Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924086360587 CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY 3 1924 086 360 587 In compliance with current copyright law, Cornell University Library produced this replacement volume on paper that meets the ANSI Standard Z39.48-1992 to replace the irreparably deteriorated original. 1999 CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY FROM Tlie ^a^e School of pbiloscphy A HISTORY OF ESTHETIC HISTORY OF ESTHETIC BY BERNARD BOSANQUET, M.A. (Oxon.) Hon. LL.D. (Glasgow) Ftnnerly FtHmi of VnaienUy College, Oxford LONDON : SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO. LIM. NEW YORK: THE MACMILLAN CO. 1904 First Edition, May, 1892. Skcond Edition, April, 1904. Butler &» Tanner The Selviood Priming M^orkt Frmite and Londm PREFACE. ^Esthetic theory is a branch of philosophy, and exists for the sake of knowledge and not as a guide to practice. The present work is, therefore, primarily addressed to those who may find a philosophical interest in understanding the place and value of beauty in the system of human life, as conceived by leading thinkers in different periods of the world's history. It is important to insist that the aesthetic philosopher does not commit the impertinence of invading the artist's domain with an apparatus belli of critical principles and precepts. The opinion that this is so draws upon aesthetic much obloquy, which would be fully deserved if the opinion were true. Art, we are told, is useless ; in a kindred sense aesthetic may well submit to be useless also. The aesthetic theorist, in short, desires to understand the artist, not in order to interfere with the latter, but in order to satisfy an intellectual interest of his own. But besides professed students of philosophy, there is a large and increasing public of readers who are genuinely attracted by a fairly clear and connected exposition of any philosophical science the subject- matter of which comes home to them, be it Logic or Ethic, Sociology, or the theory of Jleligion. Such readers are approaching philosophy through the subject-matter that already interests them, instead of approaching the particular subject-matter simply because it is an integral part of philosophy. I confess to cherishing a hope that in spite of the defects which deprive this book of the charm that a more skilful writer might have given to such a subject, many intelligent lovers of beauty will be glad to make acquaintance, through it, with the thoughts of great men upon this important element of the spiritual world. I have regarded my task, however, as the history of aesthetic, and not as the history of aestheticians. I have not paid much attention to the claims of historical justice. While I feel sure that no writer of the first rank is omitted, I could not venture to say that all the Xll PREFACE. writers included are more important than any that are excluded. I have thought first of the arrangement necessary or convenient in order to exhibit the affiliation of ideas, and their completest forms, and only in the second place of the individual rank and merit of the writers to be dealt with. Moreover, as the first chapter will show, I have not been able to persuade myself to treat my subject as a mere account of speculative theory. No branch of the history of philosophy can be adequately treated in this way, and the history of aesthetic least of alL My aim has therefore been to exhibit philosophic opinion as only the clear and crystallized form of the aesthetic consciousness or sense of beauty, which is itself determined by conditions that lie deep in the life of successive ages. I have desired, in fact, so far as possible, to write the history of the aesthetic consciousness. Many readers may complain of the almost total absence of direct reference to Oriental art, whether in the ancient world or in modern China and Japan. For this omission there were several connected reasons. I was hardly called upon, even if I had been competent for the task, to deal with an aesthetic consciousness which had not, to my knowledge, reached the point of being clarified into speculative theory. It was, moreover, necessary to limit my subject in some definite way; and it seemed natural to exclude everything that did not bear on the continuous development of the European art-con- sciousness. In so far as contact with Oriental art influenced the early Greek, and again the Byzantine development, a reference to it is im- plied in Hegel's and Morris' treatment of those periods. And finally, this omission is not without a positive ground, though here I really touch on a matter which is beyond my competence. The separation from the life of the progressive races, and the absence of a reflective theory of beauty, must surely have a fundamental connection with the non -architectural character pointed out by Mr. Morris in the art of China and Japan (p, 456). Without denying its beauty, therefore, I regarded it as something apart, and not well capable of being brought into the same connected story with the European feeling for the beautiful. A study of such art from a competent hand, in the light of aesthetic theory, would be a welcome aid to modern speculation. With reference to my use of authorities, while there is often more egotism than modesty in calling the public to witness the course of an author's reading, I feel absolutely bound in this case to warn my readers that the reliability of the different parts of my work is unequal. For the mediaeval period between Plotinus and Dante, and in a lesser PREFACE. Xin degree for the Hellenistic period between Aristotle and Plotinus, my knowledge is not, for the most part, at first hand, and represents a voyage of discovery rather than a journey on ground familiar to me. I have not for these periods been able to follow the scholar's golden rule — never to quote from a book that he has not read jfrom cover to cover. 1 have drawn my quotations from works of reference, and though I iiave, as a rule, carefully verified them and endeavoured to judge of the context, my estimate of the writer's position usually rests on the authority, in many cases Erdmann's History of Philosophy and the articles in the Encydopcedia Britannica, which I have consulted for information. In the case of Thomas Aquinas in particular, I pro- fess no original knowledge at all. The very full quotations most courteously furnished me by Dr. Gildea appeared too significant to be left unused, and his authority warranted me in supposing that in these passages the principal materials for forming a judgment were before me. I do not desire it to be understood that he agrees with me in the estimate which I have formed of St. Thomas's aesthetic views. It would have been foolish, I thought, to omit the more obvious points of the mediseval development, both in art and in opinion, the mere mention of which might be suggestive to my readers, simply because I had to take them from such writers as Prof. Adamson, Prof. Seth, Prof. Middleton, Mr. Morris and Mr. Pater, and not from original research. Some division of labour must be allowed, though the fact that it has been resorted to should always be made known. Acknowledgments for assistance are due from me above all to Prof. A. C. Bradley, who not only furnished me with a list of books which has been of the utmost service, but lent me out of his own library many of those works, which I might otherwise have had a difficulty in procuring. I also owe the most cordial thanks to Mr. J. D. Rogers, for permitting me to embody in an Appendix his analyses of some instances of musical expression — models, as I think, of what such analyses should be— and to Dr. Gildea, for the information mentioned above. And, finally, it is only right to say, that it is on the Council of the Home Arts and Industries Associa- tion, and in contact with its workers, that I have learned to appre- ciate, as I hope, with some degree of justice the writings of Mr. Ruskin and Mr. Morris, which may easily remain a sealed book to those who have not observed in simple cases the relation of work- manship to life. Many readers, who are familiar with the average XIV PREFACE. work of the classes of that Association, may think that it reveals no great mystery of beauty ; but I am convinced that the leaders of the Association have sound insight, and that experience, to an in- creasing extent, is justifying their principles. London, April, 1892. PREFACE TO SECOND EDITION. My chief duty in preparing a second edition of this work has been to remove so far as possible, by corrections in the form of notes, the defects which arose from its being published previously to Professor Butcher's Treatise on Aristotl^s Theory of Poetry and Fine Art. I have made no pretence of re-writing, as it was impossible for me seriously to attempt the task. I have therefore let the text stand, except in case of obvious misprints, and have admitted errors or made observations on criticisms in notes appended to the chapters which they concern. These notes are indicated by letters of the alphabet, and will, I hope, be readily distinguished from the footnotes indicated by numbers. On meeting with a reference " a," the reader has only to turn to the last page of the chapter before him, where he will find the note referred to. I do not think that my general view of the relation between ancient and modern .(Esthetic is seriously modified by Professor Butcher's treatment of Aristotle, while my aesthetic theory on the whole is corroborated by it. As a worshipper of the Greeks, I am only too glad to follow him towards ascribing on the whole a deeper suggestiveness to their views than I had previously permitted myself to find there. In my anxiety not to go too far, I may hardly have gone far enough. At any rate, I wish to say that my references to his work cannot possibly discharge a reader who cares for the subject from the duty and pleasure of studying it for himself. I have not attempted to modify my interpretation of Aristotle's definition of Tragedy, which is simply that of Bernays. Professor Butcher has developed a modification of this view, which the student should learn from Professor Butcher's work. I hope that the fact of a second edition of a work like this being called for may indicate that with all its defects it has a point of view which is felt to be valuable. And I hope that this point of view may soon come to be more effectively presented by more capable critics and more attractive writers than the author. St. Andrews, March 1904. TABLE OF CONTENTS Preface ...... xi CHAPTER I. PAGE Proposed treatment, and its connection with the definition OF Beauty. 1. The History of .Esthetic, and the History of Fine Art . . i 2. The relation of Natural Beauty to the Beauty of Fine Art . 3 3. The definition of Beauty, and its relation to the History of .^Esthetic 4 CHAPTER 11. The creation of a poetic world, and its first encounter with reflection. 1. Early Reflection hostile to Art 10 2. Creation of the World of Beauty 10 3. Reason for the Attitude of Reflection 11 4. Neglected Suggestion in the Idea of Imitation . . . .12 5. Wide use of term " Imitation " in Ancient Philosophy . 13 6. Further Explanation how Greek Art could be called " Imitative " 13 i. Facility of Imitative Art makes it Ideal . . 13 ii, Hellenic Art not so Abstractly Ideal as has been thought . 13 7. The Ground prepared for .Esthetic Theory . . . .15 CHAPTER III. The fundamental outlines of Greek theory concerning the beautiful. The Principles and their Connexion 16 I. The Moralistic Principle 17 a. How it shows itself 18 p. Its ^Esthetic Value 21 aiv XVI TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE 2. The Metaphysical Principle 23 a. How it shows itself 23 j8. Its Esthetic Value. 28 i. Esthetic Semblance 28 ii. Semblance inadequate to Reality 29 3. The Esthetic Principle 30 a. General statements in Ancient Writers 32 p. Particular cases .... 34 i. Colour and Tone . ■ 34 ii. Elementary Geometrical Forms 35 iii. Simple Song-music . • 36 iv. Ethical and Logical Wholes 36 V. The Lesser Arts and Formative Art - 38 vi. Poetry and the Drama 39 4. Illustration from Fechner, and Conclusion . 40 CHAPTER IV. Signs of progress in Greek theory concerning the beautiful. 1. The three Antitheses 43 2. The Pre-Socratics .... • 43 3- -SpjQiates . ... 44 a. " Can the Invisible be imitated? " 44 p. .(Esthetic and Real Interest . • 45 4- Pjatesoreanism, . 46 0. Symbolism .... 46 p. (omitted). y. Concrete Analysis . . 46 S- ?Mp • 47 a. Symbolism • 47 p. Esthetic Interest . SO y. Concrete Criticisms •J 54 6. jA^jistotl®-. .... 55 a. Symbolism ■ 56 i. Selection of Phenomena. 56 ii. The Ugly 57 iii. Poetry Philosophic 59 iv. Musical Symbolism 60 V. Art corrective of Nature 61 p. .(Esthetic Interest 62 i. Beauty, Virtue, and Pleasure 62 iL Educational Interest 63 TABLE OF CONTENTS. XVU iii. The Function of Tragedy a. Materials from Aristotle . 6. Estimate of his meaning Concrete Criticism . i. History and Elements of Drama ii. Plot and character-drawing CHAPTER V. PAGE 64 64 66 68 68 70 CULTURE TO THE REIGN OF I. Alexandrian and Greco-Roman CONSTANTINE THE GrEAT. Character of the Period 77 General Philosophy and Art 81 a. Philosophy . 81 Poetry . . . . ... 86 i. New and Latin Comedy 86 ii. The Idyll 87 iii. The Anthology 88 /8. 88 93 99 99 100 iv. Roman Poets .... y. Formative Art and Architecture .... Reflective .Esthetic i. Stoic ii. Epicurean . ...... iii. Aristarchus and Zoilus 102 iv. Later Greco-Roman Critics 102 V. Plotinus Ill a. Symbolism . . . . . -113 p. .(Esthetic Interest 114 y. Concrete Criticism 115 CHAPTER VI. Some traces of the continuity of the esthetic consciousness throughout the middle ages. Our Attitude to the Renaissance I. Tendency to extend Renaissance back towards Christian Era i. Bs£j&aEibiaelite..Eauiiing . ii. Thirteenth Century French Literature iii. A belar d ... iv. Architecture and Decoration back to Sixth Century V. Christian Art and Song of the Earliest Centuries vi. Necessity of an Interval of Austerity 120 120 121 122 123 123 126 130 xvin TABLE OF CONTENTS. Intellectual Continuity of Esthetic from Plotinus . i. From Emanation to Evolution ii. Dualism and Love of Nature .... iii. Augustine on " Beauty of Universe " iv. Suppression of Paganism and Increasing Austerity v. Significance of Iconoclasm .... vi. The System of Scotus Erigena vii. Anticipation of End of World in looo a.d. viii. The Modern Mind in St. Francis ix. The .^Esthetic Ideas of St. Thomas Aquinas . PAGE 132 133 133 136 137 139 143 144 146 CHAPTER VII. A COMPARISON OF DaNTE AND SHAKESPEARE IN RESPECT OF SOME FORMAL CHARACTERISTICS. 1. Limits of the subject 2. The Selection of Artistic Form by the two Poets 3. The Kind of Significance aimed at by each 4. The true Relations of the later Renaissance . 151 152 156 162 CHAPTER VIIL The PROBLEM OF MODERN jESTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 1. The Process of Preparation .... 2. The Prolonged Interruption of .^Esthetic . 3. Preparation of the Problem : Descartes to Baumgarten i. The two Tendencies, " Universal " and " Individual " ii. Distinguished from Ancient Philosophy From each other Connexion with Mediaeval Dualism .^Esthetic Ideas in pre-Kantian Philosophy «• ii^fepitz .... b. ^baft§sl3igry . c. ^.pie .... d. Nature of the Advance . e. Baumg^iJeo . 111. V. 166 166 170 170 171 173 174 175 177 177 178 180 182 TABLE OF CONTENTS. XIX CHAPTER IX. The data of modern esthetic philosophy. Limits of the Subject 1. Classical Philology . i. Joseph Scaliger ii. F. A. Wolff . 2. Archaeology . i. Early Discoveries on Italian Soil ii. Early Ti-avels in Greece . iii. Hercnlan«um and Pompeii iv. Greece proper 3. Art-criticism i. Pierre Comeille ii. Fontenelle and Voltaire . iii. The British Writers a. Burke and Lord Kaimes . a. Burke's Purgation Theory 6. The Sublime akin to Ugliness c. Painful Reality not Disagreeable d. Anticipations of Later Ideas p. Hogarth .... y. Reynolds iv. Germans before Lessing . o. Gottsched p. The " Swiss " . V. Lessing .... a. His Conception of Criticism j8. Aim of the Laocoon y. Demarcation of " Painting " and Poetry 8. Lessing's Attitude towards the Problem of Ugl £. A point in which his Classicism was justified C His Theory of the Drama vi. Winckelmann. His Characteristics . a. Feeling for Art as Human Production /3. True sense of a History of Art y. Recognition of Phases in Beauty 8. Conflict between Beauty and Expression vii. Data not utilized by the Critics . viii. Indications of a Transition 188 188 188 189 190 191 192 192 197 197 201 202 203 203 203 204 205 206 209 210 211 214 216 217 220 223 225 229 230 239 240 242 244 248 251 252 XX TABLE OF CONTENTS. CHAPTER X. PAGE Kant — The problem brought to a focus. 1. His Relation to the Problem and the Data . . . • ^SS 2. Place of the Esthetic Problem in his System . . .256 3. Why the Esthetic Judgment is the Answer to the Problem . 261 i. Demarcation of Esthetic Consciousness . . . -265 ii. Positive Essence of Esthetic Consciousness . . . 265 iii. Its Subjectivity . ... 266 4. Conflict of Abstract and Concrete in Kant's Esthetic . . 267 5. Range and Subdivision of .(Esthetic Perception . . .274 '. Theory of Sublime 275 ii. Classification of Arts .279 6. Conclusion 280 The II. CHAPTER XL first steps of a concrete synthesis — Schiller AND Goethe. Schiller . 286 I. Objectivity of Beauty . 288 a. .Esthetic Semblance . 292 b. The Play-impulse . . . . • 294 2. Opposition of " Antique " and " Modern " . 296 3. Schlegel on Schiller ■ 30° 4. Schiller on Schlegel . 301 Goethe . . • 304 I. Gothic Architecture . .... • 305 i. Attitude to the Renaissance Tradition . 306 ii. " Gothic " as a disparaging term . ■ 307 iii. " Characteristic " Art • 309 2. Definitions of Hirt and Meyer ■ 3" 3. Goethe's Analysis of the Excellent in Art . • 312 4. Conclusion • 316 CHAPTER XII. Objective idealism — Schelling and Hegel. I. Schelling ... .... i. Objectivity of Art and Beauty .... ii. Historical Treatment of " Ancient and Modern " iii. The Particular Arts 317 3^9 322 327 TABLE OF CONTENTS. XXI PAGE II. i. Hegel — Dialectic in the Esthetic 334 ii. The Conception of Beauty 33^ o. The Beauty of Nature 337 (i) Beauty of Abstract Form . . -338 (2) Beauty in Unity of Sense-Material . . -339 /?. Beauty of Art ; the Ideal 34° (i) Nature and the Ideal 34° (2) The Ideal in Life and Action . . . -343 (3) Evolution of the Ideal 345 The Symbolic Art-form .... 346 Classical Art-form . . • . 34^ Romantic Art-form 347 (4) Classification of the Arts . . • -349 a. The Double Basis 349 yS. Facts that Support the Double Basis . 350 7. Principle of the Analytic Classification . 352 iii. Four Leading Conceptions Defined . • -355 (i) Ugliness ....-.•• 355 (2) The Sublime 35^ (3) The Tragic 35^ (4) The Comic 3^° IV. Conclusion • S^o CHAPTER XIII. *'Exj\.ct" /esthetic in Germany. 1. Need of Exact .(Esthetic 2. Schopenhauer i. Schopenhauer a kind of post-Kantian ii. His account of the Beautiful, and, its Modifications iii. Criticism of Schopenhauer . . . ■ 3. Herbart • " i. His Formalism and its Consequences ii. His Division of Esthetic Relations . iii. Classification of the Arts iv. Criticism and Estimate 4. Zimmermann ..••••_•• i. The Distinctive Work of Formal .Esthetic ii. Meaning of the "Together" . • • • iii. Elementary and Simple Forms iv. Psychological Meaning of the Theory, and its Value 363 363 363 365 368 368 369 370 371 372 373 374 376 377 380 XXll TABLE OF CONTENTS. 5. Fechner i. Criticism of Previous Inquiries ii. Experiments with Rectangles, etc. iii. Esthetic Laws 6. Stumpf — Scope of his Analysis 7. Conclusion i. How to judge of Formal ^Esthetic ii. Lesson of its History Iii. Inclusion of Exact Esthetic in Idealism PAGE 381 381 382 384 387 388 388 389 391 CHAPTER XIV. The METHODICAt COMPLETION OF OBJECTIVE IDEALISM. 1. Type of the later Objective Idealism . . . • • 393 2. Transition to the later Objective Idealism ' 394 u. Solger 394 p- Reference to Weisse and Vischer ... • 397 y- Rosenkranz .... . 400 i. Ugliness as such 401 ii. Ugliness in art . ' . • 403 iii. The forms of opposition . . 406 3. The later Objective Idealism . • 409 a. Carribre ^ 410 i. The Ugly 411 ii. Division of the Arts 411 iii. Attitude to the Renaissance 412 /8. Schasler .... 414 i. Conceptions indicated by the " History " . 414 ii. Ugliness, and Modifications of the Beautiful . 417 iii. The Classification of the Arts 419 a. The Parallelism 420 i. The Mimic Dance . 422 c. The Material . 423 y- Hartmann .... 424 i. Significance of the History 425 ii. The Degrees of Beauty ; and Ugliness 429 a. The Orders of Formal Beauty . . . . 429 i. Ugliness in Nature .... 429 (. Ugliness in Beauty ? . . . . 431 (i) No Ugliness in Beauty . , . . 432 (2) Real Ugliness 435 iii. The Division of the Arts . 436 TABLE OF CONTENTS. XXUl CHAPTER XV. PAGE Beginnings of a theoretical reunion of content and expres- sion. 1. Philosophical Conditions of Recent English i^isthetic . .441 2. General Influences of the Time 442 a. Antiquities 442 6. Science . 444 c. Romantic Naturalism 445 d. The Democratic Spirit 446 3 Synthesis of Content and Expression 447 i. The Characteristic 448 ii. The Life of the Workman 45 1 iii. The " Lesser Arts " 454 iv. Penetrative Imagination and the Limits of Beauty . .458 V. Classification by Material, Applied to Poetry . . . 460 4. Conclusion .... 462 i. Requirements of ^Sisthetic Science to-day . . . 465 ii. The Future of Art 467 APPENDIX I. Hegel's Abstract of his Esthetic System 47 r APPENDIX II. Some Analyses of Musical Expression, by Mr. J. D. Rogers . 488 Bibliography 495 Index 499 NOTE. In compliance with repeated suggestions it has been decided to issue the present -volume of the Library of Philosophy in a slightly smaller size than that adopted for the preceding volumes. Future editions of the latter and new volumes of the series will be uniform vnth this volume. HISTORY OF ESTHETIC. CHAPTER I. PROPOSED TREATMENT, AND ITS CONNECTION WITH THE DEFINITION OF BEAUTY. ^'tS'Znd I- It was not before the latter half of the eight- tie^HJ^t^ ** eenth century that the term " Esthetic " was adopted with the meaning now recognised, in order to designate the philosophy of the beautiful as a dis- tinct province of theoretical inquiry. But the thing existed before the name ; for reflection upon beauty and upon fine art begins among Hellenic thinkers at least as early as the time of Socrates, if not, in a certain sense, with still earlier philosophers. If, then, "-Esthetic" means the Philosophy of the Beautiful, the History of Esthetic must mean the History of the Philo- sophy of the Beautiful ; and it must accept as its immediate subject-matter the succession of systematic theories by which philosophers have attempted to explain or connect together the facts that relate to beauty. But this is not all. It is found ilecessary in a historical treatment, even of logic or of general philosophy, to bring them into continuous relation with the concrete life that under- lies the formal conceptions which are being passed in review. The speculation of every age issues on the one hand from the formal teaching of the past, but on the other from the actual world as it urges itself upon consciousness in the present. As the history of logic or of general philosophy cannot be wholly dissociated from the history of science or of civilization, so the history of ethical or of aesthetic ideas is necessarily treated in some connection with the history of morals or of fine art. But within this analogy there is a notable distinction. HISTORY OF ESTHETIC. When we read, for example, the history of the Inductive Sciences in connection with the growth of logical theory, we can take little interest in the bygone phases of particular branches of knowledge, except in as far as they help us to understand that development of the human mind which is at the moment the subject of our study. Antiquated chemistry or astronomy have for us an interest of curiosity no greater than that which a pile-dwelling or a flint hatchet has for the anthropological student. The same is true of many other elements of civilization, such as the details of political form or of social custom, the niceties of language, the minutiae of reli- gious dogma. In all these aspects of life, although it is true that to have deciphered the past greatly aids us in under- standing the present, yet on the whole, excepting with a view to scientific research or historical realization, we are accus- tomed to let bygones be bygones. Moral and religious ideas, indeed, such as have been all-powerful in a remote past, gener- ally retain a capacity of arousing our present interest ; so deep is the identity of man's moral nature throughout all its mani- festations. But nothing is in this respect on a level with the greater creations of fine art, including noble literature. They alone have an importance which rather increases than dimi- nishes as the ages go by. And thus when, we attempt the task of tracing the aesthetic consciousness through the stages of its development, we have before us a concrete material not of mere antiquarian interest, but constituting a large propor- tion of what is valued for its own sake in the surroundings of our present life. The History of Fine Art is the history of the actual aesthetic consciousness, as a concrete phenomenon ; aesthetic theory is the philosophic analysis of this conscious- ness, for which the knowledge of its history is an essential condition. The history of aesthetic theory, again, is a narra- tive which traces the aesthetic consciousness in its intellectual form of aesthetic theory, but never forgets that the central matter to be elucidated is the value of beauty for human life, no less as implied in practice than as explicitly recognised in reflection. In spite of the natural repugnance which may be felt against analytic intermeddling with the most beautiful things which we enjoy, it must be counted. an advantage ol this branch of the history of philosophy that it promises us not merely a theoretical interpretation of what is past and gone, but some aid at least in our appreciation of realities PROPOSED TREATMENT. which appear to be the least perishable inheritance that the world possesses. 2. I have assumed in the last section that Fine ^at^'Beauty Art may be accepted, for theoretical purposes, as *of Fii»*Art^ the chief, if not the sole representative of the world of beauty. It is necessary to explain the point of view from which this assumption appears justifiable. All beauty is in perception or imagination. When we dis- tinguish Nature from Art as a province of the beautiful, we do not mean to suggest that things have beauty independently of human perception, as for example in reactions upon one another such as those of gravitation or solidity. We must therefore be taken to include tacitly in our conception of natural beauty some normal or average capacity of aesthetic appreciation. But if so, it is plain that " nature " in this rela- tion differs from " art " principally in degree, both being in the medium of human perception or imagination, but the one •consisting in the transient and ordinary presentation or idea of the average mind, the other in the fixed and heightened intuitions of the genius which can record and interpret. Now in studying any department of physical causation, we should not think it possible to restrict ourselves to consider- ing the so-called facts which daily meet the eye of the un- trained observer. It is from science that we must learn how to perceive ; and it is upon science that we rely, both in our own observations as far as we are qualified observers, and also in the organized and recorded perceptions of others, from which almost the whole of our natural knowledge is practi- cally derived. Nature in the sphere of aesthetic is analogous to the percep- tion of the ordinary observer in matters of physical science. In the first place, it is limited for each percipient to the range of his own eyes and ears as exercised on the external world, for it does not exist in the form of recorded or communicable contents ; and in the second place, it passes into the province of art, not by a sudden transition, but by continuous modifica- tion, as the insight and power of enjoyment to which the beauty of nature is relative are disciplined and intensified by esthetic training and general culture. Therefore, just as in speaking generally of the real world we practically mean the world as known to science, so in speaking generally of the ■beautiful in the world we practically mean the beautiful as 4 HISTORY OF ESTHETIC. revealed by art. In both cases we rely upon the recorded perceptions of those who perceive best, both because they are the best perceptions and because they are recorded. This habit does not exclude the necessity of interpreting, appre- ciating, and, so far as may be, correcting the recorded perceptions by help of our own. Nor does the beauty of art, thus understood, exclude the beauty of nature. The fact that a completed " work of art" is a definite thing or action, which in some cases does not even represent any natural object, must indeed be duly considered, and the creative spirit must be recognised as a factor in artistic production. Nevertheless, it is a blunder to imagine that there is no art where there is no " work of art," or that whenever the painter is not at work on a picture he sees the same nature as we see and no more. For this reason it is justifiable in theory, as it is necessary in practice, to accept fine art as the main representative of the beautiful for the purpose of philosophical study. Even such an analysis of natural beauty in the light of physical fact as has been attempted by Ruskin in the Modern Painters is chiefly directed to showing how great artists have extended the boundaries of so-called natural beauty, by their superior insight into the expressive capabilities of natural scenes and objects. The standard by which the critic measures the achievement of the artist, when he says that he is measuring it by nature, is of course in the last resort his own artistic feeling and more or less trained perception. Nature for aesthetic theory means that province of beauty in which every man is his own artist. THe Definition of 3* There is no definition of beauty that can be Beauty and said to have met with universal acceptance. It its BeuLtion to ■* . , \ the History of appears, however, to be convenient that an ex- ^tietic. planation should now be given of the sense in which the term will be employed in the present work. And if in such an explanation the fundamental theory of the ancients can be presented as the foundation for the most pregnant conception of the moderns, the resulting definition will at least lend itself readily to the purposes of a history of cEsthetic. Among the ancients the fundamental theory of the beauti- ful was connected with the notions of rhythm, symmetry, harmony of parts ; in short, with the general formula of unity in variety. Among the moderns we find that more emphasis DEFINITION OF Bi^AU TY. is laid on the idea of significance, expressiveness, the utter- ance of all that life contains ; in general, that is to say, on the conception of the characteristic. If these two elements are reduced to a common denomination, there suggests itself as a comprehensive definition of the beautiful, " That which has characteristic or individual expressiveness for sense-perception or imagination, subject to the conditions of general or abstract expressiveness in the same medium." The quality which is thus defined is of wider range than the predicate " beautiful " as commonly understood. It will be for the subsequent historical treatment to show that neither fine art nor average aesthetic perception can in the long run be confined within narrower limits than these. A few words may be added here by way of anticipatory ex- planation. The commonplace view is not wholly at fault which sees in the great art of the ancient Hellenes chiefly the qualities of harmony, regularity, and repose. Although the whole theory of modern aesthetic may well find application and support in the real variety and significance of Hellenic decoration, sculp- ture, and poetry, yet, as science begins with what is most obvious, it is not surprising that aesthetic reflection should have called attention in the first instance to their pervading harmony and regularity. Qualities of this type, because they symbolize, in a mode that appeals to sense-perception, the most abstract relations of systematic and orderly action or existence, may fairly be set down under the head of general or abstract expressiveness. The recognition of these relations as con- stituent elements of the beautiful was the main contribution of ancient philosophy to aesthetic analysis. But when with the birth of the modern world the romantic sense of beauty was awakened, accompanied by the craving for free and passionate expression, it became impossible that impartial theory should continue to consider that the beautiful was adequately explained as the regular and harmonious, or as the simple expression of unity in variety. The theory of the sublime now makes its appearance, at first indeed outside the theory of the beautiful ; but it is followed by the analysis of the ugly, which develops into a recognised branch of aesthetic inquiry, with the result of finally establishing both the ugly and the sublime within the general frontier of beauty. The instrument by which this conciliation is effected is the HISTORY OF ESTHETIC. conception of the characteristic or the significant ; and the conflict between the harsher elements thus recognised and the common-sense requirement that all beauty should give pleasure, is mitigated, on the one hand by a de facto en- largement of average aesthetic appreciation, and on the other hand by the acceptance of such primary relations as harmony, regularity, or unity, in the light of essential elements or- ganically determining all imaginable contents, and demanding, in their degree, characteristic expression for sense. Thus in the definition of beauty above suggested, the pregnant conception contributed by the moderns is merely a re-application in more concrete matter of the formal principle enunciated by the ancients. In the widest sense, then, and omitting to insist upon the narrower and commoner usage in which the characteristic — in the sense of individually charac- teristic — is opposed to the formal or symmetrical, it would be sufficient to define beauty as " the characteristic in as far as expressed for sense-perception or for imagination." If, indeed, we were attempting a psychological determina- tion of the feeling that attends or constitutes the peculiar enjoyment known as the enjoyment of beauty, we should probably have to deal with a term not mentioned in the defi- nition above proposed — the term pleasure. But in attempting to analyse the content which distinguishes perceptions or imaginations productive of this enjoyment from others which are not so productive, it appears to me that we should commit a serious error of method if we were to limit " expressiveness " or " characterization " either by beauty, which is the term to be defined, or by pleasantness, which is a quality not naturally coextensive with the term to be defined. The former error is not, in my judgment, wholly avoided by Goethe, when he insists that the characteristic, although essential to art, is yet a principle limited and conditioned by beauty in the strict sense, which is needed to soften the rigidity or abstraction of the characteristic. Thus the definition is made self-destruc- tive, beauty being at once the term to be defined, and an unanalysed limiting condition in the defining predicates. The latter error is committed in any such definition as that suggested by Schlegel, " the pleasant expression of the good." Things give pleasure sometimes because they are beautiful^ and sometimes for other reasons. They are not beautiful simply because they give pleasure, but only in so far as they DEFINITION OF BEAUTY. give cesthetic pleasure ; and the nature of the presentation that gives aesthetic pleasure is the matter to be ascertained. It will be seen that the part played in Goethe's account by the term beauty or grace, as a formal condition of artistic treatment, and in Schlegel's account by the differentia plea- sant, intended to guard against caricature or defect of har- mony, is transferred in the definition which I have ventured to suggest to the formal or general element of characteristic expression, the element- of unity or totality as symbolised by harmonious, symmetrical, or coherent dispositions of lines, surfaces, colours, or sounds. It would be tautology to super- add the condition of pleasantness to this formal element of the characteristic, if the two terms mean the same thing, as I believe that in aesthetic experience they do ; while if pleasant- ness were taken in the normal range of its psychological mean- ing, and not as thus both limited and extended by identification with cesthetic pleasantness, the definition would become in- disputably too narrow, even supposing that its other elements prevented it from being also too wide. The highest beauty, whether of nature or of art, is not in every case pleasant to the normal sensibilility even of civilized mankind, and is judged by the consensus, not of average feeling as such, but rather of the tendency of human feeling in proportion as it is developed by education and experience. And what is pleasant at first to the untrained sense — a psychological fact more universal than the educated sensibility — is not as a rule, though it is in some cases, genuinely beautiful. The definition, then, should be either purely analytic of contents accepted as beautiful — purely metaphysical, if we like to call it so — or purely psychological. To introduce a psycho- logical differentia into a metaphysical definition obtained by comparing the actual data of beauty, is to introduce a factor which we cannot control, because the differentia so introduced is itself in need of analysis and limitation on purely psycho- logical ground before it will coincide with the data to be in- vestigated. Some attempts at psychological analysis will be recorded and criticised in the course of this history ; I will at present simply suggest as an approximate psychological defi- nition of aesthetic enjoyment "Pleasure in the nature* of a feeling or presentation, as distinct from pleasure in its momen- tary or expected stimulation of the organism." Such pleasure would always, it is my belief, be connected in fact with the 8 HISTORY OF .ESTHETIC. significance of the content of feeling, but the meeting-point of the psychological and metaphysical definitions would not fall within the scope of psychology. In hope of dispelling any prejudice that may be raised gainst this conception on account of its apparent tendency to intellectualism, I will show in a few words how it is generated by consideration of extreme cases in the domain even of non- aesthetic feeling. If anything in the region of taste, smell, touch, heat or cold, has a value akin to that of beauty, it is not, surely, either the strongest or the most delightful sensa- tion, but rather the most suggestive sensation, or that which is most highly charged with associated ideas, so normal that we do not take them to be accidental. Not the scent of Eau-de-Cologne, but the smell of peat smoke or of the sea, not the comfortable warmth of the house, but the freshness of the morning air, are sensations of a kind in which we may feel a certain disinterested delight not wholly dissimilar to aesthetic enjoyment. The merest germ of the sense of beauty seems to imply a distinction between stimulus and signifi- cance. I have thus, I hope, justified in three respects the procedure which I intend to adopt. First, I have given my reasons for treating the history of Esthetic as an account, not merely of aesthetic systems, but, so far as may be in my power, of the aesthetic consciousness which has furnished material for these systems, and has formed the atmosphere in which they arose. Secondly, I have explained the necessity which compels aesthetic theory to accept fine art as the main representative of the beautiful, and I have attempted to show that this necessity-does not force us to neglect any important element of the facts with which we are to deal. Thirdly, I have propounded, in a few words, a definition of the beautiful which lends itself to the development of modern out of ancient aesthetic by a natural progression from the abstract to the concrete, analogous to the equally natural ad- vance from the classical to the Christian world of artistic pro- duction and insight into nature. And I have attempted to lay down a thorough distinction between the analytic and comparative treatment of beautiful presentations with reference to their common properties qua beautiful as progressively recognised in the development of culture, and the psychological DEFINITION OF BEAUTY. inquiry into the nature and differentia of that enjoyment which these presentations produce. It is plain that these two investigations have a common frontier in the connection be- tween elements of presentation and elements of enjoyment ; but in order that they may effectually co-operate, it is essential that they should not at the outset be confused. In the next chapter I propose to begin the examination of the aesthetic feeling and theory prevalent among the ancient Hellenes. a. This definition has been condemned as obscure. Yet I have seen no other, professing to be more distinct, which does not rest simply on a part or consequence of the character- istic here laid down. The point is one which cannot be grasped without some attention, because it involves the distinction of two aspects of sense-perception, which probably coexist in all perceptive experience, but appear as if at a certain level the one took the place of the ■other. 1 refer to what might roughly be called the mental and the bodily aspect of a. sense- perception. There is its peculiar character, by which it addresses us differently from any other sensational content ; warm, blue, high or low (of sound), and so on. There is also the disturbatice or excitenjent which it causes, whether pleasurable or painful, merely, I suppose, in virtue of the physical reaction to stimulus which it involves, in common with every physical reaction which enters into consciousness at all, say, for instance, organic sensation. I have expressed this distinction by the words "nature" and "stimulation." I would willingly replace " nature " by " form," if it were clearly understood that this had nothing to do with space or time in particular, and might include, for example, a significant intensity ; or by " relation, " if it were understood that this did not exclude the special sensation-quality of a colour or sound, in so far as this speaks to us differently from the content of any other sensation of the same or of another sense. Take, for example, our plea.sant feeling of the warmth of the fire on a cold day, and that ■of a simply pleasant colour, without pattern, say, in curtains or wallpaper. It seems to me quite plain that in the enjoyment of the colour there are two distinguishable elements. One which it has in common with higher perceptions of beauty in art and nature is an interest in the peculiar utterance of the colour as if a word in the great language of the sensuous world. It is different for every colour and spatial arrangement of colour, and different for colour from what it is for any other sensation. It is not an abstract intellectual meaning, but it is to the colour what meaning is to a word. The other element may be described by contrast as *' physical." It is the bare fact that in the sensation we are pleasurably excited, soothed, or gently stimulated. The supposed perception of colour has it in common with the feeling of warmth, and with many cases of the organic feelings. I do not doubt that some casual connexion exists between the two elements. But it seems to me incontrovertible that the relation is not directly proportional. The enjoyment of warmth or of health feels in •one way exactly like the simple enjoyment of the colour. But it seems to be in want of something. Its " mental " element, or " nature," is hardly traceable; its pleasant stimu- lation is almost, though not quite, a blank fact per se. Now I do not doubt that these two sides are really present in all sensation and sense- perception, from organic feeling to the highest regions of aesthetic enjoyment. But they are not proportional, and in complex cases may be discrepant, as when a " sensation " mars the unity of what would be a good work of art, and thereby increases the enjoyment of the weaker spectators. The reasons for admitting the presence of the "nature" throughout are first that it seems a truism that every state of consciousness has a nature, if we were skilful enough to detect it ; secondly, that great writers sometimes show us, through their unusually delicate analysis, the presence of a significant nature where we should fail ourselves to detect it (cf. Dr. Middleton's praises of wine in the Egoist) ; and thirdly, that thus by this distinc- tion we remove the difficulty arising from the early stages of almost physical attractiveness on the part of sensation, as when a child turns towards a bright light. CHAPTER II. THE CREATION QF A POETIC WORLD, AND ITS FIRST ENCOUNTER WITH REFLECTION. ^rtitoto^" I. If we approach the earlier Greek philosophers, or even Plato, the prophet of beauty, expecting to find in them a simple reflex and appreciation of the plastic and poetic fancy of their countrymen, we shall be seriously disappointed. The thought of Hellas passed through all the phases which were natural to profound and ardent intelligence at first freely turned upon the world ; and the partial truths which it successively attained were uttered with a definiteness and audacity which conveys a first impression of something like perversity. When a modern reader finds that the fair humanities of old religion aroused among the wisest of early philosophers either unsparing condemnation or allegorical misconception, he is forced to summon up all his historical sympathy if he would not conclude that Heracleitus and Xenophanes and Plato, and the allegorising interpreters of whom Plato tells us, were in- capable of rational criticism. But in reality this moral and metaphysical analysis, directed against the substance of a poetic fancy which was thus beginning to be distinguished from prosaic history, was the natural sequel of artistic creation, and the natural forerunner of more appreciative theory. Creation of the 2. The Creation of Hellenic poetry and forma- worid of Beauty, tjyg ^ff ^^j j^g regarded as an intermediate stage between popular practical religion and critical or philoso- phical reflection. The legendary content of this art was not the work of the poet or the formative artist, but of the national mind in its long development out of savagery. Its imagina- tive form, on the other hand, was due indeed to the national mind, but to this mind chiefly as it acted through the individu- ality of poetic genius, investing the national thought and emotion with progressive significance and refinement. For although it may be doubted whether the word corresponding CREATION OF A POETIC WORLD. II to beauty or the beautiful was ever used in the whole range of Hellenic antiquity in a meaning perfectly free from confu- sion with truth or goodness, yet it is certain that art is more than nature, and that the definite presentation of ideas in beautiful shape cannot but prepare the way for an explicit aesthetic judgment by developing a distinct type of sentiment and enjoyment. Thus in Hellenic art and poetry, as it existed in the middle of the 5th century b.c., we find embodied a consciousness in relation to beauty, which, if much less than theoretically ex- plicit, is much more than practical and natural. There is a naive apprehension of a profound truth in the familiar saying of Herodotus,^ that Homer and Hesiod made the Hellenic theogony, and determined the forms and attributes of the gods, for Hellenic belief The full force of this reflection is mea- sured by the interval between the early wooden image and the Phidian statue, or between the superstition of a savage and Antigone's conception of duty. It was in the world of fine art that Hellenic genius had mainly recorded, and, in recording, had created, this transformation. Season for the 3" When therefore the first recognition of the Attitude of existence and significance of art takes the shape of e ec on. hQgtjjjj-y jq (jjg anthropomorphic content which it retains, we see not only that the reflective idea of beauty is. still conspicuous by its absence, but that theory in advancing beyond the popular faith fails to recognise the actual refine- ment of that faith by which poetic fancy has paved the way~ for the speculative criticism which condemns it. On the other hand, we must observe that the criteria now actually applied — the wholly unsesthetic criteria of reality and of morality — spring from a principle from which we shall only in part escape within the limits of Hellenic antiquity. This principle is, as we shall see, that an artistic representa- ; tion cannot be treated as diflerent in kind or in aim from a ; reality of ordinary life. To make distinction between them is. always a hard lesson for immature reflection ; but for a Hellenic thinker there were reasons which made it all but impossible. The Greek world of ideas, before or outside the philosophic schools, was wholly free from dualism. Its parts were homo- geneous. The god, for example, was not conceived as an 1 Hdt. 2. S3. J 2 HISTORY OF /ESTHETIC. unseen being merely capable of an incarnation, such as could not express or exhaust his full spiritual nature ; rather his real shape was human, though to reveal it to mortal eye might be a rare favour, and he lived in a particular hill or in a particu- lar temple. The representation of a divine being was to the Greek not a mere symbol, but a likeness ; not a symbol which might faintly suggest Him who could be known only in the spirit, but a likeness of one who dwelt on earth, and whose nature was to be visible, and not to be invisible. Thus, in speaking of a question about the supernatural in Homer, Schelling has said that in Homer there is no supernatural, because the Greek god is a part of nature. And therefore, although a work of creative idealization unparalleled in the history of the world had been performed by the plastic fancy of Greece in the age that culminated with the highest art of Athens, yet in the absence of any mystic sense of an invisible order of realities the prevalent impression produced by this world of beauty was rather that of imitative representation than of interpretative origination. Ne lected 4- Even the idea of imitation, indeed, contains snggestiou In the germ of a fuller sesthetic truth than was ever ideaofimitauon. attained by Hellenic thought ; for the translation of an object into a plastic medium involves a double and not merely a single element, — not merely a consideration of the object to be represented, but a consideration of the act of imaginative production by which it is born again under the new conditions imposed by another medium. Natural com- mon sense expressed this truth in one of the earliest aesthetic judgments that Western literature contains, when on the shield of Achilles, the Homeric poet says,^ " the earth looked dark behind the plough, and like to ground that had been ploughed, although it was made of gold; that was a marvellous piece of work." The " marvel " is that the mind can confer on a medium of its own choosing the characteristic semblance of what it desires to represent. But of all that depends upon this side of imitation — the spiritual second birth of beauty — we hear but little ex- plicitly in Hellenic science, although, within defective formulae, som^ glimpses of it forced themselves upon Aristotle. For the reasons which have been indicated — the tendency of all 177.17.548. IMITATION AND IDEALISM. 1 3, immature reflection to judge by reality and utility, and the absence of a belief in anything which could not be visibly imitated — the poetic or creative side of artistic representation did not wholly come to its rights in antiquity. Perhaps it was even less regarded by the philosophers than it was, in the consciousness of poetic inspiration, by the epic and lyric poets, or by Plato himself outside his formal treatment of the metaphysic of imitative art. widetrseaf 5. It is howevcr the case that the term imita- tdon^in^i^ttion in ancient aesthetic theory is opposed rather pwioBophy. tQ industrial production than to artistic origina- tion, and is compatible with a considerable variation and expan- sion of import, which I shall endeavour to trace in a separate chapter. It is natural that the earliest formula adopted by reflection should be strained to breaking point before it is abandoned. Further Er- ^- I* ""^7 Still appear extraordinary to us, after pianation how all is said, that the art which we contrast with Greek Art could ' . ,, • 1 1 1 n be called "imi- our owii as m a peculiar sense ideal, and as equally tatiTo." remote from the vicious attempt at illusion, and from the justifiable delight in detail, should have been charac- terized by enlightened opinion in its own day as a mode of imitation or mere representation. If this is our feeling, we may profitably consider in two respects the nature of the art which we are discussing. Facility of imi- *• ^" the first place, just because the Hellenic tatiTo Art makes artist or poet was free from the overwhelming ' *^ sense of spiritual significance which is the essence of mystic symbolism, he was able to delineate in large and " ideal " outlines the general impressions which he gathered from life by a scrutiny not too microscopic. It is not unnatural that the art which sets itself to portray what attracts it in a complete and actual world should be more full of repose and less tormented with the subtleties of expression than an art to which every minutest human or natural feature may be of unutterable symbolic significance. Heuenic Art not ii. And if we thus see how an imitative art, id^i^hS'f unburdened with a " mission " or revelation, may heen thought, bg ideal simply because it is at ease; on the other hand we must to some extent correct our traditional conception of the degree in which Hellenic beauty was devoid of strangeness, and humour, and animated expression. The 14 HISTORY OF ESTHETIC. ■critics from whom we have derived our current notions of the " classical " and the " antique " have of course performed a necessary task, and have revealed a distinction as deep as life between the ancient and the modern world. Yet, after all, the ancient world also was alive, and possessed a range of sympathetic expressiveness which was but inadequately ren- dered in the first impression made upon modern theorists by fragments of its monumental sculpture. The identification of the ancient ideal with the general or abstract, which a due regard to Greek literature might at once have proved to be a very partial truth, has been further modified by the labour of more than a century in piecing together the plastic surround- ings of this ancient life, and appreciating the descriptions which assist us to realize them. " The task before me," ^ writes one whose work in this direction must be a revelation to all who are not specialists in archaeology, " The task before me is touched with inevitable sadness. The record we have to read is the record of what we have lost. That loss, but for Pausanias, we should never have realized. He, and he only, gives us the real live picture of what the art of ancient Athens was. Even the well-furnished classical scholar pictures the Acropolis as a stately hill approached by the Propylsea, crowned by the austere beauty of the Parthenon, and adds to his picture perhaps the remembrance of some manner of Erechtheion, a vision of colourless marble, of awe, restraint, severe selection. Only Pausanias tells him of the colour and life, the realism, the quaintness, the forest of votive statues, the gold, the ivory, the bronze, the paintings on the walls, the golden lamps, the brazen palm-trees, the strange old Hermes hidden in myrtle leaves, the ancient stone on which Silenus sat, the smoke-grimed images of Athene, Diitrephes all pierced with arrows, Kleoitas with his silver nails, the heroes peeping from the Trojan horse, Anacreon singing in his cups ; all these, if we would picture the truth and not our own imagination, we must learn of, and learn of from Pausanias. " But if the record of our loss is a sad one, it has its meed of sober joy ; it is the record also of what — if it be ever so little — in these latter days we have refound." It is not a false opinion that harmony, severity, and repose 1 Mythology and Monuments of Anct. Athens, by Miss J, E. Harrison, xi.. THE BEGINNING OF THEORY. 1 5 are fundamental characters of Hellenic craft and fancy ; th« history of a single decorative form, such as the acanthus foli^e, is enough to illustrate the profoundness of the contrast thus indicated between the antique and the modern. But we must master and adhere to the principle that although the given boundaries of Greek aesthetic theory can be in some degree justified by the comparative limitations of the art which was its material, yet this justification is only relative, and means not that Greek aesthetic was an adequate account of Greek art, but only that it was a natural and obvious one. Thus we shall find that true aesthetic analysis among the Greeks extended only to the most formal element that enters into Hellenic beauty ; while its passion and its human signifi- cance and its touches of common things attracted the censure of an unsesthetic criticism and supported the classification of the whole range of artistic utterance under the superficial title of " imitation." Had the realism of the antique been less modest and refined, it would have challenged an analysis which would have replaced censure by explanation. But the time for this was not yet ; and it will be seen that in spite of the protests of the philosopher and the satirical comedian, theory was forced in the long run to become more subtly appreciative as art became less severely noble. 7. We have now arrived at the point where Freparedior the Strictly philosophical consideration of aesthetic ^stheuc Theory, phenomena may be expected to begin. A world of beautiful shapes and fancies has been brought into being, which must of necessity have trained the perception to re- cognise beauty as displayed in the corresponding province of nature, that is, mainly in the human form, and must have developed some partly conscious sentiment of the beautiful as distinguishable from the good and the true. This imaginary world has been recognised as a new creation both negatively by the claims of the metaphysician and the moralist, and positively by the naive appreciation of the historian and the allegorising construction of the mystic. The mystic is the forerunner of a later age ; but the historian and the philo- sopher agree, by their acquiescence and their censure respec- tively, in treating it as claiming to pass for a simple reproduction of natural reality. And thus the immense panorama depicted by Hellenic imagination enters the range of philosophic vision under the title of mimetic or representative art. CHAPTER III. THE FUNDAMENTAL OUTLINES OF GREEK THEORY CONCERNING THE BEAUTIFUL. ^d SSroto- '^^^ present chapter will be devoted to stating nexion. in logical connexion, regardless of any historical development within the limits of antiquity, the general prin- ciples which determine all Hellenic thinkers in their inquiries concerning the beautiful. The task of tracing historically the pressure which progressive insight and experience brought to bear upon these conceptions, with the consequent straining of the formulae until breaking point was reached, will be attempted in the following chapter so far as space and ability permit. The cumbrous expression, " theory concerning the beauti- ful," has been intentionally adopted. For of the three con- nected principles which constitute the framework of Hellenic speculation upon the nature and value of beauty, there is one only that can claim the more convenient title of "aesthetic theory." The two other principles in question might be respectively described as moralistic and as metaphysical, although the common root of both is itself a metaphysical assumption which is also responsible for the limitation of true aesthetic analysis in the third principle to the abstract conditions of expression. This metaphysical assumption, natural to incipient specula- tion, is to the effect that artistic representation is no more than a kind of common-place reality — of reality, that is, as presented to normal sense-perception and feeling — and that it is related precisely as the ordinary objects of perception are related, to man and his purposes, subject only to, a reservation on ac- count of its mode of existence being less solid and complete than that of the objects from which it is drawn. This belief is intimately bound up with the conception of a homogeneous or thoroughly natural world, which makes it ART AN INFERIOR REALITY. 1 7 necessary to assume that the essence of art and beauty does not lie in a symbolic relation to an unseen reality behind the objects of common sense-perception, but in mere imitative relation to those common objects themselves. It "was tTiis prevalent idea that dictated the philosophical treatment to be accorded to the newly recognised phenomena of an art which produced only images of things, and not the useful realities known and handled in every-day life. It was not as yet ob- served that the ultimate import of these phenomena, involving the total separation of aesthetic semblance from practical reality, was incompatible with the idea which throughout antiquity controlled their interpretation, A sufficient verification of the predominance of this principle is to be found in the current generalisation by which both Plato and Aristotle gathered up the arts which we call the fine arts under the name "imitative" or "image-making" as contrasted in the first instance with those which are " produc- tive" or "thing-making."^ Even in Plotinus imitation is the general term which describes the attempt to create beautiful forms or fancies for the purpose of aesthetic enjoyment. It may be well also to point out a passage in Aristotle's Politics * which may fairly be paraphrased, as asserting that man is, as a matter of course, affected by the reality of a fact in the same way as by its representation, so that what we learn to like or dislike in the semblance for its mere form, we shall similarly like or dislike in the reality. This is a doctrine which Aris- totle in part knew how to qualify, as will be seen in the next chapter ; but Plato followed it uncompromisingly through his entire theoretical treatment of the imagination. From this metaphysical assumption there arise in close connection the two principles concerning beauty, which I have called metaphysical and moralistic respectively ; and also the restriction of esthetic theory proper, to what is contained in the third principle. I arrange these principles in an ascend- ing order according to their aesthetic value. Moralistic I. If artistic representation is related to man prtodpie. only as common-place reality, then to represent an immoral content is only to double the exanaples of immorality, and to strengthen, by suggestion, the incitements to it. In other words, it, follows that morally the representations of art : 1 Plato, Sophist, 266 D. Ar., Mys., 199 a. i5.« * Ar., Fol., 1340 a. 26; De Part. Anim. 645 a. 4 (see Butcher, 155;. 1 8 HISTORY OF ESTHETIC. must be judged, in respect of their content, by the same moral criteria as real life. Metaphysical 2. If artistic representation differs from the Principle, nature which it represents, whether human or other, only in the degree and completeness of its existence, then it differs only for the worse, and is a purposeless reduplication of what already was in the world. In other words, it follows that, metapkysically, art is a second nature, only in the sense of being an incomplete reproduction of nature. jEsthetic 3- If artistic presentation can never have a Principle, deeper content than the normal or common-place object of perception which it represents, then there can be no explanation of beauty involving any deeper attributes than those which normal perception is able to apprehend in com- mon-place reality. In other words, it follows that, eest helically, beauty is purely formal, consisting in certain very abstract conditions which are satisfied, for example, in elementary geo- metrical figures as truly as in the creations of fine art. I will discuss these principles in order, with reference to their general predominance in Hellenic theory, and to their aesthetic significance. Moraustio I- It would be idle to deny that both Plato and Principle. Aristotle are encumbered with moralistic consider- ations throughout the whole of their inquiry into the nature of fine art. How far either of them approached the accepted modern doctrine that aesthetic interest in the beauty of a pre- sentation is distinct from the real or selfish interest in its actual existence for the satisfaction of desire, is, according to the plan which I have adopted, a question for the next chapter. It is enough at present to establish the general point of view before us as actual in Hellenic theory by the following con- sideration. How It shows «• The moral and practical judgment is the firs itseit intellectual outcome of organized social life, and i: inevitably turned upon the world of beauty so long as this i: undistinguished from the objects which constitute the mean and purposes of real action. Not only Heracleitus and Xeno phanes, with their condemnation of Homer, but Aristophanes with his praise of him as a teacher of good life, and with hi corresponding censure of Euripides, are examples of thi mode of opinion, which, in fact, persists strongly in unpractise minds even in the modern world. MUST THE HERO BE GOOD ? 1 9 The two great philosophers betray in this respect, though in somewhat different degrees, a naive directness of judgment extremely trying to any modern reader who is not thoroughly trained in the habit of historical appreciation. They appear to abandon themselves almost unsuspectingly to the above- mentioned principle, that the resemblance has the same effects as the normal reality. The distinction between image and object, which was destined in the long run to grow into a recognition that beauty and practical reality affect the mind in quite different ways, has for Plato mainly the effect of intensi- fying his moralistic suspicion of the unreal simulacrum which fancy supplies. For the imagination, he believes,^ is psycho- logically connected with the emotions ; and therefore the imaginary world of art, while sharing the power of the real world to form habit by example, possesses that of creating emotional disturbance in a far greater degree. And it cannot be maintained that Aristotle breaks the net of this assumption, which we saw that he expressly formulates, however much he may have done to strain it. The student of modern sesthetic will find himself, when he reads the Poetics, in a region almost wholly strange to his ideas of criticism. It is plain, for example, that Aristotle shrinks from- a true tragic collision,* in which passion or character determine the indi- vidual's destiny, and this in spite of the abundance in which such individualities as those of Prometheus, Clyteemnestra, CEdipus, Aias, Antigone and Medea, were presented to his view by ancient tragedy. And the reason plainly lies in his subjec- tion of all criticism to his division of character into good, bad, and indifferent,^ excluding, ipso facto, all that conflict of a great passion or purpose with the surrounding world, in which tragic interest properly consists, and which make the character a symbol of forces that lie behind the phenomena of life as named by current morality. The conclusion that the hero of tragedy must be neither very good nor very bad,* and that his fate must be determined by error* and not by wickedness, is unintelligible to modern judgment. We think that the hero may be both very good and very bad, that is to say, that he must above all things be great, and comprehend in himself the 1 Republic, p. 606. 2 Poet., xiii. 3 and 4. See Susemihl's notes, which represent Aristotle's idea in the most modem colours possible. » Ibid. * Ibid. 20 HISTORY OF .lESTHETIC. differences which make possible the highest discord, and there- fore the highest harmony. All these ideas are excluded ab initio by the moralistic categories under which Aristotle sub- sumes his species of tragic plots. Then again, as we should expect, it is his preference ^ that the fatal action in which a tragedy culminates should be done in ignorance, and its nature only discovered afterwards ; for the discovery, if made in time, would have, he thinks, the effect of preventing the terrible action from taking place. The plot of the Medea, which he mentions in this context, is therefore naturally censured by implication as shocking. So, too, with the classification of artists. Here the natural pre-eminence of the moralistic point of view is very trenchantly laid down. It is simplest to quote the passage (the point being to distinguish species of imitation, according to the objects which they imitate): — * " Now all artistic representation is of persons acting, and these must necessarily be either noble or inferior (for all moral temperament [ethos] conforms to this distinction ; for it is goodness and badness of moral temperament by which all men are distinguished from each other) — that is, either better in comparison with us, or worse, or just like ourselves. So we may see with the painters : Polygnotus painted people better, Pauson worse, Dionysius just like ourselves. From all this it is clear, that each of the kinds of representation which has been mentioned will include these differences, and will have different species according as the objects which it repre- sents differ in this way. For these dissimilarities may occur even in dancing or in performances on the flute or the lyre, and so too poetry may display them whether it be with or without verse ; for instance, Homer represents nobler char- acters, Kleophon average ones, Hegemon of Thasos, the first to make parodies, and Nicochares, who wrote the Deliad, below the average. . . . And this is the difference that distinguishes tragedy from comedy, for the latter aims at representing worse people, and the former better, than those of present reality." Here again the student, not only of Shakespeare and Goethe, but of Homer and of the Attic drama, entirely loses his bearings. It seems to him that the poetic world is stronger * Poet., xiv. 6, 8, 9. 2 Poet., ii. GREEK MORALISM. 2 1 and more emphatic in its attributes, alike in the good as in the evil, than the world of every-day life, as presented to every- day observation. What about Thersites ? as Mr. Mahaffy asks. The poet who should represent individuals as only better than common men, or again as only worse, would be to us simply a monster, except in so far as the art of Aristo- phanic comedy is concerned ; and even here the adjective "worse," with its moralistic associations, does not at all express the true bearing of the representation, which it seems probable that Aristotle was unable to appreciate. Many subtleties might be urged against this interpretation of Aristotle, and to some of them it will be attempted to do justice when we speak of modifications within Hellenic theory. But it does not appear to me that we should be justified in hampering ourselves by such refinements, to the extent of denying that Plato and Aristotle had their feet firmly planted within the compass of naive practical moralism, however much they may have looked away to other and more fertile regions. j:stiiettc value . ^- ^' "^"^' ^^ remembered, however, that grant- ing the almost total absence of a distinctively : iESthetic standpoint, there is no form in which a healthy sense of relative values could assert itself with respect to art, except the form of moralistic criticism. The content of such a criticism is the determination that the central core of life shall have justice done to it in the representation of life, and this determination is characteristic of the temper in which not only genuine speculation, but the greatest works of art, have always originated. The development of moral reflection by Plato into apparent hostility to nearly the whole world of classical beauty must be regarded historically speaking as a reduction adabsurdum, not of the human content, but of the non-zesthetic form of the principle which he professed to be advocating. And it is hard to believe that in this and other respects he was wholly unaware of some such ironical import in his own speculations. The technical defect thus revealed consists in substituting a direct connection of subordination for an indirect connection of co-ordination between the spheres of beauty and of the moral order. By this subordination beauty is required to represent the moral order as moral, and nothing more ; whereas it is really an expression, co-ordinate with the moral 22 HISTORY OF ^ESTHETIC. order as a whole and not bound under its rules, of that larger complication and unity of things which reflects itself in the sense of beauty on the one hand, and on the other hand in the social will. But not only is the substance of early moral criticism sound; in one definite relation even its form is justifiable. Beauty, indeed, within its own territory of expression for expression's sake, is secure from praise or censure upon purely moral grounds. But wherever expression is not for expres- sion's sake, but is determined by alien motives such as the promotion of virtue or knowledge, or again the stimulation of sensuous desire, then it is outside the aesthetic frontier, and moral criticism upon it is justified not only in substance but also in form. It is doubtful, indeed, whether ancient philosophy ever thoroughly applied the distinction between aesthetic and practical interest ; but it is plain that this very failure to distinguish between them in theory is largely owing to the constant confusion between them in practice, and that the censure which pronounced much of fine art to be immoral involved a consciousness that true aesthetic interest must be pure, and was only mistaken in admitting that which it con- demned to be fine art at all. Then the estimation of beauty by the practical standard of right and wrong, although unaesthetic in form, contains two elements of aesthetic value. It bears witness to the instinctive demand for depth and completeness in art as representing the powers that reveal themselves in that order of the world of which the moral order is one among other significant reflec- tions ; and it embodies the conviction that there is a spurious art and beauty, which being not free but subservient to a practical or sensuous end, cease to be objects of aesthetic judg- ment and become the legitimate prey of moral censure or commendation. And censure of these must indeed always be one degree truer than commendation ; for a fraud, however pious, can never be wholly satisfying to morality. Now the pretence of beauty, in a presentation the true interest of which is other than aesthetic, must always be in some degree a fraud. A difficulty presents itself at this point which cannot be treated in full till we come to deal with the niceties of modern analysis. At present we can only observe that this distinction between free and servile or spurious beauty depends not on PLATO ON IMITATION. 23 the description, necessarily abstract as all language is, which the artist or percipient may give of his own purpose or ground of enjoyment, but on the degree in which, as a matter of fact, an abstraction due to an alien purpose of any kind whatever is apparent as distorting the presentation. The Metaphysical 2. The formative and poetic art of Hellas at Principle. j^e close of the 5th century b.c. had attained a completeness in itself which was emphasized by a pause in its development and an indication of new tendencies. It was natural that at such a moment its significance should challenge the attention of the great contemporary philosopher, and also that his treatment of it should consist in an explicit formulation of the current Hellenic conception, such as on the one hand to lay by its help the foundation-stone of all sound aesthetic theory, while on the other hand to exhibit by a reductio ad absurdum the onesidedness of the conception itself. In estimating the achievement of such a philosophy, it is not necessary to consider how far it was intentional. We have to accept its doctrines in their actual significance, and not to inquire whether Plato may ever have entertained any other view of art and imagination than that which he found it necessary to analyse. Hov it shows a. I quote a passage which summarises the Itself. doctrine of Plato's well-known polemic against all representative art.^ "And there is another artist [besides the workman who makes useful real things]. I should like to know what you would say of him. Who is he ? One who is the maker of all the works of all other workmen. . . . This is he who makes not only vessels of every kind, but plants and animals, himself and all other things — the earth and heaven, and the things which are in heaven or under the earth ; he makes the gods also. . . . Do you not see that there is a way in which you could make them yourself 1 — there are many ways in which the feat might be accomplished, none quicker than that of turning a mirror round and round — you would soon make the sun and the heaven and the earth and yourself, and other animals and plants, and all the other creatures of art as well as of nature in the mirror. * Republic, bk. x. Jowett, marg., p. 596-7, 24 HISTORY OF ^ESTHETIC. " Yes, he said ; but that is an appearance only. " Very good, I said, you are coming to the point now ; and the painter, as I conceive, is just a creator of this sort, is he not? " Of course. " But then I suppose you will say that what he creates is untrue. And yet there is a sense in which the painter also creates a bed .'' , " Yes, he said, but not a real bed. " And what of the manufacturer of the bed ? did you not say that he does not make the idea which, according to our view, is the essence of the bed, but only a particular bed ? " Yes, I did. " Then if he does not make that which exists he cannot make true existence but only some semblance of existence ; and if any one were to say that the work of the manufacturer of the bed, or of any other workman, has real existence, he could hardly be supposed to be speaking the truth. — No wonder then that his work too is an indistinct expression of truth. — Well then here are three beds, one existing in nature which as I think that we may say, is made by God — there is another which is the work of the carpenter ? And the work of the painter is a third ? Beds then are of three kinds, and there are three artists who superintend them : God, the manu- facturer of the bed, and the painter ? — God, whether from choice or necessity, created one bed in nature and one only ; two or more such ideal beds neither ever have been nor ever will be made by God. . . . Shall we then speak of Him as the natural author or maker of the bed ? "Yes, he replied, inasmuch as by the natural power of creation He is the author of this and of all other things. " And what shall we say of the carpenter ; is not he also the maker of the bed .'* " Yes. *' But would you call the painter a creator and maker ? " Certainly not. " Yet if he is not the maker, what is he in relation to the bed ? " I think, he said, that we may fairly designate him as the imitator of that which the others make. " Good, I said ; then you call him who is third in the descent from nature an imitator; and the tragic poet is an POPULAK NOTIONS OF ART. 25 imitator, and therefore like all other imitators he is thrice removed from the king^ and from truth ? " That appears to be the case. Then about the imitator we are agreed. And now about the painter ; I would like to know whether he imitates that which originally exists in nature, or only the creations of artists [artificers] ? " The latter. " As they are, or as they appear ? you have still to determine this. — I mean, that you may look at a bed from different points of view, obliquely or directly or from any other point of view, and the bed will appear different, but there is no difference in reality. Which is the art of painting — an imitation of things as they are, or as they appear — of appearance or of reality ? "Of appearance. " Then the imitator, I said, is a long way off the truth and can do all things because he only lightly touches on a small part of them, and that part an image. For example : a painter will paint a cobbler, carpenter, or any other artificer, though he knows nothing of their arts ; and if he is a good artist, he may deceive children or simple persons when he shows them his picture of a carpenter from a distance, and they will fancy that they are looking at a real carpenter. And whenever any one informs us that he has found a man who knows all the arts, and all things else that everybody knows, and every single thing, with a higher degree of accu- racy than any other man — whoever tells us this, I think that we can only imagine him to be a simple creature who is likely to have been deceived by some wizard or actor whom he met, and whom he thought all-knowing, because he himself was unable to analyse the nature of knowledge and ignorance and imitation. And so when we hear persons saying that the tragedians and Homer, who is at their head, know all the arts and all things human, virtue as well as vice, and divine things too, for that the good poet must know what he is talking about, and that he who has not this knowledge can never be a poet, we ought to consider whether here also there is not a similar illusion. Perhaps they may have been deceived by imitators, and may never have remembered when they saw their works that these were but imitations thrice ' The allusion is to bk. ix. p. 586 ff. 26 HISTORY OF ^ESTHETIC. removed from the truth, and could easily be made without any knowledge of the truth, because they are appearances only, and not real substances ? Or perhaps after all they may be in the right, and poets do really know the things about which they seem to the many to speak well ? — Now do you suppose that if a person were able to make the original as well as the image, he would devote himself to the image- making branch ? Would he allow imitation to be the ruling principle of his life, as though he could do nothing better ? — 1 he real artist who knew what he was imitating, would be interested in realities and not in imitations ; and would desire to leave as memorials of himself works many and fair ; and instead of being the author of encomiums, he would prefer to be the theme of them." Here we see the theory of imitation laid down in a definite metaphysical form, ostensibly as an annihilating criticism on the value and reality of art, though consisting in a simple formulation of the current conception regarding it. Three decisive points in the passage call for our notice. fBtbetic !• Art works with images only and not with Semblance, realities such as can act or be acted upon in the world of ordinary life. Eeiattonto ii- These images are not symbolic of the ulti- oommon Reality, j^^te reality as created by God ; that is, in our language, of the relations and conditions which to a perfect knowledge would be present as determining or constituting any real object in the order of nature. The appearances in which fine art consists are superficially imitative of the second or common-place reality which is relative to every-day purpose and sense-perception. Inferiority by "i- The images of art must be judged — and tbia standard, therefore condemned — by their capacity of repre- senting common reality either with sensuous completeness or with intellectual thoroughness ; the reality is in every way preferable to the imitation,^ and, it is added lower down, even beauty depends on a correct representation of use. Of these three characteristic assertions the first must be reserved for treatment under the head of aesthetic value. Here we need only observe that it is fundamentally and abso- lutely true. * Plato, Rep., p. 60 1. DUALISM IN PLATO AND ARISTOTLE. 27 The second and third constitute the differentia of the non- aesthetic account of art natural to Hellas ; and till their contentions are fairly challenged and repudiated, we are safe in saying that no true aesthetic of representative or concrete art has been attained or is possible. For, so long as they are admitted, the standard of judgment lies ex hypothesi in the appearance and purposes of reality as accepted by every-day action and experience. Whether Plato is serious or consistent with himself in in- sisting that the relation of art is to the " second," and not to the " first" reality, does not concern us here. It is sufficient to note that the essence of a mimetic theory could not be more trenchantly formulated than by this classification of realities, on the assumption which I believe to be indisputable, that Plato's first and highest reality has for us an intelligible meaning as practically corresponding to the completes! con- ception in which the order of nature can be presented to a human mind. It may occur to the reader that Aristotle, not holding to the metaphysical dualism so sharply expressed by Plato in the passage which has been quoted, was not under the necessity of repudiating the relation of art to common reality there laid down, so definitely as Plotinus afterwards repudiated it. Com- mon perceptible reality, it would then be alleged, contained for Aristotle the true real and universal, and therefore the dependence of art upon the former was not for him definitely separable from its dependence upon the latter. And hence, it might be urged, the refinements which we shall find in his theory and his criticism, are not mere practical qualifications of the old conception, forced upon him by increasing critical experience and closer observation of the healthy love of beauty, but are satisfactory evidence of a fundamental change of standpoint in the direction away from the mimetic and towards the symbolic art-consciousness. I believe, however, that such a view would be erroneous. In the first place, the cfifference between Plato and Aristotle in regard to philo- sophical dualism is not at all such as is commonly supposed, or such as the above passage from the Republic might lead a reader to imagine, who is unacquainted with the varying and subtle gradations in which the so-called " doctrine of ideas " presents itself throughout Plato's writings. The appearance of dualism is produced by efforts to apprehend the principle 28 HISTORY OF ESTHETIC. that the object is relative to the subject, and bearing this principle in mind we shall not find more than a difference in degree between the metaphysical position of the two great philosophers. The distinction between reality for perception and reality for thought is essentially the same to both of them. And in the second place, if we add to the evidence above referred to regarding Aristotle's moralistic position that which has also been adduced with respect to his view on the effect of resemblance in comparison with that of reality, and if we observe the weak psychological qualification by which alone he limits this latter principle,^ we cannot doubt that as a matter of fact Aristotle thoroughly adhered in metaphysical as in moral criticism to the conception of art as a mimetic representation of the world"^ in the shape which it takes for normal action and perception. Its asthetio |8. This metaphysical estimate of image-making Value. fjjjg g^j^^ closely associated at least in Plato with an analogous psychological estimate of the imagination, although in form non-sesthetic, and profoundly hostile to the value of the poetic world, is in substance an important foundation- stone of sesthetic theory. iEatuetic sem- i- It is not Sufficiently recognised that in the boanoe. Polemic of Republic, Book X., taken in con- junction with other well-known passages in Plato, there is laid down the essential doctrine of sesthetic semblance as plainly as in Schiller or in Hegel. The imputation of inferiority — that the appearance is superficial compared to the sensuous reality — is of merely transient importance in itself, but is of the highest significance as a phase of estimation through which the aesthetic appearance must naturally pass on its way to com- plete recognition as distinct from common-place fact. The double-edged nature of the phenomena of imitation now neces- sarily begins to reveal itself. " To imitate," means no doubt to produce a likeness of; but what is a likeness ? In what medium does it exist ? Of what relations to practice and to reality is it capable } To all these questions the criticism of naive metaphysic has its answers. A likeness is a projection or superficial reproduction of a real thing, in a medium in- capable of exhausting the content of the original reality, or of fulfilling the purposes or satisfying the interests which ^ See cb. iv. ESTHETIC SEMBLANCE. 29 attach to it. And art is constituted entirely of likenesses, and its mental "medium is the imagination or image-receiving faculty. The censure of inutility which follows upon this trenchant distinction, by denying the naive conception of an adequate^ relation to reality, leads us to the recognition of an aesthetic interest which is not that of utility, nor of relation to any satisfaction connected with the sensuous impulses. More- over, when Plato insists that the appearances employed by the artist are in relation not with the unseen world of thought and law, but with a lower reality which is itself only an image of that unseen world, it is impossible not to observe in this a strong though negative suggestion of the function of beauty as a symbol for spiritual things. And indeed as regards beauty, though not as regards art, this suggestion even takes a positive form, when it is laid down ^ that the Creator in making the world beautiful necessarily modelled it on the ultimate underlying order ; whereas anything modelled upon the created world itself, and therefore especially such presen- tations as those of art, must inevitably be devoid of beauty. There could not be a more definite challenge to subsequent reflection, which could hardly fail to ask, whether to reveal the beautiful in the deeper significance thus accorded to created things might not be the purpose and essence of art. semblance In- ."' Besides enforcing the truth implied in the *^ReaSt?*** inimetic theory, Plato reduces to an absurdity its element of falsehood. This element, it must be remembered, he found expressed in the reflective opinion of his time,* just as he found an element of non-aesthetic in- terest in its artistic practice. All that he has to do, is to for- mulate the received opinion with perfect self-consistency, and draw the inference which immediately presents itself Whether in his own mind he sympathized with that inference, I be- lieve that we can never know. If it were possible to con- jecture, on the basis of his general and less strictly scientific utterances, I should venture to think it possible that the pro- blem pressed upon him as one of fundamental importance ; that the current Plellenic theory, within which he found himself, agreed only too well with some phenomena of existing art, and was profoundly unsatisfactory to the great thinker ; and that he therefore examined this theory seriously, with the re- ^ Timceus, 28 B. ^\.c. above, p. 25 30 HISTORY OF ^ESTHETIC. suit, " If, and in as far as, this is the true explanation of art, art has not the value which popular judgment assigns to it." The further suggestion, " There must be more in it than this," must no doubt have presented itself to him, as we can partly see, in various forms, with various degrees of explicitness and urgency. But his final utterance as a metaphysical theorist on representative art considered as imitation of reality, is in brief: "so far as the value of aesthetic appearance depends either upon its sensuous or upon its intellectual adequacy to natural and human reality so far it is a failure and does not merit the attention of serious men." That is to say, either artistic representation is worthless, or, out of the conditions imposed and possibilities revealed by reproduction in the medium of appearance, there must be developed an aim and interest, other than the aim and interest presented by the reality which is represented. It should be added that al- though the conclusion as here stated and motived is absolutely just, yet there is also a minor question of true aesthetic in- volved in discussing the degree of the artist's actual know- ledge. Though his object is not to rival reality, but to seize its suggestions, he depends profoundly and increasingly on his knowledge of it, which Plato seems to us to under-estimate. The above negative result, together with the former and positive result that "Art has its being in appearance," not yet extended to the generalization "that beauty has its being in appearance," form the elements of permanent aesthetic value contained in the metaphysical principle upon which Hellenic theory concerning fine art is founded. iEstheac 3. We now approach the consideration of the Principle. Q„g t^yg aesthetic principle recognised by Hellenic antiquity in general. This may be described as the principle that beauty consists in the imaginative or sensuous expression of unity in variety. I call this an aesthetic principle in contradistinction to the moralistic and metaphysical principles which we have hitherto been examining, because it raises no question of other attri- butes or relations in the beautiful object, such as conducive- ness to virtue, or degree of reality, nor does it involve the assumption which underlies such questions, that art is a mere reflection of nature ; but it does, directly and in general form, attempt a solution of the problem, " What is the nature of beauty as a characteristic of experienced presentations } " FORMAL BEAUTY. 31 The Hellenic answer to such a question was necessarily- formal. The reasons for which art appeared at first to be the mere reproduction of reality are also the reasons which prohibited sesthetic analysis from insisting on the concrete significance of what is beautiful in man and in nature. So long as common reality — the object of average percep- tion — is regarded as the standard of art, there is an insur- mountable barrier against the identification of beauty with the spiritual expressiveness which only a higher perception can apprehend. Or, in other words, to accept the imitation of nature'^ in the widest sense as the function of art, is simply to state the problem of concrete beauty in the rudest manner possible, adniitting a total inability to solve it. For to say that the material of beautiful presentation is in some way drawn from the objects of sense-perception does not touch the question, " What can art do more than nature ? " But when we ask tn what respects, that is, in virtue of what general character or conditions, a reality, whether presented or repre- sented, is beautiful, then we have raised the specific question of aesthetic science. And to this a mimetic theory, for which one reality is, in strictness, as good a model as another, has ex hypothesi no answer. But there are simple cases and traits of beauty which either have nothing to do with the direct representation of life and nature, or are to be found in such representations merely as limiting conditions imposed by the same principles which con- stitute the entire content of the former and simpler cases of beauty. The analysis of these cases and characteristics is not barred by the mimetic theory, which has only a remote and metaphorical application to them. And although we asserted that for ordinary Greek life there was no unseen or spiritual world to which a sensuous presentation could be related as a mere symbol, yet the most general principles of action and knowledge soon became familiar to the intelligence of so gifted a race, and were naturally applied by its thinkers as spiritual principles to the analysis of such formal and abstract beauty as obviously did not consist in the reproduction of natural reality. In dealing with a true aesthetic conception we need not, as before, separate the account of its application from the esti- mate of its aesthetic value. A review of the cases in which it is applied, beginning with the most general statements of its \ 32 HISTORY OF ^ESTHETIC. range, forms the best criticism of the principle, which may be further elucidated at the close of this chapter by comparison with some modern researches. General state- a. The synthesis of the one and the many was, menta In Ancient as we all know, the central problem and the cen- writers. ^^.^j achievement of Greek philosophy. The con- ception of unity in variety is the indispensable basis of that idea of system or totality of interdependent parts, which was destined to be the structure erected by modern speculation upon the definite foundation laid by the Greek thinkers. The relation of whole to part — a slightly more concrete ex- pression for unity in variety — has never been more perfectly elucidated and more justly appreciated than by Plato and Aristotle, and it is in recognising the satisfaction afforded to the mind by the sensuous or imaginative embodiment of this relation that they make a first step in genuine aesthetic analysis. When we say with approval of a poem or of a musical composition, that it has a beginning, middle and end, we are probably not aware that we are repeating a principle which Aristotle, in dealing with the drama, after the precedent of a less explicit passage in Plato, ^ has defined with naive pro- foundness. "A tragedy ^ is a representation of a whole action — a whole is what has beginning, middle, and end. A begin- ning is what does not necessarily come after something else, but is so constituted as to have something else come after it ; an end, on the contrary, is what is so constituted as to come after something else but to have nothing after it ; and a middle is what is so constituted as to come after something else and also to have something else after it — for beauty depends upon size [so that the relation of the parts may be appreciable] and order." So, again, we may often hear about any beautiful object, " it would be impossible to add or take away the smallest part without spoiling it." This is genuine Greek esthetic. " Just as," Aristotle says,^ " in all other representative arts a single representation is of a single object, so the story [of a drama] being the representation of an action, must be of a single one, which is a whole ; and the parts of the scheme of incidents must be so arranged that if any part is transposed or removed i Fhcedrus, 268 D. See ch. iv. * Ar., Poet, vii. 1-4. » p^gf^^ yjjj ^ FORMAL BEAUTY. 33 the whole will be disordered and shattered ; for that of which the presence or absence makes no appreciable difference is no part of the whole." Moreover, the relation of the one to the many or of the part to the whole is represented in comparative purity by geometrical figures, or again by rhythms or spatial intervals that bear numerical relation to one another. And for this reason Greek philosophy is inclined to select mathematical form, ratio, or proportion, as the pure and typical embodi- ment of beauty. " Now since the good and the beautiful are different (for the former is always a property of action, but the latter extends to objects free from motion), those are mistaken who affirm that the mathematical sciences say nothing of beauty or good- ness. For they most especially discern and demonstrate the facts and definitions relating to them ; for if they demon- strate the facts and definitions relating to them, though with- out naming the qualities in question, that is not keeping silence about them. The main species [elements ? e'S^'] of beauty are order, symmetry, definite limitation, and these are the chief properties that the mathematical sciences draw attention to." ^ I subjoin a passage from Plato, to which reference will have to be made again. It is worth while to observe that almost all the actual material of Aristotle's thought, as distinct from the method of his treatment, may, as in this case, be discovered in Plato. " The principle of goodness has reduced itself to the law of beauty. For measure and proportion always pass into beauty and excellence." * " I do not mean by the beauty of form such beauty as that of animals or pictures, which the many would suppose to be my meaning; but, says the argument, understand me to mean straight lines and circles, and the plane and solid figures which are formed out of them by turning-lathes and rulers and measurers of angles ; for these I affirm to be not only relatively beautiful, like other things, but they are eternally and abso- lutely beautiful, and they have peculiar pleasures, quite unlike the pleasures of irritating an itching place (which has been taken above as the type of pleasure mixed with pain). And there are colours which are of the same character, and have similar pleasures. . . . When sounds are smo^h and ^ Ar., Metaph., 1078 a. ^ Fhilebus, marg., p. 64. D 34 HISTORY OF ESTHETIC. clear, and utter a single pure tone, then I mean to say they are not relatively but absolutely beautiful, and have a natural pleasure associated with them." * The exclusion of life and pictures of life, in this passage, from the realm of absolute beauty, to which regularity and unity are essential, is a striking case of the limitation which we have seen to be inherent in Greek aesthetics. The concrete individual unity which underlies the apparent disorder of the beauty of life was not likely to be appreciated until after the same principle had been recognised in the more abstract or formal cases and conditions of its embodiment. And it is plain that formal beauty, as recognised in such passages as these, of which all Greek philosophy is full, is constituted by a symbolic relation — a presentation to sense of a principle which is not sensuous. Such " presentation," in default of a more precise term, may sometimes be called an " imitation " ; * but it is impossible to " imitate " a non- sensuous principle in a sensuous medium. Particular /3. Of such symbolism or presentation we find casea. ^.j^g following principal cases to have attracted the attention of Plato or Aristotle. Colour and i- There is no more obvious type of unity appeal- Tone, jng J.Q sense than is to be found in the self-identica quality of a colour extended in space or of a tone extendec in time. These, as was shown in the passage quoted abovf from the Philebus, Plato recognised as beautiful,* and, accord ing to the whole context of the passage and the expression; employed in describing the sounds in question, for the reasoi here suggested, namely as sensuous presentations of unity Not, of course, that this is the reason apprehended by th« subject whose enjoyment is being analysed. That would a once transfer beauty from perception to reflection. It is onh suggested as the cause, observed and assigned by the theoris who is conducting the analysis ab extra. The same observation upon the beauty of pure colours am sounds as types of unity in diversity is made by Kant, am will have to be considered as a question of modern aesthetic It is obvious that not only the facts of artistic perception, bt the physical analysis furnished by science, throw a certai difficulty in the way of the explanation. For if "pure" mean Philebus, marg., p. 51. « RepubL, iii. 400 A. ^ Cf., Timaus, 80 B. FORMAL BEAUTY. 35 unmixed, as Kant defines it to mean, are such pure sounds or colours, even if they can be said to exist at all, the most beau- tiful ? It will be found however that the explanation will maintain itself, though in a more subtle form than that suggested by Plato, or even by Kant. Mr. Ruskin's account of " Purity as the type of divine energy," ^ while solving the difficulties referred to, presents a wonderful analogy with the idea as it first dawned on Plato. Elementary "• Elementary geometrical forms, even the °^^r^°^ straight line, and more particularly certain tri- angles, are set down as absolutely beautiful.^ We have interpreted this to mean that they are among the purest examples of unity in the form of simple regular or symmetrical shape. Strange as this assertion may appear to our aesthetic per- ception, which demands a more varied and concrete revelation of order or unity, I do not think that it can justly be denied. There is a degree of beauty belonging to every shape or structure which in any way affects perception with a sense of regularity or symmetry, that is, of the unity of parts in a whole as it displays itself where the whole is lacking in highly concrete differentiation. And if we bear in mind that architecture and decorative ornament, of the severe though refined type congenial to Greek civilisation, fell outside the frontier of imitative repro- duction, we may better understand how a Greek theorist might be content with a plain curve as a type of beauty, and how such a type might really involve a degree of delightful refine- ment which later ages have not again attained by such simple means. Plato indeed is apparently contemplating such ■examples as the straight line and the circle ; whereas, if our •experts may be trusted, these most abstract of shapes are replaced in Hellenic architecture and decoration by delicate curves due to the skilled eye and hand of the artist-workman. But this contrast would only show, what the whole history of aesthetic must illustrate that theory follows but tardily after practice. In such cases as the above, although the principle of unity is presented under very different sensuous embodiments, yet they all agree in being highly abstract, and the principle * Mod. Painters, vol. ii. * Phtlebus, \.c., Timaus, I.e., An, Metaph., l.c. 36 HISTORY OF ESTHETIC. therefore appears rather as their substance than as their limit- ing form. In any case we have here solid observations of jesthetic fact. If the explanation which Greek theory offers should appear inadequate, still it has done good service in drawing attention to these simple instances of beauty, which would in that case have to be dealt with on one or other of the two extreme views known respectively as Formal JEs- thetic, and as the .Esthetic of Feeling. We now turn to those cases in which the abstract principle of unity is plainly inadequate to the concrete significance of the content, and yet is the only aesthetic explanation of it which Greek theory could furnish. Here, then, organic unity though alleged to be the substange is in fact nothing more than the condition, of beauty, simple song- 111^ Plato's restriction of permissible music to music. yery simple song-tunes of a severe type, although it has a moralistic aspect, is also a result and example of his genuine but inadequate aesthetic. The long discussion of music and metre in the third book of the Republic, in which the conception of unity that permeates the ideal common- wealth is repeatedly contrasted with the multiplicity and variety inherent in imitative or dramatic music, makes it plain that the simple song-tune is acceptable to Plato partly because he is able to formulate to himself its symbolic function as expressive of a principle which has profound import for the soul. The music which he rejects is partly indeed for him expressive of evil — and so far his rejection of it is moralistic and not aesthetic — but to a far greater extent its defect in his eyes consists in being concretely reproductive of natural reality, and therefore not expressive of ideas nor related to life in any way that he is able to comprehend. And his refusal on this ground to recognise such music as healthy art is a proof of genuine aesthetic insight. What has no expres- siveness is not beautiful. As a matter of fact very simple tunes ^ have an unrivalled capacity of symbolising elementary' moods and ideas. Aristotle, following Plato, observes upon this phenomenon with results to which we shall have to return in the next chapter. EtMcaiand iv. The extreme generality of the principle which Logical •vmoies.y^e are tracing in its applications produced a dan- 1 Mr. L. Nettleship in Abbott's Helknica, p. 118. THE BEAUTIFUL SOUL. 37 ger of confusion which Greek philosophy did not entirely escape. But we must not overrate the extent of this evil. It is true that we constantly find in Plato fine arts or their productions compared, in respect of systematic reasonableness,^ both with moral or political relations and with industrial or non-representative crafts. But we must bear in mind that this is an absolutely just comparison, so long as it only serves to insist upon the common character of organic unity by help of the pre-eminent examples which fine art affords. The comparison of a member in a political whole to a feature in a statue,* with regard to the subordination which is essential in the one case as in the other, is perfectly adequate for the purpose for which Plato employs it. And no one is entitled to accuse him of a confusion between morality and aesthetic because he compares right and beauty in a point in which they are fairly comparable. But although it is an error to charge Plato on this ground with introducing ccsthetic ideas into ethical or logical reason- ings, yet there was one direction in which, owing to the generality of its principle, Greek aesthetic unquestionably cast its net too wide. Beauty, as we understand it, is only for sense aad„. for sensuous imaginaLtion. The " beautifiil soul " of modern] romance appears to derive its appellation from a metaphor which indicates a certain directness of delight afforded by the contemplation of its spiritual qualities, analogous to the direct- ness of delight which attends the perception of sensuous beauty. Beauty of soul, or beautyin the supra-sensupus world, as recognised by Greek philosophy,' depends upon a some- what similar metaphor, enforced by a degree of failure in differentiating the unreflective traditional use of the term "beautiful" and therefore partaking of the nature of a confusion, although an expressive confusion. More espe- cially the notion of an intellectual conception or archetype of beauty such as itself to be beautiful, is a very serious niis-| take in aesthetic. We should have hoped to find that beautyl was regarded as essentially the sensuous expression — not of the beautiful, nor even of the good — but simply of the real. 1 Republic, i. 349 D. ^ Republic, iv., init. ' Plato, Fheedrus, passim, and Ar., Rliet., 1366 A. 38 HISTORY OF iESTHETIC. This idea is plainly close at hand in the distinction between the beautiful and the good, but is destroyed by the co-ordina- tion of the two as equally archetypes in a supra-sensuous world. We must not however make the matter worse than it is. It is not the case that the principle of beauty, though in metaphorical passages spoken of as beautiful, was alleged to be the sole genuine beauty to the exclusion of the things of sense. Plato does not regard it as a mistake to believe in the beauty apparent to educated sense-perception ; on the contrary, both he and Aristotle make the acquisition of such perceptive capacity a main purpose of education. What he censures is not the belief in many beautiful things, but in many conflicting "beauties";* that is, conflicting principles or standards of beauty, nn. T-.., A^. V. Grantiner however that the generality of the Tie lesser Arts r^i 1 -111/- 1 and relation of whole and part misled the Greeks onna ve . j^^^ making their sesthetic theory too wide in one direction, it at least encouraged them not to make it too narrow in another. If they erred by including moral and mental qualities in beauty, they did not err, as modern philo- sophy has been apt to, by neglecting to notice the lesser arts and handicrafts as within the region of the beautiful. Al- though, as we have seen, the distinction between representa- tive and directly productive art was forcing itself into prominence in the fifth century b.c., yet no such contrast as that between art and industry had as yet entered into ordinary language ; and the profession, the trade, the craft, and the fine art, were all designated by the same term, and regarded alike as examples of reasonable systematic activity. And wherever such activity took form in objects that ap- pealed to sense-perception, there, for the Greek philosopher, the aesthetic sphere was entered. But with regard to the content to be expressed in their varied concrete shapes, from the works of architecture and decoration and the accompanying lesser crafts of life to the great independent formative arts of painting and sculpture, theory in Hellenic antiquity takes us no deeper than the analysis which seemed adequate for the beauty of a simple ^ Republic, V. 479 D, "Ta tSof jroXXSv TroXXa voutua KaXoS re irepi koX ruiy aUa)V.» EXPRESSIVE WORKMANSHIP. 3a curve, say, of a plain moulding, or of a single colour or tone. " And ' all life is full of them," we read in the Republic^ at the close of the discussion on music and metre before re- ferred to, " as well as every constructive and creative art — painting, weaving, embroidery, the art of building, the manu- facture of utensils, as well as the frames of animals and of plants ; in all of them there is grace* or the absence of grace." It is worth noticing that the beauty of animals and of plants is here mentioned in the same line with the beauty of various arts, showing how impossible it is to distinguish in any theoretical treatment between the direct perception or beauty of nature and the artistic perception or beauty of art. The limitation is remarkable as well as the inclusion. We find nothing about the mountains, or the sea, or the sky, and might have risked the suggestion that the forms of inanimate nature had not caught the eye of the Greek artist and critic, were it not for the magnificent sense of cloud movement, revealed without warning or sequel by Aristophanes.* Certainly how- ever the Greek expression for " painter" in the sense of artist — a painter of living things — is full of strange suggestiveness. In all this region of expressive workmanship, which we must judge not merely by its relics but by written records, aesthetic theory had nothing to point out but propriety of form (" grace "), rhythm, symmetry or balance. But in presence of concrete significance and expression all these ideas sink into postulates, that the relation of the unity to the diversity or of the whole to the part shall be right and just ; shall be, that is to say, whatever the individual import of the presentation may demand, subject to a general regard for the principle of systematic reasonableness as one that can never be neglected without loss in any sensuous or imaginative expression. Much as these postulates signified to the Greeks— whose splendid composition, we are told, distinguishes their commonest work * from that of all other beauty-loving men — they are in themselves, for aesthetic theory, mere abstract formulae or conditions, embodying only the fundamental fact that system is the first law of expression. Poetry wid the vi. And even in reflecting upon the most Drama. profoundly human of all arts, upon poetry and 1 Republic, Jowett's trans., marg., p. 401. « ^S,vaxi)^oa