.iiinuiiitnimn)iiinim!uiiiiuiiii(imiin»ll|llllllllHl|l|lll|lll|lllilll!liiiin BOUGHT WITH TH-E INCOME FROM THE • ■ ' SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF lienrs W. Sage 1891 ^A^^-y^~:.. 6896-1 SiUZ ' i Date Ehie JUL g 8 VMT mr MAY . 61! ) A8 B . MAYliimsJt :rr^ ^jratsaasai^jr ^. Cornell University Library The original of tliis bool< is in tlie Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924029019417 Cornell University Library B832 .P91 What is..Bra9ma«sm,?,B);,,,S,t;„Smi ''' 3 1924 029 019 417 olin WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? Bv THE Same Author "THE PSYCHOLOGY OF RELIGIOUS BELIEF'* New York. The Macmillan Company. 1907 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? BY JAMES BISSETT PRATT, Ph.D. ASSISTANT PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN WILLIAMS COLLEGE NjiD gorfs THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 1909 All rights reserved H> 'Ho Copyright, 1909, By the MACMILLAN COMPANY. Set up and electrotyped. Published February, 1909. Reprinted June, 1909. J. 8. Gushing Co. — Berwick & Smith Co. Norwood, Mass., U.S.A. JOHN EDWARD RUSSELL THE KEENEST AND KINDLIEST CRITIC OF PRAGMATISM * THIS BOOK IS INSCRIBED IN GRATEFUL AND SINCERE AFFECTION PREFACE During the spring of 1908 I received an invitation from Mr. Stephen F, Weston to give a course of six lectures the following summer at the Glenmore Summer School, and to choose my own subject. Unfortu- nately for the school, as it turned out, I decided to make use of the opportunity to say certain things about pragmatism that had long been stirring in my soul; and " Pragmatism, A Critique," was, accordingly, advertised in the circular of the school as the subject of my lectures. I say my choice was unfortunate for the school, for when, after a twenty-mile drive into the heart of the Adirondacks, I reached Glenmore, I found that the patrons of the school had to a man (and almost to a woman) postponed their arrival to the following week, and it looked as if Mr. Weston and myself would Vlll PREFACE constitute the bulk of the audience. By the help of the neighbors, however, we managed to corral several philosophers who were known to be at large in the mountains, and several lovers of philosophy, who by their kindly interest and helpful suggestions more than made up for the paucity of their num- bers. The purpose of the publication of this book is, therefore, to show those who did not go to Glenmore last summer (and this in- cludes a fairly large portion of the human race) how much they missed. The criticisms of my friends at Glenmore proved decidedly valuable, and the following pages have, therefore, been somewhat recast since I gave the lectures; yet it has seemed advisable to retain the lecture form as best adapted to somewhat popular and informal exposition. For though I have nowhere allowed the desire for simplicity and popu- larity to interfere with thoroughness of treat- ment, and though I have used technical language where exactness demanded it, my aim has been throughout to give an exposi- PREFACE IX tion and critique of pragmatism which the general reader could follow without too much effort. I cannot flatter myself that he will always find the following pages inter- esting or easy, but if he really cares to know about pragmatism and hence comes armed with patience, he will, I hope, find them clear. Although the controversy over pragma- tism has now been waging for several years, and although the non-pragmatists have been quite as numerous and as active as their opponents, their contributions to the dis- cussion have been confined almost entirely to the technical periodicals, whereas the pragmatist side has been presented to the public in three or four books which have commanded a fairly wide reading. Of course the " public " never reads the technical periodicals, and there is, therefore, a place for a book which (while not presupposing any prior knowledge of the subject) shall present, with some attempt at comprehensiveness and unity, the position of those who find them- X PREFACE selves unable to accept the pragmatist view. Two such books have appeared in France, but there is as yet (so far as I am aware) no book in English which has this aim. It is, of course, with this aim that I have written the following pages. It would be disingenuous in me should I not frankly declare war on pragmatism even in my preface. But I hope my readers will do me the justice to believe me when I say that to criticise pragmatism has been only my secondary object, my chief aim being to understand it and to help others to do so. When the movement first began I was an enthusiastic pragmatist, and my enthusiasm lasted until I came to understand clearly what it really meant. And though I am no longer one of its supporters, its charm is still so strong upon me that L am eager to see it completely developed and carefully expressed, and the good seed which indu- bitably is in it threshed out and separated from the immense amount of chaff which bears its name. Threshing only can save PREFACE XI whatever of value there is in it ; and I hope my pragmatist friends will at least see in my book a sincere attempt to aid them in our common task of "making our ideas clear." My thanks are due to the editors of the Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Sci- entific Methods, for their courtesy in permit- ting me to make use (in Lectures II and III) of material taken from two articles of mine which appeared in their Journal during the years 1907 and 1908. And most of all I wish to acknowledge with sincere gratitude the invaluable and unfailing assistance, ad- vice, and guidance which I have received from Professor John E. Russell of Williams College. It was at first his intention to collaborate with me upon a book of this nature, but lack of time prevented him from carrying out his part of the plan, — to the very considerable loss of the many who would have read this book had he been its principal author. But the loss has not been absolute ; for those of my readers who have Xll PREFACE followed the controversy over pragmatism will recognize that very much of what is best in this book is due to him. WiiiiAMSTOwN, Mass., Febiuaiy i, 1909. CONTENTS LECTURE I PAGE Meaning and Method in Pragmatism . . . i LECTURE II The Ambiguity of Truth 47 LECTURE III The Pragmatic View of the Truth Relation . 81 LECTURE IV Pragmatism and Knowledge 133 LECTURE V Pragmatism and Religion 173 LECTURE VI The "Practical" Point of View . . . .211 Index 255 LECTURE I MEANING AND METHOD IN PRAGMATISM WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? LECTURE I MEANING AND METHOD IN PRAGMATISM I REMEMBER once hearing a professor of " Real Property " in one of our leading law schools discuss very learnedly and at con- siderable length the question whether any one in the United States really owned any land. To put it in the professor's words, the question was (if I remember aright) whether the title to land was ever actually vested in the individual or whether he was merely an occupant, the real owner being the state. On the one hand, the professor pointed out, the individual could do what he liked with his land, could deed it to whom he pleased and dispose of it in any way that suited him. But, on the other hand, there was the power of eminent domain, the right 3 4 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? of the state to condemn the land and take it from him, for a suitable consideration, at any- time. This being the case, in whom is the ownership really vested? The conclusion to which most of us came, as I remember it, was that this was one of the mysteries of the law which the mind of man could never fathom. Doubtless the land belonged to some one ; in fact, it very obviously belonged either to the individual or to the state. But to which of these it really belonged was a question which could probably never be answered. Now if there had been among us at the time a pragmatist philosopher, he would prob- ably have addressed us in some such words as these : " My friends," he would have said, "your difficulty is all of your own making. You think you are puzzling over a very deep problem ; but there is really no problem here to puzzle over. What you take for depth is in fact only the muddiness of your own thought. For consider: What you want to know is in whom the ownership of MEANING AND METHOD 5 the land is vested. That being the case, your first question should be, What do we mean by ownership? And the answer to this is simple enough; namely, the right to do this, that, and the other with the object owned. Enumerate all the things that can be done with land ; then the right to do just these things is ownership. And once you have enumerated these rights, you have ex- hausted the meaning of the term. If owner- ship means anything more than this, what is it? You cannot say. Except in the con- crete and practical sense I have defined, '^ ownerships means just nothing at all, — it is a mere term without content. Of course, one's ownership may be more or less limited, according as one has the right to do fewer or more things with the object one 'owns.' Hence, to return to your particular question, the individual owns the land in the sense of being able to dig in it, build on it, sell it, or give it away, etc.; and the state owns it in the sense of being able to take it from the individual if it desires. And so your ques- 6 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? tion answers itself. In short, your insoluble mystery is merely gratuitous mystification of your own making. It seems a mystery only because it is meaningless." I have used this illustration, drawn from a field at some distance from philosophy, to show how the pragmatist may often succeed in solving our problems for us by simply demonstrating to us that they are no problems at all. Don't seek to solve a question, says pragmatism, until you know what you mean by it. Think so far as possible in concrete terms. Never let your- self be hoodwinked and browbeaten by big words and verbal abstractions. Remember that the meaning of philosophical terms may often be in inverse proportion to their length. Words are but pragmatists' counters; they do but reckon with them; but they are the money of non-pragmatists. Concerning every object of discussion ask the question : What is it known as ? What does it mean to me? For, as G. H. Lewes has said, and as Aristotle said long before MEANING AND METHOD 7 him, a thing is what it does. All that it can ever mean is just the difference that it can make to some one. There is no genuine difference that does not make a difference. Well, every pragmatist will tell you this is pragmatism; and I trust all my hearers are good pragmatists. It goes without say- ing that I am one. Who, indeed, could resist a doctrine so delightfully healthy, clear-cut, simple, and helpful ? It has the salt air of the sea in it and the ozone of the mountains. With this philosophy within one's grasp, who would choose to be bound down in servile submission to verbal abstractions, and to spend one's days discussing problems that have no meaning? Rather let us think clearly and to the point, and sign an intellectual Declaration of Independence from all unmeaning con- cepts. It is not surprising that the new philosophy is advancing victoriously over the land, and that all sorts and conditions of men are joining the procession. In the 8 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? glow of our loyalty we are willing to march against any foe, under our banner, upon whose ample folds we have written, " Away with Logomachy and Meaningless Abstrac- tions ! " But alas ! where is the foe ? Who is it that is championing logomachy and meaning- less abstractions ? If belief in clear thought and the other admirable things named above be pragmatism, are we not all pragmatists? — Indeed, we do not all practice what we preach (not even all the leaders of pragma- tism do that), but who would not give his enthusiastic assent to the laudable doctrines and admonitions set out above ? — And if we are all pragmatists and there be no foe to fight, the rather disconcerting question presents itself why we should make such a fuss about it. Unless pragmatism has something more distinctive and original to offer, is it really anything more than a new and rather superfluous name for some exceedingly old and common ways of think- ing? MEANING AND METHOD 9 Of course pragmatism is more than this, — otherwise it would resemble a Fourth of July oration on " Liberty " in a New England village, or a revival among the sanctified. Pragmatism seeks and claims to be strenuous, militant, — a plan of cam- paign rather than a celebration or an ex- perience meeting. So much of pragmatism as I have described thus far is only its spirit ; but it is in addition to this a definite and technical doctrine or group of doc- trines on certain fundamental philosophical questions. " Pragmatism (according to Mr., James) is a temper of mind, an attitude ; : it is also a theory of the nature of ideas and truth ; and finally it is a theory about reality." ^ More specifically, it may be said that pragmatism offers us a theory of mean- ing, a theory of truth, and a theory of knowledge; that it is trying to work out a theory of reality; and that it is also a general point of view or way of looking » Professor Dewey in " What does Pragmatism mean by Practical ?" Jour, of Phil., Vol. V, p. 85. lO WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? at things, — a way that is in part peculiar to pragmatists, in part adopted by them from a larger tendency or attitude which colors much of contemporary thought. I shall take up each of these things in turn in the following lectures, beginning to-day with a consideration of the pragma- tist doctrine of the nature of meaning and of the method of dealing with philosophical problems which pragmatism naturally de- duces from that doctrine. " Meaning " and " method " are, I confess, not intrinsically interesting subjects. I wish I had something more attractive to offer you, but it really is not my fault. I might, of course, give you just a general " point of view " which would, perhaps, not be alto- gether without interest; but I mean to do no such thing. I mean to treat the techni- cal doctrines of pragmatism in as exact a fashion as I can — any other treatment of them I should consider an insult to my audi- ence. Pragmatism has been defined by its founder as a way "to make our ideas clear"; MEANING AND METHOD II hence its doctrines must themselves certainly be clear and capable of exact formulation. We should not be satisfied — and so far as we are good pragmatists we cannot be sat- isfied — with any loose definitions and any vague tendencies and generalities. So long as we allow ourselves to be soothed and satisfied by them we shall be very far from making our ideas clear. We must there- fore do pragmatism the justice to take it seriously, to sift the formulations of it given by the leading pragmatists, and not to rest satisfied till we see exactly what they mean. Such a thorough-going examination of prag- matic meaning and method may seem to some of you at times dry, difficult, and per- haps over-technical. But if you are really consistent, sincere, and honest pragmatists at heart, you will not hesitate at any diffi- culty in the effort to make your ideas clear and to free yourselves from the power of mere words and phrases. Those, on the^ other hand, who are pragmatists in name only I am sure will stay behind, content with 12 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? " words " and " tendencies," and will continue to throw their caps in air, shouting, " Hurrah for Pragmatism ! " without being over-curious as to what it really is, or why they should make such a noise about it. Pragmatism may be regarded as the result of two confluent, though not altogether con- sistent, streams of tendency. The first, and i probably the less influential, of these may be ! traced back as far as Kant's doctrine of the I primacy of the practical reason. We cannot, said Kant, prove the reality of God, freedom, immortality, and the moral law. But since we are volitional, active, rational beings we have both the right and the duty to postulate the reality of these things and whatever else may be essential to moral action. It is in- deed possible that we are not free; but we are bound to act as if we were free, and since freedom is essential to morality, it is our duty to believe in it. Practically this same brave moral doctrine was revived and reformulated in 1896 by Professor James's "Will to Believe," — a MEANING AND METHOD 1 3 book that has stirred America as have few philosophic works of our generation. In the first essay of the volume (which gave its title to the whole) Professor James points out that faith is itself a force and often makes real its own object ; and that when we are faced with genuinely possible alternatives we have a right to accept and believe that one whose acceptance will contribute most to our moral life. Here and elsewhere, moreover, James shows that in morality and metaphysics and religion, as well as in science, we are justi- fied in testing the truth of a belief by its usefulness. The second and probably the more im- portant source of pragmatism is the modern scientific view of the meaning of h)^otheses. Hypotheses, " natural laws," scientific gener- alizations, etc., are, as most scientists now maintain, merely short-hand expressions of human experience. They are handy ways of telling us what has happened or what we may expect. They are not so much de- scriptions of an outer and independent " na- 14 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? ture " as ways of summarizing and explaining our experience. Their whole meaning is ex- hausted after they have told us (directly or indirectly) how things act upon us and how we react upon things. That I may be sure not to misrepresent the modern logic of science as pragmatism understands it, let me make use of a sentence from Ostwald, quoted with approval by Professor James in his recent book. " All realities influence our practice, and that influence is their meaning for us. I am accustomed to put questions to my classes in this way: In what respects would the world be different if this alternative or that were true.? If I can find nothing that would be- come different, then the alternative has no sense." ^ In a somewhat similar spirit Karl Pear- son defines a law of science (or of " nature ") as "a resume in mental shorthand, which replaces for us a lengthy description of the sequences among our sense impressions." * 1 Quoted by James in " Pragmatism," p. 48. ' " Grammar of Science," p. 87. MEANING AND METHOD 1 5 The scientist, in short, sees that his hypoth- ; eses and laws ultimately get all their mean- ing from our experience. And, moreover, he no longer regards them purely as ends in themselves; rather are they now his instru- ments by the use of which human action may profitably be guided. Hence he is less con- cerned than were his predecessors with the ; question whether his hypotheses are true; what concerns him most is their usefulness.'. His great question concerning any proposed generalization is, Does it work? And this; for two reasons: in the first place, because its working is practically more important to him than its merely theoretical truth; and secondly, because the only test he has for its truth is its successful working. Unless it works, he has no reason to believe it true. Moreover, as truth and usefulness are both forms of value, the scientist who has no time nor fondness for what he calls "logic chop- ping" has a tendency to. identify the two, without asking himself too curiously whether his hypothesis is true because it is useful or useful because it is true. 1 6 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? It was from this view of the nature of scientific hypotheses that pragmatism, in the 'more technical sense, took its rise. The name originated with Mr. C. S. Pierce, who in 1878 pubHshed his epoch-making article (for so it turned out to be) entitled " How to make our Ideas Clear." ^ In this paper Mr. Pierce laid down the thesis that the whole meaning of any object consists in the habit or reaction it establishes or induces (directly or indirectly) in us. " Consider what effects which might conceivably have practical bear- ings we consider the object of our concep- tion to have. Then our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object.'"* The word "practical" Mr. Pierce is here using in its strict and etymological sense, as referring to action.* Thus we are told that to develop the meaning of a thought " we have simply to determine what habit it induces, for what a thing means is simply what habit it involves." * " There is 1 In the Popular Science Monthly, Vol. XII, pp. 286-302. ' p. 293. ' From the Greek irpSyfia, action. * p. 292. MEANING AND METHOD 1 7 no distinction of meaning so fine as to con- sist in anything but a possible difference of practice."^ Quite in line with this view of the practical nature of meaning is Professor Dewey's use of the word idea as synonymous with " plan of action " or " intention to act in a certain way." * Now the assertion (if intended to be taken literally) that all distinction of meaning con- sists in a possible difference of practice cannot be allowed to go unchallenged. It may be true that most concepts and beliefs — or, if you insist, that all concepts and beliefs — result ultimately in action. From that it does not follow that all their meaning con- sists in such resulting action. Doubtless much of their meaning does consist in that. — My concept of an object is largely made up of the way I should act in its presence. As Royce has well said, I do not know the meaning of "//o»" if I think it an animal I might pat on the head, saying, " Nice little 1 p. 293. s Cf., for instance, Mind, Vol. XVI, pp. 335-336, and Jour, of Phil, Vol. V, p. 88, etc. l8 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? lion." — But though this is true, there re- mains always in our concepts and beliefs a group of characteristics which are not to be reduced to any reactions or habits of our own. These may be of as many sorts as there are kinds of experience or psychic states in addition to action. Sensational and emotional facts are of course the most obvi- ous. The distinction between a red house and a green house does not consist in a. dif- ference of practice. Even granted there is a difference in practice or "attitude" resulting, that would not constitute the whole of the dis- tinction. " Practice " surely cannot be taken to mean the whole of experience. (If it were so taken, Mr. Pierce's expressions about it would become the most absurdly obvious truisms.) But if it be not the whole of experi- ence, there is no good reason for insisting that it is the only type of experience which contrib- utes anything toward the meaning of ideas. This point is so obvious that I surely need not labor it further. And I am made still more confident that I may be relieved of this MEANING AND METHOD 19 ungrateful task by the fact that Professor James long ago saw this weakness in Mr. Pierce's formulation of pragmatism, and therefore " transmogrified " it (as Pierce puts it) and laid the foundations of his own pragmatism in more inclusive terms. In his famous California Address of Au- gust 26, 1898, — which we might almost call the birthday of pragmatism, — he says : — " I think myself that it [the principle of pragmatism] should be expressed more broadly than Mr. Pierce expresses it. . . . I should prefer to express Pierce's principle iby saying that the effective meaning of \any philosophic proposition can always be jbrought down to some particular conse- ^quence in our future practical experience, whether active or passive; the point lying rather in the fact that the experience must be particular than in the fact that it must be active." ^ This interpretation of the term practical as meaning concrete and particular rather than as referring to action, Pro- ^Jour. of Phil., Vol. I, p. 674. Italics mine. 20 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? fessor James has consistently maintained ever since/ Taking this modified and enlarged state- ment of the pragmatic view of meaning, let us try to see exactly what it amounts to. As I understand it, pragmatism aims by it to do two things. First, it seeks to give us a definite, exact, and technical doctrine of the nature of meaning — to show us what meaning consists in and, therefore, when it is present and when absent. And, sec- ondly, by means of this doctrine, it aims to formulate for us a method of choosing our problems, which shall eliminate for us a number of meaningless questions and help us to see what is worth discussing and what is not. With these aims in view, let us now examine some of the more carefully worded statements of the pragmatic doctrine. In Baldwin's " Dictionary of Philosophy," Professor James defines pragmatism as ^ Cf. his definition of pragmatism in Baldwin's Dictionary and his artide, " The Pragmatic Account of Truth," in the Phil. Rev. for January, 1908, especially p. 14. Also " Prag- matism," Lecture II, passim. MEANING AND METHOD 21 "the doctrine that the whole 'meaning' of a conception expresses itself in practical consequences, consequences either in the shape of conduct to be recommended or in that of experiences to be expected, if the conception be true ; which conse- quences would be different if it were untrue, and must be different from the consequences by which the meaning of other conceptions is in turn expressed. If a second conception should not appear to have other consequences, then it must really be only the first conception under a different name." The fundamental postulate of " imme- diate empiricism " (a pseudonym for prag- matism) is, according to Professor Dewey, just this : " that things are what they are experienced as being; or that to give a just account of anything is to tell what that thing is experienced to be." " The real significance of this principle is that of a method of philosophical analysis. If you wish to find out what any philosophic term 22 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? means, go to experience and see what it is experienced as'' ^ In the same spirit Papini writes : " The meaning of theories consists uniquely in the consequences which those who believe them true may expect from them." * Dr. Schiller puts it thus : " To say that a truth has consequences and that what has none is meaningless, means that it has a bearing -upon some human interest. Its 'conse- quences ' must be consequences to some one for some purpose. If it is clearly grasped that the 'truth' with which we are concerned is truth for man and that the 'consequences' are human too, it is really superfluous to add either that the consequences must be practical or that they must be good."^ Owing to a misunderstanding of some of the pragmatists' statements, they have J " The Postulate of Immediate Empiricism," Jour, of Phil., Vol. II, pp. 397 and 399. ' " Introduzione a] Pragmatismo," Leonardo, February, 1907, p. 28. » "Studies in Humanism," p. j. MEANING AND METHOD 23 been accused of including among the ' consequences ' that give meaning only such as are practical in the ordinary sense of the word, — bread and butter con- sequences one might call them. Put in this bald and sweeping way, this criticism is based on a radical misunderstanding of pragmatism. All the leading pragmatists insist that among these ' practical conse- quences ' they include such things as logical consistency, intellectual satisfaction, harmony of mental content, etc. James has more than once made the statement that to him practical means simply par- ticular or concrete;'^ and Schiller has fre- quently pointed out that what are commonly called theoretical consequences are prac- tical in his broad use of the word, and that, in fact, " all consequences are prac- tical sooner or later." ^ If all consequences are practical sooner or later, it is at first, indeed, a little hard to see why so much 1 a. Jour, of Phil., Vol. I, p. 674; Phil. Rev., Vol. XVII, pp. 14 and I J. ^ " Studies in Humanism," p. 6. 24 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? emphasis should be laid upon their being practical, or why so much ado should be made over the word; it would seem to be something like a distinction without a dif- ference, rather useless as a guide or tool, and hence most unpragmatic. Moreover, there are passages in which the pragmatists seem to forget their own broad use of the word practical, and to condemn certain " intellectualistic " questions as unworthy of discussion because far removed from our "practical" needs. And it must also be added that while the pragmatists usually recognize the value of our theoretical in- terests, they insist that in the last analysis this value is entirely dependent on the " practical " in the narrower sense of the term, — that our intellectual activities get all their worth ultimately from the fact that they guide and influence the reaction of the individual upon the environment. This is what Dr. Schiller really has in mind when he says, "all consequences are ,,^/practical sooner or later." It would seem, MEANING AND METHOD 25 therefore, that the " bread and butter " criti- cism is not altogether without foundation. Of this, however, I hope to have more to say at another time. For the present the impor-i tant thing for us to note is the fact that prag matism is not justly open to the charge of completely disregarding our theoretic! interests, — no matter how it may, later on, interpret them. And now let us come to closer quarters with the pragmatic doctrine of meaning. There are one or two points in it which have never been clear to me, and which, so far as I am aware, no pragmatist writer has attempted to clear up. As these points are vital to our problem, I must have more light on them before I know whether I am a prag- matist or not. So let us return for a moment to our definitions. I repeat: According to Professor James, "the meaning of any phil- osophical proposition can always be brought down to some particular consequence in our future practical experience." According to Dr. Schiller, the "consequences" must 26 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? be " consequences to some onc,/or some pur- pose." Now I ask (and it is an important question), What does James mean by "our experience " ? To whom does Schiller refer by the words " some one " ? Obviously there are three possible interpretations. The prag- matist may mean, namely, that only that con- cept or theory has meaning which makes a ("practical") difference (i) to me, the individ- ual, or (2) to all human beings of all times, or (3) to all actual or possible rational or senti- ent beings. If the pragmatist theory is to be of any help to us whatever, we must know which of these three positions it takes. In the lack, therefore, of any authoritative statements on this subject from the pragmatists, let us examine each of these possible positions in turn for ourselves. The first position suggested above may, I suppose, be dismissed at once. It is most unlikely that any pragmatist will hold that only that has any meaning which has con- sequences in the shape of conduct or experi- ences in his own individual life and -mind. MEANING AND METHOD 27 For even if one should hold so preposterous a position, he could scarcely give it out seri- ously as a philosophic method. The ques- tion whether there will be a railway to the north pole five hundred years hence can cer- tainly not be expressed in consequences to me as an individual, " either in the shape of conduct to be recommended or in that of experiences to be expected." And yet the question certainly has meaning, because its consequences may be expressed in the con- duct or experience of some one else. For the same reason various questions of ancient history have meaning, even for me. Nor can we logically stop short of the whole human race, in interpreting the meaning of " some one." But what justification have we for stop- ping here .'' How can we logically disregard the real or possible experiences or any real or possible sentient beings ? Would there be no meaning in saying that an ichthyo- saurus, who perished ages before the birth of the first man, suffered pain or perceived the 28 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? light? Is there now no meaning in Mr. Percival Lowell's assertion that there are sentient and rational beings on Mars ? There is, so far as I can see, not a single detail of any human experience that would in any way be different, whichever side of these ques- tions you should take. And yet the ques- tions certainly have a meaning, and have a meaning to us, because they have conse- quences in the conduct and experiences of real or possible sentient beings ; namely, the ichthyosaurus and the Martians. The consequences which give meaning, therefore, cannot be confined to the human race, but must include all those which occur in the experience of any sentient creatures. If from this, however, we are tempted to con- clude that there is nothing unique or original in the doctrine of the pragmatist, he may remind us that we have as yet failed to note one of its most important characteristics. The " consequences " which, according to pragmatism, alone give meaning are " conse- quences in OMT future practical experience." MEANING AND METHOD 29 It is not past nor present consequences, but "conduct to be recommended" "experiences to be expected',' that count in giving signifi- cance to a proposition. A good deal is made, first and last, in various pragmatic writings, of this conception that it is only in the future consequences that meaning resides, and it will therefore be worth our while tb consider it in some detail. This we can best do by applying it to a concrete example.^ The example I shall choose is the one which appears most often in Professor James's writings* as an illustration of the pragmatist doctrine of meaning. " Imagine," says Professor James, " the entire contents of the world to be once for all irrevocably given. Imagine it to end this very moment, 1 This same emphasis upon the future is implicit (as Pro- fessor Montague has shown) in the pragmatic attempt to make truth only a kind of goodness. ^ It occurs both in the California Address and in " Prag- matism " (from which I here quote it, p. 96), and we would seem, therefore, to be justified in taking it as a typical illustra- tion of pragmatic meaning — provided, of course, that we do not raise against it the criticism forestalled by Professor James himself in his "Pragmatic Account of Truth," Phil. Rev., Vol. XVII, p. 5, note. 30 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? and to have no future ; and then let a theist and a materialist apply their rival explana- tions to its history. The theist shows how a God made it; and the materialist shows, and we will suppose with equal success, how it resulted from blind physical forces. Then let the pragmatist be asked to choose be- tween their theories. How can he apply his test if the world is already completed .? Concepts are things to come back into ex- perience with, things to make us look for differences. But by hypothesis there is to be no more experience, and no possible dif- ferences can be looked for. Both theories have shown all their consequences, and by the hypothesis we are adopting these are identical. The pragmatist must conse- quently say that the two theories, in spite of their different-sounding names, mean ex- actly the same thing, and that the dispute is purely verbal."^ The point of this illustration is, of course, 1 Professor James adds here a parenthetical sentence which, if taken as in any sense limiting or modifying his illus- tration, destroys the entire force of his argument. I have therefore^omitted it. MEANING AND METHOD 31 to show that it is only in y^«/«rtf consequences that genuine meaning can reside. Now, in the first place, it is important to note that, with the pragmatist view, and under the sup- posed conditions, — the end of the world, — any question of past or present fact would necessarily be unmeaning. The theistic- materialistic controversy is not peculiar in this respect. To say at the end of the world, " Professor James wrote the book ' Pragma- tism,' " and to say, " Mr. Bradley wrote it," would mean exactly the same thing, since the consequences are once for all what they are, and no future consequences can be looked for. That this must be true of all questions, no matter how full of meaning they now seem to us, follows necessarily from the very nature of the case, once you admit the prag- matic doctrine. For if all meanings can be brought down to consequences " in our future practical experience," and if, by hy- pothesis, we have no future practical experi- ence, it must follow, as the night the day, that there can no longer be any meaning in anything. 32 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? And it must also be noted that this con- clusion not only will, according to pragma- tism, hold true at the end of the world for all questions, but that, on the same principles, it must also hold true of many questions even now. To take a very commonplace example : suppose three gentlemen discuss- ing after dinner the age of the wine they have been drinking. One of them says that it is three years old, one that it is thirteen. Reasons are given by both, but neither can prove his point to the satisfaction of the other. The dispute is referred to the third gentleman, who happens to be a pragmatist. How can he apply his test, since the wine, having become once for all what it was, has now been drunk, and the bottle is empty? Both theories have shown all their con- sequences, and these are identical. " The pragmatist must consequently say that the two theories, in spite of their different -sound- ing names, mean exactly the same thing," that to say the wine is three years old is only another way of saying it is thirteen years old, MEANING AND METHOD 33 and that the dispute is purely verbal. In like manner, the date of Sargon I, the authorship of the Pentateuch, the question of the Greek tactics at Salanais, all being without future consequences to us, must be for the pragma- tist absolutely meaningless. In short, from history, geology, biology, astronomy, — from every field of human thought, — come ques- tions over which scholars are spending years of research, yet which are certainly even now fully as meaningless as the theistic- materialistic controversy will be at the end of time, and which therefore according to the pragmatist doctrine are purely verbal disputes.^ The response may be made that the hy- potheses and questions just referred to have pragmatic consequences in the sense of fit- ting in more or less well with our otherwise 1 By the above I do not, of course, mean that no pragma- tist has a right to a past fact ; I simply wish to point out that he has no right to one so long as he sticks to his assertion that all meaning is confined to future consequences, and more especially to the interpretation of this assertion exemplified by James's illustration of the end of the world. 34 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? grounded beliefs, and hence producing greater or less mental harmony. But the answer to this is, in the first place, that this can be the case only on condition that these questions and hypotheses already have meaning. Their harmonizing with our other beliefs presup- poses their meaning and does not produce it, — hence their meaning does not consist in these consequences. And in the second place, if this answer of the pragmatist holds of the questions I have suggested, it holds equally well of the materialistic-theistic con- troversy at the end of the world and of every question which rationalistic philosophers are to-day discussing. There is scarcely a ques- tion seriously raised to-day by any school of philosophy so " intellectualistic " that it is lacking in consequences of intellectual har- mony, hence not one which the pragmatist formula, if thus broadly interpreted, would rule out. Pragmatism must choose between the broad and the narrow interpretation of its doctrine. If it chooses the latter, it must MEANING AND METHOD 35 maintain explicitly that only that has mean- ing which (i) has consequences in the expe- rience or conduct of us human beings, or (2) has future consequences for some one, or (3) has both. Some of the expressions used by the pragmatists seem clearly to show that they prefer the narrow interpretation. But, as I think must now be clear to you all, this position is untenable. For, to repeat, (i) that obviously has meaning which has con- sequences to any conceivable sentient crea- ture. Though theism and materialism should have identical consequences for me and for all human beings, they certainly have not for God (whether he be real or hypothetical). It makes a difference to God whether He exists or not, even if this be the last moment of time. And there is no more reason for ruling out God's experience or that of the ichthyosaurus or the Martian, or of Jupiter or Thor, than that of Adam or of Sargon I. Surely I know what I mean when I speak of the experiences of Betsy Prig or Sairey Gamp or even those of the 36 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? doubly mythological Mrs. Harris. Whatever makes a difference to any conceivable sentient creature has at least some meaning. And (2) it is impossible to see why only future consequences should count, and past ones give no meaning. If the pragmatist is unable to get any meaning out of past con- sequences, or out of consequences to sen- tient beings who are not human, that is his misfortune. But as for the rest of us, we know perfectly well what we mean when we say Mars is inhabited, or the birds preceded the mammals, quite aside from any conse- quences, future or past, to human beings. And in like manner, were this the last mo- ment of time we should know perfectly well what we meant by saying, The world is due to an intelligent, self-conscious Being, or. The world is due to the concourse of uncon- scious atoms ; and we should know also that these two meanings were altogether different. It would seem, therefore, that pragmatism is logically forced to adopt only the broadest possible interpretation of its doctrine, an MEANING AND METHOD 37 interpretation which could be expressed as follows: the meaning of any conception ex- presses itself in the past, present, or future conduct or experience of actual or possible sentient creatures. And if this is the prag- matist doctrine, it certainly is sound. But the odd thing about it is that it exhibits pragmatism as (so far forth) nothing but a restatement of idealism. If this be prag- matism, we shall soon find the subjectivists and the pan-psychists joining the procession ; yes, even the prophets of the Absolute will be donning pragmatist colors and learning war no more. The lion shall eat straw like the ox ; and James and Royce, Dewey and Lotze, Schiller and Bradley (!), shall lie down together. Only the radical realists shall be left out of the love feast. I do not want to be understood as seeking a cheap and easy victory over pragmatism, nor as desiring to ridicule it. What I want is genuinely to understand it. And I seri- ously contend that pragmatism either must take the untenable position of denying 38 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? meaning where meaning obviously is, or else must admit that there is nothing unique in its doctrine. It either stands for an absurd- ity or else, so far as I can see, it has contrib- uted nothing of importance to the problem in question and has merely repeated the gen- eral view of idealism, which it might almost as well have quoted (in somewhat different words, to be sure, but in substance and with- out all this ado) from any one of several passages in "Appearance and Reality." What shall we say, then, to these things ? Is Bradley also among the pragmatists ? If any pragmatist or pragmatist proselyte has consented to follow me thus far, he will probably say at this point. At least pragma- tism offers a practical and useful method for determining what philosophic questions are really worth discussing, and by application of this method we shall be enabled to elimi- nate a large body of worthless and abstract problems which are now lumbering up our minds to no useful purpose. This method, he would probably continue, might be summed MEANING AND METHOD 39 up in the rule never to discuss anything unless it has some genuine human interest, unless it makes a real difference to some one. Now if by this rule pragmatism means, once more, simply the maxim to avoid lo- gomachy, we shall certainly say Amen to its time-honored admonition. But if it means something more than this, we must ask. What is really meant? Truly we should discuss only that which is worth discussing ; but who is to determine what this is ? And the point upon which we are here most in need of enlightenment is this : Does prag- matism include among its "genuine human interests " the intellectual desire for knowl- edge for its own sake ? If it does not, then we must at least point out the fact that " in- tellectualistic metaphysics " is not the only thing tabooed. A large proportion of the problems of higher mathematics, history,] archaeology, astronomy, geology, literaryjf criticism, etc., are as certainly vetoed and forbidden. The courses in our universities must be cut down by half. For in every 40 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? field of scholarly inquiry there are innumer- able questions which awaken no more " re- sponsive active feelings " in " us practical Americans " and call for no more " particu- lar conduct of our own " than do the vari- ous theological and metaphysical problems against which the pragmatists inveigh. The distance of the nearest fixed star, the problems of the higher mathematics, the age of the Rig Veda, awaken as little " sense of reality " in most of us as do the various " philosophic propositions that will never make an appreciable difference to us in action." One and all, they are open to the same reproach of not " making any differ- ence " to a living soul — except the differ- ence which comes with the satisfaction of knowing. But by what right, after all, shall these things be declared not worth discuss- ing? Surely every genuine question — every question, that is, which has meaning and is not logomachy — is worth solving to him who wishes to solve it. If you, per- sonally, are not interested in mathematics or MEANING AND METHOD 4 1 metaphysics, by all means steer clear of them. But it is surely unworthy of the broad, human, and empirical spirit that characterizes all true pragmatists to attempt to dogmatize as to what all men shall find or ought to find interesting. In fact, if the question be thus put, the pragmatists might, perhaps, say that the purely theoretic interest should be taken into account and recognized as one of the things that give problems their value. But if this is the case, again I ask. What prob- lem, then, is ruled out beyond mere verbal disputes which all would rule out? How does the pragmatist rule or method assist us in choosing our problems ? Can the prag- matist name us one single problem which philosophers are discussing to-day which should not, on his own showing, be recog- nized as worth while ? Take, as a concrete example, the most extreme case thinkable, — or, letting the pragmatists choose for us, consider the one Professor James has selected as his favorite mark, — the " aseity " 42 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? of God.^ The choice was excellent for the purpose, for it seems to interest but few, and the name sounds remote and even absurd. Yet there certainly have been many, and still are some, who would genuinely like to know whether there is a divine Being who derives his existence from himself, or whether everything in the universe, " God " included, is bound on the weary wheel of external derivation. And in spite of the disrepute into which Scholasticism has brought the subject, I think, on the whole, nearly every one of us here would be more genuinely interested in knowing about the attributes of God than about the distances between the fixed stars. Of course the dis- cussion of these theological things is not reli- gion. But to condemn all such discussion because it is not this that "keeps religion going" is like condemning astronomy be- cause it does not give us light and heat. 1 Cf. James's California Addttss, /our. of PhU., Vol. I, pp. 680-681, and " Varieties of Religious Experience," pp. 445- 446. MEANING AND METHOD 43 And, to conclude, the whole matter may be put in the form of a dilemma : If, on the one hand, the various questions which pragma- tism would taboo are of genuine intellectual interest to any one, they are, on pragmatist principles, worth his investigation and dis- cussion. And if, on the other hand, they are not of interest to any one, it would seem hardly pragmatic to spend breath, ink, and time in attempting to prevent their investi- gation. If, therefore, the intellectual desire to know be admitted as a pragmatic interest, I cannot see that pragmatism helps us one whit in the selection of our problems, — un- less, indeed, we are to take seriously the implication sometimes given by certain pragmatist writers ; namely, that only those topics are worth discussing which are to their taste. This, for instance, is the im- pression one gets on reading Papini. The pragmatist, he tells us, will "not concern himself with a large part of the classical problems of metaphysics (in particular with 44 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? the universal and rational explanation of all things), which are for him unreal problems and devoid of meaning. . . . He will have an antipathy for all forms of monism . . . and for the ' reality ' of the ordinary man. . . . For the pragmatist, no metaphysical hypoth- esis is truer than another. He who feels the need of having one may choose according to his purposes and tastes."^ But in spite of Papini, most pragmatists (including Papini himself) have a metaphysic ; and certainly no American or British pragmatist would take seriously the suggestion one seems to get out of the rather dogmatic article from which I have just quoted — the suggestion, namely, of an Index Expurgatorius, to be issued by a pragmatic pope, proscribing all questions which are not of interest to him. It is disappointing indeed to come back from our long search thus empty-handed. But if we are to be honest with ourselves, I think we must admit that pragmatism's ^ " Introduzione al Pragmatismo," Leonardo, February, 1907, pp. 28-30. MEANING AND METHOD 45 much-vaunted method, if it is to save itself from absurd dogmatism, really sifts down to the following rather trifling rule : Never dis- cuss a question which has absolutely no interest and no meaning to any one. Prag- matism's insistence upon the concrete and its warnings against logomachy, I confess, are admirable. And its view of meaning as de- pendent on some ones experience seems philosophically sound. But both of these things are to be found in almost every school of philosophy and are far too common to be appropriated by any one group of thinkers as their peculiar merit or message. And when pragmatism attempts to go beyond these somewhat commonplace precepts, it lands in dogmatism and absurdity. Meaning and method, however, are, after all, but the beginning of pragmatism. Im- portant as these are in judging it, its doc- trine of truth is more vital still. It may be, then, that here we shall find something both unique and tenable, — a genuine and val- uable contribution to philosophy and to 46 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? clear thinking. But " truth " is a large and perplexing question (as you will soon see to your sorrow), and the consideration of it must therefore be postponed to the next lecture. LECTURE II THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" LECTURE II THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH"' Pragmatism has been likened by one of its foremost exponents to the corridor of a hotel. It is a way of approach to a number of diverse but related philosophic doctrines, rather than itself a new philosophy. And yet, in spite of the perfect intellectual free- dom and non-conformity of the pragmatists, all or nearly all of them would insist that there are two or three important articles of faith common to all pragmatist creeds ; and that the most important of these is the new meaning which pragmatism has given to the word truth. This new theory of truth is by far the most fundamental and important doctrine yet proposed by the new movement. It gives the point of view 1 Portions of this and the following lectures appeared in the Jour, of Phil., Vol. IV, pp. 320-324, and Vol. V, pp. 122-131. E 49 50 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? from which the pragmatist sees his world, it is the center from which most of his other doctrines take their start. It is, in fact, even more like the corridor of a hotel than pragmatism itself, — its doctrine of meaning being the front steps. To get at any of the other pragmatist doctrines one must first of all pass these. The ques- tion of truth, moreover, is even more impor- tant than that of meaning, and is, in fact, the most fundamental, the most crucial point to be met with in the whole pragmatic prob- lem, and a thorough understanding of it is essential to all our subsequent studies. Prag- matism stands or falls with its conception of truth. Before attempting an exposition of the new meaning assigned to this word, how- ever, it may be well to remind you (what you undoubtedly know perfectly well) that ever since Pilate's time the word truth has been notoriously ambiguous. Stop half a dozen men in the street and ask them, What is truth ? and you will prob- THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 5 1 ably get as many different answers. The number of ways in which the word truth may be used seems, however, to be reducible to three, and a clear understanding of these and of the distinctions between them is absolutely indispensable to any one who would thoroughly comprehend pragmatism. This lecture, therefore, will be devoted to an attempt to clear up this rather difficult subject, and to explain some of the different meanings given to the word truth — our exposition and criticism of the more techni- cal pragmatist use of the word being re- served for the next lecture. The subject, I say, may prove difficult ; yet I trust it will not be hopelessly so. For it is my firm belief that the difficulties which it usually presents are almost entirely due to a neglect of the distinctions referred to, and to a constant and unconscious confusion between the different senses of the word truth. The three different ways in which the word truth is commonly used are, then, the 52 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? following : (i) as a synonym for " reality " ; (2) as a synonym for known " fact " or verified and accepted belief; (3) as the relation or quality belonging to an " idea " which makes it " true " — its irueness. We shall now consider each of these in their order. The first of these uses is quite common in popular speech. The word is thus em- ployed as synonymous sometimes with the whole of reality, more often with a part only ; namely, that rather indefinite part which in popular discourses is referred to as Infinite, Eternal, Changeless, etc. Nor is the identification of truth with reality confined to popular speech; philosophers of the Platonic and Hegelian type — the absolutists in general — have often a ten- dency in this direction. Truth is thus re- garded as " objective," " systematic," inde- pendent of our human thinking, and as really another name for ultimate reality. This general position is maintained, for in- stance, by Mr. Bradley and Mr. Joachim. THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 53 Thus in a recent article ^ Mr. Bradley tells us that " Truth is the whole Universe realiz- ing itself in one aspect." Truth and reality must be identical, for were there any dif- ference between them, truth would fall short of reality and so fail to be true. Against this view of truth pragmatism — using especially the sword-like pen of Dr. Schiller, — has done magnificent battle, and has, in my opinion, come off with most of the spoils of war. It has shown the confusion which such a view brings into our termi- nology, its lack of self-consistency, and the almost inevitable skepticism consequent upon it, owing to its " dehumanizing " of truth. In all this pragmatism is decidedly in the right; for the philosophic identification of truth with reality seems, to me at least, quite untenable, and the popular use of the word in this sense most unfortunate. Mr. Bradley himself has shown that truth " in passing over into reality" ceases to be mere truth 1 " On Truth and Copying," Mind, April, 1907. 54 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? and that "truth at once is and is not reality." In short, this kind of reasoning, so far from what Professor Dewey calls the concrete situation, is most unsatisfactory and inevita- bly develops its own destructive "dialectic." Nor is the popular use of " truth " in the sense of reality any more satisfactory, al- though not open to the same logical criti- cisms. Its tendency toward vagueness, rhetoric, and a capital T ought to be enough to condemn it in the eyes of all those who would think clearly. To use the mildest of epithets, it is at least exceedingly unfortu- nate, both because of its haziness and also because the word truth is badly needed else- where, — a remark which applies to both the popular and the philosophic use of the word referred to. The English language is none too rich in clear-cut philosophic terms, and it is most unwise and most conducive to ambiguity to use up a good word like truth on something for which we already have another good word, namely reality. For, of course, if "truth" is to mean everything, it THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 55 will end by meaning nothing. In its attack upon the identification of truth with reality, pragmatism has, therefore, done a genuine service to the cause of clear thinking. The second general meaning commonly applied to the word truth is perfectly clear- cut, definite, and justifiable — its identifica-' tion, namely, with known fact, with the true and more or less completely verified beliefs that go to make up the mass of human knowledge. That twice two is four, that the earth revolves upon its axis, that virtue is its own reward, — these we speak of as " truths." In like manner, we speak of the various " truths " of science or of the body of moral and religious '' truths." Or we may go still further, and, combining all the general and important facts known to the race, we may speak of this whole as truth, — or even, if you like, as Truth. A capital letter is no serious danger if you keep your eyes open. Only we must remember that here as else- where eternal vigilance is the price of safety; and the history of philosophy shows many 56 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? examples of the inherent human tendency toward worship manifesting itself in an apotheosis of this very capital T. Thus it has come about that the human element in all the truth we know has often been quite lost from sight- Now it may very well be that there is an Absolute or Divine Mind, and that in that Mind there exist all manner of truths which have in them no human element. It is far from my purpose to decry monism or abso- lutism. But certain it is that the only truths we know or ever can know contain ipso facto a human element, and that this element can- not be lightly despised. It is in the pointing out of just this fact, in the emphasis laid upon just this human side of human truth, that the chief merit of pragmatism or humanism lies. It may indeed be seriously questioned whether the " intellectualists " in their treatment of truth have so completely left out of account its human side as they are accused of doing. I know of few who maintain the existence of "truth with no one thinking it," which pragmatists often refer to as the type of THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 57 truth of the intellectualists. There are, to be sure, a few English thinkers who hold to that doctrine. But I should certainly challenge the assertion that this is the dis- tinctive doctrine of the non-pragmatist and the consequent implication that in attacking it pragmatism has been quite original. As a non-pragmatist I repudiate any such doctrine. " Discarnate truth," truths which no one, not even an Absolute, thinks, like Platonic Ideas in an abstract empyrean, are as little to the taste of most non-pragmatists as to that of James, Schiller, and Dewey. And we have only sincere admiration for the brilliant exposition given by them of the contributions which we men make to our own truth. In his admirable paper on " The Ambigu- ity of Truth," Dr. Schiller makes a useful distinction between those beliefs which have not yet been vindicated and those which have been proved true. " If not all that claims truth is true, must we not distinguish this initial claim from whatever procedure 58 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? subsequently justifies or validates? Truth therefore will become ambiguous. It will mean primarily a claim which may or may not turn out to be valid. It will mean, secondarily, such a claim after it has been tested and ratified, by processes which it be- hooves us to examine. In the first sense, as a claim, it will always have to be regarded with suspicion. For we shall not know whether it is really and fully true, and we shall tend to reserve this honorable predicate for what has victoriously sustained its claim." ^ In other words, at least two things are essential, according to the pragmatist, for the definition of " a truth" in the full and exact sense of the word : (i) it shall be a claim which some one makes, a belief or judgment which some one holds ; (2) it shall have been validated and verified as true. A claim not yet verified is not yet a truth, insists the prag- matist. And, here though we might indeed quarrel with him, we need not. There is of course an obvious difference between a claim's 1 " Studies in Humanism," pp. 144-145. THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 59 being true and its being known as true ; and hence, if one cared to do so, one might very consistently maintain that a true claim is " a truth " even if not yet verified. Such an ob- jection to the pragmatist's definition, however, would be largely verbal, and upon questions of terminology either side may well make concessions. It makes but little difference whether we call a claim which is true but unverified " a truth " or merely a true claim. And as it is my earnest desire not to be hypercritical but to go with the pragmatist just as far as possible, I shall agree to define " a truth " as a true claim that has been 1 verified.^ 1 With this understanding of our terminology, therefore, the non-pragmatist need not and does not insist on unverifi- able truths, though he does insist that there may be and doubtless are innumerable beliefs which are true though as yet unverified or even unverifiable. The failure to grasp this distinction is the cause of Dr. Schiller's caricature of the non- pragmatist position. Cf. his review of Professor James's book in Mind, Vol. XVI, p. 600. The non-pragmatist is not driven to assert " unknowables " in any other sense than that there doubtless are many things in heaven and earth that we can never know — an assertion which, I suppose, pragmatism would hardly deny. 6o WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? So much being agreed and understood, let us now take a brief survey of the pragma- tist's admirable description of the way our truths originate and grow. In doing so, how- ever, let me remind you of the importance of keeping in mind constantly that here' there is as yet no question of the true- ness of a claim or belief. The distinction between "a truth" and the trueness of that truth must never be lost from sight. A large part of the writings of the three leading pragmatists is taken up with admir- able psychological descriptions of "the making of truth." For being part of the content of our minds, our truths have a natural history, and the general course of their development may be clearly traced. Each truth which you or I possess originates and grows within a perfectly concrete situation and is due to perfectly definite conditions. Our beliefs are intellectual tools which serve us in more or less useful ways. The process by which they get themselves verified and thus cease to be mere claims and become truths, the THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 6 1 application of these " truths," and the modi- fications they undergo, — all this can be traced within the stream of consciousness as concrete psychic fact. If now we ask our- selves how, more in detail, our claims are verified and proved true, we find that, if the answer must be given in a single phrase, the best way to describe what happens is to say that those claims are accepted as truths which work, which are useful, which combine har- moniously with our previously accepted truths. By their fruits ye shall know them. As we never can get outside of our own ex- perience and compare our truths with any- thing beyond them, the best if not the only test left us by which we may separate the sheep from the goats, the potential truths from the invalid claims, is to see which of several possible combinations of claims is the most self -consistent and inclusive; or, if it be a question of a single cl3.im, to observe how well it works, how far it aids in harmoniz- ing all our experience. Thus when a jury is weighing the two possible views of the evi- 62 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? dence presented respectively by the defense and by the prosecution, what it is really about is an endeavor to see which view is most consistent with itself and which, at the same time, is able to interpret and harmonize the largest number of individual claims. Or when a scientist is trying to decide whether an hypothesis is true, his test is again the question, How useful is it in harmonizing all the accepted facts and leading the mind out of its state of uncertainty to a feeling of in- ner peace and intellectual satisfaction ? The truth is that which works best, and that which works best is the truth. Successful working is therefore the tag or ear-mark by which we distinguish the true idea. But, as you doubtless perceive, this only leads us to the more fundamental and difficult question as to what we mean by the idea's being true, the question of the nature of the thing tagged or marked. For it is clear enough that there is a difference be- tween a thing and its tag, — between an object and the sign which proves to us the THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 63 presence of that object. Although we have been informed how to tell a true idea when we happen upon one, we must still ask what is meant by the truth of the idea, what it is that the sign of it signifies. The distinction between a thing and the evidence of it, be- tween an object and its tag, is doubtless plain as day to you all ; but as the distinction is an extremely important one, and as it is often overlooked, I shall, in good pragmatist fash- ion, seek a concrete illustration of it from a realm of practical life far removed from the abstractions of philosophy. Let us, for ex- ample, suppose that Mennen's face is, as he says, upon every box of toilet powder made by him. The presence of his face would, then, be a good test by which to determine whether in any given instance we have the genuine article or not. But the important thing about the powder, after all, is its own nature and make-up rather than the pretty picture associated with it ; and we should hardly say that the contents of the box is what it is because its cover bears the image 64 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? of Mennen's never-to-be-forgotten face. If a pupil asks his teacher about a triangle, the latter may refer him to page 52 of Loomis's Geometry and page 63 of Wentworth's for a diagram, and the pupil may learn to distin- guish a triangle from a square in this way. But even if the triangle were figured on no other pages than these, one would not define triangle as "the figure on pages 52 and 63," nor give this as the meaning of the term. In other words, the meaning or nature of a material, a quality, a relation, is one thing; the sign by which you make sure of its pres- ence is another. And, in like manner (to return to the question that immediately con- cerns us), the ear-mark by which we have now learned to tell a true idea from a false one does not answer the further question, what we mean by its being true. Doubtless ideas are proved true by their consequences, as the pragmatists say; but when we prove them true, what are we proving ? What is it that such a process of verification verifies? A mere psychological description of what THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRITTH" 65 happens within our experience is obviously here quite insufficient. And this brings us to the third use of the word truth, the true- ness of a belief. To put it Jersely, then, what do we mean when we say that an idea is true? To this question there are certainly two and possibly several quite distinct answers. And it will throw light on the real meaning of the answer which pragmatism gives if we first consider the answer which pragmatism rejects, — the interpretation, namely, given by " common sense," or " intellectualism," or " realism " (as you like). This interpretation commonly goes under the name of the " cor- respondence theory," and runs in brief some- what as follows : The truth relation, or the quality of trueness, is neither a part of our thought or experience, nor a part of the other reality to which our thought refers, but is rather a relation between our thought and its chosen object, between our idea or judg- ment and the thing which it means. And this relation is simply one of correspondence. 66 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? A caricature of the theory frequently set up by its opponents maintains that correspondence must mean copying, and that the thought which thus "copies" reality is a sort of pho- tograph of the original ; that we \\3.y& pictures of things in our heads, and that if the pic- tures are good pictures we have truth. Now the upholder of the correspondence theory will agree with his critics that the copy theory as thus described would deserve, all the uncomplimentary epithets they are so able in devising for it. Such a theory would be both bad psychology and bad episte- mology. For, in the first place, it is obvious that the great majority of all those thoughts which can be called either true or false are not pictures ; and if they were, it is hard to see how their simply being like external things could make them true. A billiard ball is not true, no matter how much it may resemble another billiard ball. Two pains are not true, though they be as like as two peas. Whatever truth may be, it is at any rate something more than chance resem- THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 67 blance. The knowing thought must mean its object, must choose and adopt it, and once it has done so no copying will be necessary. The real common-sense theory, as I under- stand it, may then be stated as follows: " Truth," or the relation of " correspondence," means, not copying, but merely this simple thing, that the object of which one is thinking is as one thinks it. Or, to put the same thing in other words, the truth or trueness of an idea is its conformity to fact. It would seem, oddly enough, that this very obvious and natural explanation of the meaning of the truth relation is the one thing in the universe which is capable of bringing together the absolutist and the pragmatist. Deadly enemies at every other point, they stand manfully shoulder to shoulder in attacking the correspondence theory. Whatever else truth may mean, they are agreed it shall not mean this. For Mr. Bradley it is far too simple, and for Professor James, apparently, it is not simple enough. In commenting upon the formulation of the 68 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? doctrine just given (that the object of which one is thinking is as one thinks it), Professor James finds the word " as " to be " anything but simple." " What it most immediately suggests," he continues, " is that the idea should be like the object; but most of our ideas, being abstract concepts, bear almost no resemblance to their objects. ... I now formally ask . . . what this ' as 'ness in itself consists in — for it seems to me that it ought to consist in something assignable and de- scribable and not remain a pure mystery."^ Paulsen has somewhere remarked that " the absurd has this advantage in common with truth, that it cannot be refuted." And it might be added that the most ultimately simple expression of the commonest fact has this disadvantage in common with the self- contradictory, that it cannot be explained. As Dr. Ewer has pointed out in connection with this very question of Professor James's, " We recognize similar questions about in- 1" Professor Pratt on Truth," Jour, of Phil., Vol. IV, pp. 466-467. THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 69 dubitable facts that have no answer : ' How can a body move ? ' 'How can a body exclude other bodies from the space it occupies ? ' ' How can one event follow another ? ' . . . To them no answers can be given which do not contain the very ideas of motion, temporal succession, etc., that are under fire. Details and accessories of the process may be elucidated, but the essential character is implied throughout."^ In short, it is the very simplicity of the re- lation between our thought and the thing of which we are thinking that makes it in- capable of reduction to simpler terms. It may be a " pure mystery " no doubt ; but if so, then I ask in turn that something be named me which is not a mystery. And even if the nature of the case permitted my accepting Professor James's challenge and naming something else which " this 'as 'ness in itself consists in," he could again ask the same question concerning this new thing, and so ad infinitum. i«The Anti-realistic ' How?'" /'w- of PhU., Vol. IV, p. 631. 70 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? But though I cannot analyze an ulti- mately simple relation into its parts and tell what 'as'ness consists in, it will, I feel sure, clear up the matter completely to the non-pragmatic reader if I apply the corre- spondence theory of truth to a concrete and very commonplace example. John, let us say, thinks Peter has a toothache ; the ob- ject of John's thought is Peter's present experience ; and as a fact Peter has a tooth- ache. And John's thought is true, accord- ing to the correspondence theory, because its object is as he thinks it. That is what con- stitutes it true, that is the meaning of its trueness. And I confess it is impossible for me to see how anything could be simpler than this. To torture it into some sort of mysterious and crude " copy theory," and to insist upon further simplification and de- mand what ' as 'ness consists in, seems to me a manufacture of unnecessary difficulties. At any rate, if this explanation of the mean- ing of " true " be not simple and clear, I despair of ever making anything clear to philosophers. THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 7 1 But lack of simplicity is not the only charge brought against the correspondence theory by pragmatism. Leaving this ques- tion to Professor James, Dr. Schiller attacks it in two other quarters. In the first place he tells us that this view of truth " speedily leads us to a hopeless impasse once the question is raised — How are we to know whether our ' truth ' ' corresponds ' or ' agrees ' with its real object ? For to decide this question must we not be able to com- pare ' thought ' and ' reality,' and to contem- plate each apart from the other ? This, however, seems impossible. ' Thought ' and 'reality' cannot be got apart, and conse- quently the doctrine of their ' correspond- ence ' has in the end no meaning. We are not aware of any reality except by its representation in our ' thought ' and per contra, the whole meaning of 'thought' re- sides ultimately in its reference to * reality.' " ' By the above, Dr. Schiller can hardly mean simply that all reality is some form 1 " Humanism," pp. 45-46. 72 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? of experience, for there is, of course, nothing to prevent two independent experiences — my thought and my neighbor's experience, for instance — from corresponding (in the sense defined above). More probably Dr. Schiller means that we can never get imme- diately at any reality but our own thought or experience, that we can never get outside of our own minds, and that every part of reality which is to be directly grasped by us must become part of our own experience ; and that, hence, we are not able to compare and contemplate thought and reality apart from each other. If I am right in this in- terpretation, then by saying, " Thought and reality cannot be got apart," he means that we cannot get them apart. Certainly this is far from proving that they cannot be apart and correspond, and that the " doctrine of their correspondence has in the end no meaning r Its meaning is perfectly obvi- ous — at least to every one whose eyes are not afflicted with pragmatic cataracts. But, to make it concrete, let us again take an ex- THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 73 ample. I am thinking, let us say, that my friend B is in Constantinople. Let us say, too, that though I am and remain without any experience of Constantinople, my friend B actually is there. Surely thought and reality are here " apart " — though it remains a fact that they cannot " be got apart," i.e. by any individual human experience. Dr. Schiller's argument would therefore seem to prove nothing more than that if truth con- sists in correspondence, it must transcend the individual human mind — it must be a rela- tion such that only one of its terms is in the individual's experience ; which is exactly what the upholders of the theory in question have always maintained. Dr. Schiller has, however, another objec- tion to the doctrine of correspondence, — namely, that if truth consists in this relation we can never know whether in any given case the correspondence holds or not ; we shall never be able to tell whether a given thought is true. In answer to this an upholder of the old 74 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? theory might well respond : " What of it ? Suppose this so; would that make the na- ture and meaning of truth as defined incon- sistent or impossible ? " And here we come upon a point of considerable importance — the question, namely, whether my thought can be true if I do not know it to be true. On this the pragmatists seem to be divided. Sometimes they admit that such a thought would be true,^ sometimes they avoid the issue,* and sometimes they flatly deny the possibility.* This latter position seems to rest upon a failure to distinguish between " a truth," and the truth relation, the quality of trueness or of being true. Granted that a " claim " must be verified to become " a truth," does it follow that there are no such things as true though unverified claims ? Surely the pragmatist would hesitate to call all such claims false. And it is rather hard to see how they could be neither true nor false, though simple enough to understand that (according to the useful though arbitrary i^'.^. James. « ^.^. Schiller. '£'.^. Dewey and Schiller. THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 75 definition) they are as yet neither " truths " nor falsehoods. It is therefore one thing to have a true idea or make a valid claim, and quite another to know that the idea is true or the claim valid. Hence Dr. Schiller's as- sertion that we cannot find out whether our thought is true is utterly irrelevant to the question what we mean by its being true. The test of truth is one thing ; the nature or meaning of truth quite another. But it is not the case that on the corre- spondence theory we cannot tell whether a thought is true- To be sure, the shadow of a very theoretical doubt may always be left us in all matters outside of our immediate here and now. The proofs that my friend B is in Constantinople may be false, I may be dreaming, this may be a solipsistic world, etc. But such a doubt is so exceedingly theo- retical that it ought to have no terrors for any man — least of all for a pragmatist. If. however, his pragmatic conscience is still un- accountably troubled by so purely theoretic and academic a question, let him tell us how 76 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? his theory of truth avoids the difficulty. And to show that it is here no better off than the much-reviled correspondence theory, I need surely do no more than summon Pro- fessor James as my witness. For in dealing with this very question he writes, " If there is to be truth, both realities and beliefs about them must conspire to make it ; but whether there ever is such a thing, or how any one can be sure that his own beliefs possess it, pragmatism never pretends to determine."^ — The fact is, as a practical matter, much the same tests of truth hold, no matter what your theory. If you grant that it is at all possible for me to prove that Boston is in Massachu- setts, that Caesar lived before Napoleon, that my friend B is in Constantinople, then on the correspondence theory as well as on any other I can know that my thought is true. This being the case, it is really hard to see why pragmatism has rejected it. The 1 " The Pragmatist Account of Truth," Phil. Rev., Vol. XVII, p. 8. THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" ']^ correspondence view of truth is perfectly con- sistent with the humanistic attitude toward truth and the making of truth. It not only admits but insists that our human thought is indispensable to the truth relation, and that without it such a relation could not exist. It is essentially realistic (which ought to please pragmatism, for pragmatism at least pretends to be realistic), and it combines more natu- rally and easily with empiricism than with rationalism. And it is glad to admit that the way our ideas " work " in the broad sense is one of the most important tests of their being true. In spite of all this, however, the leading pragmatists, one and all, refuse to accept the theory, considering it either quite inadequate or flatly meaningless and false. This is a fact which I wish especially to emphasize. One frequently gets the impres- sion from the writings of the pragmatists that all they have done is innocently to call attention to an obvious characteristic of the truth relation, which their opponents have 78 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? thereupon unaccountably and wickedly de- nied, and that the latter are, therefore, at all points the aggressors. As a fact, the exact opposite of this is the case. No one, so far as I know, denies the usefulness of truth nor the value of successful working as verification of the true idea. And if the pragmatists had been satisfied with pointing this out and with their further (rather con- fusing and unwarranted) endeavor to identify the word " truth " with " successful working," and had stopped there, no one would have thought it worth while to dispute with them over a matter which would obviously have been one of terminology only. But they have not stopped there; and the question at issue is really one of fundamental importance to clear thinking for the reason that the pragmatists have not only appropriated the word truth to their own meaning, but also insist that the meaning which most other philosophers have given to the word is no meaning at all. It is they, therefore, rather than the non-pragmatists, who are the real THE AMBIGUITY OF "TRUTH" 79 aggressors and who refuse, rather intoler- antly, to recognize the existence of any other relation or characteristic of a true idea besides that which they themselves designate by the word truth. In one of his latest contribu- tions to the subject. Professor James says of the correspondence theory: "Surely this is not a counter-theory of truth to ours. It is the renunciation of all articulate theory. It is but a claim to the right to call certain ideas true anyhow; and this is what I meant by saying that the anti-pragmatists offer us no real alternative, and that our account is literally the only positive theory extant." ^ Unconditional surrender, in other words, is the only terms pragmatism will offer its opponents ; and the non-pragmatist, no mat- ter how peaceable his disposition, is thus forced to take up arms in very self-defense. This categorical denial by the pragmatists that there is any meaning in the correspond- ence theory must be kept constantly in mind 1 Review of Hubert's " Le Pragmatisme," Jour, of Phil., Vol. V, p. 692. 8o WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? in our attempt to understand the theory (or theories?) of the truth relation which they propose in its place. This, however, is a large question, and we must postpone con- sideration of it to the next lecture. LECTURE III THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF THE TRUTH RELATION LECTURE III THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF THE TRUTH RELATION No one can fully grasp the pragmatic meaning of the truth relation without first understanding the pragmatic view of the nature of " a truth " or verified human claim discussed in the last lecture. And the reason is, as I shall try to show, that the former grows out of the latter and is the result of a complete confusion between the two uses of the word truth. It is impossible to read half a dozen pages of pragmatist writing on this subject without coming upon at least one, and usually many, instances of utter failure to distinguish between " truth " as known fact, or mental possession, and "truth" as trueness or that quality or rela- tion characterizing a true idea which makes it true. I trust that by this time you all 83 84 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? are clear on this distinction and appreciate its importance. For it is from a failure to make this distinction that pragmatism has fallen into the pitiful and unnecessary diffi- culties, inconsistencies, and impossible situa- tions, which I shall try to point out. There are several roads by which pragma- tism seems to have moved from its position on the nature of " a truth " to the meaning it has given to the truth relation. Of these I shall point out two. (i) We have noted the emphasis placed by pragmatists upon the concrete, psychological nature of our human truths. These do not, they insist, dwell apart in a Platonic realm ; they are all of them concrete mental facts, they are of such stuff as dreams and feelings and sensa- tions are made of. To banish the abstract from philosophy so far as possible and to sub- stitute for it the individual concrete in the interests of clear thinking has been one of the great and excellent aims of pragmatism. What more natural, therefore, than to use the same concrete method in dealing with. THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH 85 the further question of the trueness of ideas ? If truth in this sense be a relation, it must, insists the pragmatist, be a concrete relation. In fact, long before pragmatism was heard of Professor James sought in his " Principles of Psychology " to interpret every relation con- cretely so far as possible/ This principle applied to the truth relation makes it no mere correspondence as defined above, but rather the chain or succession of things or events or experiences that are to be found either between an idea and its object or between a judgment and its vindication. Not only, therefore, is " a truth " concrete ; pragmatism insists that its trueness also shall be a concrete thing or group of things. It is this chain of intermediating things or experi- ences that not only proves it true but also makes it true, and constitutes its truth. The truth relation is therefore not " saltatory " but " ambulatory " * — it consists not in the mere fact that our object is there as we think it, but 1 See especially Vol. I, pp. 243 ff- ; Vol. II, pp. 148 flf. s « A Word more about Truth," Jour, of Phil., Vol. IV, pp. 396 f. 86 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? in the actual experiential process of getting at it or as near it as may be. " The links of ex- perience sequent upon an idea, which mediate between it and reality, form and, for the prag- matist, indeed, are the concrete relation of truth that may obtain between the idea and that reality. They, he says, are all that we mean when we speak of the idea ' pointing ' to the reality, ' fitting ' it, ' corresponding ' with it or ' agreeing ' with it, — they and other similar mediating trains of verifica- tion. Such mediating events make the idea 'true.' The idea itself, if it exists at all, is also a concrete event ; so that pragmatism insists that truth in the singular is only a collective name for truths in the plural, these consisting always of series of definite events." ^ I shall not at this point offer any criticism of this view that trueness is a collec- tive name for concrete psychic truths, being concerned here merely in pointing out this first mode of transition from the latter to the former. 1 " The Pragmatist Account of Truth," Phil. Rev., Vol XVII, p. II. THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH 87 (2) Another road which has led the prag- matist to the same result starts from the view already dealt with that our "truths" are made, that they begin as claims and are verified within our experience, and that the test of their verity is their working, their consequences, their application. Now the pragmatist contention that a claim must be verified in order to become " a truth " is neither novel nor open to any serious criti- cism ; but the pragmatist takes it for granted that once this is admitted it follows that the claim is made true by being verified and that its trueness consists in its verification. Verification thereby ceases to be the pro- cess of proving an idea to be true and becomes the process of making it true. " Truths are logical values," says Dr. Schil- ler ; and he adds, " It directly follows from this definition of truth that all 'truths' must be verified to be properly true. . . . To become really true it has to be tested, and it is tested by being applied. . . . The truth of an assertion depends upon its appli- 88 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? cation. ... In short, truths must be used to become true, and (in the end) to stay true." ^ Just how "it directly follows" "that all truths must be verified to be properly true " may hot seem so obvious to us as it does to Dr. Schiller ; for the premise to such a con- clusion must evidently be that no belief can be true unless it is known to be true, and the logical consequence is, of course, that there are no such things as true but unveri- fied beliefs, and that before a belief is veri- fied it is either false or else neither true nor false. Let me sum up this rather difficult point in a few words. We all agree that verifica- tion is essential to the making of a claim in- to a truth; but the pragmatist draws from this the conclusion that the truth {trueness) of the claim depends on and consists in its verification. This, I maintain, is a flagrant case of using the word truth in two per- fectly distinct senses as if it meant the same thing both times and as if it had but one 1 " Studies in Humanism," pp. 7-9. THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH 89 meaning. It is a confusion between a "truth" and "trueness," — a fallacy from which flow, as will be seen, the most serious consequences. Or, to put the same thing in another light, the claim being proved true by its working, by its consequences, it is said to be made true (notice, not made "a truth" but made true) by these consequences. Its true- ness thus consists in these consequences. "The truth (validity) of a truth (claim)," says Schiller, "is tested and established by the value of its consequences,"* This sen- tence is perfectly harmless, but the pragma- tist does not stop here. From it he deduces the rather amazing conclusion that since its usefulness proves it true, its trueness con- sists in its being useful. The test of truth and the meaning of truth are thus com- pletely identified. So much for pragmatism's roads of ap- proach to its final view of the truth relation. And now, lest I should unwittingly misrep- 1 <' Steadies in Humanism," p. 160. 90 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? resent that view, let the three great prag- matists speak for it : — Professor James: "Theoretical truth is no relation between our mind and the arche- typal reality. It falls within the mind, be- ing the accord of some of its processes and objects with other processes and objects."^ ■' Truth happens to an idea. It becomes true, is made true by events. Its verity is in fact an event, a process; the process, namely, of its verifying itself, its •ven-ficaiion. Its validity is the process of its vaMd-ation." ^ " The truth of our beliefs consists in general in their giving satisfaction." * " The links of experience sequent upon an idea, which mediate between it and a reality, form, and for the pragmatist, indeed, are the concrete re- lation of truth. . . . Such mediating events make the idea true." * " The truth relation is a definitely experienceable relation. . . . The relation to its object that makes an idea 1 " Humanism and Truth once More,'' Mind, Vol. XIV, p. 198. 2 "Pragmatism," p. 201. »«Tlie Pragmatist Account of Truth," PMl. Rev., Vol. XVII, p. s- ♦/&• " Reality and the Criterion of Truth for Ideas," Mind, Vol. XVI, pp. 335-337- 94 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? has published since the appearance of his " Pragmatism " — there runs, parallel with the view expressed above, a difEerent and decidedly less radical description of the na- ture of the truth relation.^ Thus verifiability is often spoken of as being as good as veri- fication. And in the Journal of Philosophy for August 15, 1907, he writes, "Truth is essentially a relation between two things, an idea, on the one hand, and a reality outside of the idea, on the other. This relation, like all relations, has its fundamenium, namely the matrix of experiential circumstance, psy- chological as well as physical, in which the correlated terms are found embedded. . . . What constitutes the relation known as truth, I now say, is just the existence in the empiri- cal world of this fundamentum of circum- stance surrounding object and idea and ready ' I should add, however, that in his latest treatment of the subject, namely in his review of Hubert's recent book on Pragmatism, Professor James seems to have returned part way to the more radical view, while still maintaining the reality and independence of the object. See the Jour, of Phil, for December 3, 1908. THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH 95 to be either short-circuited or traversed at full length. So long as it exists and a satis- factory passage through it between the object and the idea is possible, that idea will both be true, and will have been true of that object, whether fully developed verification has taken place or not. The nature and place and affinities of the object, of course, play as vital a part in making the particular passage possible as do the nature and associ- ative tendencies of the idea; so that the notion that truth could fall altogether inside of the thinker's experience and be something purely psychological is absurd." And in a more recent article,^ while still maintaining that the truth relation must be a chain of " concrete " links, he comes still closer to the correspondence theory. " The pragmatizing epistemologist posits a reality and a mind with ideas. What now, he asks, can make those ideas true of that reality? Ordinary epistemology contents itself with the vague 1 « The Pragmatist Account of Truth," Phil. Rev., Vol XVII, pp. 1-17. 96 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? statement that the ideas must 'correspond' or ' agree ' ; the pragmatist insists upon being more concrete and asks what such agreement may mean in detail. He finds first that the ideas must point to or lead towards that reality and no other, and then that the point- ings and leadings must yield satisfaction as their result." " The pragmatist calls satisfac- tions indispensable for truth-building, but ex- pressly calls them insufficient unless reality be also incidentally led to. If the reality he assumed were canceled from his universe of discourse, he would straightway give the name of falsehoods to the beliefs remaining in spite of all their satisfactoriness. For him, as for his critic, there can be no truth if there is nothing to be true about. Ideas are so much flat psychological surface unless some mirrored matter gives them cognitive luster." " Ideas are practically useful which we can verify by the sum total of all their leadings, and the reality of whose objects may thus be considered established beyond doubt. That these ideas should be true in advance of and THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH 97 apart from their utility, that, in other words, their objects should be really there, is the very condition of their having that kind of utility." And even in his " Pragmatism " Professor James in one place writes, "When new experiences lead to retrospective judg- ments, using the past tense, what these judg- ments utter was true, even though no past thinker had been led there." ^ How far Dr. Schiller goes with Professor James in his modified view of truth, I am unable to say. Professor James insists that he and Schiller agree absolutely on the sub- ject.** Yet it is certainly very difficult to find in any of Dr. Schiller's writings anything comparable in explicitness to the expressions just quoted from Professor James. And Pro- fessor Dewey certainly stands firmly on the expressions quoted from him and remains always consistently radical. After listening to the quotations I have just read you from the three leading prag- 1 p. 223. ' See his review of Hubert's " Le Pragmatisme," in the Jour, of Phil., Vol. V, pp. 693-694. 98 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? matists, you may understand why the critics of pragmatism have been so constantly — and justly! — accused of misunderstanding it. And I am free to confess that it is beyond my power to formulate, on the basis of what the pragmatists have written, a single con- sistent and harmonious pragmatic doctrine concerning the nature of the truth relation. The best I can do for pragmatism is to make two doctrines of truth out of the expressions quoted above ; and, indeed, it must be evident to you all that we have here two quite dis- tinct views — one radical and one somewhat modified — as to the meaning of truth. The former of these holds that truth is the pro- cess of verification which goes on within experience ; that it consists in the successful working of the idea, in the concrete steps within consciousness that lead from the unverified claim to the full and satisfying assurance of its " goodness." The modified view, on the other hand, maintains that there are two factors which go to make up the THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH 99 trueness of an idea: namely, (i) the concrete steps of its leading and the subjective satis- factions resulting (as described by the radical view); and also (2) the actual presence in reality of the object which the idea means. Let us note a little more in detail three of the most important differences between these two views. (i) The most obvious difference is the recognition found in the more moderate view that it is indispensable for the trueness of an idea that its object should really " be there." ^ Truth thus ceases to be " wholly within our experience," or "an experienced relation," and becomes instead a relation which com- pletely transcends (or may transcend) any single finite experience. It is not merely a " process " nor a felt " leading " from one part of our experience to another. It is no more psychical than physical in its nature. It is a relation between an idea and a reality 1 Numerous expressions of the moderate pragmatist show that by the object's being really " there " he means not only that the object exists but that it exists independently of the individual's experience, and (at times) outside of it. lOO WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? which may be " beyond the direct experience of the particular cognizer," ^ a relation which, apparently, no one short of a Roycean Ab- solute need ever experience. It must be evident to all how completely this differs from the radical view which takes no note of any reality outside the individual's expe- rience as essential to truth, and which makes truth wholly a process within expe- rience. And this brings us to the second difference between the two theories. (2) Since the modified view of truth rec- ognizes an outer reality as relevant and es- sential, it can and does maintain that an idea may be true before it is verified, whereas the radical view insists that truth consists in the actual process of verification, and that, hence, the idea is not true till so proved. Thus we have here another case of flat contradiction. Professor Dewey saying that the idea is not true before verified, and Professor James say- ing that it is. A less obvious but equally 1 Professor James in the Jour, of Phil., Vol. IV, p. 403, note. THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH lOI important phase of this same disagreement is the question of verifiability. Professor Dewey and the left wing maintain, as has been seen, that actual verification is essential to truth ; Professor James and the right wing maintain that verifiability is quite sufficient ; while the center, under both Dr. Schiller and Professor James, insists that after all there isn't any real difference between the meanings of these two words. Whether there is such a difference or not, I must leave to your judg- ment. For my own part, I had always sup- posed there was the same difference as that between mere possibility and the concrete process of making the possibility an actuality; and I had also thought that this was a real difference. Columbus's idea that he could cross the Atlantic was merely verifiable so long as he stayed in Spain, and this its quality of verifiability (which it already possessed while he was still in Spain), had always seemed to me quite a different thing from the concrete steps of getting ships, manning them, hoist- ing anchor and raising sail and all the other I02 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? links in the chain of actual verification. And it must, I think, be evident to all who are not pragmatists that it is one thing to say the full process of verification is essential to truth and a very different thing to say that verifiability alone is essential. For verifia- bility is not a process nor a succession of events in time, it is not included within any one's experience, but is a general condition or set of conditions which transcends every single finite experience. It is not a felt "leading," it is not a "form of the good," nor a "satisfactory working," nor any other ex- perience or experience-process. It is, if you like, the possibility of these, but it is not these. It is a totality of relations which are not, and will never be, within any finite ex- perience. It is a present condition of the idea, not something that " happens to " it. It is not " made " ; it is already there. It is immeasurably more harmonious with the correspondence theory of truth than with that of radical pragmatism. The harmony which Dr. Schiller has brought about be- THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH 103 tween verification and verifiability is of the same sort that usually obtains between the lion and the lamb when they lie down to- gether. "It is," he tells us, "impossible to separate verifiability from verification — the potentiality does not exist apart from the ac- tuality from which it is an ex post facto in- ference. A claim to truth, therefore, can only be regarded as verifiable on the strength of past experiences of verifications, and a ' verifiable ' truth which is never verified is really unverifiable." ^ It would seem, thus, that the reason why verification and verifia- bility cannot be separated is the same that makes it impossible to separate the lion and the lamb after they have lain down together. It is, therefore, obvious why Dr. Schiller in- sists that there is no difference between the two; to his pragmatic mind there really is "^ "■MVaaa. 'Ra.'ao'i'" Jour, of Phil., Vol. IV, p. 493, note. The non-pragmatist, of course, agrees with Schiller that a po- tentiality cannot exist apart from an actuality, but he insists that the actuality which makes an idea verifiable is not actual verification, but the existing condition of relevant reality, the nature of the &ct in question and the idea's conformity to that &ct. I04 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? no such thing as verifiability, it having been completely swallowed by verification. All of which is new evidence of the great differ- ence between the view that considers mere verifiability without verification sufficient for truth and that which insists that actual veri- fication is essential. (3) The third difference between the left and right wings of pragmatism is hardly more than a variant on the second, and yet deserves especial notice. It is, namely, con- cerned with the question of the " successful working," or the " consequences," of an idea. Radical pragmatism maintains that these not only prove the idea true, but make it true and constitute its truth. Modified pragmatism denies the latter statement. Professor Dewey says, " The effective working of the idea and its truth are one and the same thing — this working being neither the cause nor the evidence of truth but its nature." Pro- fessor James says, " That these ideas {i.e. useful ideas) should be true in advance of and apart from their utility, that, in other THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH 105 words, their objects should be really there, is the very condition of their having that kind of utility." In other words, to put it briefly, the left wing of pragmatism main- tains that ideas are true because they are useful ; the right wing maintains that they are useful because they are true. Let us now examine more in detail this modified form of the pragmatic doctrine. In the first place, it is obvious that this is an attempt to steer a middle course between radical pragmatism and the old correspond- ence theory. It has sought for a combi- nation of pragmatism and common sense as a sort of golden mean. The result has been, on the one hand, that it has avoided some of the difficult positions of the radical form ; but, on the other hand, it is question- able whether it has not sought to reconcile several things which are quite irreconcilable. It would seem to be trying that notoriously difficult feat of eating one's cake and keep- ing it too. Thus it is hard to see how " satisfactions " and the concrete " links of I06 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? experience " are " indispensable " to truth, if at the same time an idea can be true in ad- vance of and apart from these satisfactions and links of experience. The modified pragmatist view would therefore seem to be open to two dififerent interpretations, according to which of its two seemingly inconsistent factors one chooses to emphasize as the essential part If one emphasizes the assertion that the idea is true before it is verified, that its truth consists just in the existence of the relation between it and its object even if this be " short-circuited," and that it is its truth that makes it useful rather than its usefulness that makes it true, it is indeed no longer subject to criticism, because it has simply turned into the old correspond- ence theory under a new name. All that was distinctive in it has evaporated, and all that remains is the name " pragmatic " — like the grin on the face of Alice's Cheshire cat after the face of the cat had faded away. But if, on the other hand, we choose THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH 107 to say that the indispensability of the sat- isfactions and of the concrete Hnks of ex- perience forms the essential part of the doctrine, then we shall have avoided the frying pan, indeed, but only to fall danger- ously near the fire. There will, of course, still be this difference between moderate and radical pragmatism : that for the former the object must really " be there " and that the satisfactions, etc., though indispensable, will not -be sufficient. Yet, if these satis- factions are really indispensable, a belief which is verifiable but not yet verified is not true. My idea that my friend is in Constantinople will not be a true idea (even if as a fact he is there) until I have actu- ally gone through the links of concrete ex- perience which verify it and actually have the satisfactions which witness to its truth. Truth and the test of truth will thus still be largely confused; the proof of a propo- sition will form at least a part of its true- ness. This doctrine, therefore, though -differing in some details from the radical I08 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? pragmatism of Professor Dewey, will still be subject to most of the criticisms to which the latter view (as Professor James himself, apparently, sees perfectly well) is so manifest a mark. Hence, modified pragmatism must either return to the much-abused correspon- dence theory or else accept most of the absurd consequences to which radical prag- matism will lead us. I see no way of avoiding this dilemma. To stick to both interpreta- tions and to use the word truth in " this large loose way " is to contradict oneself. One can- not long ride upon two horses going in op- posite directions ; one must choose between them — or fall between them. Here as else- where it will ultimately prove impossible to run with the hare and hunt with the hounds. We come now at last to a closer examina- tion of the more radical pragmatic view of the truth relation. And to understand it thoroughly we must first notice a cer- tain peculiarity in the use of the important word idea which will go far to explain the rather startling conclusion as to the THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH 109 nature of truth to which it comes. When one first dips into the literature of pragma- tism, one is somewhat mystified by recurrent phrases such as " the efficient working of an idea," " the idea's leading," etc. The various uses of this phrase point, I think, to an important difference in the intellectual- istic and the pragmatic meaning of " idea " in connection with the truth problem. To the pragmatist the word idea means any representative content that leads to action or helps to bring order into a given situa- tion. Hence Professor Dewey's synonym for it — namely, "plan of action." Thus the important thing about an idea to the pragmatist is, not its present relation to its object, but its influence upon conduct, its motive power or guiding force. Starting from the biological view of mind, the prag- matist insists that the purpose of thought is, not the acquisition of " truth," but the useful reaction of the organism upon the environment. Our " ideas " are thus essen- tially tools by which to handle and to no WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? mold our experience. In short, they are to the pragmatist, as I have said, not so much beliefs or judgments as "plans of action." From this it follows naturally and almost inevitably that if the term truth is to be applied to such " ideas," it cannot be in the sense of " correspondence " as de- fined above.^ As " a plan of action " is not an assertion about something outside our experience, but a way of grouping our data or guiding our conduct, it cannot, of course, be maintained that its "truth" depends upon its relation to some outer reality. One indeed may wonder that the word truth should be applied to it at all, but once so applied it is evident that there is nothing for it to mean but usefulness and successful action. A true idea in this sense is there- fore one that works. This is especially manifest in the case of the laws of science, and I believe it was partly in this connection that the pragmatic identification of truth with usefulness first suggested itself. In so far as 1 See p. 67 THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH III a scientific law is a mere short-hand expres- sion for our experience, a mere formula for the condensed description of perceptions, its truth may be said to consist in its work- ing.^ In short, if an hj^othesis proves itself a useful tool, it is forthwith called true, — true, that is, for immediate practical purposes, — and thus truth comes to be re- garded as merely a "form of the good." As an example. Professor Dewey speaks of the invention of the telephone as a plan of action or idea that worked itself out, i.e. proved itself " true." And it is evident that if the word true is to be applied to inventions and similar plans of action at all, their " truth " is indeed " wholly an affair of making them true." Before entering any criticism upon this view we must first note, for the sake of our own comprehension of the subject, the 1 A deeper reflection, however, will inevitably raise the question why it works, and this can hardly be answered with- out reference to an environing reality ; and thus we shall be brought back to the stricter sense of truth and the correspond- ence theory. 112 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? decidedly different meaning given to "idea" by the non-pragmatist. When the non- pragmatist says an " idea " is true, he uses the word to mean, not a plan of action, but a judgment. To him an idea which is not a judgment but is a mere image or plan or formula may lead in what direction it likes, it may be useful, successful, satis- factory, or their opposites, it may have any function you will, but it is not in the category of things that can be either true or false. In Bosanquet's words, " truth and falsehood are coextensive with judgment." ^ This being the case, the non-pragmatist does not and cannot consider " true " a predicate of the same kind as " benevolent " or " luminous " or " good " (as the pragma- tist suggests), nor can he identify " truth " (in the sense of trueness) with a " function " or " leading " or " process." And now to return to the pragmatist use of the word. Granted that, if the term truth is to be applied to a plan * " Logic," Vol. I, p. 72. THE PRAGMATIC VIEW OF TRUTH II3 or purpose at all, it may as well mean successful execution as anything else, is not the use of the word in this connec- tion, to say the least, unnatural and unnec- essarily confusing? An invention may be useful and may work and be successful, my plan to go downtown may be wise and good, but to call either of them true would seem to be a step toward the invention of a new language. And in spite of the undoubted truth in the biological view of mind, in spite of the fact that all ideas in some sense work them- selves out, it is not true that all " ideas," judgments included, are merely plans of action. A judgment has at least two differ- ent aspects. From one point of view it is indeed a motor idea which influences con- duct and works itself out. From another point of view it is an assertion about some reality not itself, and between it and that reality there is a relation which simply is not to be identified with the results of the judg- ment. This distinction between the two 114 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? aspects of a judgment, or between judgments and plans of action, seems to be quite overlooked by thinkers of widely different schools — e.g. by Professor Dewey, on the one hand, and Professor Royce,^ on the other. These writers often deal with the subject of truth as if there were no distinction between judgment and purpose. Thus Professor Dewey tries to interpret judgments as plans of action by saying " the agreement, corre- spondence, is between purpose, plan, and its own execution, fulfillment."^ But take any ordinary judgment such as " The sun is shin- ing," or " The Greeks defeated the Persians 1 Professor Moore has conclusively shown that if " idea " be taken to mean purpose, as Royce insists it shall, then the "truth" of an idea must be the fulfillment of the purpose within our experience, and not (as Royce says) the " corre- spondence between our ideas and their objects." To reach any relation between an idea and a reality outside of one's private stream of consciousness, Royce has practically to give up the purposive function of ideas as their most essential characteristic, and to speak of them as representative. See " The World and the Individual," Lectures I, VII, and VIII, and Moore's " Some Logical Aspects of Purpose," in " Studies in Logical Theory," pp. 341-382. " « The Control of Ideas by Facts," / 2S3-2S9> 309-319- * pp. 53-80. 6 pp. 239-270, PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION l8l Moreover, the fundamental epistemological principles of pragmatism have a necessary and direct bearing upon the religious prob- lems which even a non-pragmatist has a right to point out. The present lecture, therefore, falls naturally into two parts, — it must deal with the general attitude which most pragmatists by temperament hold to- ward religion, and, secondly, it must outline more definitely and in particular the view which pragmatism as such ought to hold if its presuppositions are to be logically carried out. The same temperamental bias which makes the pragmatist lean toward a vol- untaristic psychology and define truth in terms of value usually tends to make him also a pluralist rather than a monist, a be- liever in free will rather than in determin- ism, an upholder of the strenuous, dynamic, dramatic view of the universe in which there are real dangers and genuine crises, rather than an advocate of absolutism with its peaceful and static world in which every- thing is saved from all eternity. To the l82 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? pragmatist of the James-Schiller type, re- ligion means something very vital and real. The religious view of the world for him is not just the naturalistic view under a new light and with a new name, as is the case too often with some Hegelian philoso- phers ; it is a genuinely and practically dif- ferent world — different in the pragmatic sense of making a difference. " Religion," says Professor James, " in her fullest exercise of function, is not a mere illumination of facts already elsewhere given, not a mere passion, like love, which views things in a rosier light. It is indeed that, but it is something more ; namely, a postulator of new facts as well. The world interpreted religiously is not the materialistic world over again, with an altered expression ; it must have, over and above the altered expression, a natural constitution different at some points from that which a materialistic world would have. It must be such that different events can be expected in it, different con- duct be required." ^ 1 <• The Varieties of Religious Experience," p. JiS. PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 1 83 And, to be more explicit, the pragmatic temper finds especially congenial the psy- chological rather than the scholastic view of religion. It likes to look upon religion neither as a divine revelation nor as a phil- osophical construction, but as an essentially human product and one which gets its justi- fication and authority, and its proof (so far as it has any), from the very nature of man, and from its own usefulness to man. Pro- fessor James speaks of his method of evalu- ating religions as " the elimination of the humanly unfit and the survival of the hu- manly fittest, applied to religious beliefs " ; and, he adds, "if we look at history candidly and without prejudice, we have to admit that no religion has ever in the long run established or proved itself in any other way. Religions have approved themselves; they have ministered to sundry vital needs which they found reigning. When they violated other needs too strongly, or when other faiths came which served the same needs better, the first religions were supplanted."^ ^ "The Varieties of Religious Experience," p. 331. 1 84 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? Hence the pragmatist is likely to look with a good deal of favor on the " psychology of religion " and to emphasize the human utility of the various religious concepts. Nor does this involve any lack of belief in the religious view of the universe on the part of the pragmatist. He is indeed skeptical of the value of the historical proofs of God, and is the chief antagonist of the idealistic Absolute. Yet, for all that, he is, as a rule, essentially and temperamentally religious, and he has his own arguments for a religious Weltanschauung. One of these he finds in the very nature of man and of re- ligion as portrayed by contemporary psy- chology. Religion goes deeper than do any of its intellectual formulations ; it springs not from the abstract reason but from the whole man. It is biological rather than intellec- tual, and is an almost instinctive reaction of man to his environment. Religious belief of some kind is a normal and almost a neces- sary human product, and for this reason may be and (in fact) must be trusted. Moreover, PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 1 85 our trust in it is justified in the same gen- eral way in which scientific hypotheses are justified : it stands the test of usefulness. It works; it ministers to human needs ; it com- bines harmoniously, on the whole, with hu- man experience, and it furthers human life and happiness. This, says the pragmatist, is the only kind of verification to be found in science, and though in the case of reli- gion the verification is much less exact and complete, it is essentially of the same nature and is sufficient to justify our trust until positively overthrown. For although the beliefs of religion are as yet only partially verified, that is what one must expect from the enormous magnitude and complexity of religion's problem ; and it must be remem- bered, too, that the relatively simple " laws " and " truths " of science, now universally accepted, were one day in the same position and started out as mere postulates. " Sci- ence too takes risks, " as Schiller says, " and ventures herself on postulates, hypotheses, and analogies, which seem wild, until they 1 86 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? are tamed to our service and confirmed in their allegiance. She too must end by say- ing Credo ut intelligam. And she does this because she must. For, as Professor Dewey has admirably shown, all values and meanings rest upon beliefs, and, 'we cannot preserve significance and decline the per- sonal attitude in which it is inscribed and operative. . . .' We start, then, always from the postulates of faith, and transmute them, slowly, into the axioms of reason. The presuppositions of scientific knowledge and religious faith are the same." -^ Pragmatism thus seeks to prove the truth of religion by its good and satisfactory con- sequences. Here, however, a distinction must be made ; namely, between the " good, " harmonious, and logically confirmatory con- sequences of religious concepts as such, and the good and pleasant consequences which come from believing these concepts. It is one thing to say a belief is true because the logical consequences that flow from it fit in * " Studies in Humanism," pp. 361-362. PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 1 87 harmoniously with our otherwise grounded knowledge ; and quite another thing to call it true because it is pleasant to believe. We may conceive, therefore, two perfectly distinct methods of verification through con- sequences. The first is exactly that used by science ; the second (namely, through conse- quences which flow not from the idea as such but from our believing it) is very far removed from the scientific method, and is held only by pragmatists — if it be really held even by them. That it is so held by some at least, would seem to be clear from such expressions as the following : " If theologi- cal ideas prove to have a value for concrete life, they will be true, in the sense of being good for so much. " " So far as the Absolute affords comfort it surely is not sterile, it has that amount of value ; it performs a concrete function. As a good pragmatist I myself ought to call the Absolute true in so far forth then; and I unhesitatingly now do so."^ It would seem, therefore, that any- 1 " Pragmatism," p. 73. 1 88 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? thing is true " in so far forth " which it is comfortable to believe. But whether prag- matism really holds this doctrine is doubtful. As Professor Dewey says, " Light would be thrown upon how Mr. James conceives this matter by statements from him on such points as these: If ideas terminate in good consequences, but yet the goodness of the consequences was no part of the intention of the idea, does the goodness have any ver- ifying force ? If the goodness of conse- quences arises from the context of the idea in belief rather than from the idea itself, does it have any verifying force .'' If an idea leads to consequences which are good in the one respect only of fulfilling the intent of the idea (as when one drinks a liquid to test the idea that it is a poison) does the badness of the consequences in every other respect detract from the verifying force of these conse- quences V'^ Certainly if pragmatism means that any- 1 " What does Pragmatism mean by Practical ? " Jour, of Phil., Vol. V, pp. 93-94. PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 1 89 thing may be proved true if the consequences of believing it are comforting, it is provided with a very cheap and easy method of dem- onstration. Pragmatists are always indig- nant at the common accusation that they teach us we may believe whatever we like ; but it must be admitted there is consider- able excuse, as Professor Dewey has himself pointed out above, for this interpretation of their doctrine. However, I shall not press this point farther nor take seriously the im- plication that any good consequences which flow from our belief in an hypothesis can be used to prove its truth. And certainly if pragmatism does not mean to use this rather questionable method of verification, but seeks to demonstrate the truth of religious doctrines purely from their own proper and necessary consequences, it is on good logical and scien- tific ground. How far these consequences actually do prove the doctrines referred to is, of course, another question ; and it must be admitted that pragmatism has as yet made but little serious attempt in concrete detail I go WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? to furnish this sort of verification for our religious concepts. So much for the pragmatist's way of prov- ing the truth of our religious beliefs. But this is only a part of what he has to say in defense of faith. For, he continues, even if the proof of religion be not complete, it is at least as good as that of the opposite view, and therefore, seeing that one must choose between rival hypotheses neither of which can be demonstrated, one has a right to take refuge in the will to believe. For belief, after all, is no mere cold intellectualistic state of mind, but has in^it an element of will and of emotion. On vital questions where there is genuine uncertainty one cannot forever keep decision in abeyance. Hence the prag- matist, as a general thing, takes his stand and makes his life venture on the side which promises most if once accepted. Life is better, sweeter, more worthy and worth while with some sort of religious belief than with- out it ; hence, says the pragmatist, since such a belief is at least as well grounded as its PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 191 rival, let us deliberately adopt it as a working hypothesis until it is discredited. Thus a road is opened to religious faith even for those who feel (as modern men are coming more and more to feel) that demon- stration in religious matters is no longer to be expected. For such men, this is perhaps the only protection against a rather sad skep- ticism. And it is a protection because it shows that skepticism itself is quite as much a voluntary choice as is the religious attitude. Choose we must, whether we will or no. Says Professor James, in the famous book which is the very Gospel of this Justification of Faith, " We cannot escape the issue by re- maining skeptical and waiting for more light, because although we do avoid error in that way, if religion be untrue, we lose the good if it be true, just as certainly as if we posi- tively choose to disbelieve. . . . Skepticism then is not avoidance of option ; it is option of a certain particular kind of risk. Better risk loss of truth than chance of error — that is your faith-vetoer's exact position. He is 192 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? actively playing his stake as much as the be- liever is ; he is backing the field against the religious hypothesis, just as the believer is backing the religious hypothesis against the field. To preach skepticism to us as a duty until 'sufficient evidence' for religion be found, is tantamount, therefore, to telling us, when in the presence of the religious hypoth- esis, that to yield to our fear of its being error is wiser and better than to yield to our hope that it may be true. . . . And dupery for dupery, what proof is there that dupery through hope is so much worse than dupery through fear? I, for one, can see no proof; and I simply refuse obedience to the scien- tist's command to imitate his kind of option, in a case where my own stake is important enough to give me the right to choose my own form of risk. If religion be true and the evidence for it be still insufficient, I do not wish by putting your extinguisher upon my nature (which feels to me as if it had after all some business in this matter) to for- feit my sole chance in life of getting upon the PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 1 93 winning side — that chance depending, of course, on my willingness to run the risk of acting as if my passional need of taking the world religiously might be prophetic and right." ^ This, as I have said, is the position taken by most pragmatists. That it is so is due to the general tendencies of their disposition and temperament, rather than to any logical and necessary connection between it and their epistemology. Nor is it by any means pecul- iar to them. It was already old long before pragmatism was born, and is to-day enthusi- astically supported by many pronounced antagonists of pragmatism. Cicero voiced something very like it when he said he would rather be wrong with Plato than right with Plato's opponents. And every one will remember that Kant came even nearer to the " will to believe " when he destroyed knowledge in order to substitute faith. It was, of course, this general point of view that prompted his advocacy of the primacy 1 "The Will to Believe," pp. 26-27. 194 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? of the practical reason and his moral argu- ment for God. This same attempt to found religion on the moral will was carried farther by Fichte and still farther by Ritschl. The merit of Professor James's brilliant book lay not so much in its originality, as in its giv- ing this century-old doctrine a broader philosophical setting and foundation, by showing that not only religious belief but nearly all belief is in part a matter of will, and in presenting the right to believe in a form at once so persuasive and so inspiring. I think I shall be justified in saying that James's " Will to Believe " has been one of the greatest influences for genuine religious faith that have appeared in the last half century. So much for the religious views actually held by many pragmatists. And now for the less interesting but really more important attempt to work out the logical consequences of pragmatic epistemology as applied to re- ligious problems. Our question therefore is not, What attitude does the pragmatist usually PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 1 95 take? but What attitude ought he to take if he is going to be faithful to his own presup- positions ? I have said that the view which holds the beliefs of religion to be true because of their value for life, and which maintains that we have a right to believe them even when unverified, is not peculiar to pragmatism, and that it does not follow from the funda- mental principles concerning knowledge, truth, and meaning which alone are uniquely pragmatic. But one must go farther than this : and, in fact, the thesis which I shall seek to maintain will be that it is logically inconsistent to proclaim and carry out the more extreme and radical pragmatic prin- ciples, and at the same time cling to the religious view of the universe and seek to uphold genuine belief in it. The extreme pragmatist view, if I under- stand it aright, maintains that the meaning of any philosophic proposition can always be brought down to some particular conse- quence in human experience. A true belief 196 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? if it has any meaning always " has a bearing on some human interest." "Theoretical truth is no relation between our mind and the archetypal reality. It falls within the mind, being the accord of some of its pro- cesses and objects with other processes and objects." It is " an experienced relation," or " the effective working of an idea," or the process of the idea's verification. Hence all genuine meaning and all truth (and, of course, all knowledge as well) lie within the individual's experience, or, at the broadest, within the experience of the human race. The beliefs of religion, on the other hand, — the very beliefs for which we have seen the pragmatists so valiantly fighting, — are largely concerned with matters which by their nature lie beyond the limits of human experience. Primal among these, for ex- ample, is the belief in a God, — not merely in future experiences of yours and mine which will be " the same as if " there were a God, but in the actual present existence of a divine being who by definition is not within PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 197 the experience of any or all of us. What- ever the pragmatists may mean by God, this at least is what the religious man means by the term and what the pragmatist is natu- rally supposed to mean when arguing for the religious hypothesis. And it must be clear to every one that if all truth and meaning are confined to consequences within our human experience, we are deprived of all right to talk about and believe in a being who by the very conditions of the argument is not included within our experience. To this the pragmatist will reply that the very peculiarities of the pragmatic epistemol- ogy which I have pointed out make it really the only sure salvation from philosophic doubt. All other views of truth and knowl- edge but his own, the pragmatist will main- tain, are by their nature doomed to end in skepticism. For once admit the necessity of transcendence, the existence of a chasm be- tween your idea and its object, and you have made knowledge forever impossible. Knowl- edge is possible and skepticism vanquished 198 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? only for a theory which denies the existence of any chasm and the necessity of any tran- scendence. This is exactly what pragmatism does. It points out that the whole of your genuine meaning can always be summed up in some possible difference in your own (or other human) life ; that truth is only a con- crete process within the mind ; and that knowledge is a succession of the doubt-in- quiry-answer type and " lives wholly inside the tissue of experience." Hence your idea and its object are not separated by any chasm, but are both parts of the same chain and united by intermediaries of the same nature. Your idea therefore may genuinely know its object and may be proved true since its truth consists just in its satisfactory working. Ap- ply this now to religion, and all becomes clear. " If theological ideas prove to have a value for concrete life, they will be true in the sense of being good for so much." " On prag- matistic principles if the hypothesis of God works satisfactorily in the widest sense of the word, it is true." ^ Of course, you must 1 " Pragmatism," pp. 73 and 299. PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 1 99 consider with care the question whether it does really work satisfactorily ; but if it does, that is all you mean by its being true, and thus the chasm and the need of transcend- ence is avoided. Thus pragmatism attempts to save us from philosaphic doubt by making knowledge, truth, and meaning have their entire being within the tissue of human experience. Buti it was not the things within human expe-< rience which we were ever tempted to doubt. It was the things outside human expe- rience, — God, immortality, the moral nature of the universe, the final victory of the right, — it was of these we felt doubtful. And how does pragmatism help us here ? It does not pretend to tell us what our future expe- rience will be, much less to declare to us the things that are outside all possible human experience. Its message is really this : You may believe there is a God because all you mean by a God is certain " adjustments of our attitudes of hope and expectation." A " vague confidence in the future is the sole 200 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? pragmatic meaning at present discernible in the terms design and designer." " Other than this practical significance, the words God, free will, design, have none." ^ " When I affirm that the metaphysical the- ory of the Absolute is false," says Schiller, "I only mean that it is useless, that it simplifies nothing and complicates everjd:hing." ^ And the consistent pragmatist, of course, holds the converse of this; namely, that when he affirms that the theory of God is true he means only that it is useful, that it simplifies things within experience — not that there really is a God. This (if I understand him) is the avowed attitude of Professor Dewey, and it certainly is the only logical and con- sistent attitude of any pragmatist who takes his own doctrines of truth and meaning seriously. Of course, this view of religion is not what the reading public understands the pragmatist to mean when he so bravely tells us we have a right to believe in God. * " Pragmatism," pp. iij, 121. ^ " Humanism," p. 59. PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 20I There is a general impression abroad that pragmatism has somehow discovered a short cut to God and religion which makes skepticism no longer tenable, and that if one ever became a real philosophical prag- matist, one would understand what it was. And in fact nearly all the pragmatists themselves, except perhaps Professor Dewey and some of his followers, at times feel the need of something more solid and objective than the sort of " God " one comes to by strict pragmatic principles. Thus at the close of his " Varieties of Religious Experi- ence," Professor James points out that one's " subjective way of feeling things " is not all one wants from religious beliefs; one wants to know also about the "objective truth of their content " ; and he adds in a note, " The word ' truth ' is here taken to mean something additional to bare value for life." ^ The attempt of Professor James to prove the old-fashioned God by the new- iashioned argument is well criticised by » p. 509. 202 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? Professor Dewey in the admirable article from which I have already quoted. " Con- sider," he says, " the case of design. Mr. James begins by accepting a ready-made notion, to which he then applies the prag- matic criterion. The traditional notion is that of a "'seeing force that runs things.' This is rationalistically and retrospectively empty; its being there makes no difference. But ' returning with it into experience, we gain a more confiding outlook on the future. If not a blind force but a seeing force runs things, we may reasonably expect better issues. This vague confidence in the future is the sole pragmatic meaning at present dis- cernible in the terms design and designer* [quoted from James]. Now," Dewey con- tinues, " is this intended to replace the mean- ing of a ' seeing force which runs things '.? Or is it intended to superadd a pragmatic value and validation to that concept of a see- ing force.'' Or does it mean that, irrespec- tive of the existence of any such object, a belief in it has that value .'' Strict prag- PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 203 matism would seem to require the first in- terpretation, but I do not think that is what Mr. James intends." Professor Dewey then takes up the ques- tion of theism and materialism. Strict pragmatism would tell us that the only meaning of theism lies in the differences it makes to us, and would therefore substi- tute these concrete experiential differences for the old view of God as a " superhu- man power," and would, as Dewey says, " simply abolish the meaning of an ante- cedent power." ^ In short, we have in the common, loose, pragmatic treatment of religion another illus- tration of the tendency to smuggle in " intellectualistic " results to fill out the deficiencies left by pragmatic methods. " When God is presented as the name of an experienced fact, and theistic theories are taken as methods of interpreting that fact for purposes of response, we are on 1 " What does Pragmatism mean by Practical ? " pp. 90 and 91. 204 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? good pragmatic ground. But when it is declared that 'On pragmatist principles if the hypothesis of God works satisfactorily in the widest sense of the word it is true,' the implication to the innocent reader is far otherwise. We can hardly put the same eloquence into the naked pragmatic assertion, 'If the hypothesis of God works satisfac- torily in the widest sense of the word it does work satisfactorily in the widest sense of the word.' God as an addition to an already smoky image of reality at large, God as an aesthetic anticipation of what visual and other experiences we may have face to face when we have passed over the river, God in these simple 'copy' ways of con- sidering our ideas must be omitted, God must be the name of a fact in our experi- ence, and the determination of His ways must be the determination of our way of working out our wills in the light of that fact." 1 ^ Max Eastman in " The Pragmatic Meaning of Pragma- tism," a paper read before the Psychological Section of the New York Academy of Sciences. PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 205 The logical outcome of pragmatism, there- fore, when applied to religion is not salva- tion from philosophic doubt, but a necessary and ineradicable skepticism. This, indeed, might have been foreseen from the outset. We shall recognise it clearly enough if, with the light we have now attained, we read over again some of its fundamental principles. Take, for example, its chief "postulate," as presented by Professor Dewey. " Things — anything, everything, in the ordinary or non-technical use of the term thing — are what they are experienced as. Hence if one wishes to describe anything truly, his task is to tell what it is experienced as being." " The real significance of the prin- ciple is that of a method of philosophical analysis. If you wish to find out what sub- jective, objective, physical, mental, cosmic, psychic, cause, substance, purpose, activity, evil, being, quantity — any philosophical term in short — means, go to experience and see what it is experienced as." And, the pragmatist would of course continue, God 206 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? and the other objects of religion are what we experience them as, and (for us and our belief at least) nothing more. Certain aspects of our experience is all they can mean for us. And it is the same with their truth. Since the truth of an idea means merely the fact that the idea works, that fact is all you mean when you say the idea is true. Nothing more, noth- ing " transcendent " nor " cosmic " must be sought from it. It is a very simple matter, you see, — like the multiplication table, — "we simply fill the hole with the dirt we dug out. Why are twice two four.? Be- cause, in fact, four is twice two." It is thus a very easy thing to prove our belief in God to be true by the good consequences that flow from it, because all we mean by God is just those good consequences. The real out- come of pragmatism is therefore an assur- ance that the questions in which ordinary religious people are interested are essentially insoluble, — hopelessly insoluble, in fact, because of the very nature of knowledge and truth and meaning, — and that we should PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 207 therefore go about our business and fulfill as an hireling our day. For, as Professor Dewey says, " The appropriate subject- matter of awareness is not reality at large, a metaphysical heaven to be mimeographed at many removes upon a badly constructed mental carbon paper which yields at best only fragmentary, blurred, and erroneous copies. Its proper and legitimate object is that relationship of organism and environ- ment in which functioning is most amply and effectively attained ; or by which, in case of obstruction and consequent needed experimentation, its later eventual free course is most facilitated. As for the other reality, metaphysical reality at large, it may, so far as awareness is concerned, go to its own place." ^ This consignment of all questions about reality at large which do not directly concern the functioning of the organism to their " own place " (which may be anywhere you i"Does Reality Possess Practical Character?" in the Columbia Festschrift for James, pp. 70-71. 2o8 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? like except amongst suitable subjects for human discussion) is perfectly justified by, and, in fact, is the only logical conclusion from the fundamental principles of pragma- tism. For if these principles be correct, 'tis idle for us creatures of a day, who cannot even mean anything beyond our own experi- ence, to spend our time on questions neces- sarily so remote and inaccessible as are those which religious people think they are dis- cussing and about which they think they care. From them we are separated by a chasm much more impossible to pass than that which the rationalists seek to bridge with their method of transcendence. For if pragmatism be true, it is not a chasm, but an infinite stretch of empty space that bounds each of us — or at least the race — on every hand, so that if there be another side we at least can neither know nor even mean it. On such an epistemology the discussion of the old problems of religion becomes essen- tially a silly waste of time and gray matter, which might better be spent in tilling the PRAGMATISM AND RELIGION 209 soil and nourishing our psychophysical organism. " The Infinite, the Eternal, the All-good — these are names empty of all real meaning, idle fancies for minds that will dream or idly speculate instead of seeking to know and to make better the only real world there is, the world of experience. This world admits no reference to a superhuman reality. We are thus left with reality that is fragmentary only, with experience that is made up of flying, ever changing moments, with thought that never wins final truth, with temporal processes and no eternal to justify and give them meaning; with finite progress and no goal finally won; with a better and no best as the ultimate standard of value judgments. For the satis- faction of ethical and religious ideals and aspirations we must look to our possibly better selves. Our idealized selves are our gods; and the cry after the Divine, the Eternal, the Complete in knowledge and goodness, must be satisfied with that frag- ment of truth and goodness which is all 2IO WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? that our finite lives can possess in their best estate."^ Of course, this is not what most pragma- tists actually hold. But it is, I maintain, the logical outcome of their fundamental princi- ples — the principles which alone are pecul- iar to their philosophy. In short, if strictly carried out to its logical conclusions, prag- matism is essentially a philosophy of skepti- cism. Or better still, perhaps, in Papini's naive and ingenuous expression, " Pragma- tism is really less a philosophy than a method of doing without one." ^ Professor Russell, " Objective Idealism and Revised Empiricism — Discussion," Phil. Rev., Vol. XV, p. 633. LECTURE VI THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW LECTURE VI THE "PRACTICAL" POINT , OF VIEW "Howsoever these things are in men's depraved judgments and affections, yet truth, which only doth judge itself, teacheth that the inquiry of truth, which is the love- making or wooing of it; the knowledge of truth, which is the presence of it; and the belief of truth, which is the enjoying of it, is the sovereign good of human nature." These words of Francis Bacon contain within them the ultimate justification of all philosophy. Whoever accepts them will hold that philosophical investigation is an end in itself, needing no apology or de- fense ; while to the man who challenges them most philosophy will seem but a sorry/ waste of energy. The present controversy over pragmatism may at times appear to the non-technical 313 214 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? reader a battle between ghosts and shad- ows, a smoky discharge of weightless pro- jectiles, a ridiculously noisy war of words in a realm so far removed from the world of real life as to be quite out of touch with any genuine human interest. And even those of us who have somehow got en- tangled in the struggle feel now and then {crede experto) a disheartening doubt that perhaps the game is not worth the candle after all, and that maybe our manuscripts were better used for building fires and baking bread. This sense of uncertainty, however, and of the possible worthlessness of one's efforts, is not peculiar to those involved in the pragmatist controversy. Doubt of the same discouraging sort is apt to come at times upon every one en- gaged in theoretical pursuits of any nature and make him question seriously and sadly the value of his work. The Spirit that Denies is not far from any one of us, and is ever ready with his disconcerting sugges- tion, " It may be clever, but is it worth THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 215 while ? " At such moments it is well to turn back to our Francis Bacon and read again the comforting words of the father of English philosophy. They bring back courage to our hearts as the touch of earth renewed the strength of Antaeus. The possession of truth is "the sovereign good of human nature." We again feel sure that this is so ; for " truth, which alone doth judge itself, teacheth " it. To make "an unusually obstinate attempt to think clearly and consistently,"^ to carry out our thoughts to their logical conclusions, to see what we really mean and must mean by knowledge and truth, these may be pecul- iarly difficult and dreary tasks, but they are worth our while if the possession of truth is worth our while. The pragmatist controversy is not logomachy nor is it un- important. If the traditional view of truth and knowledge is meaningless, as the prag- matists contend, then we ought to know it, and not slumber on in dogmatic confidence ^ James's famous definition of metaphysics. 2l6 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? that our old bottles will stand the strain of the new wine which modern logic and modern science are pouring into them. If new bottles are necessary, by all means let us have them before the old ones perish and the wine be spilt. And if, on the other hand, the pragmatist substitutes for our older concepts are self-contradictory and land us in absurd and untenable positions, that too we ought to know. For clear think- ing is worth while for its own sake, and knowledge of the truth "is the sovereign good of human nature." Nor is the aim of either the pragmatists or their opponents merely controversial. At times it may seem so, but this appear- ance is merely superficial. To get the better of the other side is merely an inci- dental aim, and deep down below this runs the genuine and serious desire of both parties to get at the truth for its own sake. In a very real sense there is no controversy here but an investigation, there are not two parties but one, and the aim of all con- THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 217 cerned is to give each other mutual aid in the common search. The non-pragmatists genuinely wish to see pragmatism com- pletely developed and clearly expressed, and the pragmatists welcome all criticism, adverse or favorable, knowing that this will only aid them in thinking out their own thoughts logically and to the end. We are really partners rather than opponents, each seeking the same thing, each making common cause with the rest, and each wishing the other Godspeed. In man's long search after truth — " the lovemaking and wooing of it," as Bacon would say — it is possible to make out two chief tendencies or types of attitude. One class of mind has been so carried away with the joy of mental achievement, so en- chanted by the glory of truth, that in seeking and proclaiming it as the supreme end of life it has quite overlooked the fact that truth is not only an end but a means as well ; that it not only is a good, but also is good for something. The other type of 2l8 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? truth-seeker, noting the error of overem- phasis on truth merely as an end, has sought to counterbalance this mistake by laying its emphasis upon the practical value of truth and its possession ; pointing out that truth and knowledge are means to all sorts of other good things, that they are tools and implements which should be used as well as enjoyed, and that in our enthu- siasm over the possession of these things, the humbler practical values of life must not be slighted. It is to this latter tendency that pragma- tism belongs and it is to this broad, living, human point of view that it owes its rather striking popularity and the rapid progress that it has made among non-technical read- ers. For certainly it is not the special technical doctrines of pragmatism that have aroused so much real interest among the reading public. There is no great sponta- neous curiosity in the community at large concerning the interpretation of the terms "meaning," "truth," and "knowledge." It THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 219 is rather the pragmatist's large, big-hearted, practical way of looking at things that has attracted the general attention to what he has to say. The reading public is seldom interested in the technical and exact side of any science or discipline. It naturally and quite properly hates exactness. It likes X-rays and electrons and geological periods and light years and the survival of the fit- test; but when it comes to technical meth- ods and exact descriptions and definitions, it "wants to be excused." And, therefore, it loves pragmatism not as a technical phil- osophical doctrine, but as an interesting, belligerent, " practical " point of view. As such, however, pragmatism is, as I have said, only a part of a larger tendency, — a tendency which, though one of the most important characteristics of contempo- rary thought, is rather difficult to name or define. It might be called the empirical or the biological or the historical or, perhaps, simply the practical point of view. It has permeated so much of our thinking and has 220 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? taken on so many shades and aspects that it has no longer very much unity except as a general "psychological atmosphere," and also, perhaps, as a universal protest against the point of view which it opposes and has in part replaced. To make more plain what I have in mind, it will be necessary to say a few words about this prior point of view, which may be called (for want of a better name) that of excessive intellectualism. By this I mean, of course, the tendency already pointed out, which considers truth only as an end and never as a means, and so in part divorces truth and knowledge from the world of active and practical life. This way of conceiving things probably ante- dates history. It had no father, and it seems to have dominated in large part the thought of many of the ancient philosophers. The most famous of its early repfesentatives was, of course, Plato,^ For his severance of the ' It should also be pointed out, however, that there is a decidedly pragmatic tendency in Plato, inherited from his spiritual father, Socrates, and seen especially in his doctrine of the Idea of the Good. THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 221 world of " illusion " from the " real " world of Ideas, however great its value in some re- spects, was certainly the first long step toward the separation of " true knowledge " from the practical world of action and con- crete experience. And, immeasurable as is Plato's gift to philosophy, it cannot be denied that his sharp separation of our meanings from our individual, living experience, in which alone they are genuinely real, was fatal for both. The inaccessible and change- less world of abstract concepts, which Plato is at least supposed to have believed in, was erected for the purpose of explaining the changing world which we actually experi- ence, and the chasm which was made be- tween them defeated the very purpose for which the two had been distinguished. The purely and abstractly logical and intellec- tualistic, purified from all human taint, was so completely divorced from the emotional and volitional, from the struggle and en- deavor of concrete, pulsing actuality, that it became next to useless as a means of 222 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? rationalizing the world of our actual human experience. And while philosophy was con- structing this purely " ideal " realm, an ab- stract psychology was dividing man's mind into three sharply sundered faculties, and not only made reason supreme (as indeed it should), but abstractly " pure " and in- dependent. How far the above is a statement of Plato's philosophy and how far a caricature of it, is a question which for our present purposes is irrelevant ; for this at least is the interpretation of his meaning which has had most influence in the history of human thought. And it resulted in an exaltation of the abstract intellect and a contempt for the "passions" and feelings, the impulses and will attitudes of man, which dominated thought for two thousand years. Man was regarded and defined as a " thinking animal." That he was an animal was most unfortunate ; for thought, " pure " thought, was his " essence." The animal nature of man was hardly worthy of THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 223 investigation, the proper study of mankind being the abstract " Universals " of medize- val "Realism." Other influences besides that of Plato were brought to bear in this direction, — in fact, almost every philosopher for more than a thousand years contributed his share. Aristotle's was certainly too catholic a na- ture, too empirical a mind, to be a slave to any such excessive intellectualism ; yet his thought was so interpreted and his work so used that for centuries his influence also tended to bind philosophy and science in intellectualistic fetters. This was largely due, of course, to his placing the " theoreti- cal reason " far above the " practical reason." The syllogism, moreover, which he had contrived as a practical tool for man's use was made a fetish, and elaborated for its own sake. And the questions upon which it was used and to which most scholastic thinkers devoted their lives were sadly re- mote from human experience. Doubtless the abstractions and absurdities of mediaeval 224 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? thinkers have been greatly and unfairly exaggerated; yet, when all is said, it must be admitted that their views of man's na- ture and of man's problems were often false in the extreme, and their quibbles and logom- achy, their absurd interest in purely verbal questions, their expenditure of years upon mere fantastic puzzles, meant a pitiful and irreparable waste of really great intellectual power. The point of view of excessive intellec- tualism did not die with the mediaeval school- men. It has its representatives to-day, and it is against this tendency to worship the purely abstract intellect and its artificial problems that the modern spirit in general, and pragmatism in particular, protest. The newer point of view made its appearance in philosophy long, long ago; but from the growth of the natural sciences in the last century, the development of the historical sense, and especially the spread of biologi- cal ideas, it has taken new strength and even a new form. The attitude of the age THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 225 is expressed by the motto, " Knowledge is power." The suitable subjects for human investigation are seen to be those which - belong to this very world in which we live, and to our actual experience, — the prob- lems whose answers will make a real dif- ference to us. Already two hundred years ago it was perceived that " the proper study of mankind is man " ; and now that man has come to be studied seriously, empirically, scientifically, it is seen that he is a very different sort of creature from that which scholasticism painted him. A "thinking ani- mal," if you like, he is indeed ; but the modern conception puts the emphasis on the " animal " rather than on the " thinking." For, as it views him, man is not an ani- mal in order that he may think ; he thinks in order that he may be a better animal. Life is no longer conceived as existing for thai sake of knowledge ; knowledge exists for the sake of life. Thought is not the " essence " of man, nor is it for its own sake. It is^ merely one of man's tools by which he may 226 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? the better react upon his environment, and therefore stands iipon the same plane as his eyes and his stomach. It was developed by the struggle for existence according to the law of the survival of the fittest, for the defi- nite purpose of guiding the organism and so of helping to preserve the individual and to perpetuate the race. And contemporary physiological psychology, adopting the bio- logical point of view, has carried it out in detail, showing the exact place of thought in the economy of nature, — its position in the reflex arc pointing to its sole function; namely, the guidance of the individual's action upon the environment. Conscious- ness is really only a stop-gap for mechanical action. In the words of an eminent German psychologist,^ it is the " defect of habit." And our own foremost physiological psy- chologist writes as follows : — " The structural unity of the nervous system is a triad, neither of whose elements has any independent existence. The sen- 1 Max Dessoir in " Das Doppel-ich." THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 12-] sory impression exists only for the sake of awakening the central process of reflection, and the central process of reflection exists only for the sake of calling forth the final act. All action is thus r)?-action upon the outer world; and the middle stage of con- sideration or contemplation or thinking is only a place of transit, the bottom of a loop, both of whose ends have their point of application in the outer world. If it should ever have no roots in the outer world, if it should ever happen that it led to no active measures, it would fail of its essential function, and would have to be considered either pathological or abortive. The cur- rent of life which runs in at our eyes or ears is meant to run out at our hands, feet, or lips. The only use of the thoughts it occasions while inside is to determine its direction to whichever of these organs shall, on the whole, under the circumstances actually present, act in the way most pro- pitious to our welfare."^ > James, " Reflex Action and Theism," in « The Will to Believe," pp. 113, 114- 228 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? The difference between what may be called the intellectualistic and the practical views of thought and knowledge is admi- rably stated in another passage by the same brilliant writer. To the question, he says, why we must intellectualize, interpret, and understand our originally pure or raw expe- rience, rationalism and pragmatism give dif- ferent answers. " The rationalistic answer is that the theoretic life is absolute and its interests imperative, and that to understand is simply the duty of man, and that he who questions this need not be argued with, for by the fact of arguing he gives away his case. The pragmatic answer is that the environment kills as well as sustains us, and that the tendency of raw experience to extin- guish the experient himself is lessened just in the degree in which the elements in it that have a practical bearing upon life are analyzed out of the continuum and verbally fixed and coupled together, so that we may know what is in the wind for us and get ready to react in time. Had pure experi- THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 229 ence, the pragmatist says, been always per- fectly healthy, there would never have been the necessity of isolating or verbalizing any of its terms. We should just have experi- enced inarticulately and unintellectually en- joyed. This leaning on ' reaction ' in the pragmatist account implies that whenever we intellectualize a relatively pure experi- ence, we ought to do so for the sake of redescending to the purer or more concrete level again ; and that if an intellect stays aloft among its abstract terms and general- ized relations, and does not reinsert itself with its conclusions into some particular point of the immediate stream of life, it fails to finish out its function and leaves its normal race unrun. " Most rationalists nowadays will agree that pragmatism gives a true enough ac- count of the way in which our intellect arose at first, but they will deny these later implications. The case, they will say, re- sembles that of sexual love. Originating in the animal need of getting another genera- 230 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? tion born, this passion has developed second- arily such imperious spiritual needs that if you ask why another generation ought to be born at all, the answer is : ' Chiefly that love may go on/ Just so with our intellect : it originated as a practical means of serving life; but it has developed incidentally the function of understanding absolute truth ; and life itself now seems to be given chiefly as a means by which that function may be prosecuted."^ All of which the upholders of the practical or biological point of view of course deny. The advantages of this viewpoint are, of course, too obvious to need enumeration. It brings down knowledge from the skies and makes it concrete, useful, and living. It directs investigation into paths which lead us to genuine and valuable results. And it brings about a simplification and systematization of our knowledge which, to the scientist, is hard to overvalue. The i"The Thing and its Relations," Jour.of PhU., Vol. II, pp. 30-31. THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 231 various facts of psychology now get a defi- nite setting and fit in with the biological facts, with a place for everything and every- thing in its place, like beads on a string. The one great biological purpose — the forwarding of the life of the individual and of the race — is seen to dominate and to determine each detail, and thus makes the whole circle of the life sciences beautifully systematic and complete. Nor is it the life sciences alone that have thus been systematized and illumined by the newer point of view. The biologists have found it possible to apply their for- mula to ethics as well ; and by the aid of it have sought to throw new light on the meaning of duty and the moral imperative. Thus from them we learn that man's chief end is to put himself in line with the prog- ress of evolution and to make the purpose and aim of evolution his own. This aim and purpose is, we are told, the preserva- tion of the individual and the reproduction and "development" of the race. This is 232 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? shown by such facts as the following : that the organism is brought to full per- fection at the age of reproduction, that after that age is passed degeneration begins to set in, — the teeth decay and fall out, the eye grows less keen, the bodily force is abated, etc., etc. Individual preservation and race reproduction being thus the purpose of the evolutionary process, a " scientific " psychol- ogy must interpret all of man's functions in this light. His emotions are for the sake of stimulating him to action, his thought is for the guidance of that action, the action always aiming directly or in- directly at self-preservation or race repro- duction. Nothing else is for its own sake ; or, at any rate, if there seem to be other ultimate aims than action, they are either pathological or abortive. Hence knowledge is purely "practical" and for the sake of action, and the end of righteousness and ground of morality is the preservation of the race. Nor have the physiological psychologists THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 233 been behindhand in assisting the biologists to reformulate our ethical concepts. From one of the most enthusiastic of their num- ber, for example, I quote the following: — "Although to-day the old-fashioned dual- ism of sense and reason has been set aside in the higher scientific circles, and although psycho-physiological science is now in a con- dition to provide the necessary data for a detailed psycho-physiology of the Moral Im- perative," ethics " still continues to waste its efforts in the quest for the criterion of conduct." To seek for a moral criterion is vain, nor is the real truth about the prob- lems of right and wrong to be discovered by the antiquated and intellectualistic meth- ods of the ethical philosophers. It is to be gained only by a study of the reflex-arc. Genuinely to understand the moral impera- tive, it must be got at from the psycho- physiological point of view. Such a truly scientific study shows that "the Moral Im- perative is the psychic correlate of a reflec- tive, cerebro-spinal, ideo-motor process, the 234 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? efferent end of which is organized into motor tracts coordinated for a specific action." ^ After what I have said of the over-em- phasis in years past upon the abstract intel- lect and of the great value of the more modem practical point of view, I hope I shall not be accused of doing the latter injustice if I say that in some ways the reaction seems to have gone too far. The last quotation will perhaps illustrate my meaning. The biological tendency of con- temporary thought has contributed a great deal of value to our science and philosophy, but like many another excellent tendency it has, in my opinion, been somewhat over- emphasized. It has pressed its splendidly useful and illuminating formulae too far, it has attempted to simplify too much, and in doing so it has become somewhat narrow, somewhat blind, and somewhat unempirical.. Its formulae are able to explain a great deal ' Professor Leuba in " The Psycho-physiology of the- Moral Imperative," Am. Jour, of Psy.,Yo\. VIII, pp. 529-530. THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 235 of our reality; but, in our enthusiastic ap- plication of them, many things which they do not fit have been either bent out of shape or completely disregarded and left out of account. In fact the whole point and pur- pose of this lecture is to protest against this excessive practical or biological point of view, and to urge a partial return to some- thing like the old-fashioned intellectualism. I am very far from denying either the ex- cesses to which intellectualism has been carried, or the great value of the newer tendency. The reaction was needed, and it has been wonderfully productive and fruit- ful. But, to my thinking, the pendulum has now swung too far in the anti-intellectualistic direction. Especially is this the case with the bio- logical view of morality and knowledge. As to the former I need only point out that it is a very loose kind of reasoning which would hold it possible to determine anything about the highest good and the moral imperative from either the course of 236 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? evolution or the nature of the reflex-arc. It may be indeed that the " progress " of evolu- tion tends toward the highest good, but if we know this to be so it is because we know independently of the facts of evolution what we mean by the highest good. The moral imperative may indeed be " the psychic cor- relate of a reflective, cerebro-spinal, ideo- motor process," but it is not the moral imperative because of its correlation to this fearful and wonderful function. The ques- tion how duty is possible, the question what obligation means, are hardly answerable by pointing to the reflex-arc. The truth is, in our reaction against scholastic "logic-chop- ping," description is being substituted for definition, psychology for logic, the ought is neglected for the is, and questions of meaning are set aside or " answered " by theories of origin. Above all (in "the higher scientific circles" especially), the mighty shibboleth " Evolution " and the facts of physiological psychology are com- ing to be regarded as having the answer THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 237 to nearly all real questions. " Develop- ment" is the catchword of the times — without too much curiosity as to what we are developing toward, or why we should do it. Nor should the " practical " view of knowl- edge go altogether unchallenged. No one, indeed, would any longer deny the practical value of knowledge and thought in guiding, the reaction of the individual upon his eni vironment. But when it is maintained that this is the only value to be found in knowl- edge and reason, that all human values are ultimately matters of action, and that the possession of truth is always a means and never an end in itself, then, as it seems to me, it is time to call a halt and to reassert the old and trite thesis that to know the truth is worth while for its own sake. The whole splendid tradition of humanity's scholars and thinkers from the Greeks to the present day is evidence of this. The existence of pragmatism itself proves it. The noble army of "those who know," from 238 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? their master down, rises up to testify to the fact that knowledge itself, and even apart from its practical results, is one of the things most exceedingly worth while. And not only " worth while " is it ; it is as gen- uinely human, as genuinely natural and normal as is digestion or movement or reproduction. In the words of " that im- mortal sentence" of Aristotle's — '■'^ All men by nature desire knowledge^ ^ Nor can I here refrain from quoting a little more at length from "the master of those who know." " If men philosophized in order to escape ignorance it is evident that they pursued wisdom just for the sake of knowing, not for the sake of any advantage it might bring. This is shown too by the ••urse of events. For it is only after practically all things that are necessary for the comfort and convenience of life had been provided that this kind of knowledge began to be sought. Clearly, then, we pursue this knowl- edge for the sake of no extraneous use to 1 "Metaphysics," I, i. THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 239 which it may be put; but, just as we call a man free who serves his own and not another's will, so also this science is the only one of all the sciences that is liberal, for it is the only one that exists for its own sake. . . . More necessary, indeed, every other science may be than this ; more excellent there is none."^ I have ventured to dwell thus at length on the value of knowledge for its own sake to the human mind because the tendencies of contemporary thought (of which prag- matism is one of the most conspicuous representatives) seem to call for a protest from some one. This is perhaps the first time since the days of Plato when such a protest has been needed. That the posses- sion of reason and of truth was in itself one of the many genuine values of human life, irrespective of what you could do with them, was to our fathers simply a truism. But we, in our enthusiastic assertions that reason is for the sake of life, are almost forgetting ' lUd., I, 2 (BakewelPs Translation). 240 WHAT IS PBAGMATISM? that reason is a part and a product of life, — in fact its finest product and " the sov- ereign good of human nature" — and that in a very true sense, therefore, life may also be for the sake of reason. And I speak of this not only because the protest seems to me timely and need- ful, but also because in the modern de- thronement of reason, the new disregard of certain old distinctions, and the partial substitution of psychology for logic, there is apt to be involved a loss of respect for careful thought and a decreased endeavor after logical consistency. In our revolt against " rationalistic abstractions " and "pure reason" we are in danger of for- getting that the Principles of Contradiction and Identity still hold whether we recog- nize them or not, and that the canons of Aristotle's Logic cannot be disobeyed with impunity. We decry the logomachy, the hair-splitting distinctions, and the "logic- chopping " of the scholastics ; yet it may well be that in throwing these aside we THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 241 are surrendering some of the clear think- ing that went with them. Unless I have quite failed of my purpose in the preceding lectures, I need bring forth no further evidence of the dangers just referred to than pragmatism itself. Pragmatism is one of the signs of the times and is perhaps the most typical repre- sentative of the tendencies of which I have been speaking. A brief repetition and sum- mary of its principal positions will therefore not be out of place in concluding this, our final lecture. Pragmatism has too great contempt for " logic-chopping " and " hair-splitting dis- tinctions " to be willing to define for us exactly its view of the nature of meaning. The meaning of any concept, it assures us, is limited to the future practical conse- quences which come from it; — but, as it turns out, these ''practical consequences " mean theoretical ones also ; and it is not at all certain that the "future consequences" need be future after all. Pragmatism is in- 242 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? deed fully persuaded that nothing can have meaning which has not consequences in some one's experience ; but whether this " some one " refers merely to " ourselves " or may include sentient beings of the re- mote past and the distant future, God, and even purely imaginary beings, we cannot yet be perfectly sure. The new doctrine of meaning, on which pragmatism is founded, therefore amounts to this: that meaning is somehow or other related to experience, and probably limited to human experience. Further than this the pragmatist is pre- vented from refining, — for fear, apparently, of chopping logic. In his treatment of truth the pragmatist again on principle refuses (or is unable) to recognize a somewhat subtle but very real and important distinction; namely, that between the meaning of a thing and the proof of it, the distinction between the nature of a relation and our knowledge of it. The assertion that an idea might be true when not known to be true seems to THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 243 him meaningless; nor is he willing to admit any distinction between the truth of an idea and the concrete verification of its truth. When you prove the truth of a thing, the proof and the thing proved are one. In like manner, once you admit that a true idea usually " works," so that you can test its truth by its working, pragma- tism immediately concludes that its truth consists in its working, that its working is all you mean by its truth. In other words, since trueness and working usually go together, the two are identified, and we are told that we have here not two conJ cepts but one, and that when we say truel ness we mean working. And the question is not even asked whether the idea is true because it works or works because it is true — the one conception being simply substituted for the other.* All of which, in good, old-fashioned, much-derided scho- lastic language, is a complete confusion ' Here I should make exception of Professor James, who, in one passage, says plainly (as has been pointed out) that the idea works because it is true. 244 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? between " essence " and " accidents " ; i.e., between what we mean by truth and the mark or incidental quality by which we decide whether we have it or not. Failure to make distinctions of this kind and to seek for exactness in definition, and possibly also in part a pragmatic belittling of the rules of formal logic have led the pragmatists into the still more serious logi- cal difficulties pointed out in our second lecture on Truth. The moderate pragma- tists hold that the working of an idea is essential to its truth, yet that the idea may be true before it works ; while the radical school which makes the truth of an idea altogether a matter of satisfactory sequent experience is forced thereby to admit that under certain quite natural circumstances contradictory opposites must both be true at the same time and in the same sense. And both schools in all their writings are con- stantly seeking to establish for their theory the very kind of truth which that theory maintains is impossible and meaningless. THE "PRACTICAL" POINT GF VIEW 245 In the pragmatic doctrine of knowledge both the odd characteristics of the " large, loose way of pragmatism " (as the prag- matists so picturesquely and truthfully designate their method) reappear ; namely, its curious habit of shying at impor- tant distinctions and the consequent want of consistency that naturally results from looseness of thought. Thus prag- matism will not admit that there is any conceivable difference between a defini- tion of the nature of knowledge and a psychological description of the mental pro- cesses experienced by the individual when he knows. It will not consider the possi- bility that knowledge can be a different sort of thing from an individual's mental process. When you ask what is meant by knowledge pragmatism answers by telling you how you feel when you have it. The possibility of transcendence being thus dog- matically denied, error too becomes, in the long run, merely the way you feel. It is, therefore, quite possible for you and me to 246 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? hold diametrically opposite views on the same subject and both be said to know, provided we are both satisfied and remain satisfied with our respective opinions. Each man thus becomes for himself the measure of all things, and each man has knowledge provided his experience continues to feel satisfactory. And yet the pragmatist is cer- tain that on this question he is in posses- sion of knowledge and you are not, no matter how you feel about it. These principles concerning meaning, truth, and knowledge are, as I have said, the presuppositions and foundations of prag- matism. But before bringing these lectures to a close one word more should perhaps be added concerning the general pragmatic view of metaphysics and religion. Before doing this, however, I must make a dis- tinction between the pragmatists ; for in their metaphysical and religious attitudes they are far from being of one mind. Professor James has divided all thinkers into two types, the " tough-minded " and the THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 247 " tender-minded." The former tend to take the naturalistic, scientific, strictly logical view of the world, uninfluenced by human aspirations and desires. The latter look at things in more idealistic fashion ; with them religion and beauty and optimism have more influence than the bare facts of sci- ence or the cold results of reasoning. James has also pointed out that pragmatism is a compromise between the two types, sharing in the characteristics of each. This de- scription seems to me most apt, in respect both to the two tj^ies in general and to the position of pragmatism in particular. To carry it still further into detail, one might say more specifically that the pragmatist is tough-minded intellectually and tender- minded emotionally; or, better still, perhaps, that he is tough-minded and tender-hearted. It might, however, be more exact to say that there is really no such being as "the pragmatist," but that there are many prag- matists and that they are divisible roughly into two schools, — the tough-minded and the tender-minded respectively. 248 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? The tender-minded school is by far the more popular of the two — and, I suppose, justly so. It is interested in the logical and episte- mological principles of pragmatism not so much on their own account, as for the sake of the more humanly important and interest- ing conclusions that may be drawn from them. Its heart is really not so much in logic as in metaphysics and especially in religion. Its pragmatist technique it re- gards purely pragmatically, as a means rather than as an end. The eternally ab- sorbing questions of philosophy which have always appealed and always will appeal to the popular and the philosophic mind alike, are the things it really cares for. It is also essentially human. It dislikes blood- less abstractions and technical terminology and strives always to be clear, concrete, and vital. It is broad in its sympathies, charitable in its interpretations, and impa- tient only of scholastic logic-worship and the rationalistic Absolute. It has a fine feeling for reality, and will not allow its THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 249 own logical presuppositions permanently to hide from it the real living world. Its view of the universe being essentially opti- mistic (or at least " melioristic "), it likes interesting things and believes in them, Uninteresting things it finds hard to accept. [The rationalistic view of the world must be (false because it is " inert," " static," " stag- 1 nantly intellectualistic," — and the opposite ' view must be true because it is " dynamic " I and " dramatic." The tender-minded prag- matist is, in fact, the very impersonation lof the will to belifeve and the great pro- ■tagonist in the world of philosophy of the strenuous life. He treats philosophical questions in a large, generous, practical way, hates logic-chopping, and does not take even his own principles too seriously. It is fortunate for his conclusions that this is the case ; for they are reached not because of the pragmatist principles so much as in spite of them. No better illustration could be given of the oft-repeated remark « that our philosophical arguments are, as a 250 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? rule, afterthoughts which we construct to excuse or buoy up beUefs that originate and subsist quite independently of reason- ing. Only, in the case of pragmatism the philosophical presuppositions do not even excuse the belief. The tender-minded prag- matist accepts " God " and the conclusions of a religious metaphysics in much the same way as does the old-fashioned thinker, quite oblivious of the fact that if knowledge be merely experienced transition and truth be merely satisfactory consequences and transcendence be nothing but nonsense, it becomes quite absurd to take the old religious beliefs seriously. This fact is seen with perfect distinct- ness by the tough-minded pragmatist. He was, in truth, the first to point it out, nor has he been the last in drawing attention to the inconsistencies of his tender-minded brother. Thus, as we saw in the last lecture. Professor Dewey, with his tough- minded disregard for our prejudices, shows that if we cling to our pragmatist presup- THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 251 positions we can no longer mean by " God " a " seeing force that runs things," but only a vague expectation of better issues in our own experience. Both he and James, in fact, unite in saying : " This vague con- fidence in the future is the sole pragmatic meaning at present discernible in the terms design and designer." For the old notion of " God " as an antecedent Power who was and is and is to come, the consistent , pragmatist will carefully " substitute " the concrete differences which under certain conditions we shall experience, and he will "simply abolish the meaning of an antece- dent power." With the same unemotional logic, the tough-minded pragmatist points out that the biological view of thought and knowl- edge leads one inevitably to the same conclusion and shuts out the hypothetical objects of metaphysics and theology from the proper field of human thought. The mind exists for the purpose of guiding the reaction of the psycho-physical organism 252 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? upon its surroundings, and " its proper and legitimate object is that relationship of organism and environment in which func- tioning is most amply and effectively at- tained." The only realities that have or can have any genuine meaning for us are of the " practical " sort. All other " reality " — " metaphysical reality at large " — may, therefore, go to its own place. By thus deducing the logical conse- quences of his doctrine the tough-minded pragmatist has put us decidedly in his debt ; for now we can see clearly that the prag- matist controversy is not a mere academic discussion, but has truly pragmatic impor- tance. For it opens up the whole ques- tion of the nature of man and his position in Reality. Is man indeed what the bio- logical pragmatist considers him — a crea- ture of the environment, a successful animal, whose one aim is practical reaction upon his surroundings.? Or is he a twofold being.? Is he what the pragmatist de- scribes and, in addition to that, also what THE "PRACTICAL" POINT OF VIEW 253 Plato thought him — a citizen of the realm of eternal reason, the outgrown ape, who means more than he is, whose reach should and does exceed his grasp, who " partly is and wholly hopes to be " ? If the pragmatist is right, if it be true that man cannot mean more than he ex- periences, that his reach cannot exceed his grasp, if " God " and the " moral nature of the Universe " in the old sense are really meaningless terms, and if all this follows inevitably from the analysis of our mean- ings and our knowledge, then let us by all means know it, and give in our adherence to the pragmatic and biological view. But let us not accept this analysis too lightly nor without long weighing of its worth, forgetful of the consequences which such acceptance must logically carry in its train. The concepts we have been considering in these lectures may have seemed abstract and lifeless, but the deepest questions of our destiny ultimately hang upon them. And the attitude which we shall adopt 254 WHAT IS PRAGMATISM? toward the pragmatist principles will, if we be consistent, determine our whole philos- ophy, our whole outlook upon life and upon the world. If this fact be clearly- grasped I am sure no further excuse need be pleaded for the difficult and, I fear, dreary discussions that I have led you through during the course of these lectures. INDEX Absolute, 37, 56, S7i 100. 184, 187, 200, 248. Action in Pragmatism, 16, 18, 19, 226, 227, 237. Aristotle, 223, 238-240. Bacon, 213, 215. Biological View of Mind, 109, 113, 225-230, 234-237, 251- Bosanquet, 112. Bradley, 31, 37, 38, 52, 53, 67. Cicero, 193. "Claim," 57-63, 74, 75, 83, 87-89, 98, 103, 127. Correspondence Theory of Truth, 6S-79, 95. 96. 102. 106. 108, III note, 128. Dessoir, 226. Dewey, 9 note, 17, 21, 37, 57, 74 note, 92, 93, 97, 100, loi, 104, 108, 109, III, 114, 115, 123 note, 124 note, 125 note, 143, 145, 146, 150, 152, 163, 166, 179, 180, 186, 18S, 200-303, '°5> 207, 250. Eastman, 204 note. Ethics, see Morality. Ewer, 68. Faith, 13, 186, 190-194. Fichte, 194. Future Experience, 19, 38-37, 199, 241, 351. God, 12, 30, 35, 42, 13s, 184, 196-206, 209, 242, 250, 251, =53- "Idea" in Pragmatism, 109-115, 124 note, 125 note. Intellectualism, see Rationalism. James, 10, 12-14, 19. =Oi =3. =5. 26, 29, 30 note, 31, 33 note, 37, 41, 42 note, 57, 67, 68, 71, 74 note, 76, 79, 85, 90, 93- 97, 100, loi, 108, 129, 139, 142, 146-150, 152-159, 166, 180, 182, 183, 188, 191, 194, 201-203, 215 note, 226-230, 243 note, 246, 247, 251. Joachim, 52. Kant, 13, 193. Knowledge, 9, 131, 135-171, 177, 179, 196-199, 206, 213, 215, 216, 218, 220, 225, 230, 232, 235. 237-239, 242, 345, 346, 250, 253. Leuba, 233, 234. Locke, 135, 136. Logic, 14, 124 note, 136 note, 129, 130, 178, 236, 244. Lotze, 37. Lowell, 28. Man, 222-232, 352, 253. Materialism, 30, 31, 33-36, 303. Meaning, 9-46, 50, 63-65, 72, 74, 75. 78, 79. 139. 154. <77. 256 INDEX 186, 195-200, 202-206, 209, 218, 221, 236, 241, 242, 246, 253- Metaphysics, 13, 39, 4i, 43, 44, 177, 207, 246, 248, 250-253. Method in Pragmatism, 10, 12, 20, 38-45- Modified Pragmatism, 94-108, 244. Montague, 29 note i, 115 note. Moore, 114 note, 123 note. Morality, 13, 231-236. Ostwald, 14. Papini, 22, 43, 44, 210. Paulsen, 68. Pearson, 14. Pierce, 15, 16, 19. "Plan of Action," 17, 109-115, 144. Plato, 127, 137, 141, 143. 165, 193, 220-223, 239, 253. Practical Experience, 16, 19, 25, 28, 241. Rationalism, 77, 142, 220-224, 228-230, 235, 237-240, 249. Realism, 37, 65, 223. Reality, Pragmatic Theory of, 9, 178-180. Religion, 13, 42, 175-210, 246- 248, 250-253. Ritschl, 194. Royce, 17, 37, 114. Russell, 130 note 2, 210 note. Satisfaction, see Usefulness. Schiller, 22, 23, 25, 26, 37, 53, 57, 59. 71-73. 74 note, 75, 87-89, 92, 97, 101-103, 130, 179, 182, 185, 200. Scholasticism, 42, 223-225, 240. Science, 13, 14, 55, no, 185, 187, 224, 233, 239, 247. Skepticism, 130, 131, 191, 197, 201, 205, 210. Socrates, 220 note. Successful Working, see Useful- Theism, 30, 31, 33-36, 203. Theoretic Interests in Pragma- tism, 23-25, 39-43- Transcendence Theory of Knowl- xcdge, 138-140, 143, 149-162, 168-171, 197-199, 206, 208, 245. 250- Trueness, 52, 60, 65, 67, 70, 74, 83, 85, 86, 88, 89, 107, 112, 243- Truth, 8, 13, 15, 22, 45, 46, 47- 131. 141. 161, 177, 181, 185, 196-201, 204, 206, 209, 213, 215-220, 237, 239, 242-244, 246, 250. Usefulness, 13, 15, 61, 62, 90-121, 124 note, 125 note, 126, 145, 158, 159, 164-169, 185-189, 196, 198-200, 204, 206, 243, 244. 250- Verifiability, 94, 101-104, 118, 119. Verification, 61-64, 78, 86-88, 90- 107, 115-121, 127, 128, 145, 165, 185-190, 196, 198, 243,