CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME OF THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND GIVEN IN 1891 BY HENTIY WILLIAMS SAGE Cornell University Library B2923.27 R45 olin 3 1924 029 044 125 The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31 9240290441 25 THE ETHICAL THEORY OF HEGEL Oxford University Press London Edinburgh Glasgow Copenhagen New Tork Toronto Melbourne Cape Town Bombay Calcutta Madras Shanghai Humphrey Milford Publisher to the University The ETHICAL THEORY of H E G E A Study of the L PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT By HUGH A. REYBURN, M.A., Professor of Logic and Psychology at the University of Cape Town D.Phil. OXFORD At the CLARENDON PRESS I 9 2 I Ho TO SIR HENRY JONES, LL.D., F.B.A. THE GREATEST TEACHER WHOM I HAVE KNOWN PREFACE This book was written for the most part before the war, and, save for a slight revision in the early part of 1915, is untouched by war influences. In spite of the long delay which has ensued before publication, I have thought it better to leave my work as it stands. No doubt a very much better book could be written, but any alterations which I should be inclined to make at present would alter the purpose which the book is intended to serve. My intention was to write not on ethical and political theory but on Hegel, and I have made no attempt to recast the Hegelian doctrine in the light of our present knowledge. A reconstruction of our modern problems and outlook on the basis of Hegel's teaching would be an exceedingly valuable contribution to knowledge, but it is a larger task than is attempted here. The first step toward it is a reasonable knowledge of the authentic Hegel himself, and it is only this step that I have tried to take. Much of the criticism of Hegel current to-day and in the last few years appears to be vitiated by an unsympathetic and somewhat inaccurate interpretation of Hegel, and my endeavour has been to provide an account which will make his view more intelligible. Accordingly criticism has been reduced to a minimum, and has been undertaken only when the comprehension of the theory itself seemed to demand it. Nothing which I have seen since the book was first written has led me to alter my view of Hegel's teaching. My indebtedness in carrying out this work has been great. What I owe to the literature will, I hope, be sufficiently viii PREFACE obvious from the text. My greatest debt, however, is to Sir Henry Jones of Glasgow University, under whose influence I began this study and from whom I obtained not only valu- able detailed assistance in the study of Hegel but also the im- pulse and encouragement which led me to attempt the work. He has read through the manuscript and enabled me to make it a better book than it could otherwise have been. Portions of the manuscript have also been read by Professor J. W. Scott of Cardiff, Professor A. R. Lord of Grahamstown, and Principal Hetherington of Exeter University College. They are not responsible for my views and mistakes, but they have given me valuable advice. In the labour of preparing the book I have been greatly helped by my wife. HUGH A. REYBURN, University of Cape Town, August 1921. CONTENTS Introduction PAGE xi Chapter^. The Logical Background . I --'II. Fundamental Logical Categories 17 ^III. The Real and the Rational • 45 n\ Mind . ■ 76 V. Subjective Mind 90 VI. Abstract Right . . 115 VII. Wrong and Punishment . 143 VIII. The Principles of Morality 158 AX. Moral Teleology .... 185 X. The Ethical Order and the Family . 197 -^l. Civil Society or the External State . 214 --Jtll. The State 226 ,i'nVino- a rp Riihiective and its results omectiver laws of thinking are subjective and its results oDjective: Such knowledge implies independent acquaintance with the real world in order to compare it point for point with the content of knowledge. The argument need not be elaborated farther : it is clear that this view of logic is so far from being free from epistemology and metaphysics that it is based on a view of knowledge which separates knowledge from things, and it has sufficient information about reality to distinguish the laws of the latter from the modes and principles of the content of thought.^ This contention, however, by no means settles the question. Perhaps if we give up the untenable dualism between the content of knowledge and the object known, we may devise a distinction within the content of knowledge between subjective modes of organizing the material apprehended and objective principles of things. But such a distinction, although a genuine one when regarded in a certain way, is an abandonment of the original scope and task of logic. It gives up the problem of analysing the forms of knowing as a whole, and breaks up the total content into two sections without exposing what they have in common. If log'ic identifies its object with one' of these divisions there remains room for another logic, more faithful to its primary duty, which will lay bare the principles involved in any appre- hended content, whether existing in external nature or not. Hegel's logic claims this larger task. If logic is to maintain itself as the science oi the principles of the content of know- ledge', it must cease to diminish its stature to the measure of the merely subjective, and must advance to an analysis of the structural principles of a thought which can apprehend any object. But it is obvious that such an analysis is meta- physical as well as logical. It is conversant not only with the principles of thinking, but also with those of that which is thought ; and it cannot but seek to determine the con- ditions of an intelligible world, the only world with whic| we have any concern. Naturally, if reality is identified will 1 For an acute criticism on historical lines of the attemnt tn ..pnarate logic from metaphysics v. Adamson, A Short i?«to« of S^t, ?"i6^ reprinted, with additions, from the Encyclopaedia Britanmca THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND actual existence in space and time, and metaphysics identified with the science of such a reaUty, then logic is wider than metaphysics. But such is not the sense of metaphysics in which Hegel's logic is metaphysical. Existence in space and time is part of a wider whole ; and there are principles which are operative in things, but which cannot be said to have existence in this limited sense. This point may become clearer at a later stage of the argument ; at present it is enough to note that from the present point of view the object of metaphysics is the entire scheme of things, the wholeness of the world, of which existence in nature is but one mode. Logic, as metaphysical, is the science of the principles of a thought whose content is the whole, the absolute, the real, or whatever else be its name. Having found the standpoint of logic, we may refer briefly to its Umitation. The known world, for Hegel, faUs into two main divisions^ viz., nature and mind. These are part of one world known by a single apprehending consciousness, and therefore subject to the fundamental laws which make knowledge and an object intelligible. But nevertheless each realm has forms and laws of its own ; each has a character which cannot be attributed to the other, and it works out the basal principles of intelligible objects in its own way. For our present purpose it is perhaps better not to regard the special laws of these realms as new principles ; they are rather more concrete developments of the fundamental forms of all knowledge, fresh and separate ways of exemphf5dng them, articulations of them, their expression in new media. This throws into relief the conununity of spheres, and it is to i these underl5dng principles of both realms that logic is limited. I The philosophy of nature is the account of the principles as they appear in the outward world ; the philosophy of mind ;exposes them in the shapes which they take in conscious life ; logic is the discussion of them by themselves, without reference ito their higher special embodiments. We may now consider briefly the historical development of iHegel's position from that of Kant. Kant had inquired into Ithe conditions of synthetic a -priori judgements. Mathematics offered him a type of these judgements, and he raised the 'question. How is it possible for such knowledge to be universal md necessary and yet to apply to objects ? Mere analysis THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND which keeps within the realm of mental concepts had, for him, an obvious universality, but it could not add to our knowledge of things, could not prophesy new conjections in experience. Its breadth was due to its shallowness. On the other hand, empirical knowledge provides a synthetic union of diverse elements of experience, but it dare not transcend the present moment and the actual synthesis given. But these strange judgements of mathematics speak confidently, not depending on experience, and yet giving us fresh know- ledge of objective things ! In order to explain this kind of knowledge Kant found it necessary to carry over that" activity of knowledge, in accordance with which its decrees possess universahty in the realm of mind, into the province of actual experience. If the objects of experience, he argued, are amenable to the universality which belongs of right to thought and which cannot be obtained empirically, then thought must have a share in the constitution of the objects of experience. The problem soon broadened out from its original form. Previous philosophy, Kant thought, had gone on the assump- tion that the task of knowledge is to correspond to an inde- pendent object out of essential relation to knowledge, and scepticism had been the outcome. For if the object is ex vi termini beyond knowledge and independent of it, there is no guarantee that the content known stands in any relation to the independent and unknown real. Taking his stand, there- fore, on the validity of knowledge, Kant asks, What must be true of the object in order that it may be known ? The boasted independence of the object quickly disappears under this treatment, and Kant discovers one condition of know- ledge after another to which objects must conform if they are to be intelligible. These conditions, Kant thought, do 'not hold of the independent object, the thing-in-itself, but they govern the phenomenal object, that which can be known. Kant, however, does not dismiss the conception of the inde- pendent object, but continues to contrast it with the known object ; and by virtue of the opposition condemns the latter as subjective. The extent to which Kant transcended this crude dualism does not concern us here, because the thing-in-itself never disappears from his argument. Even when other reasons are offered for the subjectivity of the known object, e.g. in the THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND antinomies, the conflict within experience has ultimately no other basis than the original dualism of mind and outward reality. The various minor collisions, e.g., between sense and understanding, understanding and reason, constitutive and regulative principles, practical reason and theoretic reason, and so forth, are all modifications of the primary uncritical supposition ; and if it is withdrawn their substance has vanished. So long as they remain unchecked, the influence of the thing-in-itself persists. That is to say, Kant's inquiry into the conditions of an intelligible world is conducted under the guidance of a fiarm dualism of subject and object, in accordance with which universahty and form are attributed to the former, particularity and content to the latter. If experience manifests universahty, he argues, it is mind-made and subjective. From this Hegel dissents.^ Fgr Kant, in so far as he is a duahst, the distinction between subjective and objective coincides with that between knowledge and what is beyond knowledge. And, although his main contribution to epistemology is a new sense of objectivity which falls within experience, yet there remains in the background the original conception of the objective as independent and trans-sub- jective. Such a distinction is, for Hegel, unmeaning. The unknowable is the most absurd of all conceptions, and the least interesting to rational beings ; it is a direct contradiction in terms. The only significant distinction between subjective and objective falls within the field of knowledge ; it marks off various contents from one another, and does not separate the knowable from the unknowable. When the trans- subjective thing-in-itself vanishes, the contrast between it and the phenomenal or subjective object loses all point ; and hence the phenomenal objectivity which Kant had set up within experience developed for Hegel into real objectivity. With this change of attitude came a great change of content. The fundamental principles which make experience possible were, for Kant, few in number, and the principles of pure thought involved amounted only to twelve. Hegel pushed the analysis much further ; he found logical principles continuous with the categories and principles of the understanding both above and below them ; and thus in place of Kant's limited list there arises the whole elaborate structure of Hegel's logic. ' Cf. Encyclopaedia, § 41, Zusatz 2, WW. VI. pp. 87-y. 8 THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND Before dealing with any of the detaUs of this scheme we may summarize Hegel's position. Kant found an a prion element in experience, a universaUty which transcended the given ; but he wrongly identified it with the subjective, the mind^made. Hegel swept this identification aside. These principles, he argued, apply to the known as such, subject as well as thing ; they are doubtless principles of thought, but they are no less principles of the world ; they go beneath the opposition of subjective and objective, they characterize all experience, and are not more truly called mental than are particular laws of nature — ^nor less so. Kant's Critique professed to be epistemological, an inquiry into the nature and limits of the knowing faculty ; Hegel's investigation is frankly logical and metaphysical. It deals directly with the known world, and investigates the knowing which apprehends objects. Hegel's objective standpoint has given rise to the charge that he proposes to evolve the world out of his own inner consciousness. The criticism may mean many things. It may imply that Hegel sat down in the seclusion of his study, shut out in so far as he could aU reference to common experi- ence, and concocted an arbitrary scheme from the idios}^!- cracies of his private fancies. This is a matter of evidence and need not raise the general question of the ultimate relation of reason and science ; for such capricious imaginings are condemned as much by the sanity of thought as by experi- mental knowledge of fact. Hegel must not be prejudged on this point, for he claims that his method is not private and fanciful but open and rational. On the other hand the criticism may cut deeper. It may rest on the assumption that reason and the truth fall apart, and that a theory may be wholly rational and yet untrue. From this point of view, to evolve the world out of one's inner consciousness means simply to exercise a rational and critical activity. It is only in this sense that Hegel would admit the truth of the state- ment, and his whole theory is a denial of the accompanying supposition that apart from and beyond reasonable knowledge there is anything with which knowledge is in any way con- cerned. It should be clear from what has been said that from Hegel's standpoint the nature of the cognitive subject is fundamentally one with that of his world. The constitutive THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND principles of his rational mind are also those of that which he apprehends. Thus it is true that in unfolding the nature of mind Hegel is analysing or remaking for knowledge the principles of things ; but it is no less true that the evolution of an arbitrary scheme in the mind is not the analysis of reality — it is not the analysis of mind itself. By bringing the world and mind into harmony Hegel has made meta- physics possible, but at the same time he has made logic, the key, more difficult by extending its content and forcing it to wai* on the nature of things. Sometimes Hegel's argu- ment seems capricious and fine-spun, but in general there is no reasonable doubt of his conviction that, in the order of learning, experience is prior to rational thought.^ We live before we reflect on life, and a wide experience is necessary for the ingathering of the meaning of experience. Indeed, one of the more striking characteristics of Hegel's own thought is its persistence and perseverance ; and his contempt for fanciful speculation and for formaUsm is unbounded.^ Experi- ence, or fact, is the basis of aU thought and all science ; and a philosophy which cannot cover life and is built in abstraction from the considerations of practice is a futility of the under- standing. But experience is only the beginning. What is given is not the final truth, not the finished perfect work which alone deserves the name of the real ; it is rather a problem, a vague we-know-not-what. Thought has to interpret the datum, and solve the problem ; and the succession of general principles by means of which we attempt this interpretation is the content of logic. One of the most fruitful ways of regarding Hegel's Logic is to look upon it as a protracted and thorough I study of the relations of unity and difference, or of universal I and particular. Each category, or determination, is a general i principle by which we seek to make experience a consistent ! whole and render it a concrete universal ; and each has its own 1 way of relating the two root factors, viz., unity and difference. j Before discussing any of the categories themselves, however, J it is necessary to glance at three preliminary points ; the ; connexion of the categories, the order of their exposition, and s the motive power of the development. 1 • V. Encyclopaedia, §§ 6-9, and notes ; WW. VII. p. 18. f ^ V. Phenomenology, WW. II, Vorrede, in particular pp. 55-6. 10 THE LOGI CAL BACKGROUN D___^__ In the first place, the principles of thought are inter- connected. For a genuine empiricism the world is not a whole but a series of numberless parts-parts m no wise connected with one another. The series can be a unity for an appre- hending consciousness only if it is thought under principles which hold it together and connect its various portions. Every principle of thought has this function, and the task of knowledge is to discover them. Kant, as we have seen, gave these principles a subjective turn, and supposed that they were foisted upon the material of knowledge,* and that the mind made its objects. . Hegel is quite aware of the activity of thought here, but he recognizes the objective side also. The laws and principles in question are those which constitute the world ; they are those which things must contain if they are to form an intelligible world at all— and what is not intelligible is not a world. But it is not enough ; that there should be a variety of laws discernible in the objects of knowledge. A number of separate principles would give us, not one world, but as many worlds as there are special; forms of unity. Moreover these worlds would be absolutely out of relation to one another, and could have no commerce. Moreover, they could not be known to one and the same mind ; indeed, to speak more accurately, we should have no right to call them all worlds, for to be a world is to possess a special type of unity, and ex hypothesi the types are all different. Mind is a unity, intelligence is the same in principle in all its activities, and all the objects it can know must belong inher- ently to the one scheme of things. If the objective anarchy which we have suggested were the case, we should need as many minds as there were principles in order to apprehend them, and the mind would be shattered into fragments. If the mind is to be a unity, its object must also be a unity and constitute one world. But the various portions of the content of knowledge can form a whole only if unifyinf;: principles themselves cohere ; for the principles are the unity of the world. That is to say, what Kant calls the synthetic a priori principles of knowledge, or what we may call the constitutive principles of what is known, are linked together and form a rational and coherent whole. Their own inter- connexion is, on the one hand, the essence of the unity of the intelligible world, and, on the other, of the rationality of the THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND ii knowing mind. We are not dealing with two quite differently organized things, a mind and a world ; we are dealing with the fundamental principles of the intelligible content of rational thought ; and the coherence of both aspects depends on the coherence of the principles themselves. The second point is the order of the philosophic exposition of these principles. Hegel's view of this is somewhat complex, and is to be fully understood only when the complete exposi- tion is mastered. The peculiar method he adopts is called by him the dialectic, and I shall have to recur to it at various stages of the discussion. The point to be indicated here is an obvious and somewhat superficial one. Hegel sets out from the barest and emptiest of the principles of possible thought ; he begins at the bottom and works upwards. The main alternatives seem to be either that of beginning any- where and working at random, or that of beginning at the top and working downwards. The first of these alternatives is plainly inadequate. It is not a method, but the failure of one ; and it cannot exhibit the categories in their rational inter-connexion. Lotze seems to think that it is the only possible attitude for a modest mind ; but if this be so, then it seems clear that the mind in question has not pushed its investigation of experience far enough to reach the level of philosophy. It is stiU preoccupied with the order of learning, and has not attained to the order of explanation. Such a process is preliminary to philosophy, and Hegel himself went through it ^ ; but he did not put his results forward as logic until he had emancipated himself from the adolescence it implies. The other method is that expressly enunciated by Spinoza, and Hegel rejects it. Spinoza begins with the whole, with substance, the final reality. But the difficulty immediately arises : If we start with the perfect principle why do we go further ? Spinoza makes progress because what he calls the whole is not really such, but has beyond it another world of ' modes ' — in general, Natura naturata.^ Hegel calls this method that of emanation. ' It is a series of » For the history of the development of Hegel's logical theory V. Baillie, Hegel's Logic- ' In his Larger Logic Hegel points out the greater concreteness of the mode when contrasted with the absolute or substance : WW. IV. pp. 184-99. 12 THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND deteriorating stages ', he says, ' which begin with the complete, with the absolute totality, with God. God has created ; and from Him have come forth radiations, reflections, and likenesses, of which the first is most akin to Him. The first production also shows activity, but less completely, and so downwards ... to the negative, matter, the extreme of evil. Thus the emanation ends with the lack of all form '} There is a sense in which* we must begin with the whole. Until we become aware of the wholeness of being we are not on philosophic ground, and are unable to trace the inter- relations of the principles of experience. The order of the dialectic process is guided by an ever present consciousness of the highest stages, and it is not until we reach the last of the three main divisions that we see clearly by what path we have come. At first it is not explicitly known to us that the principle we use is that of single reality : we begin with the poorest possible way of characterizing things and pass upwards to more concrete attitudes of thought. This order may be regarded in two ways ; it is a process from abstracl to concrete, and it is a movement from the external to the internal. The effort of thought at first is to take one thing at a time ; the unities which thought imposes on things are very loose, and express but few of their relations. As thought rises in the scale its principles become more concrete, they gain wealth and depth. That is to say, they express the object more truly. They present more adequately its relations to its context and to the whole system of which it forms a part ; and that is why Hegel uses the word, concrete, in this connexion. The other way of characterizing the movement gives us a point of transition to the discussion of its motive power. The lower categories are abstract because they are external. Most of reality lies beyond their grasp ; things are presented singly, and thought does not see how each determines the nature of the others and enters into their being. In Hegel'l view the Nemesis of such thought is that it turns into its opposite. Take the simplest example. The first category of the Logic is being. The simplest, barest, and least affirmation we can make is that indicated by the word ' is '. But if we say no more than this, what have we said ? We must strip off the idea of a ' thing ' ; the assertion is not that such and ' WW. VII. p. 35. THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND 13 such a definite object is, for a ' definite object ' involves much more than does mere ' being '. We are to say ' is ', and nothing else. But when we have said this our meaning is indistinguishable from ' nothing '. If we take away all the particular qualities of things, we abstract from them every- thing by means of which we distinguish what is from what is not. Being which is not existence in some place and time, and under some special circumstances, and so forth, is as good as non-existence — ^it is the same as non-existence. Hegel's contention is that if we are in earnest with our thought and carry it as far as it will go, such a category changes in our hands and shows a meaning which we try to exclude from it. This state of things can be mended only when we adopt a more concrete principle which includes both aspects as part of itself. That is to say, the implication of the one aspect in the other is at the first level a force compelling thought from outside ; at the second level it is part of the content of thought itself. When we force reality, as it were, into one of these primitive categories and try to take it abstractly, it avenges itself by turning into another form. The neglected aspects appear in spite of us, and the despised unity of the system as a whole reveals itself by forcing a half -idea to turn into its opposite. This change, however, is not part of the category itself. That is to say, the change is immediate for the thinker who uses such principles ; he does not apprehend the inner nexus which produces the conversion, and each term is, for him, unmediated by. its opposite. Generally speaking, we are offered the alternative of unity or difference by these bare and elementary forms of thought ; and the abstractness of our choice amends itself by the unforeseen passage of the one element into the other. In the higher reaches of the dialectic the various aspedts have been incorporated by thought to such an extent that the process is not from one aspect to its com- plementary by this primarily negative path, but is a more straight-forward development ; and Hegel speaks of it as mere play.'^ This brings us to the third point, the power behind the process. This has been said to be contradiction .^ But such 1 Encyclopaedia, WW. VI. § 161 and note. 2 For a discussion of this view v. McTaggart, Studies in Hegelian Dialectic, p. 5 ff . 14 THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND a view is shallow ; for one immediately asks, What is behind the contradiction? Contradiction itself is the immediate opposition of one phase of an object by another ; but at the back of it is the power of the whole. We may use Hegel's theory of tragedy to throw some light on his Logic at this point. Qlegel finds the essence of tragedy to lie in a conflict between spiritual forces which jhelong to one system and which ought to be in harmonyA The^_caX s str o ph e-4S-4];g ass ertion by_ _the_whQle-i:if its ccmiplexity agai nst the one- sigedness of ' s ome.^np£rf ect ^aspect. When theconfEcf is "between two individuals, each, from the tragic point of view, is dominated by some aspect of the whole good, perhaps an ethical claim such as the duty to one's kindred, perhaps a wider end, such as natural justice, honour, or the ambition of a strong man ; and this is followed to the exclusion of all else. The devotion to this abstract ideal, good in itself but imperfect when set against the rest of life, brings the agent into collision with other factors and with the whole ; and in the conflict the tragic hero is overthrown. The final note of tragedy, however, isjiflUoss. Over and above the con- fusion and destruction of that which is imperfect and by the nature of things transitory there is the assertion of the full and rounded characteivpf reality. The positive side, of course, is not fully developed irrtragBli^, but if it be utterly lacking the tragedy is imperfect and inartistic — it is merely a pitiful tale. Behind the sympathy with the fallen there must be a feeling of the greater good which the agent himself was unable to grasp, and his fall is a vindication of the deeper truth. We need not discuss any of the details of the exposi- tion ; the only point of present importance is that the fate which destroys a tragic hero is not a mere external force, it is in him as well as about him. Mr. A. C. Bradley gives excellent expression to the situation thus. ' If . . . this necessity were merely infinite, character- less, external force, the catastrophe would not only terrify (as it should), it would also horrify, depress, or at best provoke indignation or rebellion ; and these are not tragic feelings. The catastrophe, then, must have a second and affirmative aspect, which is the source of our feelings of reconciliation, whatever form they may assume. And this will be taken into account if we describe the catastrophe as a violent self- THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND 15 restitution of the divided spiritual unity. The necessity which acts and negates in it, that is to say, is yet of one substance with both the agents. It is divided against itself in them ; they are its conflicting forces ; and in restoring its unity through negation it af&rms them, so far as they are compatible with that unity. The qualification is essential, since the hero, for all his affinity with that power, is, as the living man we see before us, not so compatible. He must die, and his union with ' eternal justice ' (which is more than ' justice ') must itself be ' eternal ' or ideal. But the qualifica- tion does not abolish what it qualifies. There is no occasion to ask how in particular, and in what various ways in various works, we feel the effect of this affirmative aspect in the catastrophe. But it corresponds at least with that strange double impression which is produced by the hero's death. He dies, and our hearts die with him ; and yet his death matters nothing to us, or we even exult. He is dead ; and he has no more to do with death than the power which killed him and with which he is one.' ^ Now logic in principle is even more than tragedy ; for it is the express reconciliation of the subordinated dements, and the rational completion of lower principles in a whole into which they are carried without remainder. Logic is not encumbered by the actual living man, and the dialectic is not a history of personal sufferings which cannot be made good. Although at first dialectic changes are external and unintel- ligible to the mind which uses elementary principles, yet these changes themselves are seen by fuUer knowledge to be a self- evolution of the complete truth. In its higher stages thought has to include the lower categories, and the elements of perfect knowledge are known by it as opposites.^ But although tragedy and the dialectic differ in completeness, the power is the same ; it is the whole. Thought is one system, and lives in every member. When a part in its finitude is taken as the whole, its truer nature breaks through in the form of contradiction, and cannot be satisfied until it renders explicit the fullness and truth against which the imperfect assertion sinned. The imperfect aspects can collide only because they have a proper relation and ought to be recon- ciled. The dialectic thus is a development of reason from ' Oxford Lectures on Poetry, p. 91. ' Cf. below, p. 40 ff. i6 THE LOGICAL BACKGROUND within, and its moving force is the implication of the whole in every part and the systematic continuity of the knowable world. Such then is the general logical standpoint which Hegel adopts, and we shall have to recur to it in our discussion of the method of the other branches of philosophy. At present, however, we must be content with this outline, meagre as it is, and proceed to discuss some of the special principles which the dialectic of logical thought contains. CHAPTER II FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES We have seen that the dialectic is the process by which the principles of knowledge pass for thought from abstract- ness to concreteness, and that the moving force of the develop- ment is the logical compulsion exercised by the whole system within each of its fragments. We must now look at some of the special stages of this development in order to be able to determine the logical nature and position of the main con- ceptions which we must use in ethics. For this purpose it is desirable to pay special attention to some of the categories of the second division of the Logic, viz. the sphere of essence. It is not possible, of course, to deal with them all in their proper order and succession, but we may gain sufficient for our purpose if we take a suitable selection. I propose to indicate the general division of the Logic and to refer very briefly to the general nature of the categories of the first section. In connexion with the categories of essence I shall begin with the conception of ' thinghood ' because it throws some light on the relation of mind to nature, and is of impor- tance in any discussion of the transparency or opaqueness of nature to moral purposes. I shall then pass to the concep- tion of substance, which has to be examined carefully for two reasons ; firstly, because it, together with its subdivisions, manifests the full nature of the non-spiritual world, and contains within it the principle of necessity and external determination, and secondly because it is the stepping stone to the notion. The notion is itself the key to mind and the spiritual world in general ; it is the logical principle of which the free self is the concrete realization. We may, therefore, consider somewhat closely the development of the dialectic from substance through causality and reciprocity into the notion. Hegel's logic falls into three main divisions or stages : first, the categories of being ; second, the categories of 2211 C i8 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES essence ; and third, the categories of the notion. Tj.«^ ^^^ be regarded as three main ways in which unity and ditterence may be presented in thought. Taking the matter m broad outline, there are three modes in which we may apprehend these two aspects. We may be offered any of three alter- natives— («) unity or difference, or (6) unity and difference, or (c) unity because of difference. Under the control of the categories of being we may say simply that a content ' is ', and the negative aspect (non-being) may for the moment be entirely excluded from the explicit content of our thought. Or again we may say that it is one, excluding multiphcity ; or many, excluding unity. This is the poorest form of thinking, and corresponds to the most superficial aspect of objects. The inadequacy of such principles is obvious and need not be laboured. In full truth every aspect of the intelligible world is in profound harmony with every other, and contains within it a reference to the whole. Hegel's proof of this lies in the complete dialectic : the full implicatioi of the whole in each aspect or fragment is not made full} clear until the end, viz. the stage of the notion (in the widf sense) ; the defects of the categories of being are, at theii own proper stage, shown only externally, and fresh light is shed on their true nature at each step in the argument. The thinker who uses the categories of being, however, is far from apprehending this truth. He tries to isolate each aspect and to take it merely by itself. Each thing is itself, he says, and not another ; and he is quite unaware of the deeper nature oi each element whereby it has community with every othei element and with the whole. We have seen the fate which overtakes this kind of thought. If we try to grasp reality under these categories it eludes us ; reality will not be confined in these abstract forms, and the strange result which greets us is that it is Protean and changes as we hold it.^ In the categories of essence this false simplicity and externality of thought begins to disappear. The thinker notes a distinction between the aspects of appearance and essence. The surface show of a thing is not its whole truth ; behind that show there is a certain identity and permanence — an essence. As we progress in this series of categories we gradually discover that things are inter-connected ; and " Cf. above, p. 12 f. FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 19 we now see that we have not said the complete truth when we affirm that a thing is itself — it is also bound up with the rest of the universe and contains implications of the whole within the four corners of its being. We may take ' thinghood ' as our first example of these principles of essence. This is a very common category of ordinary thought, but it is not so simple as it may appear at first sight ; ^ and Hegel identifies it with the principle of sensible perception. We may note that a thing is not a simple quality, it is a totality of some sort standing in relation to differences ; it is a thing with many properties. Each of these properties is distinct from the others, each has a being of its own and does not modify the others. The properties he side by side, as it were, untouched by one another, and their relation is that of indifference. But at the same time they all come together ; a thing is not a mere name given to a random collection of entirely unrelated qualities. In the Phenomenology Hegel points out that the unity in question is found chiefly in space and time. The treatment of thinghood in the two Logics is naturally more abstract, and Hegel speaks of the form of unity without pointing to the mode of concrete experience in which it is primarily manifested. Since we are not con- cerned with logic purely on its own account, it seems per- missible to introduce here the type of experience which Hegel mentions in the Phenomenology, and has in mind in his discussion in the purely logical analysis. ' This salt ', he says, ' is a simple " Here " and at the same time manifold ; it is white and also pungent, also cubical in shape, also of a specific weight, and so on. All these many properties exist in a simple " Here " where they inter-penetrate one another. None of these has a different " Here " from the others ; each is everywhere in the same " Here " where the others are. At the same time, without being divided by different " Heres ", they do not affect each other in their inter- penetration ; its being white does not affect or alter the cubical shape it has, and neither affects its sharp outline, and so on. On the contrary each is simple relation-to-self, it leaves the others alone and is related to these merely by ' There are three accounts of the nature of thinghood ; Pheno- menology, WW. II. pp. 84-99 ; Larger Logic, WW. IV. Abschnitt 2, Kap. I ; Encyclopaedia, WW. VI. § 125 ff. C 2 20 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES being also along with them, a relation of mere indifference. This " also " is thus the pure universal itself, the " medium ", the " thinghood " keeping them together.' ^ But there is more than this to be said about a thing. We have seen that the properties are different from one another, and this involves that they do stand in some relation to one another. If they were utterly and merely indifferent they would not even be distinguished, i.e. they would not be determinate qualities. The attributes of a thing, then, involve in their being a rudimentary opposition to one another. But in holding its properties apart the thing develops a further aspect in itself ; it becomes more than a mere togetherness or inter-penetration of the properties. ' The process of distinguishing them, so far as it does not leave them indifferent, but effectually excludes, negates one from another, thus falls outside the simple " medium ". And this, consequently, is not a mere also, a unity which is indifferent to what is in it, but a " one " as well, an excluding repelling unity.' ^ Thinghood thus implies a certain activity ; the thing shuts out other properties and holds its own together. It is more than the sum, or the place, of its properties — ^it is something behind them, something which has them and which refuses to have others. It is an essence. In this conception of thinghood we have the factors of more developed thought, at least in germ ; but they are confused and not set in their proper relations. A thing is not a perfectly coherent object of thought. This does not mean that ' things ' do not exist ; indeed the analysis of thinghood is almost identical with the statement of the meaning of existence for Hegel. To exist is to present oneself thus in space and time ; and if this form of presentation turns out to contain contradiction, the conclusion is not that it does not exist, but that existence itself is an inadequate and abstract mode of thought and reality. We may give definite names, for the sake of convenience, to the aspect? of thinghood ; the surface show, the attributes which when regarded as belonging to the thing are called properties, these are the immediate aspect, and the thing which has the properties is the mediate aspect. Thinghood is one of the many ways in which thought tries to relate these two ' WW. II. pp. 86-7, BaiUie's trans. I, pp. 107-8. ^ Ibid. FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 21 ides. In his Logic Hegel shows that this conception fails a its task by noting how the essential, or mediate, aspect 3 upon closer scrutiny deposed from its proud position of dentity with the real nature of the totality, and becomes tself a surface show ; it ceases to be the principle of union md becomes one term among others requiring relation and )rganization. We may take a shorter route here. The hing falls into two discordant aspects, unreconciled in hought. On the one hand the thing is its properties ; if ;hey are abstracted there is nothing left behind. On the )ther hand the thing is other than its properties, it is that which has them, their substrate or bearer. It is thus one md many. But it provides no reconciliation of these two aspects ; it contains both, but they are simply conjoined. There is nothing in the positive aspect to explain the negative power of the thing, its capacity for distinguishing its own properties and refusing others. ' Togetherness ', in fact, is the mere name of unity without the substance, an abstract identity resting on differences which are at the same time beyond and outside it. The thing is an effort to think the surface show and apprehend its deeper self, but the attempt is not fully successful. The whole sphere with which we are dealing, viz. that of the categories of essence, is infected with the flaw manifested here. In essence unity is taken along with difference, but the inner nexus of the two is not apparent. Before passing to our next category, the conception of substance, and determining the advance made by it on thinghood, we may note that when Kant endeavours to distinguish sharply between the subject of knowledge and the things of experience, he is, in effect, led to ascribe the characteristics of thinghood to the subject. The weakness Df the conception of the thing is that it is an abstract unity, presupposing differences which it cannot supply. It involves its properties and yet is distinct from them. This is also the nature of the transcendental unity of apperception. The ' I think ', according to Kant, gathers the manifold into a synthetic unity, and is conscious of its own identity only in the unity of its synthetic act. But at the same time Kant assures us that the pure ego is an analytic unity or pure self-identity, and that it does not include the concrete detail which it implies. That is to say, it belongs to the realm of 22 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES essence in Hegel's sense of the word ; for the defect of all the categories of essence is that in their nature they involve other factors which are also external to them. Indeed, tor theoretic reason, the transcendental ego is m a more evil plight than the thing, for the latter is at least present— at the minimum it is the unity of the ' here ', and has spatial identity — ^but the pure ego must be abstracted even from space, it is pure identity as such and has no realiza,tion. We may now come to the last main subdivision of the realm of essence, viz. reality ; and in particular we may con- sider the transition from the conception of substance to the notion. As Hegel's analysis goes deeper it endeavours to lose nothing that has been already gained ; the distinction of mediate and immediate, or of essence and appearance, must therefore remain in the higher categories, but it must be thought in such a way that its incoherence disappears.' Kant had already analysed substance in a somewhat one-sided way. He began with the fact of change, and found that change implies identity ; change is change of something. If objects consisted of a mere succession in time we could not be conscious of change ; each impression as it appeared would be all, and the problem of permanence would not arise for us. Change is essentially a principle of contrast, and has meaning only by reference to an underlying substance which has the change and remains one and the same throughout. Kant's conception is very much that of an indestructible matter 2 whose appearance alters and which takes different shapes, but whose quantity is constant. Kant's analysis, however, is incomplete and one-sided. Substance, like the other categories of essence, is a correlative conception. Kant presupposes the one aspect, viz. difference or change, and deduces the other : Hegel tries to bring out the nature of both ahke. Generally speaking, the elements of substance are those of thinghood over again at a deeper level and more closely bound together. Change, Kant has taught us, in order to be perceived must be determinate and must proceed in accordance with a rule. A mere flux would not be per- > For a slightly different view of the progress of the Logic — particu- larly in regard to causaUty — v. McTaggart's Commentary on Hegel's Logic. ' Energy is an equally good form of the principle. FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 23 ceived as a unitary process at all, and hence not even as a flux. This determinate character of change is brought to the_ forefront by Hegel in his analysis of substance and accident. Substance advances beyond thinghood in two points. Firstly, the two aspects, essence and non-essential, are brought closer together, they are even identified ; secondly, the accidents are thus conceived as not merely indifferent to one another, but as standing in a determinate relation and as forming a totaHty. I. The unity of the thing and its properties is a loose one.; the thing is the medium of the properties, and can often be deprived of one of them without loss of identity. A house may be painted a different colour and yet be the same house.^ Substance, however, is its accidents ; it appears in them and exists only in appearing. The word, substance, is some- times used in an abstract and one-sided way as referring to a mere identity behind or beneath its attributes, a mere substrate. This interpretation Hegel considers to be in- adequate.^ He prefers to speak simply of essence when the object is so conceived, and to retain the word substance for the object, which is thought under the conception that is here analysed. The sense he rejects can be found as the guiding conception of certain would-be philosophical physicists. In the effort to penetrate to the nature of ' matter ' the thinker sometimes forgets that in the appropriate category, viz. that of substance, the essence exists only in appearing. The accidents of substance are, of course, the subordinate and even the unessential aspects ; but this is falsely taken when it is supposed that they can be brushed aside as non-existent or as subjective. Sometimes in the effort to think matter the investigator strips off each of its properties and functions as unessential and superficial. But unluckily at the end, instead of discovering what matter is, he finds in his hands a bare identity with no intelligible content — the mere emptiness of ultimate abstraction. Too often the thinker proclaims the bankruptcy not only of his special category but of reason as a whole. The inner nature of things, he says, is an inscrutable mystery, and no human wit can read the riddle which has baffled him. The mystery, however, is of his own making, ' V. Encyclopaedia, § 125 note, last' sentejicc. " V. Larger Logic, WW. IV. p. 221. 24 FUNDAMENTAL LOGI CAL CATEG OBJES^___ and he has failed to find the meaning of matter because it has been identified with a substrate which has no attnDutes, and is in truth nothing at all. Substance exists only in appearing ; it is not the mere togetherness of thinghood, but a more intense unity con- stituted by the accidents in determinate relation to pne another. How is this unity to be understood ? Perhaps the physical eonception of energy is the clearest instance of it. Energy remains constant in quantity through all its changes! a,nd is a permanent amid variety. Yet it exists only in its forms, it is not a colourless substrate of which the definite forms are illusory appearances. The destruction of one of the forms would destroy it itself. When we think by means of the conception of substance we organize the material of knowledge into a whole such that the details are set in their, place by a necessity which flows through them. Theii difference, thus, is not the last word about them, for each of them is the embodiment of the one substance ; their nature is to reveal the immanent whole.^ 2. Substance appears in its accidents as power or necessity, Kant, approaching the question from one side, had asked thet nature of the principle which made it possible for mind to have duration or permanence presented to it in the object ; and he found that there is required for that end the per- , manence of the phenomenal substrate itself, an enduring:! object which is the bearer of all change.^ Hegel, rejecting the one-sided approach and bringing both aspects, change as well as permanence, within the scope of the deduction, renders the conception as that of substance appearing as power in its modes. Substance gives itself actual shape by establishing one form or accident, then passes into another, so that the first accident is withdrawn by it and replaced by another. Substance is thus a category of necessity. The full meaning, of necessity is not yet reaHzed, and will appear only later; but substance differs from thinghood in that its attributes;.: are not indifferent to it but express it and constitute a deter- minate order by virtue of this inner power which ' posits '| ' ' Substance, as this identity of the appearing, is the totaUty of the whole, and includes the accidents ; and the accidental is the whole : substance itself ' {Larger Logic, II. p. 221). = V. Critique of Pure Reason, First Analogy. FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 25 them. Each is only what substance makes it, and cannot stand when substance withdraws itself and takes another shape. ^The nature of substance, thus, may be summed up in three phases : the self identity of substance and the variety of the accidents ; the immanence of substance in the accidents ; the power of substance over the accidents. We may now look at the defects of this conception when taken as a final category. Briefly, they spring from the fact that the unity of substance is abstract. The two aspects, universal and particular, have been brought within the compass of one thought, but they are stUl external to one another. Substance is the self-identity of the process, and although it exists only in the variety of the accidents, yet it does not include that variety as part of its own nature. The explanation which uses substance as its highest principle dissolves the particular in the universal ; it traces the uni- iversal in the particular, but it does not take the universal concretely. If the conception of physical energy is used in 5uch a way that it embodies this principle, then explanation will consist in tracing the identity of the quantity of energy in the consecutive forms ; potential energy will be resolved into an equal quantity of kinetic energy, that into heat, and 50 on. The constant quantity of energy will be regarded as l:he reality, and thought will be satisfied when the quantitative identity is demonstrated. -The defects of this method of thinking are obvious, for no account is given of the transformation from the one mode to the next. The change of the accidents faUs without sub- stance ; and when the accidents are resolved into substance their aspect of difference and variety is lost. The essence 3f the situation appears to be this. Substance is the all- pervading power in each accident and is the reality of each ; but in referring an accident to substance we do not organize the accidents into a systematic whole, but merely dig within gach for the hidden identity. We find, e.g., that the quantity of energy in question is present in the kinetic form and are satisfied ; we do not trace the peculiar nature of the kinetic form back into potential energy and forward into heat. That is to say, we do not regard the differences as fundamental to substance, and so we explain each form not by its context 26 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES but by its immanent principle. Substance thus is to be identified with merely inner necessity, and has not yet developed into a system of inter-acting parts. But substance can have necessary power over its accidents only if its power appear in the accident itself, for substance exists only m appearing. The necessity of the whole ought to have an adequate manifestation, and should appear in each accident as the power modifying and determining the others. That is to say, the inward necessity must also appear outwardly, Since the accidents manifest substance they ought to show in themselves the power of substance, i.e. they ought to determine one another. -"Hegel puts the point thus: 'The show, or accidentahty, is intrinsically substance through the power ; but it is not posited as this self-identical show. [The accidental is the evanescent.] Thus substance has as its actual shape or positivity only the accidental, and not itself ; it is not substance as substance. The relation oi substantiality reduces itself to substance which reveals itseli as formal power, but whose differences are not substantial^ in fact, it is only the inward of the accidents, and the latter are only in substance.' ^ Hegel's general meaning may be expressed in another way which will apply more directly to the ethical questions we have to consider afterwards. Substance is conceived as the underived and supreme, but the thought is one-sided. Sub- stance is the ground of the accidents, and they receive their justification and truth from it ; their immediate appearance is traced back to substance and based on it. But, on the other hand, substance does not ground itself in its accidentSi it is prior to them and does not develop through their chang| What is posited is the accident and not substance : substance: is the original, the underived. Now this conception has, perhaps unwittingly, been used by many thinkers who treat of freedom. Freedom is represented by them as that whioli is not bound, that which acts in the world but is not enthralled by it. Time, change, and accident, they say, do not enter into .freedom ; and the attempt to explain a man by his time, his parentage, his training, and so forth, they regard as a weak surrender to the forces of determinism. The inward freedom of the will, on this view, cannot be bound by the . ' Larger Logic, WW. IV. p. 223. FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 27 acts in which it appears, and hence is untouched by any ! actual consequences it may produce. Kant's teaching leads ■ to something like this :— for him freedom is merely inward ; ' we ought to act, he holds, as if -we were members of a kingdom ' of ends. Libertarianism carries the conception to the extreme. Naturally, too, the determinist accepts the same view of ! freedom, and the rival schools strive within the unity of 'a common assumption. —The indeterminist accepts this sunderived existence as a fact, while the determinist, on the Mother hand, is unable to find room for it within the world of f knowledge. Now, we must discern that the category of substance is not adequate to freedom : the conception is in 1 truth self -contradictory . Substance makes the most important ^of all assumptions — it assumes itself. This difficulty is Joften felt in regard to freedom. One of the arguments for ideterminism is that the will is bound by the character ; ^actions spring of necessity from the nature of the agent, and ihe has no control over his character. The utmost reply the nindeterminist can make to this is that the agent is not fedeteijnined by external circumstances, i.e. by environment. But this reply, even supposing its truth, is not sufficient. liFor the whole man is more than a bare character ; he is sa living concrete agent, .with both structure and function, an sindissoluble unity of inward and outward. And when a separation is made between the two aspects, the character is no more equivalent to the man as a whole than is environ- cment ; it becomes a force working in him from behind, and jits externality is as real as that of circumstances, although ■that takes a temporal form while this is chiefly spatial.^ IjThat is to say, for ethical purposes the alleged underived ijcharacter of man's nature comes to the same thing as external [derivation. The self has no power over itself, and the (mysterious inborn nature of it is an alien force. ! * This is the characteristic defect of the categories of essence. IsSubstance must have accidents, it exists only in its accidents ; [but yet it gains nothing by going out into them. It is in se jand not in alio ; yet it is only in going forth into finitude. ;The two aspects, mediate and immediate, universal and jiparticular, unity and difference, infinite and finite, original li ' Hegel indicates the sublation of the past in the identity of thing- hood in the Encyclopaedia, § 125. 28 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES and derivative, or however else one likes to name them, lie side by side in the categories of essence. They are both present, but they are not harmonized. The terms are corre- lative, and each has a nature of its own. Substance is the permanent and powerful, the accidental is the unstable and impotent ; and their mutual impUcation is merely another factor along side the others, on equal terms with them. Each term, as it were, falls into two ; on one side it is private,- on the other it has outward relations : but the two aspects are not reconciled, they merely go together. In the effort to find more adequate principles of though! we have to do two things. Firstly, we have to incorporate the element of difference more thoroughly within the positive principle ; secondly, we have to regard the positive principle not merely as underived, but as self-derived. Hegel begins to perform the first of these tasks within the realm of essence itself, and thereby provides the transition to the third and last main section of the dialectic where the second task is also accomplished. Substance is present in each of its shapes ; in a jense, then, each accident is substance. Hegel at this stage takes the identity of substance with its accidents in full earnestness, and treats it as something else than a mere phase added to the others. Substance is inner necessity, the immanent power over the accidents ; but if this inner necessity is to be inteUigible it must come out, and the accidents must become in their external character what they are inherently. That is to say, we must surrender that aspect of the con- ception of substance according to which the accidents do not determine one another, and must grant to them as to substance manifest, power over one another. This gives us the category of causality. In pure substance the accidents merely pass into one another ; i in causality they determine one another, In the relation of substantiaUty A follows B because of the > ' The accidents, as such, . . . have no power over one another. . , , In so far as such an accident seems to exercise a power over anothefi It is the power of substance which grasps both in itself, as negativily [i.e. as negating power] posits an unequal value, and determines the one as the passing, gives the other another content and determines It as the subsisting, or, in other words, determines the former as lapsing ™\° 1*? Possibihty and the latter as coming into reahty ' (Larger Logic, WW. IV. p. 222). ^ ° " ,f FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 29 necessity of substance in each ; in the relation of causaHty A, as the embodiment of substance, determines and produces B. Substance in this conception has dirempted itself into two shapes, each of which is itself substantial. Two points require emphasis here. The ordinary conception of causality is dogmatic and rests on unexamined assumptions. It begins by assuming separate things, finds that they follow one another in a determinate order, but instead of thinking out what is involved in this determinate order gives it a name, causality, and passes to some easier problem. The main difficulties in causality arise from the assumption that cans?" and effect are purely separate facts, and that the relation between them, viz. invariable sequence, is external to their nature. Naturally, if we grant that in full truth A and B are merely self-identical, any essential relation between them is unin- telligible. Hume made this assumption, and in consequence reduced causahty to mere sequence together with the expectation engendered by the experience of that sequence in the past. Kant saw that if causahty is to be intelligible as an objective relation, the assumption of the absolute lindependence and self-sufficiency of its factors must be given up ; and in his view the relation is constitutive of the terms.^ ; Causahty, the type of objective order, is an a priori principle .for Kant, without which the unity of the subject and hence (knowledge in general is impossible. In Kant's theory, how- jever, there is a gap between this transcendental principle and ithe concrete matter of sense by which it is filled ; and so far 1 as the empirical sequence of events is concerned, Kant stands Jvery close to Hume's position, not discerning the imperative gueed for the revision of the hard and fast boundaries between jiperceived objects. Hegel brings out the identity of cause ,.and effect in a way which Kant failed to do. Kant's view i^is confined in effect to the necessity of the objective coherence of events in time and space ; Hegel realizes that in order to i«think this coherence we must be prepared to take the identity Jof the factors seriously, and not be content with its mere '^ ' For a brief account of Kant's view of causality v. Adamson, On '^Jhe Philosophy of Kant, pp. 57-66 ; of. Macmillan, The Crowning Phase "pf the Critical Philosophy, pp. 127-34, where stress is laid on th% am- 'tiguous position of inner sense in Kant's view. 30 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAI^CATEGORIES '^ assertion as a transcendental principle in conjunction with an uncritical view of the phenomena of expenence. Ihe cause, Hegel insists, is cause only in the effect, and the effect is such only in relation to the cause ; the two aspects have an identical content. This may be clearer if we discuss an imaginary objection to it. It is admitted, it may be said, that the real meaning of the conception is the transformation of energy from one phase to another. The cause of the heat; generated by the impact of a bullet on a target is the kinetic energy of the moving bullet, but the previous shape of the energy does not pass into the later one. The shapes alternate ; the constant content is merely a constant quantity of energy. Thus Hegel's statement seems to go too far, the truth being that cause and effect have only in part a common content, while in part each has also a private element, viz. the shape or form of the energy.^ In reply to this statement it may be j said that the conception embodied by it is not causality but i substance. It was this omission of difference that set the problem which Hegel is here trjdng to solve, and it is hardly probable that he overlooked this. Hegel's illustrations ai not always the truest index of his meaning,* but he does seer to meet this difficulty. In the Encyclopaedia he says, ' Th rain (the ca^se) and the wet (the effect) are the self-sam existing water. In point of form the cause (rain) is dissipate or lost in the effect (wet) : but in that case the result ca: no longer be described as effect ; for without the cause it i nothing, and we should have only the unrelated wet left.' The cause involves its effect in its conception, and vice versa ' Both cause and effect are thus one and the same content and the distinction is primarily only that the one lays dowii and the other is laid down.' * But if this be so, there is onl; one substance present ; only in the effect does the cans become cause. That is to say, the cause determines itseli and in going into the effect it is really becoming itself. ' Tb cause, consequently, is in its full truth causa sui.' ^ Tb difficulty which ordinary thought has in grasping this con '■ Cf. McTaggart, Commentary on Hegel's Logic, §§ 173-4. ^ Cf. Bosanquet in Mind, January 1911, p. 82. ' § 153, Wallace's trans, p. 277. , ■■ Ibid. § 153 note, Wallace's trans, p. 278. ' Ibid. § 153, Wallace's trans, p. 277. FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 31 ception may be due to its inveterate habit of taking time determinations as final.i When the effect is present, it says, the cause is past, and surely the past cannot be present. If we are to understand the conception of causahty, however, we must rise above this naive view ; we must remember that we are looking for a connexion that is not broken by the passage of time, and that the externality of moments of time to one another cannot be the last word on the subject. If time enters at all its proper place is within the single content, not between two isolated facts with separate contents of their own. Further, one must rise above mere picture thinking. A material effect does not have a material repro- duction of its cause inside it ; we are dealing with conceptions, not with images. If a material thing is conceived as cause, it contains in its conception a reference to that which it pro- duces ; and if the two are separated in time it is only by thinking a unity which can transcend temporal distinctions that we can think of causaUty at all.^ Secondly, we must note the other aspect. Following Hegel's view of causa sui, we have seen that he regards cause and effect as one content. But this unity is not achieved at the expense of difference : such a course would imply ' ' There is at any rate a presumption against the truth of this doctrine. It is against the ordinary usage of language. In ordinary empirical propositions about finite things we never find ourselves asserting that A is the cause of A, but always that A is the cause of B. The Cause and Effect are always things which, irrespective of their being Cause and EfEect, have different names. The presumption is that there must be some difference between things to which different names are generally given ' (McTaggart, Commentary on Hegel's Logic, p. 176). For Hegel one of the disadvantages of the ordinary usage of language is that it is quite unable to apprehend at once the mutual impHcations of unity and difference, that in its clumsy analysis of itself it is content to have things either the same or different, and that it is bewildered when its attention is drawn to the concrete categories of the notion towards which the dialectic is here tending and which it cannot avoid embodjring in the concrete. He would probably be surprised, however, to find a philosopher setting forth the inadequacies of ordinary speech against the concreteness — the incipient unity of opposites — of the higher categories of essence. Cf. Encyclopaedia, § 153 n. * This does not mean that time is eUminated by causaUty, or that the unity in question is an abstract strand indifferent to change. Causa sui finds its full truth only in the notion, or ultimately the ' idea ', which is a system containing all determinations within it as content. 32 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGOR IES entire failure to cope with the problem which substance left on Hegel's hands. Cause and effect must be two as weU as one ; for if their difference were neglected the whole con- ception of production would vanish, and, as Hegel says, we should have only the unrelated wet left.' i Substance divides itself into appearances which are themselves substantial: that is to say, substance has not only to appear in each factor but also as each, and in its conception it must include the operation of the accidents on and in each other. The conception of causahty, thus, involves two points of view. Cause and effect are two substantial terms, and they are one substance. Identity and difference are balanced against one another, but they do not properly cohere. Perhaps the general position is expressed most clearly when we say that the nature of the cause is to pass into an effect which is other than itself. In interpreting Hegel here we must not be misled by the emphasis he lays on the conception of causa sui : that is the point which is new to us, and we are apt to lose sight of the other aspect. The precise way in which causality unites unity and difference must be carefully noted, because a failure to take it sufficiently concretely will give us an abstract view of the higher category, the notion. Causality is the embodiment of necessity : in a causal series nothing can call itself its own ; everything has been made what it is by forces which are other than it and which it regards as alien. That is to say, in causality itself the inherent upity is not yet in its own true form, it is not able to master and possess the element of difference. To put it another way, the aspects of the conception of causality, viz. identity and difference, pass immediately into one another, and the rationale of the movement is seen but imperfectly. This analysis may be difficult to apprehend at first sight, but it is involved in concrete shape in countless numbers of our ordinary judge- ments. We do mean something when we say that one thing becomes another, and we do not mean simply that one thing always follows another. Common sense does not know that Kant has shown that things are related in time only in virtue of a further relation of the things themselves, and that points of time are meaningless apart from a specific content within them. But it does feel that when the empiricists reduce 1 V. Larger Logic, WW. IV. pp. 230-5 ; Encyclopaedia, § 154. FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 33 causality to unconditional sequence (whatever unconditional may mean), they have omitted an identity — connexion if you will — that common sense asserts.^ When A becomes B, A does not merely pass away and B arise ; A becomes that which it is not : the cause becomes an effect, other than it, yet involving it in its conception as effect. This is a contradiction, but it is asserted by every judgement of causality ; and it is difficult to see how it can be expressed otherwise than by saying that in causality the identity of cause _and effect is immediately one with their difference. The cause and the effect have nothing in them that is not in the other also ; their being is not their own. In the Larger Logic Hegel draws a careful line between the categories of substance and the categories of necessity, but the distinction is too minute to occupy us here.2 Causahty is the embodiment of necessity ; and the nature of both principles lies in the dissipation of a thing into externaUty. A thing is compelled and does not act freely when a process, which works in it, and as it, cancels it and sets it up as something else. If one looks carefully, one sees that an external force acts on a thing only because the thing answers to it and that it is not merely external ; but the relation is that of necessity when the very nature of the thing, in virtue of which it might claim to be self-determining, is not its own, but is constituted in it and as it from without. Hegel insists that any natural object which is subject to neces- sity is unable to sustain the contradiction within it. When the externality of its content or substance becomes apparent the thing is destroyed : only a higher principle than causality can attain unity and selfhood in and through externality. At first, however, the conception which we have stated is not complete. The one factor is called cause or active, the other effect or passive ; and only part of the full meaning of substance is given in each element. The unity already found ' Dr. McTaggart is not wrong in appealing to ordinary speech in this connexion : his error, I think, is in naaking the appeal to one aspect in order to exclude another. His argument in effect opposes one moment of the conception to the other and attempts to exclude the aspect of identity because o'f the presence of difference. Hegel admits both and their inconsistency as they appear here : the dialectic would stop at this point if the conception were genuinely self-consistent. ' For Dr. McTaggart's view — a critical one — v. Commentary, chap. VII. 34 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES in causality demands more than this, and hence J" P^^e': ^ realize itself the conception becomes that of reciprocity. A preliminary effort to remove the difficulty may be made by conceiving an endless chain of causes each of which is the effect of a preceding cause and the cause of a subsequent effect! This however, gives inadequate satisfaction to the identity of causality stated in the doctrine of causa sui; and we are forced to the conception of reciprocity. The nature of the effect depends not only on the cause, but also on the passive factor, i.e. that in which the effect is produced. The cause does not act in the void, but presupposes something else on which to operate. The so-called passive factor must therefore be conceived as cause with reference to this event, and not merely to a subsequent one ; for without it the cause would not have its character as active. Further, the form of activity exercised by the cause depends on and varies with the other factor ; hence the result is the common product of an interaction . Causality thus impUes an action and reaction of elements in which each is both cause and effect of the other ; each becomes itself in determining the other. It is- through the conception of reciprocity that we pass beyond the sphere of essence altogether ; and we must be careful to note exactly where we stand. In tracing substance into the truer category of reciprocity it is important that the positive side of the former should not be lost. We have seen substance sunder itself into individual factors which were respectively cause and effect, and we insisted that it is still one substance which appears thus. Cause and effect are two and also one ; and we have refused to lighten the difficulty by casting overboard the aspect of unity. For the position does not become any easier in that way, and the case becomes without remedy if we assume that we are dealing with inherently indifferent and unrelated factors. This remains true of reciprocity, and we are faced with the same problem still. When the world is thought under the conception of reciprocity it becomes a system of mutually determining parts, ' ' Thus the cause has an effect, and is itself effect ; and the effect not only has a cause but is itself cause. But the effect which the cause has, and the effect which it is — ^like the cause which the effect has, and the cause which it is — are distinct ' (Larger Logic, WW. IV. PP- 234-5). FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 35 each of wJiich is substantial, and each of which is necessary to make the others what they are. They interact, and achieve their own being only in determining others and in being determined by these others. Each thing is part of a system, and has no character except in so far as it reacts on other things and is in turn reacted on by them — only by going out of itself and estabUshing other things has it a private or inward nature of its own. This is the highest principle of essence, and in it the difficulties come to a head. The con- tradiction which infects the whole reahn is this : the factors of its categories have a private independent nature, and at the same time involve a reference to something other than themselves. Thus the ' thing ' is the mere medium of its attributes, but it involves a reference to these attributes and to the concrete detaU which lies outside the mere unity of ' togetherness '. Similarly, substance is the original, the underived, that which is in itself ; but it involves a reference to the particular differences of the attributes which inhere in it. In reciprocity the contradiction is acute ; for the only private being of each term is the reference beyond itself to other factors of the system ; its nature is to establish them. Consequently, it is always easy to attack any content of knowledge whiich is erected on this plan and to dissipate its structure to the winds by setting the aspects against one another. There are no relations without terms, the criticism says, and the only terms offered are nothing but relations.^ This point of view may be clearer if we consider a concrete instance "of it ; and we may take as an example Spencer's criticism of altruistic Hedonism. ' The sympathetic nature gets pleasure by giving pleasure ; and the proposition is that if the general happiness is the object of pursuit, each will be made happy by witnessing others' happiness. But what in such case constitutes the happiness of others ? These others are also by the hypothesis pursuers and receivers of altruistic pleasure. The genesis of altruistic pleasure in each is to depend on the display of pleasures by others ; which is again to depend on the display of pleasures by others ; and so on perpetually. Where, then, is the pleasure to begin ? Obviously 1 The Realist critics of so-called internal relations seem to have some such reciprocal system as their target. In that cage they can find good material for missiles in Hegel. D2 36 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES there must be egoistic pleasure somewhere before there can be the altruistic pleasure caused by sympathy with it. Obviously, therefore, each must be egoistic in due amount, even if only with the view of giving others the possibility of being altruistic. So far from the sum of happiness being made greater if all make general happiness the exclusive end, the sum disappears entirely.' ^ Spencer sees clearly enough that in a reciprocal system the nature of each term forbids that the other terms with which it co-operates should be self- contained, and also that the other terms are not this one but are definitely other than it. His point is that in the system of altruistic pleasures each individual has no substantial satisfaction and depends for his pleasures on others who have none of their own to give. Now, how is this difficulty to be surmounted ? Any solution is to be rejected which simply drops out an element and falls back on some conception already shown in the dialectic to be imperfect. We must find some conception which will retain all that this one has in it, and yet avoid its defect. This is, in brief, what Hegel does. He brings us to see that in a reciprocal system we have something which is inherently more than a set of mutually determining parts. The paradox which troubles us rests on an assumption, viz. that we have to begin from the point of view of an isolated individual. It is quite true, for example' that if we have to understand the moral ideal by beginning with the pleasure of a private individual and working over from that to the others, the whole conception is self-contradictory. For in stating that the pleasure of the individual comes only from that of others we have robbed the individual of a substantiaHty which cannot be restored to him from others which are in a like case. The step we have to take is to recognize that there is more present than one term and others, there is the whole. We have assumed the substantial unity running through the terms, but we have not thought of taking it as the main feature and proper starting-point. We have tried to enter the system at the side, as it were, and we failed ; we may now try to enter into the spirit of the system as a whole and recogpize that it is the true individual. Before proceeding, we may gather together the main points ' The Data of Ethics, 3rd. edit. pp. 227-8. FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 37 ■ which have emerged. Substance, we saw, appeared in its accidents and exercised power over them ; but it was faulty because it could not give an adequate account of difference, and because it did not really determine itself in its accidents. It constituted or posited its accidents, but presupposed its own nature. The first of these defects was partly removed by causality and reciprocity, where substance divided itself into manifestations which were themselves substantial. Reciprocity, however, is an imperfect category, for it sets the negative element on equal terms with the positive and dissipates everything it touches. When thought leaves the seemingly solid standing-ground of the particular, it demands some support' on which it may stand and find rest. Reci- procity has turned out to be a veritable flux, and endless movement into externality. The step which thought now takes brings it out of this infinite relativity. There is only one thing stable, and that is the whole ; and whenever thought lays hold of experience as a self-articulating principle, the negative element — relativity — ^becomes subordinated to the positive. This is the point of view of the notion. To revert to our former terminology, experience has ceased to be merely one and many, a one that is also many, and has become one because of its multiplicity and difference. The notion is a principle which owns its differences, and in developing an opposite brings into explicit being a unity strong enough to sustain and include the opposition within it. By over-reaching the relativity of its content and including difference and externality within itself, thought has tran- scended the second flaw in the conception of substance, viz. the mere presupposition of the essence. The system is an organism. It appears in its members ; their acts are its acts, and in their mutual determination of one another it determines itself. If we regard the nature of the principle and of each of its manifestations as private and self-centred, as something which stays at home with itself and is purely self-contained, then the notion is unintelligible. In order to understand it we must see that the nature of each member is found in an outgoing activity, and that what it establishes is not merely alien but is also itself. The inward nature of the thing and its outward reference are not merely conjoined, as in essence ; they are identical. This is also true of the 38 FUNDAMENTAL LOGI CAL CATEGORIE S system as a whole. The principle — the notion — establishes itself in its members, and the act whereby each posits itself in its other is a process whereby the whole estabhshes itself. Thus the one-sidedness of the relation of substance disappears in the notion, for the latter posits itself in and as its accidents. Substance is absolute merely because it is underived ; the notion is absolute because it is self-determined. The move- ment of the accidents has become a movement of substance itself, and the outward reference falls now within the whole, not merely as an additional factor, but as an integral element. It is that through which the notion reaUzes itself. Thus the notion is a category of activity ; its nature is to go out of itself and find itself in this movement. There is nothing mysterious in the statement that the notion is absolute not because it is underived but because it is self-determining. There is a dangerous tendency in thought to revert to the principles of essence when dealing with the notion, and to raise old problems which have really been answered. In this mood it is urged that the self-determination of the notion does not free it from the difficulties of substance ; it, too, has a nature which it must presuppose. And this logical problem is the basis of the charge that Hegel's con- ception of freedom amounts merely to that of a so-called spiritual mechanism, determinism in a subtler medium. Now, in dealing with this difficulty it is important to see clearly what is at issue. Doubtless the notion has a nature, but that is not a defect — ^it is not the defect we urged against substance. The question is. Must the notion presuppose its nature in the same sense as that which was found to mar the conception of substance ? We may therefore ask for a clearer statement of the meaning of presupposition in this connexion. We have seen that substance is in truth indeterminate. Accidents, of course, appear on the surface, and substance dwells in them and has power over them. But there are within it no differences to account for the differences it produces in its appearance ; it is indwelling and hidden. When we force this point to the utmost it yields the con- clusion that substance does nothing. Doubtless "it posits its accidents and determines them ; but how can there be a power that acts and is unaffected by its action ? Substance is unmoved ; and the movement must therefore be in some FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 39 way illusion — if substance is the whole truth. But against this we have to set the reality of the movement ; for to deny the movement is to annihilate the accidents and substance along with them. Substance, therefore, is noj indeterminate ; since it acts it must have within it principles of action, means for the production of differences. What are we to make of this antinomy ? The first side, the indeterminate aspect, is the outer show, the appearance which substance wears when it is not taken with the light of the notion upon it ; and it is the vacuity into which inadequate thought must retire. The second aspect, the inward determinateness of substance, is a statement of the nature of substance in the knowledge of that which it becomes in the upward trend of thought. Substance musi be determinate, but at its own proper level this determinateness is hidden and not made open. Therein lies the underived character. The charge, then, is no gratui- tous one ; it voices the demand that substance should show what shape it has, and insists that substance seems to be a featureless abyss merely because it is in shadow. The point may be put in other words. In any ordered world of thought which has risen to the level of substance, change and process find a place. And such change has an explanation. But if the first principle, substance itself, contain no such explanation, then beyond it there lie forces and powers which it cannot control, and which are alien to it. But the first principle, substance, at the same time claims supremacy and completeness ; it itself is the sole truth : and hence it falls into contradiction with itself. Substance may reconcile the discrepancy only by genuinely accepting the determinateness of its accidents as its own proper content. It will then leave nothing standing beyond it to bind it, and it wiU have a right to claim as its own those powers which it asserts to be concealed within it. It is this step that the notion has taken ; it has brought into harmony the implicit nature and the overt appearance. The first step appears to be one of renunciation ; the supreme has limited itself in each of its members. But that step, though essential, is only one side of a complete act ; for the principle thereby gains the whole as its content, and all that is faUs within its scope. Growth, we have been told, is not mere aggregation, it is creation. And the nature of 40 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES spirit, we are assured, is to pass for ever into forms which are unique and new. Hegel might agree with this, but he would certainly add that at the same time spirit was only coming to its own full stature. The notion is a principle whose nature is to elaborate itself from within and to become a concrete system. The factors are embodiments of the whole, they are organs in which the whole is present as such, and each, when taken in its context and truth, has the power and value of the whole. Thus the notion — unUke substance-:^ expresses itself in a form which is worthy of it, and in going into its opposite it is realizing what there is in it to be. Its inherent nature is brought out in" its development ; and it is — in Hegel's terminology — for itself what it is in itself, an und fur sich, the absolute. It may be useful to express this conception with reference to the terms universal and particular. Previous to Hegel no thinker succeeded in resolving the opposition between these two. Aristotle's conception of the individual is ambiguous, because at times he seems to regard it as the union of two disparate elements, matter and form, while at others he treats it as the infima species itself. It seems fair to suppose that, on" the whole, Aristotle's thought was dualistic, and that he regarded the universal as incapable in itself of giving the concrete detail of life. Universal and particular do come together for him, as in Hegel's categories of essence, but the reason of their union is not present in their nature. Even Spinoza failed to meet the difficulty. Unlike Aristotle he refuses to give the particular any content that is beyond the universal ; but in bringing the particular within the universal he restricts the nature of the former and does not do justice to its negative aspect. In Hegel's category of the notion the universal is not merely an abstract principle which is made concrete by being dipped in a foreign matter, such as the matter of sense intuition ; it is a concrete whole having internal differences, the equipoise of opposed yet united aspects. On the other hand, the particular is not an exclusive unit — it is a way in which the system appears ; its nature is in no part merely private but is drawn from the whole. The notion obliges us to affirm the identity of the universal and the particular ; and in concrete thinking the two aspects are at one with each other, and each is the other. FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 41 This identity of opposites is, of course, the great stumbling- block in Hegel's logic to many minds, and it has been the butt of much mockery. But to reject this category is to deny the validity of every step of the path to it. Hegel has already shown the identity (not the sameness) of opposites. It is there for the thinker who traces the dialectic. Being turned in our hands into not-being or nothing ; that which merely is, equally is not. The identity is there and is patent in the dialectic, although it is not manifest to the mind limited to such principles. If imperfect thoughts do imply their oppo- sites, there must be some more perfect principle of thought within which this implication falls as content. And such thought is an identity of opposites. In this category of the notion Hegel has brought within the content of thought the power which gave the dialectic life ; the dialectic has now become for itself what it is in itself. If we, in real earnest, reject this position, it is difficult to see what shift thought can make. There is no stable mean between the utter nominalism of Antisthenes and the concrete logic which treats the assertion of the identity of different things not as a sign of the impotence of thought, but as a statement of the nature of reason and of reality. When we think coherently, so that the identity of the universal and particular is manifest, the result is the concrete universal or true individual. The unity lives only in the differences, and the latter have their meaning and being only in the whole which they utter forth. The universal which does not thus articulate itself is abstract ; it is at most a common element — a glorified particular — and hence not really a universal at all. Similarily, the particular abstracted from its context loses all that makes it what it is, it lapses into the pure being which is nothing. The con- crete universal, thus, or the notion, is the truth both of the universal and of the particular ; it is the category where they are identical. ; This analysis, however, must not be understood abstractly ; the identity in question does not exclude difference. The [fault of Spinoza's philosophy is that he achieves unity "at the , expense of difference ; he files down the two aspects until they have an indifferent shape and so can be mistaken ^or one another. But for Hegel the negative aspect, difference, ':ension, opposition, is a moment — though only a moment. 42 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATE GOR IES The universal must limit itself, must take on the forms o finitude, and preserve that finitude even while going beyont it. We shall see later how the self, which is the actual embodi- ment of the notion, denies itself and goes forth into its other^ into a world which is the not-self. The 'outgoing moment is essential and in the spiritual life it involves strenuous effort and bitter sacrifice ; indeed the concreteness of the identity of the whole depends on the stress of the outward process.; There is not full joy in the harmony of thought if in its nature it has not gone info a far country. To minimize the reality of the alienation is to diminish the fullness of the union, and to translate an identity of opposites into a bare tautology.^ We cannot trace in detail Hegel's analysis of the sphere of the notion ; but it is necessary to note one distinction. The description we have given is that of the character of the whole of the third division of the logic, which is called in general the doctrine of the notion. But the sphere comprises a number of categories of differing grades. The name, ' notion ', is given by Hegel to the first of these as well as to the whole ; and the last one, the only adequate and complete principle of thought, is called the ' idea '. It is perhapsi enough for our purposes to say that the notion, in the narrow! sense, is the principle of such a system capable of complete! articulation but as yet undeveloped. The ' idea ' is thej complete system actually seen to be the concretion of thej simple immanent principle. The notion involves the ' idea 'iJ and is the bud of which the latter is the fruit. The former is inward, immanent, undeveloped : the latter is always an inward principle which expresses itself outwardly and hasi actually mastered the external. The ' idea ' is the truth m the notion, the full self into which the notion develops itself.*] In the sequel, unless the context forbids, it is to be assumed i that the term, notion, is used to indicate the narrow catego|j rather than the whole sphere, for the distinction between the principle and the concrete achievement is of great impor- tance. But we cannot dwell longer on the point in its bare logical form, and can characterize it further only in more concrete embodiments. By way of transition to this more concrete realm we may discuss a possible misconception of the meaning of Hegel's ' Cf. Phenomenology, WW. II. pp. 15-16. FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATEGORIES 43 lalysis. We have spoken of the identity of opposites, but e are not thereby committed to the absurd statement that .1 opposites are identical, and that it is a matter of indifference hether we say yea or nay. The categories are not themselves le world, they are at most the principles of it ; and, although om a scientific point of view they are the more weighty spect, yet in their abstractness they are a poor substitute )r a world constituted by them. That is to say, when we ave analysed a category we have only stated a demand ; le task still remains of satisfying that demand, of finding or rganizing an experience which manifests the form of unity lat the category reveals. It is one thing, e.g., to determine 1 the abstract the nature of Substance, and another to ossess a content of knowledge which in all its concreteness is ■ self a substance. Similarly, in the notion the demand for 1 world or medium in which the unity of opposites is achieved ; not lightly satisfied. Ignoring for the present the difficult roblem of the ultimate relation of the various spheres to one nother, we may represent the various categories as the rinciples of various grades or realms of experience. Form ad matter are inter-dependent, and each matter has a limit i) its capacity of yielding forms. Some matter of experience :, as it were, too coarse to take on the finer forms, and the igher categories cannot be realized in it ; on the other hand, erne matter is inherently too fine to be held by the rougher jid less adequate forms. Hegel does not seek to find the rjtion and the ' idea ' in their proper shapes in the purely 'lysical world of space and motion ; the lower categories in rliich externality predominates are the appropriate form of J;.ch stuff. Nor does he suppose that the categories of being, ■: even of essence, can give us the truth of the moral and ^tellectual hfe of mind. The proper field for the notion is glf-conscious mind, and the ego is the reahzation of that jiinciple.i If we are unable to think the nature of the notion jj the abstract, and must have examples of it in the concrete if, order that the ' identity of opposites ' be more than ''' ' When the notion has developed into such existence as is free, it nothing else than the ego or pure self-consciousness. Of course, ifiave notions, i.e. determinate notions ; but the ego is the pure notion (felf, which, as such, has become a definite fact ' (WW. VI. pp. 13-14)- Macran, Hegel's Doctrine of Formal Logic, p. 123. 44 FUNDAMENTAL LOGICAL CATE GORIES a confused phrase, it is only in the life of self-conscifiji rational mind that illustrations can be found. The opposite of external nature are not identical for thought ; the sphen is, therefore, in itself, confined to and governed by lowei categories, and is not fully rational. Mind alone over-reaches its other, denies itself in order to find itself, and brings the notion into being. In discussing the Philosophy of Ri^U itself we may see more closely the way in which logical demands are met by the ethical life, and to what extent the answers are adequate. CHAPTER III THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL In the previous chapter we discussed the meaning of the rinciple of thought which Hegel calls the notion, and we sliall id that this is the fundamental principle of which the ethical orld in all its forms is the articulation. But before examining le notion in its shape as an ethical system we have to deal ith it in another of its forms. We have already briefly dicated the attitude of Hegel's philosophy to things, but e have confined our attention ahnost exclusively to his gical standpoint. We must, therefore, determine more recisely the view he takes of the special nature of ethical lilosophy. In so doing we shall be elaborating the analysis : the notion, for philosophy is a form of reflective thought, id its moments are articulations of the basal principle of all ental life. Hegel's adoption of a scientific attitude in ethics is provoked severe criticism ; and in order to understand recisely what Hegel means by science here we shall examine s attitude in its general bearings. The main topic we have I discuss in this chapter is the identity of and distinction 5tween the philosophy of nature and the philosophy of the hical world. It seems advisable, therefore, to pursue our quiry at first with special reference to Hegel's explicit atements regarding the philosophy of nature. The identity id difference which we seek will thereby become plainer hen we analyse the specific nature of mind. For Hegel philosophy is a concrete attitude of mind ; it is Dt mere practice, nor yet is it what is usually called mere leory. Both in his early voyage of discovery, the Pheno- enology, and in his more mature Encyclopaedia he places highest in the ranks of the concrete attitudes of mind, f course philosophy is not itself the whole of being ; its mtent is not the absolute in all its fullness, breadth, and ;tail ; nor is it all knowledge, for it treats much that is known, id which doubtless deserves to be known, as irrelevant, and 46 THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL confines itself to main principles. But philosophy in Hegel's view is the notion of the whole, and its content is the prin-i ciple of which nature and mind are the embodiment.^ Ther are two attitudes to objects which Hegel definitely repudiate as inadequate to philosophy.^ The first of these we may cal intellectualism, the purely theoretical standpoint. From thii point of view the task of knowledge is to conform to the real we have to leave things unaltered, to refrain from imposing our subjective ends upon them : we must simply accept them as they are in themselves. This, of course, is the basis of all empiricism ; and it is not without justice that empiricists, such as the English school, are charged with intellectualism, Hegel points out, however, that we cannot rest in this attitude ; the passivity which it enjoins is incompatible witl the proper activity of thought. Thought is essentially universal ; it cannot accept a mere datum, but must think it and^discover law and coherence in its object. We may seel earnestly to examine things disinterestedly and try to-adopi a purely objective attitude to them', but thought will nol permit us. Thought itself has a determinate structure anJ mode of functioning : we may intend to take each particulai fact merely as it is and by itself, but thought insists on tak,iii| its objects not as mere particulars but as instances, m apprehends the minutest detail not merely as ' this ' ol ' that ' but as ' such '.^ Whether we will or not, thought lead us to centre our attention on the universal, on the law, w. to put the bare fact into the background as the mere vehidi of the law. Hegel does not need to be told that reahty (fli experience) is richer than thought. ' The more thinkinf enters into imagination ', he says, ' the more the particulaif| and immediacy of things disappears from nature. By tl mvasion of thought the wealth of the infinite variety of natuif IS depleted, its vernal growth bhghted, and its colours blanchel The sound of noisy life in nature is stilled in the silence ol ' V. Phenomenology, WW. II. ' Das absolute Wissen ', pp. 6io-b! trans, pp. 820-3. . ^'^ ^ Of course the division may be carried much farther— the entJ Phenomenology is an analysis of attitudes of which only the lasti^ adequate But the division indicated in the text is also Hegel's ownj and IS sufficiently representative for present purposes _> V. Phenomenology WW. II, 'Die Sinnliche Gewissheit Oder dd Dieses und das Meines ', p. 73 ff., trans, p. 90 If ■ THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL 47 bought ; its warm profusion, which clothes itself in a thousand vonderful shapes, withers into barren forms and universals hapeless as murky northern clouds.' 1 By thinking it we have iltered the given, and thereby set up a dualism. Things as given us are detailed, concrete, individual — indeed particular ; )ut the content of our thought is universal. Have we not ;onverted real existences into contents of knowledge, into ;omething which we have made ? In trying to grasp objects ve have altered them, and we seem to have missed our hold. We make the thing universal and our own, and yet qua latural thing it ought to be free and independent.' ^ Intel- ectualism thus has two sides. It puts forth ' realistic ' inten- ;ions, and assumes that reality is the given, that which is ndependent of the apprehending subject. But at the same lime it is an attitude of thought, and all thought is a transform- ng and appropriating principle ; thus it chooses the relevant Tom the irrelevant, links up and interprets what is not given n that fashion, and in general bullies experience into supply- ng it with-contents marked by its own characteristics. On this side it manifests an unconscious idealism, and presents another nstance of inadequate thought turning into its opposite. The assumption which intellectualism takes as its explicit principle, and which its performance flouts, is that the object Df knowledge is a hard and impenetrable reality, inherently )ut of touch with the nature of apprehending knowledge, rhis assumption the opposite abstraction to pure theory, Az. the practical attitude, flatly denies. It assumes that ;hings are utterly in relation to mind, and is a thorough-going dealism. The satisfaction of any desire or impulse naively crosses the gulf which intellectualism has declared to be mpassable. ' The wit and need of man ', says Hegel, ' has found endless ways of changing and mastering nature. . . . Whatever powers nature evolves and looses against man, :old, wild beasts, water, fire, he knows means against them, md indeed he takes these means from nature and uses them igainst itself. The craft of his reason enables him to set one latural force against another, to destroy the one by the other, md so preserve and maintain himself.' ^ In the practical ittitude the- objective is subordinated to the subjective. » Encyclopaedia, WW. VII a. pp. 12-13. » Ibid. p. 14. " Ibid. p. 10. 48 THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL The end lies in the satisfaction of the self ; and so the objective thing is regarded merely as a means whose end is the restora- tion or fulfilment of the harmony of self-feeling — the removal of discomforts and oppositions within the self. The task which intellectualism regards as impossible is performed, ikegel points out, by the animals, which, all unconscious of the unattainable character of things, reach out to them and devour them. This attitude gives us the point of view of finite tele- ology. But when it is exalted to be the method of dealing with things, and claims are made for it as for an ultimate standpoint, it manifests as grave deficiencies as the opposite abstraction, viz. intellectualism. It is true that things are determined by us as relative to our purposes ; but this is not the whole truth. The power of mind to bend things to its designs is narrowly limited. Man may overcome this, that, or the next thing, ' but he cannot master nature itself, the universal, in this way, and trim it to his end '.^ We shall see later ^ that a finite end is in the grasp of something greater than itself, and how great a failure mind is when it erects its private purpose — its subjectivity, as Hegel calls it — to the level of omnipotence. Further, teleology of this kind can afford but a spurious and external spirituality. Mind is interpreted as finite, i.e. as having an independent nature of its own to which things, indifferent in themselves, are arbitrarily subordinated. This is not the teleology of Aristotle, fof whom the' end is immanent in the thing as its own proper nature ; it is rather that external form which reads its arbitrary satisfactions into things as their inner meaning. It declares that ' the wool of the sheep is there only to provide me with clothes ', and it wonders at ' the wisdom of God in providing cork trees for bottle stoppers, vegetables for weak stomachs, and cinnabar for cosmetics '? Mere objectivity and mere subjectivity are equally one- sided ; if a genuine philosophic standpoint is to be reached the receptive attitude of theory must be united with the purposive character of practice. Philosophy is a practical attitude, and involves the right to transform the given, to think it, and to find law and order in it. But at the same ' time it must not be arbitrary and subjective ; it must not proceed from principles which are external to nature, private » Encyclopaedia, WW .\H a. p. lo. = Chap. IX. ' Ihid. p. lo. THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL 49 ends and the like, but must ascertain what the world itself is. In thus combining the theoretical and practical in a fuller and more adequate attitude we must alter each of them. Practice must forego its subjective limitations, and theory must renounce its intellectualism ; we must be realistic and idealistic at once. We must, therefore, assume that in thinking things we are not departing from their true nature, but reaching forward to it ; the truth comes to us not as datum but as result. By way of contrast we may indicate a false method of uniting theory and practice — a method which ignores the transformation required in each attitude. The defects of the purely theoretic consciousness — its entire : subversion of the realism it professes — are in this theory : accepted as final, and the equally one-sided practical attitude : may simply be added to it as a supplement. The two imper- : feet aspects are not seen to be abstractions from a deeper ! attitude, but are set forth as interacting functions or faculties ! of mind. The result is, of course, a compromise. One shape - this doctrine has taken in modern philosophy is the view :l that the universals of knowledge are mental constructs, they : are classifications and arrangements made only for the ; convenience of thought and not because they are funda- li mental determinations of reality. The deficiency thus ad- s mitted may be filled up in more than one way. For example, J the conception of a purely objective reality may be retained, i and the task of reaching the unknowable may be handed over f to the practical function of mind under the guise of faith or i moral teleology. Another method, in which the practical I side predominates, gives up the conception of the indepen- j dence of the objective and makes finite purpose the motive I and test of thought itself. Thought does not reach independent reality, it admits, but there is no independent reahty to reach. li We have been making a false demand on thought ; its real J function is to satisfy our purposes. It is a means to our ji satisfaction, and if it achieves that end no further claim should j be made upon it. Satisfaction is thus put in place of reahty, : and thought becomes a moment in a finite will. J Hegel's attitude is thoroughly opposed to this compromise. ^ He will not surrender any of the positive aspects of the ^ inadequate powers of mind, and he beheves that the realism ^ of naive theory has a certain truth. All his teaching is an 50 THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL effort to bring together the moments of reality and rationality, and he denies that the idealism of true thought inhibits its adoption of a realistic standpoint. He therefore questions the assumption that the universals of thought are merely mental. If universals were mere convenient marks of things and aids to distinguishing them ' we might, e.g., take the lobe of the ear as the sign of man, for no beast has it. But we feel at once that such a determination does not succeed in knowing the essence of man '.^ The first step in the solution of this duahsm of mere thought and mere purpose is the denial of the adequacy of the datum. ' The truth of things is that qua immediate and particular they are only appearance and show.' That is to say, the negative or destroying aspect found in the attitude of desire and purpose to objects in their immediate appearance is the first moment of philosophic thought. ' Intelligence familiarizes itself with things not in their sensible existence, but by thinking them and by setting them as content in itself.' ^ But the universal which thought finds is not arbitrary ; it is the law of the thing. From Hegel's standpoint it is an unjustifiable assumption to hold that the world is an aggregate of ^particulars ; in the last resort it is a coherent system— and perhaps even system is an inadequate expression. Law, universality, context, and mediacy are constitutive of the barest fact ; and when we must choose between the aspects, universaHty is the truer and deeper side. We express more, and are nearer the heart of things, when we know the law of an object, than when we can merely look at it and point. ' The universal of the thing is not something subjective, depending as it were on us. Rather in opposition to the transitory phenomenon it is the noumenon, the objective, the reality of the thing itself; and It IS the Platonic " Idea ", existing not afar off, but in the mdividual thing as its substantial genus. The inscription on the veil of Isis, " I am that which was, is, and shaU be; and no mortal hath Hfted my veil ", dissolves before thought. Nature , says Hamann with justice, " is a Hebrew word written only with consonants, and the understanding must point it . Hegel does not suppose that the categories • Encyclopaedia, WW. VII. p. 17. z ^j,-^^ jg •■' Ibid. p. 17. ' THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL 51 are the whole of the known world ; they are the ' diamond net into which everything is' brought and thereby made intelligible '. The universal is abstract apart from that full realization of it which is reality in its entirety, the con- crete existing worlds of nature and mind ; but, for knowledge, it is the fundamental aspect, the outline and essential nature of the whole, the notion of which the absolute itself is the ' idea '. Philosophy is thus both receptive and active. It transforms the given, but at the behest of the deeper truth in the given. The task of science is to make things intelligible and discover rationality in them. It is active but not arbitrary. Discovery is a process, and involves digging beneath the surface till the gold is laid bare ; but the gold must be found in the rock and not be put there from without. In order to determine Hegel's view further we may look at the distinction between philosophy and positive or induc- tive science. The philosophy of nature — and the same thing is true of the philosophy of mind — is not a substitute for the sciences of nature ; it does not itself discover laws from the actual facts and sift the phenomena of sense. It presupposes inductive science. ' The philosophy of nature takes the material which physics has prepared from experience, at the point to which physics has brought it, and reconstructs it in such a way that experience is not its final warrant and base. Physics must work into the hands of philosophy , and the latter translates the universal, which the understanding has yielded, into the notion, and shows how as an intrinsically necessary whole it proceeds from the notion.' ^ In the last chapter we saw the nature of the notion, and indicated that the dialectic itself is an illustration of it. The notion is a principle which develops itself into a system ; and thus the barest principle of pure thought, being, was forced by the pressure of the whole within it to pass step by step into the articulated body of logic. The same thing is to be discovered in the philosophy of nature or of mind. The universal aspects of the special subject-matters can no more be left in a confused aggregate than can the categories of pure reason. They have to be reduced to order and congru- ence, their juxta-position must be resolved into mutual » Ibid. p. 18. E2 52 THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL implication, and the unity which the notion demands bestowed upon them. But this unity must not be capricious. The notion, we have seen, develops itself into the ' idea ' ; the variety which it achieves is not attained simply by applying a static principle in many directions, but is a genuine self- evolution, a deepening and maturing of the principle itself. To this end the philosophic science of nature must be dialectic. Its goal is the entirety of the explanatory principles of its object, and it must show them as interlocked and as mutually supporting. Naturally, then, since the system is the goal or result, we must begin at the other end from it, for we have to meet and bring with us every aspect of the whole. The simplest conception of the object, therefore, is the starting- point. When the inadequacy and incompleteness of that appears, we move to the next category, one stage more concrete, and so on, until the notion becomes the ' idea '. Only when we have brought the notion out into the ' idea ' is the complete explanation, the rationale, of the object in our hands. So long as we do not know the various aspects this philosophic dialectic transcends our powers, and in this sense experience and induction are the necessary preliminary- foundation, if you will — of philosophy. But, on the other hand, so long as we are acquiring information of, and seeking acquaintance with new aspects, and passing haphazard, as chance and imperfect knowledge lead us, from one point to another, we cannot fully explain our objects. The middle terms of all our arguments are still merely rationes cognoscendi and are not yet rationes essendi. We note the appearances, and can say why we are certain of their existence ; but what it is in truth that is before us we cannot tell. Like Plato's cave dwellers we see the shadows on the walls but not the veritable things themselves. Now, since philosophic explana- tion is a genuine system or organism, its parts are not to be conceived as independent, self-subsisting factors. Each law or universal aspect which falls within the compass of the completed science has its meaning and verification from the entirety of its context. Each is an abstraction which breaks into contradiction when thought in isolation. It is plain, therefore, that the metaphor of a ground or basis is misleading. The full truth, the explication of the significance of each element, comes to us only at the end. And philosophy THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL 53 is not an edifice resting on those categories which come first in the order of statement. It is rather a self-balancing system no part of which will stay in place unless each of the others is present. If we lay any stress on the order of the exposition in time, the ' warrant and base ' of the whole is in the last stage ; and although ordinary speech may resent the inversion of its metaphors, yet it is reasonable to believe that thinking is a movement towards knowledge and certainty and not away from it. Now, although this is the fundamental nature of thought, inductive science does not grasp it. It is busy building up, or acquiring, and emphasis is laid on the relations of points of importance in the acquisition of know- ledge. The metaphors of foundations and grounds are appropriate to it. Thus, a change of method marks the transition from inductive science to philosophy, and this is the meaning of Hegel's statement that the philosophy of nature reconstructs the material of physics ' in such a way that experience is not its final warrant and base '. Experience is not to be despised — far from it. Until mind has wandered over the whole of its field it cannot map the whole. The philosophy of nature cannot make physical facts, nor dare it really ignore them. But a fact by itself is nothing for thought ; the true interpretation is the essential, and that, as such, is not a datum of experience but the product of universalizing and comprehending thought. Philosophic knowledge, then, is knowledge in the notion. That is not to say, of course, that a ready-made form is fitted to the material ; as we have seen, the bare logical notion is a mere demand. The actual notion of a science is a proper product of the subject-matter, the principle of the things concerned, and each step of the development is the natural and inevitable consequence of the unfolding of the special nature of the fundamental conception. The notion of nature is not the notion of mind, and each develops into its ' idea ' by a path determined by its own character and needs. But this they have in common, that they are principles which develop from within, and which pass into a concrete system in which they are not lost but reaHzed. Hegel's conception of philo- sophy thus is neither a priori nor a posteriori : it stands above both. He admits the growth of knowledge, and the dependence on experience and on a posteriori methods which 54 THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL that implies : but at the same time he insists that knowledge in itself is otherwise constructed, and is its own guarantee. The a priori and the a posteriori are both confused abstractions from the full method. Both regard the approach to know- ledge as if it were itself all knowledge ; the a posteriori taking the faulty steps of the learner as the type of the march of maturity, the a priori imagining that there is no need for the learner to stumble and that he may march at once. Such in brief outline is Hegel's conception of philosophy. We may now proceed to determine more closely his attitude with regard to the ethical world. In the preface to the Philosophy of Right there occurs the following statement : ' What is rational is real, and what is real is rational. Upon this conviction stands not only philosophy, but also every unsophisticated consciousness ; and from it proceeds the view of the spiritual universe as the natural.' ^ The objections which present themselves to this proposition are manifold. Some spring from the claims of the subjective consciousness. Freedom and spontaneity seem to be infringed by this objec- tive doctrine, and it is complained that Hegel's view leaves no room for sin and error. Hegel's own account of the claims of subjectivity will be presented in due course, as will also his view of evil from an ethical standpoint. We may confine ourselves in this chapter to the way in which Hegel's ethical theory attempts to unite the objectivity of science with the freedom of the subject-matter. We must discover what difference is made to the articulation of the underlying conception of philosophy by the all-important consideration that ethics deals not merely with facts but with the will and with ideals. There is undoubtedly a grave difiEiculty to be overcome by him, for he seeks to bring together the aspects of reality and validity or worth, and it is commonly alleged that from no standpoint can these be seen in ultimate harmony. We may, therefore, look at his criticisms of two rival methods of ethics, each of which Hegel regards as holding fast to one side and omitting the other of the necessary whole. The first of these is ethical empiricism.^ Empiricism objects ' WW. VIII. p. 17. ■ \?^!''^'! ^**'*"f ^ to empiricism, as well as to the view which follows 111 the text, VIZ. formalism, is defined in his earliest ethical treatise. THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL - 55 to the ' high a priori road ', and rests its view on experience. It is a form, as we have seen, of intellectualism. Experience presents to us an endless series of determinations, each filling out its own moment of time, and passing away again. In a pure empiricism none of these has pre-eminence over the others ; for all are facts, and it is only as facts that they are interesting. This very infinity of material, however, is embarrassing ; for empiricism calls itself science and wishes to think ; it would be a theory and not a meaningless record of details. Therefore this pure realism in ethics must follow the appointed path of its downfall ; it becomes idealist and transforms the given. Some one feature of experience, or group of such features, is plucked forth from among the undistinguished crowd, and regarded as the essence of the matter. Other phases are subordinated to it and treated as means. For example, in the theory of punishment, the aspect of the reformation of the offender may be made the end, and everything judged from that point of view. Or in the relation of marriage and the family, the education of the children may be set forth as the purpose of the whole, and the rest deter- mined as relative to that end. But this procedure does violence to the other determinations. There are many other aspects of punishment than reformation ; why should these be slurred over ? There is the protection of society, the deterring of others, and so forth : are not these as valid ends as the one chosen ? The privileged feature has no special right to predominance ; for in the long run each is a fact, and every fact is as good as its neighbour so long as it lasts. Having chosen a feature for chief place, empiricism makes it absolute, putting it forth as a binding law of life. The so-Ccdled law of self-preservation, or the hedonistic proof of the happiness principle, may serve as examples of Hegel's meaning. Some concealed criterion is adopted— physical necessity, common practice, &c.— and the aspect of things which fits this is- called a duty. But this is a mere tautology. When we examine this so-called duty we find that it has its place not because it is binding, but merely because it is. If all men ought to seek happiness simply because in point ' t)ber die Wissenschaftlichen Behandlungsarten des Naturrechts ', WW. I. Lasson VII. 56 THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL of fact they do, then ' ought ' adds ^ nothing to the fact. ' I ought ' is a disguised way of saying ' I do '. Hegel continues the analysis. Ethical empiricism apes science further. Science is a unity, a system ; and so em- piricism must seek to reduce the complex field of appear- ances to a single principle. The unity to which it reduces the variety of its data, says Hegel, ' can signify only as simple and poverty-stricken a group of qualities as possible, from which it thinks it can extend to knowledge of the rest '} Hegel is thinking of Hobbes. In the absence of a rational method empiricism tends to throw its doctrine into a pictorial form, and imagine (whether with historical accuracy or not^ does not much matter) a ' state of nature ', a chaos from which the ethical life springs. But a descriptive study of the transi- tion from a state of nature to civilized society would be a mere chronicle, and not an ethical or political philosophy. Empiri- cism must pretend to make chaos account for society, and to that end it imports into the state of nature the ' capacity ' or ' possibility ' of all that comes out of it. Empiricism thus drifts into arbitrariness and formalism in its effort to become science, and Hegel reminds it of its realistic basis. Pure empiricism is incoherent and unscientific, but it has a relative truth against the one-sidedness of this pseudo-philosophy. Life presents an infinite variety of cases, and philosophy must be wide enough to cover them all, It is a legitimate demand upon a formal view that it should develop itself in experience. Naive empiricism ' rightly insists on its resistance to such an artificial erection of principles, and prefers its own empirical inconsistencies to the consistencies of such philosophizing, and its own con- fusion ... to the absolute exclusion by one another of these different aspects of one and the same intuition, a.nd to the determination of the whole itself through a single one of these qualities. . . . Finally, empiricism justly charges such philosophizing with -ingratitude, since it has given the latter the content which its notions have, and has to see them become spoiled and distorted '.^ In this criticism we find reiterated in the sphere of ethical science two points which we have already discerned in 1 WW. I. p. 333, Lasson VII. p. 338. ' WW. I. pp. 341-2, Lasson VII. p. 345. THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL 57 general ; the necessity for experience and the necessity for its transformation. Ethical philosophy is not the whole of the ethical world, but it is the principle of the whole ; and if it is to be as comprehensive as experience it must be the notion of which the empirical is the embodiment. Hegel considers the failure of an ethical theory to cover social life as a totality to be a radical defect, and he believes that the true notion is the immanent principle of all ethical experience. Secondly, the details of social experience cannot be worked into a totality as they stand ; they must be recast and recon- stituted. No one feature is to be picked out as the essence ; for the essence is not one aspect but a principle — right in general and not this or that right. His point of agreement with empiricism is that the notion comes out of experience and must be found in it ; the notion is not a fiction of the mind but the nature of the facts. The point of disagreement is that for Hegel the apprehension of this objective right is not attained by simple inspection but by conceptual thinking, by apprehending the rationality of the ethical world. We may now consider the method most opposed to empiri- cism, viz. the moral idealism of which Kant's theory is one of the highest forms. Empiricism has treated the ethical as the existent, Kant insists that the ethical is the rational. We have seen that the existent as apprehended by empiricism falls short of rationality, and Kant accepts the tacit dualism. The i characteristic of Kant's ethics is the opposition of reason to i experience and the emphasis laid on the primacy of practical ; reason. Empiricism in its purer form lays hold of the real s in its immediacy, in its definite temporary moments as facts. ! The critical philosophy, on the other hand, recognizes that i there is another aspect, universality or wholeness, and that I the latter is the more fundamental for science and reason. s Empiricism claims, as we have seen, to be science ; but it 8; fails to discern that scientific totality cannot be reached either I, by the mere aggregation of particulars or by capricious selec- If tion among them. The particular must be radically trans- formed before it can become a member of an organic whole. 5 The compilation of separate parts can give only a mechanical and superficial unity ; it cannot reach the entirety and con- gruence which rationality or intelligibihty demands. The critical philosophy begins with the perception of this failure. 58 THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL When thought has made this step, two paths open before it. One is to maintain the dualism of matter and form, of experi- ence and reason, and to preserve an apparently scientific attitude by rejecting experience and the particular and by holding fast to reason and the universal. The other course is to revise the assumption which leads to the dualism, viz. the impenetrability and atomic character of facts. At first sight experience is not a rational system, it is a patch-work of particular details : so much is common to empiricism, to Kant, and to Hegel. Against empiricism Kant and Hegel insist that the mere particular is not intelligible. Kant, however, agrees with empiricism that the facts are in truth as they appear, and assert that the incompleteness which he sees in them is their final character. Therefore, he thinks, in order to attain rationality in the moral world we must forgo the facts and turn to the intelligible content of reason. Hegel questions this. He allows to empiricism the truth of its assumption that the rational is the real, but breaks both with Kant and empiricism by denying that the immediate object, the relatively uninterpreted datum, is what is truly there. Kant, however, does not take this step. Recognizing the universality and completeness which empiricism fails to provide, he exalts it to the place of the whole, and isolates it from the particular. The form, he thinks, must be coherent and self-complete, or as Hegel phrases it, infinite and absolute ;' and since the matter of experience yields nothing final, we must obtain the form not from the matter but from another source, viz. reason. Kant's ethical system is, therefore,: a mode of the a priori and formal type of thought. Pure practical reason, for Kant, is the essence of the moral order, and the moral law is the result of its legislation. But having made a cleavage between matter and form, and given to reason control merely over the latter, Kant is unable consistently to find any real content for the legislation of pure practical reason. Its commands have no point of contact with the world of actual practice, and Hegel insists that, if thought clearly, it shows itself to be utterly empty. The understanding which apprehends experience is, for Kant| a faculty of parts which constitute no whole ; while practical:" reason is a faculty of wholes which have no parts. Kant, of course, could not afford to recognize the full force of this THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL 59 lilemma, and he gradually fills the legislation of practical eason with a foreign content to which it has no right. His ;ask is difficult, and he adopts the expedient of appl3dng the 'ormal unity to various matters of experience and allowing t to articulate itself in conjunction with but not by means )f them. When a practical course of action is in question, TO may bring it to the bar of reason. Reason, however, will lot itself provide a deliverance, for such action would bring t down from its lofty a priori status and stain it with the nire of contingency and fact. The moral law is not deter- nined by its instances, but is an authoritative standard to ivhich they refer. Pure practical reason, thus, falls into the ;ategory of substance in contrast with the notion. And Hegel's node of attack is to point out that so long as Kant holds the universal to be independent of the particular, so long is the [after in its turn independent of the former. If the form is not the form of the matter, the matter is untouched by it. Kant tells us that the morality of a maxim of the will is its pure universality, its self-consistency ; and he obtains an apparent content for the moral law by laying hold of the implications of universality. The moral maxim is the universal ; hence that which can be universalized is moral, and that which cannot is immoral. To this Hegel rejoins that an illicit step has been taken. The essence of the ethical ideal, on Kant's fundamental assumption, is not universality in its concreteness as the principle of a system, but mere universality, form without matter, self-consistency in the narrow sense. ' When Kant recognized that a universal criterion of truth would be that which was valid of all cases of knowledge without distinction of their objects, and that, since we thereby abstract from all content of knowledge — and truth is concerned precisely with this content — it is quite impossible and absurd to ask for a sign of the truth of this content of cases of knowledge when the sign is not to penetrate to the content, he pronounced judgement on the principle of duty and right which is set up through practical reason. . . . It is thus inherently self-contradictory to look within this absolute practical reason for an ethical legislation which must have a content ; for the essence of the former consists in having no content.' ^ The moral law is an abstract principle ' WW. I. p. 351, Lasson VII. p. 353 ; cf. Larger Logic, WW. V. p. 28. 6o THE REAL AND THE RATIONAL of reason out of all relation to experience, and cannot pasi criticism on any particular mode of action or life. Kan] escapes the tautology which is his sole right by the illicil introduction of experimental detail. We may follow this in an example. ' The commonest understanding ', he says, ' can distinguish without instructi