325 CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY GIFT OF THE FORD MOTOR COMPANY FUNP UNDERGRADUATE LIBRARY Cornell University Library JC 325.H68 1918 The metaphysical theory of the state :a 3 1924 014 749 539 The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924014749539 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY of the STATE BY THE SAME AUTHOR SOCIAL DEVELOPMENT: ITS NATURE AND CON- DITIONS THE RATIONAL GOOD: A STUDY IN THE LOGIC OF PRACTICE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL JUSTICE BY J. A. HOBSON AND MORRIS GINSBERG L. T. HOBHOUSE : HIS LIFE AND WORK THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE A Criticism By L. T. HOBHOUSE London GEORGE ALLEN & UNWIN LTD Ruskin House Museum Street FIRST PUBLISHED IN 1918 SECOND IMPRESSION IQZZ THIRD IMPRESSION 1 926 FOURTH IMPRESSION 1938 FIFTH IMPRESSION I951 This book is copyright under the Berne Convention No portion may be reproduced by any process without written permission. Inquiries should be addressed to the publishers PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN BY PHOTOTYPE LTD. LONDON DEDICATION TO LIEUTENANT R. O. HOBHOUSE, R.A.F My Dear Oliver, If you can carry your memory across the abyss which separates us all from July 1914, you will remember some hours which we spent reading Kant together in a cool Highgate garden in those summer days of peace. I think by way of relaxation we sometimes laid aside Kant, took up Herodotus, and felt ourselves for a moment in the morning of the world. But it is of Kant that I remind you, because three years later I was reading his great successor in the same garden in the same summer weather, but not with you-. One morning as I sat there annotating Hegel's theory of freedom, jarring sounds broke in upon the summer stillness. We were well accustomed to the noises of our strange new world that summer. Daily if the air was still we heard, as some one said, the thud of guns across the northern sea, and mur- mur of innumerable 'planes. But this morning it was soon clear that something more was on foot. Gunfire, at first distant, grew rapidly nearer, and soon broke out from the northern heights hard by. The famiUar drone of the British aeroplanes was pierced by the whining of the Gothas. High, above, machine guns barked in sharp staccato an(f distant thuds announced the fall of bombs. 6 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE Presently three white specks could be seen dimly through the light haze overhead, and we watched their course from the field. The raid was soon over. The three specks drifted away towards the east, the gunfire died down, the whining faded away, and below the hill the great city picked up its dead. The familiar sounds resumed their sway, the small birds chirruped from the shrubs, and the distant murmur of the traffic told of a world going steadily on its accustomed course. As I went back to my Hegel my first mood was one of -self-satire. Was this a time for theorizing or destroying theories, when the world was tumbUng about our ears ? My second thoughts ran otherwise. To each man the tools and weapons that he can best use. In the bombing of London I had just witnessed the visible and tangible outcome of a false and wicked doctrine, the foundations of which lay, as I believe, in the book before me. To combat this doctrine effectively is to take such part in the fight as the physical disabilities of middle age allow. Hegel himself carried the proof-sheets of his first work to the printer through streets crowded with fugitives from the field of Jena. With that work began the most penetrating and subtle of all the intellectual influences which have sapped the rational humanitarianism of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, and in the Hegehan theory of the god-state all that I had witnessed lay implicit. You may meet his Gothas in mid air, and may the full power of a just cause be with you. I must be content with more pedestrian methods. But " to make the world a safe place for democracy," the weapons of the spirit are as necessary as those of the flesh. You have described to me times when your lofty world is peaceable enough — above the Canal in the dawn, when all the desert lies gray and still before the first sunbeam sets the air moving, or alone in the blueness, cut off by a bank of DEDICATION 7 cloud from earth. When at such times the mind works freely and you think over the meaning of the great contest, I should like to think that you carried with you some ideas from this volume to your heights. At any rate you will bear with you the sense thit we are together as of old, in that in our different ways we are both fighters in one great cause. Your affectionate father, L. T. HOBHOUSE. NOTE The substance of this volume was given in a course of lectures at the London School of Economics in the autumn of 1917. I have to thank my colleague Dr. A. Wolf for reading the MS. and making several useful emendations of detail. CONTENTS DEDICATION page s I. The Objects of Social Investigation II II. Freedom and Law 26 III. The Real Will 44 IV. The Will of the State 71 V. Varying Applications of the Metaphysical Theory 96 Conclusion 134 APPENDIX I. Hegel's Theory of the Will 138 II. The Theory of the Absolute 150 Index 155 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE LECTURE I THE OBJECTS OF SOCIAL INVESTIGATION People naturally begin to think about social questions wh«n they find that there is something going wrong in social life. Just as in the physical body it is the ailment that interests us, while the healthy processes go on without our being aware of them, so a society in which ever5rthing is working smoothly and in accordance with the accepted opinion of what is right and proper raises no question for its own members. We are first conscious of diges- tion when we are aware of indigestion, and we begin to think about law and government when we feel law to be oppressive or see that government is making mistakes. Thus the starting-point of social inquiry is the point at which we are moved by a wrong which we desire to set right, or, perhaps at a slightly higher remove, by a lack which we wish to make good. But from this starting- point reflection advances to a fuller and more general conceptidn of society. If we begin by criticizing some particular injustice, we are led on to discuss what justice is. Beginning with some special social disorder, we are forced to examine the nature of social order and the purposes for which society exists. The social theory which we reach on these lines is a theory of ends, values, purposes, which leads us up to Ethics or Moral Philosophy, to questions of the rights and duties of man, and the means by which institutions of society may be made to 12 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE conform thereto. The principles of Ethics are supreme, or, as they have been called, architectonic. They apply to man in all relations and to life on aU sides. They guide, or are meant to guide, the personal life of man no less than his collective and political activities. They provide the standard by which all human rfelations are to be judged. When, therefore, we study social and political institutions with a view to ascertaining their value or justification, our inquiry is in reality a branch of Ethics. Our results rest in the end on the application of principles of well-being to the social organization of man. This is one perfectly legitimate method of social inquiry, and as involving an analysis of common experi- ence, leading up to or down from a theory of ends or values, it is appropriately called Social PhUosophyi Legitimate as it is, this method of investigating society ( has its special danger. In pursuing the ideal it some- times loses hold of the actual. In analysing the meaning of institutions it may overlook their actual working, and if we follow it too blindly we may end either in abstract propositions which have little relation to practical possibility and serve only to breed fanatics ; or in abandoning the interest in actual society altogether and amusing ourselves with the construction of Utopias. In reaction from this tendency many students would say that the primary business of social theory is to inves- tigate the facts of social life as they are, the historical development of society and its several institutions, the statistical description of any given society as it is, the endeavour to ascertain the laws of cause and effect which, it is held, must permeate social life as they permeate every other sphere of reality. In place of a social philosophy, then, we have a social science, and it is held that by a social science we can ascertain, measure and predict, just as we can ascertain, measure and predict the behaviour of any system of physical bodies. Without touching here on the question whether in social science prediction is possible or not, it is suffi- cient to say that the scientific study of social life or the THE OBJECTS OF SOCIAL INVESTIGATION 13 endeavour to ascertain the relations of cause and effect is not only a legitimate object but one which has in point of fact yielded good results. Few would now deny that the strictly scientific method has its place in social inquiry. But objection may stUl be taken to the dis- tinction between ideals and facts. To begin with, it may be urged that the social inquirer could not if he would lay aside his ideals. Whenever we are dealing with social life we are dealing with a matter of profound interest to ourselves. When the chemist wishes to ascertain the temperature at which a soHd Uquefies, or a liquid boils, he has in the end to read off a certain obser- vation, and it is not a matter of profound human interest whether the figure that he reads is 150° or 160° ; but when a social student inquires how an institution is working, whether a new law is attaining its object, whether Trade Union activity is or is not succeeding in raising wages, shortening hours or otherwise improving the condition of the operatives, the answer to his question is not only in reality much more dif&cult to ascertain but is also one which stirs prejudices, confirms or refutes presuppositions, is certain to be challenged by lively interests. The diflftculty is not pecuUar to the study of contemporary fact. History, even ancient history, is written in a certain spirit and a certain temper de- pendent on the personal presuppositions of the writer. Human affairs are so complex and the interweaving of cause and effect so subtle that in the presentation of an historical development there will always be an element dependent on the point of view of the writer and on the selection and emphasis which may honestly seem the fairest selection and the natural emphasis to the par- ticular writer, but which may seem quite other to a different investigator approaching the same object with a different background of thought. Nor is this all. Putting aside aU that may be said as to the bias of investigators, it may be urged that the subject of investigation itself is charged throughout with the ideals, emotions, interests of men and women, both 14 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE ^ as individuals and as corporate bodies ; and, moreover, the logic of those ideals, the very thing which social philosophy investigates, the degree, that is, of their mutual consistency or inconsistency, is a matter of pro- found importance to their actual working. If two ideals penetrate the same nation or the same class and those two ideals are at bottom in conflict, the results must show themselves in the tangle of history. They must manifest themselves in divided aims and ultimately in failure. If, on the other hand, they are coherent and harmonious, then once more that result must appear in the greatness of the success attending their historical development. Thus, if we start with the most rigid determination to adhere to facts, we shall find that ideals are a part of the facts, and if we say that nevertheless we will treat them as facts without examining their truth, we shall find it hard to adhere to that position because their consistency and coherence, which are intimately relevant to their truth, deeply affect their practical efficiency. It may be granted that it is easier to distinguish the philosophical and the scientific treatment of society in principle than to keep them apart in practice. In prin- ciple we call the philosophical inquiry that which deals with the aim of life, with the standard of conduct, with all that ought to be, no matter whether it is or is not. The scientific method we call that which investigates facts, endeavours to trace cause and effect, aims at the establishment of general truths which hold good whether they are desirable or not. The distinction of principle is clear, but in point of fact the inquiry into ideals can never desert the world of experience without danger of losing itself in unreality and becoming that which the poet of idealism was unfairly called, " a beautiful, ineffec- tual angel beating in the void his luminous wings in vain." The ideal, though it has never been realized and perhaps may never be realized, must grow out of reality. It must be that which we can become, not that which is utterly removed from the emotions and aspi- THE OBJECTS OF SOCIAL INVESTIGATION 15 rations which have grown up within us in the actual evolution of mind. The ethically right, Professor Hoffding has said, must be sociologically possible. Thus, even as pure theory, the philosophical view cannot afford to disregard the facts. Still less can it do so if it passes over, as philosophy should, into the constructive attempt to reorganize life in accordance with its ideals. If the principles which it discovers are to be realized in this workaday world, this can only be by intimate knowledge of the details of this world, by the control of events through their causes, for the discovery of which we must go to pure science. Social Science, on the other hand, as we have seen, cannot ignore the elements of idealism as a working factor, as one of the forces, if you will, among the other forces, which it studies ; nor can it dis- regard the logical consistency or inconsistency of ideas, upon which their working force depends. Thus the philosophical, the scientific, and the practical interest, however distinct in theory, tend in their actual operation to be intermingled, and it must be admitted that we cannot carry one through without reference to the other. Nevertheless, to keep the issues distinct at every point is the first necessity of sound reasoning upon social affairs. What is essential for social investigation, whether it starts with the philosophic or scientific interest, is that in putting any question it should know precisely what that question is ; specifically, whether it is a question of what is desirable, of what ought to be ; or a question of what has been, is, or probably will be. These two questions, though necessarily related, are no less necessarily distinct, and to confuse them is the standing temptation of the social inquirer. If the social philosopher has sometimes thought to legislate for society without first informing himself of the facts as to what is possible and what is not, the scientific sociologist on his side is not innocent of all encroachments. It is a standing temptation to overbear questions of right and wrong by confident pre- dictions, which in reality rest more on the prepossessions of the prophet than on his insight into cause and effect. i6 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE It is the weakness of human nature that it likes to be on the winning side, and just as in an election the argu- ment most effective in catching votes is the demonstra- tion that we are winning already — a demonstration which might seem to make effort on that side superfluous — so in the study of social and economic development it is rhetorically effective to demonstrate that a particular social change is at hand, that it is an inevitable conse- quence of a concatenation of events that is bringing it about whether we will or not ; and this demonstration exercises, and is intended to exercise, a kind of coercion upon our minds whereby we resign ourselves to accept the change as desirable on the strength of arguments which have never touched its desirability at aU, but have proved, if they have proved anything, nothing more than the probable effect of certain operative causes. Intel- lectually, this method is one of confusion ; morally, it js paralysing to the will. If there were nothing for us but to accept the trend of events as we find it, then our science would relapse into fatalism, and, as members of the society which we study, we should be in the position simply of knowing the course of the stream which carries us along without any increase in the power to guide it, whether it happen to be taking us into the haven or over Niagara. When we allow Social Science thus to persuade us of the inevitableness of things, we are reversing the normal course of science. For, whatever else may be said of science, one of its functions is to increase human power, and this applies to sciences which deal with human life as well as to sciences which deal with inanimate objects. When we know the etiology of a disease we acquire for the first time a real prospect of controlling it. So it should be in social affairs, but so it can only be if we hold firmly to the distinction between the desirable and the actual, if we grasp clearly the principles which should regulate social life, and do not allow ourselves to be shaken in our hold of them by any knowledge of the changes which are actually going on among us. The THE OBJECTS OF SOCIAL INVESTIGATION 17 foundation^ therefore, of true social method is to hold the ideal and the actual distinct and use our knowledge of the one as a means to realizing the other. We may pursue the two investigations, if we will, side by side, for we have seen how very closely they are interwoven. But every question that we ask and every statement that we make ought to be quite clearly a statement as to fact or an assertion of what ought to be, and never a hybrid of the two. This distinction would, I think, be accepted both by the bulk of ethical thinkers and of scientific students of society, but there exists a form of social theory which repudiates it in principle. The foundation of this theory is the beUef that the ideal is realized in the actual world, and in particular in the world of organized society, not in the sense already noted above that there are ideals operating as psychological forces in human beings, but in the sense that the world at large, and in particular the social world, is, if properly understood, an incarnation or expression of the ideal ; that, as one thinker would put it, the Absolute is perfection ; or, as Hegel, who may be considered as the father of this school, laid down, " the insight to which . . . philosophy is to lead us is that the real world is as it ought to be." ^ The theory of society on this view is not to be detached from general metaphysics ; it is an integral part of the philosophy of things. Just as in a simple form of religion, the powers that be are ordained pf God, so with the metaphysician who starts from the belief that things are what they should be, the fabric of human life, and in particular the state system, is a part of an order which is inherently rational and good, an order to which the lives of individuals are altogether subordinate. The problem of social theory upon this view will not consist in the formulation of ideals as distinct from anything actual, yet capable of becoming actual if once human beings grasp them with a very firm determination to reahze them ; still less can it consist in investigating facts in distinction from • Philosophy of History, p. 38. 2 i8 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE ideals, for the very foundation of society as a part of the fabric of things is the ideal which it enshrines. The problem will be neither ethical nor scientific. It will start by a repudiation of the distinction upon which we have been insisting, and its task will be to state the nature of society in terms revealing the ideal elements which mere facts have a tendency to veil from our human eyes. This, then, is the metaphysical theory of the state. It is the endeavour to exhibit the fabric of society in a light in which we shall see ic, in or through its actual condition, as the incarnation of something very great and glorious indeed, as one expression of that supreme being which some of these thinkers call the Spirit and others the Absolute. There is no question here of realizing an ideal by human effort. We are already living in the ideal. It does not much matter whether we are rich or poor, healthy or enfeebled, personally aware of happiness or misery ; nay, it does not seem to matter very much whether we are just or unjust, virtuous or depraved, for we all are integral parts in something much wider and nobler than the individual life, something to which mere human good and evil, happiness or misery, are small matters, mere constituent .elements that, what- ever they may be for each one of us, play their part right well in the magnificent whole. Evil is indeed necessary to good. It is a part of the Perfection of the Absolute, and anything which would point to its extirpation as an ideal is condemned as an offshoot of popular notions of progress or ridiculed as a piece of humanitarian enthusiasm. Such, then, is the spirit of the metaphysical theory of society which I propose to examine in the shape given to it by its founder, Hegel, and his most modem and most faithful exponent. Dr. Bosanquet. This theory is com- monly spoken of as idealism, but it is in point of fact a much more subtle and dangerous enemy to the ideal than any brute denial of ideahsm emanating from a one- sided science. Against every attempt to construe the world as mere fact which we cannot modify, there will THE OBJECTS OF SOCIAL INVESTIGATION 19 always spring up the reaction of human hope, of human endeavour, of the deep-seated indignation at injustice, the " rebel passion " of pity. If the scientific man insists that as this world rose out of the whirl of atoms, agitated by mechanical forces, so it will ultimately dis- appear in the cold and darkness, none the less men will say " Here are we, conscious living beings palpitating with emotion, with feeling, products it may be of your whirl of atoms, yet allowed meanwhile some latitude to shape our lives, to avoid the worst evils and to cultivate some fleeting happiness ; let us at least stand together against this unkindly fate and make the best of life while we can, not only for our short-lived selves, but for our feeble race." Thus mechanical science stimulates at least the etliics of revolt. But when we are taught to think of the world which we know as a good world, to think of its injustices, wrongs and miseries as necessary elements in a pjerfect ideal, then, if we accept these argu- ments, our power of revolt is atrophied, our reason is hypnotized, our efforts to improve life and remedy wrong fade away into a passive acquiescence in things as they are ; or, still worse, into a slavish adulation of the Abso- lute in whose hands we are mere pawns. These, it may be said, are questions of general rather than social philosophy, but the point is that to the idealistic school, social philosophy is an application of the theory of the Absolute to human affairs. As Dr. Bosanquet tells us,' " the treatment of the state in this discussion is natu- rally analogous to the treatment of the universe." The happiness of the state is not to be judged by the happiness of the individual ; the happiness of the individual must be judged by the goodness of the state. It is to be valued by the perfection of the whole to which he belongs. In the conception, therefore, of the state as a totality, which is an end in itself, an end to which the lives of men and women are mere means, we have the working model of an Absolute. For the thoroughgoing ideaUst, all the conscious beings that live under the shadow of ' The Prittciple of Individuality and Value, p. 3ii« 20 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE the Absolute seem to have just as much or as little title to independent consideration as the cells of fhe human body. Now, for Hegel, the state is a form of the absolute spirit, which is the essence of aU things. " The state is the divine idea as it exists on earth." ' For " all the worth which the human being possesses — all spiritual reality he possesses only through the state." » " The state is the spirit which stands in the world and realizes itself therein consciously. . . . The existence of the state is God's movement in the world." 3 " The state is the divine will as the present spirit unfolding itself to the actual shape and organization of a world " {Ph. d. R. p. 327). " It is the absolute power upon earth " (p. 417). "It is its own end (Selbst-zweck). It is the ultimate end which has the highest right against the individual, whose highest duty is to be a member of the state " (p. 306). The method followed by this theory is not ethical because it does not seek to find reasons for human con- duct in any ultimate goal of human endeavour or in any rational principle of human duty. It does not seek these because it denies that the reflective reason of the individual is the method by which truth about ideals is to be ascertained. All true ideals are actual ; they belong to what is called the objective mind ; they are incarnated in the laws, traditions, customs of the society to which we belong. Nor, again, is the method scientific. It is neither historical nor statistical. It does not con- cern itself with the varying forms of social institutions, nor with the correlations of co-existence or succession. It assumes certain abstract conceptions 4 and expounds them dogmatically in general terms, putting aside the appeal to experience. If actual societies differ from the idealistic conception of them, so much the worse for « Philosophy of History, E. T., p. 41. » Ibid. p. 1.0 f. 3 Philosophie des Rechis, pp. 312-13. < Not that they are admitted to be abstract. They are believed by the idealist to be the very soul of reality (see, e.g., Phil, des Rechts, p. 58). THE OBJECTS OF SOCIAL INVESTIGATION 21 those societies. Thus the centre of discussion is "the state," as though there were precisely one and only one type of social organization to which the name applies and which can be described without reference to experi- ence in universal terms. Dr. Bosanquet in his latest restatement justifies this procedure. " The state," he tells us, " is a brief expression for states qua states." ' Now it may be perfectly true that there are propositions which hold of states as such, distinguishable from propo- sitions which hold of some states and not of others ; but the urgent question for any science is how such general truths are arrived at. Is it by induction — a comparison of states, from which the points of agreement and differ- ence may emerge ? No such inductive process is to be found in the metaphysical theory. Is it by self- evidence ? Is it, for example, self-evident " that states represent differentiations of a single human spirit . . . whose extent and intensity determine and are determined by territorial limits " ? » Is this a proposition which commands acceptance by intuition like a mathematical axiom ? If not, on what evidence is it based ? When Hegel asserts that the state must have a monarch to complete its personaUty and that the monarch must be determined by a natural method, and this is primo- geniture, are these self-evident propositions ? Do they rest on intrinsic necessities revealed to Hegel's intuition or do they really do no more than clothe the practice of the Prussian state in sounding generalities ? The truth is that in social investigation large and unproven principles are apt to be either mere generalizations of customs or institutions which happen to be famihar to the writer, or expressions of his ideals, or very possibly a fusion of the two. Dr. Bosanquet thinks that his critics, dealing unguardedly " with states " (positively wandering off into the region of fact), " attribute to states that which qua states they are not, namely, defects which the state organization exists to remove." For him the state is the power which, as the organization • Social and International Ideals (1917), p. 274. ' Ibid., p. 275. 22 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE of the community, " has the function of maintaining the external conditions necessary to the best Ufe." If one objects that many states maintain conditions that are quite adverse to the best life, Dr. Bosanquet retorts that we must distinguish a function from its derangement. States qua states do not maintain bad conditions. It results that the state is not the actual organized commu- nity, but only so much of the organized community as makes for good. This is to define the state by an ideal. But elsewhere ' Dr. Bosanquet defines the state as that society " which is habitually recognized as a unit lawfully exercising force," a definition which would apply to the rule of the Czar or Sultan. The second definition is much nearer to common usage, which certainly thinks of the state as an organization which may serve good or bad ends, maintain good or bad conditions, but is a state as long as it holds together and maintains law and government. It is a violent departure from usage, which at best would only lead to constant misunder- standing, to restrict the term to the good elements of any such organization. But things are still worse if the state means at one time that which is actually common to stable political organizations and at another the ideal functions of a possible political organization.' Such methods of definition are equally fatal to science and ' The Philosophical Theory of the Slate, p. 186. » It may be permissible to define a structure by its function, provided the definition be unambiguous. For this purpose the structure must only have one function, and we must know what it is, and that it is invariably performed. If every government performed the function of promoting the common good and no other, there would be no harm in defining the state as that which exists for the common good, but if, e.g., the state is in the hands of a governing class which governs for selfish ends, it does not perform this function. Do we then mean by the state the organ- ization which sustains government or the organization which sustains a peculiar kind of government aiming at a particular kind of purpose ? If the latter, we must get another name instead of the state for every actual organization in so far as it deflects from our ideal, otherwise we shall never know whether we are talking about the ideal world or the real world. THE OBJECTS OF SOCIAL INVESTIGATION 23 philosophy, and our general charge against the method of idealism must be that it starts with and never corrects the fundamental confusion of the ideal and the actual.' In older days we passed by the Hegelian exaltation of the state as the rhapsodical utterances of a meta- physical dreamer. It was a mistake. The whole con- ception is deeply interwoven with the most sinister developments in the history of Europe. It is fashionable to conceive German militarism as a product of the reaction against a beautiful sentimental idealism that reigned in the pre-Bismarckian era. Nothing could be more false. The political reaction began with Hegel, whose school has from first to last provided by far the most serious opposition to the democratic and humanitarian con- ceptions emanating from eighteenth-century France, sixteenth-century Holland and seventeenth-century Eng- land. . It was the Hegelian conception of the state which was designed to turn the edge of the principle of freedom ' The truth seems to be that idealists suppose actual states to I be so good that the error is insignificant. Thus, Hegel interrupts one of his rhapsodies (Phil, des Rechts, p. 313) with the caution, " In the idea of the state one must not have particular states before one's eyes nor particular institutions. One must rather treat the idea of this actual god on its own account {fur sich)." For the moment the reader thinks that after all Hegel has only been romancing harmlessly about an ideal world. But he goes on, " Every state, though one may recognize this or that fault in it, has always, especially when it belongs to the developed states of our own time, the essential moments of its existence in itself." The god, it seems, is actually incarnated in actual states, though it seems to have some little trouble in the flesh. There is a case for restricting the use of the term " state " to those political organizations which recognize the rule of law and some measure of self-government. The present writer has himself used the term in this sense (Morals in Evolution, ch. ii); but this still defines the state by actual and assignable features of its organ- ization, not by the way in which that organization performs its functions ; and the term " state " is in practice used by many writers in a much wider sense, as applicable to all communities that possess an organized government. In the Hegelian state in par- ticular, though the reign of law is certainly postulated, there is no notion of self-government. 24 THE. METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE by identifying freedom with law; of equality, by substi- tuting the conception of discipline; of personality itself, by merging the individual in the state ; of humanity, by erecting the state as the supreme and final form of human association.' The direct connection between Bismarckian ethics and Hegelian teaching was ably worked out many years ago by a close student of the relations of ideas and facts in the political sphere, Mr. William Clark, but it is not in Germany alone that the Hegehan influence has pro- foundly affected the course of thought in one form or another. It has permeated the British world, dis- crediting the principles upon which liberal progress has been founded and in particular depreciating all that British and French thinkers have contributed. Perhaps it has been none the less dangerous because it has capti- vated men of real humanity, genuinely interested in liberal progress, so much so that in the hands of T. H. Green the Hegelian theory was for a time transmuted into a philosophy of social ideaUsm, a variant which has a value of its own and does not lack distinguished living disciples. But as a fashionable academic philosophy genuine Hegelianism has revived, and the doctrine of the state as an incarnation of the Absolute, a super- personality which absorbs the real living personality of men and women, has in many quarters achieved the position of an academic orthodoxy. For academic purposes, indeed, it is a convenient doctrine ; its bed-rock conservatism is proof against all criticisms of the existing order. It combats the spirit of freedom in the most effective method possible, by adopting its banner and waving it from the serried battaUons of a disciplined army. It justifies that negation of the individual which ' Above the state stands the Spirit which realizes itself in world history and is the absolute judge of the state. There is here a hint of a wider view which perhaps explains how it was that Karl Marx could reach internationalism from a Hegelian basis. But for Hegel combinations of states are only relative and limited {Phil, des Rechts, p. 314). THE OBJECTS OF SOCIAL INVESTIGATION 25 the modem practice of government is daily emphasizing. It sets the state above moral criticism, constitutes war a necessary incident in its existence, contemns humanity, and repudiates a Federation or League of Nations. In short, we see in it a theory admirably suited to the period of militancy and regimentation in which we find ourselves. The truth or falsity of such a theory is a matter of no small interest ; indeed, it is not a question of theory alone but of a doctrine whosQ historical importance is written large in the events of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. I propose in the following lectures to set out the fundamentals of this theory and endeavour to discover the processes of thought by which, in the judg- ment of so many able men, the state assumes in the modem world a position which earlier ages might have given to the church or to the Deity Himself. LECTURE II FREEDOM AND LAW During the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries estab- lished authority came under criticism from many points of view. The authority of the church was challenged by the claims of conscience ; the authority of law and government was opposed by the natural right of the individual. Presently the whole social structure, the notions of political prosperity and national well-being were scrutinized in. the interest of the happiness of individual men and women. It is not my purpose here to trace the movements of these theories, nor to show how in some forms they were brought round to a justi- fication of the social order, while in others they issued in a more or less revolutionary ideal. I call attention only to the tendency to judge the state, the fabric of law and government, the structure of social institutions in terms of and by reference to the conscience or the rights or the happiness of individuals. This tendency is not very happily or fairly described when it is called a tendency to put the individual above society. This suggests a kind of "egoism, as though one man counted for more than millions. It is more fairly to be described as an effort to go back from institutions, laws and forms, to the real life that lay behind them, insisting that this was a life of individual men and women with souls to be saved, with personalities to be respected, or simply with capacity for feeling anguish or enjoying their brief span of life. The danger was that the emphasis on personality might be exaggerated to the point of depreciating the FREEDOM AND LAW 27 common life, that criticism might degenerate into anarchy, and what was valuable in the social tradition might be thrown away along with what was bad. The natural man might be endowed with none of the vices and all the virtues of his civilized counterpart, and it might be supposed that, if left to himself, or enabled to start afresh without the incubus of the established order upon him, he would build up a new life incomparably more free and beautiful. The exaggeration of revolution is the opportunity of reaction, and in the new world of theory, partly reflecting, partly anticipating the world of action, exaggerated individualism paved the way for reconstructions. Of these the most far-reaching and in the end the most influential was the metaphysical theory which challenged the whole assumption, tacit or avowed, of the critical school in all its forms, by setting up the state as a greater being, a spirit, a superpersonal entity, in which individuals with their private consciences or claims of right, their happiness or their misery, are merely subordinate elements. The starting-point of this theory, reduced to its lowest terms, is the principle that organized society is some- thing more than the individuals that compose it. This principle cannot be as quickly disposed of as some indi- vidualists think. Every association of men is legitimately regarded as an entity possessing certain characteristics of its own, characteristics which do not belong to the individuals apart from their membership of that associa- tion. In any human association it is true, in a sense, that the whole is something more than a sum of its parts. For example, the whole can do things which the parts severally cannot. If two men in succession push a heavy body, they may be wholly unable to move it. If they work together, they bring it along. Mechanically the simimed output of energy in the two cases is equal, but in the one case it will be dissipated physically in heat, morally in the sense of frustration and loss of temper. In the othof case it will succeed in its object and shift the resisting weight. The association of the two there- 28 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE fore has palpable effects which without the association could not be achieved. On the other hand, it is important to remark that the result of the joint effort of the two men working together is simply the sum of their efforts as they work together, though it is something other than the sum of those efforts when not co-ordinated. Any association of people involves some modification, tem- porary or permanent, superficial or fat-reaching, in the people themselves. The work or the life of the association is something different from the work which could be achieved or the life lived by the same people apart from that association. But it does not follow that it is an57thing other than the sum, the expression or the result of the work that is being done, or the life that is being lived, by aU the members of the association as members. When we are told, then, that the whole is more than the sum of its parts, we must reply that this depends on the sense in which the " parts " are taken. Further, we must observe that the statement, so far as it is true, is true generally ; it holds of all associations, not only of that particular association which we call the state. Family hfe, for example, necessarily exercises a profound indQuence upon its members. The family is a whole which co-operates for certain purposes and in which the various members lead lives quite other than that they would do if the family were scattered. On the other hand, the fanuly as it stands at any given moment is sin^ply the co-ordinated or associated whole of its members as they stand at the same moment. It is an expression of their lives so far as lived in common or in close association with one another. The family in particular has no well-being, no happiness, no good or evil fortune, which is not the well-being, the happiness, good or evil fortune of its members one or more. In an organized body, a profession, for example, a Trade Union, a business, a factory, there is again a whole nimibering so many scores, hundreds, thousands of individuals as its members. In every case the members are in greater or lesser degree modified by the association into whiqh FREEDOM AND LAW 29 they enter. Of the Trade Union, of the profession or business, certain things will hold true, which would not hold true of the individuals who belong to any of those associations if they did not belong to them. But again in the whole there is nothing but the co-ordinated or associated activity of the individuals which constitute it. This remains true though the organization may be permanent and the individuals changing. A college may have for hundreds of years a certain peculiar character and stamp of its own. The number of individuals pass- ing through it and affected by it is quite indefinite. It is not constituted solely by the number present within its walls at any given time ; nor can we enumerate those who may have come within its influence during the whole period of its estabUshment. Nevertheless its tradition, its spirit which seems to be lodged in no single individual, is maintained by individuals, propagated ;from generation to generation, sometimes perhaps broken by the influx of a new type of character which fails to assimilate the tradition which it encounters. Thus, in discussing society, we are Uable to two fallacies. On the one hand we may be tempted to deny the reality of the socieil group, refusing to conceive it as a distinct entity, insisting on resolving it into its component indi- viduals as though these individuals were unaffected by the fact of association. On the other side, in reaction from this exaggerated individualism, we are apt to regard society as an entity distinct from the individuals, not merely in the sense that it is an aggregate of individuals viewed in some special relation, but in the sense that it is a whole which in some way stands outside them, or in which they are merged to the prejudice of their individual identity. Further, having reached the con- ception of a superpersonal entity in which individuals are submerged, we are inclined to look f6r this entity, not in all the varied forms of associated Mfe which inter- sect and cut across one another, but in some particular form of association which seems to include the rest and so to preseht itself as a whole to which the individual 30 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE must belong as an element. This entity, idealist writers have found in the state. There are thus two points which we have to consider, first the general notion of a superpersonal entity and, secondly, the identification of this entity with the state. We have seen that the notion of a superpersonal entity appears at first sight to express a very obvious fact. It may also appear to formulate a clear principle of ethics. The conception of duty, it may be said, teaches us that the individual lives not for himself but for a greater whole to which his own claims must be subordinated. An abstract individualism might regard the individual as possessed of certain rights, but rights are a function of the social group, since rights involve demands made upon others either for positive services or for negative forbearances. The rights of A impose obligations on B and C. They are obligations incident to" and arising out of social relations, and can only be justified if their fulfil- ment is held to be for the good of the society — ^temporary or permanent^ — for which they are prescribed. Thus the individualistic conception defeats itself and leads us back to the whole and the duties rendered to the whole by each of its members. Now, in maintaining the superiority of the whole to any of its parts, the idealist, it may be thought, is merely asserting the superior claims of society to any one of its members. But here again there is an element of danger in the contrast between society and the individual. Any one individual is but an insignifi- cant element in the great society, and may justly feel that his small interests must be subordinated to those of the greater body. But we cannot thus contrast a society with all the individuals which belong to it. Ethically there would be no sense in the demand for the sacrifice of all the individuals who belong or may belong to a society to the interests of that society. The million is more than the one, the interests of the miUion greater than the interests of the one. The question is whether the society of the miUion has any interests other than the conjoint interests of the million belonging to it. If the FREEDOM AND LAW 31 socielty is something other than the individuals, such a position is arguable, and we shall have to consider it as we proceed. What has to he said here is that it by no means follows from the ethical claim that the interests of the individual must give way to those of the whole to which he belongs. That claim is satisfied by the conception of the whole as the organized body of living men and women. We are not speaking here of associa- tions that exist to promote objects beyond themselves — a conspiracy, for example, aiming at a political revo- lution. Here the whole society of conspirators might rightly judge that it were better for them all as individuals to- perish than that the movement should be lost. " Que mon nom soit fl^tri, que la France soit libre." This, indeed, might be the motto not only of the individual but of the association too. We are speaking of a society regarded as an end in itself. If we ask what good is actually reaUzed in a society other than the good of its members, we certainly get no answer from the ethical consciousness which bids us do our duty to others and love our neighbours as ourselves. These requirements are amply recognized by the conception of ourselves as human beings placed among other human beings, whose happiness and misery our actions sensibly affect. The method by which the ideaUst turns the flank of these arguments is to contend in substance that the individual possesses no independent value, ultimately we may say no independent life of his own. He is absorbed in the organized political society, the state of which he is a member. He claims freedom. The claim is ad- mitted. E(J&€aiQm.Js.JJia.-stattiHg-p€>iBt of .the,.-.Hfig,eUan philosophy of the state, but freedom in Hegel's sense turns but to be conforroty with, the law „a,u.d custom as iirtfeTpreted by .the.„!Eit]3i£aJ. spirit ^qf the particular society to"'which the individual belongs. He claims the right of judgment, he aims at anilional order of ethics. The claim is admitted but the rational order is that of the objective mind, and this on analysis turns out to be the system of institutions and customs which the state has 32 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE engendered and maintains. Finally he claims to be at least himself, an independent centre of thought and feeling, palpitating with its own emotions, subject to its own joys and sorrows, but not even selfhood is left to him, for his self is realizable only in the organized whole in which he is a kind of transitory phase. Thus the edge of the revolutionary weapon is turned, or rather the hat is grasped and the point directed towards the revolutionary himself. The freedom which the revolu- tionary, the hberal, or for that matter the plain man of the modem world, asserts is accepted and transmuted into obedience to law. His demand for rationality in society is granted, but granted in order to be attributed to the existing social order. The very sense of person- ality, instead of being checked and chastened by the stem assertion of duty, is gently and subtly resolved into a phase or expression of the general will. There can be no finer example of the supreme maxim of dialectical art, that the admission of an opponent's contentions is the deadliest method of refutation. It will be convenient to set out in briefest possible terms the central points in the conception of society with which we have to deal. The point of departure in Hegel is his doctrine of freedom. Freedom is, in his view, falsely conceived in ordinary thought as equivalent to absence of constraint. That is a negative and, in the end, Hegel argues, a self-contradictory idea. True free- dom is something positive. I^: is self- determination. The free will is the will which determines itself. The sense in which the will can determine itself is this, that it forms a rational whole or system of conduct, in which any particular act or deliverance of the will performs a certain necessary function. Such a system of conduct is not achieved by the individual on his own account but is incorporated in the law and custom of society. Law alone is merely the external side of this system, but law, developed by the moral consciousness of man and worked out into the detail of custom that regulates daily life and society, constitutes the actual fabric that FREEDOM AND LAW 33 we reqmre and is the objective expression of freedom. That which sustains this fabric of a rational life is the state, which is therefore the realization of the moral idea. The state is its owrL end^ a^nd Jtl^Jiigh^t^u±;^ of ^J^^jn^ddvidual is to be a rnember of .Ihs^statc^Bfiyond ' -the state there is no higher association and state^ lB5ve noT duties^ tojone another or to humanity^ Butjhar^ rise~and fall is the process of universal history, which is the ultimate court of judgment before whose bar they come. In order to examine this very summary account, we see we have (i) to consider the meaning of freedom. We have to understand the process of argument by which freedom is defined as self-determination and self-deter- mination as the subordination of action to an articulate system ; (2) we have to inquire into the identification of this system with law and custom, and that will bring us (3) to the conception of the state and the reasons why it is regarded not only as an end in itself but as the supreme and the highest form of human association. In his theory of the freedom of the will lies the key to the Hegelian theory of the state, of morality and of law. This theory consists in essentials of three posi- tions.' (i) The underl5H[ng principle is that freedom consists not in the negative condition of absence of constraint but in the positive fact of self-determination. Will is freedom because it is self-determination. What then does self-determination mean ? This will bring us to the second position. The will is determined by its purposes or objects, and we are apt to think of the object as something external, puUing at it, so to say. So to think is to abandon self-determination, and in reaction from this view we think of the will as exerting free choice as between its objects. But again freedom, so con- ceived, is an uncharted, motiveless freedom, for if I choose one thing rather than another, there must surely ' I confine myself here to the essentials of the argument as I understand it. A somewhat expanded statement of Hegel's view will be found in Appendix I. 3 34 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE be something in the thing which moves me or my choice appears groundless and irrational. Here arises a form of the familiar controversy between determinism and free will which Hegel holds to be insoluble on this plane of thought. The position {2) reached then is that the will must be determined by its object, but that if this object is independent of the will, an insoluble dilemma ensues. This brings us to the third position, namely, (3) that the object of the will is determined by the will itself. Before asking how this could be, let us note the reasoning. Freedom is understood to be self-deter- mination. The will is determined by its object, but the object is determined by the will. Ultimately, therefore, the will is self-determined and free. But in this reasoning there appears to be a circle. How can the will be determined by its object and yet determine the object ? To escape the circle we must realize that the object of the will is not outside the will at all, it is the will itself. At first sight thi^' seems peri- lously near to sheer nonsense. How can the wiU will itself ? The line of answer seems to be that the will at any given moment and in any given relation may have the whole nature of the will as its object. Thus, to suggest an example, we might think of the consistent Christian who directs his action from hour to hour by the light of a principle running right through his life. This principle he has adopted for good and all. It has become the comprehensive expression of his will. So in each act of his will it is his own will that is its object. If then the will is determined by its object, it is here determined by itself, that is, it is free. Two lines of criticism suggest themselves. First, the Christian himself would probably say that it is not his own will but the will of God which he seeks to obey, and whatever illustration we might take, the answer would in essentials be the same. I must will something that is not yet realized, otherwise I achieve nothing. Even if I will to reform myself, the one case in which I do seem to have my own will for an object, this means FREEDOM AND LAW 35 that I, as I am now, set a different self before myself as something to be achieved. And if I could attain perfect consistency of action, this would mean that I should consistently serve some comprehensive end beyond myself and only to be realized by my action. The end or object then is always other than the will as it is when acting for the end. Will, like other acts of mind, has relation to an object, and things that are related are not the same. The identification of subject and object fails here as elsewhere and with it the whole scheme of self-determination breaks down. The second criticism has a special bearing on the use which Hegel makes of his definition of freedom. Grant, for the sake of argument, that self-determination is some- thing more than absence of constraint. But it is not less than absence of constraint. Where and in so far as an act of will is constrained, it is not free. What is absolutely free is absolutely unconstrained. What is relatively free is relatively unconstrained. Freedom in one thing may indeed imply restraint on something else — if I am secure in freedom to go about my business, this implies that others ar6 prevented from hindering me in doing so — but the thing which is free is not in the respect in which it is free also restrained. To be free in one part or in one relation it will have to be restrained in another part or relation, but in that in which it is restrained it is not also free. Now in adopting a principle of conduct we may be acting on our own motion in response to an internal conviction. So far we are free. But the principle may be such as to put heavy constraint on a part of our nature, and if so, that part of our nature is not free. We may be slaves to our principles, as well as to our impulses, and in fact common experience tells us that there are those who would be better men without their principles, if they would only give their natural emotions free play. But a life of uncharted impulses cannot be free, because unregulated impulses not only restrain but utterly frus- trate and destroy one another. But neither is a life 36 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE of narrow principle free, because such a principle at best holds a great part of us subdued, perhaps sullen and unsatisfied.' In a word freedom for one element in our nature, be it an impulse or a conviction, may mean the subjection of the rest of our nature. If there be such a thing as freedom for our personality as a whole, its parts must have as much scope as is compatible with their union. This cannot mean absolute freedom for each part, for no one must override the remainder. It means freedom limited by the conditions of develop- ment in harmony, and by nothing else. If we suppose a whole of many parts capable of a harmonious develop- ment, and if we suppose this whole to be subject to no restraints except those which it itself imposes on its parts to secure the common development, then we have an intelligible sense in which the whole may be termed free. Now the self is a whole capable of a harmonious develop- ment, and it may be termed free when it orders its life accordingly. The principle of freedom then springs from the nature of the self as a coherent whole. It is to be distinguished from a principle cramping harmony of development, even if accepted by our own consent. Still more is it to be distinguished from one imposed from without by suggestion, authority and perhaps some mingling of compulsion. Now Hegel does not draw these distinctions. Discarding absence of con- straint from the idea of freedom, and concentrating attention on the element of unity which the will un- doubtedly introduces into action, he tends to identify freedom with mere acceptance of a principle of conduct and thus paves the way for its further identification with law. He saw that freedom involved restraint on something but did not see that it was restraint on some- thing else, that which is free being in the respect in which it is free necessarily unconstrained. ' It may be said that it is the function of will to subdue nature, but this is precisely to give it the freedom of a despot, and leave the personality unfree. To do Hegel justice, no such antithesis seems contemplated in his argumentt FREEDOM AND LAW 37 Hegel's first position is now before us. / Freedom fori him rests not on absence of constraint but on the accept- ance of a principle expressing the true nature of rational will running through and unif57ing all the diverse pur- poses of men.^ The embodiment of such a principle and therefore of freedom Hegel finds in the system of right and law. Two terms here require some consider- ation before the meaning of this principle can be under- stood. By the term " embodiment " I have rendered the word Daseyn. Daseyn in the Hegelian philosophy is a term used in contradistinction to what we ordinarily call a mere idea or bare thought of a thing, for example, or to its mere potentiahty. We must not, however, translate the word Daseyn by "reality" or even by "exist- ence," as both of these terms are assigned to distinct phases in the Hegelian dialectical development. We may, however, think of the embodiment of a political idea in an Act of Parliament or of a political principle in an institution or a constitution, as giving what Hegel would call Daseyn to that idea or that principle. That being understood, we see in general the meaning of the phrase that freedom is embodied in right. But the term " right " or law also requires comment. Hegel's term is Recht, and it would seem better to use the German term whenever ambiguity is to be feared. Ac- cording to Dr. Bosanquet it is the advantage of the German term that it maintains in itself the intimate relation between right and law. It may be urged on the contrary that the very fact that German writers use one term for these two related but quite distinct notions is an obstacle to clear thinking in their Juris- prudence and Ethics in general, and in the Hegelian philosophy in particular. The consequence of its use is that we begin and go on with the confusion of two issues, which it is the particular purpose of social philo- sophy to hold distinct. The one issue is the nature of right, the foundation of moral obhgation, the meaning, value and authority of a moral system ; and the other the meaning, value and authority of law; and the final 38 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE question of political philosophy consists of the relation between these two distinct things. That relation can never be clearly set forth if we use terms which imply a~.confusion between the terms related. ' But in what sense is Recht the embodiment of free- dom ? ' Let us first, for the sake of accuracy, supply a correction, without which we should do injustice to Hegel, though the correction does not touch the essence of the question. Mere law is only an external embodi- ment of freedom, Hegel fully admits. Law is abstract, general, and regards primarily the externals of behaviour ; to complete it we want something which is on the one hand more concrete, more closely adapted to the require- ments of individual life, and, on the other hand, some- thing expressing the inner acceptance of the rule of society as well as its external observance. This con- ception we find in the word Sittlichkeit, a term which can hardly be rendered in English by a single word. We cannot translate it " morality," because Hegel uses the word Moralitat as something which is purely inward and subjective, whereas Sittlichkeit is objective as well. Dr. Bosanquet translates it by the phrase " ethical use and wont," and we may understand it as the whole system of customs and traditions as accepted by the normal member of a society, as forming the fabric within which he has to live. This system is, in Hegel's phrase, the conception of freedom come to self-consciousness in the world in which we hve.» (Restating our question there- fore we have to ask, in what ^ense is the social tradition an embodiment of freedom ? ) The examination of this question takes us into the heart of the Hegelian concep- tion of the relation of the individual man to society, and this again will be found to be a particular case of the relation of the individual to the universal, which is the central point of the Hegelian metaphysics.N It will have been noticed in discussing the Hegelian theory of the will we have always to speak of the will. We have not spoken of the wills of different men and ? Phil, des Rechts, p. 205. FREEDOM AND LAW ,39 their relations to xme another. We have never used the plural term. ( We have always spoken of the will as though it were one subsitantive reality ; and this is in fact the Hegelian viewA But in society there are many wills and in obedience to law we conform, as we suppose, to the will of another. How then can we talk of the will as if there were only one ? The question will lead us ultimately into the metaphysical problem of the one and the many, for the Hegelian theory of the universal underhes the whole issue. But let us first set out the problem with more fullness and consider the solution proffered by Hegel's most recent and most faithful exponent. At the first blush it must be owned it is difficult to attach any clear meaning to the statement that the social tradition is the actual or concrete realization of freedom. Freedom, as we have been told, means self-determination. Self-determination, we were further told, imphes deter- mination by a principle as against mere impulse. But even if we waive for the moment all controversies on these points, it remains that if there is self-determination, the determining principle must be a principle of our* own choosing, an expression of our own character, the real bent of our own selves. The established ethical tradition may of course fall in with our desires, and if so, we are aware of no constraint in accepting it, but socially and ethically the question of freedom only arises where there is a clash of wills. Suppose then that our will happens to be in conflict at one point with the social tradition, what are we to understand ? To say that in such a case we ought to yield up our judgment and conform is at least an inteUigible, though sometimes a disputable proposition ; but that is not what is said or intended. The proposition before us is that in con- forming to the social tradition and only in conforming to it we are free. It does not appear to matter whether we ourselves fi!nd the rule which it propounds contrary to our happiness or opposed to our conscience. Our freedom liesj, it would seem, in the surrender of our own 40 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE happiness, even in the stifling of our own conscience, for we are free only as we conform to the moral tradition embodied in and supported by the state. Freedom is self-determination, yet freedom is realized only in the submission of self to something which may at any time conflict with all that is strongest and all that is deepest in ourselves. The use and wont of the organized political society to which we belong may, for example, at certain points conflict with the teaching of the religious body to which we belong, or it may involve injustices and oppressions against which our conscience comes to revolt. Now it is not merely contended that in such a conflict we ought to surrender our judgment. That is at least arguable. It is contended that in submitting ourselves, and in this alone, we are actually free. We seem faced with something like a contradiction. And, however we define the state, this particular contradiction does not seem to be resolved. For we may think of it as essentially an organization of persons Uke ourselves. In that case, in obeying it against our own will we are simply under the constraint of others ; or we may think of it as something impersonal, superpersonal, or, as Hegel calls it, divine, and in that case we are obeying an impersonal or divine authority. Even if we are free in shielding to it, that would seem to be the last act of our freedom. It is an abdication, a final discharge of our authority over ourselves. Now something like this conception of the relation of freedom to the general will goes back to Rousseau. Dr. Bosanquet ' quotes Rousseau as sa3dng " that who- ever shall refuse to obey the general wiU shall be con- strained to do so by the whole body, which means nothing else than that he will be forced to be free." He goes on to say, " In this passage Rousseau lays bare the very heart of what some would call poUtical faith and others political superstition. This lies in the conviction that the ' moral person which constitutes the state ' is a reality." If we follow the development of this con- ' The Philosophical Theory of (he State, pp. 95, 96. FREEDOM AND LAW 41 ception, we shall find the key to the difficulty before us. Reviewing his examination of Rousseau, the details of which we need not follow. Dr. Bosanquct writes : " (a) The negative relation of the self to other selves begins to dissolve away before the conception of the common self and (b) the negative relation of the self to law and government begins to disappear in the idea of a law which expresses our real will as opposed to our trivial and rebellious moods. The whole notion of man as one among others tends to break down and we begin to see something in the one which actually identifies him with the others and at the same time tends to make him what he admits he ought to be." This passage really seems to contain the sum and substance of Idealistic Social Philosophy. There is a common self, and this is no metaphor. It does not mean a community among selves because " the whole notion of man as one among many tends to break down." It is a self which is a higher unity than the legal or moral person, and this self seems to be identified with the real will, which is also, it seems, the self that one ought to be. We now begin to see why that which appears to us a stark contradiction is seen in quite a different light by the idealist. Our difficulty was that self-determination cannot be the same thing as determination by other selves, or by an impersonal state. The answer is that the division between self and others dissolves away into the conception of a common self and the division between the individual and the state disappears in the conception of a law expressing our own real will ; so that in con- forming to law, we are submitting ourselves neither to other persons nor to something impersonal. We are conforming to our own real will. But if in point of fact we happen to will just the opposite to that which the law ordains, how can this be ? The answer lies in the distinction between the actual and the real will. We must give Dr. Bosanquet's statement of this dis- tinction with some fullness. 42 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE " It was observed above that what Rousseau had before him in his notion of the General Will might be described as the ' Will in itself,' or the Real Will. Any such conception involves a con- trast between the Real Will and the Actual Will, which may seem to be meaningless. How can there be a Will which is no one's Will ? and how can anything be my Will which I am not fully aware of, or which I am even averse to ? This question will be treated more fully on psychological grounds in a later chapter. For the present, it is enough to call attention to the plain fact that often when people do not know what they mean, they yet mean something of very great importance ; or that, as has com- monly been said, ' what people demand is seldom what would satisfy them if they got it.' We may recall the instances in which even Mill admitted that it is legitimate to infer, from the inherent nature of the will, that people do not really ' will ' something which they desire to do at a given moment. . . . Now the con- tradiction, which here appears in an ultimate form, pervades the ' actual ' will, which we exert from moment to moment as conscious individuals, through and through. A comparison of our acts of will through a month or a year is enough to show that no one object of action, as we conceive it when acting, exhausts all that our will demands. Even the life which we wish to live, and which on the average we do live, is never before us as a whole in the motive of any particular volition. In order to obtain a full state- ment of what we will, what we want at any moment must at least be corrected and amended by what we want at all other moments ; and this cannot be done without also correcting and amending it so as to harmonize it with what others want, which involves an application of the same process to them. But when any con- siderable degree of such correction, and amendment had been gone through, our own will would return to us in a shape in which we should not know it again, although every detail would be a neces- sary inference from the whole of wishes and resolutions which we actually cherish. And if it were to be supplemented and readjusted so as to stand not merely for the life which on the whole we manage to live, but for a life ideally without contradiction, it would appear to us quite remote from anythinp which we know." Postponing for a moment any critical examination of this conception, let us take stock of our position. According to Dr. Bosanquet, then, there is underl3dng the actual will, of which we are aware, a deeper real will, which is the actual will reorganized and made completely consistent or coherent. It is in fact that organized system of purposes which we found in the FREEDOM AND LAW 43 Hegelian will, and in a later passage Dr. Bosanquet adopts the Hegelian phrase—" the will that wills itself." But now, if we grant for the moment this underlying will and suppose ourselves to be free only when we con- form to it, we still have not reached the connection between the real self and the common self, which is the state, in which the distinction between self and others is absorbed and whose will is expressed in the social tradition. The connection is explained by Dr. Bosanquet (p. 123), where we are told,(" The habits and institutions of any community are, so to speak, the standing inter- pretation of all the private wills which compose it." And this seems to be taken as the content both of the general and the real will. It is an imperfect represen- tation of the real will because " every set of institutions is an incomplete embodiment of life." On the other hand " the complex of social institutions " is " very much more complete than the explicit ideas which at any given instant move any individual mind in volition." The essence of the position is now before us. Moral freedom — we shall see later that Dr. Bosanquet candidly recognizes the distinction between moral and legal liberty — lies in conformity to the real will. The real will is the general will and is expressed in the social fabric. The expression is not perfect and admits of progressive development, but it is in the main what we require. Social tradition, if not the complete expression of our- selves, is the fullest available to us at any given time. The vehicle of social tradition, or rather the organizing principle which gives it vitality, meaning and coherence, is the state. The state, therefore, is the true self in which the mere individual is absorbed. This is the comer stone of moral and political obligation. Briefly, we are morally free when our actions conform to our ^MLHivill, our real will is the general will^ and.the^ general will is most fully embodied in the state. These are the governing positions of the metaphysical theory which we have to examine. LECTURE III THE REAL WILL (a) The steps by which the conception of the real will is reached by Dr. Bosanquet are contained in the passage quoted in the last lecture, and may be summ.arized thus. ( What we will from moment to moment is called our actual jpvill. This actual will is always incomplete and dfteiT contradictory and inharmonious. To get at a full statement of what we will it would have to be corrected by (a) what we want at all other moments, and (6) by what others want. If this correction were carried far enough, our " own will would return to us in a shape in which we should not know it again." Yet the whole process would only have been a logical series of inferences from the whole of the wishes and resolutions which we actually cherish. And if, going further than this, we suppose criticism carried to a point at which it would achieve a life ideally without contradiction, then the will to such a life " would appear to us quite remote from anything which we know." Remote as it is, this is what Dr. Bosanquet seems to mean by the real will. We are then left with the paradox that our real will may be something which we never really will because we do not even know it and could not recognize it if it were set before us. What is the explanation of this paradox ? How does Bosanquet arrive at it ? (i) The justification appears to be that the objects which we set before us, at which we consciously aim, are not always what we really want. They do not really satisfy us. This is a THE REAL WILL 45 form of words expressing of course a perfectly well-known truth. A man's nature is constantly driving him on to ends which he imperfectly appreciates and the concrete shapes which these ends take are often quite unsatis- factory. They give illusions of desirabiUty which cheat him on attaining them. None the less, so far as he really chooses them that choice is for the time being his real will, in the true sense of real as that which is not merely supposed to be but is. Moreover, the fact that he so chooses them and makes a mistake in doing so is a real limitation of his will. The illusoriness of the will is pre- cisely as hard a fact, as stubborn a reality, as the persistent background of want and unrest, which is the other side of the matter. The man's will is in short just what it is with all its limitations and not what it might be if these limitations were removed. It may be suggested, and this is what Bosanquet seems to mean, that logically a man must be taken to will all that his actual will impUes. But this is quite fallacious. On the contrary, show me a consequence following from an act of my will, which I have not yet seen, and it is quite possible that I may recoil from it. In any case the act seen with fresh impli- cations is a different act, the will which chooses it a different will. We may reasonably say that the man who has gone through the long process of criticism and judgment described by Bosanquet in the evolution of the real will has become in that process a very different man. But there is a more fundamental objection to the term "real will." Strictly there is no part in me which is more real than any other part. There are elements in me which are more permanent, and if the self is permanent, there are, let us say, moods or actions which really belong to myself more than others do, but one mood is not more real a mood or one act more real an act than another. The term " Real "is in fact in such passages as these used rhetorically, that is, in a way which does not distinguish between its adjectival meaning, connecting a particular phase of myself with myself as a whole, and 46 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE its substantival meaning, in which the term " Reality " is something which must either be simply asserted or simply denied, and there is no more or less. A particular emotion is either something which I have and then it is real, whether permanent or transitory, reasonable or un- reasonable ; or it is something which, say, you falsely attribute to me and then it is unreal. For the contrast between the real and the unreal then should be substi- tuted the contrast between the self as it is permanently constituted and the self as it acts in some transitory excitement. (2) The real will then, if it means anything, means the permanent underlying nature of any one of us, but this again does not mean our nature as it might be if we were spiritually born again, transformed by no matter what process of rational reflection, hortatory suggestion or moral and emotional re-orientation. This has a most important bearing on our second position. (i)r. Bosan- quet's assumption is that the real -will is in fact identical with the general will. The supposed ground is that the real will must be one which would be perfectly harmonious with itself. This is assumed to involve a harmony with other wills. The assumption begs the principal question of Ethics, but let it pass for the moment. Let us agree that the perfectly rationalized will involves a harmony of self and others. What ground is there for assuming that this harmony would express the true permanent nature of John Jones ? John Jones, if you unrolled before him the life which you expected him to lead as a rational being, might repel it with scorn. Ho might say, if articulate enough, that it makes no room for certain elements which he finds very real in him, his passions, his physical appetites, his desires to get the better of others. How arc you to prove to him that these are not i-eal parts of himself ? The answer seems, to be that if you carry John Jones through the pro- cess of rational criticism, he will discover elements of contradiction in these warring desires. As long as you present this to him as an intellectual proposition, how- THE REAL WILL 47 ever, John Jones will reply, " Consistency be hanged ! I will have my life in parts, each as good as I can make it. It is these that are the true John Jones." To this again the only reply available seems to be that the process of revealing the true rational harmony to John Jones cannot be an intellectual process merely, it must be one which touches his emotions, his will itself. But what is this but to admit that the true John Jones must undergo a change ? If he is to be formed into a rational will, he must be transformed. I would be far from densdng that every human being is capable of such refor- mation. I insist only that it is a reformation which is a transformation and that the will, which Bosanquet calls real and which I would call rational, harmonious or simply good, is not real in the average man, nor even in its completeness in the best of men.* Bosanquet's ' In the discussion of the criminal (pp. 226, etc.) there are some instructive remarks, illustrating the nature of the real will. Bosanquet says justly that if an uneducated man were told that " in being punished for an assault he was realizing his own will, he would think it cruel nonsense." Some who are not the criminal might also think it nonsense ; and the only reason why they should not think it assigned by Bosanquet is (a) that the criminal would quite well understand that he was being served, as he would say, in the same way as somebody else would be served who had dqne the same thing. (6) That the punishment is the reaction on the criminal of a system of rights to which he is a party. As to (a) the essential difference between the criminal and the good will is that while the criminal may be prepared to judge others, he makes exceptions in favour of himself. Very often he cannot see the identity of his act with another which he condemns and even if he can see it, so far as he is criminal, his attitude is " I don't care." If an acute dialectician were to argue with him, he would no doubt entangle him in inconsistencies and show that if he were a reasonable man, and if he admitted universal rules applying to himself and others, he would not be a criminal. But if this argument is to have effect, it must not only convince the man's intelligence but convert his will. In order genuinely to condemn himself, the criminal must therefore become another man than that which he in fact is. And we see very clearly from this instance that the good, rational or social will imputed to the criminal as his real will is precisely the will that the criminal, as criminal, really does not possess. The fallacy consists in describ- 48 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE own description of course shows he is perfectly aware of this, yet he confuses the whole issue by the use of the adjeqtive "real." It is misleading to contrast real with transitory, trivial aims. It is not merely one's super- ficial or casual interests that clash with others and exhibit contradiction with one another so that they interfere with the best life, it is also the deepest passions and some- times the most fervid conscience. A man may feel, and the feeling may be no illusion, that a personal passion goes to the very foundation of his being, and yet the passion may be lawless or it may collide with the entire bent of his life in other directions, his devotion to public duty, for example, or perhaps deeprooted obligations of family and friendship. If the real self means that which goes deep, we cannot deny that it contains possi- biUties of contradiction far more serious than the colHsion between permanent interest and passing desire. There is conceivable a will which is perfectly rational and harmonious in all its deliverances. There is con- ceivable a system of wills so harmonizing with themselves ing as a real will 'sometliing which a logician regards as being implied in the actual will of the criminal. This implication rests on some principle of impartiality which the logician may have very good grounds for maintaining ; but this is precisely the principle which the criminal, as criminal, either ignores or definitely rejects. As to (6), at bottom the same analysis apphes. The criminal acquiesces in the system as far as he chooses, as far as he finds it suits him, or perhaps as far as he is unable to resist it, but, qua criminal, does not in the least care for the incon- sistency, as a rational man would judge it to be, involved in his departure from the system where that departure suits him better. In brief, the murderer does not really want himself to be hanged unless he has repented and ceased to be the man that he was when he committed the murder. It must be added here that the conception of punishment as expressing the will of the offender has a sinister application to the rebel. It may be said that the rebel has accepted the social system and thereby the punishment which will follow upon him when he comes to challenge it. From the rebel's point of view the answer may be that he never willingly accepted the social system as a whole but found himself involved in it and could not react against it until the moment for rebellion had arrived. THE REAL WILL 49 and with one another ; such a perfect harmony we may legitimately speak of as the ideally rational life and the ideally good life and, as such, may contrast it with any actual life which is imperfect in these respects. Again, we may grant that there is something real within us which answers to the conception of such a life, and some- thing real within any society of human beings which, in a sense, moves us towards such a life. At any rate, from the nature of the case contradiction tends to defeat itself and harmony to fructify. Thus by continual trial and error society moves on. Unfortunately the inhar- monious elements are equally real and the disharmonies are not merely trivial, transitory, superficial, but rooted in the structure of the self and^what is almost as im- portant, in the social structure. / Every group of human beings acquires a corporate life and with it only too probably a collective selfishness, which over long periods may hold the development of other groups in arrest. The contrast is between the rational harmonious good and the irrational conflicting bad. When this contrast is con- fused with the contrast between the real and the unreal the problem is stated in wrong terms and does not admit of solution.^ The peculiar vice of this statement is that, in laying down a certain kind of life as expressing the real will of the individual, the ground is prepared for the argument that in the compulsion of the individual to lead such a hfe there is no interference with his real will. He^is supposed to be merely unable to judge for himself. Thiis, in principle, there is no limitation to restraints upon the individual, no core of freedom which collective action should not touch. And yet it must be plain that no actual human being, or association of human beings, knows what the real will is, for it is admitted that the process of eliciting it is so roundabout and involved that a man would not recognize his real will if it was put before him. Why not then admit that it is not real but ideal — an ideal which is beyond human nature though it may be a legitimate object of human endeavour ? (b) The General Will. If for the " real " we write the 4 50 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE ideal or rational will, we have next to ask whether this would be a general will. We may grant that if the will in you or me were made completely rational, it would accept principles upon which we should agree. Thus, in all rational wills there would be a qualitative identity. We should so far be like one another in our fundamental attitude towards life and conduct. But when we pass from the conception of like persons or like selves to a corporate person or a common self, there is an inevitable transition from qualitative sameness to the sameness of continuity and numerical unity. The assumptions are (i) There is in me a real self, my real will, which is opposed to what I very often am. (2) This real will is what I ought to be as opposed to what I very often am. (3) There is in you a real will and in every other member of society a real will. All these real wills are what you and every other member of society ought to be. In quality and character these real wills are indistinguishable. They are therefore the same. (4) This sameness constitutes of all the real wills together one self. But the kind of unity involved in what is called qualitative identity or sameness of character is quite a different unity from that involved in the self or from that involved in the state. The self is a continuous identity united by strands of private memory and expectation, comprising elements of feeling, emotion and bodily sensation, which are its absolute exclusive property. No such continuity unites distinct selves, however alike, or however united in their objects. So at least it seems to those whom Dr. Bosanquet dis- misses with contempt as " theorists of the first look." For them human individuality is and remains some- thing ultimate. To Dr. Bosanquet on the other hand ' individuality is only a particular case of the distinct contribution offered by parts within a system which he calls the universal. The differences within the self are for him in their essential nature identical with the differ- ences between selves. I am of course in a sense one, but I am in a sense many. I am a centre of many experiences, ' The Philosophical Theory of the State, ch. vii. THE REAL WILL 51 and even of many groups of experiences, each of which has its own controlling principle. This makes me, as popular metaphor has always recognized, a kind of miniature state ; and for Bosanquet this metaphor ex- presses the real truth. Two passages may be taken as summing up his discussion. " If we consider my unity with myself at different times as the limiting case, we shall find it very hard to establish a difference between the unity of what we call one ' mind ' and that of all the ' minds ' which enter into a single social experience." ' And again in the following chapter : « " Individuals are limited and isolated in many ways, but their true individuaUty does not lie in their isolation but in that dis- tinctive act or service by which they pass into unique contributions to the universal." Common sense confronted by these statements has a feeling of outrage which makes it disinclined to argue. It is inclined to say that the difference between self and another is as plain as the difference between black and white, and that if a man does not see it, there is nothing plainer to appeal to. It is inclined to add that, if certain views of the state are reduced to justifying themselves by such confusion as this, that is their sufficient refutation. But it is not quite satisfactory to leave the argument at this point. We must trace the roots of the fallacy. Let us first ask in what sense it is true that individuals have a common life or a common experience. To begin with they Uve in the same world. A and B may be said to have a common experience when they both perceive the same object. For example, both are reading the same book, studying the same subject, have before their eyes the same rose, are partners in one enterprise, members of one society. Here is a real unity, a numerical unity, but this unity is in the outer world, the world with which both minds are in contact. It may be in the actual existing world, as in the case of the rose which « P. 178. « P. 183. 52 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE both see and both smell, or it may be in the processes of the world and the changes to which both contribute, the purpose which both desire to realize, but in any case it is external to both. The unity is in the object — a term here which may be conveniently used in its popular ambiguity as meaning sometimes a real thing, sometimes a purpose. The individuals are subjects, distinct centres of sensation, perception, thought, feeUng, active will, standing in relation to that object. They are two, while the object is one. But, secondly, even between A and B, as two, there is a kind of unity. They are, or may be, similarly affected by or to the object. The rose smells sweet to both. The success of the business is an object of eager interest to both- The relation here is one which some would call resemblance, others identity of character. When spoken of as identity of character it is easily merged in thought with the numerical identity belonging to the object. Nevertheless it is a distinct relation. These then are the two foundations of identity as between individuals, the relationship to an identical world and the partial identity of character in themselves. How do these relations differ fundamentally from the relations between parts of my experience to one another ? For example, I may smell the same rose twice and pursue the same object through successive days and with con- siderable differences of mood, slackening and tensioning of interest and so on. The answer is that there is some- thing common in me to all my acts and experiences which is never common to you and me. I am aware in myself not only of the object that I experience but of the act of experiencing it, but I am never aware of your act of experiencing any object. Certainly I believe that you experience objects but I believe it on inference, you being a person hke myself and acting in ways sufficiently similar to mine to enable me to interpret th^. When it is said that our experience is common there is an ambiguity in the term " experience " which is overlooked. There is a sense in which you share my experience. There is also a sense in which your experience is absolutely THE REAL WILL 53 and for ever private to you, and mine absolutely and for ever private to me. Experience may mean a series of objects that is before the mind, and in that sense it may be common, or it may mean what Professor Alexander calls enjoyment, or what might with more propriety be called suffering. Mind is always dealing with objects, apprehending them, thinking about them, operating upon them and so on. The dealing, the thinking is not the object dealt with, the object thought about, it is the act or state that is enjoyed or suffered. True it becomes known and is in that sense an object, but it is an object of a distinct class, the character of which class is that everything in it is known as the subject of some other object. The entire system of these subjective acts or states forms a continuum, constituting what I know within me as my individuality or myself. My consciousness of myself rests upon a distinction between this thread of enjoyment and suffering and the entire system of the objects to which it relates, and my sense of personal identity is my recognition of the continuity of this thread. This is the element of isolation which, in contradiction to Bosanquet's dictum, is the true core of individuality. This isolation is not merely physical. My body is a part of the objective world to me. I know it by the senses as I know the rose, but the experience, as suffering, is always located in the body, felt within the body, and the physical separateness of my body from another, though not the ground of my isolation, is inseparably connected with it. What in practical philosophy is even more important is that the whole series of my feelings belongs to the thread of suffering. True, I am aware of my feelings and can name and classify them and to that extent they are objects to me, but I always know them as feelings of my own, which I enjoy or suffer as being attributes or states of the subjective continuum that is distinct from the outer world as being in me incom- municably private. When I am said to share another's feeling, that is confused metaphor. The sight of another's pain may arouse pain in me but it is another pain. 54 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE Normally, it is not even qualitatively the same pain. I do not feel toothache when my child is suffering from toothache but pity or anxiety, an emotion not a sensation. There are cases of what is sometimes conceived to be sympathy in the strictest sense in which the sight or description of physical torture seems to stimulate some- thing of the same anguish in myself, but even here it is a qualitative and not a numerical identity that is in question. And it is fortunate that it is so, for if I felt all the real anguish of the sufferer, I should hardly be in a position to come to his relief. We trace the foundations of Dr. Bosanquet's identi- fication of individuals then to a confusion in the use of the term "experience." Experience as meaning a world of objects may be common to many selves. Experience as that which each self enjoys or Suffers is absolutely private. In the former sense different minds can enter into a single experience ; in the latter sense never, though they may know about one another's experience. In the former sense experience is not as such a universal but rather one comprehensive world of objects to which all individuals are related. In the latter sense it is a uni- versal in the true sense of a class of individual beings resembling one another or possessing identities of character. I ' It would be unfair to Dr. Bo-sanquet to suggest that he ignores the exclusiveness of consciousness. In the present work he tells us, for example (p. 183), " In a sense it is true that no one con- sciousness can partake of or can actually enter into another." And similarly in his Principle of Individuality and Value he writes (P- 47) • " No one would attempt to overthrow what we have called the formal distinctness of selves or self. This consists in the impossibility that one finite centre of experience should possess as its own immediate experience the immediate experience of another." But he seems to regard what we have called enjoy- ment as a kind of form, to which the object of experience gives content. So in the same work a little earlier (p. 38) we read : " The pure privacy and incommunicability of feeling as such is superseded in all possible degrees by the solf-transcendence and universahty of the contents with which it is unified ; and as these contents are constituents of our individuality, the conception that THE REAL WILL 55 The privacy of enjoyed experiencr , and in particular of feeling, has an important bearing on the doctrine of force individuality or personality has its Centre in the exclusiveness of feeling, neglects the essential feature of individuality or person- ality itself. It has an aspect of distinct unshareable immediacy ; but in substance and stufi and content, it is universal, communi- cable, expansive." And so we learn a little later (p. 48) that the inevitable distinctness of any immediate experience, which is said to contain the essence of individuality, is a very different thing from the inexplicable and fundamental foreignness commonly postulated as between different persons. " It merely comes to this, that they are organizations of content, which a difference of quality, generally thoiigh not strictly dependent on belonging to different bodies, prevents from being wholly blended." There must, it would seem, be some characteristic differences between you and me, just as there are characteristic differences between any two parts of the same thing, but not such as to interfere with our fundamental sameness, not radically distinct from the differ- ences which may be discerned within myself at different times or in different relations. This position is developed on p. 58. " With the one exception, of the thread of coenassthesia, com- patible with any degree of hostility and foreignness, there is no ground of unity with our past and future selves which would not equally carry us to unity and fellowship with others and with the world. Our certainty of their existence is in both cases inferential, and on the same line of inference, both are cemented to it by the same stuff and material of unity, language, ideas, purposes, contents of communicable feeling ; and, as we have seen, the other may in these ways be far more closely knit with me than is my previous self." Hence we are not surprised to learn in the same book (p. 62) that " Separateness is not an ultimate character of the individual, but is a phase of being akin to externality, and tending to disappear in so far as true individuality prevails." It appears from these passages that in spite of admissions as to the exclusiveness of finite centres of experience, the radical dis- tinction between the. subject and the object, between enjoyment and things experienced, escapes Dr. Bosanquet. His whole world is, as it were, on one plane. It is all experience more or less articulate and complete, more or less partial and confused. Individuality means a relatively high level of articulateness, and for that reason all individualities, in proportion as they develop, approximate to one and the same limit, the single experience which is wholly articulate. This conception of the entire fabric leading up to it and down from it falls to the ground as soon as subject and object are distinguished. 56 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE and freedom. When Bosanquet comes in chapter viii to deal with the limits of state action he finds the difficulty to lie in the antithesis between force and the spiritual character of the real will. The state has to rely on rewards and punishments (p. 190) that destroy the value of an action " as. an element in the best life." " An action performed in this sense under compulsion is not a true part of the will." This, so far as it goes,_ is very sound and undoubtedly touches one of the true motives for restricting the operations of the state/ but ' It is only fair to Dr. Bosanquet to say that he recognizes the character of moral liberty more fully than some other writers and in particular than Hegel. His general conception of Uberty, as explained in The Philosophical Theory of the State, is that the self is free when it is master of its passions, or, more precisely, when the real will is the master of the false will. But it is recognized by a piece of candour, w^hich should be acknowledged, that this is not the literal or elementary sense of liberty. That Uteral sense means the absence of constraint exercised by one upon others, and in going beyond that we are more or less making use of a metaphor (p. 137). It is, however, maintained that we may acquiesce as " rational beings in a law and order, which on the whole makes for the possibility of asserting our true or universal selves, at the very moment when this law and order is constraining our particular private wills in a way which we resent or even con- demn." The term " condemn " here is odd. Does it mean we condemn the law judicially, that is rationally ? If so, there would seem to be a contradiction. What Bosanquet must mean is that we recognize law to be necessary, or rather perhaps recognize law- abidingness to be necessary even if a particular law is bad. But the real question lies beyond this. In what sense is law as such an instrument of moral liberty ? The suggestion is apparently that the coercive repression of warring impulses in me sets my real, that is rational, will free. Thus, there would be no objection in theory to the plan of making men good by legislation. But this hardly seems to express Bosanquet's own meaning because at a later stage he frankly recognizes the limits of coercion, and fundamentally the whole idea is untrue. If my rational will has conquered the erring impulse, then it has estabhshed its own mastery, and may be called free in the moral sense. But, if and in so far as the erring impulse is overcome by an external restraint, my will is not only not free but not even efiective. The best that can be said for making men good by coercion is that coercive restraints at a given moment may prevent an irreparable error THE REAL WILL 57 the denial of individuality leads Bosanquet to repudiate the view that force, or generally speaking state inter- ference, lies in the intrusion of others upon the self (see p. 183). To him in principle there are no others. I should be inclined to subjoin that, if that is so, there is no force. What is at the back of force and what does it rest upon ? The isolation of the individual. When we speak of forcing a man to do a certain kind of action, we do not mean that we take hold of his hands and make him do it. A nurse may do that with a small child but it is not what is intended or practical in adult life. What we mean is that pains and penalties are imposed, that there is an appeal to fear of future suffering or to the hope of future reward. Now whin A puts forth force on B, what is the situation ? B, let us suppose, is the subject of a certain impulse, craving or feeUng which is absolutely private to him, not shared and not necessarily in the least understood by A. B, if he yields to this impulse, is under the fiat of A to suffer a penalty. Once more the feeling of pain, grief, perhaps agony, is abso- lutely private to him, unshared and perhaps Uttle appreciated by A. The danger is that A may be indifferent to B's feelings. There is nothing necessarily to com- municate to A the experience either of the craving or of the penalty by which he represses it. Now if A literally shared all B's experiences, there would not be this danger. In prescribing for B, A would have to go through the same thing himself and would have to take his own prescription. If there were always this community of experience in the sense of a community of suffering, there would be no special practical danger in the use of force, and in a democratic and uniform society we do in fact expect to find greater mildness in the use of penalties to which all are equally exposed. But in so far as there is a dis- and so make it possible for me to recover my genuine self-control later on ; just as, if I am prevented from suicide, I have at least the opportunity of living to do better another day. But if I am permanently in tutelage, I am permanently unfree and without means of freedom. 58 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE tinction between the governors and the governed, the use of force is subject to great abuse, which consists precisely in the fact that it is an intrusion on one set of people by others who are in a large measure immune from the practical working consequences. We may carry the theoretical point a little further, and we may ask if a man could ever put force upon him- self in the sense in which he could put force upon another. We have seen that when he puts force upon another there is the threat of pain, not necessarily following from the action and not a pain which he will feel himself. Neither of these conditions is realized when a man puts force on himself. When a man puts force upon himself he conquers an impulse, that is to say, he brings the whole force of his nature to bear, or more accurately, the organized system of convictions, principles, interests, which is his personality, and does not in tnith so much conquer himself as win a victory for himself. He does not threaten himself with a penalty which he will not share. He does not, strictly speaking, threaten himself at all. It is true he may fear a penalty, rernorse it may be, or a headache it may be, and he may say to himseliE that this will follow as surely as day follows night. This, however, is not a threat but an anticipation, and it is an anticipation, not of something arbitrarily attached ab extra to the act, but of something following from it as an inherent consequence. Obviously, too, it is not some- thing from which the author of the supposed menace is to be immune. The only sense in which a man can be said to threaten himself would be under some artificial form of self-reformation in which a man undertakes a vow to himself to undergo a specific penance for a specific trespass. Such a case, if we may regard it as real, would be an analogical transfer t-o the sphere of self of the re- lation of self and others, and can only belong to the sphere of play-acting with our moral nature. I conclude, therefore, that the use of force is essentially what Bosanquet denies it to be. It is an imposition on the individual by others, and its practical dangers lie THE REAL WILL 59 precisely in that isolation of the individual feelings through which force acts, which Dr. Bosanquet dismisses as of secondary importance. We cannot, therefore, accept the definition of freedom suggested by Dr. Bosanquet in his new volume. To the question how self-government is possible, he replies that the answer is drawn " from the conception of the general will which involves the existence of an actual community of shch a nature as to share an identical mind and feeling. There is no other way of explaining how a free man can put up with compulsion and even welcome it." ' On the surface this theory is attractive. In an ordered society I am free, though under compulsion, because the will of society is my own will, and the compulsion is exercised by myself upon myself. But these are mere words. The will of society may be radically opposed to my own, and yet I must obey. It may even be my duty to obey, and normally it is so, even though I think the law wrong, because society must be kept together ; and if its deUberate decision is to carry no weight with its dissentient members, profound disorganization must ensue. The evil of one bad law is not, unless in a very extreme case, to be weighed against the evil of diminishing the authority of all law. The only sense, therefore,' in which I am conforming to my own will, in obedience, is that of two evils I prefer the lesser. If in this I am free, it is not because I am a member of a society like-minded with myself, but simply because I am master of my own actions and can choose, if I will, to abide by the penalties which disobedience wni entail. If freedom depended upon identity of will, there would not be much of it in a complex world. In general freedom depends (i) on the defined and restricted use of compulsion. If the state prevents another man from coercing or oppressing me by force or the use of superior economic power, it augments my freedom ; and the uniform compulsion of law is in fact the only known method by which individuals can be assured in the enjoy- ment of a common liberty from possible oppression by ' Social and International Ideals, p. 271. 6o THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE one another. If, on the other hand, the law prevents me froip drinking or compels me to serve in the army, it is ab?urd to maintain that it is in these very respects augmenting my freedom. It may be justified in either of these actions by other considerations — even by the consideration of other kinds of freedom — ^if, for example, it has been right in judging that compulsory service is necessary to national freedom. That does not alter the fact that freedom is impaired at one point even if it is gained at another, and the man who is compelled against his will to give up his drink or to join the army is mocked if you tell him that in doing that which he most resents his will is free because the decision of society is his own. Essentially political freedom does not consist in like- mindedness, but in the toleration of differences ; or, positively, in the acceptance of differences as contributing to richer life than uniformity. Freedom, as something shareable by all members of a community, involves restraint upon that which prevents such sharing. A society is on the whole free not because there is in it little law or much law, but because the law is such as to secure scope for personal development and free associ- ation as a common possession by restricting those develop- ments, and those only, in which the fulfilment of one is the frustration of another. It is free, not where a common mind shapes the individual, but where all minds have that fullness of scope which can only be obtjiined if certain fundamental conditions of their mutual intercourse are maintained by orgariized effort.' ' Properly interprete On the other hand, it is depreciated undnly in its external relations. Dr. Bosanquet rei>eats the allegation that there exists no organized moral world, prescribing the course of duty to the state. It is not the mere absence of sanction that makes the difference between the state and the individu^ ; it is more—" the absence of a recognized moral order such as to guide the conscience itself." On this I have two comments to make. In the first place, if the state is the conscience of mankind, the sole guardian of rights and duties, the moral individual in a much more real sense than the simple man or woman, how comes it that it has built up no moral order in its - P. 282. > p. 284. VARYING APPLICATIONS 113 external relations ? Here are states (Dr. Bosanquet must in this relation admit the plural) in constant inter- course with each other. Each of them is a moral being with a conscience much more highly developed than that of any individual, yet on his showing these gifted beings have built up no recognized order to guide their consciences. They are left to anarchy and to do what is right in their own eyes, for this is what it comes to when it is said that the state must see in the moral world of which it is the guardian, the only definite guide in any difficult problem of its relations to others. It is a paradox that verges on contradiction that highly moral beings in close relations to one another should evolve no moral order and no common understanding. Secondly, Dr. Bosanquet depreciates unduly the partial moral order which has actually been established. I do not recollect to have come across the phrase " international law " in the course of his discussion, nor in fact do I see it in the index. There is a law as between states and there has been " Sittlichkeit " between them, very imperfect no doubt, yet not without its value. What has paralysed the development of international law and morality is, on the side of theory, just that doctrine of state absolutism of which the idealistic theory of the state is the most subtle justification. Every organization of men tends ta become conscienceless because it forms an internal public opinion wherein men back one another in the pursuit of everything that tends to the interest or feeds the pride in which, as members of the organization, they share. But in so great an organization as the state the impartial opinion of outsiders scarcely makes itself heard and every plea for right or reasonableness is denounced as treacherous. It is the high duty of philosophy to look beyond this narrow standpoint and seek the universal view. When philosophy deserts its duty, who wiU fulfil it ? International anarchy is not due to philosophy but to the passions of men, but the restraint which humanitarian philosophy has sought to im^se has been fatally loosened by the sophistications of idealism. 8 114 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE Developing his position in his recent volume. Dr. Bosanquet finds a double difficulty in the conception of " an organism of humanity " which he admits to be the natural extension of the idea of the social organism. The difficulty is {a) that humanity in fact possesses no com- munal consciousness whatever. Neither did England under the Heptarchy, nor France under the Merovingians. A common consciousness is a thing which grows, and Dr. Bosanquet admits that the defect might be overcome. The idea of humanity is due in part to the Stoic philosophy and in part to the great world religions, and if it has never fully matured, neither has it ever perished. It has never lost its appeal to the greater and deeper thinkers and teachers and it has continually inspired the missionary effort of the church. The conditions of an effective unity of mankind to-day are at least as matured as the conditions of an effective German unity in the eighteenth century, or an effective French unity during the Hundred Years' War. And just as a farsighted and wide-minded Frenchman or German was he who realized the unity underlying dif- ferences and prepared the way for its growth, so the far- sighted man of to-day is he who holds to the unity of human nature and the common interests of mankind and places them above all causes of quarrel. But (b) Dr. Bosanquet finds no adequate expression of the higher human quaUties in the aggregate of human beings. The valuable things are the possessions of particular communities and. " to put it bluntly, a duty to realize the best life cannot be shown to coincide with the duty to the masses of mankind." We do not need to be told that the achievements of ancient Athens and modern France are not shared by Hottentots and Kaffirs. But it does not follow that Hottentots and Kaffirs are outside the pale of rights and duties, and I do not suppose Dr. Bosanquet would contend that they are. But to say this is to admit the fundamental principle of universalism, that all human beings, as human, are within the scope of the fundamental moral law. Special obligations arise in distinct communities, but these are developments of common obligations which man owes to VARYING APPLICATIONS 115 man. To make them override these fundamentals, to push devotion to a group to the point at which it breaks with the common rule, is the sin of all group morality, of which the Machiavellian doctrine of the state is the standing example. Finally, Dr. Bosanquet imputes to the Comtists the mistake of identifying humanity as a real corporate being with the aggregate of human beings. That this is a com- plete misapprehension will be shown by the following passage by a distinguished Comtist : " No one thinks that when he mentions the word England or France or Germany, he is talking of a ghost or a phantom. Nor does he mean a vast collection of so many millions of men in the abstract ; so many million ghosts. Man in the abstract is of all abstractions the most unreal. By England we mean the pre- judices, customs, traditions, history, peculiar to EngUshmen, summed up in the present generation, in the living representatives of the past history. So with Humanity. ... Is such a religion self-worship ? . . . What explains the error is the behef that by Humanity we mean the same thing as the human race. We mean something widely different. Of each man's life, one part has been personal, the other social : one part consists in actions for the common good, the other part in actions of pure self-indulgence, and even of active hostility to the common welfare. Such actions retard the progress of Humanity, though they cannot arrest it : they disappear, perish, and are finally forgotten. There are lives wholly made up of actions such as these. They form no part of Humanity. Humanity consists only of such hves, and only of those parts of each man's life, which are impersonal, which are social, which have converged to the common good." ' The " Comtist " Humanity is mankind in so far as it forms a spiritual unity. To this unity individuals, races, communities contribute, some more and some less, some perhaps not at all ; and the contribution may be conscious or unconscious. Dr. Bosanquet should find no difficulty here. The state is for him a real corporate being which has an aggregate of citizens for its members, some of whom contribute to its unity much, some little, and others, as individuals, perhaps not at all, while the contribution ' J. H. Bridges, Essays and Addresses, pp. 86-8. ii6 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE may in any case be conscious or unconscious. There are difficulties in the Comtist conception, but it is both more spiritual and truer to fact than the idealistic conception. More spiritual because it goes below the externals of unity and relies on the permanence and penetrativeness of the inward forces which, uniting man to man, have built up the fabric of collective achievement. It is, so to say, a unity of the church rather than of the state. More true to fact because it recognizes that the higher values, on which Dr. Bosanquet insists, are not the achievements of one state or one nation, but of many, that the history of thought, ethics, religion or art, is not a history of separate communities but a world history. The co-operation, conscious or unconscious, which has wrought the best things in civilized life, is one to which races and peoples have contributed unequally, and some have not contributed at all, but it is one which far transcends the limit of any people or nation, not to speak of any state. But bielow the idea of humanity, which he deems merely a confusion, Dr. Bosanquet detects a darker and more dangerous aspiration. He " suspects " current ideas of the international future to be seriously affected by popular notions of progress and an evanescence of gvtI, which should " compensate for the wrongs and sufferings of the past." To the idealist this is sheer blasphemy against the Absolute Dr. Bosanquet tells us that he personally believes in a nobler future, but since the Absolute is perfection and since evil exists, evil is necessary to per- fection and its evanescence seems " altogether contra- dictory." Its disappearance is certainly a remote danger. The world need not be under the apprehension of a pre- mature drying up of the springs of misery and wrong. In the meanwhile it is instructive to find that in the last resort the gospel of state absolutism and opposition to the League of Nations rests on the necessity of evil as a part of the permanent scheme of things. Dr. Bosanquet may say that at any rate future good is no compensation for past wrong. In a sense, we must all agree, wrong done cannot be undone. Blighted and ruined lives cannot VARYING APPLICATIONS 117 be lived anew. Yet, if it is a question of the depth and genuineness of the feeling that a better future for the world is worth the sacrifice of the present generation, the ideahst may bethink himself of many a young man, German as well as English, who has found in this thought an alleviation of the stark horrors of the trenches and the near approach of mutilation or death. It is not a question of compensa- tion, but of the final meaning of the painful struggle of human life. If the world cannot be made incomparably better than it has hitherto been, then the struggle has no issue, and we had better strengthen the doctrine of the militant state and arm it with enough high explosive to bring life to an end. At any rate the final question is laid bare. There are those who believe life can be made good. There are those who believe it is good enough already. There are those who see life as an effort towards a harmony, gf which as yet we see only the germs. They are well aware of all the tragedy that is involved in growth and do not delude themselves with any dream of personal reparation, but they recognize in the evolutionary process a principle which is neither the bUnd whirl of conflicting passions nor the clash of egoisms, but the emergence of a spirit of harmonious freedom, and on this they rest, and with this they identify themselves. There are those again for whom the world as it is is the incarnation of the ideal, for whom change is .secondary and of no vital significance. For them evil must be justified as essential to good, though a more self-contradictory conception than that of good maintaining evil for its own purposes cannot well be devised. To the former the turning-point in the development of harmony is the clear consciousness and the adequate expression of the unity of mankind. To the latter it is a source of apprehension because it would cut the tap- root of those egoisms of state and nation, class and sex, colour and race, which engender the massive miseries of the world. We have summed up the metaphysical theory in three propositions, (i) The individual attains his true self ii8 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE and freedom in conformity to his real will ; {2) this real will is the general will ; and (3) the general will is embodied in the state. We have seen reasons for denying all these propositions. We have maintained that there is no distinction between the real will and the actual will, that the will of the individual is not identical with the general will and that the rational order, which the general will is supposed to maintain, is not confined and may be opposed to the state organization. We have suggested that serious fallacies, as calamitous morally as they are logically vicious, are involved in the political philosophy which turns upon this conception. But it would be unfair to the metaphysical theory of the state to leave the im- pression that it has always received the kind of interpreta- tion which we have here examined. In the hands of Green, for example, the notion of the general will is stated in terms which bring it into closer relation to the facts of experience, and the relation of the state to the individual is so defined as to approach far more closely to the organic conception of society. It is not my purpose here either to explain or criticize Green's Principles of Political Obligation, a work of great power and of some weaknesses, which could not be adequately examined in anything short of an independent treatise, but for the sake of fairness to Green and to living writers who have drawn their principal inspiration from him rather than Hegel, I would call attention to one or two points in which Green departs notably from the Hegelian model. First and above all, the right of the individual runs through Green's entire argument. For Green, each man has to attain his own good, realize his own perfection as an integral part of the common good. If society has a claim upon him for the performance of his duty, he like- wise has a claim upon society for the power to fulfil it. (P. 347:) "The claim or right of the individual to have certain powers secured to him bj' society, and the counterclaim of society to exercise certain powers over the individual, alike rest on the fact that these powers are necessary to the fulfilment of man's VARYING APPLICATIONS 119 vocation as a moral being, to an effectual self-devotion to the work of developing the perfect character in him- self and others." The state does not absorb the indi- vidual. It is (p. 443) "a body of persons, recognized by each other as having rights and possessing certain institutions for the maintenance of those rights." The reciprocal relations of state and society could not be put better in a single and succinct phrase. The rights of the individual certainly do not exist independently of society, but they are conditions of its own best life and therefore of the best life of the individuals which constitute it, which society is bound to recognize. (P. 351 :) " Only through the possession of rights can the power of the individual freely to make a common good his own have reality given to it. Rights are what may be called the negative realiza- tion of this power. That is, they realize it in the sense of providing for its free exercise, of securing the treatment of one man by another as equally free with himself ; but they do not realize it positively, because their possession does not imply that in any active way the individual makes a common good of his own. The possession of them, however, is the condition of this positive realization of the moral capacity, and they ought to be possessed because this end (in the sense explained) ought to be attained." Where Green is less happy, as I think, is in his discussion of the rights which society ought to recognize but does not. Thus he tells us on p. 416 " a right against society, in distinction from a right to be treated as a member of society, is a contradiction in terms." The truth which this sentence contains is that a right is a social relation just as much as a duty is a social relation, your riglit being something which I or some one else or society at large owes to you. But Green is apt to confuse the social character of rights with the recognition of rights, even going so far as to say (p. 446) " rights are made by recog- nition. There is no right ' but thinking makes it so.' " This is not consistent with his admission (p. 351) of " rights which remain rights though any particular state or all 120 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE states; refuse to recognize them " ; a sense in which he has justly said a slave has natural rights. He gives the truth in the following sentence (p. 450) : " They are ' natural ' in the sense of being independent of, and in conflict with, the laws of the state in which he lives, but they are not independent of social relations." What is needed to make these positions consistent is merely to observe that social relations are not all conscious relations. The position is well stated in an early lecture (p. 353) : " The capacity, then, on the part of the individual of conceiving a good as the same for himself and others, and of being determined to action by that conceptioni is the foundation of rights ; and rights are the condition of that capacity being reaUzed." Such a condition is something objective, independent of recognition. If any one can prove that some specific condition is in fact requisite to' the realization of a good life, then that condition is scientifically demonstrated to be a right, though it may never have been recognized from the beginning of time to the present day, and though society may refuse to recognize it now. It is in this sense that all true rights are natural rights. In all this discussion Green is on the track of the truth, but is obstructed by his idealistic presupposition that what is real must somehow be in the minds of men. Enough, however, has been said to show that Green's conception of the common good, far from overriding the individual, assumes his participation as an individual, and, far from ignoring his rights, jealously preserves them as conditions under which he is a free and rational being to achieve a good which is his own as well as the good of society.' ' In liis new volume, Social and International Ideals, Dr. Bosanquet advances a fresh definition of the state, which is more in hne with Green's way of thinlcing. " I understand by the state the power which, as an organ of the community, has the function of main- taining the external conditions necessary to the best life. These conditions are called rights. They are the claims recognized by the whole of the community as the sine quA non of the highest obtainable fulfilment of the capacities for the best life possessed by its best members." This seems to carry a much fuller recognition of the individual than is usual in Dr. Bosanquet's writings. If VARYING APPLICATIONS 121 Nor does the general will in Green figure as the common self. It is rather an element in popular psychology, which Green finds in experience. Thus he speaks (p. 404) of " that impalpable congeries of the hopes and fears of a people, bound together by common interests alid sympathy, which we call the general will. ' ' For Green it is the common will and reason of men, that is " the will and reason of men as determined by social relations, as interested in each other, as acting together for common ends." In these expressions we are at any rate in contact with reality. It may ba said that they are vague, but Green might reply that so also are the facts which he is describing. That is to saj', the actual extent to which men arc swayed by com- mon interests, the degree of their allegiance to the social order, the strength of the emotion prompting to obedience or warring against it are not rigidly determined, they fluctuate from people to people, even from district to district and from occasion to occasion. There is, he seems to say, a common good, which to the reflective mind is a definite conception and a clear ideal, but which is vaguely and partially apprehended bj' the ordinary man, so that it is rather the diffused sense of the common good than a clear purpose of realizing it which operates as a force in the ordinary life of society. These are propositions, I would suggest, rather in social psychology than in meta- physics. When Green goes on to contend that will, in the sense which he has described, and not force is the basis of the state, it becomes clear that his conception of the state has to be shaped to suit his definition. But of course he ad- mits the element of force and shows how it is fused with moral factors and in the end saves his general proposi- tion by excluding political organizations based on power. (P. 443:) "We only count Russia a state by a sort of consistently pressed, it would, I think, lead to the reconstruction of his entire theory, but the chapter from which it is taken is pro- fessedly not a correction but a restatement of his theory of the state, and the criticisms on this theory in general must therefore stand unaffected. 122 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE courtesy on the supposition that the power of the Czar, though subject to no constitutional control, is so far exer- cised in accordance with a recognized tradition of what the public good requires as to be on the whole a suscainer of rights." Green's principle, therefore, is less paradoxical, perhaps also less important, than appears at first sight. If will not force is the basis of the state, that is because only that society is a state which is based liot on force but on will. It would be unfair, however, to reduce Green's argument to a truism. We may fairly put his conclusion in this form. In every organized society there are other elements than force sustaining the general conformity to law, and in the higher organization of society conditions are realized in which force recedes further and further into the background, goodwill at each step taking its place. Only societies which have made some sensible progress in this direction deserve the name of states. This definition would seem to be justified by the compara- tive study of political institutions. Enough has perhaps been said to show that in Green's hands the conception of the general will is not allowed to overwhelm the individual, nor to override the moral law, but that the state is thought of rather as a guarantor to the individual of the conditions which enable him to fulfil his functions as a moral being. It may be objected that if we go behind Green's philosophy to his metaphysics, we shall find ourselves involved in the old difficulties of the universal and the particular and once more find person- ality absorbed in the universal self. This may be true, but it is a criticism of Green as a metaphysician rather than of Green as a political thinker. His living interest was in practical life, the strength of his grasp lay upon the hard problems of social reform. He was at his best in working through practical issues to the principles guiding them. As he receded from these principles to the ultimate theory of ethics and metaphysics, his grasp grew weakef and his meaning is often lost in obscurity and con- fusion. Descending again from this misty region to the VARYING APPLICATIONS 123 living world, we find the man for whom principles at least mean something which will affect the life of human beings, which will guide them in wisdom or mislead them in folly, wiU teach them to ensue the happiness of their kind or justify them in their pride and ambition, which are the cause of misery in society. In his political lectures Green never forgets that theoretical principles are charged with weighty meaning for the lives of men. If we compare Green's account of the general will with that of Bosanquet and others, we shall, I think, arrive at the conclusion that several distinct conceptions are covered by this term which must be held apart if any such phrases are to be used at all without breeding confusion, (i) In the first place there is a conception of the common good, whether real or supposed. The common good is not the same thing as the common will, though if there were such a thing as a common will, it is presumably the common good at which it would aim. The common good is the well-being actually shared by .the members of society, or conceived as desirable for the members of society, either, therefore, something actually existent or something which may be brought about. It may be regarded as realized or realizable in certain permanent institutions and conditions of life. (2) We may distinguish such per- manent conditions from a particular object which may be conceived as a part of the common good for the time being, e.g. victory in war. This we may call a common aim. (3) Corresponding to the common good or the common aim there may be a will to maintain the common good or to achieve the common aim. This may be called the good will.i It may exist in any individual, but, as existing in a single individual, it would not seem appropriate to speak of it as a general will. It is just the will of a particular man to secure a common good or a common purpose. (4) But, further,, such a will may be diffused more or less widely in society. If the will of a society were so united that every one of its members willed one and the same I Good at least from the point of view of the society. One might call it the loyal will. 124 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE common object, as e.g. if the whole society is bent upon victory in a war, there would be something which we could appropriately and unambiguously describe as a general will, that is to say, a will active in all the members ot a society as individuals to achieve an object by their organized efforts for their society as a whole. (5) If, further, we suppose all the members of a society to understand and appreciate the permanent good of the society as a whole and to will the necessary means for securing it, there would similarly be a general will to promote the common good. We may allow a little further latitude, and if such a will is shared, not by the whole of society but by a majority, we may still call it a general will, but for this particular case no special term really seems requisite. The general will here is simply the will of the majority. (6) But this is not the sense of the general will which seems really to be intended by the phrase. To interpret Green's ex- pressions we must think rather of a network of psycho- logical forces making on the whole in a determinate direction, generally speaking for the maintenance of a certain social structure, and more specifically for the attainment of certain definite objects. This network of forces will in a free society obtain expression ultimately in the will of the majority, but it is a good deal more complex and subtle than the content of any majority vote on a specific issue. What goes to make up the bent of the public mind in this sense is not merely so many definite acts of will in such and such a number of individuals. It is the intense conviction in some, the relative feeble- ness in others, the tacit acquiescence in one man, the partisan feeling in another, the support of a certain section on one particular part of the issue in spite of indifference or hostility on other portions of the issue, a prejudice which buttresses up the case on this side, a weakness which paralyses opposition on another side — a miscel- laneous congeries of impulses driven hither and thither, out of all of which there will emerge through reams of controversy some tangible result. Will, which means the basis of clearly thought out action, is really a bad expression VARYING APPLICATIONS 125 for this unorganized mass of psychological forces of every sort and kind that actually go to the making up of great political decisions. It will probably be true, with Green, to hold that within this congeries thei-e is a permanent element partly above and partly below the level of con- sciousness, guided directly or indirectly by considerations bearing on the common good. There are, for example, people who will not put themselves about much for justice in general but will be shocked by some act of concrete iniquity with which they come into personal contact. Those who have not been troubled to oppose a bad law in principle find themselves irked by one of its applications. Conversely, the normal man who does not generalize about the social good will deal with practical issues often enough in the way which principle would require. (7) And lastly, though we have taken exception to the description of the social tradition as an embodiment of the objec- tive reason, we have not of course denied that thought and will have gone to the building up of institutions. It is not, as we have repeatedly maintained, one thought and one will, but the combination of many minds thinking and wilUng, each by its own lights and each acting too often in accordance with its selfish interests. None the less there is a sense in which the institutions and traditions of society imply a certain social mentality. The accept- ance of such traditions, though generally unreflective, cannot be wholly unconscious, and each individual as he accepts them fits himself into a scheme of life, not as volimtarily choosing that scheme as a whole, but as accepting his part in it. This acceptance affects the mind of each individual, calling forth one faculty and repressing another, and so modifies the mental growth. Thus the outer behaviour of society as seen in its manners and customs must have an inner mentality to match. So far as there is discrepancy a change will take place in institutions. To express this aspect of social life, we might speak of social mentality, provided we understand that the kind of unity which the term expresses is not the unity of a person or self but that of many centres of thought and will in interaction. 126 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE One or another of these meanings seem to be in the mind of those who use the term "general will" ; but the real objection to the term is that in so far as it is wiU it is not general, and in so far as it is general it is not will. The common good is explicitly willed by a minority of thinking and public-spirited individuals. What is general is more undefined and perhaps indefinable, a participation in the variegated mass of psychological forces out of which the actions and development of the community emerge. We may be asked in conclusion whether after all we are to entirely deny any further meaning and reality to the general will. Was it not admitted at the beginning that there is a sense in which society is more than its members, and is it not this sense which the general will expresses ? We can understand the service of our country. Can we in the same way appreciate the service to an indefinite number of individuals like ourselves, and is that what we rely upon in patriotism or in other forms of social duty ? Is the collective life of society to go for nothing, and can it all be resolved away into its constituent atoms ? The broad answer to this question can, I think, only be found in the qualifications w^hich we introduced to the statement that the life of a whole is more than that of its parts. The proposition is true, as we saw, only in this sense : that the life of the whole is more or other than that of the parts as they exist or would exist outside the whole. The body is something other than the cells which compose it, for this simple reason among others, that the cells die when separated from the body and therefore rapidly cease to be that which they at present are. But that the body is other than the totality of the cells composing it as they exist within the body, as they function in unison with one another, is a different and, as I think, an untrue proposition. We move in this region between two poles of fallacy. Wherever we have a whole consisting of parts, we are tempted to say that the whole is something other than the sum of its parts, whereby our view of the parts is distorted and the effect of their interactions ignored. VARYING APPLICATIONS 127 Or, in reaction from this view, we are tempted to say the parts alone are real and that the whole is only a way of regarding them or at best a superficial consequence of their juxtaposition in certain relations to one another. Both these theories are untrue. The first theory always and the second of those wholes which have any distinctive character of their own. If I cast my eye idly over the leaves strewn on the lawn, I may count them and discover that there are thirty-seven, and treat the thirty-seven as forming a whole. This numerical whole is nothing to the actual leaves. As I count, three of the thirty-seven have run away with the wind and instead of thirty-seven I have thirty-four^ which not having been moved are just what they were before. Such a numerical whole is the limiting case in which the parts are unaffected by the totality. It is just their arithmetical sum, no more and no less. If I gather the leaves into a heap, they are at least an aggregate that can be picked up and carried away. But still the aggregate has no permanence and its effect upon the parts is very small and very casual. Unless they happen to be somewhat crushed out of shape by pressure, the leaves will experience no change in passing into the whole and out of it again. If, on the other hand, I consider the leaf itself, even the dead leaf, it is something more than an aggregate. It consists of parts no doubt-, but the parts are connected by definite ties. The leaf acts as a whole. If the wind catches a part of it, that part carries the rest along with it. Such a whole of parts in a determinate arrangement which for some purpose act together, is a structure which is in every respect as real and significant as the elements which compose it. What we call the onesided analytic tendency is the tendency to deny this, to think the cells something more real than the leaf, which is thus conceived only as a certain arrangement of cells, and the molecules of protoplasm more real than the cells and the atoms more real than the molecule. We get rid of a bunch of fallacies incidental to this Une of argument when we refuse to speak of more or less real altogether. 128 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE Atoms, molecules, protoplasm, cells, leaf, all are just real or unreal. What we can say is that in many cases the elements are more permanent than the whole which they constitute. Certain physical molecules, for example, remain, I suppose, when the dead leaf begins to decompose, and it is this permanence, or supposed permanence, of the simple elements underljdng complex structures, which has given the illusion of their greater reality. Conversely, in many cases the whole is more permanent than the parts. E.g. the living organism is always absorbing and excreting material elements. It remains while its components change. The components do not indeed pass out of existence when they leave the whole, but in proportion as the struc- ture is organic they are profoundly modified. The cell does not survive the leaf, nor does the protoplasm, as protoplasm, the cell. Of any organic structure this principle will hold true. The parts will not survive the structure unaltered. Something in each may survive, but it will not be exactly that which existed within the whole. Now in human society, as in the material world, there are many fortuitous aggregations, producing slight con- tact between individuals. The people who happen to be walking along a street at a particular time may be numeri- cally conceived of as a whole, though they are barely modified by any contact with one another. A crowd is more united than this, though it has no structure, but for the time being people are affected by close contact with one another, and to that extent even a crowd is a unity and a reality, though Hot one with endurance. Passing on, we find all sorts of associations into which men can enter, affecting their lives in very varying degrees. When the effect is slight, we may well say that it is the individuals that are permanent, and if the society is broken up, it is just resolved into its component individuals, who remain very much what they were before. When we come to the deeper and more stable associations, tliis would no longer be true. The life of the family is an integral part of the men and women that compose it. When it breaks up the lives of those that remain may be tragically altered ; VARYING APPLICATIONS 129 certainly they are very different from what they would have been if they had never known a family life. The same thing would be true of a religious body, or of a state, or of any great movement, intellectual, social or political, into which a man throws himself. All these deeper associa- tions are of the organic type. They express important elements, perhaps fundamental elements, in the lives which compose them, so that without them those indi- viduals would be essentially other than they are. If thus for a moment we think of the life or value of such an association in terms of individuals, we must in turn think of the individuals as contributing and con- sciously contributing to the life of the whole. If the soldier is told that to die for England means to die for English men and women, he might say that that was good enough for him, but he might also go on to say that it is not merely for men and women as men and women, but for men and women as continuing to lead a certain life, as maintaining and developing the tradition which is essentially England. This tradition lives in nothing but individuals ;- all of it that is incorporated in material, even the land itself, however much that is the object of affec- tion, vanishes into insignificance apart from the humanity which it subserves. The tradition, on the other hand, might flourish as well on foreign soil, as colonization proves, and as was understood by William the Silent when he thought of transporting the entire population of Holland and Zeeland to a part of the world where they could maintain their life free from the empire-state which was crushing it. Thus the character of a social whole is as much in danger of being misunderstood when it is resolved into its com- ponent individuals as it is when conceived as separate from them, as though it were not made by them. The true organic theory is that the whole is just what is con- stituted by the co-operation of the parts, neither more nor less, not more real nor less real, not of higher nor of inferior value. In saying this we must take time into account. All the parts strictly means all that have been 9 130 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE or will be while the whole endures. When this succession of members is taken into account, it is true to equate the perfectly organic whole with the sum of its parts in their co-operative activity. But there is a sense in which a whole may be less, and a sense in which it may be more than its existing parts, (i) Wholes in general, even relatively organic wholes, may engage only a portion of the activity or capacity of their members. This is emi- nently true of human associations, none of which embrace the entire life of man. In such a case it is only the portion incurred in the whole that can be said to hve or die with the whole, and only so far as that portion is concerned that there is an5i:hing of the nature of an organic union. One of the fallacies of the metaphysical theory is to identify the individual with one particular association, and to speak of his obUgations to that association in terms only applicable to the sum of his duties and interests in all the relations of his life. {2) While some wholes are less, others, and particularly those which engage the deeper nature of men, are more permanent than their members. When we go, for example, below the state to the nation and beyond the nation to the great movements of civilization, we come to things in which the whole truly is something far greater than any of the parts that constitute it at any one moment. What concerns humanity is that such wholes should be maintained in so far as they serve its abiding interest. But this again is not, if we think it out, to erect the whole into an object distinct and opposed to those who have been, are or will be its members. It is merely to grasp its far-reaching extension, its deeply rooted continuity. The nation is aU the generations which compose it as long as they maintain a certain imity and as long as the thread of causation remains uncut. More than this it is not.' ' When taken as more it will be found to be really less. If the good of the state is opposed to that of its component members, it is because its good is being found in ends which do not make life really better, for exa.mple, glory, wealth, expansion and power. Such ends the masses may serve in their capacity of " cannon- VARYING APPLICATIONS 131 In what terms we are to describe the reality of the social wholes is a standing difficulty of sociology. They are, as we have seen, of organic character, yet, if we speak of them as organisms, we are liable to confound them with animals or plants, which they are not. Essentially they are unities of mind. Their component elements are minds and the relations into which these elements enter are determined by mental operations. Yet if we speak of them as personaUties, we are liable to the fallacy of the common self. Social inquiry suffers from nothing so much as a lack of technical terms or of suitable metaphor to supply the place of technical terms. It has to use words derived from other orders of experience and conceptions elaborated in other sciences. What we must most eschew is any term suggesting a form of unity reaUzed in some other whole than the particular social whole which we are consider- fodder," but then they are not parts of the state but mere hving tools, the effective organization consisting of the rulers and generals who want the glory. At bottom,, when any organized human society is alleged to have a good other than that of its members, it means a good, at least a supposed good, of some of its members without regard to the remadnder. It may be said that these unhappy ones acquiesce, e.g. when the multitude lets itself be dominated by its chiefs and led by them to the slaughter in the desire to share even in a subordinate capacity in the glory of reducing other peopl6 to a still more abject subjection. This is the solution suggested in a pecuUarly sinister passage in Nietzsche. If so, the people constitute themselves partners of a common good of a false and inhuman sort. So far as the illusion of service to a state standing above its members encourages such false values, it is practically mischievous as well as theoretically false. Where an organized society has a " good " opposed to the summed up gain and loss of its component members, it is either that some of those alleged members are treated merely as instruments external to the body they share or that the good is a false good, cheating even those that partake of it. When we speak of a good we mean a good supposed to be realized in the life of society itself. So far as any society subserves ends beyond its own limits, as, e.g. a state may be said to owe, and even to perform, a service to civilization, different principles of course apply. It may be right and good for a state hke Belgium to risk all in such a case, but even here there is no final distinction between the duty or well-being of Belgium and of the Belgians as Belgians. 132 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE ing. Such a term is " a common self " or " the general will," suggested by a particular unity which connects the parts of a personality and which is precisely the form of unity that different persons do not achieve and into which they cannot enter. Such a term as " mind," " soul " or " spirit," though not satisfactory, is more appropriate, if so used as to suggest a collec- tive character rather than a substantial unity. We can speak of the soul of a people, meaning thereby certain fundamental characteristics of their psychology which we believe to be widespread and important in the shaping of their social behaviour. We speak of the spirit of the times not inappropriately as a summary name for certain moral and intellectual tendencies, and generally the term " spirit " is appropriate for the relations of finite centres of intelligence each thinking, feeling and acting with reference to one another, and so linked together by mental and moral causation, just as physical structures are united by mechanical forces. But whatever terms we use, the rule of logic is simple. Our reasonings must always stand the test of substituting the thing defined for the definition. We must avoid importing into our defining term the associations which belong to it in another capacity. If we keep this rule before us, the terms which we use to describe society will have a less disturbing effect upon the progress of sociology. Thus, if we speak of a society as organic, we must not think of it as a great Leviathan, a whole related to individuals as a body to its cells. We must regard the organic as a genus into which animals and plants fall as species and society as another species. So considered, an organism is a whole constituted by the interconnection of parts which are themselves maintained each by its intercon- nection with the remainder. Its mutual determination is the organic character which any given structure may share in greater or less degree, a structure being organic in so far as this character prevails and otherwise inorganic. In its completeness the organic is an ideal. But actual societies have a touch of the organic character, some VARYING APPLICATIONS 133 more and some less. It is on this character that social ethics depends. It is through this character that societies, like biological organisms, maintain their plastic adapta- bility, their power of adjustment to new circumstances, of repairing injuries, of resilience to strokes of fortune. It is by reference to this character that their development is to be measured. This principle is set at nought when society is so resolved into individuals that the character of the life which they share is left out of account. It is equally set at nought when its life is regarded as other than that which its members live in their dealings with one another. The happiness and misery of society is the happiness and misery of human beings heightened or deepened by its sense of common possession. Its will is their wills in the conjoint result. Its conscience is an expression of what is noble or ignoble in them when the balance is struck. If we may judge each man by the contribution he makes to the community, we are equally right to ask of the community what it is doing for this man. The greatest happiness will not be realized by the greatest or any great number unless in a form in which all can share, in which indeed the sharing is for each an essential ingredient. But there is no happiness at all except that experienced by individual men and women, and there is no common self submerging the soul of men. There are societies in which their distinct and separate personalities may develop in harmony and contribute to a collective achievement. CONCLUSION The best and the worst things that men do they do in the name of a religion. Some have supposed that only supernatural religion could mislead. The history of our time shows that if men no longer believe in God they will make themselves gods of Power, of Evolution, of the Race, the Nation, or the State. In the name of such gods will they drench a continent with blood, and the youth will offer themselves up as wiUing martyrs. There is no double dose of original sin which estabhshed this worship in Germany, It is the product of a combina- tion of historic causes — the long division of the people, their geographical situation, the national reaction agauist Napoleon, the achievement of union by military means, the fear of the Czardom, causing the acquiescence of the more pacific elements in militarism, the loss by emigration of those who would not tolerate the governing system. The idealized exaltation of the state supervened to reconcile the thinking classes and give them a creed justifying their dislike of humanitarianism. In Hegel's hands this creed had, as we have seen, its ideaUstic side, and events had to move before this could be shed, and the naked doctrine of Power be proclaimed by Treitschke. But the elevation of the state above men means at bottom the supremacy of Power. It is the natural creed of an aristocracy or a bureaucracy, as insistence on PersonaUty is the natural creed of the people. Theories of poUtics or of conduct that live long and retain influence have something more than theory behind them. They appeal to powerful instincts and interests, and the Hegelian »34 CONCLUSION 135 philosophy is no exception. It appeals to the instincts and interests of counsellors and kings, of privileged classes, of Property and Order. It plays on the fear of fundamental criticism, of the razor-edge of thought, of the claim of conscience to scrutinize institutions and ordinances. It appeals to the slavishness which accepts a master if he will give the slave a share of tjnranny over others more deeply enslaved. It satisfies national egoism and tlass ascendancy. It was by no accident that the Greatest Happiness Principle took root and flourished during and after the last great war that devastated Europe. The spectacle of the massive misery caused by Governments had its recoil. Men began to test institutions and ideas of life by their effect on the felt happiness and misery of millions, and they found in the " happy fireside for weans and wife " a truer measure of a nation's greatness than stricken fields and extended territory. To that view in essence we are returning to-day. Much has been learnt in the interval, and a modem thinker could not regard happiness crudely as a sum of pleasures, or divorce it from the mode of Ufe which is its substance, or judge the well-being of a whole society by the contentment of a numerical majority. But the desire to arrest the misery of mankind will revive in double strength. Europe has undergone its martyrdom, millions in the service of false gods, other millions in resisting them. It will ask itself what is the true God and where the true religion. The answer, what- ever it be, must rest on this truth, that the higher ethics and the deeper religion do not come to destroy the simplest rights and duties of neighbour to neighbour, but to fulfil and extend them. Great purposes, vast schemes, haunt the imagination of man, and urge him on to achievements without, which life would be relatively poor and stagnant. But too often such purposes are built on foundations of human misery and wrong. It is the rarer insight which sees in the great good the com- prehensive unity of all the Uttle things that make up the life of the common man. The theory of the state 136 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE is a case in point. The state is a great organization. Its well-being is something of larger and more permanent import than that of any single citizen. Its scope is vast. Its service calls for the extreme of loyalty and self- sacrifice. All this is true. Yet when the state is set up as an entity superior and indifferent to component individuals it becomes a false god, and its worship the abomination of desolation, as seen at Ypres or on the Somme. When it is conceived as a means to the extension of our duty towards our neighbour, a means whereby we can apply effectively and on the large scale what we know to be good in the simple personal relations of life, no such discord arises. The purposes of political action are no way narrowed, but purified and humanized. We leani to think of our political conduct in terms of the vast reverberation of consequences on thousands and millions of lives, great and lowly, present and to come. We cannot, indeed, ever adequately interpret gr«at general truths in terms of the particulars which they cover. To give to vast social issues all their human meaning is beyond the power of imagination — an imagination which recoils even from the effort to appreciate the daUy list of casualties. But the true progress of political thought lies in the cultivation of imaginative power. It insists on going back from the large generahty, the sounding abstraction, the imposing institution, to the human factors which it covers. Not that it wishes to dissolve the fabric. Men must continue to build, and on deeper foundations and with larger plans. But there must be no slave buried alive beneath the corner stone. Or rather, the fabric is no building, but a tissue of living, thinking, feeling beings, of whom every one is " an end and not a means merely," and the value of the whole is marred if it requires the suffering of any single element. There is no lack of vast- ness in this design. It might rather be accused of vague- ness, if it were not tht^t it starts with the simple relations of man and man and bids each of us seek to realize in political conduct anji through social institutions, on the widest scale and iti impersonal delations, what we well CONCLUSION 137 understand in our private lives as " our duty towards our neighbour." Political morality is not super-morality, setting ordinary obligations aside. It is morality extended and defined, stripped of the limitations of class or national prejudice, generalized for application in great impersonal organiza- tions, the only thing that can save such organizations from becoming inhuman. It may be said that institutions and politics generally can do little to make individuals happy. That may be true, but they can do a vast deal to make individuals unhappy, and to cut off this great source of woe is no unworthy aim. That is why a sound political philosophy will always insist on the individual, the freedom which is his basis of self-respect, the equality which is his title to consideration, the happiness whereof " the tiny bowl is so easily spilt." It is not that our little lives are rounded in ourselves. On the contrary, if we find happiness an5nvhere, it is only in merging our- selves in some greater object. It is that if all objects worthy of effort may be considered as contributing to the advancement of mankind, this advancement, properly understood, goes not over the bodies and souls of individuals like a Juggernaut's car, but through their heightened activities and larger lives like a quickening spirit. Here precisely lies the issue between two views of the state. In the democratic or humanitarian view it is a means. In the metaphysical view it is an end. In the democratic view it is the servant of humanity in the double sense that it is to be judged by what it does for the lives of its members and by the part that it plays in the society of humankind. In the metaphysical view it is itself the sole guardian of moral worth. In the democratic view the sovereign state is already doomed, destined to subordina- tion in a community of the world. In the metaphysical view it is the supreme achieveriient of human organization. For the truth let the present condition of Europe be witness. APPENDIXES APPENDIX I HEGEL'S THEORY OF THE WILL In Lecture II the attempt has been made to elicit and criticize the main principles underlying Hegel's theory of freedom. A somewhat fuller explanation is here subjoined. Hegel approaches the subject by a somewhat imfortunate analogy. The will is free in the same sense as matter is heavy. Gravity, he thinks, constitutes bodies. This in itself seems to be a mistake, partly of fact, but principally of definition. The expression " body has gravity " is a way of putting the fact that bodies, when otherwise unconstrained, move towards one another with a certain assignable acceleration. This statement by no means exhausts all that is known about bodies. If bodies were not known independently, that is, had no other attributes, we should not say that bodies had weight, but merely that weight exists. Whether aU bodies do behave in the way referred to is a sheer question of empirical fact. But in any case gravity is not body, but is an attribute of body or, if it is preferred, a way in which bodies do behave. In the same way, if it is true that the will is free, it is certainly not in the sense that freedom is wUl or that wiU is freedom, but that freedom is a characteristic of will or an expression of the way in which wUl behaves. But will is not only freedom to Hegel, it is also thought. Will and thought are not two special faculties, but will is a specific mode of thought. It is thought as translating itself into existence,' " In thinking, according to Hegel, I turn an object into a thought, stripping the sensible element from it and making it essentially and immediately mine. Thought penetrates the object, which no longer stands opposed to me because I have taken from it what was peculiar to it, which it had over against me. Similarly, in willing there appears at first an opposition between myself and my object, and in making a choice I make a distinction between a determinate end and my abstract potentialities. But this dis- J38 APPENDIXES 139 setting before itself an object with which it is in a manner identi- fied. Ordinary language would recognize these expressions as having a loose metaphorical justification, but to Hegel they are the kernel of philosophy, and his conception of free wiU in particular will be found to depend upon taking them seriously. It is through his identification of the will with the system or totality of its objects that Hegel is able to speak of the will as determined only by itself, oif the will as willing itself, and thus free from any other determination. The development of this conception follows the ordinary dia- lectical process of Hegelian philosophy. We start with the conception of a will that is free in the sense of being quite indeter- minate, so that it can choose anything and everything. But a will so indeterminate as this in fact chooses nothing and defeats itself. Hegel likens it to the anarchical movements of politics that want everything in general and nothing in particular. To escape from this barrenness we take refuge in particular objects or ends. But if the particular ends are isolated and disconnected they just miss that unity of action which dis- tinguishes will. The truth then must be that, while the will sets a multitude of particular objects before itself, those objects must be united by some underlying principle. It is in this unity of principle that Hegel finds what he calls freedom. The connection is by no means obvious,' but the drift of the argument may be gathered from the account of free- dom as ordinarily, and in Hegel's view, falsely understood.* tinction is after all my own, and the object, as I achieve it, belongs to me. It is mine when accomplished. The object is what I have done. There is a trace of my spirit in it. ' The argument is that since all the objects of the will fall under the same principle or have, as we might say, a function in one and the same system, they do not really limit the will as they seem to do, but express it in different forms. In seeming to limit itself, the will is expressing itself. This, according to Hegel, constitutes the freedom of the will, which is its substantive reaUty, as gravity is the substantive reality of body. » It may be well to note the dialectical phases by which the conception of spurious freedom is reached. First, in § 8 we have what Hegel calls the formal opposition of the subjective to the objective. The will is something within me, contrasted with the outer world in which it seeks to realize its end. These particular ends form the content of the will, but, in adopting such ends (§ 10), the will does not fully attain its freedom. Its freedom is 140 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE This false conception emerges when the will stands contrasted as a distinct faculty or power of choice with the various impulses which direct it towards particular objects, each of which counts as distinct from and possibly opposed to others. The power of the will to choose between them is the kind of freedom which Hegel calls caprice {Willkiir). And according to him it is at this point that the ordinary controversy as to freewill arises and on this plane that it is conducted. As long as the will is regarded as a bare potentiaUty, what Hegel calls something formal, standing over against impiilses and promptings that proceed from else- where, whether within our nature or without it, you can argue with equal force either that it is determined or that it is undeter- mined. You can argue that it is determined on the ground that a mere potentiality, a bare form, has nothing within it to make it decide one way rather than another, whence you conclude that the propelling force must come from the impulse or from the presented object. You can argue equally that the will is undetermined because you can show that it can take up or drop any one of these objects and that what it can take up it can cancel, no matter what the strength of the impulse may be. In reality, according to Hegel, both arguments fail because both rest on a false conception of the relation of the will as a unity, or what he would call the universal, to its particular acts and im- pulses. The truth is that these particulars emanate from the universal character of the will itself. The will, therefore, does not stand over against the impulses which solicit it, but is itself the source of each movement in which it accomplishes and fulfils itself. The argument seems to ignore the distinction between impulse and will,' but again let us suspend criticism and try to follow the drift of the reasoning to the end. implicit. It is in the will itself but it does not exist for, the will. That it should exist in this fuller sense, the will must realize itself as an object. There is a will operating whenever I adopt some definite end, and since there is a will operating there is freedom, but not, it would seem, the consciousness of freedom, not that organic connection between a particular end and a permanent underljring principle which constitutes self-determination. This is the stage which Hegel calls the immediate or natural will with its separate impulses and desires. The wUl stands above all these particular objects and can freely compare and choose between them. This brings us to the position examined in the text. ' Impulses antagonize one another, and one may calculate which impulse would bring the greatest satisfaction, but such calculation APPENDIXES 141 To do this we must think of the will as expressing itself com- pletely in a system of purposes all related to one another. When it grasps this system as a whole it is said to exist for itself and to be its own object.' The meaning is that this system completely expresses the nature of the will and therefore for Hegel (here we get back to the ultimate identity of subject and object) is the will. True, there is always a distinction between subjective and objective, inner and outer aspects. Subjectively the will is the rational self -consciousness, objectively it is the rational system of ends. But to get the full " idea " of the will these aspects must be held together. The will therefore in wUling its object is said to will itself. Thus for the will to be determined by its objects as a whole is to be determined by itself, and to be determined by itself is freedom. This is the substance of the entire argument, which culminates in the formula that the idea of the will is the free wiU which wills the free will. This peculiarly difi&cult phrase proceeds directly from Hegel's identification of subject and object. Just as in the sphere of knowledge the mind, taken in its full concrete reality, is the system of the objective world which it knows, the knowledge itself being an aspect of the system, so we are to understand again is mere caprice. According to Hegel, any identification of myself with some one impulse is a distinct limitation of the univer- sality of the self, wliich is described in this section as the system of all impulses. This conception gives rise to another dialectical stage. The different impulses which issue immediately from the will are held to be good. On the other hand, as natural impulses, they are opposed to the conception of the spirit and have to be eradicated as bad. The truth is that they must be purified by being changed from their immediate or natural character and restored to what he calls their substantive essence, that is to the form in which they can play a part in the rational system which is the will. The conception of happiness, involving some correlation of the different impulses, is a stage towards a rational life, but only a stage, because happiness lies in the individual human being, that is in his subjective feeUng, so that what was to be universal turns out to-be particular, something realized in particular people that is not an organic unity of all consciousness. The underlying truth {§ 21) is the self-determining universal, and this is will and freedom. I And therefore infinite, for it turns back into itself like a circle, which, for Hegel, is the true representative of infinitude. 142 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE that in action the will is the system of accomplished purposes, the purposiveness of it being a part of that system. We are to conceive a system of activity penetrated throughout by a single principle or rather, we should say, engendered in all its variety of detail by a single principle, which requires infinite variety of forms in which to express itself, but a variety which by the interconnection of all its parts makes up an organic whole. This whole Hegel conceives as determined by nothing external to itself ; any part of it may be regarded as detennined by the will, but is in fact equally a determinant of the will. Its nature is to be a part of that will. So, in a sense, the will wills itself. Wherever you start, pursue the track of determination and you will come back to the point from which you started. This is the circle in which Hegel finds the meaning of infinitude, and that is why infinitude and self-determination are to him in the end the same thing. In seeking to render the meaning plain to ourselves, we are constantly brought up against the initial difficulty of conceiving a will which wills itself. Surely when we will we are making, creating or bringing about something that does not exist ; some- thing, whatever it may be, which is at any rate other than the act of making it. To avoid this fundamental difficulty and to discover, if we can, what substance xmderlies the Hegelian argument, let us put it, in more modem phrase, that the will Mid its object are conceived as an organic unity to be understood by the contrast in which it stands to that mechemical relation- ship which Hegel calls caprice. In this mechanical relationship there are a number of distinct and separate impulses, and a will apart from them all, moving above them and choosing now one and now another. In the organic relationship the different movements of the will, though distinct from one another, are emanations from one and the same principle. They could not exist without that principle, nor yet could the principle exist without them, nor indeed without any one of them, for each is an organic part of the whole. ' Each impulse is, as it ' The only determinant of the will which Hegel contemplates is the object. If then he can show that the object emanates from the will, he proves on his presupposition that the will determines itself. It is to this that his demonstration is addressed. He does not consider the determinist point that the will with all its pur- poses (to admit that these emanate from within) arises out of antecedent conditions. But he is not really thinking of the will of an individual, but rather of the world spirit. APPENDIXES 143 were, a bit of the will. Each bit of the will is determined by the will as a whole. Thus will is determined by will, that is by itself. And if, again, the will be considered as a whole which is determined by nothing external, but by its constituent parts, then similarly the will as a whole is self-determined. All its different objects are parts of a whole which hangs together and in which it is always expressing itself. This organic relationship is what Hegel understands by freedom, and so understood we have in this conception a system of action, the object of which is to maintain itself as a free system. This is what is expressed in the phrase "the free will which wills the free will." Putting aside the phraseology, which depends on the impos- sible identification of subject and object, we have before us the conception of an organic or harmonious system of con- duct. What precisely is a harmonious system ? It is one in which there are many parts, but so related that they all main- tain or support one another. If we think of some occupation or some, purpose which we deem desirable as a whole and which interests us in all its successive details, we have the model of a harmony of this kind. We take each step for its own sake because it is inherently attractive, and we also take it as a step in a journey, the end of which is equally attractive ; and thus there is at every stage a double motive, the immediate object for its own sake and also as contributory to the wider object which is intrinsically desired. If all Ufe could be like that, it would be a perfect harmony and it would have nothing to do but to maintain itself. It would in fact be a self-maintaining system, such as Hegel contemplates, a system, that is, in which each part in effecting itself helps to give effect to the whole. Now the ideal to which moral purpose strives is a system of this kind, a harmony within the individual, a harmony as between all individuals — a unity, that is, in which each individual playing his own part, hving a life which is desirable to him, is forwarding and consciously forwarding the life that is desirable for all mankind. In such a harmony, moreover, there would be perfect freedom, for the individual would be expressing himself imconstrainedly, and yet in ex- pressing himself and by expressing himself, would be serving the requirements of the whole. But the freedom would be possible only because there is harmony and it would be truer to say that in such a system it is the will to maintain harmony 144 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE than that it is the will to maintain free will which is the vital principle. This leads us to inquire further into the relation between freedom and harmony. What is really meant by freedom ? Ordinary thought translates freedom as absence of constraint. Hegel takes freedom as self-determination. In a world where nothing stands alone, where every act or event is related to some- thing from which it follows and which is said to determine it, it is clear that of the action of anything whatever that we can regard as a continuous object, that we can identify through successive moments, one of two things is true. Either that action is an action of the object itself, proceeding from the nature of the object, arising out of the state in which the object has been, and consisting in a further state of activity which is just what the object of itself becomes. In that case the object may be said to determine its own action, or, regarding the object as one through successive phases, that is, before the action and in it, we can speak of the object, if we wiU, as self-determined in its activity. The other alternative is that the object should be determined by some- thing else acting upon it. Then we speak of it as constrained. In the purely physical world, ordinary thought recognizes this contrast between freedom and constraint. A lever may be said to move freely about its fulcrum. The law of gravity expresses the way in which two bodies move freely, the pendulum moves freely about its support, all in contrast to the way in which these objects would behave under the constraint of some external force operating upon them. It may be objected that no one of these bodies really moves of itself. The pendulum, for instance, is part of a system of forces. There is its point of support, the weight attached to the rod, the rod itself and the earth. Never- theless the swing of the pendulum is the resultant of just this particular system of forces acting without constrcdnt by others, and that absence of constraint is what is meant when it is said that the pendulum swings freely. That particular system of forces determines of itself, and without the impingement of any other forces, just the particular set of motions which we discover. On the other hand, if the pendulum is deflected by a magnet, a push or a catch, a new force intervenes by which it is constrained. The whole system, including this new force, again may be said to act freely if no other intervenes. But in every case freedom from some external constraint will mean determination by the forces that are within the particular object or system of objects, which is the subject of our discourse. APPENDIXES 14s When we come to the action of Uving things, and in particular to the will, we still mean by freedom primarily this same thing, the determination of the act by the character of the living thing itself, in particular of the will, as against determination by any- thing other than itself. What I choose to do at this moment, if I choose freely, expresses the character of my will at this moment. True, some extemsd thing may be the stimulus which sets the will in motion, and it is because I see the rose perhaps that I have the impulse to bend down and smell it or pick it. But the rose does not constrain me, rather it suggests an experi- ence, and the fact that I think of that experience as pleasing is a circumstance of my inner nature emd precisely the circumstance which expresses itself in my impulse. In so far as any external object does constrain me and in so far as it awakens in me that which I cannot resist, I am deemed, and rightly deemed, not to be free, to be a slave to the external thing. Or again, if this craving is, as rightly regarded it should be regarded, rather inner than outer, then I am a slave to one of my impulses and my will is not free. If, on the other hand, knowing quite well what I am about and what was coming from my act, I perform that act with a view to that result, then that act is an expression of my will. It is unconstrained by anything external, not merely to myself, but to my will, and my will is free. But there is a further sense in which the will is free which does not apply to material things. Given the pendulum duly attached to its support and raised from the vertical and then set free, that is, released from all external constrdnt, the result will be uniform and certain. The pendulum will swing to and fro. Each swing is determined accurately by the past swing. The movement of each moment is determined by the configura- tion of the preceding moment. Thus the mechanical system, though free from external restraints, is never free from its own past. The question of the freedom of the will morally considered has been whether the will can ever be said to be free from its own past. The answer to this must be in a sense' negative and in a sense affirmative. There is no reason to doubt that what my will is now is something which has come out of all that it and that I have been ; and there is no ground for assigning at any point a breach of continuity. The difference between the will and the mechanical system is this. The will looks towards that which is coming out of it ; it is in a sense determined not 10 146 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE by the past but by the future ; and yet that future is something which it itself creates. It creates the end by which it is itself determined. The fact that the will creates this end is itself the determining point of its activity. It is in this sense that the will is self-determined in a way in which nothing that is mechanical can be. The pendulum does not swing because it wants exercise or because it wants to get to the other side. It swings as a result of the forces that are working within the system to which it belongs. The will, it may be said, also operates in accordance with the forces working within it, but these forces are such afe to create a result which it foresees and it is because they create this result that the wiU acts as it does. The consequence is that there is no limit to the self-determination of the will. If at any point in the course of its activity something indicating a different result, previously unforeseen, emerges the wiU is able to adapt itself to this new circumstance. There is no fact bearing upon the issues of its action which the will is constrained by its pas"t to omit. The past has made it what it is, but what it is is something looking to the future, determining its move- ments by their relation to the future. Self-determination in general then means the operation of an object in accordance with its own character and the self-determination of the will in particular, its operation in accordance with the character of a creative impulse. Unconstraint and self-determination are thus two expressions for the same thing, the one negative and the other positive. With this definition in mind, we can easily recognize that the "harmonious system of conduct, or let us say the harmonious will, is also in its inward relations a free system and a free will. Let us think of such a system as produced in each pju-t by a several and separate act of will. Each act expresses itself, or rather in each act as it is at the time and in the relations appropriate to the action, the will is expressing itself without let or hindrance from other acts or relations of the will. Not only without let or hindrance from them, but furthered, main- tained and supported by them, while also yielding to them furtherance and support. We think of the will in each act as looking not only towards the act itself, but also towards the entire system of willing of which it is a part, as expressing itself in both relations and finding the two relations harmonious. In such a harmony each deliverance of the will is free, that is it is unconstrained by any othier deliverance of the will. Now for APPENDIXES 147 any single act of will there is just the same freedom if it is per- formed without any consciousness of relation to the will as a whole, for it is performed without constraint and it is therefore self-determined. But the will as a whole can only have freedom within if its purposes harmonize, otherwise there is constraint of some of its deliverances by others and they cannot all be free. In particular, if the permanent character of the will, its main tendency or its general principle, is in conflict with and overbears its own impulse in some particular case, the result in that case is not freedom but constraint. Here it would seem that Hegel would rejoin, " Yes, but the constraint that you speak of as exercised by the will in one particular relation is a constraint exercised by the will as a whole upon the will at a particular moment, that is, a constraint exercised by the will upon itself. Thus it is still self-determination and therefore it is freedom." But if this argument is advanced, it must be rejoined that self- determination so interpreted is by no means a satisfactory definition of freedom. If there is self-determination without harmony, what results is that the particular act or phase of will may be to any degree constrained, deflected, inhibited in its self-expression by the will as a whole, or, if the phrase be pre- ferred, by the imifying principle of the will. Thus instead of the freedom of each several act of will we may have an absolute constraint exercised by the whole upon the parts. If it be said that this at any rate leaves the general principle of the will free to express itself, it must be replied that all we know of this principle is that it consists in the complete domination of all distinguishable phases or acts of will. The will is not willing itself, but against itself. Thus, in place of the free will that wills the free will, we have the conception of the will that in its freedom wills the total subordination of will ; or, in other words, freedom without harmony turns out to be con- straint, the subordination of the particular to the universal. On the other hand, the freedom which is found in harmony is the expression of each particular phase of will in its own nature, and it is only if order and harmony are assumed to be con- vertible terms that it is possible to lay down a priori that a system dependent on a single principle is at once self-main- taining and free. The truth is that the Hegelian conception of freedom really points towards an idea of harmony which Hegel himself does not seem to have appreciated. Freedom in the sense of absence of internal friction could be 148 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE realized in a completely harmonious order of conduct but in no other. But free will, as Hegel uses the expression, is simply will which carries through a single principle, that is really a self- disciplined will — disciplined in accordance with law and custom — and wherever he uses the term " freedom," the term " self- discipline " should be substituted to make sense of his argument. In place of the will that wills the free will we should speak of the disciplinarian will that wills the subordination of all those partial impulses. In this conception there is, if you like, freedom for the central principle of the will, but for that alone — a freedom like that of James I's free monarchy, which meant that the monarch was free to do what he wished with every one else. It follows quite clearly from Hegel's view that the bad will is not free, but on this point he must be charged with distinct incon- sistency, for when he comes to deal with the responsibility for wrong-doing (§ 139, p. 183) he explicitly maintains, as against the view that evil is necessary, that " the man's decision is his own act, the act of his freedom and his guilt." But it is clear that in his usage of the terms this could only be true if wrong-doing were the universal principle of the will. Hence the man who acts wrongfully is not free ; he is expressing caprice {WillkUr) and has no freedom. Hegel cannot have it both ways. Either freedom means self-deteimination expressing itself in the choice between good and bad, and therefore as distinctly in the bad as in the good. In that case man as a moral agent is free, but free to do both ill and well. Or, freedom means subjection to the discipline of the goodwill. In that case man is free when he does good, but is not free to choose between good and evil. To sum up, Hegel's conception of freedom depends upon a confusion between two distinct conceptions. On the one hand there is freedom in the sense of self-determination in any act of the will which is carried through without restraint. Freedom in this sense does not depend on any positive relation between one purpose and another, but might be realized in an isolated act without conscious relation to any other. On the other hand, in the will as a system of purposes there is freedom from any internal check or restraint only if all these purposes are in har- mony. Hegel's account seems to fuse these conceptions, taking control of the partial purpose by the whole to be self-determina- tion and therefore freedom, without postulating harmony as a condition. Now in the conception of a moral order which APPENDIXES 149 is a perfect harmony the freedom of the whole is the gathered fruit of the freedom of each part. In self-determination without harmony there is for the partial manifestations no freedom but subjection, and for the governing will no ideal of freedom but only of order. To speak of the latter conception in terms only applicable to the former is the fallacy that nms through all Hegel's theory of the law and the state. APPENDIX II THE THEORY OF THE ABSOLUTE Dr. Bosanquet's theory of the state is so intimately bound up with his general, theory of Reality, that a discussion of his social philosophy can hardly be complete without some reference to his conception of the Absolute as contained in the two volumes of his Gifford Lectures, to which reference has several times been made in the preceding chapters. Indeed, for him the state seems in a manner to be the medium, it is certainly one of the media, by which the individual comes into contact with the Absolute. The Absolute is sovereign Lord, but the state is its vicegerent here and now. What then is the Absolute and how is it related to our lives ? The Absolute is that in which all contradictions are reconciled. But this definition really includes two characteristics which are perfectly distinct. By contradiction is meant, in the most natural and straightforward sense of the term, logical contra- diction. It is clearly true, but it is also a platitude, to say that logical contradictions caimot exist in reahty. If the Absolute then is an expression for reality as it is in its completeness, it is certain that within it there can be no contradictions. Whether we should say on this point that within it contradictions are reconciled is not so certain. Contradictions really exist in the world of partial knowledge, and it would be truer to say that they must necessarily be reconcUed, that is, resolved away, in complete knowledge, while in reahty they cannot really exist. However, to let this verbal point pass, it is clear that in the Absolute all elements of reality which as partially or separately known to us are imperfectly understood, and thus give rise to apparent contradictions, are so related by underlying principles of connection as to constitute a consistent whole. All this is httle more than platitude, put it as we may. But there is a second meaning of contradiction — practical J 50 APPENDIXES 151 contradiction, conflict, opposition, under which, in general, pain, misery, evil and destruction may be grouped. That there exists any being, call it what we will, in which aU such conflicts are reconciled, is a much more doubtful proposition. It can by no means be regarded as a postulate of thought, as the first proposition may be, and I suspect that its plausibility depends upon an unconscious transition from the first meaning to the second. That contradiction in this second sense may be somehow reconciled in undoubtedly the aspiration of the reUgious consciousness, but its realization is not a fundamental postulate of philosophy. What has here to be asked, however, is whether Bosanquet's Absolute does in fact provide any such reconcilia- tion ; and if so, at what cost to our moral and reUgious ideas ? Bosanquet's view is that the Absolute is perfection and that aJI the content of our experience, whether we call it good, bad or indifferent, would be found, if we had full knowledge, to play its necessary part in this perfect scheme. What we have to ask is in what way evil, pain and conflict and destruction can have a part to play in a perfect scheme. One answer would be that these things are necessary incidents of a process in which some life is evolved or some plan being worked out so good and glorious that if we could understand it all, we should deem it worth the cost. This conclusion, however, is expressly barred by Bosanquet, who refuses to conceive the Absolute as the realization of a purpose. In point of fact, the conception of purpose is only applicable if we think of it as operating upon material which is given to it, or at least under conditions by which it is so limited as to make the suffering and destruction necessary to the completeness of its work. At bottom this is why Bosanquet rejects the conception of purpose. It cannot characterize the whole. But he does not seem to consider the alternative that the whole might be something in which the element of purpose is that which we really value, so that the ultimate success of this purpose would reconcile us to the cost. Rejecting purpose, we have to be satisfied with a world which is not going to be any better than the world of our experience but is of one tissue with it, only complete. We might perhaps value such a world if we could think of it, for example, as a kind of living organism, as an organic unity. But the charac- teristic of an organic unity is that it maintains the parts by which it is constituted. Thus, if there is destruction and pain within the organism, it is either because the organism is acted upon by foreign bodies or because it is in some way imperfect. The 152 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE universe is not acted upon from without, and if organic at all, must be imperfectly so. But the difBcuities that arise here are not relevant, for Dr. Bosanquet's Absolute is the very reverse of organic in its conception, being quite indifferent to the permanent welfare of the units, spiritual beings, selves, which go to make it up. The Ufe of any one of them may end in disruption and despair, and yet reconciliation is supposed to be found in the Absolute. The Absolute thus presented is something utterly inhuman, without bowels of compassion. It is below the moral categories, as everything that pretends to be above them invariably is. But if the Absolute is neither purpose nor an organism, what is it ? Bosanquet answers that it is perfection. It is not good and it is not evil strictly, for we judge things good or bad by reference to the perfection of the whole. Can this perfection give us any reconciliation ? The answer is that it may reconcile logical contradictions, but for that we need no conception of perfection but simply of reality, or, to phrase it better, of reality thoroughly understood ; but that there is only one way in which conflict, pain, evil and ills can be said to be reconciled either with one another or with any scheme or order to which our emotions and admiration and satisfaction can attach themselves, and that is by showing that they are necessary steps in the fulfilment of some purpose which we regard as fully adequate to the heavy cost which they represent. If reconciliation means anj^hing other than this, the meaning should be specified. There is no suggestion that it means anjrthing else except the over- coming of contradictions, which has been shown is a different concept not to be surreptitiously identified with the ideal in question. Certain passages in Bosanquet suggest a possible line of reply approaching more nearly to the ordinary ethical and religious view of reconciliation. An evil, it may be said, is transformed into something which is not evil and perhaps even good by the way in which we take it, by our fortitude, by our resignation, by our accepting it as the burden which we must bear for others, and so on. Now, it is true that by our attitude an evil may be modified and in some respect turned to a good account ; but, though modified, the evil is not cancelled. If the sufferer does not resent it for himself, we resent it and are right to resent it for him. The finer his attitude, the stronger should ]be its appeal to us onlookers as a flagrant wrong wbicb APPENDIXES 153 man, or nature, or an Absolute, if you will, has imposed on a being who is showing himself worthy of better things. In the individual sufferer who uses his suffering nobly there is reconciliation, but it is precisely not in the Absolute that this reconciliation is achieved. It is in reality as a whole that the wrong remains, and so far as it is overcome it is the work of the human spirit operating in reality. Lastly, if we really need pain and evil as a substratum for our good, then it may be true that the most we can do is to maintain a life of struggle. This cannot be attributed to the perfection of the Absolute, but to a deep-seated dissonance in the structure of things, which not only is not, but on this principle never could be reconciled. It must be added that if, as Bosanquet appears to maintain, effort cannot ever fundamentally improve this situation, then effort is fundamentally hopeless and discord is absolute. If, on the other hand, effort can make an improve- ment, then, though the discord is there, it is capable of mitigation and it becomes conceivable that through effort, conscious and active beings may achieve a hfe worth the pain and travail. It is in the notion of such a life, either here or hereafter, either for .others or for- ourselves, that every one who has not argued about the issue, but felt it, looks for that which may repay the terrible cost of human suffering. INDEX Absolute, 17, 18, 19, 20, 24, 116 Theory of the, 150, 151, 152, 153 Alexander, Professor, 53 AiistotJe, 60, 73 Body, S3 Bosanqnet, Dr., 18, 19, 21, 22, 37, 38, 40, 41, 42, 43, 44, 45, 46, 47, so, SI. 53. 54. 55. 56. 57. 58. 59. 60, 61, 69, 70, 73, 74, 7S, 76, 77. 78. 79. 80, 81, 82, 83, 84, 85, 86, 94, 102, 103, 104, los, 106, 107, 108, 109, no. III, 112, 113, 114, IIS, 116, 120, 123, 150, 151, 152, IS3 Philosophical Theory of the State, 22, 40, so, 56, 74, 94 Principle of Individuality and Value, 19. 69, 79, 82 Social and International Ideals, 21, 59, 94, 106, 120 Bridges, J. H., IIS Church, the, 88, 89, 90 Clark, Hr. WiXUam, 24 Common Aim, 123 Common Good, 123 Comtists, IIS, 11^ Cynics, 72 Ethics, II, 46 Force, 74, 77, 122 Freedom, 26, 31, 32, 33, 34, 3s, 36, 37 .39. 40, 59. 60, 139, 141, 145, 147. 148 Moral, 43 Gravity, 138 Green, T. H., 24, 83, 96, 99, 118, 119 120, 121, 122, 123, 124, 125 Principles of Political Obligations, 116 Goethe, 98 Harmony, 36, 46, 47. 143 Hegel, 17, 18, 20, 21, 23, 24, 31, 32, 33, 34. 35. 36. 37. 38. 39, 40, 56. 62, 64, 65, 68, 69, 79, 87, 88, 9S, 96. 97. 98, 99. 100, loi, 102, 103, 118, 134, 138, 139, 140, 141, 142, 143, 144, 147. 148, 149 Philosophy of History, 17, 20 Philosophic des Rechts, 20, 23, 24, 38. 79. 87. 96 Hegel's Theory of the Will, 38, 138 Hbfiding, Professor, 15 Humanity, 115, 116 Hume, 63 Ideals and Facts, 14, 18 Idealistic Social Philosophy, 41 Individual, si, 66, 67 Kant, 100, loi Law, 26, 32, 38, 92, 114, 149 League of Nations, The, 25, 106, 107, 116 liycopbron, 60 Marx, Earl, 24 Uazzlni, 106 Metaphysical Theory of the State, the, 18, 21, 73, 76, 117, 118, 122, 130 UiU, 42 ?55 156 THE METAPHYSICAL THEORY OF THE STATE Mind, 53 Finite, 82 Moral Philosophy, 11 Aloraliliit, 38 Morals in Evolution, 23 Nietzsche, 131 Newton, 69 Organization, 75, 76, 78, 96, III, II2, "3 Plato, 72, 73 Power, 134 Reality, Theory of, 150 Recht, 38, 6r RouBseau, 40, 41, 42, 74, 80 Self, 41 Common, 13, 41,43, 97, 99> 132. I33 Determination, 33, 35, 38, 39, 40, 41, 146, 147, 148, 149 the Real, 43, 48 Sittlichkeit, 38, 88, 98, 113 Social Investigation, 1 1 Philosophy, 12 Science, 12, 15, 16 Theory, 12, 17 Society, 76, 81, 82, 83, 102, 103, 118 Spirit, the, 18, 24 SUte, the, 18, 21, 33, 43, 56, 59, 60, 71, 72. 73, 74, 75, 76, 77, 78, 79, 82, 86, 88, 8g, 90, 93, 94, 95, 96, 97, 100, loi, 102, 103, 104, 105, 106, 107, 108, 109, no, III, 112, 113, IIS, 118, T19, 120, 121, 122, 130, 131, 134, 136, 149, ijo Stoics, 72, 114 Theory of the State, the, 135 Treitschke, 103, 134 Universal, 62, 63, 64, 65, 66, 68, 69, 76, 96, 122, 141 Will, 32, 33, 34,35, 42, 47, 79, 81, 108, 124, 138, 139, 140, 141, 142, 144, 14s, 146, 147, 148 Actual, 42, 44, 118 Common, 123 Free, 32, 139, 143, 144, 146, I47, 148 General, 32, 40, 42, 43, 46, 49, 50, 59, 71, 80, 82, 85, 99, 107, n8, 121, 122, 123, 124, 126, 132 Hegelian Theory of, 42, 46, 49, 50, 59, 71, 80, 82, 85, 99, 107, "8, 121, 122, 123, 124, 126, 132 Individual, 79 Particular, 139 Real, 41, 42, 43, 44, 45, 46, 47, 48, SO, 56, 68, 71, 80, 84, 85, 86, 118 of the State, the, 71 Universal, 68 Willkiir, 98, 140, 148 BERTRAND RUSSELL AUTHORITY AND THE INDIVIDUAL Cr. ivo. 6s. net 'An exceptional lucidity of mind combined with clarity and grace of expression, make these six lectures a notable contribution to a subject perhaps more important than any other today.' Daily Telegraph 'Russell is as incapable of being dull as he is of being shallow.' The Observer THE PRINCIPLES OF MATHEMATICS Sm. Royal 8vo. Fifth Impression, Second Edition 21s.net The Principles of Mathematics, first published in 1903, sets forth, as far as possible without mathematical or logic symbolism, the grounds in favour of the view that mathematics and logic are identical, what is commonly called mathematics being merely later deductions from logical premisses. The detailed proof of this thesis was subsequently given by Professor Whitehead and the present author in Principia Mathematica; in the 'Principles' it is defended against such advance philosophical opinions as were at that time current. It has since been attacked, and in a new Preface the author defends his thesis against adverse opinions. A CRITICAL EXPOSITION OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF LEIBNIZ Demy ivo. Third Impression, Second Edition iZs.net Leibniz's importance as a philosopher has become more evident owing to the growth of mathematical logic and the discovery of his manuscripts on this and kindred subjects. 'A work of much brilliance . . . which is still, in its new edition, as in that of 1900, indispensable to the English student.' Record 'Masterly monography.' Nature THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL JUSTICE by L. T. HOBHOUSE 'Demy Svo. Third Impression izs. 6d. net 'The light that streams into darkness from Dr. Hobhouse's study window is clear, bright and steady ... A remarkably able book.' The Times 'He combines profound penetration with wide range and catholic S}rmpathies. Unlike so many philosophical books, this one is written in English that is good to read.' Manchester Guardian 'Profoundly interesting . . . possesses the high quality of truthfulness and scientific good faith." Westminster Gazette THE SOCIAL SCIENCE SERIES Titles recently reprinted: Rousseau: THE SOCIAL CONTRACT OR PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL RIGHT Translated with Introductions and Notes by HENRY J. TOZER Cr. 8vo. 6s. net Godwin: POLITICAL JUSTICE A Reprint of the Essay on Property Cr. Svo. 6s. net Engels: THE CONDITION OF THE WORKING CLASSES IN ENGLAND IN 1844 With a Preface written in 1892 Cr. &vo. is. 6d. net Engels: SOCIALISM— UTOPIAN AND SCIENTIFIC Translated by Edward Aveling Cr. Svo. 6s. net HAROLD J. LASKI TRADE UNIONS IN THE NEW SOCIETY Demy 8vo. ,oj. ^^ Harold J. Laski was one of the most important political philosophers of our time. The ideas expressed in his books, from A Grammar of Politics to his great work on the American way of life, The American Democracy, have had a profound influence on Socialist thinking. All his life he was a close observer of the growing power and place of organized labour. In this book he examines the changes that have occurred in the status of trade lAions and the place they occupy in the present democratic world. He contrasts their function in a capitalist or socialist country with what it has become under Russian totalitarianism. THE AMERICAN DEMOCRACY Royal 8110. 2SS. net 'A profound analysis of the American scene. With his usual aplomb Professor Laski tackles nearly all the main facets of American life- politics, the commercial world, the professional and labouring classes, religion, education, culture, press, films and the radio.' News Chronicle LIBERTY IN THE MODERN STATE Cr. 8vo. Third Edition 8s. 6d. net A new and welcome edition of an important work that has long been unobtainable. This volume has particular relevance at the present time, when the concept of liberty, though fought for in the greatest of all wars, is in danger of being submerged in the chaos of the present world situation. GEORGE ALLEN AND UNWIN LTD GEORGE ALLEN & UNWIN LTD London: 40 Museum Stkekt, W.C.i Cape Town: 58—60 Long Street Sydney, N.S.W. : 55 Yoke Street Toronto: 91 Wellington Street West Calcutta: 17 Central Ate., P.O. Dharamtala Bombay: 15 Graham Road, Ballard Estate Wellington, N.Z. : 8 Kings Crescent, Lower hutt