Ferdinand Lassalle as a Social Reformer £ "TON Hh im Waxmll Itoiwwitg ptawg BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME FROM THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF fienrg W. Sage 1891 A, wssjjl .; ..2.0/j/j^.. 5474 DATE DUE PH03 QDMPj f ffATLA^' DE£J. » 1075 r: 1 _ k i 1 CAVLOMO PfllNTCO IN U S.A Cornell University Library HX276.L345 B53 1893 Ferdinand Lassalle as a social reformer. olin 3 1924 030 356 442 The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924030356442 FERDINAND LASSALLE -fe- v^w C g-b FERDINAND LASSALLE AS A SOCIAL REFORMER EDWARD BERNSTEIN FORMERLY EDITOR OF DER SOZIAL DEMOCRAT. TRANSLATED BY ELEANOR MARX AVELING LONDON SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO NEW YORK : CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS 189? '1m H PREFACE. The short account of Lassalle here submitted to the English reader is, with some slight alterations, a transla- tion of my Introduction to the complete edition of Las- salle's Speeches and Works. I was asked to edit these by the executive of the German Social-Democratic Party of Germany in the spring of 1891. In the German this In- troduction bears the title Ferdinand Lassalle and his Significance in the History of Social-Democracy. I did not adopt the same title for the English edition in order to avoid confusion between my own and other works already published in England under similar titles. Indeed, this sketch is not intended to compete with elaborate works like that of Mr. W. H. Dawson. It is intended rather to act as a complement to Mr. Dawson's book and other works dealing with Lassalle and German Social-Democracy. For a full treatment of the subject it is far too incomplete, and its constituent parts are of purpose unequally balanced. Thus many important statements and criticisms were in the original reserved for the special introductions to the various works of Lassalle, and these I have not incorporated in the English volume. But, on the other hand, it deals with questions almost ignored by other writers, and after I have had access to documents hitherto unknown to them. Further, it is written at the same time from a Social- Democratic and a critical standpoint, whilst other critics of Lassalle have mostly been more or less opposed to Social- Democracy, or, in the case of Socialists who have written about him, they either did not criticise him at all, or criti- cised only his acts, and did not enter into any analysis of vi Preface. his theories. But such treatment of the subject is indis- pensable now that Lassalle is being exploited by the enemies of Socialism against Social-Democracy. It is undeniable that Socialism in Germany to-day has no resemblance to the special characteristics of Ferdinand Lassalle's Socialism. The more this became evident, the more Lassalle became the hero of the middle-class littera- teur, and was held up as the " good " Socialist, as opposed by the middle-class politician to the " bad " Social-Demo- crats of to-day. Was he not a national patriot, in contrast to the unpatriotic internationalists, destitute of " fatherland " — the followers of Karl Marx and Frederick Engels ? Was he not a real statesman, as compared with these mere demagogues or abstract theorists ? Had he not, at least, a scheme, even though it may have been wrong, for bringing about the peaceful socialisation of society, whilst these men do nothing but draw bills on a future revolution ? With all this cant we have had to deal in Germany, and that it has been imported into England is only too evident. This is why I have allowed passages dealing with this point to remain unabridged in the translation. The reader will at once see that my standpoint is that of Karl Marx and Fr. Engels, whose doctrines are to-day ac- cepted by the Socialist Parties — with some few exceptions — all over the world. Many misrepresentations and misunder- standings have been circulated as to the relation of Fer- dinand Lassalle's Socialism to these doctrines, and as to his personal relations with the author of Das Kapital. To some Lassalle is a disciple of Marx and Engels, who only differed from them on the question of productive co-opera- tive associations ; to others he is an original Socialist thinker, who merely took a few details of his criticism of capitalist production from Marx. Neither view holds Preface. vii good on closer examination. Lassalle was much more in- debted to Marx than he admitted in his writings ; but he was a disciple of Marx only in a restricted sense. As to the former point, even in the book in which he speaks of Marx — Herr Basliat-Schulze — Lassalle takes much more than he acknowledges from the book of Marx to which he refers. Very important deductions and even quotations from this book are made use of without any allusion to the original. In his speeches and pamphlets, again, in which he never refers to any of his Socialist predecessors, the in- fluence of these must strike the reader acquainted with Socialist literature. This does not apply to Marx and Engels only, but also to Louis Blanc and other French Socialists. The points in which Lassalle — sometimes consciously, sometimes unconsciously — differed from Marx and Engels I have dealt with explicitly in this book, and therefore I need not recapitulate them here. But upon one point a few "words should be said, as it bears upon a question much discussed recently on this side of the channel. Marx has been reproached — and this even by a section of English Socialists — with basing his Socialism upon the Ricardian theory of value adopted, and but slightly modi- fied by him. In his History of Socialism, written, on the whole, in the fairest spirit, Mr. Thomas Kirkup, e.g., says that when the Economists did not follow the Ricardian principle to its obvious conclusion — " that if labour is the source of wealth, the labourer should enjoy it all," it was " otherwise with the Socialists," and " as posited by the Economists, and applied by the Socialists, Marx accepted the principle." It "was made and continues to be, the foundation-stone of the system of Marx, and is really its weakest point." (Page 147.) viii Preface. Now, already in the treatise which Mr. Kirkup quotes on this occasion, the Misere de la PhUosophie, written and published in 1847, Marx says — "All the egalitarian con- clusions which Mr. Proudhon draws from Ricardo's theory are based upon a fundamental error, for he confuses the value of commodities measured by the quantity of labour embodied in them with the value of commodities incurred by the value of labour '' (p. 3 1 of the French, and p. 30 of the first German editions). After showing why and how this is inadmissible, Marx gives the names of the English Socialists who before Proudhon — who posed as the in- ventor of the idea — had made an " egalitarian " application of Ricardo's formula, and gives as examples passages from Bray's Labour's Wrongs and Labour's Remedies, London, 1839. And afterwards he proves that Bray's ideal of im- proving society by following out Ricardo's theory " to its obvious conclusion " is nothing but the reflex of society as it is. This was written, as I have said, in 1847, i.e., at a time when Marx had not yet completely worked out his own theory. Even then he saw clearly that what Mr. Kirkup, in accordance with, or may I say, misled by, many other writers, calls " the foundation-stone of the system of Marx " was a theoretical impossibility. In his Zur Kritik der Politischen CEkonomie, published in 1859, Marx refers again to the egalitarian application of Ricardo's formula by Eng- lish Socialists, and again makes it clear that he does not agree with them. He states four objections to the Ricar- dian theory of value (the second of which is the one taken up by these Socialists), and lays them down as so many problems to be solved by a closer analysis of the society from which the Ricardian theory is drawn, viz., modern capitalist society. A little further on he quotes John Gray, another Preface. ix English Socialist, earlier in date than Bray, who attempted an egalitarian application of Ricardo's formula, and again proves its fallacies and intrinsic contradictions (c. i., p. 40, and pp. 61-64). 1 In Das Kapital Mr. Kirkup could have read, firstly, that "labour is not the only source of material wealth" (p. 18 of the second edition of the German edition, and p. 10 of the English). Wealth and exchange value are two very different things. Secondly, although Marx lays bare all the tricks of capitalist exploitation of the workers, he does not by a single word claim for the workers " the full value of their labour." Why not ? Because, as he shows, "value," in an economic sense, is a quality belonging to commodities only, and which, therefore, can only occur in a society where products are exchanged as commodities, the value of a commodity being measured by the socially necessary labour embodied in it. Labour being, therefore, the measure of value, can have no value of its own. But it is quite different with the labour-power of the workers. This labour-power in our actual state of society is a com- modity, is recognised as such by all political economists, and, therefore, not only can have, but actually has, a value. And this value is determined by the quantity of socially necessary labour required for its production, maintenance, 1 Here, too, as in La Misere de la Philosophie, Marx refers to W. Thompson's Inquiry into the Distribution of Wealth, dkc, as a book which went wrong on the same question. This alone should have warned readers against accepting the assertion of Dr. A. Menger, re- peated by English critics, that Marx took his theory of surplus value from Thompson, an assertion based upon nothing but the fact that the words surplus value are occasionally used by Thompson ; but any- one who takes the trouble to read Thompson's book will at once find that surplus value with him is quite another thing than surplus value as defined by Marx. Cf. the article Jwristen Sozialismus in the New Zeit, year 1887, pp. 49 sqq. x Preface. and reproduction, that is to say, required for the produc- tion, maintenance, and reproduction of the actually living labourer. The price of this labour-power or the rate of wages may at a given time be higher, and at another lower than the actual value of labour-power, as the same thing occurs with the prices of commodities ; but whatever form the wages take, whether that of time-wages or piece-wages, under our system of capitalist production, based upon com- petition, they are but the price of labour-power. Now, if in the assertion that the workers are entitled to the full value of their labour, by labour is meant labour-power, that would mean no change in the present conditions ; but if it is to mean the full value of the product of their labour, that would mean the abolition of capitalistic production, and, with it, of the category of " value " altogether. To put it in the words of Frederick Engels : " The con- clusion drawn from the Ricardian theory, that to the workers, the only real producers, belongs the sum total of the product of society, their product, this conclusion leads directly into communism. But from a purely economical point of view, it is no argument at all, for it is but an ap- plication of moral rules to political economy. According to the laws of political economy, the larger share of the product does not go to the workers who have produced it. If, now, we say : this is wrong, this ought not to be, we assert something which prima facie does not concern poli- tical economy at all. We merely state that this economical fact is in contradiction with our moral sentiments. Marx, therefore, never based his communistic demands upon this argument, but upon the inevitable breakdown of capitalist production, a breakdown the evidences of which are becoming more palpably apparent every day. He only says that sur- plus value consists of unpaid labour, which is simply stating Preface. xi a fact. But a statement may be economically wrong in form, and yet right historically. If the moral conscience of the masses declares an economical fact to be unjust, as it did in former epochs declare slavery or corvee labour to be unjust, this is a proof that this same fact has outlived itself, that other economical facts have come into being, in con- sequence of which the former has become unbearable and untenable. Such an application of economical theory, though formally wrong, may therefore hide an economical truth of undoubted reality." (Preface to the German trans- lation of La Philosophic de la Mislre, first edition, pp. 10, II.) And Marx sums up the result of his researches in the first volume of Das Kapital by saying that the impending expropriation of the expropriators will establish individual property, based on the acquisition of the capitalist era, i.e., on co-operation and possession in common of the land and of the means of production. There is nothing said here of the mode of distribution of wealth corresponding to that new state of society. But this reconstructed society will not come into being all at once, ready-made like Minerva ; it will be subject to evolution as well as society in the past, and therefore the mode of the distribution of wealth will vary with the different phases of its evolution. It will de- pend upon the degree in which the economical, intellectual, and moral emancipation from capitalism shall have been accomplished. It will depend also upon the mass of wealth at the command of society, and upon many other questions. In a letter written in 1875, criticising the pro- gramme of the newly united Socialist party in Germany, and published in Die Neue Zeit (vol. i., p. 565, 1890-1891), Marx has fully explained his views on this point. But if Marx did not base his Socialism on the Ricardian xii Preface. theory of value, this cannot be asserted of Lassalle. He took his economic criticism of capitalist society from the then published works of Marx and Engels, but for his remedy he had recourse to the French and earlier English Socialists. To counteract the Ricardian law of wages, which he accepted in full, even along with its Malthusian foundation, he proposed as a remedy co-operative pro- >etuctive associations, subventioned by the State. I have shown in Chapter VII. of this book why, in my opinion, his remedy was wrong. A few words upon another question — the question of political tactics. In reading over this book again, it strikes me that in some respects the situation it describes re- sembles the situation in England at the present time. In England also we see a young Socialist party striving to secure a position independent of the existing political par- ties. Thus the criticisms upon the tactics of Lassalle might also be taken as applying to the tactics of my English com- rades. I therefore ask the reader to keep in mind that in Prussia at the time of Lassalle there existed only a sham constitutionalism. Parliament did not rule, but the King and his Ministers, Parliament possessing only a very re- stricted veto. All the powers of government were in the hands of the Crown and the classes behind it : the aristo- cracy, the small but influential party of landlords and Church bigots, the military, and bureaucracy. In Prussia, least of all, therefore, was it good policy to let oneself be se- duced by the cry of " no political but economic reforms." It meant, as this mostly means, neither the one nor the other. The battle-cry of the workers, as long as they have not se- cured the political rights necessary to make them the rulers of society, must always be: "political and economic reforms." When in 1866 the North German Confederation was c/ Preface. xiii founded, manhood suffrage was granted for the Reichstag, while certain restrictive laws affecting working-men's trade societies and strikes were abolished. The foundation of the German Empire in 1871 wrought no change in this re- spect. In Prussia and other German States the " three class " electoral system (see page 7), or rather high census franchises, still exists, and neither the Reichstag nor the State diets have the power to enforce Bills of their own. A Bill agreed to by five-sixths of the Reichstag is useless, or worse than useless, if the Federal Government will not consider it. And there is no likelihood that this degrading state will be altered by our German middle-classes, or that any serious steps in this direction will be taken by them. But if little progress has been made with regard to poli- tical rights in Germany since the days of Lassalle, econo- mical and social progress has proceeded by leaps and bounds. A few facts to illustrate this. In 1 860, the value of yearly manufacture was in millions of pounds sterling, 310 in Germany, 380 in France, 577 in the United Kingdom. In 1888 it was 583 in Germany, 485 in France, 820 in the United Kingdom. The steam- power used was (expressed in thousands of horse-powjr) : — United Kingdom. France. Germany. i860 2450 1 120 850 1870 404O 1850 2480 1888 9200 4520 6200 And if we take only the steam-power of fixed engines, i>e. s that used for manufacturing purposes, we. have this result : — United Kingdom* France. Germany. i860 700,000 l8l,000 200,000 1870 940,000 341,000 900,000 IS88 2,200,000 695,500! 2,000,000 (Mulhall's Dictionary of Statistics, 1892, pp. 365, 545, etc.) 1 These figures (for France) apply to the year 1885. xiv Preface. If the German middle-class have not fulfilled their poli- tical mission as the British and the French middle-classes did in their time, they are the more eager to fulfil their economic mission. The frequent statement that the won- derful growth of Social-Democracy in Germany js only the result of the backward condition of economical and poli- tical conditions in Germany is based on very little know- ledge of actual facts. It is true that the defective political institutions of the empire account, to a certain extent, for the growth of the " subversive " party ; but that growth is still more accounted for by the economical development — one might almost say the economic revolution — of the last twenty or thirty years. Industrially, Germany is already too advanced for our middle-classes to be inclined to seriously fight the Monarchy. Having regard to the immense num- bers of the proletariat in the many rapidly growing towns, they think it better to do as monarchs do elsewhere — to reign, but not to govern. There have been, and there will be, between semi-absolutist monarchs and the German bourgeoisie, only little family disagreements, which have been, and may again be noisy wrangles, but will never lead to any serious struggle. Both know too well that they have need of each other. Social-Democracy, besides its own historical mission, has to complete the unfulfilled missions of its predecessors. In a few passages I refer to England. In respect to them, the reader will kindly remember that they were originally addressed to, and intended for, a German public. EDWARD BERNSTEIN. CONTENTS. 15 44 CHAP. I. THE POLITICAL POSITION IN GERMANY AT THE BE- GINNING OF LASSALLE'S AGITATION II. LASSALLE'S YOUTH AND EARLY MANHOOD — THE HATZFELD LAWSUIT, 1848— " FRANZ VON SICKIN- GEN". ...... III. LASSALLE AND THE ITALIAN WAR IV. "THE SYSTEM OF ACQUIRED RIGHTS," AND OTHER MINOR WORKS (1860-1861) ... 64 V. THE STRUGGLE FOR A CONSTITUTION IN PRUSSIA— LASSALLE AND THE "PROGRESSIST PARTY"— THE WORKER'S PROGRAMME . . . gi VI. BREACH WITH THE PROGRESSIST PARTY— THE "OPEN REPLY LETTER''; ITS POLITICAL PORTION . 1 17 VII. THE "OPEN REPLY LETTER"; ITS ECONOMIC PORTION — THE IRON LAW OF WAGES, AND PRODUCTIVE CO-OPERATIVE SOCIETIES WITH STATE-HELP 1 34 VIII. LASSALLE AS AGITATOR AND LEADER OF THE AS- SOCIATION . . . . . .148 IX. VAIN ATTEMPTS TO COMPEL IMMEDIATE POLITICAL SUCCESS — APPROACHING THE REACTIONARY GOVERNMENT OF PRINCE BISMARCK — LAS- SALLE'S DEATH . . . . .166 X. CONCLUSION — LASSALLE'S LEGACY TO THE GERMAN WORKING-CLASS MOVEMENT . . 185 FERDINAND LASSALLE. CHAPTER I. THE POLITICAL POSITION IN GERMANY AT THE BEGINNING OF lassalle's AGITATION. So long as there have been ruling and oppressed, exploiting and exploited classes, there have also been revolts of the latter against the former ; there have been statesmen and philosophers, self- seekers and enthusiasts, who have proposed certain social reforms for the mending or for the ending of these conditions of exploita- tion. If all these efforts are to be summed up under the head of Socialism, then Socialism is as old as civilisation. But if we keep to more definite characteristics than the mere desire for a harmonious state of society and universal well-being, the Socialism of to-day has only this much in common with that of any former epoch, that it, like these, is the reflex of the special conditions of the class-struggle of its time. In all cases the structure of the society upon whose soil it has grown, sets its stamp upon the Socialism of the particular epoch. Modern Socialism is the product of the class-war in capitalist Society ; it has its root in the class-antagonism between the bour- geoisie and the modern proletariat, an antagonism that finds expression, in. actual struggle, comparatively early in history, al- though, it is true, the combatants themselves did not at first grasp its exact bearing. In its revolt against the privileged classes of Feudal Society, as in its struggle against State absolutism, the middle-class is induced to assume the part of advocate of the in- terests of all the non-privileged, and it is always in the name of A Ferdinand Lassalle. the whole people that it demands the abolition of institutions un- favourable, and the creation of institutions necessary, to the de- velopment of its own forces. And in this the middle-class acts, for a long time, in good faith, since only the ideas which it itself con- nects with these demands appear to it rational and commendable to the sound common-sense of humanity. The rising proletariat, however, so far as it has freed itself from the prejudices of the guild burghers, takes the promises of the middle-class spokesmen for sterling coin, so long as that middle-class is exclusively in opposition to the representatives of existing institutions. But once it has conquered the latter, or has, at least, so far beaten them, that it can set about realizing its own aspirations, it be- comes evident that the plebeians behind it have an altogether different conception of the promised Kingdom of Heaven upon earth from that of their quondam friends and protectors, and the result is strife, the more violent the greater have been the former illusions. But the proletariat is not yet powerful enough to keep up its resistance ; it is forced into silence by ruthless violence, and disappears again, for a long time, from the scene of action. This was the case in all the middle-class risings of the six- teenth, seventeenth, and eighteenth, and even in the first de- cades of the nineteenth century. The rapid development in the revolution of the conditions of production, during the century, have, however, changed the relation of the proletariat vis-a-vis of the bourgeoisie. Exceptional circumstances were no longer needed to make manifest the antagonism between the interests and aims of these two, and without these that antagonism found expression in the more advanced countries. Workers began to organise for resistance against the capitalist class ; bourgeois conditions of society were subjected to criticism from the proleta- rian standpoint ; an anti-bourgeois, Socialist literature arose. Relatively unimportant dissensions within the bosom of the bour- geoisie itself, the simple conflict of one of its wings with another, sufficed to allow the more active elements of the pro- letariat to enter the lists as an independent party, with demands The Political Position in Germany. of its own. The Reform movement of middle-class liberalism in England was the signal for the Chartist movement; the July Revolution in France inaugurated first a purely Republican, but then a Socialist and revolutionary proletarian propaganda, which, in importance, scarcely fell short of the Chartist agitation. In the forties the movement — literary and propagandist — passes to Germany. Writers and politicians, who had been abroad, either as exiles, or in order, for a while at least, to escape the smell of the police at home — become proselytes of Socialism, and seek to transplant it to Germany. German artizans, who, during their " Wanderschaft," 1 had worked in Paris or London, bring the Socialist teaching picked up there back to their homes, and carry it from one house of call to the next. Secret revolu- tionary propagandist societies are started, and finally, on the eve of the year of Revolution, 1848, the Communist League comes into existence with a programme that proclaims with unsurpas- sable revolutionary keenness and clearness the antagonism be- tween proletariat and bourgeoisie. But it also declares that the peculiar conditions in Germany made it necessary for the pro- letariat to fight, for the time being, alongside of the bourgeoisie against absolute monarchy, feudal squirearchy, and petty bour- geoisie. 2 The February Revolution in France, and the March Revolution in Germany, found the former, in its chief centres, absolutely honeycombed with Socialism, and found the latter permeated by a relatively large number of socialistic, and socialistically-inclined workers. In Germany, as in France, the workers already sup- plied, though possibly not in the same proportion, the most active 1 The mediaeval custom of journeymen travelling from place to place, and even country to country, was, and to some extent still is, kept up in Germany. The " He.rbe.rgen" or houses of call, are the inns and hostelries where, on their journeys, they put up. 2 "In Germany, they, [the Communists] fight with the bourgeoisie whenever it acts in a revolutionary way against the absolute monarchy, the feudal squirearchy, and the petty bourgeoisie." [" Manifesto of tlie Communist Party," by Karl Marx and Frederick Engels. Translated from the,Germanby S. Moore (published in 1847), and published by W. Reeves.] Ferdinand Lassalle. elements of the Revolution. But the conditions in France, de- spite her political and economic superiority, were not much more propitious for the realising of Socialism than were those of Germany. In the country small peasant proprietorship pre- dominated, while in the town and industrial centres, although the Grand Industry had made great strides, it had not conquered a complete monopoly. By the side of it there existed — and this chiefly in Paris, the main centre of the trade in articles de luxe — handicraft on a smaller and larger scale, which, if it had lost its old guild-like character, and was worked mostly for large em- ployers, still played a relatively important part, more especially in the so-called " artistic " handicrafts. Consequently, French Socialism, even where it had freed itself from mere Utopianism, was only of the petty bourgeois type. Nor did even the February Revolution, and the terrible lesson of the June massacre make any difference. They gave the death-blow to Utopian Socialism among the French workers, but in its stead there appeared for many a year — Proudhouism. In this relative unripeness of the economic conditions lies the explanation of the otherwise incomprehensible fact, that while the France of this period swarmed with Socialists, while over two hundred members of the Chamber of Deputies called themselves " Social Democrats," the Bonapartist tyranny was able to put the workers off with empty phrases. In Germany the unripeness was, of course, even greater. The great mass of the workers was not merely imbued with the petty bourgeois spirit, but to some extent actually with that of the mediaeval guilds. At the various working-men's congresses which 1848 called into existence, the most reactionary propositions were discussed. Only a comparatively small minority of the German workers had grasped the revolutionary mission of the working-class. If they everywhere fought in the front rank of the advanced parties ; if, wherever they could, they tried to urge on the middle-class democracy, they paid the cost of all this in their own person. The Communists of 1848 fell on the barricades, on the battle-field of Baden ; they filled the prisons, The Political Position in Germany. 5 or they were obliged, when the reaction triumphed all along tie line, to go into exile, where a large number of them died in misery. The young working-men's organisations, which the spring of 1848 had called into existence, were indiscriminately dissolved by the Government, or worried literally to death. Such Socialists as still remained in the country either entirely withdrew from public life, in the hope of belter times, or became Philistine, and joined whatever seemed to them the most likely faction of bourgeois liberalism. This applies more especially to the spokesmen of the " semi-cultured," " semi-sans-culotte," "true" Socialism, who had made their appearance with such great eclat. But the workers themselves, more or less intimidated, gave up all thought of their organisation as a class with inde- pendent aims, and fell under the tutelage of the radical bourgeois parties, or the protection of well-rneaning bourgeois philanthro- pists. A development came about which, in all essentials, agreed with that which had preceded it in England and France under similar conditions. The failure of the renewed agitation of the Chartists, in the year 1848, had the effect in England of forcing to the front the Christian Socialism of the Maurices, Kingsleys, Ludlows, and induced a portion of the workers to seek their emancipation in self-help co-operative associations — not only their economic but their " moral " emancipation from " egotism," "class-hatred," etc. And if these Christian Socialists did not combine with their efforts selfish, personal aims, and if they did not help to grind the axes of any one of the parties of the posses- sing classes, the result of their propaganda among the workers — so far as its influence went — was none the less to divert them from the general interest of their class, i.e., was one of political emasculation. So far as they succeeded in getting rid of " class- egotism," this was, in most cases, replaced by a disgusting egotism of co-operation, and a not less disgusting cant of "culture." The Trades Union movement, on its side, was almost wholly absorbed in the pursuit of only its most immediate interests, while most of the Owenites threw in their lot with the so-called Free-thought movement. Ferdinand Lassalk. In France it was the defeat of the June Insurrection that- forced the working-class into the background of the revolutionary arena. At first, however, only into the background. Not even that colossal blood-letting had been able to kill the strong politi- cal spirit of the Parisian proletariat, which, as Marx says in the "Achtzehnter Brumaire," always tries to press forward again whenever the movement appears to make a fresh start. Nevertheless, its strength was broken ; it could no longer obtain even a momentary triumph. " As soon as one of the upper strata of Society is stirred by a revolutionary ferment, the proletariat enters into a union with it, and so shares all the defeats which the different parties experience one after another. But these retro- active blows grow weaker and weaker, the more they are spread over^the whole surface of Society. Its more notable leaders in public assemblies'and in the press, one after the other, fall victims to the Law, and figures more and more equivocal appear at its head. In fact, it throws itself into doctrinaire experiments, ex- change banks and workers' associations, into a movement, there- fore, in which it "gives up revolutionising the old world with its great collective means, but rather seeks, behind the back of Society, by individual effort, within its own narrow conditions of existence, to bring about its redemption, and, therefore, of necessity fails." (18 Brumaire, 3rd ed., pp. 14 and 15.) Finally, in Germany also, where there can be no question of an actual defeat of the workers, since they had not yet even sought to take any considerable action as a class, all attempts worth speaking of, on the part of the workers at independent action, remained for a long time in abeyance. While middle-class philanthropy was busying itself in clubs " for the benefit of the working-classes," with questions of the housing of the working- classes, sick funds, and other harmless matters, a democrat of the petty bourgeois class, the Prussian Member of Parliament, Schulze of Delitzsch, started solving the social question by founding self- help co-operative societies, in which praiseworthy undertaking the economic backwardness of Germany stood him in especially good stead. The Political Position in Germany. 7 From the very outset, Herr Sehulze-Delitzsch hnd intended his co-operative societies not' only for the workers, but also for the small handicraft masters ; these were, by means of credit and raw material clubs, to be enabled to compete with modern industry. And as modern industry was but little developed in Germany, and as, on the other hand, there were large numbers of small masters, who had not yet, like the small masters in France and in England, adapted themselves to the conditions of modern industry, but were rather on the look-out for some sort of protection against it, his idea was bound, so far as they were concerned, to fall on fruitful soil, since these co-operative associations, in so far as modern industry had not appropriated their particular branches of production, really were of some use to them. So the credit and raw material associations blossomed forth gaily, and together with them distributive associations also, while in the background — as crown of the whole — loomed the productive co-operative associations that were to be the realisation of the freeing of labour from capital. Just as little as the English Christian Socialists, did Herr Sehulze- Delitzsch wish to further the interests of any political party by his self-help co-operative propaganda ; like them he was simply practising a philanthropy in harmony with his class instincts. At the time when he started this movement, the party to which he belonged — the left of the Prussian National Assembly— had with- drawn from active political life. After this party had let the Government and its beloved squirearchy lead it by the nose after the most approved fashion, it had, when the Prussian Government insisted upon introducing the " three-class " x electoral system, 1 The " three-class " electoral system is roughly this : the whole of the tuxes in any given parish, ward, or district, forming a unit. of any electoral constituency, are lumped together, and the sum thus obtained is divided into three parts. Those persons paying the highest taxes, i.e., one-third of the whole amount, form the " first class'' voters ; those paying the second- third, the " second class," and the rest of the tax-payers form the " third class." Each class elects two "electors" (" Wahlmiinner"), and all the " electors " of a constituency elect two members to the diet. The whole of the voting is open. Thus all the voting can be watched by the authorities, employers, etc Moreover, the votes are restricted to tax-payers, and the Ferdinand Lassalle. done the wisest thing it could do : it had clenched its fists in its pockets, and left the reaction to settle their own hash. Petty bourgeois from the crown of his head to the sole of his foot — but petty bourgeois with liberal views, and well-meaning in his way, Schulze-Delitzsch, after he had been prosecuted by the reaction, took up an idea which was then in the air. "Associa- tion " had been the cry of the Socialists in the thirties and forties ; " association " now cried the bourgeois philanthropists, ; " associa- tion " dogmatised the Conservative writer, B. A. Huber. Why should not the Liberal district Judge Schulze also plead for " association " 1 As we shall have to consider the association question later on, we here only quote a few passages from a work of Schulze-Delitzsch, published in 1858, in which he tells us the effect he expects his co-operative associations to have upon the condition of the workers. '• And as regards those workers who are still wage workers, the competition of the co-operative associations with the employers has, for them also, the most beneficial results. For must not the increased demand, on the part of the employer, tend to raise the wages of the workers 1 Are not the proprietors of large works thus obliged to offer their employees the very best conditions of labour, because they otherwise risk their men going over to already existing co-operative associations, or indeed, of themselves starting one, a proceeding to which, of course, the ablest and most eneigetic workers would most incline 1 Assuredly, only by these means — by the workers themselves competing with the employers — can wages be permanently raised, and the conditions of labour generally improved, wealthy classes can always outvote the mass of the people. It has happened, for example, that a single individual has represented the whole first class electorate, and has alone nominated two " electors." There are rarely more than a score of "first class " voters ; the " second class " number three or four times as many, the " third class " seventeen or eighteen times as many as the " first class." No wonder Prince Bismarck at one time denounced this system as " the most wretched of all electoral systems." It is true this was at a time when the Prussian middle-class opposed him. He after- wards opposed every effort to do away with, or even to amend, the system; The Political Position in Germany. aud never, as we have seen, can this be permanently accomplished by compulsory laws or by appeals to humanity " " When once a number of such co-operative establishments have been started by working-men, and the existing monopoly of the large employers has thus been broken down, it is inevitable that the enormous profits formerly reaped by them alone will diminish, because they will be obliged to let the workers have their share of them. Thus, while wealth ou the one hand will assume rather more modest dimensions, poverty will, on the other, disappear more and more, and conditions will begin to tend towards a universal level of well-being. With this also a bound is set both to plutocracy and to pauperism, those unholy outgrowths of our industrial system, in which we see two powers equally hostile to true culture. . . . '' " Only, we must constantly insist upon this : that until the workers of their own strength and impulse venture to start such undertakings, and to practically demonstrate that they can carry them on alone without the participation of the other classes, these in turn will probably take good care not to come to their assist- ance, since it is far too much to their interest to maintain the workers in their former state of dependency. Only when this proof has been given, and so giveu that their competition has made itself felt, only when they have at last met the employers as employers themselves, will their wishes be considered, and will the public support them, more especially the capitalists, who will only then begin to regard them as people who have also to be reckoned with, and who, until then, will regard them as mere ciphers, that, standing alone, couut for nothing in the calculation. In the domain of commerce, self-interest, after all, rules supreme, and aims and aspirations, however just and fair in themselves, only then command attention when they have become so power- ful that they can force themselves to the front in some irresistibly effective and vigorous form." 1 1 See Schulze-Delitzsch : " Die Arbeitenden Klassen und das Assoziations Recht in Deutschland " ("The Working-Classes and Co-operation in Ger- many"). Leipzig, 1858 ; pp. 58, 61, and 63. 10 Ferdinand Lassalle. Meanwhile, at the Congress of Political Economists in the summer of 1862, Herr Schulze had to admit that so far there were scarcely any productive co-operative societies, and that there were only a very small number of distributive ones. Only the credit and loan societies, composed of manufacturers, small masters, and small business men, flourished, and with these, al- though in smaller numbers, the raw material co-operative societies. We have here somewhat anticipated the course of events from 1848 to the beginning of the Lassalle agitation, and now we pick up again the dropped threads. The Crimean War had already dealt the European reaction a severe blow by seriously shaking that "solidarity of the Powers" which was one of its conditions of existence. The rivalry between Prussia and Austria again became manifest in the different attitudes of their Berlin and Vienna cabinets towards Russia, while the death of Nicolas I., and the position in which the Empire of the Tzar was at the end of the war, deprived the reactionary parties in Europe of their strongest bulwark. The hands of Russia were for the time being so full with its own internal affairs that for years to come it was not in the position to take up the cause of law and order " on principle " in any other country, and for the time being was no longer a factor in the internal policy of the neighbour states. The rivalry between Prussia and Austria was, however, still confined to petty cabinet intrigues, while, so far as their people were concerned, both govern- ments still maintained their "solidarity." A second blow was dealt the reaction by the general stagnation of trade that began in 1857 or 1858. Just as the general pros- perity of 1850 bolstered up the tottering thrones, so the industrial crisis of 1857 — greater in extent and intensity than any of its forerunners — again set the thrones tottering. All circles of society suffering through the crisis were in a state of ferment ; every- where the Opposition found fresh strength in this discontent of the masses ; everywhere the " subversive elements " again reared their head, and most menacingly in France, where, it is true, the throne was least stable. Once more Napoleon III. had recourse to The Political Position in Germany. 1 1 draconic prosecutions, the pretext for them be : ng afforded by the Orsini attempt. But when he found that he was thereby rather weakening than strengthening his position, he had recourse to other methods, and by means of a popular foreign war sought to again consolidate his regime at home, and to protect his life against the daggers of the Carbonari. These had, through Orsini, given their quondam fellow-conspirator to understand that if he did not keep his word to them, avengers would again and again arise against him. It was thus the Italian war was inaugurated. Almost at the same time the "new era" began iu Prussia with the regency of William I. 1 Dominated by the desire — still kept secret however — of breaking the supremacy of Austria in Germany, William I., then Prince Regent, sought to win over the liberal middle-class, and appointed a ministry agreeable to them. At first, all went well. Touched at once again having the chance of making themselves heard, and that altogether without effort on its part, middle-class Liberalism surpassed itself in all sorts of protestations of loyalty. The National Union was founded with the programme : Unification of Germany, with Prussia at her head. To Prussia was assigned the honour- able part of realising the political and national aspirations of the liberal bourgeoisie. A new spring-time for the people seemed at hand, and a far more beautiful one than that of 1848, for it promised the rose without the thorns. In a revolutionary rising one can never be sure where things are going to stop, or what elements may be let loose in its course. But now there was no need to stir up the unknown masses ; everything promised to come off after the most approved Parliamentary fashion. But if, against all pro- bability, the worst should come to the worst — why, had not the example of the Schulze-Delitzsch provident and distributive societies, his loan and raw material co-operative associations cured the workers of their socialistic Utopias, and given them proof i 1 In the autumn of 1858, the illness of King Frederick William IV. of Prussia— softening of the brain — which had set in in 1857, or even earlier, became so advanced, that he was unable even to sign a decree. As he had no children, his brother William was proclaimed Regent. 1 2 Ferdinand Lassalle. positive of the great tilings they might expect from self-help, con- vinced them that they wanted nothing, absolutely nothing more than the " liberties " of the Liberals 1 Whoever now — thirty years after — re-reads the literature of German Liberalism of those days, is chiefly struck by the colossal naivete predominating in it with regard to all questions that extend beyond the narrow horizon of the enlightened tallow-chandler. They were all very cultured, and very well-read, and they knew all about the ancient Athenian Constitution and English Parliamentary Government. But the practical application drawn from all this was invariably that the enlightened German tallow-chandler or iron- monger was the normal man, and that what was not to his tastes deserved to perish. It was this self-satisfied naivetd that forced on the constitutional conflict iu the Prussian Parliament, even before they were firm in their saddles ; with this naivete' they managed to estrange the working-classes, long before any serious class- differences gave occasion for the estrangement. They knew a terrible lot of history, but they had " learnt " really nothing at all from it. Then began the constitutional conflict in Prussia. The Govern- ment in 1 860 proposed a reorganisation of the military system, in accord with its "German policy." The wiseacres of the Landtag, however, instead of either voting or refusing to vote the required supplies, resorted to the expedient of voting them " provisionally " for one year. The Government began the work of reorganisation, and still went on with it, even when a majority of the Landtag, displeased with certain acts and declarations of the king's of rather too arbitrary a nature, subsequently refused to vote fresh supplies. Liberalism suddenly found itself, not knowing how, involved in a violent dispute with that same Government which it had cast for the fine part of re-establishing the German Empire, and to which it had promised supremacy in Germany. However, this was provisional only — unlucky, but not a misfortune. The Liberal party had, in the meantime, become so strong, it could afford to hold out for a good while. Thanks to the narrow-minded T/ie Political Position in Germany. 13 obstinacy of its opponent, it had well-nigh the whole of the people at its back. All classes of the population were carried away by this national movement; all, with the exception of the little family party of the squirearchy and clericals east of the Elbe, left it to the then recently constituted Progressist party to fight it out with the Prussian Government. Whatever mistakes this party may have made, however heterogeneous its composition, however inadequate its programme, it represented at that moment — as against the coalition of landlordism and police absolutism once again raising its head — a cause whose triumph would be to the interests of all who did not belong to the feudal elements of society. But to entrust a party temporarily with a political mission is not to give oneself over to it body and soul, not to abjure all inde- pendence with regard to it. And this the more advanced German workers felt. The part of supers which the Liberal leaders ex- pected them to fill ; the fare set before them at the educational and other clubs patronised by these leaders, could not satisfy them in the long run. The old Communist and revolutionary traditions had not yet completely died out. There was, indeed, still many a working-man who had either himself been a member of one of the Communist Sections, or had been enlightened by other members as to its principles, and had been supplied by them with Communist literature. Among these men, and prompted by them in ever-widening circles of working-men, the question began to be discussed, whether the time had not come for constituting a working-men's society, with its own working-men's programme, or, at least, to create a workers' league, which should be something more than the mere creature of the Liberal party. If the gentlemen of the Progressist party and the National Unionists had only learnt something from the history of other countries, it would have been an easy matter for them to prevent this movement from becoming one hostile to themselves, so long as they were still fighting the Prussian Government. But they were much — too much— imbued with the conviction that as they re- presented the people's cause, "the people," especially as "the 14 Ferdinand Lassalle. people of thinkers," were superior to the narrowness — that is to say the class-struggle — of foreign countries ; and thus they failed to see that here also they had to reason with a movement which was bound to set in sooner or later, and that all they had to do was to seek some reasonable way of arriving at a common under- standing. But so enamoured were they of themselves, that they were utterly incapable of grasping the idea that the workers could actually want anything further than the honour of being repre- sented by them. The workers asked that the conditions of mem- bership of the National Union should be made easier, and the reply: "All workers might consider honorary membership of the Union as their birthright," i.e., might have the honour to remain outside it — was thoroughly characteristic of the inability of the Schultzes and the rest to understand anything, except the philo- sophic " shopkeeper," — their own image, their God. Thus came about those discussions in the working-men's meet- ings at Leipzig, which finally resulted in the sending of three delegates to Berlin, and the opening up of negotiations with Ferdinand Lassalle. CHAPTER II. lassalle's youth and early manhood. — the hatzfeld lawsuit, 1848. — franz von sickingen. When the Leipzig Committee applied to him, Lassalle was in his thirty-seventh year, in the full force of his physical and mental development. He had already lived a strenuous life; he had made himself a name politically and scientifically — both, it is true, within certain limited circles ; he was in relations with the most prominent representatives of literature and art; he had ample means and influential friends. In a word, according to ordinary notions, the Committee, composed of hitherto quite unknown men, representing a still embryonic movement, could offer him nothing he did not already possess. Nevertheless, he entered into their wishes with the utmost readiness, and took the initial steps for giving the movement that direction which best accorded with his own views and aims. Quite apart from all other considerations, he must have been particularly attracted by the movement, from the fact that it had as. yet taken no definite form, that it offered itself to him as a mass which, without any great difficulty, he could himself mould into shape. First, to give it form, to mould it into an army after his own mind, this not only fell in with his high-soaring plans ; it was a task that must have strongly ap- pealed to his natural inclinations. The invitation appealed not merely to his Socialist convictions, but to his weaknesses. And so he accepted it with the greatest readiness. The present work does not pretend to be an actual " Life " of Ferdinand Lassalle, or to add one more to the very large number of biographies of the founder of the General German Working Men's Association, which, in the space at my disposal, could only be a repetition of oft-told facts. What this work aims at, above '5 1 6 Ferdinand Lassalle. all, is to portray the personality and the historical significance of Ferdinand Lassalle, so far as his political, literary, and propagand- ist work is concerned. Nevertheless, a glance at Lassalle's career is indispensable, since it gives the key to the understanding of his political line of action. Even his descent appears to have exercised a great, one may even say a fatal influence, upon the development of Lassalle. I am not here speaking of any inherited qualities or inclinations, but simply of the fact that the consciousness that he was of Jewish origin was, according to his own confession, painful to Lassalle even in his more advanced years ; and, despite all his efforts, or perhaps because of these efforts, he never really succeeded in be- coming indifferent to his descent, in getting rid of a certain self- conscious awkwardness. But it must not be forgotten that Lassalle was cradled in the eastern part of the Prussian kingdom — he was born at Breslau on the 11th of April, 1825 — where, until the year 1843, the Jews were not formally emancipated. Lassalle's father was a wholesale silk merchant, and is described by those who knew him as a very honest, genial, and intelligent man. His mother, on the other hand, appears to have been a somewhat capricious woman, with that love for dress and jewellery so often found in Jewish middle-class women. The wealth of his parents saved Lassalle from mtmy of the miseries under which the poorer Jew's had at this time to suffer, but it did not protect him from all sorts of petty mortifications, to which all belonging to an oppressed race, even those in good circumstances, are exposed. And these, in so self-conscious a nature as Lassalle's was from his youth, induce first a defiant fanaticism of revolt, which later not infrequently veers round to its very opposite. How great the fanaticism of the young Lassalle was we see from his " Diary " of the years 1840 and 1841, recently published by Herr Paul Lindau. On the 1st February, 1840, Ferdinand Lassalle, not yet fifteen years old, writes in his diary : ..." I told him this, and, in fact, I think I am one of the best Jews in existence, although I disre- gard the Ceremonial Law. I could, like that Jew in Bulwer's 'Leila,' risk my life to deliver the Jews from their present crush- Youth and Early Manhood. iy ing condition. I would not even shrink from the scaffold could I but once more make of them a respected people. Oh ! when I yield to my childish dreams, it is ever ray favourite fancy to make the Jews armed — I at their head — free." The persecution of the Jews at Damascus, in the May of 1840, drew from him the cry : " A people that bears this is hideous ; let them suffer or avenge this treatment." And to the statement of a reporter : "The Jews of this town endure barbarities such as only these pariahs of the earth would suffer without a horrible reaction," he added the characteristic remark : " Lo, even the Christians marvel at our sluggish blood, that we do not rise, that we do not rather perish on the battlefield than by torture. Was the oppression against which the Swiss one day rebelled greater 1 . . . Cowardly people, thou dost merit no better lot." He expresses himself even more passionately a few months later (30th July) : "Again the ridicu- lous story that Jews make use of Christian blood. The same story at Rhodes and Lemberg as in Damascus. But that this accusation goes forth from all corners of the earth seems to say to me that the time will soon be at hand when we, in very deed, will help ourselves with Christian blood. Aide toi et le del t'aidera. The dice are ready, it only depends upon the player." These childish ideas disappear more and more as his views broaden, but the effect of such youthful impressions upon the mind remains. The immediate result was, that the sting of the " tortures " of which he writes, doubly incited the precocious Lassalle to secure recognition and respect for himself at all costs. On the other hand, the rebel against the oppression of the Jews is soon turned into a political revolutionist by the Christians. And yet, after seeing Schiller's " Fiesco," he remarks — showing extraordinarily acute self-criticism : " I know not, although I now have revolutionary-democratic-republican inclinations with the best of them ; yet I feel that in Count Lavagna's place I would have acted just as he did, and would not have contented myself with being Genoa's first citizen, but would rather have stretched forth my hand to the crown. From this it seems, when I look at the matter in the light of day, that I am simply an egotist. Had B Ferdinand Lassalle. I been born prince or ruler I should have been an aristocrat, body and soul. But now, as I am only a poor burgher's son, I shall be a democrat in good time." It was his political radicalism also, which, in 1841, induced the sixteen-year-old Lassalle to give up the idea, entertained for a time, of devoting himself to a commercial career, and to get permission from his father to prepare for the university curriculum. The generally accepted opinion 1 that Lassalle had been sent to the Commercial School at Leipzig by his father, against his own will, has been shown by the diary to be entirely wrong. Lassalle himself managed his transfer from the Gymnasium to the Com- mercial School, not, it is true, from any passing predilection for a business life, but to escape the consequences of a number of thoughtless escapades, which he had committed in order not to be obliged to show his father the bad reports which he — in his opinion, undeservedly — was always receiving. But when he got on no better at the Leipzig Commercial School than at the Breslau Gymnasium, when he there too came into conflict with most of the masters, and especially with the head-master, conflicts that grew more and more bitter as his opinions became more radical, Lassalle there and then gave up the idea of a com- mercial career. In the May of 1840, Lassalle entered the Commercial School, and already, on the 3rd of August, he " hopes" that "chance" will one day rescue him from the counting- house, and throw him upon a stage where he can labour for the public. " I trust to chance, and to my own strong will to devote myself more to the muses than to ledgers and journals ; to Hellas 1 A view adopted also by MK Dawson in his "German Socialism and Ferdinand Lassalle." It must, however, be remembered that this book was written long before the " Diary " had been published. Another story of Lassalle's youth, that has been repeated by nearly all his biographers, to the effect that once when a difficulty arose in the family, Lassalle took matters in hand, and over the heads of father and mother settled the affair, also finds no confirmation in the " Diary." On the contrary, Lassalle al- ways shows himself most respectful, even submissive, to his father. In the matter of school certificates, he imitates his mother's signature Without a scruple, but is afraid to do the same with regard to his father's. Youth and Early Manhood. 1 9 and the East than to indigo and beet-root ; to Thalia and her priests than to shop-keepers and their clerks ; to care more for Freedom than for the price of goods, to execrate more deeply those dogs of aristocrats, who rob man of his first and highest possession, than the rival competitors who briDg down prices." And he adds : " But I shall not content myself with execrations." And with this Radicalism there grew in him an ever stronger longing to shake off the Jew in him, a longing which at last be- comes so overwhelming that when Lassalle informed his father in May, 1841, of his "irrevocable" determination to go to the university after all, he at the same time refused to study medicine or law, for " the doctor and the lawyer are both tradesmen who traffic with their knowledge." He would study " for the sake of what can be done with knowledge." The father, it is true, did not acquiesce in this last idea, but nevertheless consented to Las- salle's preparing for a university career. Lassalle now worked with such desperate energy, that, in 18+2, he was already able to pass his matriculation examination. He be- gan by studying philology, then turned to philosophy, and sketched the outline of a great philologico-philosophical work, on the Philo- sopher Heraclitus of Ephesus. That he should have chosen this thinker of all others as the subject for his researches — a thinker whom the greatest Greek philosophers themselves admitted they could never feel sure of understanding rightly, and who was therefore called the " Dark " — is strikingly characteristic of Lassalle. And what attracted Lassalle even more than the teach- ing of Heraclitus, whom Hegel himself had acknowledged as his forerunner, was the conviction that here only by brilliant achieve- ment could laurels be won. And with this longing to dazzle all men by some extraordinary achievement, already referred to, Lassalle was convinced that he was equal to any task he might set himself. This boundless self-confidence was the bane of his life. It helped him, indeed, to undertake, and to carry through, things from which thousands, even though endowed with Lassalle's intellectual gifts, would have shrunk; but, on the other hand, it was the cause of many fatal mistakes, and finally of his unhappy end. 20 Ferdinand Lassalle. After completing his course of studies, Lassalle went, inl844, to the Rhine, and later to Paris, partly in order to work at the libraries there, partly in order to see the world-city, the centre of the intellectual life of the time. The tide of the socialist move- ment was running very high in Paris at this moment, and it is probable that here Lassalle found his socialist Damascus. Whether, or to what extent, Lassalle became acquainted with the German socialists living in Paris — Karl Marx, after the " Deutsch-franzosischen Jahrbucher " had gone under, and the " Vorwarts " was suspended, had been expelled from Paris, and had migrated to Brussels, in January, 1845 — on this point we have no reliable information. But on the other hand it is known that he associated much with Heinrich Heine, to whom he had an introduction, and to whom he rendered the greatest services in an unpleasant money transaction, (a disputed inheritance). The letters in which the sick poet expressed his gratitude and admira- tion for the twenty- year-old Lassalle are well-known, and as they are quoted in Mr. Dawson's work, x may here be omitted. Having returned to Germany, Lassalle, in 1846, made the ac- quaintance of the Countess Hatzfeld. For years the Countess had been trying to obtain a judicial separation, and the restitution of her fortune, from her husband, Count Hatzfeld, who had sub- jected her to the grossest ill-usage and insults. The whole case affords a curious illustration of the habits of the German aristocracy before the Revolution of 1848. Though not a lawyer, Lassalle took it upon himself to conduct the Countess' case. It was an extraordinary undertaking, requiring all the skill, astuteness, and acumen of an experienced lawyer. But if Lassalle could not bring to the work the advantage of experience, he brought, besides his rare intellectual gifts, the zeal, the devotion, the audacity, and the pertinacity of youth, and with these succeeded where probably the most eminent lawyer would have failed. The warfare between Lassalle and Count Hatzfeld lasted for years. Its most famous incident was the oft-told story of the " casket-robbery." One fine day Count Hatzfeld attempted, in the form of a loan, 1 Pages 115-117. Youth and Early Manhood. 21 to make over the whole of the fortune of his second son, Paul — whom he hated, because the boy had remained with his mother — to one of his mistresses, a certain Baroness von Meyendorff. The affair was discovered, and the Count, caught in the act of perpetrat- ing this fraud, promised to cancel the deed of gift. But he did this simply to gain time. A few days later he refused all further negotiations, and the Baroness von Meyendorff secretly left the place, taking with her a casket, supposed to contain the deed of gift. Lassalle immediately induced two of his friends — both rich, and one himself a judge — to follow the Baroness, and to ascertain, at all costs, whether she was in possession of the document, or whether the deed of gift had been cancelled. They ran her down at Cologne, and by unexpected luck for a while obtained possession of the casket, but failed to retain possession of it. They were subsequently arrested, and — such a lottery is justice ! while he who had seized the casket — the judge — was acquitted, the man to whom he handed it over — a physician — was condemned to five years' penal servitude. Lassalle, though a younger man than either of the others, was prosecuted for " inciting to the theft of a casket." Fortunately, he was tried by jury, in August, 1848, when the Revolution of March, in the same year, had somewhat altered the state of things in Germany. After a seven days' trial, at the end of which Lassalle spoke for six hours — (the " Casket Speech ") — the jury dismissed the charge. It is interesting to note that the young Count Paul Hatzfeld referred to is the present Ambassador from the German Empire to the Court of St. James's. There has been much speculation on the motives which induced Lassalle to take the Countess' case in hand. Some have explained them by a love affair with the no longer youthful, but still very beautiful, woman, whilst Lassalle himself, at the " Casket Trial," passionately protested that his sole motive had been one of pity for a persecuted woman, deserted by her friends, the victim of her social position, the object of the brutal per- secution of an insolent aristocrat. There is absolutely no reason for refusing to believe this statement of Lassalle's, Whether 22 Ferdinand Lassalle. Lassalle did not for a time enter into closer relationship than that of friendship with her in later years we cannot say. But even on purely psychological grounds, it is improbable that such a relation- ship should have existed at the beginning of their acquaintance, when Lassalle took up the lawsuit. It is far more probable that, in addition to his perhaps somewhat romantic and exaggerated, yet most worthy partisanship of a persecuted woman and hatred of the great aristocrat, Lassalle was attracted by the fact that here was an affair which only the use of extraordinary measures, and the display of extraordinary energy, could bring to a success- ful issue. What would have repelled others, unquestionably attracted him. He came out of the lawsuit victorious ; he had the triumphant satisfaction of seeing the insolent aristocrat forced to capitulate to him, the " stupid Jew boy." But he did not come out of the struggle scatheless. To win it he had certainly been obliged to resort to extraordinary measures. But it was not, or rathor it was not merely, a matter of extraordinary grasp of the legal issues, of extraordinary readiness and dexterity in parrying the enemy's thrusts. There were also the extraordinary measures of underground warfare ; the spying, the bribery, the burrowing in the nastiest scandal and filth. 1 Count Hatzfeld, a coarse sensualist, stuck at nothing to attain his ends, and in order to thwart his dirty manoeuvres, the other side resorted to means that were not much more clean. No one who has not read the documents of the case can have any conception of the filth raked up, and again and again dragged forward, of the nature of the accusations on both sides, and the witnesses. And the after effects of his inverted Augean labours in the Hatzfeld Trial Lassalle never quite shook off. I do not say this from the point of view of Philistine morality, or in reference to his later love affairs. I refer rather i Thus, a printed document of over seventy large quarto pages contains nothing but the enumeration of Count Hatzfeld's misconduct with women of all classes. It is impossible to imagine more disgusting reading than this, Youth and Early Manhood. 23 to his readiness, henceforth again and again manifested, to wel- come and to make use of any means that seemed likely to further the ends he had, for the time being, in view ; I refer to the loss of that feeling of tact which forbids a man of convictions, even in the thick of a violent struggle, to take any step opposed to the principles he represents ; I refer to that loss of good taste, that want of moral judgment, henceforth so often shown and most strongly marked during the tragic closing episode of his life. It was as a youthful enthusiast that Lassalle had plunged into the Hatzfeld Case. In his "Casket Speech," he himself uses the image of the swimmer : — " What man, being a strong swimmer, could see another swept away by the stream without goiug to his aid 1 Well, I considered myself a good swimmer, I was free, and so I plunged into the stream." True, no doubt, but the stream into which he plunged was a very muddy one, a stream that ended in a vast quagmire. And when Lassalle emerged from it he had been infected by the rottenness of the society with which he had had to deal. For a long time his originally finer instincts struggled against the effects of this poison, often successfully beating them back, but finally he after all succumbed. What I have said may to some seem too severe, but we shall see in the course of this study that it is only just to Lassalle. It is not for me to write an apology, but rather to give a critical representation, and for this the first requisite is to explain the effects by the causes. Before proceeding further, however, we must first consider the part played by Lassalle in 1848. On the outbreak of the Revolution of March, Lassalle was so deeply entangled in the meshes of the Hatzfeld Case that he had at the beginning almost condemned himself to political inaction. In the August of 1848 lie was tried for " inciting to the theft of a Casket," and his hands were full preparing for the trial. It was only after his acquittal that he again found leisure to take a direct part in the political events of this stirring time. Lassalle, who was then living at Diisseldorf— the birthplace of Heine, — as Republican ancl Socialist, of course was on the extreme. 24 Ferdinand Lassalle. left of the Democratic party, whose organ was the Neue Rheinische Zeitung (the New Ehenish Gazette), edited by Karl Marx. Karl Marx had, moreover, for a time been a member of the District Committee of the Rhenish Democrats, whose headquarters were Cologne. 1 A double opportunity was thus given Lassalle for bringing him into closer relations with Marx. He communicated by word of mouth and by letter with the District Committee mentioned above, he frequently sent communications and corre- spondence to the Neue Rheinische Zeitung, and occasionally even appeared at the editorial office of the paper. Thus, gradually, a friendly personal relation came about between Lassalle and Marx, and this later, when Marx was living in exile, was kept up by letters, and now and again by visits. Lassalle frequently came to London, while Marx, during a journey to Germany, in 1861, visited Lassalle in Berlin. Nevertheless, there never at any time existed any deeper friendship between the two ; for this their natures were far too diverse. Other matters that stood in the way of any intimacy beyond comradeship in the political fight will be discussed later on. Lassalle's attitude with regard to the inflowing tide of reaction in 1848 was identical with that of the editors of the Neue Rheinische Zeitung, and of the party at the back of them. When, in November, 1848, the Prussian Government disbanded the i Mr. Dawson is not quite accurate when he says that Marx, Engels, and Wolff " saw in the foment of that period an opportunity for further- ing their long-cherished Communistic designs." The authors of the " Communist Manifesto " and their friends recognised clearly that before they could do this they must further the political revolution in Germany. In accordance with the principles enunciated in the Manifesto, they sup- ported the most advanced and the most resolute wing of the Radical Middle-Class party. The Neue Rheinische Zeitung pointed out their duty to the German middle-classes, while, at the same time, it answered the treachery and cowardice of the so-called " moderates," and denounced the proceedings of the Reactionary Government. No Socialist or Communist "scheme " was ever propounded in the Neue Rheinische Zeitung, and the Socialist principles of the editors found expression only in articles like that of Marx on the June Revolution in Faris, or in the publication of Karl Marx' lecture on " Wage-labour and Capital." Youth and Early Manhood. 25 Berlin civic guard, proclaimed a state of siege in Berlin, and removed the seat of the National Assembly from Berlin to Brandenburg, a small provincial town, and when in time the National Assembly impeached the Prussian Ministry for high treason (i.e., violation of the Constitution), and declared this ministry had forfeited the right of levying taxes, Lassalle, follow- ing the example of the Neue Rheinische Zeitung, called upon all citizens to organise and offer an armed resistance to the collection of taxes. Like the Committee of the Khenish Democrats, Lassalle was also indicted for inciting to armed resistance against the King's authority, and like them, too, he was acquitted by the jury. But the Beaction, growing more and more high-handed, brought a further charge against Lassalle of inciting to resistance against Government officials, with the object of getting him tried before the Correctional Police Court. And, in fact, this court — the Government undoubtedly knew its own judges — eventually did condemn Lassalle to six months' imprisonment. Lassalle's answer to the first of these charges has been published under the title "Assize Court Speech" (" Assisen-Rede"). But, as a matter of fact, it was never really spoken, and everything that has been said in the various biographies of the "profound" impres- sion it produced upon the jury and the public therefore belongs to the domain of fable. Even before the trial came on, Lassalle had sent the speech to the printer's, and as some complete proofs had also been circulated beforehand, the court decided to exclude the public. When, in spite of Lassalle's protest, and his declaration that the proofs had been circulated without his knowledge, and very probably at the instigation of, and through bribery by, his enemies, the court decided to maintain its decision, and thereupon Lassalle declined to defend himself, but was none the less acquitted. Whether spoken or not, the Assize Court Speech, in any case, is an interesting document for the study of Lassalle's political de- velopment. In it he takes almost the same standpoint as that taken three months earlier by Marx in his speech to the Cologne Jury. 1 A comparison of the two speeches demonstrates this as ' On the 9th February, 1849, Marx, together with Karl Schapper and 26 Ferdinand Lassalle. clearly as it demonstrates the difference of the natures of Marx and Lassalle. Marx refrains from all oratorical flourish ; he goes straight to the point, in simple and terse language ; sentence by sentence he develops incisively, and with ruthless logic, his own standpoint, and, without any peroration, ends with a summary of the political situation. Anyone would think that Marx' own person- ality was in no wise concerned, and that his only business was to deliver a political lecture to the jury. And, in fact, at the end of the trial, one of the jurors went to Marx to thank him, in the name of his colleagues, for the very instructive lecture he had given them ! Lassalle's peroration, on the other hand, lasts almost from beginning to end ; he exhausts himself in images — often very beautiful — and superlatives. It is all sentiment, and whether he refers to the cause he represented or to himself, he never speaks to the jury, but to the gallery, to an imaginary mass meeting, and after declaring a vengeance that should be " as the solicitor Schneider, was tried for "iuciting the people to armed resist- ance against the Government and its officials," by publishing, on November 18th, 1848, in the name of the Provincial Committee of the Rhenish Democrats, the following proclamation : — The Provincial Committee of Rhenish Democrats calls upon all democratic associations of the Rhenish Provinces to secure the acceptation and execution of the following measures : (1) The Prussian National Assembly having itself refused to vote the taxes, all attempts to collect such taxes by force are to be resisted in every way. (2) The " Landsturm " (armed men) are everywhere to be organised for resisting the enemy. Those without means are to be supplied with arms and amunition by the municipalities, or by voluntary contributions. (3) The authorities everywhere to be called upon to declare publicly whether they intend to acknowledge and carry out the wishes of the National Assembly. In the event of their refusing to do- this, committees of public safety to be formed, whenever possible, in conjunction with the municipalities. Any municipality opposing the Legislative Assembly to be replaced by a new one duly elected. After a masterly speech by Marx, and short addresses by Schapper and Schneider, the three were acquitted, although they had declared that by " the enemy " they meant the armed forces of the Government. (See " Karl Marx yor den Jtolner Geschwornen," Zurich, 1885.) Youth and Early Manhood. 27 tremendous " as " the insult offered the people," he ended with a recitation from Schiller's Tell. Even -when in prison, where, by his energy and pertinacity, Lassalle obtained privileges not usually granted prisoners — thus he frequently received permission, a proceeding he himself later on declared illegal, to plead in the Countess Hatzfeld's law suits — and for many years after this, Lassalle's energies were almost wholly absorbed by the Hatzfeld affair. Besides this, Lassalle kept open house for his political friends, and for a long time gathered around him a circle of advanced working-men, to whom he delivered political lectures. At last, in 1854, the Hatzfeld case came to an end. The Countess received a considerable fortune, and Lassalle was assured a yearly income of 7000 thalers (£1050), which allowed him to order his way of life after his owii heart. For the time being Lassalle continued to reside at Diisseldorf, and here worked on at his " Heraclitus." Moreover, he undertook all sorts of journeys, among others, one to the East. But in the long run, not even these could reconcile him to residing in a provincial town, where all political life had died out. He longed for a freer, more stimulating life than the Rhenish town could offer or permit him, for intercourse with notable personalities, and for a wider sphere of action. And so, in 1827, he managed to obtain, through the instrumentality of Alexander von Humboldt, permission from the King of Prussia to take up his abode in Berlin. His petition, as well as the permission granted, deserve notice. In May, 1849, Lassalle had branded in burning words the " shame- ful and insufferable Government by force that had burst forth in Prussia;" he had cried aloud : "Why with so much force is there so much hypocrisy? But that is Prussian," and "Let us forget nothing, never, never. . . Let us cherish these remembrances carefully, as the ashes of murdered parents, the sole heritage from whom is the oath of vengeance bonnd up with these ashes." (Assize- Court Speech). After taking up this attitude, it must assuredly have required a good deal of self-abnegation to address such a petition to the very Government which had been attacked in this way, and to appeal to that Government's good-will in order to obtain 28 Ferdinand Lassalle. it. Lassalle must have been desperately anxious to live in the Prussian capital, and one can hardly wonder if this step of his met with the disapproval of some of his political friends. Lassalle, who could be very rigorous towards others, and who, e.g., many years later urged Marx to give up all intercourse with Liebknecht, because the latter was at that time the correspondent of the Augsburger Allgemiine Zeitung, applied a different rule where he was himself concerned. He was thirsting for recognition, for fame, for action, and for these the capital itself was necessary. Nor is it impossible that Lassalle had been informed, through the relations of the Countess Hatzfeld, which were pretty far- reaching, that a new wind was about to blow in the higher circles of Prussia. How far-reaching these relations were, is shown by the information which Lassalle sent to Marx in London on the outbreak of the Crimean War in 1854. Thus, on the 10th February 1854, he forwards Marx the text of the declaration sent, a few days before, by the Berlin Cabinet to Paris and to London, and describes the situation in the Berlin Cabinet — the King and al- most the whole Cabinet for Bussia, only Manteuffel and the Crown Prince of Prussia for England — and the measures decided upon by it in the event of certain contingencies. Upon this he writes : " You can look upon all the news sent herewith as if you had it from ManteuffePs or Aberdeen's own lips ! " Four weeks later he again sent all kinds of information about the steps the Cabinet contemplated taking, based upon informa- tion received, " not, it is true, from my ' official ' source, but still from a fairly reliable one." On the 20th May, 1854, he deplores that his " diplomatic informant " had started on a long journey. " To have so excellent a source of information that kept one in- formed as if one had been in the Cabinet, and then to lose it again for so long a time is exceedingly annoying." But he still has other sources of information that keep him posted as to the internal movements of the Berlin Cabinet, and so, among other things he had received early information of Boniu's dismissal, etc. Some of these "informants" were very closely connected with the Berlin Court, and their reports may have iuduced Lassalle to Youth and Early Manhood. 29 take the step he did. The mental alienation of Frederick William IV. was at this time already very far advanced, and even though the faithful ministers and the guardians of the monarchical idea did not yet think it advanced enough to declare the King incapable of reigning, yet everyone in well-informed circles knew that the Kegency of the Prince of Prussia was now only a question of months. At Berlin, Lassalle now completed his " Heraclitus,'' which was published at the end of 1857, by Franz Duneker. Authorities differ as to the value of this work. Some regard it as epoch- making ; others declare that in all essentials it contains nothing Hegel had not already said. Certain it is, that here Lassalle al- most throughout his work accepts the old Hegelian standpoint. Things are developed from ideas, categories of thought are treated as eternal metaphysical entities, whose movement begets history. But even those who question the epoch-making charac- ter of Lassalle's work, admit that it is a very notable achievement. It gave Lassalle an honoured name in the scientific world. But as characteristic of Lassalle and his mental development, " The Philosophy of Heraclitus the Dark of Ephesus," is not simply noticeable because it shows us Lassalle as a determined dis- ciple of Hegel. Herein we agree with the well-known Danish lite- rary historian, G. Brandes, when in his study 1 of Lassalle — a work that often deals pretty freely with facts for the sake of literary effect — he says that various passages in the work on " Heraclitus " supply the key for the understanding of Lassalle's view of life. This, of course, applies especially to Lassalle's cult of the idea of the State — in this, too, Lassalle was an old Hegelian — and to his conception of honour and of fame. With regard to the former, Brandes says : "The ethic of Heraclitus," Lassalle says (Vol. II. p. 431), " is summed up in the one idea, which is also the eternal funda- mental concept of the moral itself : ' devotion to universal- ity.' " This is at once Greek and modern ; but Lassalle cannot i Ferdinand Lassalle, " Ein literarisches Charaterbild." Berlin, 1877. G. Brandesi 30 Ferdinand Lassalle. resist the temptation of demonstrating in his working-out of this idea by the old Greeks that they were in accord with Hegel's philosophy of the State (Vol. II. p. 439). "As in the Hegelian philosophy laws also are conceived as the realisation of the uni- versal actual Will, while this conception is not for a moment considered in relation to the formal Will of the individuals and their enumeration, so is the universality of Heraclitus equally removed from the category of empirical totality.'' Nor was Brandes wrong when he recognised a contradiction be- tween this conception of the State, that recurs again and again in Lassalle, and his confession of democratic faith and belief in uni- versal suffrage, which, after all, expresses the rule of " the formal will and of the individual," a contradiction " no one can harbour , in his mind without taint.'' In the domain of principle it is, he says, the counterpart to that contrast which " expressed itself out- wardly when Lassalle with his studiously elegant dress, and studiously fine linen, and his patent leather boots, addressed a circle of sooty-faced and horny-handed factory workers." 1 This is expressed in the terms of the litterateur. As a matter of fact, Lassalle's old Hegelian state-concept led him, in his sub- sequent struggle with the Manchester school, to overshoot the mark. As to Lassalle's conception of honour and fame, Brandes says : " Another point of similarity, the last between Heraclitus and Lassalle, is the passionate desire, despite all self-sufficiency and pride, for fame and honour, for the admiration and the praise of others." Heraclitus has enunciated the oft-quoted axiom (Vol. II. p. 434) : " The greater destinies achieve the greater fate." And he has said, throwing the true light upon this saying (Vol. II. p. 436) : " That the masses, and those who deem themselves wise, follow the singers of the people, and seek counsel from the laws, not knowing that the masses are bad, a few only good; but the best follow after fame. For," he adds, " the best ever seek one thing rather than everything, the everlasting fame of mortals." So fame was for Heraclitus identical with that greater lot, which 1 Brandes : p. 42. Youth and Early Manhood. 31 the greater destinies achieve ; his striving after honour was not merely the immediate striving that is in the blood, but one based upon reflection and philosophy. "Fame," says Lassalle, " is, in fact, the antithesis to everything, the antithesis to the categories of immediate, actual Being as a whole, and of its in- dividual aims. It is the Being of man in his non-being, a con- tinuance in the decay of sentient existence itself ; it is therefore the immortality of man attained and made real." And he adds with warmth : " Just as this is the reason why fame has always so mightily stirred the great souls and lifted them beyond all petty and narrow ends, it is the reason why Platen, singing of it, says it can only be attained ' hand in hand with the all-testing Angel of Death,' so also is it the reason why Heraclitus recognised in it the ethic realisation of his speculative principle " (p. 45). ^ Truly it was not in Lassalle's nature to content himself with the fame that is only to be attained hand in hand with the Angel of Death. In contrast with the Heraclitean contempt for the masses, he thirsted for their applause, and with the utmost self- complacency took any sign that seemed to promise him this, no matter how insignificant, for the applause itself. The pre- dilection for the sentimental, which was so very marked in Lassalle, usually implies cynicism and hypocrisy. Now if Lassalle cannot be altogether acquitted of having had a certain amount of the former, no one can accuse him of ever making any secret of that which Brandes calls "his unfortunate fondness for the noise and the drum-beatiug of Fame, and for the blare of its trumpets." In his writings, in his speeches, in his letters, it is displayed with a frankness, whose nafoete to some extent disarms one. When Helene von Rakowitza in her " Apology " says that Lassalle pictured to her at Berne how he should one day, as the people's chosen President of the Republic, make his entry into Berlin " drawn by six white steeds," one is tempted either to believe that the authoress is exaggerating, or to assume that Lassalle hoped by picturing so enticing a future to obtain a firmer hold upon the heart of his lady-love. However, the well-known " Soul's Confession," written to Sophie von SolutzeW, proves that this 32 Ferdinand Lassalh. picture of the future was by no means the sport of an idle hour, or a lover's fancy, but that it was an idea with which Lassalle in- toxicated himself, whose magic exercised a mighty charm upon him. He calls himself — in 1860 — " the head of a party," with regard to which " almost our whole Society " has divided into two parties : the one — a portion of the bourgeoisie and the people — " respect, love, aye, not infrequently, honour " Lassalle, for it he is " a man of the greatest genius, and of almost superhuman character, of whom they expect the greatest deeds." The other party — the whole of the aristocracy and the greater portion of the bourgeoisie — fear him "more than anyone else, and therefore hate him 'in- describably.' " If the women of this aristocratic society will not forgive Sophie von Solutzew for marrying such a man, on the other hand, many women will not forgive her because such a man has married her, " will envy her a good fortune that is beyond her deserts. And truly, I will not conceal from you, that, if certain events come about, it might well be that a flood of action, sonorous and splendid, would burst upon your life, should you become my wife." Exaggerated as all these utterances appear, little as they all corresponded to the actual facts, at a time when there was no thought of a Social Democratic party, and when indeed Lassalle was socially on the best of terms with the middle-class Liberals and Democrats, and had just published a pamphlet that was, in the main, at one with the aspirations of the Prussian Cabinet, they yet contain a great subjective truth : Lassalle himself believed in them. Lassalle believed in the party that acknowledged him as its head, even though that party for the time being consisted of himself alone, and though even in his own ideas it was yet- of the vaguest. The party was himself — his aims, and his plans. Every word of recognition from his friends, or from those he took for friends, was a confirmation of his mission, every clever piece of flattery, frank homage. Marvellous are the contradictions of which human nature is capable ! Lassalle, as we know from his intimate acquaintances, and as we can see from his letters, was extremely lavish of flattering adjectives ; but when he used them Youth and Early Makkood. 33 himself they were to him only worthless dross ; when applied to him by others he took them for pure goldi So interwoven was his party with himself in his own imagina- tion, that when later he really did stand at the head of a party, or, at any rate, at the head of a party that was in course of formationj he could only regard it from the point of view of his own person- ality, and treated it accordingly. Let me not be misunderstood. It is absurd to say that Lassalle created the General German Workingmen's Association only to serve his own ambition ; that Socialism was to him only a means, not an end. Lassalle was a convinced Socialist. Of this there can be no doubt. But he would have been incapable of sinking himself in the Socialist movement, of sacrificing his personality — note that we do not say his life — to it. So much on this matter for the present. The Greek philoso- pher was followed by a German knight. Shortly after the " Her* aclitus " had appeared, Lassalle completed a historical drama that he had already sketched out at Diisseldorf. This, after an arrangement of it for the stage anonymously sent in had been refused by the manager of the Koyal Theatre, he published under his own name in 1859. It was called "Franz von Sickingen, a Historical Tragedy.'' That the play was unsuited to the stage Lassalle himself subsequently admitted, and he attributed this chiefly to its dearth of poetical imagination. As a matter of fact, the drama, in spite of some most effective scenes, and pregnant language, gives on the whole an impression of dryness ; its tend- ency is too obtrusive, there is too much reflection in it, and above all, there are too many speeches. The metre also is extraordinarily awkward. Brandes says that a friend of Lassalle's, whom, whilst working at "Franz von Sickingen," he asked for advice, and who had been a skilled versifier, told Lassalle he had better write the play in prose, and I agree with Brandes that better advice could not have been given. For Lassalle's prose really has many excellent qualities, and even the strongly - marked tendency to drop into declamation would not have mattered in a drama like "Sickingen." But Lassalle was not to be dissuaded 34 Ferdinand Lassalle. from his idea that the metrical form was indispensable for the drama, and so not only his knights and heroes halt along on the most turgid of five-footed iambics, but even the insurgent peasants strut on the stilts of blank verse. The only exception is in the well-known riddle : " Loset, sagt an : Was ist das ftir em Wesen ? Wir kbnnen von Pfafien und Adel nicht gonesen." 1 And the effect is really refreshing. However, these technical questions are of less moment for us than the subject-matter and the tendency of the drama. In " Franz von Sickingen,'' Lassalle wanted to improve upon the historical drama as created by Schiller and Goethe ; to go a step further. The historical struggle was not, as is especially the case with Schiller, merely to supply the background for the tragic conflict, while the real dramatic action is concerned only with purely individual interests and destinies. The historical conditions of the times and of the people were to be the actual subject of the tragedy, so that this should not concern itself with individuals as such, individuals who are but the representatives and embodiment of the conflicting interests, but with the great- est and most potent destinies of nations — " destinies which determine the weal or woe of the general spirit of the time, and which are made by the dramatis personas with the con- suming passions begotten of historic aims, the one question of their life." " And with all that it is possible," Lassalle thinks, " to endow these characters, out of the clearness of thought atid aim which is theirs, with definite, firm, and even pronounced and realistic individuality." (See Preface to " Franz von Sickingen.") If, and to what extent Lassalle solved the problem he had set him- self, how far the problem is solvable at all, under what conditions the great struggles of humanity and of the peoples can be thus embodied in individuals in such a way that neither the one side 1 " Hear ! what species of existence this ? For priests and lords we cannot live," Youth and Early Manhood. 35 nor the other, neither the great and vast significance of those struggles, nor the living personality of the individuals should be unduly neglected, are questions which must here be left un- touched. Suffice it to say that Lassalle, in working out his drama, started with this theory. And now as to the drama itself. As its title indicates, its central idea is the struggle of Franz von Sickingen against the German princes. Sickingen, a Fran- conian nobleman, was one of those nobles who, at the time of the Reformation, stood out not only against the princes of the various German states, but also against the rule of the Church of Kome iu Germany. Sickingen towered above others of his class by his moral and intellectual qualities, his military capacity, his broad views, and his readiness to succour the oppressed. Together with his learned, and even more enthusiastic friend, Ulrich von Hutten, he attempted to bring about a revolutionary movement, with the object of restoring to the German Empire its past glory, but freed from the influence of Rome. But their efforts failed. The burghers in the towns and the peasants in the country had no confidence in the nobles, while most of the latter deserted then- leaders. Sickingen was defeated by the superior armies of the princes, and fell, mortally wounded, at Landsthul in 1523. Hutten was forced to fly to Switzerland, where he died, in poverty, at the little island of Utnau, on the Lake of Zurich. This truly remarkable man, Franz von Sickingen, and his friend and adviser, Ulrich von Hutten, are the heroes of the drama, and it is difficult to say which of the two, the military man and statesman, or the representative of the views of the small German nobility, is the more interesting. Oddly enough, Lassalle attempted to paint himself, not in the former, but in the latter. "Read my tragedy,' he writes to Sophie von Solutzew ; " everything I could say to you here, I have made Hutten say. He too had to bear all kinds of calumny, every form of hatred, every species of malevolence. I have made of him the mirror of my soul, and I was able to do this as his fate and my own are absolutely identical, and of astounding similarity." It would have been difficult even for Lassalle to prove this astounding similarity, especially at the time 36 Ferdinand Lassalle, when he wrote this letter. He was leading a luxurious life in Berlin ; he associated with members of all circles of the well-to-do classes, and as a politician was very far from being hated in the same way as was the Franconian knight, the inspirer of the passionate polemical pamphlets against the sway of the Eomish priests. Only in a few external points can we find any analogy between Lassalle and Hutten. In this case, however, the actual facts are of less importance than what Lassalle himself be- lieved, and what inspired his work. People of such enormous self-sufficiency arc, as a rule, easily deceived about themselves. Enough that we have before us, in the Hutten of the play, Lassalle as he was thinking at that time ; and the speeches he puts in the mouth of Hutten thus acquire a special value for the understanding of the Lassallean range of ideas. Here we may chiefly note Hutten's answer to the doubts of Oekolampadius as to the proposed rising : " Moat honcmred sir ! you know not history well. You are quite right, and reason is its theme." 1 A thoroughly Hegelian phrase, "And still its form remains for ever Force." And then when Oekolampadius has spoken of the "profanation of the teaching of Love by the sword " : " Most honoured sir ! think better of the sword ! A sword that's lifted high for Freedom is The Word made flesh, the Word of which you preach, The God, in very truth, new-born to us. By sword our Christianity was spread ; By sword was Deutsehland baptized by that Carl, Whom we to-day, still wondering, call the Great. And by the sword was heathendom overthrown, And by the sword the Saviour's grave was freed ! It was the sword drove Tarquin out of Rome ; i In translating the verse we have adhered as literally as possible to the original, and have tried to put it in metrical form. (Translator. J Youth and Early Manhood, 37 It was the sword whipped Xerxes home from Greece, And Science and the Arts were born to us. With sword smote David, Samson, Gideon. So now as ever has the sword achieved The noble things that History has seen; And all things great that ever will be done Will owe all their success unto the sword." No doubt there was a great deal of exaggeration in the lines : "And still" — i.e., History's — "form still remains for ever Force," " and all things great that ever will be done, will owe all their success unto the sword." Nevertheless, the statement that the sword that's lifted high for Freedom is the " Word made flesh," that whosoever would attain Freedom, must be prepared to fight for it with the sword, was fully justified at a time when large numbers in the circles of the ci-devant democracy were becoming more and more inclined to expect everything from the power of the Word. Very timely, too, and not only for that particular period are the words Lassalle makes Balthasar Schldr speak to Sickingen in the last act : " Oh, not the first are you, nor yet will be The last of those men doomed to lose their heads By cunningness in great affairs. Disguise Upon the mart of history counts nought. Where in the whirl the people recognise Thee only by thy armour and thy badge ; So always clothe thyself from top to toe With boldness ; wear the hue of thine own flag. So canst thou prove in the colossal strife The motive power of thy foundation sure, And thou dost stand and fall with thy whole will." And Sickingen's words : " Show not the end and aim, but show the way, For here so intermingle way and end That one still changes with the other's change, And. other ways lead still to other cncU,'' 38 Ferdinand Lassalk. are a phrase from Lassalle's own political confession of faith. Unfortunately, however, he disregarded it exactly at the most critical period of his political career. But we will not dwell upon isolated passages; rather let us consider the drama as a whole, get at the quintessence of it. The part actually played in history by Hutten and Sickingen was an entirely different one from what they thought or meant it to be. Both were representatives of the feudal knights, a class, at the time of the Reformation, in its period of decadence. What they wished to do was to stop this process of decay, an idle effort, inevitably doomed to failure, and that only expedited what it meant to stave off. As Hutten and Sickingen by character and by intellect towered high above their class, we here certainly have the making of a true tragedy — the hopeless struggle of strong personalities fighting against historical necessity. This aspect of the Hutten-Sickingen movement is, oddly enough, ignored in Lassalle's drama, despite its great significance to — I will not say Socialists alone — but even to the modern, scientific conception of history. In the play the efforts of Hutten-Sickingen fail, because of a mass of fortuitous circumstances — want of forethought, error of judgment, treachery, etc. And Hutten-Lsssalle concludes with the words : " To future ages I bequeath an avenging." This in- voluntarily reminds one of the thoroughly unhistorieal conclusion of Gotz von Berlichingen : a " Woe to the century that rejected thee ! Woe to the future generations that deny thee ! " But if we can understand why the youthful Goethe, in the eighteenth century, could choose for his hero a representative of this decadent knighthood, it is more difficult to understaud how, almost a century later, and at a time when historical research had opened up quite different views for understanding the struggles of the Beformation- period, a Socialist like Lassalle could choose two representatives of that very knighthood as the standard-bearers " of a historico- social process," upon the result of which, as Lassalle says in his pre- i A youthful drama of Goethe. Gotz von Berlichingen was a Snabian knight, and he too rebelled against the German Princes. But he representa a type infinitely inferior to that of ifutten and Sickingen, Youth and Early Manhood. 39 * face, " our whole actual society depends." " I wished, if possible," he adds in the same preface, " to make this process of historical development once again pulsate consciously and with quivering passion through the veins of the people. The power to attain such an end is only given to poetry, and so I determined to write this drama." Now, it is true that besides representing the cause of Knight- hood, Hutten and Sickinggh also represent the struggle against the supremacy of Rome, and for the unity of the Empire ; two demands which, while ideologically those of the decaying Knight- hood, were historically in the interest of the rising bourgeoisie. And thus, when Germany has developed, and has recovered from the immediate effects of the Thirty Years' War, they :igain come to the front, and in the nineteenth century were championed above all others by the Liberal middle-class. It was only after the establishment of the new German Empire that the German nobility remembered it had once produced so respectable a person as Franz von Sickingen — Hutten it cannot stomach even yet. In the fifties, and even later, " Gartenlaube Liberalism " L honoured Hutten and Sickingen as the advanced guard of the national and advanced movement, and ignored their efforts on behalf of their class. And Lassalle does exactly the same in his drama. Ulrich von Hutten and Franz von Sickingen fight against the Roman Antichrist solely for the sake of intellectual freedom ; against the princes only in the interest of the national cause. " What we desire," says Sickingen, in his dialogue with Hutten, " That is a single Deutschland, might} - , great, A shattering of all government by priests, A final breaking with all Roman ways, Pure teaching that is Deutschland's only church, A new birth quite commensurate with the old, Of old Germania's common liberty ; Complete destruction of our Princelings' sway And of the rule by middlemen usurped, And mighty stress and strain of time, 1 " Gartenlaube" is the German equivalent of our " Mrs. Grundy." 40 Ferdinand Lassalle. Firm based and deeply rooted in her soul One evangelic chief as Kaiser at the head Of the great realm." And Hutten answers, " True is the picture." In fact it is less true than analogous. It fits in wonderfully — since it ignores the aims which Hutten and Sickingen pursued besides fighting against Rome and the princes, and for the " timely " new birth of old Germanic freedom — with a pro- gramme which, over three hundred years later, became the watch- word of Kleindeutsch x Liberalism; it breathes the spirit of the approaching Prussian " new era." As Lassalle distinctly describes "Franz von Sickingen" as a drama " with a purpose,'' we have in it an explanation of the change that took place in his — still ideal — attitude towards the political tendencies of the time. But it was not long before this change of attitude showed a leaning towards the views of the North German "Vulgar Demo- cracy," and that, too, with regard to a concrete question of the day. " Franz von Sickingen " was finished in the winter of 1857-lb58. Lassalle, as he writes to Marx, had already conceived and begun it while still working at the "Heraclitus." It had been, he says, a necessity to him to escape now and then from that abstract world 1 A word of explanation as to this word " Kleindeutsch "—literally " Small German." I may remind my English readers that before the German Empire had been established, there were, amongst Germans, great differences of opinion as to the way in which the unification of Germany was to be brought about. One party — composed chiefly of Protestant middle - class persons in North Germany — was for uniting Germany under the supremacy of one of the two great rival German powers — i.e., Prussia, thus excluding Austria. But as this also meant the ex- clusion of some seven million Austrian Germans, the party was dubbed "Kleindeutsch" by their opponents. Their opposition to Austria being largely based upon the Catholicism of Austria, they went in for a good deal of "no popery " agitation. They were, moreover, opposed not only by the Catholic party and Ultra Conservatives, but by all the Radical parties, who were in favour of one great German Commonwealth, embrac- ing all German peoples. Youth and Early Manhood. 41 of thought, in which, during that work, he had had to " emmesh himself," and to turn to a subject which bore directly upon the great struggles of humanity. And so he had between whiles also studied the Middle-Ages and the .Reformation period. He had " been drinking deep " of the works and life of Ulrich von Hutten, when the reading of a wretched " modern " drama, which had just appeared, suggested the idea : " That — the struggle of Hutten — would be a subject worth treating.'' And thus, without origin- ally thinking of himself as the poet to carry out this design, he had sketched the plan of the drama. But soon it had become clear to him that he must also complete it himself. "A kind of inspiration " had possessed him. And, indeed, one feels that the drama was written with his warm heart's blood. Despite the faults I have pointed out, it, nevertheless, towers immeasurably above the whole democratic literature of the period. Not one of his German contemporary poets could have done better than Lassalle. I had just concluded this chapter when, owing to the kindness of Frederick Engels, the letters of Lassalle, found among Karl Marx' papers, were placed in my hands. Among these letters is an extremely interesting one addressed to Marx and Engels ; it consists of 34 quarto pages, and refers exclusively, with the ex- ception of a few lines, to " Franz von Sickingen." When the drama appeared in print Lassalle had sent three copies to Marx : one for himself, one for Engels, and one for Feiligrath, and had, at the same time, asked for their frank criticism of the play. Marx and Engels both acknowledged the many merits of the drama, and both independently — Marx was living in London, and Engels at this time was living in Manchester — seem to have come to much the same conclusions as to its faults. So much did their criticisms coincide that Lassalle replies — in the long letter just referred to — to both at once, because, as he says, "the letters without being ab- solutely identical, deal, on the whole, with the same points." And Lassalle's letter shows that these points were those which we have also urged above. " You both agree," writes Lassalle, " that even 42 Ferdinand Lassalle. Sickingen is drawn too much in the abstract.'' This says in a nut- shell what I have also enlarged upon. Lassalle's Sickingen is not the warrior knight of the earl}' sixteenth century. He is the nine- teenth century Liberal, masquerading in the latter's armour, i.e., liberal ideology. His speeches are for the most part altogether out of keeping with the period in which they are supposed to be spoken. "You both agree," writes Lassalle in another passage, " that I have too much left in the background the peasant move- ment," . . " that I have not given it sufficient prominence." . . " You x (Marx) found your argument upon this : I should have made Sickingen and Hutten perish, because they, like the Polish nobles, were only revolutionary in their own imagination, but in reality represented a reactionary cause. ' The aristocratic repre- sentatives of the Revolution,' you (Marx) say, ' behind whose catchword of unity and freedom there ever lurks the dream of the old empire and of " Faust recht," 2 ought, therefore, not to absorb all the interest as they do with you, but rather the representatives of the peasants, and especially these and the revolutionary elements of the towns ought to have supplied a far more living background. Then, too, you could to a much greater extent have let the most modern ideas express themselves in their naivest form, while now, as a matter of fact, besides religious freedom, bourgeois unity re- mains the main idea.' . . ' Have you not yourself,' you (Marx) exclaim, ' like your Franz von Sickingen, to some extent fallen in- to the diplomatic error of ranking the Lutheran-knightly op- position above the plebeian-burgher one ? '" I have omitted Lassalle's intercalated remarks, because they mostly refer to other matter, and would here be unintelligible. In the main, Lassalle defends himself by trying to prove that he has given sufficient prominence to the knightly narrowness of Sickingen — so far as it really existed in the historical Sickingen — by this : that instead 1 In writing to Marx, Lassalle, of course, always uses the familiar " du '' — thou. Where he uses the plural form he is addressing both Marx and Engels. 2 The practice of armed knights to waylay and plunder merchants travelling from town to town. Youth and Early Manhood. 43 of appealing to the whole nation, instead of calling upon all the revolutionary forces in the empire to rise, and placing himself at their head, Sickingen begins, carries on his revolt as a knightly one, and he finally perishes because of the narrowness of his knightly means. And it is just in Sickingen's failing because he did not go far enough, that the tragic, and at the same time re- volutionary, idea of the drama lies. Moreover, in the one scene of the play in which he brings the peasants themselves upon the scene, and in the frequent references to them in the speeches of Balthasar, etc., he had given them all the significance, and even more, than the peasant movement actually possessed. Histori- cally, the peasant movement had been as reactionary as that of the nobles. This latter view, as is well known, Lassalle also supported in several of his later writings, among others, in the " Workingmen's Programme." But, in my opinion, it is by no means a correct one. That the peasants formulated demands which meant a return to the past, does not, as such, stamp their movement as a reactionary one. Truly, the peasants were not a new class, but they were by no means like the knights, a decaying class. The reactionary part of their demands is only formal, not essential. This Lassalle overlooks, and as a Hegelian falls so completely into the error of deriving history from " ideas," that after Marx' remark, " Then, too, you could, in far greater extent, have let the most modern ideas express themselves in their naivest form," he puts two marks of interrogation, strengthened by one of exclamation. The rest of Lassalle's defence would be justified, if in the play there were even the slightest indication that Sickingen's confining himself to his knightly means was due to his own knightly limita- tions. But this is not the case. In the play, this is treated essentially as a tactical mistake. This suffices for the tragic idea of the drama, but does not set forth the historical anachronism of the Sickingen revolt, which was the actual cause of its failure. CHAPTER III. LASSALLE AND THE ITALIAN WAR. In the beginning of 1859, "Franz von Sickingen" ajjpeared as a printed play. At the time of its publication Europe was on the eve of a war which was to react seriously upon the development of affairs in Germany. It was that Franco-Sardinian campaign, already agreed upon in the summer of 1858, at Plombieres, be- tween Louis Napoleon, and Cavour, for the freeing of Lombardy from Austrian rule, and the overthrowing of Austrian supremacy in central Italy. Austria, at this time, belonged to the German Confederation, and so the question as to what attitude the rest of the Confederate States should assume in this contest was naturally raised. Was it the duty of the rest of Germany or not, especially as opposed to France, to identify itself with Austria ? The answer to the question was rendered the more difficult in that the nature of the war was an equivocal one. For the Italians concerned in it, it was a national war of emancipation, which was to help the cause of the unification and emancipation of Italy a step forward. For France, on the other hand, it was a cabinet war — a war undertaken to bolster up the Bonapartist regime in France, and to enhance the authority of France in Europe. This much, at any rate, was certain. Moreover, it was common talk that Napoleon had driven a pretty bargain with his ally, the King of Sardinia, that his support was to be paid for in territory (Nice and Savoy), and that the unification of Italy should, at that time, only proceed so far as was compatible with the interests of Bona- partist Imperialism. It was on these grounds that, e.g., so im- passioned an Italian patriot as Mazzini denounced, even at the end of 1858, the secret treaty concluded at Plombieres between Napoleon and Cavour as a mere dynastic intrigue. This much, 44 Lassalle and the Italian War. 45 at least, was certain, that whoever supported this war, was first of all supporting Napoleon III. and his plans. But Napoleon III. needed support. Against Austria alone, he could, in league with Sardinia, wage war, but if the other states of the German Empire, and above all, if Prussia went to the aid of Austria, the affair became at once much more critical. And so, through his agents and his emissaries, he used every means at the German courts, in the German press, and with the German party leaders, to agitate against the war being treated as a matter that in any way concerned Germany. What possible interest could the German people have in upholding the despotism of Austria in Italy, or, indeed, in lending any support to so arch-reactionary a state as Austria ? Austria was the sworn foe of the freedom of the peoples ; if Austria were crushed, a fairer morning would dawn for Germany also. On the other side, Austrian writers demonstrated that, if the Napoleonic plans in the South were realised, the Ehine would straightway be in danger. The next attack would be directed against it. Whoever wished to protect the left bank of the Rhine against the greedy hands of France, must assist Austria in main- taining her military position in northern Italy unhampered ; the Rhine must be defended on the Po. The watchword of the Napoleonic emissaries coincided in many essential points with the programme of the Kleindeutsch party (the unification of Germany under the leadership of Prussia, and the expulsion of Austria from the German Confederation), and was on exactly the same lines. Nevertheless, a large number of Kleindeutsch politicians could not make up their minds, just at this juncture, to separate the cause of Austria from that of the rest of Germany. This seemed to them the less admissible, since it was also known that Napoleon was carrj ing on the war in col- lusion with the Government of the Tzar at St. Petersburg ; that this war, therefore, had the farther aim to aid and abet Russian intrigues in the south-east of Europe. They inclined far more to the opinion that the first thing to be done now was to repel Napoleon's attack. Only when this had been done could they 46 Ferdinand Lassalk. discuss the matter further. But until this was done the Italians, so long as they fought under the segis of Napoleon, must put up with being treated simply as his confederates. Now, it cannot be denied that, from the Kleindeutsch stand- point, another view of the situation might also have been arrived at, and that which has just been set forth deemed inconsequent. If Austria, and especially its extra-German possessions, were to be expelled — and that the sooner the better — from the German Confederation, why not gladly welcome an event which was a step towards the realising of this programme X Had not Napoleon declared he was fighting only Austria and not Germany 1 Why, then, support Austria against France, especially as doing this also entailed war against the Italians, who surely were fighting for the justest cause in the world 1 Why defend the Ehine before it was attacked, before there was even a hint that any attack was intended ? Why not rather turn the difficulty of Austria and Napoleon's manoeuvres in Italy to account in furthering the cause of the unification of Germany under the leadership of Prussia, and that by positive methods 1 To this — I repeat — from the Kleindeutsch standpoint, logical polic3 r , Lassalle gives expression in his work published at the end of May, 1859 : "Der Italienischer Krieg und die Aufgabe Preussens." 1 With great energy he combats the view advocated in the two Berlin organs of North German Liberalism, the National Zeitttng and the Voiles Zeitung — in the former, among others, by Lassalle's subsequent friend, Lothar Bucher — that, in face of an attack emanating from Bonaparte, Prussia, as a member of the Con- federacy, must stand by Austria. Lassalle, on the contrary, demanded that Prussia should seize upon this moment to impress upon the Kleindeutsch states its German supremacy, and, if Napoleon reconstructed the map of Europe in the south on the principle of nationalities, to do the same, in the name of Germany, in the north ; and if he liberated Italy, Prussia on its side should seize Schleswig-Holstein. The moment had now come, " while the decay of Austria was proceeding of itself, to provide for the raising ' " The Italian War and the Mission of Prussia." Lassalle and the Italian War, 47 of Prussia in the estimation of the Germans." And, he adds in conclusion, " the Government may be assured of this. In this war, which is of as vital interest to the German people as it is to Prussia, the German democracy itself would carry the standard of Prussia ; would sweep all obstacles from its path with an expansive force of which only a seething outburst of national passion is capable ; a passion which, crushed down for fifty years, stirs and palpitates in the heart of a great people.'' On the strength of this pamphlet, attempts were subsequently made to stamp Lassalle as an advocate of the " German " policy of Bismarck, and it canuot be denied that the national programme set forth in it bears as such a great resemblance to that of the National Club founded in the summer of 1859, and, in the same way, mutatis mutandis, to the policy pursued by Bismarck in bringing about the unification of Germany under the leadership of Prussia. But then Lassalle, for all his theoretical radicalism, was still in practice pretty much imbued with Prussian jingoism. Not that he was a narrow Prussian " Particularist " — we shall soon see how far removed he was from that — but essentially he looked at the national movement, and its relations to foreign policy, through the spectacles of a Prussian democrat. In this respect his hatred of Austria was just as exaggerated as the Prussophobia of many South German democrats, and even many Socialists. For him Austria is " the most dangerous state- concept in regard to all culture that Europe can show ; " he would " like to know the negro who, placed by the side of Austria, would not seem white;" Austria is "a reactionary principle ; " " the most dangerous enemy of all ideas of freedom ; " " the state-concept Austria must be crushed, destroyed, torn to shreds, annihilated — scattered to the four winds.'' Every political infamy with which Napoleon III. might be reproached, Austria also has upon its conscience. And, " if the reckoning were other- wise pretty equal, yet, despite his patronage of the priests, Louis Napoleon has not signed the Roman Concordat." Even Russia fares better than Austria. "Russia is naturally an empire of barbaric force, which its despotic Government is trying to civilise 48 Ferdinand Lassalle. as fav as is compatible with its despotic interests. Barbarism has here the excuse that it is a national element." It is altogether otherwise with Austria. " Here the Government, in opposition to its peoples, represents a barbaric principle, and artificially and violently crushes them beneath its yoke.'' In this one-sided and relatively — i.e., relatively if we compare it with other states — exaggerated blackening of Austria, and also in many other points, Lassalle's pamphlet is at one with a work which had appeared a few weeks earlier, the drift of which was also to exhort the Germans to leave Napoleon, so long as he played the part of Liberator, a free hand in Italy, and to applaud the annihilation of Austria. This work was the notorious one of Herr Karl Vogt : "Studien zur gegenwartigen Lage Europa's," 1 a shameless piece of hack work, strung together in the Bonapartist interest. I should have hesitated to quote this work in connection with Lassalle's, were Lassalle not so entirely above all suspicion of complicity with Vogt and his crew, that it is impossible to place him in a false light by a comparison, which on theoretical grounds seems to me necessary, of these works. But farther, I shall now quote a passage from the preface to the " Herr Vogt '' of Karl Marx, the work which proved that Vogt was at this time writing and agitating in the interest of Bonaparte, proofs which were substantiated nine years later by documents found at the Tuileries. This passage fits in here because it indubitably refers to Lassalle. Marx writes : "Men who even before 1848 were in accord that the independence of Poland, Hungary and Italy, was not only a right of those nations, but was also in the interests of Germany and of Europe, expressed altogether contradictory views with regard to the policy to be pursued against Louis Bonaparte by Germany on the occasion of the Italian war of 1859. This contradiction arose from contradictory views as to actual as- sumptions — -to decide between which must be left to a later time. I, for my part, have in this work only to do with the opinions of Vogt and his clique. Even the opinion which he professed to represent, and in the imagination of a number of uncritical persons 1 " Studies on the present situation in Europe." Lassalle and tlie Italian War. 49 did represent, does not, in point of fact, come within the scope of my criticism. I deal with the opinions which he really re- presented." 1 In spite of this, it was naturally unavoidable that where Vogt used arguments which also occur in Lassalle, the latter is also criticised in Marx' work. This, however, did not prevent Lassalle from declaring in a letter to Marx, dated 19th January, 1861, that after reading " Herr Vogt," he thought Marx' con- viction that Vogt was bribed by Bonaparte, " perfectly right and justifiable," while the internal proof of this — that Vogt was a somewhat doubtful personage, Lassalle, who originally defended Vogt, had admitted earlier — was "supported by an immense weight of evidence." The book was " in every respect a masterly thing." At any rate, " Herr Vogt " is an extremely instructive book for the understanding of the history of the nineteenth century. This pamphlet contains a mass of historical material that would suffice to furnish forth a dozen essays. But from our point of view it has also a special interest. The correspondence between Marx and Lassalle was at no time so active as in the years 1859 and 1860, and a large portion of it deals with this Italian war and the attitude to be taken in regard to it. Whether the letters of Marx to Lassalle on this subject are still in existence, and if so, in whose hands they are, is not at present known, nor whether their present owner is prepared to publish them. From Lassalle's letters, however, the attitude taken by Marx at this time can only be imperfectly gathered, and still less the reasons for it, since Lassalle, quite naturally, confines himself chiefly to explaining his own standpoint, and refuting, as far as possible, the objections to it. But no further explanation is necessary to explain why, in a work on Lassalle, written for Socialists, not only his personal relations to the founders of modern scientific Socialism, but also his relation to their theoreti- cal teaching and their treatment of social and political questions are of especial interest. 1 Karl Marx : " Herr Vogt." Preface, v. vi. D 50 Ferdinand Lassalle. The literati of the day have, as we all know, a cut and dried formula as to this relation. As to politics, in the narrower sense, it runs thus : Lassalle was national ; Marx and Engels were and are international ; Lassalle was a German patriot ; Marx and Engels were aud are without fatherland, they ever cared only for the Universal Eepublic and the Eevolution ; what became of Germany was a matter of indifference to them. I regret that there is a bitter disillusion in store for the in- ventors of this formula and those who repeat it. Even before Lassalle's " Italienischer Krieg" (" Italian War ") appeared, the same publishers had issued another pamphlet, deal- ing with the same subject. It was entitled " Po und Rhein" (" The Po and the Ehine "). Like the first edition of Lassalle's work, it appeared anonymously. The author sought to prove, from the military point of view, that the watchword given by the organs of the Austrian Government, that Germany needed the Italian provinces for its defence in the south-west, was false ; that without these provinces Germany still had a strong defensive position in the Alps. This would be especially the case so soon as a free and united Italy had been created, since Italy would hardly be likely ever to have any valid reason for quarrelling with Germany, but might often enough have cause to seek a German alliance against France. Northern Italy was an appanage which at the very most might be useful to Germany in war, but could only be a danger in times of peace. And even the military ad- vantage in a war would be bought at the price of the sworn enmity of 25 million Italians. But, the author then continued, the question of the possession of these provinces is one between Germany and Italy, and not between Austria and Louis Napoleon. Pace to face with a third factor, a Napoleon, who interfered only to further his own, in other respects anti-German, interests, it was simply a question of a province that one only cedes under com- pulsion, of a military position one only evacuates when it is no longer tenable. " If we are attacked we shall defend ourselves." If Napoleon wanted to pose as the paladin of Italian Independence, let him begin at home, and restore Corsica to the Italians. Then Lassalle and the Italian War. 51 it might be seen how far he was in earnest. But if the map of Europe is to be revised, " then we Germans have the right to demand that it shall be done thoroughly and impartially ; that it shall not be after the approved fashion of demanding that Germany alone should make sacrifices. 1 ' "But the final result of this whole investigation," the pamphlet concludes, "is that we Germans would be driving an excellent bargain if we exchanged the Po, the Mincio, the Etsch, and the whole Italian bag of tricks for the UNiTr of Germany . . . which alone can make us strong at home and abroad." The writer of this pamphlet was no other than — Frederick Engels. Needless to say that Engels had published it in agree- ment with Karl Marx. Lassalle had found a publisher for it. And Lassalle had also, as appears from one of his letters, reviewed it in the Vienna Free Press, at that time still an independent organ, whose editor was a relative of his. So he was quite familiar with its contents when he wrote his " Italian War," and therefore opposes it when he combats its conclusion that, as Napoleon's leadership transformed the war from a war of inde- pendence into an enterprise directed against Germany, which must, of necessity, end in an attack upon the Rhine, Germans must treat it as such. On the other hand, as I have already said, Lassalle's work was also criticised in the criticism of '" Herr Vogt," 1 in Part V. 14, "Da-da Vogt and his Studies." 1 So, too, in a second pamphlet by Engels : " Savoyen, Nizza, unci der Rhein " (" Savoy, Nice, and the Rhine "). Lassalle in his pamphlet had declared the annexation of Savoy to France a quite self-evident, and pro- vided Germany received a satisfactory equivalent for this increase of territory, a " perfectly unobjectionable " proceeding. Now Engels showed what an extraordinarily strong military position the possession of Savoy would give to France, vis-d-vis of Italy and Switzerland, a matter which surely also deserved to be taken into consideration. Sardinia abandoned Savoy because, for the time being, it got something more in exchange. But the Swiss were by no means edified at the transaction. Their states- men — Stampfli, Frei-Herros6, among others— did their utmost to prevent the delivering over into the French hands of the ground of Savoy, hitherto neutral. In " Herr Vogt" may be read an account of the manoeuvres by which the Bonapartist agent in Switzerland counteracted these efforts. The rest may be seen by a mere glance at an atlas. 52 Ferdinand Lassalle. How strikingly Lassalle's arguments frequently coincided with those of Vogt one example will show. On the side of Austria the treaties of 1815 had been referred to, by which the possession of Lombardy had been guaranteed to Austria, To this Vogt and Lassalle reply as follows : — Vogt. " It is remarkable to find such language in the mouth of the only Government " (the italics are Vogt's) " which has, so far, im- pudently violated the treaties. All other Governments have, so far, respected them ; Austria alone has violated them, by stretching out in the midst of peace, and without any provoca- tion, its wanton hand against the Republic of Cracow, protected by these same treaties ; and, without more ado, incorporat- ing it with the Austrian Empire." ("Studien," 1st Ed., p. 58.) Lassalle. "The treaties of 1815 could no longer, even from the diplo- matic point of view, be appealed to. Seriously violated by the creation of the Belgian Constitu- tion, trodden under foot and torn to shreds by this same Austria, through the forcible occupation of Cracow, against which the Cabinets of Europe did not fail to protest, they have lost all righteous validity for every member of the European state family." (" Italienischer Krieg," 1st Ed., p. 18.) Now, let us hear Marx against Vogt: "Nicolas, of course, destroyed the Constitution and Indepeudence of the Kingdom of Poland, guaranteed by the Treaties of 1815, out of 'respect' for the Treaties of 1815. Russia respected the integrity of Cracow in no less degree when, in the year 1831, it invested the Free City with Muscovite troops. In the year 1836 Cracow was again invested by Russia, Austria, and Prussia; was in all respects treated as a conquered country ; and even in the year 1840, on the strength of the Treaties of 1815, appealed in vain to England and to France. Finally, on the 22nd February, 1846, the Russians, Austrians, and Prussians once more invested Cracow, in Lassalle and the Italian War. 53 order to hand it over to Austria. The treaty was violated by the three northern powers, and the Austrian Confiscation of 1846 was only the last word of the Russian entry of 1831." ("Herr Vogt," pp. 73, 74.) Further, in a note, Marx refers to his pamphlet, " Palmerston and Poland," in which he had shown that Palmerston, since 1831, had also had a hand in the intrigues against Cracow. This, however, is a question which has no special interest for us here, but it is of interest to note another matter demonstrated by Marx : that Vogt, in referring to the example of Cracow, was again only repeating and paraphrasing an argument advanced by the Bonapartists. In a Bonapartist pamphlet, published at Paris in the beginning of 1859, by Dentu : " La vraie question — France, Italie, Autriche " (" The real question — -France, Italy, Austria ") — it was said literally : " More- over, with what right could the Austrian Government appeal to the inviolability of the Treaties of 1815, that Government which violated them by the confiscation of Cracow, whose independence these treaties had guaranteed 1 " After the true sycophant method, Vogt had everywhere played an extra trump. Such catch words as " the only Government," " in impudent fashion," " wanton hand," are his stock-in-trade. And so, too, when at the end of the passage quoted above he pathetically invokes a " political Nemesis against Austria." Lassalle, when he wrote his pamphlet, had not yet seen Vogt's production ; but that his work was influenced by the " cries " set going by Bonaparte, and repeated through a thousand channels in the press at home and abroad, the above quotation, to which a whole series of others of the same kind might be added, leaves no doubt. When the National Liberal Bismarck worshippers to-day claim that the policy of their idol was sanctioned even by Lassalle, they are overlooking only one fact : that the programme proposed to the Prussian Government by Lassalle, in whatever sense Lassalle himself meant it, was to all intents and purposes the same as the programme which Bonaparte was then trying to palm off upon the German patriots, in order to win them over to his temporary policy. All the "prophecies " in the " Italienischer 54 Ferdinand Lassalh. Krieg,'' which to-day excite the admiration of the Brandeses, etc., are also to be found in Vogt's "Studien," and in a whole series of other Bonapartist pamphlets. Yes, Herr Vogt knew, even as early as 1859 — before the re-organisation of the Prussian army — that should Prussia stir up a German civil war, for the re-establish- ment of a unified central power, this war " would not last as many weeks as the Italian campaign would months." 1 Moreover, Vogt, who was "in the swim," was really better informed on many points than Lassalle, a fact which should be distinctly noted to Lassalle's honour. Vogt, e.g., knew perfectly that the Berlin Cabinet would leave Austria in the lurch. According to him, it must be clear even to the " most short-sighted person," that " an understanding existed between the Prussian Government and the Imperial Government of France, that Prussia would not draw the sword in defence of the extra-German Provinces of Austria . . . that Prussia would prevent any attempt of the Confederation or the individual members of the Confederation on behalf of Austria ... in order to receive its wage for these efforts, in North German lowlands." 2 More predictions cannot really be expected from a prophet. Lassalle, on the other hand, seems, just at this time, to have been very inadequately advised of the intentions of the Berlin Cabinet by his informants. "My pamphlet, ' Der Italienischer Krieg und die Aufgabe Preussens ' " (" The Italian War and the Mission of Prussia"), he writes, on the 27th May, to Marx mid Engels, " will have reached you. I don't know if you over there read enough German papers to see from them, at least approxim- ately, what the feeling here is. Absolute Franco-phobia, hatred of France (Napoleon only the pretext, the revolutionary develop- ment of France the real, secret reason), that is the string on which all the papers here are harping, and the passion which by playing upon the national sentiment they are trying — unhappily with some success — to instil into the heart of the lower classes and democratic circles. Useful as a war against France, undertaken by the Government against the will of the people, 1 " Studien," 2nd Ed., p. 155. °- " Studien," p. 19. Lassalle and the Italian War. 55 would be for our revolutionary development, just so dangerous must be the effect upon our democratic development of a war supported by blind popular enthusiasm. And besides other reasons adduced under this head in the 6th chapter of my pam- phlet there is this : that they are already allowing the rift that divides lis from our Governments to be entirely ani completely closed. In the face of so menacing a danger, I felt it my duty to throw myself into the breach. ... Of course, I am not for a single moment deluding myself into a belief that the Government could or would take the way proposed under Section III. On the contrary ! But I felt all the more bound to make this proposal, because it at once turns to a reproach. It may act as a sea-wall, against which the waves of this false popularity are beginning to break." From this it appears that Lassalle, in writing his pamphlet, was more anxious to forward the revolutionary than the national movement — to subordinate the latter to the former. The idea in itself was right enough. The only question was whether the means were right ; whether these must not force the national movement — as to which, for the time being, there was absolutely no difference of opinion between Lassalle on the one hand, and Marx and Engels on the other — into a wrong path. Marx and Engels were of opinion that the first thing to do was to counter- act the manoeuvres directed against Germany as a whole, by the common action of all Germans, and at a time when such a plot was brewing, not to support, even apparently, a policy which must lead to the dismemberment of Germany. The difference of opinion between them and Lassalle on this question was mainly due to the fact that whilst they regarded the question from its wider historical and international side, Lassalle was influenced rather by the immediate relation of Germany's internal politics. Hence, too, arose the contradiction that while he strongly marked off the difference between the people and the Government of France, he identified Austria with the house of Habsburg, and proclaimed the destruction of Austria, when surely only the destruction of the Habsburg regime was involved. 5 6 Ferdinand Lassalle. In one of his letters to the well-known and remarkable Econom- ist Rodbertus, Lassalle quotes a passage from a letter written by Rodbertus to himself: "And I yet hope to see the time when the heritage of Turkey shall have fallen to Germany, and when German soldiers, or Workers' regiments, are established on the Bosphorus." And to this Lassalle says : " It moved me strangely when, in your last letter, I read these words. For how often have I — in vain — pleaded for this very view against my intimate friends, and had to put up with being called a dreamer by them for my pains ! All the putting off of the Eastern question that has been taken up so many times since 1839, has, to me, always seemed reasonable and logical, only because it must be put off until its natural reversioner, the German Revolution, solves it. We seem to have come into the world as spiritual Siamese twins." l How Germany was to enter into the Turkish heritage, after Austria had first been " annihilated," and Hungary and the Slav States torn from Austro-Germany, 2 is difficult to under- stand. Another passage from Lassalle's letters to Rodbertus fits in here : " If there is one thing I have hated in my life, it is the Kleindeutsch Party. Everything Kleindeutsch is Gothaism and Gagerism, 3 and pure cowardice. A year and a half ago, I held a meeting here of my friends, when I formulated the matter thus : We must all will for a united Germany, moins les dynasties. I have never written a line in my life that could be counted to the good of the Kleindeutsch Party ; I consider it as the product of sheer dread of earnestness, war, revolution, the republic, and as a good slice of national treason." 4 It is evident that if Lassalle had been in earnest over the National Programme as set forth by him in " The Italian War," 1 Letters of Ferdinand Lassalle to Carl Rodbertus-Jagetzow, edited by- Ad. Wagner. Letter of the 8th May, 1863. " " Italienischer Krieg," p. 30. 3 " Gothaism "—i.e. the Gotha Party ; the name given the Kleindeutsch Party. Gagern, the " Statesman " of the Kleindeutsch Party. 1 Letter of the 2nd May, 1863. Lassalle and the Italian War. 57 it would have been impossible for him to have written the above lines, for that programme was most certainly a Kleindeutsch one. He was rather only using it as it seemed to him expedient for his much more advanced political aims, and for bringing about the Revolution which was to solve the national question in the " greater " German sense. In his letters, following that of the 27th May, 1859, to Marx and Engels, he expresses himself more and more explicitly in this sense. Space forbids my giving more than certain parts and short re'sum-e's of Lassalle's very lengthy letters. About the 20th June, 1859 (Lassalle's letters are very often undated, so that the date has to be determined from the context), Lassalle writes to Marx : " Only in a popular war against France ... do I see a misfortune. But in a war unpopular with the nation, immense benefit for the Revolution. . . . The work then divides itself thus : our Governments must make the war (and they will do this), and we must make it unpopular. . . . You, 1 over there, absent from here ten years, seem to have no idea how little dis-monarchied our people is. I also only understood it, to my sorrow, at Berlin . . . now, if in addition to this, the people were induced to believe that the Government was conducting the war as a national one, that it had risen to the height of a national act, you would see how complete the reconciliation would be, and how, especially in case of reverses, the bond of 'German fidelity' would bind the people to its Government. . . . The following, then, is evidently to our interest : " 1. That the war be made. (This, as already said, our Govern- ment will look after itself.) All the information I get from a re- liable source bears out that the Prince is on the point of declaring for Austria." (The " reliable " source to which Lassalle here refers seems to have mystified him badly.) " 2. That it (the war) shall be mismanaged. This, too, our Governments will themselves look after, and this the more com- pletely, the less the people are interested in the war. " 3. That the people shall be convinced that the war has been 1 The " you " here refers to both Marx and Engels. 58 Ferdinand Lassalle. undertaken in an anti-popular, in a dynastic, and counter-revolu- tionary sense, therefore against their interests. This only we can look after, and to look after that is therefore our duty." Lassalle then goes into the question, what end could be served by " wishing to stir up a popular war amongst us against France 1 " But here also there are two considerations which he accepts as conclusive. (1) The reaction upon the prospects of the revolu- tionary parties at home and abroad ; and (2) the reaction upon the relations of the German Democracy to the French and Italian Democracies. The interests of Germany as a nation he does not touch upon at all. To the reproach that he was recommending the same policy as Vogt, who was writing in the pay of France, he answers : " Would you reduce me on account of the bad company I keep ad absurdum ? Then I might return you the compliment, for you have the misfortune to be of one mind, this time, with Venedey and Waldeck." Then he boasts that his pamphlet has had an " immense " effect ; that the Voiles Zeitung and the National Zeitung had sounded a retreat ; the latter " in a series of six leading articles, having executed a complete face about." Strange that Lassalle should never have asked himself why these organs of the Kleindeutsch school allowed themselves to be so readily converted ! In a letter to Marx in the middle of July, 1859— after Villa- franca — he says : " It goes without saying that between us it was not principles, but rather as you say, and as I have always under- stood it, ' the most expedient policy,' upon which we differed." And that there may be no doubt in what sense he means this, he adds the words: "i.e., therefore, after all, the most expedient policy for the Eevolution." In the beginning of 1860, he writes to F. Engels : " Only to avoid misunderstandings, I must say that even last year, when I wrote my pamphlet, I heartily wished that Prussia should declare war against Napoleon. But I wished it only on this condition, that the Government should declare it, and that it should be as unpopular, and as much hated by the people as possible. Then, truly, it would have been a great boon. But then, the Democracy Lassalle and the Italian War. 59 ought not to have written aud made propaganda for this war. . . As to the present situation, we are probably quite agreed, and shall, no doubt, agree also as to the future." In the same letter, Lassalle also refers to the scheme of military re-organisation which was just then being broached, and which, as is known, subsequently led to conflict between the Government and the Liberal bourgeoisie. The mobilisation of 1859 had con- vinced the Prussian Government how ill prepared the Prussian army still was, and that drastic changes were necessary to fit it for taking the fieLl, either against France or Austrin, with any chance of success. Whoever then was in earnest about " the German mission of Prussia," must also endorse the re-organisation of the army, or, at least, must objectively admit its justification. This, in fact, the Progressists at first did. Now let us hear Lassalle : " The Bill is shameful ! Dissolution — complete, only masked, of the Landwehr, as the last democratic relic of the times of 1S10 — creation of an immensely powerful weapon for Absolutism and the Squirearchy— that, in two words, is the evident meaning of the Bill. Never would ManteufFel have dared to pro- pose such a thing ! Never would he have carried it through. Whoever lives in Berlin now, and doesn't die of Liberalism, will never die of vexation ! " Finally, one more quotation from a letter of Lassalle's to Marx, written from Aachen on the 11th September, 1860. Marx, in a letter to Lassalle, had referred, among other things, to a circular note of Gortschakoff's, which had declared that if Prussia went to the help of Austria against France,- Prussia on its side would intervene on behalf of France — i.e., would declare war upon Prussia and Austria. This note, Marx had explained, was a proof, first, that there bad all along been a plot of which the freeing of Italy was only the pretext, the weakening of Germany the real object, and secondly, that it was a shameless interference of Russia in German affairs, which must not be endured. To this Lassalle now replied that he could not see any insult in the note, but even supposing it did contain one, it would after all only affect " the German Governments." " For, diable ! what does the strong position of the Prince of Prussia 60 Ferdinand Lassalle. matter to you or me 1 As all his tendencies and interests are directed against the tendencies and interests of the German people, it is much rather in the interest of the German people, if the Prince's position is externally as weak as possible." So one must rather rejoice at such humiliation, or, at the most, only use it against the Government in the same way that the . French had done under Louis Philippe. It would be difficult to express oneself more '"treasonably" than in all this, and those who have hitherto held up Lassalle as the pattern of a good patriot in the National-liberal sense of the word, against the Social Democracy of to-day, will, after the pub- lication of Lassalle's letters to Marx and Eugels, simply find they have not a leg to stand on. The motives that influenced Lassalle in writing the " Italian War " were anything but an acknowledg- ment of the national mission of the Hohenzollerns. And far from it being the case — as most of the bourgeois biographers declare — that in Lassalle the party-man was sunk in the patriot, it would be truer, on the contrary, to say that the party-man, the repub- lican revolutionist, forced the patriot into the background. Undoubtedly, the question might with a certain appearance of plausibility be asked : " But if the standpoint which Lassalle works out in his letters to Marx is so essentially different from the one set forth in the pamphlet, who can prove that the former was really the one which Lassalle in his inmost heart accepted 1 Since in any case he must have concealed his true face once, may not this have been from Marx?" There are so many reasons against this assumption that it is hardly worth while con- sidering it. The most important is, that the contradiction be- tween the pamphlet and the letters, is, after all, only an apparent one. Where Lassalle says anything in the pamphlet which does not square with the ideas expressed in the letters, he always speaks hypothetically, with a big "If." And to this "If" he adds at the end : " But if not— then," and formulates his " then " thus : "Then this will only prove again and again, that Monarchy in Germany is no longer capable of a national act." As to the positive declarations of the pamphlet, these he maintains also in the Lassalle and the Italian War. 61 letters. He was perfectly sincere in the main contention of the pamphlet, that the Democracy — by which he understood the whole of the decidedly opposition parties— must not sanction the war against France, because they would thereby identify themselves with the oppressors of Italy ; and he was also quite in earnest in his desire for the crushing of Austria. Up to this point the pamphlet, whether one agrees with the standpoint set forth in it or not, is thoroughly justifiable as a subjective expression of opinion. Not so with regard to the last chapter. Here Lassalle transgresses the limits that divide the politician fighting for his convictions, for definite principles, from the demagogue. The former will never recommend anything which he does not really wish to happen. Lassalle certainly qualifies his expressions, but in so ambiguous a way that the uninitiated reader cannot but believe that Lassalle ardently desired the Prussian Government to pursue the policy which he there suggests. The qualified form explains the contradiction to the letters to Marx, Engels, and Kodbertus, but by no means justifies the double dealing. The lawyer trick of recommending a course because one believes it will not be taken, is, after all, an altogether false method in politics, only cal- culated to mislead your own followers — as, indeed, happened subsequently in this case. The example which Lassalle cites for his own tactics is the most unfortunate one imaginable. The foreign policy of the Eepublican opposition in France under Louis Philippe, of the gentlemen of the National, subsequently smoothed the path for the murderer of the Republic, for Bona- partism. Just as the " Pure Piepublicaus " had used the Na- poleonic legend against Louis Philippe, Lassalle believed he could play off the legend of Frederick the Great against the Prussian Government of the time. But the Frederick tradition, so far, at any rate, as it was here concerned, had, by no means, been given up by the Prussian Government, and Lassalle was making propaganda not against, but for the dynastic policy of the Hohenzollerns. How later, when Prussia felt itself militarily strong enough, the policy was energetically followed ; how it next led to a civil 62 Ferdinand Lassalle. war between North and South Germany ; how Austria was hap- pily forced out of the German Confederation, and the unification of the German rump consolidated, we have seen. But the realisa- tion of the programme set forth iu the " Italian War " bears the same relation to the one Lassalle dreamed of as the camel does to the horse of Lessing's fable. Whither has the Prussian solution of the national question led Germany 1 ? Setting aside the question of Alsace and Lorraine — the annexation of these provinces was an additional blunder — let us only consider- the position of the German people face to face with Bussia and Panslavism. The expulsion of Austria from the German Confederation has furthered the panslavistio propaganda to the highest degree. The Austrian Government is, to-day, forced to make the Slavs one concession after the other ; and, con- sequently, the latter are making ever greater demands. Where they would formerly have been content with a recognition of their language and nationality, they to-day wish to rule and to oppress. At Prag, to - day a Tchech town, the Tchech fraternised with the French Jingoes and drank to a war against the German. The incorporation of the German portions of Austria with Ger- many, will, of course, come sooner or later, but it will be under ten times more disadvantageous circumstances than before the glorious expulsion of Austria from the German Confederation. To-day, the German Empire is obliged to look calmly on, while these districts are being made more and more Slav. For the Bis- marckian method of unifying Germany has made Bussia so strong, that the present German policy has the greatest interest in the maintenance of even this Austria. Half a loaf is better than no bread. And assuredly so long as Tsarism, with its panslavist aspirations, rules in Eussia, so long the existence as a state even of the Austria of to-day has justification. Lassalle, of course, wanted something quite other than the mere expulsion of Austria from the Empire. He wanted the de- struction, the annihilation of Austria, whose German provinces were to form an integral part of the one and indivisible German Bepublic. So much the less, then, should he have drawn up a Lassalle and the Italian War. 63 programme, the immediate consequences of which must be a civil war in Germany, a war of North Germany against South, for the South Germans in 1859 were distinctly on the side of Austria. Only Lassalle's strong tendency to sacrifice to his immediate object all considerations outside it, can explain this return to a diplomacy which he had only just denounced with the utmost severity in "Franz von Sickingen." Then, too, in the writing of the pamphlet, there was in addition the passionate longing of Lassalle to take part in actual politics. This longing again and again finds expression in his letters. When Lassalle, at this time, refuses to entertain any matter on the ground of the scientific work he was still contemplating, it is with the reservation : If there is any immediate possibility of in- fluencing the development of the Revolution, then he will give up science also. Thus on the 21st March, 1859, he had written to Engels : "Rather, I suppose, I shall henceforth devote myself to the study of national economy, the philosophy of history — I mean history in the sense of social development— unless, indeed, as is to be devoutly hoped, practical movements begin at last to stop all more serious theoretical activity." "How gladly would I leave unwritten what I perhaps know, if instead we [the "we " is here used as referring to the party,] may succeed in doing a little of what we might." And could Lassalle, six weeks after writing this, have gone over to the monarchical " Kleindeutsch " camp? No. His policy was wrong, but his aim had remained the same : the Revolution for the one and indivisible German Republic. That is what is meant when he prefaces his work with a motto from Virgil : " Flectere si necqueo superos acheronta movebo." If I am unable to influence the gods — the Government, I will move Acheron — the people. CHAPTER IV. " THE SYSTEM OP ACQUIRED EIGHTS," AND OTHER MINOR WORKS. (1860-1861.) Lassalle's next work, after the " Italian War," was a contribu- tion to a periodical, appearing in book form, and edited, during the summer of 1860, by the democratic writer, Ludwig Walesrode, under the title of "Democratic Studies." This was the essay, subsequently issued as a pamphlet : " Fichte's Politisches Vermachtniss und die neueste Gegenwart." 1 It may be considered as an epilogue to the earlier work, where Lassalle says openly what he had thought well to put earlier in a veiled form. The "Political Legacy" of Fichte, as Lassalle explains, quoting from a sketch on a political essay found among Fichte's papers, " is the unification of Germany, but as a unified Republic ; otherwise, a united Germany would anyhow be impossible. Were Germany conquered by any one of the existing German States, that would not constitute national unity ; but only the forcing upon the other German races the specific Haus-geist 2 of the conquering tribe, and their becoming Prussianised, Bavarianised, Austrianised !".... " And inasmuch as that balancing which is still possible between their different idiosyncrasies would disappear, the German people would find themselves uprooted in their spiritual life also." " The conquest of Germany, not in the special ' Haus-geist,' but rather by the free absorption of that spirit into the national spirit and its aims, would assuredly be something very different ! But it would be sheer madness to expect the idealism of such a de- cision from men," — Lassalle is speaking of the German princes, and especially of the King of Prussia — " whose mental personality, i " Fichte's Political Legacy and the Immediate Present." i.e., local spirit. 64 " The System of Acquired Rights''' 65 like that of all other men, is a definite product of the various factors in their education, traditions, inclination, and history ; as mad as to expect it of any one of us, had his training and educa- tion been exclusively determined by the same factorsi" These are the last of Lassalle's own comments in the essay. The rest is taken up with quotations from Fichte, demonstrating how and why the unity of Germany is only possible on the basis of " complete personal freedom," and that for this very reason, the Germans, " in the eternal plan of the Universe,'' are called upon to represent a " true kingdom of right,'' a kingdom of " freedom, founded upon the equality of all that bear the face of man." And, Lassalle concludes, " Far be it from us to weaken the inimit- able strength of these words by adding any of our own." Then, addressing the editor : " And now, dear sir, if I have not been able to comply literally with your request (i e., to write an article on a " burning question of the day "), yet I think your object has been attained, and mine also." Now, what was Lassalle's "object" in publishing this essay, which is dated January, 1860? This also we learn from a letter to Marx. On the 14th April, I860, Lassalle writes to the latter explaining why he had accepted Walesrodc's invitation, although his whole time was taken up with the completing of a great work. To begin with, he had found Walesrode a very honest man, brave and stout-hearted, as his meritorious pamphlet, " Politische Todenschau," 1 proved, and who deserved that one should do something for him. But then Lassalle continues: "Finally, the book might, after all, produce some salutary effect upon our German Philistines, and if I had refused the invitation, it would in any case have been addressed to one far less determined than myself. Yes, unquestionably, to some one coquetting with monarchical or some such democratism, or Kleindeutsch ideas, while the invitation gave me an opportunity of once again uttering a genuine republican war-cry, and thus, in the name of our party, taking possession of the book, which, it seems to me, from its contents, although I know no particulars as to these or the contri- 1 " Political Post-Mortem." E 66 Perdin&nd Lassalle* butors, was hardly likely to spread our ideas of strengthen the influence of oaf party. " So, willy-nilly, an article came to be written. I have asked for a special advance copy of it only that I might send it to you. (The book itself will not appear till the October season.) I am forwarding it with this letter ; please read it, then send it on to Engels, and finally write me if you like it. " I believe that amid all this disgusting Gothaist turmoil it will produce the vivifying effect, that beyond the mountains there are yet men ; that a Republican Party still lives ; the effect of a trumpet-blast." The book, the completion of which was at this time occupying Lassalle, was the "System der Erworbenen Rechte." 1 It is odd, and yet to anyone who has attempted a great work, comprehensible enough, to hear Lassalle complain that the thing is dragging so, and that he has " already conceived an intense hatred of it." But this " damned work," as he calls it in another passage of the same letter, was not to be finished even in the three months he now gave himself as a limit. In 1860, Lassalle was again seriously ill with an attack of that chronic disease 2 to which he had already referred in the Diissel- dorf Assize Court Speech, and from which he continued periodically to suffer. " I have been, and still am, very ill," he begins a letter to Marx, that must have been written at the end of January, 1860. " I have again been ill, and worse than before," is the beginning of the letter quoted above. " Have I been overworking of late, or is too long neglect taking its revenge now?" he continues. " In short, it seems my health has ceased to be that indestructible rock upon which I could once build so confidently." To get thoroughly cured, Lassalle, in the summer of the same year, went to Aachen. There he made the acquaintance of a young Russian, Sophie Solutzew, who had accompanied her father — who was also taking the waters — to Aachen. This young lady so fascinated Lassalle that he there and then, at Aachen, made her an offer of marriage. 1 " System of Acquired Rights.'' 2 Probably syphilis. " The System of Acquired Rigkis." 6j This, after a few weeks' reflection, Mademoiselle Solutzew de- clined. All that has so far been made known of this episode in the agitated life of Lassalle, is through the account of Mademoiselle Solutzew, now the wife of a landowner in South Kussia, pub- lished in 1877 in the St. Petersburg review, " The European Messenger.'' A German translation of these statements was pub- lished a year later by F. A. Brokhaus, at Leipzig, under the title of "A Love Episode in the Life of Ferdinand Lassalle." 1 Everything was perfectly correct. Sophie Solutzew says that Lassalle certainly made a deep impression upon her, and that for a time she thought she might love him. But she was always doubting, until she became certain that a love that doubts is not love — above all is not the kind of love which Lassalle, with his references to the struggles that the future would bring him, ex- pected. Possibly the prospect of these struggles frightened the young lady more than she is willing to admit ; the confessions of a journal and of " memoirs " notoriously never speak the whole truth. On the other hand, that view of the affair which counts it almost a crime on the part of Mademoiselle Solutzew to have 1 When these statements of Mademoiselle Solutzew first appeared there were some who doubted the genuineness of them and of the letters of Lassalle which they contained. A German fifth or sixth rate penny-a- liner set himself to prove their apocryphal nature, to prove indeed that they were forged by the Countess Hatzfeld for her own honour and glory. But to anyone who knew the styles of Lassalle and Countess Hatzfeld, it is certain that even if the Countess had been foolish enough to plan the letters, she could never have been clever enough to write them. Further, in a legal action brought by Mademoiselle Solutzew, the genuineness of the letters was proved in court. I should not have mentioned this absurd canard except for the fact that the pamphlet of Kutschbach (the above- mentioned journalist) has induced an English writer of the position of Mr. Clement Shorter, to repeat this ridiculous story in his Preface to the new edition of Meredith's " Tragic Comedians." The " Lassalle Legend " ha3 given rise to many silly statements, but to none more silly than the one that Lassalle's last love affair was also his first. It is true the love affair with Sophie von Solutzew was not particularly in- teresting. 68 Ferdinand Lassalle. been loved by Lassalle without returning his love, seems to me really a little too sentimental. The lady had a most unquestion- able right not to bestow her heart upon Lassalle, and Lassalle himself, passionate as his wooing was, very soon consoled himself for his mishap. Far more interesting than the love affair itself are the letters to which it gave rise from Lassalle to Mademoiselle Solutzew, above all the letter already referred to — ' : The Con- fession of a Soul," a MS. covering over thirty-five pages of printed matter. This is one of the most interesting documents for the understanding of Lassalle. If his first "journal" shows us the boy developing into a youth, here we see the youth grown into a man, and laying bare his inmost self. Surely what has just been said of "confessions" in general may apply also to this particular case, but one of the most remarkable characteristics of Lassalle is his — I might almost say, unconscious — sincerity. Lassalle's was, as his constant tendency to drop into the pathetic proves, a theatrically-inclined nature. He liked a little acting, and was far too much a society man to see any harm in using speech, according to Talleyrand's saying, to conceal his thoughts. And yet, as a human being he could not show himself other than he really was. His inclinations and his passions were far too strong not to betray themselves everywhere ; his personality far too marked to hide itself under any disguise he might care to assume. Thus, even from the picture of himself which Lassalle drew for Sophie Solutzew, a picture in which he painted himself as he wished to appear to the young girl, the real Lassalle looks out — the real Lassalle with all his qualities and with all his defects. In every line of this his huge self-confidence and vanity reveal themselves. I have said how in this MS. Lassalle suns himself in the light of his future fame ; how he represents himself as the leader of a party, while, in fact, no such party as yet existed ; depicts aristocracy and bourgeoisie as hating and fearing him, while at this time any cause for fear and hatred was wanting. In the same way he exaggerates his successes so far achieved. " Nothing, Sophie," he writes of the success of the Casket Speech, " The System of Acquired Rights." 69 " can give you any idea of the electrical effect that I produced. The whole town, the population of the whole province, was, so to say, swimming upon the waves of enthusiasm .... all classes, the whole bourgeoisie, were drunk with enthusiasm .... this day secures me, in the Rhenish Provinces, the reputation of a transcendent orator, and of a man of unbounded energy, and the newspapers are spreading this fame through the whole kingdom .... since this day the Democratic Party in the Rhenish Pro- vinces has recognised me as its chief leader." Then he writes of the Dusseldorf Trial that he came out of it " with not less glory." "I will give you my speech at this trial, as it also is published ; it will amuse you." He does not add that the speech was never delivered. But along with the traits of perfectly child-like and childish vanity, there are not wanting those of legitimate pride ; legitimate, because founded upon principle and not upon any outward honours, while all through the letter rings a note of true con- viction. Even when speaking of the " glory," which, with the occurrence of " certain events " — the expected revolution — would be shed upon the life of his future wife, Lassalle immediately adds; "But — is it not so, Sophie? — that in such great matters, which make up the end and aim of the efforts of the whole human race, we must not merely speculate on individual happi- ness ; " aud goes on, " and that is why we must in no wise reckon upon that." In auother respect, also, Lassalle's " Confession of a Soul " is of interest. In it he speaks very circumstantially of his relations to the Countess Hatzfeld. Now, though much in respect to his earlier relations to her may be idealised, this much, at any rate, is certain, that Lassalle could have no reason, when writing to a girl whom he was seeking in marriage, and whom he was trying so desperately hard to win for wife, to paint his feelings towards the Countess — beyond those of mere respect and gratitude — as being stronger than they really were. As a matter of fact, how- ever, Lassalle in the letter indulges in expressions of positively passionate tenderness for the Countess. He loves her " with the Jo Ferdinand Lassalle. tenderest filial love that has ever existed ; " " three times as much as his own tenderly-loved mother." He demands of Sophie that if she accepts him for her husband, she shall "love the Countess with the true tenderness of a daughter," and hopes, although the Countess, being of " exceptional delicacy of feeling," and not knowing if Sophie Solutzew loves her, would not wish to live with the young couple, that they may be able to persuade her to, so that " all three may live happy and united." From this it is evident that those who represent the Countess Hatzfeld during this time at Berlin, and later on also, as forcing herself upon Lassalle, have, to say the least, exaggerated enor- mously. The Countess Hatzfeld had her great faults, and, in my opinion, her friendship was, in many ways, extremely harmful to Lassalle; but because I think this, I feel it my duty to protest when this woman is unjustly dealt by. There could be nothing more ridiculous than the statement, made by several writers, and taken from the well-known pamphlet of Becker, that Lassalle had, later on, plunged into the Donniges affair in order to get rid of the Countess. Sophie Solutzew, moreover, speaks very favourably of the im- pression made upon her personally by the Countess Hatzfeld. Three letters from Lassalle to Marx belong to this period of his stay at Aachen. Of course he in none of them refers to the Solutzew love affair. Only a few remarks, in one of the letters, as to the situation at the Kussian Court, seem to point to the Solutzews as their source. But the letters contain much else that is interesting, and a passage in one of them is especially note- worthy, as it shows us what Lassalle, even at a time when he was on the best of terms with the Liberal Opposition lfeaders at Berlin, thought of the Liberal press, and of Prussian justice, which the Liberals were then praising to the skies. As it is as brief as drastic it may be quoted here. Marx had tried to bring the editor of the Berlin National Zeitung, Zabel, to book for libelling him ; Zabel having, under cover of Vogt's pamphlet, imputed the most dishonourable con- 4uct to Marx, But before the case could come into co^rf, Marx " The System of Acquired Rights." 71 had been non-suited in three different courts. For the said justices of the Stadtgericht, the Kammergericht, and the Ober Tribunal of Berlin, all found that if Zabel repeated, and even trumped, all Vogt's calumnies against Marx, he could not possibly have had the intention to insult Marx. Such a proceeding as this Marx had, however, thought impossible even in Prussia, and wrote as much to Lassalle. To this Lassalle, who, from the beginning, had advised Marx against the action because justice was not to be hoped for anyhow, now replied as follows : — " You write that you now know, that with us it depends upon the judges whether an individual can even get so far as to bring an action ! Dear fellow, how I wronged you once lately when in one of my letters I said you saw things in too dark colours ! I beat my breast remorsefully, and retract this entirely. Prussianjustice, at any rate, you seem to have regarded in far too rosy a light ! But I've had to endure far other things than you from this crew ; could bring far stronger proof for what you say, have experienced far worse cases altogether at their hands, and that three times three dozen times, and in criminal, and more especially in purely civil cases. . . . Uff ! I must drive away the remembrance of all this. For when I think of this daily judicial murder of ten long years that I passed through, then waves of blood seem to tremble before my eyes, and it seems to me as if a sea of blood would choke me ! Well, I have got the better of all this long ago, and lived it all down, and time enough has expired since then for me to think of it all coolly. But never do my lips curl with so deep a smile of contempt as when I hear our judges and justice spoken of. Galley-slaves seem to me very honourable persons compared with our judges. " But you will be quits with them, you write. ' At any rate,' you say, 'the Prussians provided you with material, the pleasant consequences of which they shall soon see in the London press ! ' No, dear friend, they will see nothing at all. Of course, I don't doubt that you will expose and annihilate them in the London press. But they will see nothing of this, absolutely nothing; it will be as if you had not written at all. For English papers are not 72 Ferdinand Lassalle, read by us, and you see, of our German papers not a single one will take any notice of it, not a single one will say even one poor little word about it. They'll take good care not to ! And our Liberal press most of all ! Where then would these calves-heads breathe the slightest word against their most sacred bulwark, ' the Prussian judges,' at the bare mention of which they gasp with ad- miration—why, they never utter the word but with inflated cheeks — and bow their heads to the ground with respect ! Oh ! nothing at all will they say of it, and from the Danube to the Rhine, and as far as ever ' the German tongue is spoken,' they will quietly ignore it in a conspiracy of silence. What's to be done against this press conspiracy 1 Oh ! one may say what one likes, but our police is, after all, a far more liberal institution than our press ! That — heaven help us ! I really can find no other word for it — that is a more ." (The word Lassalle uses here is too strong to be reproduced in print : the reader may fill it in for himself.) In 1861, Lassalle published, in the second volume of the " Demoscratische Studien," a short essay on Lessing, which he had written in 1858, on the appearance of Stahr's " Lessing's Leben und Werke." \ Finally, in the same year he brought out his great work on the " Philosophy of Jurisprudence " — " Das System der Erworbenen Rechte '' (" The System of Acquired Rights "). The essay on Lessing is comparatively unimportant. Its form is still predominantly in the old Hegelian manner, and its matter inclines strongly towards the views set forth by Heine in his " Uber Deutschland," with regard to Lessing's import for the literature and public life of Germany. Like Heine, Lassalle also extols Lessing as the second Luther of Germany; and when, at the end of the essay, referring to the great resemblance between the situation in Germany at that day, and the time of Lessing, he exclaims : " Like situations bring forth like characters," he may have been thinking of Heine's words : " Yes, a third man, too, will come, and he will conclude what Luther began, what Lsssing continued, a man of whom the German fatherland stands 1 " Life "and works of Lessing." " The System of Acquired Rights." J2> in such sore need — the third liberator." For was it not Lassalle's highest aspiration himself to become this third liberator? As in the Hutten of his " Franz von Siekingen," as in the Lessing of this essay, Lassalle's own attitude of mind is mirrored. Even the apotheosis of the sword is not wanting. " But even when we have carried out Lessing's conception in the domains of art, of religion, and of history, how about politics 1 " asks Lassalle. And to remove any possible doubts from the minds of those whom Lessing's- attitude with regard to the above-mentioned subjects had not yet convinced, he quotes from Lessing's fragment " Spartacus." The passage quoted is that where Spartacus, replying to the jeering question of the consul : " I hear thou dost philosophize, Spar- tacus 1 " — makes answer : — " What 1 thou would'st not have me philosophize. Philosophize ! it makes me laugh ! Well, then, we will fight ! " Twenty years later this prophecy of Lessing's was fulfilled in the French Eevolution. And this solution would, according to Stahr, "be also the end of the business between the Spartacus and the consul of the future." The " System of Acquired Rights " is Lassalle's chief theoretical N work. Although it is primarily written only for jurists, the sub- ject with which it deals is far more akin to the practical struggles of the present day than is that of the " Heraclitus." Hence I shall attempt to explain, at least, the chief ideas of this work, which Lassalle was justified in referring to on one occasion as " a gigantic piece of human industry." . On one point the specialists are pretty well agreed — that " The System of Acquired Rights " j testifies at once to the extraordinary mental creative powers, as well as to the juridical acumen of its author. On all these grounds I shall be justified in dealing with this work at some length. The task which Lassalle had set himself in writing this book, which he divided into two parts, is shown by the sub-title : " Eine Versohnung des Positiven Rechts und der Rechts Philosophie." 1 From the preface, which treats of the work of the Hegelian School i "A Reconcilement of Positive Rights with the Philosophy of Jurisptu- / dence," 74 Ferdinand Lassalle. in the domain of the law, it is at once seen to what an extent Lassalle still relies on Hegelian principles. It is true he here adopts an attitude more independent of Hegel than he had done in the '' Heraclitus," but he still holds not merely to the method, but to the fundamental principles of the Hegelian philosophy — i.e., not merely to the dialectic treatment of the subject to be in- vestigated, and to the dialectic form of that investigation, but also to the Hegelian idealism, to the tracing back of historical phenomena to the development and the movement of ideas. Like Hegel, Lassalle, too, stops half-way. He quite rightly points out that the institutions of the law are not the realisations of logically eternal, but of historical categories ; yet he deals with these categories as with " realisations of mental concepts histori- cally evolved," while he entirely ignores the question as to the circumstances under which these mental concepts have developed, as to the economic conditions whose expression they are. In fact, he actually reverses that relation, and " tries to prove from the concrete materials themselves, that the alleged purely positive and historic facts are only the necessary outcome of the historical, mental concept of the corresponding time." (Vol. I., p. 61.) 1 Thus, despite the most brilliant display of acumen, Lassalle is of necessity driven to erroneous conclusions. As the most colossal example by which this causal dependence of the so-called '' purely positive and historic facts " upon historical mental concepts, is demonstrated in his book, Lassalle refers to his general exposition of the law of inheritance in the second volume of his work entitled : " Das Weseu des Romischen und Germanischen Erbrechts in historisch-philosophischer Entwick- lung," ("The Nature of the Roman and Germanic Law of Suc- cession in its Historical and Philosophical Development)." The strength of this work lies in its unity, in its logical working out of the main idea, and in its often really brilliant style. Through all forms of law bearing upon the subject, Lassalle aims at working out the Idea that the Roman law of inheritance is based upon the Idea of the immortality of the subjective Will of the testator in J The quotations are all from the Second Ed, of the " System," The System of Acquired Rights."" 75 the heir, while in the old Germanic law of inheritance, the law of intestacy (i.e., of inheritance without testament) is mainly based upon the idea of the family. This law is, therefore, exactly what the Roman law is erroneously supposed to be, " the real family law.'' This is right enough on the whole so far as it goes. But now comes the weak sidj of Lassalle's work. His dialectic, acute as it is, remains on the surface. It is true that he again and again probes that surface, leaves no inch of it unex- plored ; but that which lies beneath remains absolutely untouched. Why is it that the Roman law of inheritance expresses the con- tinuity of the subjective Will % Because of the Roman concept of immortality, because of the cult of the Lares and Manes. Why is it that the Germanic law of inheritance is the family law ? " Because of the concept of the Germanic family." What is the Roman concept of immortality 1 The continuity of the sub- jective Will. What is the concept of the Germanic family t " The moral identity of those individuals who have for actual basis . . . conscious unity of the mind or love.'' (Page 480.) This leaves us exactly where we were. We are moving in a circle of ideas and concepts, but get no explanation why these ideas here and those concepts there were able to play the part assigned them. Nor does Lassalle by a single word attempt to explain the juridical notions and actual laws of the Romans and Germans by their actual life conditions : the original source of the law every- where appears as the Volks-geist. 1 And here Lassalle falls into the same error with which he, quite rightly, elsewhere re- proached former jurists. He certainly distinguishes between the Roman and the Germanic Volks-geist, but he ignores the whole of the historical development of the Roman people themselves. He constructs, once for all, a Roman Volks-geist that embraces all the thousands of years from the foundation of Rome to the destruction of the Roman Empire — -a "spirit" that stands in about the same relation to the Germanic Volks-geist, — con- structed after the same fashion — as does "Willto Love." (II. p. 480, note 3.) Of course, we must bear in mind that at the time * " Folk-Spirit," i.e, " National Spirit," J 6 Ferdinand Lassalle. when Lassalle wrote his " System of Acquired Eights," true historical research, with regard to the origin and development of Eoman society, and of primitive Germanic society, was still in an elementary condition, and that even professed historians were still, on these matters, feeling their way in the dark. He can, therefore, not so much be reproached with not having answered the question correctly, as with not putting it correctly. Indeed, a correct answer would not, at this time, have been possible. It is only through Morgan's epoch-making investiga- tions that sufficient light has been thrown upon the primitive development of the different peoples, to allow us to understand why the Eomans appeared in history with an entirely different law of inheritance from that of the Germanic races at the time of Tacitus. These were just then passing through the stage of development from the middle to the upper stage of barbarism ; the transition from the matriarchate to the patriarchate, from syn- dyasmic marriage to monogamy, was not yet complete, they still lived in gentile groups founded upon consanguinity, and primitive communism yet prevailed. A law of inheritance based upon the subjective Will was, therefore, simply a matter of im- possibility. If "Love" — a much more modern invention — has nothing, consanguinity has everything to do with the old Ger- manic law of inheritance. With the Eomans, on the contrary, even before the abolition of the so-called kinship, the old order of Society, based upon personal blood-relationship, had begun to dis- solve, and a new one, an actual state system, based upon territorial divisions and differences of property, been put in its place. l Private property in the soil, and the disruption of consanguineous groups as the economic unit, is the ground upon which the Eoman Testa- ment grew, not as a peculiar product of the Eoman Volhs-geist, but rather as a product of the same causes that created this special Eoman Volks-geist, i.e., the spirit that animated Home at the time of the Twelve Tables.' 2 If the Eomans did give i See F. Engels' " Ursprung der Familie, des Privat Eigenthums unci des Staats. Im Anschluss von Lewis H. Morgan's Untersuchungen." 1st Ed., p. 93, 2 About 450 u.c. The System of Acquired Rights" JJ to the Testament a certain solemn consecration, this by no means justifies us in representing the Testament as a rite whose symbolised action — the transference of the Will — whose main point and substantial essence — the transference of property — were mere insignificant details. In certain stages of culture, even well into a state of civilisation, the people clothe all impor- tant economic acts in the form of religious rites ; we need but re- call to mind the solemn rites at the partitioning of land, at the consecration of the marking of boundaries, etc. What would be thought of the historian who should represent the Roman Terminus-worship as a product of the peculiar nature of the Roman Volks-geist, the expression of a specially Roman "Idea," of which the main point was the concept of finiteness, aud the bounding of the land only a secondary consideration 1 What would be thought of a jurist who should ascribe the growth of Roman private property in land to the worship of the god Ter- minus? Yet this is exactly what Lassalle does when he ascribes to the worship of the Manes and Lares, the origin of the growth of the Testament among the Romans, and traces its final cause to Roman mythology. 1 In this way Lassalle arrives at a conclusion as unhistorical as it is illogical. He maintains that the Roman Law of the Twelve Tables, by assigning the heritage to which there was no testa- mentary heir, to the nearest agnate (i.e., nearest of kin on the male side), and in the event of there being no agnate, to the Gens, proved that the Testament, in point of historical time, also ap- peared first, while the law of intestate inheritance was merely a subsequent and subsidiary introduction. As a matter of fact, it is this very Law of the Twelve Tables which, although it reverses the order of events, demonstrates the true course of historical development. It begins by enunciating the newly-introduced legal principle of testamentary freedom — that any one to whom the testator devises his property by testament shall be heir. But should there be no testament, the earlier law of inheritance again i Recent researches have proved that ancestor-worship coincides amongst all people with the transition from the matriarchate to the patriarchate. 78 Ferdinand Lassalle. comes into force, the original law of intestacy; the heir is the nearest agnate, and then the Gens, i.e., the primitive consan- guineous group. The first institution historically appears last in the Twelve Tables, because, being the oldest, it is the most com- prehensive, and as such naturally forms the final court of appeal. How essentially artificial, on the other hand, Lassalle's construc- tion is, we may see from the fact that in order to maintain hia theory that the Roman law of inheritance was based upon the "Concept of the Will," he is diiveu on one occasion to assert that " absolutely no physical idea lies at the basis of the blood- relationship of the Agnates " (Vol. II., p. 339), and to speak of the agnates as a " community of individuals brought about by the bond of force." (Vol. II., 323.) As orthodox old Hegelians, the ancient Romans have, " with cogent consistency of conception," arrived at the " profound proposition of speculative logic " that the unexpressed Will of the individual is the universal Will, whose content is " the universal Will of the people or the State in whose organisation the former is realised." (II., 323.) The testament and the freedom of testacy are older than the Roman State, but intestacy was introduced by the State. One fine day the State appointed agnates and the gentile community as subsidiary heirs, and this, not on the ground of an identical descent, but in its capacity of the State as by law established, as expressions of a common Will. To-day, we know that the exact opposite was the case ; that it is not the State which conferred upon the Gens rights not formerly po3sessed by it, but rather that the State deprived the Gens of one right, and of one office after the other, constantly curtailed its functions, and that it was only with the disintegration of the gentile community, and with its internal dissolution, that the State, and with and through the State, the freedom of the testator, became possible. As Lassalle knew nothing about the Gens, he, like all the jurists who at his time, and before him, dealt with the original Roman law of inheritance, was of necessity forced to arrive at false conclusions. But instead of coming nearer the truth than " The System of Acquired Rights!' 1 79 his predecessors, he seems rather to he further from it than they were. Bent upon constructing things out of the speculative con- cept, he cuts himself off from the possibility of recognising their actual connection. The celebrated Professor of Jurisprudence, Edward Gaus — also a Hegelian — had represented the Eoman laws of intestacy and of inheritance by testament as two antag- onistic ideas, with no sort of common intellectual origin, and had endeavoured to explain them as a historical class difference be- tween the Patricians and Plebeians. Erroneous as this interpreta- tion is, the idea underlying it is right, i.e., that we here have to do with a fundamental antagonism, and that the two opposing concepts of law sprang up upon different historical soils. Lassalle, however, in this very interpretation, discovered a relapse into the "error of the historical school," which assumes that " what should be deduced from the Idea" is "an external and historical event." (Vol. IT., p. 318.) And, on the other hand, lassalle declares it is a "fundamental error," when the other jurists start from the assumption that " the Roman law of intestacy is, in its Idea, a true family law." As a matter of fact, it is nothing else. Only that the family here considered does not coincide merely with the Roman family, but comprehended the wider gentile group. 1 We cannot here enter more fully into this question, but even from what has already been said, we may see that the edifice so ingeniously raised by Lassalle rested upon an absolutely unten- able foundation. Close and severely logical as the argument is, dexterous and witty as the analysis is, shrewd as many of Lassalle's i The Romans, too, use the word familia not simply to denote the indi- vidual family, gathered into one house under one head, but also for the more or less loose union of the gentile group. A passage from Ulpian, quoted by Lassalle, explicitly distinguishes between the ' ' familia " in the narrower sense (jure propria) and the " familia" in the wider sense ( communi jure). To the latter "all those belong . . . who have sprung from the same family and the same gentile group." (See "System," etc., II., p. 343.) ToLassalle the above passage is a further proof that the Roman law of intestacy was not a family inheritance. " For," says he, among other things, " surely no one would represent the laws of inheritance of the gentile group as a family law of inheritance. '' 8o Ferdinand Lassalle. commentaries are, that which he meant the whole of his book to demonstrate with regard to the Roman law of inheritance he has not demonstrated. The Eoman Idea of immortality is not the basis of the Roman Testament, but its ideological garment : it explains its form, but not its content. This still remains even when the re- ligious background disappears. And to my thinking, the many forms and formalities upon which the Romans made the validity of Testaments contingent, were but a further proof that the Testa- ment was not, as Lassalle thinks, the earlier, but on the contrary the later institution, and that probably — as with the Germans also, after they had adopted the Roman law — it was, for a long time, the exception, while intestate inheritance was still the rule. But what is the practical application which Lassalle draws from his theory that the Testament is only to be explained by the Roman Idea of immortality — i.e., the perpetuation of the sub- jectivity of the Will after death — and that with this explanation it must " as a concept" stand or fall? That after the Roman immortal- ity of the Will had yielded to the Christian Idea of the immortality of the Spirit, an immortality no longer based upon the external world, but upon the " Spirit withdrawn into itself," the modern law of Testament was nothing more than a huge mistake, a " compact theoretical impossibility?" (II., 494.) This brings us to the first part of his work, of which the second, despite its being complete in itself, is, after all, only a kind of appendix. The first part of the " System der Erworbenen Rechte " bears the sub-title : " Die Theorie der Erworbenen Rechte, und der Kollision der Gesetze." 1 In it Lassalle endeavours to establish a legal and scientific principle which shall once for all determine under what circumstances, and how far laws may be retroactive without violating the idea of right itself. In other words, where a new law or right comes into collision with an old law or right, when the former and when the latter is to be final ; when a right is to be respected really as an " acquired " right, when it is to be made retroactive without any further ado. In answering this question, the weakness of Lassalle's method 1 " The Theory of Acquired Rights, and the Conflict of Lawsi" " The System of Acquired Rig/its." of investigation mentioned above is less noticeable, while all its ad- vantages, the acuteness of perceptive thought, the comprehension — within certain limits — of the historic moment, together with a revolutionary audacity in following out an idea to its ultimate con- sequences, stand out conspicuously. And thus the result is far more satisfactory than in his inquiry into the nature of Eoman Law. At whatever value we may estimate such inquiries into legal-philosophic themes, it certainly cannot be denied that Lassalle solves the question stated above in such a way that both jurist and revolutionist comes by his own. And that is surely no inconsiderable performance. Lassalle begins by laying down the two following propositions as premisses : " (llern throne from the now galling yoke of the squirearchy east of the Elbe, and of the bureaucracy. Yet this, compared with the pro- gramme as formulated by Lassalle, must tmdoubtedly seem the lesser evil to the King. '■' By special request," Lassalle published this lecture, which he had repeated at three other Progressist meetings — a proof that the Progressist electors saw nothing questionable about it. In the meantime the elections to the Landtag had resulted in a brilliant victory of the Progressists over the Government, and everyone was waiting with bated breath to. see how, under these conditions, the conflict between the two would work out further. In the spring of 1882, Lassalle also gave a second lecture in Berlin — in the Artisans' Club of the Oranienburger suburb, the engineers' quarter of Berlin. He called it : " On the Special Con- nection between the Idea of the Working-class Estate and the Present Historical Period." This second lecture also he had care- fully prepared. And if it is not altogether above criticism in The Struggle for a Constitution in Prussia, 101 certain details — its very title provokes criticism — it is yet one of the best, if not the best, of Lassalle's speeches. Language as clear as it is beautiful; argument terse, flowing, nowhere extra- vagaut, and yet never dry ; a systematic, progressive development of the fundam:ntal idea, from proposition to proposition, are its excellencies of manner; while its matter — w ith, as we have said, some exceptions — may be taken as an excellent introduction into the world of thought of Socialism. And it in nowise detracts from its value if I call this speech a paraphrase of the '• Communist Mani- festo," adapted to the time and circumstances under which it was delivered. In the main it develops in detail what the Manifesto, in its historical portion, had already laid down on broad lines. It is true that Hegelian ideology and the juridical point of view still run through the argument, but along with these the note of the economic basis of history is also sounded. That the working- class, thanks to its class conditions in modern bourgeois society, is the really revolutionary class, the class destined to place Society upon a new basis — the fundamental idea of the ''Communist Manifesto," — is also the leading idea of the " Arbeiter Programm," 1 under which title the lecture was. subsequently published. Only for Lassalle, this principle at once crystallises into juridical con- cepts, aud becomes impregnated with ideological notions. Lassalle's constant use, both in the title and all through his lecture, of the term " Arbeiterstand," (working-class estate), might be looked upon as a mere concession to a common phrase, to which only a pedant could take exception. To his honour it must, however, be said, that Lassalle never set about his choice of words lightly. It was not a mere acceptance of a popular phrase that induced him to speak of the " working-class estate," of the " fourth estate," but rather the consequence of hi.s essentially juridical point of view. It is the same reversion to the juridical method that makes him derive the concept of the bourgeois not from the actual power which the possession of capital confers, and which is due solely to its economic effects and forces, but from the juridical and political privileges which the bourgeois enjoys or claims on 1 " Worker's Programme,'' 102 Ferdinand Lassalle. the strength of his property. Instead of clearly pointing out the fundamental difference between the modern bourgeois and the feudal lord of the Middle-Ages, he, on the contrary, obliterates it, and only then admits that the possessor of capital becomes a bourgeois when he lays claim to the State and legal position of a feudal lord. (See pp. 20 22, " Arbeiter Programm," 1st Edition.) And, as always, logical even in his error, Lassalle represents the class or census electoral system as the distinctive feature of bourgeois society, represents it, that is, not as a, but as the dis- tinctive feature. The Prussian three-class electoral system, intro- duced by the feudal-absolutist reaction against the bourgeois .Revolution of 1848, is, according to him, the electoral system of the modern bourgeois Slate. This may, perhaps, have some meaning if the concept bourgeois is confined to the few large capitalists a la Stumm, but then what becomes of the " fourth estate"? As a further characteristic of the bourgeois State thus defined, Lassalle takes the development of the system of indirect taxation as a means for shifting the burden of the taxes upon the non- privileged classes. That every privileged class has the tendency to free itself as far as possible from taxation, may pass uncon- tested, but when Lassalle makes the concept of the class-state depend upon the existence of electoral rights, his theory is at once vitiated by the simple fact that in the very country where direct, and universal franchise has longest existed, the system of indirect taxation is most completely developed. Very questionable also is Lassalle's deduction that of the 97 million thalers paid to the Prussian State in taxes, in the year 1855, only some 1 3 million resulted from direct taxation. He calmly declares the 10 million thalers of laud tax an indirect tax, on the ground that it is not paid by the owners of the land, but is shifted by them on to the price of corn. This shifting was, however, by no means an easy matter, so long as the frontiers had not been closed against importations from abroad by means of Protectionist duties. For a long time, indeed, the land tax did affect landed property as a fixed charge ; such, too, it was felt to be by the landed pro- The Struggle for a Constitution in Prussia. 103 prietors, and as such it was treated in cases of alienation. Nine million thalers' revenue from law costs might be called in* direct taxes, but as the poorest class is by no means the one that most enters into litigation, one cannot — whatever else one may think of the law costs — speak of it as a tax for the relief of the great capitalist. In short, the relative exemption from taxation of the great capitalists is not necessarily a criterion of bourgeois society. This last, indeed, differs from feudal society, by the fact that it is not bound to legalised olass-difPerences by statute, but rather continues to exist in spite of the formal equality of all before the law. Lassalle is more correct when he cites the enforced depositing of newspaper " caution "-money and the newspaper stamp-duty as a proof that " the bourgeoisie maintains the supremacy of its own peculiar privilege and element — i.e., of capital — -with even severer logic than did the nobles in the Middle-Ages, with regard to landed property." Newspaper " caution "-money, and the news- paper stamp-duty were, in Prussia, by no means governmental measures of the bourgeoisie, but of the semi-feudal and bureau- cratic reaction. Lassalle need only have turned to England, where the bourgeoisie had reached the highest point of develop- ment, in order to convince himself that, even without the petty measures of a retrograde system of government, the press may be- come, and that to a greater extent than in Prussia, " a privilege of the great capitalist." Right as it of course was to speak out against the methods of political repression, it is yet another proof of Lassalle's juridical bent of mind, that when he wishes to de- pict the effect of bourgeois supremacy upon the condition of the press, he refers exclusively to formal legal institutions, and abso- lutely ignores the influence of the economic factors. Finally, his ideology leads him to sing psean to the State, to the " Concept of the State." The " fourth estate " has " quite another, quite a different conception of the ethical aim of the State from the bour- geoisie." The State-concept of the bourgeoisie, Lassalle declares, is that of the Liberal Free-Trade School, according to which the sole 104 Ferdinand Lassalle. funotion of the State is to protect the personal freedom and pro- perty of the individual. But this, he says, is a " night-watchman idea." x History is "a struggle with Nature ; with the misery, the ignorance, the poverty, the helplessness, and, therefore, with the enslavement of all kinds that hemmed us in when the human race first appeared at the beginning of History. A progressive victory over this help- lessness — that is the development of freedom that History shows us." To accomplish the development of the human race towards freedom, this is the true mission of the State. The State is " the unity of individuals in an ethical whole," its object being " to make it possible for the individuals, by means of this unity, to attain such ends, such a stage of existence, as they as individuals never could attain; to enable them to attain a degree of culture, power, and freedom, that would be, to everyone of them as individuals,absolutely unattainable." And further, the object of the State is "to bring man to positive expansion and progressive development, in other words, to fashion the human destiny — i.e., the culture of which the human race is capable — into actual being;" it is "the education and development of man to freedom." So clearly is this "the true and higher mission " of the State that this mission " has been more or less carried out by the State through all time, by the force of circumstance, and even without its own will, even un- consciously, even against the will of its leaders." And the working-class " estate," the lower classes of Society generally, thanks to the helpless position in which its members, as individuals, are placed, bad " the profound instinct that this i3j and must be, the destiny of the State." And a State dominated by the idea of the working-class estate, would make this " moral uature " of the State its mission, " with the clearest perception and complete consciousness," and " would bring about an elevation of thought, the development of a sum of happiness, J Lassalle here refers to the idea of the Manchester School (of Germany), that the duties of Government were not to exceed those of a. constable of the watch, The Struggle for a Constitution in Prussia. 105 culture, well-being, and freedom, uuparalleled in the history of the world." This interpretation contains a great error in relation to the his- torical moment : despite all the emphasis laid upon the histori- cal changes of State and of Society, the State itself is represented as being in its concept and essence one for all time, as having had from the beginning a definite aim underlying its " idea," an " idea " occasionally misunderstood, only partially understood, or entirely ignored, and which must therefore be helped to a com- plete recognition. The concept of the State is, so to say, an eternal one. In this sense, Lassalle quotes a passage from an address of Baeckh's, in which the celebrated antiquarian appeals from " the State-concept of Liberalism," to the " antique culture " which has now, once for all, become the inalienable foundation of the German mind, and which has given birth to the idea that the concept of the State must be so far enlarged that " the State shall be the institution in which the whole virtue of mankind shall realise itself." Comprehensible, and, within certain limits, justifiable as was this protest against the theory, at that time so cock-a-hoop, of absolute social and political laisser oiler, laisser faire, Lassalle here overshot the mark. The " State " of the ancients was based upon conditions of society differing so fundamentally from those of the present time, that the ideas of the ancients about the State are as little applicable to the present time as their ideas about labour, money, and the family. Like these ideas, the ancient idea of the State only supplies material for comparative research, not for a theory capable of modern application. ^ If, according to Boeckh, the State-concept as understood by Liber- alism involved the danger of a " modern barbarism," so the graft- ing upon the society of to-day, of the State-concept as understood by the ancients, involves the danger of a modern State-slavery. Then, too, Lassalle is quite wrong in what he says of the effects of the State. These have, indeed, greatly differed at different periods. Immense strides were made in civilisation before a State existed, and great civilising missions were fulfilled without either help from, or opposition to the State of that time. In the 106 Ferdinand Lassalle. main, no doubt, the State has aided the advance of mankind, but it has also often been a hindrance to it. Of course, Lassalle did not look upon the matter from so un- historical a standpoint as to desire the restoration of the State- concept of the ancients unchanged — nor had Bceckh any such idea either — but the direct derivation of the State-concept from theirs made matters not better, but worse. The cult of the State as such, means the cult of every State, and even if Lassalle's democratic, and socialist views made it impossible for him to sup- port directly the existing State, it did not prevent this cult from being exploited later on by the advocates of the existing State in its interest. Indeed, the Achilles heel of all ideology, of all theory built upon preconceived concepts, is that, no matter how revolutionary in intention, they are really always in danger of be- ing transformed into a glorification of existing, or of past institu- tions. Lass;dle's concept of the State is the bridge that was one day to bring together the Republican Lassalle and the men fight- ing for absolute monarchy, the Revolutionist Lassalle and the out- and-out reactionaries. Philosophical absolutism has at all times had a tendency inclining it to political absolutism. Thus this lecture, despite its merits, in other respects contains in germ all those errors that came out in the subsequent Lassallean movement. In conclusion, Lassalle exhorts the workers to steep themselves in the thought of the great historical mission of their class, and to find in it the duty of taking up an eutirely new position. " The vices of the oppressed, the idle indifference of the thought- less, and even the harmless frivolity of the smail-minded, no longer become you now. You are the rock upon which the Church of the present is to be built ! " As I have said, Lassalle had this lecture printed. Cautious as he had been, carefully as he avoided drawing any immediate political conclusions, the Berlin police — especially as Lassalle's political views were well known to them — at once scented what the lecture was really driving at. They seized the whole edition of 3000 copies brought out by a Berlin publisher, and instituted The Struggle for a Constitution in Prussia. 107 criminal proceedings against Lassalle. The pamphlet had ap- peared, and had been confiscated at the end of June. On the 4th November, 1862, the Public Prosecutor, Von Schelling — a son of the philosopher Schelling — applied to the Berlin Stadtgericht for permission to proceed against Lassalle for " exciting the non- possessing classes to hatred and contempt of the possessing class." On the 17th November, the Court decided to grant the request, and on the 16th January, 1863, the case came before the Court of the First Instance. In spite of 3, truly brilliant defence, in which Lassalle proved himself superior both to the Crown Attorney and to the President of the Court, and in which he especially flagel- lated the former, he was sentenced to four months' imprisonment. He appealed, and had at least this satisfaction, that the Kammer- gerieht commuted the sentence of imprisonment to one of a com- paratively small fine. The confiscation of the pamphlet was certainly upheld, but Lassalle in the meantime had a new edition published by Meyer and Zeller at Zurich. Meyer and Zeller also published the three pamphlets on the trial before the Court of First Instance. Of these pamphlets the first consisted of Lassalle's Defence, (published under the separate title of "Die Wissenschaft and die Arbeiter" 1 ); the second, the verbatim report of the pleadings at the trial ; and the third, a rather tedious criticism of the sentence of the Court of First Instance ; and finally, under the title of " Die Indirekten Steuern end die Lage der Arbeitenden Klassen," 2 his defence be- fore the Higher Court. We shall return to the consideration of these pamphlets later on. Here, and now, we must go back to the time in which the lecture itself was delivered, the spring of 1862. It is easy to understand that the speech, as such, should not, at first, have created any particular sensation. Greatly as its actual contents differed from the kind of fare that the Pro- gressist orators were at this time setting before the Berlin workers, its exoteric political tendency differed but little from theirs. Radical phrases, allusions to a new edition of the 1848 Revolution, 1 " Science and the Workers." " Indirect Taxation, and the Position of the Working-Classes," ioS Ferdinand Lassalle, attacks upon the indirect taxes, etc., were plentiful enough in the speeches of dozens of Progressist democratic orators. Indeed, as the latter interlarded their speeches with denunciations of the Government, these usually sounded far more radical than Lassalle's address, with its almost completely academic form. When the Philistine does side with the opposition, he can bluster with the best of them. As a speech, the " Worker's Programme " did not produce any great effect either upon the workers or upon the middle-class. And so, in this same spring, Lassalle was elected by the Berlin " Philosophical Society," of which he was a member, to deliver the address at their forthcoming celebration, on the 19 th May, of the centenary of the Philosopher Fichte. Neither his social nor his political radicalism, which, of course, were well known in these circles, gave offence at this time. As the majority of middle- classdom was with the opposition, its savants also were still i allowed to indulge in ideology. Sis months before, in the "Democratic Studies,'' Lassalle had celebrated Fichte as the Apostle of the German Eepublic, and to entrust him now with delivering the address at the celebra- tion was really nothing less than a ratification of that essay. And Lassalle took care to turn this opportunity to account, and to repeat what he had then said in another form. The speech is entitled " Die Philosophie Fichte's, und die Be- deutung des Deutschen Volks-geists." 1 And it is not only in its representation of Fichte's philosophical political ideas that it is entirely ideological. Lassalle himself here again falls into the most approved old Hegelian ideolog}'. The German Volks-geist is the metaphysical Volks-idee {i.e., National-idea), and its meaning consists in this : that the Germans have the great historical sig- nificanca of creating for it, from the " pure spirit," " not only a real actuality," but even " the very locality of its existence, its arena. . . . Because here the existence is begotten of the ' pure spirit ' itself, intermingled with nothing historical, natura 1 , 1 " The Philosophy of Fichte, ami the Significance of the German Volte- c/eist." The Struggle for a Constitution in Prussia. 109 special, it can only be the actual picture of the pure Thought, and herein bears the necessity of that determination towards the highest and most perfect spirituality of freedom that Fichte predicts for it." And what Fichte had philosophically enunciated in his loneliness as a thinker, this, making good another of his axioms, had already " become a religion," and beat " under the popular and dogmatic name of German Unity in every noble German heart." To represent the striving for German unity as the result of the " pure spirit, intermingled with nothing historical " — this outdid even the ideology of Liberalism. And so it appears that this address, though worked oat with rigid logic and consistency of thought, entirely failed to impress the public gathered to hear it. As B. Becker tells us, the audience, to the intense annoyance of Lassalle, gradually left the room (where the speechifying went on) " to make for another, where an appetising meal was spread." Becker forgets to add that the audience did not consist only of members of the Philosophical Society, but chiefly of guests in- vited by them ; people who, for the most part, attend such meet- ings because it is " the thing." Lassalle published this speech also in separate form, and sent it, together with the "Julian Schmidt," and the " Lecture on the Essence of the Constitution," through Lothar Bucher to Mars. He had "begun a little of practical political agitation," he writes, on the 9th June, to Marx. " Thus I delivered the Constitution speech to four associations. And, besides, I have written a much longer address on the Worker's Estate, and delivered it before a workman's club." This is the " Workei's Programme." " And I have now made up my mind," he adds, " to have it published ; it is already in the press. As soon as it is ready I'll send it you." Later on in the letter he Jagain refers to the fact, that owing to his intense pre-occupation with other things during the last three years, the national-economic matters in his mind had become " well-nigh fossilised." Not until <; it had all become fluid again '' would he proceed to a second reading of Marx' book, " A Criticism of Political Economy," and at the same time to a review of it, no Ferdinand Lassalle, rmi to the carrying out of his own economic work — " this last, it is true, will take a very long time." Moreover, this programme would, in any case, be interrupted by a two months' journey, as he could not stand a summer in Berlin. In July he would go to Switzerland, or come to London first, and then go to Switzerland. He decided in favour of the latter. But before this he once again wrote to Marx : " Dear Marx, — The bearer of this is Captain Schweigert, who has served with distinction under Garibaldi, and especially under my friend Rustow. He is the most honest and reliable fellow in the world. C'est un homme d'action. He is at the head of the Wehr- Vereine (Arms-Club) that he has organised from Coburg, and is now proceeding to Loudon to try and raise the money for getting 3000 muskets, which he requires for the Wehr- Vereine. I've no need to tell you how desirable this would be. So be good enough to put him in communication with people from whom he can obtain money for this purpose, or any kind of assistance to- wards this end. Do your best. The probability of my coming to London grows. — Thine, " F. Lassalle. "Berlin, 19/6/62." The Wehr- Vereine being organised from Coburg, belonged to the camp of the "National Club," which had its headquarters in that town. It is evident that Lassalle had not yet by any means entirely broken with this Club. His emphasis on the " homme d'action,'' and his great interest in the acquisition of 3000 muskets are a further confirmation of what has been said above with regard to Lassalle's revolutionary plans. With two short letters, written in London itself, that refer to visits and to an excursion to be undertaken together, the letters which I have from Lassalle to Marx end. It would, however, be a mistake to conclude from this that the visit to London had led to a rupture between the two. Such a rupture never occurred. But it is very possible that in talking things over with Marx, The Struggle for a Constitution in Prussia. 1 1 1 Lassalle understood more clearly thau lie had hitherto done the fundamental difference of the standpoints of the two men. At any rate, after Lassalle's return to Berlin, in the autumn of 18G2, the correspondence entirely ceased. All the more closely did La«salle attach himself to Bucher, who later also brought him into relation with Rodbertus. At the end of the summer of 1862, it seemed for a moment as if the Prussian Government were going to adopt a more concili- atory attitude towards the Chamber. Negotiations were again carried on until the King suddenly informed the Chamber in the bluntest way that he would not consent to any concessions with regard to the shortening of the term of military service, and that he felt no inclination whatever to recommend a special grant for the unconstitutional procedure with regard to the re-organisation of the army. To this the Chamber replied that by 308 votes to 11 it had rejected the demmd of the Government to include the expenditure for the re-organisation of the army among the ordinary items of expenditure in the budget. In order to break down the resistance of the majority, the King now summoned the Prussiau Ambassador to France, Otto von Bismarck, who was just then in Berlin, to take the place of Herr von der Heydt in the Ministry. In all probability the churlish way in which the King in his message had laid stress upon his sovereign privileges, was the result of an understanding with Bismarck. Bismarck, who had appeared in the "United Landtag" of 1847, and in the Prussian National Assembly of 1849, as the Hotspur of the feudal squirearchy, had, in the meantime, developed into the " modern statesman." He had thrown his landowner ideologies overboard, in order the more effectually to guard the "consolidated land-owning" interests. He had given up the absolutism proclaimed before the March days, thereby to assure the monarchy an even more advantageous position by saddling the Chamber with the responsibility — and only the responsibility of the demands of the monarchy. In short, he had adopted the maxims of that system of government known as Bonapartism, which, when it speaks of democracy, means governmental H2 Ferdinand Lassalle. violence, and which proclaims its care for the well-being of the poor, when it is meditating a campaign of taxation against the pockets of the workers. From Eussian diplomacy he had learnt how one can maintain an absolutist Government and intrigue under the rose with revolutionists ; and from French diplomacy that one must always accuse an opponent of a dis- honourable action at the very moment when oneself is contem- plating exactly the same action. Besides this, he made a specialty of the trick of all astute diplomatists and sharpers, of displaying, on certain occasions an astounding " bluntness," so that the next time they may so much the more successfully make use of language in order not to speak the truth. It was with this " bluntness " that Bismarck made his debut in the Chamber, and naturally his German programme was not believed in. His declaration in the Budget Commission that the German question would only be solved through " blood and iron,'' merely intensified the opposition. The House stuck to its resolu- tion to vote nothing to the Government until its constitutional rights had been acknowledged by the latter, whereupon Bismarck prorogued the House with the declaration that, for the time being, the Government would take the money wherever they found it. Meanwhile, Bismarck's position was by no means a very secure one. He certainly had the force of thcGovernment — i.e., organised force — at his back, while the Chamber had nothing but " public opinion" on its side. But he knew perfectly well that he could not " sit " upon the Prussian bayonettes. Unequivocal success in his foreign policy, likely to win over the ex-" Gothaer," i.e., the weak-kneed Kleindeutsch Liberals to the Government, was, for the time being, not to be reckoned upon. So he had to seek else- where for allies against the Progressist party. It was about this time, in the autumn of 1862, that at various working-men's clubs, which had either been actually started by the Progressists, or were supported by them, the notorious " working- man," Eichler, suddenly appeared. He accused the Progressist Party of incompetence, and inveighed against the Schulze-Delitzsch co-operative associations as useless to the workers. The " self-help," The Struggle for a Constitution in Prussia. 1 1 3 about which the Liberals were making such a fuss, was no good ; the State alone could help the workers. Eichler, who declared that his employer had dismissed him on account of his adverse criticism of Schulze's " self-help " ideas, nevertheless found means to travel to Leipzig, where the local Working-men's Club was eagerly discussing the summoning of a General Working-men's Congress for the purpose of founding an independent working-men's organisa- tion. He tried to induce the Leipzig Central Committee to call the Congress at Berlin, and on their coming to closer quarters with him, at last, in the heat of the discussion, came out with the declara- tion, that he knew for certain that the Prussian Government was willing to help the workers, especially with the starting of pro- ductive co-operative associations. He could inform them also that Herr von Bismarck was prepared to give 30,000 thalers for start- ing a productive co-operative machine-making association — the Berlin machine-makers being then, and for a long time after, the picked battalions of the Progressist army ! Of course the workers would have to make up their minds to turn their backs upon the Progressist Party, as this was the party of the bourgeoisie, the greatest enemy of the workers. In this Herr Eichler failed completely, for the people in Leipzig who were organising the Workers' Congress desired anything rather than to oblige the Prussian Government by attacking the Progressists in the rear. Herr Eichler went home again without accomplishing his purpose, and seems to have done little in Berlin either. When called to account for his notoriously luxurious mode of life, which was so little in keeping with an " out-of-work," he made mysterious allusions to a rich aristocratic lady who had taken a fancy to him, and as he was a good-looking fellow, this was not altogether improbable. Eichler then disappeared from the scene, to turn up later on as a Prussian police official. When, sixteen years after, at the sitting of the Reichstag of the 16th September, 1878, Bebel twitted Bismarck — meantime made a Prince — with the Eichler " mission," Bismarck, the next day, tried to shake off Eichler by taking advantage of a slip of Bebel's as to date (Bebel had spoken of September instead of October, 1 14 Ferdinand Lassalle. 1862), as the period of Eiohler's Leipzig performance. But trusting to the effect of this dodge, he was betrayed into the confession that later on Eichler " made demands upon me for services he had not rendered me," and that " it was only then that he remembered that Herr Eichler had been in the service of the police, and that he had sent him in reports." (Sec the official ver- batim report on the debate on the Anti-Socialist Law, 1878, page 85, published under the title of " Die Sozial-democratie vor dem deutschen Reichstag." 1 ) In other words, the supposed aristo- cratic lady, or as the Leipzig Vollcstaat once upon a time drasti- cally put it, " the aristocratic strumpet," turned out to be the Berlin " Scotland Yard." About this time — i.e., after Bismarck had prorogued the Landtag on the 13th October, 1862 — Lassalle gave his second address, " Was nun 1 " 2 In this he declares that events have justified the contentions of his first address. The Kreuz - Zeitung (the organ of the Squirearchy), the War Minister, Von Boon, and th.e actual President of the Ministry, Von Bismarck, had confirmed his theory that constitutional ques- tions are questions of force. Relying upon the force at its dis- posal, the Government had gone on disregarding the decisions of the Chamber. It was now less a question of how to assure the continuance of the Constitution of 1850 — in a portion of whose provisions the people had no interest whatever — than a question of maintaining the right of the Chamber to vote supplies, and the making of parliamentary government a reality, for " upon it, and it alone, does the existence of every true constitutional Government depend." Should they refuse to pay the taxes? No, answers Lassalle. This is, in itself, an effective weapon only in the hands of a people which, like the English, has on its side the many powerful means of organised force. Such a step would only be • wise if it were meant to provoke a general rising. But of this " it was to be hoped no one, under the present circumstances, would dream." The only way was to say what the actual facts 1 "Social Democracy in the German Reichstag." 2 "What next?" The Struggle for a Constitution in Prussia. 1 1 5 were. As soon as the Chamber re-assembled " it must say what the real facts were." This was " the most powerful, political method." The Chamber must make it impossible for the Govern- ment to go on governing with mere sham constitutionalism. As soon as the Chamber re-assembled it must, at once, press a vote to the effect that so long as the Government went on violating the Constitution, it would not, by continuing to sit and to legislate, play into the hands of that Government, would not help to main- tain' the mere semblance of a constitutional state of affairs, and that therefore " it would adjourn for an indefinite period, aye, until the Government gav9 proof that it would not continue to ignore the vote of the Chamber against supplies." When once the Chamber had passed such a vote, the Government would be beaten. Dissolution would be useless to the Government, since the members would be re-elected on the same lines. But without a Chamber it could not govern. Its credit, its reputation, its in- fluence abroad would be so seriously damaged that sooner or later it would be forced to give in. But there was no other way of terminating the conflict. Continuing to sit and refusing to vote other, or, indeed, all Government supplies, would only accustom psople and Government to the pleasant habit of disregarding the votes of the Chamber. It would be still worse if the Chamber consented to a compromise possibly as the price for agreeing to the two years military term of service. No ; no surrender in the constitutional principle here at stake. The more obstinate the Government proved, the greater would be its humiliation, when it found itself forced to give in. The Government would all the more recognise the social form of the citizen as the superior force, if, after veering round, it had been forced to bow before the people and the Chamber. And, therefore, no "reconciliation-twaddle, gentlemen." No new compromise with the old absolutism, but rather " the hand at the throat, the knee on the breast." In this address, Lassalle, on the whole, assumes a conciliatory attitude towards the Progressist Party. " B'or the sake of unity " he will suppress all these serious accusations against them that he has at heart. He only attacks the Volks Zeitung and its n6 Ferdinand Lassalle. backers, for their policy of saying that which is not. These "poor creatures,'' in their attempts to "lie" the Government into a constitutional one, were largely responsible for the present condi- tion of things. But " peace to the past, gentlemen ! " Whether Lassalle really in his heart felt so peaceably inclined, whether he really believed the Progressists would accept his suggestion, or whether all this talk of reconciliation was only rhetorical flourish meant to give him a free hand later on as against the Progressists, is difficult to say. Both may be true. That Lassalle was by no means disinclined to work with the Progressists we have already seen. Mauy of his personal relations, indeed, must have made such an alliance seem desirable, while from the theoretical standpoint, nothing could, under the circumstances, be advanced against it. On the other hand, however, it had become more and more doubtful whether the Progressists would have anything to do with him, and whether they would allow him to exercise that influence upon their tactics, to which he thought himself entitled. CHAPTER VL BREACH WITH THE PROGRESSIST PARTY.— THE " OPEN REPLY letter"; ITS POLITICAL PORTION. Meantime, however, the Progressists did not accept the terms of the peace— i.e., the method of fighting recommended by Lassalle. And looking at it from their point of view one cannot blame them. Lassalle's proposition was very good if one was prepared to force things to a head at once, and was in a position to answer a coup d'etat — and a coup d'e'tat was the only resort these tactics left the Government — by a revolution. But the Progressists had not yet progressed so far, and, therefore, preferred the dilatory method. Without a revolution in immediate reserve, the volun- tary renunciation of the tribune of the Chamber must end in that notorious " passive resistance " of which Lassalle himself quite rightly made fun. By persistently refusing to vote supplies, one could "say what is '' quite as loudly and as drastically, could stimulate public opinion as effectively as, or even more effectively than, by means of an indefinite prorogation, which would, into the bargain, give the Government a semblance of right in their viola- tion of the Constitution. But this was the main tactical idea of the Progressists — to make the Government above all else appear as the representative of Might against Right. " Their chief spokes- men," says B. Becker, very justly, " were for the most part men of the juridical and legal profession, accustomed therefore to the law's delays, and inclined to look upon the struggle between the parliamentary majority and the Government as a protracted legal struggle." And so they again accused Lassalle of placing, like the Govern- ment, Might above Right. And now — not as Becker, and after him all the " historians " of the Lassallean movement say, at the time of 117 1 1 8 Ferdinand Lassalle. the first pamphlet on the " Constitution " — Lassalle wrote his essay, " Might and Right," in which he openly threw down the gauntlet to the Progressist Party. It was easy for him to show in a few words the whole absurdity of this accusation, and to prove to the Progressists to boot that their idol, Schwerin, whose declaration that in Prussia " Right goes before Might," they applauded so loudly, had taken part in a round dozen violations of Right where Might went before Right. " No one in the Prussian State has the right to speak of ' Right ! ' " he exclaims, " save the Democracy — the old and true Democracy. For it alone has always held to the Right, and has never con- descended to any compromise with Might." And : " All Right is with the Democracy alone, and with it alone loill be Might ! " This declaration of war, sent in the form of a statement to the Radical Berlin Reform, a paper for which Lassalle, so late as June, 1862, had put in a good word with Marx, was refused insertion in its columns, and the Vossische Zeilung did the same. The latter also refused to insert the article as a paid advertisement, where- upon Lassalle had it published as an "Open Reply Letter " at Zurich. That the choice of this place for the publication really justified the doubts of the Vossische Zeitung "on account of the press laws," did not trouble Lassalle. Between the publication of the lecture " Was Nun 1 " (December, 1 862), and the drawing up of the " Open Letter '' (February, 1863), two more months passed. But meantime (in January, 1863), the deputation of the Leipzig Central Committee — consisting of the author, Dr. Otto Dammer, and the working-men, F. W. Fritsche and Julius Vahlteich — had been to Berlin to make one last attempt at co-operation with the leaders of the National Association. Nevertheless, they do not seem to have taken this attempt very seriously They were all three Socialists, and were anxious to get out of the Progressist leaders' own mouths the declaration that they would not hear of an independent working-men's movement, but wanted to keep it in the leading strings of bourgeois Liberal- ism. And their hopes in this respect were not disappointed. "With regard to the question of admission to the National Associa- Breach zvith the Progressist Party. Ii<5 tion, they were given the classical answer, already mentioned, that the workers should consider themselves " honorary members " of the National Association. With regard to the question of the franchise, Unruh, Schulze-Delitzsch, etc., were themselves divided, and, moreover, did not look upon it as a burning one. The three- class electoral system had returned such an excellent Chamber, that surely it might be left alone for a while. That the excellent — i.e., anti-governmental — Chamber was wholly the result of the special conditions of the time never occurred to these gentle- men. The young Berlin Democrat, and subsequent Progressist mem- ber of the Chamber, Ludwig Lowe, directed the attention of the deputation to Ferdinand Lassalle, and, on their return to Leipzig, they entered into communication with him. It is easy to under- stand how much this must have strengthened his resolve to with- draw his " Peace to the past, gentlemen." When he issued his Open Letter, " Eight and Might," it had already been arranged between himself and the Leipzig Committee that the latter were to ask him, in an official communication, to set forth his opinions upon the mission of the working-class movement, and the ques- tion of the associations — {i.e., the co-operative societies) — in any form he might think fit, and that this form should be that of a fly-sheet. The Leipzig people — i.e., the active elements in the Working-men's Association — knew perfectly well what they were driving at ; what they were still undetermined about was less the essence of the action to be undertaken than the programme of that action. It was by no means " the consciousness of their own want of lucidity," as Bernhard Becker, with his claim to speak truth above everything, says in his " History " of the Las- sallean movement — which induced the Leipzig Committee, in an " Appeal to the German Workers," dated 10th February, to declare themselves simultaneously in favour of expediting the summoning of the Workers' Congress, and against over-precipitancy in the matter. The Congress was to be held as soon as possible, but not too soon to prevent Lassalle's answer from first produc- ing its effect. It is only Becker's personal animosity towards Dr. 120 Ferdinand Lassalle. Otto Dammer that here induces him to falsify history, and to represent the Committee " as beating a retreat " when nothing was farther from their thoughts. At the same sitting in which the appeal just referred to was drawn up, the Committee decided to write the following letter, which was duly forwarded the next day, to Lassalle : — " To Herr Ferdinand Lassalle, in Berlin. " Most honoured Sir, — Your pamphlet, ' Ueber den beson- deren Zusammenhang der gegenwartigen Geschichts-Periode mit der Idee des Arbeiterstandes ' (' On the Special Connection between the Present Historical Period and the Concept of the Workers' Estate,') has everywhere here met with great approval from the workers, and the Central Committee have given expression to this feeling in the Arheiter Zeitung. On the other hand, very serious doubts have been expi-essed in many quarters as to whether the associations recommended by Schulze-Delitzsch can really benefit the vast majority of the workers, who possess nothing, and especially whether they could alter the position of the workers in the State to the extent that seems necessary. The Central Com- mittee have expressed their views upon this matter in the Arheiter Zeitung (No. 6) ; they are convinced that co-operative associa- tions cannot, under our present conditions, do enough. But now the views of Schulze-Delitzsch are being everywhere advocated as imperative upon the working-class, by which we mean the most oppressed class of the people, and as no doubt other ways and means than those proposed by Schulze-Delitzsch might be sug- gested for attaining the ends of the working-class movement — i.e., political, material, and intellectual improvement in the con- dition of the workers — the Central Committee, at its sitting of the 10th February, unanimously resolved : " ' To request you to express your views, in any form you think fit, upon the working-class movement, and the tactics it should pursue, and especially upon the value of the associations for the entirely unpropertied classes of the people.' "We attach the greatest value to your views as expressed in Breach ivith the Progressist Party. 121 the above-mentioned pamphlet, and shall therefore be thoroughly able to appreciate any further communications from yourself. Finally, we would ask you to grant our request as soon as possible, as we are very anxious to push forward the development of the working-class movement. " With greeting and good wishes on behalf of the Central Committee for summoning a General German Workers' Congress, " Otto Dammer. "Leipzig, 11th Feb., 1863." The answer to this letter was the " Offene Antwortschreiben an das Zentral-Komitee zur Berufung eines Allgemeiuen Deutschen Arbeiter-Kongresses zu Leipzig," 1 dated the 1st March, 1863. With this work, and its acceptance by the Committee and by the Leipzig Workingmen's Association itself, begins the actual Socialist agitation of Lassalle, and the history of the "General German Working-men's Association." Lassalle's " Open Reply Letter " begins by controverting the idea that working-men do not need to concern themselves with politics. On the contrary, it is just with politics that they must concern themselves, only they must not do this in such a way as to look upon themselves as the "disinterested choir and sounding-board " of the Progressist Party. The proof that the Progressist Party had no such preten- sions is deduced mainly from their conduct during the constitu- tional struggle, and is, therefore, not always equally convincing. When, e.g., Lassalle on p. 4 of the pamphlet reproaches the Progressist Party for having " made .... only .... the asserting the right to vote supplies the essence of their struggle," he forgot that in his lecture, " Was Nun 1 " he had himself denned this as the real and main object of the struggle that must be upheld with the utmost energy. In the same way the Progressist Party might have quoted himself when he counts it a political sin to them that " Their dogma of the supremacy of Prussia forced them to see in the Prussian Government the chosen Messiah of i " Open Reply Letter to the Central Committee for the Summoning of a General German Workers' Congress in Leipzig, by Ferdinand Lassalle." 122 Ferdinand Lassalle. the new birth of Germany. Yet there is not a single German Government, including Hesse, that is politically inferior to that of Prussia, while there is scarcely a single German Government, includ- ing Austria (! !), that is not considerably superior to that of Prussia." 1 In the main, however, Lassalle was, of course, quite right. The organisation of the workers, as an independent political party with a programme of their own, was a historical necessity. If the development of the political conditions in Germany was such as to make it seem doubtful whether this was the most propitious moment for separating the workers from the army of the Progressist Party, then fighting against absolutism, yet this party had done enough to challenge such a separation. Moreover, the independent organisation of the workers did not as yet, in itself, mean any interference with the aggressive force of the Progressist Party. That this was actually the result is largely due to the Progressist Party itself, and to their extremely narrow attitude towards the new movement. Partly, no doubt, it was also due to the programme which Lassalle gave to this movement. In discussing the " Worker's Programme," we saw what an abstract, purely ideological idea Lassalle combined with the concept " the State." It is no exaggeration to say that of the idea of the State he made a veritable cult. " The immemorial vestal fire of all civilisation, the State, I defend with you against those modern barbarians " (that is the Manchester Party), he ex- claims to the judges of the Berlin Kammergericht (Court of Appeal) in his speech on " Indirect Taxation," and similar passages occur in almost all his speeches. The " State " is the weakest point in the Lassallean doctrine ; in the truest sense of the word, its Achilles heel. The old Hegelian ideological concept of the State induced Lassalle to instil into the workers a semi-mystical reverence for the State at a time when, above all, it behoved them to shake off the police State. It sounds pretty enough when in the " Open Eeply Letter " he cries to the workers : " What, you want to discuss the right of free migration 1 I can only answer you with Schiller's distich : 1 Page 7, 1st Edition. Breach with the Progressist Party. 123 " ' Jahrelang beclien' ieh mich sohou meiner Nase zum Rieohen, Aber hab ieh an sie auch ein erweisliches Recht V" 1 Free migration, and the free choice of handicrafts were things which, in a legislative body, " one dumbly and in silence decrees but no longer debates." As a matter of fact, however, these things, like the right of combination, did not even yet exist, while the workers unquestionably needed them. The true reason why the questions of free migration and free choice of handicraft had to be assigned a relatively insignificant position at a working-men's congress, was because they were also, to a large extent, demands of middle-class Liberalism. But the discussion of them was not superfluous, if only because in working-class ch'cles themselves much confusion as to their meaning still prevailed. Lissalle pushed these questions on one side, because the demand for State-help seemed to him more important than they were. .First for its own sake ; but secondly, because he saw in the project I of State-help the only effective means of rousing the working-class to political action, of at once emancipating them from the yoke of the bourgeois parties, and of stimulating them to the obtaining of their democratic demands. And, no doubt, for the time being, the second reason was the more weighty one to him. It was so also from the position of affairs themselves. The only question was whether the method and the me.uis, by which he sought to attain this end, were the right ones. To convince the workers of the futility of self-help as preached by the bourgeoisie, Lassalle adduced the law of wages in capitalist production as formulated by the classical political economists, and more especially and most emphatically by Kicardo. The " iron aud inexorable law, according to which, under the domination of supply and demand, the average wages of labour remain always reduced to the bare subsistence which, according to the standard of living of a nation, is necessary for the mainten- ance of life and the reproduction of the species." If wages periodi- 1 " For years I have already used my nose for smelling, But have I really a demonstrable right to that organ 1 " 1^4 Ferdinand Lasialle. cally rose above this average, the greater number of marriages and births caused an increase of the working-class population, and with it, of the supply of labour, in consequence of which, wages again sank to their former level. If they fell below this average, emigration, greater mortality among the workers, abstin- ence from marriage, and fewer births, caused a diminution in the supply of labour, in consequence of which wages again went up. Thus " workers and the wages of labour circled for ever round the extreme margin of that which, according to the needs of the time, constitutes the necessary means of subsistence,'' and this " never varies." Therefore, every attempt of the working-class to improve its condition by the individual efforts of its members, was, of neces- sity, condemned to failure. It was equally useless to attempt improving the condition of the workers by means of co-operative societies. So long as these were isolated, they might here and there procure the workers certain advantages. But from the moment these societies became general, the workers would, as producers, again lose in wages what, as consumers, they had gained in the purchase of their goods. Indeed, the condition of the working-class could only be permanently freed from the pressure of this economic law, if the wages of labour were replaced by the possession of the products of labour, if the working-class be- came its own employer. But this could not be done by the start- ing of self-help societies, since these had not the necessary means, and since they were only too often fated to become permeated by the employer-spirit, and its members to be transformed into the " repulsive caricature of working-men with working-men's means, and employers' minds." Great problems could only be solved by great means, and, therefore, societies must be started on a vast scale, and must be extended to the factories of modern industry, but the means to do this — the necessary capital, i.e., the necessary credit — must be provided by the State. This was certainly in no way Communism or Socialism. " Nothing could be further removed from so-called Communism or Socialism than this demand which would allow the working-classes Breach with the Progressist Party. 125 to retain just as to-day their individual freedom, their individual ■mode of life, and the individual reward of labour," and to stand in no other relation to the State, than that through its agency the required capital, i.e., the credit necessary for their societies, would be obtained. Now the true function of the State was to facilitate and help on the great forward march of mankind. " For this the State exists, for this it has always served, and must serve." But " what then is the State ? " And Lassalle cites the figures of the Prussian statistics of incomes for the year 1851, according to which in that year 89 per cent, of the population had had an income of less than 200 thalers, and 1\ per cent, of the population an income of from 200 to 400 thalers, so that, therefore, 96^ per cent, of the population were in a miserable, oppressed condition. " To them, then, gentle- men, to the suffering classes does the State belong, not to us, to the upper classes, for of them it is composed ! What is the State ? I asked, and now you see from a few figures, more easily than you could from big volumes, the answer : Yours, the poorer classes' great asso- ciation, — that is the State." And how to obtain this intervention from the State 1 This would be possible only by means of universal and direct suffrage. Only when the legislative bodies of Germany were returned by universal and direct suffrage, " then, and then only, will you be able to induce the State to undertake this its duty." Universal and direct suffrage ..." is not only your political, it is also your social fundamental principle, the funda- mental condition of all social help." Therefore let the workers organise for a universal German Working-men's Association, whose object should be the introduction into all German countries of universal and direct suffrage. If this demand were taken up by the 89 to 96 per cent, of the population as ^question of the belly, and therefore distributed with the warmth of the belly throughout the whole of the national body, there was no power on earth that could withstand it long. " The whole art of practical success lies iu this : in the concentration of all power, at all times, upon one single point — upon the most important point, and in turning neither to the right nor to the left. Don't look either to the right or to the left, be deaf to all that is not 126 Ferdinand Lassalle. called universal and direct suffrage, or is related thereto, and may lead to it.'' This, roughly speaking, is the informing idea of the " Open Reply Letter," and, at the same time, of the whole Lassallean agitation. For though, of course, this does not represent the whole of Lassalle's aims, nevertheless, to the very end Lassalle held fast to limiting the movement to this one point : " Universal suffrage in order to obtain State help for productive co-operative societies," and this on the principle stated above, that the art of practical success consists in concentrating all forces, at all times, upon one single point. It is important to keep this in mind, for those who wish to estimate rightly Lassalle's labours as an agitator. These labours, in the beginning at least, had been directed towards obtaining an immediate practical result. In the " Open Reply Letter " Lassalle specially refers to the agitation and success of the Anti-Corn Law League in England, and it would seem that he had the English Chartist agitation in his mind also. This is proved by the sentence about the " question of the belly," which recalls the declaration of the Chartist preacher, Stephens : " Chartism, my friends, is not a political question, but a fork and knife question." If we now ask ourselves whether an immediate practical success was actually possible for the agitation thus planned out, under the then existing conditions, I believe I may unhesitatingly answer in the affirmative. That Bismarck later on — it is true only for the North German Reichstag — actually introduced uni- versal suffrage, does not, it seems to me, affect the question. All kinds of circumstances might have prevented this, without alter- ing the fact that Lassalle's calculation was, for the time, a right one. On the contrary. Although the three-class electoral system was retained for the Prussian Landtag, Lassalle's calculation was, all the same, right; it was quite in keeping with the existing political situation. Lassalle knew perfectly well that if in the Progressist camp universal suffrage had many enemies, and, on the whole, only lukewarm friends, the governmental circles, on the contrary, looked more and more askant at the three-class Breach with the Progressist Party. 127 electoral system. The governmental papers spoke quite openly in this sense, and, moreover, as we have seen, Lassalle had plenty of connections to keep him well informed as to which way the wind blew in court and official circles. If the Government would not give way on the constitutional struggle, it could, unless a foreign war came about — and that also might prove fatal — do nothing but emulate Napoleon III. : dissolve the Landtag and introduce another more " democratic " suffrage. And the Government was the more driven to such a step that a strong movement inde- pendent of the Progressists was growing up, which had inscribed upon its banner the abolition of the three-class electoral system. Especially, in view of a possible war, this must have seemed to the Government the best way to escape having a whole nation as an enemy attacking them in the rear. 1 1 We have already, whilst considering his " Italian War," seen with what coolness — quite inconsistent with the rdle of "good patriot" — Lassalle regarded the reaction of external complications upon internal politics. Very characteristic of this attitude is a passage in his pamphlet ' ' Was Nun ? " This passage should be quoted here because the proposition there set forth by Lassalle, practically admits of only two solutions : either a coup d'dtat or a revolution. Thereupon Lassalle, to show how impossible and untenable would be the foreign diplomatic position of the Prussian Government if his proposition were accepted, proceeds : " Let none of you, gentlemen, imagine this is an unpatriotic argument. The politician, like the naturalist, must, once for all, consider all that is, and must, therefore, take into consideration all active forces. The an- tagonism of States, their differences, their jealousies, their diplomatic conflicts, are an active force, and whether for good or for ill must, there- fore, be reckoned with. And in addition to this, gentlemen, how often, in the stillness of my chamber, busied with historical studies, have I had occasion to completely realise the great truth — that it is almost impossible for us to conceive in what a condition of barbarism we, and the world generally, would still be plunged, were it not that the jealousy and antagonism of governments have since all time been an effective means for forcing a government to progress internally. But finally, gentlemen, the existence of .the German people is not of so precarious a nature that a defeat of their governments would constitute a real menace for the existence of the nation. If, gentlemen, you study history carefully, and with true insight, you will see that the strides in civilisation achieved by our 128 Ferdinand Lassalle. From the point of view of immediate, practical success, Lassalle was, then, undoubtedly right. It was possible to obtain universal suffrage in the way worked out by him. Truly for a price. If the Government granted it to avoid being obliged to give in to the Progressist Party, the solution of the constitutional struggle would be, at least, still further postponed. " Be deaf to all that is not called universal and direct suffrage, or is related thereto, and may lead to it," he says in the " Open Reply Letter." Universal suffrage once obtained, it would also — at least, one is logically bound to assume this as self-understood in Lassalle, although he does not expressly say so — solve this question. But was Lassalle's expectation in respect to universal suffrage, as well as the expectations which he based upon this, justified by actual facts ? The only experience obtainable in Lassalle's time with regard to universal and direct suffrage, was furnished by France. And here the results were not particularly in its favour. During people, are so gigantic and powerful, have been such a guidance and exemplar for the rest of Europe, that there can be absolutely no question of the necessity for and indestructibility of our national existence. So that should we be involved in » great foreign war, it is possible that our indi- vidual governments, the Saxon, Prussian, Bavarian, might break down under it, but Phoenix-like there would arise from their ashes, indestruc- tible, that which alone can concern us — the German people ! " (" Was Nun?" 1st Ed., pp. 33-34.) These lines contain much that is true, but two facts must not be lost sight of. First, that important a factor in the progress of nations as the rivalry of governments may have, and undoubtedly has been, it has very frequently acted in the opposite direction, and lias proved an obstacle to progress. We have only to call to mind the two phases of the militarism of to-day. Secondly, although a foreign war would not remove a great civilised people from the ranks of the nations, yet it might so seriously affect them in their vital interests, that war is a contingency we may take into consideration, but should not speculate upon. In the passage quoted, Lassalle only does the former, but as its concluding sentence, and his letters show, he was not disinclined towards the latter course also — a not uncommon habit, by the way, but not on that account the less reprehen- sible. Breach with .the Progressist Party. 1 29 the February Republic, Universal suffrage had certainly sent a number of Socialists to the National Assembly, but the voice of these Socialists had been drowned by that of the representatives of the different bourgeois parties, and universal suffrage had so little prevented Bonaparte's coup d'e'tat^ that, on the contrary, Bonaparte had been able to make the coup d'etat as the " champion of universal suffrage.'' And moreover, the February Republic, ■when it came into existence, was hailed by the Parisian proletariat as the social Republic. Its proclamation had been preceded by a period of immense Socialist propaganda on a very large scale, and so warranted the assumption that this Republic might have become in course of time a really Socialistic Republic. Why didn't it come about? Why, rather, was it overthrown by the Empire ? When Lassalle at the end of the "Worker's Programme," says that what was overthrown on the 2nd December, 1851, was " not the Republic," but the bourgeois Republic, which, by the electoral Law of May, 1850, had abolished universal suffrage, and had introduced what amounted to a property qualification in order to exclude the workers ; when he says that the Republic of universal suffrage would "have found in the breasts of the French workers an insurmountable barrier," he is simply echoing one of the cries of the small middle - class Revolutionists, a la Ledru Rollin, which does not answer the question, but only evades it. Where was this " insurmountable barrier," when the Chamber, elected on the basis of universal suffrage, repealed that suffrage 1 Why did not the Parisian workers prevent this " coup d'etat of the bourgeoisie " ? If Lassalle had asked himself this question he would have found that the February Republic could not endure as a social Republic, because the class upon which it would as such have had to rely, was not yet sufficiently developed — i.e., not sufficiently developed in the social sense of the word. The modern industrial proletariat was there ; it had even been strong enough for one moment to overthrow the whole existing order of things, but not strong enough to keep it down. Here we 1 ijo Ferdinand LassalU. again see the fundamental fallacy of the Lassallean method of thought. Even when he tries to enter into the deeper causes of historical events, his juridical bent of mind prevents his really getting to the bottom of the social side of these, and even when he deals with their economic side he does so when this has already — if I may so express myself — crystallised in the juridical form. This alone can explain why Lassalle, to show the workers of what elements the population of the State is composed, confined himself, and that exclusively, to the statistics of incomes. The dispute, which arose out of this passage in the " Open Eeply Letter," is comparatively unimportant. Whether Lassalle's percentages were slightly inaccurate in this direction or in that, at bottom matters very little. The fact that the great mass of the population lives in poverty, while only a small minority riots in superfluity, this the Wackernagles and his fellows, who at this time opposed Lassalle, could not, with all their pettifogging arguments, argue out of the world. It is far more important that Lassalle com- pletely ignored what different elements composed that 96 or 89 per cent, of the population, whose "great association" he called the State. Nor does he at all note how great a proportion of these were small artisans, and small peasants, and, above all, agricultural labourers, a section of whom were still absolutely under the spiritual control of their employers. Over half the population of Prussia was at this time agricultural ; the larger towns did not play any thing like the part they do to-day, and, from the stand- point of industrial development, the whole eastern portion of the kingdom was only a desert with isolated oases. 1 Under such conditions, what difference could universal suffrage make in the composition of the Chamber? Was a better result to be expected from it than from universal suffrage in the France of 1848 and 1849? Surely not. It might send a certain number of labour representatives to Parliament, and this, in itself, was i While 3,428,457 persons were employed ill agriculture in Prussia at this time, only 766,180 were employed in factory industries, including the business managers and clerks. Breach with the Progressist Party. \%\ certainly desirable. But for the rest it was bound to debase the composition of the Chamber instead of improving it, and this, the more fully it realised what Lassalle expected — i.e., returned a legislative body that should be " the true and faithful image of the people that had elected it." (" Worker's Programme.") For miserable as the Chamber then was, yet it was at least bourgeois- liberal. Lassalle forgot that the indigent classes, although they may under certain circumstances collectively supply revolutionary troops, are by no means wholly and solely revolutionary classes ; he forgot that of the 89 per cent., only a portion as yet consisted of modern proletarians. If, therefore, it was possible to obtain universal suffrage, it by no means followed that this would bring about, within a measurable time, that which universal suffrage itself again was to be a means of obtaining. Considering the degree of education, political and otherwise, of the great mass of the population, the immediate effect of the suffrage might have been the very opposite. Instead of sending representatives of modern principles to the Chamber, it might have increased the number of representatives of retrogression. Not all Progressists were the opponents, or luke-warm friends of universal suffrage from class-interest. There were among them a large proportion of ideologists, whom the development of events in France had rendered sceptical as to its value. Socialists also thought thus. We need but refer to Eodbertus, who, in his " Open Letter " to the Leipzig Committee, also points to France as an example that universal suffrage " does not of necessity give the power of the State into the hands of the working-class." It had been said, he goes on, that universal suffrage was to be only a means towards the end, but means " may be used for different ends, and occasionally for the most opposite ones." " Are you," he asks, " certain that here the means must of absolute necessity lead to the ends desired by you ? I do not think this." From Lassalle's letters to Rodbertus it also appears that Rodbertus's reason for refusing to join the General German Workers' Association, in spite of Lassalle's urgent im- portunities, was almost more due to his opposition to universal t3 2 Ferdinand Lassalle, suffrage than to his hostile opinion as to the value of the produc- tive associations. 1 And whatever else one may think of Rodbertus, his motives are unmistakably set forth in the concluding sentences of his letter. He there advises the workers — although Lassalle was right to say such questions were no longer to be discussed — to place the demand for free migration and free choice of calling in their pro- gramme as self-understood, in order to warn off as effectually as possible any reactionary who might harm them. If Rodbertus and others exaggerated the danger of Bonapartism, Lassalle on his side certainly made too light of it. The way in which he actually did, later on, veer round in this direction, was, from the outset, to be expected with his method of reasoning. In this connection a passage in Lassalle's letter to Marx — from which I" have already partly quoted — of the 20th June, 1859, that deals with the Italian war, is very characteristic. Lassalle writes : " In the beginning, when the national cry for war against France broke out, and was taken up so passionately everywhere, the Volhs Zeilimg (Bernstein, in my opinion an arch-reactionary, is its editor) exclaimed triumphantly in a leading article : 1 Would you know what this outcry of all the peoples against France means 1 Woiild you understand its world-wide historical import 1 The emancipation of Germany from the political develop- ment of France — that is what it signifies.' Need I explain in detail to you the ultra-reactionary meaning of this shriek of triumph 1 Surely not ! A popular war against France — and our petty bourgeois democrats, our decentralists, the enemies of all 1 Originally Rodbertus had said in his "Open Letter '' : "And I repeat that from the productive associations also I expect absolutely nothing, as u, contribution to what is called the solution of the social question. 1 ' At Lassalle's request these words were, however, omitted in print, as in matter they were a repetition of what had already been said in the letter, while in this drastic form they necessarily "must discourage the workers, if they saw such marked differences between the leaders." (Letter of Lassalle to Rodbertus, August 22nd, 1863.) Breach with the Progressist Party. 133 social advance, gain, for a long, long time, an incalculable increase of power. Even when we are well into the German Kevolution, the effect of this tendency would make itself felt. Assuredly we do not need to infuse new strength into this the most dangerous enemy we have — i.e., the German petty-bourgeois individualism, by a bloody antagonism to the Eomance - social spirit in its classical form in France." Thus Lassalle. The editor of the Volks Zeitung, now dead, un- questionably deserved the title Lassalle gives him, in many re- spects : but least of all, perhaps, on account of the passage quoted by Lassalle. The political development of France was, at that time, Bonapartism, while the party of the Volks Zeitung swore by England as its political model. This was, certainly, very one- sided, but still not reactionary, or only reactionary in as much as it was one-sided. But Lassalle's conception, which saw in the State centralisation of France a product of the " Komance-social " spirit, and identified this with the fundamental idea of Socialism, whilst entirely overlooking its reactionary side, was not less one-sided. So much for the political side of the Lassallean programme] Let us now consider its economic side. CHAPTER VII. THE "OPEN REPLY LETTER"; ITS ECONOMIC PORTION. THE IRON LAW OF WAGES, AND PRODUCTIVE CO-OPERATIVE SOCIETIES WITH STATE-HELP. The law of wages upon which Lassalle based his theory, and to which he added the name " iron,'' corresponds — as I think I have demonstrated elsewhere 1 — with a particular method of production — small industry — and a condition of society resulting from it, aud has, therefore, at least been outlived in the society of modern industry, with its increased facilities of communication, its acceler- ated cycle of crises, stagnation, aud prosperity, its rapid advance in the productivity of labour, etc. Moreover, this theory pre- supposes an absolutely free movement of supply and demand on the labour market. But this movement is at once interfered with as soon as the working-class, as an organised body, faces the employers, or as soon as the State, by its legislation, interferes with the regulation of the conditions of labour. So that when the Liberals replied to Lassalle that his law of wages no longer held good, that it was antiquated, they were to some extent justified. But only to some extent. For these good people, in their turn, fell into far graver errors than Lassalle. Lassalle laid special stress upon the " iron " character of the laws determining wages, because he believed he was dealing the deadliest blow at modern Society by proving that the worker never, under any circumstances, received the full product of his labour, his full share of the commodity produced by him. He gave the question a legal character, which, from the propagandist point of view, proved extremely effective. But he himself by no means went to the heart of the question. Even under earlier i See Nme Zeit : 1890-91 : " The Iron Law of Wages." '34 The "Open Reply Letter"; Its Economic Portion. 135 forms of production the worker did not get the full results of his labour ; and if an " iron " law prevents wages from permanently falling below a given minimum, and if this minimum itself rises — as Lassalle expressly admitted — in the course of develop- ment, rises slowly, it is true, but still rises, it became difficult to give proofs of the actual necessity for the intervention of tho State. The really material question at issue was not raised by Lassalle un- til later on, and then only incidentally. The position of the working- class in modern Society is so unbearable, and compares so unfavour- ably with every former method of production, not because the worker receives only a fraction of the new value produoed by him, but because this fractional payment is combined with the uncer- tainty of his proletarian existence ; because of the dependence of the workers upon the contractions of the world-market following one another in ever shorter periods of time, on constant revolutions of industry, and altered conditions of distribution ; because of the crying contrast between the character of production, ever becom- ing more socialised, and its anarchical distribution ; and with all this the growing impossibility for the individual workers to free themselves from the double dependence upon the employing class, and the vicissitudes of the industrial cycle ; because of the constant threat of being thrown from one sphere of industry into another lower one, or into the army of unemployed. The dependence of the worker has only become greater with his apparent freedom. It is this which, with iron weight, presses upon the working-class, and its pressure grows with the growing development of Capitalism. The rate of wages, on the other hand, varies to-day with the various branches of industry, from literally starvation wages to wages which represent a certain amount of comfort. In the same way the amount of exploitation in the different industries also varies considerably, in certain cases wages being higher, in others lower, than in the earlier epochs of production. Both depend upon very variable factors ; both differ, not only from industry to industry, but are in each of these subject to the greatest changes. The only thing constant is the tendency of capital to raise the 136 Ferdinand Lassalle. rate of exploitation, to squeeze surplus-labour in one way or an- other out of the worker. The chief fault of Lassalle's proposed remedy lay, from the very outset, iu his representing as the essential cause of the misery of the working-class in the Society of to-day, that which is cer- tainly not the characteristic feature of the modern method of production — for, as we have said, the worker has at no time received the full results of his labour. He ignores, or to be just to Lassalle, he underrates the strength and extent of the laws of the production of commodities, and their economic and social re-action upon modern economic life as a whole. Here again we must carefully distinguish between Lassalle's means and Lassalle's end. His end was, of course, to abolish the present production of commodities ; but his means left it untouched. His end was organised, social production; his means were individual association, which so far only differed from the Schulze plan in that it was to be brought about by means of State-credit and' State-help. Every- thing else, the fusion of the associations, etc., was left to their own voluntary decisions. It was expected of them, but was not made a condition. The State was to advance the necessary means, by guaranteeing credit, but only to such workmen as desired to start associations. The associations in any given industry, so long as they did not embrace the whole of that industry, would, therefore, have to compete with establishments of the same kind already in existence, and would thus be forced to submit to the conditions of such competition. The inevitable consequence of this must be that, within the associations themselves, differences of interest would arise ; thnt every association would have to try and force up its own profits as high as possible, even though it were at the expense of other associations, or of other categories of labour. With or without State-credit, the associations remained private concerns, made up of more or less large groups of workers. Individual qualities, individual advantages, individual good fortune, played a conspicuous part in them ; the question of profit and loss had the game significance, for them as for other private business concerns, The "Open Reply Letter": Its Economic Portion. 137 Lassalle certainly believed, first of all — judging from the eagerness with which productive co-operative associations had been taken up in Paris in 1848 — that at least all the workers engaged in certain industries in particular localities, would immediately unite to form one great association in each such place. Secondly, he distinctly declared later on in his " Bastiat-Schulze," that in each town the State would have to allow only one association in every particular trade the benefit of State-credit, leaving all workers of that trade free to enter into such an association. (See " Herr Bastiat-Schulze," p. 217, 1st Ed.) But even such locally homogeneously-organised associations would still remain nationally competitive. The economic consequences of this national competition were to be further neutralised by great insurance and credit unions of the associations amongst themselves. It is obvious, however, that this insurance society was a chimera, unless it was simply another name for a national organisation, and for a national monopoly of industry. Otherwise over-production would very soon break up the insurance association. And over-production was unavoidable if the State, as required by Lassalle, kept the entrance to these associations " open '' to all workers of the same trade. Here Lassalle, pricked on by his Socialist conscience, involves himself in a great contradiction. " To keep the entrance into the association open," was to bind the association to admit every worker who ap- plied for admission. But, according to the " Open Reply Letter," the association was to be entirely independent, vis-a-vis of the State, only giving the latter the right of approving the rules, and of looking after the business management in order to safeguard its own interests. But under the arrangement set forth above, the association was, on the contrary, transformed from an independent into a public; — i.e., under existing conditions — into a State institute — an internal contradiction, on which it must inevitably be wrecked. And yet another contradiction in the Lassallean productive associations. So long as the associations included only a fraction of those belonging to any given branch of industry, they were subject to the compulsory laws of competition, and this the more 138 Ferdinand Lassalle, as Lassalle had in his eye that working of production on a great factory-like scale, which makes the great industries of the world- market. But wherever there is competition there is also com- mercial risk ; competition forces the concern, whether managed by an individual, a joint stock company, or an association, to take its chance of its goods being at any time thrown on the market as below value — i.e., as products of not socially necessary labour. Competition and over-production, competition and stagnation, com- petition and bankruptcy, are, in the Society of to-day, inseparable. Command of production by the producers themselves is only pos- sible in proportion as competition is done away with among them, is only attainable by means of monopoly. But while, in our Society of to-day, competition has the important mission of protecting the consumers against fraud, and constantly reducing the costs of production, monopoly, on the contrary, tends to defraud the con- sumers for the benefit of the monopolists, and to hamper, where it does not altogether arrest, the development of technical skill. And the latter is especially the case where the workers concerned are themselves the monopolists. The getting rid of their com- mercial risk for the associations, must, therefore, within the frame- work of our capitalist society, necessarily be brought about — if, indeed, it could be brought about at all — at the expense of the consumers, who, in any case, represent, as compared with the pro- ducers, the vast majority. In a Socialist community it would, of course, be easy to prevent this. But such a community will not proceed to the socialisation of production by way of subventioned productive co-operative societies, but will, even though the co-operative form should be made use of, start with organising production on a socialised basis. Transplanted into the midst of a capitalist society how- ever, co-operation must, in one way or another, always assume a capitalistic character. The Lassallean co-operative societies would only have differed from those of Schulze-Delitzsch quantita- tively, not qualitatively ; only in extent, not in essence. Such also was the opinion of Eodbertus, who was far too ac- complished art economist % overlook this weak side of the The "Open Reply Letter": Its Economic Portion. 139 Lassallean co-operative societies. We have seen from the letter of Lassalle to Rodbertus, already quoted, how sharply Rodbertus had intended criticising these in his " Open Letter," and the sub- sequent letters of Lassalle to Rodbertus show us clearly enough what had been the latter's chief objection. But this is shown even more clearly in the letters of Rodbertus to Rudolph Meyer, and it may not be without interest to quote some of the passages referred to here. On the 6th September, 1871, Rodbertus writes : ". . . . In addition to this it is also demonstrable that that collective property which the Social Democrats are to-day striving for — that of agrarian communities and productive co-operative associations — is a far worse form of landed and capitalist property, leading to far greater injustice than the present individualist form. In this the workers are still following Lassalle. In my letters I had, however, convinced him of the absurdities and injustice which must result from such a form of property, and (what especially annoyed him) that he was not the creator of this idea at all, but had borrowed it from Proudhon's ' Idee Generale de la Revolution.' ' !1 Letter of May 24th, 1872 : " I have yet a third reason, of a general nature, to urge against this mode of payment. [He is referring to the sharing of business profits.] It must remain either a bonus, as Settegast rightly says — and the social question will not be solved by means of ' tips ' — or it must develop into a claim to participate in the management of the concern, and with this finally into collective property in the individual funds of the concern. But this col- 1 Proudhon himself had " borrowed " his productive associations from Louis Blanc, or, more correctly, had botched up Louis Blanc's association- plan in his own way. Lassalle's proposition comes midway between those of Louis Blanc and of Proudhon ; in common with the former, he asks for State aid, and with $he latter the independence of the associations, j 40 Ferdinand Lassalle. leotive property does not move along the lines of social develop- ment. The proof of this would take me too far afield, but still I had already forced Lassalle so far in our correspondence that he wrote to me in one of his last letters : ' But who tells you, then, that I want the funds for carrying on the concern to belong to the productive association 1 ' [sic /] And, indeed, it can't be done ! The collective property of the workers, in the individual concerns, would be a far worse kind of property than the individualist pro- perty in land and capital, or even than the property of a capitalist association. . . ." Such a passage as is here quoted, appears in none of the hitherto published letters of Lassalle to Eodbertus. But it is hardly to be supposed that Rodbertus would have spoken so positively unless he had had the actual text before him. Pro- bably he later on mislaid this letter. Moreover, there is no valid reason against Lassalle's having, in fact, once expressed himself in this way. In all Lassalle's speeches it is rather of the interest which the associations are to pay the State on the capital advanced that he speaks. Thus, in this sentence there is not even a con- cession to the standpoint of Rodbertus. But, on the other hand, we do find such a concession, and so strong a one that it is tanta- mount to a condemnation— unconsciously — of the productive associations in Lassalle's letter to Rodbertus on the 26th May, 1863. He there says : "But, on the other hand, it is clear as daylight that when the land, capital, and the products of labour belong to the worker, 1 there can be no question of a solution of the social problem. The same result will, therefore, be approximately attained also when land and capital are provided for the worker's use, and the pro- duct of labour belongs to him. In the agricultural associations 1 In Professor Ad. Wagner's edition of Lassalle's letters the passage reads "does not belong." The "not," however, as the subsequent text shows, is a printer's error. Nor does it appear in Rudolph Meyer's repro. duction of the letter. (See loc, eit, , p. 463. ) The " Open Reply Lettir" : Its Economic Portion. 141 the worker will then get either more or less than the product of his labour. In industrial associations he will, as a rule, get more than the results of his labour. I know all this perfectly, and when I write my economic work, shall demonstrate it very explicitly." In the next letter, either because Rodbertus had not thoroughly grasped the import of the above passage, or because he wanted to force Lassalle into a corner, Lassalle declares himself still more definitely. He writes [I omit a parenthesis of no importance here] : " My statement : ' In agricultural associations the worker ■will then get either more or less than the product of his labour,' is surely easy enough to understand so far as the ' more ' is con- cerned. I can't in the least understand any difficulty arising with regard to this passage. " The associations in the more favourable or better situated lands, would-, in the first instance, get exactly the same rent of land as the individual owner of them does now. And conse- quently get more than their actual produce, the actual product of labour. " But from this fact alone, that an individual in Society gets more than his legitimate product of labour, it follows that another must get less than with a legitimate division of the product of labour — as we both understand this (see the end of your third Social Letter) — he would receive as the reward of his labour. " More accurately : What is the fair product of my labour (in the sense of the final solution of the social question, therefore, in the sense of the 'idea' which I here always assume as the criterion and measure of comparison in the ' more or less ') ? Is it the agricultural or industrial product which I individually can, under certain given conditions, produce, while another, under more advantageous conditions, can, with the same amount of labour, produce more, and a third, under more unfavourable con- ditions, with the same amount of labour, produce less 1 Surely not ! My product of labour would be the share in the common socialised productions, which is determined by the relations in 142 Ferdinand Lassalle. which my quantum of labour stands fco the quantum of labour of the whole of Society. "After the conclusion of your third Social Letter, you cannot possibly dispute this. " And consequently, so long as the workers of the one associa- tion receive rent of land, the workers of the other associations that are not in this position, get less than their due share, less than the legitimate product of their labour." Thus far, Lassalle. A misunderstanding is here no longer possible. The "idea" which Lassalle assumes in his "more or less," is the Communist idea, which takes the total social pro- duct of labour, and not the product of labour of an individual or a group. Lassalle was perfectly conscious of this : that so long as the latter forms the standard of comparison, a portion of the population will receive more, another necessarily less than under a fair division should come to it as its share of the common socialised labour ; — i.e., that, in the first instance, the associations would create a new inequality. And for this very reason he had, as Lassalle declares again and again, carefully avoided the words, " solution of the social question " — in the working out of his pro- posal, " not from any practical timidity and diffidence, but on these theoretical grounds." In the course of his letter, Lassalle explains that the inequality between agricultural co-operative associations could easily be overcome by a graduated land tax, which is to " abolish all rents of land, i.e., placing them in the hands of the State, and leaving the workers only the actually equalised results of their labours" — rents of land in the Ricardian sense. 1 The land tax would provide for the payment for the handing over of the soil to the associated workers, and — as Lassalle expresses it — " even from justice or envy, would be warmly supported " by the agricul- tural associations. But this rent of land would " supply the i i.e., as the excess of the product of the land, above a certain minimum amount, below which, indeed, the land is not cultivated, because it does tiot even yield an equivalent for the labour put into it. The "Open Refity Letter": Its Economic Portion. 143 State with means for defraying the costs of education, science, art, and public expenditure of all kinds." In the industrial associations, on the other hand, equalisation was to be brought about by the associations of every single branch of trade, as soon as they were combined in one great association, abandoning all private middle-man business, all sales being carried on in sale- rooms provided by the State. " Would not this at the same time make an end of what to-day men call over-production and industrial crises 1 " The idea of State-ownership or the socialisation of rents of land x is a thoroughly rational one — i.e., contains no intrinsic contradic- tion. And in my opinion it is extremely probable, that at a certain stage of development it will, in some way, be realised. The idea of uniting into one body the associations is, on the contrary, only a pious hope, which may be brought about, but need not necessarily be accomplished so long as participation in it is left to the good pleasure of the individual associations. And even should this be accomplished, this would by no means prevent members of the individual associations from receiving in their share of the pro- ceeds of them a larger, or under certain conditions, a smaller quota of the common socialised product, than would be due to them on the basis of the totality of labour expended. There would still be the interests of the associations as against the social interests. Let us listen once more to Rodbertus. In a letter to Rudolph Meyer of the 16th August, 1872, he refers to an article in the Neue Sozial Democrat, 2 which main- tained that Lassalle had belonged to the " most advanced tend- ency of Socialism," and thinks this is probably true, but "it is just as true that Lassalle, and the (New) Sozial Democrat origi- nally had striven for a productive co-operative association like that which Schulze-Delitzsch wanted, that is, one in which the pro- 1 Not to be confounded with the suggestions of Henry George, Fliir- scheini, etc., since Lassalle assumes the universal existence of the associa- tions, without Which, as we have seen earlier, every reform of taxation must, in his opinion, be wrecked by the iron law of wages. 1 The New Social Democrat. 144 Ferdinand Lassalte. fits of capital were to belong to the workers themselves, only that Sehulze-Delitzsch wanted them to save the capital for this pur- pose themselves, and Lassalle wanted the State — our present State, too — to provide it for them (whether as gift or loan, is per- haps not quite clear). But a productive association, which pockets the profits of capital, assumes capitalist property, and ownership. How then is it possible to reconcile that most advanced tendency with such an association % " Eodbertus now considers the question whether the productive association could be regarded as a " provisional institution," and after a few remarks of a general nature, continues: "Enough, the productive association which Lassalle and the Sozial Democrat really did strive for, cannot even serve as a transition stage towards those ' most advanced ' aims, for, given human nature, it would not lead to universal brotherhood, but would take us back to the most acute form of corporate property, in which only the persons of the possessors were changed, and that would prove a thousand times more hateful than the individualist property of to-day. The transition from this to universal State property can never be by means of guild or collective property (they come much to the same thing) ; rather, it is exaetly this individual property which is the transition from co-operative property to State property. And in this lies the confusion of the Social Democrats (and in it lay Lassalle's) : i.e., that along with this most advanced aim (which, with Lassalle, too, was not yet to excite any practical interest), productive association is to be attained by means of capitalist profits, and therefore, capitalist property. Never, then, has the cart been put before the horse so thoroughly as by the Berlin Social Democrats (and their leader, Lassalle, also, in as much as he, too, strove after this 'most ad- vanced aim ') and Marx knows this very well." (Letters, etc., of Kodbertus-Jagetzow. I., 226 et. seq.) I have quoted Eodbertus so fully because his was the most objective attitude assumed towards Lassalle, because his concep- tion of the State had much in common with Lassalle's, and because no one probably discussed the productive associations with Lassalle The "Open Reply Letter": Its Economic Portion. 145 so thoroughly as he did. Certainly his judgment is not altogether unbiased either, for it is notorious that he had a theory of his own on the solution of the "social question" — i.e., the working normal worh day (fixed not only by time but by the amount of work done), and wages of labour in proportion. But in the main matter he places his finger quite rightly on the weak point in the Lassallean association when he says that it puts the cart before the horse. Lassalle desired the socialisation of production, and of the means of production, and because he thought the time not come for saying so already to the "mob" — by which he meant the rabble of idealess persons of all parties — and yet wished to disseminate the idea itself among the masses, he set forth what seemed to him a less dangerous postulate of productive co-operative associations with State-credit. In this he committed the same mistake which, in his essay on " Franz von Sickingen," he represented as the tragic fault of Sickingen. As that essay puts it, he "juggled " with the "idea," and deceived his friends more than his enemies. But, like Sickingen, he did so in good faith. Though Lassalle repeatedly assured Rodbertus that he was ready to give up the associations as soon as the latter would show him an equally easy and effective means to the same ends, we should not conclude from this that Lassalle was not thoroughly convinced of the excellence of his own means. Everyone makes such declarations, and the greater his faith in his own cause, the more readily will he make them. And how much this was the case with Lassalle is shown by his last remarks on the associations in answering Rodbertus : " In short, I can't understand how anyone can fail to see that the association, proceeding from the State, is the organic germ of development that will lead on to all that lies beyond." He must, then, be entirely acquitted of the reproach of having, in this demand, recommended to the workers something of whose justice he was not convinced, a reproach that would be far more serious than the. making of a theoretical blunder. Lassalle believed that in the means of co-operative associations with State-credit, means that were to serve the final end — i.e., the K 146 Ferdinand Lassalle. realisation of a Socialist society — all the chief essentials of that aim were already contained ; and that here, in fact — and upon this he lays such great stress — " the means themselves are abso- lutely imbued with the very nature of the end." Now, certainly, co-operation in a small way is, of course, a partial realisation of the Socialist principle of Communism, and the demand for State- help is an application of the idea for using the State machinery as a means towards the economic emancipation of the working- class, while it is also a means of possibly maintaining the con- nection of this with the question as a whole — a connection that was lost in the associations of the Schulze type. So far, we not only cannot reproach Lassalle, but must warmly acknow- ledge the unity of his conception. We have seen what his conception of the State was, how for him the State was not the existing political expression of a particular social condition, but the realisation of an ethical concept, the eternal " truth " of whose nature might be modified by existing historical influences, but could not be subverted. Holding such a view, it is, however, only logical to see in the demand for State-help something more than a mere practical measure, and as Lassalle did, to ascribe to it as a fundamental principle of Socialism the significance of an inde- pendent principle. 1 And in the same way, the demand for productive co-operative societies stands in the closest intellectual relation to Lassalle's theory of the iron law of wages. It is based upon the same economic hypotheses. In a word, I should say that everything here is cast in the same mould. But that Lassalle believed in the Tightness of his meana does not justify him in expressing himself as vaguely as possible as to his aims. He who, in the already quoted essay on " Franz von 1 So, too, holding this view, it was only logical for Lassalle, in his Leip- zig speech on " The Working-Class Question," e.g., to blame the so-called Manchester men among other things, because if they could, they " would allow the State to be submerged in Society." As a matter of fact, how- ever, the really characteristic point is that the Manchester men would like the State to be submerged in Capitalist Society. The " Open Reply Letter " : Its Economic Portion. 147 Sickingen," Lad so admirably demonstrated the danger that lurks "in concealing the true and final aim of the movement from others (and often, therefore, even from oneself) ; " he who had seen in this concealment of Sickingen his " moral crime '' that must lead inevitably to his destruction, the result of a want' of confidence in the strength of the ideas he represented, a " devia- tion from his own principle," a " half defeat," — he should have been the last to direct the movement towards a means, instead of to its actual end. The excuse that the " mob " must not yet be told what this end was, or that the masses were not yet to be won over to it, does not hold. If the masses could not yet be in- terested in the actual end of the movement, the movement itself was premature, and then, even were the means attained, they would not lead to the desired end. In the hands of a body of working-men aot yet able to understand their historical mission, universal suffrage might do more harm than good, and productive co-operative societies with State-credit could only benefit the existing powers of the State, and provide it with a prsetorian guard. But if the body of working-men was sufficiently de- veloped to understand the end of the movement, then this should have been openly declared. It need not have even then been re- presented as an immediate aim, to be realised there and then. Not only the leaders, however, but every one of the followers that were led ought to have known what was the end these means were to attain, and that they were only means to that end. The public would have been no more incensed than they were by the struggle to attain the means alone. Lassalle himself points out how subtle is the instinct of the governing classes, when it is a question of their own existence. "Individuals," he rightly says, in this con- nection, •'' may be deceived, classes never." Those who consider what I have said above as doctrinaire may be referred to the history of the movement under Lassalle, and after him. To the consideration of that history I now proceed. CHAPTER VIII. LASSALLE AS AGITATOR AND LEADER OF THE ASSOCIATION. It is impossible, -without expanding this sketch into a large volume, to enter into all the details of the Lassalle agitation. I must confine myself rather to indicating the general features of the movement. The "Open Reply Letter" for a time only partially produced the effect which Lassalle had promised himself from it. He might well write to his friend Gustav Lewy, at Diisseldorf : " The whole thing reads so easily that it must at once seem to the working-man as if he had known it all for years." The pamphlet was indeed a masterpiece for agitation ; instructive and yet not dry ; eloquent without phrase-mongering, full of warmth, and yet written with the most trenchant logic. But — the workers mean- while did not even read it ; only where the soil had already been pre- pared, did it take root among them. This, as we have al- ready seen, was the case at Leipzig ; so, too, at Frankfort-on-the- Maine, in a few of the larger towns and industrial centres of the Rhine, and in Hamburg. To some extent political refugees who had returned had carried on aSoeialistic propaganda in a small way, while, to some extent — especially along the Rhine — the traditions of the Socialist propaganda before and during the Revolution of 1848, revived again. But the mass of the workers who took part in the political movement, for a long time yet remained unmoved by this appeal, and looked upon Lassalle in the same way as he was regarded by most of the leaders of the Progressist Party — as a cat's-paw of the reaction. For so far as the Progressist Party in Prussia and outside Prussia, is concerned, the " Reply Letter " had certainly raised a perfect storm — that is, a storm of indignation, of passionate re- 148 Lassalle as Agitator and Leader of the Association. 149 sentment. They had felt themselves so great, so paramount in their role of knights of the threatened rights of the people — and now, suddenly, from the left, a voice cried out that they had no claim to this title, that they had proved themselves unworthy of the confidence hitherto placed in them by the people, and that, therefore, everyone who really cared for freedom, and especially every working-man, must turn his back upon them. No fighting party will tolerate such an accusation, least of all when it is in such a position as that of the Progressist Party at this time. The feuds between it and the Prussian Government had gradually attained such dimensions that a forcible solution of the conflict seemed well-nigh unavoidable ; at any rate, one must be prepared for the worst. To the contention of the Government organs that the Progressist Party had not the people really at their back, they had hitherto been able to reply with contempt and scorn, that the masses, the thoughtful people who cared for politics, were unanimously with them, and confident of this, they had always used more and more threatening language. For though the Pro- gressists might not have a great desire to make a revolution, they were by no means chary of threatening with one. x And precisely at such a moment as this they were to allow a man, who spoke as a democrat, as an opponent of the Government, to reproach them with having betrayed the cause of the people, to look on quietly while this man sought to gather the workers around himself under a new banner 1 To expect this was to ex- pect the superhuman. Why, the very sense of self-preservation forced the Progressists - I can still remember this period very well although I was only a school- boy ; my first political impressions date from it. In school, in the play- ground — everywhere — in those days we talked politics, and, of course, we boys only repeated in our own way what we heard at home, in our surroundings. My class-mates belonged to the middle-class ; my play- fellows to the proletariat ; but the former were as convinced as tho latter that a revolution " must come," for " my father says so, too." Every ex- pression of the Progressist leaders that could be construed into a reference to the revolution, was triumphantly passed from mouth to mouth ; so, too, the satirical verses on the King and his ministers, etc. ISO Ferdinand Lassalle. to do their utmost to prevent the Lassalle agitation from gaining ground. And subsequent criticism has to do only with the manner of their counter-attack — not with the attack itself. The former was so natural it cannot be considered as a reproach to them — but the manner of their counter-attack can only be described in two words — beneath contempt. That they represented Lassalle as a cat's paw for the reaction, is really the very least they can be re- proached with. For after all it cannot be denied that Lassalle's " Keply Letter " just then brought grist to the mill of the Prussian Government. But instead of confining themselves to attacking Lassalle where they had a strong case against him, they fastened, for their attack, upon those points where they were weak, and with this proved themselves so impotent, that their helplessness would almost provoke pity — but for the fact that it was accom- panied with such colossal self-assertion. To Lassalle's one-sided concept of the State, they opposed an absolutely ridiculous nega- tion of all the social-political duties of the State. To his theory of the iron law of wages — based as we have seen upon a partial misapprehension — they opposed the feeblest glorification of the bourgeois-capitalist system of competition. In their blind rage they so completely forgot the actual condition of affairs, every- thing that tbey themselves had formerly said in regard to the evil effects of capitalist production, that they even justified the exag- gerations of Lassalle by the absurdity of their own contentions. From petty-bourgeois opponents of capitalism, Schulze-Delitzsch and Co. suddenly became its panegyrists. We need only com- pare the passages from Schulze-Delitzsch's work, published in 1858, quoted earlier in this volume (pp. 8, 9), with the statements in his " Kapitel zu einem deutschen Arbeiter Katechismus " x — a collection of six lectures, the later ones of which were meant to annihilate Lassalle critically before the Berlin working-men. While in the former work the helping to cut down the profits of the employer was eulogised as one of the most admirable results of the self-help associations, in the latter Schulze - Delitzsch declared that " science knew nothing of such a thing as em- 1 "Chapter towards a German Workers' Catechism." Lassalle as Agitator and Leader of the Association. 1 5 1 ployer's profits," and consequently, of course, knew nothing of any antagonism between the wages of labour and employer's profits. They recognised only " (a) wages of enterprise and (6) profits of capital." (See Sohulze-Delitzsch ; Kapitel, etc., p. 153.) One did not even need to be a Lassalle in order to cope with such " science "as that. Yet, despite his intellectual superiority, despite his powerful rhetoric, Lassalle was not so successful in his campaign against the Progressists as he expected to be. There was not then the remotest idea of the " Open Reply Letter " having an effect like that of the Theses Luther nailed to the church door at "Wittenberg — an effect which Lassalle, however, as he says in the letter to his friend Lewy, already quoted, had expected. On the 19th May, 1863, at a public meeting at Frank- fort-on the-Maine, held at the conclusion of the "Maine Dis- trict Workers' Congress," Lassalle, who had attended the Congress, which sat two days, and who delivered a speech of four hours, got a resolution passed pledging those present to do their utmost to start a General German Working-men's Association on Lassallean lines. Thereupon, on the 23rd May, 1863, the "General German "Working-men's Association " had been formed at Leipzig, when delegates from ten towns (Hamburg, Leipzig, Frankfort - on - the-Maine, Harburg, Cologne, Diissel- dorf, Mainz, Elberfeld, Barmen, Solingen), were present, the rules having been drawn up by Lassalle, together with a friend of his, the Democratic Progressist member of Parliament, Ziegler. In conformity with these rules, the organisation was a strictly centralised one ; which was due partly to the German laws affect- ing association, and partly to the fact that the founding of a General Workers' Insurance Society had originally been intended. This idea had been dropped, but Lassalle retained the rules that affected himself solely, more especially those which guaranteed the personal prerogatives of, and gave positively dictatorial powers to, the president, who was, into the bargain, to be elected for five years. There were certainly already some signs of opposition to these rules at this first assembly for the foundation of the Association, 152 Ferdinand Lassalle. but in the face of Lassalle's express wish that the rules should be accepted without alteration, the opposition fell through. By an all but unanimous vote (only one delegate, York from Harburg, voted against him) Lassalle was elected president, and after some hesitation, the assembly having further given him power to elect as often, and for any term of office he chose, a vice-president, he accepted the presidentship. By virtue of this he became the acknowledged leader of the new movement ; but for a long time to come the movement was limited to a very small number of adherents. Three months after its foundation the General German Working-men's Association numbered scarcely 900. In itself this would have been no mean success, but Lassalle had counted upon figures very different from these. He did not want to be the leader of a propagandist society, but the head of a popular movement. Only the masses kept aloof from the new organisation. Lassalle was a splendid worker. At times he was capable of developing a positively colossal energy; but it was not given to him to do steady, solid, persistent work. The Association was barely six weeks old when the new president started upon a long holiday of many months, first going to Switzerland, and then to the North Sea. It is true that Lassalle was not inactive during his travels. He kept up a lively correspondence, tried to win over all sorts of notabilities to the Association, and was not very particular in his choice. But the main thing — the agitation among the masses — he left severely alone. Farther, he did not even, strangely enough, seek to secure for the Association at least a good weekly organ, although he had the means to do so. He contented himself with the occasional subventioning of small papers — the Nordstern, pub- lished in Hamburg, by the old free-lance Bruhn, and the Leipzig Zeitgeist, — by the way a very doubtful organ — edited by the litterateur, Ed. Lowentbal; subventions which kept these papers for a time above water, but did not prevent them from constantly hovering between life and death. Like the mass of the workers, most of the advanced Democrats, and middle-class Socialists, whom Lassalle invited to join the Lassalle as Agitator and Leader of the Association. 1 5 3 Association, kept away from it. A large number of these people were, as I have already pointed out, steeped in philistinism or, at any rate, -were on the high road to it ; others were prevented by a vague, personal distrust of Lassalle from openly declaring for him, whilst others again thought the time very inopportune for an attack of the left wing upon the Progressists. And even those who did join the Association, for the most part contented them- selves with simple membership, and for the rest remained passive. As a set-off against these, however, other members of the Associa- tion, especially those belonging to the working-class, agitated the more energetically, while the secretary of the Association, Julius Vahlteich, showed a positively feverish activity in trying to get new members for the organisation. But their success was by no means commensurate with their efforts. On the one hand the indifference of the still undeveloped masses of the workers, on the other, the all-absorbing interest of the hour — the national move- ment, together with the constitutional struggle in Prussia — seemed almost insurmountable difficulties. In many places, indeed, the members of the Association eagerly discussed the question whether some sort of bait of a non-political nature, as, e.g., the starting of benefit funds, etc., should not be offered in order to attract members. Lassalle himself was at one time inclined to enter into the dis- cussion of this question — see his letter of the 29th August, 1863, to the secretary of the Association, quoted by B. Becker in his " History of the Working-Class Agitation," p. 83 — but he gave it up again, because he saw that were this done, the character of the Association must necessarily be changed. It would have ceased to provide a political machine always ready to hand, and this was the only value it had in Lassalle's eyes. While still at the Baths, Lassalle had worked out the main ideas of a speech with which he intended recommencing the agita- tion on his return, — to begin with at the Bhine where the posi- tion had proved most favourable to him. This was the speech : " Die Feste, die Presse, und der Frankfurter Abgeordnetentag." x 1 " The Fetes, the Preas, and the Frankfort Congress of Members of Parliament." 1 54 Ferdinand Lassalle, This speech, which Lassalle delivered from the 20th to the 29th September, at Barmen, Solingen, and Diisseldorf, marks the turn- ing-point in his agitation. What influences had been brought to bear upon him during the summer months, it would hardly be possible to prove, but we shall not be far wrong in concluding that they were those of the Countess Hatzfeld and her connections. The Countess had, naturally enough, an even greater desire to see Lassalle successful than he himself had ; for her all interest in Socialism was completely absorbed in interest in Lassalle, through whom, indeed, she had first become socialistically inclined. As- suredly, also, she was only moved by her great affection for Lassalle, when she urged him on to steps which could only serve to satisfy his personal ambition, and which could not but very seriously compromise the movement itself. But to the Countess the movement was Lassalle, and Lassalle the movement ; and she looked at all things from the point of view of what she believed to be Lassalle's interests. Such disinterested friends are, how- ever, as a rule, of very doubtful value. And when they are into the bargain, by education, social position, etc., warped with special class prejudice, and when they have no independent sphere of action, their co-operation often works more dangerously than poison. They foster all the failings and weaknesses of the object of their love ; they constantly work upon his sensibility by calling attention to every injustice apparently done to him; and more bitterly than the injured person himself, do they thirst to be avenged for the injustice done ; they hound, they egg on, they intrigue — always with the best intentions — but to the greatest detriment of him whom they mean to serve. The Countess Hatzfeld was, in her way, an able woman, who, very inferior as she was to Lassalle in knowledge and energy, was yet his superior in experience. Where his passions did not stand in the way, he attached great importance to her advice, — and her advice was doubly effective when it chimed in with his passions. In a letter written to the Countess towards the end of his life, he says to her that, after all, it was really she who had induced him to accept the presidency of the General German Working-men's Lassalle as Agitator and Leader of the Association. 1 55 Association. Thi3 must certainly not be taken literally. Even without the Countess, Lassalle would probably have accepted the presidentship. But in such situations one likes especially to let one's good friends talk one over into doing what one has a mind to, because it seems to lessen one's responsibility. So the Countess probably soothed Lassalle's scruples, and it is more than likely that she did this by preferring to call his attention to matters then impending in the higher circles of Prussia, I need but remind my readers of Lassalle's statement in his defence at the trial for high treason, that from the first day in which he began his agitation, he had known that Prince Bismarck would grant universal suffrage, and his further statement that when he issued the "Open Reply Letter," it was "clear" to him that "great foreign conflicts were imminent, conflicts which would make it impossible to ignore the masses," It is true that he here tries to represent this as a matter which everyone who was carefully watching events must have known. But from his letters to Marx, we have seen how much he allowed his political acts to be influ- enced by the " information " given him from " diplomatic sources '' as to what was going on in governmental circles. The Countess had certainly been even more disappointed than Lassalle himself at the slow progress of the General German Working-men's Association. Led by all the educational influences of her life to trust to the use of intrigue and scheming, she was now also bound to think of attaining by roundabout means what it was difficult to obtain in an open struggle. In this design she found only too ready support in Lassalle's tendency to win success on which he had once set his mind, at any price, in his reckless temperament and his enormous self-esteem. In how far the threads by which Lassalle was led to the palace of Prince von Bismarck were already knotted together it is impos- sible at this time of day to say. But both the words which, as he was preparing his speech, " The Fetes, the Press," etc., for print, he addressed to his friend, Lewy, " What I am writing here I am writing for only a few people in Berlin," and above all the subject- matter of the speech itself prove that at least these threads were i $6 Ferdinand Lassalte. being eagerly spun. The speech is interlarded with attacks upon the Progressist Party, which in certain cases are very much exag- gerated, while, on the contrary, Herr von Bismarck is positively nattered. If hitherto the democrat and the socialist in Lassalle had always mastered the demagogue vein in him, here the dema- gogue masters them both. In June, 18(>3, after dismissing the Landtag, the Prussian Government had issued the notorious Press Eegulatious, which empowered the Government officials, after giving two warnings, to prohibit, " provisionally or permanently," the further publication of any Prussian newspaper or periodical " for pursuing a line of conduct dangerous to the public weal." The Liberal press, ex- clusively in the hands of private individuals, had thereupon, for the most part, preferred to say nothing more whatever about in- ternal politics as long as the Press Regulations were in force. This was certainly anything but bold, but it was not such vile treachery to their own cause as Lassalle represented. Lassalle intentionally overlooked the fact that in issuing the Press Regulations it had been Bismarck's deliberate intention to ruin the opposition papers that were objectionable to him commercially, in order to replace them with a press of his own, or one more agreeable to himself. In the preamble to the Press Regulations it was distinctly stated : — • " The direct counter-effect against the influences of the above — (i.e., the Liberal press) — by means of the Conservative press, can only partially attain the desired results, because most of the opposition organs, through long years of habit on the part of the public, and through the commercial side of the said organs, have a circulation which it is not easy to combat." If, therefore, the Liberal papers did not run the risk of being pro- hibited, the Government also had no possibility of smuggling other journals into their place, or of stealing their advertisements. The one object of the measure was therefore defeated by this temporary silence on internal politics. And not less did it defeat the second Lassalle as Agitator and Leader of the Association. 1 57 direotly political object. In his speech, Lassalle says that if the Liberal press allowed itself to be suppressed, if the Philistine had been unable to get his customary paper at breakfast, the exaspera- tion amoug the people against the Press Regulations would have grown to such a pitch that the Government would have been obliged to give in. Meanwhile, the exasperation was not the less if the Philistine continued to get his customary morning paper, while its contents daily demonstrated to him that his organ was gagged ; when he got his paper, but without the beloved leading article. Moreover, the Press Regulations were a measure that could not be kept up after the Landtag had assembled. It was a pro- visional measure, and while it lasted there was no reason whatever why the Liberals should — as Lassalle expresses it — for the love of Bismarck, " die with honour." The anger of the Government was, of course, not little, and its organs naturally reflected this anger. Lassalle thus expresses this : " Even (!) the reactionary papers could, at this time, hardly find words to sufficiently express their astonishment and indigna- tion at this attitude." Aud as a proof he quotes the Berliner Revue, the organ of the most reactionary mugwumps. Of course, the reactionaries resorted to the device of hiding their attacks upon the Liberal press beneath a thin socialistic mantle, and pretended to attack it because of its capitalist character. And yet, instead of protesting against this misrepresentation of the Socialist idea, and of repudiating all connection with it, Lassalle actually played up to the Bismarckists by representing their false coin to the workers as pure gold. Certainly, the fact that the press of to-day is a business concern is a great evil, a mighty factor in the corruption of public life. But, so long as capitalist private property exists, it will scarcely be possible to obviate this — least of all, by restrictive laws. So far as this can be remedied to-day, it can only be by freedom of the press. But of this the Prussian Government -would not hear, and Lassalle supported them. For while advocating complete freedom of the press, he at the same time declared that such free- 158 Ferdinand Lassalle. dom would be powerless to alter the nature of the press, if, at the same time, the right to publish advertisements were not pro- hibited. For then the press would cease to be a lucrative business speculation, and only such men would write for the newspapers as were fighting for the well-being and intellectual interests of the people. Is any particular argument needed to show how absolutely in- effective this remedy would be 1 Lassalle had only to look be- yond the frontiers of the Prussian State, to England and to France, to convince himself of his error. In England, the adver- tising system formed, and still forms, a very essential source of income to the press ; while in France, though the insertion of ad- vertisements in newspapers was not directly prohibited, it was made almost impossible, and was reduced to a minimum, by a very high tax. Was the French press any better on that account than the English ? Less at the service of Capitalism, less corrupt than the latter ? Not a whit. The absence of advertisements, on the contrary, made it very much easier for Bonaparte to corrupt the press to his own ends, and, on the other hand, it has not prevented the political press of France from rendering far greater service to the big financiers than the political press of England has done. For all that, Lassalle was, in this portion of his speech at least, touching on a question which must certainly be designated as one of the sores of our modern public life. Even though the time was badly chosen, though the remedy was of problematical value, in itself the fact remains, that the press, with or without adver- tisements, is becoming more and more a capitalist institution, a cancerous growth to which the attention of the working-class must be called, if they are to free themselves from the influences of the capitalist organs. But altogether beside the mark was what Lassalle said of the fetes which the Progressists held in 1863 in defiance of Bismarck. He must have known that the fltes were nothing but propagandist meetings, but demonstrations against the Government, such as had been held, under like conditions, in France and England. Had he wished to criticise them, he should have shown that by Lassalle as Agitator and Leader of the Association. 1 59 fetes alone nothing can be done ; that if they stopped at these the cause of the people against the Government was not advanced a single step. But instead of doing this he contented himself with repeating the phrases of the Government press on the fltes, and even exaggerating the scorn beneath which the latter tried to con- ceal their vexation. No one who is intimately acquainted with the history of the Prussian constitutional struggles of the year 1863 can read this passage of Lassalle's speech without disapproval. The third part of the speech, the criticism of the Congress of the German members of Parliament that had met at Frankfort-on- Maine in the summer of 1863, would have been justified if Lassalle, at the very moment when he was reproaching the Progressists for coquetting with the German Princes, in order to frighten Herr von Bismarck — we have seen how in his " Open reply letter " he had twitted them with the " Dogma of Prussian Supremacy " and had represented Prussia as the most reactionary of the German States — it would have been justified if, at the same time, Lassalle had not been playing the same game as the Progressists, only that he was coquetting with the other side. His entire speech does not contain a single word against Bis- marck and the Prussian Government, but is full of direct and indirect flattery addressed to them. He represents them as ignoring the resolutions of the Chamber " with the quiet smile of genuine contempt,'' and provides Bismarck with the certificate that he is " a man," while the Progressists were old women. One more passage in the speech bears witness to Lassalle's change of front. The leader of the National Verein, Herr von Bennigsen, had closed the Congress with the following words, and it may be as well to recall them once again. " The violence of the Volkspartei, and the hide-bound nature of rulers, had often led to revolu- tionary upheavals. But the German people were not only unanimous, but also so moderate in their demands, that the German National Party — which desired no revolution, and which could make none — could not be held responsible if after it another party should appear, which, because no reform was any longer possible, should resort to a revolution." 160 Ferdinand L asset lie. To any one who can read, this declaration, though a very weak- kneed threat, is yet a threat of a revolution. " We don't want a revolution — God forbid — we wash our hands of it, but, if you don't give in, the revolution will come all the same, and then you'll only have yourselves to thank for it." A very cowardly way of threatening when you have the whole nation at your back, but, unfortunately, also a very common way of threatening — so common that, as I have said, it is impossible to misunderstand the meaning of the declaration. But what does Lassalle do? He pretends not to have understood the threat, and he makes this pretence not in order to challenge the Progressists to speak out more decidedly, but in order to threaten them in the event of a revolution or a coup d'dtat. He quotes the above passage from Herr von Bennigsen, and adds the following pronunciamento : " Let us lift up our arms and pledge ourselves, if this revolution should come about, whether in this way or in that, to remember that the Progressists and members of the National Verein to the last declared they wanted no revolution ! Pledge yourselves to do this, raise your hands on high." And " the whole meeting raised its hands in great excitement," we are told in the report of the speech — which Lassalle him- self edited. What did this threat, this " remembering," mean ? It was almost impossible to explain otherwise than that the Progressists were to be, if not directly attacked, yet left in the lurch in the event of a violent conflict arising " in this way or in that." But such a threat, and at such a moment, could have but one result — instead of forcing the Progressists forward, to make them yet more pusillanimous. At a meeting at Solingen there was a bloody conflict. A number of Progressists, who had attempted to interrupt Lassalle, were attacked with knives by some of his fanatical adherents. In consequence of this, the Burgomaster, half an hour later, dissolved the meeting. Thereupon Lassalle, followed by a cheering crowd, hurried to the telegraph office, and sent off to Bismarck the well- known telegram, beginning with the words : " Progressist Burgo- Lassalle as Agitator and Leader of the Association, i&i master has just, at the head of ten gendarmes armed with bayonets, and several policemen with drawn swords, dissolved a working-men's meeting called by me, without any legal justifies tion ; " and ending, " I ask for the severest, promptest, legal satisfaction." Even taking into consideration everything that is to be said in Lassalle's excuse — his bitterness about the repeated attacks upon him by the Progressists, his disappointment at the comparatively small success of his agitation, his profound distaste for the cowardly tactics of the Progressists, his one-sided but still sincere antagonism to the liberal economic doctrines — in short, however much we may try to put ourselves in his place at this time, still one thing unquestionably results from this telegram, taken in connection with the speech described above — that when Lassalle returned to Germany he had already lost his mental anchorage, had lost, if I may so say, his standpoint. No conservative would have been forgiven such a telegram ; far less a man who had been proud to call himself a revolutionist, and who certainly, in his heart, still believed himself to be one. If no other considerations did, the simplest feeling of tact should have prevented Lassalle from mak- ing an appeal for State-force, that began with a political denuncia- tion. And even were it possible to excuse this telegram on the ground of his excitement at the breaking up of the meeting, other steps soon followed, undertaken with the coolest deliberation, which were as diametrically opposed to the political principle which Lassalle claimed to represent. Here, but one example, one which is, more- over, closely connected with the events to which I have referred. Some working-men, who were said to have used their knives at the Solingen meeting, were, in the spring of 1864, condemned to several months' imprisonment. And it was Lassalle, who in all seriousness, and repeatedly, suggested that the condemned men, supported by a general address of the working-classes, should pre- sent a petition for mercy to the King of Prussia. Think of the Lassalle, who only a few years before (see page 57 of this volume) had written that it was only in Berlin that to his grief he had seen L 162 Perdinand Lassalle. " how little the people in Prussia were (lis monarchied ; " who at Frankfort-on-Maine had exclaimed : " I have no desire and no call to speak to any others than to Democrats " ; he, whose duty as leader of the new movement it especially was to set his followers the example of democratic dignity, urged them to beg for mercy from the King of Prussia. However, the workers proved them- selves more tactful in this case than their leader. On the 20th April, 1864, the Solingen delegate of the workmen, Klings, an- nounced that there was a general objection to Lassalle's proposal. All the chief members of the Association had declared against it. " The two from here who have been condemned belong to the most outspoken Working-men's Party, and even if the sentence were four years, it would be impossible to induce them to present a petition for mercy, because it goes against their convictions to be indebted to His Majesty.'' This opposition awoke Lassalle's democratic conscience, and he wrote to Klings that the refusal of the people filled him with great pride. He did not yet, however, give up his idea of an ad- dress to the King, but tried to prove that even without the petition for mercy from the condemned men, this might be very advantageous. " Perhaps, too," he actually writes, " the following advantage might ensue, that if the address were signed by many thousands of workers, this step might be so interpreted in the highest circles — without at all binding us — that they would feel the more encouraged, on the next opportunity, to proceed with the introduction of universal and direct suffrage : a step which, as the accompanying leader from the ministerial organ {Nord-deutsche Allyemeine Zeitung) shows, they are just now again considering." However, even this prospect was unable to convince the Solingen workers of the fitness of the step recommended, and so the move- ment was spared this humiliation. When, in the beginning of October, 1863, Lassalle returned to Berlin, he set about winning over the capital to his cause with the utmost zeal. He drew up an appeal " To the Workers of Berlin," of which he published 16,000 copies, a portion of which he had distributed gratis among the working-men of Berlin. Lassalle as Agitator and Leader of the Association. \6% Although the appeal was very effectively written, and the connect- ing of it with the garbled reports of the Ehenish meetings in the Berlin Progressist press ( Volks Zeitung and Reform) was especially able, yet its success was at first a very modest one. Lassalle was unable to hold any large meeting without its being broken up by the Progressists ; and when, at one of his meetings, by order of the Berlin authorities, Lassalle was arrested, some fanatical work- ing-men actually applauded. And even those who, under the effect of Lassalle's lectures and writings, had their names entered in the books of the Association, soon dropped out again, so that the Association, which, in the beginning of December, 1863, had in Berlin had over 200 members, in February, 1804, counted barely three dozen, the greater number of whom, moreover, were not working-men. Besides the agitation, Lassalle was much occupied with his lawsuits and other conflicts with the authorities. For, however agreeable his agitation, so far as it was directed against the Pro- gressist Party might be to the Bismarck ministry, this yet knew well enough that it had not in Lassalle a supporter who would allow himself to be used as a complaisant tool. It could only be agreeable to the ministry, therefore, if the lower officials continued to overwhelm Lassalle with prosecutions, etc. By this means the ministry was in a position either, at the right time, to get rid of an obnoxious firebrand, or, perhaps, even to " bring him to his knees" after all. However this may be, the Diisseldorf Public Prosecutor had the speech " The Fetes, the Press," etc., confiscated, and brought a charge against Lassalle of violating Sees. 100 and 101 of the Prussian Code [Inciting to disorder and propagating false statements, with the intention of discrediting regulations of the authorities]. The prosecution caused Lassalle infinite worry, and after a sentence of one year's imprisonment pronounced in contumaciam by the first court, ended, after his appeal to a higher court, in a sentence of six months' imprisonment. For the pamphlet " To the Berlin Workers," the Berlin authorities brought a charge of high treason against Lassalle, and, as I have already mentioned, had him arrested, when, however, he was liber* 164 Perdinand Lassalle. ated on bail. It is possible that both the charge and the pre- liminary arrest may have been due to the personal spite of the Attorney, Von Schelling, whom Lassalle had so belaboured a year before at his trial before the StadtgericM. At the trial that took place on the 12th March, 1864, before the StadtgericM of Berlin, the Public Prosecutor asked no less than that Lassalle should be sentenced to three years' penal servitude and five years' police sur- veillance. The Court, however, so far as the charge of high treason was concerned, dismissed the case, and referred the minor charges of breaches of the Code, brought by the authorities, to the Courts competent to deal with them. Lassalle's speech in his defence at this trial is an important document for the history of his agitation. Before considering it, however, a big socio-political work of Lassalle's must be mentioned. It was published at the end of January, 1864, and must rank as his foremost work in the way of agitation. This is his polemic " Herr Bastiat-Schulze von Delitzsch, der Okonomische Julian, oder Kapital und Arbeit." a I have already referred, in passing, to the lectures delivered in the spring of 1863 by Herr Schulze-Delitzsch to the Berlin Working-men's Association, and published under the title " Kapitel zu einem deutschen Arbeiter Katechismus," as a counterblast to the Lassallean agitation. These lectures, a re-hash of the tritest com- monplaces of liberal political economy, provided Lassalle with a wel- come opportunity for annihilating — theoretically — Herr Schulze- Delitzsch, and withhimtheparty which revered himas their economic hero. If we bear in mind that Lassalle had never been able to do any systematic economic work, and that at the very time when he wished to set about the preliminary studies for his book on econo- mics he was prevented from doing so by his practical agitation ; if, further, we bear in mind that while Lassalle was writing the "Bastiat-Schulze," he was constantly interrupted by his lawsuits, and the labour of managing the Association, one cannot but see in this book a fresh proof of the extraordinary talent, the marvellous 1 " Herr Bastiat-Schulze von Delitzsch, the Julian of Economy, or Capital and Labour." Lassalle as Agitator and Leader of the Association. 1 6$ versatility and elasticity of Lassalle's mind. It is true that the " Bastiat-Schulze " at the same time bears traces of the conditions under which it was written. However much the popularity of the pamphlet is helped by its polemical form, the circumstances under which this controversy arose — the extreme irritation of Lassalle, that was all the greater because he felt keenly that he was placing himself iu a more and more false position, his dis- illusions on the one hand, and his efforts on the other, to blind himself as to these disillusions — were fatal to the tone of the polemic. But intrinsically, too, the work is by no means always up to the level of its subject ; it frequently degenerates into small verbal quibbling, which, moreover, is not always accurate. 1 Then, too, the fundamental and theoretical part of the work, brilliant as it is in many points, is not free from contradictions. Taken all iu all, however, the " Bastiat-Schulze " has still the great merit of having largely advanced the historical sense, and the under- standing of the deeper problems of political economy amongst the German workers. In parts the presentation rises to the height of the best writings of Lassalle, and in these passages his genius ap- pears once again in its most brilliant light. 1 Thus, e.g., Lassalle's first objection against " Schulze-Delitzsch," that " wants" and the "impulse to satisfy wants," were only "two dif- ferent expressions for the same thing," is incorrect. Both, as a rule, coincide, but are by no means the same thing. A few pages later on Lassalle makes fun of Schulze-Delitzsch because the latter sees the difference between human and animal labour in this — that the former labour provides for future wants. He himself, however, falls into the still greater error of seeing the difference only in this, that man works con- sciously, and the animal without any such consciousness. And so in many other passages. CHAPTER IX. VAIN ATTEMPTS TO COMPEL IMMEDIATE POLITICAL SUCCESS. — AP- PROACHING THE REACTIONARY GOVERNMENT OP PRINCE BIS- MARCK. bassalle's DEATH. All that Lassalle wrote and said after the " Bastiat-Schulze,'' gives ever clearer proof of inner lassitude, of mental enerva- tion. His energy is no longer the original energy, the natural result of belief in his own force, and the strength of the cause championed — it is forced. Compare the " Worker's Pro- gramme" with the Ronsdorf Speech; the defence speech, "Science and the Workers" with his defence in the trial for high treason, and what I have just said will be understood. The inner energy has gone, and violent language replaces it ; logical flourishes replace incontrovertible logical arguments ; instead of convincing, Lassalle takes more and more to declamation. That with which he had but recently reproached the Progressists he now does himself — he intoxicates himself with imaginary successes. At the trial for high treason, Lassalle, in defending himself against the charge that what underlay his agitation, was the ulti- mate use of physical force, very ably used the picture of Schiller's Wallenstein on the night before his going over to the Swedes, and quoted the verses of the monologue in the first act of " Wallen- stein's Tod " : " War's moglich ? — Konnt ich nioht mehr wie ioh wollte ? Nicht mehr zuriik, wie mir's beliebt " i It is wonderful how these lines fit in with Lassalle's own situa- tion at this time ; how like his position was to that of Wallenstein 1 " Is't possible ? Could I no more do as I would 1 No more turn back, as I desire ? " ?66 Vain Attempts to compel Immediate Political Success. 167 when he speaks these words. He, too, like the Friedlander, had— to use his own image — " done things that he could turn to ac- count a deux mains." He had not contented himself with study- ing the course of internal and foreign politics objectively, with a view to seizing the right moment for forwarding his own plan of cam- paign ; he had already begun to treat with the representative of one of the powers against whom he was fighting ; he had entered into direct negotiation with Herr von Bismarck. Assuredly, he too could still say with Wallenstein : " Noch ist sie rein, nooh ! Das Verbrechen kara Nioht iiber diese Schwelle noch ! " 1 As yet he had broken no pledge. But was he still really free in his inner heart 1 Might not the logic of events force him also to consummate the " deed " because he " did not put away temptation from him ? " That in the winter of 1863 to 1864 Lassalle had repeated and important conferences, tete-a-tete wilh the then Herr von Bismarck, there can now be no doubt whatever. The life long confidante of Lassalle, the Countess Sophie von Hatzfeld, when, in the summer of 1878, Bismarck introduced his gagging Bill against German Social Democracy, on her own initiative told representatives of that party of these facts, adding circumstantial details. When the member of the Reichstag, Bebel, in the sitting of Septembir 16th, 1878, brought the matter before the Reichstag, Bismarck the next day admitted having had interviews with Lassalle, and only made an attempt to deny that they had had reference to any political negotiations. Bebel, on the strength of the communica- tions made by the Countess Hatzfeld, said : " These conversations and negotiations turned upon two different matters : firstly, upon the granting of universal suffrage ; and secondly, upon the granting of State-help to the productive co-operative associations. Prince Bismarck had been completely won over to this plan by Lassalle. 1 " Yet it is pure, — as yet ! For never crime Has passed across this threshold yet,' 1 68 Ferdinand Lassalle. He only refused to introduce universal suffrage until such time as the Schleswig-Holstein war had been satisfactorily concluded, and only refused to push it through immediately as Lassalle wished. In consequence of this difference of opinion, serious disagreements arose between Lassalle and Prince Bismarck ; and it was not the latter who broke off the negotiations, but it was, as I must em- phatically state, Lassalle who caused the breach, and who declared he could not enter into further negotiations." To this Bismarck replied : " Our conversations undoubtedly turned upon the question of universal suffrage, but under no cir- cumstances upon an introduction of it. I never in all my life entertained so monstrous an idea as to grant universal suffrage in this way by forcing it upon the Chamber.'' He had accepted it " with some reluctance " as a "Frankfurt tradition." As to the productive co-operative associations, he was "not even to-day con- vinced of their inexpedience." Only, the political events at that time had not allowed of the carrying out of the experiments initiated in this direction. Moreover, it was not he but Lassalle who had desired these meetings, who had written to request them, and he, Bismarck, had consented to meet Lassalle's wishes as a mere' caprice. " What could Lassalle have offered or given me ? He had nothing at his back. The do ut des is at the bottom of all politi- cal negotiations, even when one doesn't, for decency's sake, say so. But when one is forced to say to oneself, ' what can you, poor devil, give 1 ' There was nothing he could have given me as minister." It is perfectly clear that the man who has " never lied officially " here deals very unofficially with the truth. Lassalle would not have gone to the minister, nor would the latter have repeatedly sent for the "revolutionary Jew " — Bismarck himself admits this may have occurred some four times, while the Countess Hatzfeld main- tains that it was oftener, three or four times a week — and have discussed with him for hours together just for the sake of a chat. Further, one has but to read over the speeches of the repre- sentatives of the Government in the Chamber, and the articles in the official press of this period, to be convinced how greatly the Bismarck ministry was then taken up with the idea of introduc- Vain Attempts to compel Immediate Political Success. 169 ing universal suffrage; and under the then existing circumstances, this could hardly have been done in any other way than by that of royal force. Lassalle himself, in his defence before the Stadtgerichthof, quotes some remarks to the same effect, and sub- sequently adds in connection therewith the celebrated declaration, which can only now that his interviews with Bismarck are known, be rightly appreciated. " The prosecutor accuses me of wishing to introduce universal and direct suffrage, and thus to overthrow the Constitution ! " Well, gentlemen, although I am but a private individual, I may say to you : not only do I wish to overthrow the Constitution, but perchance, ere one year shall have passed, I will have over- thrown it ! " But how 1 Without one drop of blood having been shed, without a hand having been raised in violence ! Perchance not another year shall have passed, but universal and direct suffrage will have been introduced by the Government in the most peace- ful manner in the world. " The strong hands, gentlemen, can be played with exposed cards ! It is the strongest diplomacy that does not need to con- ceal its calculations with any secrecy, because it is founded upon iron necessity. "And so I proclaim to you, here in this solemn spot, perchance not another year shall pass— and fferr von Bismarck will have played the role of Robert Peel, and universal and direct suffrage shall have been proclaimed ! " Lassalle certainly adds that he had known this from the be- ginning, "from the very first day on which, by issuing my 'Beply Letter,' I began this agitation, and it could have escaped no one who looked at the situation with his eyes open." But if it is in- dubitably true that already in the winter of 1862-1863 the ques- tion was being mooted in Government circles, whether it would be possible to break up the Progressist majority in the Chamber, by a change in the electoral law, and to this end they began dabbling in the social question ; x yet Lassalle would scarcely have spoken 1 Let me again remind readers of the attitude taken up by Eichler, The 170 Ferdinand Lassalle. with such certainty of a speedy introduction of universal suffrage, have constantly recurred to it, unless he had been convinced from his conversations with B'smarck, that, whether introduced before or at the end of the Danish campaign, this measure had been de- cided upon. On the other hand, Bismarck's contention that it hnd never come to any rupture between himself and Lassalle is more credible. The negotiations may have dropped for a time, when Lassalle became convinced that Bismarck wanted to wait events before undertaking this, after all, risky step — and explains why Lassalle always speaks of the possible introduction of the measure within a year's time. But that the relations were not finally broken off, is proved by the fact that Lassalle continued to send, through the secretary of the " General German Working-men's Association," a copy of all his publications, etc., under cover and marked "■private" to Bismarck. So, too, we may believe Bismarck that his negotiations with -7- Lassalle could come to no definite settlement, because of the do ut des. Of course, matters were not quite as Bismarck would represent them with his churlish, " what can you, poor devil, give 1 He had nothing he could have offered me as minister." At this time Bismarck was by no means so secure in his position as not to need every help he could get, and Lassalle could, all the same, have given him something. The fact was only this, that it was not enough to decide Bismarck to yield to Lassalle's im- portunities. Perhaps, too, this is one of the reasons why Lassalle, after his return to Berlin, exaggerated his successes in a positively following passage from the conclusion of a speech delivered by Herr Her- mann Wagener — the confidant of Bismarck, the inspirer and director of the Kreuz-Zeitung — at a meeting of the Prussian Conservative Volksverein, on the 2nd November, 1862, is also of interest. "Gentlemen, let us not de- ceive ourselves, let us learn from our opponents, for they rightly say, if you do not succeed in solving the social question, all your toil and labour will be in vain. I, therefore, conclude with this appeal — let us set about that which we recognise as the task and requirement of the immediate future, let us set about this with even greater energy, let us set about it not only at election times," Vain Attempts to compel Immediate Political Success. 171 morbid manner; he, who had written so late as July, 1863, to Vahlteioh : " You cannot allow our delegates to tell untruths. So you cannot, therefore, ask them to speak of 10,000 men, when perhaps we haven't got 1000. We may be silent upon this point, but is not meet that we should lie.'' He now wished, at all costs, to seem to possess power, even though he had no actual masses to lead. But Bismarck was probably kept sufficiently well posted by other informants as to the real condition of the movement. And there was also another side to this " giving." Bismarck can hardly have doubted even for a single moment that in Lassalle he would have a political ally only for so long, and in so far as the alliance would be to the advantage of Lassalle and his political ends : in other words, that Lassalle would do by him exactly as he would do by Lassalle — i.e., turn mercilessly against him as soon as he had got what he wanted out of him. His first inter- view with Lassalle must have convinced him that the latter was not — what Bodbertus once well called Bucher, " a fish without bones " — but that, on the contrary, he had very portentous bones and maw. The bait of some small office — not to speak of money — was useless in the case. Universal suffrage once assured, Lassalle might easily become very unpleasant — so why be over- hasty ? Anyhow, Lassalle's agitation was being turned more and more fiercely and one-sidedly against the Liberal Party, and this was, for the time being, all Bismarck wanted. In his defence speech — " Die Wissenschnft und die Arbeiter," J delivered on the 16th January, 1863, Lassalle had declared : " Can any one even assert that with us the three-class electoral system is to be laid at the door of the possessing classes, of the German bourgeoisie ? ... It is the Prussian Government alone, not the possessing classes in Prussia, which for all time, and before all the world, must bear the blame and responsibility for enforc- ing the three-class electoral system." And : " Bourgeoisie and workers, we are members of one people, and quite united against our oppressors," i.e., against the Government. But before the Stadtgerichthof, on the 12th March, 1864, 1 " Science and the Workers," 172 Ferdinand Lassalle. the constitutional conflict in Prussia has become to him only a struggle between the monarchy and a " clique." To this " clique " the monarchy could not yield, but "it might well call the people upon the scene, and trust to them. To do this, it need but call to mind its origin, for all monarchy has originally been the monarchy of the people.'' " A Louis-Philippe monarchy, a monarchy created by the bourgeoisie, certainly could not do this ; but a monarchy that still stands as kneaded out of its original dough, leaning upon the hilt op the sword, might quite certainly do this, if it determined to pursue truly great, national, and democratic aims." This is the language of Csesarism, and during the course of his speech, Lassalle even intensified it by representing the existing Constitution as a boon conferred upon the bourgeoisie by the monarchy. But no one "cares to let his own boon be twisted into a rope wherewith to strangle himself, and no one can be blamed for this, and, therefore, neither should the monarchy be blamed." Constantly driven back upon ostensible "right," the monarchy had "remembered that it was more fitting to its position to rely upon true right, and to marshal the people upon the stage, than to yield to a clique, and to allow a handful of individuals to twist its own boon into a rope, wherewith to strangle it." So would he, Lassalle, speak on the day when the monarchy should have overthrown the Constitution, and have introduced universal suffrage, if he were accused of being the intellectual originator of this overthrow of the Constitution. Lassalle had now got so far that he not only did the reaction a passing service by the existence of his agitation, which, under certain conditions, was unavoidable. He fell more and more into the habit of speaking the language of the reactionists. Truly he could still cry with Wallenstein : " Beim grossen Gott des Himmels ! Es war nicht Mein Ernst, besohlossene Saohe war es nie ! " i l " By the Great God of Heaven ! It was not In earnest, It was never so resolved," Vain Attempts to compel Immediate Political Success. 173 He was playing with the reaction, believed he was using it for his own ends, and that at a given moment he could shake it off with one wrench. In this sense it was that he once spoke to the Countess Hatzfeld of Bismarck as his "delegate." But he forgot that there is a logic of facts which is stronger than even the strongest individual will, and that inasmuch as he was playing for success, instead of trusting to the very strength of the move- ment itself, and of devoting his energies exclusively to it, he had, according to his own theory, already, to. some extent, partially given up that movement. In fact, to return once more to the already quoted essay of Lassalle on the fundamental idea of his "Franz von Sickingen'' : with the volte-face performed since his return from the waters, Lassalle had arrived at exactly the same tactics which in this essay he had designated as the " moral guilt " of Franz von Sickingen. It is worthy of note how accurately Lassalle there foreshadowed his own fate. He too had come to that " self- complacent good sense," which seeks to attain revolutionary aims by diplomatic means ; he had assumed a mask in order to deceive his antagonist — the Prussian Government — but, in fact, he de- ceived not it, but the mass of the people, without whom he was nothing ; the movement itself remained limited to a small group of personal friends. And as Lassalle writes of Sickingen that, " this great diplomatist and realist, who had carefully calculated everything beforehand, and wished to entirely exclude chance, is at last forced by the most accidental of chances to lose every- thing," and " while the calculation based upon this delusion was doomed to failure through the semblance of chance and of the non- essential in the existing condition of things, the ultimate de- cision, instead of proceeding as he wished from what had been pre- pared, proceeded from the first unlooked-for chance." 1 So, too, Lassalle finds himself forced now to reckon only with chance, and to make everything in home and foreign politics dependent upon chance constellations. Lassalle played, trusting to his real 1 See No. 45, 1890-91, of the New Zeit, p. 588, etc., where I have published this essay. I f4 Ferdinand Lassaltt. ability. But he forgot that the game is to him who has the best chance of wearing out his opponent, to him who holds the most trumps in the political game, — therefore, to him who can com- mand the greatest number of really powerful factors. And as in this case, Bismarck was in this position and not Lassalle, it was inevitable that in the long run Lassalle should become Bismarck's " delegate," rather than Bismarck his. Such was the situation when Lassalle delivered the Ronsdorf Address: "Die Agitation des Allgemeinen Deutschen Arbeiter- Vereins und das Versprechen des Konigs von Preussen." 1 It was his last, and, at the same time, the weakest of his agitation speeches, conceived solely with a view to external effect. How very con- scious Lassalle was of the weakness of this speech is proved by the published version of it, edited by himself : this is full of interpolated remarks as to the effect of certain passages — crutches which a sound lecture can well dispense with, and that would indeed mar the impression of a really pregnant speech. The Konsdorf Address has none of the qualities of Lassalle's early agitation speeches, while on the contrary, it emphasises all their defects. Moreover, the speech is not merely inherently weak, its ten- dency also is more reprehensible than anything Lassalle had until then said or written. Some Silesian weavers, impelled by their misery, and encouraged by the social demagogy of the Feudal Party, had sent a deputa- tion to Berlin, to petition the King of Prussia for help against the wrongs under which they suffered. And at last, as the employees of a Progressist manufacturer were concerned, they had, on Bismarck's instance, been received by the King. In answer to their complaints, they had been told that the King had instructed his ministers " to prepare to render them some legal redress, so far as this was possible, with all despatch and energy.'' That Lassalle should represent this step of the Silesian weavers, and the reception of their deputation by the King, as a result of 1 "The Agitation of the General German Working-men's Association, and the Promise of the King of Prussia." Vain Attempts to compel Immediate Political Success. 175 his agitation, no one — \^ggerated as the claim ia — will find any great fault with. '' as, like so many other exaggerations in his Address, is to be explained by Lassalle's position. But Lassalle did not content himself with this. He placed such a construction upon the reception of the deputation by the King, and upon the King's words, as could only result for the time being in a glori- fication of the King and his Government. He reads the working- men a report from the semi-official Zeidler 'schen Korrespondem on the reception of the deputation by the King, and reads those very passages that are most favourable to the monarchy — as he expressly says in the printed version of the speech — "in the most impressive tone, and accompanied with the most effective gestures of the hand." 1 , In the King's words, he declared, there lay " the recognition of the main principle to advance which we are beginning our agita- tion"—?'^., that a dealing with the labour question by legislative means is essential. Further, Lassalle declares, " the promise of the King that this dealing with the labour question, aud the doing away with the misery of the workers, shall be brought about by legislative means ; " and, thirdly, as " a Progressist Chamber, a Chamber elected by the Three-Class Electoral Law, would never vote the money necessary to the King for this object, or even, could this object be attained without money, would ever give their consent to such legislation;" the kingly promise, "through the intrinsic force of logic, included also a promise of universal and direct suffrage." At these words the report represents " the meeting which had listened to the whole of this last part of the speech with extra- ordinary keenness," as " bursting into indescribable cheers," start- ing afresh every time Lassalle tried to continue his speech. ' The passage reads thus : " With the hope of a very speedy legal settle- ment of the question, and thus of the redressing of their grievances, His Majesty dismissed the deputation. The royal promise will echo encourag- ingly and helpfully through all the valleys of the Riesengeblrg, and will inspire many hundred of honest, patient families with new hope and new strength for brave endurance." t?6 Ferdinand Lassalle. If the cheers were really so loud, it proves that the workers took Lassalle's interpretation of the King's promises for current coin — the very worst evidence that could be given against this speech. There can be no doubt that this speech was intended, so far as the workers were concerned, to urge them to the greatest and most enthusiastic activity on behalf of the Association, by paint- ing the success already achieved in the most brilliant colours possible. But the speech was intended for others besides working-men. In reply to a review of his " Bastiat-Schulze," pub- lished in the Ereuz Zeitung, and emanating, according to Lassalle, " from too important a source " for him to ignore the questions there addressed to him, he especially refers the reviewer in the Government organ to the Ronsdorf speech, and sends his reply and two copies of the speech under cover " personally '' to Bis- marck. Both speech and review were intended to make an im- pression upon the Government — were written ad usum delphini. The " indescribable cheers " were to be a bait for Bismarck and the King. But no one man can serve two masters. The attempt to turn the speech so that it should produce the desired effect in higher quarters really gave it an out-and-out Caesarian character. It is doubly a pronunciamento of Ceesarism — Csesarism within the ranks of the party, and Csesarism in the politics of the party. " Yes, there is nothing more incapable of organisation and more impotent, nothing more unintelligent," writes Lassalle in his reply to the ICreuz Zeitung, "than the restless, malcontent, liberal individualism, this great malady of our time ! But this restless, malcontent individualism is by no means a malady of the masses ; it is, indeed, necessarily and naturally rooted only in the fractional intelligences of the bourgeoisie." " The reason is obvious : the spirit of the masses, as behoves their position as masses, is always directed towards objective, positive aims. The voices of restless, vain-glorious individuals would be drowned in this volume of voices without even being heard. The oligarchical is the only homogeneous fruitful soil for Vain Attempts to compel Immediate Political Success. \JJ the negative, acrid individualism of our Liberal bourgeoisie, and its subjective, obstinate self-glorification.'' And so, in the Rons- dorf speech, he says : " There is another, a most remarkable element in our success, upon which 1 must touch. That is the solid spirit of complete unity and discipline that prevails in our Association ! And in this respect, too, in this respect above all, perhaps, our Associa- tion stands out — epoch-making, an entirely new figure in history ! This great Association, spreading over well-nigh all German lands, moves and has its being with the solid unity of an individual ! I am personally known to, and have personally visited but a small number of districts, and yet from the Rhine to the North Sea, and from the Elbe to the Danube, I have never heard a 'No;' and, at the same time, the authority with which you have invested me is one that rests entirely upon your own continued confidence in me ! . . . Wherever I have been, I have heard words from the workers, that may be summed up in the sentence : We must weld the wills of all of us into one single hammer, and must place this hammer in the hands of a man in whose intelligence, integrity, and good faith we have the necessary confidence, so that he may be able with that hammer to strike ! " The two contradictories which our statesmen have heretofore regarded as irreconcilable, whose fusion they have looked upon as the philosopher's stone— freedom and authority— these most ex- treme contradictories have been completely reconciled by our Association, which thus becomes on a small scale the prototype of our next form of society on a large scale. With us there is not a trace of that malcontent spirit of Liberalism, of that malady of individual opinion and superiority with which the body of our bourgeoisie is eaten up. . . . 1 There is a formally correct idea underlying these words, i.e., i " Die Agitation des Allgemeinen Deutsohen Arbeitervereins," etc. (" The Agitation of the General German Working-men's Association,") 1st Edition, p. 37, etc. 173 Ferdinand Lassalle. that in modern Society the workers are under normal conditions compelled to common action far more than any other class of society ; and that, in fact, the very conditions of life of the modern industrial proletarian, develop in him the spirit of solidarity. The bourgeois, on the contrary, is only impelled towards common action by abnormal conditions, and not by the very nature of his social existence. This correct idea, however, receives a totally false interpretation by the above generalisation. The action of the masses does not, by a long way, mean persoual dictatorship : indeed, where the masses abdicate their will, they are already on the road to become, from a revolutionary factor, a reac- tionary one. In the struggles of modern Society, personal dictatorship has invariably been the sheet-anchor of the reactionary classes, seeing their existence imperilled ; no one is so ready to renounce " negative acrid individualism " as the modern bourgeois so soon as his money bags and his class privileges seem seriously threatened. In such moments the cry of " a reactionary mass " becomes a true one, and when the tendency becomes a general one Bonapartism flourishes. The classes that feel themselves in- capable of self-government do that which Lassalle is here imputing to the workers : they abdicate their own will in favour of a single person, and condemn every attempt to oppose any private interests of this person as "restless, malcontent individualism." Thus, in the seventies and eighties, the German bourgeoisie accused the very party — the Freisinnige — which was most consistently - de- fending their class interests, of betraying these interests, because by their " malcontent " they were hampering the self-preserving activity of the State. And so in 1851, the French bourgeoisie attacked their own parliamentary representatives, whenever they attempted to refuse Louis Bonaparte the means for his coup d'etat, as "disturbers of the peace," "anarchists," etc., until Napoleon was strong enough to proclaim himself dictator against the bourgeoisie, instead of contenting himself with the role of mere maintainer of law and order for the bourgeoisie. A growing revolutionary class has absolutely no reason to abdicate its will, to renounce the right of criticism, to renounce Vain Attempts to compel Immediate Political Success. 179 its "superiority," vis-a-vis of its leaders. And we have seen, in the Solingen affair, that whatever stress Lassalle might lay upon his superior intelligence, vis-a-vis of the workers, it was from amongst the ranks of these workers that he had had to take a very distinct and energetic " No," and that surely not to the detriment of the movement-. In Berlin, too, on one particular occasion, he had to take a like " No," and when he boasted at the Association directed by him that he had realised " authority and freedom " as represented above, he was expressing a wish rather than stating an actual fact. In addition to those personal qualities of Lassalle's which made the idea of such dictatorship so sympathetic to him, there was now too actual need for it. The policy he was pursuing could only be carried through if the members and adherents of the movement followed their leader without criticism, and did his bidding without a murmur. Just as Lassalle himself dealt with the promise of the King of Prussia to the Silesian weavers in such a fashion that only by a small, quite casual reservation, did the democrat, — one is tempted to say — salve his conscience — while the rest meant nothing but pure Caesarism; so his adherents also were to be ready, on the word of command, to don the livery of loyalty. If there is one thing that can at least humanly excuse the Ronsdorf speech, it is the fact that it was, under the given circumstances, a necessity for Lassalle. He needed the dictator- ship in order to be sure of the workers whenever lie should require them for his actual ends, and he needed the endorsement of his dictatorship to appear to those in higher circles as a power to be treated with. The speech was the necessary step in the path once entered upon — it was no longer possible to stop. And so the subsequent steps taken by Lassalle, both as regards the internal management of the Association, and its immediate external action, followed in the same direction. In the Association he insisted upon the expulsion of Vahlteich, who had opposed him in matters concerning organisation. And he not only made this a Cabinet question — he or I ? — so that the members of the Associa- tion had hardly any other choice than to sacrifice the working-man i8o Ferdinand Lassalle. Vahlteich to the president, he also acted most unloyally in this affair in other ways. Thus, e.g., he gave directions for having the very voluminous written indictment he had drawn up against Vahlteich circulated in such a way that Vahlteich himself only learned its contents after it had already influenced the rest of the members of the executive against him. Now, whatever one may think of Vahlteich s proposals for changes in the organisation, the way in which Lassalle represented the mere idea of a reform of the Association as treachery, was the less justified that he, Lassalle himself, had already half made up his mind to drop the Association if his last attempt "to bring pressure to bear upon events " should fail. This attempt, or, as Lassalle himself has called it, this " coup,'' was to be carried out at Hamburg. It had reference to the affairs of the Duchies of Schleswig-Holstein, just then conquered from Denmark. When, in the winter of 1863, the death of the King of Denmark forced the Schleswig-Holstein question to the front, Lassalle, who was at this time already in communication with Bismarck, and therefore had every interest to induce the Association to support any policy upon which the Prussian Government should decide, had been working up the members of the Association against the " Schleswig-Holstein craze," ] and had drawn up and had every- where got a resolution passed in which it was said that : " The unification of Germany would of itself settle the Schleswig-Holstein question. In the face of this great mission, the question — so long as there are thirty-three princes in Germany — whether one of these is a foreign prince seems of comparatively very subordinate interest." 1 In a letter of Lassalle's to the vice-president, Dr. Dammer — to whom Lassalle in the first excitement seat two absolutely contradictory telegrams — he actually said: "The first telegram I sent off at once because the whole Schleswig-Holstein craze is, in many respects, extremely unpleasant for me.'" The contradiction in the telegrams is now explained by the position, full of contradictions, into which Lassalle had drifted. He was, without knowing it himself, no longer free. Vain Attempts to compel Immediate Political Success. 181 For the rest, the resolution is made up only Of more or less general phrases. It was the duty of all German Governments to enforce, " if need be by force of arms," the incorporation of the Duchies with Germany, but the people are warned to be on their guard ; " to let themselves be drawn away from their great central mission by nothing.'' Against the Progressists and mem- bers of the National Verein, the reproach is levelled of " seeming to want to use Schleswig-Holstein as an opportunity for diverting attention from the internal situation, and for shirking the solution of a conflict to which they are not equal, under the guise of Patriotism." This in the December of 1863. The Duchies were now conquered, and the question was what to do with them. A large proportion of the Progressists were in favour of tbe legitimate claims of the Duke of Augustenburg, whilst the influential Prussian circles were for the annexation of the Duchies to Prussia. Now, however little interest the Demo- cratic Parties had in adding a thirty-fourth to the already existing thirty-three sovereign princes in Germany, they, on the other hand, had no reason for conferring any augmentation of power upon the most reactionary Government in Germany at that time. Lassalle, however, had now so completely lost all his sense of . political tact, that he in all seriousness contemplated holding a large public meeting at Hamburg, and getting it to pass a resolu- tion to the effect that it was the duty of Bismarck to annex the Duchies to Prussia against the wishes of Austria and the other German States. No words are needed to point out what a part Lassalle thus took upon himself, nor for what a part he wanted to use the socialistically-inclined workers of Hamburg, who felt such warm gratitude and veneration for him. The project, how- ever, was never carried out, and the Hamburg workers were happily spared a conflict between their democratic convictions, and their supposed duty towards their leader. Lassalle, after fighting another lawsuit iu Diisseldorf, had gone to Switzerland. His first stay was at Rigi Kaltbad, and here, on the occasion of an excursion, he received an invitation from Fraulein Helene von Donniges, whose acquaintance he had made 1 82 Perdinand Lassalle. iu Berlin in the winter of 1861 to 1862, and to whom, accord- ing to her statements, he had already then offered his hand. Out of this visit grew that love affair whose final result was the premature death of Lassalle. - The details of the Lassalle-Dbriniges affair are to-day so well known, all the steps taken by Lassalle in this business that are really characteristic of him are placed so absolutely beyond doubt, that a repetition of the whole story is unnecessary here. More- over, during the affair Lassalle did not show himself in any new light ; — he rather developed only such qualities as are already familiar to us ; — it may, indeed, be said that the Donniges affair on a small scale, and in another domain, is essentially a repro- duction of the history of the Lassalleau agitation. Lassalle believed he had found the wife of his choice in Helene von Donniges. The only difficulty was to obtain the consent of the parents. But Lassalle had not the faintest doubt that the influ- ence of his personality must overcome this difficulty. Self- consciously, and yet at the same time with circumspect calcula- tion of every possible contingency, he drew up his plan of cam- paign. He will come, will conquer the good-will of the parents, and wring from them their consent before they really know what they are doing in acquiescing. Then suddenly a small unforeseen obstacle comes in the way. Through the indiscretion of the young lady the parents learn earlier than they should do of the engagement, and declare that they will not accept Lassalle as son-in-law under any circumstances. Lassalle, however, does not yet give up his plan. His triumph will only be greater the greater the opposition of the parents. Strong iu his self- confidence, he takes a step which gives such a turn to the situation, that all hope of attaining his end in the way planned out is excluded, a step that shakes even the girl's own faith in him. . . . Well, then, if not in this way, then in another. And regardless of what he owes himself and his political position, Lassalle begins a struggle in which there is for him but one point of view — success. Every means is right that promises success. Spies are employed to watch the Donniges family, and to report Vain Attempts to compel Immediate Political Success. 183 their every movement. Through the instrumentality of Hans von Biilow, Kichard Wagner is entreated to induce the King of Bavaria to intervene on Lassalle's behalf with Herr von Donniges, while Bishop Ketteler, of Mainz, is . offered Lassalle's conversion to Catholicism, in order that the Bishop may exercise his influence in Lassalle's favour. Lassalle did not in the least care how un- worthy it was of the historical mission he had set himself, to dance attendance upon a Minister von Schrenck, so that the latter might help him to his love, nor did he care how little worthy he was proving himself of his prototype Hutten, when he petitioned the incarnate representative of Rome to help him to obtain a wife. Here where he might have shown pride, where he should have shown it, he did not. And yet success did not come. The Bishop of Mainz could do nothing, because Helene von Donniges was a Protestant, and the attempted mediation undertaken by confidential representa- tives sent to the scene of the struggle by the Bavarian Minister for Foreign Affairs only seemed to prove to Lassalle that by his method of proceeding he had placed himself and the woman he was fighting for in a totally false position. Although he knew that Helene was absolutely without strength of will, and had indeed perceived in this an advantage for his future life together with her — " Keep Helene for me in the submissive frame of mind in which she now is," he had written on the 2nd August to the Countess Hatzfeld— he all at once ex- pected her to do that which demanded a very strong will, and was indignant because she tried to back out of it. Upheld by his self-esteem, and accustomed to look at things exclusively from the point of view of his own moods and interests, he had entirely left out of his calculations that it is the most submissive human beings who most easily change their impressions, and thus he saw " boundless treachery," and the " most-unheard-of trick '' of an " abandoned jade," where there was nothing more than the instability of a grisette in high life. Meantime, however, his nervous system was completely shat- tered, and for a long while he no longer possessed the energy 184 Ferdinand Lassalle. of a healthy will. Sudden resort to violent means, anxiety to move heaven and earth about every petty matter, inability to bear with contradiction, or to deny oneself any desire, are not proofs of mental strength, but of extreme weakness. And the rapid alternations between outbursts of anger and of tears that, accord- ing to the unanimous testimony of eye-witnesses, at this time manifested themselves in Lassalle, point unmistakably to an ab- solutely shattered nervous system. In this condition it was impossible for him to take his defeat quietly, and he sought to obtain satisfaction in a duel for the insult which, in his opinion, had been offered him. Foolish as duelling is in itself, it was comprehensible enough under these circumstances. In the circles of society in which this affair occurred, a duel is the cleansing bath that removes all stain and all insult, and if Lassalle had not the moral strength to resort — no matter what he was fighting for — only to means such as became the representative of the party of the socialistic reorganisa- tion of Society, then it was but logical that he should try to obtain satisfaction for the supposed insult offered after the fashion of his surroundings. He who faced the Bojard Janko von Racowitza in duel was not the Socialist Lassalle, but Lassalle the would-be aristocrat mer- chant's son, and if in the person of the latter the former, i.e., the Socialist, was also shot down in the duel, he thereby expiated the sin of having allowed his other self to gain the ascendancy. CHAPTER X. CONCLUSION. LASSALLE's LEGACY TO THE GERMAN WORKING-CLASS MOVEMENT. Thus did an early death abruptly end Lassalle's political career, his plans and hopes. Perhaps it was well so, perhaps in his last hours he himself did not think it a misfortune. The goal that he had believed he could take by storm had again receded into the dis- tance, and for the quiet work of organisation he did not believe himself fitted. Thus his immediate future seemed problematical enough, and this may have contributed largely to the almost frantic passion with which he threw himself into the Donniges affair. No doubt it is idle to speculate as to what Lassalle might have done if he had not fallen beneath the bullet of Herr von Itacowitza. And yet this question has hitherto been, for the most part, answered in such a way as to justify a brief examination of it. For it is generally contended, that had Lassalle lived, there would have been nothing left for him, as things were, but to follow the example of his friend Bucher, and to accept office in the service of the Prussian State. But this is to judge Lassalle quite wrongly. Certainly, the policy finally adopted by him must, if logically carried out, have led him at last into the Government camp, but it is just this last step which Lassalle would not himself have taken. He would never have donned the Prussian livery. He possessed sufficient means to live as he pleased, and such a post as the Prussian Government could offer him, would have no more satisfied his ambition, than it would have been congenial to his innermost and always unchanged convictions. In this respect he could rather have said to Bismarck than Bismarck to him : " What canst thou, poor devil, give ?" 1 85 i86 Ferdinand Lassalle. It is far more probable that as soon as the sentences pronounced against him had come into effect, he would have permanently settled down abroad, and there awaited some change in the condi- tions of things in Prussia and in Germany. For it is self-evident that the Hamburg " coup," even though the meeting had been held, and the resolution passed, would have had practically no effect upon the actual situation. How poor the outlook was may be seen from the fact that the mere consent of Helene von Donniges had sufficed to seriously shake Lassalle's opinion as to the probable effect of the " coup." On the 27th July, he had written of this project to the Countess Hatzfeld : ! 'I must get to Hamburg first, where I am going to make a great, very great, perhaps really im- portant ' coup '." The following day he obtains Helene's consent to be his wife, and then writes to the Countess that he doesn't promise himself " anything much '' from the Hamburg attempt. The passage referred to in this letter has certainly been quoted very often, but as it is extremely characteristic of Lassalle's mood at this time, it may again be quoted here. It runs : " How you misunderstand me when you write : ' Cannot you, for a time, be satisfied with science, friendship, and the beauties of nature ] ' You think I must have politics. "Ah! how little you are au fait with me. I desire nothing more ardently than to be quite rid of all politics, in order to devote myself to science, friendship, and nature. I am sick and tired of politics. Truly, I would burn as passionately for them as ever if there were anything serious to be done, or if I had the power, or saw the means to bring it about — such means as should benefit me — FOB WITHOUT SUPREME POWER NOTHING CAN BE DONE. For child's play, however, I am too old and too great. That is why I very reluctantly undertook the presidentship ! I only yielded to you. And that is why it now weighs upon me terribly. If I were but rid of it, this were the moment when I should decide to go to Naples with you ! But how get rid of it 1 " For events, I fear, will develop slowly, slowly, and my glowing soul finds no joy in these children's maladies, and chronic processes. Politics mean actual, immediate activity. Everything else can be Cohdusioiti 187 done as well by science. I shall try to exercise pressure on events in Hamburg. What the effect will be, I cannot say, nor do I promise myself anything much from it ! "Ah ! could I but get out of it ! " In another passage in the same letter, Lassalle writes that he is " in good spirits and full of strength," and, "well, the old strength is still there, and the old good luck too." They were, therefore, essentially political considerations which dictated these lines full of resignation. When, after his stay with Helene von Donniges at Bern, Las- salle arrived on the 3rd August at Geneva, he appears to have made up his mind as to provisional expatriation. Among the papers of Johanu Philipp Becker, there is a permis de sejour of the Geneva Government made out for " M. Ferdinand Lassalle, pro- fesseur," living " Chez M. Becker," and upon the wrapper the follow- ing remarks in the hand of the old veteran of freedom : "When friend Lassalle, on his arrival in the fatal year 1864, told me that he felt his strength exhausted, and that he must give himself pause ; that he had believed he could bring the Socialist movement to a head in about one year, but that he now saw that it would take decades, for which he did not feel his physical strength sufficient, and that, above all, he could never stand the im- pending imprisonment ; hereupon I advised him under these circumstances, to seek a definite residence somewhere, and to this end, at once to settle down in Geneva, and when in conformity with the law, he could prove a two years' sojourn, to have himself naturalised, which would have caused no difficulty at this time. Meanwhile, he could, of course, travel as much as he liked. Lassalle unhesitatingly agreed, and on the 11th August, 1864, I obtained for him the permis de sejour." The permit itself is made out for six months. During the four weeks of his struggle for Helene von Donniges, the letters that reached Lassalle from the Secretariat of the General German Working-men's Association, were not even an- 1 88 Ferdinand Lassalle. swered by him. It was only on the evening before the duel, when making hia will, that he again remembered the Association, and left its Secretary, Willms, 500 thalers a year for five years, for purposes of agitation, and 150 thalers a year for his personal use. He recommended the Frankfort delegate, Bernhard Becker, as his own successor. He was to hold fast to the organisation ; " it will lead the working-class to victory." Among the members of the Association, the news of Lassalle's death caused no little consternation. For a long time it was im- possible for them to grasp the idea that Lassalle had actually fallen in a mere ordinary love affair. They believed in a pre- meditated plot batched by his opponents to get rid of the dangerous agitator, and did homage to the fallen man as the victim of a vile political intrigue. A veritable Las alle cult now grew up, a kind of Lassalle religion, the propagation of which was, above all, stimulated — for very natural reasons — by the Countess Hatzfeld. The personal attitude which Lassalle had adopted to the workers also contributed largely to this cult. Amiable as he could be in his intercourse with them, he had constantly taken care to impress upon tliem both by his outward appearance and his manners, his social and mental superiority. Further, he had with the utmost complacency allowed himself to be feted at Ronsdorf as a kind of founder of a new religion, and had himself taken care that an account exaggerating the actual occurrences should appear in the Nordstern. In his speeches his own personality had come more and more to the front — to such an extent that when he spoke of himself in connection with others, he had invariably put the I first. Some persons may have been repelled by this attitude, but upon the masses, especially in the salad days of the movement, it cast a great charm, and the more a legendary halo invested the per- sonality of Lassalle, the greater became the after-effects of that charm. It would, however, be altogether a mistake to deny the fact that this cult for the personality of Lassalle did, for a long time, greatly help on the movement. When all is said and done most persons Conclusion. 1 89 like to see a cause, which, the more far-reaching its aims at any given moment, must seem the more abstract, embodied in one indi- vidual. This craving to personify a cause is the secret of the success of most founders of religions, whether charlatans or visionaries, and in England and America it is a recognised factor in political party- struggles. This craving is so strong, that at times the bare fact that a certain personality has withdrawn himself from a body of men, his equals or even his superiors, is sufficient to raise him above them, and to procure him a power that has been obstinately refused them. We have only to recall the Boulanger fever in France, which is by no means without its prototypes in the history of other countries. Dozens of members of the French Chamber were Boulanger's superiors in knowledge, ability, and character, and could point to the most honourable scars gained in the service of the Republic, but they became mere ciphers side by side with him, whilst he became the great One, and his name enkindled hundreds of thousands. Why ? Because an idea was suddenly incorporated in him, while the Chamber of Deputies, despite the sum of knowledge and of experience which it represented, was nothing but an anonymous quantity. The name Lassalle became a standard which created more and more enthusiasm among the masses the more Lassalle's works spread among the people. Intended to produce immediate effect, written with extraordinary talent, popular, and yet setting forth the theoretical points of view, they had, and to a certain extent still have to-day, a great effect in agitation. "The Working-men's Pro- gramme," the " Open Reply Letter," the " Worker's Reader," etc., have won over hundreds of thousands to Socialism. The strength of conviction that breathes in these writings has enkindled hun- dreds of thousands to struggle for the rights of labour. And with this, Lassalle's writings never degenerate into a jingle of meaning- less phrases : they are pervaded by a sensible realism, which cer- tainly at times is mistaken as to means, but always seeks to keep actual facts in sight, qualities which have through his writings been communicated to the movement. That whereof Lassalle in practice had, perhaps, something too much, he has given, in his first and 190 Ferdinand Lassalle. best propagandist works, the right measure which the working-class movement required. If the German Social Democracy has always recognised the value of a strong organisation, if it has been so con- vinced of the necessity of the concentration of forces, that even without the outer bond of organisation it has yet known how to perform all the functions of one, this is largely a heritage of the agitation of Lassalle. It is an indisputable fact that in those places where, amongst the workers, the traditions of the Lassallean agitation were strongest, as a rule, most was accomplished in the way of organisation. However, one cannot have the advantages of a thing without having to accept its disadvantages into the bargain. We have seen what a doubly two-edged weapon the Lassullean agitation was, two-edged in its theoretical foundation, two-edged in its practice. And this continued, of course, long after Lassalle him- self was dead. Aye, it became worse. Adhesion to Lassalle's tactics meant adhesion to the change of front executed by Lassalle during the last months of his agitation, he himself knowing, and making the mental reservation that he should be able to turn back and throw off the mask at any moment. But in his own words : " individuals can dissemble, the masses never.'' His policy, if literally carried out, meant misleading the masses. And the masses were misled. The time of the Schweitzer dictatorship came. Whether Herr von Schweitzer was ever, in the literal sense of the word, a Government agent, seems to me very doubt- ful ; but there can be no doubt that his tactics were at times those of a Government agent. Why, under his leadership, it even came to this, that agitators of the " General German Work- ing-men's Association " declared a republican to be synonymous with a bourgeois, because republics so far have been bourgeois republics. Schweitzer was unquestionably the most gifted of Lassalle's successors. But if he almost equalled Lassalle in talent, he surpassed him in all his worst faults. He was a real cynic, and he therefore coquetted with the Social demagogues of the Prussian Court with even less hesitation than Lassalle had done. But that he should have been able to do this without once failing Conclusion. iqi to find some passage justifying his manoeuvres in Lassalle's speeches is a reproach from which Lassalle cannot escape. Even Schweitzer has done nothing worse than to designate as a simple " clique " the parties that were fighting for the constitutional rights of the people's representatives, among whom were men like Jacoby, Waldeck, Ziegler, etc. Other faults of Lassalle's also were reproduced in the movement, and it cost long and sharp struggles before they were completely overcome. As to the theoretical errors of Lassalle, which I have dealt with more fully above, I need here only remind my readers what violent struggles it cost before a right appreciation of the Trades Union movement could make headway in the ranks of the German Socialist working-men ; how long Trades Unions were op- posed by a large portion of the Socialists, on the strength of the '•' iron law of wages.'' The result of the personal colour that Lassalle gave the movement, was that after his death it drifted into the current of sectarianism, and floundered about in it for long years to come. Persons who have played a prominent part, and developed re- markable qualities, usually beget a large number of imitators. So, too, Lassalle. The semi and semi-demi Lassalles after his death blossomed forth all over the land. But since for want of his ability, they were forced to confine themselves to imitating, " Wie er sich gerauspert, und wie er gespuckt," 1 and as we have seen, this not being his best side, they formed one of the most obnoxious excrescences of the working-class movement. To-day all this has been overcome, and we can speak of it quietly, and without bitterness. But there was a time when the movement suffered from it, and that is why it is referred to here. But enough. Else the impression of what I have said of the heritage which Lassalle left the workers, even to this day, might be weakened, and this is by no means my intention. So long as I had to consider Lassalle's work in detail, I was bound to be severe ; for greater than the fame of the individual is the interest of the great cause for which we are fighting, and that above all 1 " The way he hawked, and the way he spat.'' 192 Ferdinand Lassalie. else demands' the truth. The Social Democracy has no legends, and needs none ; it regards its champions not as saints but as men. It does not, on this account, value their services the less, but honours the memory of those who have done well in the work of freeing the working-class. And this Lassalie did in an eminent degree. Perhaps in a more eminent degree than he himself suspected on the eve of his death. Things came about differently from what'he believed they would \ but the movement to-day is the same as that for which he raised the standard in the spring of 1863. The ends for which it strives are the same to-day, even though they be striven for in other ways and with other demands. A few years hence it may, perhaps, be fighting in yet other ways, and still it will be the same movement. No man, even the greatest thinker, can foretell the march of Social Democracy in detail. We know not how many struggles still lie before us, nor how many fighters will have to perish before the goal of the movement is reached ; but the grave-stones of our dead tell us of the progress of the movement, and fill us with the certainty of its triumph in the future. Lassalie no more created German Social Democracy than any other man. We have seen how great were the stir and ferment among the advanced German workers, when Lassalie placed him- self at the head of the movement. But even though he cannot be called the creator of the movement, yet to Lassalie belongs the honour of having done great things for it, greater than falls to the lot of most single individuals to achieve. Where at most there was only a vague desire, he gave conscious effort ; he trained the German workers to understand their historical mission, he taught them to organise as an independent political party, and in this way at least accelerated by many years the process of development of the movement. His actual undertaking failed, but his struggle for it was not in vain ; despite failure, it brought the working-class nearer to the goal. The time for victory was not yet, but in order to conquer, the workers must first learn to fight. And to have trained them for the fight, to have, as the song says, given them swords, this remains the great, the undying merit of Ferdinand Lassalie. THE END. SOCIAL SCIENCE SERIES. SCARLET CLOTH, EACH 2t. 6d. 1. Work and Wages. Prot J. B. Thobold Roqers. " Nothing that Professor Rogers writes can fail to be of interest to thoughtful, people."— Athencewn. 3. Civilisation : Its Cause and Cure. Edward Carpenter. " No passing piece of polemics, but a permanent possession." — Scottish Review. 8. Quintessence of Socialism. Dr. Schaffls " Precisely the manual needed. Brief, lucid, fair and wise."— British Weekly. 4. Darwinism and Polities. D. G. Ritchie, M.A. (Oxon.). New Edition, with two additional Essays on Human Evolution. " One of the most suggestive books we have met with." — Literary World. 6. Religion of Socialism. E. Belfort Bax 6. Ethics of Socialism. E. Bei.fort Bax. " Mr. Bax is by far the ablest of the English exponents of Socialism." — Weetmintter Review. 7. The Drink Question. Dr. Kate Mitchell. " Plenty of interesting matter for reflection. '-» graphic. 8. Promotion of General Happiness. Prof. M. Macmillan " A reasoned account of the most advanced and most enlightened utilitarian doc- trine in a clear and readable form."— Scotsman. 9. England's Ideal, ftc. Edward Carpenter, " The literary power is unmistakable, their freshness of style, their humour, and 1 their enthusiasm." — Pall Mall Gazette. 10. Socialism in England. Sidney Webb, LL.B. " The best general view of the subject from the modern Socialist side." — Alhenceum. 11. Prince Bismarck and State Socialism. W. H. Dawson. " A succinct, well-digested review of German social and economic legislation since 1870."— Saturday Review. 19. Godwin's Political Justice (On Property). Edited by H. S. Salt. " Shows Godwin at bis best ; with an interesting and informing introduction."— Glasgow Herald. 18. The Story of the French Revolution. E. Belfort Bax. " A trustworthy outline." — Scotsman. 14. The Co-Operative Commonwealth. Laurence Gronlund. " An independent exposition of the Socialism of the Marx school." — Contemporary Review. 16. Essays and Addresses. Bernard Bobanqoet, M.A. (Oxon.). " Ought to be in the hands of every student of the Nineteenth Century spirit" — Echo. " No one can complain of not being able to understand what Mr. Bosanquet means."— Pall Mali Gazette. 16. Charity Organisation. C. S. Loch, Secretary to Charity Organisation Society. " A perfect little manual." — Athenaeum. " Deserves a wide circulation."— Scotsman. 17. Thoreau's Anti-Slavery and Reform Papers. Edited by H. S. Salt. " An interesting collection of essays." — Literary World. 18. Self-Help a Hundred Tears Ago. Q. 3. Holtoakb. " Will be stndied with much Deneflt by all who are interested in the amelioration of the condition of the poor."— Morning Post. 19. The New Tork State Reformatory at Elmlra. Alexander Winter. With Preface by Havelock. Ellis. " A valuable contribution to the literature of penology."— Black and White. BOCIAL SCIENCE SERIES— (Continued). &[, Common Sense about Women. T. W. Higoinson. " An admirable collection of papers, advocating in tbe most liberal spirit Che emancipation of women." — Woman's Herald. $1. The Unearned Increment. W. H. Dawson. "A concise but comprehensive volume. "—Bcho. -22. Our Destiny. Laurence Gronlund. "A very vigorous little book, dealing with the influence of Socialism on morals and rengion.— Daily Chronicle. S3. The Working-Class Movement In America. Dr. Edward and E. Marx Avelino. " Will give a good idea of the condition of the working classes in America, and of the various organisations which they have formed." — Scots Leader. '24. Luxury. Prof. Emilb de Laveleyh. " An eloquent plea on moral and economical grounds for simplicity of life."— Academy. 25. The Land and the Labourers. Rev. C. W. Stu&bs, M.A. "This admirable book should be circulated in every village in the country."— Manchester Guardian. 36. The Evolution of Property. Paul Lafabqub, "Will prove interesting and profitable to all students of economic history." — Scotsman. 37. Crime and its Causes. W. Douglas Morbisoh. " Can hardly fail to suggest to all readers several new and pregnant reflections on the subject." — Anti-Jacobin. $8. Principles of State Interference. - D. G. Kitchie, M.A. " An interesting contribution to the controversy on the functions of tbe State."— Glasgow Herald. 39. German Socialism and F. Lassalle. W. H. Dawson. "Asa biographical history of German Socialistic movements during this century it may be accepted as complete."— B'-msh Weekly. #0. The Purse and the Conscience. H. M. Thompson, B.A. (Cantab.). " Shows common sense and fairness in bis arguments."— Scotsman. ■81. Origin of Property in Land. Fustel de Coulanoes. Edited, with an Introductory Chapter on the English Manor, by Prof. W. J. Ashley, M.A. " His views are clearly stated, and are worth reading."— Saturday Review. $2. The English Republic. W. J.Linton. Edited by Kinbton Parke a. " Characterised by that vigorous intellectuality which has marked his long life of literary and artistic activity. '—Glasgow Herald. >a Ji The Co-Operative Movement. Beatrice Potteb. "Without doubt the ablest and most philosophical analysis of the Co-Operative Movement which has yet been produced."— Speaker, 34. Neighbourhood Guilds. Dr. Stanton Cora, "A most suggestive little book to anyone interested in the social question.* 1 — Pall Mall Gazette. &6. Modern Humanists. J. M. Robertson. " Mr. Robertson's style is excellent— nay, even brilliant— and his purely literary criticisms bear the mark of much acumen."— Times. $6. Outlooks from the New Standpoint. E. Belfort Bax. "Mr. Bax is a very acute and accomplished student of history and economics." — Daily Chronicle. $ff. Distributing Co-Operattve Societies. Dr. Lxjigi Pizzamiglio. Edited by ,P. J. Snbll. " Dr. Pizzamiglio has gathered together and grouped a wide array of facts and statistics, and they speak for themselves."— Speaker. £8. Collectivism and Socialism. By A. Nacquet. Edited by W. Heafobd. " An admirable criticism by a well-known French politician of tbe New Socialism of Marx and Lassalle."— Daily Chronicle. SOCIAL SCIENCE SERIES-(Co»'mue<2). 39. The London Programme. Sidney Webb, LL.B. " Brimful of excellent ideas."— Anti-Jacobin. 40. The Modern State. Paul Leroy Beaulxbtj. "A most interesting book; well worth a place in the library of every social inquirer."—^. B. Economist. 41. The Condition of Labour. Henry Geo rob. " Written with striking ability, and sure to attract attention. "— Newcastle Chronicle. 42. The Revolutionary Spirit preceding the French Revolution. Felix Rocquain. With a Preface by Professor Huxley. * The student of the French Revolution will find in it an excellent introduction to the study of that catastrophe. "— Scotsman. 43. The Student's Marx. Edward Aveling, D.So* "One of the most practically useful of any in the Series."— Glasgow Herald. 44. A Short History of Parliament. B. C. Skottowe, M.A. (Oxon.). " Deals very carefully anil completely with this side of constitutional history.*— Spectator. 46. Poverty : Its Genesis and Exodus. J. G. Godard. *' He states the problems with great force and clearnesi " — N. B. Economist. 46. The Trade Policy of Imperial Federation. Maurice H. Heevby. " An interesting contribution to the discussion."— Publishers' Circular. 47. The Dawn or Radicalism. J. Bowles Daly, LL.D. " Forms an admirable picture of an epoch more pregnant, perhaps, with political instruction than any other in the world's history. "—Daily Telegraph. 48. The Destitute Allen In Great Britain. Arnold White; Montague Crack a n- thorpe, Q.C. ; W. A. M'Arthur, M.P.; W. H. Wilkins, &o. "Much valuable information concerning a burning question of the day."— Time*. 49. Illegitimacy and the Influence of Seasons on Conduct. ALBERT ItEFFINGWELL, M.D. We have not often seen a work based on statistics which is more continuously interesting."— Westminster Review. £0. Commercial Crises of the Nineteenth Century. H. M. Hyndman. "One of the best and most permaneutly useful volumes of the Series. "—Literary Opinion. 61. The State and Pensions in Old Age. J. A. Spender and Arthur Acland, M.P. "A careful and cautious examination of the question."— Timet. 62. The Fallacy of Saving. John M. Robertson. " A plea tor the reorganisation of our social and industrial system."— Speaker. £3. The Irish Peasant. Anon. 'A real contribution to the Irish Problem by a close, patient and dispassionate investigator."— Daily Chronicle. 64. The Effects of Machinery on Wages. Prof. J. S. Nicholson, D.So. " Ably reasoned, clearly stated, impartially written."— Literary World. 55- The Social Horizon. Anon. "A really admirable little book, bright, clear, and unconventional."— Daily Chronicle. 66. Socialism, Utopian and Scientific. Frederick Engels. " The body of the book is still fresh and striking." — Daily Chronicle. 67. Land Nationalisation. A. R. Wallace. "The most instructive and convincing of the popular works on the subject."— National Reformer. 68. The Ethic of Usury and Interest. "Rev. W. B lis sard. "The work is marked by genuine ability." — North British Agriculturalist. 69. The Emancipation of Women. Adelb Crepaz. " By far the most comprehensive, luminous, and penetrating work on this question that I have yet met witb. "— Extract from Mr. Gladstone's Preface. 60. The Eight Hours* Question. John M. Robertson. "A very cogent and sustained argument on what is at present the unpopular ■ide."— Times. 61. Drunkenness. George R. Wilson, M.B. " Well written, carefully reasoned, free from cant, and full of sound sense."— National Observer. 63. The New Reformation. Rambden Balm forth. " A striking presentation of the nascent religion, bow beat to realize the personal and social ideal."— Westminster,- Review. 63 The Agricultural Labourer. T. £. Kebbb,^ " A short summary of his position, with appendices on wages, education, allot- ments, etc., etc." 64. Ferdinand Lassalle as a Social Reformer. £. Bernbtiibv " A worthy addition to the Social Science series-"— Worth British Economist. . SOCIAL SCIENCE SERIES— (Continued). 66. England's Foreign Trade In XlXth Century. A. L. Bowleg. " Full of valuable information, carefully compiled."— Timet. 66. Theory and Policy of Labour Protection. Dr. Schaffle. " An attempt to systematize a conservative programme of reform." — Man. Guard. 67. History or Rochdale Pioneers. G. J. Holyoake. " Brought down from 1844 to the Rochdale Congress of 1892."— Co-Op. News. 68. Sights of Women. M. Ostragobski. "An admirable storehouse of precedents, conveniently arranged. "—Daily Chron, 69. Dwellings of the People. Locke Worthington. "A valuable contribution to one of the most pressing problems of the day." — Daily Chronicle. 70. Hours, Wages, and Production. Dr. Brentano. " Characterised by all Professor Brentano's clearness of style." — Economic Review* 71. Rise of Modern Democracy. Ch. Borgeaud, " A very useful little volume, characterised by exact research." — Daily Chronicle. 72. Land Systems of Australasia. Wm. Kpps, "Exceedingly valuable at the present time of depression and difficulty. "— Scots. Mag. 73. The Tyranny of Socialism. Y 'ES Guyot. Pref. by J. H. Levy. " M. Guyot is smart, lively, trenchant, and interesting."— Daily Chronicle. 74. Popnlation and the Social System. Dr. Nitb. " A very valuable work of an Italian economist."— Went. Rev. 75. The Labour Question. T. G. Spyer». " Will be found extremely useful." — Times. 76. British Freewomen. C. C. Stopes. "The most complete study of the Women's Suffrage question."— English Worn. Rev, 77. Suicide anb Insanity. Dr. J. K. Strahan. " An interestesting monograph dealing exhaustively with the subject." — Timet. 78. A History of Tithes. Rev. H. "W. Clarke - " May be recommended to all who desire an accurate idea of the subject." — D. Chron. 79. Three Months in a Workshop. P. Gohre, with Pref. by Prof. Ely. " A vivid picture of the state of mind of German workmen."— Manch. Guard. 80. Darwinism and Race Progress. Prof. J. B. Haycraft . "An interesting subject treated in an attractive fashion." — Glasgow Herald. 81. Local Taxation and Finance. G. H. Blunden . 82. Perils to British Trade. £. Bhrgis. 83. The Social Contract. J J. Rousseau. Edited by E. J. Tozer. 84. Labour upon the Land. Edited by J. A. Hobson, M.A, 85. Moral Pathology. Arthur E. Giles, M.D., B.So. 86. Parasitism, Organic and Social. Massart and Vandervklde. 87. Allotments and Small Holdings. J. L. Green. 88. Money and its Relations to Prices. L. L. Price. 89. Sober by Act of Parliament. F. A. Mackenzie. 90. Workers on their Industries. F. W. Galton. 91. Revolution and Counter-Revolution. Karl Marx. 92 Over-Production and Crises. K. Rodbertus. 93. Local Government and State Aid. S. J. Chapman. 94. Village Communities in India. B. H. Baden-Powell, M.A., CLE. 95. Anglo-American Trade. S. J. Chapman. 96. A Plain Examination of Socialism. Gustave Simonson, M.A., M.D. 97. Commercial Federation & Colonial Trade Policy. J. Davidson, M. A., Phil.D. 98. Selections from Fourier. C. GrDE and J. Franklin. 99 Public-House Reform. A. N. Cummin©. DOUBLE VOLUMES, 3s. 6d. 1. Life of Robert Owen. Lloyd Jones. 2. The Impossibility of Social Democracy : a Seoond Fart of " The Quintessence- of Socialism ". Dr. A. Schaffle. 3. Condition of the Working Class in England in 1844. Frederick Engels. 4. The Principles of Social Economy. Yves Guyot. 6. Social Peace. G. von Schultze-Gaevernitz. 6. A Handbook of Socialism. W. D P. Bliss. 7. Socialism: its Growth and Outcome. W. Morris and E. B. Bax. 8. Economic Foundations of Society. A. Loria. SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO., Lim., LONDON, \TT7TKT \Tf\T>TT .