iOETHE o o o o o o o Representative of the Modern Art Spirit o o o o o o o By WILLIAM M. BRYANT l\ ) THE GIFT OF . '^ ^ ^2^., :^. ...Ar.H.t.l^. "^.Z^/f-^:. . .193.89?" ""'™""'>"-"'"^ 3 1924 026 180 343 The original of tliis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924026180343 BY THE SAME AUTHOR: I. The World-Energy aud its Self-Conserya- lion.— 12 mo $1.50 II. The Philosophy of Art, being the second part of Hegel's uEsthetik, in which are unfolded, historically, the three great fundamental phases of the art-activity of the world. Translated and accompanied with an Intro- ductory Essay giving an outline of the entire ^sthetik. (Out of print.) III. Philosopby of Landscape Painting.— 16 mo., pp. 300 $1 00 IV. Eternity, a Thread in the Weaving of a Life. — 16 mo., pp. 40 $0 25 V. A Syllabns of Psychology.— Second Edition |o 25 VI. A Text-Book of Psychology. (In prepara- tion.) VII. The Sonl of Myths. (To appear shortly.) ■piRF'TM" Men T-^T ©BEIP i^IT 5fI11T ^MTE SO@@L ®F rHIL@S@riHlT/'' ST, ^^-^.^^ «u«,. Kimn Ho lETi^r 1663; TmE RlVEf^lDE PCiBLI^MINCj CO. 706 Olive .StkeeTj •5r, Loaia, Mo. q? CcPYnOMTED - - 1669. "if , DEDICATED TO iLLi^n To M/^iKiis, LL ho Leader of PhujO-sopmic Thouqut IN America. mtrm s said to have once exclaimed : "Happy is he who from his 1 youth knows what art is." In this respect, as in so many others, he is himself to be counted as one of the happy. For if the art of which he had knowledge in his youth was not of the highest degree of excellence, it was nevertheless of such character and variety as greatly to stimulate his interest in every department of art. At the same time, during the period of his youth, there was a veritable confusion of tongues in Germany respecting the proper standard of work and achievement in art. And this was, as might be expected, especially true of poetry — the most complex of all the forms of art and, as it proved, the form in which Goethe was to unfold his finest powers. Safely out of this confusion of tongues he was to be led by the clear voice of the greatest of English singers. Other influences there were indeed, but this was the greatest of all for him. Under the influence of Shakespeare, Goethe became perfectly clear that the heart, the very soul of a great poem, as of any other work of art, must be a great theme ; so that the poem itself is but a living idea spontaneously unfolded into a rhythmic organic form. It is in this relation between these two great poets that I find the clue to what I shall have to say to you at the present time. Goethe himself makes explicit reference to the dependence o f the individual upon the characteristics of his own time, and declares it to be inconceivable that one should be the sam^ individual had he been born ten years earlier or ten years later. Applying this principle to the case of Shakespeare, an acute critic has remarked that the preeminence of this poet over all others is to be explained, not merely by his transcendent genius, but also by the altogether unique conditions of the mental and moral life of his time. Within the century a new world had opened up for exploration and conquest. Everywhere new hopes had been awakened and the intellectual life quickened. Through this process the untitled man had given abundant evidence of his worth; so that there was emerging into ever clearer view a title likely to prove superior to all others — manhood for its own sake. To this class without titles, but creating for itself a new title, the writers as well as the performers of dramas belonged. The great world itself had become a most fascinating stage, and men and women, without distinction of rank, had proven to be players of most extraordinary parts upon this stage. There was a wonderful access of life in man, and especially in the man of low degree who had hitherto seemed to have no ground for confident self-assertion. Now all had changed. And with the buoyant sense of achievement there grew a desire to see the re- enactment of the great deeds of the world. With such conditions the revival of the drama on a new basis was btit inevitable. Equally natural too was it that, as our critic further suggests : " The distinctive feature of the English drama should be this : that it had its birth among the common people ; that its appeals were made to common people ; and that its growth was the natural development of the forest plant, not the artificial development of the conservatory." In other words, the English drama is specifically the outgrowth of extraordinary conditions, through which men were awakening to a more rational view of themselves and of the world in which they lived. Evidently then, if we would rightly estimate Shakespeare in his character as a man of genius, we must regard him as not merely — 4 — the finest product, but also as a perfectly natural product of that great, unique period of discovery in which the Middle Ages cul- minated, and which also served to usher in the Modem Time. The world of antiquity had been characterized by the mutual exclusion and antagonism of different peoples. The period still so persistently called the Dark Ages, was characterized by the forcible subordination indeed of one people by another, but also, and not less decidedly by the complete blending of the conquerors with the conquered. It seemed, orrather it now seems to us on first view, to have been a period of utter confusion. And yet, on closer view, the confusion is seen to have been but the outer aspect of the profound process of the interi-a&vaa. of the finest elements then existing in humanity. Race blended with race. Thought fused with thought. Language mingled with language. Europe was a vast laboratory. European history was a mighty and prolonged chemical reaction ; and the product of all this activity was: that new and still more finely en- dowed races sprang up, with vastly increased powers of intelligence, requiring and spontaneously producing a correspondingly increased complexity of modes of expression. The middle age period was a period of ever intensifying eager- ness and reasonableness of inquiry. Hence it could not fail to culminate in a great period of Discovery — the crowning triumph in which is the matured, and yet ever maturing, self-discovery of Man. It was, doubtless, in some sense a period well worthy of being named the Dark Ages. But in the midst of it all there was ever working a divine process which was but the continuation of what was long ago symbolized as the "Light shining in darkness," while at every step in the process it became more and more evident that "the darkness quencheth it not" and can never have power to per- manently reduce its splendor. To repeat, then, the man of antiquity was limited by the very conditions of his Ufe to the narrowest provincialism. The man of the Middle Ages in his turn was swept onward by a current he was -5- unable to comprehend. But this current may now be seen to have been essentially nothing else than the determined struggle of human reason toward complete self-consciousness and therefore toward genuine Freedom. And this struggle it was which, with ever^n- creasing victory, prepared the way for, and also gave rise to. Mod- ern Man who, as a conscious citizen of the world of Reason, is now working out, and must henceforth continue to work out, his own salvation — no longer indeed with fear and trembling, but rather, as becomes him, with boundless hope and indestructible self- reliance. This is especially the character of the Modem Man as por- trayed in the dramas of Shakespeare. Nay, it is precisely this unconquerable enthusiasm, this divinity in humanity, that consti- tutes the central theme of all modern history. Everywhere man is seen to be approaching with ever-increasing steadiness, and along all the natural avenues of the world, toward his own maturity as a rational being and hence toward his own complete reconciliation with the divine World-Order. And if the process, now visibly going forward in and through modern man, seems less miraculous than the life of the man of mediaeval times it is nevertheless more truly godlike. The struggle is not less earnest, but far more intelligent, and thus it is successful in a far higher sense and in far higher degree. It is, I repeat, this concrete unfolding of Divinity in Humanity that constitutes the central theme of all modern art. And I have now to ask you to consider with me the question : How far may we reasonably regard Goethe as a representative of the spirit that, on the one hand, creates our modern works of art, and, on the other hand, is appealed to in those works ? The true answer can, as 1 think, be found in no other way so well — perhaps in no other way at all — than through a consideration of successive characteristic works in which Goethe's own views as to art are unfolded. In this way we shall see that in this as in other respects Goethe's views passed through several clearly distinct stages in attaining maturity. And we shall also find that the fully matured Goethe is the true representative of the modern art-spirit. Three of his works especially serve to illustrate the essential stages of progress in his general estimate of the nature and functions of art. The first is the Goetz von Berlichingen. The second is the Iphigenie auf Tauris. The third is the Faust, and especially the Helena, or so much of the second part of Faust as deals directly with the relation between the Classic and the Romantic world. The Goetz von Berlichingen is the earliest of Goethe's serious attempts at dramatic representation. In it the youth of but twenty- two years proves himself the enthusiastic disciple of Shakespeare. He will not be bound by the letter of the narrow, conventional rule of the "unities." He will simply note how the world he has chosen to represent unfolds into outer reality through the workings of its own inner nature. Thus and not otherwise will he portray it. The theme is historical. More specifically it is the transition from the feudal to the imperial phase of the social organism. In the development of this theme the heroic individual is made the representative of the self-asserting exclusiveness characteristic of the feudal system. His noble qualities compel our admiration and even our personal sympathy. And yet a calm judgment no less certainly compels our assent to the justice of his overthrow. It is true that his exalted personal integrity shines out all the more conspicuously in contrast with the unscrupulous cunning of those who represent the opposite cause. Thus far his indignation at their want of honor is wholly justified. And so long as the cause is lost sight of in the individual, we can- not but regard the culmination of this drama as an immoral one — though even here the evil-working individuals are represented as suffering the just penalties of their evil deeds. On the other hand, however, there is offered us in this drama by no means a portrayal of a conflict between mere private interests. Such conflict appears only incidentally, and not as the real theme of the representation. Rather the overthrow of Goetz is demanded by the highest law of morality, because he has identified himself with the doomed cause of exclusivism — doomed because it bars the way to the further development of man. The perpetuation of feudalism is the perpetuation of provincial- ism. It is to hopelessly confine the growing youth of the world in a cradle of oak and thus to make of him a monstrous dwarf. Thus, however abundant, and varied, and substantial may be the grounds for admiration of the hero as an individual, his life must inevitably prove a failure, for the reason that his life has come to depend for its chief significance upon a cause which in its very nature is doomed to perish. On the contrary the imperial cause stands for the widening and enriching of the conditions of human progress. It is a means — and at this stage an essential means — serving to lift man out of the dwarfage of provincialism and to make of him a citizen of the world, symmetrical, and of full stature. Hence it is that the representatives of this cause, even though they may be hopelessly dwarfed as individuals, are yet borne onward to certain success in its outward, conspicuous form. Their security as individuals, their only real significance in the world, lies in the fact that they are identified with a cause which in its very nature is destined to present victory and to the final conquest of the world — though in the course of this conquest the cause in its outward aspect must undergo many and radical transformations. It is better then that the misguided hero, while preserving his" personal integrity, should fail in the outer purpose of his life rather than that, through his success in this mistaken outer purpose, he should be the cause of failure in the essential inward lives of multi- tudes of other individuals. On the other hand it is better also that a few unworthy individuals should be allowed a momentary outward success so long as, by being the chance representatives of a valid cause, they prove to be instruments in advancing the conditions for the truest success on the part of a people, which truest success con- — 8 — sists in the symetrical unfolding of their intellectual and moral life. At the beginning of the Christian era it was better that the legions of Varus should be destroyed, so that the German people might have unrestricted opportunity to develop the noble qualities of their race to maturity. At the beginning of the sixteenth cen- tury of the Christian era^ when the German people had matured those qualities so far as was possible for them to do in isolation from the other elements of a fully rounded civilization, it was better that such men as Goetz — the representatives of continued exclu- sivism — should perish, so that the German people might be brought into complete organic relations with the rest of the world, and thus enter with all their noble vigor into genuine, cosmopolitan life. Considered in and for himself each individual is of infinite sig- nificance. But any one individual considered with reference to his mere accidental private interests proves to be wholly insignificant, and especially when he puts himself in opposition to the essential, permanent interests of all other individuals. Nay, to do this is to put himself in opposition to that universal, ideal, or true self toward the realization of which it is the common duty of all men to struggle. In other words : when any one indi- vidual enters into conflict with all other individuals, he also in that very fact enters into fatal conflict with his own true self. And the consequence of this is, necessarily, not self-fulfillment, but self-annul- ment. Such, as it seems to me, is the central thought of this earliest of Goethe's dramatic representations. But what has all this to do with Goethe as a representative of the modern art-spirit ? Explicitly, nothing. Implicitly, very much. Goethe speaks here as an artist, not as an art-critic. He has discovered the chief of all the unities and revels — ^nay, rather, as yet he struggles — in the discovery. Underlying his rejection of the formal unities of the traditional drama there appears the clear, un- hesitating acceptance of that vital, all-inclusive unity which is to become the guiding principle of modern art and which may be — 9 — named : the absolute continuity of human Life. The life of every man is bound up organically with the life of every other man. In this, too, there is involved the corollary that provincialism or exclusivism is no less fatal to the ultimate interests of art than to the ultimate interests of any other phase of man's existence. At the same time it is not to be denied that this special applica- tion to art of the fundamental idea dramatically unfolded in the Goetz is only latent there. The artist is ever a spontaneous critic ; the true art-critic has ever latent within him the essential character- istics of the artist. To which of these two classes any individual will ultimately be found to belong must depend upon whether the critical or the creative predominates within him. With Goethe there can be no question that the creative pre- dominates through his whole life. Nor can there be any question that through his whole life the critical unfolded continuously into ever greater clearness and power as a factor of his mind. For this reason is he known as a "philosophic poet." Reflection comes more and more to the surface, even in his poetic work, as he ad- vances in years. Hence while the guiding principle of his art-work is to be traced out from that work itself, yet suggestions of utmost value to the art-critic are found in explicit, though detached, form throughout his conversations and other incidental utterances. A marked advance in both the creative and the critical aspect of Goethe's power is evident when we turn from the Goetz to the Iphi- genia. The former is and remains a prose drama. It represents the prosaic-historical. In it too Goethe is still himself so far a pro- vincial as to dwell with decided partiality upon the hero of provin- cialism. Doubtless the most explicit factor in the motive which impels him to this representation is the feeling that the Teutonic hero should be vindicated. And yet, as we have seen, he accepts without hesitation the necessity of the final overthrow of his hero. If prose is felt to be the proper form of expression in which to rep- resent the career of so one-sided a hero, yet the true art-spirit, already so vigorous and clear in Goethe, will not permit that, in the culmination, poetic justice should be left unsatisfied. The Iphigenia, on the other hand, passes through a remarkable transformation, or even series of transformations, being first written out in prose and afterward with a fairly loving care and with intense enthusiasm developed into the beautiful versified form in which it is now commonly known. What interests us here especially however is the new point of view at which Goethe had arrived respecting art. And this again is to be found, partly in the central conception of the drama, partly in the chief inference to be drawn from that conception. We have but to note at the outset that the selection of the theme indicates the character of the newly unfolded tendency, while in the mode of its treatment we may trace the limits of the newly formed creed. The theme indeed is of special significance. It is found, too, not in the Teutonic world, but in the classic world of antiquity. The pure maiden who was about to take upon herself the sacred obligations of wedlock has been sacrificed for the purpose of secur- ing the restoration to the family of one who has proven herself unfaithful to those obligations. At the same time Helen, as the wife of a Grecian prince, repre- sents the sacred institution of the family, and this in direct con- nection with the state, through the power of which alone the family is rendered secure. And not only so, but as the most beautiful of women^ she represents the fundamental art-interest of symetry, of perfect rhythmic form. Doubly then is her restoration demanded — on the one hand, that the morality of social life may be reaffirmed as inviolable ; and on the other hand that the world of art may not permanently lose one of its essential factors. The destiny of Helen is the destiny at once of morality and of art. Nor can these elements of human life be preserved — still less can they be restored when lost — otherwise than through sacrifice ; and no sacrifice can be acceptable to the Gods save as the sacrifice is based upon purity of purpose and of life. Neither can the unwilling sacrifice avail aught. Agamemnon may indeed present his daughter as an offering to the offended divinity, but unless the will of that daughter fully coincide in the offering, preferring the furtherance of the sacred cause of the Greeks to her own happiness, the sacrifice will be to no purpose ; as even Euripides did not fail to see and emphasize in his representa- tion of this theme. Thus Iphigenia also represents a divine element ; and this element is the very soul of that of which Helen more conspicuously forms the type. Unless vivified by purity the element of perfect rhythmic beauty cannot survive as such, but must swiftly pass into monstrous forms. It is this divine element of purity, already clearly involved in the ancient myth, which Goethe takes up and unfolds into beautiful form akin to the finest models of classic grace, and yet so as to radiate from every line the deeper estimate of purity which the modern mind has formed. Even to the mind of antiquity, indeed the clue to this deeper estimate was in some sense already visible. There too the sacrifice which the pure one is called upon to make shall in no sense be a sacrifice of purity itself. If from Iphigenia there is taken away the happiness and sacred offices of wedded hfe, she is given in lieu of this a miraculously preserved life with a wholly divine destiny. Significantly enough, too, is this secured to her; for in the moment of sacrifice she is caught up unhurt and borne away to unknown regions by the very Goddess at whose demand the sacri- fice has been made. Truly from the solution of one problem another mystery beckons ! And it is in pursuance of this divine intimation that Goethe has been able to discover and make plain to us the positive, diviner import that from the first lay enfolded in this myth. It is true that the divinity does not permit the daughter of Agamemnon to enter upon the expected office as priestess in that temple of purity known by the name of Home, but the same divine will has decreed that through her sacrifice on this side, she shall soon find herself officiating as priestess before the altar in the temple of the Goddess of Purity herself — ^her mission henceforth being to tame the wild passions of men and bring them into glad harmony with the same divine will to which she freely bows, and thus to secure their ennobling along with her own. Nay, the very furies themselves shall lose all their power to cause distress to him who bows as suppUant when she ministers. It is this richer phase of significance that Goethe discerns in the myth and unfolds for us with so much enthusiasm in this beau- tiful work. And now with this central thought of the work in view, let us see what further intimation it may have for us. It is to be noted in the first place, that while Goethe was occu- pied in developing this poem intaits final form, his mind was com- pletely filled and satisfied with it ; and yet no long time had passed when it seemed foreign and indifierent to him. Through it he had seemingly been carried for the time quite over into the classic phase of life, and out of the modern. On the other hand, with the reaction from this extreme state of absorption in the modes of thought and feeling peculiar to antiquity, he seemed for a time again to separate himself completely from those modes of thought and feeling and to hve exclusively as a modem. Of course in either case this could not be altogether so in fact, but this oscillation serves to show how much, even yet, the classic and the modern (in the sense of the romantic) phases of thought and feeling, lacked of being completely blended in Goethe's mental life. In this poem then, as I venture to think, there lies latent a sug- gestion that belongs to and grows out of the distinctively modem consciousness as represented by Goethe himself, even when most completely absorbed in the modes of the antique spirit. — 13 — For, after all, Goethe is not merely Goethe. He is necessarily in greater or less degree a representative of the modern modes of consciousness. And the fuller, the richer, the grander his individu- ality, the more perfectly does that representative character belong to him. Thus, when he works upon a theme drawn from antiquity, it is still as a modern that he works. All the essential interests of the modern world are necessarily his interests. The deepest, worthiest sentiments of the modern spirit are his sentiments. By these is he actuated. These are of the very soul of his finest work. As a poet, he can neither speak nor breathe without them. They are his by inheritance. They are his by education. They are his by over- whelming preference. He could not live out of them even if he would, and clearly he would not even if he could. For this reason it seems to me to be no mere illusion if we find in this nobly beautiful poem an implicit suggestion of the subtle, re- fining factor that is evermore completely permeating and trans- figuring modern life. For this we must look to the essential aspects of Christianity as being the vital element of the modem world. When this faith began unfolding in the world the element of sensuous beauty had long been severed from the element of purity. The Asiatic tendency had once more come and taken possession of Helen. But now instead of bearing the individual Helen away, that tendency had remained as a deadly corrupting influence in the lands which previously had been the lands of Beauty and Purity in unison. No longer was there a whole world of invincible heroes to rise up and join in the rescue of Helen from her false position of union with impurity. On the contrary impurity was welcomed; and instead of heroic believers in the Gods as the defenders of beautiful purity, there was only a world of scoffers at both Purity and the Gods. Such the condition of the world into which was born the new — 14 — faith with its infinite insistance upon absolute purity, even of the very heart, as the one condition without which no man could ever hope to behold the Divinity! No wonder then that those who accepted this faith should turn away with horror from forms that, however beautiful outwardly, were still only the more to be feared as allurements toward inward deformity ! Far better was it that Iphigenia should be consecrated to per- petual service in the temple of the Goddess of Purity (which now assumed the mystic form of the Church) than that she should become a participant in the life of so corrupt a world ! And the ministration of the priestess, through centuries, has not been without avail. The ferocities of the Scythian world have been measurably subdued. The noble Ideal, so long and so faithfully presented to men, has by insensible degrees wrought itself into realization until the priestess has long since become free to resume her place in that other Temple of Purity there to continue securely the same sublime mission. The worship of the Madoana — the virgin Mother of God — has been one of the most effective agencies in the rescuing of Helen, the sensuous element in the Beautiful, from all degrading tendencies. By degrees this worship is becoming substantial and universal. The aureole and the nimbus have vanished from our canvases, not because there is less faith than formerly, but rather because faith has deepened into clearer vision. The divinity of the one Madonna is not denied because of the recognition that divinity pertains to Motherhood as such ; nor is the divinity of the Son of Mary in any way endangered because the world is coming to see, in the perpet- ual development of conscious units in the eternal Process of Crea- tion, the ceaseless birth of the Son of God. This vital unity and continuity of human life as the progressive interfusion of the Moral and the Beautiful seems to me to constitute the finest thread of significance in the poem we are just now con- sidering. As portrayed by Goethe Iphigenia is the exalted spirit of spotless purity, and that in its most positive significance. She rep- — 15 — resents conscience rendered stainlessly beautiful, as well as invinci- ble against evil, through being completely interfused with sun-clear intelligence and utmost delicacy of truthfulness. That is what I conceive to be in all men the "eternal- womanly" which, through all confusions and spite of all unworthiness, still lingers and ministers as the veritable priestess in the holiest of tem- ples to lead us above. And yet, permit me once more to repeat, this lies rather as a latent intimation in Goethe's Iphigenia. The full development of this point of view required the entire life's work of Goethe. And this entire life's work, it is well known, is represented most ade- quately in the Faust. In that poem we see portrayed the life of a man of superior natural gifts. When first introduced to us he has already passed through the traditional forms of culture only to find, when he has fairly entered into the struggle of life, that all ordinary human ambi- tions are but empty mockeries. Thus there arises within him, and yet as if before him, the "spirit of negation" whereby the vaUdity of human Kfe itself comes to be questioned. Man is everything or nothing. But which is he ? Faust can find true answer to this question only by traversing the entire world — ^partly goaded, partly lured by this same "spirit of negation." Recklessly following a law of his own nature he presently finds himself in deadly conflict with a far higher law which inheres in his nature no less certainly. As the inevitable result his outer world crumbles into ruin, while his inner world becomes the wild vortex of Walpurgis-night. Man then is at least a destroying, suffering Reality. Hence with returning sanity there comes a supreme effort toward expiation. Faust would assume the consequences of his own deed. In this lies the one hope of restoration for himself; and the more since it is not the thought of self-restoration that prompts him. But those whom he has involved in his misdeeds — they too have — 16 — been moral agents. The deed of the individual cannot be indi- vidual merely. Margaret, too, can find atonement only through expiation; and though the spirit of negation sees only the fact that she is judged, yet the spirit of affirmation beholds in this judgment that true justice, which is not merely "tempered with mercy," but which is mercy itself in its veriest reality and through which the lost one is saved. Dreaming humanity strays unwittingly into the demonic. But through the anguish inevitably following it awakes to a conscious- ness of the Divine, eagerly lays hold upon the Eternal, and is lifted through madness and death to wholeness and life. Man is not merely a destroying, suffering Reality. He is also a struggling, strangely unfolding, but none the less truly divine Reality. Thus, even while following the lead of the spirit of negation, Faust has nevertheless learned that his own individual experiences extend beyond himself, and necessarily involve the world in which he lives. Hence, to trace out his essential, positive relations to that world and to develop his life in consistency with those relations — this be- comes the one all-absorbing purpose of his further existence. Preparatory to this new career his powers are refreshed by imme- diate contact with nature. Here, separated from all human kind, his distracted spirit is soothed and calmed by the subtle influences of sky and air, and verdure-clad earth-masses. Here there can be no evil. A subtle music as of the upper spheres enwraps him and permeates his very being, bringing him by degrees into unison with itself as with a dawning world of Reason. He is found seeking sleep, and yet these soothing influences awake him to a nobler consciousness. As with the coming of dawn, Ariel sings of the storming of the hours and cries out : " What wild tumult brings the light?" so Faust finds his "life's pulse beat- ing freshly vital," and with joy greets the earth as one that " Wakes and stirs a mighty resolution Toward highest being ever forth to struggle." — 17 — This struggle is itself, in truth, that "wild tumult" which the dawning light of Reason brings. Thus, and thus only, is life to be made rhythmical, attuned to nature in the highest sense. Faust has sought unconsciousness only so far as to be freed from that special sense of guilt that takes away all power of resolution towards a worthier life. And this attained he is prepared to under- take all labors, to endure all dangers, to make any sacrifice, so that Life in its uttermost Reality may be achieved. Nor even here can the spirit of negation be wholly cast aside ; for thus must affirmation also lose its highest import. In due sub- ordination that mode of Reality named " Satan" is but the critical, carefully discriminating power by which man is able to "prove all things," that thus he may surely acquire and securely " hold fast to that which is good," and to that alone. Inseparable from each human life then, is this spirit of negation. Only in its excess, only when it becomes perversive, and therefore destructive of the good must it be utterly cast out. The affirmative Faust is often quite lost to view indeed. But this is in part because in the human world many forms are them- selves nugatory, and hence must be met by the spirit of negation so that the Good may survive and attain commensurate Reality. Thus Faust's first entrance upon his truly positive career, is in connection with the existing forms of political life — that is, in con- nection with the world of human institutions. The critical spirit, viewing these in the forms in which they are practically unfolded at any given time, easily finds them sadly wanting. Hence we see Faust dealing with them in the spirit of irony. They are but tran- sitional forms, and hence cannot be taken altogether seriously by the truly serious man. To Faust all this is at the outset scarcely more than a pageant. And yet, dealing with it as such and tracing its natural history, he finds even in the pageantry of the world a factor that is valid, and which must therefore be respected. — i8 — This valid factor is the instinct of play. And this in truth is but the rhythmic form of Reason. In other words, the one valid element in the world's pageant is the soul of Truth in man seek- ing, through these tentative, spectacular modes, to unfold itself into commensurate outer form. And this can take place only in progressive stages. Hence, with each succeeding age there is ever increased necessity for critical research. The positive Faust must borrow from the spirit of nega- tion the magic key by which he descends into the mysterious depths of antiquity, and receives from the mystic " mothers " all that is living in the treasures of the Past. At first this is undertaken chiefly with the hope of pleasing Royalty — itself ever the chief figure in the world's great pageant. But in the midst of the accomplishment of this initial purpose Faust finds himself seized with a passionate longing to wholly and finally possess as his very own these wondrous living treasures which he has redeemed out of what had been previously looked upon as the dead Past. And yet the spirit of negation insists that these are only phan- toms. The positive Faust is enraptured at sight of Helena, the glorious image of all that ever was vital in the antique world of art. This surely shall be his and his forevermore. And yet in the self-same instant the negative Faust, in other words the relentless spirit of destructive criticism in the person of Mephistopheles, mockingly declares that this Helena is really nothing but the phantom which Faust himself has just been conjuring up. Thus it is that, at the very moment when his life seems at the point of being made perfect by the addition to it of this matchless form of beauty, the form itself vanishes wholly from, his view. In the same way too the form of Paris which had been revealed along with that of Helena, now, by the merest touch of the magic key of critic- ism, bursts into vapor and swiftly melts into utter vacuity, never more to attain to visibility. — 19 — To Faust the shock is overwhelming. For the moment he sinks into unconsciousness ; and when we next see him he is lying in his old narrow Gothic chamber relapsed into provincialism — only the negative phase of his character (that is, Mephistopheles) wholly at home and active. And this too is not without its deeper import. For even the positive Faust will be brought to declare at length that : "It is full well, indeed, each way to give attention, To see, as e'en the Devil sees, the whole creation." At the same time the aggressive Teutonic spirit cannot rest in mere negation. Out of science is bom a new, fresher spirit of inquiry. This new, starry power, Homunculus, takes confident command of the negative Faust — of Mephistopheles himself — and thus bears away the positive Faust to a region suited to the renewal and rationalization of his search for Helena. • But this search cannot even yet be successful without a due course of preparation. Faust must pass through the classical Wal- purgis-night before he can find true alliance with Helena. And let us note the fact that this classical Walpurgis-night is radically different from that Scythian one through which Faust had already passed. The latter was a culmination in a downward career. The former is the initial stage of an upward career. It shows itself to be mainly a commingling of the ruder, more enig- matic forms evolved from the art-spirit of the ancient world while that spirit was in its initial stage of development. At first the nega- tive Faust finds these forms altogether strange and uncouth. Whence, as Mephistopheles, he meets them in a spirit of mockery. But by degrees Faust apprehends their deeper import. Thus he becomes once more positive and learns through these strange forms the way to the discovery of and rational union with Helena ; and Helena, let us l-emember, represents the most refined forms of beauty which were evolved from the art-spirit of the ancient world when that spirit had attained maturity. As Faust becomes more familiar with these strange forms he finds himself drawn into fiiendly communion with them. Above all he questions eagerly the nobler ones among them ; though this is always with reference to the one chief object of his search. His first appeal is made to the Sphinx, whose destructive char- acter had ceased with the discovery on the part of man that he him- self is the growing solution of the world's greatest riddle. This mighty being, now grown benevolent, exerts its dim gift of premoni- tion in Faust's behalf and directs him to Cheiron, the noble centaur who had been the wise instructor of Achilles. And Achilles in his turn was, as we know, the greatest of the heroes in that expedition the chief purpose of which was the restoration of Helen to her right- ful place in the world's order. It is this same Cheiron who, with his clearer knowledge and something like scientific foresight, now gives to Faust the clue that shall surely lead him to successful issue of his search. The negative Faust (Mephistopheles) asserts himself, indeed, but also speedily becomes entangled and bewildered. But from this state he is rescued by Homunculus, the new starry phase of the positive Faust. Thus, passing through ceaseless metamorphoses, and following the clew given him by Cheiron, Faust is brought into vital relation with still more adequate aids. These are now wholly human and appear in the characters of Thales and Anaxagoras, representatives of the more matured intelligence characteristic of the classic world. Following such guides he will discover the deeper truth of the world of classic art. Thus is figured the pupilage through which Faust must prepare himself to rightly apprehend and thus to gain complete possession of the antique world of Beauty represented by Helena. He can hope for rational union only upon condition that he learn to rightly apprehend the whole course of development of the intellectual and moral life of the Greeks. For it was precisely this life that blos- somed out at length into the classic forms of Beauty. From Troy to Marathon and Salamis the supreme mission of the Greeks was to save this divine element of Beauty from destruc- tion. This too, let us repeat, is the more significant as Helena at the same time represents the sacred moral factor of human life embodied in the family. And here again, though the individual representative may be ever so imworthy, yet even for her own sake, and still more in so far as she represents a sacred institution, no sacrifice can be too great to bring about her restoration. Nay, led by the enthusiasm developed into truly divine great- ness through this long heroic struggle the Greeks nourished the ele- ment of Beauty into fullest life. And by preserving its union with the element of morality they had the happiness to behold its devel- opment under their care into its divinest forms. And yet they themselves were to become alienated from it and to lose all genuine interest in its preservation. Thus at length it is to Faust, who has put aside his provincial- ism and has become a man of world-wide culture, that Helena now comes of her own accord seeking protection and prolonged life. And yet no sooner does she appear than her. matchless beauty secures to her the undisputed rank of queen. For through his recent pupilage Faust has not only become the master of a widely- extended world but in so doing he has learned to render to genuine Beauty the homage due to her divinest quaUties. His love for this born queen of the world has become genuinely rational and has thus assumed a transfigured form. And now from this union of the Classic and the Romantic phases of the human spirit there is born Euphorion, the clear and fearless art-spirit of the distinctively modern world, whose work is everywhere characterized by a consciousness both of the unity of the world and of the divine nature and destiny of man. Euphorion appears wilful, indeed, refusing recognition of all outer authority. Neither Faust nor Helena, neither the rules of Classic art on the one hand nor those of the Romantic spirit on the other, can altogether control him. He knows no law but the law of rational self-consistency, which often, indeed, in the initial stages of its practical development seems little else than mere caprice. Tra- dition merely as such is impatiently set aside. And yet he that "hopeth all things" also "endureth all things" — it may be even death itself — in his pursuit of what seems to him of divinest significance. Above all things indeed that which is of divinest significance must ever be the exclusive object of pursuit to this new spirit. Not the accidental, but the essential; not the fleeting but the abiding is its aim. Evidently then the modern art-spirit as represented by Goethe repudiates absolutely the dictum that "the first rule of art is to please." On the contrary, the first rule of all genuine art, and of modern art more than of any other, is : Absolute faithfulness to Truth. And the faithfulness of art to Truth is this : that it shall make Truth pleasing and that alone. True art, like true human effort of every kind, is addressed to rational, normal human beings. Doubtless to please them is the proper task of art. And art can please a ratiortal human soul only in two ways : positively by exhibiting the True in its native beauty ; and negatively by exhibiting the untrue in its native deformity. Nor can the latter be the exclusive, nor even the chief, content of any genuine work of art. The monstrous can be admitted into such work only in contrast with and in distinct subordination to the symmetrical, the indestructibly vital and rational. The cry of "art for art's sake" is but a thinly disguised reappear- ance of the ancient sophism that "man is the measure of all things." It is altogether ambiguous. It is not the purpose of art to please a degraded taste. And if this is once admitted, then it follows that true art and morality can never be divorced — that the highest and sole task of art is to represent to mankind the beautiful forms into which Truth in its native character must forever unfold. Nay according to Goethe's representation each age must strug- gle to find appropriate artistic expression for the richest phases of truth to which fi-om time to time it attains. Whence, it may be remarked by the way, that was evidendy a — 23 — wholly mistaken view of art which, in the early part of the present century, led a group of German artists to suppose that the best interests of art require of its votaries that they should relapse into a past and less adequate phase of faith and thought than that by which their own age is characterized. On the contrary when Euphorion dies — that is, when he passes out of the initial into the maturer phase of his existence — Helena too in her corporeal part, in so far as she is a mere representative of the antique spirit, vanishes out of the embrace of Faust leaving him only her mantel and veil, only the ideal of perfect plasticity and grace of form to be applied henceforth in such new representations as the advancing apprehension of Truth on the part of man may demand. Such then is the culmination. The strictly modem form of art begins with the renewed and more complete interfusion of the Clas- sic with the Romantic form under the influence of the critical, scien- tific spirit. It is the completely rationalized form of Romantic art ; and, to indicate its close and vital relationship with the so-called Humanities, it might very properly be called the Humanistic phase of art. But passing over this latter point as something merely incidental, so far as the present purpose is concerned, it will be well to note in more explicit form the central conclusions at which we have arrived. We have seen that the outer, crude, natural man as represented in the Goetz von Berlichingen, can find continued existence only by being tamed and disciplined into a self-restrained, morally symetrical being, through the ministration of the Priestess of the Temple of Purity, represented by Iphigenia. Thus only may he attain at last to a fully rounded, rhythmic life, through a rational union with Belena, the perfect ideal of plastic Beauty, for whose redemption and ultimate preservation the sacrifice of Iphigenia was made. To Faust at the beginning of his career it seemed a question whether man were all or nothing. To the matured Faust, man is both all and nothing. He is the latter only in so far as he is merely self-nugatory — the persistent Mephistopheles. He is the former in — 24 — ever truer sense with the rational unfolding of his life. For all that is noble and pure and divine is found to be involved in his ultimate nature. He treats with lofty scorn the eager, childish, imperial desire for mere amusement with its obliviousness of sacred duty, and finds more and more that that alone is worthy of genuine admiration which proves itself to be the rythmic unfolding of eternal Truth. That is the central, saving factor in the modern art-spirit, as it has been, in greater or less degree of explicitness, the central, saving factor in the art-spirit of every age. The glib cry of "Art for Art's sake," can have no real meaning apart from the infinitely significant motto : '■'•Life for Life's sake" though here too it must be added that Life itself is really significant for and worthy of man only so far as it is the process of unfolding the divine nature into reality in the concrete individual man. So far, then, from any natural conflict existing between art and morality, no such conflict is really possible. The apparent existence of such conflict is due solely to the perversion of the means and methods of art to immoral purposes — as is the case with so much of what is presented to the world to-day under the name of "P'rench Art." And yet in such case the truth is that the product is not a work of art at all — any more than a will-o'-the-wisp is a star. Such pro- duct contradicts the fundamental conception of art as the beautiful expression of what is truest and divinest in human life. Nay, that the art-interests of a people should become prevail- ingly equivocal in moral tone, is itself a proof that such people is aheady far advanced toward dissolution. Such state of art will ever be found to be but one of many symptoms presaging utter national decay. Such was the case with the ancient Greeks in the declining period of their art. Such was the case with the Italians, and especially those of Rome during the sixteenth century. Such, it seems but too evident, is the case with the French of to-day. — 25 — Even in the blooming time of the Renascence the finest works of art were done in Rome — but not by native Romans. To-day the finest works of art are done in Paris — but not by native French- men. The general conclusion here reached respecting the relation be- tween art and morality, may be confirmed by contrasting the Romance with the Teutonic form of Christianity. The Romance form was developed among the Italians, a peo- ple from of old passionately fond of the spectacular. Nothing so impressed and satisfied them as magnificent pageantry. To the Roman populace at the beginning of the Christian era there were two necessities — ^bread and the circus. And much de- privation of the former would be endured by them if only the latter were sufficiently frequent and bloody. This was art divorced com- pletely from morality. The later Italians were descendants of those Romans. The ancient taste for the spectacular was inherited without diminution in degree, but with complete transformation in character. Instead of the ferocities of the circus, there was now the mysterious, but magnificent and awe-inspiring pageant of Mother Church. In this the Italian, into whose soul truth found easiest entrance through the eyes, saw what were to him impressive evi- dences of a present Divinity, restraining him from evil conduct, and beckoning him toward a gentle, serenely beautiful life. This grandly beautiful pageant which he saw before him appeared to him as something that had come down out of Heaven. That it was something which had arisen out of the depths of his own soul and of the souls of those like him he could never have so much as dreamed. In truth it did come down out of Heaven, and also arose from the depths of the Italian soul. It was under the divine stimulus of the Christian faith that the Italian spirit became creative of these magnificent forms through which the truths of Religion appealed, and must ever appeal most effectively to souls whose highest en- — 26 — dowment is in the art-i)roducing and art-appreciating quality of the mind. Thus with this people there was matured the outer rhythmic form of the Christian Religion. What charmed them chiefly was the element of outward Beauty which this faith, shining through their souls, presented. On the other hand, as soon as the Teutonic people came to have a really vital appreciation of Christianity, they found this cere- monial worship altogether ioreign to their mental constitution. The pomp and pageant so dear and even so necessary to the Italian mind, only obscured instead of revealing the essence of this faith to the Teutonic inteUigence. The Italian mind was eagerly perceptive and imaginative. The Teutonic mind was self-restrained and predominantly reflective. Hence to the Teuton the highest religious experience was, to feel the presence of the Divine in his own soul. The outer show was to him a hollow mockery. Thus, through mutual exclusion the religion of the Teuton came to consist almost solely of the inner Power of Godliness, while that of the Italian tended more and more to confine itself to the outward Beauty of Holiness. In the Italian, then, we see a superficial morality, coupled with a dominant delight in external form, while in the Teuton of the Reformation period there is manifest, along with a rugged morality, the complete sacrifice of outer form to inner substance. Accord- ingly, as we would expect, the art of the Italians lost sadly in character, while the art of the Teutons lacked sadly in plasticity and grace of form. And yet the Reformation was based upon the principle that gives to modern art its chief element of vitality. For the Reforma- tion was but the bringing into more explicit form that central affirmation implied from the first in Christianity — ^the affirmation that each individual human being has the absolute right, and there- fore the absolute responsibility of private judgment. As was indi- — 27 — cated at the outset, the principle here is : Manhood for its own sake. It is by his own deed that man stands or falls. Thus the Reformation is the emphatic reannouncement of the divinity of man's nature. Though in present realization he may be as nothing, yet in ultimate Ideal he is all. And to lift himself from this initial nothingness to that divine all- ness, or wholeness — that is the supreme mission of man. Through that, and only through that, is he to give final and convincing proof of his godlikeness. In this principle, I repeat, there is found the chief element of vitality in modern art. For, following this principle, modem art must and does seek its themes, not from a far-away divine world, but from the present divine world of humanity. The fundamental relations of man to man — these constitute the essential themes of modern art. And when we reflect that the essential practical relations of man to man constitute the very substance of all morality the insepara- bility of art and morality is found to have its most explicit and most emphatic affirmation precisely in the art-spirit of modern times. Nay the essentially religious character of modern art especially is also shown in the very same consideration ; and the more if we are to accept the definition which makes the practical, positive aspect of religion to consist in rendering rational aid to those who are in real need — in ministering to the necessities of the typical or universal Christ-nature by giving food, of body and of soul, to the least no less than to the greatest of those who may be counted among the brethren of the Christ. It is true that productions which are irreligious and immoral are now and then thoughtlessly classed among works of modern art simply because of their faultlessness in a technical sense. And yet these are at best no more than elaborate studies in technique, while the immorality of the theme must exclude them utterly from being classed as works of art at all. As already insisted they are simply — 28 — examples of the perversion of the means and methods of art to im- moral and therefore inartistic uses. In this connection however it is to be carefully noted that though the theme of a true work of art, as well as the mode of treat- ment, must in every case be thoroughly moral, this by no means excludes the representation of the immoral from such works. On the contrary the moral quality may be heightened and the artistic effect intensified by the representation of the moral and the immoral side by side and allowing each to follow out the dialectic of its own nature— the one to its own natural constructive result, the other to its own and equally natural self-annulment. Once more then the immoral cannot, on its own part, be the theme for a genuine work of art ; nor can its introduction into such work be justified at all save in so far as it is distinctly subordinate and accessory to the proper moral content of the work. And this it can be only in so far as it satisfies the demand of reason that the self-contradiction inherent in immorality shall be shown to work out its own natural effects in the agent adopting an immoral course of conduct. Tried by this standard Goethe's works are by no means found wanting. The immoral appears often enough indeed ; but never as a thing worthy of admiration or of imitation. Rather its fatal defects and the dreadful destiny of the immoral individual are ever kept before the mind as if in vivid warning. The immoral appears not as something to be sought and cherished, but as something to be shunned and hated or despised. On the other hand the themes of his works are without excep- tion thoroughly moral, and in the mode of treatment of these themes Goethe shows how clear and how complete is his comprehension of the nature of the moral quality as a self-preserving and self-unfold- ing power whose native form is Beauty. Finally the many-sidedness of Goethe — his splendid adequacy as a representative of the marvelously complex modern art-spirit— is shown in the Faust indeed more adequately than in any other of his — 29 — works as an artist ; but it is shown even still more adequately in his enthusiastic personal interest in all forms of art. As I have already intimated he became more and more explicitly an art critic as he advanced in years, so that much is to be learned respecting the true method of criticism from his incidental suggestions concerning the nature and extent of the several forms of art. Not an element was omitted firom his all-embracing view ; and his investigations in each field were betimes as eager and minute as if he were an exclusive, life-time specialist in that field. How clearly too he himself appreciated the fact that the most perfect work of art is the individual Life in which the Beautiful and the moral are completely interfused is shown most impressively in the closing part of the Faust. When Helena vanishes from Faust's embrace her mantle enfolds him and bears him back to the scenes of his former efforts. Here he is to enter once more into the prosaic practical phases of life. And yet henceforth the very prose of his life is to unfold in accord- ance with the plastic, rhythmic forms of Reason. Life itself shall become the noblest of all works of art. His own individual life shall attain its utmost completeness and beauty of form through redeeming the waste places of the earth and adding to the favorable conditions for the rational unfolding of other human souls. Through long years of such struggle much is accomphshed — so much that Faust is able to vividly anticipate as aheady near at hand a degree of fulfillment in his noble purposes, such that he can sincerely desire the passing moment to stay and not pass because of its exceeding fulness and rhythmical perfection of accomplishment. Thus, by imperceptible degrees, through the rhythmic, reason- guided struggle of a long-extended life, the vanishing, temporal aspects of his existence have dissolved, and Faust is revealed to us as a being whose true form is that of Eternity. For in his soul, the torturing conflicts of passion have ceased, and in their stead there -30 — has developed the abiding serenity of a beautiful, self-harmonized power. As, with Helena, the outer plastic form proved to be the enduring element, so now with Faust the inner and ethical proves to be the undying factor, the infinite vitality of which involves an exhaustless capacity for the creation of ever new and richer forms in which to give itself ever more beautiful expression ; the capacity to enter into ever more perfectly rhythmical reality. It is at this exalted moment, too, when the positive Faust has attained to approximate completeness, that the merely negative Faust is utterly consumed by the merest contact with the glowing beauty of Truth and Purity, symbolized in the roses of Paradise with which the angels fill the air ; while the redeemed Margaret, under the direction of the glorified Madonna, leads the positive, self-harmonized Faust, still upward into yet diviner spheres of ex- istence. "AH that is transient here Proves but a shadow ; The unattainable Here is the Real ; What can't be clothed in words Here blooms into deeds ; Th' Eternal-womanly Draws us toward God." With such final, significant words^ Goethe shows us that, in his estimation, the closing of the Faust-drama is simply the transition from the human to the divine world. The Beautiful is inexhaustible. The one absolutely perfect work of art is the ever-widening drama of a noble life. — 31 —