m Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924029308066 Cornell University Library BT75.R61 E23 Faith and fact: a.±.^v of .ffiffl^^ 3 1924 029 308 066 olin FAITH AND FACT A STUDY OF RITSCHLIANISM MACMILLAN AND CO., Limited LONDON ■ BOMBAY • CALCUTTA MELBOURNE THE MACMILLAN COMPANY NEW YORK • BOSTON • CHICAGO ATLANTA • SAN FRANCISCO THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Ltd TORONTO FAITH AND FACT A STUDY OF RITSCHLIANISM BEING THE ESSAY FOR THE NORRISIAN PRIZE, igo8 BY ERNEST A. EDGHILL, M.A. SUIIWARDEN OF THE C0LI.E<;E OF ST. SAVIOUR IN SUUIHWAKK AND WILBERFORCK WISSIONF.R SOMETIME SCHOLAR OF KING's COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE BELL SCHOLAR AND CROSSE SCHOLAR AUTHOR OF 'the EVIDENTIAL VALUE OF PROl'HECv' WITH PREFACE BY THE RT. REV. THE LORD BISHOP OF SOUTHWARK u^ ovTdts ifjidOeTe tov ^ptcrrov MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED ST. MARTIN'S STREET, LONDON I 9 lo GLASGOW : PKINTED AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS BY ROBERT MACLFHOSE AND CO. LTD. PREFACE When I was asked by the writer of this Essay for some sort of preface, I feared that a preface to an essay might be disproportionate and incongruous, and only consented out of gratitude to the writer for great services to my diocese, and from admiration of the way in which one so brilHantly endowed devotes time and labour without stint to the children of the poor. But when I came to read his work, my mind changed altogether. If this is an essay by origin, it is hardly less a handbook by character: and it may be useful to point out that we have in it something which was really needed, and is, so far as I can judge, exceedingly well done. For the interest of the subject reaches entirely beyond the limits of theological or philosophical speculation. It concerns, and vitally concerns, all those who think about the relation of Christian faith to modern thought and knowledge. It concerns them in two ways. Ritschlianism is both influential and typical. As an influence it has reached far, and is present in many places where it is not named or recognized. One who does not know the influence at its source will deal clumsily with its results. But it is also typical. Many minds in the last few decades have vi PREFACE been Ritschlian without knowing it If there had been no Ritschl, there would have been some one else very like him. His is a system which fastens upon some of the most characteristic features of modern thought, detects their illuminating meanings, discerns in them the means of deliverance from old mistakes, both in speculation and practice, and revels in the discovery that what seemed an enemy is first a liberator, and then a defender, of the essentials of that great faith which has given to Europe all that is best in her civilization, and carries the only promise of a world-religion. To watch such an attempt with appreciative and admiring attention, to see how it works out, what it gives us, and what after all it may take away, to observe in this great and typical instance what is the characteristic strength, and what are the equally characteristic weaknesses, of one whole great way of thinking, is evidently a duty, and a duty of keenest interest, to all who are themselves trying to think upon these great topics. I value and dare to recommend Mr. Edghill's essay because it seems to me to be quite an admirable attempt to help us in this useful and delicate task. It is quick and lucid, without shrinking from detail. It sets the subject skilfully into its context with the previous developments of thought. But its greatest merit is that it is entirel)- respectful, and yet quite independent. It shows that combination of real and eager docility, with a secure standard of judgment, which belongs to the best and most hopeful forms of Christian theology. I am less diffident in so speaking when I remember that other parts of Mr. Edghill's theological work PREFACE vii have won him marked approval and trust from the mature and critical judgment of Professor Swete. Perhaps having said thus much I have done my part, and should at once make way for the Author. But the interest of the subject tempts me to go a little further. Why is it that Ritschlianism is so typical, and the study of it therefore so instructive ? I think first and chiefly because it was the most important attempt to challenge for Christianity the thought of an intensely empirical or inductive time. ' To believe in nothing which you could not claw ' was, we remember, in conversational caricature, the tendency of the time. At last it seemed that the overdue achievements of Bacon's prophecy were to come true. The old things were to be left behind. A new way and method was to open the closed doors, and reset all the problems, and sweep onwards to victory in every sphere. It Was the way of the chemist's or biologist's analysis, and of the inductive logic which was its counterpart. The method and the logic brought over the associations of the sciences of external nature to which they had been first triumphantly applied. Metaphysics were old- world lumber. Mysticism, if the word may be used to gather up the action of any direct or intuitive capacities of the human spirit, was tabooed as perilous, or despised as sentimental. It was a difficult time for the Religion which had old and honourable alliances with metaphysics, which was at home with deductive logic, and had always claimed a commanding place in regard to truth and morals for the intuitions of faith and conscience. Then vin PREFACE it was that to Ritschl, but not to Ritschl alone, there came hooie the thought, simple, luminous and far-reaching, that Christianity was after all an inductive religion. Alone of the religions it had come in along the way of fact. Fact, not theory or ideal, was its theme and burden. Before men talked of development and evolution, the evolution of Christianity out of the old Covenant, and its own reliance on development were anticipations of what they would say. But above all, one fact unique, supreme, but central, had been alike its credential and its message, and its standard both of what was true and what was good : the fact of Jesus Christ, living, dying, risen. Further, that fact was of such a kind that it interpreted and heightened the values of all the lesser facts of like sort, the voices of prophets, the examples and testimonies of saints, the moral victories of the defeated, and the truths won by the childlike, over a range of echoing experience not less wide than life. So 'back to Christ' was the common thought of varying minds : and men read the Gospels more and talked of ' the Gospel ' less : and some, forgetting that fact demands analysis, spoke of all ' doctrine ' as though it were an encroachment on life ; while others delighted to shov^ that not by a prion methods, but by the analysis, largel}^ intuitive and Spirit-led, of what Christ had been and spoken and done, the Christian doctrine had grown. But every way it was a great change. The note of it rang clear to us in Oxford when Scott Holland preached his first sermons before the University, and I well remember how a representative theologian PREFACE ix of the elder school said to me, " I have always been trained to think of Christian theology as derived by deduction from fixed principles : but this seems an assertion of its inductive character." The criticism was significant and partially true. Further, the temper of the time was not only inductive, but agnostic ; blankly so in many who held any spiritual truth to be unprovable and un- certain, and who became for the time the most formidable antagonists of Christian faith: but equally so, though ' with all the difference,' in believers who recognized what the best lessons of time had done to rebuke hard dogmatism, and to emphasize the consciousness of ignorance as a necessary part of all true knowledge. It was to them one true link between Christians and their opponents. Christian agnosticism was the reverent temper which made men draw the morals that were sug- gested by the stupendous extension of knowledge, by the resetting of truth in all departments, by the historical survey of many phases of thought positive in their day but transient. Such men felt that the knowledge of Himself which God had surely given was a truth ringed about and interpenetrated by the ignorance of fallible and finite minds to whom it was entrusted. This feeling, paral3^sing to faith in some minds, but in others recognized as giving to faith more depth and reality, prepared a ready response for teachings which, like those of Ritschl, offered the prospect of a sufficient certainty, while disowning speculative ambition. One other point less obvious, but not, I believe, less real, in which Ritschlianism seemed to meet a X PREFACE deeply felt instinct of Christian need. Men felt that for Christian faith something more was needed than the relative approval and compliments which were the best testimony that the truth could receive from the critical and comparative labours of contemporary thought. Something was wanted that was unique, supreme, and commanding. This could never be given by observing that Christian speculation had reached (if it were so) further than Plato's, or that the Christian West had thought more clearly and effectively than the non-Christian East or gave a more lucid and practical treatment to the moral problem. It could be found only in that which was the very centre of the Gospel, namely, the way in which it had come, distinct from all the philosophies and from all the movements, reversing and yet fulfilling all the common ways of thought and life. Ritschl stood forth to meet this with the offer of allegiance to the Christ who needed no proof but Himself, and to a Christianity which boldly began with Christ as Christ, without stopping (as it were) to enquire for any better reason than that He was what He was, and came as He came ; without look- ing round to ask how this was philosophically justifiable, or what theology it presupposed. No wonder that the offer seemed to be a godsend : to correspond with penetrating discernment to the exact needs of the time. How far Ritschlianism answered to and justified these hopes will be seen by those who keep Mr. Edghill's company through these pages. If previously unacquainted with the matter, he will give them the opportunity of forming some estimate. But I think PREFACE xi that those who know more will be glad to review and reconsider the topic with such skilful help as his. It seems to me that the rise of such a system so fresh, so strong and vital, enlisting the allegiance of minds so various and powerful, at a time when older ways had grown out of use and so many guns had been put out of action, is a marvellous testimony to the permanent and enduring value of the Gospel. I believe that many of the characteristic features of Ritschlianism represent, or at the least point to, ad- vances in a real understanding of the Christian witness which our time has been allowed to make. But this is quite compatible with the conviction, that as a system, and through some of its parts, Ritschlianism, if accepted as the norm of Christian apologetics, would be as one of those reeds upon which if a man lean it pierces his hand. That can be shown in two ways — a priori, and by observation of its results. A priori, it is one more attempt to cut faith and reason apart ; to secure the former by disparaging the latter. It is quite true that Christianity cannot construct a philosophy, nor base itself upon one ; but one of its noblest results has been to shed illum- ination upon the great things of God and man which are the subject matter of speculative thought : and one of the noblest witnesses to it has been that of philosophy. Ritschlianism surely fails from the old fault of treating as worthless what is not complete or demonstrative. Christianity, confident in the truth of the Living God, recognizes in the highest work of the reason a real though imperfect value, and lines of thought converging towards a synthesis which the wisdom of God is alone qualified xii PREFACE to make or understand, and which it were irrational to suppose could be within grasp of the reason of man. Mr. Edghill has pointed out several ways in which Ritschl, the enemy of metaphysics, was metaphysical in spite of himself. Possibly the best instance of all is that he fell into the metaphysician's mistake of contempt for relative or qualified know- ledge. An imperfect but aspiring metaphysic, an imperfect but aspiring ethic, an imperfect but advanc- ing knowledge of things visible — Christian faith recognizes them all, learns from all, despises none ; gathers, as it believes, witness, confirmation, and enlargement from all, and so is really in a degree, and wholly in desire, a rational faith.^ " The earth is the Lord's and the fulness thereof" If, on the other hand, we turn to the results, there is the unwelcome but necessary task of pointing out that Ritschlianism issues in an express denial of some of the things which in spiritual practice as well as in theological expression are of the very essence of the Christian faith. That the Gospel should have won from such thinkers as Ritschl and his followers the title of * the perfect religion' is indeed a splendid and arresting fact of homage to Christ. But our glad and grateful sense of it cannot cause us to entrust ourselves into RitschFs hands for guidance, when we remem- ber on the one side the havoc which he makes of all the natural evidences of God in creation and the ^ I might quote, as being to myself instances ofwhat has been said in the text, the relations, independent but deeply indebted, of Christianity to T. H. Green's idealism, to Darwin's revelation of the meaning of process, and to the positive side of Mill's Utilitarianism^ with its stimulus to social effort, and its practical insistence upon the principle of love. PREFACE xiii heart of man, and on the other side discern (by the help of Mr. EdghiU's able summary in his final paragraphs), what Ritschl has surrendered of the things that are most essential to the truth of the Gospel and to its power. EDW. SOUTHWARK. AUTHOR'S PREFACE The progress of thought in recent times has necessi- tated a corresponding advance in theology, if the kingdom is not to be taken from her and given to another. Science has swept aside scholasticism, and reason, it is claimed, has discredited religion. Yet theology, the queen of the sciences, refuses to abdicate, and hears unmoved the lamentations of those that mourn. For, many a time, if the figure may be allowed, has she attended her own obsequies ; and many a time also witnessed her own resurrection. In the beginning, religion grasped reason by the hand, and they two went on together ; though young reason had at times hard work to keep pace with her swiftly striding sister (for in those days religion did the pulling). In more modern times reason has rushed ahead, but religion will not release her hold. She has grown somewhat old with the passing of the centuries ; and, the experience of ages suggesting caution, she moves somewhat slowly ; yea, she halts as she goes. Be not unequally yoked, is a sound saying ; and many demanded that the partnership should be dissolved. "Let go my hand," cries reason, impetuous to explore undiscovered and even forbidden realms. " Let her then go, to self-destruction, if she will," suggest man}^ that would not see religion XVI PREFACE ruined. " Stop before it is too late ; for you know not to what abyss you are being hurried along, to perish evermore." Yet timorous counsels have not prevailed ; and still religion grasps reason by the hand, and refuses to disclaim relationship. This situation, however, is well-nigh impossible; some modus vivendi must be found, but who shall discover it ? Then rose Ritschl and chode with her. " What ! wilt thou always cling to another ? Hast thou not power in thyself? Art thou not conscious of self- sufficient life within, for thy sufficiency is of God ? Why needest thou this constant comradeship ? Why claim an unfounded, and harmful relationship ? Why cling on, hindering and hindered ? Rise in thy God- given strength : address thyself to thy task and redeem the world. Let reason fly withersoever she will (if independent, yet grateful for release), over the shoreless sea of speculation. But thy call is clear." Religion, however, is yet reluctant to leave reason : and it is well. Notwithstanding, Ritschlianism is an earnest endeavour to face and to solve the religious difficulty of the present day. It will be the object of this essay to examine how far it has succeeded in its enterprise. The materials for a study of this new theology are abundant ; the author has consulted the following works : Albrecht Ritschl.— Die christlicheLehre vender Rechtfertig- ung und Versohnung, 3 vols, ist edition 1870, 4th edition 1895. English translation by various scholars of the third German edition (identical with the fourth). Unterricht in der Christlichen Religion (a most useful and compendious summary of Ritschlian teaching). 6th edition 1903. PREFACE xvii Theologie und Metaphysik, 2nd edition 1887. Schleiermacher's Reden. Drei Akademischen Reden. W. Herrmann. — Der Verkehr des Christen mit Gott. 2nd edition 1892 ; 6th edition 1908. (English translations, both of second and third editions.) Die Metaphysik in der Theologie. Die Religion in Verhaltniss zum Welterkennen und zur Sitthchkeit. Julius Kaftan. — Brauchen wir ein neues Dogma ? Die Wahrheit der christlichen Religion. Das Wesen der christlichen Religion. Adolf Harnack. — What is Christianity? History of Dogma. Otto Ritschl. — Albrecht RitschPs Leben. Ueber Werthurtheile. Kahler. — Die Wissenschaft der christlichen Lehre. The above-mentioned works may be considered as "sources"; the following are rather expository or critical, and have also been consulted with profit : ECKE. — Die Theoiogische Schule Albrecht Kitschl's und die Evangelische Kirche der Gegenwart. Stahlin. — Kant, Lotze und Ritschl (mainly philosophical). Kattenbusch. — Von Schleiermacher zu Ritschl (an admirable introduction). LiPSlus. — Die Ritschl'sche Theologie. Pfleiderer. -Die Ritschl'sche Theologie kritisch beleucbtet (excellent, but most unfavourable). Development of Theology. Frank.— Zur Theologie A. Kitschl's. SCHEIBE. — Die Bedeutung der Werthurtheile. Reischle. — Ein Wort zur Controverse, etc. R. M. Wenley. — Contemporary Theology and Theism (much too smart). XVlll PREFACE Garvie.— The Ritschlian Theology. H. M. Scott. — Nicene Theology. James Orr.— The Ritschlian Theology and the Evangelical Faith. Ritschlianism — Essays critical and expository. The Christian View of God and the World. A. Swing.— The Theology of Albert Ritschl. A. Sabatier. — Religions of Authority and of the Spirit. The importance of Ritschlianism can hardly be over-estimated ; it is a serious and systematic attempt to restate the entire Christian position. Its influence is both wide and deep ; and in no sense whatever confined to the land of its birth. By way of conflict or defence it has set many minds a-thinking : and such labours have contributed largely to the fresh understanding of Christian experience and Christian theology. Moreover, its principles, often unrecognized, and perhaps more often unacknowledged, lie at the root of many powerful tendencies in modern religious thought. It is perhaps characteristic of the difference between the religious interests of Englishmen and Contin- entals, that while all Germany was recently divided into hostile camps concerning Ritschl, England was simultaneously distracted with controversies about ritual. The centre of interest has now shifted, and we can spare time to attend to, and discuss, the claims of the Ritschlian theology, which in one form or another is making great headway in this country, where anything that tends to the discredit of syste- matic and speculative theology may be sure of a ready welcome, PREFACE xix Starting, then, with the cry of a theology without metaphysics, Ritschlianism found a glad response in many hearts. Driven from this untenable position by arguments impossible to withstand, it took refuge in the alluring promise of a religion without theology. This was succeeded by much subtle discrimination between facts of faith and facts for faith, but those who will not be deceived by the voice of the charmer will find the truest description of this new theology as an elaborate and elusive system of faith without facts. The almost overwhelming pressure of continual and exacting engagements made me well nigh despair of ever being able to compile a satisfactory index to this book. Miss Baily, of Purley, Surrey, most kindly came to my aid ; and it is a pleasant obligation to acknowledge the sympathetic discrimi- nation and careful industry with which she set herself to compile an index which will contribute very materially to the usefulness of this book. The Bishop of Southwark, than whom no one even among the busy bishops of the present day could be busier, has most generously found time to read the proofs and to contribute a preface, for which I am sure all readers of this book will share my gratitude. My own obligations to the Bishop for counsel and encouragement in this as in other matters are so constant and numerous that I despair of ever repaying even the half thereof, but inadequate as is this expression of my gratitude, I could not take the risk of allowing a respectful silence to convey the erroneous impression that I was not deeply appreciative of his kindness. CONTENTS PAGE Preface v Author's Preface - xv INTRODUCTORY CHAPTER I. Kant, Lange, and Lotze i II. Schleiermacher and the Romantic School 28 EXPOSITORY AND CRITICAL III. RiTSCHL : His Age and his School 44 IV. Theory of Knowledge 67 V. The Judgments of Value. I. 87 VI. The Judgments of Value. II. 108 VII. The Christian Idea of God 120 VIII. The Kingdom of God 140 IX. The Doctrine of the Trinity 160 X. The Person and Work of Christ 174 XL Sin and Salvation 204 XII. Conclusion 239 Index 264 RITSCHLIANISM CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY: KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE RiTSCHLlANISM has effected a revolution in the sphere of systematic theology. It is not long since the Hegelian philosophy and historical criticism attempted to reconstruct the doctrines of the Christian faith in accordance with their own pre- possessions. Now modern empiricism and Neo- Kantism, the avowed antagonists of all speculative philosophy, are striving to remodel Christian dog- matics. The Ritschlian theology has proved by its rapid progress that it is in no sense the arbitrary product of a single mind, but that it represents the prevailing tendencies of the age and is deeply rooted in the theological and religious consciousness of the present day. Ritschl himself (as we shall have occasion to remark on more than one occasion) lays the very greatest stress upon his theory of cognition, which is the psychological presupposition of all his theology. "Every theologian," he says, "as a scientific man is under the necessity or duty of proceeding in accord- ance with a definite theory of knowledge, of which he must himself be conscious and the legitimacy of 2 RITSCHLIANISM which he must be prepared to defend," Accordingly it is absolutely necessary for an understanding of the Ritschlian theology to discuss at some length those theories upon which it is avowedly based, that are associated with the names of Kant and Lotze. Kant tells us that he was awakened out of his dogmatic slumber by Hume. The result of the Humian philosophy was to discredit dogmatism which laid down positions that it was unable to establish, and to bring in a scepticism which seemed to involve the entire extinction of all knowledge. Kant's aim, therefore, was to vindicate the objectivity of human knowledge in opposition to the Humian scepticism and at the same time to insist upon its limitations in opposition to the theories of the dog- matic school. It was Kant's belief that that which gave necessity and objective validity to knowledge was not to be found in the things themselves but in the human mind. Accordingly he undertook a critical examination of the cognitive faculty, and it was upon the theory of knowledge thus established that he bases both his system of ethics and his philosophy of religion. To proceed, then, with Kant's theory of knowledge, we must learn to distinguish that which our cognitive faculty brings with it and that in the object which exists independently of our knowledge.-^ Our cogni- tive faculty is itself capable of a double division, into (i) sense, which is the capacity to receive impressions, ^ A brief resum^ of the main presuppositions and conclusions of the Kantian philosophy is necessary to the argument : a fuller discussion of some special points will be found in the additional note at the end of the chapter. KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 3 and (2) understanding, the capacity to form concepts. Sense supplies some a priori contributions to every act of knowledge, that is, the forms of space and time, while the understanding uses concepts to think objects supplied through sense. These concepts are the categories which do not belong to the things in themselves, but to our own faculties of perception and conception. Yet these same categories are universally and necessarily valid, for without them nothing can become an object of knowledge. What then, we ask, remains in the thing? Nothing, but an unknown quantity, which is the cause of our impressions. All knowledge therefore is phenomenal and deals with appearance and not reality ; the thing in itself remains as it ever was, entirely outside our know- ledge.^ Kant intended to establish the objective reality of human knowledge, but it is hardly too much to say, that his theory ends in the overthrow of all objective validity. For what we know, and what we can know, according to this theory, is only phenomenal appearance. I n dealing with the phenomenal we must dis- tinguish between matter and form; the matter is ^ It is difficult to see, if this theory be logically applied, how anything can ever become an object of knowledge, for though the thing itself may be supposed to cause our impressions, yet causahty is itself one of the categories. We are thus reduced to an obvious dilemma. The unknown and unknowable thing in itself being a cause precedes the categories, but in the fact of being so conceived it becomes subject to the very category of causality which it is supposed to precede. The Kantian theory aims at limiting all human knowledge to phenomena ; yet Kant cannot gain the starting-point of his theory without affirming something of the things in themselves which it is the object of this theory to render wholly inaccessible to human reason. 4 RITSCHLIANISM sensation, that is, the impression the thing in itself makes upon our sensitive faculty. The form again is nothing but sensuous intuition or perception as it exists in the ideas of space and time. To quote the words of Kant himself, "the form lies ready a priori in the mind." The phenomenal, therefore, exists only in the mind, both as to form and as to content; in other words it is wholly subjective, and may be not a manifestation of the thing in itself at all, but merely a modification of our own consciousness. How then are we to attribute objective reality to our knowledge? It can only be given when the phenomena are brought under the categories which are the necessary forms of all thought. Thus they are combined according to law and consequently acquire universal validity. But the strange part of this theory lies in the fact that when we consider what it is that confers this objective validity we find that it is itself subjective and we are thus reduced to^ believing that our know- ledge can only be composed of " elements or constituents which appertain solely to the subject." The human mind lamenting its own subjectivity and barely able to peep through the prison bars of phenomenalism, must reluctantly abandon its attempt to reach the promised land of objective reality — a land of far distances whereof it is dimly conscious but whose joys it may never taste. Thus speaks Kant himself, "Even if we were to carry our empirical intuition to the highest degree of clearness we should not thereby approach any nearer to a knowledge of the objects considered in themselves. . . . What the objects may be considered in themselves, would never become known to us, even though we should KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 5 attain to the clearest possible acquaintance with that which is alone within our reach : viz. their appear- ance." ^ This seems to take away all possibility of objec- tive truth in knowledge. The. fact that this subjec- tivity is universal and " necessary " does not obviate the fact of its delusive character, but makes it all the more lamentable. The Kantian theory of knowledge is in reality a philosophy of agnosticism : and objective reality can only be maintained by directly controverting the principal position on which Kant's Critique is based. Having laid down his epistemological principles, Kant proceeded in his Transcendental Dialectic to consider the conceptions of Pure Reason. The understanding concerns itself with finite things under the form of conceptions, and therefore never passes the bounds of empirical possibility. Reason concerns itself with the unconditioned, and therefore arrives at conceptions by way of inference, not of reflection, and deals with ideas which must necessarily and eternally remain beyond experience. Unity is essen- tial for knowledge: so Kant proceeds to discuss the three great ideas of unity — the soul, the world, and God. It follows naturally from Kant's premises by which all real knowledge is limited to experience, that although Kant is prepared to allow them a regu- lative value, such ideas cannot claim any constitutive validity ; for the human mind is incapable of knowing ultimate truth. At first sight this position seems to tell in favour of the Christian idea of revelation: but ^ Kant, Critique of Pure Reason^ p. 59. 6 RITSCHLIANISM a moment's reflection will convince us that no revela- tion would be possible at all unless the mind were capable of receiving it. The knowledge that revela- tion gives, must itself be subjected to the laws of knowledge, if it is ever to be appropriated by the human mind. The Kantian philosophy overthrows the objectivity of knowledge by its theory of the fatal deficiency of the human intellect, but thereby makes both revelation and religion theoretically impossible. It is needless to pursue the subject at length, through all its psychological and cosmological ramifications, ultimately leading up to the refutation of the tra- ditional theological proofs of the existence of God. Kant's difificulties largely arise from a dualistic con- ception of consciousness, involving an abstract separ- ation between subject and object. How complicated if not self-contradictory the discussions on free-will and determinism become, may well be imagined. With reference to the theological position, it is only just to say that Kant succeeded in completely over- throwing the usual form in which the arguments of rational theology were stated. But, after all, Kant argued on his own presuppositions ; and till these had been tested, the victory could not be pronounced ultimately decisive. Yet for a moment everything was swept away before this imperious onslaught — the soul, human freedom, God Himself: and a blank agnosticism was left to mock the efforts of speculative reason. It was impossible, however, to imagine that metaphysic at a moment of renewed youth should be slain by a single sword; and it is now universally acknowledged that Kantism is in no sense the last word on the subject of metaphysical speculation. KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 7 Indeed the necessity for unity of knowledge (such as is guaranteed by a belief in the absolute, whether viewed from a theistic or pantheistic point of view), is not merely a result of a practical impulse but a necessity of the theoretic reason. Otherwise all knowledge is dissolved into doubt, reason into con- tradiction, and truth into seeming. Kant's theory of knowledge sets a limit to know- ledge which it shall not pass. Led by theoretical reason we arrive at a point, like Israel of old, where the impassable sea rolls in front, the illimitable desert stretches on the further side, and the inexorable foe presses on behind. Flying before the onset of materialism, knowledge finds itself between the sands of doubt and the waves of scepticism. The situa- tion is desperate and nothing but a divine interposi- tion can save. Such a deus ex machina Kant finds in his theory of Practical Reason. Theoretical knowledge hems us in on every side, but it is impossible that man can thus live or live content : there must be freedom, scope for development, wide regions of religion and morality, through which the soul may wandering wonder, and wondering worship, and worshipping reign. Kant sees clearly how im- possible it is to rest content with the barren delusions of the theoretic reason. So by a tour de force the practical reason regains what the theoretic reason had lost, or rather thrown away : and we are introduced to what must ultimately prove to be two realms of reality. In the one, theoretic reason reigns supreme, and thought languishes under its stern despotism ; in the other, practical reason gives freedom and erects a spacious edifice, wherein 8 RITSCHLIANISM religion and morality may dwell securely and none make them afraid. The Critique of Practical Reason starts with the idea of a moral law. This is regarded as a fact of reason, which there is no gainsaying. The existence of a moral law which is the determining principle of the will necessitated the assumption of moral liberty. Similarly a will determined by the moral law neces- sarily seeks the realization of the highest good. The highest good, however, can only be realized by the perfect conformity of the will to the moral law. But this never takes place in the world of sense : hence we are driven to postulate the immortality of the soul. The practical reason is not yet content. The highest good is the combination of virtue and happiness, and this demands that nature should be in harmony with morality. But if this is so, there must be not only a cause of nature outside nature, but a cause which is necessarily a complete manifestation of the perfect moral law. Hence as a necessary postulate of the practical reason, we must assume the existence of God. So all things are restored that were lost — freedom, immortality, God. And these great doctrines, freed evermore from the fluctuating speculations of theo- retical philosophy, are exalted to the unassailable heights of moral certainty. But we are not per- mitted to ascribe to these things any theoretic value. As Kant himself says, more than once : " We can only think the Supreme Being; we cannot know him or ascribe anything theoretically to him." The proof of God's existence rests in no sense whatever on demonstration, but solely and entirely on the practical KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 9 postulates of the moral consciousness. Kant, indeed, seeks to maintain the objective reality of the three great conceptions to which we have alluded, but emphatically denies the possibility of their ever becoming objects of theoretic knowledge. Under these circumstances, however, it is really impossible to assert their objective truth. Kant's anxiety to defend the aprfority and originality of the moral law leads him to assert " the autonomy of the will as the sole principle of moral laws and their corresponding duties.'' Stated otherwise, the obligatoriness of the moral law is to be found in the moral constitution of human nature, and in no sense in its correspondence with, and manifestation of, a perfect will of absolute good, wholly independent of man, and serving as the standard to which all ideals of morality must con- form. It may be granted, and Kant has proved it well, that the moral law is a fact of our reason. But this proves no more than it states ; and then we must hold our peace. The postulates of the practical reason are thus no more than hypotheses and assumptions based upon our moral consciousness, and the neces- sary presupposition of man's moral activity : they can in no sense whatever be said to be characterized by objective necessity or truth. Starting from the necessity of the subject, rather than that of the object, they may indeed maintain their position as real constituents of human nature, but only to be rapidly dissolved into complete relativity. By far the greatest difficulty of the Kantian theory of knowledge has yet to be examined — the complete separation of the theoretic and practical lo RITSCHLIANISM reason. Such a separation it would be hard to justify, save as a theoretical distinction conveniently- drawn for the purposes of the critical examination of elements recognized to be essentially inseparable. This, however, is in no sense the meaning of Kant. For him the two realms of knowledge are not merely distinct, but mutually exclusive ; and mutual exclu- sion may at any time pass into avowed hostility. The unity of knowledge is practically sacrificed ; for there seems no possible method by which the a prioTi moral law, a form of the practical intelligence, can ever become subject to the categories of the under- standing. How then can the moral law ever become an object of knowledge, unless the former or the latter abandon their peculiar characteristics ? It almost seems as if the principles of theoretic know- ledge compel us to deny the possibility of the practical postulates ever becoming an object of knowledge or thought, or, indeed, having any real existence. It need hardly be said that this result in no way corresponds with Kant's intention. His fundamental antithesis between the two realms of knowledge has a very different object, that of setting religious truths free from all fear of philosophical assaults. Theoretic knowledge being limited to phenomena and never attaining to the things in themselves which are the pattern of the true, the reason could no longer claim absolute supremacy. A fair field was left for faith : for where knowledge is, faith is done away : but where knowledge is not, there faith can be active ; for faith is the evidence of things not seen, nor known, nor understood. Knowledge may ■even be regarded as the fount of unbelief : and the KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE ii Kantian philosophy, by dennonstrating the subjec- tivity and insecurity of knowledge, claimed to have cut off the waters of that fountain for ever. Reason was dethroned and faith declared triumphant. But the victory was too dearly purchased ; for faith and knowledge are so closely interwoven the one with the other, that when one perishes the other pines. By reducing all knowledge to phenomena, faith itself became nothing but subjective presentation ; and in this overthrow of reason religion is itself over- thrown. The theory of knowledge which Kant elaborated is the pivot of the Ritschlian theology, and, speaking generally, it is quite impossible to understand the religious thought of the nineteenth century, without a thorough appreciation of the principles and pre- suppositions of the Kantian philosophy. Its theory of knowledge dominated many minds and many schools : but in other directions also it was not with- out far-reaching influences, some of which we may briefly indicate. (i) The critical philosophy marks a real stage in the advance of thought in its relation both to empiricism and dogmatism. The scepticism of Hume furnishes an historical illustration of the ultimate resting place of philosophical empiricism. Kant attacked this negative conclusion through the premises; and established the transcendental spon- taneity of the human mind. He vindicated the truth and certainty of the categories, and the right of reason to form its own laws. (ii) Even more important was the overthrow of dogmatism, >vhich airned at demonstrating the 12 RITSCHLIANISM ultimate identity of truth and being. While not quarrelling with the conclusion (which is inevitable for any systematic unity of thought) Kant rightly demonstrated the inadequacy of the methods by which it was reached. By Kant's masterly explica- tion of the idea of reason, the old metaphysic was not only discredited but practically destroyed. (iii) In vindicating the originality of a moral law, Kant shook off the fetters of empiricism and materialism. These latter made common cause in attempting to reduce morality to the social and physical causes of environment and heredity. Kant's assertion of the " categorical imperative " as no empirical growth in society nor any result of custom or education, but as an essential factor in the inmost constitution of the human mind, raised human feeling above the mechanical and material theories which sought to deny this fundamental attribute of humanity. (iv) Kant's real greatness lies in the fact that he inaugurated a tremendous and lasting revolution in the world of thought. Ritschl himself states with force and directness the great problem of human existence. " Man as a spiritual being on the one hand, makes the claim to be of greater worth than the whole natural system ; and, on the other, finds himself limited, hemmed in, and subjected by the latter." ^ This difficulty was felt most acutely towards the close of the eighteenth century : the problem was how to reconcile freedom and depend- ence. Practically, the question had been settled ; for freedom was denied. Doctrines and institutions, ^ Drei akademische Reden, p. lo ; cf. R. V, iii» 199. KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 13 political and ecclesiastical, were decorous and dead ; for the spirit which gives life had fled to seek a more congenial home. Forces moved beneath the surface — volcanic forces of terrific power : forces and fires the more violent because the longer suppressed. These fierce desires were awhile inarticulate : it was Kant who first gave them conscious and reasoned expression. The Kantian philosophy represents the rebellion of the human spirit, against the lifeless externalism which threatened to crush the soul out of existence. Kant reiterated with emphasis the necessary and original freedom of the human mind : and so doing voiced the passionate protest of the human spirit against those soulless forces by which it seemed at times that it must be inevitably over- whelmed. In this respect the critical philosophy marks a turning point in the history of freedom, progress, and religion. (v) We may in conclusion glance at the manner in which specifically Christian doctrines are treated by Kant, especially as not a few have in this form been taken over into the Ritschlian theology. Kant's conception of the highest good led him to conceive the world as a teleological system, and to postulate its moral government by God. The issue would result in the realization of a universal fellowship of men bound together by the laws of virtue ; or, in other words, a consummation of humanity in the Kingdom of God. In his Religion within the Limits of Reason^ Kant somewhat alters his earlier point of view : for, while in the Critique of Practical Reason Kant deduced the idea of the Kingdom of God from the idea of God himself, as 14 RITSCHLIANISM the supremely moral Being, in his later work he bases his deduction on man's need of moral fellowship by which ultimate victory is to be secured. Ritschl himself exhibits many changes of opinion, but he remains constant in asserting that here we have " Kant's weightiest thought for theology." Thus, in the first edition of his monumental work he claims that " This teleological interpretation of the system of the world, derived from the valuation of fellow- ship in action, according to moral law as the final aim of the world, stands in direct analogy to the Christian view of the world " ; ^ while in the third he again declares that " a judgment of the moral destination of men which attaches itself to Kant's fundamental position serves as the ground of know- ledge for the validity of the Christian idea of God as solution of the problem of the world." ^ (vi) Kant's doctrine of human freedom was of the utmost importance to any doctrinal system which nucleated itself round the great ideas of justification and atonement. As part of the phenomenal world, man is under the laws of natural necessity : as part of the noumenal world, of realities, reason prescribed to itself its own laws, and man is thus free. These ideas were appropriated by Ritschl, in whose hands they received systematic enlargement and theological interpretation, " The high importance of Kant's contribution to the right understanding of the Christ- ian idea of reconciliation lies less in any positive contribution to the structure of the doctrine than in the fact that he established critically — that is, with scientific strictness — those general presuppositions of ^ R.V. iii^. 13-15. 2^. F. iii3. 215. KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 15 the idea of reconciliation, which lie in the conscious- ness of moral freedom and moral guilt." ^ And again, in reference to the Kantian system, Ritschl declares, " A sharply marked and continued consciousness of guilt without which the whole Christian idea of re- conciliation is unintelligible, becomes methodically possible only when we judge ourselves after the idea of transcendental freedom." ^ (vii) One feature of Kant's theory of the objective character of guilt brought him into sharp antagonism with the Illuminist Theologians, The latter held a view of Divine punishment, which cannot be more finely or more tersely expressed than in the noble words of Clement of Alexandria, Unto salvation and reform and conversion are the punishments of God. Kant, followed by Ritschl, on the other hand, maintains strongly the retributive as opposed to the reformatory character of Divine justice, and sees in the former, rather than in the latter, the essential meaning of punishment " From the idea of our practical reason which sets the transgression of the moral law in the light of guilt, it follows also that transgression deserves punishment." "^ It is difficult to bring Ritschl's later views into harmony with his early and emphatic approval of Kant's position in this respect, but at first its anti-mystical tendencies strongly appealed to him. " Herein Kant s opposition to the Illuminist treatment of the idea of punishment holds firm ground, and in itself the thought is one of undoubted truth." * We may now take leave of Kant : our all too brief ^ op. cit. i. 408. '^ Ibid. 394. ^ Ibid. 417. * Ibid. 417. i6 RITSCHLIANISM examination, or rather indication, of his main posi- tions will have made it clear how powerful a stimulus they afforded to thought, and how profoundly the philosophical conclusions of this great thinker modi- fied all subsequent attempts at systematic religious reflection. Indeed, it is no exaggeration to say that the Kantian philosophy necessitated not merely a restatement, but a reconstruction of traditional theo- logy. A few words must be added on the subsequent development of the Kantian philosophy by those who are generally described as Neo-Kantians. The pre- vailing distaste for metaphysics, the disillusionment consequent on the break-down of the speculative movement of the first half of the nineteenth century, the triumph of the experimental sciences, all combined to produce a reaction of which " Back to Kant " was the watchword and battle-cry. For Kant's theory of knowledge secured two things — the existence and the unknowableness of the thing in itself The latter sets science free to pursue its own course, unhampered by metaphysical or theological inter- ference : while the assertion of the former left open a wide region for religious feeling and imagination. Thus Materialists and Idealists both united in the demand for a return to Kant. The chief representative of this tendency is Lange, whose History of JMaterialism is recognized as the fullest and ablest exposition of the principles of the Neo-Kantian School. Lange practically abolishes the thing in itself: he certainly denies its objective reality. It can only be affirmed as an epistemo- logical category. We cannot know whether the KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 17 thing in itself exists ; all we can say is that the conception of any true nature of things is " nothing more or less than the progeny of an antithesis (between the thing in itself and the phenomenon) posited by our organization, with regard to which we are ignorant whether it has any significance whatever relatively to that which is outside us." ^ From the physiological experiments on the organs of sense, Lange concludes that sense and understanding can no longer be treated as separate. Accordingly for Pure Reason he substitutes " physico-psychical organ- ization." Here then we seem to have drifted into thorough-going materialism ; but we are violently plucked out of the vortex into which we are sinking, and are landed in the syrtes of idealism. For Lange's philosophy is no naive materialism, but critical materialism. He does not attribute reality to matter : on the contrary he insists on its pheno- menal character. It is difficult to admit the success of this curious synthesis of discordant elements : Proteus-like Lange's philosophy now appears ideal- istic, now changes rapidly and inexplicably into a materialistic form. If this is the result of Kant's theoretic philosophy, we cannot be surprised at the overthrow of his prac- tical system. " The entire practical philosophy," says Lange, " is the mutable and transitory part of his system . . . The whole significance of the great reform inaugurated by Kant must rather be sought in his Critique of the theoretical reason." Even with regard to our knowledge of ourselves, the conclusion is drawn with resistless logical force that " the corner- ^ Lange, op. cit. ii. 57. B i8 RITSCHLIANISM stone of the Critique of Reason is that we do not know ourselves as we are, but merely as we appear to ourselves," Our knowledge, then, is wholly limited to the phenomenal, and though the human mind longs to reach transcendental truth, it is an endless journey, a hopeless task. What, then, becomes of religion?^ There is a choice between two alternatives. (i) Its function should be transferred to science and to art ; but this might involve spiritual im- poverishment, and might even provoke fanatical reaction. (ii) By penetrating to the kernel of religion, we can consciously rise above the actual, thereby vanquishing fanaticism and superstition, and at the same time abandoning for ever the attempt to falsify the actual by means of the mythical. The kernel of religion must not be sought in certain doctrines which are incapable of withstanding the solvent powers of criticism — the end whereof is complete negation ; but in the elements of the soul above the actual where it can have the promise of a spiritual home. Religion is really a product of phantasy, a free creation of the imagination ; and its value lies in its ethical, not in its logical substance. Kant set bounds to reason to make room for faith ; Neo-Kantism would abolish faith to make room for religion. But it is only on one condition. Religion must freely own itself poetry, not reality ; relative, not absolute ; subjective, not objective. She must not adorn herself in truth's stolen feathers lest her nakedness appear, and she become a laughing-stock ^ Cf. Lange, ii. 546, 547. KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 19 for all mankind. But dwelling in the region of phantasy, she is secure from the attacks of science and the doubts of philosophy. Indeed, religious ideas will thus be strengthened. Their theoretic truth is destroyed, but their practical value is enhanced. Even the self-created illusions of religious belief may be both beautiful and beneficial. But the scepticism and illusionism whither Neo- Kantism leads is no haven where we would be ; nor can we think that Truth is a seemly sacrifice for Illusion's altar, even though by some unexplained means a more suitable victim at the last moment takes her place, and she is preserved, like Iphigeneia of old, to continue her life in some far distant shrine, removed from the haunts of men. Illusion, that is conscious illusion, can neither claim to possess true beauty nor to confer lasting benefits. It must not be supposed that Neo-Kantism has not fulfilled a valuable service in the development of human thought Against empiricism it insisted on a /;7*d?;7' constituents of human knowledge ; against neo- dogmatism it insisted upon a scientific examination of fundamental presuppositions. Neo-Kantism is, therefore, a true starting-point for further advance, but cannot claim to have reached the goal of all philosophical reflection. We must finally examine the outlines of Lotze's philosophy — for though the most diverse critics are agreed in regarding Ritschl as a Neo-Kantian, he himself emphatically repudiates the Kantian epistem- ology, and declares his adhesion to Lotze.^ We may perhaps, in passing, mention that Lotze ^ Theologie und Metapkysik^ passim. R. V. iii. 19. 20 RITSCHLIANISM himself took a very different view as to the place of epistemological considerations in constructive theology than that which Ritschl advocates. The latter, it will be remembered, definitely laid down that every scientific theologian must proceed in accordance with a clear theory of knowledge, the legitimacy of which he must be prepared to defend. Lotze, however, considered any such preliminary investigation into the psychological conditions of the origin of know- ledge as " wholly unwarranted " and " essentially unsound, if the purpose is to build upon that most obscure of all problems any metaphysical system ; on the contrary, these problems themselves have neces- sitated the discovery of fresh methods of solution." ^ It is important, therefore, to realize the position that Lotze's theory of cognition holds to the rest of his philosophical system. It is not as with Kant the fundamental presupposition, but the natural out- come of his philosophy. Lotze agreed with scientific empiricism in assuming an infinite multiplicity of simple beings which con- stitute the sensual world ; with Spinoza he believed in the substantial unity of all being ; with Plato in the idea of the infinitely good. Thus he maintains that the multiplicity of ' reals ' is embraced in an absolute substance, in one infinite being, of which they are really nothing but the modifications. Never- theless, their independence necessitates their being thought of as soul-like beings in which the infinite being is spiritually immanent. Lotze therefore controverts Kant's theory of knowledge, for though he held with Kant that the ^ Lotze, Metaphysik^ 1 5. KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 21 world of science is phenomenal, he yet maintained the possibiHty of the things in themselves being the object of theoretic thought. Having thus shown how far a rational view of the world was susceptible of theoretic demonstration, he proceeds to contrast and compare it with the inde- pendent sphere of moral and religious truth. In this realm the mind has its own ideals ; and as it is impossible that these, which are the most valuable products of the human mind, springing from its innate capacity for the appreciation of real worth, can be mere illusions, he postulates for them an actual existence. Thus, ethical good conceived as all-personal is exalted to the throne of the universe, and is crowned both by the theoretic thought and the religious consciousness. This idea of good is finally identified with the conception of the living love of the living God, from which is deduced a grand spiritual and teleo- logical view of the whole world as leading to eternal blessedness. It remains to indicate those two directions in which the teaching of Lotze exercised the greatest influence. (i) Ritschl sums up Lotze's theory of knowledge in the following words : " He holds that in the phenomena, which in a limited space exhibit changes to a limited extent and in a definite order, we recognize the thing as the cause of its qualities operating upon us, as the end which they serve as means, as the law of their constant changes."^ Plato and Kant, in Ritschl's estimate, are both in ^ R. V. iii. 19, 20, 22 RITSCHLIANISM error in separating the thing in itself from its attri- butes and activities. Lotze's theory makes no such separation, so that we can state that the thing may- be known in its phenomena. Thus while Kant would consider the knowledge of the things in themselves, were it attainable, as a higher form of knowledge than that which we have, Lotze holds that the things are only the means to produce those representations which we actually possess, and that therefore the higher knowledge con- sists " rather in tracing the meaning bond and laws of the phenomena than in pursuing anxiously beyond the power of thought the means by which the latter are produced." Notwithstanding, Ritschl's refusal to treat the phenomena as anything other than subjective ap- pearances, and his curious suggestion about the origin of the thing in itself as a memory picture of repeated intuitions, does not take us much further than the Kantian doctrine of the unknowableness of the things in themselves. But to this we must refer later. (ii) Lotze consistently maintained a sharp dis- tinction (capable of ultimate reconciliation) between the religious consciousness and theoretic philosophy. Man has a faculty for judging according to worth. With this capacity he is originally endowed, and through it he becomes conscious of a world of values, as well as of a world of forms. This world of values, the true sphere of religious consciousness, has needs and ideals, and even a language of its own quite distinct from those of the merely intellectual view of the world. There can be no question that KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 23 Lotze's theory of these two types of representation directly paved the way for the doctrine of value- Judgments which plays so conspicuous a part in the Ritschlian theology. Additional Note. Another problem that suggests itself is the origin of sensation. Kant would ascribe this to the thing in itself, but it is plain that this cannot be empirically deduced, for experience itself can only arise when phenomena are brought under the categories of the understanding. Pure experience will not help us to discover whether the thing in itself can have any existence independently of our own consciousness. In other words, we cannot tell whether the things have transcendental or merely empirical reality. " Properly speaking, I cannot perceive external things : I can merely infer their existence from my inner perception by treating this latter as an effect, of which something external is the nearest cause." ^ But this inference is problematical in the extreme, owing to the possibility of the plurality of causes, and consequently our perceptions of external things may be nothing but modes of repre- sentation or modifications of our own consciousness. There seems no doubt that a legitimate inference from Kant's language in his first edition of the Critique would be that he left the existence of the thing in itself as a wholly open question ; but in his second edition was added the much disputed Refiitation of Idealism. The account Kant himself gives of this passage is that it was intended to clear up the obscurities of his former state- ments and to obviate consequent misunderstanding. Kuno Fischer, perhaps the greatest scholar in matters Kantian, ^ Critique oj Pure Reason, 1st edition, p. 367. 24 RITSCHLIANISM prefers the original form of the doctrine, which he considers to be a genuine representation of Kant's meaning. He holds that the later editions blunt the force of the idealism with which, as a matter of fact, the Critique of Piire Reaso7i is bound up. *'The Critique, in its first form, was the Critique from Kant's own point of view : in its subsequent form it was the Critique from the point of view of the Kantians." ^ The Kantian philosophy exercised a strong power of attraction for many minds : yet the philosophy which resolved all phenomena into mere mental repre- sentations could never permanently secure the enthusiastic advocacy of any large number of converts. The dogmatic mind demanded as a condition of its acceptance of the Kantian philosophy a single concession which however seeming slight yet was a surrender of the crucial point. The limits of the human understanding suggested an adequate explanation of the unknowability of the ultimate meaning of phenomena. Kant was prepared to accept the inevitable. In the second edition we are confronted with a realistic modification of his original view, the logical consequence of which was plainly in irreconcilable conflict with the main presuppositions both in regard to the thing and to the thinking subject underlying his whole work. The fact is that Kant, dreading lest he should be drawn into the vortex of metaphysical idealism, threw over some of his elementary principles to save his philosophy, which yet had to cling to them for the support elsewhere denied. Thus Kant refutes idealism yet lands us in inevitable scepticism as to the things in themselves. Have they real existence or no? Kant leads us to uncertain inferences and insoluble doubts. Berkeley, against whom the Refu- tatio7i of Idealism was chiefly aimed, was more thorough- ^ Kuno Fischer, Geschichte^ etc. iii. 444. KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 25 going : " What conclusion can determine us to assume the existence of bodies outside the mind as the ground of that which we perceive, seeing that not even do the advocates of the doctrine of matter maintain that there is any necessary connection between bodies and our ideas?" Kant attempts to answer this question, but succeeds only in repeating it. For the whole essence of Kant's famous criticism of the ontological proof of Gods being is the inadmissibility of passing from idea to reality. Kant severed the thing in itself wholly and entirely from the phenomenon : the two are in no wise related as two aspects of the same object, nor is the thing in itself the phenomenon stripped of sensuous representation. For the phenomenon stripped of its sensuous character vanishes into the empty air. Between the phenomenon and the thing in itself a great gulf is fixed : nor is there any possibility of passing from one to the other, even for those who would fain do so. The thing in itself must therefore remain theoretically incognoscible forever. But if so, how can the existence of the thing be justifiably maintained? For all existence must be determined, nor can being be separated from the mode of being. Kant indeed declares that the thing in itself is merely a limitative conception of exclusively negative use ; it is therefore "Noumenon" as opposed to that which is empiri- cally given. But even here we are not free from a crowd of inconsistencies. The thing can only be thought under the form of the categories which control all thought ; and yet the categories are inapplicable to anything that lies beyond the phenomenon. The thing in itself cannot be known : nor can it be thought. And we may well ask how can the unthinkable exist ? The trend of the Kantian philosophy inevitably involves the abolition of the thing in itself. What then becomes 26 RITSCHLIANISM of the distinction between the thing in itself and the phenomenon, on the basis of which distinction the entire edifice of Kant's theory of knowledge, as vcell as his practical philosophy, has been erected? Historically Fichte carried Kantism to the only logically legitimate conclusion, when he represented the thing in itself as merely the non-ego ; not in the sense of anything actually independent of the ego, but as a self-posited limit of our own con- sciousness It is hardly an exaggeration to say that the principles of the Kantian system demand a suppression of its presuppositions. The Kantian theory of knowledge seems to terminate in complete subjectivism, if not in solipsism, and tends to the entire overthrow of all objective knowledge. It may be answered that we can predicate actual existence of the many finite consciousnesses which compose the human race. But it is difificult to see on these philosophical principles what relation the human race can bear to the individual con- sciousness other than as a species of subjective repre- sentation. Yet it was on the assumption that reason was common to all the members of the human race that Kant asserted the necessity and universal validity of human knowledge. But if the human race may itself be a subjective representation, how then can human knowledge acquire objective validity? Kant set out to vindicate the objectivity of human knowledge : he sought a sure foundation ; but he has built his house upon the sands. The quicksands of subjectivity would have indeed swallowed him up quick, but he was himself saved by the inconsistencies which ■destroyed his system. For, in spite of much self-con- tradiction, it was always a fundamental thought of the Kantian philosophy that beyond the confines of experience lay another region vague and dim, possible only to specu- KANT, LANGE, AND LOTZE 27 lation, but capable of independent justification as a matter of faith. Kant's theory made the thing in itself absolutely inde- terminate and indeterminable, and wholly disconnected with the phenomenon. The inconsistencies and self-contradic- tions which beset this position, do not merely indicate its weakness, but suggest a possible answer. Kant's failure to establish his position shows the lines along which a reconstruction must be attempted. The distinction between the phenomenon and the thing in itself is an impossible abstraction. Kant would fain drive us to an unjustifiable alternative. If with Hume we suppose that the categories are derived from experience, we must deny their aprioristic and necessary character ; if on the other hand with the Rationalists we regard them as conditioning all possible experience, he would have us assert that they are only determinations of the mind, and therefore possess nothing more than subjective value. This however is a false dilemma. If in the mind, not in the things, says Kant ; and therewith destroys the possibility of objective knowledge. The reply is easy. If in the mind then also in the things. If the categories are only con- ceivable in the understanding, then there must be some necessary correspondence between the knowing mind and the known things. In other words, the existence of the categories in the understanding points to the existence of an understanding independent of our minds in the things also. CHAPTER II SCHLEIERMACHER AND THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL The nineteenth century marks a well-defined period in the history of religion. The extraordinary re- vival of philosophy — whether rational or experiential — had given rise to a series of questions of universal import. The sciences were rapidly emerging from the subordinate position they had hitherto been content to hold, and threatened to sweep all meta- physical speculation off the field. What should be the attitude of the Church amid prevailing uncer- tainty and intellectual unrest ? Would she adapt herself to her new environment ? Would she abate her exclusive claims ? Would she descend from the clouds and mingle among men to raise them to heaven ; or would she remain inaccessible to the new demands of human reason ? The question was one of pressing importance ; perhaps more so in Protestant than in Catholic circles, for the former possessed no such logical and self-enclosed theory of infallible authority as the latter. It was seen that the earlier method of Protestantism was doomed, but what was there to put in its place ? The answer to this question was given by Schleiermacher, who set himself in his two great works — the Discourses THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL 29 on Religion and the Doctrine of Chinstian Faith — to restate theology in the terms of the new learning. Such restatement was sorely needed ; and just at the psychical moment appeared Schleiermacher's monu- mental work, in which all the tendencies of the expiring century were woven into a kind of unity, while the trend of thought thus set in motion is yet operative in the present day. The abiding service that Schleiermacher rendered to religion was his de- liberate undertaking to systematize theology. His masterly work — Die Glaubenslehre — grasped the idea of a system and developed its significance : his entire outlook is dominated by the conception of a whole in dogmatics. He will have no peace with the popular theology of the day which reposes upon fragmentary " passages " of Scripture. Calvin, it is true, had bequeathed to the orthodox theologians of the reformed school distinctly systematic tendencies; not only by the impress of his own masterful per- sonality but also as the necessary outcome of his conception of the elect community in whose redemp- tion the whole of God's world-plan is accomplished. Lutheranism, with no such stimulus to a systematic theology, tended more and more to become pure traditionalism. Orthodoxy proved a dour mistress. The Scriptures, from which a connected view of Christian theology was to be drawn, had at all costs to be preserved entire. Orthodoxy appointed and approved the material, and even if some parts of the material should be flagrantly out of har- mony with the rest of the building, they must not be discarded as superfluous but retained as being of quite special value. The authority of Scripture, so RITSCHLIANISM supported by the dogma of plenary inspiration, was employed to give ample shelter to the unintelligible and even to the irrational — which by an extra- ordinary perversion both of faith and reason was supposed to contain a special manifestation of the supernatural and to be the special object of venera- tion among the mysteries of the faith. The tendency of modern Lutheranism even among the theologians of the confessional (or orthodox) school to shake off the shackles of tradition and to elaborate a con- structive and systematic theology is wholly due to the influence of Schleiermacher, who was really the first to apply the modern scientific spirit to the study of dogmatic religion, Schleiermacher, then, inaugurated a new era in theology by his systematic restatement of Christian dogmatics. It is in his conception and development of a systematic whole in religion that his real originality is revealed. But his conspicuous and enduring services in this respect were only made possible by a new view as to the origin of dogma. " Vixere fortes ante Agamemnona " : and Herder, to mention no other names, had anticipated Schleier- macher in maintaining the distinction between faith and doctrine, religion and theology. The latter, how- ever, was the first to make this distinction a real and determining factor in his treatment of theology. For the new rationalism zn essence differed but little from the old theology, in that both conceived religion as the assent to certain dogmatic propositions. Ortho- doxy naturally fastened on the scriptural dogmas formulated in the creeds and ecclesiastical con- fessions as the essential propositions of Christian THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL 31 faith. Rationalism while reducing these essentials to far smaller proportions nevertheless demanded assent to its own propositions. These might be conceived as natural truths and might claim the support of Scripture : but the fact remains that while rationalism and orthodoxy differed profoundly as to the real essentials of Christian faith, they both agreed in assuming some such essentials, and in demanding assent to their own propositions as the only valid basis of religion. The whole and the only point in dispute between the two may be narrowed down to the amount of things necessary to be believed and the exact position of reason in theology. Schleiermacher broke with both schools : indeed, he showed little patience with either. In their place he substituted his well known theory — religion is neither knowledge nor action, but feeling ; — and dogma is the expression of the inner significance of this religious feeling. Hereby dogma was deprived of all external and ad- ventitious authority. Such authority as dogma con- tinued to possess was derived solely from its character as the necessary expression of the religious conscious- ness. In this connection Schleiermacher joined issue with the Rationalists : for their exaltation of reason as man's highest power led them to seek the truth of this thought in a kind of abstract independent self- sufficiency which ultimately sacrificed man's really highest power, the ability to initiate new departures in life and history. Rationalism by a kind of false isolation spoke of the qualities inherent in mankind, as in the abstract. With this abstraction Schleier- macher shows himself wholly unsympathetic. He knows nothing of human beings qua human beings ; 32 RITSCHLIANISM but of human beings definitely and historically char- acterized. Similarly in his view there is no such thing as abstract religion but only concrete religions ; that is to say, religion is never actually realized save in a variety of individual and independent religious fellowships. Every religion has its strongly marked individual characteristics, largely historically deter- mined : and every religious faith must have reference to its own religious fellowship. We may, in passing, refer to Ritschl's appreciation of the importance of this conception. He considers it one of the most important truths taught by Schleiermacher " whereby he has given a new aspect primarily to ethics, and secondarily to theology ; and has risen above the field of vision both of the Kantian and Wolfian schools." Schleiermacher will have nothing to do with the natural religion of rationalism, nor with its thesis that all religions are ultimately the same and that their historical peculiarities are of little or no account. On the contrary he insists with vehemence that it is only from within the religious community, only in the faith and fellowship of a definite Church, that it is possible to arrive at any distinction between the essential and the accidental features of a religious body : and that, in drawing such a distinction, the definite historical characteristics must be taken as absolutely determinative. Schleiermacher's reduction of religion to feeling needs further amplification. The particular form of feeling is characterized as a sense of dependence. The feeling may, of course, be undeveloped or even misdirected, but where it exists in a pure and healthy form, there exists also true religion. The THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL 33 feeling arises in this manner. Our conception of the world does not give us the realization of the highest values. There is not the immediate harmony which we naturally desiderate between the explanation and evaluation of existence. As a result of this discord between the valuable and the actual, man sets him- self in earnest to see to it, that whatever happens the former shall be preserved. Were man omnipotent, no difficulty would be felt nor would any religious feeling necessarily arise. But the reverse is the case. In his struggle for the preservation of value, man finds himself perpetually opposed and constantly thwarted. It is here that religion comes to the rescue, for there arises that feeling of dependence upon an ultimate reality in which value and existence are harmoniously united. Schleiermacher's scheme is certainly open to the suspicion of pantheistic tendencies. Each man, nay every being, is a microcosmos, enshrining and repeat- ing in itself the powers and problems of the universe. When this secret of existence has been apprehended, when the relation between the individual and the universe has been realized, then comes this feeling of dependence, in other words the origin of true religion. When we come to press the question on what exactly man depends, the answer is, on God. But God is not apparently conceived in His transcendental rela- tion to and above the world, but merely as a convenient symbol, a kind of " Whereon " to round off the idea of dependence. Schleiermacher himself protested against any such deductions from his teaching : and it may be inferred from his writings that while laying stress on the immanence of God as c 34 RITSCHLIANISM the principle of universal order, he is yet prepared in the idea of a universe to separate though not to sever the world from God. It may be asked (as indeed it has been, not once nor twice) of what value this doctrine of dependence can be to the human mind. Would not the constant recollection of our bonds, the continual remembrance of our limitations, fetter all free development and progress ? Can religion do no more for us, save to oppress us with a melancholy insistence on our own powerlessness ? Schleier- macher's answer must be found in his conception of the world. To him, as to Goethe, the world in nature and in history is one vast drama in which each man, each thing, has an important and even indispensable part to play. All is a manifestation of perfect and supreme intelligence. From this standpoint dependence is the only possible expres- sion of man's individual relation to the whole. In his recognition of this fact, in this feeling of depend- ence, man learns to acquire for himself both freedom and happiness. This is the task and test of all religion which, if properly conceived, cannot fail to issue in man's perpetual blessedness. Briefly to summarize Schleiermacher's main posi- tions with special reference to their subsequent influence on systematic theology, we should draw attention to the following points : (i) Schleiermacher aimed at a synthetic and systematic exposition of Christian dogma. His work was marked by unity and continuity ; and laid the foundation of the modern restatement and even reconstruction of theology. Thus Ritschl himself pays his tribute : " He is the only one since the THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL 35 Reformation who has employed the scientific method of proof in theology.'' (ii) By placing the essence of religion in feeling, Schleiermacher opened the door to a completely subjective interpretation of religious experience which had the most far-reaching results. (iii) Schleiermacher's conception of dogma as the expression of ever-varying life, and the consequent denial of any permanent authority in the statement of religious belief, was of immense importance for the subsequent development of theology. In this con- nection we may note his remarkable anticipation of the results which the comparatively modern science of psychology has brought to light in the sphere of religion. " Everything immediate in religion is true, for otherwise how could it have come into existence? But only that is immediate which has not gone through the conceptual mill, but has grown up on the soil of pure feeling." (iv) The doctrine of dependence was violently assailed and zealously defended. Its logical conse- quences seem to lead to Pantheism: its "immediacy" is not without traces of mysticism. It may perhaps be admitted that Schleiermacher did not lay sufficient stress on the activity which precedes and conditions this acknowledgment of dependence. (v) Most important of all, perhaps, was his over- throw of rationalism and natural religion by insisting on the definite historical character of all religions. The far-reaching effects of the application of this principle to the origin and development of Christi- anity as a positive historical religion can hardly be exaggerated. 36 RITSCHLIANISM (vi) Finally, Schleiermacher laid down with em- phasis the true relation of our Lord to the community He founded. Moses may be taken from Judaism, and the law remains : Mahomet may be taken from Islam and the pious Moslem can still practise his accustomed ceremonies. But to sever Christ from Christianity even in thought is an impossibility. The Redeemer and the redeemed are indissolubly joined. For the Christian religion is a life ; and its principle is : " Because I live, ye shall live also." The idea of the relation subsisting between Christ and the Church was rightly apprehended by Schleier- macher and exercised the greatest influence on Ritschl, who agreed with him that Christ is " the Founder of a society only in virtue of the fact that the members of that society become conscious through Him of their redemption." Schleiermacher was not immediately succeeded by Ritschl. In the interval three great schools of thought — the Liberal, the Conservative or Confes- sional, and the Mediating schools — took their rise, whose characteristics must be briefly examined, if we wish to form a right conception of Ritschl's true relation to contemporary theology and his real place in nineteenth century thought. In most respects the three schools are widely separated and even bitterly opposed : but in one particular they are all united. From Schleiermacher they learn to regard an empiri- cally-acquired feeling or an immediately-given self- consciousness as the true starting-point of theology. Schleiermacher may himself rightly be regarded as the pioneer and champion of romanticism in theology ; and in this respect the three schools of thought which THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL n followed him were his disciples. Herein we can trace the fundamental agreement and historical point of union between these tendencies so widely different, yet so closely related. For, however deep their dis- agreement in particulars, they are all united in the importance and indeed pre-eminence to be attached to subjective impressions and aesthetic considerations. It is a proof of the vigorous vitality of romanticism that it shewed itself capable of such manifold and diverse development. The two most important representatives of German Liberal Theology are Pfleiderer and Lipsius; but it is important to notice that they were influenced by Hegel as well as by Schleiermacher. It is well known that these latter two regarded each other as irrecon- cilable adversaries: and it is true that both in termin- ology and in their theory of knowledge they exhibit a fundamental difference. On this subject it may be enough to state that Schleiermacher was the true successor of Kant, while Hegel sought to re-establish by a new method the positions of the pre-critical philosophy. But apart from the methods and phrase- ology employed, it is very doubtful whether their conception of religion was not really the same. Both were the determined foes of rationalism, both looked upon man as a microcosm in which the whole life of the universe received compendious but complete ex- pression. In both, religion is the realization of the infinite in human consciousness. But what is accom- plished for Schleiermacher by his formula of absolute dependence, Hegel accomplishes through the process of speculative thought. It is plain that the Hegelian philosophy can come to terms with orthodoxy: for 38 RITSCHLIANISM all its historical and dogmatic progress is viewed in its relation to the development of the central idea of truth through antithesis. Each dogma, then, each period has a true and even necessary value in the great unfolding of the world-idea towards the perfect light of Christianity. It must be admitted that this treatment of all ecclesiastical history as furnishing countless and ceaseless illustrations of this single con- ception is apt to become unspeakably monotonous. And yet this conception of religion is perhaps superior to Schleiermacher's in the value it attaches to the religious idea. Hegel develops where Schleiermacher describes : and though the Liberal theologians lay great stress on the identification of religion with feeling they are naturally attracted by the idea of development, and thus exhibit great affinity to the scheme of the Hegelian dialectic and dogmatic. Schleiermacher's empirico-historical conception of religion resulted in his drawing up a table of religions which in an ascending scale should manifest most clearly the central idea of complete dependence. At the head of the series stands monotheism which may be viewed from two standpoints as leading either to action or to contemplation. The former he regards as the highest possible religion and considers that in Christianity *'teleological monotheism" finds its most perfect embodiment. The peculiar characteristic of Christianity which distinguishes it from all other re- ligions of the same order is to be found in the perfect redemption it offers through Christ. Thus Schleier- macher and all his school lay the greatest possible stress on the right interpretation of Christ's work and Person, rightly regarding these as all important and THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL 39 really constitutive facts in Christian piety. Redemp- tion implies alienation : and thus Schleiermacher's conception of Christianity gave a great impetus to a thorough re-examination of such leading theological thoughts as sin, atonement, regeneration and justifi- cation. This necessarily led to much difference of view, but it also concentrated attention upon those dogmas which were in the greatest need of restate- ment, and we have already noticed the influence of Schleiermacher in this respect on the presentation of the Ritschlian theology. The strongest opposition to Liberal tendencies was offered by the Confessional school of modern orthodoxy. The connection of this school with the historical movement in German history known as the Awakening is universally conceded. It was an at- tempt to import into theology a stronger and fuller tone than could be found in rationalism ; a tone which should be more in keeping with the new-found theories of national life and national freedom. A special form of this theological awakening may be found in the revival of pietism, which in its insistence upon indi- vidualism and strictly Biblical theology, brought to the front a series of new and pressing problems. It was natural that the pietistic movement should inspire those who viewed its individualistic tendencies with misgiving, with a renewed interest in the mainten- ance of orthodoxy in matters of religious belief and practice. The chief exponents of orthodoxy are to be found in the Erlangen school of theology. This school contains such well known names as Hoffman, Thom- asius, and Frank. Their dependence upon Schleier- 40 RITSCHLIANISM macher is obvious : yet it was his method rather than his results that they adopted. Schleiermacher was really the first to draw up a system of Lutheran dogmatics. This, of course, was in itself no new thing: the new thing was to call it Lutheran rather than Christian. In Schleiermacher's view it had become necessary to choose between two historical types of religion — evangelical or catholic : where- upon he consciously and deliberately accepted the situation and added to the title of his work on the *' Christian Faith" the definite limitation "according to the principles of the evangelical church." Thus in a manner Schleiermacher gave a clear call to particularism and confessionalism. In this connec- tion we must once more lay stress upon his conception of Christianity as a positive historical religion; to him Christian dogma was the true expression of the life and experience of the Christian community. Chris- tianity is the religion of those who are conscious of their redemption through Christ: and the relation to Christ is the absolutely determining factor in the religious life of the individual or of the Church. It is in these formulas of Schleiermacher which approxi- mated so closely to and justified so clearly the results of ecclesiastical dogma, that the theologians of Erlan- gen chiefly show themselves his disciples. Hoffman, like Schleiermacher, recognized the need of a systematic theology. Starting with the personal experience of the Christian he worked backwards to the experience of the Christian Church, as expressed in its creeds and confessions ; and thus further to the documentary proofs in Scripture upon which all is based. In his work on prophecy and fulfilment his THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL 41 system receives careful elaboration. It may suffice to say that the view of prophecy here taken is mechanical in the extreme. It would appear that prophecy itself has little value and even little meaning save as unfolding and foreshadowing reformation theology. Notwithstanding, the book has its value for its philosophy of religion ; it conceived religious history as a system of real facts, and Hoffman may even be said to have inaugurated a new method in theology in which he found many followers. Thomasius in his history of doctrine is clearly influenced by the principle of Hegelian dialectic. He attaches the very highest importance to ecclesiastical dogma, not as marking a real stage in a perpetual process of development, but as the final and complete expression of reasoned theology. Frank is perhaps the best known, as he is also the most able, representative of this school. His theo- logical system is based upon an elaborate self-analysis. The personal experience of the Christian is the test by which all dogma must ,be tried ; and it is not found wanting, though at times it emerges in a form in which it would hardly be recognized by its original defenders. In this manner Biblical theology and ecclesiastical dogma (at anyrate in its Lutheran form) are found to be in complete harmony, and to afford a sufficient ground for Christian certainty. Finally we come to the Mediating school of theology. The best known names are Dorner, Rothe, and Kahler. The " Vermittlungs-theologie " had ample scope for its powers of pacification. In two respects especially did this school endeavour to effect a rap- prochement between opposing tendencies. In the 43 RITSCHLIANISM first place they insisted upon the many points of resemblance and contact between the Lutheran and Reformed Churches, in their common opposition to the spirit of Catholicism. Moreover, believing that dogma divided where ethics made one, they laid the main stress on the ethical side of Christianity. In both respects they followed closely in Schleiermacher's footsteps, and professed also to be followers of Melancthon among the reformers. In the second place, they strove to mediate between theology and philosophy. From Schleier- macher they inherited the idea of Christianity as a historically given, historically conditioned religion, while from Hegel they derived the impulse to demon- strate its essential reasonableness and intelligibility. Dorner's great work on the system of Christian doctrine is a typical example of the labours of this school In it faith and doctrine, religion and science are happily combined. This combination may seem to destroy the character of unity which is to be desiderated in a systematic exposition of theology ; but none the less this lack of unity in no wise hindered but rather increased the practical influence of the work. Rothe's books are characterized by much originality (though sometimes of a rather fantastic nature), by a thorough-going aestheticism and by a bold use of speculation. Kahler abjures speculation, and aims at a Biblical theology. Dogma is for him the conviction concerning the Saviour's work experienced first by the apostles and evan- gelists, then by the Church, ultimately recovered and clarified by the Reformers. But Kahler never seems equal to the task of satisfactorily adjusting the claims THE ROMANTIC SCHOOL 43 of religious conviction and those of history. Was Christ really He whom the Apostles were convinced He was ? We may admit that the convictions of the disciples coloured their narrative, but not to so great an extent that it is impossible to recover the lineaments of the historical Christ The reliance upon evangelical experience in the last resort suggests that the fascination of Schleiermacher's subjectivism is still unbroken. It was reserved for Ritschl to break the spell ; and having indicated the character- istics of contemporary religious thought, we are now in a position to consider the significance of his own contribution to theology. CHAPTER III RITSCHL; HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL Our survey of the main theological tendencies in Germany during the nineteenth century will have taught us to realize how clearly all schools recognized the urgent need for a restatement of theology which should bring the facts and ideas of religion into harmony with the changed attitude of modern thought, and how earnestly they applied them- selves to the task. The need was indeed very sore, for though religion in a sense was more than ever reverenced as a motive to practical conduct, or as affording scope for man's spiritual powers, theology came to be regarded more and more as an essentially impossible science, mas- querading in the borrowed plumes of truth, while a philosophy of religion was increasingly viewed as a contradiction in terms. Briefly to recapitulate, and to summarize some of the causes which contributed to this result, we may notice : (i) The prevailing distaste for metaphysics which was the logical outcome of the Kantian philosophy. Kant had set the strictest limits to the bounds of reason. He was the real founder of theoretical RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 45 agnosticism. In Germany the Neo-Kantians set out like the Seven against Thebes to the overthrow of all objective knowledge. In England, Herbert Spencer, with reiterated and almost monotonous insistence, proclaimed the entire unknowability of that which lay beyond the world of sense ; that the reconciliation of religion and science could only be effected on the basis of a frank recognition " of this deepest, widest and most certain of facts that the Power which the Universe manifests to us is utterly inscrutable.'' (ii) But the age was characterized not merely by a positive dislike for, but a still more profound distrust of metaphysics. The critical reaction to- wards the Kantian position relegated religion to a sphere, unknown and unintelligible ; while for theology, extinction was confidently predicted. But at this stage, philosophy appeared no longer as a foe but as a friend. The Hegelian dialectic was zealous to take Christianity under the shelter of its wing. But it is perilous indeed to identify the Christian religion with any particular form of metaphysical speculation. Whither is it leading us : to what does it commit us ? It will be little use demanding a separation when the union is become well nigh indissoluble ; or at any rate when the mischief is done. "Timeo Danaos et dona ferentes." Even Hegelianism- — if it does not lead (as it seems inevitably to do) to the rejection of the miraculous and a pantheistic view of the worlds- regards the ideas of the religious consciousness as nothing but wholly inadequate images of the perfect truths of speculative reason. 46 RITSCHLIANISM Thus whether philosophy chooses to attack, or offers to defend, makes little difference. The modern mind is simply obsessed with the idea that metaphysics offers far too insecure and precarious a foundation upon which to rest our religious con- victions and most cherished beliefs. (iii) In striking contrast to this anti-metaphysical tendency is the advance and success of the experi- mental sciences. New knowledge, new experience make fresh demands upon our faith, which at times it seems powerless to meet. " And yet the very vastness of those demands serves to obscure and conceal their true character. . . . The worlds of knowledge and of action have assumed such huge proportions, have accumulated such immense and complicated resources, have gained such supreme confidence in their own stability, have pushed for- ward their successes with such startling power and rapidity, that we have lost count of their primal assumption. In amazement at their stupendous range we are overawed : we dare not challenge them with their hypothetical origin."^ We are indeed in perpetual danger of forgetting that empirical science has imposed on itself definite limitations in order to achieve its two practical objects : to facilitate intercommunication, with a view to social co-operation, and to economize intellectual labour by the creation of generalized conceptions. It seems obvious that the success of the empirical sciences in describing and calculating the course of events must lie in the rigid exclusion of all moral, aesthetic, historical, and metaphysical considerations. ^ Lux Ahmdi {i2th Edition), 17. RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 47 Thus the interest of physical science is in no sense the logical one of consistent thought about ultimate reality, but the practical one of successful inter- ference with nature. The wonderful achievements of science over an enormous field have blinded our eyes to its real character, namely, as a series of practical postulates whose truth has been demon- strated only within the strictly limited sphere of their practical applicability. For science starts with special restrictions and arbitrary exclusions. Practi- cally this method has justified itself by its success. But it has no claim to be regarded as a philosophy of absolute truth. For physical science, asking special questions of nature, determines the character of the answers it wishes to receive. Notwithstanding, the progress of science has been so rapid and all- embracing that the purely practical, descriptive, and hypothetical character of its postulates has been forgotten, and they themselves have been treated as the indispensable conditions of all existence and all knowledge. Hence the truths of mechanical science are perverted into the falsehoods of mechanical philosophy,^ and a materialism presses on, threaten- ing to sweep away spiritual and idealistic interpre- tations of life in a universal overthrow. (iv) On what basis then must religion rest ? For long the authority of the Bible seemed all sufficient. But the Sacred Scriptures have themselves been subject to the most searching criticism ; and, though it may be admitted that they have emerged triumph- antly from the test, yet in very many cases the ^ For all this section see an admirable chapter in Taylor's Elements of Metaphysics on " the descriptive character of science." 4^S RITSCHLIANISM traditional accounts of theii* origin and authorship have necessarily been given up. In many minds the authority of the sacred books was so closely bound up with their authenticity, that the critical theories, even when their reasonableness was completely established, proved extremely distressing and disconcerting. But the higher criticism did not lose itself in questions of date and style : a far deeper question was involved. For the overthrow of Biblical infallibility necessitated an entirely new conception of the inspiration which might be claimed for the records of revelation. The character of revelation was itself treated as an open question. The human side received such abundant illustration, such unsparing criticism, such reiterated emphasis that the divine side receded further and further into the distance. Delighted to discover that the Bible was intelligible because it was in the language of men, a newer age appeared to forget that it was authoritative because through it came the voice of God. (v) In no sense less modern or less powerful than the scientific doctrine of the uniformity of nature is the conception of the continuity of history. Historical science is even yet in its youth : but it makes exact- ing demands. The historian's task is not merely to record but to explain events. To do so, he must trace out cause and effect ; for to believe in causeless events violates every principle of rational intelligi- bility. But when once the belief that history is all continuous, passes from a working hypothesis to a speculative doctrine, what becomes of inspiration or miracle, or of that crowning miracle of all, the Incar- nation of the Son of God? This view of history has of RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 49 late years become increasingly attractive: but we must insist that it is rather a philosophical conception than a conception of the world either derived from, or proved by, history itself. It has however done real service in refusing to countenance any further the arbitrary distinction between sacred and profane, which de- stroyed that community of character between man's religious aspirations and secular experience, from which so much that is valuable may be learnt and on which modern science has done well to dwell. Yet in its extreme form the doctrine of the continuity of history makes havoc of the catholic conception of Christ. We quote from Pfleiderer's well known work on the philosophy and development of religion : * The appearance of a heavenly being for an episodic stay upon our earth breaks the connection of events in space and time upon which all our experience rests and therefore it undoes the conception of history from the bottom."^ (vi) Perhaps however the most pressing problem is the relation of Christianity to those social questions which the advance of science and the expansion of in- dustry has in recent times forced to the front. A con^ victiorl has seized the Church that it is entrusted with a social mission.^ Other-worldliness, once a praise, has become a reproach : the social question is almost universally recognized as ultimately a religious ques- tion, and a gospel of social regeneration, as well as, if not instead of, a gospel of individual salvation is everywhere preached. It is plain that much social ^ Pfleiderer, Development of Religion^ ii. 43. ^Cf. Ys\^^'% Social Evolution \ Peile's Reproach of the Gospel \ and the- speeches and papers at the Pan-Anglican Congress on Socialism. D so RITSCHLIANISM enthusiasm must immediately be won, if it is not to be permanently lost, to the Church. Accordingly we cannot be surprised if these tendencies have had no little effect in the increased importance given to representation of the Church as a body, as a kingdom with practical and ethical ideals, by which Christ is exalted as the ultimate authority and sovereign over every department of human life and thought. Such were the principal influences at work which created the " Zeitgeist " into which Ritschl was born. The Ritschlian theology is a serious attempt to answer the intellectual and social demands of the age, to rescue theology from its perilous plight, and set it up upon a rock of stone. It might seem superfluous to trace the history of Ritschl's theological career ; but he learned so much from many teachers, incorporating many elements of their teaching, and rejecting others, that some acquaintance with his earlier associations forms an indispensable preliminary to the study of his matured theology. For Ritschl's mind was extraordinarily receptive, and yet at the same time remarkably inde- pendent. Born in 1822, he soon showed an aptitude for theology " not merely from the child's natural desire to be what his father was (his father being * bishop ' and general superintendent of the Lutheran Church in Pomerania) but from a resistless speculative im- pulse to comprehend the highest truth." ^ In 1839 he began university life at Bonn, where Nitzsch enjoyed a great reputation. His first purchase in Bonn was a copy of Hegel's Logic, Two years later, ^ Leben, i. p. 1 8. RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 51 dissatisfied with Nitzsch he moved to Halle, where Tholuck, Muller and Gesenius were the most distin- guished theologians. That was Ritschl's period of stress. His religious views were undergoing profound modification. Reluctant to part with his strong and early belief in the supernatural, he nearly threw him- self into the arms of Hengstenburg, the most famous representative of extreme conservatism. At this time, however, Erdmann was lecturing on the Hegelian philosophy, and Ritschl embraced with enthusiastic conviction the tenets of this, at that time, all-dominant school ; but it is doubtful whether he ever entirely sacrificed his independent and essentially ethical view of the world to Hegelian intellectualism. However that may be, his philosophical speculations brought him into renewed contact with Baur's doctrine of re- conciliation, and after a brief association with Rothe in Heidelberg, he definitely attached himself to the Tubingen School, the reputation whereof was then at its height. Here he produced a work on the relation of the third Gospel to Marcion's expurgated edition in which (in accordance with much that was produced at Tiibingen) the theory of an Ur-Lukas figured pro- minently. But it was Ritschl's fate to be always alternately attracted and repelled. In 1846 he left Tubingen to begin lecturing as a " privat-docent " in Bonn. In the subsequent year Ritschl showed his independence by a vigorous review of Baur's work on Pau/j the Apostle of Jesus Christ. Two years later appeared Ritschl's first work of permanent value, on the Rise of the Old Catholic Church. In the preface he refused to allow historical criticism to be drawn into the service of any dogmatic presuppositions, whether 52 RITSCHLIANISM negative or conservative ; while in the book itself he broke completely with the Tubingen theory of early Christianity. Baur maintained that Gentile Chris- tianity was the product of exclusively Pauline influences : Ritschl shows that it was really due to the failure to appreciate the significance of the Pauline ideas. A second edition, almost wholly re- written, appeared in 1857, in which he sought to obliterate the personal element. The book showed that its author accepted practically the entire New Testament Canon, and in the sphere of Church History insisted that external reconciliation would have been impossible save on the basis of internal agreement. Ritschl had waited six years before he received official recognition ; but in 1852 he was appointed "Professor Extraordinarius " and in 1859 "Professor Ordinarius." Meanwhile, though lecturing on exegesis and ethics, he began to devote himself more and more to the study of Dogmatics ; and when in 1864 he accepted the position of Professor Ordinarius at Gottingen, his attention was almost exclusively concentrated upon a fresh presentation of dogmatic theology. In 1870 appeared the first volume of his magnum opus on Justification and Reconciliation. Ritschl approached this work as an avowed Kantian, accept- ing Kant's limitations of the theoretic reason, and his deduction both of God and of the Kingdom of God as postulates of the moral consciousness. He had also seriously studied Schleiermacher, whose methods and conclusions we find him alternately emphasizing and repudiating. Traces of mysticism discoverable in the latter's theological system were wholly to be RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 53 abhorred. In some of the letters of this period, Ritschl professes himself to be positively repelled by Schleiermacher's theology. Four years later, when studying the Discourses on Religion, his tone is no longer depreciatory but almost enthusiastic ; indeed, he does not hesitate to declare that " he is the only one since the Reformation who has employed the scientific method of proof in theology." ^ Schleier- macher's opposition to natural reHgion, his insistence on the historical origin and character of all religions and on their embodiment in an organized fellowship ; above all, the employment of a systematic and scientific method in theology, were all ideas which appealed powerfully to Ritschl, and he incorporates them all into his own work. From a specifically Christian standpoint, Ritschl also borrowed much from Schleiermacher — the conception of Christianity as a positive historical religion, the function of the Church as the sphere and witness of Christ's redeeming activity, the utter impossibility of a Christian religion without Christ : yet Kattenbusch seems to be in the right when he sees the real significance of Ritschl in the fact that he broke more completely than any of his predecessors with Schleiermacher's method. For while the latter made the pious consciousness his starting point, Ritschl starts from the Gospel, thus exactly reversing the leading principle of the three chief schools that followed Schleiermacher. Dogmatics for Ritschl is not the interpretation of anj/ actual state of piety within the Christian community, but the unfolding of the norm of all piety in the Christian Church.^ ^ Reden^ p. l8. ^Kattenbusch, Von Schleiermacher zu Ritschl^ p. 60. 54 RITSCHLIANISM But there is a third influence which worked strongly on Ritschl's mind. His removal to Gottin- gen brought him into contact with Lotze, with whom he formed a close friendship, and from whose philo- sophical works he derived many suggestions. In particular, he declared himself a follower of Lotze rather than of Kant in his theory of cognition, though both his biographer and his critics agree in thinking that epistemologically he remained a Kantian to the end. More important is his obvious dependence on Lotze in the development of his theory of value-judgments, for it was Lotze who insisted with the utmost clearness on the inde- pendent value and reality of the religious — as opposed to the intellectualist — view of the world. Ritschl had published the first volume of Justifi- cation in 1870, containing a history of the doctrine. The second volume appeared four years later and contained the Biblical material: the third in 1875, ex- pounding " the positive development of the doctrine." The same year witnessed the publication of his treatise on Schleiermacher's Discourse on Religion, where he assigns a high and honoured place to one towards whom he has at times assumed an almost bitter and uncharitable attitude. We ought also to mention the Instruction in the Christian Religion, published in the same year, a little work originally intended for the use of higher forms in schools, but of great value as a compendious and careful exposi- tion of the chief tenets of the Ritschlian system. His next great work was the History of Pietism, in three volumes, the first of which appeared in 1880, and the third in 1886. In 1881 he wrote a defen- RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 55 sive pamphlet on Theology and Metaphysics, It cannot be pronounced a very happy effort, nor is it charac- terized by the same fine grasp or lucid exposition of the subject which Ritschl's other works might lead us to expect. Meanwhile he busied himself in preparing new editions of his great work. Some of the differences between the first and later editions are most remark- able, and we shall have occasion to allude to some of the more noticeable alterations at a later stage. But there is nothing here for surprise, as Ritschl's views never reached finality. He himself states that he had learned infinitely much in the preparation of his dogmatic work, and was still learning.^ It was, as we have intimated, mainly in the di rection of a Lotzean epistemology, and of the definition of religious knowledge as value-judgments that the most striking modifications are to be found. In 1889 Ritschl died, leaving behind him a band of earnest disciples who set themselves with fervour to propagate the principles of their new found faith. It is important to notice wherein the followers of Ritschl were united, and where they are in complete disagreement, for the independence of the disciples is so strongly marked that friend and foe have alike raised the question as to whether it is possible to speak of a Ritschlian school in any sense at all. Thus Herrmann, the most illustrious representative of Ritschlianism, states : " A Ritschlian school as it exists in the warlike minds of its opponents, does not exist as far as I know. Of the theologians whom it is customary to regard as specially belonging to that ^ Lebm, ii. 150. 56 RITSCHLIANISM school, none is ready to uphold Ritschl's theology at all points. But we have learned more from him than from any other theologian since Schleiermacher." ^ Similarly Kaftan, after Herrmann the most noted of the older Ritschlians, writing twelve years ago, maintains that " The Ritschlian school as a definite unity which represents the same theology, exists only in the imagination of its opponents. The differences among us are very great. Nevertheless in some essential points we all agree." ^ What then are these points of agreement ? And what is it that these eminent theologians have learned from Ritschl ? They have imbibed a principle rather than adopted a system. Thus Kattenbusch in the exceedingly able pamphlet to which we have referred declares that " RitschFs theological principle is infinitely richer than Ritschl's system. Any man who seriously seeks to make Christ understood, can bring new thoughts to supple- ment those of Ritschl. Yet no such man will be in a position to think slightingly of dependence on Ritschl, for he has done so much for our better appreciation and understanding of Christ that there is no man who would not feel himself bound to admit having received thoughts from him of the greatest weight"^ It was the principle of Ritschl — the principle that saw in the historical person of Christ a full revelation of things divine — that drew together men of the most diverse temperaments and views. And this diversity, so far from being an essential weakness of the ^ Herrmann, Verkehr^ 2nd edition, p. 4. 2 Zeitschrif/f '96, p. 378. ^Kattenbusch, of, cit. p. ()7,. RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 57 school, tends to establish the real greatness of Ritschl, who could unite such heterogeneous elements and stimulate them to a common activity. ^ Thus in the very beginnings of a Ritschlian school it becomes obvious that the peculiar charac- teristic of the school is not to be found in any unanimous agreement of its members in any identical propositions, but in their common acceptance and working out of definite principles. ^ Pfleiderer (who asks the same question as Herr- mann — whether there is such a thing as a Ritschlian school after all — and gives the same affirmative answer from a very different standpoint) sees the nerve of their opposition to the ordinary theology in their unconditional rejection of that which they persist in calling " natural religion," but which is usually known as the religious disposition of human nature, the aprioristic foundation of all religious and moral development, the Divine image or natural revelation implanted in mankind.^ Here at any rate we have a negative unanimity ; but it is possible to discover a community of ideas and aims (derived generally from this root principle) shared by all the members of the school. Thus Herrmann speaks of the funda- mental ideas which have drawn together a group of theologians in such an agreement as is not to be met with elsewhere with so great a number. ^ These fundamental ideas are admirably described by Professor Orr : " The strong contrast that the ^ Herrmann, Verkehr^ 2nd edition, 3. ^Ecke, Die theologische Schule Albrecht Ritschl s^ vol. i. p. 76. ^ Pfleiderer, Die Ritschlische Theologies 77. ■* Herrmann, Die.Gewissheit des Glaubens, 17. 58 RITSCHLIANISM Ritschlians all draw between religious and theoretic knowledge : the desire to free theology from all association with and dependence on metaphysics : the insisting on the positive revelation in Christ as the one source of true religious knowledge : the central position they all assign to the doctrine of the Kingdom of God ; the rigorous exclusion from theology of all that lies outside the earthly mani- festation of Christ ; and finally the distrust of every- thing of the nature of mysticism in religion." ^ These ideas appealed most powerfully to a far wider circle than a few professed theologians. They struck a chord which found a ready response in the heart of the people. It is claimed that it is Ritschl who has given the most powerful encouragement to the present generation of German theologians : no less it is claimed that hearts are being won almost exclusively through the influences set in motion by Ritschl. The opposition his theology encountered, the desire to do him justice and propagate his views, set all Germany in an uproar : and even now though the weaknesses of the Ritschlian theology have been frequently exposed, though the arguments employed in its internal controversies have almost neutralized each other, and demolished the whole system in its parts, yet its influence is still dominant, its adherents still increasing, its vitality yet abounding, and its popularity yet unshaken. The reason can only be found in the fact that the Ritschlian theology does indeed answer to some of man's deeper needs : and this truly represents the case. It has often been remarked that Ritschlianism is the creation of its ^ Orr, RitschHanism^ p. 55. RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 59 age : and the remark is apparently intended to be taken in a depreciatory sense, as discounting all Ritschl's claims to originality. To this it may be replied that there is a kind of originality which yields no good fruit for theology or practical religion. Ritschl's originality was not of this kind : rather it consisted in his ability to carry out new combina- tions. It was not the principles that he adopted but the manner in which these were formulated and combined that constitute Ritschl's own original contri- bution to theology. ■■■ He expressed much that was inarticulate : combined much that was sundered. He was thus enabled to propound a theology which proved itself peculiarly acceptable to contemporary thought. In this connection we cannot forbear to quote a remarkable passage from a French writer which gives the true explanation of the extraordinary influence of this new theology upon all sorts and conditions of men. " To those who are disheartened by the attacks of criticism it affirms that faith and salvation are in- dependent of the results of our historical researches. To theologians weary of dogmatic controversies it presents a Christianity freed from all foreign meta- physics. To scholars trembling to see theology fall before the attacks of the natural sciences, it shows a way by which all collision with the natural sciences becomes impossible. To students devoted to history, it unfolds the development of the primitive church. To timid Christians, it says, God has never been angry with you : He declares to you that you may return to Him. To worn-out pessimists, it cries : ^Ecke, Die theologische Schule A.R. 13-41. 6o RITSCHLIANISM Work for the advancement of the Kingdom , . . Doctrine without Christian Hfe is nothing. ... In an age greedy for Hberty and equality it establishes a social theology which makes the individual disappear in the mass." ^ Nor should we omit to notice the claim put for- ward on behalf of the new theology to be the only adequate representation of original Lutheranism, the only true development of Reformation principles.^ How far Ritschl's confident claim may be allowed will depend upon the view we take of the Reforma- tion itself Certain it is that the Reformers, struggling to be free of scholasticism, ended by erecting a similar edifice— as complete, as imposing, as fundamentally impossible (Ritschl would say), and as diametrically opposed to their own principles as that which it was intended to replace. Ritschl seizes on the idea of / freedom as the ultimately determining significance of the Reformation, and strives to carry it to a logical conclusion, and to give it shape and substance in a systematic theology : with what justification and success we shall have to enquire later. It now remains briefly to indicate the leading representatives of Ritschlianism to-day. Herrmann, Professor in Marburg, is perhaps the earliest of the school. In his Theology and Meta- physics^ published in 1876, he deals incisively with the relation of the two sciences, which he claims to ,be one of complete independence. Three years later followed another work on Religion in Relation to Knowledge ( Welterkennen) and Moi^ality^ which intro- ^ Schoen, Les Origines historiqttes de la TMologie de Ritschl^ 6, 7. aKattenbusqh, op. cit. 64. RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 6i duced the term value-judgments to theology, though of course the idea had long been familiar. But Herr- mann is best known for his book on The Communion of the Christian with God, which has now reached a sixth edition in Germany, and a second in an English translation. In this powerful book Herrmann seeks to free religion from all scholastic and mystical con- ceptions, and to ground the certainty of faith in the impression wrought upon the soul by the historical Christ, as presented in the Gospel. Julius Kaftan takes a very different line : to him religion is the life hid with Christ in God : but he is one with Herrmann in his energetic repudiation of anything savouring of scholasticism. His two chief works are on The Essence of the Christian Religion (i 888) and the Truth of the Chnstian Religion (i 889). In I 890 these were followed by a much smaller work entitled Do we need a new Dogma ? Kaftan thinks that the whole history of dogma is a sad illustration of the perpetual perversion of genuine Christianity ; but that the time has at last arrived for a synthetic and constructive attempt to find adequate expression for the chief Christian truths. The adhesion of Harnack has proved a tremendous gain to the Ritschlian theology. Not only have his profound learning, his penetrating criticism, his con- structive and imaginative faculties, his eloquent style, gained him a world-wide reputation among scholars of all nationalities, but he has deliberately set himself to popularize his own conception of religious faith and practice. " This I know," he declares in his pre- face to the English edition on his lectures on What is Christianity ? ** the theologians of every country only 62 RITSCHLIANISM half discharge their duties if they think it enough to treat of the Gospel in the recondite language of the schools, and bury it in scholarly folios." Harnack's views on the Hellenization of Christianity need not detain us here : they must be examined later : it must suffice to point out that the main purpose of his History of DocUHne is to prove that "dogma in its conception and development is a work of the Greek spirit on the soil of the Gospel." ^ It is not necessary to specify all the members of the Ritschlian school ; but mention must be made of Bender, whose extreme subjectivism led to his ulti- mate exclusion from the party : and of Schultz and Wendt who are associated respectively with very valuable work in the theology of the Old Testament and the New. The doctrine of value-judgments has created a literature of its own. Its chief upholders are Otto Ritschl (the son of the founder of the school, who has also written a full and able biography of his father), Max Scheibe, and Max Reischle. To Kahler we have already alluded : he can perhaps scarcely in strict justice be called a Ritschlian, though he has learned much from Ritschl. His standpoint, as we have seen, is " mediating." Ecke follows Kahler in his irenical standpoint, and has produced a book on the theological school of Albrecht Ritschl and the evangelical Church of to-day, which must rank as a very thorough and valuable contribu- tion to the hterature of the subject (1897). In France, Sabatier has written with fervour and eloquence in defence of the principles of the Ritschlian theology. It must not be supposed that there has ^ Dogmagesckichte, i. i8. RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 63 been direct or conscious borrowing; but it is admitted by Sabatier and others that there is a kindred spirit " with the theological movement to which Ritschl has given his name, the doctrines of which, while not to be confounded with ours, yet approached them on the chief points." ^ Sabatier's standpoint may best be seen in his Esqicisse cTiate Philosophie de la Religion. He thinks that the younger generation have been driven into an impasse when they are bound to choose between pious ignorance and brutal knowledge : when they must continue to live by a morality which contradicts science, or build up a theory of the world which science condemns.- He sees an escape in a philosophy of religion, based upon a study of psychology and history.^ Moreover he adopts the Kantian epistemology which denies the possibility of knowing of God, save " symbolically '' : and also Ritschl's distinction between judgments of essence, and judgments of value. Thus he reaches the conclusion that in the face of the subjectivity of religious knowledge, symbols alone can adequately express religious ideas.* We can thus see how nearly the school of Sabatier approached to Ritschl, whose theology had for them the supreme merit of giving an answer to the needs of the present generation. It is only in recent years that Ritschlianism has begun to attract any attention in English speaking countries : and here such attention as it has received, has been almost invariably unfavourable. Excep- tions, however, must be made in the case of Professor Swing, who appears as an enthusiastic disciple in ^Menegoz, Publications Diver ses^ 236. -Sabatier, op. cit. v. ^ Op. cit, XV, ^ P. 303. 64 RITSCHLIANISM America, and Dr. Garvie who also follows Ritschl — yet sometimes afar off. The latter's " critical and constructive exposition and estimate " of the Ritsch- lian theology is perhaps the fullest as it certainly is the most sympathetic account of the aims and doctrines of the movement in the English language. We ought perhaps also to mention Professor M'Giffert, whose History of Christianity in the Apostolic Age (1897) clearly exhibits the Ritsch- lian " Tendenz," though the subject obviously does not admit of any detailed exposition of theological presuppositions. Quite lately, however, a great change has taken place. " Modernism " has been attempting to do for Catholicism what Ritschl tried to achieve for Pro- testantism, that is, to set religion free from all precarious connection with historical criticism or scientific speculation. The attempt to suppress the movement by invoking authority had the inevitable effect of concentrating attention upon its claims and characteristics. Almost simultaneously the standard of the New Theology was raised in one of the most prominent Nonconformist pulpits. To those un- acquainted with the liberal tendencies of modern theology, the advent of the New Theology appeared startlingly sudden : all were surprised ; most were shocked. Yet, as a matter of fact, the theology as then propounded was anything but new, and its appearance anything but sudden. It was merely the place and moment of its publication that were in any way really sensational. For the New Theo- logy is but one more attempt to mediate between the relis:ious and scientific views of the world ; RITSCHL: HIS AGE AND HIS SCHOOL 65 between modern thought and ancient doctrines ; between present needs and past ideas. It repre- sents to a great extent the English phase of the RitschHan movement. In some respects the EngHsh version of the New Theology is sundered most widely from the theology of Ritschl and his followers : it is connected with a Hegelian philosophy which Ritschl would have energetically repudiated ; notwithstand- ing, it is not far removed from that vigorous modern pragmatism which makes man the measurer of all things, and would distinguish the Christ of history from the Christ of experience, not with the view of reconciling or rather combining two independent presentations, but of forcing them apart as funda- mentally opposed and incapable of reconciliation. The Ritschlian theology is a challenge to our age. The old theology has failed apparently in recent years to arouse enthusiasm, to inspire social effort, or to encourage independent thought. An almost pessimistic despondency hovers around the seekers after truth. ^ What is to be the end of these things ? Cannot religion be saved apart from reason ? Can- not faith persist without creeds ? Cannot theology be systematized without dependence on metaphysics ? Cannot the miraculous be eliminated without any real loss to the Christian believer ? The Ritschlian school has given its answer to these questions : an answer clear and definite and systematic. It is incontro- vertible that in many directions it has succeeded ^ In this connection we may call special attention to two remarkable books of recent years. Kidd's Social Evolution^ and Balfour's Founda- tions of Belief. The latter has been warmly welcomed by Kaftan as strongly supporting the Ritschlian position. E 66 RITSCHLIANISM where other attempts had failed. It should, there- fore, in no sense be treated without sympathetic respect, without a willingness to learn : nor should it be rejected until, after a searching examination, it should be found unfitted to take the place of that theology which it was intended to supersede. To such an examination we must now address ourselves. CHAPTER IV THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE The 'Ritschlian theory of knowledge is the basis upon which the whole edifice of the Ritschlian theo- logy has been erected. We have already alluded to Ritschl's own words in this connection. He insists that every theologian whose aim it is to treat his subject in a scientific method, must proceed on a definite theory of knowledge, of which he must be deliberately conscious, and which he must be pre- pared to justify and defend. ^ It must be admitted that this seems a strange beginning for a theology professing to abjure all metaphysics. For to establish an epistemological theory, some kind of metaphysical enquiry becomes essential. But Ritschl will not leave us in doubt as to his meaning — for he continues : " If I am scienti- fically qualified in theology, then I shall follow a theory of knowledge which in the determination of the objects of knowledge will be regulated by a con- ception of things, and thus will be metaphysical." So the promise of a theology without metaphysics was somewhat delusive after all : for the only way to reach it is along a metaphysical road. Arrived at our destination we need traverse that path no more : ^ Theologie und Metaphysik^ 48. 6S RITSCHLIANISM yet if we put up " no thoroughfare,'' how will others come thither? We climb up to the height of theology without metaphysics, where we can dwell securely, but it is only by a metaphysical ladder that we have attained thereto. If from our point of vantage we kick away the ladder as of no further use, how shall others find their way to our dwelling- place ? Yet, Ritschl, embarking on a metaphysical venture to reach the place where metaphysics may not intrude, on the one hand allures those who entertain a deep-seated distrust of philosophy with a promise of theology without metaphysics, and on the other insists upon the necessity of metaphysical appliances if men are ever to reach the haven where they would be. He affirms with emphasis that it is *' an inconceivable and incredible contention that we should be charged with excluding all metaphysics from theology," and asserts that the real point at issue between him and his opponents, is not whether, but what metaphysics are to be employed. After this repeated insistence upon the necessity of a theory of knowledge for any systematic handling of theology, it is somewhat disconcerting to read after an interval of only a few pages that " as Chris- tianity is neutral in regard to the differences between Jewish and Hellenic morals, so also as a religion it is indifferent in regard to the different theories of knowledge by means of which its intellectual contents may be scientifically arranged." ^ The only coherent meaning to be gleaned from this glaring inconsistency is that while theology depends upon a theory of knowledge, religion does 1 T.M. 46. THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 69 not. We must therefore assume that theology and rehgion represent two wholly independent points of view ; or, in other words, that theology without meta- physics has passed into religion without theology. Apparently Christianity is identified wholly with religion, and dissociated from theology : for Chris- tianity is indifferent to theories of knowledge, while theology cannot possibly pretend to indifference as to the character of its fundamental presupposition. But could any proposition well be more questionable than a theory which entirely divorces religion from theology, and makes what is fundamental to the one a matter of indifference to the other? However, with- out dwelling unduly upon this initial difficulty, we will proceed to consider Ritschl's own view as to the different theories of knowledge which have held the field, and the reasons which have led him to accept the Lotzean epistemology. Within the domain of European thought Ritschl distinguishes three theories of knowledge. The first is due to the influence of Plato, and has found a home in the realm of scholasticism. This theory, which exercises perhaps the widest influence and may be almost identified with the conceptions of popular epistemology, maintains (according to Ritschl) that the thing itself can be distinguished from its effects upon ourselves. Thus while the thing works upon us by means of its mutable qualities, arousing our sensitive and perceptive faculties, yet it really rests behind its qualities as an unchanging self- equivalent unity of attributes. In other words this theory holds that we can know the thing in itself apart from its effects, and that everything 70 RITSCHLIANISM may be deduced from universal ideas; thereby over- looking the fact that the thing in itself is merely the permanent memory-picture due to repeated impres- sions or intuitions of effects by which our sensation and perception have been stimulated. Ritschl next discusses the second theory of know- ledge which he holds to have been promulgated by Kant. This would confine our intellectual knowledge to the world of phenomena, but declares the thing in itself or the things in themselves, in whose reciprocal changes the changes in the world of appearances have their origin, to be unknowable. The latter part of this doctrine Ritschl holds to be a well-justified repudiation of scholastic philosophy : but in the earlier part of the theory he maintains that Kant has himself fallen into the chief error of scholasticism — the separation of the thing from its appearances. For a world of phenomena can be posited as the object of knowledge only if we suppose that in them something — that is, the thing itself — appears to us or is the cause of our sensations and perceptions ; otherwise the phenomenon can only be treated as an illusion. Thus, by his use of the conception of phenomenon, Kant contradicts his own principle that real things are unknowable. Before proceeding to mention the third theory of knowledge which is due to Lotze and is adopted by Ritschl,^ we must offer a few remarks on his criticisms of the two forms of epistemology which he rejects. In the first place it is hardly fair to credit ^If we can take Ritschl's own word for it: but all are agreed, both friend and foe, that despite slight modifications of phraseology, he remained a Kantian to the end. THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 71 Plato with a theory of knowledge. Plato's object was to discover not the necessary factors of human knowledge but the ultimate nature of reality. His intention therefore was not epistemological but meta- physical; and his method was logical and deductive rather than analytical and descriptive. He ought therefore to have been contrasted rather than com- pared with Kant ; and contrasted rather in method and intention than in result. Moreover it is astonishing to be told that the naive realism and empiricism of ordinary thought should be identified with Platonic idealism. But when we come to the criticism of the Kantian theory our astonishment is increased. For it passes understanding to conceive how the unknow- ability of the things can be justified, if the limitation of knowledge to phenomena, which this theory ob- viously necessitates, is to be condemned. The diffi- culties with which we are thus confronted at the very outset of our examination of the Ritschlian position (when moreover he is simply attempting to describe the standpoint of others, and not elaborating a meta- physical theory of his own) afford a sure indication that Ritschl's strength does not lie in philosophical enquiry but in systematic theology — a conclusion for which our further investigations will be found to afford the completest justification. Having thus dismissed the Platonic and Kantian theories, Ritschl declares his adhesion to that propounded by Lotze. He holds that "in the pheno- mena which in a limited space exhibit change to a limited extent and in a determinate order we cognize the thing as the cause of its qualities opera- ting upon us, as the end which these serve as means, 72 RITSCHLIANISM and as the law of their constant changes." This theory Ritschl accepts as his own, referring the reader for a further treatment of the subject to his Httle book on Theology and Metaphysics^ where in trenchant, controversial and, it must be admitted, confused style he elaborates his theory of know- ledge. Having as it were appealed unto Caesar, to Caesar shall he go, and we with him. But before our departure, we must insist that Ritschl's theory — we know the thing in its appearances — by which he supposes the problem of knowledge to be solved, seems hardly to be aware of the existence of such a problem at all. It seems intensely simple and illuminating to assert that we know the thing in its appearances ; so simple, that, as Pfleiderer says with justice, we naturally wonder why it should never have occurred to such talented people as Plato and Kant ! ^ The formula entirely ignores the real difficulty, whence do the phenomena originate? Wherein do appearances consist ? Are they ex- ternal to ourselves, or merely subjective represen- tations of our own consciousness ? The latter seems the only conceivable alternative on this theory, but what then is the relation of the appearance to the thing ? How in the face of repeated contradiction are we to reconcile knowing and being, reality and appearance ? The theories - of Lotze, as we have seen, carry us far beyond the non-intelligent formula which Ritschl employs : but it is precisely such metaphysical theories as those of Lotze that Ritschl either abjures or ignores. We ought also in this ^ Pfleiderer, Die Ritschhche Theologie^ 2. THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 71 connection to remember how very strongly Lotze himself condemned all epistemological enquiries, as affording any adequate basis for religious or theo- logical construction. Wherefore Ritschl's claim in reference to the Lotzean epistemology must be accepted with many reservations. We are now ready to accompany Ritschl, and to undertake the examination of his Theology and Metaphysics^ by the study of which our ideas as to the real significance of his theory may receive considerable enlightenment. Here we find a repe- tition of the statement that the distinction commonly drawn between the thing as it is for us, and the thing as it is for itself, lacks real foundation, but originates in a memory-picture which represents something constant and invariable behind the im- mediate appearance. This unchanging somewhat is however no more than an imaginary or " shadowy " representation of reality. But now we are face to face with the old question, what is reality ? The things in themselves, that is, the things independent of our consciousness, are nought but a deceptive shadow-picture : yet the identification of the real things with the products (for Ritschl's theory forbids us to say objects) of our representing conscious- ness seems incredible. This however seems to be Ritschl's intention. In proof of our assertion we must quote a passage of great importance. " One knows," he says, " a self-sufficient thing first in its qualities. . . . The appearances, which are perceived in a limited space in the same position or succession, and their changes in a definite order and method are combined by our faculty of representation in the 74 RITSCHLIANISM unity of the thing after the analogy of the cognizing soul, which in the change of its corresponding sen- sations feels and remembers itself as a permanent unity. Accordingly the thing which we represent for ourselves is an existence in itself . , . Accord- ingly the isolated thing will be thought as its own cause and its own purpose. Thus considered the thing loses all its peculiar qualities. It is a purely formal conception without all content." ^ Ritschl lays down that a doctrine of things is only formally employed in theology ^ : in the same way he says a few pages previously that the formally correct statement of theological doctrines is dependent on a conscious or unconscious theory of cognition. ^ What Ritschl means (and indeed explicitly states in another passage) is that the laws laid down have no exclusive bearing on religious knowledge, but are applicable to all knowledge as such. In the first volume he speaks of the necessity for theologians of ideas which have originated outside the fact of Christianity, and which, even though they should be only logical, will yet have a determining influence upon the theological presentation of Christianity. ^ Professor Swing, an ardent champion, would mini- mize the significance of Ritschl's declarations con- cerning the dependence of theology upon a correct theory of knowledge : Ecke, followed to some extent by Garvie, suggests that this theory of cognition is a foreign element in the Ritschlian theology. To this, however, it must be replied that the aban- donment of the Ritschlian theory of knowledge would ^ See additional note at end of chapter, '^K.V. iii. i8. '^Ibid. i6. "^ R.V. i. 571. THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 75 mean an entire transformation of the whole theo- logical system. It is indeed only too clear that it is because of the theology that Ritschl concerns himself with knowledge ; and that the theory of knowledge is intended to prescribe for theology the bounds which it shall not pass. A further quotation from Ritschl's Theology and Metaphysics will throw light both upon the theory and upon his own curious lack of self-consistency. " The idea of a thing originates from the different sensations which in a regular order attach themselves to some- thing which experience fixes in a limited space. An apple we represent as a round, red, sweet thing . . . what we mean is that we know the subject of this proposition only in its predicates. The impression that the thing is a unity in the changes of the qualities springs from our own persistent sense of unity amid the succession of our sensations produced by the thingP ^ The last sentence contains an obvious self- contradiction. The whole passage has made it perfectly plain that the idea of a thing is a purely formal conception, a unity of phenomena, which is due to the activity of our representing consciousness through its experience of simultaneous sensations. The unity of the thing corresponds to the continuity of ourselves who, amid changing surroundings and successive experiences, are conscious of our abiding unity. This is not to be distinguished from subjec- tive idealism — a philosophy in flagrant contradiction with the certain facts of life, and moreover psycholo- gically false. It fails, moreover, to give a satisfactory ir.^. 37. 76 RITSCHLIANISM answer to fundamental questions such as the origin of sensation and the nature of unity- ascribed to things. Stated in whatever form it rarely fails to embody a contradiction.^ But the contradiction is rarely expressed in such paradoxical form as is done by Ritschl in the passage quoted above : for in the last sentence, after carefully explaining the subjective origin of the thing, he adds a few words which can have no other meaning save that the thing is itself the cause or origin of our sensations. How these two conceptions are to be reconciled must remain a mystery, for Ritschl is him- self, to all appearances, sublimely unconscious of his mutually exclusive representations. Yet it is plainly impossible that the same thing should have been conceived both as the product and the cause of our sensation. Pfleiderer is a severe critic : but both Garvie and Orr admit the justice of his criticism at this point. " The whole secret of the Ritschlian method is here exhibited in this perplexing and capricious swaying and skipping between an idealistic and realistic mode of consideration." ^ The claim to represent the epistemological standpoint of Kant and Lotze must be set aside in favour of an extraordinary combination or rather confusion of naive realism and subjective idealism which makes havoc of any attempt to reach the objective realities with which theology must surely be concerned. For as we have already intimated, this theory of knowledge stands in closest connection with Ritschl's presentation of theology, since it enables him at one and the same time to confine our attention to things as they are ^Cf. Taylor, Ele7nents of Metaphysics^ 7S-79. ^pflej^erer, op. cit. 5. THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE ']^ for us, and yet to claim for them some kind of objective reality. In his Theology and Metaphysics he lays down and elaborates the epistemological principles by means of which he proposes to establish his theological positions. Let us briefly glance at the effects of this theory on the three theological conceptions of God, Christ, and the Soul. (i) " If God is to be reckoned among objects of knowledge for scientific theology, then every claim that we can learn anything of God in Himself^ apart from what may be known for us through the revela- tion which was given indeed by Him (we know not how) but made manifest in our sensations and our perceptions, every such claim must be pronounced unfounded. This claim is yet advanced by Frank who would have us regard God as the Absolute, and by Luthardt who distinguishes the nature and attri- butes of God in Hiviself as prior to the attributes as manifested in activities /i?;- ^/.y." ^ This Ritschl holds to be the source of all the false metaphysic which is generally characteristic of popular thought, and yet has no claim to represent scientific truth in spite of its constant appearance in Christian dogmatics. Now Ritschl is pushing at an open door when he contends that no knowledge or doctrine of God is possible without our having felt and perceived a revelation from Himself The real question is whether on the basis of that revelation we are entitled to draw further conclusions as to the nature and character of that activity, that cause in which the revelation itself originated : in other words, why 1 T.M. 34. 7^ RITSCHLIANISM should we not from the character of the revelation proceed to certain inferences as to the character of the Revealer ? When, further, it is taken into account that the revelation is itself largely concerned with the nature and character of God, it becomes impossible to see why such enquiries should be regarded either as unscientific or unchristian. The rejection of all speculative effort to under- stand what God is in Himself and for Himself, and the limitation of all our knowledge of the Divine to what God is for us, seem to lead straight to an atheistic view of the world. This danger has been vividly recognized even by disciples, and is all the more pressing because Ritschl was inclined to apply the Feuerbachian theory to all non-Christian re- ligions. To make a solitary exception in the case of Christianity, to which alone a supernaturalistic theory of Revelation is held applicable, must be pronounced an exceedingly hazardous experiment.^ But the insistence that we can only know things in their appearances, renders the conclusion inevit- able that God can only be known in His historical manifestations. The Being of God can logically have no significance save as a general expression for the moral government of the world : and God is lost in His attributes. The Deity is merely a personifica- tion of the Divine in which all human beings share. This conclusion is energetically repudiated by Ritschl, who holds strongly to the doctrine of the Personality of God.^ Ritschl moreover speaks of a self-end of God into which the world-end is merged. But such conceptions are wholly incompatible with 1 Troeltsch, Zeitschrift, 95, p. 375. '^ R. V, ii. 215-227. THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 79 the language previously employed. There Ritschl states that it is impossible to know God in any other way, save in so far as He exists for us. But Pfleiderer is surely right in his contention that *' personality is a being for self which apprehends itself as such, and distinguishes itself from others, which is not lost in the manifoldness of its modes of activity and expression, but abides as a constant unity, with itself and in itself" ^ In the same way the idea of a self-end of God (which is prominent in Ritschlian theology) certainly implies a being for self which is not exhausted in a being for others. Ritschl is not true to his own premises; his strong insistence on the personality of God is not to be reconciled with the philosophical principles on which his theory of knowledge is based : it is preserved because in some strange way what is denied to philosophy, he allows to theology. Such then is the theory of God that is given by this theory of knowledge. We shall, of course, have to deal with his doctrines at greater length at a later stage : here we are merely illustrating how funda- mental is this theory of knowledge to the correct presentation of theology as conceived by Ritschl. We must now touch upon this theory as it affects the doctrine of Christ, and the doctrine of the Soul. (ii) Ritschl, as we shall see later, professes to derive all his theology from the historical Person of Jesus Christ. That is an unexceptionable position for Christian theology. But Ritschl uses it as a pretext for refusing to take any account of those questions ^ Pfleiderer, op. cit. 8. 8o RITSCHLTANISM as to the transcendental element in Christ's person, which are forced upon us by an impartial examina- tion of the history. " What think ye of Christ ? Whose son is he ? " are questions which cannot be evaded, if we are aiming at a historical interpretation of the Redeemer's life and work. The Ritschlian theory of knowledge, on the other hand, lays down the impossibility of knowing any character or person- ality save through such words and works as are manifestations of spiritual activity.^ This again all would admit : but the meaning which the author gave to these words is very different from that of orthodox Christianity. We, like him, would start with the historical acts as manifesting character ; but unlike him we would not remain in them, but start from them. It would be hopeless to reconstruct for ourselves a conception of a personality by merely piecing together the fragmentary notices of his historical activities : it would be monstrous to sup- pose that in such occasional indications a character was contained, rather than expressed. The Ritsch- lian theory professes to follow a historical method which would make all true history impossible ; for it would be reduced to a barren enumeration of names and dates. The theory is intended to exclude all discussions as to the nature of Christ's Person ; but logically applied it would exclude everything that would make the outward words and works intel- ligible. For by assuming that the entire personality was confined to recorded actions, it would forbid all consideration of possible motives, all tracing of pur- poses, all thought of feeling — in fact everything most 1 T.M. 30. THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 8i necessary for any true delineation of character. That any history thus constructed, should be accepted as other than provisional, we do not for a moment contend ; but that any representation of a personality, drawn from historical actions, without any consideration of the motives underlying those actions, should be considered adequate, is wholly inconceivable. But the Ritschlian theology does not aim at logical consistency, it aims rather at sweeping metaphysics from theology. So in order to preclude the discus- sion even of Christ's pre-existence, or the union of Divine natures, we are told that " the Godhead of Christ must be apprehended in the definite traits of his historical life as an attribute of his temporal existence." ^ Everything else would be rendered meaningless by the theory of knowledge which sees the reality of the thing only in its activities and attributes. (iii) What then of the Soul? RitschFs language is unambiguous. " We know nothing of the soul exist- ing in and for itself, nothing of a self-enclosed life of the spirit above or behind those functions in which it is active, living, and present to itself as a being of special worth." ^ So the One is dethroned, and the Many reign : the One becomes appearance, and the Many reality. Yet Ritschl appeals constantly to the consciousness of self-identity amid change : and it is from the knowledge of our own permanent unity according to his theory that we ascribe unity to things around us. But how this consciousness of self-identity, and this knowledge of permanent unity can either originate or survive, in a hypothesis which i^.K iii. 383. -'R.v. iii. 21. 82 RITSCHLIANISM makes the manifold functions the only reaHty, and explicitly denies the existence of an underlying, all- comprehending unity, must remain a mystery. We are invited to hold a theory of the soul without a soul at all. As for the immortality of the soul, it is impossible to imagine on this hypothesis how the soul could survive the suspension of those functions conditioned by its attachment to a bodily frame, unless it has a permanent unity, a real existence in and for itself. Nothing would be a greater mistake than to ima- gine that this extravagant theory of knowledge could without loss be removed from the Ritschlian theo- logy : for it is upon the foundation of this theory of knowledge that the entire theological system reposes. Ritschl is careful to tell us so himself. " Theology," he declares, " has nothing to do with the natural order, but only with the conditions and activities of the spiritual life of man. Hence the use of psychology is necessary. In this connection we are confronted with a collision between two concep- tions corresponding to the first and third theories of knowledge. The first gives rise to the assumption of scholastic psychology that behind its special activi- ties of feeling, thinking, and willing, the soul itself remains at rest in its self-equivalence as the unity of the corresponding powers, the spiritual faculties." ^ This theory he criticises and rejects, he then, in harmony with that theory of knowledge which he has adopted, propounds his own idea of the nature of the soul. What it is, we have seen : whither it will lead us, we see, also, too clearly. ^ iV, V. ii. 20 (free and slightly compressed translation). THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE 83 We thus arrive, by means of this conception of knowledge, at a theology where, to quote the words of Dr. Garvie ("sympathetic" as ever, if yet critical for the nonce): " God is, so to speak, lost in His kingdom, Christ in His vocation, the Soul in its activities." ^ It really seems incredible that this result represents Ritschl's intentions. Many indications including per- petual inconsistencies seem to point in an opposite direction, and perhaps we may conjecture with a penetrating critic "that Ritschl did not make this theory of knowledge the basis of his theology from the first, but propounded it subsequently in its defence." ^ Additional Note. We quote the passage in its full context : "Accordingly the isolated thing loses all its peculiar qualities. 7/ zs a purely formal conception without all content. So in>.ignificant is the conception of the Absolute proclaimed by Frank with so much stress as God ! " No slight stir has been raised concerning the sentence italicized. StahUn seized upon it as a convincing proof of the subjective idealism which underlay the entire Ritschlian theology. Favre follows suit, and declares that Ritschl must be counted as one of the extreme subjectivists. Pfleiderer is equally decisive, and Professor Orr describes "the whole process as subjective, hypothetical, imaginative and never leading beyond phenomena '' ; and interprets this particular passage as a description of the thing only as " a mental fiction." Wherefore it needed considerable courage for Dr. Garvie to maintain that all these scholars were labouring under an entire misapprehension: that the passage ^Garvie, p. 62. ^Pfleiderer, Development of Theology, 183. 84 RITSCHLIANISM was intended as Ritschl's repudiation of Frank's views, rather than a declaration of his own. Now it may be admitted that the argument seems intended to prove the worthlessness of the conception of the Absolute in theology, particularly as the term is employed by Frank. In this argument is included the analysis of our formation of the conception of the thing, showing that it is nothing but a conception divested of all content ; and this con- clusion naturally discredits still further the metaphysical position adopted by Frank. From this "sympathetic scrutiny of the passage " Dr. Garvie concludes that the words do not refer to the view of the thing that Ritschl holds as his- own, but to the perversion of that view of which he thinks Frank is guilty. That certainly is an extremely sympathetic interpretation : it is ingenious also. But is it correct? It seems unlikely in the highest degree. (i) Ritschl refers to this passage later : and there he identifies himself with the present argument. "The impression that the perceived thing in the changes of its qualities is one, arises as has been remarked above (p, 19) from the persistence of the feeling of self in the succession of our sensations excited by the thing. Further, the conception of the thing as cause and purpose of itself arises from the certainty that I am cause and I am purpose in the activities which I initiate."^ Now it was directly in connection with the thing conceived "as its own cause and as. its own purpose' that Ritschl declared that this idea amounted to "a purely formal conception without any content." As, moreover, in the later passage he proceeds to appeal to Lotze in favour of his view, there seems to be no reasonable doubt that he is here stating his own conclusions. (ii) Conclusions perhaps ; but not his own. This, how- 1 T,M. 38. THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE -85 ever, cannot be maintained : he gives an account of how the conception of a thing is formed, and shows that from his point of view, it must lead to an impossible abstraction. •How then does the conclusion discredit Frank's rather than his own views ? The answer is simple. Ritschl will not suffer metaphysical questions to intrude into the domain of theology : Frank, on the other hand, sets out with the avowed intention of effecting a reconciliation between the speculative reason and theological dogma. Ritschl pro- ceeds to show the logical conclusion which must inevitably (as he thinks) follow from such a proceeding. Psycho- logically, Ritschl's statements are not to be justified : logically, arguing from his own premises, they are undoubtedly correct. He is unable to conceive of a thing save as a formal conception without content, and this is an idea which he thinks reduces all metaphysical theology to absurdity. (iii) Dr. Garvie, contending that Ritschl has been grievously misunderstood and misjudged, quotes a passage from another work which he thinks might have been expressly written to guard against such misconceptions. " For the doctrine of the thing it is assumed that our mind is not of itself the cause of sensations, perceptions, etc., but that these distinctive activities of the soul are excited in coexistence with things to which even the human body also belongs."^ The meaning is perhaps not so clear as Dr. Garvie seems to think, but even if it were, the passage would prove nothing save Ritschl's inconsistency in all such matters, an inconsistency which even his stoutest defenders (such as Traub and O. Ritschl) are constrained to admit. The quotation, however, suggests another. Mention is made ^ R, V. iii. 18. — A work in which the doctrine of things is plainly at variance with the more subjective philosophy of Theology and Meta- physics. 86 RITSCHLIANISM of "the distinctive activities of the soul." We shall have occasion to speak further of RitschFs doctrine of the soul, but it will at present suffice to quote Dr. Garvie's own estimate of Ritschl's teaching on this point. " In his denial of the metaphysical existence of the soul, and his restriction of personal life to spiritual activities, he im- plicitly contradicts the unity and identity of the ' self,' the possibility of character, the certainty of immortality." ^ This will help us to gauge the value of the analogy Ritschl draws from the identity of the soul to the unity and reality of the thing. ^ Garvie, op, cit. 225. CHAPTER V THE JUDGMENTS OF VALUE I The suggestion that the Ritschlian theory of know- ledge was in a manner a happy afterthought to cover the deficiencies of the Ritschlian theology, derives a considerable measure of probability from the fact that the theory of value-judgments was only expounded in the second edition of Ritschl's great work on Justi- fication and Atonement, though it has since been elaborated with remarkable modifications by different members of the school. It will have been clear that the epistemology we have been considering cannot afford any certainty for religious knowledge. Ritschl therefore boldly declares religious knowledge to be exempt from the inexorable laws governing all other knowledge, insist- ing that between theoretical and religious knowledge there is a difference profound and fundamental. In his first edition Ritschl distinguished sharply between religion on the one hand, and philosophy and science on the other. The former, starting with the conception of the unity of God, naturally viewed the world also as a unity, as a whole in which the 8S RITSCHLIANISM Divine life was manifested, or the Divine will was operative. This conception of the world as a whole is plainly not a fact of experience : wherever it appears, it is due to the religious representation. Science and philosophy have indeed neither material nor method for arriving at such a conception. They deal with general laws of knowledge and existence : their function can only be to observe and explain the world in its parts : a unified view of the world can be given by religion alone. The claim of philosophy to find the highest law of being must inevitably bring about a collision with religion. But in truth this is no part of the task of theoretic knowledge. Where philosophy aims at rising to a systematic unity, we can immediately detect a religious impulse. Even in materialism, with its strivings after unity, a blind confused religious impulse is at work. Thus collision between religious and theoretic knowledge becomes an absolute impossibility, so rapidly and entirely are the two spheres kept apart. It is plain that this theory, whatever RitschFs intention, can bring about no truce between religion and philosophy. The latter may indeed in the middle ages have surrendered its claim to look for a whole in things: but the entire history of philosoph}- is a history of its emancipation from ecclesiastical control, and of its determination to solve for itself the problems of ultimate reality. In other words, philosophy does seek for unity, and does aim at comprehending the universe under one supreme law. We must also notice the obvious inapplicability of this theory to polytheistic religions which cannot b}- any stretch of imagination be said to come to a THE JUDGMENTS OF VALUE Sg unified view of the world through the idea of the unity of God. In later editions Ritschl considerably modifies his earlier view. We are indeed invited to adopt an en- tirely new theory as to the relation between theoretic and religious knowledge. It will no longer allow us to rest content with the pleasing delusion that Chris- tian knowledge comprehends the world as a whole, while philosophy fixes the special and universal laws of nature and spirit. For with this task every philo- sophy likewise combines the ambition " to compre- hend the universe under one supreme law. . . . Even the thought of God, which belongs to religion, is employed in some shape or other by every non- materialistic philosophy." ^ The two spheres of knowledge can, therefore, no longer be kept utterly and entirely separate. Where, then, is the principle of discrimination to be found? As the distinction is not to be sought in the object of knowledge, we must seek it in the subject. Herrmann, to whom the actual introduction of the term value-judgments is due, is a strong supporter of the principle of discrimination which Ritschl here adopts. The new theology, cham- pioned by De Wette, had grasped the symbolical character of theological representations, and was thus led not merely to a historical re-examination and re- construction of early Christian history, but also into a psychological investigation into the functions of the human spirit. The progress in this latter direction has been so rapid that psychological science has assumed far different proportions from those of its 1 i?. V. iii. 90 RITSCHLIANISM initial stages; and the merely descriptive type of theology has been discredited as insufficient. Reli- gion was obliged to listen to the most gloomy and confident predictions of her own overthrow, if Christianity should prove unable to the task of exhibiting the entire world-view in a systematic connection. We can understand how anxiously the theologians sought for allies among eminent scientists and philosophers who, discontented with the dis- connected results of empirical investigation, sought in religion the idea of unity which science and philosophy were alike powerless to bestow. But the hopes to which such an alliance naturally gave rise were more than counterbalanced by the extreme reluctance to make the most cherished truths of religion dependent on the successful issue of so pre- carious and far-reaching a venture. At any rate Herrmann feels justified in insisting upon a searching investigation as to the real place of metaphysics in theology. He begins with the obvious. By way of enlisting the sympathy of his readers, he introduces Melancthon as drawing a distinction between the imperfect idea of God given by reason and that mediated through the Church; and declares, though he leaves it uncertain whether he expresses the views of Melancthon or his own, that this latter idea of God is a matter not for metaphysics, but for ecclesias- tical doctrine. He then proceeds to establish another obvious conclusion — namely, that the idea of God, if given at all in metaphysics, must have a totally different significance to that which it bears in theology. At last we come to the point. Religious ideas are THE JUDGMENTS OF VALUE 91 fitted to solve the riddle of the universe: but what relation do these conceptions bear to theoretic know- ledge? The methods of modern science, resolving all qualities into mathematical relations, have given to man a dominion over nature. The feeling of exaltation thus inspired has inevitably led man to forget that the real discovery of modern science is the hypothesis of mechanical necessity, a theory which yet teems with countless contradictions, when applied to other spheres than that of natural science. Yet this view of mechanical necessity seems to be the practical postulate upon which all the experimental sciences are obliged to proceed, if they are either to progress or to succeed. No theory, however, could be more utterly out of harmony with the religious view of the world. If, then, scientific and religious knowledge are opposed, there is equal opposition between meta- physics and theology: for in the former we seek after universally valid forms in which all being and happen- ing may be combined without contradiction. For the correctness of these representations no account whatever need be taken as to the relation in which the things stand to our aims and wills, our weal or woe. This, on the contrary, is exactly that on which, in a religious view of the world, all depends, while the metaphysical problems we have mentioned are in such a connection a matter of entire indifference. We have thus arrived at a stage where it becomes necessary to admit that religious knowledge is independent, on the one hand, of those mechanical formulas with which the empirical sciences seek to achieve their practical purpose of controlling natural 92 RITSCHLIANISM forces, and, on the other, of these metaphysical formulas by means of which philosophy seeks to penetrate beneath appearance to ultimate reality, and to resolve the contradictions of the world into a unified and systematic view of the universe. To such matters the Christian may be indifferent, as far as his religion is concerned. For Christianity is concerned with an ethical aim, and has a sufficient assurance in the certainties of religious experience. The Christian is content to know that God helps ; he does not seek to enquire how the help is given. There is an irreducible difference between the feel- ing of the value of goodness, and the knowledge of facts. Every religious view of the world is an answer to the question, how must the world be judged if the highest good is to become real ? Any attempt to reconcile religious with theoretic knowledge involves only a fxeTa^a