M84 1853 : .. :■ --,.'■; -;''■.'■ The Anthon Libi\ary. < i » i » COLLECTED BY CHARLES ANTHON, Professor of Greek and Latin in Columbia College* Pwchased by Cornell University, 1868. BT111 .M C 8 4 e i853 VerS,,y "^ Investigatiori o| the Tririity of Plato an olin 3 1924 029 373 671 Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924029373671 AN INVESTIGATION OF THE TRINITY OF PLATO AND OF PHILO JUDvEUS. Be'Xrioy tffws eiriarKe\j/a(TdaL t Kal dtawoprjaai, tus XeytTai, Kaiirep 'TrpocrdvTovs tjjs TOtavTTjv yevofievij'S ^ijTtfcreu**, ita t^ ipikovs ai/8pa$ tlvayayelv Ta eMij. delete 3' av ?o-ws (34\tiov eli/ai, «ai 3eii/ ctt! i\o. vvv &e ireipa>p.e8a toOto fir) KaTakiireiv. [p. 973. A,B.] EPINOMIS. intitle any one to the name of a wise man. He then proceeds to inquire, what knowledge that is, the want of which would render man the most irrational of animals. This, he says, is the know- ledge of number, which he considers as the gift of some god to man. For it would be absurd to sup- pose, that the author of all other good things to us should not be the author of the greatest also, which is Wisdom. Without the knowledge of number a man cannot have reason (X070S 3 ;) if he were destitute of sound reason, he would not be wise, if he should not attain wisdom, which is a 3 very considerable ingredient in all virtue, he would: not be completely good or happy. The God, that gave number, is the heaven, who taught men the first principles of numera- 3 Srepd/ieros Se diKridovs Xdyov, aoKpos ovk av JTOTe •yevoiTO" otio Bi aocpia pr] irpcxreir), jrdo-rjs aperfjs to piyiarov pipos, ovk av ere reXeW dyaBbs yevopsvoS) evba.Lp.atv Trore yevoiTO' ovrats dptBpbv piv dvdynri irao-a viroTl8eo-8ai.. [p. 977 D.] This doctrine is similar to what he says in his Republic, (Lib. vii. p. 522.) to ee re Kal ra Svo Kal ra Tpla ftiayiyvdo-Kew. Ae'yo) 8e avrb cor iv K£up.ev abtkfpovs r thai, Kai iv ade\,rar, eavp.aa-uordras 8e ras Kivjo-w KaX xopeias, iv rd| fo -«< npp.otrp.ivas Ka \ Aprf^ a 'xa- \oyiats Kai mpdbav av^avims. 'Ev oh faao-i ■njv apxi-rmroj) EPINOMIS. knowledge of number and its proportions there cannot be reason (\6yos), without reason, wisdom, without wisdom an harmony of soul, virtue, and happiness 8 . According to this interpretation of the passage 5 before us, it does not immediately relate to the creation of the world, nor does it at all express the personality of the Logos. Pythagoras first called the world ko*>* a(j> tjs ol fiera ravra avOpconoi ypayjrdp.epoi rais eavrcou TJrvxdZs, avayKcuoTaTTjv Kai dfa'kip.wTaTTjv Te^vr/v rm /3i'o> TrapeSocrav. 9 Thus Cicero, Le Legibus, i. 7 : Dasne igitur hoc nobis, Pom- pom (nam Quinti novi sententiam) Deorum immortalium na- tura, ratione, potestate, mente, numine, sive quod est aliud verbum, quo planius significem quod volo, naturam omnem regi? — Id, quod tibi concessi, quorsum pertineat, expecto. — Hue pertinet, animal hoc quem vocamus hominem generatum esse a summo Deo — Solum est — particeps rationis — Quid au- EPINOMIS. In the Dialogue before us, Plato, when hey speaks of the universe merely as a production, ascribes it to soul (\|/-ux>7)> an active and governing p. 988. [d.] principle (^pv^rjs o'varis aiTias tov bXov), in opposi- tion to body, which is passive and subject to con- p. 983. [d] trol (apxpnevov Kai ava'iTiov iracrijs Tra9>]s). But when he is speaking of the harmony and congruity of the parts of the whole, he assigns it to reason or intelligence, that faculty which is conversant with order and proportion, in opposition to chance or the random tendencies of matter. The doctrine maintained in this Dialogue, is essentially the same, as that which has been em- bellished in modern times by the pens of Shaftes- bury and Hutcheson, viz. that virtue is founded in a love of order and proportion. It is a doctrine 8 which appears everywhere in the writings of Plato, tern est, non dicam in homine, sed in omni coelo atque terra, ratione divinius? Quae cum adolevit, atque perfecta est, no- minatur rite sapientia. Again, ii. 13 : Cum summos Deos esse coneedamus, eorumque mente mundum regi, et eorundem be-, nignitatem hominum consulere generi. And to this same pur- pose in his Dialogues, De Nat. Dear. ii. 38: Quis enim hunc hominem dixerit, qui, cum tarn certos cceli motus, tarn ratos astrorum ordines, tamque inter se omnia connexa et apta vide- rit, neget in his ullam inesse rationem, eaque casu fieri dicat, quae quanto consilio gerantur, nullo consilio adsequi possumus? An cum machinatione quadam moveri aliquid videmus, ut sphEeram, ut horas, ut alia permulta ; non dubitamus, quin ilia opera sint rationis ? Cum autem impetum coeli cum admirabili celeritate moveri vertique videamus, constantissime conficien- tem vicissitudines anniversarias cum summa salute et conser- vatione rerum omnium ; dubitamus, quin ea non solum ratione fiant, sed etiam excellenti divinaque ratione? Xenophori Memorab. i. 4. speaks of Zpya yvv Kai prj Kakas drjptovpyTjdevrcov i] fir/ Kakms fpvvrcov 6£vraT av al- adavoLTo'] 6 e«€i rpav] ret pep Ka\a iiraivo'i, Kai ^alpcuv, Kai KaTabexopevos els ttjv \jtV)(Tp> TpecpoiT av an airrav, Kai ylyvotro Kakos T€ KayaOos : Lib m. p. 401 [d].. Again, 'Opas odv on as appovia nvi rj o~a>(ppoavvi] Tat. IV. p. 431 [e]. PARMENIDES. HTHE Parmenides is perhaps one of the most diffi- 9 -*- cult of the Dialogues of Plato. The expression and the reasoning are so general and abstracted, particularly in the part where ei>, ev 7roXXa, and ev Kal 71-oXXa are discussed; that it is not easy to determine precisely the meaning of those terms. Serranus supposes the one infinite Being and second causes to be the subjects of discussion. Other authors, deservedly of great name, have thought that they have discovered the three per- sons of the ever-blessed Trinity delineated under the articles ev, ev troWa, and ev Kal noWa. Le Clerc, in his Ars Critica, P. 11. S. 1. cxiv, delivers his opi- nion concerning it in the following terms : Primus omnium tria principia constitute Parmenides, et post eum Plato ; qui an consenserint, non satis liquet, quod Parmenidis non supersit prater obscura fragmenta. Plato autem dixit primum esse to ov, o'ltiov airavTwv, ens, causam omnium rerum : secundum vero Xoyov, Rationem et Rectorem prcesentium et futurorum : ter- 10 tium denique yj/v^v koct/ulov, animam sive spiritum mundi. The passages, referred to in support and illus- tration of this opinion in other parts of Plato's writings, will be considered in their order. I shall at present confine myself to the Parmenides, con- PABMENIDES. cerning the subjects of which Dialogue Cudworth Int &c - authority of Plotinus, as appears from the following extract : " Wherefore Parmenides his whole philoso- phy (saith Plotinus) was better digested, and more exactly and distinctly set down in Plato's Parme- nides, where he acknowledged three Unities subor- dinate, or a Trinity of divine hypostases. Which observation of Plotinus is, by the way, the best key, that we know of, for that obscure book of Plato's Parmenides " The last part of the quo- tation seems to me to imply that he accepted this key, not because he was perfectly satisfied with it, but because he knew of no other so good for unlocking the intricacies of that obscure book. He in fact appears to have considered it as the most plausible hypothesis that had fallen in his way. If, therefore, we can obtain a key from the book itself, which will unlock its intri- cacies in a manner consistent with the subject of the discourse, with the train of reasoning adopted i in it, with the philosophic principles of the charac- ters introduced, and with the manner of their ap- plying those principles ; I am persuaded that every judicious reader will acknowledge such a key to be infinitely more valuable, than any arbitrary hypo- thesis of Plotinus, however specious it may have appeared, before this key was presented to him. Before I enter upon the investigation, it will be proper to observe, that Parmenides is the chief speaker of the Dialogue; and that the princi- ples, advanced in it, are the principles of that io PABMENIDES. philosopher, from whom Plato differed in opinion on some particular points, as we are told by Aris- totle. Let it be no objection to this observation, that the discourse was held in the presence of Socrates* that he bore a part in the beginning of it, and that he was in a great degree the occasion of the whole. Socrates was the master of Plato ; and the sentiments and reasonings which are assigned 1 to him, may in general be safely considered as the sentiments and reasonings of Plato himself. It was likewise the usual custom, and indeed the chief employment of Socrates, to correct what he saw amiss in the practice and opinions of those with whom he conversed ; and, above all, to detect the fallacious principles, and refute the false rea- sonings of the philosophers and sophists of his time. His express approbation, therefore, and his tacit aquiescence, had commonly the same ten : n dency, though perhaps not so often the same force. But upon the present occasion, Socrates is represented in a situation, in which he does not often appear in the works of Plato. He is intro- duced in this Dialogue at a time of life when he was not a teacher, but a learner ; when it was customary with him, as he tells us in his Phcedo, to attend the different philosophers of distinguished note ; in order that he might be able, by impartial observation, to discover whose doctrine was most consistent with the reality of things, and of course, under whose guidance, he should put himself in his PARMENIDES. future inquiries. It was not till he despaired of receiving any effectual assistance from others, that he struck out a method of philosophizing pecu- liarly his own. In this Dialogue, therefore, con- trary to what is the case in most others, we must not consider the acquiescence and approbation of Socrates as the same. Yet even here Plato appears to treat his mas- ter with exquisite delicacy. He makes him indeed propose his objections to the principles of Zeno, and defend the consequences deduced from those objections with an ingenuousness suitable to his age ; and he at length makes him, with the same ingenuousness, acknowledge himself confounded by his veteran antagonist, who was by long practice versed in all the subtleties of disputation. But 13 when Parmenides is prevailed upon to explain his own principles, the office of replying, and of course either of opposing or of expressing an acquiescence, is transferred to Aristotle ; and So- crates takes no part in the remainder of the Dia- logue. I have thought it necessary to make these observations, lest any one should think, that it is a serious objection to the interpretation here pro- duced, if the principles attributed to Parmenides should seem not always exactly to agree with the principles maintained by Plato under the character of Socrates, in other parts of his writings. I will now proceed to examine the Dialogue itself. Among the persons of the Dialogue was Par- menides, an old philosopher, who had maintained morgan. B 12 PABMENIDES. ev eivai to irav, av, 1( that the universe is (one thing j; by which, I conceive, he meant one (system^ and that all the things which subsist have a mutual connexion with each other, and subsist in it as parts of one whole. Zeno was a friend of Parme- nides, and some years younger than himself. He had maintained, ov iroXXa eivcu, ' that [it] is not many', does not consist of separate unconnected parts. Socrates, then a youth, was desirous of knowing the meaning and foundation of those 14 doctrines, which Zeno affirmed not to be pre- cisely the same, though his reasoning operated as a defence of the doctrine of his friend. The first point which demands our attention, is to discover what is the real subject of the Dia- logue. The nature of the objection urged by Socrates, the reply to it by Parmenides, and the defence of it afterwards by Socrates, deserve our serious consideration ; as they may fairly be sup- posed to be founded upon the subject of debate. — As so many parts enter into the composition of the universe, it is obvious, that, if it can be deno- minated one_thing, it must be so, because it is capable of being comprehended under one e!$09 or general abstract form. Now the difficulty that oc- curred to Socrates in the doctrine of Zeno, which 1 It is probable, that his theological opinion did not essen- tially differ from that of Thales : 6AAHS vovv tov koVjxou rbv 6e6v rA 8e irav eptyvxov apa Kai Smpovav ir\ijpes u Stobsei Eclogce Physical, 1. [2. § 29]. This was also the great outline of the theology of the Stoics. 2 Ov vopifas clvai aM Kaff avrb cld6s rt 6poi6Tr,ros, K al r<5 toioirtp aS SXKo ti ivavriov, & tan avofioiov; tovtoiv 8e, Svoiu- PARMENJDES. 13 denies a plurality, was this, that there are many distinct 2 ei'5jj, general abstract forms, each sub- sisting separately and independently. What does Parmenides reply to this ? Does he say, You mis- take the nature of the thing or being, the unity of which I maintain ? No. He undertakes to shew 15 the contradictions, which, according to his rea- soning, would arise from supposing, that the several eiStj, ' species' or general abstract forms, subsist unconnectedly, and in a manner that is inconsistent with the unity of to irav, 'the universe' 3 . I am well persuaded that the language and mode of reasoning adopted in this Dialogue, will appear very harsh and forced to modern appre- hensions, which are more conversant and better pleased with the dictates of sound sense confined within its proper limits, than with the logical sub- tilties of ancient metaphysics. But if we would arrive at the genuine sense of an author, we must be contented to accompany him upon his own terms, and to reason with him upon his own prin- ciples. The specimen, which I have produced, will perhaps be sufficient to convince most people that I have rightly stated the subject of the debate. If ovtoiv, koi ipe kcu to hi bv ur/, [p. 143 a.] This will appear very peculiar reasoning to those, who have not some acquaintance with the language of ancient metaphysics. But Aristotle tells us, that this verb, e'o-ri, is, by its efficacy to destroy the unity of unit in being predicated of it, gave such disturbance to the philoso- phers, who maintained an unity of principle, that some of them, as Lycophron, struck it out. Others changed the form of the expression ; as, for instance, they would not say, The man is walking, but, The man walks ; lest, by applying the word is, they should make one thing to be many. As if, says Aristotle, unity and existence were expressed only in one manner : 'Edo- pvjiiovvTo 8e xai oi vo-repot, KaQajrep oi dpxatoi, prj 7rore o-vpfialvti airoTs apa to giro hi flvai Km noXKa. Aid oi piv to eo-rii/ dv io-Ttv, dXka ^aSifei- iva p), T0 ? i"' irpoo-dirTovres, jroXXa elvai noiao-i t& h>, as pova X S>s Xeyopevov row ivbs fj tov ovros.—Natur. Auseult. Lib. I. [Oh. 2. ed. Sekk.] Plato in Thecetetus gives a similar account of the PARMENIDE13. 17 two, and consequently can be no longer one 6 . Now 19 says he, unity, when by the hypothesis it partakes of existence, becomes many ; though, when it is contemplated alone by the understanding in its simple state, it appears Only an unit 7 . This rea- soning of our author is thus ridiculed by Theopom- pus, ev yap e. 26.] Moreover, not only ev, when it partakes of ovaia, 'existence', will become many in number, that is, branch out into an infinite multitude of units or species ; but also each of those will be rendered limited in its nature, {treTrepauixevov av eirj) distinguished by a particular form. The specific forms, thus infinite in multitude, though they branch out from ev, ' unit' 8 , and centre in it, will be doctrine of some philosophers concerning the material elements: "Ey© yap av eboKow aKOveiv Tivav, on ra pev irpayra olairepeX q-toi- \eia, c§ av ijpe'is re o-vyKclucOa fan TaXXa, \6yov ovk ex 01 ' a ^ ro yap Kaff avrb ekaxrrov ovopaaai povov e'lrj, irpoo-evnelv 8e ovbtv aXXo 8vvar6v, oijff as eariv, ov6* as ovk eo-nv 17817 yap av ovo-lav, rj prj ov- ariav avra npoarWeo-dai. deiv 8e oiiSev irpoo-cpepeiv, elirep airo eKeivo povov tis epei, p. 201, 2. ? Auto to ev, 6 Si} cpap.iv ova-ias peTe\eiv, eav airo tj diavoiq povov Kaff avrb \aj3apev, avev tovtov, 0$ (papev pere^eiv, Spa ye ev povov (pavrjo-erai r) (cat jroXXa to avrb tovto ; ev, oipai eyaye, [p. 143 A.] s Plato in the Philebus explains at large the process of re- ducing many distinct things to one. Things, which in their own nature admit of more or less, such as hot, cold, swift, slow, &c, are not only many and various, but also opposite to each other. Yet being collected and classed under the genus of un- limited, they become one. Or, as he expressed it again, The unlimited presented many genera ; but being impressed with the genus of more and its opposite, it appeared one : IloXXa ye Kai rb aireipov wapea , \eTo yevrj' Spas 8' £irur Kai 7ro\\d) connected with time, and partly partaking of existence and partly not?. These individuals, subject to generation and de- struction, are unlimited both in number and in nature 10 . The specific form gives them a limitation 21 in their relation to other species ; while their own nature produces an unlimited variety in the parti- culars of the same species. This will receive illustration from the Philebus, in which Dialogue Plato makes Socrates divide the paKXov Kai ivavrlov yevei ev et), p. 26 [d]. How much more easy is it, says he, to reduce under one head those things, which by their nature are limited, and are not severally many ! Kal pfjv to ye trepas otfre jroXXa eiftev, °" T ' ebvo-Ko\aivopep as ovk fjv iv (pvo-ei. — lb. 9 T6 iv el eoTiv, otov SieXrfKvdapev, ap* ovk dvdyia] avrb, ev re ov Kai TroXXa, Kai pyre iv prjre TroXXa, (cat perexo" XP^ V0V ' "" /*'" eanv ev, oio-ias pere^etv jrore; on Se ovk coti, p.rj pere^etv aS irore ovo-ias, [p. 155 E.] They are called iv Kai TroXXa, as con- sisting of idea or form, which is one, and matter, which is de- nominated many. 10 Ovkovv ovtcos de\ o-Koirovvn avrfjv Kaff avTrjV tiji/ erepav (bvo-iv tov e?8ovs, So-ov av avrrjs del opmpev, aireipov eo-rai irkridei Xoir aXXots &j tov evos avp.flal.vei, ck pev tov ivbs Kai eg eavrav Koiva- PARMENIDE8. tp principles of things into two kinds. First, matter and its qualities, which admitting in its own nature degrees of more and less, and having nothing in its nature to confine those qualities, he calls airetpov, 'unlimited'. Secondly, specific form, which con- taining in its own nature a principle of limitation, he calls yrepas, and e%ov irepas 11 . The first he likewise calls 7ro\\a, as being many in its nature 12 . But the latter is opposed to it as being characteristically different ; since it does not admit of that denomination in its nature 13 . Though he had 14 before Said that each kind is divided into many in number. Out of these two conjoined arises a third class, which comprises all particular things 15 . %% Of this union he produces several instances : among others, in disorders a proper limitation, ap- plied to the constituent parts of the body, produces health 16 . Again, limitation being applied to sharp, flat, swift, and slow sounds, which are in their own nature unlimited, constitutes music. vt\aavrav, as eolKev, erep6v ti yiyveaBai ev avTois, o 8rj wepas 7rdpeo~xe 7rpbs aXkrjXa' 77 fie avratv pa- £eiv. [p. 24A.] 13 Kai ji-qv Toye irepas oifre fl-oXXa el%ev. [p. 26 D.] M Ta hio tovtchv ireipdficda noWa eKarepov eo~xio~p.evov (cat 8iev Kai dXX^Xa>v Koivaviq Travraxpv avra£6p.eva, sroXXa eo-8ai eKaarov, p. 467 [a]. Again in the tenth book: EiSos yap ttov tl iv eKao-rov elddapev TiSca0at 7ripl eKaa-ra Ta iroWa, oh Tavrov ovopa emopas Kai e'iBrj. — Nat. Ausc. I. 6. [Ch. 4. ed. Bekker.J 22 PABMENIDES. and to comprehend all subsisting beings : 7ras yap Acyos /ecu Tracra emaTr/txri twv kol9o\ov kch ov twv etr^aTtoi/, coctt eir] av ovtw twv TrpwTwv yevwv Tavra 06 ytyvoiT av to tb ov Kat to eV raura 'yct/j jkaKiaT av VTro\rj eKdGTov), were considered as the only real existences and the objects of knowledge. The sensibles, which were the many (rd iroWd), being of a very different description, were the founda- tions of opinion only. Under the class of sensibles he comprehended not only every particular external object, of what kind soever, but also every particular act or con- crete quality belonging to it. There were many beautiful, many good, and many just things (71-oXXa KaXa, TroXXa dyaOd, kcli iroWd di/cata), which were all classed under sensibles {a'ujQrird) ; since the 26 notice of all particulars is conveyed by the senses. But the intelligibles (ret vonrd) were those things which are to be comprehended only by the under- * Ta flip Sfj opaadai (pafiev, voel&dai 8' ou- ras 8' ad Ibeas voeicrdat fiey, opa&dai 8' oil.—De Rep. VI. p. 507 [b]. 84 PLATO'S Doctrine of Ideas. standing with reason 2 . In this class were included not only spiritual substances, but also all general . abstract qualities (t. e. to ayadov nai to 6ikcuov.) So that, in fact, ev eKacrrov vorirov was the general or abstract idea, and to -koXKo. aiaOrird the several particulars arranged under it. Aristotle, who viewed nature with a more curious eye, and who was not so much under the influence of a lively and refined imagination, formed a very different judgment upon the sub- ject. He maintained that bodily or material ob- jects were most properly entities 3 . He divided entities (owi'ai) into primary and secondary. By primary entities he meant particulars, as a particu- lar man or a particular horse. By secondary en- tities he meant the species and genus, under which the particulars are classed. Thus the primary entity is a particular man : and the secondary en- tities are the species man and the genus animal 4 . His doctrine, therefore, is in this respect directly 27 opposite to that of his master. For he maintains 2 No^o-ft pera \6yov irepikriirrov. — Timceiis, p. 28 [a]. 3 Ovalai be im\i(TT efoai Sokovcti to. cra'fiara. — De Anvnui) II. 1. And again : Aeyto 8' ovcrlas p-ev ra tc air\a trajxaxa, olov irvp (cm yfjv, Ka\ $ dvdpairar yevos be rov eioavs earl to £S>ov bevrepai oiv avTai. Xeyovrai ovo-lai, oloV o re avdpcoiros Kal t& £5>ov. — Categor. 5. 5 At Trp&Tai, oio-lai, bia. to rdis aXXois anraaiv vnoKela-Bai— KvpuoTwra ovo-lai Xeyovrai — Mi) oia-Sv oiv rav Trparmv ova-lav, dbvvarov ratv SXXav n etvai. — Ibid. 6 Udo-a be ova-la Sonet rdbe n o-qpaiveiv on p,ev olv rav PLATO'S Doctrine of Ideas. 25 that particulars are the only proper entities : that the species and genus exist only in a second- ary sense ; and that they could not exist at all, were it not for the particulars or primary entities 5 . Now, says he, an entity seems to point out some actual and particular thing, which a primary entity truly and indisputably does. Indeed by the con- struction of the sentence a secondary entity ap- pears to do so, but does not in reality. It expresses only the quality 6 . The reason why many philosophers held general ideas to be the real entities, was, as Aristotle very justly observed 7 , that they regarded particular objects as transitory and fleeting. On this account 38 Plato characterizes his entities as always the same, and permanent in their nature and rela- tions to each other (act Kara ra aura teal wcravTws e^ovra). In the Philebus he divides knowledge into two kinds : First, experimental knowledge, which he places in a secondary class, as being con- versant about fluctuating and perishable things. irpt&Tcov ovfritav dvaptfiurfiriTrjTOV Kal dKjjdes corn* on rode ti enj- fiaivct- aropov yap Kai €v dpidpcp to drjXovpevov io-Tiv. eVi 8e tcou deurtpav ovencov (palverai pAv opolcos tco o-fflpan Tfjs TrpotT- rjyoptas robe Ti orfpaivtiv, orav c'ttt; avdpairov 17 £&ov ov pf/v akqdis ye- aKKa paKKop 7roiov ti o-rjpaiver oi~ yap \cv inserit Bekker] cart ra viroKeipevop, aJcnrep f] irpaTTj oucr/a, aXXa Kara 7roXkcov 6 avdpanros Xeyerat Kal to £g>ov. — Ibid. 1 Ta pev ovv iv toIs alo-8r]ToXs KaBeKaara peiv ivopi£ov Ka\ pivciv oioev airav. — Metaph. xi. 12. 2we/3i7 &' ij nepl rav clSSv 8o|a rots tlirovtn, Sta ro ireioSrjpat nepl ttjs a\r]6eLas rois 'HpaK\eiTelois Xoyois, cos ndpTtav rav al(r6r]Tcdv ael peavtcov. cuctt f e'lirfp £moTr)pri twos coral Kai (ppoinjo-is, erepas detv Tipas (fivcreis curat irapa rar alo-BrjTas pevovcras ; ov yap curat r&v peovrav cVt- arfjprjv. — lb. cap. 4. 26 PLATO'S Doctrine of Ideas.' Secondly, abstract knowledge, which is entitled td the first class, as it respects things unchangeable and permanent 8 . Philo Judseus, no inconsiderable Platonist, founds a curious interpretation of Scripture Upon mpi-m? this doctrine of Plato. He says that the sacred Xepou/SijuL, p. 116, §15. wr it m g S on this account style God the husband, not of a virgin ; for that is changeable and mortal — but of virginity, which is of a permanent na- ture 9 . 8 'Emavep6v. [Ibid. D.] Concerning TO ArAeoN. 29 perfect enjoyment, or a mixture of those several ingredients 7 . Socrates was asked again, whether he thought the greatest good to be knowledge, or pleasure, or something else different from those 8 . He told them that he could not display to them to dyaOop itself; but he would set before them its offspring most like itself, which he afterwards explained to be knowledge in the mind and truth in things. By which I conceive him to mean, that to dyaOov, the most general idea of good, must be an abstract of the universal good, an object infinitely beyond the capacity of the human intellect, at least in the present state of man ; but that some resemblance of it may be attained by knowledge exercised upon 32 the truth of things. These, he says, are not to p sw- dyaOov, but dyaOoeiSij. They spring from the uni- versal good. In the Second Alcibiades, Socrates is [p i« &] made to ask what kind of state that would be which should be composed of men skilled in all other arts and sciences avev tjJs tov jSeXtio-toii eiriaT^ixrj^. Alcibiades is soon prevailed upon to acknowledge that it would be a state of the greatest confusion and anarchy: 'Ap ovk av opOws Xeyoi/uev, (jxxvres [p. us b] ttoAAjJs Tctjoa^jjs Te Kai avo/x'tas /xecrrrjv elvai Tt\v ToiavTtjv iroKiTe'tav. 6 Pinem bonorum, quo referuntur omnia, et cujus apiscendi causa sunt facienda omnia. — De Legg. 1. 20. Or, in the lan- guage of Plato, o &tj &6)kei pev cmcura ijrvx'l' Kai tovtov eveKa Ttdvra irparrei. • 1 Tayadov 8e oIkcwv ti Kai bvcrafpalperov. — Arist. Ethic. Nicom. I. 3. 8 TL&Tfpov eitujTr\p.r)V to ayadov <\>rjs eivai, rj rjhovfjv, % oaXK ti itapa Tavra, p. 606 [b]. 30 Concerning TO ArAedN. p.99[c]. Plato, in the Phcedo, makes Socrates, in dis- cussing the doctrine of Anaxagoras, speak with disapprobation of his not referring things to good- ness and fitness as their causes : ws aXtjOws ro dya- 66v ical Seov %vv$e7v /ecu fyveyeiv oiioev oiovrai. Here Seov, and of course to dyaQov, to which Socrates would refer the composition and support of things, must be the final cause. If any doubt of this could remain, it would be completely dispelled by a reference to what Socrates said in the pre- ceding page he expected from the profession of Anaxagoras. 'When', says he, ■ Anaxagoras pro- fessed that things were disposed by mind, I never imagined that he would assign any other cause for them than this, that it is best they should be in the manner in which they are' 9 . I will endeavour to throw some light upon this 33 subject from the works of contemporary writers. Xenophon was a scholar of Socrates at the same time with Plato, and has also handed down to posterity many of the discourses of that great teacher of morality to the Gentiles. Not being, like Plato, the founder of a sect and a lecturer by profession, he did not study to form an ingenious system with materials, culled with the nicest art from the traditions of diverse countries and the spe- culations of diverse masters. He told his artless tale with an unaffected though elegant simplicity. 9 Ov yap av jtotc ovtov wpyv, (pio-Kovrd ye u ff A v0 $ a t T fr KeKoa-fiTJcrdai, aXkTjv riva avrois alriav eireveyKuv, rj on BeknaTOV avra ovrtas *X flv *°' 7 ""'j e^et. io Ei n elbeiij ayadov. [i.e. if he knew of any thing good.] Concerning TO ArA90N. 31 It is not wonderful that the discourses of Socrates should appear different in the hands of such differ- ent relators. One of the most striking points of distinction is this, that in Xenophon Socrates always leads those who dispute with him from ab- stract and general reasonings to particulars. It happens that he has preserved a discourse between Socrates and Aristippus concerning the very subject of which we have been treating. As Xenophon is supposed not to have been on the most friendly terms with Plato, I cannot help think- ing that by a particular expression he meant to cast some ridicule upon this doctrine of our author, which Aristotle likewise seems to have thought very open to reprehension from the frequent strictures which he has passed upon it. 34 Xenophon tells us that Aristippus, desirous of mmorab.m, ensnaring Socrates, asked him if he knew what good is 10 ? Do you mean, says Socrates, good for a fever ? No. For weakness of eyes ? No. For hunger ? No. Then, says he, if you ask me whe- ther 1 know anything good, that is good for nothing, I neither know nor desire it 11 . He then proceeded to shew that there was nothing absolutely and uni- versally good ; for that good referred to some end ; and things that were handsome and good for some purposes, were unseemly and bad for others. Aristotle begins his Ethics with asserting that 11 \pa yap [leg. ye] eur(3riTov). Thus Xenophon and Aristotle arrive at the same point by different roads. It appears most evident to me, that Aristotle 36 throughout this whole chapter is controverting the doctrine of Plato concerning to dyaQov, and all his reasonings imply, that he understood his master to mean by it one general abstract idea of good, under which all other things intitled good are classed, which he calls koivov n kclOoXov kuI ev, and again, ev ti to Koivfj KaTtiyopov/xevov ayaQov. Aristotle begins his Cheat Morals with an enquiry about the same to dyaQov, which he pro- nounces to be the end of all knowledge and power (jrdo-rieiv) . Otherwise he would resemble a man, who, in order to prove that the angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles, should begin with proving the soul im- mortal. Now we can prove the proposition, with- out proving the immortality of the soul; and in like manner we can speculate upon other goods, without the abstract universal idea of good (aveu tov Kara Ttjv loiav aya9ou). Therefore this is not the peculiar principle of that good which you are seeking. La. i. s. Most of this reasoning is repeated in his Ethics to Eudemus, particularly, that a general abstract good is of no use in politics 16 . He calls it likewise to tov ayaGod e?8os. And that you may not SUp- 18 "On iih oiv ovk ea-nv ax/ro n dya66v, %« dnoptas roiairas, rail Sn oi XPWW H? ttoXitikS, aAXa ?8i6v ti aya66v, avirep icai rats SXKais. Concerning TO ArAGON. 33 pose it different from other species or general ideas, he says, wut etvai avro to dyadov tijv 3° iceav tov ayaQov' Kal yap ywpicrTrjv etvai tuv [xere- ■yovTiav, wairep Kal ras ak\as iSeas- I think, I have now said enough to prove that Plato did not intend by the term to ayaQov to express a person, and therefore that he could not mean by it the supreme Being, the first person of the Trinity ; but rather the final cause of things, as he says in the Philebus, to ye fiyv ov eveica to p 5t eveKa tou yiyvofievov aei ylyvoiT av ev Trj tov ayaQov fxo'ipa. eicelvo eo~Ti. In the Philebus, in which Plato professedly treats of the same subject, he does not soar quite so high into the regions of abstraction. The ques- tion having been started, whether pleasure (j^oi»J) or intellect and knowledge (vovs Kal eiriar^ixr)) are the greatest good ; in the course of the en- quiry he divides both pleasure and knowledge into two kinds, differing from each other in degrees of truth and reality; and concludes, that neither of them separately, but that a mixture of the most pure parts of each, constitutes that good which is the subject of enquiry. II NCv 87 Tis \6yos ifiqvv&ev rjpiv, acrirep Kai tear ap^as, prj fijTeiv iv t& afilitra /3io> rdyaBbv, dXV iv ra fitKrut, [p. 61 B.] Et to. akrjde&TaTa TprjpaTa eKarepas ISoipev Trp&rov £vp.p.i£avTes, apa iKava. ravTa £vy]fi[xe\e[a9 to aaifia eyovTt, e/c oe tjJs d9a- vctTov aTroppoqs tov vovv oia\aix/3dvovTi — 'loiov oe crap- kwv fxev rjoovai, vov oe \oyos — evTavda To'tvvv yjTei to avOpwTrov ayadov, birov to 'epyov — evTavda to epyov, birov to bpyavov ' evTavda to bpyavov, oirov to aw^ov — tl 'yvyris opyavov , vovs- C*]T6i to epyov- tl vov epyov ; (ppovrjcrK ' evpes to ayaOov. Dissert. XXXIV. 47 EPISTLES. The Second Epistle to DIONYSIUS. THE reasoning and expression used in the Phi- lebus will serve to throw some light upon a passage in the second Epistle to Dionysius : »)s [p. 312 d.] yap o»7 Kara, tov ske'ivov \6yov, ov% Ixavws aTrooeoei^- 6ai croi wept Trjs tov wpcoTov (pvcxews. Qpacneov or/ o~ol 01 awiyixwv — woe yap e%ei Trepi tov iravTwv pa- ciXea iravT eo~Tt Kai eiceivov eve/ca iravTa' Kai eicelvo aiTiov airdvTixiv twv koKwv. oevTepov oe irepl tu oevrepa Kai Tp'iTov Trept Ta Tp'iTa. When we consider the character of Dionysius, and call to mind that the 'purpose of Plato's visit- ing him was to inculcate moderation upon him ; it is natural to suppose, that the reasoning used in the Philebus, would constitute a very important part of the Lectures delivered by the Philosopher to the 48 Prince. He would state to him that there are in the universe three principles, a-rreipov, irepas, Kai to Trj/au- ovpyos and irctTtjp. 5 i CRATYLUS. THE same terms in the Philebus are likewise ex- planatory of the following passages in the Cratylus: Ov yap'ecrriv rifxiv nal toIs etXAots Traatv, [p. 39c a.] octtk earlv a'lrios [xaWov tov <£rjv, rj 6 ap^wv re Kal j3a 8eos elvai, 01 bv t£rjv aei Traai toTs ^waiu vwap-^ei. Cudworth saw the necessity of referring here to \J/-ux>7 \ the third hypostasis of his Platonic Trinity, those very titles, which in other passages he supposes to be applied as distinguishing characteristics to the two other hypostases. But the truth is that they all refer to that one principle of life and intelligence, which was supposed to per- vade the universe, and regulate all its motions and operations. 1 Hanc ego mallem interpretationem junioribus, a quibus profecta est, Platonicis, Plotino et ceteris reliquisset vir doctis- simus, quam suam fecisset. Nee enim, quamvis Plato Saturni, Jovis et Coeli loco isto mentionem faciat, ullum ego ibi vesti- gium video trium illorum principiorum, multo minus cum tri- bus his Platonicorum principiis tria Grrsecorum nomina componi cerno. Pessimi, meo judicio, Platonis interpretes sunt, qui post natum Servatorem Platonicorum adoptarunt sibi vocabulum. Quorum quidem animi, quoniam tribus illis principiis toti erant infecti et imbuti, ideo ubivis ea quoque sagacius, quam fas erat, in Platone venabantur, cujus quippe prsecepta videri volebant unice inculcare. — Mosbem. in he. Tom. 1. p. 380. TIMM US. & fFHE Timceus of Plato cuts so distinguished a -*- figure in the present question, and has been so often quoted and referred to by authors, that we may venture to enter upon an examination of it without any further preface. [p. 27 dj Timseus, who is the supposed expositor of the system advanced in this Dialogue, divides things into two classes. First, what is without beginning and unchangeable, which is comprehended by the understanding with reasoning. Secondly, what is made, and perishes, and is the subject of opinion only, being in its nature variable, and having no- thing in it so stable, as to furnish the materials of knowledge properly so called. What is made, necessarily implies an author. Now whatever the Creator forms, looking at what is invariable and using such a pattern, must be completely beautiful. But whatever he forms, looking at what has been made and using such a pattern, will not be completely beautiful. Having considered the universe, and concluded from its being visible, that it was made ; he next enquires whether the Creator in forming it looked 53 at an invariable pattern, or at one that was made, and asserts, it is manifest, from the beauty of the work and the excellence of the Creator, that he TIM ^E US. 49 looked at what is unchangeable. For, says he, that is the most beautiful of the things which have been made, and he is the best of causes. Thus it was formed according to a pattern, comprehensible by reason and thought, and unvarying. Having thus distinguished the image and the pattern, he states the nature of the account which he is about to give. He calls it only a probable rp 29 ci story and probable reasonings (eiKora pvOou kvos nXarfflV o&x 6/»oXoy«i, Xeyav dpxas ehat Qebv, Kai v\r]V Kai irapaSeiypa Her- mise Irrisio Gentil. Philosoph. [c. xi. p. 221]. 50 TIM^EUS. he composed the whole, that he might complete a work most beautiful and excellent in its nature. Thus ought we to say, according to a probable account (/caret \6yov tov eiKora) that this world was in truth made an animated and intelligent being by the Providence of God (Sid rfiv tov Qeou yeveaOai irpovoiav). The whole composition of the soul, he says, was completed according to the mind of the composer (Kara, vovv ^vviaTavri). When he speaks afterwards of the production of time, in which this animated and intelligent being should exist, he says, Therefore from such [p. 38 c] reasoning and consideration of God (e£ ovv Xo- •you Kal eiavoias Qeou roiavrrjs) the sun, &c. was made. From all this it appears most evident to me, that \oyi ° s avT0 l** v KaXov Kai ibeav Tiva ovtov KaXKovs firjbefiiav qyeiTai del Kara Tavra acrav- Ttos ()(ov(rav TroXXa be Ta KaKa vofii^ei eKelvos 6 L\o6eap.a>v, Ka\ ovftofifi avexop-evos, av Tiff ev to Ka\ov fpi} eivai Kai biKaiov Kai TaAAa ovra. True philosophers he characterizes thus, [p. 479 e] : tow aira cKaara deapevovs Kai del Kara to avra acravrms ovra. Again, in the beginning of the following book, he defines phi- losophers, [p. 484 a], oJ tov del Kara Tairq. daavras expvTos Svvapcvoi iairT£v elbav ev eKaorov atbiov tc Kai v6rjpa, Ka\ irpbs tovtois airades' bio Kai (pr/a-iv iv tj (pvaei Tas Ideas iaravai KaBanep napa- Seiypara- to. 8' aWa Tairais carnival, tovtov opoiiopara Katfeo-roTa. [Lib. iii. Segm. 13]. 52 TIM^US. to it. What was formed at the creation by the conjunction of these two, is called their offspring (to. 6/c tovtcov eKyova). Information concerning these three is attained by three different ways — : concerning idea or specific form, by the mind according to knowledge — concerning elemental [p. Mb] matter, by spurious reasoning (Xoyia/xip voOqi), so called, because it does not arrive at that certainty and precision which are attained by abstract rea- soning — concerning their offspring, particular ma- terial objects, produced by the union of specific form with elemental matter, by sensation and opi- nion. q>. 94 c] y? e are t understand, says the philosopher, that, before the creation, there were Idea or ab- stract form, Matter, and God the Creator. Now God saw matter assuming specific form (rrjv iSeav) and changing, in all ways indeed, but disorderly. He was therefore desirous of bringing it to order, 57 of converting it from its indeterminate state, and of making it determinate — that there might be dis- tinctions of bodies, and that they might not receive undirected changes. Let us now consider Plato's description of the pattern. He says that it contained within itself all intelligible animals ; as this world contains us and all other living creatures. For God, desiring to make this world resemble, as much as possible, the most beautiful of intelligibles which was in all respects perfect, made it one visible animal, having within it all corresponding animals, according to its nature. If due allowance be made for the TIMJEUa. 53 peculiar language of the Pythagorean and Pla- tonic schools, nothing can be more plain than that the pattern signifies no more than the abstract idea, according to which the universe was formed, with parts in the one answering to parts in the other 3 . Aristotle distinguishes the causes of things into mur. ausc. four kinds : Pirst, the subject matter, as brass in the composition of a statue, &c. Secondly, the specific or generic form. Thirdly, the author. Pourthly, the final cause. The terms in which he describes the second kind, or specific and generic forms, are these, to el^os /ecu to izapa- 58 oeiyixa' touto o earlv 6 Xoyos o tov t'i r\v elvai koI to. tovtov yevrj. With respect to the nature of the soul of the universe, it may be proper, first, to observe that mind and soul do not signify two distinct inde- pendent existences, as some have supposed, "fyvyfj, soul, when considered separately, signifies the prin^ ciple of life : Now, mind, the principle of intelli- gence. Or, according to Plutarch, soul is the ?w. Quast. cause and beginning of motion, and mind of order and harmony with respect to motion 4 . Together they signify an intelligent soul (evvovs ^x>7) which is sometimes called a rational soul {^vyri XoyiKtj). Hence, when the nature of the soul is not in ques- tion, the word ^v^ is used to express both. Thus 3 Notjtos lirayji Koo-fios to tov (pawopJvov rov8e ap^erv7rov, Ideais aopaTois o~vo~Ta8e\s too'irep ovtos aap.ao'i.v opaTots. — Philo Judseus, De Confus. Ling. p. 345. 4 *UXV y<*P atria Kivrjcrcws Ka\ ap)(ij, vovs &e rd^eas Ka\ avp.- (pavias irep\ kIvtjo-iv, 54 TIM2EU8. P79M. in the Phcedo the soul (ypv X v) is said sometimes to use the body for the examination of things (t<£ a-wfxari irpocrxprJTai ek to (TKOire'iv ti) ; at which times, according to the principles of Plato, it forms confused and imperfect notions of things, and is involved in error. But, when it examines things by itself, it arrives at what is pure and always existing and immortal and uniform, and is free from error. Here the highest operations of vov$, ' mind,' are indisputably attributed to ^vyy, ' soul.' Aristotle, describing \|/ux»7; ' soul,' says, that 59 during anger, confidence, desire, &c. it participates with the body ; but that the act of understanding belongs peculiarly to itself 5 . Again, he says, Plato in the Timceus, in the same manner as Empedocles, makes the soul out of the elemental principles of things; for that like is known by like 6 . Soon after he says, that soul has in it a principle both of mo- tion and of knowledge 7 . It is evident, that irav To$e or KocxfMK, here treated of by Plato, is the system of heaven and earth, and of the several natures contained in them 8 . And that vovs /ecu ■\|/u^>) kog/jlov is, as Cicero ex- presses it, vis quondam sentiens, quce est toto confusa mundo, performing the same functions in the great body of the universe at large, that human souls do in our bodies, giving life and motion to its several 6 $aiV€rai Se rav TrXetarau ovOev avev aafiaros Trdtr^ew' ovte iroictv, oiov opyi£e avrbv Tp6rrov iv to Tipdlw TtKaTav tij» ■^rvx^v Ik to>v crmx'iuv 7roiei- yiyvda-Kea-dai yap 6/xoi'oj opowv. cap. 11. TIM^EUS. 55 parts, directing those motions with consummate wisdom, and communicating different portions of its essence to the different beings that are contained 60 within the bounds of its all-comprehending circum- ference ; thus effecting and maintaining the varia- tions of times and of seasons, the changes of or- ganized and unorganized matter, and the uninter- rupted succession of animated and rational beings. The proof of the existence of this rational soul, animating and directing the universe, was derived, as has been already observed, from the observable fecundity of nature, and the order and harmony of its parts and motions. That Trctv ToSe or Koo-fios was not eternal a parte ante is manifest from the whole tenor of the rela- tion. We have the reasoning of the Creator con- cerning this future God, before he was created {XoyiafjLos Qeov irepi tov ecro/xevov 6eoi>). We have a [p. 34 b.j direct assertion of the creation of it : Sid §q tov [p. 30 b.] \oyuTfwv Tovoe, vovv fiev ev ^v%fj, -vJ/v^j/i/ Se kv gco/uuxti avviuTas, to irav ^vvereKTctlveTo : on account of this reasoning having constituted a mind in a soul and a soul in a body, he composed the whole. Thus this world was made by the providence of God an animated and intelligent being (£wov e/u.\f/v- VOl/ eVVOVV T€). Nay, the philosopher does not even stop here, 1 'Eirel Be Kal kivt)tikov e'8ok« tj ^v^fj ttvai as Sq t&v oXow koV/uov Xeyovow eivai 6ebv, SraHKOi ph tov irpmrov' ol d' airb liKdravos tw Seirepov. — Contra Celsum, Lib. V. p. 235. TIM2E US: 59 The Stoics maintained the eternity of the world. They had therefore occasion to account for no more than the succession of beings, and the wisdom and order with which the affairs of the universe were conducted. For this the soul of the world was sufficient, and was esteemed their first God. The Platonics derived most of their opinions from the Timceus, in which the doctrine of a Creator is taught. He therefore was necessarily the first God; and the soul of the world could occupy only the second place of dignity in this system. An atten- tion to this distinction will serve to account for that apparent inconsistency in the principles of Plato, to which Cicero makes Velleius the Stoic DeNat - Dm '- lab. 1. cap. 12. object. It would be easy to produce a great number of instances from the writings of Plato, Cicero, and others, in support of what is here laid down. But, as on any supposition it is equally impossible to discover in this Dialogue the doctrine of the Holy 6S Trinity; it would lead me too far from the imme- diate subject of my enquiry to dwell any longer upon this topic. For the same reason, because I would not meddle with anything that is not imme- diately and necessarily connected with my subject, I have declined entering into the controversy con- cerning Plato's opinion of the nature and mode of the subsistence of ideas. Whether it be determined that Plato taught that they subsisted notionally or substantially in the divine intellect ; the decision, I conceive, will not of itself tend in the slightest degree to prove Plato's doctrine to have been, that morgan D 6o TIMJEUS. the intellect is personally distinct from the Supreme Being, to whom it belongs. Still less, if possible, can the question be affected by any other hypo- thesis concerning the nature and mode of the sub- sistence of ideas. Having examined all the principal passages, which are produced from the writings of Plato, to prove that he was acquainted with the doctrine of three hypostases in the divine nature ; and having shewn, as I conceive, that none of them, in their true and genuine signification, do actually counte- nance the hypothesis; I will endeavour to inves- tigate the subject farther, and trace out the origin and progress of the opinion in later times. 66 OF THE ORIGIN AND PROGRESS OF THE OPINION OF THE PLATONIC TRINITY. OEVERAL sects of Pagan Philosophy in a man- ^ ner derived their origin from the school of Plato, yet no one of them, whether it professed to adopt his opinions in the whole, or only in part, either affirmed or denied this article, which, if it had been really maintained by Plato, must have held so distinguished a place among his tenets. Even Cicero has taken no notice of this striking peculiarity; though he not only was a passionate admirer and imitator of Plato, but also made it the chief employment of his latter days to trans- pose into the Roman language the most important doctrines and reasonings of the several sects of Grecian Philosophy. This profound silence is too remarkable and too general to be attributed to chance. Neither the high estimation in which the writings of Plato were held, nor the penetration and industry of the many learned men, who either propagated or avowedly deviated from his opinions, will permit us for a moment to suppose that this article could have been wholly overlooked, or re- garded as a circumstance of no moment. 67 If this opinion cannot be found in the writings of Plato, and is not attributed to him by the sub- sequent philosophers of Greece and Rome, it is of D2 6a Of the PL A TONIC TRINITY. importance to investigate, by what means it gained admission among men. For this purpose it will be necessary to examine at large the writings of Philo, an Hellenist Jew, who studied at Alex- andria. ■* ^ 68 AN ENQUIRY INTO THE DOCTRINES OF PHILO JTJDiEUS. Num censes igitur subtiliore ratione opus esse ad hcec refellenda ? Nam mentem, fidem, spem, viriutem, honorem, victoriam, salu- tern, concordiam ceteraque ejusmodi, rerum vim habere vide- mus, non Deorum. — Cic. de Nat. Deor. hi. 24. TDEFOEE I enter upon this enquiry, I wish to -^ remark, that it is confined entirely to the opi- nions of Philo himself. I do not mean to deter- mine any thing about the doctrines of the Jews relative to the divine nature in the time of Philo : though all expositions of them, which are founded Upon different interpretations of Philo, must, as far as they depend upon such interpretations, be affected by my reasonings, if they be allowed to be valid. Least of all would I have it supposed, that I mean to deny that many passages of the Old Testament refer to the second person of the ever-blessed Trinity, when I deny that Philo's in- terpretations of them have any such reference. A distinguished 'writer upon this subject has affirmed that Philo was not a Platonist. If he 69 had meant by this assertion that Philo did not adopt all the opinions of Plato, it must have been admitted. For it was scarcely possible for him to do this, without abandoning the religion of his fathers, which, with all his bias towards philo- 1 Allix's Judgment of the Jewish Church, p. 354. 64 Doctrines of PHILO JUDJEUS. sophy, he does not appear to have entertained any thought of doing. But the author, to whom I refer, goes farther. He says, Philo had been so little acquainted with Plato's works, that he brings some of Plato's opinions upon the credit of Aris- totle 2 . It is a question of words, whether he should be called a Platonist or an Eclectic ; be- cause he did not abandon Judaism, and, embracing all the opinions, prove his doctrines by the au- thority of Plato. But it is of importance to the present enquiry to shew, that Philo was so well acquainted with the principles of Plato, that he made great use of them in his own theological works. Philo has adopted Plato's division of things into the two great classes, Intelligibles and Sen- sibles (vorird Kal a'icrdr)Ta), the former of which he characterizes in the language of Plato, as always the same in their properties and relations (del Kara ra avra Kai tfcraJrais eyovTa) ; but the latter he states, on the contrary, to be subject to per- veomfkio petual changes (fl-ae yap to alaBr/Tov ei> yevecret Kal fxeraftoXals, ovoeTrore Kara rd aura ov.) Like p. is. him in Philebus, he calls the stars living and intel- ligent beings (£wd re etvai XeyovTai Kal £a)a voepd ;) 70 where likewise he says, that man derives his ideas of music, and virtue, which consists in well-har- monized affections, from the harmony that is con- spicuous in the works of creation. From this men, who were formed after them, inscribed on their 2 I presume he alludes to what Philo says, Tlepl \(p6ap %s o\ fierd p. ir. Tavra avOpaiiroi eyy pcttyafxevoi Tails eavrwv y]/vj(ats dvayKaioTaTyv /ecu wviuv apeTwv.) In the same language p 326 - he describes vicious folly to be an inharmonious, discordant, untuneful symphony (dvdpfuxrTov ko.1 p- 32a eKixeXrj ko.1 a/iovaov avn / ., p. 298. auev). But, above all, it is most evident that he had the Timceus of Plato in his eye when he wrote his treatise of the Creation of the World, and that he grounded his explanations upon the same prin- ciples. Thus, having divided things into intel- ligible, which are eternal, unchangeable and per- manent ; and sensible, which are generated, are 71 changeable and fleeting; he enquires, whether the world had a beginning. This question he answers as readily as Plato did, and upon the same prin- ciple : Since it is visible and the object of sense, it must have been made (e-irel oi/v ojootos re ical alaOrj- [ P . 3.] tos 606 o kocthos, avayicala) 1 } av e'/jj Kal yevtjTo?.) This is precisely the reason which was before as- signed by Plato in Timceus for the world's having had a beginning: It was made; for it is visible and tangible, and has a body, that is, a body of 66 Doctrines of PHILO JUD^US. [p. 28 b.] gross matter (yeyovev' oparos yap airTOv 6 6ebs are Gf or, ort plpr/pa Kakbv ovk av jrore yevoiro Kakov 8ix a 7rapa8eiypaTos t ovde tl tcov ala&rjTtov aWTratnov, b pfj 7rpos apx^TVirov Kai voryrrpi IBeav aTreiKovtadr], f$ovkrj8els top oparbv tovtovL Koirfwv drjpiovpyrjo-ai, 7rpO€^€TV7T0V tov vorjrbu, Iva Xpnp-evos aacopara Kai deoetBeo-TOTa irapaSeiypari, tov (TcopariKov drrepya(TT]Tai, p. 3. In this passage he clearly had in his eye the following one of Plato upon the same subject in the dia- logue above mentioned : "Onov pcv ovv av 6 Srjptovpyos, tt/jos ro Kara ravra t-^pv fikiirav aei, roiovra tw\ irpovxpripevos TrapaSeiy- fiari rrpi I8edv Kai '8vvap.iv &irepyatj]Tai, Kakbv ef dvayKrjs ovrais xiiroTeXetcroai Trav* oS 5' av els to yeyovbs, yevvrira irapabeiypati Doctrines of PHILO JUD^US. 67 city that is to be built, temples, places of exercise, courts of justice, market-places, harbours, docks, &c. Then, having received the types of each of them in his mind, as in wax, he frames an intel- ligible city, and stamps the images of the several parts on his memory. To this model he looks 73 when he begins to execute his well-arranged plan with stone and wood, making the material sub- stances like each of the incorporeal ideas. Some- thing of this kind must we conceive of God, who, having purposed to build a capital city, Erst ima- gined the types of it ; of which he constituted the intelligible world, and then used it as a pattern, when he finished the sensible world. As there- fore the city, predelineated in the architect, had no external place, but was stamped upon the mind of the artist ; in the same manner also the world composed of ideas cannot have any other place than the divine intellect, which arranged it. Having discoursed a little upon the cause of God's creating the world, he returns to his ana- logy. If, says he, any one would use plain words, unadorned by figures, he would say, that the intel- 7rpo tiv\ Xiyeiv rj vnovoelv, ov Qepnov jj 8' iKpco~Tr]Kev elaopefla, TrapaKoXovdrjo-avTes eUopi TU/J tS>v Trap' fjpiv. [p. 4] . D5 68 Doctrines of PHILO JUDJEUS. ligible world is nothing else but the 6 intellect of God, while he was now making the world. For the intelligible city is nothing else but the rea- soning of the architect, while he is now projecting to build the material city. The plain meaning of all this is, that the divine Being, when he purposed to create the world, first conceived ideas of the several parts 74 of which it was to consist. These ideas he formed into one plan, and thus constituted the intelligible world. This he used as a pattern in his creation of the material world, which he made to corre- spond with it in every particular, the several sub- stances which composed the one answering to the several ideas which composed the other. It is not allowable to assert or suppose that this intelligible world, thus composed of ideas, had a real and external existence, as some philosophers may have maintained. It was no more than the ideal plan in the intellect of the Creator ; in the same manner as the ideal plan of a city, which is to be built, subsists only in the intellect of the architect, and has no existence external to it. So that, to use plain language, the intelligible world is nothing else but the reasoning of God, when he was about to create the material world ; just as the intel- 6 If the reader wishes to see a complete specimen of the exertions of a subtle genius in support of a system, let him look into Norris's Theory of the Ideal or Intelligible World. He will there see how much that ingenious writer, aided by St Augustin and Malebranche, could extract from this doctrine. 1 T&v fieXKovrav anoreXeicrdai p.dTaiv do-cofiarovs ISeas rrj V™X3 dewpmv, irpos as efiei, KaBairfp an dp^irxmov ypapayi$as tov ts^vitov Tals irpoo- prjra rav Xprjo-poiv o-Ktds Ttvas too-avei aaparcov eipai, ras 5* ipifiaivopevas Swdpeis xa ietTTcoTa okr/deia irpdypara!\ •;6 Doctrines of PHILO JUDjEUS. denominated, and consider a few instances under each, which may serve to explain all others of the same class. First, we will consider it as being the image of [ugisAiiegw. God (eiKwv) and the shadow of God (cncia). Philo in. § 31, p. v # / _ . 79 •' has explicitly declared, in the explanation of Bese- leel, how /cdoyios i/ojjtos, the intelligible world, the reason or intellect of God, the abstract form of the universe, is entitled to these appellations. " The shadow of God is his \oyos, or reason, which he used as an instrument or organ, when he made the WQrld. This shadow and image is also another archetype. For as God is the pattern of the image which we have now called the shadow; in the same manner the image is the pattern of other things 11 ." Having thus shewn that the pattern and shadow 83 and image are relative terms, and that koct/uos voijtos, the intelligible world, which he also calls \6yos Oeov, and which is the pattern of the sensible world, is also itself the shadow or image of God, he pro- ceeds to shew in what sense it is the shadow. [§ 32, p. 79] " The wisest philosophers have maintained, that it H [2/aa Oeov 5e 6 \6yos aiirov eariv, tp KaOdnep opydva 7rpo- (rxpriv ewrrap^ovo'av tovtois Svvapeav avri- \rjijriv e7roirjtrdp,eda rov alriov. Qcnrcp yap ei ns iSot deSrjfitovp' yr/pevr/v olxtav e'lripeXas, irpmrvKaiois, aroats, dvSpacri, yvvaiKavinm, toXs SKKois olKo8ofirifiatnv, tvvoiav \rfyerai rov rfxybrov, — oi yap avev rexyr)s Kai brjpiovpyov vofuet rr)v olieiav diroTeXeadijvai, rbv airov Si rpoirov Kai e'jrl TrdXecoy, xai veu>s , Kai iravrbs eXarroj/or rj Doctrines of PHIL JUDjEUS. 11 is from the world and its parts and their powers that we must derive our conception of its author. For if a person should see a house, a city, a tem- ple, or any other building, constructed with their several parts harmonizing with each other, he would form a conception of an artist. For he would sup- pose that those things could not have been exe- cuted without skill and a builder. So also, when a person has entered into this world, as into a very great house or city, and has beheld the heaven re- volving in a circle, and all things contained within it ; and the planets and fixed stars moving harmo- niously, &c. — and moreover, living beings, mortal and immortal, and different kinds of plants and fruits; he will truly reason, that those things were not formed without perfect art ; but that God was and is the disposer of this universe. They, who reason thus, have a conception of God by means of his shadow, forming a notion of the artist by means of his works 12 . 84 . The plain meaning of this is, that the mind of man in its natural state, represented by Beseleel, is not able by its own strength to attain any idea fxelfrvos Ka.Tas, -fiv 8e top petrairaTov %apov Xa^ovaav, v&aros re Kai depos xuaeis ev fiedopitp reraypivas, en 8e f(3a Bvryra re av Kai dOavara, Kai (pvrav Kai Kaprtatv 8mpi£ei, as av diro o~Kcas t6 pevov dXX* virepKvtyas to yevvrjTov, %[irt o-o' oi irpbs Tqv aKpav a\jri8a irapairepCpSels t&v votjt&v in avrov Xevai Sokci top peyav $ao-ikea. T\ixop.ivov he l&eiv, Beiov (fxaros aKparoi Kal apiyeis avyal Xupappov rpoirov eKxeovrai, ms rats pappapvyais to ttjs htavoias Sppa ovcoTodmap.] 15 Plato in his Dialogue De Rep. Lib. v. p. 477. [c], gives this definition of powers : v 6 peaos, os iv rais If pais ypa(pais Kvpiq ov6pan KaktiTai 6 "Qv at be wap* e/carepa irpepfivTaTai Kal eyyvrarai tov ovtos bvvdpeis, Sv ij pev iroirjTiKrj, rj de av ^ao-iKiKr/ Trpoa-ayopeveTai. Kal ij pev JTOM/TtKq Beos- TavTjj yap idr/Ks tc Kai SieKoo-prjo-e tA 7rSv. 'H 8c ftao-iKucfi Kvpios- Blpis yap ap^eiv Kal Kpareiv t& 77eiroir}Kos tov yevopevov. Aopvs KaBapBe'iaa i) '^fVX'l' Kal M povov Ta irkrjdr] Tap dpidp&v, dWa Kal Trjv yeiTova povdbos bvdba imepfiao-a, npos Tt)v apiyfj Kal do-ipnkoKOV Kal Kaff avTrjv oibevos embea to irapdirav Iheav eVe/yi/raf Tpiav be, orav prjiru ras peya- \as TekeaBela-a TeXeraf, in ev Tais Ppaxyripais 6pyid(rjTai, Kal prj Doctrines of PHILO JUD^US. 81 principle of his existence, but his relations to other things {varavel irpos t'i). As, when his regal and beneficent powers are spoken of, he must be a king of some thing, and a benefactor of some thing; that which is governed or benefited being alto- gether distinct from it. Akin to these is also his creative power, which is called God: for by this power, the father, who begat and framed, establish- ed all things. Hepl rwv MeTovofnaXfifiLevaiv, p. 1048. 1,r It may be proper to observe, that in the former instances which I quoted, the image, or shadow of 87 God, is spoken of as one, as it referred to that power of God which was delineated and shadowed out in the creation of the world ; but in the latter quotations, there is also another shadow of him, as governor and judge of that world which he created. Those who have maintained from this and other similar passages, that Philo had a knowledge of a plurality of persons in the Godhead, have done it principally to shew, that he had a more accurate ftvvrjTai to ov Svev erepov Tivbs i£ avTov povov KaTakafielv, aXKa bia Tav dpapivcov, fj kti£ov rj ap^ovJ] H ['AXXa yap ovd" enelvo wpoarJKev ayvoitv, on to iyd dpi #e6s trbs XeyeTat Kara^pijo'TiKas ov fcvpias. To yap ov, § ov iaTiv, oi^i rav np6s ii' avrb yap eavrov wXiJpes, Kai airb cavra iKavbv, Ka\ npb ttjs tov Kotrpov yevecreas, Kai pera rfjv ylveaiv tov Travrbs iv opoia. "Arpewrov yap Kai a/ieTajSXijrov, XP$£ 0V erepov to irapairav ovoevbs, more auToC p£v chat to iravra, prjSevbs fie Kvpias atrA. T hend the simplicity of one self-existent, independent being, and by arguing a priori to perceive how from this pure essence as from their proper foun- tain, proceed the powers of creation and govern- ment, and the several objects upon which those powers are to be employed. Finite intelligences, which cannot thus contemplate him at once in his essence, are obliged as it were to divide him, and view him in detached parts in his acts, but chiefly 18 Origen in his first Homily on Isaiah, viz. on chapter vi., seems to have derived his ideas from hence, when he is ex- plaining the vision of the Lord sitting upon a throne high and lifted up, surrounded by Seraphim. The passage is thus ren- dered by his translator : Si video eum regnantem coelestibus virtutibus, video eum sedentem super thronum excelsum et elevatum. Quid est, quod dicit, Coelestibus virtutibus ? Throni, dominationes, principatus, potestates, virtutes ccelestes sunt. — » Qua: sunt ista duo Seraphim ? Dominus meus Jesus et Spiritus Sanctus. Testimonium enim dat Scriptura, quia ejus mundan- Doctrines of PHILO JUDJEUS. 83 in those acts of his which are prior in time to all others, most immediately arise out of his essence, and extend to all created beings, viz. his acts of creation and government. Thus arguing a poste- riori they ascend to the summit of intelligibles, and there contemplate images of the power and goodness of the first cause impressed upon his works, and catch as it were a shadow of him who cannot be contemplated in his essence. These powers are called (Ile^t Xepovfil/x, p. 112) his goodness and authority or sovereign power, and are denominated the two highest and first powers belonging to the one truly existing God. By his 89 goodness he created the universe, and by his sove- reign authority he governs what he created. Be- tween both these is his \070s, which is expressed by the symbol of the flaming sword. This con- nects them together; for it is by his X070S that God is governor and good. This preceded all things, and was meditated before all things, and is conspicuous in all things 19 . Here \6yos is the plan, the design, by which (to speak after the manner of men) God acted in the creation and government of the world. The unity of design in both so con- nects his goodness and authority, that there are tur labia ab uno ex seraphim, qui missus est ad auferenda ejus peccata. Unus autem ex seraphim Dominus meus Jesus Chris- tus est, qui ad auferenda peccata nostra a patre missus est. 19 [p. 113. *EA.eye de fioi, Kara tov eva ovrtos oWa 6ebv bvo ras ava>Tara> eivai Kai irpdras Svvaueis, dyadorrjTa Ka\ iijovo-iav. Kai ayaSoTrjTi p.ev to Trap yey evvrjKevat, e^ovala Se tov yevvrjdevTos ap^civ. Tpirov 8c crvvaycoybv a/Kpoiv p-eaov thai \6yov \6yta yap Kai ap%ovTa ku\ ayaObv eivai tov 6gov. avrb iravra obdavav irapTjpel- ifraTo, Kal irpb iravrav voovfievov Kai eVri irao~i tpaiv6p,eyov~]. MORGAN E 84 Doctrines of PHILO JUDjEUS. manifest indications of each in the acts of the other. When the general design of the universe, form- ed by the existent Being, is spoken of, it is called \6yos. His several designs of the separate parts, though included in the general design, are called plurally \6yoi, and are said to be sent, as well as nepi toS the singular: rows eavrov Xoyovs GiriKovplas evem &4' 5 2>w- T< "" (pi^apeTwv atrosTeWei. By these powers was S.Vms-*" formed the incorporeal and intelligible world, the archetype of this which appears, being composed of invisible ideas, as this is of visible bodies. Hep;™; The supreme Being is perpetually said to be on arpeiTTOv ^solns'ai surrounded by these powers, as guards of state and 90 attending ministers, Sopv(popov/xei"p irpos tcov Svvd- peoov. Not to mention that Isocrates uses the same expression to signify a person's being guarded by the good-will of the citizens (tj5 twv ttoXItuv evvolq. £. e l ?a""" r ' 1 82 <'°P v( P P '"f x evo$'); Philo uses it to express the human mind's being attended by the senses, whose busi- ness it is to furnish it with notices of colours, ■Btpmiyx- sounds, tastes, and smells. Again, wealth, fflorv. SiaA. p. 822, ° > o J > !"t5;£. T ° B and honours, are said to be the attendant ministers p ' m - (J)opvopv(p6poi mi vwepixcfxpi y[svxfjs. And sacred and holy reasonings and words are called the garrison and sentinels of p. 324 the soul: \epovs nal 6aiovs Xoyovs aJ-j-JJs (bpovpovs tcai (pvAciKas ovtcis. These powers of the one existent Being, and. Doctrines of PHILO JUDiEUS: 85 the external expressions of them, his words and *■ 32i] actions, are said to be spoken of in the Scriptures under the emblems of angels. Thus, when young and old in Sodom are stated to have combined against the angels, the spiritual doctrine contained under that narrative is that there was a general disposition to wickedness ; and that young and old, with one accord, as if they had bound themselves 91 together by an oath, set themselves in opposition to the divine words and actions, which it is cus- tomary to call angels: lias h', ws (prjaiv, 6 Xaos TrepieKUKktotrav a/xa rrjv o'ltclav, veoi tb /cat irpeapvTai, Kara twv Oe'tcov 'epyaiv Kal Xoywv avvo^oaafxevoi, o'us Kakeiv edos ayyeXovs. Again, aOavarois Xoyois, obs ny^i too Ka\e7v 'e9os ayyeXovs. p - m One of the passages produced to prove the personality of the Xoyos, according to Philo, is that wherein he says that the angel who met Hagar, when she fled from the face of Sarah, and brought n ep i xe P0 ^. p. 108. her back, was the divine Xoyos. But who or what, according to the same interpretation, was Hagar, and Sarah from whom she fled? By Hagar is meant human discipline and the circle of the arts and sciences, who departed from her mistress, Sa- rah, the emblem of virtue, and was brought back by the angel, who is the divine Xoyos 20 (os eo-ri Oelos Xoyos), which he elsewhere calls 21 right reason 20 Tr/v \x.iur\v jrmSeiav Trjv tols iyKVxktois yiopevovcrav opSjiev *&.yap, d\s /iev e£iovs 6p66s \6yos, os KvptcoTepq KXytrei irpov (piXapirav txTrohpavai fiiov (TTrovSaarj. p. 109. 23 UpotrqyopiKas p,ev yvvaiKa, ovofiacmicas 8e EiW, alviTTop.cvos aur8rjaiv. Ilepi XepovPip., p. 118. 2 * 'SrpaTos Se Btios al apcrai, (pihoBeav inep/ia^ol ^v)(&v, p. 198. Doctrines of PHILO JTJDjEUS. p-341. -wisdom. It is also called the first-born \6yos, the 94 eldest angel, being as it were the archangel with p £ 9* many names. The sensible world is called the younger son of God, and the intelligible world is called the elder son. In the passage, " The horse and the rider hath he thrown into the sea," the rider, he says, is the mind, and the horse the passions 25 . And when the lawgiver forbids the use of horses in war, he says, he does not speak of real cavalry, which is necessary for both offence and defence, but of the irrational and un- restrained and ungovernable motions of the soul 26 . p. 48. Virtue in general is expressed by paradise, and the several virtues by the trees planted in it. The divine Xo'yo? is said to be the cement, the bond of union, by which the several parts of the universe are kept together 2r . But the same properties are likewise ascribed to the order and plan according to which the universe was con- structed 28 . Mosheim supposes that Philo (De Abrahamo, p. 367) alludes to some among the Jews who as- serted the doctrines of three natures in God. Whereas in the passage alluded to Philo appears most evidently to me to be speaking of those who are not, as he figuratively expresses it, initi- ated into the great mysteries, and who are not 25 Terpairovv Kai aKiprr)TiKhv Kai vmpavxov — mi6av Te Kai Kcuuav akKifiaiTaTov oritpos — irpbs Se km 6 cmftaTrjs avrmv vovs, p. 199. 26 'AXXa wept Tij r Kara ^jruxV" oX^yov Kai apirpov Kai aireidovs (popas, p. 200. Doctrines of tt±LLiU JVuJETJS. 89 able to contemplate the existent Being in his simple state, without something else to aid their concep- tions. They are therefore obliged to have recourse to his acts, and to consider him as creating or governing, when they endeavour to form a notion of him. Indeed the notion, which is formed in this circuitous manner, partakes of a pious opi- nion ; but that which results from a direct view, does not partake of, but is, a pious opinion, or rather, surpasses opinion and is the truth itself. This is the language in which he generally speaks of the popular and the sublime theology, as distinct from each other in degree rather than in kind. 2 ? Actyo) afplyyerat Beta' kgWci yap eart Kai §es bia.fiefiaioiiJ.e8a- Ka\ ovx ly/ieis dyvooiifiev povov ttjv e/c ivaTpbs tov vlov yevvrjo~\v, dWa Kal nao-a yewrjTTj (pio-is. — Cyril. Catech. xi. p. 96. PHOTIUS informs us that from Philo was derived the allegorical method of interpreting Scripture, which prevailed in the primitive Church, This arose from very natural causes. First, they who have been favoured with a divine revelation, and have by grace availed them- selves of it, enjoy a great and manifest advan- tage over those who are left in a great measure to the exertions of their own minds, and are obliged to trace out the invisible things of God by intri- cate reasonings and deductions from the things, which do appear in the constitution and govern- ment of the world. What even learned men among the latter do hardly guess and with labour find out, is plain and obvious to the meanest and most uncultivated understandings among the 97 former. Yet this advantage, great as it really is, has not always been sufficient to satisfy the pretensions of those who have been blessed with a divine reve- lation. Not contented with the bright sunshine which blazes around them, they will scarcely allow The Fathers of the Christian Church. pi the benighted heathen the dim taper of human reason to guide their steps in their laborious travels over the dark mountains. Whatever the Apostle Paul may have said in his various expostulations with the Gentiles, and particularly in his Epistle to the Romans, there are some far wiser, in their own conceit, than seven men that can render a reason, who boldly maintain, that whatever glimmerings of light the Pagans of old have been able to strike out by mere dint of labour and study, have been all either directly or circuitously derived from the sacred writings 1 . Traces of this opinion are to be found in some degree in the works of ancient authors, both Jewish and Christian, though it did not shoot up to the extravagant height to which some have carried it in later days. I should depart from the tenor of my subject, if I did more than barely mention the well-known example of Josephus among the former. 98 Among the latter, the instances are numerous. As I proceed with my work, I shall, in confirmation of what I have here advanced, produce some strong and pointed passages from Justin Martyr and Cle- mens Alexandrinus, both of them writers of the second century. To Christians who had embraced these senti- ments, the writings of Philo must have been an invaluable treasure. The manner in which he has applied the principles of Plato to illustrate the Mo- saical account of the Creation and other parts of 1 *E£ ov ($[\<0Vos) olfxai Kal 7ras 6 dWTjyopcKos ttjs ypa(prjs ev TJj iKKki)arlci Xoyos eV^ex apx^v titrpvijvm, Photius, p. 96. E 5 9 2 The Fathers of the Christian Church. the Old Testament, was admirably calcixlated to flatter their prejudices, and furnished them with specious arguments in support of the opinion which they so strenuously maintained. Secondly, many were converted to the Christian religion who had previously made considerable pro- gress in the Platonic or 2 Eclectic Philosophy, and retained many of their former prejudices. Others were struck with the great respect that was paid to philosophy, and with the superior skill which its 99 professors displayed in the arts of controversy. On this account they frequented the schools of Alex- andria, in which masters of profound learning and great celebrity explained and inculcated, with be- witching eloquence, the speculations of the sages of ancient Greece. These men, having the sacred volumes in one hand and the writings of Plato in the other, if they believed them both to be true, must have thought the principles and doctrines of each consistent with those of the other : for it is impossible that one truth should be opposite to, or at variance with, another. To these men, therefore, the writings of Philo must have been as acceptable as to those 2 The following is a description which Clemens Alexandri- nus gives of the Eclectic philosophy. " By philosophy I mean neither the Stoic, nor the Platonic, nor the Epicurean and Aristotelean. But whatever things have been properly said by each of those sects, inculcating justice and devout knowledge, this whole selection I call philosophy." ®iKoo-of, SiKatoavvrjv ptr evo-efiovs imtrrrip.-qs exSiSao-Koira, tovto (rv/xTrav to (kKcktikov ment 8 : that when he made el$o$, ' specific form,' the third principle after God and matter, he was led to the use of the expression by a passage in the writ- ings of Moses, which, for the want of an enlight- ened instructor, he did not correctly understand : Exoa. xxv. -to. "Look, that thou make them after the pattern which was shewed thee in the Mount." And again, " According to all that I shew thee, after the pat- tern of the tabernacle and the pattern of all the instruments, even so shall ye make it 6 ." Plato, says he, having met with these passages, supposed that some separate specific form existed, before 4 'Evravda 6 TlXaratv o-atp&s Kai (pavep&s tov iraKaibv Xoyou Mavtreais ovouafci v6p.ov^ tov pev ovopaTos Mtovo-eW, ©e<5 vo-ea Kai tovs \oirrois 7rpo(pJ]ras ; a>v Tals irpos (paiverai, to pev tov etfious ovopa dnb T&V The Fathers of the Christian Church. $5 what is the object of the senses ; which form he also often calls the pattern of the things that were 102 made 7 . He then proceeds to point out the mis- takes into which Plato fell in reading the Mosaical account of the Creation, and the manner in which he was led by those mistakes to imagine an intelli- gible world, and other opinions that appear in the Timseus. It is unnecessary to give a minute detail of these things, and of the allusion which, in the second Apology for Christians, Justin states theMp»'»M Philosopher to make to the shape of the cross, the knowledge of which he is supposed to have obtained from the story of the brazen serpent in the history of Moses. In his Dialogue with Trypho the Jew he asserts, p.k[»j that the devil formed many of the mythological stories of the Greeks in imitation of the several circumstances foretold of Jesus Christ ; in the same manner as the magicians of Egypt imitated the miracles that were performed by Moses. One instance of this is Bacchus, the son of Jupiter, who, having been torn to pieces, after his death rose again and ascended into heaven ; whose mysteries also are celebrated with wine. Another instance is jEsculapius, who is represented as curing diseases "^ Moluccas pepa8r]Kcbs prjrmv, ov 8iSa^5eir Se TrfViKmira irapa t£>v eiSorw on ot&ev ektos pvo-TCKfjs Beapias tS>v dno Mavs flpt]- pevav P to " rov irpovnapxeiv toO alaBr/Tov- o Ka\ irapao'eiyp.a T&v yevopevav ovopa- £ei TToAXdias. p. 29 [a]. g6 The Fathers of the Christian Church. XApoiog. i. c. and raising the dead. Again, we hear of Perseus; 22 : Dial, cum p^'cb. 6 /' 1 w ^o was born of a virgin. Again, when the Per- 103 sians say that Mithras was born of a rock, they are supposed to have taken the idea from the book of the prophet Daniel, where the kingdom of God is pre- figured by a stone cut out of a rock without hands. p ■«• Clemens Alexandrinus, in his Admonition to the Gentiles, expostulates with Plato, and asks him whence arose his conjecture about truth and genu- ine piety. I know your teachers, says he, though you may wish to conceal them. You are indebted to the Hebrews for such of your laws as are true, and for your opinion of God 8 . To the same origin, he refers the knowledge which Xenophon had at- tained of the Supreme Being 9 . In the first book of his Stromata he gives an instance of a law which, he says, Plato borrowed from the Hebrews ; wherein he orders every one to abstain from the water of his neighbour, till he has tried every method, without success, of pro- 3 Pc-L-f' curm g water in his own possessions 10 . In page 8 H66ev, <» liKdrav, akrjBeiav alptTTj] ; irodev 17 r£j> \6yav a(p- 6ovos xoprjyla ttjv 6eoo-ej3etav fiaj/reverac ; otfia o~ov tovs fitfia- (TKaKovs, Kav arroKpvTTTeiv edeXrjs — v6povs, ocroj aXr/Seis, jsal ho^av ttjv tov 6eov, irap' airav tocpcXr/o-ai tosv ''Efipaiav : [p. 60. ed. Pott. §70.] 9 H60€v Spa 6 tov VpvWov croc/>i£ei-cu ; rj 817X089 Trapa rtjs irpo- (pr)Ti.hos rtjs 'Efipaiav 8eo-m£ovo-rjs (SSe Tray; [Ibid. § 71.] 10 '■£„ yoy V TO ts No/* cus 6 ■«£ 'Ej3pcuW vhcap trap' cTepa>v, eav firj irporepov opv£avTes 7rap' avT&v a^pi TJ ? ff TTap8evloy KaKovp.evrjs, avvbpov ivpao-i t!jv yrjv: p. 274. [p. 321. ed. Potter.] 11 Qihoo-otpia bk ovk aneo-TaXrj imb Kvplov akX rj\8e, tp7jO-\, KXaffeTcra, rj irapa KXeWou 8o0eio-a- c'It otv bivapis rj ayyeXos /ladav n ttjs dXrjdeias na\ jifj mrafiuvas iv avTrj, Tavra cvemievae ko\ The Fathers of the Christian Church. 97 IO4304, he says that Numa was a Pythagorean ; but that it was in consequence of what he learned from Moses, that he prohibited the Romans from making an image of God. In page 309 is quoted, from [|vu. ^m. the Gospel of St John, the saying of our Saviour, rs. John x. sj that all before him were thieves and robbers. This some men applied to the philosophers, to whom the 11 arch-apostate surreptitiously communicated detached portions of divine wisdom. Yet, says Clemens, this philosophy, stolen as it were by Pro- metheus, retained a little fire emitting some useful light, a faint resemblance of divine wisdom. The Grecian philosophers, who lived before the coming of our Lord, may indeed be called thieves and robbers, for having, without acknowledging it, taken portions of truth from the Hebrew prophets, and appropriating them, as if they were their own doc- trines 12 . He produces the authority of Aristo- bulus to prove that Plato was guided by the law of 105 the Jews 13 . He quotes the following passage from Numenius, a Pythagorean philosopher : What is Plato but Moses speaking the Attic language w ? Kktyas cil&agev. p. 310. [§ 17, p. 366.] 13 'Eotu/ ovv kuv i\olq rfj KAan-ei'077, Kadanep viro Xlpo- pr/Scas, nvp dXiyov (Is as cmrqdaov xpr]irLpa>s ^anrvpovpevov, i%vos ri o-otpias Kai kii/tj(Tiv XaftovTes, aAA* cos T&ia a]v twv o\wv Qewpovvres aicpipaJs vtto Qeov yeyovvlav 15 Uapa Mwvaias roiavra v pv8a>P alirxiovs fieri Kal aTonwepat, to prj&apfj prjSapas appoo-8ijvai Sv- papepa, Qavpacrrj} tlpl kcu iravrairao-ip apaitjQr\T<£i pcopiq ovpaTTTOVtrat. coixe Be irepX t&p $i\copos (rvyypapparap ravra \iyeiv, rj xal rap The Fathers of the Christian Church. to signify a man endued with various knowledge. In p. 583, the three days which Abraham spent [§ rf. p. 690.] in going to the place where he was to sacrifice his son, are made to signify the degrees by which a man advances to the knowledge of spiritual things. And in p. 574, he bestows high encomiums upon ts i*. p. 6T9] the utility and dignity of these allegories, and the interpretations of them. Theophilus, in his second book of Autolycus, [§ 13 toil] p. 94 foil, partly with hints taken from Philo, partly with additions of his own, to make the whole apply to Christianity, deduces a variety of allusions to 109 the great mysteries of religion, the nature of God, the doctrine of the Trinity, the condition of man, and the dispensations of Providence, from the number of days employed in the creation of the world, the portion of them which preceded the creation of the luminaries of heaven, and the differ- ent productions of the several days. I think I have now incontrovertibly established these two facts. First, That the early Christians entertained the opinion that the philosophical principles and my- thological stories of Pagan antiquity were de- rived either immediately or circuitously from the books of the Old Testament. Secondly, That the allegorical writings of Philo ert apxaioT€oa>v, oiroia cart ra 'ApMTToftovXov. trro^a^opai Se rbv KfXow pr/ aveyvmKevai ra /3i/3Xi'a, «rel 7roXXa^oO ovtcos eVire- Tcvx$at jioi (paiverai, wore alpeBrjvai av mi roiis iv "EXXijtri (pi* \oovvTas oiro rav \eyop.£vn>v iv ols ov /xovoi/ 17 (ppacrts i^r/- OTci/rcu aXXa nai vo^fiara Kal Soy/iara jcai ij xprj&is twv as o"erat airb tgbv ypatpav fivdav 6 KeXtroy, p. 198. 102 The Fathers of the Christian Church. were in high estimation among the same people, and that the principles of interpretation which he had adopted were received as just and wise. I shall now proceed to enquire into the effects which these two opinions conjointly produced in the reasonings of the Christians of the second century. The first effect which I shall point out is this. We saw that Philo by an allegorical mode of interpretation explained the things, persons, and transactions, recorded in the Old Testament, to signify moral and intellectual qualities and opera- tions. The Fathers of the Christian Church pro- ceeded farther, and again converted those quali- ties and operations, with the supposed emblematic n C things, persons, and transactions, into other per^ sons and transactions under the Gospel covenant. Because in the Timceus of Plato the Creator is said to have used an ideal world as a pattern when he formed the present sensible one, Philo also, when he commented upon the Mosaical ac- count of the creation, and applied to it the prin- ciples of Plato, represented the Supreme Being as forming within himself a plan of the work which he was about to accomplish. This plan, he says, was nothing else but the reason or reasoning of God, in the same manner as the plan of a city, formed by an architect, is the reasoning of that architect. Because the arrangement of this plan of course preceded the creation of the things which were to be formed according to it, he calls it the first-born (irpwTOToicos), by which word he The Fathers of the Christian Church. 103 expresses likewise the difference of its nature from that of external things, since it was the natural production of the divine intellect by a reflex act, if we may so express it. In other parts of his works he makes several things, persons, and actions, emblematically representative of the divine wis- dom and its dealings with men. Because St John has called Christ 6 \6yos, and he is elsewhere styled TTOfciTOTOKos, it has been concluded that all in which Philo has said of what he calls 6 \6yos, is expressive of Christ in a literal sense. Philo asserted that the two Cherubim over the mercy-seat were intended to signify the creative and governing powers of God. The creative power is said by Justin Martyr to be Christ, and is called by him a certain rational power, which God begat of himself in the beginning, before all created beings 19 . In his second Apology for the Christians, he calls the author of our salvation the reason, of which the whole human race partakes ; and asserts, that they who lived according to reason are Christians, even though they were esteemed Atheists ; as among the Greeks Socrates and Heraclitus, and such as were like them 20 . In like manner Athenagoras, stating the eter- nity of the son of God, and his consubstantiality with the father, says, I will tell you in short what !9 \px¥ irpo iravrav rav KTitTfiurav 6 Geoy yeyivvt]K€ Svvap.lv Tiva eg iavroi Xoyiicnv: p 284 [a. Dialog, c. Tryph. § 61.] 20 \6yov ovra, ov ttav yeW avBpamav peTeo-x^ *<" ol pera \6yov Pidaavres Xpumavoi A, irarpi rr/v re iyK.vKki.ov naiSeiav Kai to Xlkdraivos, p. 428. [p. 511.] AokcX Se poi Kal tov likaravos napaiaiKOfvai ev rjj TroXireia \5>s SeSeixdai ij/ilv vopi£a>, ras a(j>oppas rav |«Va>v boypartav rap MapKia>va irapa HXdraivos d^apla'Tcos re Kai apad&s eTk-qtyivai, p. 434, [520]. -qyeirai Se 6 yevvaios ovros HkaraviKco- rcpov, p. 466, [553]. 15 n6 The Fathers of the Christian Church. p. 466. — Tertullian calls Valentinus apostate, here- [p. 375a] tic, and Platonist. {De Came Christi, cap. xx.) Relucere ideis semina Gnostidce et Valentininw hcere- seos. De Anima, p. 322. It would be easy to multiply passages from Tertullian and others, in support of what is here advanced. I will close this topic with one testi- mony from the writings of an author in the begin*- ning of the next century; a testimony upon this subject as unexceptionable as any one that can be obtained. The author whom I mean is Plotinus ; a man inferior to few in application, acuteness of genius, and profound knowledge of the various me- thods in which the men of those times interpreted the philosophical opinions of Plato, and applied them to subjects of theology. The ninth book of his second Ennead was writ- ten professedly to discuss the doctrines of the Gnostics. After having examined some of their principal doctrines at large, he says, ' These things have been partly taken from Plato; but whatever i^5 new things they have introduced, in order to form their own system of philosophy, those are found to be destitute of truth 38 .' He then produces one in- rTtaams.p. stance of this from the Timwus. Plato said, that as mind sees ideas in that which is a living being, the Creator devised that the universe should con- 38 OXtoff yap avrois to. pev irapa roO Itkaravos eTKrjnTar ra Be, o rrjs aKr)6tias evprjrai, p. 203 [p]. 39 'E.L7t6vtos yap avroV) jj7rep odv vovs ivovvas Ihias iu T<5, 6 ecrrc fSov, Kadopa, Tooravras Kal 6 To8e iroiwv to nav bitvorjOri (r^eiw ol Se, oi (Tvvivres, tov piv eXa/3oj» iv ^o-v^lq. 'i^ovra iv airm iravTa The Fathers of the Christian Church. 117 tain as many. But the Gnostics, not understanding this, conceived one mind at rest, having in it all entities; another mind beholding what was in it; and a third mind devising 39 . He next shews in what manner their ideas of the corruption of matter, and the impurity of all terrestrial things, were de- rived from Plato's direction to abstract the thoughts, and to withdraw the mind as much as possible from the influence of the body. He again intimates, p. 215 [g.] that they were led to hate the nature of the body in consequence of having heard Plato 40 complain much of it, on account of its being so great an im- pediment to the soul. 127 The conclusion, which I would draw from the whole of the topic, is this : First, that the original general principles, adopted by both the orthodox and the heretics of the second century, were the same, and that the latter differed from the former, chiefly in consequence of the more unrestrained and licentious use which they made of those princi- ples. Secondly, that the chief of those principles were derived immediately from the mythological stories and the tenets of the philosophers of Greece, particularly of Plato. I have been the more particular in this enquiry, because Mosheim, and after him Brucker, has as- serted, that the Gnostic heresies were derived Ta ovtcl' rov fie vovv erepbv irap avTov Oeapovvra, rbv fie 8iapoovp.e- vov, p. 204 [a.] 40 Ka/rot et kcu fiKTsiv avrois eVoiei ttjv tov (rdpaTos (pvaiv, fitdrt aKTjKoacn TjXdravos TroWa fMefi-^ajxevov td> crco/urn, ota iji7r6- fiiov irape^av [ipmohia Trape^ei, Oreuzer] t% tyvxti- 1 1 8 the Fathers of the Christian Church. solely from the oriental philosophy. The real state of the case seems to me to be this : First, The genuine doctrines of Plato, in many points, bear a strong resemblance to the oriental philosophy; whence indeed they were derived by Pythagoras and Plato. The same may be said of the mythologies of ancient Greece, which in a great measure originated from the same source. Secondly, This resemblance was increased by the manner in which the philosophy of Plato was taught at Alexandria, when that city became a distinguished seat of learning. Thirdly, It was customary for those who aspired to eminence in their profession, to affect a more profound knowledge of the sublime doctrines of philosophy relating to God and the human soul. 138 Por this purpose they were not satisfied with what Plato taught upon those subjects ; but, after they had gone through the course of education in his school, they applied to the oriental philosophy, siramm. Lib. from which Plato himself drew. Clemens Alex- 1. p. 274. [p. 322.J andrinus enumerates the several masters under whom he himself studied. Among these one was from the east. Plotinus, who was himself a kind of second father of the later Platonists, undertook, though he failed to accomplish, a journey into the east, for the purpose of perfecting himself in the philosophy of those countries. We may hence be able to account for the high pretensions to wisdom which the Gnostics ad- vanced, and for the contempt with which they treated Plato and his followers, with whom they The Fathers of the Christian Church. 119 had set out in the pursuit of truth. They looked upon him as one who had made but very little pro- gress in the ways of true knowledge, and was qualified to teach men only the first rudiments of science. But they arrogated to themselves the name of sages, who were initiated into the great mysteries of God and nature. This contemptuous treatment of Plato and his doctrines could not fail to produce a proportionable degree of animo- sity in the later Platonists, whose vanity was se- verely wounded by the arrogant pretensions of the Gnostics. 139 These patch-work systems of heresy (if I may be allowed to borrow the idea of Irenseus) will the less surprise us, if we recollect an opinion, which generally prevailed in that age, that most of the sects of Grecian and Barbarian philosophy contained severally some scattered portions of truth, which it was the business of a wise man to collect and combine in one consistent scheme 41 . While these general principles prevailed, as well among the orthodox Christians as among heretics, Ammonius Saccas, who was educated a Christian, established a school at Alexandria. Phi- losophy at this time had gained an undoubted 41 This opinion is thus stated by Clemens Alexandrinus : £u/t- iravre s ovv "EXKrjvcs re nal Bapftapoi, oo-oi TakrjSovs dpixBrjaav, oi fxkv ovk okiya, 01 8e fitpos n, Amp apa, tov rijs aKrjdetas Xoyou i'xovTzs dvabet^Oelev ovrats ovv 17 re fiapfiapos tf re ^'EXKrjviKrj s cv 'ttro on Karoi/^crat tx\v akr\6uav. Slromm. Lib. I. p. 298, [p. 349.] i2o The Fathers of the Christian Church. ascendency in the church ; and the nature of the situation, in which Ammonius was placed seemed ■I' to call upon him to support at once the character \ of divine revelation and human philosophy. As he left no writings behind him, we can judge of his abilities only from their effects, and the testimony of others. These unite in placing him in the most conspicuous point of view. In his endeavours to render more complete the agreement between the 130 several stories of Pagan mythology, the tenets of the Grecian and Oriental philosophers, and the doctrines of the Gospel, he entirely changed the whole state of the question, effected a complete revolution in philosophy, and made no inconsider- able impression upon the Christian profession. By the refinements of his speculations and the copi- ousness and force of his eloquence, he seems to have exercised an almost uncontrollable influence over the minds of men in the personal discharge of his office as a public teacher. And from him sprung a sect, the members of which, for their learning and acutenesss, have been the admiration of great numbers in all succeeding ages. Ammonius is said to have differed in prin- ciples from Clemens in the following respect. Clemens affirmed, that truth was dispersed in dif- ferent portions through most of the stories of Pagan mythology and the several sects of philo- sophy; and that the great error of the heathens consisted principally jn this, that each nation, party and sect, having but a portion of truth, and some of them a very small portion of it, persuaded The Fathers of the Christian Church. 121 themselves that they possessed the whole 42 . Where- as Ammonius is said to have affirmed, that each sect and party would be found to be possessed 131 of all the most important doctrines of true reli- gion, if their principles, tenets, and mythologies, were properly interpreted. This step alone was wanting in order to make the junction between Christianity and Paganism complete. If the point could be fully accomplished, it would follow of course that the school of Ammonius would be frequented by men of all parties who repaired to Alexandria for instruction in philosophy and reli- gion. The event was answerable to the greatness of the undertaking, and the splendid abilities of the undertaker. Before the time of Ammonius, Christian writers had for different purposes endeavoured to make out a conformity between their own profession and the traditions and principles of those to whom they addressed themselves. Sometimes they did this in order to mitigate the abhorrence in which they were held by their Pagan persecutors, and to convince them of the innocence and reasonableness of the doctrines which they taught and practised. At other times their views were more extensive and disinter- ested, and were directed to the conversion of those to whom their discourses were delivered. They represented to them, that the mythological tradi- tions and philosophical speculations, which were so 42 At Ttjs (pikoo-ocplas ttjs ts fiapfiapov rrjs re 'EWrjviKrjs alpl- ■ Lib. ix. Cap. i. and elsewhere.) This doctrine, so conspicuous and important in the Christian dis- pensation, he endeavours to prove by abstract reasoning, to support by the authority of Plato, and to illustrate by mythological stories. He calls his three principles, the first, the good (rd'yadov) or the existing (to ov), the second, mind {vow), the third, soul (^y'^Jj). He says, that mind is the archetype and pattern of this world, which is the image of it, and which exists by means of it 44 ; that the nature of mind and the existing is the true and first world 45 . Mind, having imparted something of itself to matter, made all things, itself remaining motionless and quiet. That which 136 flowed from it was reason 46 . It was reason that gave harmony and an unity of composition to all things 4r . But this universe is not, like the intel- ligible one, mind and reason. It only partakes of mind and reason. Wherefore it stood in need of harmony by the concurrence of mind and necessity. The latter tends to defect and dis- 46 NoCj roivvv SoCs ti iavrov els vXtjv, aTpefifjs (tal r/av^os xa ■nkvTa elpydfero- ovtos 8e 6 Xdyor, i< vox) pveis. Cap. 2, [p. 256 A.] 47 ToO Sc Xdyov in alroU rrjf Appoviav Ka\ piav rrjv avvra^ai els xa oXa jroiov/iivov. Ibid, [c] 126 The Fathers of the Christian Church, proportion ; but mind controls necessity 48 . He again repeats this sentiment, that the reason or soul, which presides over this universe, is not, like that of the intelligible world, pure mind and soul, but suspended from the latter, and, as it were, an effulgence from both 49 . This reason therefore, though it proceeds from one mind and one life, each of them perfect, is neither one life nor one mind, nor every where perfect ; and does not impart itself whole and entire to those things to which it imparts itself 50 . \Ennmd. in. Jn his treatise on the nature of Love, he Lib. v. p. 292 ' G foll] makes use of these principles to explain the birth 137 of that urchin, as related by Plato in his Sym- posium. There was, he says, a twofold Venus : one the daughter of Jupiter and Dione, the other the heavenly Venus or the divine soul, descended from Ccelus the first principle, but the immediate production of Cronus, mind, the second principle, without a mother, that is, without any commu- nication with matter, and without any relation to marriage ; as there is no marriage in heaven, every thing there being pure and unmixed. It is more immediately connected with mind than the light with the sun. This heavenly Venus, following 48 'EotI yap to irav roSe 011%, aancp eKct, vovs Kal \6yos, aWa fiercx " vov Kal ^dyov 816 Kal i&fq&r/ appovlas, ovvekSoVTOs vov Kal dvdyKTjs. rrjs pkv irpbs to x^p°» e\(cou. 294 » ] attending her, who is concerned in marriages. This love was begotten at the birth of Venus, in the gardens of Jupiter, upon Tiev'ia, poverty, by Tl6pos, abundance. In this fable, he says, that Jupiter [ P . 298 b.j does not mean the third principle, as it usually does, but the second, viz. mind. For Venus signi- fies the divine soul. Tl6pos signifies the reason of all things : not abstract universal reason, or, as he expresses it, reason remaining in itself, but an effulgence from it, and mixed with Ylevla, inde- finite matter void of qualities 51 . Nectar, with which 138 IIojoos is said to have been intoxicated, signifies divine wisdom, flowing into the soul at the birth of Venus. The gardens of Jupiter are the glory and splendor of the divine mind. (C. viii. ix. x). [pp- 298,299.] In the fifth JSnnead, the first book, and the seventh chapter, he applies the story of Cronus or Saturn, Rhea, and Jupiter, to a similar pur- pose. Cronus, the wisest God, signifies the divine [p. 489 b.] intellect, which devours its own offspring 62 ; that is, absorbs within itself the divine reasons, not suffer- povs ovtos eKarepov, ovk ea-Tiv ovre £0)77 p.La, ovre vovs ris ety, ofire eKatrra^ov 77X77/377?, ovde didovs eavrov ols didatrtv o\ov re Kal TTavra. Ibid, [s], 51 'Ek Xoyou ou /lelvavros iv avra, aXka p.i)(8evTOS .dopioria. Enn. m. Lib. v. cap. 7, [p. 297 b.] 62 The Stoics interpreted Cronus to signify time, his off- spring days, months, and years, etc. "Kpovos dicitur, qui est idem xpovos, id est, spatium temporis. Saturnus autem est 128 The Fathers of the Christian Church. ing them to sink into matter, and to be fostered by Rhea. From him, however, sprung Jupiter, the divine soul, the light and impression of the mind, revolving round it, and attached to it : a power too great to be unproductive. In aid of this solemn trifling he had recourse to the philosophical principles of Plato. In the prosecution of his plan, he considers the Par~ menides, the Timceus, and to ayaOov or universal good, and contemplates them as if they all treated the same subject in exactly the same point of view ; though the Parmenides was intended to explain the phsenomena of the universe, accord- ing to the principles of Parmenides, on the sup- 139 position of its having existed from eternity. Ti- mseus, on the other hand, proceeds upon the sup- position that the world was created, and under- takes to delineate the order in which that great work was performed, the relative dignity of the separate parts, and the ingredients of which they were severally composed. In neither of these trea- tises does Plato make himself absolutely respon- sible for the doctrines which are advanced in them. And in his dialogue concerning a Eepublic, he is not treating of the first and efficient cause, appellatus, quod saturetur annis. Ex se enim natos comesse fingitur solitus, quia consumit setas temporum spatia, annisque pneteritis insaturabiliter expletur." Cio. De Nat. Deor. Lib. ii. cap. 25. 63 AvrapKee ov avra els ayaBbv, ovbev av deoiro Tijs voytreas ttjs nepi avrov. Erin. vi. Lib. vii. cap. 38, Tp- 730 a]. The terms in which lie describes it, are not unlike the account, which Cicero gives of the Gods of Epicurus : " Nihil agit : nullis occu- pationibus est implicatus : nulla opera molitur : sua sapientia The Fathers of the Christian Church. 129 but of the final cause. It is obvious how forced an interpretation it must be that aims at blend- ing such inconsistencies in one system. But this is not all. The manner in which this scheme is conducted adds greatly to the confusion that necessarily arises from the nature of the scheme itself. He affirms that the terms ev, ev iroKka, and ev Ka\ noWd in the Parmenides signify the three principles in the divine nature ; and that to dya- [p. 490 bj 6ov, which I have shewn to signify the final cause, is equivalent to ev the first principle, {Ennead VI. [p. 731.] Lib. vii. C. xl. and elsewhere) the root, as it were, of the tree, {Ennead VI. Lib. vin. C. xv. Ennead V. !> wo d, p . Lib. iv. C. i.) the first intelligible, a simple unit {Ennead V. Lib. 11. C. i.) ungenerated and selfsuf- [p. sis.} ficient, not standing in need of intellect to com- 4oplete its perfection 53 . Whereas the second prin- ciple, mind, which, he says, is the same as ev 7roX\a, requires the intelligible for the exercise of its powers and the fruition of its enjoyment, and of course for the perfection of its nature 54 . Mind has essence and intelligence, which are many. {Ennead VI. Lib. vii. C. xxxvii, [p. 728] M ). It is also all things, and therefore many. {Ennead III. efc virtute gaudet : habet exploratum fore se semper cum in maxumis turn in seternis voluptatibus." De Nat. Deor. I. 19. 54 c O fiev yap vovs toO ayaQov, to d* ayadov ov deirai eKtlvov. Enn.iu. Lib. viii. cap. 10, [p. 352 d]. 'Opa 6 vovs intlvov koi deiTai avrov fiovov e/cetvos Se tovtov oiidev. JEnn. v. Lib. i. cap. 6, [p. 487 P]; Lib. iv. cap. 2, [p. 518]. Da Avo ovTa tovto to ev opov vovs Kai ov, kcii i/ow kcli voovpevov. 6 fiev vovs Kara to voeiv to be tv Kara t6 voovfxevov. JEnn. V. Lib. i. cap. 4, [p. 485 e]. 130 The Fathers of the Christian Church. f«; : |sy Lib. m. C. iii — Ennead V. Lib. ix. C. vi.) It is generated of the first principle by a reflex view of itself 66 . As mind is generated from the first principle by a reflex view, so it also, being at rest, out of 14 its essence produces soul. The soul, not indeed at rest but in motion, begat likewise an image. Looking at the principle whence it sprung, it was filled ; and having proceeded to different and con- trary motion, she generated an image of herself, sensation, and the nature which is in plants 5r . Soul is the reason of the mind, and an energy of it ; as that is of the first principle. But the rea- son of the soul is obscure 58 . As the emitted reason is an image of the reason in the soul, so is the soul the image and reason of the mind ; and it is all energy and life, which it sends forth for the subsistence of other things. One may be com- pared to the heat which resides in fire, the other to that which it communicates 59 . The soul, being one as subsisting in the divine nature, is also many 68 lias ovv vovv yevva, r) on tJ iirurrpotpfj irpbs avro impa. jj fie opao-is avrrj vovs. Enn. v. Lib. i. cap. 7, [p. 488 a] : ov yap TeXziov ra prjSiv ijjreiv pr)hk %x ilv > M$* Bei) 8c irpbs avTO 6ea, top vovv. eVet ovv cart [earij I. Creuz.] irpbs aWb Iva tfifl, opov vovs yiyverai /cat ov. Enn. V. Lib. ii. cap. 1, [p. 494 b]. 6 ' Ovtojs ovv ov olov eKelvos, Ta ofioia 7rotet, bvvap.iv irpo^eas noXkrjv. etfios fie /cat tovto avTov, aairep avro avTOV irporepov irpoe%ee. Kfl! avTT] e'x Trjs ovcrias ivipyeia i/'ux? 5 W^OT '■ Creuz.], tovto pevovras eKeivov yevopevrj. /cat yap 6 povs pivovros tov irpb avTov iyevero. y fie ov pevovo-a iroiel, dXXct KtvrjBeto-a eyivva e'ISoikov. The Fathers of the Christian Church. 131 ^aas consisting of the reasons of the things that are made 60 . She made all animals, breathing into them Eim.v.v&.i ' ° c. 2. [p. 482 a. life : whatever the earth or the sea nourishes, and p - 48S] whatever are in the air or in heaven, the stars and the sun. She arranged this great heaven, and makes it revolve in regular order, being a nature different from the things which she arranges, and moves, and causes to live. When she communi- cates life to them, they come into being ; when she quits them, they perish. Without her, matter is a dead carcass ; but she flows into it, and en- lightens it. As the rays of the sun, illuminating a dark cloud, make it shine, and give it an aspect of golden splendor, so also soul, entering into the body of heaven, gave it life and immortality. It should seem that it would be a bold under- taking and an arduous task to reconcile this theory with the doctrines laid down in Timwus. In this theory mind and soul are stated to be the second and third principles, and to be co- ito? flip ofiv (SKeirovtra odev iyevsTO, i:\rjpovTai. 7rpoi\0ovo~a Se eiff KtVTjtnv aXKrjv Kai ivavriav, yevva etdcoXoz/ avrfjs, aiffBijiriv Kai (pvcriv ■rijv iv toIs (pvroXs. lb. [p. 494 c] 68 'H tyvxr] \6yos vov, Kai ivepyeid tis, axrirep avTos eKeivov. nXXa i/'i'x? 5 F £> " ap-v8pos 6 \6yos. Erin. v. Lib. i. cap. 6, [p. 487 f]. 69 'H T|t>X') — eiKciv Tis icm vov. oTov \6yos 6 iv npocpopa \6yov tov iv ^fv^fj, ovtcd toi Kai owj \6yos vov. Kai r) Tvatra ivipyeia. Kai r\v itpoterai £torjV els aXXou vvoo-Taaiv. oiov irvpos, to fiiv J} o-vvovo-a Sepporris, i) Se fjv napix™- Erin. v. Lib. i. cap. 3, [p. 484 B.] 60 To 8i ttoiovv qv ^v^Jj, tovto Spa ?rXJ;#os iv. ri ovv to irkrj- 601; oJ Xoyoi tSv yiyvop.ivav. Enn. vi. Lib. ii. cap. 5, [p. 699 b]. MORGAN Gr 132 The Fathers of the Christian Church. eternal and co-essential with the first principle, and to flow necessarily from it by a gradual process ; that is, mind from the first principle, and soul from mind. Soul, in like manner, from the same necessity of its nature diffusing the emana-i tions of its essence through matter, and giving it form and life, constituted the visible world, with all that it contains. In the Timceus the three prin- ciples, as has been justly observed, are the Cre- ator, Idea which is denominated the pattern, and Matter. Out of the two last the first is said by a voluntary and deliberate act (/3oi/X»?0ety kcu Xoyiea- fxevos) at the beginning of time to have made the universe, consisting of mind in soul and soul in body. But Plotinus was not discouraged by the difficulty, that would have deterred a less enter- prizing genius ; and he has shewn by the manner in which he surmounted it, that nothing is arduous to a sophist, who is indulged with an arbitrary assumption of abstract principles and senigmatical interpretations. He says that Plato does not always appear to assert the same doctrines ; so that it 61 Ov tclvtov Xeyrnv 7ra.vTa.xrj (paiverai, Iva av Tis in paoias to tov avopos PoiXriixa dSev. Enn. IV. Lib. viii. cap. 1, [p. 469 B.] Cicero in his dialogue, De Nat. Deor. Lib. i. cap. 12, makes Velleius the Stoic bring the same charge of inconstancy of principles against Plato : De Platonis inconstantia longum est dieere, etc. The instances which he produces, are taken from the Timceus and the Books of Laws. If he had thought that the Timceus and the Parrnenides treated precisely of the same subject, and that in both those dialogues Plato intended to convey his own sentiments; the strongest possible argument that could have been advanced, might have been obtained from a comparison of the different doctrines maintained in those two dialogues. For Velleius clearly perceived, that the positive The Fathers of the Christian Church. 133 is not easy to ascertain his opinion 61 : that he i44does but obscurely intimate, (yviynEvos — aiviTro- ftevos. Ennead VI. Lib. ir. Cap. xxii.), that mind [p. en a.] sees ideas in the first principle, together with the principal consequences deduced from it : that when the production of mind or soul is mentioned, it is not intended to signify a production in time, but only to point out the order of causes 62 : that ac- cording to Plato mind sees ideas in the living, which he calls also the intelligible : that by the contemplation of those ideas is generated reason or soul, which divides them into the several exist- ing reasons or souls : that the universal soul was not any where, and did not come any whither ; but body, being near it, partook of it : it was not in body, nor does Plato say so ; but body was in it. Other souls proceed from it, and return to it ; but itself is always above, in that, whose nature is existence. Ennead III. Lib. ix. Cap. i. ii. [pp. 356, ssr.j H5 If we consider the almost innumerable stories of Pagan mythology, together with the various me- thods of relating and explaining them, we shall creation of the world was taught in the Timceus. But Cicero understood the principles of reasoning too well to put such an objection into the mouth of any of his disputants, whom he represents as the leading men of their several sects : tree trium disciplinarum principes. It was incumbent upon Plato to pre- serve a consistency of principles and doctrines in the same dis- course. But it was by no means necessary, that he should maintain the same doctrines in explaining the physiology of Parmenides and the cosmogony of Timseus. 62 'Eiwro8<»j> Se ffjiiv rora yepea-is fj iv %p6va, tov \6yov nepl Tav ae\ ovrav 7roiovfievois. tc5 Se Xoyfi> ttjv yevetriv TvpovairrovTas avTois, alrias Kai raijtas avrols mrohaaei. Enn. V. Lib. i. cap. 6, "[p. 487 C] G2 134 The Fathers of the Christian Church. readily see that it would not be difficult for so sub- til a genius to cull something from them, which to those, who revered his authority, might seem to carry with it an air of probability, and to fall in with his favourite system. The allegorical method of interpreting the Pa- gan mythology was attacked with great spirit and {Adv Nan- acuteness by Arnobius. The new theological mode ones. Lib. iii. " ° cap. 37, sqq] Q f interpretation does not appear to have attracted his notice. He confines himself chiefly to the phy- sical explanations, which were more ancient and general, though most of his observations are equally applicable to the other. One of the most obvious objections is, that both the accounts and interpre- tations of different authors are at great variance with each other. Among other instances he men- tions the Muses, who, according to Mnaseas, were the daughters of Tellus. and Ccelus. Other accounts made them the daughters of Jupiter and Memory, or Mind. Some said, that they were virgins; 63 [Nee defuerunt, qui scriberent Jovem, Junonem ac Miner- vam Penates existere, sine quibus vivere ac sapere nequeamus sed qui penitus nos regant ratione, colore ac spiritu. Ut videtis, efc hie quoque nihil concinens dicitur, nihil una pronuntiatione finitur, nee est aliquid fidum, quo insistere mens possit veritati suk proxima suspicione conjiciens.] 64 From this account it should seem, that very little stress can be laid upon the following passage in Cudworth's True Intellectual System, p. 451. ' Nevertheless it may justly be sus- pected, as G. J. Vossius hath already observed, that there was yet some higher and more sacred mystery, in this Capitoline Trinity, aimed at; namely, a Trinity of divine Hypostases. For these three Roman or Capitoline Gods, were said to have been first brought into Italy out of Phrygia by the Trojans, but before that, into Phrygia by Dardanus, out of the Samothra- cian Island; and that within eight hundred years after the The Fathers of the Christian Church. 135 others affirmed, that they were mothers. Ephorus said, that they were three in number ; Mnaseas, that they were four; Myrtilus, that they were seven ; Crates, that they were eight ; Hesiod, that they were nine. 46 Again, concerning the Penates, Nigidius as-w. c.4o,6v okav 8ebv ipei ns apx^v, o-a(j>ais vpowlwrav on apx^l uioO o irarfjp — iv apxv V ° ^oyos, \6yov voaiv tov tiiov iraph to etvai Iv Ta irarp\ "htyopevov eivai ev apxjj> p. 17. 69 'O 8e6s pev oSv navrrj ev cart Kcii cafKovv, 6 8e awTrjp ypav TroXXa yiyverai, p. 19, [Opp. Tom. IV. p. 21 D.] W \o~d>pa.TOV {mSo-rao-iv noiKiKav Beapjjparav, ircpiexovrav tovs to>v oXav \6yovs, £aivav km olovel ep^rvxpv. Comm. in Johann, p. 36, [Opp. Tom. iv. p. 39 e.] The Fathers of the Christian Church. 139 reasonable souls, p. 99. — auTooiKaioawri vj ovaiu>§m, [Opp.Tom.iv. . j . P- 107 c] •substantial righteousness/ p. 100. — proceeding from [«**. p. ios A.J the Father, as will does from mind. He terms him the living, and, as it were, animated incorporeal 50 substance of various theorems, containing the rea- sons of all things 70 . He distinguishes the divine intellect or wisdom from the logos, though he as- signs them both to Christ. For the Scriptures so explicitly declare the logos, to which they attribute the Creation, to have been Christ, the second per- son ; that he could not, as Plotinus did, assign it an hypostasis distinct from intellect, and denominate it the third person in the divine nature. Having quoted Psalm xlv. 1, he says, the heart signifies the intellectual power of God; the logos that power which declares the things contained in it 71 ; and he says, that the logos always was in wisdom. In explaining the derivation of the third person of the Holy Trinity, he approaches very near the doctrine of Plotinus. ' The Holy Ghost,' says he, ' seems to stand in need of the Son, who adminis- ters to his subsistence, not only that he might be, but also that he might be wise, and reasonable, and just, and whatever else we ought to understand him to be, by a participation of the forementioned con- 5iceptions of Christ 72 . And I think, that the Holy l?1 Ttju Kaphiav tov Oeov ttjv vorjriKijV avTov Kai TrpoQeTiKrjv ircpi rav oXav 8vvap.1v €K\rj7rTeov, tov fie \6yov T&v eV €K€lvtj iirayyeknuov [1. cmayyekTiKov], p. 42, [Opp. Tom. IV. p. 45 E.] r 72 Movov tov povoytvovs cpv seeds of many heresies ; but he often protests ?3 Acfyov olov tot in xapbias avBpmirov vopi^ovcri tot tov 6ee>0, Rai. (rocpiav oiroiav Trjv iv ^fv^rj, teal Sm tovto irp6cr \6ya> (paaiv' awntp Kal tov avBpanrov apa t cavTov \6yco avBpamov eva. Athanasius contra Sab. Greg. p. 651, [Opp. Tom. I. p. 37 e.] W Oi'Se cos tov ivbs Sis ovopa£optvov, wore tov avrbv aWdre pev Traripa, aXXoVf 8e vibv e'auroO yiyveo-daf tovto yap 2aj3e\Xios The Fathers of the Christian Church. 141 against those heretical applications of them, and advances, in opposition, sound doctrines. The most important heresy which sprung up in the third century was that of Sabellius, whether we consider it in itself or in its consequences. He adopted the usual method of explaining the nature of the Son by stating him to be the wisdom or the reason of the Father. But he maintained that the reason of God was identically the same with God, constituting one person with the Father; in the same manner as a man together with his reason composes one man 73 . Thus the same person, being really one but having two names, is at one time the father, and at another time his own son 74 . This opinion of Sabellius was embraced by some bishops of Pentapolis in Upper Libya ; inso- much that scarcely any other doctrine relative to 53 the son of God was taught in the churches of those parts 75 . Dionysius, bishop of Alexandria, to whom the care of those churches belonged, sent and counselled those who had been guilty, to relinquish that impious doctrine, and return to the true faith. When he found that his expostulations had not produced the intended effect, he wrote them a let- ter in which he undertook to prove the falsehood of the doctrine which they were so strenuous in Ai/3w;r TTjViKavra rives Tmv etvuTKomav etppovrjaav ra 2a/3eAXiou' not topovtov 'laxvaav rats cirwoiais, v 6eAs %v it6tc SXoyos; Cont. Avian. Orat. n. p. 330, [1. p. 421, § 24, ed. B.] W Eis ha fwvoyevrj Xoyoc, (roipiav, vlbv, ix. tov Trarphs avapxas Kai dV'SifflS yeyewrjfihov. Xoyov 8e ov npofyopiKov, ovk ivbiaderov, ovk anoppolav tov rekeiov, ov Tu-rjo-ai TJjs airadovs s, oilre irpo^okrjV, dXX' vibv avTOTeXrj, £avra re Kai ipepyovvra. k.t.X. Expos. Fidei, p. 240, [Tom. 1. p. 99, ed. B.} 146 The Fathers of the Christian Church. tutes but one person ; in the same manner as a man together with his word or reason composes [Qpp.T0m.11. but one man. Cont. Sab. Greq. p. 651. Upon this i«8 p. 3Te.] j * # J he remarks that the word of a man neither lives nor subsists, and is only the motion of a living and subsisting heart ; and passes away as soon as it is uttered. But the word of the Lord, as the Psalmist declares, endureth for ever in heaven. This he elsewhere calls substantial word and substantial wisdom 80 . Arius maintained, on the contrary, that this principle which stated the real wisdom and reason of God to be the Son in the Holy Trinity, is mere Sabellianism. When he denied the eternity of the Son, he did not affirm that there ever was a time when God was without wisdom or reason. He has in himself his own wisdom and his own reason, which is not Christ, but in which he made Christ 81 . There are some passages in the writings of Athanasius, which seem to intimate that the prin- ciples of Arius were connected with some Jewish and Grecian tenets. He says, that impiety is intro- duced by their principles, or rather Judaism, differ- ent from that contained in the Scriptures, which has Hellenism closely following it 82 . In another 159 80 Oi8r]s Xoyos Kai oia-icoSrjs (ro(pta. Contr. Arian. Orat.v. p. 520, [it. § l,p. 618A, ed. Ben.] 81 26(pos [lev 4(tti Kai ovk akoyos, Ibiav be e^et ip eavTa o-o(f>lav Kai \diov \6yov, ov tov Xpiarbv 5e, dXX* eV a Kai tov XpirrTCtv eVow/o-e. Orat. v. Contra Arian. p. 522, [Or. iv. p. 620 b.] See to the same purpose the third oration, p. 408, [Or. n. p. 487, sq.] 82 'AdeSrTjs yap (K rovrav ila-ayerai, Kai fiaWov irapa tcls ypa- The Fathers of the Christian Church. 147 passage he exhibits a more particular account of the principles of Arius. By comparing that with a passage of the same import near the beginning of Philo Trepl Koa/xoirouas, it will be obvious from what source Arius, as well as Tertullian, derived his notions. God, says he, was alone, and reason and wisdom were not yet. But when he was dis- posed to create us, he then made one being, and named him reason, and son, and wisdom, that by means of him he might create us. There are then, says he, two wisdoms ; one God's own, and subsist- ing with him. In this wisdom the other, the son, was formed 33 . In this passage we have the strong- est features of the twofold logos of Philo ; viz. The intelligible world, which he calls also the reasoning of God when he was in the act of creating the world, the pattern according to which this sensible world was made : and secondly, The wisdom and intellect of God, in which that pattern, the intelli- i6ogible world, was formed. Athanasius in a great number of places controverts the principle of Arius, that the son was produced on our account, and for the express purpose of forwarding our creation; and that he is called the wisdom of God in a figu- rative sense, on account of the great display, which (pas 'lovfta'io-pos, ex av *yy^ ff eiraKoKov8ovvTa tov TLXkrjvto-fiov, p. 296, [Epist. ad Episc. JEg. Opp. Tom. I. p. 283 B, ed. B.] 83 'Hv yap, 0170-1, poms 6 Beos, Ka\ oSira rjv 6 \6yos Kai 77 o-oajia- efra SeXijaas yp-as 8r)piovpyrjo-ai, ToYe Se [S17 I. B.] naroirjKev eva nva, Kai //yx») the third hypostasis : at other times they make Sriiuuovpyos, at other times i§ea j? Trapdceiyna, at other times ^v^rj the second hypostasis. II. The second inference which I would make from the preceding investigation is, that it is ex-t tremely dangerous to affect to be wise in holy things, above what is written in the word of God. It is to this disposition, I conceive, that we are to attribute, in a great measure, the present miserable condition of the Jewish nation. They would not be satisfied with that degree of information which 171 Jehovah condescended to give them of the order of his dispensations, and of the nature of that being, who was to come from God as their Saviour and their "King. They rashly speculated upon things that were not revealed, and they framed to themselves a system of belief widely different from the truth. Hence, when in the fulness of time God sent his Son into the world, the world 158 Conclusion, knew him not : when he came unto his own, his own received him not. The same spirit of curiosity and desire of pry- ing into heavenly things have, though in a different manner, produced very pernicious consequences in the Church of Christ. The writings of Philo Judseus furnished the Fathers of the Christian Church with the fatal means of deceiving themselves and others. The figurative language in which that author delivered himself concerning the Logos, whenever he meant by it, either the divine intellect, its internal opera- tion, the ideal object of its contemplation, or the external expression of it, led them to imagine that he attributed to it a real and essential personality. From the epithets affixed to this supposed person, they naturally conceived that he could be no other than our Lord and Saviour, Jesus Christ. To make this plausible they maintained, that what was expressed by the word Logos, was not in God, as it was in man, a mere power, or operation, or notion, or word; but was a real and living sub- 17a stance, possessed of a personality distinct from the great principle of existence, to which it be- longed. This received countenance from the doc- trines of Plato, that ideas were most properly the real entities. Hence was devised the metaphysical argument for the eternity of the second person of the Tri- nity, which was built upon this plain and incontro- vertible maxim, that God the Father could never Conclusion. 159 have been destitute of reason. Hence the second person is called by Athanasius substantial Logos and substantial Wisdom. Hence arose the conceit, that he flowed necessarily from the divine intellect exerted on itself. Hence Origen styles him, The living and, as it were, animated substance of vari- ous theorems, containing the reasons of all things. It unfortunately happened, that many signal heresies were produced by men's accepting a false hypothesis and an erroneous explanation, and turn- ing them against the doctrine, for the illustration of which they were devised. — The Gnostics, pre- suming that every production of the divine intel- lect was necessarily a substance, imagined an almost infinite number of such productions, and attempted to explain by them the origin of those several orders of JEons, which constituted so strik- ing a part of the eastern philosophy. 173 Praxeas and Sabellius admitted that Christ was the intellect and wisdom of God the Father, and thence concluded, that he was one with him, as well in personality as in essence ; thus attempting to subvert a doctrine by means of an hypothesis, which was founded, if it had any foundation at all, upon the supposed truth of that doctrine, and which was advanced, not to prove, but to explain it. Arius seems to have felt the force of the rea- soning of Praxeas and Sabellius ; but he was too well versed in the Scriptures not to see, that a dis- tinct personality is in them attributed to Christ. He therefore perceived the necessity of projecting a new mode of defence; but, like many others, H3 160 Conclusion. who had gone before him, he embraced hypo- thetical explanations, to the injury of the truth, which was to be explained. He acknowledged with Praxeas and Sabellius, that the real intellect or wisdom of God was no other than God him- self. He admitted with Tertullian, that the imme- diate production of the divine intellect was neces- sarily a living substance. Hence he maintained, that Christ was, what Philo called the intelligible world; or, as Origen styled him, the living and animated substance of various theorems, contain- ing the reasons of all things ; denominated Logos, and Son, and Wisdom, though not the real wis- dom of God, yet formed in it ; not existing from all eternity, but created on our account, that God 174 by means of him might create us s . Thus it appears that, though Christians did not, as has been maintained by some, derive the great and characteristic doctrines of Iheir holy profession from the impure source of Pagan philo- sophy; they did, at a very early period indeed, adopt principles and modes of interpretation, which but ill accorded with the simplicity of the Gospel. They presumed to intrude with unhallowed step into the sanctuary of the most High, and to attempt with sacrilegious hands to tear off the veil from 2 So strongly was this hypothesis rooted in the minds of men, that it was not even yet abandoned ; and Arius has been combated on his own ground. It has been admitted, that Christ was the intelligible world, containing the ideas of all things. Yet still his proper eternity has been maintained upon meta- physical principles. The divine intellect is from its own nature ever active. Before all external creation it was employed from Conclusion. 161 those august mysteries, which God himself had concealed from human sight. The event was such as might naturally have been expected. Professing themselves to be wise, they became fools; and God gave many of them up unto a reprobate mind. 175 All the extravagancies and impurities of the several orders of Gnostics, all the impiety of Praxeas and Sabellius, the heresy of Arius, and the bloody contentions, which rent in sunder the Eastern Church, and paved the way for the reception of the impostures of Mahomet, are to be referred to this source. Hence also have arisen many of those disputes and bitter reproaches, which in latter days have disgraced the Christian name, and in- jured the cause of genuine piety. Hence was derived the most opprobrious of all imputations, that the sublime doctrine of the Trinity, the dis- tinguishing feature of Christianity in every age, was drawn from the dregs of Pagan philosophy. This should serve as a warning to men, if any thing can, to confine themselves in their researches within the bounds that have been prescribed to them by divine wisdom, and to satisfy themselves with such communications, as God has thought proper to make, of his nature and dispensations. If they would act wisely, they should exert eternity in an internal contemplation of the ideal pattern of the things, which were in due time to be created. The reader may see this argument very ingeniously drawn out and enforced by Norris, in his Theory of the Ideal or Intelligible World; who, in the true spirit of his system, maintains, that all things were made not by Christ, but according to Christ, that is, ac- cording to those ideas or patterns, which compose his essence. i62 Conclusion. their faculties, first, in proving the authenticity of revelation ; secondly, in ascertaining the genuine sense of it. For they may be well assured thatj if God has made to men any revelation of his nature and dispensations, he has revealed as much as is proper for them to know, in their present cir- cumstances. Nay, if they attempt to proceed a step farther than their heavenly guide has conde- scended to conduct them, they will not only be 176 disappointed in the expectation of making any real progress, but will even be led out of the way, and removed much farther from the object of their vain pursuit, than if they had stopped at the point where divine Providence had set them their bounds, that they should not pass. Of this every one is sensible, with respect to preceding dispensations. We are all ready to ac- knowledge, that the intimation with which God favoured Adam, respecting the seed of the woman, was adapted with wonderful wisdom and mercy to his particular situation : that it conveyed the pre- 4 cise degree of information, which the otherwise desperate state of the affairs of our first parent required ; but that it was not sufficient to enable him to trace out that amazing scheme of Provi- dence, which the divine Being afterwards vouch- safed in the fulness of time gradually to disclose to the sons of men The same observation will apply to every period of the Patriarchal and Jewish dispensations ; till God sent his Son into the world in the likeness of sinful flesh, when perhaps as much of the mystery of godliness was revealed, as is Conclusion. 163 requisite to be known by man in this our state of pilgrimage. As so extraordinary an atonement was made for the transgression of our first parents, and the depravity of their posterity, the display of that stupendous proceeding seems well calculated to 17 7 produce in men a strong sense of the heinous na- ture of sin, and a dread and abhorrence of its pollutions. It is the language of religion, that we are to consider this world as a state of discipline, preparatory to a future life of superior excellence and enjoyment ; and we have every reason to be- lieve, from the representations of the Holy Scrip- tures, that Christ will reign at the head of his saints in his kingdom of glory. In this view it is easy to perceive how expedient it was, that we, who are hereafter to be his subjects, should, in this our state of discipline, have some intimation of the dignity of our Lord and Master. But it does not thence follow, that it is either expedient or consistent with the limited nature of our facul- ties, that the mysteries of the divine nature should be completely unfolded to us ; or that we, who cannot fully comprehend the internal constitution of the most common object, which is exposed to our senses, should be encouraged to pry into the deep recesses of that Being, whose goings forth have been of old from everlasting. Error, and many times impiety, must be the consequence of so rash and overweening a conceit of our own abili- ties. It becomes us rather, and will be found in the end to be most consistent with our true in- 164 Conclusion. terest, to be satisfied with that portion of light which God himself has imparted to us in his holy word ; and not to flatter ourselves that we shall be able to encrease it by a pretended philosophy and 178 vain deceit, after the traditions of men, after the rudiments of the world, and not after Christ—, Hcec fere dicere habui de Natura Deorum, mm ut earn tollerem, sed ut intelligeretis, quam esset obscura, et quam difficiles explicatus haberet. Cic. de Nat, JDeor. III. 39. In a former 3 treatise I undertook to demon- strate, that true philosophy has no tendency to un- dermine divine revelation, and that a well-grounded philosopher may be a true Christian : that the legi- timate object of philosophy, as well as of revela- tion, is truth : that the pursuit of this object, by a careful attention to and investigation of the ap- pearances and operations of nature, has a direct tendency to enliven and invigorate the intellectual powers ; and that the possession of it enlarges the capacity of the mind, and prepares it for the reception and right apprehension of the doctrines of Christianity. — In this I have endeavoured to point out some strikingly-pernicious effects, which have arisen from the rash attempt of men to ex- plain the most profound mysteries of the nature and essence of God, by the vain and groundless conceits of speculative sophists ; instead of con- fining themselves to an investigation of the moral character of the Deity by the united aid of reason 17c 3 The dissertation, to which the honorary prize was ad- judged, by Teyler's Theological Society, at Haarlem, in April Conclusion. 165 and revelation, and of the duties which result from the several relations that he bears to them, of Cre- ator, Preserver, Redeemer, Sanctifier, and Judge. I find that in thus asserting and illustrating the use and abuse of reason, when applied to reli- gion, I have conformed, without being aware of it at the time, to the opinion of a man, whose com- prehensive and penetrating mind has contributed not a little towards advancing true philosophy to that exalted state of dignity, which it at present so justly possesses. I will produce this testimony as the conclusion of the whole. "By the contemplation of nature to induce and enforce the acknowledgment of God, and to demonstrate his power, providence, and goodness, is an excellent argument, and hath been excel- lently handled by divers. But on the other side, out of the contemplation of nature, or ground of human knowledges, to induce any verity or per- suasion concerning the points of faith, is in my judgment not safe : Da fidei, quce fidei sunt. For the heathen themselves conclude as much in that excellent and divine fable of the golden chain: That Gods and men were not able to draw Jupiter down to the earth; but, contrariwise, Jupiter was able to draw them up to heaven. " So as we ought not to attempt to draw down 180 or submit the mysteries of God to our reason; but, contrariwise, to raise and advance our reason to the divine truth. So as in this part of knowledge, 1785. [The prize-medal, which was presented on the occasion, is now in the University Library.] 1 66 Conclusion. touching divine philosophy, I am so far from noting any deficienee, as I rather note an excess r whereunto I have digressed, because of the ex- treme prejudice, which both religion and philo- sophy have received, and may receive, by being commixed together; as that which undoubtedly will make an heretical religion, and an imaginary and fabulous philosophy." Bacon of the Advance- ment of Learning. EDITED FOR THE SYNDICS OF THE Already Published. M. Minucii Felicis Octavius. The Text newly revised from the Original MS. with an English Commentary., Analysis, Introduction, and Indices. Edited by the Rev. H. A. Holden, M.A., Fellow and Classical Lecturer of Trinity College. Small Octavo. 9s. Qd. Theophili Episcopi Antiochensis Libri Tres ad Autolycum. Edidit, Prolegomenis Versione Notulis Indicibus instruxit Guuelmus Gilson Humphry, S.T.B. Collegii Sanctiss. Trin. apud Cantabrigieases quondam Socius. Post Octavo. 6s. CiESAR Mokgan on the Trinity of Plato, and of Philo Jvdavas, and of the effects which an attachment to their writings had upon the prin- ciples and reasonings of the Fathers of the Christian Church. A new edition, revised by H. A. Holden, M.A., Fellow of Trinity College. Small Octavo. 4*. De Obligatione Conscientiai Prailectiones Decern Oxonii in Schola Theologica habitce A Roberto Sanderson, SS. Theologiae Ibidem Professore Regio. With English Notes, including an abridged Translation, by W. Whewell, D.D., Master of Trinity College. Oc- tavo. 9s. The Homilies, with various Readings, and the Quotations from the Fathers given at length in the Original Languages. Edited by G. E. Corrie, D.D., Master of Jesus College, and Norrisian Professor of Divinity ; Examining Chaplain to the Lord Bishop of Ely. Octavo. 10s. 6d. Pearson on the Creed. Revised and corrected by Temple Chevallier, B.D., Subwarden of the University of Durham. Octavo. 12s. In this edition the folio of 1669 has been taken as the principal model of the text, being the latest edition to which Bishop Pearson made any additions or alterations ; and the quotations from the Fathers have been verified throughout. The passages from the Rabbinical Writings and Chaldee Paraphrases have also been carefully collated. 2 Works editkd for the Syndics of the University Press. Wilson's Illustration of the Method of explaining the New Testament, by the early opinions of Jews and Christians concerning Christ. Edited by T. Tubton-, D.D., Lord Bishop of Ely. 8*. Twysden's Historical Vindication of the Church of Eng- land in point of Schism. Edited, with the Author's MS. Corrections, by Professor Cobbie. 7s. 6d. Lectures on Divinity, delivered in the University of Cam- bridge. By John Hey, D.D. Third Edition. Two Volumes, Octavo. 30*. Cambridge Greek and English Testament, in Parallel Columns, on the same page. Edited by J. Scholepibld, M.A., Professor of Greek in the University and Canon of Ely. Third Edition. Is. 6d. Cambridge Greek Testament. Small Octavo, 3s. 6d. Archbishop Usher's Answer to a Jesuit, with other Tracts on Popery. Edited by Professor Scholefield. Octavo. 13*. 6d. In Preparation. The Works of Isaac Barrow, compared with the Original MSS., and enlarged with Materials hitherto unpublished. New Edition. Grotius de Jure Belli ac Pads : with the Notes of Barbeyrac and others, accompanied by an abridged Translation of the text, by W. Wheweix, D.D., Master of Trinity College. Three Volumes, 8vo. (Jn the Press.) TheophylaCti Commentarii in Novum Testamentum. Edited by W. G. Humphry, B.D., late Fellow of Trinity College, Vicar of Northolt, and Chaplain to the Lord Bishop of London. Tertulliani Liber de Prcescriptione Hcereticorum, with Intro- duction and English Notes, by J. J. S. Perowne, M. A., Fellow and Classical Lecturer of Corpus Christi College. Chrysostomi Liber de Sacerdotio, by Frederic Field, M.A., late Fellow of Trinity College, and editor of Chbysostom's Homilies. Works edited for the Syndics of the University Press. 3 Irenjeus, Selections from, edited by the Rev.W. W.Harvey, M. A. late Fellow of King's College. Smith's Select Discourses, edited by H. G. Williams, B.D., Fellow of Emmanuel College. Wheatly on the Common Prayer, edited by Professor Corrie, D.D., Master of Jesus College. Greek and Latin Classics with English Notes for the use of University Students by several Editors. Cicero pro Milone, and other Orations. Cicero de Ojfficiis. Demosthenes adversus Leptinem. Demosthenes contra Midiam. Euripides. Homer, The Iliad and Odyssey. Isocrates. Lucretius de Rerum Natura. Ovid's Fasti. Plutarch, Select Biographies of. Xenophon's Hellenica. Xenophon's Memorabilia, Book I.