely light ; others only relatively so. Of those which have weight we say some are lighter than others — as wood is lighter than brass." After objecting to the earlier philosophers for having only considered heavy and light bodies, without inquiring into the nature of Gravity and Levity, he proceeds to define Gravity as absolute in all bodies which tend towards the centre ; and Levity as absolute in all bodies which 17 De Mundo, II., ed. Bussemaker, p. 628. ovpavov Se /cat auTpiav ovaiav fiXv aiOipa KaXovptv, oi% &Q tiviq Sid rb irvpiiiSr) ovaav aWeaBai . . . d\\d Sid To del 9etv Kvic\o$opovii£V7]V, gtqxuqv ovaav erepov rttiv rtTraptav, aKqparov re Kal 9&ov, Compare also HE., p. 629, mvrt St] OTOx&a Tama, k.tX. 142 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. tend from the centre. " It is absurd to suppose that there is nothing in the celestial region which corresponds to Upper and Under." He contends against the notion that bodies are light in proportion to the amount of empty space which they contain. Those who reason thus forget, he says, that there must also be less substance, otherwise a large mass of gold would be lighter than a small quantity of fire, since it would contain more empty space. § 125. In the Physics he argues that place is something positive. He here argues that everything has its appointed place, to which it constantly tends : the light bodies belong to the Upper, the heavy bodies to the Lower. " To ask why fire moves upwards and earth downwards, is as if one were to ask why the curable passes into health, and not into white- ness." § 126. He inquires into the reason why bodies have different weights under different conditions. In the air a talent of wood is heavier than a mina of lead; but in the water it is lighter than the lead. The reason is : all things, except fire, have weight ; and all things, except earth, have lightness. Consequently earth, and that which contains most earth, must necessarily have weight anywhere; water also must have weight everywhere except in the earth; air also must have weight everywhere except in water and earth. In other words, everything, except fire, in its own place has weight. That even air has weight is proved by the fact that a bladder filled with air is heavier than the same bladder empty. Hence when a body contains more air than water and earth, it is lighter in water than another, but heavier in air ; since it will swim on the surface of the water, but not on the surface of the air. Water will sink below everything but earth, and air will rise above everything but fire. Thus we see that the four elements have their four places : fire at the top, earth at the bottom ; between the two air and water. § 127. He declares that the shape of bodies is not the CHAP. VH.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 143 cause of their moving up and down ; but only the cause of the greater velocity with which they move. He raises the question why flat pieces of brass or lead swim on the surface of water, whereas smaller pieces, if round, long, or pointed, sink ; and other substances, as dust, float in air ? The reader here recognizes the problem solved by Galileo in a masterly manner, both by reasoning and experiment. The solution of Aristotle is, as usual, little more than a restatement of the problem in different words. He begins by saying that every continuity is more or less divisible, and that every body has a more or less penetrating power over it. The easily limited is easily divided; air is more so than water, water more so than earth. And the smaller a body is, the more easily is it divided. The body which has a flat shape remains at the top of the water, because it has a larger quan- tity of water under it, and this larger quantity is less easily penetrated ; but a body of contrary shape sinks because there is a less quantity of water under it to be penetrated. These are all the topics needful to be noticed in this work until we come to consider his astronomical theories. The two books on " Generation and Corruption " may be passed over ; for they are in his most wearisome style of verbal dis- putation, and contain no scientific views not expressed else- where. TTT. — The Work on Meteorology. 18 § 128. This is in many respects one of his most interesting treatises. It has a more directly scientific attitude, and is guided by a more consistently inductive method than either of the works just noticed. No one will be surprised to hear that it very imperfectly corresponds with what in our days is understood by a treatise on Meteorology; nor must we » A translation of this work has just appeared by M. Baethelemt St. Hilaike: La Mtteorologie d'Aristote, Paris, 1863. 144 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. object to its including questions of astronomy, geology, and chemistry ; for at that period the boundaries of the several sciences were not carefully marked. Even at the present time Meteorology, rich in details, is eminently imperfect, aided though it is by instruments of precision, and a vast body of scientific truths which would lend their collustration, were fundamental principles established. In Aristotle, there- fore, we can still less expect to find material of value. His observations and theories wear somewhat the aspect of the observations and theories to be found in the works of the early alchemists, as compared with modern chemistry. But although the absolute value of the treatise is insignificant its historical value is considerable, and on this point, there- fore, the reader's attention may chiefly be fixed. The work shows what could and what could not be effected by Observation, when unassisted by Instruments. Aristotle, equally with moderns, makes Heat the chief agent in meteorologic changes. But this is general, qualitative knowledge, and Science demands quantitative knowledge. Wholly destitute of a measure of heat he could establish no quantitative bases for his reasonings. In like manner he was without a Barometer which could measure the weight of the atmosphere at different times and in different places. He knew that the atmosphere had weight, but was unable to measure that weight. He further wanted an Anemometer by which to measure the velocity of atmospheric currents, and a Hygrometer by which to measure the quantities of vapour. Nor had he any knowledge of Electricity, which also plays a considerable part in , meteorologic phenomena. Thus, deprived of all those puissant means of investigation which could make observation precise, we see in his work an example of the genuine commencement of Science, when man is face to face with complex phenomena, the order of which he intensely desires to discover, and finds himself reduced to qualitative observation and to reasoning. Now the remark- CHAP. Til.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 145 able point in Aristotle's treatise is that, standing as he does in the condition of the early pioneers, he does not adopt that , primitive theological mode of explanation which we have) seen (§ 31) to be generally characteristic of such a condition,! but on the contrary, adopts a strictly scientific method,! rejecting all theological explanations, and endeavouring toj range the phenomena in their natural order. He examines the facts and co-ordinates them to the best of his ability. § 128 a. Books I. to III. discuss a variety of questions. First the elements are enumerated. These are five; the Ether, which fills supramundane space (§ 123) and is endowed with circular movement, is only alluded to ; the four others are fire, air, water, earth, which compose all mundane bodies. He then gives theoretic explanations of shooting stars, comets, the milky way (which he regards as an exhalation from the earth suspended in the air ; although Demooeitxjs had already asserted it to be a cluster of stars), clouds, fogs, dew, hoar-frost, rain, snow, hail, winds, the formation of rivers, the reciprocal changes of sea and land, the saltness of the sea, the nature of winds, and the influence of sun and stars on them, earth- quakes (which are compressed winds), thunder and lightning, the rainbow, and meteors. On these multiform topics his theories, as may be imagined, are mostly wide of the mark, but they often display remarkable sagacity, and bear the stamp of an earnest investigating mind. The large accumulation of facts is very noticeable ; but rather, I think, on account of the attitude of mind which impelled him to make such an accumulation, and to insist with so much emphasis on the value of facts, than, as M. Babthelemy St. Hilaiee would have us believe, because the facts themselves display any noticeable sagacity. M. St. Hilaire is at great pains, in his commentary, to point out every occasion on which his hero is correct or approaches correctness in facts ; but a little reflection reveals that in the majority of such cases the facts are such as lie 10 146 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. open to universal observation, implying no merit therefore in the observer, while in no case have they quantitative pre- cision. It is for its method, rather than for its results, that this treatise is remarkable. I shall, therefore, content myself with this general indication. § 128 b. Book IV. is more in the nature of a chemical treatise, dealing with the elements and their active and passive principles. The hot and the cold are the active, the moist and the dry are the passive principles. This is clear from their definitions, for we call the hot and the cold active because that which coagulates bodies is certainly an active principle; the moist and the dry are passive because they are limited with ease or with difficulty, according' to the modifications impressed upon them. The hot unites the homogeneous and separates the heterogeneous ; as may be seen in the fusion of metals. The cold unites the heteroge- neous ; as we see in ice, which is the union of the heterogeneous materials of water. The moist has no natural limit, but readily accepts a limit; the dry, on the contrary, has a natural limit. From these two active and two passive principles are derived the four unions corresponding with the elements. Thus, Fire is warm and dry ; Air is warm and moist ; Water is cold and moist ; Earth is cold and dry. Each element has its appointed place. Fire and Earth are the two extremes ; they are purer and less mixed than the two intermediates, Air and Water. In the gradual development of these elements, there is an ascent from the imperfect to the more perfect. In Water there is Earth ; in Air there is Water ; in Fire there is Air. It is needless to follow him in his explanation of the liquefaction and coagulation of bodies, the fusion of metals, the phenomena of putrefaction and digestion, and the tempera- ture of bodies ; although his ideas on these subjects reigned almost without dispute for many centuries. We shall here- CHAP. Til.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 147 after find more fitting occasions for the display of such ideas. At present we must pass on to the Mechanical problems. IV. — The Mechanical Problems. § 129. Although it is certain, from his numerous references, that Aristotle wrote a work called Problems, scholars dispute how far the work which now passes under that title is genuine, and how many of the problems, thus collected together, were really written by him. On this dispute I cannot venture to offer an opinion. Nor does the question of authenticity acquire any importance for us, since the work certainly represents peripatetic views, and has always been accepted as Aristotelian. Most of these problems relate to medical and physiological subjects. Those which relate to Music have been learnedly expounded by Chabanon ; 19 those which are usually called " mechanical " have been expounded by Poselg-er, 20 who maintains that they are not correctly styled " mechanical," being strictly dialectical. It is certain that Aristotle declares it to be his intention to solve aporia, i. e. difficulties ; but if this was his intention, and if his solution of these was always dialectical, as Poseloer maintains, we may be permitted a doubt whether this be not as great a deviation from scientific procedure as the attempt, with which Whewell reproaches him, to solve mechanical problems geometrically. On this point we may remark that Aristotle could not, had he wished it, have furnished strictly mechanical answers, since mechani- cal science was not then in existence. It is to Archimedes we owe the foundation of Statics ; to Galileo the foundation of Dynamics. Aristotle could only solve the difficulties he raised with such means as were ready to his hand ; and this he did. The whole collection affords interesting proof of his 19 In the Mimoires de I'Acadimie des Inscriptions, 1793, XL VI. 20 In the Abhandlungen der mathematischen Klasse der Academie der Wis- sencha/ten zu Berlin, 1829. 10—2 148 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. immense curiosity, his ardent desire to interrogate nature, and the misdirected ingenuity with which he answered his own questions. § 130. Although he had no systematic knowledge of mechanical laws, he had gained certain glimpses which now seem surprising. The principle of "virtual velocities " was certainly known to him. This has been denied ; but Galileo himself says that he found it in Aristotle, and doubtless alludes to the following passage: — "The same force will raise a greater weight in proportion as the force is applied at a longer distance from the fulcrum, because it then describes a larger circle ; and a weight which is farthest removed from the centre is made to move through the greatest space." § 131. He also gained a glimpse of the parallelogram of forces. Poselgek thinks his statement of it superior in elegance and precision to that given by Kant. Yet in spite of this, I must still think that Aristotle only gained a glimpse of the law, as he did of the principle of " virtual velocities," since he failed to see its far-reaching importance, and made little or no use of it. In his hands it never became the instrument which it has proved in modern hands ; but was neglected for dialectical distinctions and physical hypo- theses. Montucla speaks with supreme contempt of Aristotle's mathematical insight. 21 I cannot presume to offer an opinion on such a point, but I observe that Montucla is apt to speak contemptuously on very slight grounds. Other authorities are more laudatory. 22 An unbiassed opinion is rare, the servility towards great reputations making men eager to interpret the slightest indications as evidences of mastery. This much, at least, is certain, that Aristotle made no advances in mathe- 21 Montucla : Histoire des Mathitnatiqv.es, Paris, 1758, 1., 204. 22 Libki : Histoire des Sciences Matheniatiqnes en Italic, Paris, 1838, L, 99, notices, as a fact of the highest interest, and one which has escaped notice, that Aristotle employed " des lettres de Palphahet pour designer les quantites indeterminees." CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 149 matics, and, while he frequently employed mathematical illustrations, he did not apparently devote to the science the attention devoted to other sciences. § 132. Of these Mechanical Problems now under notice, Montucla says that they gained a great reputation in those ages, when, to ensure applause, it was enough for the Stagirite to have spoken ; but that this applause will not be bestowed by moderns, who must consider the majority of the answers as entirely false, while the first and principal solution is "tout a fait ridicule." 23 Let us consider this. The problem being how a lever, or balance, of unequal arms, could hold in equilibrium unequal weights or forces. " Aristotle seeks it in the marvellous properties of the circle, of which he makes a puerile enumeration, after which he says it is not surprising that a figure so fertile in marvels should produce one in the equilibrium of equal powers." This criticism has been fre- quently repeated. It is scarcely just. Aristotle mentions, indeed, the wonderful properties of the circle; but not to draw therefrom his mechanical solution so much as to justify the dialectical nature of the problem. "Those things," he says, "are wonderful which occur according to nature, but of which the cause is hidden ; and those also which are effected by art contrary to nature. When anything is effected contrary to nature it presents a difficulty which requires art (Sia to yakvKov diroplav 7raptx El Ka ' 6£lTal te^vjic) ; and the art which resolves such difficulties we call Mechanics. Of this kind are the means by which great weights are moved by small weights, and all other mechanical problems. These are not quite the same as physical problems ; nor very different from them, but pertain to both. Mathe- matics treat of the formal, Physics of the material. The lever presents difficulties of this kind. For it seems absurd (otottov) that a great weight should be moved by a force 23 Montucla, I., 205. 150 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. which is itself added to a great weight. We can easily, with a lever, mere a weight which we could not move without one. Of all these cases, the circle contains the principle and the cause, and very naturally, since there is no absurdity in some- thing wonderful being derived from something more wonderful. A combination of opposites is the most wonderful of all, and such a combination is the circle. It is constituted by a stationary point and a moving line, which are contraries in nature, and hence it is not surprising if contraries result." In this proem he is obviously treating solely of the dialec- tical nature of the problem. He does not pretend to explain the mechanical effect from the wonderfulness of the circle ; that is explained by the properties of the lever, with which he was not unacquainted, although it is true that he " perplexed himself with loose and inappropriate notions respecting natural and unnatural movements." 2 * He says, " A body at the end of a lever has a natural motion in the direction of the tangent, and an unnatural motion in the direction of the radius. The reason why a force acting at a greater distance from the fulcrum moves a weight more easily, is because it describes a larger circle." § 133. It would needlessly occupy great space to go through these problems seriatim; many of them consist simply of questions which he does not attempt to answer. A sample or two must suffice. In the XXth he moots the question, subsequently dis- cussed by Bokelli, Mebsenne, Leibnitz, Bebnouilli, Mac- laubin and others, touching the difference between pressure and percussion. "Why," he asks, "when we place an axe upon wood, and on the axe place a heavy weight, is the wood but slightly indented ; whereas if we raise the axe, without the weight, and strike upon the wood, the wood is split, although the falling weight is much less than the resting and pressing w Whewell : History of the Inductive Sciences, 1857, 1., 61. CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 151 weight ? Perhaps because everything acts by motion (# S16V1 iravra ry kivjjo-ei Epya&rai) ; and a weight already in motion takes the motion of another more powerfully than a weight at rest? Hence in this case the resting weight acts with no motion ; but when moved, its motion is increased with that of the striker." The mind which has once grasped the con- ception of the measure of force being as the mass multiplied by the velocity finds no difficulty in understanding why the effect of the axe at rest is so much less than that of the axe in motion. But in Aristotle's day this conception was un- suspected; and he could only detect the general fact that velocity increased the effect. § 134. In the XXXHnd he asks : " Why a body in motion is more easily moved than the same body at rest — a rolling carriage being more easily moved than when it first begins to move ? Is it because it is more difficult to move a weight in a contrary direction ? For some part of the moving power must be lost, even though it be swifter, and the impulse in one direction will be slackened by reaction ; this also will be the case when the body is at rest ; for that which is at rest resists. When a body is in motion, and receives a new impulse in its own direction, it is as if the force and velocity of the moving body had been increased by so much." It is evident here that he had not fully understood the law of inertia, since he supposes it is only a body at rest which resists; but he was so near the conception of the law of accelerated motion, that we are the more surprised to find him not detecting the old error of supposing the velocity of falling bodies to be proportional to the spaces. 25 § 135. In the XXXIIIrd he asks : " Why does a pro- jectile finally come to rest? Is it because the projecting 25 We shall hare to consider this hereafter. Meanwhile the reader may look up Galileo's masterly refutation. Dialoghi, Giornata Seconda. Opere, Milan, 1811, XL, p. 478. 152 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSICS, [CHAP. VII. power ceases; or because of the reaction; or because the weight of the body overcomes the projecting force ? Or is it absurd to ask such a question, the principle being absent / » / \ ' / \ Oil \aq>£VTa tts\v a^yy\v) C § 135. In the XXXIVth he asks : " Why when a body is not self-moved does it continue moving, when the motor neither follows it, nor acts from a distance ? Is it not mani- fest that the first impulse acts upon another body, and this again upon another, and ceases only when this transference can go no further ? " The law of inertia is here entirely dis- regarded ; a proof that Aristotle had no steady conception of the law. § 136. One more, and we conclude. "Why cannot we throw a very large nor a very small body, but it is necessary there should be a proportion between the mass and the pro- jecting force ? Is it because of the necessary reaction against the impelling force ? For that which, owing to its magnitude, does not yield, or, owing to its feebleness, does not resist, cannot be impelled. That which is greater than the im- pelling force does not move — that which is much less, has no resistance." § 137. From this summary of Aristotle's Physics it is abundantly manifest that in spite of his acuteness, and his intense desire for knowledge, he had not mastered the initial conceptions of the science. Not simply deficient in the indis- pensable requisites of quantitative co-ordinated facts which distinguish Science from Common Knowledge, we find him deficient even in the transcendental postulates of Science. Disputes, but no illumination, could proceed from such pos- tulates as the Contraries, Natural and Unnatural Motions, Up and Down, Heavy and Light. These hampered while they flattered the intellect; preventing the labour of real investi- gation, by the belief that subjective distinctions represented objective facts. Of what avail was it to learn that besides the four elements, Matter has also its contraries — the hot and the CHAP. VII.] METEOROLOGY, AND MECHANICS. 153 cold, the moist and the dry — these being the principles of generation ? § 138. Such speculations are condemned to the sterile fecundity of disputation, and carry with them no possible enlightenment. I do not say that Aristotle's efforts were in vain. Far from it. The world is the richer for his genius, the wiser from his failures. But he came at a time when the continuous enployment of the Objective Method was next to impossible. He ploughed the unbroken soil, in which others hereafter were to plant the seeds. The conclusion forced upon us, therefore, is that the neglect into which his physical speculations have fallen is entirely justified. The present has absolutely nothing to learn from them, except the historical lesson to be gained from the spectacle of a gigantic mind struggling along a hopeless path./ Must we say the same of his biological speculations ? Let the following chapters furnish a reply. ( 154 ) CHAPTEK VIII. ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. § 139. The eulogies la-risked on Aristotle, as a biologist, even by men wbose own special knowledge might have made them the severest critics, remind us rather of the tone adopted in the Middle Ages, than of the more circumspect and critical language of our own age. "In Aristotle," says Cuvibe, 1 "everything amazes, everything is prodigious, everything is colossal. He lived but sixty-two years, and he was able to make thousands of observations of extreme delicacy, the accuracy of which the most rigorous criticism has never been able to impeach." This rhetorical exaggeration is painfully insincere; no one better than Cuvier could have known the worthlessness of Aristotle's observation on all points which were not open to the common eye; but that servility, too common among Frenchmen, which makes them eager to do homage to every established reputation, made Cuvier forget his own knowledge, and bow his head before the blinding splendour of a great renown. Little less rhetorical is De Blainville, who, though noto- rious for his love of contradiction, dared not whisper a word against "le grand Stagirite." "It is the Natural Sciences," he says, 2 " which owe the most to Aristotle. His plan was 1 CuviEit : Histoire des Sciences Naturelles, 1841, 1., 132. 8 De Blainville et Maupied : Histoire des Sciences de I' Organisation, 1847, 1., 212. CHAP. VIII.] ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. 155 vast and luminous ; he laid the bases of science which will never perish." Isidobe Geottroy St. HilaireI speaking from less acquaintance with Aristotle's writings, is splendid in eulogy. 3 "He is in every branch of knowledge like a master who cultivated that one only. He reaches, he extends the limits of all the sciences, and penetrates to their very depths." Our own countrymen have been somewhat soberer, although even they have written very surprising eulogies ; one of the most amusing being that of the worthy naturalist, Macgillivray, who discovers that Aristotle not only collected a mass of facts, but " elicited from them general principles, the accuracy of many of which might surprise us, if we did not reflect that in this department, at least, he followed the true method by which the physical sciences have in our own times received so vast an augmentation." 4 I have indicated the tone by these examples, partly to justify what might otherwise seem a needless severity in pointing out the deficiences of this wonderful man ; and partly also to justify the large space devoted to his biological writings. The summary treatment which sufficed in the case of the Physics would, in the case of Biology, have carried no conviction. The reader was prepared to find the Physics altogether valueless, but he is told that in the department 3 Isidore St. Hilaire: Histoire Ginirale des liegnes Organiques, 1854, 1., 18 seq. 4 Macgiluvray : Lives of Eminent Zoologists, Edinburgh, 1834, p. 32. Herschel has lent his powerful countenance to the applause of Aristotle's accuracy of observation : Discourse on Natural Philosophy (101). Grant also : Lectures on Comparative Anatomy, in Lancet, October, 1833, p. 90. We shall hereafter see with what justice. Counter-statements may occasionally be met with. Btjonafede cites the example of Burnet, who drew up a list of Aristotle's " puerilities " :— " Stati sano' disse 'O Stagirita : tu per me sarai sempre un cattivo astronome, un teologo peggiore, un pessimo fisiologo." — Delia Storia e della Indole di ogni Filosofia, II., 289 (ed. of Italian Classics, Milan, 1837). And Nizolius, after quoting the assertion of Averrhoes, that in 1500 years no error had been detected in the Stagirite, replies " non multo pauciora vel falsa vel inutilia vel etiam ridicula ab eodem scripts reperiri." — De veris principiis et vera ratione philosophandi, Parma, 1553, p. 6. 156 ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. [CHAP. VIII. of Natural History, Aristotle made important discoveries, anticipated some of the brilliant results of modern research, and laid the " eternal bases " of the Science. Nothing but a detailed examination would suffice to elicit the truth on such points ; and I shrink the less from entering upon these details, because many of them would necessarily find a place somewhere in this History, and this is as good a place as any. § 140. Biology has two grand divisions, statical and dynamical : in common language," Anatomy and Physiology. We have only to reflect how knowledge of the laws of life is necessarily dependent on accurate acquaintance with the structure of living beings, in a word, how Physiology is nothing but " animated Anatomy," as Hallee felicitously called it, to perceive the importance of commencing an examin- ation of Aristotle's biological writings, with a view of his knowledge of structure. § 141. The extent of his survey is amazing, embracing the whole animal kingdom, from sea anemones to man. But of the accuracy of his knowledge, I am compelled, after long and minute study, to form a very different estimate from what is current among critics and historians. 5 Reading his works by the light of modern discovery, we are apt to credit him with all that his words suggest to us ; we come, indeed, upon numerous inaccuracies, and on many statements which imply gross carelessness ; but whenever his language does not palpably betray him, modern readers insensibly fill out his hints with details from their fuller store. On a superficial examination, therefore, he will seem to have given tolerable descriptions ; especially if approached with that disposition to discover marvels which unconsciously determines us in 6 E. g.: — " Les travaux d'Aristote ont fait cesser en grande partie l'ignorance profonde oil l'on gtait sur la structure animale." — Lacth: Histoire tie I'Ana- tomie, Strasbourg, 1815, 1., 61. Yet he proceeds in detail to show that Aristotle really knew very little. CHAP. Till.] ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. 157 our study of ancient writers. But a more unbiassed and impartial criticism will disclose that he has given no single anatomical description of the least value. All that he knew may have been known, and probably was known, without dissection. The casual revelations of the slaughter-house and battle-field, together with the intimations gathered from auguries and embalmments, probably furnished his knowledge of man and the larger animals. I do not assert that he never opened an animal ; on the contrary, it seems highly probable that he had opened many* But I am persuaded that he never dissected one in the careful systematic style necessary for more than a general acquaintance with the positions of the chief organs. He never followed the course of a vessel or a nerve ; never laid bare the origin and insertion of a muscle ; never discriminated the component parts of organs ; never made clear to himself the connection of organs into systems. § 142. In illustration of what was meant by reading his works in the light of modern discovery, let us take the idea of the homologies of the skeleton, which he is said to have originated in a comparison of the fore and hind limbs. The analogy. was certainly noticed by him. But it is too obvious to have escaped attention. To make it fruitful, to demon- strate that what seemed to be an analogy, really was a homology, and expressed an identity of composition in the two limbs, it was necessary that this vague idea should be carried into the comparison of bone with bone, muscle with muscle, nerve with nerve, vessel with vessel. Aris- totle as may be supposed never attempted anything like this;; nor did any one attempt it, till Vicq d'Azye; and since then, Homology has become an important branch of anatomical research. 6 When we now read Aristotle's vague 6 Vicq d'Azyr : Mimoires sur les rapports entre les usages et la structure des quatre extr&miUs dans I'homme et dans les quadruples, in his (Euvres, 1805, IV., 315. Compare Owen ; On the Homologies of the Vertebrate 158 ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. [CHAP. Till. and meagre account, we read into it all that moderns have taught us. But if, disengaging the mind from such sources of mis- conception, we inquire what he really did know, we find it amounts to nothing beyond the result of casual and careless inspection. It would be unfair to compare his observation with that of the patient Swammerdamm, or that of Lyonet, who accurately describes the four thousand and forty-one muscles of the caterpillar ; 7 but it is strictly just to compare his observation with that of Galen, whose anatomical know- ledge, imperfect as it was, rested upon careful dissection. On such a comparison, his inferiority is not simply inferiority in degree, it is inferiority in kind. § 143. Aristotle knew nothing of the muscles, not even of their existence. He knew very little indeed of two or three nerves, and absolutely nothing of the nervous system. He did not distinguish between arteries and veins. 8 Thus the three most important parts of the organism, animal, psychical, and vegetal, were wholly hidden from him. Naturally, the less obvious parts were not better known. According to Lauth, he described Well the structure of men and animals, whenever he could observe the entire body, or the body Skeleton, 1848; where, however, the homologies are merely shown in the hony structure, without reference to the soft parts; and an elaborate memoir by Ger- vais: Comparaison des membres chez les verUbris, in the Annales des Sciences Naturelles, 1853, p. 21. Since then M. Martins has published a curious and striking memoir in the Memoires de I' Acad, de Montpellier, 1857, III., endeavour- ing to prove that the humerus is identical with the femur, but twisted 180 deg. on its axis, whereas the femur is straight. " Ainsi les systemes musculaires, arteriels et nerveux du bras et de l'avant bras confirment l'idee d'une torsion de l'humerus, car tous sont disposes comme ils le seraient sur un femur dont les condyles auraient execute un mouvement de rotation de 180 deg., la t6te restant immobile fixee dans la cavite cotylo'ide." — Archives Gintrales de Medecine, Oct., 1858, p. 481. 7 Lyonet : Traite" anatomique de la chenille qui ronge le bois de saule, La Haye, 1760, p. 584. 8 He refuted the old error of the head being the origin of the bloodvessels, and rightly assigned the heart as the origin. Thielmann: Veterum opinion, de angiol. atque sang, motu, 1832, p. 28. He also first distinguished the aorta from the vena cava, but went no further. CHAP. VIII.] ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. 159 opened by incisions ; but he was without the art of isolating the organs, and he erred in describing them, because to know them properly, we must begin by dissecting them. 9 It is further noticeable that many of his statements are wholly without foundation, in fact, sometimes even without the super- ficial appearance of it ; and as they could not have originated in misinterpretation of observed appearances, they were pro- bably assumed merely to suit his views. § 144. After this, it seems idle to consider the oft-mooted question whether he dissected the human body. If the answer should be affirmative, it would be still more damaging to his reputation, since it would render many of his errors unpardonable. But a close scrutiny of the evidence forces a negative answer ; and, as opinions seem to be still divided on the subject, 10 we may here examine the evidence. § 145. It is now generally accepted as beyond dispute that 9 Conhingitts, who denies that Aristotle dissected man, declares he was most expert in the dissection of animals : " ut animalium omnem rem nemo etiam illo vel fusius vel etiam accuratius prosequutus sit." — Intro, in artem Medicam, 1687, p. 147. Casteixi declares Plato and Aristotle to have been supreme anatomists: " praestantissimos anatomicos fuisse." — De optima Medico, 1637, p. 36. It is needless to cite others ; even glaring errors were either de- fended because Aristotle had put them forth, or, if refuted, were refuted tenderly. B perche" egli e Aristotele, besogna Credergli, ancorche dica la menzogna, is a couplet quoted by Redi.— Esperienze intorno alia generazione degl' insetti, in the Florentine ed. of his Opuscoli, 1858, p. 191. 10 As early as 1687, Conringius pronounced decidedly against it. " Aris- toteli, quamvis in hrutorum sectionibus peritissimus f uerit, humani tamen cor- poris insignem adeo notitiam non habuit, si sane partes internas et in ipso corpore delitescentes spectes."— Op. cit, p. 153. On the other hand, Barchusen: De Medicines origine et progressu, 1723, after citing two or three examples, says: " Hsec et similia abunde probant Anatomen quoque in hominibus sevo Aristotelis institutam, et non Herophilum, quern Tertullianus false appellat dicterio lanium, qui sexcentos exsecuit," p. 127. Haller, as cited by Harles, is of the same opinion, which Harles : Geschichte der Hirn-und Nervenlehre im Alterthume, 1801, p. 56, also adopts. Sprengel: Geschichte der Arzneihunde, 1821, 1, 456, is dubious, but inclined to the affirmative. Antonio Cocchi is emphatic in the negative, but advances no evidence.— Discorso intorno VAna- tomia. Opere,Milan,1824,I.,29. Portal: Histoiredel'anatomieetdelachirurgie, 1770, says, " II y a toute apparence qu'il n'a jamais disseque des hommes," I., 41. 160 ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. [CHAP. VIII. his predecessor, Hippocbates, never dissected the human body, and the grounds of this opinion are, first, the known feelings of the Greeks respecting the sacredness of the dead ; and secondly, the ignorance of human anatomy exhibited in his works. 11 These are also the grounds for a similar opinion in the case of Aristotle. I. — The Feeling of the Greeks. § 146. The laws were very stringent respecting immediate burial. In Athens the Demarch who allowed a corpse to remain a single day unburied was subject to a fine of 1,000 drachmas ; and victorious generals had been condemned to death because they neglected to bury the slain. The whole of that tragic masterpiece, the Antigone, turns upon the sacredness of the dead, and the necessity, higher than imperial commands, of immediate burial. The popular feel- ing against dissection remains energetic even in our own day ; and in future chapters of our History we shall see the struggles of Science against this horror at the very idea of a human body being violated by the scalpel. With the Greeks this feeling was intensified by their belief that the released soul wandered sadly on the shores of Styx during the whole period that the body remained unburied. It is exceedingly doubtful that Aristotle would have braved such feelings merely for the sake of more accurate knowledge of details ; doubtful because his was not a fierce rebellious spirit rising against the prejudices of his age ; doubtful because the Asclepiads drew 11 See Conrinqius: Op. cit., p. 152. Barchuskn: Op. cit., p. 126, consi- ders the point doubtful. Hallee has a little paper in his Opuscula Anatomica, Gottingen, 1751, p. 133, entitled, " Quod hunrana corpora secuerit Hippocrates," in which he argues that Hippocrates dissected man and not monkeys, because monkeys were rare and costly in price, and are nowhere mentioned by him. Yet in his oration, " de Amoenitate Anatomes," in the same volume, p. 330, he says — " Audaciores Grasci et ingenio ad inquirendam yeritatem excitato, ante tempora Ptolemcei Philadelphi, aut nunquam aut rarissime hominum corpora adtigerunt." See the whole ^question satisfactorily argued by Gbunkb: Analecta ad antiquitates medicos, 1774, p. 98, seq. CHAP. VIII.] ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. 161 their knowledge of anatomy from animals, and were contented with it ; 1£ and doubtful because he, who nowhere shows any pressing anxiety about the accuracy of the facts he collects, but is quite willing to accept those ready to his hand, would have wanted the powerful fascination which alone can .suppress the shuddering repulsion that keeps men from the dissecting-room. § 147. The fascination must be strong, for the disgust is powerful. Our senses are affected by the sickening scent of a corrupting body, by the painful sight of bloodstained instru- ments, and the scattered shreds of a dismembered corpse. There is also a deeper moral disgust, peculiarly affecting to imaginative minds. The spectacle of death is always accom- panied by a certain awe. At the bedside, or on the battlefield, no gazer remains unmoved : pity, and a sense of community in death, steal over every mind when unshaken by violent emotions. How much more painful the dissecting-room, where the corpse is untended by affection, and unpitied by strangers ! none of the sanctity of death surrounds it; none of the tenderness of love watches over it ; none of the ceremonials of respect defend it. There it lies, naked, and alien alike from affection and respect, flung upon a table in oblivious disregard of its having once been the temple of a human life. It is no longer that temple ; it is not even a corpse ; it has become a subject. 12 While in Rome I read, in Emil Beaun's Handbook of the Ruins and Museums of Home, 1856, p. 21], a reference to two anatomical figures in the Vatican sculpture gallery, which afforded " a practical contradiction to the widely diffused opinion that the ancients did not found their knowledge of anatomy on the study of the human body." This sent me to the Vatican with some curiosity. As usual, Bbaun was speaking in utter ignorance. The figures show no science. The skeleton of the thorax is extremely rude ; the ribs are all anchylosed. The viscera, exhibited in 1 the second figure, seem to have been modelled from memory, and the memory ill-instructed; the heart is egg-shaped, its position vertical, the apex attached to the diaphragm ; there is no aorta; no bronchi; the lungs arise immediately from the larynx; there is no pleura; and, in short, the whole representation is contemptible. If Bbaun is right in his conjecture that these figures, " unique of their kind, were probably originally in some temple of JEsculapius," it says little for the Asclepiads. 11 162 ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. [CHAP. VIII. Yet all these sources of repulsion have been, and daily are, overcome. Men sit patiently for many hours, inhaling the nauseous odours, exploring with their scalpel the winding intricacies of vein and nerve, steadfast, patient, victorious. They have suppressed the suggestions of the scene by firmly fixing their minds on the object of their task. It is not because their sensibilities have become obtuse, but because their power of abstraction has overcome the solicitations of suggestion. They have not become hardened; they have simply learned to concentrate their thoughts upon a definite pursuit. Were it not for this we might wonder that men did not consent to remain for ever unenlightened on the marvels of their organization, rather than acquire the knowledge by so repulsive a route. 13 But the passion for knowledge '« im- perious. It urges men to surmount all obstacles, to brave the prejudices of others after suppressing their own — to brave human laws, to rob the grave in the dead of night, and pursue their study in secrecy and peril. This passion furnishes the power of abstraction ; and hence it is that anatomy has been pursued by poets, theologians, and even women. Goethe, for example, a nature of the keenest sensibility, who could not bear to look upon Schilleb dead, even he was an anatomist. Haller, one of the great anatomists, was early and late a poet of some mark. Bossuet was not repelled from the study ; he wrote an anatomical tractate. Anna Manzolina made those wax preparations of every part of the body which became the pride of Bologna ; and for these she had herself 13 " Sans doute il repugne a, l'homme de voir d'aussi prSs son neant, il fttit ce triste spectacle, et il consent a s'ignorer lui memo, plutot que de s'affliger a la vue de tant de miseres." — Vicq d'Aztr: CEuvres, IV., 229. " Natura mortis horrorem nobis impressit, et contnbernio cadaverum nihil tristius est." Haller: De amcenitate anatomes. Opuscula, 1751, p. 327. " To converse with dead and putrid carcases were, one would think, a shocking and odious employment, yet some anatomists dote upon it: and I must own its usefulness has greatly enamoured me with dissection." — Boyle: Ore the Usefulness of Phi- losophy. Works, by Shaw. 1738. 1., 5. CHAP. VIII.] ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. 163 held the scalpel, "con virile e forte animo, e con incredibile costanza." w § 148. But Aristotle, wanting the imperious desire, was little likely to have overcome this repulsion, and still less likely to have braved the prejudices of his contemporaries for an object of which he did not rightly estimate the value. It is true that human dissection was practised in Alexandria some centuries later, under the Ptolemies, and the idea is not, therefore, wholly inadmissible that Aristotle may have privately dissected. 15 Not wholly inadmissible, yet wholly without evidence. All the evidence runs counter to it. Hippocrates did not, nor did Galen, four hundred and fifty years afterwards ; l6 yet both Hippocrates and Galen had incomparably more need of such knowledge for their purposes than Aristotle had for his. Although Aristotle never once intimates that he had dissected man, and, as we shall see, his mistakes exclude such a suppo- sition, there is one casual sentence which I have met with that might bear this construction : — in the De Partibus (I. 5, 645), defending the study against those who despised it, he says : — " "We cannot, without great reluctance, behold the parts of which man is composed, such as blood, flesh, bones, vessels, and the like ; but we must regard them as the "Medici: Compendio Storico detta Scuola Anatomica di Bologna, 1857, p. 357. 15 Sprbngel suggests that he may have done so in Chalcis. — Gesch. der Arzneikunde, 1821, 1., 456. 16 This also has been a disputed point ; but I consider it conclusively settled by the testimony of Galen's editor and translator, Dakemberg, who says that he has repeated every one of Galen's dissections, which has convinced him that only animals were employed. " Galien repete sans cesse qu'il decrit particulierement le singe comme etant l'animal le plus voisin de l'homme; son seul tort c'est d'avoir presque toujours conclu du singe a l'homme/" — CEuvres de Galien, Paris, 1854, I., xiv. The resistance of scholars against this truth, when first published by Vesalitjs, is singularly like the resistance of theologians to the revelations of Astronomy and Geology. The Galenists first denied the truth of what Vesalius affirmed ; when public demonstrations rendered this denial ridiculous, they fled for refuge to two explanations — 1st, that the text of Galen was corrupt ; 2nd, that the human organism had become different since Galen's days. 11—2 164 ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. [CHAP. VIM, architect regards the wood, stones, lime, &c, with which he builds." This would furnish a strong presumption were it not contrary to all the other evidence. As it is, I leave it without attempting to weaken it by another interpretation. II. — Special Ignorance. § 149. We have his own confession that the internal anatomy of man is the least known, and must therefore be studied in animals. 17 Although this does not imply that nothing was directly known of the internal parts, it very clearly implies that such knowledge was not to be gained through dissection. And the nature of the mistakes he has made points in the same direction. Some of these errors may indeed admit of a favourable interpretation; for example, he describes the lungs of man as not double, like those of oviparous animals, but single (liovo^vri) like the heart ; 18 yet elsewhere he says the lungs are always double, though least so in man. 19 Again when he describes the uterus as double, the error is manifest. It is double in the embryo ; double in many animals, such as the hare or rabbit; but even in monkeys there is only a trace, which reveals the original separation into two equal halves. In the human female this trace has disappeared. If Aristotle had ever seen an uterus, how came he to make so obvious a blunder ? Two explanations are admissible : — 1°, either he means the two ovaries (which are always by him undis- tinguished from the uterus), to represent this twofold nature ; or 2°, the uterus which came under his observation may have been one of the rare specimens of abnormal duplicity ; from this he may have concluded that normally the uterus was 17 Hist. An., I., 13, 494. dyvoiara yap Ian jiaKiara rd t&v dvBpuirmv, Hurt fiei irpig ra tuiv aWuiv Zimov dvdyovrag ckottCiv. 18 Be Parlibus, III., 7, 669. 19 Hist. An., I.;,13, 495. CHAP. VIII.] ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. 165 double. I think, however, it is more probable that he had never seen one at all ; and that his statement is simply an a priori conclusion. He thought the uterus was the analogue of the testes, and these being double, the uterus must also be double. 20 § 150. Some other statements do not admit such pal- liation. What are we to think of the assertion that the heart lies higher than the lungs, above them, avuripio rov 7t\ev- fiovoc, where the trachea bifurcates? 21 Could he ever have seen the human kidney, which he describes as lobed like that of an ox ? ^ It is no answer to say that the kidneys are lobed in the foetus ; 23 since all trace of the lobular form disappears about the fifth month, and he is not likely to have examined a foetus younger than this; moreover, he distinctly states it of the adult, not the foetus. § 150 a. His description of the spleen is inaccurate, though not so glaringly inaccurate as that of the kidney. Ves alius notices the error of attributing only eight ribs to man, as a proof that he was not speaking from direct inspection. 2 * § 150 b. He speaks of the heart having only three chambers; whereupon Lauth remarks that he only judged of its structure from the external aspect : M an error, since he mentions its septa and its tendons. Those who maintain a Be Gen. An., I., 3, 716. 21 Hist. An., I., 14, 495. Be Part, III., 6, 669. 22 Be Part., in., 9. 671, 23 " Je l'ai vu quelquefois forme de huit, plus souvent de six, ou de quatre petits reins de chaque cote."— Serkes: Precis d'Anatomie transcendante, 1824, p. 101. It is amusing to find Barchhsen apparently citing this very case of the kidney as a proof of Aristotle having dissected man. — De Medicines Origine, 1723, p. 127, note. 24 Vebalius: Opera Omnia, ed. Boebhaave and Albinus, 1725, p. 76. Sonnenbubg: ZoologUch-Kritische Bemerhungen zu Aristot. Thiergeschichte, Bonn, 1857, p. 5, adopts the convenient hypothesis of a corrupt text in this case, although he knows that the error was repeated by Punt. 85 Lauth: Histoire de VAnatomie, 1815, 1., 62. There is an amusing note on this point in the commentary of Blazius to Wesslikg's Syntagma Ana- tomicum, Amsterdam, 1666, p. 150. 166 AKISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. [CHAP. VIII. that he must have practised human dissection, refer to his mention of the heart not being vertically placed, but inclin- ing a little to the left (§ 398). But we learn from Galen that this was the vulgar opinion, derived, as he says, from the fact that the beating of the heart is felt under the left breast. 26 § 150 c. But perhaps the climax of inaccuracy is to be found in what he says of the brain, namely that it is bloodless, and that it does not extend to the back part of the skull, "which is quite empty" — assertions several times repeated. Without insisting on the fact that more blood goes to the brain than to almost any other organ 27 (which Aristotle had no means of knowing), it is enough to say that casual inspection of an uncooked brain reveals the presence of abundant blood, even the white matter being studded with red spots. 28 But in the cooked brain (or in the brain of fish) no such appearance presents itself; whence we conclude that he had never seen the human brain, since he could not have seen it cooked, and in the fresh state its blood is apparent. 29 As to the surprising and unintelligible assertion that there is no brain in the back part of the skull, if it does not prove, as Poetal remarks, 26 Galen : De usu Partium, lib. VI., ch. 2, p. 415, ed. Kuhn, 1822. This opinion he considers to be erroneous, a clear proof that he had not dissected the human body. It should be noted that Galen conceived the heart as having only two chamhers, the ventricles; the auricles were regarded merely as accessories. See Dakembekg: (Euvresde Galien, I., 400. 27 One-fifth of the whole amount, according to the estimate of Hallee : Elementa Physiotogia, Lausanne, 1762, IV., 141 ; and one-third, according to Malpighi: De Cerebro, p. 6 in Opera Omina, 1686. 88 " Dum cerebri portiones abscindis, ait, ex Plempio, Moebius, p. 592, adverte guttulas et punctula sanguinis, in cerebri substantia, et disce Aristo- telem non vera docerc dum scribit cerebrum nihil venarum in se continere." — Blazius : in comment. Wessling Syntagma, p. 214. In his anxiety to defend the Stagirite from so gross an error, Blazius adds: " Ast qua ratione proba- bunt arterias non seque sanguinem hunc exhibere in dissecto tali cerebro quam venas." 29 " Donde si raccoglie che Aristotele non anatomizzd mai alcun cadavere umano, e che la sua notomia e la sua erudizione nella storia degli animali fu molto sotto il mediocre."— Buonafede: Delia Istoria e della indole di ogni filosofia, Milan, 1837, II., 209. CHAP. Till.] ARISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. 167 that he had never opened a skull; 50 it proves that he observed carelessly. § 150 d. Examples of this glaring kind have been chosen, because mistakes which casual inspection would have prevented are more illustrative than any enumeration of errors on obscurer points. They prove that Aristotle could never have dissected a human subject, perhaps had never seen one laid open ; or else they prove that his inspection was careless, his memory trea- cherous, and his anatomical knowledge extremely superficial. § 151. Nevertheless he is said to have made discoveries, and we even read that he first discovered the nerves. The learned Haeles, in his valuable contributions to the history of ancient neurology, 31 has satisfactorily shown that no anatomist before Aristotle had the slightest knowledge of the nerves ; no one seems to have suspected the existence of such organs. Every one of the passages which later writers (Galen in- cluded) have cited, prove on close inspection that the words vtvpov and to. vtvpa refer to tendons, ligaments, aponeuroses, or even muscles, and never mean nerves. This misleading use of the word was continued long after it had come to be applied to the structures now designated as nerves. Galen did not escape the confusion, and his suc- cessors forgot altogether the original use of the term. 32 It 30 Portal : Histoire d'Anat. et de la Chirurgie, 1770, 1., 42. Scaliger attempts to palliate this by saying, " tametsi multa medulla est in quibusdam, caput iis magnum adeo,ut inanis esse cavitas Tideatur;" but Sohnenburg, in citing this passage in his Zoologish-Kritische Bemerhungen zu Aristoteles Thiergeschichte, Bonn, 1857, p. 9, truly says that Aristotle expressly declares it to be and not to seem empty. Moreover, in point of fact, it does not seem empty. Sonnen- bdrg's defence is that by the back part of the head Aristotle meant the neck. It is possible that by Iviov neck was meant ; but this does not render the passage less inaccurate. The neck is not more empty than the skull. 31 Harles: Versuch einer Geschichte der Hirn-und-Nervenlehre, 1801, 20-54. 32 Vesalius notices the mistake: Opera, 1725, p. 13; and Kohler: Aristoteles de Molluscis cephakpodibus, 1820, p. 4, remarks that even in our own time tendons and nerves have been mistaken for each other, alluding to the tendinous filaments which surround the sesophagus of the Holothuriae, and which Spix and others have supposed to be nerves; the real nervous system discovered by Moller lies above these. 168 AEISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. [CHAP. VIII. still exists in the common language of metaphor. "We speak of a nervous arm, nervous courage, and a man of nerve, an unnerved condition, "hardy as the Nemsean lion's nerve." § 152. In commencing our inquiry therefore we must begin by distinctly recognizing the fact that when Aristotle uses the word vtvpov he does not mean nerve ; 33 otherwise we shall fall into the error of Galen, frequently repeated by suc- cessors, of attributing to Aristotle the very gross absurdity of deriving all the nerves from the heart. 34 If therefore it be true, as affirmed, that he is the first anatomist by whom the nerves were mentioned, by what name are we to recognize them ? By that of iropoi or ducts (tubes, canals), this term being employed by him to designate the optic, olfactory, and auditory nerves. Galen is in error when he attributes this to Eudemus and Heeophilus. 35 The word is noticeable ; but let not the reader jump to the conclusion that it indicates any knowledge on Aristotle's part of the tubular structure of nerves, first described by Leetj- wenhoee, and made familiar to all Europe by Eheenbeeg. 36 33 See this point conclusively settled in Philippson: SXjj dv9pwirivti, Berlin, 1831, p. 12; in Harles: Op. cit, 65; and in Sprengel, I, 456. There are, indeed, a few passages where the word vtvpov correctly indicates a nerve; but it is evident that in these he mistook the real nature of the part indicated. 34 An absurdity which CiESALPmcs undertook to defend: Peripateticarum gucestienum, Venice, 1571, lib. V., ch. 3, p. 106, scornfully noticed by Tatjrel- lus in his attack on Ca3salpinus : Alpes Ccesa, 1650, p. 864. Sommering set up the defence that Aristotle wished to indicate " cor mediante cerebro nervorum principium esse:" De basi encepkali, 1778, p. 8. Galileo tells a story of having been present when a Venetian anatomist demonstrated that the origin of the nerves was in the brain and not the heart, and then demanded of an Aris- totelian what he had to say; whereupon the philosopher, after a pause, replied, " Voi mi avete fatto veder questa cosa talmente aperta, e sensata, che quando il testo d'Aristotele non fusse in contrario, che apcrtamente dice i nervi nascer dal cuore, bisognerebbe per forza confessarla per vera." — Opere, Milan, 1811, XL, 265. 35 De libris propriis, chap. HI., cited by Darekberg. 36 Leetiwenhoek: Select Works, II., 303. Ehrenberg: BeobacHung einer bisher unbekannten Structur des Seelenorgans in the Abhandhngen der Akad. der Wissenschaften zu Berlin, 1834, p. 665. Li this memoir Aristotle is credited with the discovery of three cerebral nerves; but no mention is made of his having called them tubes. CHAP. Vin.] AEISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. 169 On the contrary, he probably observed the readiness with which the semifluid contents can be pressed out of the tough neurilemma, and hence concluded that the nerves were ducts. 37 The tubular structure, of which moderns speak, is that of the seemingly solid fibres which compose the nerves; and this is visible only under the microscope. § 153. Although it is certain that Aristotle first called attention to the existence of the nerves which have their origin at the base of the brain, it is very far from certain that he had any suspicion of their being special structures, differing from all other ducts ; and it is indisputable that he never classified them with the other nerves. I am therefore dis- posed to accept the view of Philippson, that iropoi never meant organs tantamount to " nerves," but simply brain- ducts, in nowise discriminated from other ducts, except by their position. 38 "We find the word duct used for the channel of any fluid except blood ; it even designates the ureter and the intestine. But I have sought in vain for any intimation that these brain-ducts were special structures. If, therefore, on the one hand, 7ropoe is a word of very general signification, and, on the other, no special signification is assigned to it when used' to designate the optic and olfactory nerves, how can we credit Aristotle with the discovery of these nerves ? He described the course of these ducts, not accurately indeed, 37 The idea of the optic nerves being tubes, or ducts, was accepted by Aticenna and Roger Bacon. I am not aware at what period it was relin- quished. Vesalius declares that he can establish no difference between nerves founded on their being hollow, since he had never yet seen one that was so. — Opera, ed. Boerhaave and Albinus, p. 361. In spite of this the opinion con- tinued, and even in Wessling's Syntagma, 1666, the optic nerve is said to be more porous than any other, p. 220. Comp. Fabkicius ab Aquapendente : Opera Omnia, 1738, 1., 193. Willis : Opera Omnia, Geneva, 1676, 1., Ill, has no mention of ducts. 38 Philippson: vXn dvBpwmvri, p. 15-21. Trendelenbekg also says: " Medici iropovg nervos esse volunt . . . sed ab Aristotele tarn angustis terminis circumscripti non sunt. Ductus enim sunt, ut quicunque est finis, con- junctionem et quasi partium commercium adjuverit." — Notes to his ed. of the Be Anima, 1833, p. 162. Comp. ibid., p. 396. 170 AEISTOTLE'S ANATOMY. [CHAP. Vin. but sufficiently to establish his claim to this discovery ; but he never suspected the part they played in vision and smelling. He thought the optic duct nourished the eye. 39 This settles the question. In like manner, although he describes the olfactory and auditory nerves, there is overwhelming proof that he did not suppose them to be connected with smelling and hearing. 40 We conclude, then, that although he knew something of the anatomical distribution of three of the nerves, he knew absolutely nothing of the nervous system ; and as he likewise knew very little of the viscera, and of the muscular system nothing, 41 it is clear that his anatomical knowledge was too slight and inaccurate to serve as the basis of sound physiology. 39 De Gen. An., II., 6; Phimppson : Op. cit., 18; Harles: Op. cit., 113. Roger Bacon says, " nemis tamen iste in quo est hasc via humoris vitrei se diffundit." — Opus Mujus, p. 203. 40 Harles confesses this. Comp. also Phimppson, p. 19. 41 Fabricius ab Aqtjapendehte was one of the first to make this evident. — Opera Anaiomica, p. 383, ( 171 ) CHAPTER IX. ARISTOTLE'S PHYSIOLOGY. § 154. To explain the phenomena of Life, without having previously mastered the facts of anatomy, is as hopeless as to attempt an explanation of the action of a watch, in ignorance of springs, escapements, and wheels, merely from seeing it wound up, and hearing it tick. Nothing hut vague unassured guesses can he formed. Of this kind is the physiology of Aristotle. All the complex phenomena which are still hut imperfectly explained, even now that anatomy is accurately and extensively studied, aided by the minute researches of chemists and physicists, were by him interpreted from superficial obser- vation and a priori theories. Observation was necessarily incomplete ; the broad gaps left, instead of being filled up by patient research, were bridged over by considerations of Final Causes, or by analogies often fanciful, never verified. Here, as elsewhere, we find him wholly wanting in the vigilance required for testing the accuracy of the data from which he reasoned ; and very often employing great ingenuity in attempting to explain a fact which did not exist. We shall meet with many examples ; but the following is amusing no less than instructive. § 155. " If a woman, suffering from scarlet fever," he says, " look at herself in a mirror, the surface of the mirror 1 172 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSIOLOGY. [CHAP. IX. will become suffused with a kind of bloody mist; 1 and this mist, if the mirror be quite new, cannot be rubbed off without difficulty." This was doubtless one of the old woman's tales current in his day. He never thought of ascertaining the truth of the statement, but proceeded to explain it, which he does in various ways. "The cause," he says, "is that the eye not only receives the impressions from without, but reacts upon external objects, setting them in motion. The eye is full of blood-vessels, and during the fever, the blood being in commotion and inflammation, the eye, though we cannot detect it, is agitated and feverish ; the air is moved by this, and conveys the motion to the surface of the mirror. The polished surface of the mirror is very sensitive to all motions, and hence they become visible upon it." § 156. Having gained this glimpse into his mode of inter- pretation, let us briefly review his opinions on the chief vital phenomena. The obvious facts of the conversion of food into blood, and of blood into the substance of the body, were early known. But neither the anatomical nor the chemical knowledge neces- sary to our approximate theory of Digestion were familiar to him; consequently, he did not even suspect the order of changes which are impressed Upon food in the mouth, the stomach, and the intestines ; still less did he know the in- fluence of the liver, spleen, and lungs, in the final elaboration of the food. He thought that the food passed into the stomach, and was there cooked by the animal heat. He understood that food must become liquid before it is assimi- lable, since blood is its final product. Food is made liquid 1 yivtrai ri ImwoKije tov ivoirrpov olov ve^tXij «l/iar(Mijc. — De Insomniis, II., 459. In the original the occasion is not scarlet fever ; the variation, however, leaves the argument unaffected. The idea is repeated, and, as usual, exaggerated by Pliny/: " Acrescunt superventu musta, sterilescunt tactas fruges, moriuutnr insita, exuruntur hortorum germina, et fructus arborum quibus insedere, deci- dunt." — Hist. Nat, VII., 13. Even the more sceptical Roger Bacon accepts the notion.— Opus Majus, Vcnet., 1750, p. 65. CHAP. IX.] ARISTOTLE'S PHYSIOLOGY. 173 in the stomach and intestines, and this liquid steams up through the small vessels of the mesentery, which lead to the larger vessels, and thence to the heart : there it ceases to be ichor, and becomes blood. Nature acts like an economist, giving the best parts of the food to the noblest parts of the body ; as the freemen eat the prime portions, the slaves eat the inferior portions, and the rest is thrown to the dogs, so the nobler organs — flesh and the senses — receive the sweetest, and the baser organs— bones, hair, &c— receive the bitterest parts. He suspected that the liver and spleen played some part in digestion, but what part he never distinctly stated. From the heart the veins carry the cooked blood to every part of the body. The veins become smaller and smaller, until they are too small for the passage of the blood ; through these, therefore, it can find no egress, only the excretion of moisture (rijc vypag iKfiaSoe) which we call sweat (icSpwTa), and this especially when the body is warmed and the veins open wider (§ 476). This latter statement reads very like the modern idea of the blood parting with certain of its principles which ooze through the walls of the capillaries ; but such was not really his meaning. He knew nothing of the blood gushing through these capillaries and returning to the heart. He imagined that the vessels terminated in the flesh, and there the blood became flesh. Nor is this idea quite banished yet. Many physiologists imagine — or speak as if they imagined — that the organs are formed by the blood ; whereas embryology discloses that many organs exist before the blood has appeared. Instead of saying that the organs are formed by the blood, we ought to say they are nourished by it. They draw' their material from the organic plasma ; and blood, when once it has appeared, is carried byjj this plasma. It is equally true to reverse the proposition, and say the organs form the blood, since blood is affected by two different influences, 174 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSIOLOGY. [CHAP. IX. one impressed by nutritive material, and one by the organs through which it passes. § 157. Although the vascular system was altogether mis- conceived by him, yet the manifest importance of the blood leads us to expect to find all his theories having an intimate dependence on the heart, which he regarded as the centre of Life, Sensation, Motion, and Heat. It is the great cooking apparatus. 2 The blood, in being cooked, causes an expansion, or steaming, which makes the heart expand, and with it the chest expands. Into the space thus formed the cold air rushes, and by its coldness contracts the chest, which again contracts the heart. These alternate expansions and contractions cause the pulsation of the heart and blood- vessels. The blood is always formed in the heart, never returns there, but is converted into flesh, fat, bones, &c. As the great source of Heat, the heart must also be the great source of Motion, for heat is motive. Moreover, it is full of tendons, and it is the tendons which move the limbs. That Aristotle should have made the heart the origin of the tendons (vevpa) is a striking example of theoretical anatomy in flagrant contradiction with even casual inspection. § 158. On Kespiration he has written a separate treatise. In it he complains that his predecessors left unasked the question why animals breathe, or else answered it from very insufficient observation. He notices the common error of supposing that all animals respire — an error, by the way, 2 " The diastole, or dilatation, is made by the blood boyling or swelling by the spirits within it : and so Aristotele's opinion concerning the pulsation of the heart (namely, that it is made by a kinde of ebullition,) is in some sort true. For as in milk set upon fire, and in beere, we see dayly a fermentation, working, or intumescence; so is it in the pulse of the heart, in which the blood, as by a kinde of fermentation working up is distended, and then ebbs or falls down againe." — Harvey: Anatomical JExercitations concerning the Generation of Living Creatures, 1653, LI., p. 276. By Swammerdamm this idea of the heart as a great cooking centre was retained unhesitatingly. He thought the blood which returned to the heart was that which had not been competent to nourish the body, and returned to be re-cooked — urn aufs neue gekocht zu werden.— Bibel der Natur., 1752, p. 54 (written a century earlier). CHAP. IX.] ARISTOTLE'S PHYSIOLOGY. 175 from which few moderns are free — an error which arises from the latitude given to the word " Eespiration," used not to designate the act of breathing — an act compounded of two distinct yet dependent processes, inspiration and expiration — but to designate the ultimate fact of an exchange of gases taking place between the blood and the atmosphere. It is superfluous to say that this was unknown to Aristotle ; the existence of gases was unsuspected. But had he known it, he would have been justified in protesting against the con- fusion of this general property possessed by all living tissues, of exchanging carbonic acid for oxygen, with the special function of respiration possessed only by a respiratory appa- ratus of organs. It is only by an abusive laxity of language that we apply one term to acts so markedly distinct as : — l.^The inspiration and expiration of air, in animals with lungs. 2. The muscular movements which wash the gills with water, in some animals with branchiae. 3. The simple bathing of the whole surfaces with air or water in all other animals. It is true that in all three, the ultimate fact is the aeration of the nutritive fluid ; the exchange of carbonic acid for oxygen. But this community of end does not efface the differences in the functions by which it is attained. Aristotle knew that there was a community of end, which he thought was a cooling process ; and difficult as it is to. draw absolute lines of demarcation he was on the whole justified in assert- ing that Eespiration belonged only to animals with lungs. "If fish breathe," he says, "they must expire the air at the same moment that they draw in the water — which is absurd." He thought that no air entered the fish's body : an error, but his proof was not contemptible. If you place an animal under water, he says, bubbles of air will rise. Now, as none rise from fish, it is evident that they contain no air. The existence of air in the water, and the passage of the oxygen from that air into the blood, were unknown to him. Galen, who knew that the water contained air, also 176 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSIOLOGY. [CHAP. IX. knew that the gills supplied the place of lungs ; the little holes, which he supposed them to have, admitted the passage of air, though excluding the water. 3 If we regard Aristotle's theory of respiration historically, it is admirable. Indeed, no important improvement was made on it until the discovery of the circulation changed the whole aspect of the problem, which the discovery of the gases was still further to modify.* § 158 a. He thought that the fact of fish dying when removed from the water into the air was a proof that they did not breathe, since they gape like suffocated animals. Diogenes explained this as due to the fact that fish out of water receive too much air, whereas in the water they have no more than is needful. This Aristotle calls a foolish explanation, and adds, that were it true, we should observe it of terrestrial animals ; but who ever saw an animal suffo- cated because it had too much air? 5 Men fall into such 3 Galen : De Usu Partium, VI., 9, 443, ed. Kuhn. 4 Up to the time of Harvey the theory remained undisturbed, as may be seen in Fabrictus ab Aquapbndente: De liespiratione et ejus instrumentis, Opera, 1738, p. 161. The absurd criticisms of Severinus: Antiperipatias de respiratione piscium diatriba, 1661, shows the immense superiority of the Stagirite. In spite of Galen and Kondelet (who had shown that fish breathe the air in the water), we find Cardan, the most learned physician of his age, declaring most positively that fish do not breathe air. — De varietate rerum, Lugduni, 1580, lib. VII., cap. xxxvii., p. 289. (The elaborate and interesting work by Morley: The Life of Cardan, 1854, presents a curious picture of the literary life at that period.) • 5 The reason why fish die out of water is still awaiting an answer. I instituted numerous experiments which disproved the explanation pro- pounded by Flourens, namely, that the weight of the leaflets composing the gills differs but slightly from that of water, so that the least movement suffices to float them, by which their surfaces are thoroughly bathed with water. In the air , the difference between the weight of the leaflets and that of the air causes the gills to collapse j thus, instead of the leaflets floating free in the air, they are pressed together, and thus an insufficient amount of blood gets aerated; Annates des Sciences Naturelles, 1830, p. 5. This, however, is only one cause. When I kept the leaflets separated, and their whole surfaces exposed to the air, the fish died almost as rapidly as before; but when I suffered the gills to collapse, and prevented the rapid evaporation from the whole surface of their bodies, the fish lived three times longer than similar fish unprotected. Dr. CHAP. IX.] ARISTOTLE'S PHYSIOLOGY. 177 errors, he says, because they disregard internal structure, and do not ask what is nature's aim in all she does. § 159. Having argued that Life cannot exist without a certain amount of warmth which is necessary for digestion, and that the seat of this source must be the centre, or heart, he remarks that when heat is intense it consumes itself; there- fore for its preservation a certain cooling opposition is indis- pensable. Eespiration is the cooling process. Air is best adapted for it, because its lightness enables it to penetrate where water could not find an entrance. 6 This is his teleo- logical explanation ; nor is the anatomical explanation much more satisfactory. The air rushes in when the chest expands, but how the air gets from the lungs, which he compares to bellows, into the heart is far from clear. He says that this mechanism is described in another work. I can find no de- scription in the works extant. In one place he says the wind- pipe goes to the heart ; yet elsewhere he rightly says it bifurcates on its entrance into the lungs. § 160. He has also written a special treatise on Animal Movements. But when we consider that he was ignorant of nerves and muscles, it is apparent that all his explanations must have wanted a basis. 7 Accordingly in all that he has McDonnell, in his valuable paper on the Habits and Anatomy of the Lepi- dosiren (" Journal of the Royal Dublin Society," 1 860), mentions that his Lepi- dosiren managed to lire for seventy-five days out of water, because the slough it secreted prevented the evaporation from the surface of its body. It has lungs, however. Eels live a long while out of water, because their bodies are covered with a mucus which retards evaporation. 6 Oomp. Galen: De usu Partium, VI., 2; and Telesius : De natura rerum, Naples, 1586, lib. VI., p. 238. 7 Eabeicius ab Aquapendente has argued this point decisively. — De rnus- culi aetione, p. 400. Meyek: Aristoteles Thierkunde, 1855, says Eabrictcts is in error when he attributes to Aristotle the hypothesis of the pneuma moving the bones through the arteries. Yet see §161. It was distinctly the opinion of Telesius: De natura rerum, V., 197. Roulin has given an instructive sketch of the successive hypotheses, in his Recherch.es tMoriques et expfrimentales sur le me'canisme des mouvements in Majendie's Journal de Physiologic, 1821, 1, 209. Long after muscular contractility was discovered, the belief in animal spirits, as necessary to excite that contractility, remained till it was replaced by the 12 178 aeistotle's PHYSIOLOGY. [CHAP. IX. written on this subject there is no attempt at an explanation of the mechanism of motion, nothing is said which was not Common Knowledge. There is metaphysical and psycho- logical argument, but no anatomy, no physiology. He says the animal never moves but for some end, its motives being intelligence and instinct ; it is always some good which is sought. Appetite says : drink is necessary ; sense or reason says : this is drinkable ; and we drink. It is with us abso- lutely as with automata, which move by a very slight move- ment of their springs which act on other springs. The organs by which animals move are the tendons and bones; these represent the springs and wood of the automata. There is, however, this difference : In the automata the parts are in- capable of internal modification, and their action is fatal ; but the parts of animals are capable of great modification ; the same part may become larger or smaller, and its form may change, under the influence of heat and cold, or some internal cause. Imagination or thought may modify them. The idea of cold or heat, of pleasure or pain, is thus almost the same as the reality : we tremble at the very thought of certain objects. § 161. All motion has its origin in the soul, and the agent which is intermediate between soul and body is the pneuma, or spirit, which is placed in the heart. He says that he has elsewhere explained his views on the pneuma ; unhappily none of the extant works throw much light on it. He says, how- ever, that it is by nature peculiarly fitted to cause movement. 8 § 162. To the vast and important class of phenomena grouped under the sensorial functions, his attention had naturally been much directed ; but here again the anatomical basis was wanting. He had not mastered the initial discovery " nervous fluid," which was replaced by " nervous force," or— as I have pro- posed to call it — neurility. Tblbshts was fully aware of the marvel of heavy limbs being moved by so slight a spirit, tantidus spiritus ; but threw the marvel upon Infinite Wisdom. — Op. cit., p. 197. 8 Comp. Mbtek in preceding note. chap, ix.] ,aristotle's physiology. 179 that the nervous system formed the sensorial mechanism. Departing from the route which Hippocrates had at least opened, though not with much success, in assigning to the brain the faculty of sensation, Aristotle, on purely a priori grounds, placed the seat of sensation in the heart because it was in the centre of the body. He thought it was only because the chief organs of sense are in the head that some philosophers supposed the brain to be the seat of sensation. One argument against such a supposition is that the brain itself is insensible. 9 The heart is in the noblest position, the centre, and must, therefore, have the noblest function ; and its relation to the nutritive soul proves it to be the organ of sensation. 10 § 163. Having on these grounds assigned this function to the heart, it is noticeable that he never attempts to demon- strate the connection between the heart and the organs of sense, or the phenomena of sensation. It is true that he says " all the senses pass through ducts, iropoi, to the heart ; " but he does not show this. The senses -of Touch and Taste he asserts to be visibly in connection with the heart: a puzzling assertion which admits, I think, of this theoretical vindication — Touch is the universal sense, possessed even by animals which possess no other ; it is consequently directly connected with the Vital Principle, of which the heart is the centre. Taste is the sense next in universality, and for a like reason it must have a direct connection with the heart, which he styles the Acropolis of the body. 9 This is insisted on by GaiSALPiNUS: Peripateticarum Qucestionum, 1571, lib. V., quaest. 3 and 6. That the brain is the seat of sensation, he says, would be said by none, " nisi is qui crasse haec contempletur,'' p. 107. We shall here- after consider this difficulty (§ 385). 10 Roger Bacon reconciles the two opinions respecting the seat of the soul, by saying that the sensitive soul has two instruments: one, the heart, being radical and fontal; the other, the brain, being that which is first affected by the Visible Species, and which first distinguishes the operation of the senses. He quotes Avicenna to a similar effect. — Opus Majus, p. 196. 12—2 180 ARISTOTLE'S PHYSIOLOGY. [CHAP. IX. We may also notice that although he argues against the brain as the seat of sensation because it is insensible, he never undertakes to show that the heart is more sensible. The truth is that the a priori argument derived from the nobleness of a centre was the argument which coerced his conviction. § 164. Since he overlooked the real functions of the brain, we may ask what functions he assigned to it. The answer will probably raise a smile : he declared it was a moderator : its coolness, " for it is the coldest part of the body," serves to temper the great heat of the heart-region. Hence it has no blood sent to it ; only to the enveloping membranes is a small quantity sent, in order to temper its coolness. Hence also bloodless animals have no brains, since their moderate heat requires no cooling. Galen justly criticises this notion of the brain serving to cool the heart ; and he also expresses his surprise at Aristotle's opinion that the brain is cold. 11 It is interesting to consider how the idea was arrived at. 12 Clearly it was not through direct observation, since he had no means of measuring temperature in living animals, and if he judged simply by the touch, the dead brain would not be colder than the liver or kidney. If not arrived at through direct observation, it must have been from a priori considerations ; thus, believing the brain to be bloodless, he concluded it was cold. (§ 384.) § 165. From this survey of the chief vital phenomena we discern that Aristotle's physiology was entirely the physiology of conjecture ; it was without one single solid stone to serve as a foundation for future discovery. In the presence of such a result, we ask with surprise, how it comes to pass that biologists of renown can have affirmed that Aristotle laid the 11 Galen: Deusu Partium, VIII., 3. 12 See John Davy: Researches Physiological and Anatomical, 1839, 1., 157, for some attempts to estimate the temperature of the brain; hut as the ex- periments were performed on animals recently killed and decapitated, the results are only approximative. CHAP. IX.] aeistotle's PHYSIOLOGY. 181 eternal bases of their science, and that his writings are still authoritative to discerning minds. Surely the bases of Biology are to be sought in Anatomy and Physiology ? Yet these were entirely unknown to him. Although I have met the affirmation of enthusiastic eulogists by a confrontation with fact, which may seem to press somewhat hardly against Aristotle, the wish to be per- fectly equitable makes me help to restore the balance by point- ing out the philosophical generalities which he enunciated, and which arrest the attention of modern students. This will occupy the next chapter. ( 182 O CHAPTEK X. GENEBAL PRINCIPLES OP BIOLOGY. § 166. That which first led me to study Aristotle's scientific writings was the thrill of surprise on meeting with certain passages seeming to prove that he had arrived at general prin- ciples which modern biologists estimate among the most pre- cious results of philosophic speculation. This surprise, and the admiration consequent upon it, were heightened on my learn- ing that not only had he at one bound reached the summits of speculation, but had also actually anticipated some of the startling discoveries of our times. Thus both in speculation and observation he had shown himself a master and a fore- runner. This was my experience ; and it is reasonable to presume that it is not unallied to the experience of those eminent investigators who have spoken of Aristotle in terms of extra- vagant eulogy. In the next chapter we shall have to consider in how far moderns really have been anticipated by the obser- vations of Aristotle. For the present we confine ourselves to the philosophical generalities. § 167. There is no disputing the fact that several modern speculative views are to be found very clearly expressed in his writings. But it may reasonably be doubted whether these always had the same significance to him as they have to us ; CHAP. X.] GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF BIOLOGY. 183 and the ground of this doubt is chiefly that he did not make the same application of them, nor did he insist upon then- importance as luminous guides. An example has already been given (§ 142) in the supposed perception of homologies. Another may be seen in the so-called " law of economy " J which declares that Nature everywhere gives to one part what she takes from another. This law, which Geoffkoy St. Hilaibe fancied was his, own discovery, 2 and which he entitled la hi dm balancement des organes, is very questionable, and would require a vast amount of detailed proof. Aristotle's applications are few and not successful. Thus, he says, Nature cannot give the Bear a tail, because she has used up the earthy material in covering his body with hair ; and although there are other hairy animals with tails, yet the law of economy still prevails, since these animals with tails are without flesh on their legs. He overlooks the large amount of bone which coats the cartilaginous plates, when he Bays " the cartilaginous fish are without bones, because the thick- ness of their skins has exhausted all the available earthy matter." § 168. Another consideration is to be held in view. In the History of Science, as in the growth of an individual mind, it sometimes happens that the earlier speculations are nearer the truth than those which succeed them ; accordingly we find certain old ideas which had been discarded as erro- neous are reinstated by completer knowledge. On many points we find ourselves, after long wanderings, returned to the ancient starting-place, resuming the forsaken position ; but if we occupy this position anew, it is with very different arma- ments, and we are in no danger of being dislodged by the 1 De Partibus, L, 9, 655. 2 First vaguely expressed in his Phibsophie Anatomigue, 1818, p. 456. It had, however, been explicitly stated by Goethe in 1807. See his work: Zur Morphobgie. It was afterwards well stated by Bichat: Recherches sur la Vie et la Mart, 1829, p. 218. 184 GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF BIOLOGY. [CHAP. X. first assailant. The early thinkers sometimes had a correct general -view simply because they had not sufficient knowledge of details to obscure the view, or to open another. With fuller knowledge arose many difficulties; in trying to find a pathway through these, the seekers wandered from the old road. We are warranted therefore in questioning the pro- fundity of an ancient speculation, unless it can be shown to have been formed from ample details, and to have been applied extensively to the explanation of particulars. 3 To give an example : I was formerly much struck with the clear insight Aristotle displayed in avoiding the confusion introduced by later biologists, who make plants essentially distinct from animals, and make an essential distinction between Life and Mind. But although he placed himself at the loftier point of view which recognizes the identity of Plant and Animal, the identity of Life and Mind, I am now of opinion that he did so by a very simple induction such as a superficial view of the general phenomena would first suggest, but which would have been blurred by more detailed know- ledge. He identified plants and animals, but, as we shall see (§ 179), on grounds such as no modern would accept. In like manner he pronounced the sponge to be an animal; and moderns declare this judgment to have been correct. He has not told us what were his grounds ; but we may reasonably ask, whether, had he known so much of sponges as Okbn and Btjemeistee, he would have maintained, against them, that sponges were animals? Had he known the grounds upon which psychologists still, for the most part, found an essential distinction between Life and Mind, which they hold to be 3 D'Alembeet expresses a similar opinion: " La philosophic moderne s'est rapprochee snr plusienrs points de ce qu'on a pense dans le premier age de la philosophie, pareequ'il semble que la premiere impression de la nature est de nous donner des idees justes que 1'on abandonne bientot par incertitude ou par amour de la nouveaute et auxquelles enfin on est force de revemr." — Sur le Systeme du Monde. CEuvres, 1805, XIV., 79. CHAP. x.J GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF BIOLOGY. 185 two not one, would he have maintained their identity ? These questions cannot be positively answered ; his wonderful saga- city might have pierced the fallacies which have misled more instructed minds ; but on the whole, highly as I estimate his sagacity, it seems to me most probable that he would not have held his views at a later epoch in History, and with an ampler knowledge of the details. § 169. It is not because ancient ideas happen sometimes to agree in expression with our completer knowledge, that we are to assume, as a matter of course, that the ancients really held the opinions we hold. Among their many speculations manifestly erroneous, some few are found to be in seeming conformity with the latest results of research. Are we to assume in the ancients a power of divination rendering research superfluous ? or shall we not rather suppose that two or three of their conjectures turn out right by accident, not insight ? and even when these opinions were inductions from the facts, are we not justified in suspecting that they were due to the simple conception being unobscured by a multiplicity of details ? It may seem ungenerous, by raising these doubts, to deprive the ancients of their credit ; but impartial criticism is forced to raise such questions ; since otherwise we shall have to accept the dangerous paradox that truths of science may be divined spontaneously, and need not therefore be laboriously sought ; and that the ancients were by some peculiar privilege dispensed from the necessity of accurate knowledge. To state such an opinion is to refute it. Nevertheless the uncritical attitude with which men in general approach ancient authors constantly betrays them into a more or less explicit acceptance of such an opinion. When Galen happens casually to de- scribe flame as ignited air, and says that the rose-tree burns because it contains much of this air, a modern historian reads in these vague phrases a wonderful anticipation of chemical discovery. "Ne dirait-on pas que, par une sorte d 'intuition spontanee, Galien pressentit la decouverte des gaz incan- 186 GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF BIOLOGY. [CHAP. X. descents, tels que l'hydrogene, l'hydrogene bi-carbone, l'oxyde de carbone, &c. ?" 4 § 170. One of the great difficulties in interpreting ancient opinions is to guard against the tendency of reading our fulness of knowledge in their vague expressions. We often find in ancient works the precious metal we have ourselves brought with us; as the Alchemist often unconsciously put into his crucible the gold which he afterwards discovered there with surprised delight. Mueatoei 5 mentions that in a very ancient astronomical manuscript there is the figure of a man gazing at the stars through a long tube; a similar representation was noticed by Mabillon in another manu- script ; and Porta in his work on " Natural Magic " (1549) says that at Alexandria a telescope was used to descry ships at a distance. From these facts Mubatobi remarks that it would naturally be concluded that the telescope was known to the ancients; but he adds that Marville, Vegetio, and Fabbizio, correctly explain the mistake, namely, that these tubes were without glasses, and were used to assist vision by shutting out other objects. A modern, seeing the tube, infers the existence of a telescope ; imagination supplies the lenses. 6 § 171. Unless we are rigorous in our examination, we shall constantly fall into the error of attributing knowledge to the ancients which they could not have possessed. Thus Aristotle has been credited with the discovery of the vertebral theory. Lauth, who considers the theory absurd, says — " ce qui doit sur- prendre davantage, c'est son idee sur les os, qu'il croit provenir de la colonne vertebrale, idee r6produite dans les derniers temps." 7 4 Hoefer: Histoire de la Chimie, Paris, 1842, I., 173. There is much more of the same unhistorical appreciation in this work. 6 Muratori: Dissertazioni sopra le Antichita Italiane, ed. 1790, XLIV., p. 374. 6 There is a passage in Roger Bacon describing what might be effected with lenses, which has led many to suppose that he had discovered the telescope; but in a subsequent chapter of this History we shall see that, in truth, he knew nothing whatever about the telescope. 7 Lauth: Histoire de I'Anatomie, p. 61. Comp. p. 73. CHAP. X.] GENERAL PRINCIPLES OP BIOLOGY. 187 Now, the fact simply is that Aristotle described all the bones as connected with the vertebral column. His words are — " The bones, in animals, are all dependent upon one, and are con- nected together like the veins ; nor is any one to be found isolated. The origin of all the bones is the spinal column." 8 A modern reading this may read into it the vertebral theory ; but Aristotle had no such conception in his mind ; his object, moreover, was descriptive, not transcendental, anatomy. § 172. In the course of our analyses we shall meet with various examples of such seeming anticipation ; and also meet with genuine inductions, really remarkable. Of the latter may at once be mentioned his clear perception of the i important morphological law, that the greater luxuriance of the plant is at the expense of its seed ; hence the more the growth is stunted the more seed will be produced. He has made such frequent use of this principle, and always with such insight, that we cannot question his having thoroughly mastered it. § 173. He had also meditated on the progressive com- plexity of life, and in some respects he is superior to many illustrious moderns who have taught various forms of the doctrine of a chain of created beings ; in other words, of a series passing, by insensible gradations, from the simplest to the most complex. Perhaps the wildest of these was put forth by Bobinet, 9 who supposed minerals to develope into plants, and plants into animals. The scheme of Bonnet io is less extravagant. He admits that there is no transition between the mineral and the plant ; admits that Nature seems to take leaps. From the 8 to. tfhara roig Zqiotg a kvbg iravra ovvriprniikva iarl xai trvvexv dWi/Xoig & al (fKkjieg- avro Si Kaff avrb ovSkv kanv barovv. 'AfX'l & V P«X'£ ^ aTlv * v iraai roTg Ixovaiv bora. — Hist. An., III., 7, 516. 9 Robinet: De la Nature, Amsterdam, 1766. I gave an analysis of this rare work in Frazer's Magazine, Nov., 1857. 10 Bonnet: Considerations sur les Corps organises, 1768. 188 GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF BIOLOGY. [CHAP. X. plant, however, the chain is unbroken up to man. Buffon maintains the existence of a series of insensible gradations, conceiving that the whole living universe presents itself as one family, 11 an opinion also adopted by Heedee. 12 Teevibanus makes a separate kingdom of the cryptogamic plants and the zoophytes, intermediate between the two kingdoms, vegetal and animal ; and Letjckabt 13 thinks the sponges may, per- haps, form such an intermediate kingdom. Meckel w holds that all existing organisms may be modifications, by insensible gradations, of one primitive type: a view recently made popular by the " Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation," and placed on a scientific footing by Daewin. 15 Noticing the obvious objection that no such gradations are discoverable, but, on the contrary, that very great gaps occur at all parts of this pretended series, Lamaeck remarks that the animal scale only presents its degrees in the principal masses, and not in the species, nor even in the genera, 16 and therefore he rejects the idea of a connected chain. He holds that it is only at their common starting-point that the two grand divisions of organic life, vegetal and animal, are related by the simplicity of their structure. Not only does he deny the " chain of creation," but he holds that even animals do not form a chain ; they simply exhibit a progressive complexity of organization. 17 In the same spirit Geoffkoy St. Hilaiee pronounces the "chain" to be a 'chimera, and substitutes for it his doctrine of "Unity of Composition." Sebees, reproducing the arguments of Meckel, says that the " missing links " in the chain may all be discovered if we seek them in the life of the embryo. On comparing animals arrived at their complete 11 Quoted by Isidore St. Hilaire: Essais de Zoologie Genirale, 1841, p. 78. 12 Ibid. 13 Leuckart: Observations Zoologicce, p. 13. 14 Meckel: Traiti d'Anat. Comparee, Pans, 1828, 1., 83. 16 Darwin: Origin of Species, 1860. 16 Lamarck: Ph.ilosoph.ie Zoologique, 2nd ed., 1830, 1., 107. 17 Lamaeck: Hist, des Animaux sans Vertebres, 2nd ed., 1835, 1., 51, 110. CHAP. X.] GENERAL PRINCIPLES OP BIOLOGY. 189 development, we find many and wide differences between them ; but if we compared them during their successive stages of evolution, we should see that these differences were preceded by resemblances, 18 that, in fact, comparative anatomy is an arrested embryology, and embryology is a transitory compara- tive anatomy. Auguste Comte proposed to fill up the miss- ing links by the imaginative and arbitrary creation of new forms. § 174. It would be tedious to enumerate all the shapes this general conception of a connected chain has assumed ; always, I think, upon arbitrary and unsatisfactory grounds. The simplest observation concurs with the profoundest, that organic beings are not linked together in a chain nor in a series ; and, although it may flatter our propensity to arrange Nature according to our own notions of symmetry and sim- plicity, the attempt is perpetually frustrated on descending from the lofty region of speculation into that of concrete reality. Nor do the laws of development, in proving that all animal forms may have been developed, by successive modifi- cations, from one original, justify the notion of a series. The image of a tree much better represents the facts than that of a chain. An ideal series of Locomotives might be constructed, from the first rude cart or barrow up to the railway carriage and steamboat, which would have quite as much objective reality as the animal series. § 175. Aristotle's conception was that of an ascending complexity in vital phenomena from plants to man ; and this we may now see in detail. Instead of the three kingdoms — mineral, vegetal, and 18 Sekbes: Precis d'Anat. transcendante, 1842, p. 135. The progress of embryology has discredited this striking and plausible generalization, by confirm- ing the views so luminously set forth by Von Baeh: Zur Entwickelungs- geschichte, 1808, p. 199, and Nova Acta, 1826, that the vertebrate type is at the very first constructed differently from that of the invertebrate; and that not only do the analogous organs appear in different successions, but are formed on different plans. See the elaborate memoir by Lekebouixet : Becherches d'Em- bryologie comparie in the Annates des Sciences Naturelles, 1863, XX., 7. 190 GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF BIOLOGY. [CHAP. X. animal — which moderns have borrowed from the alchemists, 19 he made the more philosophical division of 1° the Inorganic, ra axpv^a, and 2° the Organic, ra ifi\fw^a. The dis- tinction between living and non-living beings is broad and palpable ; it is obviously of quite another kind from the dis- tinction between plants and animals. 20 But although the line of demarcation is broadly marked, yet Nature passes by ascending steps from one to the other ; from the inanimate she passes to animals, through beings which are not indeed to be called animals, yet are so like them that the two are only separated by slight intervals. 21 § 176. The first step is that of Plants ; which, compared with minerals, may be called animated, but compared with animals seem inanimate. Plants have Life ; "for that which nourishes itself, grows, and decays, we call living." An animated body must have a soul, since the soul is the essence and reality of an animated body. It is the first entelechie, the reality by which the body becomes active. (§ 215.) § 177. The first stage of the soul's activity is that which all living beings have in common, namely, Nutrition, or Vegetal Life, as it has been called since Bichat. 22 Plants have organs; but as these are limited to the one function of 19 A fact first noticed by Isidore St. Hilaire: Hist. desSegnes Organiques, 1856, II., 6. A fourth kingdom, the atmospheric, was proposed by Mtjssen- broek: Cours de Physique, 1769, 1., 11. 80 " J'ai depuis longtemps trouve plus convenable d'employer une autre division primaire, parcequ'elle est propre a faire mieux connoitre en general tous les etres qui en sont l'objet. Ainsi je distingue toutes les productions naturelles comprises dans les trois regnes, en deux branches principales— 1 en corps organises, vivansj 2° en corps bruts et sans vie."— Lamarck: Philosophic Zoobgique, 1831, 1., 92. He fancied he was establishing an important inno- vation, yet his illustrious countryman, Vicq d'Azyr, had already suggested the very same division, (Euvres, TV., 18-230. And Aristotle had preceded them by three-and-twenty centuries. sl r, yap fvaiQ utrafSaivu avvix&e avb tS>v fyv X wv ti'c to. ?fia Sia. tSiv Z&vrwv ptv o*k ovtuv 8k Z,6o>v oiirwe iian SokcIv '^d/iwav /uicpbv diafipuv Qaripov Baripov r, refrigere, deduxere. Contrario ab ejus opere signiflcatu. Quoniam nullibi sit animus, imxfi, quin ibi calor quoque existat. Isti quod a voce Grseca foi^oe., qui ventus CHAP, xn.] LIFE AND MIND : DE ANIMA. 223 rately, because Aristotle's view is not that of Stahl, and the celebrated Montpellier school of " animists," which conceives the Mind to be the animating principle, bestowing on the body all activity, determining all vital functions, and thus including under its supremacy all physical and physiological phenomena. Instead of conceiving Life as one of the mani- festations of Mind, Aristotle taught the precise obverse, namely, that Mind is only the highest development of Life.* He always exhibits Life as the general form of organic activity ; Mind as only one of the special forms, developed in later stages, but wholly absent from the earlier. "Plants," he says, "have no sensation. By this the animal is separated from that which is not animal. Numerically, therefore, it (the soul) is one and the same part ; but in its mode of being it is many and different." 5 est, parva admodum detorsione animum et animam derivavere. Contraria maxime a vera re sententia. Nihil enim minus, quam ventus, animus est et anima. Error hie uterque a respiratione venit. Nam ea qua? confesso ani- mam habent, animantia sunt et animalia. Hsec vero respirant. Bespiratio fit veato, ventus internum refrigerat calorem. A vento animus, a refrigeratione yjwxfi sunt efformata."— Fkancisci Patritii : Nova de universis philos., libri L V., comprehensa, "Venice, 1593: Pampsychia, I., p. 49. Stahl, in his dis- sertation, De mechanismi et organismi diversitate (Theoria Medico, Vera, ed. Choulant, Leipzig, 1831, 1., 45), tries to prove that -tyvxh is. a corruption of Qvakxn, quasi tx {ov T0 fyvav. This is somewhat in the manner of Aristotle's derivation of alBrtp from del and Bet: De cash, I., 3, 271. Plato also de- rives it from Qvoexbt aa * ne driver and sustainer of nature: ij Qvmv 6xtl Kai £X«, foakxw iirovofiaZtiv i\ian 8k Kai ipvxv v KOfnptvojievov \syuv. — Cratylus, ed. Bekk. Berlin, 1817, p. 38. But he had previously given the common deri- vation from respiration. 4 To my knowledge no writer has seen this radical distinction between the two views, owing, doubtless, to their verbal similarity. The Montpellier editors of Stahl persist in asserting that Stahl and Aristotle teach precisely the same doctrine (CEuvres de Stahl, 1860, III., p. lxi. and cxxxix.) M. Blondin says, " Stahl n'a jamais dit que c'est l'ame pensante, c'est a dire en fonction d'intel- ■ ligence, qui execute les fonctions vitales et organiques," which is true; but that Stahl attributed all the vital and organic functions to the soul as soul, and taught that this immaterial principle was pre-eminently intelligent, seems to me clear from his treatises, De mechanismi et organismi diversitate, and De diffe- rentia \6yov et Xoyur/iov. 5 De juventute, I., 467: ipiBftif \&v ovv dvaymlov tv tlvai Kai rb aiirb tovto rb fwpiov, Ttji S'tlvai jrXfifei Kai 'irepa. 224 LITE AND MIND : DE ANIMA. [OHAP. XII. § 214. There are one or two passages which raise a doubt as to whether Aristotle had made this point clear to himself in the sense in which it is held by the most advanced psycho- logists ; indeed, it is evident that he had but imperfectly appreciated the necessary correlation between an ascending complesity_jpf . organization,, and an ascending complexity in vjiaLghgao^nena, since he had not clearly and steadily mas- tered the fundamental relation between organ and function. Nevertheless, if he sometimes stopped midway, if he wavered in his conception of the relation between organ and function, the majority of moderns, even physiologists, have not been less wavering, and he stands at the point of view now gene- rally occupied by the most advanced thinkers. 6 6 " We have already pointed out the impossibility of drawing any exact limit between the vital and the spiritual facts of our nature. . . . We have first presented to us a being manifesting vital properties only ; next to this we see the nerve force appearing in the double phenomena of sensation and motion ; and then, lastly, out of these we see consciousness and intelligence gradually evolved." — Moreia: An Introduction to Mental Philosophy, on the Inductive Method, 1861, p. 28. This return to the Aristotelian point of view is quite recent. Less than thirty years ago Schroeder van der Kolk mentioned with pain that some new writers " were not ashamed " to announce that Soul and Vital Principle were words of equivalent meaning; and the object of his Dissertation iiber den Unterscheid zwischen todten Naturhraften, Lebenskraften und Seele, Bonn, 1836, is to disprove such an hypothesis. He maintains the existence of a specific nerve-force, which forms the bond of union between soul and body. It is a curious point in the history of speculation that the doctrine of Aristotle, which was regarded for many centuries as the orthodox Christian doctrine, and was declared such by the (Ecumenical Councils, should, since Descartes, have been regarded as dangerous to religion, so that its modern revival has been generally stigmatized. Descartes limited the functions of the Soul to thought alone; and having thus limited the mean- ing of the word, another word was employed to indicate Life; See Bouiller: Du principe Vital et de I'dme pensante, 1862; and Blondin: Du vitalisme animique, in the 3rd vol. of the (Euvres de Stahl traduites et commenUes, 1860. A similar change in doctrine is noticeable in the views of the early Church respecting the soul. " Je pourrais multiplier it l'infini les citations," says Guizot, " toutes prouveraient que la materialite de l'ame etaitdans les premiers siecles, une opinion, non seulement admise, mais dominante." — Histoire de la Civilisation en France, Lecon VI., Bruxelles, 1839, n., 199. See the collection of passages from the Fathers, asserting that only God is incorporeal, in Abe- lard : Sic et Non, ed. Henke et Lindenkohl, Marburg, 1851, pp. 105 seq. At the end of the 4th century the doctrine of immaterialism began to assume CHAP. xn.J LIFE AND MIND: DE ANIMA. 225 In the following analysis, the phrases " Vital Principle" and " Soul " will be used alternately, but always as desig- nating Life, of which Mind is the highest manifestation. § 215. Book I., Chap. I. — The inquiry opens with a question as to the nature of the Vital Principle : whether it is a something — an essence — or simply quantity or quality, or some one of the other categories ; also, whether it is in itself a, potentiality (w iv Svvafiti ovtojv) or a reality (tvrt\sjiia) . The reader is probably familiar with the Aristotelian distinc- tion, which subsequently played so great a part in Scholas- ticism, between potential existence and actual existence; at any rate, he must have heard often enough of the entelechie or reality (completeness) of a thing, to understand that it was no idle inquiry to ascertain at the outset whether the soul was, or was not, such an entelechie. " We have to consider also whether the Soul is divisible or without parts ; and whether every Vital Principle is, or is not, the same in kind ; and if not, whether the difference is generic or specific." He warns the inquirer against the dangers of studying man exclusively ; and insists on the study of animals being included. He settles that there is only one Vital Principle. " It is difficult to say whether we should study the parts before their functions, as the mind before thought, and sensibility before sensations. If expedient to commence with functions, it may be questioned whether it would not be better to study their opposites first, i. e. the object of perception before that which perceives, and thought before that which thinks. Now the this view ; Clatoian Mammertus (in the 5th century) exhausted all the capital arguments by which Descartes was thought to have established it irre- fragably. In the analysis of his treatise, De natura animce, given by the learned Benedictines of St. Maur, we read, " II fait voir que l'ame n'est jamais sans penser, et que la pensee n'est point differente de l'ame; qu'elle est toute volonte et toute pensee; que penser, vouloir et aimer est sa substance. Qu'il ,n'y a point de corps sans longueur, largeur, et profondeur; que l'ame n'a point ces dimensions, et que par consequent elle est incorporelle." — Histoire litt&raire de la France, V. Steele, II., 447, Paris, 1735. 15 226 LIFE AND MIND: DE ANIMA. [CHAP. XII. knowledge of anything in itself seems to be useful towards a right conception of the causes of the accidents (attri- butes — ffujuj36/3rjKora) in substances ; but the knowledge of accidents contributes largely towards knowing what the thing essentially is ; for whenever we are able, from the appearance of any substance, to recount the whole, or the greater number of its accidents, we are then best prepared to say what its essential existence is." T By essential existence, ovo'ia, is not meant noumenon, in the modern sense, but the reality of a thing as known to us. (See § 95 for an explanation of ovaia.) "The essential existence is the proper beginning for every demonstration, so that all those definitions which do not make known, or make it easy to conjecture what may be the acci- dents of any substances are to be regarded as profitless subtleties." § 216. Whether all the affections of the soul (to iraQr) rrjc' -tyvyjio) are also affections of the body is not clear ; if there is any exception to be made, it must be in favour of thought, that appearing to be most peculiar to the Vital Principle; " but whether thought be imagination of some kind, or never unaccompanied by imagination, still we must admit that it cannot exist without the body. If, therefore, there is any one affection, or function, which is peculiar to the Vital Principle, we should admit that it might be isolated from the body ; but if no one belongs to it exclusively, then we say that it cannot be separate." Here, as elsewhere, he maintains that thought is separable from the body in our abstraction, but not in fact ; the separation is subjective not objective, similar to the sepa- ration of whiteness from white bodies. § 217. It is for the physiologist (^wctikoc), he says, to 7 To a similar effect Goethe in the Preface to the Farbenlehre : — " Denn eigentlich unternehmen wir umsonst, das Wesen eines Dinges auszudriicken. Wirkungen wei'den wir gewahr, und eine vollstandige Geschichte dieser Wir- kungen umfasste wohl allenfalls das Wesen jenes Dinges." — Werke, 1840, XXXVH. CHAP. XII.] LIFE AND MIND: DE ANIMA. 227 study the soul. The Dialectician and the Physiologist would differ in their explanations ; the latter would explain " anger as an ebullition of blood, or excess of heat about the heart ; the former would declare it to be a desire for retaliation, or some such motive." The reader will probably be of opinion that the dialectician seems here to have the best of it. § 218. Chap. II. is wholly devoted to a review of the opinions expressed by the early thinkers. § 219. Chap. III. examines the Principle of Motion, and whether the Soul be self-moved, or moved externally. If moved, it can only be moved by sensations. After glancing at some other opinions, he concludes thus : — " The same incon- gruity, which occurs in most of the theories about the Vital Principle, is met with here, namely, that the writers join this Principle to a body, and place it in a body without having first settled for what purpose the body is to receive it, or how it is fitted to this office. This, however, must be settled, since it is through such a connection that one acts and the other is acted on; and these are relations which cannot be attributed to chance. There are writers who content them- selves with saying what the soul is, without determining anything about the body, its recipient, as if any kind of soul might clothe itself with any kind of body. But everything, on the contrary, seems to have its own particular species and form (riSog Kai fiopfriv). We might as well maintain that the architect could work with musical instruments; for, as each art must employ its own instrument, so each soul its own body." § 220. Chaps. IV. and V. are devoted to the examination of more theories. At the close occurs this important passage : " Since the faculties of knowing, feeling, thinking, desiring, willing, and the appetites in general, as also locomotion, growth, maturity, and decay, are properties of the soul, we may inquire whether each of these properties is given by the soul as a whole, or are different offices assigned to different 15—2 228 LIFE AND MIND: DE ANIMA. [CHAP. XII. parts ? Is Life in one part, in more than one, or in all the parts ? or is there some other cause of Life besides the soul ? Some say the Vital Principle is divisible — one part thinking, another part desiring ; but, if this be so, what holds the parts together? Not the body, certainly, for the Vital Principle appears to hold it together, since, from the moment of its departure, the body expires and decays. 8 If there be some- thing which makes it one, that something is, in the strictest sense, the Vital Principle With respect to the parts of this Principle, it is difficult to determine what is the office assigned to each in the body, for, if it is the whole which sustains the body, then we must conclude that each part sus- tains one part of the body. But this is very like an impossi- bility, for it is difficult even to conjecture what part the intellect could connect with other parts, and how it could do so. 9 Thus plants, when divided, are seen to live, and so are certain insects, as if still possessing the same Vital Principle, considered specifically, though not the same numerically. 10 Each of the divided parts has sensation and locomotion for a time ; and there is no room for surprise at their not continuing to manifest these properties, seeing that the organs necessary for the preservation of nature are absent. 11 Nevertheless, in each divided part coexist all the parts of the Vital Principle." Here he contradicts what he has said elsewhere respecting the absence of the vital centre from the separated head (§ 89). 8 Compare Stahl: Theoria Medica vera de Vita et Sanitate, p. 229. " Hajc ipsa conservatio rei tarn corruptibilis, ne ipso acta corrumpatur, est propria illud quod sub usitato vitce vocabulo intelligi debet." 9 irotov yap jiipwv, f) itHq 6 vovg avvk^si. 10 Hfu aiiTrjv %x ovTa ^"X't" r V e ^ Et > « Ka ' t"i dpiB/iif. 11 This acute remark solves many difficulties. Aristotle's view, both of lift and mind, is adopted by MtJllee: Elements of Physiology, 1843, II., 1334. For examples of " divided vitality," see Physiology of Common Life, II., 225, 421. The old writers puzzled themselves incessantly over this difficulty. See, for example, Basso: PhihsophicE Naturalis adversus Aristotelem, Amster- dam, 1649, p. 260; or Tacrbllub: Contra Ceesalpinum, 1650, p. 850; neither of them comparable to Aristotle. CHAP, xu.j LIFE AND MIND: DE ANIMA. 229 Probably he was thinking only of Plants, for he continues— "and those parts are specifically the same with each other and with the whole— with each other as being inseparable, and with the whole as being inseparable. The vitality of plants is due to a kind of Soul, common both to animals and plants ; and this may be separated from — i.e. exist without — the sentient principle; but without it no sentient principle can exist." 12 § 221. Book II., Chap. I. — The preliminary arguments of the first book clear the way for a definition of Life. Numerous as have been the attempts to frame such a defi- nition, that of Aristotle holds rank with the best. One great source of confusion has been the radical error of conceiving Life to be an Entity, apart from, and only inhabiting the organism (§ 72 b); just as the several Forces were for centuries conceived to be independent of matter, instead of being regarded as matter in dynamic conditions. To escape from such a confusion, and to have seen thus early the positive solution of the difficulty, implies immense intellectual force. A glance at some modern definitions will enable us the better to appreciate Aristotle's. Kant defines Life " an internal principle of action ; " and an organism, " that in which every part is at once means and end." Yet Fermentation, which no one calls Life, is such an internal principle. Trevtranus defines it — " The constant uniformity of phenomena under diversity of external influences," which may " In the preface to Descartes: TraiU de I'Homme, Paris, 1729, written by Schuyl, there is this remarkable passage, which contains samples of the meta- physical and scientific modes of viewing phenomena: " C'est par une impru- dence presque semblable et par nne prodigalite aussi inconsideree, que, centre I'intention du crfateur, le Peripatetisme attribue aux plantes une ame vivante ; qu'il ne fait pas simplement consister dans la disposition et le mouvement de leurs parties, en quoi consists toute la cause de la vigUation ; mais que l'ignorance ou il est de sa veritable cause, lui fait considerer, selon son caprice, comme un esprit ou une substance entiSrement differente de la mati&re ou du corps de la plante." 230 LIFE AND MIND: DE ANIMA. fcHAP. XII. be said with equal truth of a watch, since, if some external influences disturb the mechanism of a watch, external influ- ences will not less disturb an organism. Bichat's famous definition : " Life is the sum of the functions by which death is resisted," is only another form of the one already quoted from Stahl (Note 8), and is every way objectionable ; for on the one hand it is a paraphrase of the truism that " life is the means by which we live ; " and on the other hand it declares that there is a fatal antagonism in external agencies ; whereas we know that such agencies are necessary co-efficients, Life being inconceivable without a medium. Dug^s defines Life "the special activity of organized beings." Becxard says : " Life is the sum of the phenomena proper to organized beings. It consists essentially in this, that organized beings are all during a certain time the centres to which foreign substances penetrate and are appropriated, and from which others issue." De Blainville's definition, adopted by Comte and Chaeles Kobin, runs thus : — " Life is the twofold internal movement of composition and decomposition at once general and con- tinuous." But this only embraces the phenomena of vegetal life, and even there is too restricted. Herbert Spencer says, "Life is the definite combina- tion of heterogeneous changes, both simultaneous and suc- cessive, in correspondence with external co-existences and sequences." In a former work, after citing these definitions, I proposed the following : — " Life is the dynamical condition of the organism." The advantage of such a formula is that it embraces every form of life, from that of the simple cell to that of the most complex mammal. It further expresses every variation in the intensity or the complexity of vital phenomena, according to the activity or complexity of the CHAP. XII.] LIFE AND MIND: BE ANIMA. 231 organism ; and their dependence on external and internal agencies. 13 § 222. By conceiving Life simply as the function of the organism, we do not rob it of its solemn mystery. It is still the dark Dynamis which must ever remain impenetrable ; but a similar mystery hangs over the course of the planets, the ebb and flow of the tides, the vehement impulses and repul- sions of chemical elements ; yet, as in these we have detected order, and gained some glimpse of law, so in the manifold phenomena of Life, we may likewise discern order and law if we study them aright. That Aristotle conceived Life thus, may be read in the following sentences: — "Among natural bodies some have, and some have not, life ; and by life we mean the faculties of self-nourishment, self-growth, and self-decay. Thus every natural body partaking of life may be regarded as an essen- tial existence (ovaia) ; but then it is an existence only in combination (ueavvOtrri). And since the organism is such a combination, being possessed of life, it cannot be the Vital Principle. Therefore it follows that the Vital Principle must be an essence, as being the form of a natural body holding life in potentiality ; but essence is a reality (entelechie). The Vital Principle is the original reality of a natural body endowed with potential life; this, however, is to be under- stood only of a body which may be organized. Thus the parts even of plants are organs, but they are organs that are alto- gether simple, as the leaf which is the covering of the pericarp, the pericarp of the fruit. If then there be any general formula for every kind of Vital Principle, it is — the primary reality of an organism.'" u 13 Kant : Kritik. der Urtheilshraft ( Werke IV., 260) ; Tbeviranus : Biohgie; Bichat: Beckerches eur la Vie et la Mort; Duges: Physiologie Comparfe, I., 3; Beclard: Anatomie Genirale; Comte : Cours de Philos. Positive, III., 295; Herbert Spencer: Principles of Psyclwlogy, 1855, p. 354. Compare Physiology of Common Life, 1860, II., 426. 14 ivre\ex aa V itguni mb/taTog irpiv voiiv. This, if I understand it aright, means that the mind has no substantive existence, but exists only in act, as a function. The passage is very obscure. Trendelenburg, who has a long note on the parenthesis, which does not require one, is silent on the only real difficulty. Torstrik says, " intellectus non est actu idea antequam cogitet (oiiB ianv avrov fiaiQ o&Se/iia A.W i) avrn) 8n $vvaT&v=oi>8kv toriv ivcpydq, tS>v ovtuiv irpiv voilv), ed. De Animd, p. 198. CHAP. XH.J LIFE AND MIND : BE ANIMA. 241 § 241. He argues that the reflective faculty is not the sensitive faculty in a state of repose. " The mind judges of flesh and ideal flesh, either by some different faculty, or by being itself differently affected. It is by sensibility that we judge of hot and cold and other properties of flesh ; but it is either by some distinct faculty— or as a curved line is to a straight line — that we judge of ideal flesh." § 242. Chap. V.— The soul is creative. It is essentially an energizing influence. Knowledge in activity is identical with the object ; but in potentiality, it pre-exists in the indi- vidual. "Yet rigorously speaking that cannot be said to pre-exist which sometimes is, and sometimes is not, reflected on. But that alone, whatever it be, which is separate from everything else, is deathless and eternal. "We have no memory of it because it is passionless (airaOis) ; and the impressible mind is perishable, and without it there can be no reflection." § 243. Chap. VI. briefly reiterates the argument that the senses are free from error, which arises solely from the judgment. § 244. Chap. VII. — The opening sentence may be read as a vague anticipation of the modern hypothesis, that knowledge, or rather the aptitude for acquiring knowledge, becomes developed in the race, and is thus transmitted from parent to child, so that the offspring of European parents is capable of acquiring a higher degree of intellectual develop- ment than the offspring of Australian parents reared under similar conditions. Hume's doctrine 25 that the mind is simply the suc- cession of impressions is thus formularized at the close of the chapter : " The mind in the act of thinking is the things thought of." £6 § 245. Chap. VIII. is a repetition of former arguments. 25 Hoteb: Treatise on Human Nature, Works, 1826, 1, 269. 28 '6\£ dk 6 vovg iariv b Kar kv'epyuav tu irpdyfiara voSiv. 16 242 LIFE AND MIND : DE ANIMA. [CHAP. XH. § 246. Chaps. IX. and X. are devoted to the locomotive powers considered as parts of the Vital Principle. The nutritive and generative functions which belong to all living beings originate the motions concerned in the processes of growth and decay. These are motions, but how does loco- motion originate ? Not by the nutritive faculty, since animal progression has always some cause in imagination or appetite ; and no being moves except when urged by desire or fear, unless there be some external impulse. Besides, if nutrition were the cause of locomotion, plants would move. Not by the sentient faculty, since there are many sentient beings which are stationary throughout life. Not by the rational faculty, or mind, as we call it ; for the theoretic faculty never thinks upon what is to be done, or suggests what should be pursued and avoided; but pro- gression is always an act of pursuit or of flight. Nor does the rational faculty even when reflecting on flight or pursuit at once bid the animal move, since it often dwells upon some- thing terrible or agreeable without suggesting alarm, although the heart may be agitated. Moreover, although the mind may bid, and reason suggest, that something should be fled from or pursued, the animal does not necessarily move, but acts like an intemperate man, according to the dictates of passion. Finally, it is not appetite that causes progression, since the temperate, even while desiring and yearning after something, do not act in order to secure it, but follow their understanding. § 247. Having thus excluded Nutrition, Sensation, Eeason, and Appetite as incapable singly of causing locomotion, he proceeds to show that the motor principles are Appetite and Eeason; an apparent contradiction, but when read by the light of a previous passage (§ 160), seen to mean that Eeason and Appetite must act in combination to produce locomotion. "It is mind as a logical' and practical power," he adds, "and which differs from the theoretic mind in its aim. Every CHAP. XH.J LIFE AND MIND : DE ANIMA. 243 appetite has an aim ; the appetite which is the principle of the practical mind has always an object in view, and this object is the principle of action. Thus appetite and practical reason may be regarded as the two motors." § 248. Chap. XI. raises the question whether those inferior animals which have only the sense of Touch can have motion and imagination. They appear sentient of plea- sure and pain, and hence must feel desire; but how can imagination be present ? Even as their motions are indeter- minate, so also may imagination exist in them indetermi- nately. 87 The sentient imagination belongs to other animals ; the voluntary imagination only to such as are rational : for whether this, or that, shall be done is a matter of reasoning ; and as the individual is to pursue the better of two courses, he must be guided by a rule of some kind which enables him out of many images to select one. § 249. Chap. XII. reiterates the statement of an ascend- ing complexity of organisms. It is necessary that every living being should have the nutritive soul, but it is not necessary that every living being should be sentient. All animals must be sentient, if Nature does nothing in vain; since without sensibility a progressive animal would perish, being unable to select its nutriment. Creatures which are stationary obtain their nourishment on the spot. But it is impossible that a progressive animal which has been generated should possess a Vital Principle and a judging faculty, and not be sentient. Touch and Taste are the primary and indispensable senses. The other senses are given only to the higher animals ; for if these are to preserve their existence, they must not only be sensible of objects touching them, but also at a distance. 57 This is analogous to the hypothesis of many zoologists, that nerve tissue may exist in a diffused state in all those animals which manifest sensibility, yet seem to be destitute of nerves. Both opinions arise from loose conceptions of Psychology and Anatomy. An imagination without images, and a nerve tissue without definite structure, are not more acceptable than liquid crystals. 16—2 244 LIFE AND MIND : BE ANIMA. [CHAP. XH. § 250. Chap. XIII. — This final chapter argues that the animal body cannot be homogeneous, i. e. made up of one element only. The sentient organs may be composed of all the elements except earth, for these organs all receive impres- sions through media (§ 238). But Touch is made sensible by contact with bodies, and hence its name. Other organs likewise perceive by contact, but it is through media — through something foreign to themselves — whereas Touch perceives directly. So that an animal body cannot be constituted of any of the other elements exclusively, nor can it be formed of earth alone ; for Touch is the medium of tangible impres- sions, and its organ is perceptive not only of the distinctions which pertain to earth, but also of hot and cold, and all other tangible qualities. Hence it is that we have no sensation in bones, hair, and analogous parts, because they are formed of earth ; and plants, for the same reason, being formed of earth, have no sensation. § 251. "While Touch is necessary for continued existence, some animals have other senses, not simply for existence, but for enjoyment. They have Vision, in order that living in air or water, in a transparent medium, they may see. They have Taste, that by discerning what is grateful or nauseous in food they may desire and obtain, or avoid it. They have Hearing, that others may signify something to them; and a Tongue that they may signify something to others. § 252. If now we review the contents of the treatise just analysed, we shall note first how very slightly it touches on those faculties which are more prominently indicated by the modern word Soul, and how it enlarges on physiological, rather than psychological questions. Secondly, we shall note here, as in almost every one of his scientific works, the want of masterly and logical arrangement of subject, and the want of the elementary requisites of good composition. There is no progression, no culmination. One chapter might be trans- posed in the place of another, one paragraph might precede CHAP. Xn.] LIFE AND MIND : DE ANIMA. 245 its predecessor without affecting the symmetry, or rather the asymmetry of the work. "Were this not equally observable in other works, we might not unreasonably lay the blame at the door of the earlier editors and copyists ; but such an argument is untenable in the presence of compositions so uniformly defective. Thirdly, we suspect, what detailed examination proves to be the fact, 28 that the work was the great text-book of Psychology until modern times, the additions made by Aristotle's successors up to the 17th century being unimpor- tant. Fourthly, we shall note the profundity of many of its views, and their singular accordance with much that is taught in the best writings of our own times. 48 Fbies: Handbuch der paychischen Anthropologic, 1820, 1., 59. ( 246 ) CHAPTEE XIII. ON THE SENSES. § 253. Aristotle has written much about the senses in several works. The treatise De sensu, in the Parva Natv/ralia, is perhaps the hest source we can consult ; and it may, there- fore, be analysed briefly here. § 254. The early philosophers sought in the four elements, earth, air, fire, and water, for the several bodies constituting the senses. As there are five senses, and only four elements were generally recognized, a fifth element was imagined. What that element is, Aristotle does not say ; elsewhere we learn it is the Ether. I. — Vision, § 255. Every one, he says, believes Vision to be of fire ; the reason is that men misconceive the phenomenon of sparks dancing before the eyes when rubbed, especially in the dark. But if we cannot deny that we feel and see that which we see, it necessarily follows that the eye sees itself. Now, why have we this sensation only when the eye is rubbed ? The explanation offered is that smooth bodies shine natu- rally in the dark, though without producing light ; now the pupil of the eye is smooth ; and when the eye is rubbed it seems as if that which was one became two. The rapid motion makes the eye which is seen and that which sees appear different. The phenomenon is not producible unless CHAP. XIII.] ON THE SENSES. 247 the eye be rubbed . quickly, and in darkness (I suppose he means by darkness the eye being closed, otherwise the quali- fication is erroneous), smooth bodies shine no less than certain fish heads, and the ink of the cuttlefish. When the eye is rubbed slowly, the sensation is not such as to make us think that what sees and what is seen are one and the same, so that the eye may see itself as in a mirror. § 256. This, it must be confessed, is not a fortunate attempt at explanation. Newton, in one of his celebrated queries added to the Optics, first clearly stated that the sparks which arise when the eye is rubbed " arise from such motions excited in the bottom of the eye by the pressure and motion of the finger, as at other times are excited there by light for causing vision." But it was Johannes Mullee, stimulated by the Farbenlehre of Goethe, who placed beyond a doubt the fact that each special nerve of sense responds only in one special manner, no matter how various may be the stimuli, so that whatever excites the optic nerve excites a luminous sensation ; whatever excites the auditory or gustatory nerves, excites sonorous and sapid sensations; and the pressure on the skin-nerve which excites pain excites in the optic nerve not pain, but a luminous sensation. § 257. Aristotle, knowing nothing of the properties of the optic nerve, could not, of course, give an explanation of the phenomenon. But his explanation is better than that of Empedocles and Plato, who held " the eye to be of fire." He asks, apropos of this, " If vision is produced when light passes from the eye, as from a lantern, why can we not see in the darkness ? To pretend that light is extinguished by the darkness, on quitting the eye, is absurd." § 258. He thinks Democeitus " right in asserting that the vision is ' of water,' but wrong in asserting it to be an image (appearance, iiKpaaiq), for the image is produced because the eye is a smooth surface, and vision is not in it, but in the seeing faculty. The affection is a refraction, iivatcXaais yap 248 ON THE SENSES. ["CHAP. Xni. to naBoc. But in those days the theory of images and re- fraction was not understood. Moreover, it is absurd not to have asked why the eye alone can see, and not other bodies." § 259. "It is correct to say that vision is of water; not because it is of water, but because it is diaphanous, and this quality is common to air. Water;' however, retains and re- ceives it better than air, and that is why the pupil and the eye are of water. The soul is assuredly not at the surface of the eye, but within ; hence the eye must be translucent and capable of receiving light. Thus men in battle wounded near the temple, so that the optic channels (nerves, iropoi) are divided, have felt darkness come on as if a lamp had been extinguished ; for indeed the diaphanous and the pupil form a sort of lamp." § 260. " Thus it is evident we must assign an element to each sense, and say that the part of the eye which sees is of water, that which hears is of air, and that which smells is of fire. Touch is earthy. Taste is a kind of Touch. The eye is a part of the brain ; and the brain is the moistest and coldest part of the body. Touch and Taste are connected with the heart, which is the hottest part of the body." § 261. We have next an exposition of Colour. He defines Light " the colour of the diaphanous per accidens," or, as he expresses it in the De Animd, " colour is a movement of the diaphanous," which may be interpreted into an anticipation of the modern undulatory theory, the diaphanous standing for the elastic ether, and the movement being its undulations. *' When there is an igneous body (irup&j&e «) in the diaphanous, we have light ; when none, we have darkness. 1 That which we call the diaphanous does not belong exclusively ' Telesio held Light to be visible heat — lux caloris species est— which is tinged by the colours of the objects through which it passes.— DejRerum Natara, 1586, VII, 292-3. This is a much more superficial view than that of Aristotle; and the same may be said of most of his deviations from the doctrines of the CHAP. XIII.J ON THE SENSES. 249 to water, air, and other bodies which are translucent. It is some common nature and force, which not existing separately exists in these bodies and in others, in some more and in some less." 2 What that force was supposed to be I cannot discover from the writings now extant phe seems to have considered it suffi- ciently described by its name. § 262. " As all bodies have necessarily a limit, so also has the diaphanous, and this limit is colour, which is either the limit of bodies or at their limit ; and hence the Pythagoreans call colour ' the surface.'" " Colour being the limit of the diaphanous in a limited body, it is possible that that which produces light in the air will also be in the diaphanous in limited bodies, or will not be there ; and thus, as in the air there may be light or darkness, so in bodies there may be white and black. The white and black may be placed side by side, so that both may be invisible separately, on account of their minuteness, yet, nevertheless, the result of the two will be visible. But this result can be neither black nor white ; but as it must have some colour the colour will be a compound of the two. That is how different colours arise. Many colours are also produced by the combi- nation of the parts : thus three may be arranged with two, or four, and other combinations. Those colours which depend on proportional numbers are harmonious, such as purple and scarlet." 3 II. — Taste and Smell. § 263. " These have great similarity, though produced in different organs. The nature of flavours is more evident than 2 aWa rig l(Tn Koivq tpveig ical Siva/iig, ») %ti>pu;r?i fikv oiitc tanv, iv rovroig S" iori Kal roig aXKoig Oib/iaoiv Iwirapxti, roig phi fiaKKov roig S" rjrrov. 3 For an elaborate exposition of the views held by the ancients on the sub- ject of colour, see Prantl: Aristoteles iiber die Farben, erlautert durch eine iibersicht der Farbenlehre der Alten, Munich, 1849. But perhaps the most intel- ligible account is that given by Goethe: Geschichte der Farbenlehre. Werke, XXXIX. 250 ON THE SENSES. [CHAP. XIII. that of odours, because our sense of smell is less keen than it is in other animals ; on the other hand, we have Touch more sensitive than any other animal, and Taste is a kind of Touch. § 264. " Although water is insipid by nature, it is neces- sary that water should contain all flavours which escape our perception on account of their feebleness ; or that it should contain a matter which is the germ of all flavours ; or finally, that water having no difference of flavour in it, the cause is heat. Thus the flavour of fruit is developed by heat. All the flavours to be found in fruits are to be found also in the earth. At least the ancients thought that water varied with the soils through which it passed, which is evident from salt waters, as salt is also a kind of earth. 4 Thus water filtered through cinders contracts a bitter taste, and so of the rest. "We may hence see why plants have their various flavours ; for moisture, like everything else, is modified by its opposite, and dryness is the opposite of moisture. Thus moisture is modified by fire, for fire is by nature dry. Thus when some- thing sapid is dissolved in water, the water becomes sapid ; and in the same way nature acts upon the dry element, and the earthy element : it filters the moisture through the dry and earthy, setting it in motion by heat, and giving it all the necessary qualities. This modification of moisture is flavour." § 265. " As various colours arise from the combinations of black and white, so various flavours arise from the combina- tions of sweet and bitter ; and these combinations may be proportional or indefinite. Those which are agreeable depend on numerical proportion. The kinds of flavour resemble those of colour : both are seven in number." § 266. " Odours are perceptible in air and water ; they are transmitted by the diaphanous which is common both to air s 4 Who were these ancients ? The commentators declare that Metrodorus and Anaxagoras are alluded to. Perhaps so; yet the opinion may be found very distinctly expressed by Hippocrates: JDe Aire, Locis et Aquis. CHAP. XIII.] ON THE SENSES. 251 and water. That water alone suffices is proved by the fact that fish have the sense of smell. Odour is dry flavour con- veyed by the moisture in air and water. All sapid bodies are odorous." III. — Hearing. § 267. Either Aristotle forgot to include Hearing in this treatise, or else the chapter has been lost. But his views are expressed in the Be Animd (II., 8), from which we may borrow them in a compressed form. § 268. " Sound is both potential and actual ; for we say that some bodies, such as sponge, wool, &c, are without sound, and others, as brass, wood, hard and smooth bodies, have sound, because able to make sound actual by the action of the medium between the object and the ear. Actual sound is the result of something in relation to something, and in some- thing ; for its cause is percussion. But with only one body there can be no percussion ; so that the sonorous object sounds by its relation to another. Without movement there can be no percussion, and sound is not produced by the percussion of every substance; and hollow bodies create, by reflex, many percussions after the first, owing to the medium within them having been set in motion, and being unable to escape. Sound is audible in air, and less distinctly in water. 4 But neither air nor water can be the cause of sound, since there must be a percussion of solid bodies against each other and against the air." § 269. "A vacuum is justly called the lord of hearing (Kvpiov tov clkovuv), for the air appears to be a vacuum, and when moving continuously creates hearing. But being very diffluent, it gives out no sound, unless when that which is 5 An ereor which observation might have guarded against; since very simple experience shows water to be a better conductor of sound than air. The velocity with which sound traverses water has been calculated as four times its velocity through air. 252 ON THE SENSES. [CHAP. XIII. percussed is smooth: in this case the air becomes uniform over its surface, for the surface of a smooth body is one. Every sonorous body sets in motion the air which is, by continuity, one with the organ of hearing ; and sound being in the air, the air without the organ sets in motion the air within. An animal, therefore, does not hear in every part, for every part does not contain air. The air itself, owing to its diffluence, is without sound; but when confined, its motion produces sound. The air within the ear is so immured as to be incapable of escape ; 6 and this, in order that the sense may perceive accurately all variations of its movement. And thus we are enabled to hear in water ; for the water cannot gain access to the congenital air, or pass through the con- volutions of the ear. The ear is constantly giving out sound, as a horn does ; for the air within it is continually moving in some peculiar manner. Hence we speak of hearing by a vacuum and something resonant, because we hear by the part which contains the air confined within it." IV. — Sensation in general. § 270. Having passed the Senses in review, he then touches on certain general questions relative to sensation. And first of its divisibility ad infinitum. If bodies are infinitely divisible, are the impressions they make on us equally so ? This question Aristotle answers with 6 The translation in the text came spontaneously from my pen, because I was not aware that the language of Aristotle had puzzled the commentators. (See Trendelenburg, p. 386, for an example.) The sense is so plain that I cannot even now comprehend how it has been missed. Aristotle says the air in the ear is immoveable or unmoved, 6.kIvi)toq ; immobilis is Bussemaker's translation, immoveable is Collier's. Yet inasmuch as the movement of this air is men- tioned immediately afterwards, the verbal contradiction is glaring; yet it is only verbal. If we suppose that aKivijroc has reference to the air which iv roic Siaw lyKaTtfueoSS/iriTat (is immured within the ears), the meaning is obvious enough. A man is said to be immoveable from his studio or bureau without any imputa- tion on his power of movement; but commentators, boggling at small contra- dictions, and passing by great ones without remark, would point out that a man cannot be immoveable if he move at all. CHAP. XIII.] ON THE SENSES. 253 manifest superiority over Sir William Hamilton, who, pro- bably from an unsuspected reminiscence, has used the very same illustrations to justify his own doctrine of " latent con- sciousness." That our consciousness may arise out of un- conscious modifications is evident, according to Hamilton, in the fact of a minimum visible, which is the smallest surface that can be seen : " It is plain that if we divide this minimum visible into two parts, neither half can by itself be an object of vision or visual consciousness. They are, severally and apart, to consciousness as zero. But it is evident that each part must have produced in us a certain modification, real though unperceived, for as the perceived whole is nothing but the union of unperceived halves, so the perception is only the sum of the two modifications, each of which severally eludes our consciousness." T § 271. The fallacy of this argument may be disclosed in a counter illustration : the stick which at a distance of three feet just touches us, and produces the sensation of contact, will no longer produce that sensation if broken in half, and held towards us at a distance of three feet : it will not affect our consciousness at all : the two halves thus pointed towards us do not produce modifications in our conscious- ness the sum of which is perceived when the whole touches us. Hamilton's mistake lies in the vague conception of a minimum visible, which being the extreme point of visual consciousness, anything beyond that extreme must necessarily pass altogether beyond the sphere of consciousness. It does not become latent; for consciousness it becomes non- existent. The difference in degree has amounted to a differ- ence in kind. § 272. Aristotle justly says that the sensible qualities are named such because they produce sensation. " All magnitude 7 Hamilton: Lectures on Metaphysics, 1859, I., 350. It is strange that neither the erudite Hamilton, nor his erudite editors, should have mentioned Aristotle in this place. 254 ON THE SENSES. [CHAP. XIII. is necessarily sensible, otherwise it would not be magnitude. Were it otherwise there would be bodies which had no colour, no weight, nor any other quality, and which consequently would not be perceptible to us, since it is by such qualities that we have perception. But the sensible is composed of sensible qualities, and assuredly not of mathematical defini- tions. 8 How do we form any judgment of sensible things? By the intellect ? But the ideas are only possible when based on sensations. The solution of these questions makes mani- fest why the kinds of colour, taste, &c, are limited, or finite. It is because in all things which have extremes there must also be intermediate points of limitation ; now contraries are extremes, and in all sensible impressions there are contraries, as white and black in colour, sweet and bitter in taste. A body, that is continuous therefore may be infinitely divided into unequal parts, but its divisibility into equal parts is finite. That which is not continuous as a whole has its parts (species) finitely divisible. Since we call the sensible qualities species, and they are always continuous, we must distinguish between the actual and potential ; and hence we do not see the millionth part when we see the million, nor do we hear the quarter-tone when we hear the melody ; the interval is imperceptible and is lost in other sounds. It is the same with the infinitely little in other sensibles : they are potentially visible, but not actually visible when isolated. 9 Thus the line of one foot is potentially in the line of two feet; but exists actually only when alone. The infinitely small qualities are lost in sur- rounding bodies, as drops of perfume poured into the sea. This infinitely little which transcends sensation is neither " irav elvat piytQos a"ta6r]T0V &Svvarov ydp \ivicbv fiiv bpav nil iroabv Sk' il y&p p,r) oi)rw£, kvU%oiT hv dvat n aSipM. /iridkv ix ov XP&na, /u/iW /3apo£, im$ (SiXXo n toiovtov ir&Qof liar oif ala9t]Tbv 8\wf • ravra y&p t& aia9r)T&. T6 v. 'AW' StvayKaloV oi ydp Sr) ik ye tSiv fmSrijiaTiKSiv. VI., 445. 9 cvi'dfitt ydp opard, ivtpyaq $ oi, '6rav %upiady. CHAP. XIII.] ON THE SENSES. 255 sensible in itself nor by itself, for it is only sensible potentially in the larger quantity." I have preserved the Aristotelian phraseology, but the reader •will find little difficulty in disengaging the meaning, and -will perceive how this distinction of the potentially and actually visible agrees with and yet rises superior to Hamilton's idea of our being unconsciously modified by that which never reaches the consciousness, so that two zeros may make an unit. § 273. In the concluding chapter, he enters upon the question whether we can have two different sensations in the same instant of time ; a question of some psychological interest. He answers it in the negative. § 274. In reviewing Aristotle's opinions on the Senses, it is requisite to bear in mind that he was wholly without the anatomical and physiological, no less than the physical and chemical knowledge, which could have given an assured basis to his speculations. It is a subject which, even in our own day after so much laborious inquiry, is only beginning to be understood ; and the psychologist will have many years yet to wait, before science furnishes him with the data he requires. 256 ON MEMORY, SLEEP, DREAMS, [CHAP. XIV. CHAPTER XIV. ON MEMORY, SLEEP, DREAMS, AND LONGEVITY. § 275. Among the Parva Naturalia, there are four treatises which must be briefly analysed here : — I. — Memory and Recollection. This treatise, which Sir W. Hamilton in his Notes on Eeid has illustrated (obscured, some may think) with his usual prodigality of erudition, is held by admirers to be both exhaustive and profound. Let the reader judge. § 276. "What is memory ? what is recollection ? To what part of the soul do they belong ? They do not always accompany each other : sluggish minds have the best memo- ries ; the quickest minds, those which are readiest at learning, have the strongest recollection. § 277. Memory being always of things absent, the ques- tion arises : How can the mind perceive that which is absent ? All that is actually present is the affection, tradoq, of the soul. This is the explanation : the original sensation left a trace behind it, an impression, such as the seal leaves upon wax ; and it is the perception of this impression which consti- tutes memory. But as this is a description of perception itself, and as memory is something different, we must add thereto the idea of Time. The impressions, or we may say CHAP. XIV.J AND LONGEVITY. 257 the pictures painted on the mind, and retained there to be presented again in memory, require a certain physical con- dition in the sensorium, suitable to the impression. If the sensation be too violent, or if the mind be in a state of agitation, no more impression is made than would be made on running water ; and if the sensorium be too hard, as in old age, no impression is made. That is why the young and the old have no memory. Those also who are very vivacious, and those who are very slow, have little memory : the brains of the former are too moist, iiyporcpoi; the latter too hard, ff/eXjjporEpoi ; so that in the one case an image will not remain, in the other the image cannot be impressed. § 278. The problem is thus stated : How is it that, in memory, we think of the absent object, and do not think of the image which is really present ? But the answer given is purely verbal. An animal painted in a picture, he says, is both an animal and a copy, and while being that one and the same, it is nevertheless two things at once. The animal and the copy are not identical, and we may think of the picture either as an animal or as a representation. This also is true of the image within us ; and the idea which the mind contem- plates is something in itself, although it is also the image of something else. § 279. He then passes to Eecollection, which is a distinct faculty, according to him. It is in this place that he gives expression to the glimpse he had attained of the law of association of ideas, over which Hamilton has blown such emphatic trumpets. My only remark is that here, as in so many other cases, modern knowledge supplies the telescope with its lenses. Had Aristotle really conceived the law as a law, he would have applied it to the explanation of psycho- logical questions, in the way moderns have applied it. The fact that he did not attempt this, suffices to show how imperfect was his appreciation of the law. 17 '258 ON MEMORY, SLEEP, DREAMS, [CHAP. XIV. II.— Sleep. § 280. This is a problem which even yet is so far from a solution, that the very conditions on which sleep depends are under dispute. The majority of physiologists assume that sleep is caused by a temporary congestion of the blood-vessels in the brain, the pressure of this congestion suspending the activity of the brain. 1 "Were this fact established, we should still have to inquire into the cause of the congestion ; but is it established ? Although I have myself in a former work argued as if the fact were certain, I am forced now to confess that further inquiry has not only shown me that there is absolutely no good evidence for such an opinion ; but has also shown me that all the phenomena may be even better explained on the assumption of an anaemic condition. A considerable withdrawal of the circulation from the brain would better account for the general inactivity of the brain during sleep ; for the partial activity of dreams ; and for the rapidity with which the whole activity is restored by a rush of blood, under any stimulus. Congestion implies relaxation of the vessels ; the instantaneous recovery of mental energy when a sleeper is awakened by the alarm of fire, or the like, would scarcely be compatible with such a relaxed condition. § 281. Whichever view may be the correct one, we are at present condemned to conjecture, since we are without the means of verifying either hypothesis. Until some method shall be disclosed of accurately determining the condition of the cerebral circulation during sleep, we cannot know what are the conditions of the phenomenon. § 282. Aristotle, as may be supposed, had no suspicion of the brain being the important agent in sleep. He asserted simply that -Sleep and Waking are two functions of the animal economy, and are recognized by similar signs : when a man 1 In the very latest work on the subject this opinion is assumed as if it were beyond cavil. See Maury: Le Sommeil etks Reves, Paris, 1861. CHAP. XIV.] AND LONGEVITY. 259 manifests sensibility we say he is awake; when he manifests none, we say he is asleep. " Hence we conclude that it is the sentient principle which sleeps and wakes. Now sensi- bility belongs neither to the soul nor the body, but to the union of the two. Only animals sleep, because they only are sensitive ; and there is no animal which always sleeps, none which always wakes. Since every organ becomes fatigued after a certain exercise, the fatigued eyes no longer see, the wearied hand no longer grasps." § 283. Although he maintains deductively that every animal must sleep, he does not pretend that observation in every case warrants the conclusion. " Sleep has been ob- served, he says, in all terrestrial and aquatic animals ; in all fish and cephalopoda; and in all those which have eyes. Those which have hard eyes, like insects, sleep but little ; and hence the doubt has arisen whether they sleep at all. The testacea have not been directly observed ; but on this point we must be guided by probabilities." § 284. The modern naturalist will be tempted to ask what kind of observations suggest that fish, cephalopoda, and insects ever sleep ? It is evident that they take repose ; but repose is not the same as sleep. Are they shut out from all percep- tion of external objects, as is the case in the sleep of higher animals? We are completely in the dark. (§ 345.) § 285. After a survey of sleep in the animal kingdom, Aristotle concludes the chapter with the assertion still unhesi- tatingly repeated in our text-books, that Nutrition is most active during Sleep ; and that the waste- of the day is then repaired. I have endeavoured to show e that this opinion is not only unsupported by any plausible evidence, but is in flagrant contradiction with known facts and the physiological inferences they suggest. Were it true, the longest sleepers should be the strongest animals, since their repair of waste 2 Physiology of Common Life, II., 358. 17—2 260 ON MEMORY, SLEEP, DREAMS, [CHAP. XIV. would be the most effectual. "Were it true, many dreadful cases of slow atrophy might be cured by opiates. "Were it true, the sleepless maniacs, and men who sleep but little, would show a rapid destruction of their substance. To admit that muscular and nervous tissue require intervals of repose, is not equivalent to admitting that their nutrition is only, or even mainly, effected during Sleep. § 286. The cause of Sleep is thus expounded "by Aristotle. There are four causes of everything (§ 95). The final cause of Sleep is the health of animals ; but the aim which Nature has in view is not Sleep, it is "Waking, since the aim of all animals is constituted by feeling and thinking, because these are the Best, and Nature always works for the Best. § 287. This subjective explanation will probably satisfy few readers. Let us, therefore, hear his physiological explanation. When the food enters the organs allotted to its reception, an evaporation, avaOv/uaaig, takes place into the veins; there it is transformed into blood, and carried to the heart. That which evaporates must ascend to a certain height, and then descend, turning back like the tides of Euripus. Now, the warmth in every animal is borne upwards ; having reached the uppermost parts, it turns back again and descends. Hence Sleep chiefly comes on after a meal, for then there is much and thick moisture which ascends, and this standing still oppresses the head, and creates sleepiness ; no sooner does it descend and in its descent drive away the warmth, than sleep arrives, and the animal drops off. This is proved by the effects of narcotics, for all these produce a heaviness of the head ; and those who are sleeping are in a similar con- dition, unable to raise their eyelids or their heads. And it is especially after meals that such a condition supervenes, because of the great evaporation from the food. § 288. Moreover, Sleep follows fatigue, for fatigue is a dis- solves ffvvTijriKov ; and that which is dissolved acts like undi- CHAP. XIV.] AND LONGEVITY. 261 gested food, if it be not cold. Certain diseases produce the same effect, especially those which arise from excess of warmth and moisture, as, for example, Fever and Lethargy. § 289. The reader will have noticed what a supreme dis- regard of everything like evidence, or even logical connection, is displayed in this explanation ; yet Aristotle had no suspicion of its wanting either. He applies it to the elucidation of several phenomena, as if it were an established truth. Thus he says, " The reason why young children sleep much is because all their food is carried upwards," and, as this latter position may require some proof, he adds, " the proof is seen in the fact that in infancy the upper parts are larger compared with the lower parts, and because it is in the upper that the growth is most active." § 290. More is made of this excess in the upper parts. It is the cause why infants, until they are about five months old, are unable to turn their heads round ; " it is with them as with drunken men — an immense quantity of moisture is carried upwards." § 291. Nay, this also serves to explain Epilepsy. " Sleep is said to be very like Epilepsy; hence this disease often begins in sleep, and its crises never occur in a waking state," a statement which will not receive the assent of pathologists. Epilepsy is produced " when a quantity of moisture has ascended, and in its descent swells the veins, which thus com- press the windpipe," an explanation which will also be rejected by pathologists. 3 § 292. We further learn that those who have large heads and small veins are great sleepers; whereas those who have large veins sleep little ; the former because the narrowness of their veins prevents the descending moisture from descending freely, and the greatness of their heads occasions a powerful 3 It is almost unnecessary to inform any reader that Epilepsy is now known to be a disease of a nervous centre. Consult Schroder van derKolk: Bau und "Functionen der Medulla Spinalis und Oblongata, 1860, and the writings of Broww Sequaed. 262 ON MEMORY, SLEEP, DKEAMS, [OHAP. XIV. evaporation ; whereas in the latter, who have large veins, the descent is easy and rapid, unless there be some other cause of obstruction. Bilious people sleep little, because their interior is always cold, and consequently there is but small evaporation going on in them ; and for a similar reason they are large eaters and have hard flesh, their body being ill adapted to absorb. The bile, being cold by nature, makes the nutritive and secretive organs also cold. § 293. My purpose will be greatly misunderstood if these absurdities are supposed to be dragged forward in triumphant hostility to the great name of Aristotle. Admirers have carefully ignored such things, and thereby deprived the general public of the lesson to be learned from seeing how an intellect so vast and so stored with various knowledge, could, nevertheless, allow itself to be the dupe of phrases, without ever raising one question as to the validity of the facts on which these phrases were formed. Seriously contemplated, there is something pathetic in the fatal facility with which the human mind at all periods has accepted a phrase as a revela- tion, never pausing to see whether the facts truly are what they are assumed to be, but satisfied if the phrase seems to explain the difficulty. § 294. Some difficulties, indeed, he attempted to remove. They are thus stated : — " Sleep appears, from what has been said, to be an inward concentration of warmth, and a reaction, or counter action. 4 Hence in the sleeper there is much movement ; hence, also, he becomes weaker and colder, and, on account of the cold, his eyelids droop. The upper and outward parts of the body are cold, the lower and inner parts are warm ; for example, the feet and viscera. But, perhaps, some may be sur- prised that Sleep should follow meals, that wine should be a narcotic, and that other heating things should produce * 6 inrvos larl aivolds ri£ row dcp/tov Aata Kai dvmrcpiarams $voua\. CHAP. Xiy.] AND LONGEVITY. 263 Sleep. It seems incomprehensible that Sleep should be a growing cold, and yet warmth be the cause of Sleep. Shall we say that when the stomach is empty it is warm, and when full it is made cold by movement, in the same way that the passages of the head and other places are made cold when the evaporation is carried there ? Or shall we say that, as those who drink suddenly a warm liquid are seized with shivering, so here also the heat ascending, the cold which arises from concentration makes the body cold, and drives away the natural warmth ? The same effect may arise from a quantity of food being taken, which acts like wood thrown on fire. Thus Sleep comes on when the heavy evaporation is carried by warmth to the head, and, unable to ascend higher, is forced to descend. Hence also men lie down when the heat which kept them erect is withdrawn; for man alone, of all animals, has an erect position, 5 and the descent of the vapour on the heart takes away all sensibility, and afterwards imagina- tion." 6 § 295. We now perceive the part assigned by Aristotle to the brain in the production of Sleep. Its part was that of a cooler of the evaporations from food. It is the coldest organ in the body (§ 164). "As the moisture, evaporated by the sun's heat, on reaching the upper air is chilled by the cold there, and falls back again in rain, so does the vapour of food, on reaching the cold brain, become condensed, and falls back again in mucus (hence the pituitary fluxion seems to come from the head), but that portion which is nutritive and not noxious descends and tempers the heat of the body. 7 Not only is the brain cold, but the smallness of its veins 6 Compare § 391 a. 6 %anpov Si favraaiav, which Bussemakee renders " deinde vero ima- ginationes subgerit," an interpretation warranted by A.'s theory of dreams. 7 This notion of fluxions from the brain plays an important part in the history of Medicine. See Hippocrates: Be Aere, Locis et Aquis; and com- pare it with Van Helmont's amusing and energetic protest: Catarrhi delira- menta, in his Opera Omnia, 1655, p. 271. 264 ON MEMORY, SLEEP, DREAMS, [QHAP. XIV. prevents the vapour from easily penetrating ; and thus, in spite of the great heat, it becomes cooled by the brain." § 296. " When the food is entirely cooked, and the heat being gathered into a small space, overcomes the cold, and when the thick blood has been separated from the thin, we awake. The blood which is in the head is thinnest, that which is in the lower parts is the thickest and most turbid ; and it is because after meals the blood is the least separated that Sleep lasts until the thinner blood goes upwards and the thicker downward. No sooner is this effected, than the animal, freed from the weight of food, awakes." § 297. Large space has been given to this treatise on Sleep, because it illustrates the thoroughly vicious method Aristotle pursued. We may also perceive in it a great want of logical connection, even with its own premisses. III. — Dreams. § 298. This little treatise stands in favourable contrast to its predecessors. Herein we see how the mere fact that the writer is no longer called upon to expound processes discoverable only by laborious investigation, leaves his mind disengaged from the trammels in which it moved so clumsily, and allows it full,' play. By this it is not meant that Dreams are not also dependent upon physiological laws ; but that they are to be elucidated by psychological observation, and for this Aristotle was as well equipped as any modern, except that he had a smaller range of recorded facts to draw from. If, therefore, his treatise still seems remarkable, we must attri- bute it either to his sagacity, which thus early detected the real elements of the problem, or else to the circumstance that being ourselves without a true solution, we are unable to see wherein his errors lie. § 299. He begins by inquiring to what part of the soul dreams address themselves. It cannot be the sensible part, since Sleep consists in insensibility. Nor can it be the CHAP. XIV.] AND LONGEVITY. 265 understanding. We hear and see in dreams, but not as when awake. A dream is a land of image. Imagination has been defined (in the treatise De Animd) as the motion produced by our sensibility in act. Sensible things produce sensations, and the motions thus produced continue after the exciting cause has vanished. Thus on going into a dark place, we are at first unable to see because the motions produced by the sun have not yet subsided. If we look steadily at a coloured object the sensation remains when the eyes are carried to other objects. To this must be added the fact of hallucination. We are constantly liable to deceptions of the senses when in the tumult of passion. During fever the patient sees animals in the lines on the wall of his room. § 300. These motions, which in the tumult of sensations are unperceived, because overpowered by the stronger move- ments, as a small fire is by a large fire, are perceived in the calmness of sleep. The inactivity of each special sense brings all these motions, which during the day are unperceived, to the origin of sensation (i. e. the sensitive centre : sort tx\v a.pyj\v ttjc aiadrjaiue) , and in the calmness become sensible. Like the ripples and circles caused by eddies, the sensations have their after movements ; sometimes these ripples and circles are repeated in the same forms ; at others they are broken and distorted by the obstacles they encounter. Young children do not dream; nor do adults dream soon after meals, 8 because then the movement caused by the ascending heat is great, and an image can then no more be formed than in troubled water; or if an image be formed it will be distorted and unlike the object. But when the water is calm the images are clear. § 301. Thus, in Sleep, images are formed ; the after- motions of sensations, when the disturbance is great, are 8 Kant: Anthropologic, Werke, 1838, VII., 30, maintains that we never sleep without dreaming; for, he argues, to cease to dream would be to cease to live. Yet he would hardly have maintained that we dream during syncope. 266 ON MEMORY, SLEEP, DREAMS. [CHAP. XIV. either destroyed or distorted, and our dreams are terrible, monstrous. It is the same with men drunk or in a fever. But when the separation of the blood has taken place, the after-motions are perceived, and then we see and hear. It is owing to these after-motions that we often, when awake, seem to see and hear sights and sounds not really existing. § 302. Dreams are the images, or after-motions of sensa- tion. But it is not every image presenting itself during sleep which is to be called a dream ; for if, when asleep, we hear a noise, feel a touch, or perceive a light, there being actually present the objects which excite these sensations, we cannot consider these to be dreams. § 303. Such is the theory of Dreams propounded by Aristotle. If we disengage it from the peculiar physiology in which it is enveloped, it will appear not unworthy a place beside modern theories, of which there are so many. And we may further remark that the theory seems to have been entirely his own, since he does not allude to the opinions of any predecessor. IV. — Longevity. § 304. The treatise De Longitudine et Brevitate Vita has several points of interest illustrative of his physiological views. After noticing the varieties in the longevity of animals he undertakes to explain the cause. We must assume, he says, that an animal is naturally moist and warm, and that Life depends on these conditions ; whereas old age is dry and cold, and so is Death, since so it manifests itself. The material of the body being thus compounded of moisture and warmth, dryness and cold, it is obvious that in growing old we dry up. It is necessary, therefore, that the moisture should not easily dry up. Hence fat bodies are preserved from decay because they are of air, and air acts like fire in relation to other things. 9 Now fire does not become putrid. The logic of this last sentence is strangely arbitrary. If CHAP. XIV.] AND LONGEVITY. 267 fire does not become putrid, its power of drying moisture is too familiar to have been overlooked. § 305. Moreover the moisture must not be too small in quantity. Hence we see why the larger plants and animals live longer ; they have more moisture. But this is not the sole reason. There are two causes operative : the quantity and the quality. The moisture must not only be considerable, it must also be warm ; so that it may neither congeal nor dry up easily. This explains why man is longer lived than much larger animals. Those animals which have less moisture will be long-lived if the quality of their moisture makes up for its deficient quantity. There are some whose fat and warmth makes it difficult to become dry and cold. § 306. Here the reader makes acquaintance with that radical moisture which played so conspicuous a part in old medical theories, and to which Walter Scott humourously alludes. The modern may, if he please, read into it an anti- cipation of the importance of water to the organism, of which it constitutes more than two-thirds by weight ; and in the accompanying warmth, he may also detect the agent of all organic activity. But the ancient ideas of moisture and warmth were founded on very different data from ours ; and few things would have astonished Aristotle more than hearing that water formed an integral constituent of solid bone, nay, even of the hardest of organic substances, such as the enamel of the teeth; and that animal heat was mainly produced by the action of that very air which, he thought, cooled the body. § 307. Another cause of Longevity is moderation in secretion; for all secretion destroys the animal, either by causing disease, or by its own action. The action of a secre- tion is adverse and destructive both of the whole organism and its parts. This is the reason why salacious animals quickly grow old ; why the mule lives longer than its parents ; why females live longer than males ; and why male sparrows are short-lived. 268 MEMORY, SLEEP, DREAMS, LONGEVITY. [CHAP. XIV. § 308. Fatigue also shortens life. Why? "Because fatigue produces dryness, and old age is dry. Males ought by nature to be longer-lived than females, since they have more warmth. 10 Animals live longer in warm than in cold climates for the same reason that the larger live longer than the smaller ; and it is those which are by nature cold which in warm countries grow to a great size : serpents and lizards in warm countries become enormous. Warmth and moisture are the causes of growth and life. But as the moisture in animals becomes more fluid in cold countries it more easily congeals. Hence in cold countries we find animals without blood, or with very little; or if we find any, they are very small and die young. Cold takes away their power of growth. § 309. " When plants and animals take no nourishment they perish : they then consume their own substance (o-uvi-rj/cEi ■yap aura eavra). For as a flame destroys a smaller flame by consuming its food, so animal warmth which is the primary digester destroys the substance in which it is." Here again a willing admirer may read an anticipation of modern physio- logy, which has no better explanation to give. § 310. Plants are the longest lived of all beings because they are less watery and less easily congealed; they are fat and viscid, and therefore, although dry and earthy, they do not easily lose their moisture. § 311. From the knowledge gained in the preceding chapters respecting Aristotle's physiological and psychological theories, we are now in a proper condition to examine the three great treatises on the " History of Animals," the " Parts of Animals," and " Generation and Development," which will conclude our survey. 10 Modern investigations show that tho average of life is slightly in favour of women; and that their temperature also is slightly superior to that of men. ( 269 ) CHAPTEE XV. "THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." 1 § 312. "I cannot read this work," says Ctjviek, "without being ravished with astonishment. Indeed it is impossible to conceive how a single man was able to collect and compare the multitude of particular facts implied in the numerous general rules and aphorisms contained in this work, and of which his predecessors never had anj idea." z By the time we have reached the end of the chapter it will probably be seen that this astonishment was very easily excited by the prestige of a great name, and that there is no 1 The best edition of the Historia Animalium is by Schneider, 4 vols., Leipzig, 1811. That by J. C. Scaliger, Tolosse, 1619, with the notes of Maussacus, is of interest to scholars only. There is a German translation by Strack, Frankfort, 1816, which is tolerably accurate ; and a well-known French translation by Camus, Paris, 1783, with the text, and a volume of notes, which, although no longer representing the zoology of our day, has'interesting matter. I can find no Italian or Spanish version. The Spanish work of Diego de Funes mentioned by Buhle (Opera,!., 269), is not a translation at all, but a compilation. (See note 13, chap, xvi.) During the revision of these pages there have appeared, 1st, a proposal for a new translation into English; and 2nd, the execution of such a proposal. The first is by the Rev. Mr. Houghton, in the Natural History Review, April, 1862, with the first book as a specimen, and decisive proofe of the utter untrust- worthiness of Taylor's version. The execution is by Mr. Ceesswell : Aristotle's History of Animals, in ten books, 1862 (Bonn's Classical Library). 2 Cuvier: Histoire des Sciences Nat., 1841, 1., 146. Inasmuch as the works of A.'s predecessors have all perished, it is rather perilous to assert their abso- lute deficiency in rules and aphorisms. 270 " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XV. impossibility at all in conceiving how a single man achieved what Aristotle actually did achieve — which is, however, wholly different from what Cuvier supposes him to have achieved. "The History of Animals," he continues, "is not pro- perly a zoology, that is to say a series of descriptions of various animals ; it is rather a sort of philosophic anatomy, in which the author treats of the generalities of organization presented by various animals, in which he explains their differences and resemblances, founded on a comparison of their organs, and in which he lays the bases of grand classifi- cations irreproachable in accuracy." § 313. There is a difficulty, we know, in speaking of Aristotle without exaggeration; but the language of Cuvier passes all bounds permissible to sincere enthusiasm ; the more so because of the authority attached to his own eminent name. Others speak with a like exaggeration, but not with a like authority. I am very far from any desire to understate the claims of Aristotle ; but it is my purpose to control the reckless assertions of critics who would severely scrutinize the claims of contemporaries, while they lavishly exaggerate the merits of the ancients. 3 3 See Buxton: Histoire Naturelle, I., p. 62. De Blainvtixe : Histoire des Sciences de V Organisation, 1847, I. Cahus : Traiti d'Anatomie Com- pare, Paris, 1833, Introd. Isidore Geoffroy St. Hilaire : Histoire Generate des JRegnes organiques, 1854, I. Bubmeister : Manual of Entomology, by Shuckhard, 1856, p. 597. Spix : Geschichte und Beur- theilung aller Systeme in der Zoologie, 1811, p. 18. Swainson: Discourse on the Study of Natural History, p. 6 (quoted by Houghton), says, " Had this extraordinary man left us no other memorial of his talents than his researches in Zoology, he would still be looked upon as one of the greatest philosophers of ancient Greece, even in its brightest and highest age." This may be accepted; but Macgillivray passes from Greece to modem times when he says that Aristotle was not only acquainted with numerous species, " he described them also according to a comprehensive and luminous method, which perhaps none of his successors have approached ! " — Lives of Eminent Zoologists, 1834, p. 55. The simple fact being that he has not described a single species, nor even attempted it. Of the same accuracy is the assertion that he has treated com- parative anatomy with genius, " and best deserves to be taken as a model. The principal divisions which are still adopted by naturalists in the animal kingdom are those of Aristotle, and he proposed some which have been resumed after CHAP. XV.] " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." 271 Looked at historically, that is to say with reference to the works which for centuries succeeded it, the "History of Animals" is a stupendous effort; but looked at absolutely, that is to say in relation to the Science of which it treats, it is an ill-digested, ill-compiled mass of details, mostly of small value, with an occasional gleam of something better. There is, strictly speaking, no science in it at all. There is not even a system which might look like science. There is not one good description. It is not an anatomical treatise ; it is not a descriptive zoology; it is not a philosophy of zoology; it is a collection of remarks about animals, their structure, resemblances, differences, and habits. As a collec- tion it is immense. But it is at the best only a collection of details, without a trace of organization ; and the details them- selves are rarely valuable, often inaccurate. § 314. Aware of the paradoxical aspect which such a judgment must present to the mind of every reader unpre- pared by a previous acquaintance with the "History of Animals," I shall bestow some pains to justify it in the following analysis. 4 And first let me endeavour to correct the very misleading remark of Ctjvier respecting the immense variety of parti- culars implied in its general aphorisms. Are they really generalized conclusions, drawn from an exhaustive survey of particulars ? When Aristotle asserts that no terrestrial animal is fixed to the ground, that all winged insects which have their stings at the fore part of the body are two-winged, whereas those which have the sting at the posterior part of the body are four-winged — the generalizations may imply either extensive observation, or rashness in drawing conclu- having been unjustly rejected." A similar strain of exaggeration may be read in Sonnenbtjrg : Zoologische-Kritische Bemerhungen zu Aristoteks Thier- Gesehichte, Bonn, 1857, p. 6. It is not thought enough to glorify Aristotle unless moderns are dwarfed beside him. 4 The appearance of the English translation will enable eyery reader to control this analysis. 272 " THE HISTOET OH' ANIMALS." [CHAP. XV. sions. Cuvier assumes the former. He says they " sup- posent un examen presque universel de toutes les especes." Now, from my acquaintance with Aristotle's mode of pro- cedure in general, and his facility in leaping to absolute con- clusions on the slenderest warrant, I am extremely doubtful on the point of his having carefully examined many, much less all insects before he concluded as to the relation borne by the stings to the number of wings ; not only is it unlike him to have pursued this laborious plan, but it is improbable from the very absoluteness with which he states the relation. If we reflect that the fact is wholly without illumination from physiology, and that no rational suggestion has yet been offered why the diptera should not carry their offensive weapon behind, we shall conclude it to have been simple rashness in Aristotle to have done more than notice it as a coincidence in all the insects observed by him. § 315. Cuvier has instanced four generalizations to prove the immense acquaintance Aristotle must have had with particulars. I will quote four others (forty might be found), all taken from the first book, which exemplify plainly enough how easily large and careful induction could be dispensed with. 1. The lion has no cervical vertebrae, but a single bone in its neck. 2. Long-lived persons have one or two lines which extend through the whole hand ; short-lived persons have two lines, and these do not extend through the whole hand. 3. Man has, in proportion to his size, the largest and the moistest brain. 3 4. The forehead is large in stupid men ; small in lively 5 Neither statement is correct. The relative size of the brain is much greater in birds, rodents, monkeys. The notion of a greater moisture in the human brain (several times repeated by him) may have arisen from one seen in a state of decomposition; or was perhaps purely a hypothetical assumption. Elsewhere, he speaks of the brain as one of the fluids (iyptiv), adding that of fluids it is the driest or most consistent {aixH-ipirarov).— De Partibus, II., 7. CHAP. XV. j " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." 278 men ; broad in men predisposed to insanity (karariKot.) ; and round in high-spirited men. § 316. We are not justified, therefore, in assuming that Aristotle was acquainted with all, or most, of .the particulars which may be implied in his generalizations ; since we see that he is quite ready to frame generalizations in the absence of anything like an inductive warrant. § 317. Are we justified in interpreting some of his generali : zations as profound attempts at classification? This is a more delicate inquiry. There are probably few who do not believe that among his claims to eminence as a biologist, must be named the first outline of a scientific Classification ; and were this idea correct, his rank would indeed be very high, for Classification is one of the latest results of scientific research. I may say at once that it is only by bringing together certain general statements, and disregarding the whole context, that a plausible scheme can be drawn up from his works ; and so far from his having laid " the eternal bases " upon which moderns have erected their classification, it does not appear that he had ever attempted a special arrangement of the various groups of animals. The reader must not reproach me with inconsiderate antagonism. Polemical discussion is forced on me by the reckless and misleading assertions of respected historians and critics. Except Db. Whewell and Agassiz I know of no one who treats this topic of Classification with any apparent solicitude to state the simple truth. Ehetorical exaggeration is supported by an arbitrary selection of phrases, and an omission of all the passages which contradict or qualify them. " Aristotle," says Ctjvier, 6 " divides animals into two grand classes : those which have blood, and those which have 6 To the same effect Deixe Chiaje : Istituzioni di Anatomia e fisologia comparata, 1 832, 1., p. xxxv. ; and indeed almost every writer who mentions the classification. 18 274 " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XV. no blood ; in other words, he divides, as we do, animals with red blood from animals with white blood." On turning to the original, do we find any such systematic division as this ? By no means. "We find the distinction noted, but it comes in quite casually at the close of a chapter, having no relation to what has gone before, none to what comes after it. True, it is frequently referred to in subsequent chapters ; but only as to a general remark, a sort of popular distinction, useful for its brevity. It is nowhere used as a principle of classification, but simply as a generality. The succeeding chapter opens with a remark of equal generality, which is not less frequently referred to, namely, " some animals are viviparous, some oviparous, and others vermi- parous. The viviparous include man, the horse, the seal, and all animals which have hair ; also among aquatic animals the cetacea, such as the dolphin and cartilaginous fishes." The next chapter opens with another remark of the same kind : " Animals have either feet or no feet ; the former have either two feet — as man, and no other animal, except the bird ; or four feet — as the lizard or dog ; or many feet — as the centipede, or bee." From this he passes on to the fins of fish, and the feathers of birds. § 318. Occasional reference is made to each of these < three distinctions ; but no one distinction is used as a prin- ciple of classification. The reason why no attempt was made is to be read in the treatise on the " Parts of Animals." He there argues at length against the idea of forming a classification upon a " principle of negation ; " and not only does he argue thus, but specially mentions this very case of bloodless animals as being of all others " the most difficult, nay impossible." 7 7 irdvTbiv Sk KakeirotTiiTov ij SiSivarov its ret dvaifia. I., 3, 9. Titze read 8 Avrucdprnia, " contraries," instead of «'c t& avaifxa. But this lection, which has no other authority, really makes very little difference in the meaning, since under the general term of contraries must be included the special distinction of animals with and without blood. CHAP. XV.] " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." 275 § 819. Even were not his views thus explicitly stated, we might gather from his practice that he never thought the division of animals, according to their blood or no blood, was a principle of classification ; rather should we seek one, if at all, in the division of viviparous, oviparous, and vermi- parous; for he did not know the extent to which Nature overleaps such boundaries, presenting us with viviparous amphibia, viviparous snails, viviparous insects, viviparous worms, and viviparous infusoria. 8 But it is evident that he had no idea of making generative distinctions the grounds of a classification. § 320. Eeturning to the distinction of animals into san- guineous and exsanguineous, we may observe that it does not quite represent the " animaux a sang rouge, et a sang blanc," for by exsanguineous Aristotle meant without blood, and not blood of a different colour. He held that the lower animals, i. e., reptiles and our invertebrata, had a fluid which was not blood, but analogous to it. 9 8 Although he knew that some of the cartilaginous fishes are viviparous, he too precipitately generalized the fact. The genera Raia and Scyllium are oviparous: Lacepede: Histoire naturette des Poissons 1798. Aristotle ex- cepted the Lophius piscatorius ; but he erred in supposing it to be a carti- laginous fish. The viviparous osseous fishes, Blennius and Anableps, he could not have known ; the former being found only in the German Ocean, and the latter in the waters of Surinam. See Rathke : Abhandlungen zur Bildungs und Entwickelungsgeschichte des Menschen und der Thieve. 1853, H., Erste Abhand. 9 De Partibus, I., 5, 15. Compare also Kohler : Aristoteles de MoUuscis cephalopodibus, Rigs, 1820, p. 2. Delle Chiaje makes it a reproach that Aristotle " reputd senza sangue que' viventi che ne sono a dovizia proveduti, ed in taluni di essi h questo rosso, di che lo stesso gran Linneo non si awide." Istituzioni di Anat. e fisiologia comparata, 1832, 1., xxxvii. Swammebdamm first pointed out that many of the earth worms had red blood; and he adds that the blood of the snail is a viscid reddish fluid.— Bibel der Natur, Leipzig, 1752, p. 54. Cutier himself was forced to admit the "vers a, sang rouge." Since then the blood of several annelids has been found to be green, pale yellow, and red; while that of some Tunicata and the Sipuncula is red, orange yellow, yellow, violet, blue. See Seaside Studies, 1st ed., 1858, p. 66; 2nd ed., 1860, p. 70 ; and compare Rouget : Comptes rendus de la SociM de Biologie, 1859, p. 172 ; also in Brown Sequard : Journal de la Physiohgk, 1859, H, 660. 18—2 276 " THE HISTORY OF ANIMAXS." [CHAP. XV. § 321. Another distinction he names is that of winged and wingless : the winged animals have feathers, like birds, or membraneous wings, like insects, or wings of skin, like bats. The first and last have blood ; the second are bloodless. § 322. The principal classes which have blood enumerated by him are birds (not reptiles : these he held to be bloodless), fish, and cetacea. " There is also another class, covered with a shell, vulgarly called shellfish ; and an anonymous class, the soft-shelled (malacostraca), which comprises crabs, carcini, astaci ; and another of mollusca (cephalopoda) ; and another of insects. The common character of the four last-named classes is to have no blood, and to have more than four feet when they have feet at all. There are no large classes besides these, for there are many forms which are not included under any common form ; but either stand alone, without difference between them, as Man ; or, if there are any different species they have not been named." " All wingless quadrup.eds have blood. Of these some are viviparous, some oviparous. Most of the oviparousjdiave hair ; the oviparous have scales. . . . Not all animals which are viviparous have hair, since some fish bring forth their young alive ; but all hairy animals are viviparous. In the class of viviparous quadrupeds there are many genera («§»)), but anonymous ; hence we are forced to name them severally, as man, lion, stag, horse, dog. On the other hand, there is a class which is made out of animals having manes — such as the horse, the ass, the oreus (Mule), the ginnus (Hinny), the innus (also a Mule), and the so-called hemionus (Half ass) of Syria, which is called a mule from its resemblance only, for it is really a distinct genus, which breeds with its own kind." § 323. He expressly tells us that this sketch is only an outline, or foretaste ; but there is no intimation that he re- garded it as inaccurate ; nor is there an intimation that he attempted to make any other classification than what naturally presented itself in the obvious differences of structure, habits, CHAP. XV.] « THE HISTOKY OF ANIMALS." 277 and habitat. All men had spontaneously grouped animals as fourfooted, winged, aquatic, terrestrial, oviparous, &c. ; nor has Aristotle attempted any more systematic grouping. In- deed, it is to mistake the whole course of scientific develop- ment to suppose that Classification can precede the labours which it can only succeed : its principles must be eliminated from the extensive research of comparative anatomy. From the days of Aristotle to those of Linn^tjs there was no im- portant step taken towards such an elimination, and this was mainly owing to the backward state of comparative anatomy. For what is the aim of a classification ? It is to group animals in such a manner that each class and genus shall in- dicate the degree of complexity attained by the organism, -and thus the external form betray the internal structure. § 324. No such scheme ever entered the head of Aristotle. He only wished to mark out the obviously distinctive cha- racters by which the common eye could recognize each class or genus. Historians have drawn up a scheme from his remarks, and presented it as his classification. But, naturally enough, they cannot agree among themselves as to the details. Meyee, 10 after mentioning the various schemes which have been drawn up, from Pliny to Ehrenberg, points out the violent contradictions visible in these attempts, and that these writers are not agreed as to Aristotle's method, main divisions, and subdivisions. Nay, more : not only do these doctors differ respecting the nature of the disease, but there are some who doubt whether there is any disease at all : they are not unanimous as to whether Aristotle had or had not a system. Furlanus is angry at such a doubt, and cannot conceive how any one should fail to detect the system. Artedi and Eeau- mur are equally puzzled to detect one. Buefon and Cuvier see the system plainly enough. Agassiz declares that " Aristotle cannot be said to have proposed any regular 10 Metee; Aristoteles Thierkunde, Berlin, 1855, p. 64. 278 " THE HISTOKY OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XV. classification. He speaks constantly of more or less extensive groups under a common appellation, evidently considering them as natural divisions ; but he nowhere expresses a con- viction that these groups may be arranged methodically so as to exhibit the natural affinities of animals." n The fact of such dissidences, on a point which ought not to admit of two opinions, is decisive. There can be no classi- fication where students mistake both the leading principles and particular applications. Zoologists may read a classifica- tion in Aristotle's pages ; but they do violence to the plain meaning of the text ; they disregard context, and piece toge- ther from far and wide detached observations never meant to be connected with each other. Whbwell aptly remarks that the construction of a classification " consists in the selection of certain parts as those which shall peculiarly determine the place of each species in our arrangement. It is clear, there- fore, that such an enumeration of differences as we have described, supposing it complete, contains the materials of all possible classifications. But we can with no more propriety say that the author of such an enumeration of differences is the author of any classification which can be made by means of them, than we can say that a man who writes down the whole alphabet writes down the solution of a given riddle or the answer to a particular question." 18 We may add that Albebtus Magnus, Gesner, and the other followers of Aristotle, saw no system in their master's work ; and why should we ? § 325. Having cleared away some of the obstructing mists of prejudice, we may now look at " The History of Animals" with more impartiality. 11 Agassiz : Essay on Classification, London, 1859, p. 802. Compare also J. C. ScAiiGEE in his commentary on the Hist. Animal., 1619, Lib. I., c. vii., p. 53, from which it is evident that he found no system of classification in the work. 12 Whewell : History of the Inductive Sciences, 1857, III., 289. CHAP. XV.] " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." 279 The abruptness with which it opens is so contrary to the practice of Aristotle, that there can be no reasonable doubt of the original introduction having been lost or transposed. Patrizio thought that the whole treatise was a continuation of the De Partibus; 13 but this idea will not withstand close scrutiny ; the De Partibus manifestly succeeds the " History of Animals" (§ 357). The ingenious suggestion of Titze " seems at first sight to remove the difficulty. He thinks the first book of the De Partibus has been transposed from the " History of Animals," to which indeed it forms a very good introduction. To this Fbanzids, in his edition of the De Partibus, has given his assent. Yet on a due consideration, it seems to me that the difficulty is only shifted ; the one work gains an in- troduction which the other loses. A commencement of the De Partibus at the second book will be not less abrupt than the present commencement of the " History of Animals ; " moreover, there is a passage distinctly referring to the " His- tory of Animals " in this first book (§ 357). 15 § 326. Book I. opens, without a word of preamble, by a division of the organism into similar and dissimilar parts, which may be regarded as the first dawn of a conception of philosophic anatomy, such as Fallopia more distinctly con- ceived, and Bichat made the foundation of modern histology. Since Bichat, the organism has always been understood as composed of elementary tissues, which combine to form organs, and these organs combine to form systems. It is, therefore, 13 Patritii : Discussionum Peripateticarum tomi quatuor, Bale, 1581, I., c. ix., p. 118. 14 Titze : 'AfnaroreXovg \6yog o irtpi Qvoeiug rrjg £o>iKrjg /mXhtto fuBoSueog, Prag., 1819. 15 Neither Ritter nor Beandis makes any mention of Titze's proposal ; whence we may conclude that they thought little of it. It is, however, adopted by Sundebaix: Die Thierarten des Aristoteles, Stockholm, 1863 ; a valuable and candid exposition of the subject, which came into my hands too late for more than this passing recommendation. 280 " THE HISTORY OP ANIMALS." [CHAP. XV. difficult without equivoque to use Aristotle's language ; but if by similar parts, partes similares, 16 we understand those which are general, and by dissimilar parts, those which are indi- vidual, his meaning will be plain. § 327. " The parts of animal bodies," is the opening sentence, " are either simple, that is, admit of being divided into similar parts — as, for example, muscle into muscles ; 1T or they are composed of dissimilar parts — such as the hand, which can no more be divided into several hands than the face into several faces. Some of these parts are also called limbs, those namely which, while they form wholes, are com- posed of many parts, such as the head, the foot, the hand, the arm, and the thorax. All these compound parts are formed of simple parts — as the hand from flesh, sinews, and bones." § 328. In some animals all the parts are the same, in others they differ. In those which are of the" same class, the parts only differ in excess or defect. But some animals do not agree thus. They have parts which from their resem- blance may be called analogous. " Thus a bone is the analogue of a fish bone, a nail of a claw, a hand of a crab's nipper, a feather of a fish's scale, for it is plain that what the feather is to the bird, that is the scale to the fish." Here we see another germ of modern science, the thdorie des analogues, which, especially since Goethe, and Geoffeoy St. Hilaike, has given so much precision to transcendental anatomy, when coupled with the theory of homologies. § 329. After dividing the simple parts into those which are moist, and those which are dry, he proceeds to enumerate w . Aristotle was the first to use the term b/iow/upi'). Compare Phiufpson : ii\)j dvQpwirivr], p. 4. 17 olov adpiceg elg adpKag. He did not know muscle as we understand it ; yet I cannot otherwise intelligibly render the phrase. Strack says, " Fleisch und Fleisch/atfe™; " but this conveys the erroneous impression that A. knew the fibrous structure of muscles. (Cresswell is boldly literal, " flesh, into pieces of flesh.") CHAP. XV.] " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." 281 the various grounds of distinction among animals. This is done rapidly and in outline, details being left for future occasions. He then proceeds to examine the constituent parts of animals ; and first of man, because of all animals man is the best known. By this he means the external parts of man are the most familiar ; and after a very dry and some- what trivial enumeration of these familiar parts, he says that the internal parts being unknown, we must compare them with the parts of animals most resembling man. 18 § 330. He commences his exposition of the internal organs with meagre and inaccurate notices of the brain, lungs, heart, kidneys, liver, &c. Even Cuvier is forced to admit that on these topics "his ideas have not the same exactitude ; " but tries to save his character by adding, — " One sees that on certain points of d.etail he is a better observer than the majority of his successors." Now this is certainly untrue of Galen, whose knowledge of anatomy was incom- parably more accurate than Aristotle's ; nor, with the single exception of the questionable mention of the Eustachian tube, is there one point upon which Aristotle can be said to have observed what his successors overlooked. § 331. Book II. — Having in the first book described the external and internal parts of man, he now proceeds to describe those of animals. Here, as throughout, we have to note the singular prodigality of detail which is displayed : almost every line contains a fact, and often a generality em- bracing a wide range of facts. There may be, and indeed there is, considerable inaccuracy in his statements, but we see the mighty energies of dawning Science in this gathering together of facts which Philosophy was but too prone to ignore. Had he only been half as solicitous about the quality, 18 So carelessly is Aristotle spoken of even by historians of science that we find Spix declaring " A. makes man the standard both for internal and external structure, and executes his descriptions in a masterly style."— Geschichte und Beurtheilung alter Systeme in der Zoologie, p. 18. 282 " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XV. as he showed himself about the quantity of his facts, the work would perhaps have delighted his contemporaries less, but it would have been an instructor for all time. To cite a third of the examples of careless observation and rash generalization would be to inflict a needless weariness on the reader ; yet as the accuracy of Aristotle's observation is not unfrequently vaunted, a specimen or two, taken at random, must be given. § 332. I. " The male has more teeth than the female in man, 19 sheep, goats, and swine. In other animals the obser- vation is imperfect." II. " Fish have no external organs of Sense, not even the passages of hearing and smelling." III. " The heart of the ox is peculiar ; for there is a kind of ox, though not every kind, which has a bone in its heart ; and in the heart of the horse there is also a bone." (§ 389.) IV. " Some animals have a gall-bladder attached to the liver, others none. The Achainian deer seems to have one on its tail ; that which is called the gall-bladder in this animal resembles it in colour, but is not liquid, and is more like the spleen in structure." § 333. Naturalists have been interested to find the men- tion of a ruminating fish in this book. Here is the passage : " Fish have one simple stomach, but it differs in form ; in some it is like an intestine, as in the scarus, and this is the only fish which seems to ruminate." The statement is repeated twice. 20 We note that the fact is unaccompanied by any expression of surprise (compare § 201), and also unaccompanied by anything like evidence. If true, the fact must be one difficult of observation, since 10 It may be supposed that a fact so easily verified as the normal number of teeth in woman could hardly have been misstated unless on the warrant of some superficial evidence ; and ae some women never cut their wisdom teeth — a fact also noticed in certain men — an example of this kind may have famished Aristotle with his conclusion. 80 In Book VHI., c. xiv., p. 675, and in De Part. HI., 14. CHAP. XT.] " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." 283 fish will not exhibit their ruminating propensities out of the water ; and in the water, it could hardly have been watched. Is it true ? 21 § 334. Book III. continues the enumeration of the inter- nal organs. It casually reveals the fact that there were illus- trated books in those days ; since references are made to a diagram in which the letters a, b, c, d, indicate the parts spoken of in the text, just as in a modern work. The descriptions of veins, sinews, muscles, hair and flesh need not be cited here ; but the chapter on the blood is too interesting to be passed over. First be it noted that the blood is said to be, in common with the brain and spinal marrow, without sensation. What does this mean ? Probably he wishes to guard against the false conclusion that blood may be sensitive, because flesh is the medium of sensation, and blood is transformed into fat, marrow, and flesh. Or it may be that he is simply protesting against Plato, who held that opinion. § 335. " The taste of blood in a healthy condition is sweet, and its colour red ; but when of inferior quality, or damaged by sickness, it is black." The sweetness of the blood is probably a metaphorical expression. The blackness was observed in blood drawn from the veins, and, as it was only drawn in cases of sickness, the coincidence stood for cause. § 336. " Inside the body blood has a certain warmth and fluidity : but outside it coagulates, except in deer and animals resembling them. The blood of other animals coagulates, unless the fibres are removed : eav firj e^aipiOwmv al ivsq." 21 Milne Edwakds states it without misgiving in his Lefons sur la Physio- logie et t'Anat, comparte, 1861, VI., 290, referring to Owen's Lectures on the Vertebrata, as his authority. In a private note Prof. Owen informs me that the Scans named by Aristotle has not been identifie*, but that " the carp by a rotatory motion of the gullet brings the vegetable food-contents of the stomach successively within the sphere of the action of the strong pharyngeal grinding teeth, whence the pulp is returned to the stomach fitted for passing the pylorus." 284 " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XV. This is a remarkable passage. Although the blood of deer is really no less coagulable than that of other quadrupeds, there is some probability in a genuine observation having originated the error ; since modern physiologists affirm that in the blood of a hunted animal the fibrine disappears, or is so much lessened, as to prevent coagulation. Now, it is possible that Aristotle's observation was made on the blood of a hunted deer. Even more noteworthy is the mention of fibrine or fibres, al ivfc, as the cause of coagulation. One might, without an over-anxiety to read modern discoveries into ancient texts, regard this as an anticipation of Malpighi's discovery of fibrine being the coagulable material; 22 an anticipation also of the further discovery by Boeelli that this fibrine is liquid while in the blood-vessels, and only coagulates on exposure to the air; 23 since it might be argued that Aristotle knew the fibrine to be liquid in the blood ; otherwise, when specifying the fluidity of the blood, he would have excepted its fibres. Yet such an argument would be very questionable. He was only repeating the notion shared by Plato respecting the existence of fibres in the blood ; and we have but to open the Timceus to see how far that notion was from the truth. Plato thought the fibres actually existed as fibres in the blood, and that by their aid its motions were effected ! § 337. Aristotle seems to have made, or collected, some observations on the comparative rapidity of coagulation, for he states that the blood of oxen coagulates more rapidly than that of any other animal. I am not aware whether this is exact; but experiment has proved that the blood of oxen sheep and dogs coagulates faster than that of man. § 338. " Fat animals have purer blood, but in small quantity. Man has. the purest and thinnest ; oxen and asses 22 Malpighi : De Polyp., p. 125, in Opera Omnia, Loud., 1686. 23 Borelli : Be Motu Animalium, liome, 1681, II., prop, cxxxii., p. 265. CHAP. XV.J « THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." 285 the thickest and blackest." These imaginary facts are suc- ceeded by the following a priori statement, deduced from the axiom that the upper must be the nobler part: — "In the lower parts of the body the blood becomes thicker and blacker than in the upper parts." Of equal value is the assertion that the blood of woman is thicker and blacker than that of man. § 339. The book concludes with remarks on milk and its coagulation, from which may be cited the mention of the occasional appearance of milk in the male. He speaks of a male goat at Lemnos which yielded enough milk for cheeses to be made from it, and whose male descendants inherited the peculiarity. Nor is this the fable it was long held to be. Bukdach 2 * cites several well-attested cases of males yielding milk. Humboldt saw aman in A merica who suckled _his ' child for five months, during the lHnessafhis wife; and Isidore ""GIiopfroy SrTTlSATET^aT*foTsome years, in the Jardin des Plantes, a male goat with largely developed udders yielding milk. V- § 340. Book IV. — The first seven chapters of this book are devoted to the anatomy of invertebrata, and are not only rich in details, but approach more nearly to the demands of a systematic treatise than any other portion of the work. The cephalopoda are first described, and with a minuteness which could only come from familiarity with their forms. That he gathered much of his information from fishermen is obvious : yet it will be remarked how singularly free his statements are from the absurdities which commonly distort the narratives of fishermen. Not only does he withhold credence from their marvellous stories, which is in itself remarkable, when we consider how credulous were his contemporaries and suc- cessors, and how uncritical he himself often is respecting facts and explanations; but in another place he distinctly intimates the reason of fishermen's ignorance, — " that these 84 Bukdach : Traitt de Physiohgie, Paris, 1839, IV., 382. 286 " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XV. people never make direct observations for the sake of knowledge." s5 § 341. Every naturalist recognizes at once, by unmistake- able though indefinable indications, the portions of a work which are compiled without direct knowledge ; and will see in Aristotle's treatment of the cephalopoda traces of that personal knowledge which he, perhaps, first gained in the pleasant idleness of boyhood. 26 Yet although he was doubtless familiar with them from his early years, as with many other forms of marine life in his book, there are no traces of the naturalist's enjoyment. It has no out-of-doorness. We never feel the sea-breeze blowing; we never hear the delicious ripple of the waves against the advancing keel ; we never hear the creaking whirr of the net being hawled on board. From anything to be gathered from this book, we might conclude that the author had only toiled amidst the dust of libraries and museums, like the veriest professor of an inland university. 2T § 342. He next describes the Crustacea, and then the Testacea ; in both displaying more anatomical knowledge than is shown in the descriptions of the vertebrata. A brief 25 oiOtlg y&p avriav oiiBiv rrjpet rotavrov tov yv&vai %dpiv. — He Gen. Animal., HI., 5, 756. His rejection of the fables reported by writers such as Ctesias shows even more discrimination ; for as Pliny truly says, though his own excessive credulity renders the phrase rather ludicrous in his mouth, " mirum est quo procedat Graca credulitas ! Nullum tam impudens men- dacium est, ut teste careat." VHI., 22. Compared with this writer, or with Pliny, Aristotle is a model of sober sagacity ; compared with the naturalists of this century, he is somewhat easy in credulity. 26 Koiiler : Aristoteles de Moll use is cephalopodibus, Riga, 1820, has col- lected all the passages in which A. speaks of the cephalopoda in his three principal treatises. See a still more exhaustive notice in the essay by At/bert: Die Cephalopoden den Aristoteles in the Zeitschrift fur Wissenschafiliche Zoohgie, 1862, XII., 372. 27 Yet a genuine naturalist could say of it : " It is less intended as a summary of his general views respecting their organization and habits, than as a popular exordium calculated to engage the attention of the reader and excite him to the study of Nature." — Macgillivray: Lives of the Zoologists, 1834, p. 62 ; and Sonnenburg has the courage to assert that its "natural and simple style " gives it a charm which is wanting to most modern works. — Zoohgische-hritische Bemerkungen, p. 6. CHAP. XV.] " THE HISTOKY OF ANIMALS." 287 description of the structure of Insects completes his survey. No classes are proposed for worms, polypes, medusas, &c, the reason for which he has given elsewhere. " No groups have been made because there is no one form which embraces many forms." § 343. Chap. VIII. passes to the enumeration of the organs of Sense, in invertebrata. I will only pause to notice one detail. "With regard to sight and hearing in the Testacea," he says, " nothing is very clear. The solen seems to fly when any noise is made, and on feeling the approach of the iron rod which is used to capture it ; and the pecten, when a finger approaches, opens and shuts as if it saw." He here contents himself with recording the observed facts, which seem to imply the existence of senses. He did not know that the pecten has eyes, studding its mantle like jewels ; but, what- ever vision the pecten may possess, it does not open and shut at the approach of a finger. § 344. Chap. IX. is devoted to the voices of animals, distinguishing between Voice and Sound, and Speech, which is different from both. Voice is only produced by the pharynx ; therefore, no animal without lungs has a voice. The rigorous exactness of this distinction is seen when he comes to treat of ,the so-called voice of fishes. " Fish are mute, for they have no lungs, no windpipe, no pharynx. Some of them emit sounds and squeaks, which are hence said to have a voice. But some of these produce the sound by the friction of their gills which are spinous ; others produce the sound internally, near the stomach. And all have an organ of breathing (air- bladder ?) which causes a sound when pressed and moved. Some cartilaginous fishes also seem to whistle, but they cannot properly be said to have a voice, only to utter a sound." 28 88 Johannes MUiaer in his Archiv fur Anat. und Physiohgie, 1857, p. 249, has given an elaborate survey of existing knowledge on the voices of the fish with valuable additions of his own. Dufosse has also treated the subject in a Memoire addressed to the Academic des Sciences, Feb., 1858. 288 " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XV. § 345. Chap. X. treats of Sleep. In a former paragraph (§ 284) we drew attention to the distinction between Sleep and Repose; and the remark must be repeated apropos of this chapter, in which the various indications of animal sleep are brought together. Aristotle thinks it by no means clear that oviparous animals dream, but is certain that they sleep. § 346. Chap. XI. enumerates the distinctions of sex ; but this subject is more fully treated elsewhere. § 347. Book V. commences the enumeration of the chief particulars concerning Generation. Chapters I. to XIV. specify the various modes of congress, the breeding periods, and periods of puberty. Out of the mass of details here collected, true, false, and trivial, we shall only cite one ; and this not as a specimen of the rest, but as an example of the unreasoning credulity which propagates vulgar errors, and from which, as we have seen, even Aristotle was by no means free. The hen-partridge, he says, is impregnated if the wind blows from the male ; nay, at certain periods, it is frequently enough for them only to hear his voice as he flies over them and they become impregnated by his breath. § 348. Chap. XIV. suddenly quits the subject of Genera- tion and without any transition passes to a description of the structure and habits of Sponges ; a defect in composition which might justify a suspicion of this being an interpolation, did not the whole work exhibit extreme laxity in the arrange- ment of its materials. § 349. Chap. XV. to the end of the book continues the subject of Generation. § 350. Book VI. is a continuation of the same subject, the first nine chapters being devoted to Birds ; the next eight chapters to Fish; and the remainder to viviparous animals with feet. As we shall hereafter have to consider his views on generation more in detail, we need not pause over these chapters, except to notice the spontaneous generation of eels from mud. CHAP. XV.] « THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." 289 " Eels are not reproduced from sexual congress, nor are they oviparous. Dissection reveals neither sperm nor eggs, nor the generative organs. And this is the only animal possessing Hood which does not arise from congress or from eggs. That this is so, however, is evident, since after rain they appear in ponds which have heen dried up. But they are never produced in dry places, nor in ponds always full : they are nourished by rain-water. They originate in the bowels of the earth." § 351. Book VII. is only a fragment, and is devoted to a continuation of the subject of the two former books, but restricted to man. For the reason already mentioned (§ 350), we pass it over with the simple remark that in it may be found many of the notions current in medical literature up to the eighteenth century. § 352. Book VIII. opens with a description, already quoted (§ 175-179), of the ascending complexity in the scale of organic life, and then passes on to a variety of details respecting animals. First of the different localities they inhabit ; then of their food ; then of their migrations ; then of their hybernation and their various relations to tempera- ture. It next treats of the diseases to which they are subject. Here, as may be expected, there are many absurd notions, some so contradicted by ordinary experience that it is difficult to understand how a man of his amazing sagacity could have given them credence. For example, mentioning the madness of dogs, he says that all animals bitten by rabid dogs become rabid, except man. Again, " horses ranging the meadows suffer from no disease except gout, which destroys their hoofs ; one sign of this disease is the appearance of a hollow wrinkle beneath the nose." Domesticated horses suffer from various diseases. The Elephant is only troubled with two diseases, flatulence and diarrhoea. 29 Mice die if they drink during summer. 59 Repeated by Pliny, Hist. Nat, VIII., 10. 19 290 " THE HISTOBY OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XV. § 853. Book IX. is on the habits and instincts of animals. The details are frequently very interesting, and on the whole tolerably accurate; but they are merely collected as details, without any attempt at systematic arrangement, so that the book is a quarry rather than a composition. It shows Aris- totle's love of facts for their own sake ; but it shows little of the philosophic power with which naturalists have so gratuitously credited him. Like most boys, and many men who call themselves naturalists, he was eager enough in collecting facts and anecdotes ; but there is no more illumi- nation of such facts by biological principles, no more attempt so to co-ordinate them as to evolve general principles, than in the labour of species-mongers who pass their lives in registering the spots on a butterfly's wing, the curves of a shell, or the markings of Diatomacese. Spix has had the courage to avow this : " Aristotle was so far from giving a form to his wealth of details that he was content to publish a chaos of observations and opinions as materials for some future architect.. His ' History of Animals ' thus resembles a great market where each one may choose what he wants." 30 Only he must not want accuracy. § 354. From the foregoing analysis the reader will be able to judge how far Ctjviee's opinion is acceptable, and with what justification this work can be pronounced "one of the greatest monuments which the genius of man has raised to Natural Science." 31 That it is a marvellous work, consider- ing the period at which it was produced, and the multiform productions of its author, every one must admit. But this is not admitting its claim to be regarded as a great monument of Science. It is no more a monument than a brick-kiln is an architectural achievement. There are plenty of facts, some valuable, some trivial, many false. There is no colliga- 30 Spix: Geschichte und Beurtheilung aller Systeme in der Zoologie, 1811, p. 22. 31 Cuvier : Op. cit., I., 166. CHAP. XV.] " THE HISTORY OF ANIMALS." 291 tion of these facts — none of the general principles which could bind them into a serviceable system, and form a work of science. In his day it was a great thing for an eminent thinker to bestow so much care upon the collection of facts ; but this could only be a preparation for future science ; 32 and one luminous principle is worth a thousand unconnected facts, for it contains within it the seeds of a thousand discoveries. § 355. There is not a single principle established by Aristotle in this work which would lead the student to new discoveries, or enable him to illuminate the old. He could not, knowing this work by heart, class a single new animal, even provisionally, nor explain a single biological pheno- menon. And the best answer to its eulogists is History, which teaches that no zoological science was even begun until many centuries afterwards. Had Aristotle really laid the " eternal bases," had he placed in the hands of men a new instrument of research, Zoology would have advanced as Astronomy advanced from Hippaeohus to Ptolemy. § 356. Once more let me remind the reader that these objections are not directed against Aristotle, but against his careless panegyrists. They would be preposterous if urged against the great thinker in the early days of science. One might as well insult Greek civilization by a triumphant enume- ration of its deficiencies, and point to its want of a post-office or a free press. But the language of panegyrists is as sweep- ing as it is exaggerated. The real historical greatness of Aristotle does not suffice them ; they insist on our accepting him as an authority. » "In so complex a science as that which relates to living beings," says EmiH, "accurate and diligent empirical observation, though the best of things as far as it goes, will not take us very far , and the mere accumulation of facts without generalization and classification is as great an error in el- lectually, as hygienically would be the attempt to strengthen by accumulating nourishment without due attention to the print* vi^tte ™f » ^ being chiefly giddiness and confusion in the head.»-0» the Cell-Theory m the British and Foreign Medical Review, Oct., 1853, p. 291. iy— — 2 ( 292 ) CHAPTER XVI. " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." 1 § 357. The position of this treatise immediately after the one just analyzed is clearly indicated in Aristotle's programme of study. " First, we must understand the phenomena of animals ; then assign their causes ; and finally, speak of their generation." The " History of Animals " undertakes the first ; the De Partibus undertakes the second ; and the treatise to be analyzed in the next chapter undertakes the third. The work now before us has been comparatively little studied. Editors have neglected it ; translators have avoided it ; students generally have found it uninteresting. And indeed it wants the abundance of detail, and the more attractive sub- ject of the " History of Animals ; " it is, moreover, very difli- cult to understand. Yet as an attempt to explain the causes of biological phenomena, it deserves close attention. § 358. Book I., Chap. I., opens with the question whe- ther "it is necessary to treat of each individual separately, or to treat of that which is common to them all. For there are many things alike in different animals, such as sleep, respiration, growth, decay, and death. Of these we can say 1 The best edition of the De Partibus is that by Eranzhjs, with a translation and excellent notes, Leipzig, 1853. I cannot find any English, Italian, Spanish or French versions. CHAP. XVI.] " ON THE PARTS OP ANIMALS." 293 nothing clear or certain as yet. But it is evident that by separate treatment the same things must frequently be re- peated. . . . It is otherwise with those things which are included under one name, but which have nevertheless dif- ferences of kind, such as Locomotion, which may be flying, creeping, swimming, or walking. Hence we must first settle whether our inquiry is to begin with that which is common to the whole class, and then proceed to the particulars, or at once commence with each animal by itself." There being several causes, for example, the moving cause and the final cause, we must settle which of these naturally comes first. The final cause must evidently be treated first, for it is the reason, \6yog, and reason is the beginning of every product of art and nature. § 359. Here follow metaphysical distinctions respecting necessity, form, and cause, from which the following is all that need here be quoted : " We must say since man is to be, therefore he has such and such parts, for without these he cannot be. Since he is such a being, he must of necessity have such an origin, and in such a manner : therefore this part and then that part- is originated." § 360. In his teleology will be noticed an opinion directly the reverse of the one now generally current. In modern science, final causes, long since almost banished from astronomy and physics, find refuge mainly in biology ; whereas Aristotle thought that the order and regularity of astronomical pheno- mena more decidedly implied the action of a final cause than the irregular and capricious phenomena of the organic world. § 361. Without very explicitly stating his views, Aristotle gives us to understand that he held a similar opinion to that of moderns respecting Species, as real existences, or Types. " It is evident," he says, " that there must be something which we call nature, o Sq «u KaXoi/iev tfimv." The word f&nc, however, had to the Greek mind different suggestions from that which the word Nature has to us, and resembled 294 " ON THE PARTS OP ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. rather the natura naturans of Spinoza. The passage just given is thus elucidated : " For it is not any thing that issues from a seed, but a particular body from each particular seed, and every seed from its own particular body. The seed is therefore the beginning and the plastic material of that which is formed out of it. But prior to it is the Being, of which it is the seed ; for the seed is the genesis, and the final cause is the existence." 2 § 362. Chaps. II. and III. treat of classification, or of such rude attempts as were then in vogue. His criticism of dichotomy is obviously directed against Plato. As before noticed (§ 318), he considers the attempt to classify by dividing genera according to two characters, partly difficult and partly impossible. Dichotomy, he says, would scatter allied animals — some birds, for example, would be placed in one division, and others in another. The strongest objection, however, is that the dichotomist must erect Negation into a principle: " but there can be no distinctions under a negation ; for it is impossible that there should be species of nothing ; there can be no species of wingless or footless as of winged and footed animals." It is difficult to draw such distinctions even in animals which present species, as, for example, in the division of winged and wingless, since one and the same animal may be both, as in the case of the ant, the glow-worm, and some others. There can be little doubt that Aristotle has here pointed out the scientific error of all classifications founded on nega- tives ; and that his criticism reaches even the familiar division established by Lamarck, and now universally accepted, of vertebrata and invertebrata. The vertebrata form a natural division, characterized by an obvious peculiarity ; but to lump together all other animals, no matter how manifestly different, merely on the negative character of their having no vertebral * ykviaiQ utv yelp tI> airepfia, oiaia U ri t'bXoq. CHAP. XVI.] « ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." 295 column, is— except as a provisional expedient— eminently unphilosophie. 3 § 363. But although dissatisfied with the systematic attempts of predecessors, Aristotle does not offer one of his own. He follows the common method of grouping together all animals which have several obvious characters, rather than grouping them by any single character. " This is the way the vulgar have grouped birds and fishes." " No part of an animal arises without matter (SAjj) ; nor can it exist as matter alone ; since there is no animal, nor part of an animal which is simply body (avjia.) Moreover, it is necessary to distinguish between what is essential, and what is accidental Also, we must classify according to opposites; for opposites imply differences, as black and white, straight and crooked." § 364. Chap. IV. — He here says that some surprise may be felt at men not having classed aquatic and winged animals together, since they have several characters in common. But there is a good reason for it. All kinds which differ only in degree have been united under one genus ; those which only resemble each other by analysis have been separated. Birds, for example, are distinguished among each other by some preponderance, one having the wings shorter, another longer ; but fish are distinguished from birds, because their resem- blance is only one of analogy : the one having scales, the 3 On the principles of classification compare Lettckabt : Uber die Morpho- logie und die Verwandtschaftsverhaltnisse der wirbellosen Thiere, 1848, p. 7. Meckel: Traite" d'Anat. Comp., Paris, 1828, I., p. 90. Victor Carus: Systeme du thierischen Morphologie, 1853. Van deb Hooven : Handbook of Zoology, trans, by Clark, 1856. De Blainville : De I' Organisation des Animaux, 1832, I. Bronn : Die Klassen und Ordnungen des Thierreichs, 1859, I. Agassiz : Essay on Classification, London, 1859. Von Baer : uber Entwickelungsgeschichte der Thiere. Erste Theil, 1828, p. 89, 90, and the whole of the 5th scholion ; also his essay in the Nova Acta Physico-Medica, 1826, translated by Huxley in the Scientific Memoirs, Lond., 1853, 1., p. 176. Isidore Geofproy St. Hilaire : Hist. Nat. des Regnes Organiques, 1854, I. It is unnecessary to name works which will spontaneously present themselves to the reader's mind. 296 " ON THE PARTS OP ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. other feathers. But to carry this out through all animals is not easy ; for many animals have the same analogies." We see here a dim perception of the Natural Method ; but, as Schleidbn 4 justly remarks, it is only such a perception as lies in the common knowledge of all peoples, and which neces- sarily precedes the Artificial Method. To credit Aristotle with any profound insight into the superiority of the Natural over the Artificial Method, is to misconceive the whole course of historical development. He had no tolerable example of the Artificial Method before him. He had not even arrived at the conception of Class, Order, Family, Genus, and Species. His groups were all roughly marked out by certain obvious characters. § 365. Chap. V. contains an earnest defence of the study of Biology : a defence not wholly superfluous even in our own days, when protests against a "trivial curiosity respecting flies and tadpoles " may occasionally be heard issuing from grave men too facile in contempt of what they do not understand. " Even in objects unattractive to the vulgar eye, Nature offers inex- pressible delights to the philosophic mind capable of studying her causes. For it would indeed be strange and foolish if we, who take delight in such objects when we see them repre- sented in art, should not be even more attracted by Nature herself. Nor must we indulge in childish repulsions ; for in all natural objects there lies marvellousness ; and if any one/ despises the contemplation of inferior animals, he must despise himself." \ § 366. Book H., Chap. I. — He now proceeds to explain what is known of the parts of animals. Referring to the History of Animals, in which has been explained " out of what, and of how many parts they are composed," he has now to inquire into the causes why each part is what it is. Our threefold study of structure, chemical, histological, and ana- 4 Schleidbn : Grundzilge der wissenschaftlichen Botanih, 1861, p. 7. CHAP. XVI.] " ON THE PARTS OP ANIMALS." 297 tomical, may be found indicated in the opening of this book. There are three kinds of composition, he says ; the first is that of the elements— fire, earth, air, and water ; the second is that of similar parts— bones, flesh, &c. ; the third is that of dissimilar parts— face, hands, &c. This, although the order of our study, is not the order of nature, which indeed is the reverse. For that which is last formed in the animal, is the first in its essence or being ; just as a house does not exist for the sake of the bricks and mortar, but prior to them. In respect of Time, substance and its formation are prior to the formed animal ; but in respect of Eeason {i.e. according to our con- ceptions) the essence and the form are prior. It is evident that the conception of house-building includes the conception of a house ; but the conception of a house does not include that of house-building. Thus we see that the elements are for the sake of the similar parts ; and the similar parts are for the sake of the dissimilar. § 367. Some parts of the animal are functional, and others are sensitive. The functional parts are all composed of the dissimilar parts : the sensitive of the similar. The reason he alleges is characteristic. Sensation must arise in the similar parts because every sensation is of one kind. No philosopher has ventured to assert that the hand, face, or any other dissimilar part was fire, earth, air, or water ; but they have assigned the various sensations to air and fire. § 368. " Although sensation has its seat in the similar parts, yet it is natural that Touch should be in a simple, though not altogether simple, part ; for it has several kinds, such as Warmth and Cold, Dryness and Moisture; and the part which is sensitive to these — the flesh and its analogue in animals without flesh — is the most corporeal of sensitive structures. 5 . . . As it is impossible for an animal to opovi[*u>Tepa, than many animals with red blood ; and of the red-blooded those are the most intelligent which have the thinnest and the coldest blood. The best of all are those which have warm, pure, and thin blood ; they are distinguished by fortitude, avBpda, and intelligence. Hence the upper and lower parts, the right and left sides, the male and female, manifest their differences." § 371. In those days philosophers were fond of discussing relative heat and cold. He notices their discussions respect- ing the temperature of animals, some asserting the aquatic animals to be warmest, because they have to compensate, eiraviaovv, by their own heat, the cold of r the medium in 6 aicavBa must obviously be here rendered by cartilage, though elsewhere it means fishbone and porcupine quills. Of course his ideas on the nature of bone wanted the precision now attained. 7 Whatever the modem reader may think of this hypothesis, he should know that it was applauded by Habvbt : Exercitations on Oeneration, 1653, p. 282, Exer. LH. CHAP. XVI.] « ON THE PARTS OP ANIMALS." 299 which they live; an opinion very near the truth, though founded on insufficient data. Aristotle remarks that these disputes are due to the fact that warmth is a phrase used to express very different meanings ; and it is necessary to settle first in what sense a thing can properly he. called hot or cold. I quote his argument to show the inevitable weakness which arose from the absence of an objective standard, such as a thermometer, whereby heat could be measured with an accuracy impossible to any measurement by sensation. § 372. He first asks whether heat is simple or multiple. "It is necessary to ascertain how the heat manifests itself, for in one sense that body will be called warmest which most warms another body touching it ; in another sense, that which creates the most sensation when touched, especially if accompanied with pairj. This, however, often seems erroneous, for sometimes individual disposition is the cause of the pain. Further, that body is hottest which is most capable of melting the fusible, and burning the combustible. Again, when there are two sizes of the same substance, the larger is the warmer. We also say that the body which cools slowly, and warms quickly, is hotter by nature than that which is slowly warmed Boiling water heats more than flame, but flame burns the combustible, and melts the fusible, which water cannot do. Moreover, boiling water is warmer than a small fire, but water cools more, and more quickly than fire ; for fire never becomes cold ; water always does. Again, water, in relation to feeling, is warmer, indeed, than oil, but it cools and becomes solid more speedily. Blood is warmer to the touch than water and oil, but becomes solid more rapidly. Further, stories and iron, and such like, are slower in warming than water, hut they burn more when warmed. Besides, some warm bodies have warmth of their own added to what they get from others ; but there is a great difference whether a body is warm in one way or the other, for the one may be accidental, as if we were to say a musician is warmer than 300 " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI, another man, because one in a fever happened to he a musi- cian. But of two bodies, one warm by nature, the other warm by accident, the former will cool more slowly, but the latter will often seem hotter to the feeling ; the former will burn better ; for example, flame burns more than boiling water, but boiling water is hotter to the touch, although its heat is acci- dental. Hence it is clear that we cannot easily decide which of two bodies is the warmer, one being warmer in this sense, the other in that." § 373. He has repeated these statements elsewhere. 8 They curiously illustrate the nature of ancient science. They show the hopelessness of attempting to measure physical forces by subjective standards. That this is the source of their weakness, and not deficient sagacity, may be seen in the following passage from Bacon, who was equally without an instrument to measure heat: "Fire burneth wood, making it first luminous, then black and brittle, and lastly, broken and incinerate ; scalding water doth none of these. The cause is — for that by fire the spirit of the body is first refined, and then emitted : whereof the refining or attenuation causeth light ; and the emission, first, the fragility, and after, the dis- solution into ashes. Neither doth any other body enter; but in water, the spirit of the body is not refined so much ; and besides, water entereth, which doth increase the spirit, and in a degree extinguish it ; therefore, we see that hot water will quench fire." 9 § 374. Had the ancients possessed an instrument capable of measuring temperature, they would have learned, as easily as we learn, the immense difference between that of boiling water and flame, and the various degrees of heat which various flames contain. Before science had explained the phenomenon, the fact that a finger can be passed through 8 Problemata XXIII. 9 Bacon : Sylvia Sylvarum, VII. Works by Spedding and Ellis, 1857, , II., 552. CHAP, xvij " ON THE PARTS OP ANIMALS." 301 flame and scarcely feel the heat, whereas through boiling water it cannot pass without pain, naturally suggested that boiling water must be hotter than flame. The paradox disappears when we learn that before the skin of the finger can be attacked by the flame, its moisture must first be evaporated ; this moisture, which serves as a temporary shield, while the finger passes rapidly through the flame, cannot^ of course, protect the skin in water. § 375. The invention of the thermometer, or objective standard of heat, rendered a science of Thermotics possible ; but great as is its superiority over any subjective standard, the superiority of quantitative over qualitative knowledge . being thereby attained, it is itself too gross for the needs of modern science; and the more delicate susceptibility of the thermo-electric pile has revealed facts of the highest import- " ance which would have been as far beyond the reach of the thermometer as the facts revealed by the thermometer were beyond the reach of any appreciation by sensation. § 376. Chap. III. — Aristotle having explained his views on heat, applies them to Digestion, which he held to be, as the Greek word implies, a kind of cooking. Heat, and heat alone, is the agent by which food is made fluid and metamorphosed into assimilable material. 10 Plants take up, by their roots, the food prepared for them by the earth ; the earth is their stomach, and its warmth cooks their food. 11 Blood is perfected food. The conclusion drawn from this is not, however, easy to follow. He says, that because it is perfect food, blood gives no sen- sation when touched ; in this resembling every other secretion and excretion. Nor is blood the same as flesh ; for flesh when touched gives sensation. Nor is blood directly connected with flesh ; nor does it form an integral part of it ; but is contained in the heart and veins, as in a vessel. 10 leal TOVTtav fi mipig yiverca xal i) /j£ra/3oX>) Sid rrjs rov Oip/xov Swd/iiuig. " ry yap yy sal ry iv airy 9epii6rrin xpv Tai wffTfp soikia. 302 " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. § 377. Chap. IV. is also devoted to the blood, repeating what is said in the History of Animals respecting its fibrine coagulation and the dependence of intelligence on its thinness and purity. He adds that those animals which have watery blood are the most timorous, " for fear makes cold." This is rather confused reasoning. A man under terror feels cold ; the action of the heart being checked, the blood quits the surface. But how does terror affect the blood? By con- gealing its water, says Aristotle. Granting the accuracy of this assertion, it will only explain how terror might make an animal cold ; it will not explain why watery blood should predispose the animal to terror. Out of such hypothetical assumptions Logic might deduce the cause of the coldness which follows terror ; but Logic will at any rate protest against putting the effect for the cause, as Aristotle does in this case. § 378. Besides becoming cold, animals in terror are motionless, discharge excretions, and some of them change colour. It is noticeable that this is said only of the bloodless animals, and from a subsequent passage of this work (IV., 5,) it is evident that he refers to the discharge of ink and the change of colour in the cephalopoda. We are not, however, to suppose that by this he had overlooked the obvious facts exhibited by animals with blood ; but that he called attention to the less familiar facts exhibited by the cuttlefish and its fellows. 12 § 379. In contrast to the watery-blooded animals he places 12 In attributing the change of colour in the cuttlefish to a mental emotion, Aristotle is more excusable than many modern naturalists who have fallen into the same error; e.g., D'Okbignt : Mollusques vivants et fossiles, 1855, p. 113. In Seaside Studies, 2nd ed., I860, p. 100, I showed that the phenomenon was not directly dependent on the mental condition of the animal, but was mani- fested by a strip of skin from the body of a dead animal ; which also dis- proves the suggestion of Delle Chiaje, that it may be connected with respira- tion. Descrizione e notomia degli animali invertebrati delta Sicilia Citeriore, Naples, 1841, I., 15. CHAP. XVI.] " ON THE PARTS OF AKIMALS." 303 those whose blood contains more fibrine, and is consequently more earthy. These are of a more earthy character, more passionate, more easily angered. 13 " For anger makes warm, and that which is solid when warmed becomes hotter than that which is fluid; and as fibrine is solid and earthy, so anger occasions fomentations in the blood. Hence bulls and boars are so wrathful and easily driven wild with rage, their blood being exceedingly rich in fibrine." If this is somewhat wildly hypothetical, it is far less so than Van Helmont's explanation of the poisonous quality of bull-beef. 14 § 380. Chap. V. is on Fat and Suet. Both are made of the blood, which has not been devoted to the formation of flesh. " This is evident from their shining ; for the shining of a fluid is the product of fire and air. 15 Hence no bloodless animal has fat nor suet." We must not be surprised at his not knowing that the bloodless animals produced fat; the means of detecting it were then too imperfect. § 381. Fat in certain proportion, he says, is useful, but in excess injurious. Why? "If the whole body were of fat or suet, it would perish, because an animal is that which has sensation. Now flesh and its analogue are sensitive ; 13 In the words of the Spanish compiler, Diego de Funes t Mendoca : " Los animales que tienen la sangre fibrosa y llena de cosas gruessas, estos tienen naturaleza mas terrena, son mas animosos, y ayrados, 7 ansi mismo furibundos." — Historia General de Aves y Animales de Aristoteles traduzida de Latin en Romance. Valentia, 1551, p. 280. It is the title of this work which misled Btjhle into the supposition that Mendoca was one of Aristotle's trans- lators. The book is a compilation of absurdities from all ancient sources ready to hand ; and is interesting as » specimen of Natural History in the 16th century. 14 " Do you desire to be informed why the blood of a Bull is poisonous, but that of an Oxe, though brother to the Bull, is safe and harmlesse? The reason thus : the Bull at the time of slaughter is full of secret reluctancy and vin- dictive murmurs, and firmly impresseth upon his own blood a character and potent signature of revenge. A Bull dyes with a higher flame of revenge above him than any other animal."— Ternary of Paradoxes, translated by Charleton, 1650, p. 67. 15 Srjkol Si to \11rapbv airHv tiSv yap iypvv rb \tirapbv koivov depog mi mpoQ iaTiv. 804 " ON THE PAKTS OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. but, as I said before, blood is not ; consequently fat and suet are /not sensitive." He further notices why excess of fat causes sterility in females : the blood which would have formed progeny being used up for fat. § 382. Chap. VI. is on Marrow, also a product of Blood, and not as some think (alluding to Plato), a product of the spermatic fluid. In some animals marrow is fatty, in others suety. The important ganglionic mass forming the Spinal Chord, is considered by him, as it is by the vulgar of our day, to be the Spinal Marrow, bearing the same relation to the vertebrae that marrow bears to the hollow bones ; but he distinguishes it from every other marrow as being less fatty or suety. In this chapter there is nothing more to be noticed, unless it be one more example of rash generalization from imperfect observation, namely, the statement that some animals — among them the lion — have no marrow. § 383. Chap. VII. treats of the Brain, by many then held to be also marrow and the origin of the spinal marrow ; but this appears absurd to Aristotle, " for the Brain is the coldest part of the body, the Marrow is by nature warm, as is evident by its shining and its fat." This contrast of cold and warmtb, is the reason why brain and spinal marrow are in connection, Nature being careful to compensate for excess in one direction by excess in another; and the cold brain is therefore fitly placed in juxtaposition with the warm marrow. § 384. " That the spinal marrow is warm is evident in many ways." He has already mentioned its shining, which implies the presence of fire. " The coldness of the brain appears when we touch it ; it is also the most bloodless of moist parts." (§ 164.) § 385. Modern readers, accustomed from boyhood to hear the brain spoken of as the seat of sensation, will feel some surprise on meeting with a passage directly contravening that CHAP. XVI.] " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." 305 opinion, as the following: — "It is evident from simple inspec- tion that the brain is in no direct connection with the sensi- tive parts ; still more evident in the fact that when touched it yields no sensation." The first clause is a deduction from the theory of flesh being the medium of sensation. The second clause indicates an important fact — the insensibility of the cerebrum — which in our own day has caused surprise, and some absurd speculation. 16 The difficulty admits of easy explanation. When observation proves that the brain is insensible to direct stimulus — that it may be pinched, cut, torn, or galvanized without producing any evidence of sensa- sation in ,the animal operated on — the conclusion is that the brain is not a transmitter of stimuli, as a nerve is ; the brain is sensitive, and only when the stimulated nerve acts upon it is its sensibility excited. To imagine that Sensibility could be excited in the brain by the same means as Neurility is excited in the nerve (i.e. by simple external stimulus) is to overlook the important distinction between nerve-action and ganglionic action — or, as I have proposed to name them, Neurility and Sensibility. 17 In the days of Aristotle there was no suspicion of any such distinction as that of excitor and excited ; and finding the brain insensible, when touched, he was justified in denying it to be the seat of sensibility. § 386. But although the psychical office of the brain is thus denied by Aristotle, he gives it, as we have seen (§ 164) 16 Harles: Versuch einer Gesch. der Him und Nervenlehre im Alterthume, 1801, p. 80, apparently unaware of this fact, thinks that Aristotle invented it to suit his theory. Compare Gesalpincs : Peripateticarum Qucest, 1 571, lib. V., quasst. 3 and 6 ; and his antagonist Tattrellus : Alpes Casce, 1650, p. 926. The insensibility of the cerebrum is discussed by Halleb: Elementa Physio- logic, Lausanne, 1762, IV., 312 seq., where numerous observations and expe- riments are recorded. All the best modem works contain ample evidence on the point. 17 Reports of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, 1859, and Physiology of Common Life, 1860, II., 14-24. 20 806 " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. a physiological office — that of moderating the exoeasive heat of the blood. " Man has the largest brain in relation to his body, and larger than woman ; for he has the warmest thorax, which is most abundantly supplied with blood. Hence, also, man alone has an erect position, because heat in gaining strength works an increase from the centre, according to the direction of its path." 18 § 387. He also treats, in this chapter, of the sutures of the skull; and in doing so, illustrates the fanciful deduction and careless observation which characterize ancient science. " Their office, he says, is to permit the escape of vapours from the brain." I know not how long this explanation found credit, but it was still flourishing in the time of Galen. 19 " The number of sutures, he says, is greatest in man ; greater in man than in woman." The observation is in every way unfortunate. Among mammalia, the number is precisely the same ; in fish and amphibia it is much greater than in man ; and if the skulls of old women, from their more rapid ossification, do occasionally present fewer apparent sutures, a very little circumspection would suffice to discover that there is really no difference in the number possessed by each sex. § 388. Chap. VIII. treats of Flesh, the most important of the partes similares. It is the seat of sensibility; the mark of animality, " since we define an animal, that which has sensation." This is a much higher attribute than that 19 r) yap tov Beppov t/waii; lvia%vovaa iroiii rffv avZr/atv airb rov fifoov Kari. rrjv airrjg fopav. This obscure passage is thus rendered by Bussemaker: " Caloris enim natura invalescens incrementum de medio agit secundum sui itineris directionem." It may be thus paraphrased: " The direction of heat is upwards, and it will, therefore, determine growth upwards, thereby giving man his erect position." Though why animals do not more gradually approach this erect position is not stated, unless it be implied in the fact that they have too little warmth to be compared with man. 19 Galen: De usu Partium, IX.,I., 688. CHAP. XVI.] " ON THE PARTS OP ANIMALS." 307 assigned by Plato, who said flesh was made in order that it might be a preservative against the cold of winter, and the heat of summer ; besides being a shield against blows. § 388 a. " The primary sensibility is that of Touch, and its organs are the respective parts. Other sensibilities were not necessary; they might have been left uncreated; but Touch was necessary, for it is, if not the only corporeal sensa- tion, at least the most corporeal, o-wptrw&c." (§ 368.) § 389. All other parts, such as bones, sinews, skin, vessels, hair, and nails, are present only as servitors to sensation, e. g. bones being for the protection of the soft parts. § 390. Chap. X. developes this idea of the subordina- tion of parts to the Flesh ; or as moderns would say, the subordination of parts to the animal organism. Aristotle distinguishes bone from fish-bone and cartilage. He holds cartilage to be a mixture of the earthy substance of bone with soft marrow ; whereas in bones the two are separate, the marrow lying inside. He could not know that cartilage contains fat. But he might have avoided the error of asserting that bone and cartilage are alike in not being regenerated when broken or cut. Bone happens to be one of the most easily regenerated of tissues ; and hence the observed rapidity with which even large broken bones are mended, or removed pieces replaced. Cartilage, on the contrary, never regenerates, but is replaced by another structure. "When fractured, as sometimes happens with the rib cartilages, there is no reunion by cartilaginous matter, but the broken surfaces become connected by fibrous tissue." M 20 Shakpbt: in Quain's Anatomy, 1856, 1., c. vii. The physiological reason of this difference I take to he this : bones grow, and consequently are regene- rated from the periosteum, or enveloping membrane ; and hence by transplant- ing a portion of this membrane to another body, or another part, new bone will grow from it (see note 21 to Chap. X.) But cartilages do not grow from a perichondrium. 20—2 308 "ON THE PAKTS OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. § 391. Chap. X. — " All animals have two indispensable parts : those which take in food, and those which get rid of the waste. Plants have no excretory organs, for they take their food ready digested from the earth, and give in return seed and fruit. . . . Plants, inasmuch as they are fixed to the ground, do not need much variety in their organs. But those creatures which have sensation as well as life possess a more varied structure, and some more varied than others, when Nature thinks not only of life but of good life. Such is the case with man. For he is the only living creature known to us who has a portion of the divine in him ; or, at any rate, he has more of it than any other creature. On this account, and because his external forms are best known, we must speak of him first : for his parts are disposed according to Nature ; since his upper part is directed upwards to the supreme of all." 21 § 391 a. It is curious to find men in all ages laying so much stress on a very unimportant peculiarity, and making man's supremacy to consist in a power of gazing upwards, which is shared by every goose that waddles across his path. L'homme eleve un front noble et regarde les cienx, says Louis Racine, in imitation of Ovid's well-known lines : Pronaque cum spectent animalia csetera terrain, Os homini sublime dedit, coelumque tuerl Jussit. Galen justly ridicules this notion ; it is, he says, refuted by the fact that there are fish which always have their eyes directed towards the heavens, and that man can only direct his eyes upwards by bending back his head. 22 As to the erect position, no one till Isidobe Geoffboy St. Hilaire thought of the familiar fact that many birds, such as the penguins, 21 thdvq yap ml tcl fyvaei fiopta Kara tyvtnv ?x« ToirvTii) -rrvivfiari, — whatever that may be. It is an error, he says, to suppose the lungs cause the beating of the heart; "for man, alone, presents this pheno- menon of heart-beating, because he, alone, is moved by hope and expectation of what is coming." One would fancy, from this passage, that Aristotle had never held a bird in his hand. "Moreover," he adds, "it is in man the farthest removed from, and lies higher than the lungs, so that they can in no way cause the beating." § 399 d. Chap. VII. is on the single and double organs. Bichat tried to establish a generalization which has been much admired, namely, that all the organs of Animal life are double and symmetrical, while all the organs of Vegetal CHAP. XVI.] "ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." 315 life are single and asymmetrical. 31 Unhappily the facts do not fit. In the commencement almost every organ is double and symmetrical ; and only in the later stages of development do the differences appear. 32 Even in the matured organism we find many striking exceptions to Bichat's generalization. Thus the parotid, sublingual, and mammary glands, the lungs, the kidneys, ovaries and testes, are all vegetal organs, and all generally double. 33 Aud if the heart and uterus are classed as single organs, then must the brain and spinal cord be classed thus. While in birds the liver is double and symmetrical. § 399 e. Bichat's generalization is in the spirit of Aris- totle, yet Aristotle avoided it. He merely noticed that some of the viscera are single, others double. Among the single organs he names the heart and the lungs, though it is far from clear how he came to consider the lungs single, since the reason of any organ being double is because the body has two halves, each requiring its own organ, and hence the brain has 31 Bichat: Becherches sur la Vie et la Mori. 32 " Le fait primitif de tons les organismes est lenr dualite. Tous sans exception (?) sont doubles a leur apparition, tous sont pairs : on trouve a droite du jeune embryon la repetition exactement de ce qui est a gauche ; les organismes impairs qui vient plus tard sur la ligne mediane forme des arcs boutants ou des clefs de la voute, ne deviennent tels que par la fusion de la dualite primitive qui les constituait des leur debut." — Seeres: Br&cis d'Anat. transcendante, 1842, p. 238. This statement is somewhat too absolute. The intestine is at no period double, and the heart is single from the first. See Note 27. 33 Not always, nor in all animals. The lung is single in many serpents, and the ovary is single in almost all birds. Both ovaries are present, it is true, in the embryo bird, but very soon after its exit from the egg the right ovary finally disappears. The date varies. Muller says that on the ninth day of hatch- ing the diminution begins in all but birds of prey; in these latter the diminution is not visible until about the end of the hatching.— Bildungsgeschichte der Genitatien, 1830, p. 30. Yet I once found the right ovary not quite disappeared in a chick just ready to escape from the shell. In the viviparous Blenny Kaxhke says there is but one ovary. The same is true of the Perch; and I believe of some other fishes. On the imperfect symmetry in animal organs, see Meckel: iiber die aeitliche Asymmetrie im thierischen Korper in his Anat. Phy- siologische Beobachtungen, Halle, 1822. Compare also his Traiti d'Anat. Compare, Paris, 1828, 1., 20. 316 " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. a tendency ()3oiX£rai) to become double ; and the heart has its two chambers. The Liver and Spleen puzzle him, but he is disposed to regard them as balancing each other. § 399/. Chaps. VIII. and IX. treat of the gall-bladder and kidneys. As in the other chapters, there is abundance of detail, true, false, and fanciful ; but nothing needful to be extracted here. § 399 g. Chap. X. is on the diaphragm. It divides the heart and lungs from the stomach in order that the heat of the sensitive soul may be protected, and not easily endangered by the exhalations from the food, and by adventitious warmth. Nature has thus separated the Upper from the Under, for the Upper is the end and the best ; the Under is created for it. That the diaphragm acts as a protection against the warmth is evident, for when it attracts the warm secretions, thought and feeling are immediately confused ; and hence it is called phrenes, as if it participated in thinking. But it has really no part in thinking, yet, being near the organs which are active in thinking, it certainly operates a change in consciousness. § 399 h. Although Aristotle here departs from the idea of the phren as the seat of the mind, 34 he makes the diaphragm play its part in consciousness : " and when warmed it quickly makes itself felt, as we see in laughter, for those who are tickled laugh quickly because the movement quickly reaches this place." Man is the only animal that is ticklish, because of the fineness of his skin, and because he is the only animal that laughs, " and tickling is laughter from a motion of this kind of the parts about the armpit " 35 — a physiological expla- nation rather puzzling to understand. The remainder of this Book is occupied with notices of 34 The various opinions formerly held respecting the diaphragm are cited by Hallee: Opuscula Anatomica, 1751, p. 19. 35 & Sk ytip yaKuriiie yeXwj hrl Sid xivrjaeiits roiainjj rov /toplov tov wepi OHAP. XVI.] " ON THE PAliTS OP ANIMALS." 317 different forms of viscera, and a minute account of the intestines. § 399 i. Book IV., Chap. I., opens with remarks on the viscera of the Apoda. When he says that none of these, except the tortoise, possess a bladder, he is wrong anatomi- cally ; but he is wrong Aristotelically when he assigns the reason, namely that these animals drinking little because they are without blood, their moisure is converted into scales, as that of birds is into feathers. § 399 k. He separates the vipers from other serpents on the ground of their being viviparous, " or rather," he says, " they are at first ovo-viviparous, iporoKrioavTa." Had he known that all the viviparous snakes are poisonous, and the oviparous harmless, it is probable that he would have suggested some strange metaphysical cause for it. § 400. Chap. II. treats of bile and the gall-bladder. As we see in our word " choleric," the bile was thought formerly to be intimately connected with anger and other emotions. Brutus tells Cassius that he must "digest the choler of his spleen," as if that were the final clearance of bad tempers. Aristotle will not admit that the bile has anything whatever to . do with feeling, for he remarks some animals have no gall- bladder — such are the horse, the ass, the mule, the deer, the camel, and the seal. Because the word used by him, joXrj means both bile and gall-bladder, it is difficult to correctly seize his meaning ; however, except the seal, all the animals named by him are without a gall-bladder, though not, of course, without bile. He adds this strange assertion: — "In the same species some appear to have the gall-bladder, and others not to have it, as the mice. To this class also belongs man. Some men have manifestly a gall-bladder attached to the liver, others not." Does not this look very like the sort of information he might have derived from the embalmers ? It is difficult to suppose that any anatomist could have been so careless. 318 " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. § 401. After disputing the opinion expressed by Anaxa- goras, that bile is the cause of acute diseases, he adds that the bile is an excretion, and serves no end. " It is true that nature sometimes uses excretions to some good end, but we must not on that account seek a final cause in all things, but, inasmuch as certain things have certain properties, there will necessarily follow from these many effects." s6 This import- ant passage should be a set-off against the many formal declarations of teleology to be met with in his writings. It shows that he had a glimmering of the philosophic conception, and that, like the modern advocates of teleology, he was only disposed to employ final causes where proximate causes were hidden from him. §402. Chaps. III., IV., and V.— After describing the omentum and mesentery he passes on to the viscera of molluscs and insects, or to such analogues as may be found in them, for these animals not having blood cannot hate the viscera which are formed from blood. They have no vessels, no bladder, no breathing organs. But it is necessary that they should' have the analogue of a heart, "for the sensitive part of the soul, and the cause of life, has in all animals a definite seat." This seat must be the centre. Among the noticeable details of this chapter is the classi- fication of sea-anemones and ascidians as intermediate between plants and animals. §403. Chaps. VI. and VII.— He then treats of the external forms of molluscs and insects; and says that the former are inactive, which is the reason why they have not many limbs. It is doubtful whether he really meant to put the effect for the cause in this way, since the continuation of the passage, though confused, seems to indicate the contrary. " The more limbs an animal has, the more active it must be, 36 oil iikv Sul tovto SeX ZflTiiv ir&vra ivtica Hvo£ clXKa nvStv o"vtidv toiovtw 8rfj)o 1J ivdyicris av/iPaivei Sia ravra 7roWd. CHAP. XVI.] « ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." 319 because of their functions ; for more organs are required by those which have more functions." § 404. In the many discussions raised respecting the uni- formity of composition in the animal organization, much stress has been laid on the fact that in the invertebrata the relative position of the nervous system is the reverse of that in the vertebrata. The dorsal surface of the one corresponds with the ventral surface of the other. Cuvier and his followers point to this as a proof that the plan is not uniform. Geoffroy St. Hilaire and his followers declare that it only proves the mollusc to be a vertebrate animal reversed. Aris- totle sees in it only an adaptation to modes of life ; all testa- ceous animals have the head downwards, like plants. " The reason is because they take the food from below, as plants do with their roots. They have, therefore, the peculiarity that with them the Upper is Under." § 405. Chap. X. — After describing the organs of the Crustacea (in Chap. VIII.), and of the Cephalopoda (in Chap. IX.), he returns to the viviparous sanguineous animals. Man is discriminated from all other mammals by the possession of hands and arms. Not that monkeys are here overlooked ; they are always spoken of by Aristotle and Galen. as quadrupeds, or, as they have been termed since Tyson and Buffon, quadrumana. 37 37 " L'homme est le seul qui soit bimane et bipede. . . le Lamantin n'est que bimane . . le singe est quadrumane." — Buffon : Nomenclature des Singes, cited by Isidore St. Hilaike. But as Huxley : Man's Place in Nature, 1863, p. 90, points out, the word quadrumanous was first employed by Tyson in 1699 : moreover, as Huxley elsewhere remarks, " Before we accept the diagnosis that man has two hands and two feet, while apes have four hands, we must ask to have the difference between hands and feet clearly defined; and this is by no means so easy as it appears." I am not aware that any one has defined it. If the name follow the function, then it is certain that apes grasp even more than they walk, and so far seem to be fourhanded ; but the grasping function of the human foot has only fallen into disuse, and when uncramped by the use of shoes, as in savages and sailors, the toes are " very moveable, very flexible, and capable of prehension by opposition not only of 820 " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. § 406. " Man alone of all living beings is erect, because of bis godlike nature and his godlike essence. The function of a godlike nature is knowing and thinking ; but this would be difficult if the upper part of the body were large, for weight makes thought and common sensibility slow." This explanation, which is teleological, may be compared with the physical explanation formerly given (§ 386). § 407. "Animals are four-footed because their souls are not powerful enough to carry the weight of their bodies in an erect position. Therefore all animals in relation to man are dwarfs, for dwarfs are those which have the upper parts large and the organs of progression small." By the upper parts he means the trunk of the body, or thorax, as he calls it. "In man there is a proper proportion between the trunk and the limbs ; but when newly-born, the trunk is large and the limbs small. Hence infants crawl and cannot walk ; at first they cannot even crawl, nor move alone, for all infants are dwarfs. On the contrary, among quadrupeds the under part is at first the larger ; but as they develope, the upper part becomes the larger. Hence colts are little — if at all — shorter than horses, and when they are young they can touch their heads with their hind feet, which they cannot do as adults." Birds and fishes are likewise dwarfs. " Hence all animals are less intelligent, afpovsartpa, than man. And among men, children and dwarfs are less intelligent than the adult and the well-grown. The reason is, as before the toes to the sole, hut of the great toe to the second," as witness the boatmen of China, the weavers of Senegal, and the Brazilian horsemen, who put their feet to the same purposes as those for which we employ our hands; not to mention Miss Biffin and the painter Ducornet. If, on the contrary, the name follows the anatomical structure, then it is clear that " the arrangement of the bones and muscles of the terminal segment of the hind limb in every ape whatsoever is, in all essential respects; similar to that which obtains in the foot of man and other mammals, and is totally different from the hand of man and terminal segment of the forelimb of other mammals. In fact, there is no four- handed mammal in existence." — Natural History Review, January, 1862, p. 6. On the counter side compare Vicq d'Azyk: (Euvres, 1805, IV., p. 149-50. CHAP. XVI.] " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." 321 stated, because the physical principle is very difficult to move, and is corporeal. 38 § 408. Another deduction from man's erect position is, that he cannot use his anterior limbs as legs and feet, but only as arms and hands. Galen thinks this is because man has no need of the velocity to be attained by four legs ; but was meant by nature to tame horses, aided by his intelligence and his hands. 39 Elsewhere, 40 Galen highly applauds Aristotle for having, in this very place, refuted the opinion of Anaxagokas, who preceded Helvetius, in deriving the intellectual superiority of man from the possession of hands. Aristotle thinks it far more logical to say that man possesses hands because he is the most intelligent of animals. " The hand is an instrument. Nature, like a rational being, always bestows instruments on those who can use them. For it is better to give a flute to a flute-player, than to make a flute- player of one who possesses a flute ; since the inferior ought to be given to the greater and nobler, and not the nobler and greater to the inferior. If, therefore, it is better so, and as Nature always acts for the best, when possible, evidently man has hands because he is the most intelligent ; and is not the most intelligent because he has hands." The reader will not fail to appreciate how entirely the solution of a deeply interesting problem is frustrated by this seeming explanation. § 409. A little further on we meet with this amusing explanation of the statement (which is erroneous), that the lioness has only two teats. " The reason is, not because the lioness brings forth few young, for she often brings forth more than two, but because she has little milk ; and she has little milk, because her food is converted into her own substance ; and she does not eat much because she is carnivorous." 41 38 TroWifi &) dvadvriToe fori, ko\ owpaTwdrig. 39 Galen: De usu Partium, III., 1. 40 Ibid., I., 3. 41 This is improved on by Diego Funes t Mendoca, who says, " No tiene la Leone mas que dos tetas, con que cria sus hijos, y tan poca leche en ellos, que siempre los trae muertos de hambre."— Historia General de Aves y Animates, 21 322 " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. § 410. Nor is the reason alleged for the position of the elephant's teats between the forelegs less amusing. " The reason why she has but two, is because she only brings forth a single young one ; and she has them between the forelegs because she has cloven feet, and no animal with cloven feet has the teats under the groin ; finally, she has them between the forelegs because it is there that most milk is found." 48 He further observes that man has nipples, but that some male animals have them, and others are without them. Not content with this carelessness as to facts, he adds that those males which have nipples resemble their mothers. § 411. The anatomist will read with surprise that man is the only animal which has flesh on its legs ; but the cause will, perhaps, surprise him more. " There is but one cause, and that is the erect position. In order that the Upper part should be light and easily carried, Nature has taken away the substantial from the Upper, and placed it in the Lower : hence she has made the buttocks, thighs, and calves fleshy. At the same time she made the buttocks for repose (sitting) ; since quadrupeds can stand without fatigue, man needs a seat." Man has no tail, like other quadrupeds, because the forma- tion of his buttocks uses up all the available material. Nor does the existence of tailless apes disturb this argument. The ape has neither tail nor buttocks, because he is intermediate between man and quadruped : he has no tail, because he is biped ; no buttocks, because he is quadruped. § 412. The treatise we are now considering is devoted to an exposition of causes, and represents the physiology of Aristotle. On this account I have selected typical examples, 1521, p. 256 j and gravely he copies from Pliny the following: " Conoce si la leone le hahecho adulterio con solo el olor; annque ella se suele huyr, 6 lavarse en algun rio, si le ha cometido." The idea of a lioness, ashamed of her adultery, bathing herself in the stream to escape detection, is very droll. w Compare Gausn: De urn Partium, VII,, 21. CHAP. XVI.] " ON THE PARTS OF ANIMALS." 323 both of insight and error, which might convey a just idea of his method and its results. Perhaps some readers may have felt that this has been done too minutely ; but although fewer examples would have displayed the method, I believe that a less exhaustive analysis would have failed to rectify the false and exaggerated estimate of Aristotle's scientific eminence. Throughout these page3 I have had to contend against the very natural prejudice in favour of a mighty fame. Half a dozen examples, no matter how absurd, would not have shaken the prejudice, because the reader would have supposed that, in spite of these, the works contained enough to justify their reputation. In conclusion, we may, observe that, far as this treatise " On the Parts of Animals " may be from the modern standard, it is of great interest in the History of Science, not only for the material it furnishes, but also as one of the earliest attempts to found Biology on Comparative Anatomy. Although for centuries animals were studied rather as curiosities than as furnishing scientific data, and, until quite recently, Zootomy formed no recognized branch of biological research, Aristotle, we see, had early comprehended its true position, and sought for the laws of life in all organic beings. He would recognize the moderns as his inheritors, and would hear with satisfac- tion that " to Zootomy we owe almost all the important discoveries in Anatomy and Physiology." 43 Those grave physicians who sneered at John Hunter's " wasting his time over flies and frogs," might have known that it was in the study of animal organization that Harvey discovered the cir- culation; and that Aselli, Pecquet, Eudbeck, and Bar- tholinus enlarged this discovery by detecting the lymphatics, and their transport of the chyle into the veins; and that 43 Tiedemann: Physiologie de Vhomme, Paris, 1831, 1., 41. Compare also Stlvhts (Leboe): Opera Omnia, 1679, p. 875. Halleb: Elementa Physw kgiee, Lausanne, 1757, 1., 3. Delle Chiaje: Istituzioni di Anatomia « Fuw- loqia comparata, 1832, 1., p. xiu. 21— 2 324 " ON THE PAETS OF ANIMALS." [CHAP. XVI. Malpighi and Leeuwenhoek completed the great discovery by that of the capillaries. It was thus that Hoffmann, Wirsung, Stenon, and Wharton, discovered the excretory ducts of the pancreas and salivary glands. It was thus De Graaf dis- covered the function of the ovaries. It was thus Harvey, Mal- pighi, and Wolff, laid the foundations of Embryology. It was thus that almost all our knowledge of the nervous system was attained. It was thus that almost all we know of the chemical changes going on during respiration and digestion was gained. To Aristotle such information would have seemed like the realization of his dreams ; and that he should thus early have perceived the importance of comparative anatomy, is one more of the many evidences of his prodigious scientific insight. But, and the remark is important in its bearing on Method, although Aristotle fully saw how wide and fertile was the field of investigation, and how completely it was identified with the study of human life, he failed to discover a single physiological process or a single anatomical fact, not patent to the vulgar eye. ( 325 ) CHAPTEK XVII. ON GENERATION AND DEVELOPMENT. §413. The treatise "On the Generation of Animals," 1 ia the last we shall have to analyze. It is an extraordinary production. No ancient, and few modern works, equal it in comprehensiveness of detail and profound speculative insight. We there find some of the obscurest problems of Biology treated with a mastery which, when we consider the condition of science at that day, is truly astounding. That there are many errors, many deficiences, and not a little care- lessness in the admission of facts, may be readily imagined ; nevertheless, at times the work is frequently on a level with, and occasionally even rises above, the speculations of many ad- vanced embryologists. At least so it appears to me ; and the reader knows how little I am disposed to discover in ancient texts the fuller meanings of modern science, and how anxiously I strive to represent what Aristotle actually thought. It is difficult to disengage ancient texts from the suggestions of modern thought ; but I should not be candid were I to con- ceal the impression which the study of this work left on my mind, that the labours of the last two centuries from Harvey to Kolliker have furnished the anatomical data to confirm many of the views of this prescient genius. Indeed, I know no 1 A valuable edition, with a German version and notes, has recently been published by Aueeet and Wimmek, Leipzig, I860. I can find no other version except the imperfect one of Gaza. 326 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. better eulogy to pass on Aristotle than to compare his work with the " Exercitations concerning Generation " of our immortal Hakvey. The founder of modern physiology was a man of keen insight, of patient research, of eminently scientific mind. His work is superior to that of Aristotle in some few anatomical details; but it is so inferior to it in philosophy, that at the present day it is much more anti- quated, much less accordant-with our views. But in expressing my admiration of Aristotle's treatise, I am naturally solicitous not to exaggerate, nor to convey a wrong impression of the kind of excellence discoverable in it. In this chapter, therefore, as in its predecessors, the errors and deficiences will be carefully indicated. That the errors are not more numerous is marvellous, when we reflect on the enormous difficulty of embryological research, and the defi- ciency, in Aristotle's day, of those means of observation which have assisted moderns. § 414. As an introduction it may be useful to give a brief summary of the various forms of Generation and Develop- ment recognized by modern embryologists. The more so, because we have no philosophical treatise which rigorously sets them forth; and some confusion is noticeable in the common subdivisions of the subject, especially as regards three very distinct groups of phenomena relating to the origination, the development, and the gestation of the embryo. These groups not being well defined, the student is frequently perplexed, because questions of origin are confounded with questions of history. It is clear, for example, that the con- ditions which determine the origin of a new being — the union of a germcell with a spermcell — are of another order from the conditions which determine the subsequent development of that being ; and these, again, are different from the con- ditions of gestation and incubation, whether the development goes on within the parent organism, or outside it. Let us severally examine these three groups. CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 327 I. — Origination. § 415. This is genesis. If we exclude the form of Spon- taneous Generation, as not properly coming within the circle of established truths, 2 all the phenomena of genesis range under two rubrics, which may be entitled Monogenesis, when the origin is from one cell, or one parent ; and Digenesis, 3 when the origin is from two cells, or two parents. § 416. Monogenesis may occur under three forms : — 1. by spontaneous fission; 2. by external gemmation— budding ; 8. by internal gemmation — parthenogenesis. 1st. Spontaneous fission — also, but inaccurately, by a con- fusion of the ideas of origin and birth, called fissiparity — is a well-known phenomenon in the vegetal and animal kingdoms. A single cell divides into two cells ; these two again divide into four, and so on indefinitely. The cells may either cohere and form a filament, or they may separate into many inde- pendent individuals. Not only will the single cell spontane- ously divide, but, among the lower animals, a similar division of the whole organism is observed. Thus a Vorticella becomes, by longitudinal division, two distinct animals on one stem. 2nd. External gemmation — also, but inaccurately, called gemmiparity — is well known as the production of buds in plants, and is also observed in certain animals, such, for example, as the Polype. In the origination of the young Hydra from the substance of the parent body without any sexual agency whatever,* there is nothing distinguishable from ordinary processes of growth, except that, instead of forming an increase of the parental substance, it forms a new Hydra, which finally separates from the parent. The young Hydra is a bud like a plant-bud. 2 On this point see Blackwood's Magazine, February, 1861. 3 Bukdach: Traitt! de Physiologic, Paris, 1837, 1., 47, 83. Van Beneden: Minwire sur les Vers Intestinaux, Paris, 1858, p. 296. 4 Repeated examination has assured me of the accuracy of what Huxley has stated on this point in his important memoir On the Agamic Reproduction and Morphology of the Aphis, in the Zinncean Transactions, XXII., 217. 828 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. 3rd. Internal Gemmation, or Parthenogenesis, has been already explained (§ 189-190), and need not, therefore, be further dwelt on here. § 417. Digenesis may occur under two forms : — 1. Con- jugation; and 2. Fertilization. 1st. Conjugation is a phenomenon well known to botanists ; two cells, apparently similar in all respects, having, perhaps, become two by spontaneous fission, unite their contents, and originate a new cell. 2nd. Fertilization is the union of two dissimilar cells, called spermcell and germcell, or spermatozoon and ovum. This is the normal mode of genesis in the majority of plants and animals ; the exclusive mode in all the animals of a com- plex organization (see § 191-2.) It is a matter of indifference where these dissimilar cells are produced, whether in the same organ, or in organs morphologically different; whether they are produced in one and the same plant or animal, or in plants and animals of different sexes ; the cardinal fact is simply the union of the two dissimilar cells, the fertilization of the germ- cell by the spermcell. This is fundamental ; everything else is accessory. II. — Development. § 418. Here begins the history of the new being. The genesis having been effected, histogenesis (or formation of tissues) commences. In the case of the vegetal seed, a long period may elapse before this development begins. The seed may lie, as in Egyptian tombs for thousands of years, ferti- lized, yet undeveloped, because the necessary conditions of histogenesis are absent. In animals also there is often a lapse of time. In the deer for example, the impregnated ovum lies four months and a half in the uterus before development com- 5 1 am indebted for this curious fact to Proiessor Bischoff, the embryo- logist. CHAP. XTII.J AND DEVELOPMENT. 329 The various laws of histogenesis may be ranged under these two heads : — 1st. Differentiation, in which the primitive homogeneous germinal membrane becomes more and more heterogeneous, through successive differentiations, both of composition and form, giving rise to tissues, the tissues forming organs, and the organs grouping themselves into systems. 2nd. Assimilation and Disintegration, a continuous pro- cess, coincident with differentiation, by which the several elementary structures are nourished. III. — Incubation. § 419. Our third group relates entirely to the habitat of the impregnated ovum. It has obviously nothing to do with the genesis of the new being, and is only an accessory condition of its early history. There are two forms of Incubation : — 1st. Oviparity. The female having produced an egg, this is developed either entirely outside her organism,— or mainly outside, and partly inside, — or almost entirely inside. It is developed entirely outside in the majority of fishes and batrachians. 6 It is developed mainly outside, but partly inside, in some infusoria, polypes, some fishes, and all birds. It is developed almost entirely inside in what are called the ovo-viviparous and viviparous animals, and thus insensibly passes into — 2nd. Viviparity, in which the chief metamorphoses have 6 The Ephemeron (dayfly) must be franked with these, according to Swammekdamm. He describes the deposit of the eggs in the water, and their subsequent fertilization by the male. — Die Bibel der Natur, 1725, p. 100. So accurate an observer is not lightly to be contradicted, and the fact, as he states it, may be true for one species. Reaumbr, however, feels great hesitation, and says that his own observations do not confirm Swammerdamm: — Memoires four servir a I'histoire des Insectes, Paris, 1762, VI., 500. Burmeister: Manual of Entomology, London, 1836, takes no notice of it. Be the fact as it may, even if congress does occur, the impregnated egg can only remain a few minutes before it is deposited. 880 ON GENEEATION [CHAP. XVII. taken place while the embryo is within the parent's body, so that, at the time of birth, it is said to be capable of indepen- dent existence. "We have seen already (§ 201 a., 202-3-4) that, strictly speaking, no distinction exists between oviparity and vivi- parity as regards organic processes, though the terms are convenient for ordinary purposes ; and to what is there said, may be added the illustrative parallel between the development of the viviparous Blenny and the oviparous Fowl, which, as Kathke has shown, 7 presents only this difference : that after the changes have advanced to a certain stage in the hen's egg, a shell is formed and the egg is extruded, to be hatched externally, whereas the Blenny's egg is hatched internally. § 420. If now we turn to Aristotle, and ask how much he knew of the forms of Eeproduction just sketched, we shall find that, except Spontaneous Fission, they were all more or less familiar to him. The evidence upon which he believed in Monogenesis was indeed very imperfect ; still we find him positively recognizing it; and we shall see in the course of our analysis how lucky were many of his anticipations on other points. § 421. Book I., Chap. I. — The work opens with the declaration that it is a sequel to the treatise on the " Parts of Animals," and will concern itself with the parts devoted to Generation, also, with the causes of Generation. " In all animals having distinct sexes, offspring issue from the union of the sexes. But this distinction of sex is not universal, though few exceptions occur among the sanguineous animals (by the exceptions, he means certain fishes). Of ex-sanguineous animals, some have distinct sexes, which reproduce their kind ; others reproduce, but not their kind : such are those which do not issue from parents, but from putrefaction and excrement." He reckons in this class insects 7 RATHKJfy: Abhandlungen zur Bildungs-und-Entwickelungsgeschichte des Menschen und der Thiere, Leipzig, 1833, II., p. 9. CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 331 and all those animals which, like the oyster and mussel, remain fixed to one spot. These have no more distinction of sex than the plants they resemble. Plants are partly developed from seeds, and partly from putrefaction, by spontaneous generation. § 422. Chap. II. — Of plants he promises to speak in a separate work (no longer extant), and, therefore, only speaks of animals here. And first he desires us to understand the masculine and feminine principles : the masculine principle being the origin of all motion and generation ; the feminine principle being the origin of the material generated. 8 The proof is furnished by observation as to the origin of the sperm. It is because these principles are secreted from the male, and in the female, that they are masculine and feminine, " for we name masculine that which engenders in another; and feminine, that which engenders in itself. On this account we regard the earth as a mother, and the heaven, or sun, as the genitor and father." After more of such not very luciferous metaphysics, he briefly touches on the sexual differences in male and female, and notices the great disturbance in the organism occasioned by any modification of the sexual organs, which he regards as a proof that the Masculine and Feminine are veritable prin- ciples — i.e. vital causes. § 423. Chap. III. briefly describes these organs. As may be expected, his anatomical knowledge was very imperfect. He entirely misses the correct analogy of the uterus, which he makes the analogue of the testes. Yet inasmuch as he never discriminates between the uterus and the ovaries, but always employs the same word to designate both, a defence might be set up for him, were he not on other points so vague and inaccurate. It is only in Mammalia that a true uterus is present, and modern research has discovered that the uterus » t& pkv dppiv dig TrJQ Kivi) Kivr\aw, df' Siv ohdiv aVepx* rai. 22 " Cette histoire est une fable prise au serieux par AriBtote." — Coste, cited by At/bert and Wimmee, who justly remark that analogous well-authenticated examples exist. <, £, $j\ «JMf«-\ ; CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 341 and those from which the dissimilar parts are formed, it is from them the sperm comes, and that the resemblance in face and hands must have been preceded by resemblance in flesh and nails. If we suppose the sperm to come from both similar and* dissimilar parts, what will be the mode of generation ? For the dissimilar are formed out of the similar, and if the sperm came from the former, it would be the same as if it came from the latter and their union. It is as with names. If anything is derived from the whole name, it must be derived from every syllable, and if from every syllable then from the letters and their union. If therefore flesh and bone are composed of fire, and the like, we must go back to the elements. For how is it possible that sperm should arise from union? and yet without it there could be no resemblance. But if some subsequent cause produces this union, it will be the cause of the resemblance, and not anything derived from the whole." § 440. This argument is an illustration of the helplessness of the mind when trying to force a pathway through the marsh of metaphysics. Whatever may be the fallacy of the reasons he refutes, they bear at least some direct relation to the facts, as then understood ; whereas his own argument is logical quibbling, withdrawing attention altogether away from the phenomena. In continuing his objections he advances an argument which was much used in after times when the great battle of Epigenesis (§ 457) was fought. " If," he says, "the parts pre-exist in the sperm, how can they live separate ? if united, then they already form a miniature animal. And how about the generative organs ? since those organs which come from the male are unlike those which come from the female. Moreover, if the sperm is derived from all parts of both parents, the issue will be two animals, since it will have each part of each parent. And wherefore should not the female generate from herself alone, if the sperm is derived from all parts, and she has the proper receptacle ? " 342 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. Growth presents another difficulty. He agrees with Anax- agoeas that " flesh becomes added to flesh by means of food; but those who maintain that sperm comes from the whole body have to explain how increase of size can be effected by that which is different if the addition itself remain un- changed? And if the addition has the power of change, why not at once assume that the sperm has this power, and can become flesh and blood without being originally alike? For growth is not to be explained by mixture. For on this idea the sperm would contain each separate part in its purest state, but we see that it becomes subsequently flesh and blood and every other part. And the idea of one portion of the sperm being sinew and another portion bone is beyond our conception." "Another difficulty is this: many animals are not pro- duced by animals of the same kind, nor even by animals of different kind — e.g., flies and fleas; from these worms are produced. It is clear that in these cases the offspring cannot arise from sperm derived from all parts; for they ought to resemble their parents if resemblance is a proof that the sperm comes from the whole body." § 441. He then considers the other arguments. The reason why maimed parents produce maimed children is the same as that which in other respects causes the resemblance ; and he adds that many perfectly-formed children are born to maimed parents ; also that many children are unlike their parents. Finally, the female has no sperm ; this is proof that sperm does not come from the whole body. § 442. After thus viewing this question from so many sides he proceeds to define sperm thus : " Sperm is in its nature an origin, or Principle, out of which arise all things which are naturally formed. 53 There are many ways in which 23 /3ov\trat St tolovtov ttjv fimv ilvai r6 mripfia 1% oi t& Kardt tyiaiv ovvWTdjitva yivtrai irpurov, oil r but this does not remove the difficulty which lies in the word oynw. We can hardly suppose that Aristotle maintained that the sperm had within it the bulk of the embryo. 30 Compare Eveeaedtjs: Novus exortus hominis et animalium, 1662, p. 31 j De Geaae: De virorum organis, p. 27; Bakchuskn: De Medicince oriyine et prugressu, 1723, p. 44. CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 347 a secretion contained in the catamenial fluid, he refutes the notion that the fluid secreted by the female is seminal. He holds the uncomplimentary opinion that woman is an undeveloped man. " She is female by her weakness, since the coldness of her nature will not suffer her food to be cooked into sperm." 31 § 450. " In those living beings which are without the distinctions of sex, the sperm is a kind of conception (icvy/ia, a fertilized seed). I call the first mixture of the masculine and feminine principles, a conception. Hence from one sperm, one body is generated ; as one stalk of wheat from one seed, and one animal from one egg : twins are from two eggs. But in those beings which have distinct sexes, many can be generated from one sperm." The mistake here arises from his not being aware of the immense multitude of spermatozoa contained in the sperm, and from his considering the sperm as one. §451. He believes that. the males give the form and principle of motion to "the embryo ; the female giving nothing but the plastic material. 33 As in the coagulation of milk, the milk is the substance, but the rennet is that which contains the cause, so that which is furnished by the female is divided, differentiated (jiepilofxivov), by that which comes from the male. 33 The chapter closes with this reflection : 31 On this Regnier de Gkaajt: De virorum organis, p. 2, remarks, " Nee minori contumelia Aristoteles fceminam marem imperfectum appellat : vel ut loquuntur barbari Philosophi animal occasionatum." Taukellus calls the idea blasphemous.-^* Ccesce, 1650, p. 814. Comp. also Scamger contra Car- danum, p. 188, verso. But it was long maintained by very grave philosophers. » The argument of C^esalpinus is that if the male and female both fur- nished material the one would interfere with the other, or there would be two offspring in lieu of one.- Quastiones Peripatetics:, lib. V, p. 97 D. -But wny should they not be blended? He never thinks of this alternative. Taurellus laughs at him, but advances no solid argument. •„„„„, - An idea frequently reproduced. See Regkier be Graae: ^orurn oraanis p 57: and Haller: Elementa Physiologic*, Bern. 1761 VIU. 54. n^demtim'es it has assumed this modified and not less absurd form: "La generation tient a ce que la liqueur femelle est oxidee pax to sperme et reduite 348 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. " That the female furnishes no seminal fluid, but that she nevertheless furnishes something, and this something is derived from the catamenial fluid in vertebrata, and from its analogue in invertebrata, is evident from what has already been said. It is also clear from abstract considerations. Since, of necessity, that which generates, and that out of which it generates, must pre-exist; and if these are united in one, they must be different in kind ; and when separated, the substance and the nature of the efficient and recipient must be diverse. If, therefore, the masculine is that which moves and forms, and the feminine is that which is moved and formed, it is clear that the female will not add seminal fluid, but simply material ; which is indeed the fact, for the nature of the catamenia is that of a primary material." § 452. Chap. XXI. It has already been noted that the accurate data upon which modern embryology bases the conclusion that both parents furnish material and form, were not accessible to Aristotle. His view best accords with the facts then known, and far surpasses that of the majority of his successors. He held the male influence to be qualitative, not quantitative ; 3 * and he adduces this ingenious argument : " When a hen is heavy with ' wind-eggs,' if she be treaded before the eggs have so far developed as that the yolk has received its white, she will lay perfect eggs, and not ' wind- eggs.' And if she be treaded by another cock while the egg is still yellow, the whole brood of chicks will resemble this cock. Hence, those who wish to rear fine broods bring the hen to be treaded by two different birds, for they do not suppose the sperm mixes with the eggs, nor that it comes from all parts of the body, otherwise the chicks would be double. But the sperm gives a specific force to the egg; en un caillot." — Ackermann, as quoted by Burdach. Still more recently the great embryologist Bischoff has reproduced it under the form of a catalytic action similar to that observable in fermentation. 34 ovk itg t& Troaov ovjifSaXk6ii.tvov toXq Sjfoic row dppsvog d\X lig rb irolov. CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 349 and this is increased by the new sperm, which is warmed and cooked, for the egg receives nourishment as long as it is growing. It is the same with fish. No sooner has the female laid her eggs, than the male casts his milt on them, and those eggs which are reached by the milt are fertilized, the others not." There is nothing in the two remaining chapters which requires special mention here. . §453. Book II. Chap. I. — The individual is mortal because individual. The species is eternal, because it repro- duces the individual. And the Masculine and Feminine exist only for this reproduction. But inasmuch as the first moving cause which determines species is higher and better than the substance determined, so it is better that the higher should be separated from the lower ; on this account, when possible, the masculine is kept distinct from the feminine, for the masculine is the principle of motion, and is higher and more god-like, whereas the feminine represents only the substance. § 454. After tbis teleological argument he surveys the various forms of reproduction. One division of animals, he says, brings forth young alive, and resembling their parents ; another division brings forth young without limbs, and differ- ing from their parents. Of this latter division the sanguineous bring forth eggs ; the exsanguineous, worms. In rendering ffKa>A»)£ by worm, I follow the translators and commentators; and the vague notions which then pre- vailed, respecting worms, may justify the interpretation ; but it is by no means certain that Aristotle meant what would now be understood by that term ; and perhaps the word scolex would be less misleading. He thus explains himself: " Egg and scolex are in this distinguished : in an egg the embryo arises from one part, all the rest serving it as food ; in the scolex, on the contrary, the embryo is developed from the whole." § 455. " Of viviparous animals some generate their young 350 ON GENERATION [OHAP. XVIL immediately within themselves — as man, horse, dolphin. Others are ovo-viviparous, first generating eggs, which develope into embryos within the parent — as the cartilaginous fishes." Although this distinction has been destroyed by the discovery that the embryo of the vivipara is at first an egg, the nomen- clature has been retained by many writers even to our own day. "Among the ovipara, some lay perfect eggs, which never increase after they are laid — such as birds and reptiles ; others, as fishes, Crustacea, and cephalopoda* lay imperfect eggs, which increase after they are laid." The increase here alluded to is supposed by Atjbekt and Wimmbe to be the' swelling from imbibition of water ; there is no other increase ; the eggs of fish and Crustacea are as perfect as those of birds and reptiles. After noticing several other points of distinction, he touches on the protections of eggs : " fish, which have scales, and Crustacea, which are earthy, lay eggs with hard shells ; but the cephalopoda, which have slimy bodies, lay eggs imbedded in slimy matter." § 456. " Insects all bring forth scolices (worms) ; for they are all exsanguineous, and hence scoliparous." It is strange that he should not have known the eggs of insects. " Nature has admirably arranged generation in a series. The most perfect and the warmest animals bring forth their young per- fectly formed, not indeed in size, for all grow after birth ; and they generate directly within themselves. The less perfect do not generate their young directly within themselves, for they first produce eggs ; but the young are born alive. Others, again, do not produce perfect young, but perfect eggs. Those, again, which are of a colder nature produce imperfect eggs. Finally, the coldest of all do not produce eggs, but scolices, which in time become similar to eggs; for the so-called chrysalis of the insect has the power (Swa/uv) of an egg, from which in the third metamorphosis an animal is produced." § 457. He now proceeds to sketch rapidly, yet fir mly , his CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 351 doctrine of Epigenesis, which he has variously illustrated. Every one acquainted with the history of science is familiar with the long and fierce disputes which have surrounded the question, Does the embryo pre-exist in the germ? but as even men otherwise well-informed are quite unacquainted with Aristotle's views on this point, and suppose the doctrine of Epigenesis to date from Harvey and Caspar Friedrich Wolff, it may be useful here to set down the hypotheses advocated by the various schools, before expounding Aristotle's. Blumenbach states that Drelinoourt " collected no less than two hundred and sixty-two groundless hypotheses con- cerning generation advanced by his predecessors ; and nothing is more certain than that Drelincourt's own theory formed the two hundred and sixty-third." 3S All these theories may be ranged under two classes : — A. Those which relate to the action of the parents. This class may be further subdivided into : 1. The Spermatist theory — which makes the male parent the sole progenitor. 2. The Ovist theory — which makes the female parent the sole progenitor. 3. The Syngenetic theory — which makes both parents equally progenitors. B. Those which relate to the changes in the egg. This second class may be further subdivided into : 4. The theory of Evolution, which makes the embryo pre- existent in the germ, and only rendered visible by the unfold- ing and expansion of its organs. 5. The theory of Epigenesis, which makes the embryo arise by a series of successive differentiations from a simple homogeneous mass into a complex heterogeneous organism. §458. The spermatist theory is of immense antiquity. In the Hindoo code Man is considered as the seed, and *> Quoted by Allen Thompson: Art. Generation, in the Cyclopcedia of Anat. and Physiol. 852 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. Woman as the soil; by their co-operation the new being is produced. 36 In the Ewmenides of .ZEschyltjs there is the same idea. Apollo declares that the mother is not a genitrix, but merely the rearer of the young germ. Life is generated by the father. oi/K tan fifirrip 17 KeKktipivov t'ckvov roKiis, rpo^Ac dk Kvparog veoavopoV TlKTlt & 6 QphlffKtoP. v. 615. Most of the ancient philosophers held this view; and no sooner had Leetjwenhoek discovered the spermatozoa 3r than it seemed as if a positive basis had been gained for this hypothesis. The spermatozoon is a microscopic, transparent, oval particle, with a long and delicate thread-like tail. It wriggles forward with amazing vivacity, and is in no respect distinguishable from an animalcule. What wonder, then, that the oval part was pronounced to be a head, and the thread a tail? Imagination saw, and an occasional draughtsman actually figured, the lineaments of a man in this microscopic particle. 38 And as these spermatozoa are only found in repro- ductive males, and always in them, the hypothesis of the spermatists seemed to have acquired a demonstration. § 459. The ovists, however, were not without their rival 36 Manava-Dharmasastra, lib. IX., St. 33, quoted by Lucas: TraiU philos. de I'MrediU, Paris, 1850, II., 67. 37 On the claims of Hartsoeker to priority, see the note in Bostook's erudite System of Physiology, 3rd ed., 1836, p. 642. Compare also Vallisnebi: Historie von der Erzeugung der Menschen und Thiere, aus dem Italidnischen von C. P. Beegek, 1739, p. 7. ' 8 " L'imagination avait alors un vaste champ ouvert devant elle. Les uns crurent voir dans les animalcules spermatiques des embryons corporalises, qui n'avaient plus besoin que de croitre. Gautier les figura ayant des figures d'hommes. Suivant Andry, chacun d'eux va trouver l'ovaire, se glisse dans un ceuf, ferme la porte derriere lui avec sa queue, et se developpe ; si plusieurs veulcnt entrer a, la fois dans un meme ceuf, ils se fttchent, se battent ensemble, et se brisent ou se luxent les membres, ce qui donnent lieu aux monstmosites." — Bukdach: Traits de Physiologic, Paris, 1838, II., 287. In the German version of Vallisneki: Erzeugung der Menschen und Thiere, the figures drawn by Andky are reproduced. Nothing more preposterous in the way of mal- observation (if it were not a pure invention) can be named. CHAP. XVII.J AND DEVELOPMENT. 353 discovery. Stenon and De Gbaaf had detected the mamma- lian ovum, or rather the Graafian vesicle, which they mistook for the ovum, but which Von Baeb proved to contain it Tins important discovery seemed to the ovists to prove that the female furnished the germ, and the male furnished only the exciting influence. Malpighi, Vallisneei, Halleb, Spallanzani, Beaumub, and Bonnet lent this hypothesis their powerful supports They held that the embryo pre-existed m the germ, and that its evolution was excited by the influence of the sperm. § 460. The theory of Syngenesis, which considers the embryo to be the product of both male and female, is as old as Empedocles, though it had no better basis than the observed resemblance between the offspring and both parents. Modern research has furnished a scientific basis, by show- ing that, while in the higher animals both ova and spermatozoa are equally indispensable, they are themselves only modifications of one and the same anatomical ele- ment (§ 191). § 461. Let us now glance at the theories of the second class. The first of these, or the theory of Evolution, assumes that the embryo pre-exists in the germ, and is only called into visible existence by the agencies of generation and develop- ment. Not only so, but the germs themselves were all contained in the original germ ; the first generation contained all successive generations. This is the emboitement theory of Swammeedamm, Malebeanche, Vallisneei, Beaumub, and Bonnet, which was accepted by the great Halleb, and was not rejected even by Cuviee. Some one wittily observes that " l'hypothese de l'emboitement rend necessaire 1'emboitement d'un infini d'hypotheses ;" and it has the vice of being meta- physiological ; yet of course it has many plausible arguments 39 Ldcas: Op. cit, declares that De Blainville also adopted it in his Cours de Physiohgie ; but no exact reference is given, and I can find nothing in the Lecture to bear out Lucas's statement. 23 354 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. ill its favour, otherwise it would never have been maintained by the judicious Halleb. 40 § 462. In the present day no one believes in the pre- existence of germs, or the evolution of the embryo. The doctrine of Epigenesis triumphs along the whole line. Since Wolff showed how the primitive amorphous germ became an organism through successive modifications, each modification being the cause of others — part being added to part, not simply in the way of addition, but each being the product of some predecessor, and the cause of some successor 41 — the researches of hundreds of patient embryologists have made Epigenesis the only acceptable hypothesis. The argument of the evolutionists, that all the organs are formed at once, and not successively, 42 seems admissible when supported by the assertion that the extreme smallness and transparency of these organs prevent their being visible ; but both assertions fall before microscopic investigation, which shows that the impreg- nated germ passes through several successive visible stages wholly irreconcileable with this notion of a pre-existent in- visible organism. The germinal membrane, composed of three layers, is seen to form itself into two cylinders, the two outer layers curving upwards, the innermost layer curving downwards, and from each of these cylinders issue the rudimentary forms of the several organs. § 463. It will probably surprise the reader to hear that Aristotle very distinctly announced the docrine of Epigenesis, 40 Haller: Elementa Physiologies, VIII., 143-51. Compare also Vallis- neki: Von der Erzeugung, 1739, pp. 140, 442, 461 ; or Reaumur: Mimoires pour servir a I'histoire des Insectes, 1734, I., 343, seq. 41 There are few works of deeper insight or more patient research than C. F. Wolff's Theorie von der Generation, in zwo Abhandlungen erkliirt und bewiesen, Berlin, 1764, and I shall not easily forget the excitement with which I hurried through the Berlin streets in a storm to secure a copy at an old secondhand bookshop. In it may be found the origin of Goethe's Metamor- phoses of Plants, as well as the leading ideas since expounded with such mastery by Von Baer and his followers. 42 Haixer, p. 148. CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 855 a doctrine commonly attributed to Harvey. Wolff is wrong m stating that Aristotle "affirmed, but did not defend Epigenesis, simply because no one had thought of denying it." * 3 It had been denied, and a counter theory proposed which Aristotle refuted. "Either," he says, "the parts arise together and at once, or one after the other. That they do not arise at once is evident to sense ; for we see that some parts are present, and others absent; and it is certain that these latter are not invisible simply because of their smallness, for although the lungs are larger than the heart, yet in development they are later. Since one part is earlier, and another later, it becomes a question whether the one forms the other, the latter being dependent on the former, or the one simply arises after the other. The heart does not form the liver, and this again the other parts ; but the one part arises after the other, as the man comes after the boy, but not from the boy. The reason is this: In everything produced by Nature or by Art, the actual arises from the potential; and so must here the species and form exist in the earlier — for example, the liver must exist in the heart. 44. And this view is otherwise deceptive. For it is impossible that from the first a part of the plant, or animal, should exist ready formed in the sperm — whether capable or incapable of forming other parts — if all arise from the spermatic fluid. For if such a part be in the sperm, it must have been made by that which made the sperm. Now sperm must be the first ; and this is the work of generation. Hence it is impossible that a part should pre-exist. Therefore the plastic power (to ttoiovv) has no organ within it, nor without it. Yet one or the other is necessary. Let us try to reconcile this contradiction." 43 Wolff, p. 60. 44 'on iiri tov IvriKixeicj, ovrog to SvvdfiEi 'iv yivirai iv roig fvau f) rsxvy yivo/ikvots, Store Seoi &v to ildoe Kal rijv fiop$v iv Ueivy elvai olov iv ry KapSiq. rb tov ijiraTos : The reader must bear in mind the distinctions of entelechie and dynamis, and of species and form. 23—2 356 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. To reconcile these views lie adduces the comparison of the movements of an automaton in which one wheel, on being set in action, determines the movement in other parts. The sperm is this primary motor ; and has the power of communi- cating movement long after its original impulse has ceased. No organ is the cause of development. The cause is that which first originated the movement. Hence one organ arises after another, and not all at once. § 464. As the analysis proceeds, we shall still further learn how firmly the doctrine of Epigenesis was grasped by him ; for the present it is enough to have indicated his view. Chap. II. is devoted to the physical nature of sperm,, which is described as a kind of foam, or mixture of water and air. " The ancients seem to have known this, to judge from the name of the goddess Aphrodite." 45 The air (Trvexifia). here referred to, can hardly be understood as atmospheric air. It plays a considerable part in the speculations of the ancient and the Eenaissance writers ; but I have never been able to make out what was precisely meant by it. In theories of generation, it is the av/ra rising from the sperm, which, until the discovery of Spermatozoa, 46 was almost universally held to be the agent in fertilization. § 465. Chap. III. touches on other points connected with sperm. Especially worthy of note is the statement that sperm and seed are as the living animal and plant which will issue from them. "It is clear that they have the Vegetal Soul (nutritive principle), and in their further development they must acquire the Sensitive Soul, which constitutes them animals." 45 ii0p6? in Greek means " foam." 46 And even for many years afDerwai - ds. Thus, Haller: Elementa Phys. VIII., 154 ; and still later Schneegass maintained that " il se degage du melange de sperme et de mucus uterin une aura seminalis, qui monte le long des oviductes, et qui d'aprSs Ktjhlemann penetre a travers lea membranes de l'ovaire." — Bubdach: TraiU de Phys.,\l., 195. CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 357 Not only is Aristotle an upholder of the doctrine of Epigenesis, hut he is also to he ranked among the most philo- sophical teachers who have held the doctrine so luminously expounded by Von Baer, that the general and specific characters of the embryo are successively acquired, so that the mammalian embryo is first an animal, then a vertebrate, then a mammal, and finally, a particular kind of mammal. This doctrine is thus aphoristically expressed by Aristotle : " Not at once is the animal a man or horse ; for the end is last attained ; and the specific form is the end of each develop- ment. Hence it is an important question when, how, and whence comes the Intellect in those animals which possess it. We must evidently assume that the sperm and the unsepa- rated conception (ovum) must possess the Vegetal Soul (rriu dptwTiicrjv Tpw%fjv) at least potentially ; though not in reality, until the separated conception (foetus) takes up nourishment, and thus fulfils the work of such a soul. At first it seems as if the embryo lived the life of a plant ; it is only at a subse- quent period that we can speak of a sensitive and intelligent soul. These, however, must necessarily pre-exist potentially before they exist in reality. Now either they must not have been actually present, and must have come in all together ; or they were all present ; or else some were present, and others not ; and they must have come in with the germ, and not with the sperm ; or reached the germ from the sperm. If in the sperm, they must have entered at once from without, or none did so ; unless some did, and others did not. But it is impossible that they should have been actually present, since all the corporeal functions naturally require the presence of their respective organs, 4 ? e. g. there can be no walking without legs. For the same reason they cannot come from without. « I depart here somewhat from the literal rendering, in order to make this remarkable passage intelligible. The illustration o walkmg sufficiently Justified iy interpretation: Ln> yap h™ a^v v ^pyna a^ar^, *,W Sn ravrag aviv aiiftaroe dSvvarov virapx" v - 358 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. Nor can they enter alone — being inseparable from their organs ; nor in a body, for the sperm is a secretion from the metamorphosed food. Only the Intellect enters from without. It alone is godlike. Its actuality has nothing in common with corporeal actuality." § 466. This is the most decisive passage I have been able to find respecting the immortality of the soul (§ 224). It is the more explicit because it is made to express the distinction between the Intellect as a godlike and incorporeal principle, and the Nutritive and Sensitive principles which are obviously dependent on matter. 48 § 467. " The vital principles seem to belong to another body, which is of a more honourable nature than the so-called elements. And just as these principles differ in rank amongst each other, so also are they different in the nature of their common body. In all sperm there is the so-called heat, which effects generation. This heat, however, is not fire, but a breath (irvtvfia) contained in the foamy nature of the sperm ; and in this pneuma there is a nature analogous to that of the elements of the stars. Hence fire generates no living thing. But the warmth of the sun, on the contrary, has this power." § 468. Woman is undeveloped man. She furnishes the analogue of the sperm minus its vital principles. The proof of this is seen in the "wind-eggs" of the hen, which have ' the plastic substance, but which, wanting the formative prin- ciple of the sperm, never become living beings. In the Third Book (c. 7, p. 757) he explains this more clearly. The wind- eggs, he says, never become perfect chicks, because they want the sensitive soul ; they have the nutritive soul, since that belongs to all females, and all living beings. And a wind- egg may therefore be regarded as a perfect vegetal seed, but as 49 It was thus Roger Bacon understood it. " Intellectus agens est pars animas, sed est substantia intellectiva alia et separata per essentiam ab intellectu possibili."— Opus Majus, Venet., 1750, p. 20. CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 359 an imperfect animal seed. The influence of the male is neces- sary for a perfect animal. § 469. Chap. IV. is devoted to the catamenia. The intimate dependence of Lactation on this process is noticed; also the formation of the foetal membranes from the corporeal elements of the fluid, after the evaporation of its moisture. " No sooner is the conception (ro K v W a) formed, than it grows like the seed of plants in the earth. For even in the seed there is a self-contained principle of development, and from it arise stem and roots, through which it takes up nourishment. In the same way all the parts of an animal are potentially contained in the conception, and a principle of development. The heart is the first differentiated reality. For there must be an origin out of which all the rest will arise." § 470. He then passes to another problem. A concep- tion is potentially an animal, although an imperfect animal. It must have food ; but whence is the food derived ? As the plant derives food from the earth, the fetus derives food from the uterus. " Hence Nature has from the first sent two veins from the heart which, dividing into several smaller vessels, forms the umbilical cord (o 6/i(j>a\og), and this goes to the uterus. This cord is a vein, in some animals several veins, enveloped in a membrane for its protection. These veins ramify like roots over the uterus, and through them the foetus receives nourishment. It is on this account that the foetus remains in the uterus, and not, as Democbitus thinks, in order that each part may be formed like the mother. This is evident in oviparous animals which develope their parts in the egg, away from the mother." Although inaccurate in its details, this passage expresses in a general way the true relation of the fetus to the mother. He then considers this question : " If blood be nourishment, and the heart first arises in order to contain it, and if food comes from without, whence the first nourishment ? Or is it 360 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. not correct to say that all nourishment comes from without, but that just as in the seed of plants there is a milky fluid, so in the foetus there is a surplus of material from which it will receive nourishment?" § 471. " The differentiation of organs does not, as some think, take place by the attraction of like for like ; but the child resembles its mother because her secretion is potentially of the same nature as her whole body, and hence contains the possibility, though not the reality, of all her organs." This is further explained by the fact of the mother furnishing not only the plastic material but the nutritive principle, or vegetal soul. In plants there is no separation of sexes ; but in those animals' which have separated sexes the female cannot of herself produce offspring. § 472. Chap. V. — " Yet it may be asked : If the female possesses a soul, and if her secretion furnishes the material, why is the male influence indispensable ? The reason this : The animal has a Sensitive Soul, and this is wanting to the plant." Aristotle admits the power of vegetal reproduction in females, but denies them that of animal reproduction. It is true that unfertilized ova live, but what is their life ? Not the life of animals, otherwise they would become animals ; yet a life higher than that of inorganic substances, as we see by their decay. They possess only the lowest form of life — that which is common to plants and animals, i. e. the nutritive soul. This cannot form an animal organ. § 473. " If there is, indeed, a class of animals which, although feminine have no males, it is possible that such may produce young by themselves. But this is not yet credibly ascertained : even in fishes it is dubious. Of the so-called Erythrinnes no male has yet been found, but many females full of conceptions. But on this point we have no decisive experience. There are, however, fishes which are neither male nor female, such as the eel, and a species of Icestris (supposed to be the mullet)." CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 361 Aristotle thought that eels were generated spontaneously in the mud. In those days spontaneous generation was received without difficulty by all minds. 4 9 But how the sexes of mullets came to be overlooked is not clear. " Whenever the male exists the female is incompetent to generate alone; otherwise the male would be useless, and nature does nothing in vain. Hence in animals the male perfects generation, giving the sensitive soul." § 474. Since the organs are already potentially existing in the germ it is only necessary for the sperm to give the first impulse, and straightway all the organs begin to range them- selves in due succession. 50 The heart is the first to appear. It is the origin and centre of development. That it is so is seen not only by direct inspection, but also in the fact that it is the last to die; since it is a law that that which appears last disappears first. Modern research, as I have already stated, discredits the idea of the heart as primum saliens. The heart is not the first organ which appears, nor is it the last which dies, ultimum moriens. That it lives and beats for some time after the death of the animal, in amphibia for some hours, is quite true ; but other organs also survive the organism. Hair grows, glands secrete, and the stomach will digest many hours after the heart has ceased to beat. 51 § 475. Chap. VI. sketches the phenomena of develop- 49 Even so late as the 17th century we find Julius Cssar Scaliger main- taining that mice were generated from corruption. — Exercitationes contra Car- danum, Paris, 1657, p. 81. 60 " Solum semen masculum dormientem embiyonis vitam excitat." — Haller: Elementa Phys., VIII., p. 154. The whole of this 31st section might be taken as a translation of Aristotle, with the understanding that what the Greek regards as potential pre-existence, the Swiss regards as actual pre- existence. 51 Twenty-four hours, in certain fishes, according to Charles Kobin : Comptes Rendus de la SociiU de Biologie, 1853, V., 134. I found the hinder extremities of a Triton living, and capable of motion, three hours after the heart had ceased to beat. But the phenomenon is very variable, and sometimes the heart survives the extremities. 362 ON GENEEATION [CHAP. XVII. ment. Although in many points inaccurate, and in some purely fanciful, it shows that Aristotle had studied develop- ment, not indeed with the patience and caution necessary in an inquiry so delicate, but with quite as much as he thought fit to bestow on any other inquiry. He notices that the upper half of the body is first developed, the lower half being smaller and less distinct. The fact is so ; 52 but the reason assigned is erroneous. The heart, he considers, as the origin of all development, the lower part being only for the sake of the upper. § 476. " The genesis of the partes similares takes place through cooling and warmth ; ^the coagulation and solidifica- tion of some being determined by cold, and of others by warmth. The nutritive fluid filters through the veins and the canals of each part, like water in unglazed earthen vessels (ufio'ig Kspafiioig) , and becomes flesh, or its analogue, coagulating in cooling ; and hence it becomes dissolved by fire." Although we should greatly err if we interpreted this language into an expression of the modern idea of the plastic elements oozing through the walls of the bloodvessels (§ 156), we cannot but remark how much nearer the truth Aristotle was than other physiologists, until the discovery of the capillaries by Malpighi made it impossible to accept the notion of the blood being poured on the tissues. " That portion of the filtered fluid which is earthy, and has little warmth and moisture, becomes, during the cooling process, which evaporates the moisture, hard and earthy: such as nails, hair, hoofs, &c. Hence these become softened by fire, but not melted ; others by liquids : for example, the shells of eggs. But under the influence of internal warmth, which dries up their moisture, sinews and bones arise; and hence they are not soluble by fire, for they are baked as in an oven by the genetic warmth." This warmth is contained 52 Compare KOllikbe: Entwickelungsgeschichte, 1861, p, 50. CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 363 in the sperm, and possesses the motor and creative power necessary for each part. Whenever this is in excess or deficiency, it occasions a deformity in the embryo. § 477. " The skin is formed by the drying of the flesh, as we see a skin formed on the surface of cooked meat. But it is not the fact of its being the surface which causes this ; the reason is because the viscid material (to yXlcrxpov) cannot evaporate, and remains at the top. In other cases this viscid material is dry, and thus forms the hard and soft shells of bloodless animals ; whereas, in sanguineous animals, it has a more fatty nature, and hence we see only those which are not very earthy have fat under their skin— a proof that the skin arises from a similar material." § 478. The order of differentiation is noticed. In the course of this the parts are at first sketched in outline, and subsequently assume their colour, softness, hardness, &c, "just as the painter first draws an animal in outline, and then fills up the picture with colour." § 479. Chap. VII. begins with a description of the placenta, and then passes to the question why Hybrids are usually not fertile. In Chap. VIII., after examining the opinions of his predecessors on this point, and even suggesting an a priori argument in their favour, he makes this remark- able observation : " But such a proof is far too abstract and empty. For reasons not drawn from the inherent principle of things are empty and only seem to explain them. Just as those only are geometrical proofs which are deduced from geometrical principles, so also in all other sciences. The empty argument seems potent, but is powerless." He clenches his refutation of all the abstract arguments against the possible fertility of Hybrids by this pithy statement : " The fact is that many Hybrids are fertile." Yet his own explanation of the common infertility is not a whit more acceptable than the explanations he rejects. § 480. Book HI.— The first seven chapters of this book 364 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. are devoted to an enumeration of the differences in the forma- tion and development of eggs. Full of repetitions and' destitute of any attempt at systematic arrangement, these chapters, like so many others in his scientific writings, resemble the unorganized contents of a note-book rather than parts of a treatise. One or two passages of interest have already been previously quoted in these pages. § 481. Chap. VIII. — Having mentioned that the cephalo- poda are of distinct sexes, he refers to the opinion that all fishes are females, adding : " It is, however, too much to believe that cephalopoda are of distinct sexes, and fishes not ; and the opinion is only an evidence of insufficient observation." At the close of the chapter he almost anticipates the modern discovery that the embryo of the cuttlefish, instead of having the yolk on its under surface, has it attached to the head ; in fact, the embryo seems to swallow the yolk. § 482. Chap. IX. is on the generation of insects, which he describes as being partly sexual, partly spontaneous. Chap. X. is on the generation of bees, already noticed (§ 194). Chap. XI. treats of molluscs, and gives a fuller, exposition of his views on Spontaneous Generation than can be found elsewhere. To the mind of almost every biologist of our day, the idea of Spontaneous Generation appears excessively improbable, and certainly not proven, even with respect to the simplest plants and animalcules ; and with respect to worms, insects, or molluscs, it is universally rejected. 53 At present the massive weight of evidence is against the hypothesis. The chief argument in its favour rests on the difficulty of always proving the presence of germs; and this is enforced by the facility with which some minds believe that whatever is conceivable must be true. 53 The doctrine of spontaneous generation has been revived by Pouchet : Hiterogfnie ; ou traiti de la Generation spontanie bas6 sur des nouvelles expe- riences, Paris, 1859. See the Comptes Eendus of the Academy for the years 1859-63. CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 365 In Aristotle's day there was no difficulty whatever in believing that insects, molluscs, and eels were spontaneously originated in putrefying matters. Animals suddenly appeared in places where there had previously been no trace of their parents. To the ancients this was sufficient proof of spon- taneous generation. Aristotle said that all plants and animals which arise spontaneously, do so in putrefying substances to which water has been added, " It is not from putrefaction, as such, but from coction, that the new being arises : the putrid substance is only a secretion from that which is cooked. Animals and plants arise in the earth, and in moisture, because water is present in earth, and in water there is air (pneuma), and in all air there is animal heat; so that in a certain sense all things have life (soul, ^v-^rj). Hence bodies are quickly formed when enclosed in a small space, and they are so enclosed when by means of heat the fluid substance is formed into a kind of foam-vesicle. 54 The differences of nobler and ignobler species depend on that vital principle which is enclosed ; and hence we must seek the cause both in what is enclosed, and where it is enclosed. In sea-water there is much earthy matter, and hence from the sea, testaceous animals are produced ; the earthy matter being hardened on their surface, for it is not to be melted by heat ; and internally the living body is enclosed. Only a few species have been observed in congress; and it is uncertain whether generation was the result or not in these cases. We must inquire what here represents the material principle of other animals. Among females, it is a secretion which receives from the male its moving principle, and potentially 54 E/i7repiXaiJ.I3dvtTai Si zeal yiverca Oipficuvofiivuiv tSv aiajiarixav iypuiv olav dfpiaSric iro/i « fiavnvSiievoi t6 (W^^^vov Ik tS>v hk6tiov, koX wpoXafi/SavovTec wf *sffir :i iitTwioS; ^. * h — by ^ among the three modes of procuring male offspring, though he reverses the sMes ordering the mother to lie on her left side, because it is the stronger, and ml; a e formed in the stronger. He declares that he has prescribed this me hod to patients with great success.-^ subtilUate rerun, lib. XII., Lugdum. S, P- 441- Scax-igeb has nothing to object here, so we must presume he accepts the argument as valid. 368 ON GENERATION [OHAP. XVII. right side is indeed warmer than the left (which it is not) ; but, such hypotheses do not touch the real difficulty ; for that we must look into first causes." § 484. His own hypothesis is this : " The masculine and feminine are distinguished by a certain power, and a certain impotence. That is masculine which has the power of cooking, condensing, and secreting sperm containing the formative principle ; and I do not call that a principle which becomes an individual from the material, but that which is the first moving cause, either in itself, or in another; the feminine, on the other hand, is that which receives, but is incapable of con- densing and secreting sperm. If the cooking depends on heat, the male must necessarily be warmer than the female." After enlarging on this notion of heat, he adds, " Male and female are contraries, and have different generative organs, which have different functions. Moreover, according to our views, everything arises from contraries ; and when there is loss or failure (v 9opa) in the one contrary, that which cannot properly be fashioned naturally turns into, the opposite. On these grounds it is easy to explain the sexes. Whenever the formative principle fails to gain the upper hand, and, from deficient warmth, fails properly to cook the material, and so fashion it into its own shape, then will this material necessarily pass over into the contrary ; and the contrary of the masculine is the feminine. And since their difference consists in their functions, and these in their organs, the first change will be in the organs. Now when one important and dominant organ (ecoc juopiov emicaipov) is changed, then there is a change in the whole form of the organism." The reader will observe how luminously the idea of Epigenesis is expressed in the last sentence ; and lest there should be any doubt as to his meaning, he adds, " This is manifest in castrated animals, which, being de- prived of a single organ, lose their sexual appearance, so as in many respects to resemble the female. The cause CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 369 is that certain organs are origins of development, and if one of these be altered, much that is connected with it must likewise change. When, therefore, the masculine is denned to be a kind of principle and cause, and is only mascu- line in as far as it possesses these which are wanting to the feminine— and when such power and such impotence are determined by the capability and incapability of cooking the final nourishment, called blood in the sanguineous, and its analogue in the ex-sanguineous ; and when the origin of the blood is in the central organ, the source of animal heat, then it is necessary that a heart, or its analogue, should be formed, and that the embryo should be male or female." § 485. Whatever may be thought of this hypothesis, which becomes somewhat confused towards the close of the exposi- tion, when we remember that he did not, and could not know that every embryo was at first asexual, passing from this indeterminate condition into determinate organs by successive morphological changes, we shall acknowledge that his answer is quite as good as that of any of his successors, and better than most. What determines the special changes remains ', to this day a profound mystery ; all we know is that sex is not \ primitive, pre-existent, but — as was shown in Knight's experi- ments on Plants — is determined by unknown conditions of temperature and nutrition. 59 § 486. Chap. II. — Connecting his hypothesis with the statistics of birth, as known to him, he finds further proof in the fact that more females are born during the youth and old age of the parents than during their prime : in the young the animal heat has not acquired maturity, in the old it is begin- ning to disappear. He also thinks that fruitful animals produce more females than males. That more males are generated 59 See an interesting essay by Ploss: Uber die Geschlechtsverhaltnisse der Kinderbedingenden Ursachen, Berlin, 1858, and compare Pagenstechek: fiber das Oesetz der Erzeugung der Geschlecter. Aus dem Pranzbsischen von M. Thukt. Leipzig, 1864. 24 370 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. during the prevalence of the north winds, may be explained on the ground of the secretions being then smaller in quantity, and more easily cooked; a similar cause operates in the appearance of the catamenia, chiefly at the last quarter of the moon, for this part of the month is colder and moister, owing to the disappearance of the moon. He quotes, without dis- approval, the saying of shepherds, that males or females are produced according as the sheep have congress during a north or south wind ; not only so, but it is an important condition whether the animals in congress look towards the north or the south, " so trifling a circumstance being influential in genera- tion by determining heat or cold." The chapter contains other passages which raise a smile. Variations of sex are attributed to the nature of the soil and the water, which with the atmosphere, influence the food. " Hence hard and cold waters occasion the sterility of women, and partly determine the generation of females." To this day the Egyptians attribute the fecundity of their women to the waters of the Nile ; and Hippocrates, 60 who thought that water issuing from hard rocks must necessarily be hard, mentions hard and cold waters among the causes of sterility. § 487. Chap. III. treats of the hereditary transmission of qualities from parent to offspring. 61 It has long been a ques- tion whether all the qualities, physical and moral, are trans- mitted, and whether one parent transmits one group, and the other another, or both transmit all. Even Haller and Bonnet, who thought the embryo pre-existed in the germ, could not deny that Hybrids partook of the characteristics of both parents. Holding the sperm to be merely the nutriment 60 Hippocrates: De Ae're, Locis, et Aquis, XX., 19. Compare Batjhin : De Hermaphroditorum Natura, 1614, p. 59. 61 The literature of this important subject will be found in Burdach: TraiU de Physiologie, II. ; and Lucas : Traits' de VHiridiU naturelle, 1847; see also Girotj de Buzareingues: TraiU de la Generation, 1828 ; Orton : Lectures on Breeding, 1859. CHAP. XVII. AND DEVELOPMENT. 371 and excitor of the germ, they thought that the form of the embryo would vary with the quality and quantity of the sperm. It was thus they explained the fact of the mule having the ears and voice of the ass. The germ from which the mule pro- ceeds is the germ of a horse ; but the sperm of the ass containing more particles destined for the nutrition of the ears and vocal membranes, the mule resembles in these the ass. § 488. Those who held the doctrine of Epigenisis varied in their interpretations of parental influence. Some thought that the male gave the animal organs, the female only the vegetal organs. The superficial resemblance of the spermatozoon to the early form of the cerebro-spinal axis, 62 and the fact of the spermatozoon being endowed with movement, naturally sug- gested the idea of the nervous and muscular systems being due to the male, whence it was further inferred that the digestive and glandular systems came from the female. This idea has been favourably received by physiologists and cattle-breeders. I have elsewhere endeavoured to show how irreconcileable it is with the facts, 63 and may here briefly state an a •priori argument which entirely disproves it. That the whole sum of the contribution to the formation of the embryo is limited on the part of the male to the spermatozoa, and on the part of the female to the ovum, is decisively proved in the generation of amphibia and fish, since in that generation, which takes place in the water, outside the parent, there is nothing but these two elements present. Now, we have already seen that sperma- tozoa and ova are identical (§ 191) ; and when to this it is added that in some animals ova alone suffice to form a perfect offspring (§ 192), there can remain no doubt that the contribu- tion of the mother is not limited to any one system or group of organs, but embraces the whole organism. Unless, there- 82 " Si le zoosperme n'est pas im systeme cerebro-spinal, et le vitellus un syst&me digestif, ils possMent en eux les elemens necessaires au developpement ulteriearde ces bases essentieiles de l'animalite."— Laixemand: Annates des Sciences Naturelles, 1841, p. 281. 63 Physiology of Common Life, IX, 392. 24—2 872 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. fore, we return to the old hypothesis of the ovists, and regard the contribution of the male simply in the light of a stimulus to the germ (an hypothesis abundantly refuted by the facts of cross-breeding, in which the obvious characteristics of the male are transmitted), we have no alternative but to declare that both parents furnish their quota to every part of the offspring. § 489. Having thus glanced at modern hypotheses, let us consider the view taken by Aristotle. In the generation of man he says the progenitor is not simply a man, but a special individual such as Socrates or Koriskos. The individual and special have always predominance. Koriskos is man, as well as animal, but his speciality is as man rather than as animal. The individual predominates in generation because individuality constitutes the essence. But, inasmuch as when the formative principle fails to fashion the material, the contrary must be produced, so when Koriskos is a parent, if his influence qua man be feeble, his child will be a female, resembling him, his influence qua man having passed into its contrary ; and if this influence is still feebler, the child will be a female resembling its mother. If the influence qua individual be feeble, the child will resemble its grandfather. But, whatever variation take place, the child always exhibits human characteristics. The cause of all these variations is the check received by the Motor impulse from the Material moved. Action pro- duces reaction. The edge of a tool is blunted by the material which it cuts; the heating body is cooled by that which it warms; "and sometimes the reaction is greater than the action ; the warming body becomes cold, and the cold body warm, and hence the effect is lost or weakened." § 490. In extreme cases, the formative principle is so far checked that the child ceases to resemble human beings, and resembles an animal — in which case it is called a monster. Here the material is not fashioned into special forms, but the general remains Qxevei to Ka96\ov), and this is animal. " Thus, it is said that children are bom with the heads of CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 373 sheep or cakes, and other parts resembling those of animals; for example, a calf with a child's head, or a sheep with the head of an ox. All such phenomena are due to the cause before-named ; but we must not understand such statements literally; none of these monstrosities really are animals, but only resemble them. The same sort of resemblance may be seen in perfectly-formed healthy men. A Physiognomist once showed how all faces could be reduced to two or three animal types. But how impossible it is for one animal to have the parts of another is evident from the differences in the periods of gestation of men, sheep, dogs, and oxen. Each can only be formed in its own definite period." This passage displays remarkable sagacity, and might have enlightened many o*f his successors. The belief in a race of men having the heads of dogs was easy to Lord Monboddo, who confesses that such men have not been seen by any modern traveller, but they are spoken of by so many ancient authors, that he can hardly doubt of their having once existed. 64 Aristotle not only marks what is true from what is false in the popular belief, but refers to distinct physiological grounds, namely, that the child requires nine months, and the dog only nine weeks for its development. Whence he probably con- cluded that so great a difference in the development of the two would prevent any such organic union, as vulgar superstition accepted. § 491. He does not mention "mothers' marks," as we are reminded by Hallee. 65 We cannot say whether this omission was intentional ; but he is hardly to be credited with having seen through the popular fallacy which attributes the marks 64 Monboddo: Ancient Metaphysics, 1779, HI., 263. He also believed in tbe existence of a nation of one-legged men; and although he owns that StKabo rejects this as a fable, he reminds us that " a spirit of incredulity was begun as early as the days of Strabo," p. 251. He would hare found support in his credulity in Bauhin: De Hermaphroditorum Natura. 65 Haiaee: Elementa Phys., VHL, 142. 374 ON GENERATION [CHAP. XVII. on the child to the imagination of the mother, an absurdity that has found energetic defenders even in our own day. § 492. He treats of monsters par exces, in which six fingers, six toes, two heads, &c, are formed; and acutely remarks that although these phenomena are contrary to the ordinary course of nature they are not unnatural. Modern science has established on irrefragable grounds that defor- mities and monstrosities follow precisely the same laws of development as are followed in perfect embryos. 66 § 493. Chap. V. is on superfcetation. § 494. Chap. VI. treats of the condition in which the young of various animals are born, whether blind or not, and how far capable of maintaining independent existence; with several other matters not specially calling for notice here. § 495. Chap. VII. is on extra uterine gestation, and on the so-called mola. But it is too exclusively technical for this place. Chaps. VIII., IX., and X., are devoted to milk, and to the periods of gestation. He supposes that the period of gestation is in relation to longevity. § 496. The Final Book is occupied with discussions as to the cause of the variation in the colour of eyes and hair, the abundance of hah-, the sleep of the embryo, sight and hearing, voice and the teeth. But interesting as some of these are, there is nothing which induces us to expand this chapter already too long. § 497. We close our analysis of this work with the re- 66 Geoffroy St. Hilaire: Philosophic Anatomique, 1830, vol. II.; Serres: Hecherches tPanatomie transcendante et pathologique, 1832 ; Isidore St. Hilaire: Histoire des Anomalies de V Organisation, 1832. In the last-named work the literature of this extensive subject is copiously given. The treatise by Bauhin: De Hermaphroditorum Monstrorumque partuum Natura, libri duo, Oppenheimii, 1614, is an exhaustive and very amusing collection of the ancient and mediaeval opinions and fancies on this subject. I have already cited it more than once, but the following is too characteristic of what our credulous fore- fathers accepted as evidence to be passed over: — " Triginta sex filios vivos uno partu peperit Margarita Comitis Virboslai uxor, Cracoviensi agro. An. 1270, 20 Jan. Cromero et Guagnimio testibus." — P. 74. CHAP. XVII.] AND DEVELOPMENT. 375 iteration of our conviction that it is his masterpiece in science. To those who open it prepared only by knowledge derived from modern writers it will necessarily appear at times jejune and not a little absurd ; but to those who are familiar with the writers of the sixteenth, seventeenth, and eighteenth centuries, it will appear in its true greatness ; and those who have familiarized themselves with the results and speculations of the most advanced embryologists will, I think, be surprised and delighted to find how often Aristotle seems at the highest level of speculation. ( 876 ) CHAPTER XVIH. CONCLUSION. On reviewing the general impression of Aristotle's aims and achievements which the foregoing pages have endeavoured to convey, we first note the contradiction they present to the popular conception of his claims as a great observer, and a great legislator, in science. The uncritical enthusiasm of eulogists has been challenged; the unreflecting iteration of hyperbolical praises has been confronted with analyses of his works ; and yet, in spite of the rigour of our scrutiny, there has been no stint of admiration where admiration seemed deserved. The inquiry has resulted in a verdict which con- siderably modifies, yet scarcely lessens, our idea of his greatness. We have seen that the title of a great observer cannot fairly be awarded to him. Far from meriting this rank, he is not entitled to any place, great or small, among men specially distinguished as observers, in the scientific sense of the term : since not only did he fail to enrich Science with the valuable and accurate details which serve as the solid supports of speculation, he failed also to appreciate the primary con- ditions of successful observation. He collected many facts, he never scrutinized them. So long as we consider him in his historical position, no serious blame can fairly be attributed to him for failing to appreciate the importance of Verification, and the means by CHAP. XVIII.] CONCLUSION. 377 which it may be sought ; for in his day these were appreciated by no one ; they could only gain adequate recognition during the slow evolution of scientific experience. If, however, it would be unjust to blame him for an imper- fection which was universal in his day, it would be eminently unphilosophical in an historian to overlook the imperfection. To overlook it would be to miss the great lesson of History, which teaches us that even the power of Observation is a late development in the mental evolution of our race, and not, as it may at first sight appear, the easy and spontaneous exercise of human faculties. There is as wide a distinction between the untutored observation practised by the early pioneers of science, and the cultivated caution of modern observers, as between the rude polity of savage tribes and the complex civilization of advanced nations. The ancient rarely attempted to analyze complex phenomena into their several elements, rarely sus- pected even that they were complex ; and such analysis as was attempted was always executed without the aid of instru- ments of precision, consequently was inevitably imperfect and approximative. Unaided by instruments, and unaware of their indispensable value, the ancient philosopher was thrown upon his sagacity in guessing ; and it is no wonder that he constantly duped himself and his hearers by mistaking mental distinctions and verbal analogies, for Nature's differences and resemblances. The modern, on the contrary, trained in the dis- cipline of severer methods, and taught by those very methods to distrust whatever has not been rigorously demonstrated, is for ever seeking greater accuracy in his analyses, and greater delicacy of precision in the instruments by which analyses are to be made. Instead of relying on a supine credulity, he is tormented by a vigilant scepticism. Far from trusting to the uncontrolled observation of facts such as sufficed in early times, he has learned to distrust the accuracy of his senses, and to question closely the accuracy of his instruments. He has even learned the necessity of establishing what is called the 378 CONCLUSION. [CHAP. XVIII. personal equation, by which the delicate variations of sensitive organisms may be reduced to an average. Thus although the beats of a pendulum may seem accurate standards for the observation of a phenomenon in time, they admit of an in- accuracy which it is important to correct, since it has been found that no two persons agree precisely as to the moment of observation — one being always a trifle in advance of the other. Bessel found himself in the habit of noting phenomena in advance of his assistant, Argelander, by as much as l s- 22 ; and Mr. Sheepshanks found himself 45-hundredths of a second behind M. Quetelet, and 35-hundredths before Mr. Henry. In astronomy such variations would lead to enormous inaccuracies ; consequently, as a preliminary to observation, a personal equation has always to be established between the observers. The Art of Observation is a late development. Science depends greatly on this Art for its progress ; and yet the Art itself is only to be evolved during the slow advances of Science : the two go hand in hand : they act and react. In the early stages of scientific growth even an intellect so great as Aristotle's could not place itself at the point of view which is now taken by the humblest investigators. If his successors have become more cautious it is because they have been trained in a severer discipline — a discipline which it is his immortal glory to have inspired, by that scientific impulse which, as we have seen, he impressed on philosophy. Another popular exaggeration has been treated in the fore- going pages : his claim to the anticipation of modern dis- coveries has been refuted. Where intellectual force alone was involved, there Aristotle appeared a giant. But no single mind can do the work of Humanity ; no one man can antici- pate the labours of ages. Newton, in Alexandria, could not have done the work of Keplee; nor, in Syracuse, would Galileo have surpassed Akohimedes. How idle to expect that Aristotle in the fourth century before Christ should have CHAP. XVIII.] CONCLUSION. 379 made discoveries which were only possible nineteen centuries after Christ; only then possible because until then science was without the requisite data, and without the requisite instruments by which the data could be ascertained. It is, therefore, unphilosophic exaggeration destructive of the whole significance of History to say that Aristotle " laid the bases " of any physical science. He laid no bases at all. He was not a legislator. Neither by his conceptions, nor by his methods, were any sciences finally rescued from Common Knowledge, and constituted, as Astronomy was constituted by Hipparchus, or Statics by Archimedes, or Dynamics by Galileo. The coincidences of some of his conceptions with those of modern philosophers have been exhibited in various parts of this volume, coincidences some- times due to a profound sagacity, oftener due to our tendency to read into ancient texts the thoughts of modern thinkers. Instead of regarding him as a legislator, we must confess that, great as his indirect influence has been, his direct influence on the physical sciences is inappreciable. Could we eliminate the indirect influence exercised by his mind over the minds of succeeding generations, we might begin the history of every science without once naming him. But, fortunately, we cannot estimate that influence. It has been immense, and his fame is justifiably colossal. None can pretend to appreciate the extent of that influence, mingled as it is with so many concurrent streams ; but no one with a knowledge of History, and a sense of historical significance, will deny that the influence has been potent. In many pas- sages of this volume criticism wears somewhat the appearance of polemics ; an attitude to be regretted, but not to be avoided. I entered upon my task full of enthusiasm for the greatness of Aristotle, though with the determination to express in all sincerity whatever convictions might grow out of careful study. The critical attitude, proper to an historian who refuses to become a partisan, may, in my case, have been made some- 380 CONCLUSION. [CHAP. XVIII. what rigid by the reckless eulogies of many writers whom I had to consult during my labours, and perhaps also by the inevitable swing of reaction in my own mind on discovering that I had been misled by excessive and misplaced praises ; but in concluding my work I should be guilty of an injustice on the other side, if I did not endeavour to express my sense of Aristotle's intellectual supremacy. After every deduction has been made, the instinctive and popular appreciation of his greatness will be ratified by a large philosophy. Among the great heroes of Humanity, his position must ever remain conspicuous. He claims pre- cedence over hundreds who, under more fortunate conditions, have enriched science with priceless details. He rises superior to most of those who' have illuminated science with great conceptions. And this superiority is claimed not only in virtue of his many achievements, but also in virtue of his native force. His comprehensive glance embraced the whole field of research ; and if some other philosophers, ancient and modern, have taken as wide a survey, none have like him first opened the pathways they surveyed. But he might have had even greater comprehensiveness, and yet not have justified the glory which for centuries has surrounded his name. He had a greatness above this versatility. He had that kind of intellectual Force not easily defined, and mainly to be estimated through its vast results — the Force which creates epochs in the evolution of human progress. This power, which founds Keligions and Philosophies,, by changing the whole order of men's conceptions, is not to be measured by any of the standards we apply to discoveries developed from previous discoveries. It is to be measured rather by its results, immediate and remote. The creation of a Method is incomparably greater than the most brilliant application of that Method. And it is not because Aristotle himself made great discoveries, but because he deeply and extensively influenced the minds of discoverers, that his name is illustrious. CHAP. XVIII.] CONCLUSION. 381 "We, who have grown up under the influence of the revolu- tion which he began, are in no condition adequately to appre- ciate his work. Just as we cannot thoroughly understand why he was so careless with respect to accuracy in observation, just as we cannot appreciate the obstacles which in his day opposed the employment of vigilant scepticism and constant verification, so also are we at a loss to estimate what was the supreme difficulty of initiating the Scientific Method. To us it may seem little that he should steadily have renounced theological interpretations of natural phenomena, and that he should have attached primary significance to Fact as the basis of speculation. It may seem as if no alternative had been open to him. Thus we may be insensible to the value of his conception of Method, and of his gigantic efforts to apply it in all directions ; and this insensibility will make us aware only of his deficiencies. Instructed by History, we learn that in the resolute with- drawal of all explanations from theological interpretations, in the predominance assigned to Fact, and in the insistance on graduated Induction, there were the fruitful germs of as wreat a revolution as any which has hitherto modified the development of mankind. The force of Aristotle's intellect, acting through the germinating power of his Method, gave him despotic power over succeeding generations, and sharpened in the hands of his antagonists the very weapons with which they assailed him. The despotism was in many respects disastrous, as all despotisms must be. His defects became more influential than other men's excellences. His guesses were more attended to than his sober precepts. And yet it was surely not altogether his fault that his Organon became an instrument of repression rather than of research, and that his practice was more readily followed than his precepts? However he may have been impelled to systematize on imperfect bases and to reason where he should have- observed, it is not too 382 CONCLUSION. [CHAP. XVIII. much to say that had he reappeared among later generations he would have been the first to repudiate the servility of his followers, the first to point out the inanity of Scholasticism. His mighty and eminently inquiring intellect would have been the first to welcome and to extend the new discoveries. He would have sided with Galileo and Bacon against the Aristotelians. ( 383 ) INDEX, Abelaed, his Sic et Non cited, p. 224 Absolute (the), idea of Hegel's disci- ples on, 80 Abstractions, tendency towards the im- personation of, 86; Whewell on the employment of, 88 Ackermann, on male and female or- ganisms, 208; on female sperm, 347 Acoustics, their origin due to the Greeks, 39 JEschylus, the Eumenides cited, 352 After-birth. See Placenta Agassiz, on Aristotle's classification, 277. Cited, 295 Albertus Magnus, cited, 190, 278 Alexander the Great, a pupil of Aris- totle, 13 ; his reverence for his teacher, ib.; becomes Regent, 14; his magnificent patronage of Aristotle, ib.; Pliny's account of, 15; effect of his death in Athens, 16 Alexandria, human dissection practised in under the Ptolemies, 163 Ammonius, his Life of Aristotle dis- credited by Buhle, 5 Anatomy, its origin due to the Greeks, 39; failure of the Greeks in, 56; Aristotle's anatomy valueless, 157; whence he derived his knowledge of, 157, 158; Emil Braun's reference to the anatomical figures in the Vatican, 161; whence the Asclepiads derived their knowledge of, ib,; Boyle on the usefulness of, 162; absurdities of the Galenists, 163; A.'s confession as to the internal anatomy of man, 164; proofs of A.'s never having dissected the human body, 164, 165, 167; comparative anatomy an arrested embryology, 189; want of classifica- tion owing to the backward state of anatomy, 277; first dawn of philo- sophic anatomy, 279; account of the anatomy of the invertebrata, 285 Anatomists (ancient), their error re- specting the Uterus, 332 Anaxagoras, his influence on Plato, 102 ; his opinion that bile is the cause of acute diseases, 318; his reason for the intellectual superiority of man, 321; on the origin of the sexes, 342, 367 Ancients, failure of their efforts in science, 47, 49, 60, 63; Playfair's ver- dict on their failure, 49, 51 ; their large collection of scientific facts, 52; their mental activity, 53; Dr. Whewell's conclusions as to their failure, ib.; their inferiority to the moderns, 57 ; their opinion as to the velocity of a falling body, ib. ; their impatience in the investigation of science, 58; quotation from Bacon, ib.; source of their errors, 60; their chief mistake, 70; employed a Method on which all problems were insoluble, 71; their ignorance of anatomy, 161 Andry, his figures of the spermatazoon, 352 Animal Movements, Aristotle's expla- nation of, 177, 178. See Motion Animals, identified with plants, 184 ; their resemblance in the embryonic stage, 189 ; their development the third step in natural gradation, 193; hermaphroditism of, 207; conclusion that all animals are oviparous, 213 ; their metamorphoses instanced in the salamander, ib.; alleged existence of the Nerve tissue in inferior animals, 243; Aristotle's division of, 273, 274, 275; Delle Chiaje on A.'s classifica- tion, 275 ; sanguineous and exsan- guineous, 276; A.'s want of system- atic grouping, 277; design of A.'s 884 INDEX. classification, ib. ; Agassiz cited, ib. ; Sunderall's work on A.'s knowledge of animals, 279 ; analysis of A.'s Hist. Animal., ib.; A.'s "partes simi- lares," 279, 280, 298 ; analogy of parts in animals, 280 ; A.'s standard of animal structure, 281; account of the intestines of animals, 281, 282, 283; of the blood, 283, 284 ; mention of the appearance of milk in the male, 285; on the voice of animals, 287; their habits and instincts, 290; object of the De Partibus, 292; A. on then- composition, 297; on animal tempe- rature, 298, 299 ; cause of animal terror, 302; on watery-blooded ani- mals, ib. ; earthy-blooded animals, 303 ; Aristotle on animal fat, ib. ; the direction of heat, 306; use of the flesh, 307 ; Man not the only animal with the erect attitude, 309 ; but he is the only one that is ticklish, 316 ; the quadrumanous animals of Tyson and Buffon, 319; Man a quadrumanous animal, 320; why he is the most intelligent, ib.; why the lioness has only two teats, 321; Eunes de Men- doga's improvement on this last theory of A.'s, ib. ; the generation of ovi- parous animals, 350 " Animists," the Montpellier school of, 223 Anna Manzolina. See Manzolina Antigone (the), chiefly relates to the sacredness of the dead, 160 Aphis, its parthenogenesis, 202, 203 Aquapendente. See Fabricius. Archimedes, an example of true scien- tific inquiry, 59 ; the founder of Statics, 147, 379 Aristotle, life of, p. 1 ; his intellect and attainments, ib.; insignificant result of his labours, ib. ; revolt against his authority, 2, 21 ; attacked by the scientific reformers, 2; inferiority of his adversaries, 3; his biographies collected by Buhle, 4, 5 ; their con- tradictions, ib.; scant and untrust- worthy materials for a life of, 4 ; his birth, 4, 6 ; his father, 7; called the "reader" by Plato, 8; attracted to Athens, ib. ; his occupations there, ib. ; Bacon's sarcasm, 9 ; he wins for himself a position at Athens, 10; his foppery in costume, 11; his alleged ingratitude to Plato, ib. ; taught by Plato for seventeen years, ib.; his person and character, 11, 12; instance of his humour, 12; opens a school of philosophy, 1 2, 15 ; his work De Divi- natione cited, 12; alleged object of his visit to Hermias, ib. ; marries Pythias, adopted daughter of Her- mias, ib. ; story of his practising me- dicine at Athens, ib. ; goes to Mace- don, 13; fiction of his accompanying Alexander to Asia, 14; his return to Athens, 15; opens the Lyceum as a school, ib.; regarded with suspicion in Athens, 16; accused of irreligion, 17; quits Athens, ib. ; authenticity of his writings, ib.; their encyclopaedic character, 17, 18; his modem eulo- gists, 1 8 , 23 ; contrasted with Plato, 1 9 ; without rank as an artist and writer, 20; his commentators, ib. ; his errors pointed out by Gassendi, 21 ; his works declared heretical by Parlia- ment of Paris, ib.; his legitimate position assigned by Eiilleborn, Buhle, and Tennemann, 22; considered the profoundest of thinkers, ib.; various editions of his works, ib. ; his true place in science, 23 ; his remarks on scepticism in sci- ence, 40; he illustrates the excel- lence and defects of the Greeks, 41 ; his explanation of the mysteries of nature, ib.; compared with the writer of Ecclesiastes, 42; his con- fidence in science, ib.; his study of nature for the sake of knowledge, ib. ; alleged to have anticipated modern discoveries, 46 ; his failure in Biology, how far referable to the neglect of Ideas, 54; Dr. Whewell on the cause of his failure in Mechanical Science, ib. ; his carelessness in scientific in- vestigation, 59; his Physics compared with Newton's Principia, 67, 68; his formulas want the guarantee of Obser- vation, 68; on the demonstration of things beyond the senses, 69 ; A. recognized the Ideal Test, ib. ; his claim to the first outline of classifica- tion, 84; his deference to other men's opinions, 89; he defined words in order to expound facts, ib.; his de- fective conception of Method, 108; the father of Inductive Philosophy, ib. ; his contrast to Plato, ib. ; cause of his failure in scientific research, ib. ; his reliance on sensuous per- ception, 109 ; his method compared with Plato's, ib. ; on Experience and Induction, ib.; on the impossibility of thought without sensation, ib. ; his Empiricism urged as a reproach, ib.; on the parthenogenesis of bees, 110; on hybridity, ib.; on Experience as the true guide in science, 110, 111; his anticipation of modern Psycho- INDEX. 885 logy, 111 ; on the necessity of Obser- vation, 110, 111, 112; A. points out the danger of the Platonic Method, 1 1 1 j his perception of the value of experiment, 112, 113; anticipates the cardinal principles of Bacon's philo- sophy, 113; his neglect of his own method, ib.; places the Ideal above the Real Test, 117; his efforts wasted in pursuit of causes, ib.; his four causes unverifiable, 119 ; practically a metaphysician, ib. ; his chief claim to our veneration, 120; his followers fascinated by his defects, ib.; Roger Bacon's desire to burn A.'s works, 121 ; his Physics, Meteorology and Mechanics, 122 ; his obstruction of Astronomical Science noticed by Herschel, 125; ignorant of the laws and nature of Motion, 126 ; com- pared with Newton, 127; his extant writings on physics, ib. ; his defi- nition of Nature, 129; his celebrated definition of Motion, 131; his theory of projectiles, 132, 133 ; fallacy respecting continuous motion, 133; his analysis of Motion, 134, 135; his work on the Heavens, 136; on the relations of space and gravitation, 136, 137; his idea of the form of the Heavens, 138; on the substance of the Stars, 138, 139 ; his theory of Heat and Light, 139; definition of an Element, 140; his protests against the a priori Method, ib. ; ether as an Element, 141 ; on Gravity and Eevity, ib. ; on Ether as the substance of the Heavens, ib. ; his work on Meteo- rology, 143; his explanation of the Milky Way, 145; on the chemistry of the Elements, 146; his Problems, 147; made no advance in Mathematical Science, 149; on Pressure and Per- cussion, 150; his disregard of the law of Inertia, 152; deficient in the trans- cendental postulates of Science, ib ; his efforts not in vain, 153; but the neglect of his physical speculations justified, ib.; his Anatomy, 154; Cuvier's exaggerated eulogy of Aris- totle, ib.; his servile eulogists, 154, 155; De Blainville's admiration for, ib.; amazing extent of his biological survey, 156; Lauth's eulogy ; of his anatomical labours, ib. ; A.'s ana- tomy valueless, 157; whence he de- rived his knowledge of Anatomy, ib.; assigns the Heart as the origin of the Blood-vessels, 158; his ignorance of the Muscles, ib.; his ignorance of the Nervous-system, ib.; and of the three most important parts of the organism, ib.; A. did not dissect the human body, 159 ; on the parts of the human body, 163, 164; his description of the Lungs, ib.; of the Uterus, ib.; his error regarding the position of the Heart, 165; in reference to the spleen, ib.; Blazius' anxiety to defend A., 166; Buonfede on A.'s ignorance of the Human Brain, ib. ; Galen on A.'s ignorance of Human Anatomy, ib.; A.'s erroneous description of the Brain, ib. ; alleged to have first dis- covered the nerves, 167; Scaliger's palliation of Aristotle, ih.; credited with discovery of Cerebral nerves, 168 ; his alleged discovery of the nerves discussed, 168, 169 ; knew nothing of the nervous system, 170; his Physiology, 171 ; he was igno- rant of the phenomena of diges- tion, 172, 173; his ideas on respira- tion, 174, 175, 176; on the respiration of fish, 175, 176; his explanations of animal movements baseless, 177, 178; places the seat of sensation in the Heart, 179; on the senses of Touch and Taste, ib. ; fallacy of his having laid the ' eternal bases ' of Biology, 180, 181; his alleged anticipation of mo- dern discoveries, 183, 187; recognizes the identity of Plant and Animal, 184; credited with the discovery of the Vertebral Theory, 186; his dis- covery that plants are nourished at expense of their seed, 187; his idea of an ascending complexity in "Vital phenomena, 189; on Natural grada- tion, 190; his Organic and Inorganic kingdoms, ib. ; on the Heart as the centre of sensation and thought, 191 ; on the different developments of plants and animals, 192; classes the Testaceous animals as plants, ib. ; his reason for classing Sponges as animals, 193 ; his views of Plants and Animals stated by Hermolaus Bar- baras, 194; makes Man the head of Animal creation, 195 ; anticipates Einna3us, ib.; the Hectocotylus in- stanced, 199, 200 ; ignorant of the parthenogenesis of bees, 206 ; his remark on the Perch, 209; Aristotle proved by Dufosse to be right where moderns are wrong, 210 ; his reli- ance on hearsay, 211 ; aware of the existence of Placental fishes, 212; his assertion respecting the Cuttlefish verified by Kolliker, 218; his state- ment regarding the nest-building fish verified by Olivi, ib. ; on the vision of 25 336 INDEX. the Mole, 218; made no discovery in Science, 220; his treatise De Anima, 221; ^vyfi imtranslateable, 221, 222; on Life and Mind, 223 ; his doc- trine on the Soul declared orthodox, 224; on Sensation as the characteristic of the Soul, ib. ; on the nature of the Vital Principle, 225, 226 ; his concep- tion of the mystery of Life, 231 ; his views on the immortality of the Soul, 233 ; on sensibility, sight, hearing, &c, 235, 238 ; on Imagination, 240; his chapter on Intellect, ib. ; on the Eeflective faculty, 241; hypo- thesis of the development of know- ledge, ib.; his views of Locomotion, 242, 243 ; denies that the animal body is homogeneous, 244; on the sense of Touch, ib. ; his analysis of the Senses, 246 to 255; his definition of Light, 248; of Taste and Smell, 249; his explanation of Colour, ib. ; on the divisibility of Sensation, 253, 254 ; his explanation of Memory, 256 ; his treatises on Memory, Sleep, Dreams and Longevity, ib. ; his ab- surd theories on sleep, 258, 260, 261, 262, 263, 264; his treatise on Dreams, 264; his History of Animals, 269; Cuvier's description of the Hist. Animal., 270; erroneous conclusions, 271, 272; Cuvier on A.'s classifica- tion of animals, 273, 274; Aristotle distinguishes Animals into sangui- neous and exsanguineous, 275 ; on bloodless animals, 276; his sketch of those which have blood, ib. ; disputes as to his system of classification, 277; doubts as to whether he had a system, ib. ; no classification in the Hist. Animal., 278; Sunderall's work on A.'s classification of Animals, 279; analysis of Hist. Animal., ib.; his division of the organism into similar and dissimilar parts, 279,280; on the parts of animal bodies and their analogy, 280 ; A.'s knowledge of Anatomy less accurate than Galen's, 281; instances of A.'s carelessness and rash generalization, 282; on the blood of animals, 283; his account of the anatomy of the Invertebrata, 285 ; his mention of the appearance of milk in Males, ib. ; on the Crustacea, 286; on sight and hearing in the Testacea, 287 ; his assertion in refer- ence to Hydrophobia, 289; on gout in Horses, ib.; his defence of the study of Biology, 296; on the com- position of animals, 297; on animal fat, 303; on the composition of the brain, 304; on the composition of animal Marrow, ib.; cause of his belief in the insensibility of the Brain, 305 ; on the organs of Men and Plants, 308 ; his account of the Heart and Liver, 311, 312 — examples of his rash -theorizing, 311, 312, 313; his remarks on single and double organs, 3 1 5 ; his description of the Diaphragm, 316 ; his reason for the position of the Elephant's teats, 322; why man has flesh oh his legs, ib. ; asserts that man is tailless, ib. ; work on generation and development, 325 ; compared with Harvey's work on Generation, 326; on sexual differences, 331; denies the existence of sperm in females, 333, 345 ; on the testes,333,334 ; his opinion that woman is but undeveloped man, 347; his doctrine of Epigenesis, 351, 355, 368, 369 ; on development of the Embryo, 357, 358, 359 ; on the power of reproduction in females, 360; his opinion that eels are generated spon- taneously, 361; on the phenomena of development, 362 ; on the fertility of Hybrids, 363 ; supposed prefigura- tion of the Cell Theory, 365 ; origin of the sexes, 367, 368, 369; on here- ditary transmission of qualities, 370, 371 ; his omission of " mother's marks," 374; his true rank in Science, 376; his claim to have anticipated modern discoveries, 378, 379 ; his immense influence, 379, 380, 381 ; one of the great heroes of Humanity, 380; he would have been an anti- Aristotelian, 382 Arnold, Dr., his eulogy of Aristotle's Politics, 18 Artedi, cited, 277 Art, Greek, defects of, 41 Asclepiads (the), imperfectly acquainted with Anatomy, 7;. whence their ana- tomical knowledge derived, 161 Association of Ideas, A.'s glimpse of the law of, 257 Assyrians, exaggerated antiquity of their records, 37 Astronomers (ancient), their belief in the uniformity of celestial revolutions, 33; Biot's remark thereon, 34 Astronomy (Egyptian), Martianus Ca- pella on the antiquity of 37; slight acquaintance of the Chaldseans with, 66; Plato's depreciation of, 104; Aristotle's ideas of, 139 Athens, Aristotle attracted to, 8; his occupations at, ib; declining glories of, 9, 10 Atoms, hypothesis of, beyond proof, 92 INDEX. 387 Attraction, stigmatized by the Carte- sians as an occult quality, 84; the law of denuded of Metaphysics, ib. ; again restored to science, ib. ; Newton on, 93 ; its cause unknowable, 94 ; science concerned only with the law of Attrac- tion, ib. Auguries, the Druids' method of, 32 Avefrhoes, on the infallibility of the Stagirite, 155 Avicenna, cited, 169; quoted by Roger Bacon on the seat of the Soul, 179 Bacon, Lord, his sarcasm respecting Aristotle's quotations, 9 ; on the want of scientific instruments among the ancients, 58; on the psychological cause of error in science, 62 ; on the inequality of mind as a mirror of things submitted to it, 103; cause of his own failure in scientific research, 108, 113; his Novum Organon, cited, 109; not opposed to Aristotle, but to A.'s followers, 113; the cardinal prin- ciples of his philosophy anticipated by Aristotle, ib. ; his Sylvia Syl- varum cited, 300; on the action of fire, ib. Cited, 41, 367 Bacon,Roger, cited, 21, 115, 169, 172; on Verification, 82 ; Jebb's preface to the Opus Majus cited, 121 ; his desire to burn Aristotle's works, ib.; on the optic nerve, 170; on the seat of the Soul, 179; his alleged discovery of the telescope, 186; on the Intellect, 358 Baer. See Von Baer Bailly, his letters on the origin of the sciences, cited 46 Barbaras, Hermolaus. See Hermolaus Barchusen, asserts that Aristotle dis- sected the Human Body, 159, 165; his opinion adopted by Haller and Harles, 159. Cited, 160, 346 Baronio, his successful grafting of parts of animals, 191 Barthelemy St. Hilaire. See St. Hilaire Barthez, on Verification, 33 Basso, his attack upon Aristotle', 2; an admirer of Patrizio, 9. Cited, 228 Bauhin, on the origin of the sexes, 367. Cited, 370, 373, 374 Beclard, his definition of Life, 230. Cited 231 Bees, Aristotle on the Parthenogenesis of, 110, 206. See Parthenogenesis Benedictines of St. Maur, their Literary History of France cited, 32; on the soothsaying of the Druids, ib. Cited, 225 Bernard, Claude, cited, 312 Bernouilli, J., his metaphysical trifling, Biphat, on the "law of economy," 183; his famous definition of Life, 230; made Aristotle's division of the orga- nism the foundation of modern his- tology, 279; on the distinction between animal and vegetable organs, 314, 315. Cited 190, 231 Biese, his analysis of Aristotle's scien- tific logic, 116. Cited, 140, 192 Bile, Aristotle's account of, 317, 318 Biology, Aristotle's failure in, how far referable to neglect of Ideas, 54; its two grand divisions, 156; amazing extent of A.'s survey, ib. ; fallacy of Aristotle's having laid the eternal basis of, 180, 181; general principles of, 182; instance of A.'s alleged anti- cipation of modern speculations, 183 ; Aristotle's defence of the study of, 296; its obscurest problems treated in the De Generatione, 325 Biot, his work on Indian and Chinese Astronomy quoted, 34, 38 Bischoff, Professor, cited, 328, 348 Blakesley, his suggestion that Aristotle was a pupil of Xenocrates, 5. Cited, 6 Blazius, on the quantity of blood going to the brain, 166 Blondin, his Vitalisme Animique cited, 224 Blood (the), Aristotle's account of, 283, 284; the fibrine of, discovered by Borelli, ib. ; the distinctions of, 298; A. on the influence of different kinds of, 302 Bloodvessels, Aristotle's account of, 314 Blumenbach, cited, 338, 351 Bodies, their passive and static con- dition, 123; Aristotle's ideas on their weight and lightness, 141, 142, 143 Bone, reason for the growth of, 307 Bonnet, his scheme of the origin of species, 187; proves the partheno- genesis of the aphis, 203. Cited, 353 371 Books, illustrated, in the time of Aris- totle, 283 Borelli, his discovery in reference to the fibrine of blood, 284 ' Bossuet, an anatomist, 162 Bostock, his System of Physiology cited, 352 Bouiller, cited, 224 Boyle, on the usefulness of anatomy, 1 62 Brain, quantity of blood going to, 166; Blazius cited, ib. ; Buonfede on Aris- totle's ignorance of, ib. ; A.'s erroneous description of, ib. ; the seat of sensa- tion 179; functions ascribed to it by 25—2 888 INDEX. Aristotle, 180; A.'b notion of the brain criticised by Galen, ib. ; Davy's attempts to estimate its temperature, ib. ; Cuvier's error on the brain of Molluscs, 219, 220; part assigned to it in production of sleep, 263 ; Aris- totle's erroneous conclusion on the size and moisture of man's brain, 272, 306 ; its origin and composition, 304; A.'s belief that it is devoid of sensation, 305, and moderates the heat of the blood, 306 Brain-ducts. -See Nerves Brandis, cited, 6, 279 Brann, Emil, his reference to the ana- tomical figures in the Vatican, 161 Bronn, cited, 193, 295 Brown Sequard cited, 191, 208, 216, 261, 275, 345 Browne, Sir Thos., on the vision of the Mole, 219 Bruno, Giordano, cited, 2; his contempt for Patrizio, 9 Buffon, on the living universe as one family, 188. Cited, 270, 277, 319 Buhle, collects the ancient biographies of Aristotle, 4; discredits that by Ammonius, 5; his error regarding Punes y Mendoca, 303. Cited, 6, 21, 22 Bunsen, in reference to'spectrum analy- sis, cited, 70 . , , Buonfede cites Burnet's list of Aristotle s puerilities, 155; on A.'s ignorance of the brain, 166 Burdach, on milk in males, 285; on the spermatozoon, 352. Cited, 327, 348, 356,371 „„ , * Bnrmeister, cited, 184; his Manual of Entomology cited, 270, 329 Bumet, his list of Aristotle's puerilities cited by Buonfede, 155 Bussemaker, edits Aristotle's works, 22; his rendering of an obscure passage in Aristotle, 306. Cited, 263, 343 Buzareingues, Girou de, cited, 371 Cjesalpinus, his erroneous defence of Aristotle, 168; on the brain as the seat of sensation, 179; on generation, 205,347. Cited, 305 Camus, his French translation of the Hist. Animal, 269 Cardan, on the respiration of fish, 176; on the generation of male offspring, 367 Cartesians, stigmatize Attraction as an occult quality, 84 Cartilage, reason why it never regene- rates, 307 Carus, Victor, cited, 270, 295 Casaubon, his edition of Aristotle's works, 21 Castelli, declares Plato and Aristotle perfect anatomists, 159 Catamenia, modern ideas on, 345 ; Aris- totle on, ib. Caterpillar, its 4,041 muscles, 158 1 Causation, law of, transcends experience, 66; how demonstrable, 84; in itself L_ unknowable, 91, 92, 93 Cause, desire to banish it from Induc- tive Philosophy, 90; its meaning in science, ib. ; life regarded by Aristotle as a final cause, 234 Causes, no following of effects from, 91 ; causes and effects are simultaneous, ib. ; Aristotle's efforts wasted in pursuit of, 117; the four kinds of causes, 117, 118; A.'s discussion on final causes, 129, 130 Cavolini, cited, 210 Cell Theory, Aristotle's alleged pre- figuration of, 365 Cephalopoda, Von Siebold on Aristotle's acquaintance with, 199 Chabanon, his Mimoires de PAcadernie des Inscriptions cited, 147 Chaldseans, exaggerated antiquity of their astronomical observations, 37; their slight knowledge of astronomy, 66 Charles' Life of Roger Bacon cited, 121 Charleton, cited, 195, 210, 303 Chemistry of the Elements, Aristotle on, 146 Children, their resemblance to their parents, 372, 373 Circulation of the Blood, important results of the discovery, 176 Classification, Aristotle's claim to first outline of, 273; one of the latest results of scientific research, ib. ; Cuvier on Aristotle's classification, 273, 274 ; Meyer on the various schemes of, 277; general ignorance of A.'s attempts at, ib.; its mode of elimination and aim, ib. ; Whewell on the construction of a classification, 278; Agassiz on Aristotle's grouping, ib.; Aristotle on, 294; but offers no classification of his own, 295; his dim perception of the natural me- thod, 296 Claude Bernard, cited, 312 Claudian Mammertus, on the immate- rialism of the Soul, 225 Cocchi, Antonio, denies that Aristotle dissected the Human Body, 159 Collier, Dr. Charles, his translation of the be Animd, 221 Colour, Prantl cited, 249 ; Goethe INDEX. 389 cited, 249; Aristotle's explanation of, ib. Comparative Anatomy, the want of classification owing to the backward state of, 277 Comte, Auguste, on metaphysical con- ception of phenomena, 30; on mathe- matical precision, 39; on our limited physical knowledge of the planets, 70 ; his commentary on Laplace's theory of Motion, 98; led too far by his antagonism to Metaphysics, 99; on the necessity of Method and Edu- cation, 100; on the extension of gravitation beyond, the solar system, 125; his proposition to fill up missing links in nature, 189. Cited, 34 Congreve, his edition of Aristotle's Politics cited, 16 Conringius, denies that Aristotle dis- sected Man, 159, 160 Contraries, principle of, 128 Copernicus, on hypotheses, 92 Corniani, his work on Italian Literature cited, 119 Cosmology, Plato's, 105 Costa, guesses at the nature of the Hectocotylus, 198 Coste, on Aristotle's story of the woman of Elis, 340 Cresswell, his translation of the Hist. Animal., 269. Cited, 280 Crustacea. See Invertebrata Currey, his Meport on Vegetable Parthe- nogenesis cited, 202 Cuttlefish, Aristotle's assertion regard- ing, 218; cause of its change of colour, 302 Cuvier, on the existence of the " nervous fluid," 98; his eulogy of Aristotle, 154 ; describes the Hectocotylus, 198; his error regarding the brain of Molluscs, 219 ; his statement about Aristotle's predecessors, 269 ; his enthusiasm for Aristotle's Hist. Animal, 269, 270, 271,272; on A.'s classification, 273, 274; his admission of the " vers a sang rouge," 275; on A.'s knowledge of anatomy, 281. Cited, 23, 154, 210, 218, 290, 319, 353 D'Alembeet, on the truth in ancient ideas, 184 ■Daremberg, on Galen's ignorance of the anatomy of the human body, 163 Dareste, cited, 215 Darwin, cited, 188 Davies and Vaughan's translation of Plato's Eepublic cited, 103 Davy, Dr. J., his Physiological and Anatomical, Researches cited, 180, 216; his fallacious experiments on the Liver, 313 D'Azyr, Vicq. See Vicq D'Azyr Dead, feeling of the Greeks respecting the, 160 i- s De Anima (the), Trendelenberg's edition cited, 118; its great eminence, 221- editions of, ib. ; translations, ib!; Max Miiller on the meaning and equivalents of anima, 222; analysis of, 225; enlarges more on physical than psychological questions, 244; its want of logical arrangement, ib.; pro- fundity of many of its views, 245; its value as a scientific work, 290, 291 Cited, 265 De Animal. Motione (the), cited, 112 De Blainville, his eulogy of Aristotle, 154; his definition of Life adopted by Comte and Charles Robin, 230 Cited, 23, 154, 270, 295, 353 De Cmlo (the), cited, 110; analysis of, 136; Prantl's edition of, ib. Deduction, one of the modes of scientific investigation, 57 De Generatione (the), cited, 110, 112, 310; its vast scope, 325 ; Aubert and Wimmer's edition of, ib. ; analysis of, 330 to 376; pronounced the master- piece of ancient science, 375 De Graaf, commenced the discovery of the Mammalian ovum, 213; on the Uterus, 332; on Aristotle's opinion that woman is undeveloped man, 347. Cited, 332, 333, 346, 347, 353, 367 De Juventute, Aristotle's, cited, 239 Delambre, Hist, of Astronomy cited, 38 Delle Chiaje, cited, 198, 273, 323; on Aristotle's division of animals, 275; on the change of colour in the cuttle- fish, 302 Democritus, on Vision, 247 ; on the ori- gin of the sexes, 367. Cited, 145, 359 De Partibus (the), cited, 110, 163, 274, 282 ; a continuation of the Hist. Animal., 279; analysis of, 292; its object, ib.; its distinction of partes similares, 298; represents Aristotle's physiology, 322; its great interest in the history of science, 323 Descartes, his reliance on the Possible, 69 ; recognizes the Ideal Test, ib. ; on the rule of Truth, 79; his errors, 81, 83; on the habitat of the Soul, S3; his neglect of the Real Test, ib. ; his Principia cited, 92, 133; his hypo- thesis that brutes are mere machines, 196; on the functions of the Soul, 224 De Sensu (the), analysis of, 246. See Senses 390 INDEX. De Somno, Aristotle's, cited, 239 Development, Aristotle on the phe- nomena of, 362. See Generation, Parthenogenesis, Organism, Embry- ology- Diaphragm, Aristotle's description of, 316; its part in consciousness, ib. Dichogamism. See Generation, Parthe- nogenesis, Hermaphroditism Dichotomy, Aristotle's criticism of, 294 Diego de Eunes y Mendoca. See Eunes y Mendoca Differentiation of plants and animals, stated, 194 Digenesis, forms of, 328. See Generation Digestion, Aristotle ignorant of the phenomena of, 172, 173; A. on the influence of heat in, 301 Diodorus, on the antiquity of Chaldsean astronomical observations, 37 Diogenes Laertius, ' the biographer of Aristotle, 4, 17 Diogenes, on the respiration of Eish, 176. Dionysius of Halicamassus,a biographer of Aristotle, 5 Dissection, evidences against Aristotle having dissected the human body, 159; Greek popular feeling against, 160; struggles of Science for, ib.; the disgust and fascination for, 161, 162; illustrious anatomists, ib.; Boyle on the usefulness of, 162; practised in Alexandria under the Ptolemies, 163; absurdities of the Galemsts,i6.; proofs of A.'s never having dissected the human body, 164, 165, 166, 167 Dominic de Marchettis, on the ovaries of females, 333 D'Orbigny, cited, 302 Dreams, analysis of Aristotle's treatise on, 264, 265, 266; the images, or after-motions, of sensation, 266 Drelincourt, cited, 351 Druids, their method of predicting events, 32 Dufossfi, proves Aristotle to be right where Moderns are wrong, 210. Cited, 287 Duges,his definition of Life, 230. Cited, 231 Duhamel, on the growth of bone, 191 ; his eloge by Vicq d'Azyr, quoted, ib. Dujardinj his Natural History of Infu- soria cited, 193; on the Hectocotylus, 198 Dutens, his Origin of Discoveries as- signed to the Moderns cited, 46 Du Val, his edition of Aristotle's works, 21 Duvemoy, cited, 210 Dynamics, their origin to be sought "among the Greeks, 38; founded by Galileo, 147 Dzierzon, his researches on the par- thenogenesis of bees, 205 Ecclksiasticus, comparison of, with Aristotle, 42 Eels, Aristotle's opinion that they are generated spontaneously, 361 Egyptians, their scientific claims dis- credited, 37 ; their observations and annals, ib. ; without the rudiments of science, 38; their idea of female fe- cundity, 370 Ehrenberg, on the structure of the nerves, 168 Elements (the Eour), Plato on the co- hesion of, 105; Aristotle's definition of an Element, 140; the fifth element, ib. ; A. on the chemistry of, 146 Elephant assigned only two diseases by Aristotle and Pliny, 289 Elis, story of the woman of, 340 Ellis and Spedding, their edition of Bacon's works cited, 115 Embryo, the " missing links " to be sought in the life of, 188 ; its assimilat- ing power, 215; increases in utero, ib. Embryology, how far equivalent to com- parative anatomy, 189; identity of the spermcell and genncell, .203 ; identity of the male and female organisms, 208 ; summary of the modern science of, 327; origination, ib. ; development, 328 ; incubation, 329 ; its modern forms known to Aristotle, 330; A. on the origin of the sperm, 339, 340 ; on the growth of the embryo, 342 ; his diagnosis of the sperm, 342, 343, 344 ; the form and principle of the embryo derived from the male, 347; hypotheses con- cerning, 351; A. on the development of the embryo, 357, 358 359. See Generation, Organism Emil Braun. See Braun Empedocles, held " the eye to be of fire," 247 ; on the origin of male and female, 367 Empiricism, Hegel on, 80 ; urged as the reproach of Aristotle, 109 Epicharmus, cited, 343 Epicurus, cited, 137 Epigenesis, theory of, 351; its triumph, 354; idea of grasped by Aristotle, 369. See Generation Epilepsy, compared by Aristotle to sleep, 261; disease of a nervous centre, ib. INDEX. 391 Equilibrium, the action of equal oppos- ing forces, 126 Erasmus, his opinion of Hermolaus Barbaras, 118 Eratosthenes, an instance of the neglect of Verification among the Greeks, 59 Ether a fifth element, 140 Ethics (A.'s), quotation from, 11 Eulogists, Aristotle's, 18, 23, 154, 155 Eumenides of ^Eschylus cited, 352 Everardus, on female sperm, 333. Cited, 346 \ Evolution. See Generation Experiment, what, it is, 49; distin- guished from Observation, 50 ; in- stances of Aristotle's perception of, 112,113. See Empiricism Eabricius ab Aqtjapendente, cited, 169, 170, 176, 177, 332 Eact (Scientific), definition of, 71; its implied antithesis to Idea or Theory, 71, 74, 75 ; the real distinction, 75, 76, 77, 78; its indissoluble connection with Idea, 72 ; its verification, ib. ; real meaning to be assigned to, 73 ; tendency to use it as a final truth, 74 Ealloppia cited, 279, 332; on the exists ence of sperm in females, 333 Earre, Dr. A., his article on the Uterus and its Appendages cited, 216, 338 Ectichism, cause of, 86 Einal cause, tendency to invoke, a cha- racteristic of Metaphysics, 86 Eischer, Karl, cited, 46 Eish, Cardan on the respiration of, 176; why they die out of water, ib. ; the perch said to be self-reproductive, 209, 210; Aristotle's ruminating fish, 282; Milne Edwards and Professor Owen on the ruminating fish, 283 Elesh, Aristotle on the properties of, 307 ; subordination of its parts, ib. ; cartilage, ib. Elourens, his explanation of the respira- tion of fish disproved, 176 Eorce, advantage of the true conception of, 95; its existence as an entity, 96; methods of its investigation, ib.; the conception of its indestructibility modern, 123 ; the conditions under which it is apprehended, ib. ; correla- tion of forces, ib. Eour Elements, Plato on the cohesion of, 105 ; Aristotle's definition of an element, 140 ; the fifth element, ib. ; A. on the chemistry of the elements, 146 Erantzius, cited on Aristotle's Hist. Animal, 279 ; his edition of the Be Partibus, 292 Praunhofer, cited, 70 Pries, his work on Anthropology cited, Funes y Mendoca, cited, 269 ; on fibrous-blooded animals, 303 ; on the ossification of the heart, 313 ; follows Aristotle's opinion that the lioness has but two teats, 321 Eurlanus cited, 277 Galen, affirms that the Asclepiads were taught dissection, 7 ; his anatomical knowledge said to rest upon careful dissection, 158; he did not dissect the human body, 163 ; Daremberg, his editor and translator cited, ib.; on A.'s ignorance of human anatomy, 166; his conception of the Heart, ib.; his confusion regarding the nervous system, 167, 168; on the respiration of fish, 176; his De Usu Partium cited, 177; criticizes Aristotle's theory of the brain* 180 ; alleged to have discovered the incandescent gases, 185, 186 ; maintained the mortality of the Soul, 233, 234; on the three species of souls, 233; his knowledge of anatomy more accurate than Aristotle's, 281 ; on the' sutures of the skull, 306 ; mentions fish having the os sublime of Ovid, 308; on the existence of bone in the heart, 313. Cited, 176, 321, 322, 334 Galenists, their absurdities, 163 Galileo, ridiculed by the Aristotelians, 57; his experiments on the velocity of falling bodies, ib. ; his a priori idea as to the velocity of a falling body, 68 ; hesitates to identify celes- tial and terrestrial mechanics, 125; his refutation of Aristotle's theory of projectiles, 132; the founder of Dy- namics, 147; finds the principle of " virtual velocities" in Aristotle, 148 ; his Dialoyhi cited, 151 ; his story about the origin of the nerves, 168. Cited, 2, 143 Gassendi, an adversary of Aristotle, 3 ; on the errors of A., 21 Gautier, his figures of the spermatozoa, 352 Gaza, his imperfect version of the De Generatione, 325 Gegenbauer, cited, 194 Gellius, cited, 8 Generation, normal and abnormal, 207 ; male and female organisms, 207, 208 ; 392 INDEX. hermaphroditism, 208 ; conditions of development of the impregnated ovum, 214, 215; loss of weight of the egg during development, 215, 216; A. on various modes of generation, 288, 289; summary of modem know- ledge of, 327; origination, ib.; deve- lopment, 328 ; incubation, 329 ; Aris- totle on the origin of the sperm, 339, 340; and on the growth of the embryo, 342 ; various hypotheses concerning generation, 351 ; Hindoo theory pfj 352 ; discovery of the mammalian ovum, 353 ; theory of syngenesis, ib. ; of evolution, ib. ; on the physical nature of sperm, 356 ; the aura seminalis, ib. ; A. on the development of the embryo, 357, 358, 359; on the generation of fish, insects, and bees, 364 ; impro- ' bability of spontaneous generation, 364, 365 ; origin of male and female, 367 ; influence of each of the parents, 372. See Embryology, Organism Genesis, Plato's idea of, as expressed in the Timcsus, 104 Geoffroy St. Hilaire. See St. Hilaire, Geoffroy Germcell, production of, 337 Gesner, cited, 278 Giordano Bruno. See Bruno Girou de Buzareingues, cited, 371 Gland, pineal, the seat of the Soul, 83 Goethe, an anatomist, 162 ; his work on Morphology cited, 183 ; his Farben- lehre cited, 247. Cited, 226, 237, 249, 280 Graafian Vesicle, cause of its bursting, 338 ; Blumenbach, cited, ib. ; mistaken for the ovum, 353 Grafting, animal, successfully practised, 191 Grant, Sir Alex., on the meaning of in>XV, 222 Grant's Lectures on Comparative Ana- tomy cited, 155 Gravitation, law of, discovered by New- ton, 29 ; Comte on its extension be- yond the solar system, 125 Gravity, an abstraction, 95; its expla- natory use, ib. ; Aristotle's idea of, 141, 142, 143 Greeks, the inventors of astronomical instruments, 38; their scientific dis- coveries, 39; their adoption of scien- tific scepticism, 39, 40 ; Aristotle an illustration of their excellence and defects, 41 ; their desire of knowledge for its own sake, 43; the originators of science, 44; their slow progress in discovery, 45; Whewell on the cause of their failure in philosophy, 52, 88 ; their want of ideas examined, 55 ; neglect of facts, not of ideas, the cause of their scientific failure, ib.; their imperfect appreciation of the nature of evidence, 56; their recog- nition of the Inductive Method, ib. ; deficient both in facts and ideas, 58 ; their want of method and instru- ments, ib. ; quotation from Bacon, ib. ; their impatience in investigation, ib.; Whewell on their failure in science, 88 ; their superstitions respecting unburied bodies, 160; their stringent laws as to burial, ib. ; their horror of dissection, ib.; Pliny on their menda- city, 286. Greek art, defects of, 41 Gruner's Analecta ad Antiquitates Me- dicas cited, 1 60 Gubler, cited, 345 Guizot, on the materiality of the soul, 224 Halleb, cited, 159, 220, 323, 347, 353, 354, 356, 361, 367, 371, 374; his pati- ent labours in Verification, 60; on the want of patient investigation in his contemporaries, ib. ; an instance of his great labours, ib. ; his definition of Physiology, 156 ; maintained that Hippocrates dissected the Human Body, 160; on man's natural repug- nance to dissection, 162 ; his estimate of the quantity of blood going to the brain, 166; on the insensibility of the ' Cerebrum, 305; his Opuscula Ana- tomica cited, 316 Hamilton, Sir W., his eulogy on Aris- totle, 18, 22; on " divisible sensa- tion," 253; his notes on A. 's treatise on Memory and Kecollection, 256. Cited, 257 Harles, cited, 159, 167, 170 Harless, on the Asclepiads, cited, 7. Harris, his Philosophical Arrangements, cited, 22 Hartsoeker, his claim to priority in the discovery of the Spermatozoa, 352 Harvey, on the pulsation of the Heart, 174; asserts that all animals are ovi- parous, 213; on generation, 215 ; studies which led him to the discovery of the circulation of the blood, 323; compared with Aristotle, 326 ; denies the existence of female sperm, 333. Cited, 298, 305, 332, 355 Heart, assumed by Aristotle to be the seat of the Soul, 120; Aristotle's error in reference to the position of, 165 ; INDEX. 393 Galen's conception of, 166; regarded as the great source of Motion, 174; assumed by A. to be the origin of the tendons, ib.; dependence of Aristotle's theories on, ib. ; Harvey on the pulsa- tion of, i'6. ; the seat of sensation, 179; A.'s opinion that it is the first organ developed, 310; genesis of, ib.; the origin of the veins and of emotion, 311; Aristotle on the ossification of the septum, 313; the heart the origin of character, ib. ; its inability to with- stand disease, 313, 314; the origin of development, 361 Heat, Aristotle's theory of, 139; his inquiries respecting animal heat, 299; the direction of animal heat, 306 Heaven, analysis of Aristotle's work De Ccelo, 136; the form of, 138 Hectocotylus of the Argonaut, 197, 198; described by Cuvier, 198; its peculiar wonder, 198, 199; the discovery sup- posed to be anticipated by Aristotle, • ib.; A.'s passages on, 199, 200; his ignorance of the Hectocotylus, 200, 201; Von Siebold's error, 201 Heeren, his account of Classic Literature in the Middle Ages, cited, 8, 118 Hegel, his admiration for Aristotle, 18, 22 ; his disciples' idea of the Absolute, 80; his Introduction to Logic, cited, ib. ; on the meaning of Truth, ib. ; on Empiricism, ib.; his elucidation of Matter and Spirit, 81; his errors, ib.; denies the charge of Empiricism against Aristotle, 109. Cited, 21 Helvetius, his reason for the intellectual superiority of Man, 321 Herder, adopts Buffon's idea of the living universe as one family, 188 Hereditaiy transmission of qualities, 370, 371 Hermaphroditism, in fish, 207 ; explana- tion of, 208; hermaphrodites always of one sex, ib. ; Serres cited on, ib. Hermias, King of Atarneus, a disciple of Aristotle, 12; invites A. to his court, ib.; A. raises a statue to, 13 Hermolaus Barbaras, on the " final cause," 118; Erasmus' opinion of him, ib. ; Scaliger's opinion of him, 119; on Locomotion, 134 ; on Aristotle's views of Plants and Animals, 194. Cited, 190, 235 Herpyllis, Aristotle's concubine, 17 Herschel, cited on causes and effects, 91 ; notices the obstruction of Aristotle to astronomical science, 125 Hesychius, a biographer of Aristotle, 5 Hindoo theory of generation, 352 Hipparchus, on the records of the Assy- rians, 37; an example of scientific inquiry, 59 Hippocrates, an example of scientific in- quiry, 40; never dissected the Human Body, 160, 163. Cited, 179, 250, 263, 332, 370 Histogenesis, laws of, 329 Histology, Modern, foundation of, 279 Historians of Science, their carelessness, 281 History of Animals (Aristotle's), various editions of, 21, 269; proposal and specimen of a new translation, 269; new translation by Mr. Cresswell, ib. ; Cuvier's enthusiasm for, 269, 270 ; ana- lysis of , 27 1, 279 ; criticisms on Cuvier's remarks concerning its generalizations, 271; no system of classification con- tained in, 278 ; Titze's ingenious sug- gestion concerning, 279; supposed to be a continuation of the De Partibus, ib.; its abrupt commencement, ib.; the introduction supposed to be lost, ib. ; examples of its careless generali- zation, 282 Hofer, on Galen's extraction of the in- candescent gases, 185, 186 Homologies of the skeleton, Aristotle's idea of, 157 Houghton, his proposal of a new trans- lation of the Hist. Animal., 269 Humboldt, cited, 140; mentions the case of a man suckling a child, 285 Hume, his treatise on Human Nature, cited, 241; his doctrine on the Mind, ib. Hunter, his animal grafting, 191. Huxley, on the value of scientific gene- ralization and classification, 291; on the difference between Hands and Peet in Man, 319. Cited, 327, 337 Hybridity, Aristotle on, 110 Hybrids, Aristotle on the fertility of, 363 Hydrophobia, A.'s assertion in respect to, 289 Hypothesis, scientific importance of, 114 Idea, a priori, of Galileo, powerless to stand the Ideal Test, 68; the indis- soluble connection of Idea (Theory) with Fact, 72, 74, 75; the. real dis- tinction, 75, 76, 77, 78 Ideas, their reference to natural pheno- mena, 54; Aristotle's neglect of Ideas the cause of his scientific failure, ib. ; the Platonic conception of, 83; the tendency to accept them as represen- tations of things, 88; science careful 394 INDEX. of their relative truth, 93; Plato's world of permanent existences, 103 Ideal Test of Inertia, conformable with Real Test, 67 Ideal Test, when subjectively true, 68 ; recognized by Aristotle and Des- cartes, 69 ; must be supplemented by the Real Test, 80 ; placed above the Real Test by Aristotle, 117. Ideler, on Greek and Roman Meteo- rology, cited, 46 Imagination, Aristotle on its existence in inferior Animals, 243; definition of, 265 Immortality of the Soul, Aristotle on, 358 Imperato (the old Italian Naturalist), his description of Sponges, 193; on the vision of the Mole, 219 Impregnation, the union of a spermcell with a germcell, 202 ; Newport cited on artificial impregnation, 204 Incubation, the two forms of, 329 ; ovi- parity and viviparity, ib. Induction, one of the modes of scientific investigation, 57 Inductive Method, accurately proclaimed by Aristotle, 47 ; Aristotle the father of Inductive philosophy, 108 Inductive Syllogism, the basis of science, 115 Inertia, law of, an abstraction, 67 ; Ideal Test of, ib. ; law of, how demonstrable, 84; absolute Iner. a figment, 124; instance of Aristotle's disregard of the law of, 152 Inorganic: the gradation from the inor- ganic to the organic kingdom, 190; plants, the first step in the scale, ib. Insects, metamorphoses of, 214; Aris- totle on their external form, 318, 319; on their mode of generation, 336. See Parthenogenesis Instruments, scientific, Greek want of, 58 Intellect, Aristotle's chapter on, 240 Intestines, Plato's description of, 106 Invertebrata, Aristotle's account of the anatomy of, 285, 286; their organs of sense, 287 Isidore St. Hilaire. See St. Hilaire Jebe, his Preface to Roger Bacon's Opus Majus cited, 121 Johnson, his Life of Linacre cited, 119 Jourdain, his work on the ancient inter- pretations of Aristotle, cited, 21; his explanation of Roger Bacon's desire to burn Aristotle's works, 121 Kant, cited, 69, 231 ; on scientific specu- lation, 83; his proposal to form an introductory science to Physics, 84; on Plato's Method, 107; on the rela- tivity of Motion and Rest, 124; his definition of Life and Organism, 229; on dreamless sleep, 265 Kepler, his "doubts as to his own dis- covery respecting the orbit of Mars, 34; hesitates to identify celestial and terrestrial mechanics, 125 Kidneys (the), Serres' observation re- garding, 165 Kirchoff cited on spectrum analysis, 70 Kohler, on the confusion of nerves and tendons, 167. Cited, 275, 286 Kolk, Schroder van der, cited, 224, 261 Kblliker, his investigation of the Hecto- cotylus, 198; his views adopted by Von Siebold, ib. ; on Aristotle's assertion regarding the Cuttlefish, 218. Cited, 208, 310, 362 Kuhlemann cited by Schneegass, 356 Lacepede, his Histoire Naturelle des Poissonx cited, 275 Lallemand, on self-contained elements of development in Spermatozoon, 371 Lamarck, cited as an instance of the metaphysical tendency, 97 ; on the sensibility of the Polype, ib. ; on the causes of the variety of organisms, ib. ; his retort against Cuvier regard- ing the nervous fluid, 98; on the degrees of the animal scale, 188 ; on the relations of organic life, ib. ; denies the " chain of creation," ib. ; on the organic and inorganic king- doms, 193; his Philosophie Zoohgique cited, 2 1 9 ; his division of animals into vertebrata and invertebrata, 294 Lamartine, his noble description of man, 309 Language, its influence in philosophy, 88, 89 ; its theory little understood, 89; modems own no servility to, 89; Whewell on Aristotle's subservience to language, ib. Laplace, on the law of Motion, 98, 124 Laurillard, furnishes a specimen of Hec- tocotylus described by Cuvier, 198 Lauth, his eulogy of Aristotle's ana- tomical labours, 156 ; his inconsis- tency, ib. ; cited, 158 ; on A.'s error regarding the Heart, 165; on A.'s claim to the discovery of the vertebral theory, 186 Lawi, his Memorie sopra le Talpa cited, 219 Lerebouillet, his work on comparative Embryology cited, 189 Lessing, on Aristotle's Poetics, 21 Leuckart, thinks Sponges intermediate INDEX. 395 between the vegetal and animal kingdoms, 188. Cited, 208, 295 Leuwenhoek, first described the tubular structure of the nerves, 168. Cited, 352 Levity, Aristotle's idea of, 141,142, 143. See Bodies Lewis, Historical survey of Astronomy of the Ancients cited, 37 Leydig, cited, 365 Libri, on the successful scientific studies of the Italians, 38; his History of Mathematics cited, 148 Life, various definitions of, 229; the impenetrable dynamis, 231 ; poten- tial and real, id.; regarded by Aris- totle as a final cause, 234; causes of prolonged life, 266, 267, 268 Light, Aristotle's theory of, 139; his definition of, 248 Linnteus, his views regarding man anti- cipated by Aristotle, 195 Liver, Plato's description of, 106; Aris- totle on the properties of, 149, 150, 312 ; -Davy's fallacious experiments on, 313 Locomotion, A.'s views of, 242, 243 Logic, its danger, 81 ; Aristotle's scien- tific, 115, 116, 117 Longet, cited, 208 Longevity, Aristotle's treatise on, 266 ; his explanation of the causes of, 266, 267, 268 Lucas, cited, 352, 353 Lucretius, on the tendency of bodies in space, 137 Ludovicus Vives, on the comparison be- tween the moderns and the ancients, 4 Lungs, Aristotle's description and theory of, 164, 314 Lyceum, opened as a school by Aris- totle, 1 5 ; description of, ib. Lyonet, his anatomical work cited, 158; his patient observation, ib. Mabillon, refers to the figure of the telescope in ancient MS., 186 Macgillivray, his amusing eulogy of Aristotle, 155; his exaggerated esti- mate of A., 270; on Aristotle as a naturalist, 286 Magnetic Fluid, Lamarck's retort against Cuvier respecting, 98 Majendie, his Journal de Physiologie cited, 177 Malebranche, cited, 353 Malpighi, his estimate of the quantity of blood going to the brain, 166; alleged anticipation of his discovery respecting the fibrine of the blood, 284 ; discovers the capillaries, 362. Cited, 310, 353, 362 Mammals, varieties of vertebrae in, 85 Mammertus, Claudian. See Claudian Man, compared by Plato to the universe, 106; Aristotle's confession as to man's internal anatomy, 164; derivation of the word man, 195; modern attempts to separate him from the animal kingdom, ib.; the stress laid on his erect posture, 308, 309 ; Lord Mon- boddo's man, who preferred going on all fours, 309 ; Lamartine's noble description of man, ib. ; the only ani- mal that is ticklish, 316; A.'s diag- nosis of man, 319; a quadrumanous animal, 319, 320 ; A.'s inferences from man's erect attitude, 320, 321 ; A.'s reasons why he of all animals has flesh on his legs, 322 ; asserts that man is tailless, ib. ; his sponta- neous origin not incredible to Aris- totle, 366 Manava-Dharmasastra cited, 352 Manzolina, Anna, her wax preparations the pride of Bologna, 162 Mars, Kepler's doubts respecting the orbit of, 34 Martianus Capella, on the antiquity of Egyptian astronomy, 37 Martin, Henri, cited, 14 Martins, his Memoires de I'Acad. de Monpellier cited, 158; on the identity of the Humerus with the Pemur, ib. Mathematics, their Greek origin, 39 ; the most rigorous type of the true method, ib. Matter, his History of the Alexandrian School cited, 16 Matter, Newton on the formation of, 97 Matter and Spirit, Hegel's elucidation of, 81 Maurice, his felicitous contrast of Plato and Aristotle, 19 Maury, his Le Sommeil et les Reoes cited, 258 Max Miiller. See Miiller MazzucheUi, his Italian Writers cited, 119 McDonnell, cited, 177 Mechanics, Rational compared with Practical, 82; Aristotle's work on, 122; A.'s distinction between celes- tial and terrestrial mechanics, 125; Kepler and Galileo's hesitancy, ib. Meckel, on the gradation of organisms, 188; his views adopted in theVestiges of Creation, 188. Cited, 207, 210, 295, 315 Medici, his work on the Anatomical School of Bologna cited, 163 396 INDEX. Memory, Aristotle's explanation of, 256 ; analysis of A.'s work on Memory and Recollection, ib. ; Sir W. Hamil- ton's notes on Reid, ib. Metamorphoses ot Animals, instanced in the Salamander, 213 ; whence Goethe deduced his theory of the metamorphoses of Plants, 354 Metaphysical conception of Nature, Mind impeded by, 31 Metaphysicians, overlook the Real Test, 82 Metaphysics, its efforts not without fruit, 66; its vanity lies in Method, ib.-, as distinguished from Science, 84, 93; basis of, 87, 88; demands only the test of logical dependence, 90; its tendency active in the early stages of culture, 96; Aristotle a metaphysician, 119 Meteorology, Aristotle's work on, 122 — 147 ; its design and scope, 143, 144, 145; its failure for want of instruments, ib. ; analysis of, 145 Method, the Subjective and Objective compared, 35 ; origin of the Subjec- tive, 36 ; systematic adoption of Method due to the Greeks, 38 ; Mathematics the most rigorous type of the true Method, 39 ; the (rue Method impossible without scepticism, ib. ; the Inductive accurately pro- claimed by Aristotle, 47 ; the ancient Method powerless to lead to satis- factory results, ib.; Greek want of Method, 58; preference for the Sub- jective explained, 63 ; its gradual relinquishment, ib. ; the scientific failure of the ancients referable to false Method, 64 ; account of the Subjective and Objective Methods, 65; error of the Subjective tested, 81; Method the distinction between Science and Metaphysics, 84; Plato's Method examined, 101 ; his frank avowal of the Subjective, 103; Kant's happy illustration of Plato's Method, 107; Aristotle's defective conception of, 108; impossibility of applying true Method in A.'s time, 113; Aris- totle's scientific Logic, 115, 116, 117; A. protests against the a priori Method, 140 Meyer, cited, 140; on the error of Fabri- cius, 177; on the various schemes of classification, 277 Milky Way, Aristotle's explanation of, 145; theory of Democritus, ib. Milman, his Hist, of Latin Christianity, cited, 121 Milne Edwards, on Aristotle's ruminat- ing fish, 283 Mind, Plato refers the causes of all things to, 102 ; only the highest development of Life, 223 Moderns, supposed anticipation of their discoveries by the ancients, 46, 197; their superiority to the ancients in the investigation of facts, 57; psycho- logical cause of their errors, 61; own no servility to current meanings of words, 89; some of their speculative views anticipated by Aristotle, 183; their uncritical attitude toward ancient authors, 185, 186 Moisture, assigned by Aristotle as a cause of longevity, 267 ; ancient ideas of, ib. Mole (the), Aristotle on the vision of, 218; fierce debate of naturalists, 218, 219; an Italian Mole corresponding with Aristotle's description, 219 ; proved to have perfect vision by Geoffroy St. Hilaire, ib.; the Syrian Mole mentioned by Lamarck, ib. Molluscs, Aristotle on their external form, 318, 319 Monboddo, Lord, cited, 22 ; mentions a man who preferred going on all fours, 309; maintains Man's <« sublime to be merely artificial, ib. ; his belief in monsters and one-legged men, 373, 374 Monogenesis, various forms of, 327 Monsters, Aristotle's and Monboddo's opinions on, 373, 374. Montucla, his History of Mathematics, cited, 38 ; his contempt for Aristotle's mathematical insight, 148; on A.'s mechanical Problems, 149 Morell, on the Vital and Spiritual Forces of our Nature, 224 Morley's Life of Cardan, cited, 176 Moscati, cited, 309 Mothers' marks, Aristotle's omission of, 374 Motion, its laws transcend experience, 66; formula of, 66, 99; our expe- rience of, ib. ; Laplace on the law of, 98; Comte on Laplace's theory, ib.; analysis of Motion, 124, 133, 134, 135, 136; Aristotle ignorant of the laws and nature of, 126 ; the ancient conception of, ib.; Mussenbroek and Rohault's conception of Motion and Rest, 126, 127; Aristotle's celebrated definition of, 131 ; fallacy respecting continuous Motion, 133; its three divisions, 133, 134; Hermolaus Bar- baras on the " motion of place," 134; A. on accelerated motion, 151; the Heart regarded as the source of, 174; INDEX. 397 theoiy of animal movements, 178; origin of all motion, ib. ; Aristotle on the principle of, 227; Motion consi- dered as part of the Vital Principle,242 Miiller, Johannes, his patient labours in Verification, 60; his discovery of Nervous System in Holothuriaa, 167; on Aristotle's announcement of a Placental fish, 217; adopts A.'s view of Life and Mind, 228 ; on the action of special nerves of sense, 247 ; on the voices of fish, 287. Cited, 23, 207, 208, 221, 315 Miiller, Max, on the origin of the word man, 195; on the meaning and equi- valents of anima, 222 Muratori, his Dissertation on Italian Antiquities, cited, 8 ; on a drawing of the telescope in an ancient MS., 186 Muscles, Aristotle's ignorance of the, 158 Muscular contractility, theories of, 177, 178 Mussenbroek, his Experimental Physics cited, 38; his conception of Motion and Rest, 126; on the idea of Space, 131 ; proposes a fourth kingdom, 190 Mythology (Ancient), its alleged em- bodiment of a lost Science, 46 Natuke, idea of uniformity not con- ceived by Aristotle, 125; A.'s defini- tion of, 129; the principle of Motion and Rest, ib. ; her ascending steps from non-living to living beings, 190 Natural gradation: the first step Plants, 190; the second step Plant-animals, 192; the third step animals, 193 Natural History. See Anatomy, Biology Nerves, Aristotle said to have dis- covered them, 157, 168; his slight acquiantance with, 158 ; what- are their Greek equivalents, 168 ; their tubular structure first described by Leuwenhoek, ib. ; made familiar to Europe by Ehrenberg, ib.; Galileo's story on their origin, ib.; defenders of Aristotle's theory of the nerves, ib. ; A.'s alleged discovery discussed, 168, 169; A. also credited with discovery of the cerebral nerves, 169; the optic nerves believed by Aricenna and Roger Bacon to be tubes or ducts, 169, 170 . Nerve-tissue, its alleged existence in inferior animals, 243 Nervous system, Aristotle's ignorance of, 158; Galen's confusion respecting, 167, 168 NeSpow, meaning attached by Aristotle to, 167, 168 Newport, on artificial impregnation, 204 Newton, Sir I., discovers the law of gravitation, 29; his Principia com- pared with Aristotle's Physics, 67, 68; on Attraction, 93; N.'s metaphy- sical tendency, 97; on the formation, of Matter, ib. ; his hesitation in iden- tifying celestial and terrestrial Me- chanics, 125 Nicanor, Aristotle's adopted son, 17 Nicomachus, the father of Aristotle, 7; physician to Amyntas II., ib. ; his death, ib. Nicomachus, Aristotle's son, 17 Nifo's work on Aristotle cited, 221 ; his Expositio Subtilissima cited, 233 Nile, the cause of female fecundity, 370 Nizolius, his indignation against the blind worship of the Greeks, 2 ; com- pares Aristotle to the cuttle-fish, ib. Novum Organum, its defective concep- tion of Method, 108 Nutrition, the first stage of the Soul's activity, 190; Aristotle's definition of, 234; alleged by A. to be most active during sleep, 259 Objective Method, replaces the Sub- jective in science, 26; contrasted with the Subjective, 35 ; arises from positive knowledge, 36 ; its origin, a late event in the history of man, ib. ; due chiefly to the Italian Greeks, ib. ; no evidence of it in the East, 37 ; its use impos- sible without instruments, ib. ; its teaching on the "final cause," 119; its use in Physics, 123. See Subjec- tive Method, Ideal and Real Test Observation, compared with Experiment, 50; one of the modes of scientific investigation, 57; Aristotle on the necessity of, 110, 111, 112; use of the personal equation, 378; late develop- ment of the art of, ib. Oken, cited, 184, 365 Olivi, verifies Aristotle's statement re- garding the nest-building fish, 218 Oilier, M., his successful grafting of pieces of bone, 191 Optics, their origin due to the Greeks, 39 Organic, the gradation between the organic and inorganic kingdoms, 190 Organism, Lamarck on the causes of the varieties of, 97; its three most impor- tant parts unknown to Aristotle, 158; the differentiation of plants and 898 INDEX. animals stated, 194; male and female organisms, 207, 208; Kant's definition of an organism, 229 ; theory of ascend- ing complexity, 243; Aristotle's divi- sion into similar and dissimilar parts, 279, 280; Bichat on the distinction between animal and vegetable organs, 314, 315; single and double organs, 315; A. on the sexual organs, 332; various authorities cited as to the ovaries, 332, 333; A. on the testes, 333, 334; the uterus, 334; A. on the origin of the sperm, 339, 340. See Generation, Embryology Origin of Species, Kobinet's wild scheme of, 187; Bonnet's scheme, ib. Orton, his Lectures on Breeding, cited, 371 Ovaries, opinions of various physiolo- gists on, 332, 333; their functions, 338 Ovid, his description of man's sublime gaze applicable to certain fishes, 308 Oviparity. See Incubation Oviparous Animals, Aristotle on, 350 Ovulation, processes of, 337, 338; spon- taneous ovulation, 338 ; compared with semination, 339 Owen, Professor, cited, 157; his work on Parthenogenesis, cited, 202 ; on the nourishment of the embryo, 216; on Aristotle's ruminating fish, 283 " Oxidation of tissues," a phrase used to cloak ignorance, 98 Pagenstecher, cited, 369 Parallelogram of forces, Aristotle's ex- position of, 148; superior to that of Kant, ib. Parents, their mutual influence upon their children, 371, 372 Paiis, Parliament of, declares Aristotle's works heretical, 21; edict as to the doctrine of the ancients, ib. Parthenogenesis, Aristotle on that of bees, 110; one of his anticipations of modern science, 201 ; present state of opinion on, 202; of the Aphis, 202, 203; the means of, discussed, 204; fact of that of bees placed beyond doubt, 205; researches of Dzierzon and Von Siebold, ib. ; guaranteed by anatomical investigation, ib. ; the ana- tomical data unknown to Aristotle, 206 " Parts of Animals." See Be Partibus Patrizio, his enmity to Aristotle echoed by Bacon, 9; contents of his Peri- patetic Discussions, ib. ; Giordano Bruno's contempt for him, ib.; he denied all distinction between Ra- tional and Irrational, 195, 1 96 ; on the Greek and Latin equivalents for Soul, 222, 223. Cited, 279 Perch, Aristotle's remarks on the, 209 ; said by Eondelet to be both male and female, ib. ; an exception to the whole class of fishes, 210; dispute as to its self-reproduction, ib.; the Perch bi- sexual, ib. See Fish Peripatetics, origin of the name, 16 Personal equation, value of, 378 Phaedo, Plato's, cited, 102 Phenomena, three modes of conceiving, 26,27,30; invariability of , 28 ; Comte on the metaphysical conception of, 30; Vicq d'Azyr, on the Objective interpretation of, 31 j Greek and Modern interpretation of, ib.; con- ceived to be dependent on a mutable will, 32 ; criteria of their three modes of interpretation, ib. ; contrast between the metaphysical and scientific gua- rantee of, 33 ; modes of interpreting, 34; Aristotle's idea of an ascending complexity of Vital Phenomena, 189. See Method Philelphus, on the connection of Mind and Body, 232. Cited, 233 Philip of Macedon entrusts Aristotle with tutorship of Alexander, 13; builds a gymnasium, ib. Philippson, cited, 169, 170, 280 Philosophic Anatomy, first dawn of, 279 Philosophy, Greek, Whewell on the cause of its failure, 52, 88; Aristotle, the father of Inductive, 108; Prantl's reproach against ancient philosophy, 140 Physics, Kant's proposal to form an introductory science to, 84; Aristotlc"s failure to establish a transcendental idea of, 122; use of Objective Method in, 123; his extant writings on, 127; analysis of A.'s treatise on, 128; Bar- thelemy St. Hilaire's version of A.'s Physics, ib. Physiology, Aristotle's anatomical knowledge insufficient for, 170, 171; A.'s neglect of Verification, 171, 172; A.'s physiology entirely one of con- jecture, 180; studies which led to the great discoveries in, 323, 324, 325 Pineal Gland, the seat of the Soul, 83 Placenta, its use, 216 Placental Pish, Aristotle aware of their existence, 212; Miiller on Aristotle's announcement of, 217 Planets, Comte on our limited physical and chemical knowledge of, 70 INDEX. 399 Plants, Aristotle's identification of, with animals, 184; his perception of an important morphological law, 187; Treviranus makes a separate kingdom of the Cryptogamic plants and Zoo- phytes, 188; they have life, 190, 191; their designation, 191; grafting no mark of distinction, ib. ; plant-animals the second step in natural gradation, 192; Schuyl on Vegetable Life, 229; vitality of plants due to a Soul, ib. Plato, Aristotle's alleged ingratitude to, 11; A.'s teacher for 17 years, ib.; contrasted with A., 19; P.'s pernici- ous influence, ib. ; his noble faculties, 101; his Method, how far scientific and how far philosophic, ib.; his philosophy in reference to science, 102; his studies, ib.; he refers the causes of all things to Mind, ib.; the influence of Anaxagoras on him, ib. the method of eliminating scientific truth, 102, 103; his intensely Sub- jective method, 102, 103, 104; on genesis, ib. ; his idea of Science, 103; his frank avowal of the Subjective method, ib. ; causes of the scientific extravagances in the Timcpus, ib. ; his depreciation of Astronomy, 104; on the cohesion of the Pour Elements, 105; his use of the five solids, ib. ; his anatomical and physiological con- clusions, 106; his description of the Liver, ib. ; of the Intestines, ib. ; his own reason for his conclusions, ib. ; Kant's happy illustration of his Method, 107; his whole teaching vitiated, ib. ; contrast to Aristotle, 108; his method compared with A.'s, 109; taught that all knowledge was reminiscence, 111; his evidence of the true scientific method, 115; his derivation of aV0pw7roc, 195 ; on the derivation of fvxv, 223 ; held "the eye to be of fire," 247; on the use of the Plesh, 307; on the Uterus, 335 Platonic Method, Kant on the, 107 ; dan- ger of, pointed out by Aristotle, 111 Playfair, on the Physical science of the ancients, 49; inaccurate as to their scientific failure, 51 Pliny, on Alexander's assistance to Aristotle, 15; on the phenomena of scarlet fever, 172; on Greek men- dacity, 286; repeats A.'s statement respecting the induration of the Heart, 313. Cited, 289 Ploss, cited, 370 Polypes, Lamarck denies the sensibility of, 97; held by Aristotle to be plants, 192; doubt as to whether A. con- founded them with Sponges, 193; their bisexual structure, 209 Polytheism, remnants of, in the Christian Church, 29 Ildpoi, what Aristotle meant by, 169 Portal denies that Aristotle dissected the Human Body, 159; on A.'s ana- tomical carelessness, 167 Poselger, his exposition of Aristotle's Problems, 147. Cited, 148 Pouchet, cited, 338, 364 Prantl, his edition of Aristotle's Physics, cited, 128; of the De Ccelo, 136; on the priority of fire to earth, 138; his reproach against ancient philosophers, 140. Cited, 249 Precision, instance of Aristotle's scien- tific, 112 Primal Soul, see Vital Principle Problems, Aristotle's work on, 147; ex- pounded by Chabanon and Poselger, ib.; Montucla's comment on, 149; examples from, 150, 151, 152. Cited, 300 Projectiles, Aristotle's theory on, 132, 133; on the cessation of motion, 152 Psychology, modern, Aristotle's antici- pation of, 111; reason for much of its obscurity, 237 Pythagoreans, their researchesin physical science, 38; their constancy in investi- gating causes of phenomena, ib. ; the pioneers of modem science, ib. Pythias, Aristotle's wife, 12; his love for, 13 Pythias, daughter of Aristotle, 17 Quatrefages, his Unity of the Human Species cited, 195 Quiddity, one of the four Causes, 117. See Causes, Causation Ramus, cited, 2 Rathke, cited, 208, 275, 315; on the difference between oviparity and vivi- parity, 330 ; his observations on the Blenny, 332 Real Test, the criterion of Verification, 68 ; must supplement the Ideal Test, 80; necessity of, 82 Reason, Schellihg on the absolutism of, 80 Reaumur, cited, 277, 353, 354; his obser- vations on the Ephemeron, 329 Recollection, considered by Aristotle as distinct from Memory, 257 400 INDEX. Eedi, his couplet on the worship of Aristotle, 159 Reproduction, Aristotle on the power of, in females, 360. See Generation, Parthenogenesis Reptiles, held by Aristotle to be blood- less, 276 Republic, Plato's, cited, 103 Respiration, Aristotle's ideas on, 174, 175, 176; the respiration offish, 175, 176 ; A. on the process of, 177 Rest. See Motion Ritter, cited, 6, 9. 140, 279 Robbe, Dr., his edition of Ammonius, 5 Robin, C, on embryology, 203 ; on the placenta, 216. Cited, 361 Robinet, his wild scheme on the origin of species, 187 Roger Bacon. See Bacon Rohault, his definition of Motion, 127 Rondelet, on the male and female cha- racter of the Perch, 209 ; his work De Piscis Marinis quoted by Dufosse, 210 Rosmini, on the real weight of Aris- totle's authority, 22 ; his estimate of A.'s philosophy, ib. Rouget, cited, 208, 275, 345 Roulin, cited, 177 Rudolphi, cited, 210 Ruminating Pish, Aristotle's, 282 ; Milne Edwards's reference to, 283; Professor Owen's note on, ib. Salamander, an instance of the meta- morphoses of animals, 213 Saverien, quotes Pere Schot respecting the Planet Angels, 29 Scaliger, J. C, his opinion of Herma- laus Barbaras, 119; his palliation of Aristotle, 167 ; his edition of the Hist. Animal, 269; finds no classifi- cation in it, 278 ; maintained that mice are generated from corruption, 361. Cited, 347, 367 Scarlet fever, Pliny on the phenomena of, 172 Scepticism, the chief element in true Method, 39 ; due to the Greeks, ib. ; Aristotle on, 40; imperfectly prac- tised by the Greeks, ib. Schelling, on the absolutism of Reason, 80 Schleiermacher, cited, 109 Schleiden, cited, 296 Schneegass, on the aura seminalis, 356 Schneider, on Alexander's assistance to Aristotle, 15; his edition of the Hist. Animal, 21, 269 ; his Latin version cited, 199 Schoolmen (the), their grand mistake, 70; employed a method on which all problems were insoluble, 71 Schroder van der Kolk, on the union between Soul and Body, 224. Cited, 261 Schuckhard, cited, 270 Schuyl, on Vegetable Life, 229 Schweigger, his fanciful explanation of ancient myths, 46 Scientific scepticism, its Greek origin, 39 Aristotle on, 40; imperfectly prac- tised by the Greeks, ib. See Scep- ticism Science, dawn of, 24; its gradual deve- lopment, 24, 25 ; distinguished from " common knowledge," 26 ; the cri- terion or guarantee of, 33; its sup- posed origin in the East, 36 ; pre- eminently quantitative, 37; Pytha- gorean researches in, 38, 39 ; its dignity springs from disinterested- ness, 42; cause of the hostility of theologians to, 43; Greeks the origi- nators of, 44; cause of its eclipse in Europe, ib. ; prolonged infancy of, 45; failure of the ancients in, 46 ; their failure owing to disregard of Observation and Experiment, 47 ; Playfair's verdict on the failure of the ancients, 49; Playfair inaccurate, 51 ; causes of the failure of the Greeks examined, 55; neglect of facts, not ideas, the cause of Greek failure, ib. three modes of investigation, 57 Greek want of instruments, 58 source of the errors of the ancients 60, 61; the law of progress in, 62 transcendental ideas of modern, 66 ancient and modern distinguished, 67 the absolute rule of, 69 ; the two cri- teria of Verification, ib. ; definition of, 71 ; as distinguished from Meta- physics, 84, 93, 96 ; Kant's proposal to form an introductory science to Phy- sics, 84 ; Whewell on the failure of the Greeks, 88 ; the successful method, 90 ; the primary requisition of science, ib. ; meaning of the word " cause," ib.; disclaims attempts to penetrate secrets of causation, 91 ; seeks only the phenomenal and rela- tive, ib.; its range and limits, 92; Copernicus cited, ib. ; three stages of positive knowledge in, 96 ; continuous abandonment of unverified theories, 98; Plato's idea of, 103 ; Experi- ence the true guide in, 111; danger of the Platonic Method, ib. ; impossi- bility of applying the true Method in Aristotle's lime, 113; based on Induc- tive Syllogism, 115; fallacy of ancient INDEX. 401 speculations, 115; Aristotle's scientific logic, 115, 116, 117; his four scientific causes, 117, 118; struggles against the popular horror of dissection, 160; con- formity of ancient ideas with modern research, 185; curious illustration of ancient science, 300 ; summary of modern embryological science, 327 ; ancient and modem contrasted, 377 ; precision of modern, 378 ; personal equation, ib. Sea Anemones, their bisexual struc- ture, 209; Aristotle's classification of, 318 Secretion, moderation in, a cause of longevity, 267 Segni, his Tuscan paraphrase of the De Animd, 221 Sensation, Aristotle on, 235, 238, 239, 252, 297; the judging faculty, 239; divided sensation, 252 ; the distinctions of, 297 Senses, Touch and Taste the primary, 243; other senses, 244, 246, 249, 251; Aristotle's treatise on, 246 ; A.'s analysis of Vision, ib.; of Taste and Smell, 249; of Hearing, 251 Sensibility, Aristotle's views on, 235, 236, 237 Serres, on the kidneys, 165; on the means of discovering the missing links in the chain of creation, 188; his Pricis d'Anat. transcendante cited, 189; on the embryology of male and female organisms, 208 ; on the duality of organs, 315. Cited, 374 Severinus, cited, 176 Sexes, Aristotle on the differences of, 331; authorities cited on origin of, 367; Aristotle's hypotheses on, 368, 369, 370 S'Gravesande, on the differences of things, 117 Sharpey, cited, 216 Siebold. See Von Siebold Skeleton, Aristotle's ideas of the homo- logies of, 157 Skin, Aristotle on the formation of the, 363 Sleep, Aristotle's treatise on, 258; his survey of, 258, 259; he asserts it to be the most active time of nutrition, 259 ; cause and natural aim of Sleep, 260; A.'s physiological explanation of, 260, 261, 262 ; compared to Epilepsy, 261; Kant on dreamless sleep, 265 Socrates, Aristotle alleged to have been a disciple of his, 5; cause of his re- pugnance to physical inquiries, 43 Solids, Plato's use of the five, 105 Sbmmering, his defence of Aristotle respecting the seat of the Nerves, 168 Sonnenburg, on Aristotle's assertion as to the emptiness of the back part of the skull, 167. Cited, 219, 271 Soul, Descartes on the seat of, 83; Plato compares Man's soul to that of the universe, 106; Aristotle places its seat in the Heart, 120; first stage of its activity, 190; not equivalent to the tyvxv of Aristotle, 222; sensation the characteristic of, 224; doctrines on, ib.-, Claudian Mammertus on the immaterialism of, 225 ; A. on the divisibility of, ib.; on the study of, 226, 227; Galen on the three kinds of, 233, 234; Aristotle's views on the immortality of, 233,358; the "place of forms," 240 Space, useless discussions on the idea of, 131; Aristotle's profitless discus- sion on contraries in, 137, 138 Spallanzani, cited, 353 Species, Bonnet's and Robinet's schemes on the origin of, 187; Aristotle's views on, 293 Spectrum analysis, discloses metals in Sun's atmosphere, 70 Spencer, Herbert, his definition of Life, 230. Cited, 231 Sperm, whether derived from the whole body or only a part, 339, 340, 341; Aristotle's diagnosis of, 342, 343, 344; its physical nature, 356 Spermatozoon, description of, 352 ; figured by Andry and Gautier, ib. ; Lallemand on its self-contained ele- ments of development, 371 Sperm-cells, production of, 337 Speusippus, Aristotle pays 700/. for the works of, 8 Spinoza, on the hostility of theologians to physical science, 43. Cited, 79, 294 Spirit and Matter, Hegel's elucidation of, 81 Spix, cited, 167, 270; on Aristotle's standard of animal structure, 281; on A.'s wealth of facts, 290 Spleen, Aristotle's description of inaccu- rate, 165 Sponges, pronounced by Aristotle to be animals, 184, 193; Imperato's descrip- tion of, 193; A.'s opinion adopted by the Moderns, ib. Spontaneous Generation. See Genera- tion Spontaneous fission. See Monogenesis Sprengel, cited, 159, 168; suggests that Aristotle may have dissected the human body, 163 26 402 INDEX. Stagira, the birthplace of Aristotle, 6j its situation, ib. Stagirite. See Aristotle Stalil , on the functions of the Soul, 223; said to teach the same doctrine as Aristotle, ib. ; on the Vital Principle, 228 Stahr, his article on Aristotle in the Dictionary of Greek and Roman Philosophy cited, 6 Stars, Aristotle's theory of their sub- stance, 138, 139, 140 Statics, founded by Archimedes, 147, 379 Stenon, cited, 332, 333, 353 St. Hilaire, Barthelemy, his assertion of the accuracy ,of Aristotle's Physics, 46 ; his Introduction cited, ib. ; on A.'s theory of Motion, 126; his version of the Physics, 128 ; his idolatry of A., 130; his translation of Aristotle's Meteorology, 143; his version of the VeAnimd, 221. Cited, 112, 145 St. Hilaire, Geoffrey, cited, 183, 208, 218, 280, 319, 374; pronounces the chain of creation a chimsera, 188; his docjarine of the " unity of composi- tion," ib.; on the development of the impregnated ovum, 215 St. Hilaire, isi'dore, his eulogy on Aris- totle, 155;- quotes Buffon on the theory of gradation, 188; on herma- phroditism, 209; his wonderful goat, 285*. Cited, 3, 23, 183, 190, 195, 207, 208, 270, 295, 309, 374 Stilling, cited, 113 St. Maur Benedictines, their Literary History of France cited, 32 ; their account of the auguries of the Druids, ib. ; on the essence of the Soul, 225 Strack's translation of the Hist. Animal., 269. Cited, 280 Subjective Method of interpreting Na- ture, 26, 34, 35; its influence, 35; contrasted with the Objective Method, ib.; arises from ignorance, 36, 63; relied on by the ancients, 49; its gradual relinquishment, 63 ; explana- tion of the preference for, ib. ; the meta- physical phase of, 65; account of the Subjective and Objective Methods, ib. ; error of Subjective Method tested, 81; Plato's frank avowal of, 103; its inability to measure physical forces, 300. See Objective Method, Ideal and Real Test Sunderall, his Die Thierarten desAris- toteles, cited, 279 ...... Sun's atmosphere, metals disolosedm, by spectrin analyses, 70 Swainson, on Aristotle's greatness, 270 Swammerdamm, his patient observa- tions, 158 ; on the Heart as the great " cooking centre," 174; on the Ephe- meron, 329. Cited, 220, 275, 353 Syllogism, Inductive, the basis of science, 115 Sylvius (Leboe), cited, 323 Syngenesis, ancient theory of, 353. See Generation Syrian Mole. See Mole. Taste, Aristotle on the sense of, 179. See. Senses Tauchnitz, edition of A.'s works, 22 Taurellus, his attack on Csesalpinus cited, 2, 168, 228, 305, 333, 347 Telesius, cited, 2, 178; his Be Naturd Rerum, 177 ; his misconception of Aristotle's illustration of the Vital Principle, 232 ; held light to be visible heat, 248 Telescope, the, alleged to have been known to the ancients, 186 ; but theirs was a tube without a lens, ib. ; supposed discovery of, by Roger Bacon, ib. Tension, identical with vis viva, 123 Terror, its effect on animals, 302; its cause, ib. Testacea, Aristotle on sight and hear- ing of, 287 Test (Ideal), placed above the Real by Aristotle, 68, 69; when subjectively true, ib. ; must be supplemented by the Real Test, 80. See Real Test Testes. See Organism, Generation, Embryology Thales, cited by Whewell, 89 Thielmann, cited, 158 Theology : progress impeded by the theo- logical conception of Nature, 31; its hostility to physical science, 43 ; its gradual approximation to science, 44 ., . Theory (or Idea), its implied antithesis to Fact, 71, 74, 75 ; the real distinc- tion, 75, 76, 77, 78; may be trans- ferred from Metaphysics to Science, 84; or from Science to Metaphysics, 84, 85 " Thermoties, value of the science of, 301 Thompson, Allen, cited, 351 Tiedemann, cited, 323 . Tiraboschi, his History of Italian Lite- rature, cited, 2, 118 Titze, his ingenious suggestion concern- ing the Hist. Animal., 279 Timceus, Plato's, cause of the scientific extravagances in, 103; idea of the genesis, 104. Cited, 334, 335 INDEX. 403 Torpedo: weight of its eggs and of the developed young, 216 Torstrik, A., his recension of the De Anima, 221 j on the Intellect, 240 Touch, Aristotle on the sense of, 179. See Senses Trendelenberg, his edition of the De Anima cited, 118; on Aristotle's meaning of jropoi, 169. Cited, 240 252 Treriranus, makes a separate kingdom of the Cryptogamic plants and Zoo- phytes, 1 88 ; his definition of Life, 221 Cited, 231 Truth, Hegel on the meaning of, 80; Descartes' erroneous criterion of, 83 Tyson, cited, 319 UNpoRMiTT in Nature. See Nature. Universals, importance attached to by Aristotle, 116, 117 Universe, Plato's idea of the creation of, 105, 106 Uterus, Aristotle's description of, 164, 165, 215, 334, 335, 336 ; error of the ancient anatomists respecting, 332, 333; Plato's description of, 335 "Valenciennes, cited, 210 Vallisneri, cited, 352, 353, 354 Van Beneden, his M&moire sur les Vers Intestinaux cited, 327 Vander Hooven's Handbook on Zoology cited, 295 VanHelmont, cited, 263; on the " poi- sonous quality of bull-beef," 303 Vatican, the ancient anatomical figures in, 161 Vegetal Soul, an existence sui generis, . 30; Schuyl on vegetal Life, 229 Verany, cited, 197 Verification, the guarantee of Science, 33 ; the ruling principle of investiga- tion, 57, 58; its process slow and diffi- cult, 59 ; want of appreciation of amongst the Greeks, ib.; instance of Eratosthenes, ib.; A. 's carelessness of verification, 59, 171, 172 ; Haller's patient labours in, 60; instance of Miiller, ib.; the criteria of verifica- tion, 68, 69 ; its immense applica- bility, 70; insolubility of all questions beyond it, ib. ; instance of metals in the sun's atmosphere, ib. ; future verification of propositions now in- soluble, ib. ; urgent demand for, 81 ; the principle of verification our best guide in Science, 96; the slow appre- ciation of, 377, 378 Vertebrae, vaiieties of in different ani- mals, 85 Vertebral Theory, Aristotle's claim to, 186, 187 Vesalius, cited, 163, 167, 169, 332, 333; notices Aristotle's error in attributing eight ribs to Man, 165; first discovers the nature of the bone of the heart. 313 Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation, views of Meckel adopted in, 188 Vicq d'Azyr, on the objective interpre- tation of Nature, 31 ; on our natural horror at dissection, 162. Cited, 157, 190, 191, 320 Virboslai, Margaret, Countess, her ex- traordinary parturition, 374 Virtual velocities, the principle of known to Aristotle, 148 Viscera, Aristotle's diagnosis' of, 310 ; the opinion of Democritus objected to by A., ib.; remarks on the viscera of the Apoda, 317; of molluscs and insects, 318 Vision, Aristotle on, 237, 246, 247 ; Newton on the sparks of the eye, 247 Vital Phenomena, Aristotle's idea of an ascending complexity in, 189. See Nature, Phenomena Vital Principle, impersonation of, 87 ; results of its increased activity, 193 ; of plants and animals, 194; the nearest translation of Aristotle's i>vxn, 222 ; the nature of, 225, 226, 227, 228 ; " divided vitality," 228; Aristotle's conception of, 231, 232, 233; regarded by A. as a final cause, 234; the intel- lect of, 240 Viviparity. See Incubation Vogt, cited, 197, 218 Vogt and Pappenheim, cited, 332 Von Baer, on the difference between the Vertebrate and Invertebrate types, 189 ; completed the discovery of the Mammalian egg, 213. Cited, 216, 295, 333, 353, 354, 357 Von Siebold, on Aristotle's acquaint- ance with the Cephalopoda, 199; his researches on the parthenogenesis of bees, 205 Vulpian and Philipeaux, on the import- ance of Verification, 60 Warmth and Moisture, essential to growth and Life, 268 Wessling, his Syntagma cited, 169, 333 Whewell, Dr., cited, 49, 150; on the failure of Greek Philosophy, 52; his History of the Inductive Sciences 404 INDEX. cited, 52 ; his conclusion as to the failure of ancient science, 53, 88 ; this conclusion examined, 53, 54 ; his History of Scientific Ideas cited, 55; on the first attempts to comprehend Nature, 88 ; on the employment of abstractions, ib.; on the propensity to seek for principles in the usages of language, 89 ; on Aristotle's sub- servience to language, ib. ; his re- proach against Aristotle, 147; on the constitution of a classification, 278 Willis, his Opera Omnia cited, 169 Wimmer, cited, 142, 340, 346 "Wolff, C. F., cited, 310, 354, 355 Wollaston, cited, 70 Xbnocratbs, accompanies Aristotle on his visit to Hermias, 12; teaches in the Academy, 15 Xenophon, on the repugnance of Socrates to physical inquiries, 43 ZELLER,-his Philosophy of the Greeks cited, 6, 118; on Ether as an element, 140 Zoology. See Animals, Plants, Gene- ration, Biology Zoophytes, plant-animals the second step in natural gradation, 192; ex- amples selected by Aristotle, ib. See Plants. THE END. London : Printed by Smith, Eldee and Co., Little Green Arbour Court, Old Bailey, E. C.