-. •.-■■ 1(4- Gc8S 1&78 ATHENIAN CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY FROM Cornell University Library DF 214.G88S36 1878 Athenian constitutional history 3 1924 028 262 214 The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924028262214 ATHENIAN CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY. V ATHENIAN CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY, AS REPRESENTED IN GROTE'S HISTORY OF GREECE, CRITICALLY EXAMINED BY GlF. SCHOMANN: translate, toit| i\t $at|0r's pxmma% BEBNAED BOSANQDET, M.A. FELLOW AND TUIOB. OE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE, OXEOSD. JAMES PARKER AND CO. 1878. 1 . . \i I- 1 1 V 'CORNELL UNIVERSITY! LIBRARY TBANSLATOK'S PKEFACE. rpHE conclusions reached in this criticism (pub- lished, 1854) are substantially the same as those of the corresponding part of Professor Schomann's Handbuch (Berlin, 1870). This criticism, however, deals at length with the relation of Grote's opinions to the ancient authorities ; and is, therefore, of spe- cial interest and importance to English students, who may desire to verify what they read in Grote or in Curtius. It may be advantageously used as a commentary on the " Materials for the History of Athenian Democracy, from Solon to Pericles," re- cently collected by Mr. Case, to which reference might have been made on every page ; but a gene- ral reference here is sufficient. The references to Grote's pages are to the eight volume edition of 1862 ; the chapters, which are the same in all editions, have been added, to facili- tate reference. The division into sections, their headings, and the table of contents, are the work of the translator; who has also added a few notes in brackets [ ]. TABLE OF CONTENTS. § 1. Introductory ...... 1 § 2. The Four Tribes and their Divisions : — (a.) Their Names significant . . . . 3 (5.) Local as well as Family Unions . . .10 (e.) Eelation of Wvr\ and rpWrves to Phratries . . 12 § 3. Eelations between the towns op Attika before Stncecism . . . . .15 § 4. Drako . . . . . . .17 § 5. Solon: — (a.) Was there Democratic sentiment in his time ? . 19 (b.) Grote's mis-reading of Plutarch . . .20 (c.) Seisachtheia and Amnesty . . . .21 (d.) Timocratic Classification . . . .23 (e.) Principles on which distinction is to he made be- tween Solonian and later institutions . . 27 (/.) List of Solon's Constitutional enactments . . 34 {g.) Passages examined (on Powers of Assembly, and Judicial function of People) . . .35 (h.) Helisea and Popular Assembly were not the same . 38 (*'.) (i.) There were Dikasteries. (ii.) The Assembly could not legislate, (i.) There were Dikasteries. (a.) Examination of Passages . . .40 (/3.) Other Courts, lightening the work of the Dikasteries. Local Judges (koto Sf/fiovs SiKaarraV) . . 45 Disetetse . . . . .46 Nautodikse . ... 50 Archons' Judicial powers not such as to ex- clude Dikasteries .... ib. Eelation of Disetetse to Dikasteries . . 52 (y.) Comparison of Province of earlier and later DikasterieB . . . .54 V1U TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE (ii.) The Assembly could not legislate, (a.) Procedure before Nomothetse in the time of Demosthenes . . . .56 (0.) No improbability in the enactment of such a procedure by Solon . . .58 (y.) Grote's arguments against Solonian origin of Nomothetae . . . .60 § 6. Kleisthenes: — («.) Kleisthenes made only 100 Demes . . .64 (5.) Kleisthenes made 50 Naukraries . . .68 (c.) Kleisthenes admitted no free native Athenians to the Franchise . . . . .69 (d.) Difference between Orgeones and Gennetae . 71 («.) Institutions connected with the Ten Tribes . 72 (/.) The Lot introduced by Kleisthenes . . 73 (g.) The Areopagus in the time of Kleisthenes . . 82 (A.) Ostracism abused by the Athenians . . 85 («'.) Form of Procedure in Ostracism . . .86 (&.) Kleisthenes' Reforms not before 507 b.c. . . 87 § 7. Changes between Kleisthenes and Peeikles . ib. § 8. Changes under Pebiexes: — (a.) List of Changes mentioned by the Ancients, and also of those vouched for by Grote . .88 (5.) Not improbable that these latter Institutions were older than Perikles . . . .89 (c.) Judicial pay at first one Obol . . .93 (d.) Aikoi curb a-vfi^oXav included all Law-suits carried on by Allies at Athens . . . .94 § 9. The Eevision of the Laws undeb Eubxetdes not caused by the amnesty . . .96 § 10. Reasons eob Abistophon's Law about Citizenship . 98 §11. Peoposal oe Phoemisius to eesteict the Feanchise not Oligaechic . . . . .100 § 12. Ceiticism oe Geote's estimate oe the Athenian De- mocracy ...... 103 ^rbimtatm on the (Emtatittrtiottal § 1. Introductory. TN his History of Greece, Mr. Grote has produced a work, the study of which cannot be too urgently recommended to all who are concerned to acquaint themselves with Greek Antiquity. It presents a combination of merits which few historical works of any kind present in the same degree ; and certainly none of the works which have hitherto treated of Greek History. It displays the most accurate acquaint- ance, based on the profoundest and most comprehensive studies, with the whole of Greek antiquity, as far as its productions have come down to us ; the most careful con- sideration of modern researches, in all cases where consi- deration is due; penetrating criticism in the employment both of the authorities, and of the results which moderns have obtained from them ; and finally, a clear, intelligible, and interesting narrative style, by which the reader's in- tellect, and where the subject allows of such treatment, his sympathies and feelings as well, are roused and delighted. His familiar intercourse with the works of the Hellenic past, has imbued the author with the mind and spirit of that past : he can live, as it were, with the ancient Hellenes ; and he thinks and feels as a contemporary of the men whose acts and destiny he narrates. Yet, though he so perfectly adopts the stand -point of the times of which he writes, so thoroughly enters into the modes of thought and feeling of the men whom he sets before us, and though he is so ready to follow them in all their connections, relations, and ten- dencies, still he always maintains the attitude of the im- partial observer who is on a higher level than his subject ; the liveliest sympathy with the actors does not impair the independence and impartiality of his judgment. 2 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. The history of Greece must, of course, be especially a his- tory of Athens, — the eye of Greece, the Prytaneum and sacred hearth of the Hellenic world, the Hellas within Hellas. In saying that Mr. Grote has written of Athens in a way worthy of his subject, I conceive that I am giving praise which is at once his due, and the highest that can be desired. These words of praise, and of genuine gratitude for the abundant profit which I draw from repeated readings of his work, are a preface which I hold myself bound to prefix to the following pages, which are devoted to the discussion of some of the subjects, his account of which appears to me less satisfactory. The reason why the public discussion of these subjects seems to me not to be superfluous, is that the great esteem in which Mr. Grote's work is held by all who know it — and I hope that there may be many who do so even in Germany, not to speak of England, where it has been received with the most unanimous applause— may very easily have the effect of causing views put forward by Mr. Grote, to pass for the right ones with most readers, merely because it is he that puts them forward. "Where- ever he has occasion to doubt or dispute the views of his predecessors, Mr. Grote shews himself so profound and cautious a critic, that this at once inclines us to presume that he would not have brought forward what he does as his own view without the same profound and cautious criticism, and that it therefore merits entire confidence. But no judicious person, least of all Mr. Grote himself, will be offended if, in spite of my complete recognition of the excellence of his work as a whole, I do not conceal that there are many points on which I have to regret the absence of the pro- foundness and the care which his critical procedure else- where displays. I do not propose to write a review of his whole work, but will confine myself to a particular part, which I cannot persuade myself that Mr. Grote has treated more correctly than his predecessors, from whom he deviates in many points. This part is one which of course is among the most important, viz. the constitution of Athens, and the various stages of its growth. I intend very shortly to produce a more popular account The Four Tribes. 3 of Greek antiquities, in which the Athenian polity will naturally have a principal place; the present work may serve as an anticipatory justification, if in that account I merely, for the most part, repeat what I have formerly asserted in other writings about the Athenian polity, with- out entering into Mr. Grote's divergent views, for the esti- mation of which the plan of the work alluded to affords no suitable place. § 2. The .Four Tribes and their Divisions. (a.) Their Names significant. In point of fact, the history of the Athenian constitution only begins with the legislation of Solon. This was the basis of the constitution of later times, which we know from our authorities with tolerable completeness » and accuracy •' though in many cases it cannot be determined with cer- tainty, how much in the later constitution should be as- cribed to Solon, and how much to later legislators, who built on the foundations which he laid. About the times before Solon, and the earliest institutions of the state, we find in our authorities only a few isolated notices, in part obviously fictitious, from which little can be drawn that is of value for history. We hear of a union of several communities, previously separate, into a single collective state; divisions of the people by clans and classes are noticed; we are told how archons were instituted after the abolition of the monarchy, at first hereditary with a life tenure, then decennial, then an annual college of nine; and finally, there are hints of one or another deli- berative or judicial authority ; but all the more definite points of the constitution and administration are wrapped in deep obscurity, to illuminate which we have no means at command. Here, as elsewhere, there has not been want- ing an abundance of attempts to fill up the gaps in our knowledge by conjectures, and many of these conjectures cannot be denied the merit of ingenuity: but of course this gives them no claim to rank as history. Mr. Grote, rightly feeling that it is one thing to write history, and b2 4 Schdmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. another to make ingenious conjectures, has not only refrained from them himself, but has for the most part passed over in silence those of earlier authors ; and his doing so merits nothing but approval. Still there is one point in which he seems to have carried his critical reserve a little too far, and to have rejected a view which results so necessarily from unambiguous indications, that it may claim to rank as more than a mere conjecture. This point concerns the question about the original constitution of the four ancient tribes of the Athenian people, of which question I must therefore permit myself to speak somewhat in detail. The most ancient division of the people, the reality of which cannot be doubted, is that into the four tribes (Phylae), Geleontes, Hopletes, Argadeis, and iEgikoreis; which, according to the legend mentioned in Herodotus (5. 66) and Euripides (Ion, 1. 1575 ff.), were derived from the four sons of Ion, the mythical Eponymus of the Ionic race. This traditional derivation was the reason which impelled the writers of Atthides, at a later time, to venture upon conjectures as to an earlier tribal division antecedent to that in question. As the prevailing legend did not place Ion at the head of Athenian history, but named a succession of kings previous to him, the question forced itself upon these antiquaries, whether there were not tribes in the times before Ion also, and what they were. It is obvious that this question could only be answered by hypotheses. The number of the ancient tribes which hypothesis was to furnish did not need to exceed four, because there were no more of the historical Ionic tribes, and there was no reason to suppose that any larger number had been decreased by a union of several tribes into one ; and further, there was no occasion for assuming fewer than four. So the number was retained, and names were easily found for the four tribes, partly from the denominations of the principal dis-. tricts of the country; partly, perhaps, from traces of the cultus formerly prevalent in these districts. As an inscription recently discovered indicates Zeus Geleon to have been the tribal deity of the Geleontes, we may assume that the other tribes had also their tribal The Four Tribes. 5 deities; the ^Jgikoreis perhaps Athene, which may have induced Euripides to derive their name from the aegis of the goddess, the Hopletes Poseidon, the Argadeis Heph- aestus. Hence were obtained the four tribes, Dias, Athenais, Poseidonias, Hephasstias. But the mere possibility that this may have been so, is all that any judicious person would maintain. The division, alleged to be yet more ancient, into the tribes Kekropis, Autochthon, Aktsea, Paralia ; and again into Kranais, Atthis, Mesogsea, and Diakris, is ob- viously a pure invention. We may imagine tribes like Mesogsea, Aktsea, Paralia, Diakris; but no one can help regarding it as a mere conceit, that in this extraordinary way there should be aseribed to the same time two tribes Aktsea and Paralia, named after local districts, and two named not after districts, but after something else; and that the same extraordinary fact should have repeated itself in a subsequent change of names, the two which before got their names elsewhere being now named after districts, and the two before named after districts now getting named elsewhere. This is so, apart from the objection that might be taken to names like Atthis, Autochthon, and Kranais. Yet, however little we may believe these notices, we are not on that account to deny them all value. At least, they furnish an indication that the antiquaries with whom they originated, are to be counted as believing that the tribe- division was connected with the local division, and that the inhabitants of one and the same district were also associates of one and the same tribes, and that therefore the ancient tribes were local divisf ns (v\al tottlkuI) as well. Now some moderns, among \ horn is Mr. Grote, are disposed to regard them as family divisions (v\a/ces, as he calls them — he meant the Hopletes ; and likewise, that in speaking of the handi- craftsmen (Srjfuovpyols), he could only be thinking of the Argadeis. So there remain only the Greleontes and ZEgi- koreis for the priests (lepoiroioi), and the field-labourers (yempyoi), and it is open to every one to choose which he will consider as corresponding to which. I need hardly add an assurance in so many words, that I am not referring to Strabo, with the idea that instruction is really to be got from him about the system of the old tribes and their occu- pations, but only as evidence for the assertion, that even The Four Tribes. 7 the ancients believed in a connection between the tribes and the crafts or professions. Besides, Strabo's view about the crafts was clearly determined by Plato, who in the Timseus represents a division corresponding to the Egyptian castes as existing in primitive times in Attika as well, consisting of priests; craftsmen; a third class including shepherds, hunters, and field-labourers ; and lastly the war- riors. We can see that the first of these classes is Strabo's iepoiroioi, the second his Brj/jaovpyoi, the third his v)Ca,l yevmal (associations based on relationship). This is at once plain from the names of their subdivisions, the Phratries and Gentes, which clearly express a connection of relationship ; and if we enquire into the natural process of origin, it is obvious that the Gens came first, the union of several Gentes or the Phratry second, and the union of several Phratries or the Phyle third, in suc- cession. But here we must bear in mind that, although the political order is erected on the foundation of the natural, still in erecting it the natural order of things is more or less re- duced to system, and a certain degree of symmetry is intro- duced, even if it is not rigidly carried out. This result cannot be attained without interferences, and artificial ex- pedients of various kinds. Some of the ancients tell us about an equal number of households, or families, viz. thirty in every Gens, and the same number, viz. again thirty, of Gentes in the Phratry; so that, as there were three Phratries in each of the four tribes, the total number of the Phratries would be equal to the months, and that of the Gentes to the days in the year. All this I am inclined, in agreement with Mr. Grote a , to hold as a mere imagination, such as in this particular way had never been realised in fact. Still, the number of three Phratries in a tribe need not be doubted, and some sort of symmetry in the subdivisions is at least not improbable. Only it is certain that such an arrange- ment could not be initiated till after the accomplishment of the union, in a single collective state, of the earlier separate ' Vol.iii.p.269. d Ibid., p. 265. The Four Tribes. 11 communities ; which the legend ascribes to Theseus. But at the time when this political order was instituted, there can be no doubt that the Phylse and their divisions were asso- ciations connected by place as well as by relationship. The members of the same Gens, Phratry, and Tribe were also, in primitive times, residents of the same localities, and each of these divisions had its own district ; so that the country was divided into as many districts, large and small, as there were Gentes, Phratries, and Tribes. In later times, we find many Demes, or districts, called after Gentes; this is an unmistakable indication that the Gens after which it was called was resident in the district ; not that a single Gens possessed the whole territory, but that the name was given to the district from the most conspicuous among several Gentes e . What is true of the Gentes, is true also of course of the Phratries, i.e. just as the families composing a single Gens lived together in a single district, the Gentes composing a single Phratry also lived together in a single district of greater extent. That this view was not unknown to the ancients is shewn by this, among other reasons, that some one proposed as an explanation of the word " Phratry," that they had a common well (cj>peap). However bad this ex- planation may be, it is quite clear that it could not have been so much as suggested, unless the Phratries had been known as associations united by place as well as blood. About the tribes, I have already remarked that several of the names which they were imagined to have borne before the time of Ion were taken from portions of the country ; and therefore prove that the antiquaries who invented these names, must necessarily have conceived the Phylse as local, each possessing a portion of the country. Now, as long as such a relation existed — and, in sub- stance, it must always have existed — the word " Phyle " e Buttmann, Phratries, Mythol., ii. p. 232, believes Budzeus to be the author of this explanation, which he does not himself absolutely reject. No doubt it is proposed by Budseus in the Comra. 1. gr. ; but that it is ancient, ap- pears from Serving on Virg. 2En., vii. 286. The name a$d, too (= So, oXa, ovi, £><£) , means properly, a separate district. See Hemsterhus. on Hesych. in oval, Miiller, Dor., b. ii. c. 5, 3, and Bockh, ii. p. 713, where " Geschlecht" is written for " Phratrie " by an oversight [?]. 12 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. might be used in two senses : it might mean the part of the country in which the tribe resided, or it might mean the total of the tribe members, of whom the majority were no doubt resident in that part of the country, though indi- viduals might have migrated and settled in another district. This double meaning of the word must be borne in mind, if we would understand and estimate correctly the notices of the ancients about subdivisions of the Phylae other than those already mentioned. (c.) Relation ofeOvq and rplrrves to Phratries. That is to say, we are told of edvq and t/htti/69, and even that there were three of them in each tribe, so that their number was the same as that of the Phratries; and this equality in numbers has misled many into regarding the actual subdivisions as identical, and into believing that (pparpia, edvos, Tpirrvs, are only different names for one and the same thing. That this is a mistake is now generally recognised. The name edvos applies to the division into the three classes of the Eupatrids, Geomori, and Demiurgi, i.e. the nobility, the non-noble landowners, and the work- ing-classes ; and there is no doubt that each of these classes was contained in every tribe, probably even in every Phra- try, though not in equal numbers in every instance. About their political importance we only know this much, that all rights relating to political administration were in the hands of the Eupatrids, or nobility ; as it was exclusively from among them that the members of the senate, the magis- trates, and the priests, were taken. The two other classes were excluded from these privileges, and there was in this respect no difference between them ; so that it may seem as if, in political position, there were only two distinct classes, the noble and the non-noble. It is true that many writers have assumed, besides the noble and the non-noble, but free classes, yet a third class, of field-labourers who were not free, the origin of which they explained by a supposed con- quest of the country by Ionians, who had partially or en- tirely subdued the old Pelasgic population, and depressed The Four Tribes. 13 them into a position like that of Helots or Penestae. But, in reality, there is no justification for this assumption ; and as Mr. Grote does not adopt it, there is no need for speaking further of it here. Of the Trittyes we are told, that each of them con- tained four " Naukraries," each of which was under one or more Presidents, "Naukrars," who are compared with the later instituted " Demarchs, " as the Naukraries are with the Demes. They were therefore local divisions ; and, consequently, the Trittyes, or unions of four Naukraries each, were so too. Now, though the grammarians were wrong in identifying e9vr), or classes, with the Phratries, were they perhaps right in regarding Trittyes and Phra- tries as the same thing? If, as we saw above, the Phra- tries, too, are divisions of the Phyle, united not merely by kinship, but in locality as well, composed of fellow-inhabit- ants of the same district, what was the use of yet another division of the Phyle into the same number of districts as there were Phratry districts already existing? "What Mr. Grote puts forward' as the relation between the two kinds of subdivision is not calculated to assist us to clear views on the subject. He says, " These four tribes may be looked at either as religious and social aggregates, in which capacity each of them comprised three Phratries and ninety Gentes ; or as political aggregates, in which point of view each included three Trittyes and twelve Naukraries." " Com- paring these two distributions one with the other, we may remark, that they are distinct in their nature, and proceed in opposite directions." The Trittyes and Naukraries are subdivisions of the tribe, framed with a purpose, and resting upon the tribe as their higher unity ; the forty-eight Nauk- raries, as local circumscriptions, are a systematic subdivision of the four tribes, and embrace the whole territory ; while, on the contrary, the Phratries and Gentes are aggregates of natural origin, not united into tribes till a later time. It cannot be denied that this is all correct ; but it is not adequate. It does not help us to understand how the Trittyes and Naukraries, which are rightly designated as ' Vol. iii. pp. 264, 5. 14 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. local circumscriptions, can at the same time have been sub- divisions of the Phylse, which Mr. Grote has represented to us only as family tribes, formed by the union of (rentes and Phratries, which originate naturally, and therefore rest on kinship only; so that the Phylse are represented only as parts of the people, not as parts of the country. His ac- count is, therefore, open to the objection, that it leaves un- noticed the double meaning of the Phylse. But, as regards the relation of the Trittyes to the Phratries, it is obviously less probable that the two names mean the same thing, than that they mean something different ; and hence it may per- haps be assumed, that at the time when the Trittyes and Naukraries were organized the Phratries had already ceased to be local districts too, though they had formerly been so, just as much as the tribes. Also, it is easily conceivable that the primitive connection between the family and the residence of the members was destroyed sooner and more completely in the smaller divisions, or Phratries, than in the larger division, or Phylse; and that therefore the for- mer continued to exist as divisions of the people, and not as districts, while the Phylse continued to be both the one and the other. Therefore, when it was purposed to divide the Phylse districts into smaller sections, it was impossible to employ the Phratries for the purpose, and a completely new division had to be undertaken. Moreover, this division was certainly the work of a tolerably late age, not long before Solon's legislation. " Naukrars," or " ship-headmen " was the name given to those who had to equip a ship of war and command the crew, like the Trierarchs of later times; " Naukraria," or " people of a ship-headman," was the name thence given to the districts to which the Naukrars, bound to provide a ship, severally belonged. Athens can hardly have had ships of war before the time of her beginning the war with Megara for Salamis, when she came to need a naval force; and these wars belong to the age of Solon. Mr. Grote e agrees in thinkiug that the Naukraries are an institution of later times, but h he doubts the correctness of explaining the B P. 266. k p. 264. The Four Tribes. 15 Dame by the obligation to provide a ship ; and prefers, with Wachsmuth and others, to derive it from valeiv, " to dwell," and make it mean a "principal householder." How im- probable this view is has been well pointed out by Bockh, in a note to the second edition of the " Public Economy of Athens," i. 708 ; and I am convinced that if Mr. Grrote had been acquainted with that note, he would have given up his opinion. § 3. Relations between the towns of Attika BEFORE SyNCECISM. It has been remarked above, that the organization of the Phylse, and their subdivisions, could not have been intro- duced before the union of the whole people in a single state, which union the legend attributes to Theseus. In what sort of relation the small separate states stood to each other before his time, cannot be more precisely ascertained, except for what may be gathered from Thukydides' ' account in the second book ; even the notices in Strabo and others of twelve towns, which would have to be regarded as the centres of as many smaller states, have no claim to pass for certain historical tradition; perhaps they owe their origin merely to the circumstance, that those twelve towns were known as the former centres of the twelve Phratries. A connection between the towns and the Phratries has been thought of by Ignarra and Buttmann before me, and indeed nothing can be more obvious ; the objections which others have brought against it are proved, on closer consideration, to be wholly without weight. An inscription gives us the name of a Phratry, '/i^waSae, which is, moreover, the only one we know of ; so as those twelve towns are none of them called Achnia or Achnise, it has been attempted to infer that there could be no connection whatever between them and the Phratries. This inference rests merely on the assumption, that the Phratries must necessarily have been named after the capital towns of their districts, or the towns after the Phratries; an assumption, the ground- 1 Thuk.,ii. 15. 16 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. lessness of which is obvious at first sight, especially if we recollect that the Phratries were of earlier origin than the towns or villages, which gradually arose in their districts, and one of which, the most important, or the most con- veniently situated, became the capital of the Phratry. How- ever, Mr. Grote has simply not touched upon this question, and in general has not permitted himself to put forward conjectures on the relations of that most primitive time. And of this course I cannot but approve, still, I find in his pages k an idea put forward concerning Eleusis, and its re- lation to Athens, which appears to me to rest on reasoning that is overhasty and unfounded. From the Homeridic 1 hymn to Demeter, — which all through treats Eleusis as a separate state, without the least mention of Athens, or of a relation of the Athenians to the cult of the goddess, — Mr. Grote thinks himself justified in inferring that at the time when the hymn was composed, according to Voss about the thir- tieth Olympiad, Eleusis was still autonomous and indepen- dent of Athens. As if the poet must needs have touched upon the conditions of his own time, and would not rather confine himself to those of the primitive age in which his story's scene is laid, and when Eleusis was of course in- dependent of Athens. It would be equally justifiable to assert, that at the time when the Iliad was composed, there were as yet no Ionic or iEolic colonies on the coast of Asia Minor, because the poem speaks of other inhabitants all over that region ; or that there were no Herakleid and Doric states in Peloponnese, because the poet displays to us there nothing but kingdoms of Neleidse and Pelopidse. The second argument, drawn from Herodotus, is no better founded. In Herodotus' m story, Solon tells Krcesus of a certain Athenian named Tellus, who had fallen yevojjuivqs fidxVi wpbs tovavr)s ov&Ca) and not in land, into the lowest class of citizens, ranking him with the Thetes. But as regards taxation, it was possible if that took place, to impose on such a man, in spite of his position in the classes, a burden proportioned to his property. And we may be sure that in Solon's time, there were very few well-to-do citizens who were not land- owners. After the fall of the thirty, when Phormisius proposed the law that only landowners should retain full citizenship, there were about 5,000 persons, a quarter of the citizen body, who would have been excluded if the law had passed. Therefore even then, after Athens had for long been chiefly a maritime and commercial state, and while Peirseus was inhabited by a trading and manufacturing population Solon. 27 hardly less numerous than the population of the capital, still three-quarters of the citizens were landowners; how many more must have been so in Solon's time. But, above all, we must notice the possibility that Solon's classification may not have referred at all to taxation, but solely to the qualification for office, and to the obligation of military service. According to Thukydides *, the first property-tax (ela(popd) was raised about 01. 88. 1 ; not merely the first in the Peloponnesian war, but the first that was raised at all, as Bockh rightly interprets the statement of the his- torian. Whether any similar taxation existed at an earlier time, and if it did, on what principles it was arranged, we do not know. So we may regard the estimate of the Ti/jL-rifjiaTa or taxable capital, and the rules of its ratio to the landed property in each class, as an enactment which was not framed by the author of the class division, and was not devised till a later time. (rj irapavoixav, whether it is a Solonian or a later institution, we shall probably remain undecided about it, as about many ' Vol. ii. p. 323. " P. 324. b Dr. Tbirlwall, indeed, as I now see, speaks of 6,000 Heliasts, even in his account of Solon ; but this is an oversight, which might easily be excused. 30 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. other things, until a criterion is established which will dis- tinguish with precision between what is Solonian and what is not. If any one were to hope that Mr. Grote had pro- posed such a criterion, he would be disappointed. "We are, indeed, told that the Heliastic oath, which Demosthenes designates as Solonian, must necessarily be accounted later, because the Council of Five Hundred is mentioned in it; and this is a criterion which no one can doubt, but which is of very little service to us. All we learn from it is, that the oath in that form, in which it occurs in Demosthenes, could not have been prescribed by Solon ; (which, moreover, would follow from the language alone, without the mention of the Five Hundred ;) but this does not explain how much of the actual contents of the oath may belong to Solon's regulations, and how much to a later redaction. Mr. Grote says e , " Many of those institutions which Dr. Thirlwall mentions in conjunction with the name of Solon, are among the last refinements and elaborations of the de- mocratical mind of Athens, — gradually prepared, doubtless, during the interval between Kleisthenes and Perikles, but not brought into full operation until the period of the lat- ter; for it is hardly possible to conceive these numerous Dikasteries and assemblies in regular, frequent, and long- standing operation, without an assured payment to the Dikasts who composed them. Now such payment first began to be made about the time of Perikles." " It wonld be a marvel, such as nothing short of strong direct evidence would justify us in believing, that in an age when even partial democracy was as yet untried, Solon should conceive the idea of such institutions; it would be a marvel still greater, that the half-emancipated Thetes and small pro- prietors, for whom he legislated, — yet trembling under the rod of the Eupatrid archons, and utterly inexperienced in collective business, should have been found suddenly com- petent to fulfil these ascendant functions, such as the citizens of conquering Athens in the days of Perikles — full of the sentiment of force, and actively identifying themselves with the dignity of their community — became gradually com- • P. 325. Solon. 31 petent, and not more than competent, to exercise with effect." Of course, these observations are quite true. But how far they can furnish us a sure clue for ascertaining what it is possible that Solon may have enacted, and what it is not, will require more accurate consideration. Solon, Mr. Grote often insists, found no Democracy in any part of Greece ; down to his time, after the abolition of monarchy, there had been nothing anywhere but Oligarchy (that is, the rule of a privileged class, strictly exclusive as against outsiders) or the government, supported by force, of the persons known as tyrants. Now it is true that the scanty historical data which we find in the writings of ancients for the time immediately before Solon, inform us of nothing but this; and so it cannot be proved that there was anything different in other places. Achaia is the only country of which we hear d that in it Democracy, not Oligarchy, fol- lowed directly on the fall of the monarchy. This was, beyond a doubt, a very moderate Democracy, one in which participation in political power was not granted indiscri- minately to every individual, but only in a gradation regu- lated in proportion to property : this is what was more accurately called a Timocracy, and what Solon actually in- troduced at Athens. The Achsean constitution was famous, and was afterwards taken as a model by the states of Magna Grascia ; but, unfortunately, we do not know when the fall of the monarchy took place in Achaia ; and if any one an- nounced his belief that it might not have taken place till after Solon's time, we could no more refute him, than on the other side any one could be refuted who chose to conceive the event as earlier, as Dr. Thirlwall does, for instance. Now it is not on this point only, but on all earlier con- ditions and constitutional changes in almost all Greek states, that our information is slight and defective. Hence I may be permitted to suggest, at least as a possibility, that there may have been Democracies here and there even before Solon's legislation, of course moderate and limited, but still conceding to the mass of the citizens a proportionally gradu- J Polyb., ii. 41, 5 ; Strabo, viii. 384. 32 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. ated share in the essential rights of citizenship. If so, the doctrine, that down to that time nothing was anywhere known but Oligarchy and Tyranny, ought not to have been alleged as one. established by facts, but only as a conjecture, however probable ; so that the opposite conjecture is not to be absolutely rejected by comparison with it, as wholly un- allowable. But I will even lay no stress on this conjecture, because there is no proof that goes to establish it. If there was really no Democratic constitution, and no reasonable distribution of popular rights anywhere in Greece, still there were Democratic movements for a considerable time before Solon ; that is to say, there was ill-feeling and discontent among the masses of the unprivileged people at the pri- vileged position of a single class ; and there were party leaders who utilised this ill-feeling and discontent in gain- ing the help of the masses to overthrow the rule of the pri- vileged few, as was done by Orthagoras at Sikyon, Eypselus at Korinth, and Theagenes at Megara. It is true that the majority of the discontented aimed at no more than this, and were satisfied with freedom from the oppression of the earlier rule, without desiring a share in the government for them- selves; this was what made it possible for those party- leaders to appropriate the sovereignty after the fall of the oligarchs; and the mass of the people was the more easily pleased with the change, the more they saw the oligarchs kept under, and themselves secured against them. But the mass is not the whole people. There cannot but have been many whose wishes and ideas went further, and who chafed under the tyranny as much as they had chafed under the oligarchy ; while they pictured to themselves a state of things as possible and desirable, in which they, and those like them, should enjoy the freedom and justice that were their due. And it would certainly happen that the measure which constituted what was due, would appear different to different people; and there cannot have been wanting those who demanded equal freedom and equal pri- vileges for all, though they might be far from clear as to the possibility of satisfying such demands, or their capacity of using what was demanded, if realised, rightly, i.e. for Solon. 33 the good of the community. Such phenomena as these had, without doubt, presented themselves to the observation of Solon, the largest mind of his own age, as Mr. Grote rightly calls him e , in more than one of the Greek states. They presented themselves in Athens as well, though there as yet no tyranny had arisen, for the Oligarchy had suc- ceeded in defending itself against an attempt in that direc- tion. But the discontent and disaffection of the people were as great here as anywhere else ; and they had, to guide them, the experience of tyranny which other states had endured. Part of the people, no doubt, were naturally inclined to purchase the fall of the Oligarchy even at this cost ; but on the other hand, there were just as many who did not care to exchange one rule for another, and who desired freedom. Of these the unwise would wish for uni- versal equality, the wise for only such freedom as the people was capable of using, that is, gradations of political right. This is how Plutarch describes to us the feeling of the people in Solon's time, and his description carries with it the proof of its truth. Solon belonged neither to those who wished for the continuance of the Oligarchy, nor to those who thought equality without distinctions either possible or desirable; he was of the party of moderates, but had maturely reflected on the measure in which freedom should be bestowed, and on the due and appropriate gra- dation of rights and privileges as well as of obligations, taking account of property and civic virtue. It is impos- sible to determine how much, in these respects, he drew from his own reflection, and how much from experience and precedent ; but this much is clear, that he placed confidence in the people who had confided constituent powers to him ; and that he did not consider the lower classes, for all the oppression they had lived under, unworthy or incompetent to assume a share in departments of state which were far from unimportant. Such functions he calls by the name, not of Democracy (a word which perhaps had not come into existence), but Sr/fiov Kpdros, which really expresses - Vol. vi. 39, part ii. 67. D 34 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. just the same thing. He says, Ar^iw fiev yap eSaica roaov Kpa,TO9 yap Brj tov B^fiov, irporepov aTraxr- fievov irdvTcov, tot€ irphs rfjv eavrov fioiprjv irpoiredrjKaTO, k.t.X. From this Mr. Grote infers, that if Kleisthenes found the people excluded from everything, Solon could hardly have established such democratic institutions, as e.g. permanent and numerous assemblies of jurors for judicial business, and the revision of laws. I shall return to the subject of the assemblies of judges ; for the present, two remarks are suflicient. First, the read- ing in the place of Herodotus, which I have given above as Mr. Grote gives it, is by no means certain. It only rests on a conjecture of Wesseling's ; the MSS., as far as I can see from Schweighaiiser's edition, the only one I have at hand just now, read arrvwdjiivov tots iravra, or Tore irdvrmv. Schweighaiiser's text gives the former; and the passage is translated "plebem omnem Atheniensium, prius a se alienatum ( ' spretum ' would be better) suas ad partes traduxit." It is plain that itovtodv, the other reading, is not right, with the words arranged as they are now; either irporepov must be struck out before airma^evov, so that aTTcocrfievov Tore irdvrtov may go together, or Tore must be put after iravrav, so as to be taken with irpoa-eO^Karo. d2 36 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. This is what Wesseling has done, and I do not blame Mr. Grote for having followed him. But then, what does the place prove ? Certainly not that the people were excluded from everything by Solon's laws, rather, that they had been excluded from everything in spite of Solon's laws; that the tcpdros, which Solon prides himself on having given the people, had been denied them. Was it impossible for this to have happened at that time? As long as the influence of the nobility was strong in the old accustomed unions of Gentes, Phratries, and Tribes, it could not but happen that the offices of government, though legally open to non-noble persons, if wealthy, would fall, in fact, exclusively or principally to nobles. Consequently, the popular rights which Solon had established, though remaining on paper (or rather on wood), came to little practical application. This was why it was Kleisthenes' first measure to deprive those unions of Gentes, Phratries, and Phylse of their political significance, and to introduce an entirely new division, so as to put an end to the exces- sive influence of the nobility. The other place is Aristotle's Politics, ii. 9. 4. The ninth chapter of the second book of the Politics is pronounced spurious by competent judges ; that, however, is indifferent to the present question. In any case it is ancient, and I have nothing to say against conceding to it all the au- thority which the name of Aristotle can claim. This pas- sage says, that Solon gave the people no greater power than was unavoidably necessary, i.e. the power to choose their magistrates, and to call them to account; for, it adds, if the people has not thus much power, it is either the slave or the enemy of its rulers. Now let us assume that this passage involves, as Mr. Grote thinks, the assertion that Solon allowed to the people, i.e. the assembly, no fur- ther powers than that of electing its rulers, and of sitting in judgment on their conduct in office. This is to say, that the popular assembly had no competence in any department of government, excepting only the elections, and the Eu- thyne of the officials. So, then, there would be no one but the magistrates or the senatorial colleges, whether the Four Solon. 37 Hundred, or the Areopagus, who would have to decide on peace and war, or any other public questions, or legislative acts; on all such points, the people could not even claim to have the question put to them. All this is, to begin with, very unlikely in itself, and then it is certainly more than the writer of the chapter in question meant to assert. It seems to me that Mr. Grrote does not distinguish rightly between what is alleged as the author's own opinion, aud what is quoted as that of others. He regards as belonging to this latter portion the words (Sect. 2) : eoace Se SoXcov iiceiva /lev vwdpxovTa irpo- Tepov ov KaTaXvaai, Trjv re fiovXrjv (the Areopagus) kuI ttjv twv apx&v aXpeatv, tov Se Brj/iov Karapovr}iAQTio-6T]), and worthless demagogues 38 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. broke down the resistance of the reasonable politicians (t e-irteiic5>v) ; this is evidently in allusion to the later extended activity of the popular courts, and also, no doubt, to the introduction of the Dikastic pay. At this point there follow the words first quoted, to which Mr. Gfrote appeals in favour of his view of the narrow limit of the functions conceded by Solon to the people. But, in their actual context, these words are not meant to pass for a precise and complete statement of the rights granted to the people; they only insist on the two most important rights, which could not possibly be denied to it. The people was itself excluded from the offices of Government, which could only be held by the nobler and wealthier class, which was not included in the Stj/jlos ; so if the people had not even the right of electing the magistrates, and sitting in judgment on their conduct, it would evidently have been either the slave or the enemy of the Government. So these two rights were the most essential, and such as Solon simply could not avoid giving to the people ; but that he gave them only these and no more, is in no way implied by the passage in question. (h.) Helicea and Popular Assembly not the same. Still, Mr. Grote seems really to be of opinion that Solon's Constitution did concede to the general assembly of the people no more than those two rights. He calls the popular assembly also "Helisea;" for he says in a note f , "I ima- gine the term 'HXtaia, in the time of Solon, to have been used in its original meaning — the Public Assembly, per- haps with the implication s of employment in judicial proceeding." Of course, there is no doubt that the word might have meant a popular assembly at Athens, as elsewhere ; but to shew that it really had the meaning there, there is not a single testimony that deserves attention. Mr. Grote cites Tittmann h , and, in the place cited, the meaning is no doubt • established, but for places other than Athens ; and further (on p. 217, note 32), a grammarian (Bekker Anecd., i. p. 310) ' Vol. ii. p. 328. b [" Connotation" in edition of 1849.] h Darstellung der Griech. Statsverf , p. 215 f. Solon. 39 is quoted, who writes : 'Hkiala' KaXetrai Be /iiya Bi/cao-- T-rjpCov Kai ol ■)(i\iot, Biieaarai. iv tovtois ap^aipealab yivovrai Kal at fieyiarai KpLaet,s Kai al Sioifctfaeis' eKaXelro Be /cat /MeyaKT} e/cKXrjcrCa. The mention of a thousand judges is enough to make it clear that the grammarian is not think- ing of a general popular assembly ; when he goes on to make these thousand judges undertake elections to offices, and determine on administrative measures, the confusion becomes so obvious as to deprive his assertion of all value. A similar confusion is often found in the inferior gramma- rians : they sometimes treat the Helisea as the assembly of the eKK~krivo<: voftoOeTtfcravTos ovSev erepov avrois eVeXetro rj fiovop viroicpivew (better ava- Kpivetv) rovs avTihUovs. This article in Suidas is unmis- takably derived from a trustworthy source. Doubts may be raised against the second part of the statement, viz. that it was in consequence of so early a legislation as Solon's that the Archons were limited to the Anakrisis, or instruction of law-suits. Still, we must regard the first part, which says that the decisions of the Archons were avTorekel? (i.e. not subject to appeal) only down to Solon's time, as a second and not unimportant piece of evidence besides Plutarch's statement. A case decided by the Archon was Siktj aiiro- TeKrjs only so long as the decision was not subject to appeal j now, according to Plutarch, there was an appeal in the time after Solon, and so the Archon's decisions were no longer avroreXeis, which is also involved in the statement from Suidas. Therefore, the two statements agree, which makes it the less permissible for Mr. Grote to assume a confusion in Plutarch's mind with the Roman provocatio. And what does he think it was that Plutarch confused with this? A confusion necessarily pre-supposes two things: in this case, the first thing is the provocatio ; what is the other? Plutarch must have found something in his authorities which could be confused with the provocatio, and obviously this can only have been the Appeal which Mr. Grote denies ; " ii. 329 n. ° Also in away. AeJ. xpi"-. Bekker, Anekd., i. 449. Solon. 43 which, therefore, cannot have originated, to begin with, in the confusion in Plutarch's mind. Moreover, Plutarch was not in fact guilty of making that confusion ; for, indeed, he expressly distinguishes the appeal to the people, introduced by Publicola, from that to the Dikasts, which Solon intro- duced ; though he does compare the two together, as he was quite justified in doing. Mr. Grote's denial rests on nothing but his own conviction, — it would be truer to say, his preju- dice, — that jury-courts with numerous members, among whom there might possibly be persons of the lowest pro- perty-class, are inconceivable as existing in Solon's time. I have quoted above his emphatic expressions on the point ; " it would be a marvel that the half-emancipated Thetes, and small proprietors, for whom he legislated, — yet trembling under the rod of Archons, and utterly inexperienced in col- lective business, — should have been found suddenly com- petent to fulfil these ascendant functions p ." Yet Mr. Grote himself did not think it marvellous that Solon should entrust to these very same people, not only the power of electing their magistrates, but also that of passing judgment on their conduct in office. And both were to be done in the general assembly of the people, to which all, without any distinction, had access ; and in which all, with- out any distinction, rich and poor, elder and younger, had an equal vote, and exercised it without being reminded by an oath of the duty of careful and conscientious examination of the case. As Mr. Grote did not think this extraordinary, he ought not to find it so utterly incredible that Solon should have committed the judgment of offences other than those of the magistrates, and the decision of law-suits, to an entirely different assembly. For this assembly, in the first place, though numerous, was far less numerous than the general assembly of the people ; secondly, it was composed solely of men of mature age (i.e. thirty at least) ; thirdly, it was bound by a solemn oath ; and fourthly, though it, too, might contain citizens of the lowest class, yet it did not of necessity contain them ; and if it did, they were no doubt in smaller numbers. All that our authorities tell us is, that Solon con- p ii. 328. 44 Schdmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. stituted jury-courts, from which the lowest class was not ex- cluded; they give no information of details, and we are therefore limited to probable conjectures. We may be sure that the number employed was not as large under Solon's enactment as it was later, when 6,000 citizens were annually selected to act as jurors; besides, they would hardly be chosen by lot. Now if they were selected by the confidence of their fellow-citizens, then the risk that a large number of ignorant and incompetent persons might be nominated was, in Solon's time, not very great. Just as little was it to be feared that poor men would be over eager in competing for an office which cost time and trouble, and brought them nothing. We may assume with certainty that the Helisea, though legally open to all, was practically composed only, or chiefly, of the wealthier or more cultivated class. Again, we have no precise knowledge of the cases in which the He- liastic courts acted; but we may assert with confidence that they were far fewer then than later. Many are of opinion, as I remarked above, that the jury-courts were instituted by Solon only as a court of appeal ; they think themselves forced to this conclusion by Plutarch's statement (Solon, c. 18), which was quoted above. Still, Plutarch's words state nothing more than that recourse to the judgment of a Dikastery was open to any one who felt aggrieved or injured by the decisions or decrees of the magistrate. This, however, was the case in later times too, when the magis- trates were substantially no more than officials for the formal initiation of legal proceedings, and yet retained a certain limited power of inflicting penalties. But Plutarch's words do not in the least imply that Solon instituted Dikasteries simply and solely for the purpose of receiving appeals from the sentence of the magistrates, considered as judges of first instance. But, to enable ourselves to judge more correctly of the position held by the Heliastic courts in the Solonian system, we must survey the matter rather more comprehensively. Solon. 45 i. (/3.) Courts other than the Bihasteries. In the Athenian state, in the period of which our autho- rities give U3 more exact knowledge, there existed besides the Heliastic Dikasteries (omitting the Areopagus and Ephetse, which need not be introduced here,) various other descriptions of courts; viz. local judges, Disetetse, and Nau- todikse. Local Judges. . The local, or district judges, (Kara Stffiovs SiieacrTal,) were thirty in number ; later, after the fall of the so-called thirty tyrants, the number was raised to forty. They held their courts in the several Cantons, or Demes, and moved from place to place for that purpose. Probably there were fixed places for their sittings in the several parts of the country ; and it was announced beforehand at what time they were to be present at each. Their province in- cluded, at least in later times, only trivial cases (i.e. con- cerning amounts less than 10 drachmae) ; and besides these, substantial injuries (8. alicias) and cases of assault (8. fiuiitov). According to some authorities, among whom is Demosthenes, they are selected by lot, according to others by popular elec- tion; we must assume the latter for earlier times, and the lot for the later age. We are not told when they were in- stituted ; but probabilities are in favour of its having been in the earlier time, perhaps even in that before Solon. For the centralization of all authorities in the capital, which com- pels the citizens to be there constantly and in great numbers, is far more democratic than oligarchic. In oligarchies and aristocracies, on the contrary, provision is made, as far as possible, to avoid giving occasion to the people for coming to the town from the country or the villages. Moreover, we know of the Athenians, that a great part of the people were ill-pleased to leave their Demes, even at the time of the Peloponnesian war ; and a lawgiver like Solon would hardly force people to come into the town for every trifling law- suit, which would be not merely inconvenient, but, owing to the expenditure of time and money, extremely oppressive to the poorer men. 46 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. Dicetetce. Disetetee, or arbitrators, were of two kinds, — compromis- sory, chosen by the parties themselves, by way of compro- mise ; and public, appointed by the State. Compromise, by means of arbitration, was no doubt a primitive custom at Athens, as everywhere else ; it has been rightly observed that in earlier times, before the notorious love of litigation set in, it was probably not thought proper for any one to have recourse to a court of justice, till he had made an at- tempt to come to an understanding with his opponent before a private arbitrator. And no doubt it often happened that a decision was thus come to, in which both parties acquiesced, so that the assistance of the court was not required. This is what Plutarch's story refers to (Aristeides, c. 7), when he says that envy and discontent were created against Aristeides, be- cause, in consequence of his reputation for justice, he as good as deprived the courts of their occupation, by judging and determining all possible cases ; avrjprjKa)? ra ScKaa-Tijpia TfiS xpiveiv a/rravTa Kal BtKa^eiv. Mr. Grote, too, refers to the place in Plutarch i, but he has an extraordinary idea that Aristeides won his fame for justice by his discharge of the office of Archon ; and he finds in this a proof of his theory that at that time the Archons were still judges themselves. As if an official, whose special function was to administer justice, could become the object of popular dislike, because he exercised his powers justly, and discharged his office so well, that people were content to abide by his decisions. It was only in case of Aristeides' activity being unofficial, that people could take offence at it, and regard it as a disparage- ment to the Dikasteries officially established for the adminis- tration of justice. The public Disetetse may be regarded as subordinate judges, or judges of first instance. It is not made out from what date they existed, though the ruling opinion in modern times has inclined to place their institution rather late. Meier, whose treatise on the Diaetetse discusses the whole subject with his usual exhaustive profundity, thinks it i Vol. iii. p. 122, o. 31. Solon. 47 probable that they were instituted on occasion of the revision of the laws undertaken in the time of the archon Eukleides ; in which opinion other enquirers of great repute agree with him. I cannot, however, think that the grounds of this opinion are convincing. The principal reason, or, properly speaking, the only one, depends on the mention of the law concerning Disetetse by the orator Lysias, as one very lately passed. It is in a complaint made by the speaker of a speech against Archibiades, of which unfortunately only the begin- ning is preserved, in Dionysius of Halikarnassus. He com- plains that his adversary, who had brought a law-suit against him, claiming discharge of a debt, which claim the speaker alleged to be unfounded, had not listened to his requests, made after the accusation had been preferred, that the matter might be taken before compromissory arbitrators to be chosen by the friends of both parties, until the law about Disetetse had been passed j his words are, ravT i/iov irpoKa- \ovfiiwov ovSeTrwTTOTe TjOeKrfae avvekdelv, ovBe Xoyov irepl &v eveicakei irobrjaaadab ovSe Slanav eirLTpetyai, ems vfiel? tw vo/JjOv tov irepl t&v SiaiTrjTOJV edeade. Unfortunately, these words are" the end of the extract in Dionysius ; and so we can ascertain only two facts from the fragment : first, that a law about Disetetse was passed at that time ; and secondly, that the law contained something which deter- mined the antagonist not to persist in his former refusal. Then the question arises, As he did not persist in his re- fusal, what did he do ? Did he assent to the speaker's re- quest, and enter into a compromise ? This, it would seem, must be negatived ; as far as we know, there was no appeal from the decision of a compromissory arbitrator, and the case in Lysias is being pleaded before Dikasts ; therefore, if it had previously been pleaded before arbitrators, they must have been arbitrators subject to appeal ; and the public arbitrators were so subject. So the antagonist had not done exactly what the speaker wished, but he had done something like it. The speaker had desired him to leave the matter to the decision of compromissory arbitrators; he did not do that ; he submitted it to arbitration, but public arbitration, instead of compromissory. Now how far can the law about 48 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. arbitrators, which was passed in the interval, have deter- mined him to do so ? Must it necessarily be assumed, that public arbitrators were not instituted till the passing of that law ? I do not think so. Unfortunately, we have not the law itself. The only quotation which we possess from a law about arbitrators, in Demosthenes against Meidias, p. 545, contains a rule referring to private or compromissory arbitrators; we may accept this as proving at least that the law about arbitrators referred not merely to the public Disetetse, but to the private ones as well. Now, it is admitted that these were not introduced by the law in question, but quite of primitive origin ; conse- quently the public Disetetse too may have been older than this law. It is quite possible that the law may have con- tained more precise rules, confirming, amending, or com- pleting the laws previously in force about both classes of arbitrators. For instance, Th. Bergk r has supposed, with reference to the compromissory Disetetse, 'that the rule which made appeal impossible from their decisions, may have been introduced by this law ; while previously it had been open to the parties to make their compromise on these terms, or not, at pleasure; so that in many cases the function of the Disetetse was rather an attempt at conciliation, than a definitive decision of the controversy. And in reference to the public Disetetse, the law might, for instance, contain an extension of their functions. For according to the law of the orator's period, the Disetetse were competent to act in all private cases without exception. It is not improbable that before, this had either not been the case at all, or not in the time immediately preceding the new law. Now if this law extended the province 8 of the Disetetse, the case * In the Zeitschrift f. d. Alterthumswiss, 1849, p. 266 f. 8 It is conceivable, that this may have been done with the view of reliev- ing the Heliastic Dikasteries, and the officials occupied with the preliminary formalities of law-suits. It might reasonably be assumed, that appeals would not be made to the Heliasts from all decisions of arbitrators ; and if an appeal was made, at least the officials were saved the trouble- some and tedious preliminary formalities, as these had already been gone through before the Disstetse ; and the " acta " of the proceedings before them went as a rule to the Heliasts without addition. Economy might Solon. 49 in Lysias might be explained without difficulty ; the accuser had made a claim against the speaker, the amount of which exceeded the competence of public Diaetetae at that time, (i.e. previous to the new law) ; so that the case could only come either before compromissory Diaetetae, or before a Heliastic court. The former was the course which the speaker desired, but the accuser would not agree to it. Meantime the new law came into existence, making the public Diaetetae competent even for matters of the kind in question. Then the plaintiff no longer refused to bring the matter to arbitration before the public arbitrators; naturally, because recourse to the Heliastic court was still open to him, if worsted before the Disetetes ; whereas, if he had agreed to the speaker's earlier demand, and entrusted the case to compromissory arbitrators for final decision, he would have run a risk of losing his case without appeal. Perhaps other possibilities might be imagined with refer- ence to the course of proceedings in this case, in order to explain the plaintiff's original refusal, and his assent sub- sequent to the passing of the law about Diaetetae; but I am not fond of playing with mere possibilities, and shall be satisfied with that which I have suggested ; and even in its case, I shall be quite content, if only the concession is made, that it is at least no more improbable, than the hypothesis based by others upon the fragment of Lysias in question, that public Diaetetae were then instituted for the first time. The fact which is alleged as a second reason in support of the conjecture in question, is still more easily accounted for. It is true that the older orators, those before Lysias, do not mention the Disetetse; of course, as their extant orations in no case deal with private suits, there was no occasion for such mention to be made ; even Lysias mentions them only once besides, in the fragment of the speech against Diogiton; and in Isaeus, in whose time there is no doubt that they existed, no reference to them occurs. also be an object, aa trial before Diatetae was oheaper both for the state and the parties. E 50 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. Nautodikce. "With regard^to the Nautodikse, there is little that can be made out with certainty. None of the orators mention them but Lysias ; we learn from him that complaints against e/nropoi (persons engaged in maritime commerce) were laid before them ; and, if we are strict in our interpretation of the orator's expression i^ehUaaav, that such cases were tried to the end, and decided by them. Besides this, the Grammarians tell us that ypaificu ^evias (accusation of aliens on account of the illegal assumption of citizen rights) as well, belonged to the province of the Nautodikffi ; at least, in case of the unqualified person hav- ing intruded himself on the Phratries. This is not the place to hazard conjectures as to the explanation of these two-fold functions. Still, it seems to result from the state- ment of Lysias, that the Nautodikse did not merely, like other magistrates, receive the accusation, and initiate the suit, but that they had also to decide in the character of judges. This circumstance may be taken to indicate that their origin belongs to very early times ; and we have no reason to deny that even before Solon's time, the want may have been felt of a special authority for the litigation of efLTropoi. However, think as we may about the antiquity of the Nautodikffi, at least we are fully entitled to regard the cantonal judges, and the public Disetetae, as belonging to the time of Solon. Archons' Judicial powers not such as to exclude Dikasteries. In consequence of these considerations, the institution of the Heliastic courts will no doubt appear to us in a some- what different light, from that in which it appeared to Mr. Grote. Mr. Grote has in his mind no judicial autho- rities besides the Archons on the one hand, and the Heliasts on the other, (of course, not counting the courts for homi- cide). For this reason he shews a very intelligible reluc- tance to ascribe to the Heliasts, at that early time, the extensive functions which they must have had if Solon Solon. 51 assigned to the Archons only the ''Instruction" of law cases, and the judicial determination could proceed from no one but the Heliasts. Therefore Mr. Grrote prefers to represent the Archons, even after Solon, as having power to judge, as well as to initiate ; and in order as far as pos- sible to set aside the popular courts, he will not even admit an appeal to them from the sentence of the Archons, and confidently neglects all evidence which makes against his view. I have remarked above, how one passage, Plutarch, Solon, c. 18, has been misinterpreted by many, to mean that the Heliastic courts were instituted merely as courts of appeal, while the Archons remained judges of first instance. The correct view is unquestionably as follows : the Archons, in spite of the fact that they were on the whole restricted by Solon to the " instruction " of cases, yet did not entirely cease to act as judges themselves. This is sufficiently clear from the one law concerning the functions of the first Archon, quoted in Demosthenes'; "the Archon is to have the care of orphans, and heiresses, and houses that are in danger of dying out, and of widows who remain in the house of their deceased husbands, asserting that they are pregnant. Of all these he is to have the care, and to permit no one to injure them. And if any one does injure them, or act illegally towards them, the Archon shall have power to fine him within the limit fixed for his judicial competence u ." Now, as a rule, the Archon could only be aware of the offences here indicated by the laying of an information, and could only impose a penalty after satisfying himself of its truth ; that is to say, after investigation. This neces- sarily implies that he would give the accused a hearing, confront him with the informer, and receive evidence from both parties; and however summary, or informal, the pro- cedure may be held to have been, still the Archon ob- viously exercised a judicial function, inasmuch as he gave sentence after investigation. The only restriction upon him was, that he could not give judgment for more than a cer- '. irpbs MaKapraTov, p. 1076. [ u kkto rb Te'Aos.] e2 52 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. tain fixed penalty; but if the offence seemed to demand a heavier fine, he had to bring the case before a Dikastery. And the other government officials, to whom the law gave power to impose fines (e7ri/3o\a? eTriftaXkeiv), no doubt ex- ercised similar judicial functions to those of the Archons, each in his sphere. There is nothing to justify us in as- .cribing to them a larger judicial capacity in Solon's time; certainly not, as Mr. Grrote does, one so extended that there was no appeal from their sentences. Their penal compe- tence, i.e. the amount of the penalty which they had power to impose, may have been greater, and restricted at a later time; this is all that can be conceded; but for the rest, we are not justified in conceiving the judicial procedure as regulated on completely different principles from those which we find in later times, even if a considerable change had taken place in the mode of their application. The leading principle of the Attic procedure is the separation of the two stages of the case, which we may designate, for the sake of brevity, by the Roman names of Jus and Judicium. Relation qfDicetetw to Bikasteries. The only exceptions to this universal principle were in the case of the cantonal judges, the Disetetse, and probably also the Nautodikse. In all trials but those before them, it was the business of the magistrate, in the first place, simply to receive the complaint, to hear the parties, and then to arrange for further proceedings, according to circumstances, or according to the wishes of the plaintiff. As regards the arrangements which were to be made according to circum- stances, I shall content myself in this place with referring to my " Attischer Process V As regards the wishes of the plaintiff, we know that in later times the magistrate asked him whether he wished the matter dealt with before a Diae- tetes, or not. In earlier times, according to Pollux ?, no private case was brought before a Dikastery, which had not been previously brought before Disetetse; and he means - Book iT. o. 5 and 6. i yiii. 126. Solon. 53 public Disetetse, as the context is enough to prove, for he has spoken of them immediately before. Now the first thing to ask is, what is to be understood by that " earlier time?" He says, irakai. It is admitted that we must refer it to the time before the classical orators ; but this time is long ; between Solon and Demosthenes there is an interval of more than two hundred years. Now if, ac- cording to the above-mentioned opinion of modern enquirers, the public Disetetse were not introduced before the time of Lysias, the wdXai would not indicate a time before the class- ical orators, to whom Lysias of course belongs, but rather the earlier period of the classical orators themselves. If, on the contrary, as I have tried to shew above, there is no ground for denying the institution of public Disetetse to the Solonian age, then there is nothing to prevent us from ex- tending the iraXav as far back as that age. The second question is, whether what Pollux states was a legal rule, or only custom and tradition, which it was possible to follow or not at pleasure. The latter is the opinion not only of Meier, but of Th. Bergk ; who, how- ever, obviously against the context iu which the statement in question stands in Pollux, refer it not to public, but to private arbitrators. On the other hand, the former is C. F. Hermann's opinion ; and is supported also by the testimony of an ancient grammarian z , from which we learn that there really was once a law, fir) eladyeadai SUtjv, ei fir) irporepov i^eTacrdeirj -rrap' aviols (i.e. rot? 8fatT??Tai?) to Trpay/Aa. When this was, cannot be reliably ascertained. Bergk supposes that Demetrius of Phalerum enacted the rule, fixing as law what had previously existed as custom. Granting that it were really to be referred to Demetrius, still there is no reason to assume that he merely sanctioned an earlier tradition, and did not rather renew an old but obsolete law. • In the Appendix to the English edition of Photius, p. 673 ; and pub- lished, with Commentary by Meier, Halle 1834, under the title, "Frag- mentum Lexioi Bhetoriei." 54 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. i. (7.) Comparison of Province of earlier and later Dikasteries. Now suppose that cantonal judges, public Disetetae, and perhaps Nautodikae as well, existed besides tbe Heliastic courts, as early as Solon's time, having been either insti- tuted, or found and retained by him. Suppose it was a legal provision that private cases should go in the first instance before the Disetetae ; commercial cases before the Nautodikae ; trivial matters, and Siical aliclas, and fiiaiwv in the Demes, before the cantonal judges. Then there can have remained for the Heliastic courts only public accusations, and those private cases in which appeal was made to them from the decision of the other judges. Appeals would certainly not be very frequent ; public accusations were at that time un- doubtedly rarer than in the later period ; the courts of homicide were competent for a not-inconsiderable class of offences. In consequence of the superintending power pos- sessed by the Areopagus over the conduct both of official and of private persons, it may safely be assumed that many offences which subsequently belonged to the Heliastic courts, were at that time brought before the Areopagus 3 . This might take place, either in the form of an accusation proper, in which case the accuser pledged himself to carry the matter through against the accused ; or in the form of an information, by which the Areopagus was obliged to inves- tigate the matter ex officio, and then to award punishment as it might think fit. Thus there were certainly not an excessive number of cases which had to be taken before a Heliastic Dikastery. They were either such as the Ar- chons, before whom the suit was begun, did not find suf- ficiently prepared to be disposed of by themselves, by means of a brief enquiry, and a fine imposed on the loser; or * The following assertion, taken by Maximus (in the prooem. to Dionys. Areop., Opp. tom.ii. p.xxxiv.)fromAndrotionandPhilochorus, alludes to the time before the restriction of the Areopagus, effected by Ephialtes. Muller, Fragmenta Hist. Grasc, Philochorus, p. 17, [Case, Materials', &c, p. 11,] eSiKafbj' oZv 01 Apeonaynai irepl ■x&vtiuv ax&bv ruv j/ nal Trapa.vop.iwv, &s (pT\trtv 'AvSporiay iv irpdrrj koX $t\6xopos 4v dcvrzpa teal rpirrj ruv 'ArdiSoiv. Cf. Bb'ckh on the plan of the Atthis of Philochorus, in the Abhandlungen d. Berl. Ak. d. Wiss. 1832, p. 12. Solon. 55 those in which the parties, being discontented with the decision of the Archons, made an appeal, and insisted on investigation by the Heliasts. But the principle according to which nothing but the acceptance of the complaint, and the " instruction " of the suit, belonged to the Archon, except in those less serious cases, — that is to say, the separation between Jus and Judicium, must be unhesitatingly acknow- ledged as for the later times, so also as accepted in the Solonian constitution. At Rome, too, this separation was ancient, and demonstrably older than the legislation of the Twelve Tables. There is no conceivable reason for denying it to the Greeks of the Solonian age. The Archon at Athens, in referring the parties to arbitrators, was doing essentially the same thing as the Magistrate at Rome when he ap- pointed them a "judex," or an "arbiter." It was only in the court of higher instance, the Heliastic court, which in many public cases was also the first and only instance, that Athens, after Solon's legislation, had something which Rome had not. That Solon appointed for the purpose a con- siderable number of judges lay in the nature of the case ; and judicial bodies, consisting of numerous members, were previously known, not only to Athens from the time of the institution of the fifty-one Ephetae (not to speak of the Areopagus), but also to the poet of the Iliad, who, in the eighteenth book, represents an assembly of the elders sitting to judge a case about the payment in expiation of a slain man's death. Solon's Heliasts were no Homeric elders, no Eupatrid lords ; they were persons of mature age, high repute, and for the most part, no doubt, of some property. It is true that poor men were not excluded ; but there was, as I have shewn above, no danger of their finding access in excessive numbers, as happened of course in later times. In later times, the Heliastic courts obtained a sphere of activity that was constantly being extended. This was owing, in the first place, to the permission conceded to suitors to go at once before the Dikastery, even in private suits, omitting the arbitrators; an innovation the date of which cannot be definitely established, but which we may with probability place in the time of Pericles, after the in- 56 Schdmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. traduction of judicial pay. In the second place, it was owing to the restrictions on the power of the Areopagus, and the abolition of its right of superintendence, as a result of which the Heliasts took its place in all cases in which it had ceased to be competent. In the third place, the magistrates them- selves found it advisable to make no use of their right of independent decision, even in the less difficult or important cases, whenever they had reason to suppose that an appeal would be made from their decision. Such a change would result naturally in the course of events, without our being compelled to join Mr. Grote in assuming a radical change of principle, and setting down the separation of Jus and Judicium as not having arisen till a later time. Moreover, it will readily be believed that in the times immediately after Solon, the Heliastic courts really came into action rarely enough, even in cases where, according to his con- stitution, they ought to have done so; and that public accusations in particular could hardly be brought before them. For we have to remember, that soon after Solon's legislation the Peisistratid tyranny began, and it was cer- tainly not favourable to the popular courts; but after the fall of the Peisistratids, they gained a new organization by the help of Kleisthenes. The number six thousand, and the division into ten sections, or Dikasteries, belong to this time. How many Heliasts there may have been before, and how they were divided, we do not know; but their existence is none the less certain. (ii.) Legislation, (a.) Nomotheta in the time of Demosthenes. We may now turn to the second of the principal points indicated above, and consider the participation of the gene- ral popular assembly in legislation; that is, enquire what power Solon conceded to the popular assembly in respect of the introduction of new, and the abolition of old, laws. The procedure in this legislation, as prescribed in the time of Demosthenes by the laws then existing, though frequently transgressed, is as follows. In the first popular assembly Solon. 57 of the year, the question is laid before the people, whether it would admit proposals for amending or supplementing the existing laws, or not. It is self-evident that on this question there could not but be debates, some advising the admission of such proposals on grounds of utility or ne- cessity, others opposing it. If the people declared in favour of their admission (which would hardly be the case on every occasion), this decision involved nothing more than that it was now open to those who meant to make pro- posals to bring them under consideration. This was done, according to the law in Demosthenes 1 ', by going through the form of exhibiting the proposals in public on the market-place near the statues of the Eponymi, that every one might acquaint himself with them. After this had been done, the third regular assembly dealt with the question of nominating a legislative committee, the so- called Nomothetse. The Nomothetae were members of the Helisea, and therefore men over thirty years of age, and on their oath. Details of the manner of nomination, whether by lot or by election, are not given. All we learn is, that the people determined the number to be nominated, and the time for which they were to serve, according to the number and nature of the legal proposals brought forward; and that the same was the case as to the pay- ment to be made for their trouble. The proposed measures had been made accessible to every one's observation by their exhibition near the Eponymi. Nevertheless, before the Nomothetae were nominated and their sittings began, they were read aloud by a clerk in every assembly that took place in the interval, that they might be the more certain of being generally known. The proceedings before the JSTomothetse were carried on just in the form of a lawsuit. The proposers, who wished to have an old law abolished and another put in its place, or to have any changes introduced into the existing legis- lation, appeared as plaintiffs : those who pronounced the existing laws to be good and adequate appeared as defend- b kot& Ti/iOKpirovs, p. 705, SS. 58 Schdmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. ants. To guard against the want of a proper defence of existing law, and proper precautions against innovation, a number of Synegori, or public advocates of the existing laws, were elected by the people for that purpose, and others might of course join them of their own accord. (/3.) Nomothetcs in Solon's time not improbable. This is the procedure, as we learn it from Demosthenes. F. A. Wolf, in the Prolegomena to the Leptines, p. 133, considers the institution of Nomothetse comparatively late ; in the earlier period, he thinks laws were dealt with just like Psephisms (that is, special proposals made in view of particular cases, and for transient' purposes), by the public assembly only : and therefore the people collectively was not, as under the institution in question, absolutely limited to the decision of the question whether to admit amendments on the laws or not, but had the right of examining the actual proposals, and of accepting or rejecting them. I have declared myself against this view, and pronounced c the pro- cedure before Nomothetse to be the more ancient ; and the other, in which no distinction is made between laws and Psephisms, to be an abuse which forced itself in at a later time. In this, as I think, the nature of the case as well as the testimony of the ancients is on my side. It is plain of course that some points in the regulations, such as the exhibition near the Eponymi, and the payment to the Nomothetae, are not derived from Solon, but belong to a later time. But these points do not touch the essence of the institution itself, which we may regard as very ancient in spite of them. In thinking it to be Solonian, I am less influenced by the evidence of the orators, (of whom De- mosthenes ascribes it expressly to Solon, .ZEschines to the founder of the Democracy, which most naturally means Solon), than by the fact that I can find absolutely no ra- tional ground for denying it to Solon. It displays the wise foresight of the legislator, in desiring to take precautions to prevent the duty of passing judgment on the laws from c De Comitiig Ath., 265, ss. Solon. 59 devolving on the mass of the people as it conies together in the popular assembly, composed of young and old, rich and poor, rude and cultivated, without any distinction. On the contrary, he provides that every legislative pro- posal should be subject to the decision of a smaller number of older men, selected and sworn, after hearing and carefully examining the arguments alleged by the proposer of the measure on the one hand, and by the advocates of the existing law on the other. This amounts to nothing less than, strictly speaking, to withdraw the legislation from the general assembly of the people, and only to concede to it, what may be conceded without scruple, the right of de- ciding whether proposals of amendment are to be permitted at all, or not. On the other hand, a procedure in which the assembly of the people decides for itself and by itself on laws as well as Psephisms, is only conceivable in a De- mocracy which is already very advanced ; and the orators who have been referred to complain loudly of this abuse, as having recently become prevalent. Demosthenes d says it has brought things to such a pass, " that almost every month laws are carried to further the interests of the orators." — " There is no longer any distinction whatever between Psephisms and laws; the laws, with which the Psephisms should be in accordance, are later than the Pse- phisms themselves." — " Some people of influence, as I hear, succeeded in getting themselves permission to bring for- ward laws whenever and however they pleased ; and since then you have so many laws in contradiction with each other, that you have felt the necessity of electing a special commission to enquire into and indicate the contradictions in the laws ; a business which shews no signs of coming to an end." The expression "as I hear," (to? e irvvQa- vo/j,at,) might lead to the conjecture that the first author of the abuse was still remembered in Demosthenes' time, and that therefore the abuse itself could not be very ancient; but that is of no importance. Only it is certain that if there are no forms of legislation but those two to choose * Dem. o. Timokr., p. 744, in Leptinem, p. 484 f. 60 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. from, our choice which of the two is Solonian, and which is not, cannot be doubtful for a moment. I said, " If there are no forms but these to choose from," because a third course may no doubt be imagined, that is, that Solon might have ordained neither the one nor the other form of legis- lation, but have entrusted it to some existing authority, e.g. the Areopagus. However, as there is no trace or in- dication of such a measure, we may leave this idea to those who are fond of amusing themselves with mere possibilities. But there is yet a fourth alternative, and this is the one which Mr. Grote affirms ; viz. that Solon neither entrusted legislation to the general assembly of the people, nor in- stituted a legislative committee for the purpose; but that he simply framed no rules at all as to the way in which, in case it should be required, his legislation might be amended, unsuitable laws set aside, and new ones put in their place. Let us hear Mr. Grote's reasons. (y.) Grote's arguments against Solonian origin of Nomotheta. Such a legislative committee as that described above, Mr. Grote is sufficiently debarred from regarding as an institution of Solon, by the fact that he does not regard the Heliasts as Solonian. This is quite clear ; if there were no Heliasts, there was not a legislative committee composed of Heliasts. We may hope that this argument is adequately met by what has been said about the Heliasts in the pre- ceding section. And it was equally impossible for Solon to enact that proposals for new laws should be exhibited near the statues of the Eponymi, which did not exist in his time. This, too, is perfectly clear; and yet neither this, nor other traces of a later time, which are apparent in the law quoted by Demosthenes, have deterred me, and other careful enquirers who agree with me, from regarding the institution of Nbmothetse as Solonian. For we supposed that all such traces only pointed to a modification of the procedure adapted to later conditions, and did not touch the essence of the institution itself. Mr. Grote e , in saying e Vol. ii. p. 324 n, part ii. c. 11. Solon. 61 that "this admission seems to him fatal to the cogency of my proof," seems to me, on the contrary, to misappre- hend the real nature of the case. I have never said any- thing different from what I say now, viz. that those traces do not force us to doubt the greater antiquity of the insti- tution, if it is probable on other grounds. Mr. Grote, on the contrary, speaks as if the later form necessarily com- pelled us to believe in a later origin of the institution itself. Finally, we come to his main argument; "Solon," we read in the margin ( , " never contemplated the future change or revision of his own laws;" and the text s says, "To suppose that Solon contemplated and provided for the pe- riodical revision of his laws, by establishing a Nomothetic jury, or Dikastery, such as that which we find in operation during the time of Demosthenes, would be at variance (in my judgment) with any reasonable estimate either of the man or of the age. Herodotus 11 says that Solon, having exacted from the Athenians solemn oaths that they would not rescind any of his laws for ten years, quitted Athens for that period, in order that he might not be compelled to rescind them himself. Plutarch 1 informs us that he gave to his laws force for a century absolute." " Gellius k ," this is added in a note, " affirms that the Athenians swore, under strong religious penalties, to observe them for ever." " Solon himself, and Drako before him, had been lawgivers, evoked and empowered by the special emergency of the times ; the idea of a frequent revision of laws by a body of lot-selected Dikasts, belongs to a far more advanced age, and could not well have been present to the minds of either. The wooden rollers of Solon, like the tables of the Roman decemvirs, were doubtless intended as a permanent 'fons omnis publici privatique juris.' " It may be that this or that reader will be convinced by argumentation of this kind; for my own part, all that Mr. Grote puts forward seems to me devoid of cogency, and part of it to be even capable of being turned against him. He appeals principally to the precautions which Solon is said to have taken to secure the unchanged per- 'Yol.ii. p. 325, partii. o.ll. elb. h i. 29. > Solon, c. 25. k ii.l2. 62 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. manence of his laws. The statements of Plutarch, and & fortiori that of Gellius, are of course not credible to any- one like Mr. Grote ; but perhaps he holds Herodotus' tes- timony to be reliable. So I will let it pass too, though I must confess that the matter is not quite clear to me. For I do not see to what extent, and in virtue of what position, Solon, after he had fulfilled his commission and laid down his office, and after his laws had been accepted by the people, could have continued to have authority to repeal those laws, to the inviolate observance of which he had bound the people. But, doubtless, Mr. Grote under- stands that better, and so I will let my own scruples be. But, then, what follows from Herodotus' story ? Just this ; that Solon feared the Athenians would be inclined to change his laws too soon ; and that, therefore, he bound them to a strict observance of the code for ten years at least, that they might learn their value by experience. After this term, which was really not very long, they were to cease to be bound, and to be free to make changes. Solon's own re- mark in Plutarch 1 goes to shew, that he by no means regarded his legislation as perfect, or beyond improvement. Plutarch says that when he was asked whether he had given the Athenians the best laws possible, he answered, "the best which they would have accepted;" that is, not absolutely the best, but only as good as were possible with the existing disposition and sentiments of the people. So this implies the admission that, under other conditions, and with different dispositions and sentiments among the people, other laws would be better. The knowledge that men's relations and sentiments do not continue immutably the same, and that, therefore, changes of law will become desirable or necessary, is not so abstruse that we should be forbidden to give credit for it to one of the seven sages, who was undoubtedly the wisest man, "the largest mind of his own age" 1 ." There is in Plutarch another story that bears on this point, not in the life of Solon, but in the Symposium of the Seven": "Tidings came from the Spartan Chilon, that 1 Solon, c. 15. m Grote, vol. vi. 39, part ii. c. 67. " c. 7. Solon. 63 he renounced his friendship with Solon, because the latter had said that laws must be subject to change (rovs vo/jlovs /j.eTaicivTjTov'} elvat)." The anecdote may be an invention; I do not mean to deny that. But it not only gives a good indication of the difference between Spartan and Athenian feeling, but also is quite in accordance with the sagacity with which Solon may be credited. And how do we know that there had not been by Solon's time plenty of expe- riences which would call a legislator's attention to the in- evitable necessity of revising and amending laws from time to time ; and would force him to devise a method for doing so, with the greatest convenience and the least danger ° ? We are quite unacquainted with the details of the history of any other Greek state [of the time] ; we only know that in the Solonian time, and that immediately preceding, there had been conflicts between the oligarchy and the com- mons all over Greece, accompanied by numerous political revolutions and constitutional changes ; all this might be of service to a reflective observer. Indeed, Athens herself afforded a striking example of the necessity of changing existing laws in conformity with circumstances. It was not quite thirty years since Drako had made his laws, and the impossibility of retaining them had already become so evident, that Solon was obliged to repeal the whole mass, excepting only a very few. He could not but be aware that his own laws also would require many changes in course of time, and in acting as he did he shewed his wisdom. In the first place, he appointed an interval of ten years,, which was neither very long nor very short, during which the Athenians were to begin by making trial of his laws, without being allowed to make any changes in them. Then, after the expiry of this period of probation, alterations were to be allowed ; but in permitting this, he provided at the same time that such changes, or even pro- Even Zaleukus, the first author of written laws, is not said to have forbidden changes, but only to have provided, in a way which must be ad- mitted to have been somewhat rude, that they should not be proposed on frivolous grounds. See Demosth., Kara Tt/jioicp., 744, and more in Heyne Opusc. acad. ii. p. 30. 64 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. posals for change, should not be permitted, unless the need for them was generally recognised; and that if proposals were permitted to be made, they should not be decided upon without the most careful examination, or without the existing law being defended against the innovation. Fur- ther, this act of decision was not to devolve upon the popu- lace, but on a smaller number of men of mature age and tried experience. All this was most appropriately pro- vided for by the institution of the Nomothetse ; and if, as Mr. Grote thinks, Solon did not make any such provision, this would betray such a want of foresight as we ought not to lay to the charge of the wisest man of his age. I may add, to supplement the discussion, that there was a story at Athens, that Solon himself had once spoken before the judges, against some one who had proposed an unsuitable law. The account is given in Demosthenes 5 ; it proves, at least, that no doubt was felt of the fact that judicial procedure had been applied to laws in Solon's time, and may, therefore, pass as a piece of testimony to be added to the statements of the orators, who designate the law of Nomothetse as Solonian, though it was not Solonian in the form in which they knew it. § 6. KXEISTHENES. (a.) Kleisthenes made only 100 Denies. I have now disposed of the principal points in which Mr. Grote's views about the Solonian constitution appeared to me to require correction ; and so I turn to the succeeding legislator, Kleisthenes ; who on the one hand abolished, or found substitutes for, some of the pre-Solonian institutions which Solon had allowed to remain ; and on the other, gave greater space, and a freer developement to the in- stitutions founded by Solon. The statements of the ancients about Kleisthenes are of a very general and indefinite kind, so that we have little detailed knowledge of his measures. We are specially told that he essentially modified the for- '' Kaia. TtftoKpirovs, p. 765. Kleisthenes. 65 mer divisions of the people, and established in place of the four ancient Ionic tribes ten new ones, which were named after native heroes, as their Eponymi. These tribes he re- divided into smaller sections, or Demes ; making each tribe contain ten, according to the account of Herodotus, so that there were a hundred in all. For as Valckenaer rightly saw q , no other interpretation of the words of Herodotus, 5. 69, Beica Be ical tovs Btf/xovs KaTeveo/jue e? tAs v\ds, is philo- logically possible. Some writers have made up their minds to assume a transposition of the words which would be unprecedented, and in that context utterly pointless, viz., that Beica tovs Btffiovs Kareveifie is ra? v\d<;, was put for rods Sijfiovs KaTevetfie es Tas Beicci (fiv\d<;, the latter being the real meaning, and the expression which ought to have been used. But this must be set down as simply that spurious kind of historical criticism, which does not shrink from twisting the words in the witness's mouth to favour preconceived opinions. Unhappily, we see Mr. Grote join- ing in such criticism as this; "I incline," he says r , "as the least difficulty in the case, to construe Beica with ^>u\a?, and not with Bi]/j,ovs." Of the only correct construction, he says B , " such construction of the words, however, is more than doubtful, while the fact itself is improbable." The construction can only be thought doubtful, owing to im- perfect linguistic knowledge ; aud if the fact itself is really improbable, only one of two courses remains open to us; either to pronounce the place corrupt, or to say that He- rodotus has made a mistake, or at least expressed himself inaccurately, and given a round number, instead of the ac- tual number. This seems to be C. F. Hermaun's opinion ', ' The same view is taken by Eoss " Demen von Attika," Halle, 1846, p. 3. Westeimann in the Zeitschr. f. d. Alterthiimswiss, 1848, p. 37, and in Pauly's Eealeneyklop., ii. p. 952. Meier in the Hall, allgemein. Lit. Zeit., 1844, p. 1386. Dr. Thirlwall, too (vol. ii. p. 82), has the right view. [Grote has modified the note on this passage of Herodotus in the later editions, by approving of the 'suggestion that 5e'/ca may be taken with Kardneine, in the sense of Sexa nepn, but the places which he quotes hardly bear him out.] r [The reference is to the note of vol. iv. p. 177, in the edition of 1849, now modified as stated in note q above, (vol. iii. p. 113, ed. of 1862).] ■ Vol. iii. p. 113, part ii. e. 31. ' Staatsalterthiimer, iii. 12. The later editor agrees with Schumann. F 66 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. and it is unquestionably the most rational, if we are once convinced that the fact, as Herodotus states it, is improbable in itself. If we ask for the reasons which make it so, Mr. Grote mentions the two following : — First, if the change in the number of Demes had been so considerable, that a hundred established by Kleisthenes became at a later time a hundred and seventy-four (for that is the number alleged), surely some positive testimony to the change would have been found. But would this be so, even in case the transition took place not all at once, but gradually, and not noticeably? I conceive that in that case, the absence of positive testimony would not seem re- markable ; but Mr. Grote's observation deserves special no- tice, for the reason that it recognises the critical principle, that important changes of existing institutions are not to be readily believed in without positive testimony. Later, when he speaks of Perikles, we shall have occasion to re- mark how far he has remained true to his principle. His second reason is u , that " Kleisthenes would indeed have a motive to render the amount of citizen population nearly equal, but no motive to render the number of Demes equal, in each of the ten tribes." If I understand this rightly, Mr. Grote thinks that Kleisthenes found the Demes existing, and that there is no discoverable reason why he should not have retained unchanged those which he found, without troubling himself whether there was an equal num- ber of Demes in each tribe, as long as the number of citizens in the tribes was tolerably equal. Of course, there can be no doubt that Kleisthenes found existing Demes, or cantons ; how many there may have been of them we do not know ; but we may assume with certainty, that they were very unequal in size and in population. Further, it is clear that in organizing certain adminis- trative districts as subdivisions of the tribes, Kleisthenes would have to make them neither too large nor too small; a certain average area must have appeared to him to be the right one. Many of the existing cantons might more or less approach to this area ; and those there would be no - Yol. ill. p. 113. Kleisthenes. 67 reason for changing; but if there were some which were too large, or, as would be more common, too small, then the former would have to be divided, several of the latter amalgamated. This might be done without any violent change or revolution in existing relations. By uniting smaller places into a single administrative district, or throw- ing part of a canton into "one, and part into another district, nothing would be taken from them that they had before, but only something given them that they had not. It would not destroy the local institutions, of which Mr. Grote reminds us, or the festivals or temples of particular locali- ties. So, if Kleisthenes organized a certain number of ad- ministrative districts, taking as his pattern for size the greater number of the existing cantons, and if in doing so he preferred an equal number for each Phyle to making them of different numbers, and the round number a hun- dred to any odd number, there is nothing extraordinary or incredible in that. And there is this further evidence for the total of one hundred, that the Eponymi of the Demes (for they, too, worshipped certain heroes as their Eponymi) are mentioned under the name of the hundred heroes x - The hundred newly -organized administrative districts were called Sfjfioi; a name that was no doubt older, but was newly applied to mean a district of this nature, and ten of them made a Phyle. On this it must be further remarked, that locally contiguous Demes did not by any means always belong to the same Phyle, but that the Demes of one and the same Phyle often lay far apart, and were separated by others, which belonged to other Phylse ; a cir- cumstance which, as far as I know, I was the first to draw attention to y . As regards the gradual increase of the num- ber from a hundred, to a hundred and seventy-four, I must confess that I am quite unable to see why it has struck * Herodian, v. fwv. \e£., p. 17, 8. G. H. Sauppe, de demis urbanis Athe- narum. Programm d. Gymn. Zu Weimar, of 1846, in which all the extant names of these heroes are collected. * In a Programme of 1835. Cf. Antiquit. jur. publ. Gr., p. 202, 6. Mr. Grote remarks the same circumstance, vol. Hi. p. 113. f2 68 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. many critics as so inconceivable, and therefore so incredible. If a Demos had grown considerably in population, and either a new village had sprung up, or a small one had become large within its boundary, it might naturally seem advisable to make two Demes of it. In this way there arose at a later time out of the Deme Pseania, an Upper and a Lower Paeania ; and so we find Upper Ankyle and Lower Ankyle, Upper Agryle and Lower Agryle, Upper Pergase and Lower Pergase, Upper Potamos and Lower Potamos; in short, a gradual increase of the Demes by about three- quarters of their former number, is not in the least less probable, than what others have thought more so, viz., that Kleisthenes found the number of a hundred existing, and increased it to a hundred and seventy-four, or some- thing like it. (b.) Kleisthenes made 50 Naukraries. We saw above that the four ancient Ionic tribes were supposed to have been divided into three Trittyes each, every one of these containing four Naukraries; and it is certain 2 besides, that the ten tribes which dated from Kleisthenes, at a later time included Trittyes. We have no further direct testimony about Kleisthenes himself, than that he divided his tribes into Naukraries as well as Demes, but in doing so, raised the former number, forty-eight, to fifty, five to a tribe. Whether he made Trittyes as well, is not absolutely clear a ; it is at least not impossible that this division of the ten tribes was not introduced till later, when the Naukraries had ceased to exist. Its purpose was connected with military service. But granting that it originated with Kleisthenes himself, that would be no rea- 1 See Demosthenes on the Symmories, p. 184. iEsch. Ctes., p. 425. Plat. Bepubl., v. p. 475, belongs to this subject too, for he mentions the Trittyarohs as subordinate commanders, under the Strategi. » Of course, no one is likely to notice the absurdities of Michael Psellus, p. 103. Boiss. Kteitrdzi'ris els Tpi&Kovra fioipas tV 'Attik^v airaaav Siaveifias, iireiSfy rb fiev auTJJs ziriBaXaTTiSiov fy, rb Se Traps rb fioru avv&TTpuTo, beaa p.ev /ioipas ry irapa\itf ffwerevxe, 5e«a 5e /caT«TT7j Tpirri/xopioy rpmbs wvifiacrTO. Kleisthenes. 69 son for denying to him, as Mr. Grote b is inclined to, the division of his tribes into five Naukraries apiece. We know from Herodotus", that at the time immediately before the Persian war, the .Athenians possessed only fifty ships, a number which corresponds exactly with that of the Kleis-, thenian Naukraries d , and this coincidence can hardly be regarded as accidental. Mr. Grote e thinks it " hardly pro- bable that there should be two co-existing divisions, one [the Trittys] representing the third part, the other [the Naukrary] the fifth part, of the same tribes." But why should not Kleisthenes have found the division into Nau- kraries, only with two added, convenient for the purpose of the naval and cavalry service, if the resources of the country could only furnish fifty ships, and a hundred horse- men ? Whereas a division by Trittyes might be more suit- able for the infantry service. (c.) Kleisthenes admitted no free native Athenians to the Franchise. Kleisthenes' received into his newly-formed ten tribes a great number of people, who had previously not been citizens; iroXkoix; yap i(f>v\eTevae fjevovs ical Sovkovs fier- oikovs, are the words as they stand in Aristotle g ; but the right explanation of them is not known with certainty, and many writers have held the reading to be corrupt, and proposed emendations. Mr. Grote h holds it to be sound, and thinks that SovXoi fieroiKoi, as opposed to fjevoi fieroUoi, means a superior order of slaves, with regard to which he proceeds to explain further in a note. He thinks that " there must always have been in Attika a certain number of intelligent slaves living apart from their masters 1 , in a state between slavery and freedom^, working partly on con- dition of a fixed payment to him, partly for themselves, and perhaps continuing to pass nominally as slaves, after they had bought their liberty by instalments." b ii. 277, part ii. u. 10. c iv. 89. d Cf. Case, " Materials, &c," p. 19 and 20. e 1. a. ' Cf. Case, " Materials, &c. ," p. 17, ff. « Polit. iii. 1. 10. h Vol. iii. p. 109 and 10, part ii. c. 31. ' %aph oiKovnes, omitted by Schbmann. *■ These words omitted by Schbmann. 70 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. This would make them not strictly speaking a superior order of slaves, as they are called in the text, but freedmen, who could only be called slaves by an abuse of language. I must let this explanation of the passage pass (Meier ' has also taken §ov\oi as freedmen in this place), though the expression SovXot fieroiKot, still remains doubtful, and is found in no other passage. But what seems to me far more doubtful, is a third class of persons that Mr. Grote sets up, besides both the %£vol fieroi/cot, and the freedmen, as having been received by Kleisthenes into his tribes. These he describes as native Athenians, who had indeed a certain inferior franchise, but had been excluded from the old Phylse, Phratries, and Gentes, and the rights connected with them, such as eligibility to seats in the senate, and to magistracies. Of this class of persons Mr. Grote has in- formed us above, in an earlier part of his work ra , that even in Solon's time their number was probably considerable; and he gives it as his opinion in the same place, that they were discontented with Solon's constitution, because he did not admit them to full citizenship, and that this made them the more inclined to attach themselves to Peisistratus. For they all, without respect of property, belonged to the fourth class 11 , and therefore, like the Thetes, possessed no other political right than that of a vote in the general assemblies of the people . The origin of such a class, we are told, is to be explained by the numerous immigrations and settle- ments of foreigners, whose descendants, as they were very rarely received into the Gentes, Phratries, and Phylse of the old citizens, were "native Athenians," but yet, down 1 De Gentil. Attica, p. 6. » Vol. ii. p. 332, part ii. c. 11. u [It is a further difficulty, not noticed by Grote, that unless these per- sons had land, the fourth class was their natural place, and the reform of Kleisthenes would not directly improve their position. If, on the other hand, they had the right, confined as a rule strictly to citizens, of holding land, their ambiguous political position as conceived by Grote becomes more difficult to believe in than ever.] ° [In c. 31, Mr. Grote denies them this right for the period before Kleis- thenes, though in u. 11 he conceded it to them for the period after Solon. This contradiction probably results from the entire silence of the autho- rities, which leaves the political position of any such class to rest upon conjecture.] Kleisthsnes. 71 to Kleisthenes, only as it were half-citizens. I have very- strong doubts of the existence of this class. It is certain that there were many immigrants, and descendants of im- migrants, in Attika ; but they would always belong simply to the class of Metceki : that there ever was an intervening class between Metoeki and full citizens, is nothing but a fancy of Mr. Grote's. (d.) Difference between Orgeones and Genneta. But Mr. Grote rightly pronounces in favour of the view that Kleisthenes, when he organized his new tribes, left the old Phratries and Gentes as they were. From this time, therefore, they ceased to be connected with the Phylas; new citizens were incorporated in a Phyle, but not in a Phratry, or Gens ; and the same is true in later times also, though it happened in exceptional cases that a new citizen was permitted to enter a Phratry, and though there were ways by which the children of new citizens could be received, not merely into a Phratry, but even into a Gens. But this is not the place to discuss these points ; only I will take this opportunity of saying a word about the Orgeones. Isseus, Mr. Grote says p, " uses 6pv r&v > VoL iii. p. 126, note, c. 31. c vi. 104. Kleisthenes. 77 conflicting authorities are mentioned without being well discriminated 3 , that Aristeides was chosen Archon by the people, not drawn by lot ; an additional reason for believing this is, that he was Archon in the year following the battle of Marathon, at which he had been one of the ten generals. Idomeneus distinctly affirmed this to be the fact, — ov Kva- fievTov aXX 1 eXopipcop 'A6r)vaiwv, (Plutarch, Arist. c. 1)." Thus Mr. Grrote admits that Plutarch alleges contradictory authorities, without deciding clearly for one or the other e , and yet considers the result of these allegations to be, that Aristeides received the office of Archon not by lot, but by election. This being so, he must have discovered a criterion which enabled him to decide what Plutarch, according to Mr. Grote's own confession, left undecided. Let us there- fore examine the references and authorities in question a little more closely. On the one side we find Demetrius of Phaleron, a man of whom we know that he had accurately studied the his- tory and antiquities of the state, at the head of which he was for ten years, and that he wrote several works of re- pute on the subject. Now he expressly says, that Aris- teides became Archon by lot, at a time when only Pen- takosiomedimni could attain to the office; and he alleges this very fact as a proof that Aristeides could not have been so poor as many thought. On the other side there is Idomeneus, a writer not only considerably later than Demetrius, but also one of a school which has not the reputation of having spent much pains on searching and precise enquiries. That is to say, he was an Epicurean ; there are mentioned as his writings a book about the Socratics, one about Samothrace (only in Suidas), and one about Trojan history. What he said of Aristeides d Vide note below. e [" Ohne recht zwischen ihnen zu entscheiden," in allusion to the phrase by which Schomann has above translated Grote's words, " without being well discriminated." Schb'mann's translation seems incorrect ; Grote must have meant that Plutarch did not clearly distinguish what was one • author's view, from what was another's ; if so, Schomann's argument from Grote's admission is destroyed; but his examination of the passage in Plutarch holds good.] 78 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. could in any case only occur in a passing observation. According to Sintenis' careful judgment f , the specimens of his writing which occur in Plutarch and Athenseus are such " ut gravem quidem ac fide dignum scriptorem minime deceant." And Luzac's judgment on him is equally un- favourable g . Therefore, setting authority against authority, there can be no doubt which of the two deserves most credit. So if in this case the worse authority is to be preferred to the better, it must be strengthened by overwhelming ar- guments. What arguments has Mr. Grote P Besides his preconceived idea that the introduction of the lot could not possibly be so old, only this one; that Aristeides filled the office of Archon in the year after the battle of Marathon, in which he himself was one of the ten generals. He seems to think that this can only be explained, by supposing that the office was bestowed on him in consequence of his merit as displayed in the battle, and consequently not by the chance of the lot, but by popular election. And this is pretty much the conclusion which Plutarch seems to have reached ; only his words indicate at the same time that he conceived of this election as an exception to the rule of sortition, made in favour of Aristeides. He says, irdvv •KiQavbv iariv eTTi Bogy Tocravrrj kclI KwropOmfiatn Tt]\ucovTots afjiaOfjvai 6V aperrjV, ?js Sid ifKovrov 6TV Vol. iv. p. 106, part ii. e. 46. " iii. 125, c. 31. ° Aristeides, c. 22. 80 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. the invasion of Xerxes, not only had the exclusive prin- ciple of the Solonian law of qualification continued in force (whereby the first three classes on the census were alone admitted to all individual offices, and the fourth, or Thetic class, excluded), but also the Archons had hitherto been elected by the citizens, not taken by lot." The first of these facts — restriction of eligibility to the three higher classes — the place certainly does teach us; but it only teaches us the second (choice by majority of votes, and not by the lot), if the word alpeltrffai is taken as a proof of it. Ought Plutarch to have said K\rjpova-0ai ? Could he use that word, seeing that it was always the case that only some, not all, of the magistrates were taken by lot? Or was it necessary for him to express both modes of choice distinctly side by side, as by writing r/ KKijpm fj ^eiporovia alpetadai ? I conceive that Plutarch did right in adopting the general expression ; but Mr. Grote seems to deny to Plutarch below, in the note discussed just now, what he here ascribes to him. Here he represents him. as distinctly saying that election, and not lot, was in use down to the time after Platsea; while there he is described as not being able to decide between different authorities p. Hence it seems sufficiently established that all Mr. Grote's attempts to support his view by evidence, and to invalidate assertions to the contrary, are completely unsuccessful; and he himself would undoubtedly have recognised the weakness of his reasoning, if his judgment had not been perverted by the preconceived opinion, that sortition for magistracies was impossibleat the time of Kleisthenes. The lot appeared to him to be an institution which, of necessity, could only be introduced at a period of intensified democracy, such as we see, at the earliest, some years after the battle of Platsea ; be ascribes it to Perikles, not to Kleisthenes. "We have," he says i, " no positive information that it was Perikles who introduced the lot, in place of election, for the choice of Archons and various other magistrates. But the change must have been introduced nearly at this time;" and this " must " is to supply the lack of positive information. The p But see note e, p. 77, sup. ? iv. 101, part ii. c. 46. Kleisthenes. 81 question has, however, another and a very different side, and if we consider that other side, the introduction of the lot hy Kleisthenes will no longer seem so incredible. We know from Aristotle 1 that the lot had been introduced, among other purposes, with the object of putting a stop to elec- tioneering intrigues; this was the case, for instance, at Hersea, because the elections had before always resulted in favour of the wire-pullers. Now we also know that after the fall of the Peisistratid tyranny, Athens was distracted by the most violent party struggles ; and that the party headed by Isagoras carried on a conflict, with all the means in its power, against that of which Kleisthenes was the leader. Obviously, when this was going on, there must have been plenty of all sorts of electioneering factions. Isagoras himself appears as Archon for 507, clearly be- cause his faction secured the ofiice for him. Such intrigues Kleisthenes thought it his duty to provide against. There- fore he abolished popular elections, and introduced selection by lot for a great part of the ofiices; believing that this would secure appointments in most cases no worse, and in many much better, than those made by the votes of a popu- lace misled by faction and intrigue. I should have thought that even in England there had been enough opportunity to judge of the value of this kind of popular election. At least, here in Germany we have had experience which would justify us in concluding, that it was impossible to make worse appointments by the chance of the lot than by the votes of the masses, guided by demagogues and party- leaders. Moreover, it must be borne in mind that, ac- cording to the Kleisthenean constitution, even if it intro- duced the lot, still the number of those among whom the choice was made continued to be restricted to citizens of the three higher classes ; and in the case of the highest offices, to the Pentakosiomedimni. Besides, new citizens were excluded at least from all ofiices for which citizenship etc Tpuyovlas was requisite. Landed property, too, may have been a condition for many magistracies. Lastly, the poorer citizens no doubt were glad to exclude themselves, ' Pol., v. 3. 9. 82 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. because the offices were unpaid ; but they enjoyed the cer- tainty that if they did stand, they could not be thrown into the background, and set aside by richer or more aris- tocratic candidates. (g.) Areopagus in the time of Kleisthenes. About the Areopagus, its position and importance in the time of Kleisthenes, in comparison with what it was meant to be under Solon's constitution, Mr. Grrote 3 has some ex- cellent observations, to which I venture to make a few additions. According to Solon's intention, the Areopagus was to be the superintendent of the whole state, and the guardian of the laws, as Plutarch 4 expresses it. The ex- pression is extremely general, and tells us nothing in detail of the functions assigned to the Areopagus, and therefore we cannot take it ill of Mr. Grote that he uses equally general language 11 - All that we read in the Areopagiticus of Isokrates, about it and its activity in earlier times, relates only to its superintendence of the public discipline, not merely that of the youths, but also that of grown-up per- sons. It does not in any way touch upon its relations with the organs of public power, the magistrates and the as- sembly. We might be tempted to ascribe to it an im- portant part, especially in the Dokimasy and the Euthyne of magistrates, and to regard the later procedure, in which it has no share at all, as one of the innovations which were bound up with the limitations on the Areopagus effected by Ephialtes ; a conjecture which loses nothing, at least of its probability, from not being supported by express evidence. For its relation to the popular assembly, how- ever, there -is a notice about the Nomophylakes preserved from Philochorus x , which affords a fixed point, to which further inference may be attached with some certainty. Philochorus connects the establishment of the Nomophy- lakes with the lowering of the position of the Areopagus; they were instituted, he says, when Ephialtes left to it ■ jii. 128, o. 31, ' Solon, o. 19. u ii. 323, c. 11. * In the fragment of the rhetorical Lexicon that follows PhotiuB, p. 674. Engl, edition. Klei&thenes. 83 uncurtailed nothing but the criminal jurisdiction in capital cases, which it had before. From this statement we must infer, that the functions which were now transferred to the Nomophylakes had previously belonged to the Areopagus. And among those functions is this in particular, that they had their seat beside the Proedri, both in the council and in the popular assembly, and could make a protest if any- thing injurious to the state was being done ; Kaikvovres ra davfj,(f>opa rrj iroXei wpdrreiv. This can have no other mean- ing, than that they had the right to interpose their veto, and by doing so, either to prevent a proposal in the council or the assembly, which they thought mischievous, from being put to the vote, or to hinder its execution if it was actually carried. At least, the former power may be as- sumed with certainty. Now, if Solon gave the senate and the popular assembly the right of making decrees with reference to public affairs, it cannot be doubted that he would also give the Areopagus the power of superintending the exercise of this right. Plutarch says that Solon intended by means of the two councils, the Areopagus and the Four Hundred, to provide the state as it were with two anchors, to prevent the ship of the commonwealth from being driven about by the waves. He probably found the metaphor in Solon's writings; the waves are the passions of the populace, the two anchors answer to the regulative and restrictive powers of the two senates. Now Mr. Grote? observes with undoubted truth, that in the time of Kleisthenes the Areopagus must neces- sarily have consisted in great part of members who were hostile and odious to Kleisthenes and his party. The reason he gives is, that by Solon's enactment the Areopagus was composed of past Archons, and under the tyranny no one was elected Archon who was not a creature of the Peisis- tratids. On this account, "its influence must have been sensibly lessened by the change of party 2 , until it came y iii. 128. 1 Schb'mann, "Die nunmehr eingetretene StaatsYeranderung," which perhaps represents what Grote must have meant, i.e. the predominance of a new and opposed party in the government. g2 84 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. to be gradually filled by fresh Archons, springing from the bosom of the Kleisthenean constitution." He certainly does not mean tbat Kleisthenes passed de- finite laws in restriction of the power which Solon had assigned to the Areopagus. He only means, that though the legal rights of the Areopagus remained as before, yet it did not dare under the altered conditions to make use of them on the side of the party to which it really belonged, and so was inactive and acquiesced in much that was re- pugnant to it, because it could not change what was being done. There is no objection to this ; but Mr. Grote goes on : "Now during this important interval, the new-modelled Senate of five hundred and the popular assembly, stepped into that ascendancy which they never afterwards lost. From the time of Kleisthenes forward, the Areopagites cease to be the chief and prominent power in the state." This sounds as if we really had knowledge of a time at which it could claim such a predicate. As far as I am aware, we have no such knowledge. Aristotle says" the Areopagus gained a high reputation at the time of the Persian war, and so came to impart to the state a stricter (owTovcorepav, i.e. no doubt a more strictly law-abiding) character ; and all that we know of it from other sources is limited to its superintending, restrictive and censorial powers. Legislative power, on the contrary, never belonged to it ; and even as regards the former kind, we have no information as to the means it had at command, in order, for instance, to enforce its veto in the popular assembly. We are safe in assuming that its power in this respect could only be effective, if opinion was divided in the as- sembly itself ;■ and that it was powerless against the unani- mous will of that body, and would have been just as much so, if Solon's laws had continued in unbroken force, and if there had been no interval of Peisistratid monarchy, and of filling-up the Areopagus with the creatures of the tyrants. ■ Pol., v. 4. 8. Kleisthenes. 85 (h.) Ostracism abused by the Athenians. "We have still to say a few words on the ostracism, which Mr. Grote b , in agreement with the view now pretty gene- rally acknowledged to be correct, represents as among the reforms of Kleisthenes. In treating it, he explains pro- foundly and luminously the peculiar significance of the in- stitution, and gives a detailed exposition of the conditions present in free states like those of Greek antiquity, whose existence was essentially dependent on the voluntary obe- dience of the citizens to the laws and the government. In such states, it might prove easy for influential men to raise a party, by whose help they might set themselves above the laws. No more lenient and rational means could be dis- covered of averting any such danger, and avoiding the distracting party-conflicts otherwise inevitable, than that of removing betimes from the state, while it could still be done without an armed resistance, for a certain interval, those from whom such a danger might be apprehended. By this they themselves lost nothing but the chance of becoming more powerful than they ought, while the state was freed from the fear they inspired. This was unques- tionably the idea which Kleisthenes, and the lawgivers of other states in which there were similar institutions, had in their minds in devising them ; and it has not, been mis- apprehended by careful and acute enquirers. Mr. Grote c remarks with disapproval, that many writers have founded upon the ostracism accusations against the Athenians of envy, injustice, and ill-treatment of their superior men. But the accusation has not been so much directed against the ostracism itself in its original conception, as against the application which the Athenians made of it. Those who made it, imagined that the evidence of the ancients, and the instances d in point, shewed that the people were often moved to inflict ostracism, not by real danger or reasonable • fear, but rather by envy and repugnance. And in fact it i> iii. 128. c iii. 137. d [Grote enumerates the cases, and oomments on some of them, iii. 137, 8.] 86 Schdmann on the Constitutional History of Athens. would hardly be possible to oppose this view, however much inclined we may be to view the actions of the Athenian Demes in every case in the best light. («'.) Form of procedure in Ostracism. The form of procedure in ostracism is quite correctly described by Mr. Grote. In particular, he is right in as- suming e that the condition requisite for a valid decree of banishment is to be understood as the unanimity of 6,000 votes; not merely a majority, whether relative or absolute, out of 6,000 votes. The latter, indeed, is what Plutarch states; but the other view, which Philochorus affirmed, is supported by the analogy of the procedure in the case of other votes of a similar kind ; and by the circumstance, that when the assembly had carried a decree that a vote of ostracism should be taken, it was not proceeded with at once, but a later day was fixed, on which the people was to assemble for the purpose. So, if the assembly on that day was not numerous enough for a majority of 6,000 votes to result, that was a proof that the matter did not seem important enough to the people, and the voting led to nothing. If the matter was really thought serious by the people, of course they would come in great numbers, and a majority of 6,000 votes was, in that case, not too much to require. A similar procedure took place with all decrees that belonged to the category of privilegia. In these cases, too, there were separate assemblies : first, one in which the proposal was only announced, and either admitted or disallowed; then a second one, in which it was decided whether what was proposed should be granted or refused. This is particularly plain in the speech against Nesera, p. 1375 f . ' iii. 133. 1 As regards the ostracism, Bb'ckh, who before decided for Plutarch, now (in the second edition of the Staatshaushaltung, i. p. 325) declares for Philo- chorus. I myself, too, withdraw the doubts which I expressed before (de Comitt. Ath., p. 245, 6) more distinctly than I ventured to in the Antiq. jur. publ. Gissc, p. 233. Changes between Kleisthenes and Perikks. 87 (k.) Kleisthenes' Reforms not before 507 b.c. Before leaving the subject of Kleisthenes, there is one minor matter to speak of. The year in which the intro- duction of his constitution is to be placed cannot be fixed with certainty ; Mr. Grote, if we may infer from a passing remark^, seems to assume 509. But that is a little too early. As the head of the opposite party appears h t as Archon in Olymp. 68. 1 (b.c. 508-7), it must be supposed that by that time the party of Kleisthenes had not obtained the predominance which it afterwards obtained, according to Herodotus 1 , chiefly in consequence of the Kleisthenean tribal changes, and which reduced Isagoras to apply for help to King Kleomenes and the Spartans. They compelled Kleisthenes to leave the city ; and it might be assumed that this was the time at which Isagoras, whose party was again decidedly predominant, was elected Archon. But when we read in Herodotus k , how the Senate of that date offered a successful resistance to Isagoras' attempt to dissolve it; and how Isagoras himself, with his champion Kleomenes, was compelled to retire to the Akropolis, and after a short siege, to capitulate and leave the country, we shall not think his election as Archon under those circum- stances very probable. So, if the Archonship of Isagoras preceded the reforms of Kleisthenes, they cannot have taken place before 507. Besides, they were certainly not all in- troduced at once, but gradually ; many of them not till after Kleisthenes' return from the brief absence to which Kleo- menes had forced him. § 7. Changes between Kleisthenes and Pekikles. We hear of no constitutional changes in the interval between Kleisthenes and Perikles, excepting that proposed by Aristeides soon after Platsea, which made the offices of state, with some few exceptions, thenceforth accessible to all citizens not specially disfranchised, without* distinction z iii. 128. h Bockh, C. I. ii. 318. 1 t. 69. k lb., c.72. 88 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. of property-classes. The causes which made this extension of the people's rights advisable or necessary at that time are not hard to see, and are well expounded by Mr. Grote '. Of course, he repeats at this point that the offices were then filled up by election and not by lot, and that the lot was introduced some time later ; but I think I have sufficiently shewn above, that there is no cogency in the arguments he has brought forward against the introduction of the lot as early as by Kleisthenes' constitution. But I readily assent to the other conjecture, that many offices, such as those of Astynomi, Agoranomi, Metronomi, Sitophylakes, if not first instituted, were at least extended, that is, divided among several persons at this time ; that is, after The- inistokles had made Athens essentially a maritime state, and a second town was founded in Peirseus, in which part of these magistrates had to act. § 8. Changes under Perikles. (a.) List of Changes mentioned by the Ancients, and of those vouched for by Grote. "We hear much more, not indeed from the ancients, but from Mr. Grote, of the very important constitutional changes introduced during the time of Perikles. All that the ancients tell us of this, is limited to the diminution of the functions of the Areopagus, and the transference of part of them to the newly-instituted authority, the Nomo- phylakes, and to the introduction of pay for the assembly and the Dikasteries, with which we may connect the lar- gesses in money called Theorika. This and the judicial pay are the only things, the introduction of which is expressly ascribed to Perikles himself; that of pay for the assembly at least falls in his time, and may have been brought about by him, though his name is not mentioned in connection with it ; the curtailing of the Areopagus was effected on the proposal of Ephialtes, but acting in concert with Perikles. This, then, is what the ancients tell us. Mr. Grote, on the other hand, thinks it certain that it 1 iv. 32, c. 44. Perikles. 89 was Perikles who first limited the magistrates' authority, by separating from their administrative functions the judicial ones which were previously bound up with them, and leav- ing them only the right of inflicting a small fine m - That is, therefore, he was the first to make the magistrates mere agents of "instruction," instead of judges, and to introduce the distinction between Jus and Judicium. At this time, too, Mr. Grote tells us, public arbitrators were first appointed 11 , who had to decide as judges of first in- stance in private suits; and at this time the procedure, in bringing in new and repealing old laws, was regulated by the ordinance of Nomothetse, which withdrew the de- cision upon laws from the public assembly, and transferred it to a smaller body of sworn citizens . Again, it was at this time that the ypa^rj irapavofiav was introduced ; in other words, the right given to every citizen to attack as illegal, and prosecute in judicial form, a proposed law or psephism, the result being' that the law or psephism im- peached was suspended till the decision of the court, and if the verdict was unfavourable, was annulled p. All this, Mr. Grote vouches for. (b.) Not improbable that these latter Institutions were older than Perikles. Perikles and his administration are often enough dis- cussed by the ancients, and besides a number of passages in which, as occasion offers, more or less detailed mention is made of them, we have a biography of Perikles at full length by Plutarch. But neither in the occasional refer- ences, nor in Plutarch, is a single syllable said of any of these important enactments, which Mr. Grote feels justi- fied in ascribing to him with such confidence. It seems to me that this necessarily leads to the conclusion, that the ancients knew nothing of them. The great importance of the ordinances forbids us to suppose that they could have been passed over in silence, whether on purpose, or by m Vol. iv. Ill and 123, c. 46. » iv. 102, [Grote does not say they were first appointed under Perikles] . ° iv. 116. f iv. 118. 90 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. chance, if the ancients had known of them ; and it could not be thought more probable that a malicious chance should have deprived us of just those passages in which they were mentioned. Mr. Grote himself, as we saw above in treating of the Kleisthenean Demes, admits the principle that important changes ought not to be believed in without positive evidence ; here there is no positive evidence ; what is to supply its place? The internal evidence, from the nature of the case, and the impossibility of the opposite opinion. Mr. Grote i says that the opinion which represents " the popular Dikasteries, and the Nomothetae, as institutions of Solon, and as merely supplied with pay by Perikles, prevents all clear view of the growth of the Athenian democracy, by throwing back its last elaborations to the period of its early and imperfect start." Of course, if the notion really was that those institutions were not merely founded by Solon's legislation, but had the same extent of activity from the very beginning as we find them with in the Periklean age, Mr. Grote might well dispute it. But who ever entertained such a notion? The Helisea was a select committee of jurors, for the purpose of sitting as a court of highest instance in public and private cases, and assembled for this purpose sometimes in larger, and sometimes in smaller sections. Does Mr. Grote really think that such a body could not possibly exist, without forthwith assuming the position which it afterwards came to hold in consequence of altered conditions ? I have already dis- cussed the subject in sufficient detail, and mentioned the courts which existed over and above the Helisea ; viz., the Areopagus with more extensive powers, the judges of first instance, the cantonal judges, and the Disetetse, so that I need only refer to what has been said. For as for Mr. Grote's transference of the establishment of Disetetse to the age of Perikles, it is simply an arbitrary assertion', which we could only be induced to controvert by argu- ments, if he had himself supported it by any. As regards the Nomotheta?, Mr. Grote himself admits 8 that this in- i iv. 123. r [Does Grote make it? see n. .u. p. 89, sup.] ■ is, 116. Perikles. °1 stitution was an important limitation on the legislative power of the general assembly of the people. "The Ec- clesia became incompetent either to pass a new law, or to repeal a law already in existence." He fur- ther describes it as a wise provision, that legislation was not left to the excitable populace, not bound by an oath, but was reserved for a committee of sworn citizens, which was sufficiently numerous to be a complete representation of the whole, but because of the age of its members, their oath, and the prescribed judicial procedure, was better suited for careful, comprehensive, and conscientious de- liberation. But according to this, he should not have as- cribed the institution to the last elaboration and develop- ment of the democracy, which it was rather intended to counteract. In the stage of fully - developed democracy, as we see it in the times of Demosthenes, we find the or- dinance of the Nomothetse for this very reason, not indeed abolished, but continually circumvented and violated, as a restriction on popular power. And then there found its way in the form of legislation, which Mr. Grote must as- cribe to the pre-Periklean, i.e. less-developed democracy; un- less he prefers either to say that before Perikles there were no new laws passed, and no old ones repealed, or to point out some other form in which it could have been done. The r) •jrapavopwv is denied to the pre-Periklean age, with as little justice as the Homothetse. It is a second measure of precaution against democratic temerity. If the official authorities for the purpose had neglected, or had failed to hinder an illegal and mischievous decree, there was still this procedure, which opened a method to well- affected citizens, of subjecting it to the judgment of a smaller and more prudent assembly of sworn members, and possibly of annulling it. On the organization of the Helia3a, Mr. Grote says', " I do not here mean to affirm that there never was any trial by the people before the time of Perikles and Ephial- tes. I doubt not that before their time the numerous judicial assembly called Helisea, pronounced upon charges ' iv. 103. 92 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. against accountable magistrates, as well as upon various other accusations of public importance ; and perhaps, in some cases, separate bodies of them may have been drawn by lot for particular trials. But it is not the less true, that the systematic distribution and constant employment of the numerous Dikasts of Athens, cannot have begun before the age of these two statesmen, since it was only then that the practice of paying them began. For so large a sacrifice of time on the part of poor men .... cannot be conceived without an assured remuneration." The for- mation of sections out of the Heliastic body, which is in this passage admitted as an exception, and for particular cases, ought properly to be regarded as the rule. Even before there were six thousand Heliasts, there could hardly be a reason for convoking the whole body in all ordinary cases; and if so, a fixed division into sections, or Dikas- teries as the Athenians called them, was far more probable, than that on each occasion the number required should be taken by lot for that turn. But as in course of time the demand for the performance of Heliastic functions went on increasing, it was necessary also to increase their number to a corresponding extent. It is not quite clear whether the Heliasts were only taken from among those who offered themselves, or from among all citizens who possessed the legal qualifications, i.e. were over thirty, and were not disfranchised. If the former was the case, then as long as there was no pay, only the wealthier citizens would offer themselves, and to attract the poorer as well, it was neces- sary to offer indemnification, for the sacrifice in time lost from their business; if the latter was the case, it was the more right and reasonable to give them compensation for a service from which they might not withdraw, especially from the time when this service came to be so frequently demanded. Of course, we are not to conceive the sittings of the He- liastic courts as being so frequent, and consisting of so many members, as might appear from Aristophanes' es- timate of the judicial pay". Omitting the festivals, and " Wasps, 660 fi. Perikles. 93 otter days on which no courts could be held, there would hardly be sittings of every court on every court-day. In many cases whole sections of five hundred members did not sit, but only fractions of sections. A "Phasis," for instance, was tried according to Pollux before 400 judges, if it concerned an amount of more than 1,000 drachmae, but before 200, if the amount was less ; and thus we must assume that in all cases the number of judges varied with the importance of the case. In more important matters, indeed, we even find several sections united. Now a great increase of law -business dates particularly from the time at which the Athenians brought the litigation of the sub- ject allies before their own city courts ; a measure which, like the introduction of judicial pay, belongs to the Peri- klean age; and if any one ascribes also to that age the number of 6,000 altogether, 500 in each section, and 1,000 substitutes, there is no objection to be made. So much we may grant to Mr. Grote. But to go further, and ascribe the whole organization of the Helisea to no earlier time than this, and even to assume, as Mr. Grote does, an entire revolution of the judicial system in it, is not made neces- sary or justifiable by anything we know of. (c.) Judicial pay at first one Obol. The amount of the judicial pay was certainly three obols at the time of the Peloponnesian war and later ; at an earlier time it seems to have been only one obol, as Bockh has made extremely probable, even if he has not proved it to demonstration. Mr. Grote x makes some objections to his proof, but merely on the ground that he thought one obolus too small a compensation for the time which the judge spent on his duty : and it is true that an obol was not as much as one of the common people could earn in a day. So, if a man of this class was compelled to be- come a Heliast even against his will, then his pay was not an adequate compensation. But it is anything but clear whether there was any such compulsion, as I pointed out * iv. 121, o. 46. 94 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. above; and in the Wasps of Aristophanes the Heliast's function appears all through as voluntary and self-sought. An obolus might be sufficient to make those people inclined to perform the function, to whom the small receipt was not an unwelcome assistance, i.e. not the very poor, but the less rich. Later, when three obols came to be paid, it was especially the poor who came forward for the sortition. (d.) A iical airb o-vfiftoXwv included all Law-suits carried on by Allies at Athens. As I alluded above to the litigation of the allies which was brought before the Athenian courts, and as Mr. Grote y too treats of it at length, a brief observation upon it may be inserted here. Mr. Grrote supposes, with great proba- bility, that at the first foundation of the Athenian sym- machy, a court of justice was established besides 2 the Synedrion of Delos, partly to decide the disputes of the confederate states with each other, partly those between the members of different states. The latter purpose pre- supposes covenants about the principles and the form of procedure which were to be followed in litigation arising between members of different states, and covenants of this kind were, as is well-known, called crvfj,/3o\a. We may there- fore say that the confederates had not merely a avfifiaxla, but also v." But this is no proof that if they had stayed at home, and entered upon law-suits with Athenians there, these would not also have belonged to the category of SUai airb i>. It only shews that such persons were more in the habit of initiating suits against Athenians in foreign parts, having a better chance against them there. But Bockh" asks, what advantage could accrue to the plaintiff from leaving his country, if the suit initiated in his place of residence could not possibly result in any other mode of decision than would have been open to him at home ? The answer is, that I am not referring to a suit brought from the new place of residence before an Athenian court, but of a suit which the plaintiff might bring against an Athe- nian before a foreign court, in consequence of o-vfij3o\a existing between Athens and independent foreign states. That there were <7i5/*/3o\a in virtue of which the plaintiff > Att. Proo. 779. " De Csede Herodia, 745. « Staatsh. i. 530. 96 Schbmann on the Constitutional History of Athens.' 1 was not compelled to have recourse to the defendant's place of residence, but might prosecute him where he found him, I think that I am justified in assuming with Hudtwalcker a And it is clear that the plaintiff against an Athenian, was in a better position before a foreign court of justice, than before one at Athens. § 9. The Eevision of the Laws under Eukleides not caused by the amnesty. The changes in the constitution during the latter years of the Peloponnesian war, were first the establishment of Probouli immediately after the disaster in Sicily, then the oligarchy of the four hundred, and finally, after the capture of Athens by Lysander, the sovereignty of the so-called thirty tyrants. All of these were of short duration, and without permanent consequences, and so may be passed over here; the rather, that the doubts which I might express concerning Mr. Grote's account only touch some accessory points of small importance. So also the remarks I have to make about the restoration of the democracy after the fall of the thirty, and the revision of the laws, which was then set on foot, are of no great consequence ; still they may be "inserted here. Mr. Grote thinks that after it had been determined to restore the Drakonian and Solonian laws e , it was found, on closer inspection, that this was incompatible with the amnesty which had been just sworn. According to those laws, the perpetrators of enor- mities under the thirty had rendered themselves guilty, and were open to trial. Yet the amnesty had secured impunity to all of them, with some individual exceptions. To escape this consequence (i.e. to avoid the resulting contradiction between the restoration of the old laws and the amnesty), it was enacted, on the proposition of Tisamenus, to review the laws of Solon and Drako, and re-enact them, with such additions and amendments as might be deemed expedient. And this is the way in which the orator Andokides f also represents the case; but it cannot possibly be the right d V. d. Diat. 125. e -vi. 5, e. 66. « De Myster. , 82. Revision of the Laws in the time of Eukleides. 97 account. Supposing it had really been feared that the decree previously framed, enacting that the ancient laws should be restored for a time, would endanger the amnesty, the most natural and simple remedy was to affix a clause to the decree, protecting the amnesty. The psephism of Tisamenus says not a syllable of the amnestied offenders, neither has its meaning and purpose anything to do with them. It decrees a general revision of the laws, and that the necessary additions should be made B . Such a revision was necessary, even if no amnesty had preceded it. It was not ordained for the first time by the psephism of Tisa- menus; it had been decreed before, and the Nomothetse were already elected for the purpose. Obviously this de- cree was the same as that which gave temporary authority to the ancient laws, and appointed a no less temporary government of twenty persons. This is quite clear from the words of Andokides : e'i\e? av ol vofioi, redeiev Teas Be xprjcrOat, tols SoXtovos voftois teal toIs Apatcovros Oeo-fiols' for «o? av ol vofiot Tedeiev obviously means, " until the new legislation, which is to be framed on the basis of the old revised and amended, is completed." The psephism of Tisamenus only contains the particular rules of the pro- cedure to be observed in this revision, and in these ad- ditions. Besides, a general revision of the laws, in order e To save my readers the trouble of reference, I add the psephism itself, from Andok. de Mysteriis, 83, "E5o£e t£ d^pup- TtadpLtvos eiire - iroAweiWflai 'Adrjvaiovs Kara ra irdrpia, v6fiois 8e xpycrdaL tois ~2,6\vup.ous cKoneiy Tip fiov\op.epip, Kal irapa.Zi56vTatv tois apxais Iv TipSe Tip p.r,vl. robs 5e TrapaSi- Sofievovs v6fiovs fioKifiaaaTU Trpkrzpov t\ 0ov\1} Kal ol yofioderai ol Trei'TaK6inoL, otts ol Stj^^toi e'l\ovro, 4iretS^i op.up.6Kao if. ££e7vai Se Kal l$it*ny Tip /3ov\op.4yip eialovTi els t))v 0ov\i)y ovp.f$ov\eieiy, '6 ti tai ayaBbv %XV ,re P' ™ > ' "4" 1 *"'- eTieiiav Se TeBixru/ ol v6p.oi iwt/ieKetaSa t) fiov\i) 7) it- 'Apelov Trdyov t&v v6puv, oirws \\v at apxal rols kuiUvois vdpois xp&vTat. robs 5e Kvpovp.4vovs twv v6p.oiv avaypd- ipeiv els tbp to1x ov i '^ a "ftp irporepov aveypdipfiffav, ffKoireiv Tip fiov\op.hip. It may be doubted whether the form of the psephism, as inserted in the speech of Andokides, is authentic; but no valid doubts can be alleged against its matter. H 98 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. to save the amnesty, is in itself something quite inconceivable. It could only consist in rejecting all the laws which the am- nestied persons had transgressed, and replacing them by others. Were these others to have no penalties for the of- fences which such persons had committed, and for which the ancient laws prescribed penalties? I imagine the offences had penalties attached in the revised code as in the ancient ; the amnesty was a special measure in favour of individuals, and left the general legislation absolutely untouched. About the two kinds of Nomothetse who are distinguished in the psephism of Tisamenus, which I subjoined in the note, Mr. Grote pronounces for the view that those elected by the Senate are only a more select committee from among the five hundred elected by the Demotae. They had the special duty of making or collecting proposals, which were then to be made public in the way laid down in the Psephisma, and finally to be submitted to the examination of the Senate, and the whole body of the five hundred Nomothetae. This is clearly the most probable view; but it has already been put forward by C. P. Hermann \ § 10. Reasons for Aristophon's Law about Citizenship. The time of the restored democracy under Eukleides is also marked by the law of Aristophon, which enacted that citizenship should henceforward be confined to children whose father and mother were both citizens, and that those who had not citizen parents on both sides should be reck- oned aliens. Previously, the custom had been less strict, and citizenship had not been denied to the latter class. Mr. Grote ' believes that he sees the reason of this in the po- sition of Athens during the time of her maritime empire, when Athenian citizens were dispersed among the confederate states all over the islands and coasts of the ^Egean sea. This must have tended materially to encourage intermarriages between them and the women of other Grecian insular states; and k In the Jahrb. f. wissensoh. Eritik. 1842, i. p. 128. ' vi. 18, o. 66. The Law of Aristophon. 99 by recognising such, marriages as valid, and the sons born of them as Athenian citizens, the bonds between Athens and her confederates were strengthened, and a certain Pan- Hellenic sympathy was nourished. But when, after the loss of the maritime empire, her position was altered, then this consideration too ceased to exist ; and Pan-Hellenic sympathy gave place to the individualistic tendency which characterised all Greeks, and to the exclusion of aliens from the franchise. No doubt there is some truth in this view ; still, the matter has another side, which Mr. Grote overlooks. The earlier procedure had a reason, not merely in Pan- Hellenic, but also in democratic tendencies. Democracy was everywhere inclined to increase the numbers on which its power rested. So there were, as we know from Aris- totle 11 , democracies in which all sons of citizen mothers ranked as citizens, even if the fathers were aliens. He tells 1 us, too, that in order to secure the democracy, the popular leaders are in the habit of strengthening the Demos, by receiving as large numbers as possible, and making them into citizens ; not merely those born in lawful wedlock, but also illegitimate children, and those who are of citizen birth on one side only, whether by father or by mother. The great facility with which Athenian citizenship was given to all comers from foreign parts in the time of the classical orators, is the subject of loud complaints in Isokrates and Demosthenes. But as regards the law of Aristophon, Pe- rikles had carried just the same law, which was now merely re-enacted by him, forty years before, at the height of the maritime empire. Therefore, Mr. Grote' s m expression needs to be corrected when he speaks of a law which prevailed before Eukleides, according to which children of an un- equal™ marriage were nevertheless citizens. Such a law, which would have annulled that of Perikles, there was not. It was only that a more lax practice had crept in, as it crept in again soon after Aristophon. Herr Wes- k Pol., iii. 5. 7. ' Pol. , vi. 4. 16. » vi. 18. » [This would mean, where either husband only or wife only were citizens. Grote does not include the latter case.] 100 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. termaim has made it very probable tbat even the Periklean law was no more than a renewal of an old Solonian law, which had merely fallen out of use by degrees, but had never been formally repealed. The reason of its renewal by Aristophon certainly lay not so much in the change of external relations by the loss of the maritime empire, as in the endeavour to oppose some wholesome limits to the democratic elements, which were but too powerful in the state. The same endeavour is perceptible in the far more thorough proposal of Phormisius, being, however, no longer practicable, according to which only those who had landed property were in future to rank as full citizens. The law of Aristophon, indeed, was more lenient than that of Perikles had been ; it deprived no one of citizen- ship who possessed it, and only ordained a stricter rule for the future ; whereas the other had struck off not much less than five thousand citizens. § 11. Proposal of Phormisius to restrict the Franchise not oligarchic. I cannot refrain from saying a few more words on the proposal of Phormisius, because Mr. Grote has judged of it not only with great disfavour, but, as I think, with great injustice. It is entirely wrong to regard Phormisius as an adherent of the oligarchical party. We read, that he was among those who returned to the city with Thrasybulus after the fall of the thirty; he had therefore fled before the oligarchs, had probably fought on the side of their antagonists, and helped to win liberty back again. But he was no friend to the all-levelling democracy, which reigned at Athens after the time of Perikles. Granting that we are not to doubt the statement of Dionysius p , that his proposal had the approval of the Lacedsemonians, still we may assert with confidence that he did not make it in order to please them, but from a genuine conviction, and Beitrage zur Geschichte des athenischen Biirgerrechts, in the reports of the Transactions of the K. Sachs. Gesellschaft d. Wissensch. philol. histor. CI. vol. i. p. 200 ft. r Lysias, c. 32. Proposal of Phormisius. 101 with patriotic motives. Mr. Grotei says disapprovingly; "Phormisius had of course at his command the usual ar- guments, by which it is attempted to prove that poor men have no business with political judgment or action." And he then repeats the accusations which Lysias (in the frag- ment preserved in Dionysius) brings forward against Phor- misius; designating his proposal as malicious and absurd, as having for its purpose to introduce oligarchy, and to rob Athens of a great part of the power she derived from her constitution, of her patriotism, and her harmony. " Never, certainly r ," he continues, " was the fallacy which connects political depravity or incapacity with a poor station, and political virtue or judgment with wealth, more conspicu- ously unmasked, than in reference to the recent experi- ence of Athens. The remark of Thrasybulus 8 was most true, that a greater number of atrocities, both against person and against property, had been committed in a few months by the Thirty" and their adherents, "than the poor majority of the Demos had sanctioned during two generations of democracy." This is very true; but how far it can go towards justifying the reproaches made against Phormisius I do not see. Oligarchy differs toto ccelo from what Phormisius intended. His proposal, if carried, would, according to Dionysius, have deprived very nearly five thousand citizens of their full citizenship, therefore about the same number as had some decades of years before been struck off according to the law of Perikles. The question might be raised, whether the want of a citizen mother was really a more proper ground of expulsion, than the want of that kind of property which all ancient political philosophers regarded as the only security for a trustworthy body of citizens. Mr. Grote* only mentions the Periklean law in passing, and would certainly not suffer any one, by reason of that law, to re- proach the statesman whom he justly extols, with oligar- chical or even anti-democratic sentiments. Besides, a con- stitution which invites some three-quarters of the whole i Vol. vi. p. 5, e. 66. ' Id. ib. » Xen. Hell., ii. 4. 40. ' iv. 290, o. 49. 102 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. body to a share in the government, and only excludes one quarter, is still democratic enough; it is still at least a large majority, ruling over a vastly smaller minority. It is all the more democratic, that it only makes landed property, as such, the condition of citizenship, without de- manding any definite amount of it, thus not excluding even the smallest landowner. It does not even make any difference in privilege, according to different amounts of property, as Solon did, but gives equal rights to the largest and smallest landowners. There is no reason for supposing that Phormisius meant anything but this, e.g. that he had in view a timocratic arrangement by classes. Among the minority whom his proposal would have excluded from full citizenship, there were no doubt many brave and honourable people ; no one would deny that. And of course they were not all poor ; there might be individuals among them who possessed more than most of the small landowners, whom yet Phormisius did not try to exclude ; but the greater part of them neces- sarily consisted of that " banausic " and maritime popu- lation, which ancient politicians unanimously, and without exception, designate as least fitted for the decision and direction of matters of state. Is it likely that so universal an opinion rested only on imagination, and not on experi- ence? Mr. Grote quotes, on the other hand, in praise of this class, a passage from Xenophon u , which says that there was less insubordination among the common people who served on board the fleet, than among the richer classes who served as cavalry or hoplites. The remark is no doubt correct, and there were good reasons for the fact, which are partly at least indicated in Xenophon himself; that is, that the officers of the hoplites and cavalry, appointed by demo- cratic election, were very often destitute of the qualities requisite for command, whereas the ships' crews were, as a rule, under well-trained captains, and the necessity of precise order was far more obvious in the service at sea than on land. But what has this obedience and discipline to do with capacity for political rule ? Of course, it is an " Memorab.. iii. 5, 19. Proposal of Phormisius. 103 old and true saying, that in order to govern, men must learn to obey; but I do not think that the converse will hold good, and that whoever can obey is therefore fit to govern. § 12. Criticism of Grote's estimate of the Athenian Democracy. Again, as regards the comparison of the Athenian Demos and its acts with the conduct of the oligarchs, there cannot of course be a moment's doubt which side committed most, and most heinous, crimes ; but it must be repeated that such a constitution as Phormisius proposed is really anything but oligarchical ; that it is, in fact, quite sufficiently democratic. Only a madman could wish to defend the actions of which the oligarchy was guilty in this period of re-action against the democracy ; but we are not to forget in this question that the dangerous character of this oligarchy had its root in nothing else than the extreme exasperation with which the wealthy and cultivated minority saw itself subjected to the domination of the masses, which necessarily consisted in great part of rough and uncultivated persons, and which were guided by demagogues destitute of merit and worth. That such a sovereignty of the masses must have been op- pressive in the highest degree to all who did not belong to them, is clear ; and the remarks made on this point in the tract on the Athenian commonwealth among Xenophon's writings, may be set down as one-sided, but hardly as un- founded. The hostility to the democracy can be thus ex- plained, although the actions to which it led were morally most reprehensible, and even politically were mistakes. That, on the other hand, the populace of Athens compared with the oligarchs is seen to be infinitely better, any one will gladly admit. Every one will say, with the most as- sured conviction, that if ever any people was capable of self-government, the Athenians were that people. This is Pausanias' x opinion, when he says that democracy never made any people great except the Athenians, and it had * iY. 35. 3. 104 Schomann on the Constitutional History of Athens. made them great because they were superior to all other Greeks in native good sense, and transgressed least against the laws which they had. Mr. Grote's work, in many of its chapters, forms such a corroborative commentary on these words, as must satisfy the warmest friends and admirers of Athens. He has had the skill to refute successfully not a few charges which have been brought against the Athe- nian Demos, to reduce others at least to smaller proportions, and to explain and extenuate what could not be praised. Such reproaches, he remarks y, rest to a great extent on the authority of passages of Aristophanes, which cannot possibly pass as credible evidence, where the object is to obtaia his- torical truth. And it is true that Aristophanes is a cari- caturist, who idealises his figures in his own fashion ; that is, by distorting them beyond reality in the direction of what is ugly and ridiculous ; still, a good caricaturist will have skill to make the original recognisable, in spite of the distortions; and Aristophanes was no exception. Mr. Grote, too, idealises a little, and of course with an opposite tendency. Even to a Kleon, whom no one ever praised before, he succeeds in giving a tolerable, even a laudable appearance, with greater skill than Isokrates to his " illaudatus Busiris." His representation of the pro- ceedings at the trial of the generals who were condemned to death for alleged neglect of duty after the battle of Arginusse, must be called a real masterpiece, which can- not easily be matched. The defence of the Athenians against the charge of mean ingratitude in the condemnation of Miltiades, and of crying injustice in the sentence of death upon Socrates, leave nothing to be desired ; and everything good and commendable that the Athenians did at home or abroad, in peace or war, finds with him complete apprecia- tion and due honour. Yet, though we gladly agree in all the good that he says of the Athenians, though we readily listen to his palliation of their faults and failings, still all this cannot modify our judgment of their democracy. Even the noble people of Athens did not bear it long without ex- periencing in itself its mischievous effects ; even in their * yi. 38, note, c. 67. Estimate of the Athenian Democracy. 105 case it proved a dangerous gift, which ends by enfeebling and undermining the virtues by which alone it can be sup- ported. The part of the history which has yet to come will compel Mr. Grote to this admission, however warm a friend of the democracy he may be. Whether, indeed, the democracy was not inevitable is another question. It must be conceded that, without it, Athens would not have been so great and so brilliant as we see her in the fifth century. But whether precisely this kind of greatness and brilliancy was the most desirable ; whether the noblest pro- ductions of Athenian genius, which will never cease to educate and delight mankind, could not have come into being under a somewhat less absolute democracy, may be left to every one to consider for himself. But this much is certain ; that among the ancients themselves, those whom we honour as the best and wisest, the creators of the most imperishable works of genius, do not appear as friendly to the democracy in question. But it is not to my present purpose to enter upon discussions of this kind ; my purpose was only to correct, as well as I could, the points in which Mr. Grote's account of the history of the Athenian con- stitution, and the successive stages of its development, appeared to me incorrect. I desired to contribute my share to prevent false views, recommended by his autho- rity, from obtaining more general acceptance, and driving out the true. I recognise, as readily as any one, the great value of his work as a whole, in spite of the criticisms which I have made on some details ; and I am glad to end my treatise as I began it, with this recognition, and with an expression of gratitude for the pleasure and profit which the study of his work has afforded, and will continue to afford me. Jjrinith hg fraud grate an& do., (Jrofan fjtttb, . THEOLOGICAL WORKS, $c. (continued). THE BOOK OF COMMON PRAYER, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE HISTOET OF THE SUCCES- SIVE REVISIONS OF THE BOOK OF COMMON PRAYER. By James Parker, Hon. M.A. Oxon. Crown 8vo., cloth, 12s. THE EIEST PRAYER-BOOK OE EDWARD YL, compared with the Successive Revisions of the Book of Common Prayer; with a Concordance and Index to the Rubrics in the several editions. By the same Author. Cr. 8vo., el., 12s. REV. E. B. PUSEY, D.D. DANIEL THE PROPHET. Nine Lectures delivered in the Divinity School of the University of Oxford. With a new Preface. By E.B.Posey, D.D. , &c. Seventh Thousand. 8vo., cloth, 10s. (id. THE MINOE PEOPHETS ; with a Commentary Explanatory and Practical, and Introductions to the Several Books. 4to., cloth, 31s. 6d. THE DOCTEINE OE THE EEAL PEESENCE, as contained in the Fathers from the death of St. John the Evangelist to the 4th General Council. By the Rev. E. B. Pusey, D.D. 8vo., cloth, 7s. 6d. THE EEAL PEESENCE, the Doctrine of the English Church, with a vindicaiion of the reception by the wicked and of the Adoration of our Lord Jesus Christ truly present. By the Rev. E. B. Pusey, D.D. 8vo., 6s. THE LATE REV. J. KEBLE, M.A. STUDIA SACRA. COMMENTARIES on the Introductory Verses of St. John's Gospel, and on a Portion of St. Paul's Epistle to the Romans j with other Theological Papers by the late Rev. John Keble, M.A. 8vo., el., 10s. 6d. OCCASIONAL PAPERS AND REVIEWS. By the late Rev. John Keble, Author of " The Christian Year." Demy 8vo., cloth extra, 12s. LETTERS OF SPIRITUAL COUNSEL AND GUIDANCE. By the late Rev. J. Keble, M.A., Vicar of Hursley. Edited, with a New Preface, by R. F. Wilson, M.A., Vicar of Rownhams, &c. Third Edition, much en- larged, Post 8vo., cloth, 6s. OUTLINES OE INSTRUCTIONS OR MEDITATIONS FOR THE CHURCH'S SEASONS. By John Keble, M.A. Edited, with a Preface, by R. F. Wilson, M.A. Crown 8vo., cloth, toned paper, 5s. THE LATE BISHOP OF BRECHIN. AN EXPLANATION OF THE THIRTY-NINE ARTICLES. With an Epistle Dedicatory to the Rev. E. B. Pusey, D.D. By A. P. Forbes, D.C.L., Bishop of Brechin. Second Edition, Crown 8vo., cloth, 12s. A SHORT EXPLANATION OF THE NICENE CEEED, for the Use of Persons beginning the Study of Theology. By Alexander Penrose Forbes, D.C.L., Bishop of Brechin. Second Edition. Crown 8vo., cloth, 6s. THE LORD BISHOP OE SALISBURY. THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE HOLY SPIRIT IN THE BODY OF CHRIST. The Bampton Lectures for 1868. By George Moberly, D.C.L., Lord Bishop of Salisbury. 2nd Edit. Crown 8vo., cloth, 7s. 6d. SERMONS ON THE BEATITUDES, with others mostly preached before the University of Oxford. By the same. Third Edition. Crown 8vo., cloth, 7s. 6d. REV. WILLIAM BRIGHT, D.D. A HISTORY OF THE CHURCH, from the Edict of Milan, a.d. 31S, to the Council of Chalcedon, a.l>. 451 . Second Edition. Post 8vo., 10s. 6d. TKEOLOGICAL WOMKS, $c. (continued). APOLLOS ; or, THE "WAT OF GOD. A Plea for tie Eeligion of Scripture. By A. Cleveland Coxe, Bishop of New York. Crown 8vo., cl., 5s. THE HISTOET OF CONFIEMATION. By William Jackson, M. A., Queen's College, Oxford ; Vicar of Heathfield, Sussex. Crown 8vo., cloth, is. A COMMENTAET ON THE EPISTLES AND GOSPELS IN" THE BOOK OF COMMON PRAYER. Extracted from Writings of the Fathers of the Holy Catholic Church, anterior to the Division of the East and West. With an Introductory Notice hy the Dean of St. Paul's. In Two Vols., Crown 8vo., cloth, 15s. THE EXPLANATION oe the APOCALYPSE by VENEEABLE BEDA, Translated by the Rev. EDW. MARSHALL, M.A., F.S.A., formerly Fellow of Corpus Christi College, Oxford. 180 pp. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 3s. 6d. GODET'S BIBLICAL STUDIES ON THE OLD TESTAMENT. Edited by the Hon. and Rev. W. H. Lyttelton. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 6s. THE CATHOLIC DOCTEINE OF THE SACEIFICE AND PARTICIPATION OF THE HOLY EUCHARIST. By George Trevor, D.D., M.A., Canon of York; Rector of Beeford. Second Edition, revised and enlarged. Crown 8vo., cloth, 10s. 6d. THE LAST TWELVE YEESES OF THE GOSPEL ACCOEDING TO S. MARK Vindicated against Recent Critical Objectors and Established, by John W. Bueoon, B.D., Dean of Chichester. With Facsimiles of Codex s and Codex L. 8vo., cloth, 12s. DISCOURSES ON PEOPHECT. In which are considered its Struc- ture, Use, and Inspiration. By John Davison, B.D. A New Edition. 8vo., cloth, 9s. THE PEINCIPLES OF DIVINE SEEVTCE ; or, An Inquiry con- cerning the True Manner of Understanding and Using the Order for Morning and Evening Prayer, and for the Administration of the Holy Communion in the English Church. By the late Ven. Philip Freeman, Archdeacon of Exeter. A New Edition. 2 vols., 8vo., cloth, 16s. CATENA AUEEA. A Commentary on the Four Gospels, collected out of the Works of the Fathers by S. Thomas Asuinas. Uniform with the Library of the Fathers. Re-issue. Complete in 6 vols. 8vo., cloth, £2 2s. CHEISTIANITT AS TAUGHT BT S. PAUL. The Bampton Lectures for 1870. To which is added an Appendix of the Continuous Sense of S. Paul's Epistles ; with Notes and Metalegomeria. By the Rev. W. J. Ieohs, D.D., &c. Second Edition, with New Preface, 8vo., with Map, cloth, 9s. CHAEACTEEISTlCS OF CHRISTIAN MOEALITT. The Bamp- ton Lectures for 1873. By the Rev. I. Gregory Smith, M.A. Second Edition, Crown 8vo., cloth, 3s. 6d. BEDE'S ECCLESIASTICAL HISTOET OF THE ENGLISH NATION. A New Translation by the Rev. L. Gideey, M.A., Chaplain of St. Nicholas', Salisbury. Crown 8vo., cloth, 6s. * ANCIENT DOCTMINAL TREATISES, $c. THE CONSTITUTIONS AND CANONS ECCLESIASTICAL OF THE CHURCH OF ENGLAND, Referred to their Original Sources, and Illustrated with Explanatory Notes. By Mackenzie E. C. Walcott, B.D., F.S.A., Precentor and Prebendary of Chichester. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 4s. A CRITICAL HISTORY OF THE ATHANASIAN CREED, by the Rev. Daniel Waterland, D.D. Edited by the Rev. J. R. King, M.A. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 5s. THE PASTORAL RULE OF ST. GREGORY. Sancti Gregorii Papa? Regulae Pastoralis Liber, ad Johannem Episcopum Civitatis Ravennae. "With an English Translation. By the Rev. H. R. Bramley, M.A., Fellow of Magdalen College, Oxford. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 6s. THE DEFINITIONS OF THE CATHOLIC FAITH and Canons of Discipline of the first four General Councils of the Universal Church. In Greek and English. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 2s. 6d. DE FIDE ET STMBOLO : Documenta qusedam nee non Aliquorum SS. Patrum Tractatus. Edidit Carolus A. Heurtley, S.T.P., Dom. Mar- garetae Praelector, et jEdis Christi Canonicus. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 4s. 6d. S.AURELlTJS AUGUSTINUS, Episcopus Hipponensis, de Catechi- ssandis Rudibns, de Fide Rerum qua? non videntur, de Utilitate Credendi. In Usum Juniorum. Edidit C. Mabeiott, S.T.B., Olim Coll. Oriel. Socius. New Edition. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 3s. 6d. ANALECTA CHRISTIANA, In usum Tironum. Excerpta, Epi- stolae, &c, ex Eusebii, &c. ; S. Ignatii Epistolae ad Smymaeos et ad Poly- carpuin ; E. S. Clementis Alexandri Paedagogo excerpta; S. Athanasii Sermo contra Gentes. Edidit et Annotationibus illustravit C Marriott, S.T.B. 8vo., 10s. 6d. S. PATRIS NOSTRI S. ATHANASII ARCHIEPISCOPI ALEX- ANDRIA DE INCARNATIONE VERBI, ejusque Corporali ad nos Ad- ventu. With an English Translation by the Rev. J. Ridgway, B.D., Hon. Canon of Christ Church. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 5s. OXFORD SERIES OF DEVOTIONAL WORKS. Fcap. 8vo., printed in Red The Imitation of Christ. FOUR BOOKS. By Thomas A Kem- pts. Cloth, 4s. — Pocket Edit., 32mo., cl., Is. Andrewes' Devotions. DEVOTIONS. By the Right Rev. Father in God, Launcelot Andreweb. Translated from the Greek and Latin, and arranged anew. Antique cloth, 5s. Taylor's Holy Living. THE RULE AND EXERCISES OF HOLT LIVING. By Bishop Jeremy Taylor. Antique cloth, 4s. — Pocket Edi- tion, 32mo., cloth, Is. Taylor's Holy Dyingr. THE RULE AND EXERCISES OF HOLT DTING. By Bishop Jeremy Taylor. Antique cloth, 4s. — Pocket Edi- tion, 32mo., cloth, Is. Taylor's Golden Grove. THE GOLDEN GROVE; a Choice Manual, containing what is to be Believed, Practised, and Desired, or Prayed for. By Bishop Jeremy Taylor. Printed uniform with " Holy Living and Holy Dying." An- tique cloth, 3s. 6d'. Sutton's meditations. GODLY MEDITATIONS UPON THE MOST HOLT SACRAMENT OF THE LORD'S SUPPER. By Christopher Sut- ton, D.D., late Prebend of Westminster. A new Edition. Antique cloth, 5s. . and Black, on toned paper. Laud's Devotions. THE PRIVATE DEVOTIONS of Dr. William Laud, Archbishop of Canter- bury, and Martyr. Antique cloth, 5s. Spinckes' Devotions. TRUE CHURCH OF ENGLAND MAN'S COMPANION IN THE CLOSET ; or, a complete Manual of Private Devotions, collected from the Writings of eminent Di- vines of the Church of England. Antique cloth, 4s. Ancient Collects. ANCIENT COLLECTS and OTHER PRAYERS. Selected for Devotional use from various Rituals. By Wm. Bright, D.D. Antique cloth, 5s. Devout Communicant. THE DEVOUT COMMUNICANT, exemplified in bis Behaviour before, at, and after the Sacrament of the Lord's Supper : Practically suited to all the Parts of that Solemn Ordinance. 7th Edition, revised. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 4s. EIKflN BA21AIKH. THE PORTRAITURE OF HIS SACRED MAJESTT KING CHARLES I. in his Solitudes and Sufferings. New Edition, with Preface by C. M. Phillimore [On the evidence that the book was written by Charles I., and not by Gauden], Antique cloth, 5s. DEVOTIONAL. THE LIFE OF JESUS CHRIST IN GLOEY : Daily Meditations, from Easter Day to the Wednesday after Trinity Sunday. By Noitet. Trans- lated from the French, and adapted to the Use of the English Church. Third Thousand. 12mo., cloth, 5s. A GUIDE FOE, PASSING ADVENT HOLILT. By Aveillon. Translated from the French, and adapted to the use of the English Church. New Edition. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 5s. A GUIDE FOE PASSING LENT HOLILT. By Avbillon. Translated from the French, and adapted to the use of the English Church. Fourth Edition. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 5s. THE PASTOR IN HIS CLOSET ; or, A Help to the Devotions of the Clergy. Ey John Armstrong, D.D., late Lord Bishop of Grahamstown. Third Edition. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 2s. DAILY STEPS TOWARDS HEAVEN; or, Practical Thoughts on the Gospel History, for every day in the year. With Titles and Characters of Christ. 32mo., roan, 2s. 6d. Large type edition, Crown 8vo., cloth, 5s. Uniform with above. THE HOUES; being Prayers for the Third, Sixth, and Ninth Hours ; with a Preface, and Heads of Devotion for the Day. Seventh Edition, 32mo., in parchment wrapper, Is. ANNUS DOMINI. A Prayer for each Day of the Year, founded on a Text of Holy Scripture. By Christina G. Rossetti. 32mo., cloth, 3s. fid. DEVOTIONS BEFOEE AND AFTEE HOLY COMMUNION. With Prefatory Note by Keble. Sixth Edition, in red and black, on toned paper, 32mo., cloth, 2s. — With the Service, 32mo., cloth, 2s. 6d. MEDITATIONS FOE THE FOETY DAYS OF LENT. With a Prefatory Notice by the Abchbishop of Dublin. 18mo., cloth, 2s. 6d. THE EVERY-DAY COMPANION. By the Rev. W. H. Ridley, M.A., Rector of Hambleden, Bucks. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 3s. EVENING WORDS. Brief Meditations on the Introductory Portion of our Lord's Last Discourse with His Disciples. 16mo., cloth, 2s. THOUGHTS DUEING SICKNESS. By Robeet Beett, Author of " The Doctrine of the Cross," &c. Fcap. 8vo., limp cloth, Is. 6d. BREVIATES FROM HOLY SCEIPTUEE, arranged for use by the Bed of Sickness. By the Rev. G. Arden, M.A., Rector of Winterborne-Came ; Domestic Chaplain to the Right Hon. the Earl of Devon. 2nd Ed. Fcap. 8vo., 2s. DEVOTIONS FOE A TIME OF EETIREMENT AND PRAYER FOR THE CLERGY. New Edition, revised. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, ] s. PRAYERS IN USE AT CUDDESDON COLLEGE. Third Edition, revised and enlarged. Fcap. 8vo., 2s. EARL NELSON'S FAMILY PEAYEES. With Responsions and Variations for the different Seasons, for General Use. New and improved Edition, large type, cloth, 2s. INSTRUCTIONS ON THE HOLY EUCHARIST, AND DEVO- TIONS FOR HOLT COMMUNION, being Part V. of the Clewer Manuals, by Rev. T. T. Cabteb, M.A., Rector of Clewer. 18mo., cloth, 2s. THE SERVICE-BOOK OF THE CHURCH OF ENGLAND, arranged according to the New Table of Lessons. Crown 8vo., roan, 12b. ; calf antique or calf limp, 16s.; limp morocco or best morocco, 18s. 6 SEMMONS, $c. SERMONS, &c. PAROCHIAL SERMONS. By E. B. Ptjsey, D.D. Vol. I. Erom Advent to Whitsuntide. Seventh Edition. 8vo., cloth, 6s. Vol. II., 8vo., cl., 6s. . Vol. III. (Reprinted from " Plain Sermons by Contributors to Tracts for the Times.") Revised Edition. 8vo., cloth, 6s. Vol. IV. [Shortly. PAROCHIAL SERMONS preached and printed on Yarious Occa- sions, 1832— 1850. By E. B. PUSEY, D.D. 8vo., cloth, 6s. SERMONS preached before the UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD between a.d. 1859 and 1872. Vol. II. By E. B. Ptjsey, D.D. 8vo., cloth, 6s. 1843 to 1855, &c. Vol. I. 8vo., cloth, 6s. 1864 to 1876, &c. Vol. III. 8vb., cloth, 6s. LENTEN SERMONS preached chiefly to Young Men at the Uni- versities, between a.d. 1868 and 1874. By E. B. Pusby, D.D. 8vo., cloth, 6s. ILLUSTRATIONS OF FAITH. Eight Plain Sermons, by the late Rev. Edward Monro. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 2s. 6d. Uniform, and by the same Author, Plain Sebmons on the Book op Com- mon Pbayeb. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 5s. Sebmons on New Testament Chabac- tees. Fcap. 8vo., 4s. HlSTOBICAL AND PbACTICAIi SeBMONS on the Suffebings and Rebub- bection of otjb Lobd. 2 vols., Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 10s. CHRISTIAN SEASONS.— Short and Plain Sermons for every Sunday and Holyday throughout the Year. 4 vols., Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 10s. Second Series, 4 vols., Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 10s. SHORT SERMONS FOR FAMILY READING, following the Order of the Christian Seasons. ' By the Rev. J. W. Burgon, B.D. 2 vols., Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 8s. Second Series, 2 vols., Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 8s. PAROCHIAL SERMONS. By the late Bp. Aemstbong. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 5s. SERMONS FOR FASTS AND FESTIVALS. By the late Bp. Abm- strong. A New Edition. Fcap. 8vo., 5s. SERMONS FOR THE CHRISTIAN YEAR. By J. Keble, M.A. Advent to Chbistmas. 8vo., cl., 6s. Chbistmas and Epiphany. 8vo., cloth, 6s. Septuagesima to Lent. 8vo., cl., 6*. Ash - Wednesday to Holy Week. 8vo., cloth, 6s. Holy Week. 8vo., cloth, 6s. Easteb to Ascension Day. 8vo., cloth, 6s. Ascension Day to Tbinity Sunday inclusive. 8vo., cloth, 6s. Tbinity, Part I. 8vo., cloth, 6<. Tbinity, Part II. 8vo., cloth, 6s. Saints' Days. 8vo., cloth, 6s. VILLAGE SERMONS ON THE BAPTISMAL SERVICE. By the Rev. John Keble, M.A. 8vo., cloth, 5s. THE AWAKING SOUL, as Sketched in the 130th Psalm. Ad- dresses delivered in Lent, 1877. By E. R. Wilberforce, M.A. Crown 8vo. limp cloth, 2s. 6d. OXFORD LENT SERMONS, 1857, 8, 9, 60, 3, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 70 — 71. cloth, 5s. each. XX. SHORT ALLEGORICAL SERMONS. By B. K. W. Peakse M. A., and W. A. Gray, M.A. Sixth Edition, Fcap. 8vo., sewed, Is. SERMONS AND ESSAYS ON THE APOSTOLICAL AGE. By the Very Rev. Arthur Penrhyn Stanley, D.D. Third Edition, revised. Crown 8vo., cloth, 7s. 6d. ENGLISH DIVINES. 7 Wmfa of tfo £tmuM (SingM jimwa, PUBLISHED IN THE LIBEAEY OF ANGLO-CATHOLIC THEOLOGY, AT THE FOLLOWING PEICES IN CLOTH. ANDEEWES' (BP.) COMPLETE WOEKS. 11 vols., 8vo., £3 7s. The Sermons. (Separate.) 5 vols., £1 1 5s. BEVEKIDGE'S (BP.) COMPLETE WOEKS. 12 vols., 8vo., £4 4s. The English Theological Works. 10 vols., £3 10s. BEAMHALL'S (ABP.) WOEKS, WITH LIFE AND LETTEES, &c. 5 vols., 8vo., £1 15s. (Vol. 2 cannot be sold separately.) BULL'S (BP.) HABMONY ON JUSTIFICATION. 2 vols., 8vo., 10s. DEFENCE OF THE NICENE CEEED. 2 vols., 10s. JUDGMENT OF THE CATHOLIC CHUECH. 5s. COSIN'S (BP.) WOEKS COMPLETE. 5 vols., 8vo., £1 10s. CEAEANTHOEP'S DEFENSIO ECCLESLE ANGLICANS. 8vo., 7s. FEANK'S SEEMONS. 2 vols., 8vo., 10s. FOEBES' CONSIDEEATIONES MODESTO. 2 vols., 8vo., 12s. GUNNING'S PASCHAL, OE LENT FAST. 8vo., 6s. HAMMOND'S PEACTICAL CATECHISM. 8vo., 5s. MISCELLANEOUS THEOLOGICAL WOEKS. 5s. -. THIETT-ONE SEEMONS. 2 Parts. 10s. HICKES'S TWO TEEATISES ON THE CHEISTIAN PEIEST- HOOD. 3 vols., 8vo., 15s. JOHNSON'S (JOHN) THEOLOGICAL "WOEKS. 2 vols., 8vo., 10s. ., ENGLISH CANONS. 2 vols., 12s. LAUD'S (ABP.) COMPLETE WOEKS. 7 vols., (9 Parts,) 8vo., £2 17s. L'ESTEANGE'S ALLIANCE OF DIVINE OFFICES. 8vo., 6s. MAESHALL'S PENITENTIAL DISCIPLINE. (This volume cannot be sold separate from, the complete set.) NICHOLSON'S (BP.) EXPOSITION OF THE CATECHISM. (This volume cannot be sold separate from the complete set.) OVEEALL'S (BP.) CONVOCATION-BOOK: OF 1606. 8vo., 5s. PEAESON'S (BP.) VINDICLffi EPISTOLAEUM S. IGNATII. 2 vols. 8vo., 10s. THOENDIKE'S (HEEBEET) THEOLOGICAL WOEKS COM- PLETE. 6 vols., (10 Parts,) 8vo., £2 10s. WILSON'S (BP.) WOEKS COMPLETE. With LIFE, by Eev. J. Keble. 7 vols., (8 Parts,) 8vo., £3 3s. J. complete set, 80 Vols, in 88 Parts, £21. POETRY, $c. THE AUTHORIZED EDITIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN YEAR, With the Author's latest Corrections and Additions. NOTICE.— Messrs. Parker are the sole Publishers of the Editions of the "Christian Year" issued with the sanction and under the direction of the Author's representatives. All Editions without their imprint are unauthorized. Small 4to. Edition. .Handsomely printed on toned paper, with red border lines and initial letters. Cloth extra . . . . 10 6 Demy 8vo. Edition. Cloth 6 Foolscap 8vo. Edition. Cloth 3 6 24mo. Edition. Cloth, red lines . . .26 32mo. Edition. Cloth boards, gilt edges Cloth, limp . 48mo. Edition. Cloth, limp Roan . Facsimile of the 1st Edi- tion, with a list of the variations from the Origi- nal Text which the Author made in later Editions. 2 vols., 12mo., boards 1 6 1 6 1 6 7 6 The above Editions (except the Facsimile of the First Edition) are kept in a variety of bindings, which may be ordered through the Trade, or direct from the Publishers. The chief bindings are Morocco plain, Morocco Antique, Calf Antique, and Vellum, the prices varying according to the style. By the same Author. LTRA INNOCENTIUM. Thoughts in Terse on Christian Chil- dren. Thirteenth Edition. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 5s. 24mo., cloth, red lines, 3s. 6d. 48mo. edition, limp cloth, 6d. ; cloth boards, Is. MISCELLANEOUS POEMS BY THE REV. JOHN KEBLE, M.A., Vicar of Hursley. [With Preface by G. M.] Third Edition. Fcap., cloth, 6s. THE PSALTER, OR PSALMS OF DAVID: In English Verse. Fourth Edition. Fcap., cloth, 6s. 18mo., cloth, Is. The above may also be had in various bindings. Fcap. A CONCORDANCE TO THE "CHRISTIAN TEAR." 8vo., toned paper, cloth, 4s. MUSINGS ON THE "CHRISTIAN TEAR;" with GLEANINGS from Thirty Years' Intercourse with the late Rev. J. Keble, by CHAR- LOTTE M. YONGE; to wliich are added Recollections of Hursley by FRANCES M. WILBRAHAM. Second Edition. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 7s. 6d. MEMOIR OF THE REV. J. XEBLE, M.A. By Sir J. T. Cole- ridge. Fourth and Cheaper Edition. Post 8vo., cloth, 6s. THE CHILD'S CHRISTIAN TEAR. Hymns for every Sunday and Holyday throughout the Year. Cheap Edition, 18mo., cloth, Is. CHURCS POETRY, AND PAROCHIAL. V Cfjurrfj $0etrjj. RE-ISSUE OF THE POETICAL WORKS OF THE LATE REV. ISAAC WILLIAMS. THE CATHEDRAL; or, The Catholic and Apostolic Church in England. 32mo., cloth, 2s. 6d. THE BAPTISTERY; or, The "Way of Eternal Life. With Plates by Boetius a Bolswert. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 7s. 6d. ; 32mo., cloth, 2s. 6d. HYMNS from the PARISIAN BREVIARY. 32mo., cloth, 2s. 6d. THE CHRISTIAN SCHOLAR. Fcap. 8vo.,cl., 5s.; 32mo.,cl.,2s. 6d. THOUGHTS IN PAST YEARS. 32mo., cloth, 2s. 6d. THE SEVEN DAYS OF THE OLD AND NEW CREATION. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 3s. 6d. BISHOP CLEVELAND COXE. CHRISTIAN BALLADS AND POEMS. By Arthur Cleveland Coxe, D.D., Bishop of Western New York. A New Edition. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 3s. Also selected Poems in a packet, 32mo., Is. THE BELLS OF BOTTEVILLE TOWER; A Christmas Story in Verse : and other Poems. By Frederick G. Lee, Author of " The Martyrs of Vienne and Lyons," " Petronilla," &c. Fcap. 8vo., with Illustrations, cloth, 4s. lid. HYMNS ON THE LITANY, by Ada Cambridge. Fcap. 8vo., el., 3s. $arotfjtaL THE CONFIRMATION CLASS-BOOK: Notes for Lessons, with Appendix, containing Questions and Summaries for the Use of the Candidates. By E. M. Holmes, LL.B., Rector of Marsh Gibbon, Bucks. Fcap. 8vo., limp cloth, 2s. 6d. Also, in wrapper, The Questions and Summaries separate, 4 sets of 128 pp. in d tic li p t Is ptic n THE CATECHIST'S MANUAL*; with 'an Introduction by the late Samuel Wilbebfoece, D.D., Lord Bishop of Winchester. By the Bame. Sixth Thousand, revised. Crown 8vo., limp cloth, 5s. A MANUAL OF PASTORAL VISITATION, intended for the Use of the Clergy in their Visitation of the Sick and Afflicted. By a Parish Priest. Dedicated, by permission, to His Grace the Archbishop of Dublin. Second Edition, Crown 8vo., limp cloth, 3s. 6d. ; roan, 4s. THE INNER LIFE. Hymns on the "Imitation of Christ," by Thomas A'Kempis j designed especially for Use at Holy Communion. By the Author of " Thoughts from a Girl's Life," &c. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 3s. SHORT READINGS FOR SUNDAY. By the Author of "Foot- prints in the Wilderness." With Twelve Illustrations on Wood. Third Thou- sand, Square Crown 8vo., cloth, 3s. 6d. A SERIES OF WALL PICTURES illustrating the New Testament. The Set of 16 Pictures, size 22 inches by 19 inches, 12s. COTTAGE PICTURES FROM THE OLD TESTAMENT. A Series of Twenty-eight large folio Engravings, brilliantly coloured by hand. The Set, 7s. 6d. COTTAGE PICTURES FROM THE NEW TESTAMENT. A Series of Twenty-eight large folio Engravings, brilliantly coloured. The Set, 7s. 6d. Upwards of 8,000 Sets of these Cottage Pictures have been sold. TWELVE SACRED PRINTS FOR PAROCHIAL USB. Printed in Sepia, with Ornamental Borders. The Set, One Shilling; or each, One Penny. Upwards of 100,000 of these Prints have already been sold. FABER'S STORIES FROM THE OLD TESTAMENT. With Four Illustrations. Square Crown 8vo., cloth, 4s. MUSINGS ON THE PSALM (CXLX.) OF DIVINE ASPIRA- TIONS. 32ino., cloth, 2s. 10 MISCELLANEOUS. THE ELEMENTS OF PSYCHOLOGY. THE ELEMENTS OE PSYCHOLOGY, ON THE PRINCIPLES OF BENEKE, Stated and Illustrated in a Simple and Popular Manner by De. G. Rat/e, Professor in the Medical College, Philadelphia ; Fourth Edition, considerably Altered, Improved, and Enlarged, by Johann Gottiieb Dbebs- xeb, late Director of the Normal School at Bautzen. Translated from the German. Post 8vo., cloth, 6s. REV. CANON GREGORY. AEE WE BETTER THAN OUR FATHERS ? or, A Comparative View of the Social Position of England at the Revolution of 1688, and at the Present Time. FOUR LECTURES delivered in St. Paul's Cathedral. By Robebt Gbegoby, M.A., Canon of St. Paul's. Crown 8vo., 2s. 6d. PROFESSOR GOLDWIN SMITH. THE REORGANIZATION OE THE UNIVERSITY OE OXFORD. By Goldwin Smith. Post 8vo., limp cloth, 2s. LECTURES ON THE STUDY OF HISTORY. Delivered in Oxford, 1859 — 61. Second Edition. Crown 8vo., limp cloth, 3s. 6d. IRISH HISTORY AND IRISH CHARACTER. Cheap Edition, Fcap. 8vo., sewed, Is. 6d. THE EMPIRE. A Series of Letters published in "The Daily News," 1862, 1863. Post 8vo., cloth, price 6s. MRS. ALGERNON KINGSFORD. ROSAMUNDA THE PRINCESS : An Historical Romance of the Sixth Century j the Crocus, Water-reed, Rose and Marigold, Painter op Venice, Noble Love, Romance of a Ring, and other Tales. By Mrs. Alger- non Kingsford. 8vo., cloth, with Twenty-four Illustrations, 6s. THE EXILE FROM PARADISE. THE EXILE FROM PARADISE, translated by the Author of the " Life of S. Teresa." Fcap., cloth, Is. 6d. VILHELM THOMSEN. THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ANCIENT RUSSIA AND SCAN- DINAVIA, and the Origin of the Russian State. THREE LECTURES de- livered at the Taylor Institution, Oxford, in May, 1876, by Dr. Vilhelm Thomsen, Professor at the University of Copenhagen. Small 8vo., cloth, 3s. 6d. BERNARD BOSANQTJET, M.A. ATHENIAN CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY, as Represented in Grote's " History of Greece," critically examined by G. F. Schomann : Trans^ lated, with the Author's permission, by Bernard Bosanquet, M.A., Fellow and Tutor of University College, Oxford. 8vo., cloth, 3s. 6d. THE PRAYER-BOOK CALENDAR. THE CALENDAR OF THE PRAYER-BOOK ILLUSTRATED. (Comprising the first portion of the "Calendar of the Anglican Church," with additional Illustrations, an Appendix on Emblems, &c.) With Two Hundred Engravings from Medieval Works of Art. Sixth Thousand. Fcap. 8vo., cl., 6s. ARCHITECTURE AND ARCMAHOLOGT. 11 SIE G. G. SCOTT, F.S.A. GLEANINGS FROM WESTMINSTER ABBEY. By Sib Geoege Gilbert Scott, R.A., F.S.A. Witli Appendices supplying Further Particu- lars, and completing the History of the Abbey Buildings, by Several Writers. Second Edition, enlarged, containing many new Illustrations by O. Jewitt and others. Medium 8vo., 10s. 6d. THE LATE CHARLES WINSTON. AN INQUIRY INTO THE DIFFERENCE OF STYLE OBSERV- ABLE IN ANCIENT GLASS PAINTINGS, especially in England, with Hints on Glass Painting, by the late Charles Winston. With Corrections and Additions by the Author. 2 vols., Medium 8vo., cloth, £1 Us. 6d. EEV. SAMUEL LTSONS, F.S.A. OUR BRITISH ANCESTORS : WHO AND WHAT WERE THEY? An Inquiry serving to elucidate the Traditional History of the Early Britons by means of recent Excavations, Etymology, Remnants of Religious Worship, Inscriptions, Craniology, and Fragmentary Collateral History. By the Rev. Samuel Lysons, M.A., F.S.A., Rector of Rodmarton, and Perpetual Curate of St. Luke's, Gloucester. Post 8vo., cloth, 5s. M. VIOLLET-LE-DUC. THE MILITARY ARCHITECTURE OF THE MIDDLE AGES. Translated from the French of M. Viollet-le-Duc, by M. Macdermott, Esq., Architect. With 151 original French Engravings. Second Edition, with a Pre- face by J. H. Parker, C.B. Medium 8vo., cloth, 10s. 6d. JOHN HEWITT. ANCIENT ARMOUR AND WEAPONS IN EUROPE. By John Hewitt, Member of the Archaeological Institute of Great Britain. Vols. II. and III., comprising the Period from the Fourteenth to the Seventeenth Century, completing the work, £\ 12s. Also Vol. I., from the Iron Period of the Northern Nations to the end of the Thirteenth Century, 18s. The work complete, 3 vols., 8vo.,£t lis. 6d. EEV. PEOFESSOE STUBBS. THE TRACT "DE INVENTIONE SANCT^ CRUCIS NOSTRA IN MONTE ACUTO ET DE DUCTIONE EJUSDEM APUD WALT- HAM," now first printed from the Manuscript in the British Museum, with In- troduction and Notes by William Stobbs, M.A. Royal 8vo., 5s. ; Demy 8vo., 3s. 6d. NORTHEEN ANTIQUITIES. THE PRIMEVAL ANTIQUITIES of ENGLAND and DENMARK COMPARED. By J. J. A. Worsaae. Translated and applied to the illus- tration of similar remains in England, by W. J. Thoms, F.S.A., &c. With numerous Illustrations. 8vo., cloth, 5s. OUB ENGLISH HOME: Its Early History and Progress. Witt Notes on the Introduction of Domestic Inventions. New Edition, Crown 8vo., cloth, 3s. 6d. PABISH CHUECH GOODS IN BERKSHIRE, A.D. 1552. Inventories of Furniture and Ornaments remaining in certain of the Parish Churches of Berks in the last year of the reign of King Edward the Sixth: Transcribed from the Original Records, with Introduction and Explana- tory Notes by Walter Money, F.S.A., Member of Council for Berks, Brit. Arch. Assoc, and Hon. Sec. of the Newbury District Field Club. Crown 8vo., limp cloth, 3s. 6d. 12 ARCHITECTURE AND ARCHEOLOGY. JOHN HENRY PAEKEE, C.B., F.S.A., HON. M.A. OXON. AN INTEODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF GOTHIC AECHI- TECTURE. Fifth Edition, Revised and Enlarged, with 1S9 Illustrations, with a Topographical and Glossarial Index. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 5s. A CONCISE GLOSSAET OF TEEMS USED IN GEECIAN, ROMAN, ITALIAN, AND GOTHIC ARCHITECTURE. A New Edition, revised. Fcap. 8vo.,with 470 Illustrations, in ornamental cloth, 7s. 6d. AN ATTEMPT TO DISCEIMINATE THE STYLES OF AE- CHITECTURE IN ENGLAND, from the Conquest to the Reformation; with a Sketch of the Grecian and Roman Orders. By the late Thomas Rick- man, F.S.A. Seventh Edition, with considerable Additions, chiefly Historical, by John Henry Parker, C.B., F.S.A., &c. 8vo. [Nearly ready. DOMESTIC AECHITECTUEE OF THE MIDDLE AGES, with numerous Engravings from Existing Remains, and Historical Illustrations from Contemporary Manuscripts. By the late T. Hudson Turner, Esq. From the Norman Conquest to the Thirteenth Century ; interspersed with Remarks on Domestic Manners during the same Period. 8vo., cloth, £\ Is. A Reprint. . FROM EDWARD I. to RICHARD II. (the Edwardian Period, or the Decorated Style). By the Editor of "The Glossary of Archi- tecture." 8vo., cloth, £1 Is. Also, FROM RICHARD II. to HENRY VIII. (or the Perpen- dicular Style). With numerous Illustrations of Existing Remains, from Ori- ginal Drawings. In Two Vols., 8vo., £1 10s. THE ABCHiEOLOGY OF EOME. By John Heney Pabkee, OB. Part 1. THE PEIMITIVE FOETIFICATIONS. Fifty-nine Plates. 21s. Part 4. THE TWELVE EGYPTIAN OBELISKS. Eight Plates. 5s. Part 5. FOEUM EOMANUM ET MAGNUM. Second Edition, Revised and Enlarged. Forty-one Plates. 10s. 6d. Part 7. THE COLOSSEUM AT EOME. Thirty-six Plates. 10s. 6d. Part 8. THE AQUEDUCTS OF EOME. Thirty-six Plates. 15s. Parts 9 and 10. THE TOMBS IN AND NEAE EOME. Twenty- four Plates. MYTHOLOGY IN FUNEREAL SCULPTURE, AND EARLY CHRISTIAN SCULPTURE. Sixteen Plates. These Two Parts in one Volume. 15s. Part 11. CHUECH AND ALTAE DECOEATIONS IN EOME, Twenty Plates. 10s. 6d. Part 12. THE CATACOMBS. Twenty-four Plates. 15s. SEPULCHRAL CE0SSES. A MANUAL for the STUDY of SEPULCHEAL SLABS and CROSSES of the MIDDLE AGES. By the Rev. Edward L. Cutts, B.A. Illustrated by upwards of 300 Engravings. 8vo., cloth, 6s. ENGLISH COUNTEY HOUSES. SIXTY-ONE VIEWS AND PLANS of recently erected Mansions, Private Residences, Parsonage-Houses, Farm-Houses, Lodges, and Cottages, with Sketches of Furniture and Fittings : and A Practical Treatise on House- Building. By William Wilkinson, Architect, Oxford. Second Edition, Royal 8vo., ornamental cloth, £1 5s. NEW AND STANDARD EDUCATIONAL WOBZS. 13 THE ANNALS OF ENGLAND. An Epitome of English History. From Cotemporary Writers, the Rolls of Parliament, and other Public Records. A LIBRARY EDITION, revised and enlarged, with additional Woodcuts. 8vo., half-hound, 12s. THE SCHOOL EDITION OF THE ANNALS OF ENGLAND. In Five Half-crown Parts. 1. Britons, Romans, Saxons, Normans. 2. The Plantagenets. 3. The Tudors. 4. The Stuarts. 5. The Restoration, to the Death of Queen Anne. Fcap. 8vo., cloth. THE NEW SCHOOL - HISTORY OF ENGLAND, from Early Writers and the National Records. By the Author of " The Annals of England." Crown 8vo., with Four Maps, limp cloth, 5s. ; Coloured Maps, half roan, 6s. A HISTORY OF THE ENGLISH CHTJECH from its Foundation to the Reign of Queen Mary. By M. C. Stapley. Fourth Edition, revised. Crown 8vo., cloth boards, 5s. POETARUM SCENICORTJM GR^CORUM, ^schyli, Sophoclis, Euripidis, et Aristophanis, Fabulae, Superstites, et Perditarum Fragments. Ex recognitione GUIL. DINDORFII. Editio Quinta. Royal 8vo., cloth, £1 Is. THUCTDIDES, with Notes, chiefly Historical and Geographical. By the late T. Arnold, D.D. With Indices by the Rev. R.P. G. Tiddeman. Eighth Edition. 3 vols., 8vo., cloth lettered, £1 16s. JELF'S GREEK GRAMMAR.— A Grammar of the Greek Language, chiefly from the text of Raphael Kiihner. By Wm. Edw. Jelf, B.D. Fourth Edition, with Additions and Corrections. 2 vols. 8vo., £l 10s. LAWS OF THE GREEK ACCENTS. By John Geihiths, D.D., Warden of Wadham College, Oxford. Sixteenth Edition. 16mo., price 6d. RUDIMENTARY RULES, with Examples, for the Use of Beginners in Greek Prose Composition. By John Mitchinson, D.C.L., late Head Master of the King's School, Canterbury, (now Bishop of Barbados). 16mo., sewed, Is. TWELVE RUDIMENTARY RULES FOR LATIN PROSE COM- POSITION : with Examples and Exercises, for the use of Beginners. By the Rev.E.MooBE,D.D.,PrincipalofSt.EdmundHall, Oxford. SecondEdit. 16mo.,6d. MADVIG'S LATIN GRAMMAR. A Latin Grammar for the Use of Schools. By Professor Madvig, with additions by the Author. Translated by the Rev. G. Woods, M.A. New Edition, with an Index of Authors. 8vo., cloth, 12s. ERASMI COLLOQUIA SELECTA : Arranged for Translation and ' Re-translation ; adapted for the Use of Boys who have begun the Latin Syntax. By Edward C. Lowe, D.D., Canon of Ely, and Provost of the College of SS. Mary and John, Lichfield. Fcap. 8vo., strong binding, 3s. PORTA LATINA : A Selection from Latin Authors, for Translation and Re-Translation ; arranged in a Progressive Course, as an Introduction to the Latin Tongue. By Edward C. Lowe, D.D., Editor of Erasmus' " Collo- quies," &c. Fcap. 8vo., strongly bound, 3s. A GRAMMATICAL ANALYSIS OF THE HEBREW PSALTER ; being an Explanatory Interpretation of Every Word contained in the Book of Psalms, intended chiefly for the Use of Beginners in the Study of Hebrew. By Joana Julia Greswell. Post 8vo., cloth, 6s. SUNDAY-SCHOOL EXERCISES, Collected and Revised from Manuscripts of Burghclere School- children, under the teaching of the Rev. W. B. Barter, late Rector of Highclere and Burghclere ; Edited by his Son-in-law, the Bishop of St. Andrew's. Second Edition. Crown 8vo., cloth, 5s. A FIRST LOGIC BOOK, by D. P. Chase, M.A., Principal of St. Mary Hall, Oxford. Small 4to„ sewed, 3s. NEW AND OLD METHODS OF ETHICS, by F. Y. Edgewobth. Svo., sewed, 3s. 14 OXFORD POCKET CLASSICS. A SERIES OF GREEK AND LATIN" CLASSICS FOR THE USE OF SCHOOLS. GREEK POETS. Cloth, a. d. JF.sehylus Aristophanes. 2 vols. . Euripides. 3 vols. ■ Tragoediae Sex as. Sophocles Homeri Ilias Odyssea GREEK PROSE WRITERS. ■ Aristotelis Ethica Demosthenes de Corona, et 7^. JEschmWin Ctesiphontem *"' Herodotus. 2 vols. 2 2 6 Thucydides. 2 vols. Xenophontis Memorabilia — — Anabasis . LATIN POETS. Horatius Juvenalis et PersiuS Lucanus 2 1 6 2 6 Lucretius Phsedrus Virgilius LATIN PROSE WRITERS. Csesaris Commentarii, cum Sup- plementisAuliHirtii et aliorum 2 ■ Commentarii de Bello Gallico ... .1 Cicero De Officiis, de Senectute, et de Amicitia . . .2 Ciceronis Tusc. Disp. Lib. V. Ciceronis Orationes Selectee . Cornelius Nepos . Livius. 4 vols. Sallustius .... Tacitus. 2 vols. . Cloth. s. d. 3 3 6 3 5 1 4 2 2 1 4 2 6 2 3 6 1 4 6 2 5 TEXTS WITH SHORT NOTES. UNIFORM WITH THE SERIES OF "OXFORD POCKET CLASSICS." GREEK WRITERS. TEXTS AND NOTES. Ajax ( Text and Notes) Electra „ (Edipus Rex „ (Edifus Coloneus „ SOPHOCLES d. Antioone (Text and Notes) Philoctetes „ Trachinije „ The Notes only, in one vol., cloth, 3b. Pers.e (Text and Notes) Prometheus Vinctus Septem Contra Thebas Agamemnon .ESCHYLUS 1 Choepiiorje (Text and Notes) Eumenides „ sufplices ,, s. d. 1 1 1 I 1 1 The Notes only, in one vol., cloth, 3s. 6d. ARISTOPHANES. The Kniohts (Text and Notes) .1 | Acharnians (Text and Notes) 1 The Birds (Text and Notes) 1 NEW SERIES OF ENGLISH NOTES. 15 EURIPIDES s. d. Hecuba {Text and Notes) Medea „ Orestes „ Hippoltttus „ s. d. Phceniss,e {Text and Notes) . 1 Alcestis ,, .10 The above, Notes only, in one vol., cloth, 3s. Bacchs 1 De Corona {Text and Notes) . HOMERUS. Ilias, Lib. i. — vi. {Text and Notes) jESCHINES. In Ctesiphontem {Text and Notes) . . . . DEMOSTHENES. . 2 | Oi.ynthiac Orations XENOPHON. Memorabilia {Text and Notes) ARISTOTLE. De Arte Poetica {Text and Notes) . cloth, 28. j sewed 1 De Re Publica „ 3s. „ 2 2 2 1 2 6 LATIN WRITERS. TEXTS AND NOTES. VIEGILIUS. 1 | jEneidos, Lib. i. — m. {Text Bucolica {Text and Notes) Georgica „ Carmina, &c. {Text and Notes) Satir/e „ 2 | and Notes) HORATIUS. 2 I Epistol^ et Ars Poetic* {Text 1 | and Notes) . . , The Notes only, in one vol., cloth, 2s. SALLUSTIUS. Jogurtha {Text and Notes) . 1 6 | Catilina {Text and Notes) M.T.CICERO. 1 1 1 In Q. Cscilium — Divinatio {Text and Notes) . . .10 In Verrem Actio Prima . 1 Pro Lege Manilia, et Pro Archia . . . .10 In Catilinam Pro Plancio {Text and Notes) , Pro Milone ... Pro Roscio . . . , Orationes Philippics, I., II. The above, Notes only, in one vol., cloth, 3s. 6d. De Senectute et De Amicitia 1 C2ESAR. De Bello Gallico, Lib. i. — in. {Text and Notes) . . .10 LIVIUS. Lib. xxi. — xxiv. {Text and Notes) sewed 4 Ditto in cloth . . . .46 Epistol.e Selects. Pars I. CORNELIUS NEPOS. Lives {Text and Notes) . PHiEDRUS. Fabul^ {Text and Notes) TACITUS. The Annals. Notes only, 2 vols., 167720., cloth • . • • Portions of several other Authors are in preparation. 7 Uniform with the Oxford Pocket Classics. THE LIVES OF THE MOST EMINENT ENGLISH POETS; WITH CRITICAL OBSERVATIONS ON THEIR WORKS. By Sa- muel Johnson. 3 vols., 24mo., cloth, 2s. 6d. each. THE LIVES OF MILTON AND POPE, with Critical Observations on their Works. By Samuel Johnson. 24mo., cloth, Is. 6d. CHOICE EXTRACTS FROM MODERN FRENCH AUTHORS, for the use of Schools. 18mo., cloth, 3s. 16 SOOES, $c, RELATING TO OXFORD. SELECTIONS from the RECORDS of the CITY OF OXFORD, with Extracts from other Documents illustrating the Municipal History : Henry VIII. to Elizabeth [1509—1583]. Edited, by authority of the Cor- poration of the City of Oxford, by William H. Turner, of the Bodleian Library; under the direction of Robert S. Hawkins, Town Clerk. Royal 8vo., cloth, £1 Is. A HANDBOOK FOR VISITORS TO OXFORD. Illustrated with numerous Woodcuts by Jewitt, and Steel Plates by Le Keux. A New Edition. 8vo., cloth, 12s. THE OXFORD UNIVERSITY CALENDAR for 1880. Corrected to the end of December, 1879. 12mo., cloth, 4s. 6d. THE OXFORD TEN-YEAR BOOK : A Complete Register of Uni- versity Honours and Distinctions, made up to the end of the Year 1870. Crown 8vo., roan, 7s. 6d. "WYKEHAMICA : a History of Winchester College and Commoners, from the Foundation to the Present Day. By the Rev. H. C. ADAMS, M.A., late Fellow of Magdalen College, Oxford. Post 8vo., cloth, 508 pp., with Nineteen Illustrations, 10s. 6d. HISTORICAL TALES Illustrating the Chief Events in Ecclesiastical History, British and Foreign. 29 Numbers at One Shilling each, limp cloth ; or arranged in Six Volumes, cloth lettered, 3s. 6d. each. ADDITIONAL VOLUMES TO THE SERIES. ENGLAND : Mediaeval Period. Containing The Orphan of Evesham, or The Jews and the Mendicant Orders. — Mark's Wedding, or Lollardy. — The White Rose of Lynden, or The Monks and the Bible. — The Prior's Ward, or The Broken Unity of the Church. By the Rev. H. C. Adams, Vicar of Dry Sand- ford; Author of" Wilton of Cuthbert's," "Schoolboy Honour," &c. With Four Illustrations on Wood. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 3s. 6d. THE ANDREDS-WEALD, or THE HOUSE OF MICHELHAM : A Tale of the Norman Conquest. By the Rev. A. D. Crake, B.A., Fellow of the Royal Historical Society ; Author of " jEmilius," " Alfgar the Dane," &c. With Four Illustrations by Louisa Taylor. Fcap. 8vo., cloth, 3s. 6d. CHEAPER ISSUE OF TALES FOE YOUNG MEN AND WOMEN. In Six Half-crown Vols., cloth. Vol. I. contains F. E. Facet's Mother and Son, Wanted a Wife, and Hobson's Choice. Vol. II. F. E. Paget's Windycote Hall, Squitch, Tenants at Tinkers' End. Vol. III. W. E. Heygate's Two Cottages, The Sisters, and Old Jarvis's Will. Vol. IV. W. E. Heygate's James Bright the Shopman, The Politician, Ir- revocable. Vol. V. R. King's The Strike, and Jonas Clint j N. Brown's Two to One, and False Honour. Vol. VI. J. M. NeALe's Railway Accident; E. Monro's The Recruit, Susan, Servants' Influence, Mary Thomas, or Dissent at Evenly j H. Hayman's Caroline Elton, or Vanity and Jealousy. Each Volume is bound as a distinct and complete worJc, and sold separately for Pbesents.