iCORNELL LAW .UBRARY K^f^vJjiiSt.iwl dorttFll ICam ^rl|ooI IGibraty Digitized by Microsoft® KD 358.M23F53"'""""' '""'"^ V.I ^•"^ iiSStel?!. P.3P.era.. 0?. ..Frederic William 3 1924 021 686 229 Digitized by Microsoft® This book was digitized by Microsoft Corporation in cooperation witli Cornell University Libraries, 2007. You may use and print this copy in limited quantity for your personal purposes, but may not distribute or provide access to it (or modified or partial versions of it) for revenue-generating or other commercial purposes. Digitized by Microsoft® THE COLLECTED PAPERS OF FREDERIC WILLIAM MAITLAND IN THREE VOLUMES Volume I Digitized by Microsoft® CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS ILonUon; FETTER LANE, E.G. C. F. CLAY, Manager (StiinlurgI) : loo, PRINCES STREET JScrlin: A. ASHER AND CO. %tmis: F. A. BROCK HAUS jfleto lorfe: G. P. PUTNAM'S SONS JSomliaa nnlr (fCarratfn: MACMILLAN AND CO., Ltp. All rights reserved Digitized by Microsoft® THE COLLECTED PAPERS OF FREDERIC WILLIAM ^AITLAND DOWNING PROFESSOR OF THE LAWS OF ENGLAND EDITED BY H. A. L. FISHER VOLUME I Cambridge : at the University Press 191 1 Digitized by Microsoft® Camlit'tlige : PRINTED BY JOHN CLAY, M.A. AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS Digitized by Microsoft® CORNELL UNlVERSin JUN 26 1912 LAW LIBRARY INTRODUCTION WITH one important exception the three volumes here published practically represent the whole mass of Maitland's scattered writing. A few very short notices have been omitted, but wherever an article, however brief, contains a new grain of historical know- ledge or reveals Maitland's original thought upon some problem of law or history, it has been included in this collection. We begin with a philosophical dissertation suljmitted by a young Cambridge graduate to the examiners for a Trinity Fellowship and end with the tribute to the memory of a pupil composed only a few days before his last illness by a great master of history, by one of the greatest scholars in the annals of English scholarship. These papers cover a wide surface. Some are philosophical, others biographical, but for the most part they belong to Maitland's special sphere of legal and social history. Some pieces are confessedly popular, such as the brilliant outline of English legal history which concludes the second volume ; others, and of such is the bulk of the collection, are concerned with problems the simplest terms of which are not apprehended without special study. It would have «3 Digitized by Microsoft® vi Introduction been tempting to separate the more technical essays from the work of a simpler and larger pattern with which they are here intermingled ; but there were valid reasons against adopting such a course, and perhaps the convenience of the young student or general reader will be adequately consulted if the papers of a more popular character are marked by an asterisk in the table of contents. In any case it is well to remember that Maitland was both a great discoverer in history and an incomparable populariser of his own and of other men's knowledge. The size of the frame seemed to make little difference to him. Whether he worked in miniature or on a large canvas, his strokes were bold, certain and effective. ' The gladsome light of Jurisprudence' shone upon his toil. We have noted an important exception. Maitland contributed eight prefaces to as many volumes of the Selden Society as well as an introduction to the Memoranda de Parliamento or Records of a Parlia- ment holden at Westminster in 1 305, a volume published under the direction of the Master of the Rolls. These treatises, which are sufficient in themselves to furnish a substantial volume, are not included in this collection. They are easily accessible to students and could not without injury be wrenched from the texts which they are intended to introduce. Nor is there any fear that these masterly contributions to historical science will be neglected by those who are concerned with the study of our legal antiquities. The student who would know something of medieval law-reporting, or of the Digitized by Microsoft® IntroducHon vii Anglo-French language, or of the early history of the King's Court, or of the growth, extent and decline of manorial jurisdiction must have recourse to the learned and subtle discourses of the first literary Director of the Selden Society. And constitutional history in a wider sense is deep in his debt. If we would really understand our medieval parliamentary life, we must go first to the collection of records which Maitland edited for the Rolls series and out of which, placing ourselves at the threshold of the fourteenth century, we may apprehend the multitudinous clamours of medieval men, the form and shape of a medieval parliament and the course and conduct of its public operations. Save where a slight displacement might secure a convenient continuity of subject, the papers in this collection are arranged in the chronological order of their appearance. The first volume concludes with the Inaugural Lecture delivered upon Maitland's ap- pointment to the Downing Chair of the Laws of England in October, 1888, the second contains the scattered work of the Downing Professor previous to the appearance of the History of English Law in 1895, the third collects the gleanings of the last eleven years. As we leave the great History behind us we observe the flowering of fresh interests out of the massive fabric of the older knowledge. The third volume exhibits the full span of Maitland's versatile energy. Now he is handling the delicacies of the Elizabethan Church- Digitized by Microsoft® viii Introduction settlement, a subject far removed from his ordinary studies into which he was drawn by the seductions of Lord Acton ; now he is deep in the metaphysics of the Corporation ; now he appraises the latest achieve- ments of Germany either in the codification of her own modern law or in the editing of our neglected Anglo-Saxon dooms. There is no annotation either here or elsewhere on the part of the Editor, for though much has been written on social and legal history during the last thirty years, it does not in any appreciable degree affect the permanent value of Maitland's work. He wrote little, perhaps nothing, in early manhood which he would have cancelled in later years. He was always learned, always original, and in ninety-nine cases out of a hundred he was transparently right. With two exceptions the pieces here given have been previously published. The thanks of the Editor are due to the courtesy of Messrs Methuen who have kindly permitted the re-publication of the Deacon and the Jewess, a paper which forms part of Roman Canon Law in the Church of England, and to Messrs Cassell for their generous permission to make use of Maitland's contributions to Social England. He would also desire to express his gratitude to Messrs Longman, the publishers and to Mr R. L. Poole the editor of the English Historical Review ; to Messrs Stevens the publishers and to Sir Frederick Pollock the editor of the Law Quarterly Review, to Messrs Chapman and Hall the publishers and to Mr W. L. Courtney, the Digitized by Microsoft® Introduction ix editor of the Fortnightly Review, to Mr C. R. Buxton, the editor of the Independent Review, to Mr J. Sidney Stone, the editor of the Harvard law Review, to Professor Munroe Smith, the editor of the Political Science Quarterly, to Mr John Murray the pubHsher of the Quarterly Review, to the editors of the Athenaeum, of the Law Magazine and Review, of the Westminster Review, to the Council of the British Archaeological Association, to the Executive Com- mittee of the Society of Comparative Legislation, and to Messrs Sweet and Maxwell, the publishers of the Encyclopedia of the Laws of England for their kind permission to republish articles which appeared in the periodicals or books with which they are respectively connected. Fiffally, kind help has been received from Sir Frederick Pollock, and much assistance from the useful bibliography of Maitland's works appended to Mr A. L. Smith's two Oxford lectures. For the crimes of the Index the editor is solely responsible. H. F- February 191 1. Digitized by Microsoft® Digitized by Microsoft® TABLE OF CONTENTS VOLUME I Papers of a less technical character are marked by an asterisk. PAGES *A Historical Sketch of Liberty and Equality . . i — i6i *The Law of Real Property . . 162 — 201 The Laws of Wales. — The Kindred and the Blood Feud 202 — 229 The Criminal Liability of the Hundred . . 230 — 246 *Mr Herbert Spencer's Theory of Society 247 — 303 The Early History of MaHce Aforethought . . 304 — 328 The Seisin of Chattels .... . 329 — 357 The Mystery of Seisin ... . 358—384 *The Deacon and the Jewess ; or, Apostasy at Common Law 385 — 406 The Beatitude of Seisin ... . 407 — 457 The Suitors of the County Court . . 458 — 466 *The Shallows and Silences of Real Life . . . 467—479 *Why the History of English Law is not written . . 480 — 497 Digitized by Microsoft® Digitized by Microsoft® A HISTORICAL SKETCH OF LIBERTY AND EQUALITY AS IDEALS OF ENG- LISH POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY FROM THE TIME OF HOBBES TO THE TIME OF COLERIDGE \ (a) Liberty The simplest meaning of the word "Liberty" is absence of restraint. To the political philosopher it means absence of restraint on human action, and, since we are not speaking of the metaphysical freedom of the will, we may say absence of external restraint on human action. Further, as politicians, we are not con- cerned with those restraints which are due to causes over which we have no control ; we have only to deal with those external restraints on human action which are themselves the results of human action. But we cannot say that the Liberty which our philosophers praise is an absence of a// such restraints : the minimi- zation of all restraints on human action is an ideal of politics which has but lately made its appearance. No, the Liberty which our earlier philosophers praise is — (i) The absence of restraints imposed by certain persons ; or (2) The absence of certain forms of restraint ; or (3) The absence of restraints on certain classes of actions. To examine at some length the history of Liberty as a political ideal is the object of this present chapter. ' Submitted as a dissertation for a Fellowship at Trinity and privately printed in 1875. M. I Digitized by Microsoft® 2 Political Philosophy in England Naturally enough, the political question which most attracted philosophers in the seventeenth century was the question : — How can one man or body of men obtain a rightful title to rule other men. ? The great demand for political theory produced a somewhat injurious effect on the supply. Coleridge has remarked how, in times of great political excitement, the terms in which political theories are expressed become, not more and more practical, but more and more abstract and unpractical. It is in such times that men clothe their theories in universal terms, and preface their creeds by the widest of propositions. The absolute spirit is abroad. Relative or partial good seems a poor ideal ; it is not of these, or those men that we speak, of this nation, or that age, but of Man. Philo- sophers in the seventeenth century were not content with shewing that this or that government would be the best for our nation, that it would make Englishmen good, or virtuous, or happy ; they sought to strengthen their position by shewing that some form of govern- ment is universally and eternally the only right one. God and Nature, said the friends of the Stuarts, have decreed that we should submit to an absolute monarch. God and Nature, replied their opponents, have decreed that the consent of the governed can alone give a title to the governor. Both parties tried to answer the question as to what is the right form of government, without first answering more fundamental questions. They did, of course, occasionally refer to some standard, such as the good or welfare of the community ; but their main effort was to transcend such considerations, and to give a summary decision as to the right form Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 3 of government, without first considering the end for which all government should exist. They did not wish to compare, as Aristotle had done, the good and evil of various polities, but rather to shew that such a comparison is unnecessary. Such a procedure was unphilosophical. It is not possible to decide who ought to govern until we know what a government ought to do. By reversing the natural order of these questions political philosophy involved itself in a maze of fictions. These fictions were introduced as substitutes for an answer to the question : — What is it that governments ought to do .'' They were really ethical doctrines dis- guised as pieces of history. This mixture of ethics and history was very disastrous. When the limits of the royal power are under discussion, it is often hard to say whether the question is as to the limits which have been placed to the royal power, or as to the limits which ought to be placed to the royal power. In fact we can distinguish no less than four questions as involved, viz.: What limits do (i) positive law, (2) positive morality, (3) ideal law, (4) ideal morality, set to the royal power ? At the present day it would be easy to distinguish these. We can say what power law and opinion allow to the king, without trespassing on the realm of what ought to be. But in the seventeenth century this was harder to do, for several reasons — ( I ) The constitution of this country was not nearly so well defined as it now is ; there were gaps in it — points on which there was no case to appeal to. The question, "Who is sovereign?" could scarcely be answered, the fact being that sometimes the king, I — 2 Digitized by Microsoft® 4 Political Philosophy in England sometimes the king and Parliament had behaved as sovereign, and been acknowledged as such. (2) The confusion as to who was sovereign was increased by that curious doctrine of our Constitution which was being slowly formulated, namely, that though the king is subject to no law, he cannot absolve any other person from the laws made by king and Parlia- ment ; that royal immunity is coupled with ministerial responsibility. (3) The legal fiction of the perfection of the English Common Law, the supposition that there is somewhere a code of perfect law, by means of which an English judge may supplement the statutes (though at one stage of our progress necessary for the ad- ministration of substantial justice), produced injurious effects on political theory. Controversialists could so easily pass from the existing law to that law of perfect reason to which our judges appealed when in want of a new principle. This should be remembered when we hear Austin talking of "jargon" and "fustian." It may now be inexcusable to confuse law as it ought to be with law as it is, the ideal with the positive ; but in the seventeenth century it was almost impossible to draw this line, for the ideal was constantly becoming the positive. Our judges were obliged to introduce new principles, and were obliged to introduce them as if they were parts of a pre-existing law. In all these ways ethics were mixed with history, the ideal with the positive, until it is difficult to see how far an author is describing what is, how far he is giving an opinion as to what ought to be. The main question which the philosophers of the Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 5 seventeenth century had to answer was, How can one man, or body of men, acquire an authority over others which these latter ought to obey, and ought to be made to obey ? The answers which were given to this question were two. (i) God (or nature) has given to some men a title to rule, independent of all consent. (2) A title to rule can only be acquired by consent. These answers took many different forms, and some- times we find intermediate theories, but the twofold division must serve our present purpose. These two theories of the rightful title to rule we may call the natural and the conventional. I. Those who asserted that some men have a title to rule others, which does not depend upon consent, were frequent in their appeals to Aristotle. Aristotle was, for many reasons, the most popular of the classical writers on politics. In no department of philosophy, except perhaps that of deductive logic, has the influence of Aristotle been so long and so strongly felt as in that of politics. No history of the British Constitution would be complete which did not point out how much its growth has been affected by ideas derived from Aristotle. The common sayings about the excellence of a mixture of the simple forms of government, about subjecting the rulers to the laws, have an Aristotelian as well as an empirical origin, and accepted common- places are powerful agents in moulding a constitution. We cannot indeed ascribe any one very definite ten- dency to Aristotle's influence, for his Politics are singularly undogmatic ; but his disinterested curiosity discovered many-sided truths, some portions of which every school of political philosophers has been willing Digitized by Microsoft® 6 Political Philosophy in England to accept. On this very question of the title to rule he could not fairly be appealed to by any of our seven- teenth century controversialists, save perhaps Algernon Sydney. It is true that Aristotle held that some men have a title to rule others even when the consent of the latter has not been asked, but his idea of a natural title to rule scarcely suited the Caroline divines and lawyers. The classical, ideal polity, whether as con- ceived by Aristotle or as conceived by Plato, is an aristocracy, or monarchy of merit. The test of a man's natural title to rule is the possession of the power and will to rule well. No other test of a natural title was (as far as I know) ever dreamt of by a Greek philo- sopher. Now Sir Robert Filmer and his friends were glad enough to find Aristotle maintaining that some men are born to rule, and others to serve ; but this doctrine has its dangerous side — it leads to such specu- lations as those of Sydney, about the right of the virtuous man to rule. What Filmer and his colleagues had to justify was the feudal notion of hereditary right. A justification of feudalism was not to be obtained from Aristotle, so they turned to the other great source of authority — the Bible. It was said that God has given the sovereignty of the whole world to Adam and his heirs (or heirs males) for ever ; that the heir of Adam, or failing him, the heir of the last person who filled the place of Adam's heir, is rightfully king. This is as accurate a statement as I can make of a theory which, though legal in its pretensions, was never stated with legal accuracy. With this was combined the theory that civil power is in its origin paternal or patriarchal power. Now, as Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 7 far as history is concerned, the Divine Right School were nearer the truth than their opponents. Modern writers have taught us that the first rulers are fathers of families, that the fiction of relationship between the governors and the governed is kept up long after the fact has ceased, and that, on the death of the father of the family, common consent allows his power to devolve upon his eldest son. The Bible supplied these facts, and was supposed to supply them as precedents. But much more than this was wanted. It was necessary to shew that God has decreed that the power of a dead monarch shall devolve according to certain ascertain- able canons of inheritance; to shew {e.g.) that the Salic law is or is not such a canon, or that it is so in France, but not in England. It is needless to say that nothing of the sort could be done. The law which regulates the Royal Succession in England is only a law of God, if the whole of our common and statute law is a law of God. It is not even a part of Jus Gentium, the law common to all nations. Every Christian, it is true, looks upon his duties as divinely appointed ; obedience to rulers is, within certain limits, a duty, and, a Christian would say, a duty set us by God ; but this does not imply that God has singled out this or that man to rule, unless we use the words in a sense which makes every event, good or bad, the result of Divine will. The appeal to the Bible was singularly unfortunate. The Old Testament is the history of a nation which sinned in asking for a king, and which more than once interfered with the hereditary succession of the royal line. Many Puritans believed that they had precisely the same justification for killing Charles that Jehu had Digitized by Microsoft® 8 Political Philosophy in England for killing Ahab. The New Testament contains many commands of obedience to de facto governments, not one rule for selecting a sovereign de y'ure ; it is the powers that be, not the powers that ought to be, that we are to obey ; indeed, quotations from the New Testament come better from Hobbes, the supporter of de facto governments, than from the preachers of the Divine right of hereditary monarchy. It is almost impossible to believe that some of the arguments drawn from Scripture by the friends of the Stuarts were put forward in good faith. In the whole history of delusion there is nothing stranger than the claim of sovereignty for Adam's heir. Many people seem to think that this claim was a fiction of Whigs like Locke, got up to discredit the Tories ; but as a fact we find the argu- ment repeated by writer after writer of undoubted probity. Failing the support of the Scriptures, there was nothing for the theory to rest on save expedience, and this was too low a ground for the preachers of Divine right. No one (as far as I know) has asserted that we perceive intuitively that hereditary monarchy is at all times, and in all places, the one right form of government. The nearest approach to such an assertion that I can find is in the Jus Regium of Sir George Mackenzie, a reply to Buchanan's De Jure Regni, where it is said that hereditary succession is according to the law of nature ; but, after all, the law of nature appears only to give us the truism that in a hereditary monarchy the heir should succeed \ This book of Mackenzie's, for which he received the thanks of the University of Oxford, is a most extraordinary ^ Mackenzie's Works, vol. ii. p. 472. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 9 display of the weakness of the Divine Right School, and makes the grave faults of Locke's works seem venial. If the purely Scriptural argument fails, then the whole question of the best form of government is again thrown open. If its defenders cannot shew that hereditary monarchy has been expressly commanded by God, they may be required to shew that it answers to some standard of political good, that it would make a nation moral or happy. We may notice two forms of the theory : the stricter, which, giving to Adam absolute power, did not admit that any part of this had been alienated by him or his successors ; and the milder, which allowed that successive kings had granted away portions of the originally complete power which could not be resumed by themselves or their successors. The first form was advocated by Filmer, the second by Clarendon. Filmer was an acute controversialist, and hit both Hobbes and Milton some hard blows. But even he is obliged to admit that a prince is bound by his "own just and reasonable conventions " ; the prince however being the judge of their justice'. This concession renders his apology for absolute monarchy weaker than that of Hobbes, who, by making the prince the fountain of morality as well as of law, sought to deprive the subjects of any ground from which they might criticise the prince's acts. The more moderate believers in Divine hereditary right found a spokesman in Clarendon. Filmer had read the De Cive "with no small content'," Clarendon ^ The Power of Kings, etc. ^ Observations on Aristotle's Politics, etc. Digitized by Microsoft® lo Political Philosophy in England had never read a " book containing so much sedition, treason, and impiety as this Leviathan^." Like Roger Coke, and others, he thought that Hobbes had damaged the king's cause. The king, he held, had been invested by God and Nature with complete power, but some of this had been irrevocably granted away by charters, and so forth ; he speaks of monarchical power as a trust, and holds the king bound by his own and his ancestors' promises^ Sir George Mackenzie made a similar damaging admission ; he ^oes further ; the king may not interfere with the rights of property'. Now this is to surrender the stronghold of Divine right. If power be a trust, if it be possible to diminish it by grant, we must, as Hobbes knew well, retire from the high ground of natural right to the low ground of advisability. For the question arises— Is cestui que trust to have no remedy against his trustee in case of a breach of trust ? What if the king attempt to regain his surrendered rights ? Thus unless we can accept the strictest form of the theory, and go beyond Filmer himself in freeing kings from all their promises, the question is again thrown open. Though God may have given the sovereignty upon trust to Adam and his heirs, may they not forfeit it ? Clarendon's book was really a heavy blow to the straiter sect of the Divine Right School, for he brings into prominence the discrepancies between Hobbism and common sense, and Hobbes' conclusions, though not his premises, were dear to the most thorough of the monarchical party. In many respects it is a very just criticism of ^ A brief View... the Leviathan, p. 319. ^ pp. 72, 122. ' Vol. II. p. 451. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 1 1 Hobbes, it is the protest of a historian against Hobbes' practice of deciding historical and constitutional ques- tions " by speculation and deduction," from psycho- logical generalities. It is like Macaulay's protest against James Mill's Essay. MedicBval feudalism masquerading in a Hebrew- dress was a strange apparition. Of such a fiction as the original contract we may say it was never invented, it grew ; but somebody must have invented this claim for Adam's heir^and to whom the honour belongs I cannot say. There seems no evidence of its having been put forward prior to the accession of the Stuarts, and it appears to be of English origin. In the Political Discourses of James Tyrrell, a book in which the rival theories of government are discussed with much moderation, it is not suggested that any early eccle- siastical authority could be found for this doctrine. It disappeared as suddenly as it appeared. Sydney and Locke exposed the ineptitudes of Kilmer's Old Testa- ment history so thoroughly, that the work has never wanted doing again. But their arguments were power- fully backed up by the conduct of the clergy. Hobbes had seen that the alliance between the Church and absolute monarchy was accidental, and tried to justify the latter on non-religious as well as religious grounds. The clergy had made a large mental reservation when preaching the Divine right of kings, as was shewn when they refused to read the Declaration. But below the talk about Adam's heir there lay a just protest against the theory, then rising into power, which admits of no title to rule, but a title by consent. This, which I call the conventional theory, did not Digitized by Microsoft® 12 Political Philosophy in England fairly start on its course until the time of Locke, but we see it in Hooker, Milton, and Sydney, struggling with the theory that some men have a title to rule others without first obtaining their consent — that we have a duty to obey governments to which we have not consented. This theory of a natural title to rule had been mixed with the absurdities of Filmer, Heylin, and Mackenzie, and fell into bad repute ; but we find it rising again in Hume, who does not require the consent of the governed in order to make government just. The utilitarian may have to admit a title to rule not derived from consent ; and though for a moment the results of utilitarianism and of the conventional theory appeared to coincide when James Mill and Bentham put forward "the junction-of-interests principle," as a deduction from " the greater happiness principle," they have since fallen asunder, and will not again be easily united. But of this more -hereafter. 1 1 . We must now pass to the conventional theory of government, having described the antagonist with which, at the outset, it had to contend. Filmer and Clarendon did not admit that Liberty was on their opponents' side, but it must be allowed that there is nothing in the bare idea of a government not based upon consent that can be said to answer to our idea of freedom ; the upholders of the conventional theory can much more speciously claim that the government which they would establish is " a free government." Filmer and his friends might protest, with what truth remains to be seen, that the conventional theory leads not to Liberty but to license, but this theory has been generally known as the theory of Civil Liberty. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 13 It might be expressed thus — Men have a right to be under no government save that to which they have consented. Government ought to be founded on agree- ment or contract. A word as to its origin — Christian theology contemplated the relations which exist be- tween the Supreme Ruler and his subjects as partly dependent on a covenant, and it was natural (though not necessarily logical) that these should be taken as types of the relations which ought to exist between an earthly ruler and his subjects. Again, laws first appear in the history of mankind as the formulation of already existing customs, and not as the expression of the will of a superior. Hence the essential distinction between an agreement and a law is one which is slowly evolved, and we see that by some of our earlier philosophers a law was still looked upon as obtaining its binding force by being the outcome of a contract. We may add that the histories of Greece and Rome dazzled the eyes of those to whom the new learning was opened. From them, more especially from the history of Rome, men learnt to look upon the right to a share in the govern- ment (the right of self-government) as one of the privileges of a citizen, forgetting probably how small a portion of the inhabitants of Rome were citizens. We may also remark that throughout the history of English ethics there runs a tendency to resolve all duties into the duties of speaking the truth, and of fulfilling contracts. It has been thought that there is a peculiar irrationality in letting our deeds and words contradict each other. Even Hobbes occasionally falls into this strain of language\ an inconsistency which 1 Works (ed. Molesworth), iii. 119. Digitized by Microsoft® 14 Political Philosophy in England did not escape the eye of Clarke\ The " rational " moralists, looking at a right action as a recognition of a proportion or fitness, were naturally led to identify right action and true affirmation. This tendency to resolve all duties into truthfulness and fidelity is observable in the attempt to ground all our duties to God on a solemn league and covenant, and in the attempt to base all our political duties on some agree- ment or contract. Perhaps the reason for this is, that "Speak truth" and "Keep promises" are supposed to admit of fewer exceptions than do other ethical maxims. At any rate the theory that sovereignty ought to be founded on consent is laid down with great distinct- ness by Hooker, who contrasts it with the doctrine of Aristotle. He says that men knew that "strifes and troubles would be endless, except they gave their common consent all to be ordered by some whom they should agree upon : without which consent there was no reason that one man should take upon him to be lord, or judge over another ; because, although there be according to the opinion of some very great and judicious men, a kind of natural right in the noble, and wise, and virtuous, to govern them which are of servile disposition ; nevertheless, for manifestation of their right, and men's more peaceable contentment on both sides, the assent of them who are governed seemeth necessary^." Here we see the two theories lying side by side, and Hooker, in making his choice of that which requires the consent of the governed, was doing what was of more importance to the world than he can ^ Evidences, etc. (ed. 1728), p. 178. ^ Ecd. Pol. i. x. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 15 have been aware of. This theory passed from Hooker to Locke, from Locke to Rousseau, and has profoundly affected the history of mankind. For some time after its appearance it remained comparatively powerless, for it was coupled with no very definite principle laying down whose consent it is that we must require, or what is to be considered evidence of such consent. It did not become really active until it was allied with the doctrine that all men are equal, and that therefore when the governed give their consent every man is to count for one. The alliance was not firmly established until the time of Locke ; but long before this there is observable a tendency, especially among the Puritans, to look upon all men as equal, a tendency which had its origin in Christianity itself. Though submission to the powers that be is a cardinal virtue in the Christian scheme, and though it would be even harder to find the conventional than to find the hereditary theory of government in the Bible, there is in the Christian idea of all men as equal in the sight of Omniscience, a germ of that doctrine of natural equality which was required in order to give definiteness to the conventional theory. S'^jU.os /iev yo.p iyivero Ik tov icrous otlovv ovTas otecrdaL dirX-ws To-ous eTi/at\ But the idea of Christian equality was not definite enough ; and we do not find that Puritans, such as Milton, accepted that equality of faculties which is the starting point of Locke's system. The difficulty of reconciling the natural and con- ventional theories of authority is forced upon us in reading Milton's political works. For, on the one hand, he held that all sovereignty is from the people ; ^ Arist. Fol. V, i. Digitized by Microsoft® 1 6 Political Philosophy in England on the other hand, he was far from accepting the demo- cratic ideal, that in matters of government every man should have one vote, and that a majority must decide. He justifies the action of the army in interfering with the Parliament. " The soldiers judged better than the Great Council, and by arms saved the Commonwealth, which the Great Council had almost damned by their votes\" Indeed, it is difficult to see how Cromwell's proceedings could be justified by one who held that all government ought to rest upon the consent of the people. Filmer points out this difficulty forcibly, and justly. Here we see, he argues, what these Puritans mean by "the People," it is "the best principled" part, and the Army is the sole judge of good principles '^ It is impossible to reconcile the Puritan ideal of a reign of the Saints with the ideal of a Government founded on consent ; the Saints were to reign whether sinners liked it or not. If our great dogma that government ought to rest on consent be to differ from "the simple rule... the good old plan," the consent required must be more than a mere absence of resist- ance ; and if we require more than this, Cromwell had as little title by consent as had Charles. How little Milton cared for the popular voice may be seen in his letter to Monk written just before the Restoration. He wishes that good republicans should be returned to Parliament, and if the people " refuse these fair and noble offers of an immediate Liberty," then Monk is to use his " faithful veteran army." And this is called "A ready and easy way to establish a free Govern- ment." A ready and easy way no doubt, but in what ^ Defence. . . against Salmasius. '^ Observations, etc. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty i y sense would a Government established by a military coup d'^iat be ' free ' ? But sometimes Milton throws aside the pretence of founding government upon the consent of the people. " More just it is doubtless, if it come to force, that a less number compel a greater to retain what can be no wrong to them, their liberty, than that a greater number, for the pleasure of their baseness, compel a less most injuriously to be their fellow slaves'." Here the conventional theory is thrown aside ; those who can, and will preserve liberty {i.e., a popular form of government), have a natural title to rule. Milton was in a great strait, for it was becoming evident that if the people agreed upon any government, it would be government by their old tyrants. The same difficulty occurs in Algernon Sydney's Discourses Concerning Government. The title by nature is not here the Puritan title of God's elect, but the philosophic title of the wise and virtuous man. Sydney often insists on the natural inequality of men. " That equality which is just among equals is just only among equals ; but such as are base, ignorant, vicious, slothful, or cowardly, are not equal in natural or acquired virtues to the generous, wise, valiant, and industrious ; nor equally useful to the societies in which they live ; they cannot therefore have an equal part in the government of them ; they cannot equally provide for the common good ; and it is not a personal but a public benefit that is sought in their constitution and continuance.... If the nature of man be reason, ' detur digniori,' in matters of this kind, is the voice of nature'." Here is the natural theory, but when we 1 A Ready and Easy Way, etc. ^ Discourses, ch. ii. § i. M. 2 Digitized by Microsoft® 1 8 Political Philosophy in England turn to Sydney's definition of liberty we find: — "^ desire it may not be forgotten, that the liberty asserted is not a licentiousness of doing what is pleasing to every one against the command 'of God, but an exemp- tion from all human laws, to which they have not given their assent^" Here is a particularly strong statement of the conventional theory, it is stronger than Locke's definition. "The liberty of man in society is to be under no other legislative power, but that established by consent in the Commonwealth ; nor under the dominion of any will, or restraint of any law, but what the legislative shall enact according to the trust put in it I" Sydney requires the assent of the people to the laws, Locke requires that the government established shall have been consented to, and shall legislate accord- ing to certain rules which have also been consented to. But though Sydney uses this very strong expression, an expression which at once identifies Civil Liberty and Democracy, this is not his usual language. He would, I think, have been content if the legislative body were elected by the people, or even if the outlines of government were consented to by the people. But even this requirement of popular consent is scarcely to be harmonized with the "detur digniori" which he elsewhere makes his motto. Locke and Sydney speak as if civil governments ought to be based on consent, and they also assert that good governments have as a fact been the result of an agreement between the rulers and the ruled. Hobbes also makes his Commonwealth rest upon a covenant. We may ask how far these authors supposed ' Discourses, ch. i. § ii. ^ Essays on Government, ii. 22. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 19 that governments have been the resuh of agreement, how far the original contract was for them a fact ? Here we must draw a distinction. Hobbes, the defender of estabHshed governments, speaks very positively about a contract being the foundation of all dominion, but he does not make it clear whether this contract was made once for all, or whether it is renewed by each genera- tion of citizens. He knows nothing of a tacit contract, nor does he speak as if the contract was made for self and posterity, or for self, heirs, and assigns in respect of property possessed. He always speaks as if every citizen covenanted for himself, and for himself only. But at the same time he speaks as if the social contract had been made once for all. I do not think that Hobbes believed that any such contract has really been made ; he looked upon the conventional theory as an apt fiction, expressing the duties of governors and governed. But with Sydney and Locke the case was different, they really thought that all rightful government had been the result of an agreement between the rulers and the ruled ; they did not for one moment admit that the conventional theory was only a convenient fiction; they maintained that where there had been good government, that government was the result of a social contract, and that no government could be good which did not rest on such a contract. Now, as a piece of history, the conventional theory has no foundation, and is far inferior to the patriarchal theory. Not one single instance of a covenant by a whole nation, or even by that part of a nation which is not under what may be called natural disabilities, can be produced. It is not until a late period in the history 2 — 3 Digitized by Microsoft® 20 Political Philosophy in England of men that the idea of settling their social relations by contract arises. The constitutions of the American States cannot be appealed to in support of the historical truth of the theory, for they were the results of a belief in the theory. Clarendon and Filmer triumphantly ask for one solitary example of a social contract, and Sydney and Locke did try hard to produce one. Sydney promises to prove that these contracts are historical facts, " real, solemn and obligatory." But it is not unworthy of remark that this promise is followed by a hiatus in his manuscript, and is never fulfilled^ Locke again tries to find an answer, but is compelled to content himself for the most part with saying that there is no evidence to the contrary ■*. Elsewhere he admits the patriarchal origin of Government'. Then he argues for the proba- bility ^ priori of there having been a social contract^ and finally he changes his ground, the compact was not made once for all when men left the state of nature, but is made by every citizen ^ But on the whole, though Milton and Sydney admit the conventional theory to be true, and some- times state it in strong terms, their use of it is not so much constructive as destructive. They appeal to it in order to put the Divine Right School out of court, and, when this is done, they fall back upon the natural inequality of men ; the Saints, those who would "reform the Reformation," or the wise and virtuous have a natural title to rule, and it is hard to see how they would reconcile this with that conventional theory ^ Discourses, ii. xxxii. ^ Gov. ii. loi. ^ II- 76. * II. 112. = II. 117. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 2 1 which only gained its full strength when Locke, following Hobbes, preached that men are by nature equal. Here, in a sort of parenthesis, we may notice one of the greatest of our great Commonwealthsmen. Harrington was one of the first to oppose Hobbes on what would now be called utilitarian grounds. Accept- ing Hobbes' identification of reason and interest, he decides that it is not the interest of the individual, but the interest of mankind, which is Right Reason'. The argument is rather fanciful, and assumes that the different parts of inanimate nature fly to each other's assistance, so that the whole may be perfect ; and man, he thinks, must not be "less just than the creature." "Now compute well," he says, "for if the interest of popular government come the nearest to the interest of mankind, then the reason of popular government must be the nearest to Right Reason." This he decides, by rather inconclusive reasoning, must be the case. Democracy, moderated by allowing to an aristocracy the power of proposing, though not of making laws, is the best form of government. He is far from having arrived at Locke's point of view, and will do all he can to give authority to the best and wisest. He does not ignore good birth and good breeding as qualifications for power. " For so it is in the universal series of story, that if any man founded a Commonwealth he was first a gentleman," his examples include Moses, Romulus, and othersl However, the people or their representatives ought to have the power of making laws. ' Harrington's Works (ed. Toland), p. 44. ^ p. 56. Digitized by Microsoft® 22 Political Philosophy in England Harrington is a very interesting figure in the history of political philosophy. At a time when Hobbes would content himself with nothing under a universal pro- position, a proposition applicable, not to these or those men, but to Man, Harrington saw the importance of consulting the history of that nation for which we are setting up an ideal. Again, he saw how few political ideals are realizable, and while his contemporaries were talking as if we had only to choose the best form of government, and then to try and establish it by direct means, Harrington decided that as long as the distri- bution of property remains constant, only one form of government is possible ; the balance of power depends on the balance of property\ Most certainly this is not a complete analysis of the positive conditions which make the establishment of a government possible, and Hume's criticisms on Harrington are just^ but it was a step in the right direction, and Hume recognized it as such. In fact Harrington is particularly interesting because he would seem to have exercised a consider- able influence on Hume. Hume says that the Oceana "is the only valuable model of a Commonwealth that has yet been offered to the public^" and, even re- membering Plato's great work, there is much truth in this praise ; for Harrington tried always to remember that an ideal which requires an essential alteration in the nature of man has but little value. Something must here be said of Hobbes' apology for de facto governments and existing laws, an apology which is the centre of his philosophy. In Hobbes' ' Harrington's Works (ed. Toland), pp. 40 et seq. ^ Hume's Essays, i. vii. ' Hume's Essays, 11. xvi. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 23 day such an apology was by no means unnecessary. Puritanism asserting the claims of conscience and the rights of private judgment, had rushed into a sort of anti-nomianism. No laws were to be obeyed which did not come up to some standard of ideal justice. It must be doubtful which is the greatest error in theory, the assertion of Hobbes that positive laws are the measure of justice, or the Puritan doctrine that laws which are not good are not to be obeyed, though there can be little doubt that the latter is the more dangerous. The Puritans set up an ideal law of God, discoverable partly by study of the Scriptures, partly by the light of reason, and positive laws which did not agree with this law of God were looked upon as void. The jural conception of morality has always been common ; if we do not find it in Greek philosophy, we at least find it in Greek poetry'. With the Bible before him, this is the conception most natural to the Christian. Now, if we take the jural view of morality, there appears more probability of a conflict between civil law and morality than if we take an aesthetic view. But this was not all. '' Jus Naturce" had meant much more than is meant by our expression "the moral law." The idea oi Jus Naturce sprang from the Jus Gentium of Rome, when brought into contact with the later Stoic philosophy. Jus Gentium was the law administered to strangers at Rome, a law drawn from the observances common to those nations to which the strangers be- longed. A law which is found in all communities may be looked upon as natural ; the laws of this or that state may be due to caprice, to casual local circum- 1 Soph. Antig. vv. 445 et seg. Digitized by Microsoft® 24 Political Philosophy in England stances, in a word, they are artificial ; but a law which is found in all states must be due to the very nature of man. Having gone thus far, it is easy to look upon Jus Gentium as more truly a Divine law than the laws of any one state can be. It is the result of man's nature as God made it. And thus we pass ixova Jus Gentium, a real positive law — ^just as positive as the maxims of our modern Court of Chancery — to the Jus Naturce, a Divine law, to which all civil law ought, at least in its outlines, to conform. In a word, the law of nature comes to mean ideal law — law as it ought to be. But another change lay before it. By the time of which we are speaking, the idea oi Jus Gentium- is fast fading away ; scarcely a trace of it remains in Grotius' celebrated definition ; the law of nature is fast becom- ing a synonym for the moral law, i.e., a code of ideal morality. The law of nature of Butler's Sermons is no longer even ideal law ; it is ideal morality. But among the political writers of whom we are speaking, " the law of nature " retained some of its old force — it still meant something more legal and more " positive " than our " morality." The law of nature might still be appealed to in our courts of justice as supplementing and even overriding the statutes of the realm. The courts, particularly the Court of Chancery, were by no means averse to administering what passed as "natural law." Under this disguise they frequently introduced their new principles. The fiction " aequitas est per- fecta quoedam ratio, quoe jus scriptum interpretatur et emendat " was still kept up, and this perfecta ratio was a faculty discovering the law of nature. It is not uninteresting to notice that Cumberland dedicates Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 25 his book De Legibus Natures — a work on what we should call morality — to the Chancellor, as the proper custodian of the law of nature, so fused were the ideas of law and morality in the idea of natural law. Thus the law of nature was sometimes an ideal for the law maker, sometimes an ideal for the moralist, sometimes an ideal for the law administrator, the judge. Between these different meanings it was easy to flit, and con- fusion was the result. This conception of natural law led to a disrespect of positive law, to that sort of anti-nomianism which we find in Milton's works. Milton defended the regicides against Salmasius by saying that the king's execution was legal, it was according to the law of God, Reason, and Nature. If a statute can be produced giving tyrannical power to a king, this being contrary to God's will, to Reason, and to Nature, " is not of force with us." It will be observed that he does not say that if the king's execution be contrary to the positive law of the land it is illegal, but at the same time it is morally good. No, he says, though it be opposed to our statutes it is legal, for it is according to the law of God ; thus it is just as legal as the execution of a murderer under our common law. And Milton could justify himself by appealing to the procedure of law courts which daily professed to administer the law of nature. Sydney, again, heads a chapter with the startling statement " that which is not just is not law, and that which is not law ought not to be obeyed'." Milton and Sydney would probably not have said that we can never have a duty to obey positive law as ^ Discourses, etc., ni. xi. Digitized by Microsoft® 26 Political Philosophy in England positive law, that we can never have a duty to obey positive law when it commands some action which, were it not for that law, would be bad, but they habitually use language placing no limit to our duty of disobeying unjust laws. All men, when not engaged in controversy, would probably say that the truth lies between Hobbes and Milton, that the mere fact that positive law commands an action is some reason why we should do it ; that we have a duty to obey the law of the land because it is the law of the land ; but that this duty may conflict with other duties, and in such cases we must appeal to some higher rule of ethics. To the utilitarian this is obvious, and most non -utilitarian moralists would admit a special duty of Order or Obedience to Law. Thus we cannot say with Hobbes that we never have a duty to disobey positive law, nor with the Puritans that positive law cannot make it our duty to do what, in the absence of positive law, would have been indifferent, or even bad. It has scarcely been sufficiently noticed that Hobbes was, to some extent, an eclectic in politics. The pre- mises are the premises of Sydney and Locke, but the conclusion is the conclusion of Filmer. He justifies absolute monarchy by referring, not to the natural inequality of men, but to their natural equality. He will not say with Aristotle that some men are made to rule, others to serve, for this is contrary to both reason and experienced He knew well that the arguments of the Divine Right School would never stand examina- tion, and he conceived the grand idea of basing politics on a true system of ethics, which should itself rest on a ' Hobbes' English Works (ed. Molesworth), vol. ni. 140, 141. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 27 true psychology. He grants to. the Commonwealths- man all that he seems to require. Men are born with equal faculties ; they are born free ; all government ought to rest upon consent. But he attempts to turn the ideas of natural liberty and natural equality into a defence of de facto governments. He does not succeed in this, for the social covenant on which he allows government to rest is obviously a mere fiction, and he would have found it hard to answer the Common- wealthsman who said, "You admit that I wa:s born free, and that I have a natural right to be under no government save that to which I have consented. Now I affirm that I have not consented to King Charles' government." If I understand Hobbes aright, he meant that the mere fact of the existence of a government must be taken as conclusive evidence of the consent to it of all those who enjoy its protection, all express declarations to the contrary notwithstanding, and that men are morally and religiously bound by their supposed consent. But such a theory is very unstable, the premises are the legitimate property of the democrat, not of the apologist for de facto govern- ments. If it be allowed that all men are naturally free and equal, if all rightful government is founded on consent, men will not be put off with a fictitious consent ; they will say, " You admit that consent is necessary, a fictitious consent cannot be necessary, the necessary consent must be real." Undoubtedly the main doctrine of Hobbes' politics is that we ought always to obey the existing govern- ment, and our duty of obedience arises from the fact, or rather the fiction, that we have covenanted with our Digitized by Microsoft® 28 Political Philosophy in England fellows to do so. This being so, we should naturally expect that Hobbes had some peculiar notion of the superior obligation of the duty of fidelity when com- pared with other duties. But we find that it is only self-love, or rather a desire for self-preservation, which obliges us to enter into the social covenant, and abide by it when made. He has to shew that prudence, or the desire for a tolerable life, counsels us to surrender our natural right to all things, hand it over to some sovereign, one or many, and abstain from all attempts to resume it. Hallam thinks Hobbes' assertion, that all men have by nature equal capacities, not requisite to his theory'. To me it appears not only requisite, but absolutely necessary. Hobbes' chief concern is to prove that men are equal in their power of hurting others, so that he may shew that it is to the advantage not only of the weak but also of the strong to enter civil society. " They are equals," he says, " who can do equal things one against the other ; but they who can do the greatest thing, namely, kill, can do equal things. All men among themselves are by nature equaP." He certainly does go further than this, and affirms that all men are equal in their mental faculties, but this also was necessary, for it was incumbent on him to get rid of the Aristotelian natural title to rule. What however concerns him most is to shew that no man is so strong in body or mind that it will profit him to remain in the state of nature. He ought however to prove not only that every man will find it profitable to enter the civil state, but also that pru- dence, or the desire of self-preservation, counsels us to ' Hist. Lit., vol. ii;, p. 538. ^ Hobbes' English Works, vol. 11. 7. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 29 refrain from occasional backslidings towards the state of nature. This is one of his attempts at proof. Men, he says, are so equal in their power of hurting each other that it will not profit any man, however strong in body or mind, to remain in or return to the state of nature. But to this he adds a consideration which is rather out of place in his system. There would be a sort of absurdity in breaking our covenants, a sort of self-contradiction'. He does not however make it clear that prudence, or the desire for self-preservation, can never counsel us to contradict ourselves ; and this he was bound to do. Thus, instead of giving us peculiarly strong reasons for keeping our covenants, he gives us very weak reasons, for it is far from being self-evident that we can never be gainers by a breach of the laws. The absurdity of basing an absolute and indefeasible duty of obedience to positive law on our duty of self-pre- servation, comes out strongly in a passage to which we must in a moment refer ; but at first Hobbes takes care not to depart too widely from common sense. In several passages he speaks of some of our " natural rights " as inalienable, and in one (to Filmer's disgust) he seems to open a wide door for disobedience, by justifying it in cases where obedience would defeat the end for which our rights are aliened, namely, "the security of a man's person in his life, and in the means of so preserving life as not to be weary of it^" But this is exceptional, and on the whole Hobbes' doctrine ' Hobbes' English Works, vol. in. 119. (This, I think, is intro- duced for the first time in the Leviathan, the parallel passages being II. 17, and IV. 88.) ^ iii- 120. Digitized by Microsoft® 30 Political Philosophy in England appears to be that a man ought always to obey the law, but that if he have broken the law, he cannot be expected to submit without resistance to the punish- ment'. In the Behemoth he decides that a son ought to kill his own father if commanded by law to do sol But even the liberty of resisting punishment is with- drawn in the development of his system. In the religious portions of his political treatises (which may I think be appealed to, as I see no sufficient reason for believing, with some of his critics, that Hobbes' professions of religion are hypocritical) he decides that a Christian prince, that is, a prince who believes the fundamental article of Christianity, that Jesus is the Christ ^ is supreme in all matters spiritual, as well as temporal. An infidel prince however is to be obeyed only in temporal matters, not in matters relating to Divine worship. " But what ? Must we resist princes when we cannot obey them ? Truly, no ; for this is contrary to our civil covenant. What must we do then ? Go to Christ by martyrdom ^" I quote this firstly in order to show that Hobbes is not consistent in teaching that we may not disobey law, but may resist punishment, for here the doctrine is exactly reversed, we are to disobey and submit to punishment ; secondly, because we seem here to have reached a reductio ad absurdum of Hobbism, We are not to resist when the infidel prince would make martyrs of us. Why ? Because to resist would be "contrary to our civil covenants." But why should 1 Hobbes' English Works, vol. ii. 25, 26. ^ vi. 227. = II. 306, 307, III. 590, IV. 179. ^ II. 314-316, III. 600-602, IV. 186-188. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 31 we keep our civil covenants ? Because we ought to preserve our lives so as not to be weary of them. Thus the desire of self-preservation counsels us to submit to martyrdom. This shews how difficult it is to render the conventional theory conservative. Hobbes added to the difficulties which lay in his way by maintaining a peculiar psychology, which he has tersely summed up thus, "Now what seems good is pleasant, and relates either to the senses or to the mind. But all the mind's pleasure is glory (or to have a good opinion of one's self), or refers to glory in the end ; the rest are sensual or conducing to sensuality'." He greatly exaggerates the force of emulation. Man, according to him, "can relish nothing but what is eminent." He leaves the social desires out of con- sideration. He did not, as James Mill thinks, mean merely that all our desires once were purely self- regarding, but have become social by a process of " mental chemistry " such as Hartley and his school imagined; no, accordmg to Hobbes, our desires always continue to be self-regarding. Thus the whole weight of our duty of keeping our covenants is thrown on reason, that is, the cool settled desire of self-preserva- tion. Man is not naturally a social animal, his joy consists in glory, in comparing himself with other men, and thus he has no social instincts leading him to 'the civil state, he is only brought to it by a perception that otherwise his life will be " nasty, brutish, short." I am inclined to think (though there is great risk of such speculations being wrong) that Hobbes was led to exaggerate his account of man's naturally unsocial 1 Hobbes' English Works, vol. n. 5, Digitized by Microsoft® 32 Political Philosophy in England character by a desire to bring " the state of nature " into discredit. The "state of nature" was the state in which God had created man, it was an ideal state to which civil society should be made to conform. Hobbes thought that there should be no ideal to which political reformers could appeal when preaching disobedience and anarchy. So he pronounced that the state of nature is a state of war. This scandalized Clarendon and other orthodox thinkers, it was calling "nasty" and "brutish" what God had called "very good"; but if we examine the theory calmly it does not seem very objectionable. We have no sooner heard that man is naturally in a state of war than we hear of a faculty called reason, which prompts man to seek peace, and we are told that this faculty is just as natural as any other faculty. So the whole theory amounts but to this. If men were irrational, they would quarrel and fight and never form civil states, but by nature they are rational, and reason counsels them to seek peace. In fact we have here, as Hume says, only a decom- position of forces. " Human nature being composed of two principal parts, which are requisite in all its actions, the affections and understanding, it is certain that the blind motions of the former, without the direction of the latter, incapacitate men for society ; and" it may be allowed to consider separately the effects that result from the separate operations of these two component parts of the mind\" Hobbes really only performs what Hume thinks "may be allowed.^' But he lays great stress on the " preposterous conclusions " which, according to I ago, would result "if the balance ^ Treatise, etc., in. ii. 2. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 33 of our lives had not one scale of reason to poise another of sensuality," and calls the state of men, when deprived of their natural faculty of reason, the " state of nature," because he wishes to discredit one of the "sacramental phrases" of the reforming party, and thus strike a blow at anti-nomianism and anarchy. Hitherto we have spoken of Hobbes as an apologist for de facto governments, and as such he ought to be considered. Though the Behemoth is a justification of the Stuarts, he ends, it by saying that the sovereignty had passed by a circular motion from Charles I. to the Long Parliament, thence to the Rump, thence to Cromwell, thence back again to the Long Parliament, thence to Charles IL So the Rump and Cromwell had really been sovereigns, and the covenants of the nation must, during their rule, have been applicable to them. There appears to me insufficient evidence for saying that Hobbes changed his opinions, he steadily refused to allow of any title to rule save the title of a de facto government. He does not enter at length into the nice question of when a de facto sovereignty ceases, but, apart from a de facto, he knows of no de jure sovereign. The subjects, we learn, cannot get rid of the sovereign by agreement among themselves, for the sovereign has rights under the social covenant\ In the de Cive we learn that the subjects are free if the land be conquered, if the sovereign abdicate, or if the succession faiP. In the Leviathan this doctrine is extended, and the subjects are made free when the king can no longer protect them*. The 20th law of nature, added in a postscript to the other nineteen, makes ' English Works ii. 91, 92. ^ ibid. 11. 107. ^ ibid. 111. 208. M. 3 Digitized by Microsoft® 34 Political Philosophy in England him who protects the subjects sovereign^ ; and this is what Clarendon called " a sly address " to Cromwell. It should not however be forgotten that Hobbes does try to prove that a limited monarchy is an absurdity, a contradiction in terms, and in the Behe- moth and the Dialogue on the Laws does try to prove that Charles I. was an absolute monarch; and "an absolute monarch " with Hobbes means a good deal. Such an one is subject to no laws, and to no positive morality. Charles was king. The king of England is an absolute monarch : he cannot forfeit one jot of the sovereign power. To attempt to limit his authority was not only a crime, but a sin ; it was the sin of rebellion, which sums up in itself all sins, and excludes the sinner from salvation. All of this is to be found in Hobbes' writings ; but, says Austin, to call this an apology for tyranny is "rant." Hobbes tried to stop the natural course of the conventional theory, but with ill success ; it was too strong for him, and swept on towards modern demo- cracy. We have seen this theory in the works of Hooker, M,ilton, and Sydney, trying to live at peace with the theory that some men are worthier to rule than others, and that detur digniori is the voice of reason. As long as this was the case the conventional theory could never become constructive ; it was at best an engine for destroying the claims of hereditary monarchy. We must have some principle which shall decide whose consent it is that we shall require ; and this Locke provides. All men, he says, are " creatures ^ English Works iii. 703. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 35 of the same species and rank, promiscuously born to all the same advantages of nature, and the use of the same faculties," and therefore they ought to be "equal one amongst another, without subordination or sub- jection, unless the Lord and Master of them all should by any manifest declaration of His will, set one above another'." Of the truth of the assertion that all men are born with the same faculties, and of the legitimacy of the conclusion that therefore there is by nature no subordination or subjection between them, I must again speak. Here let us refer to the way in which Locke obtains his ethical first principles, the principle, for instance, that those to whom God has given equal faculties are by Him intended to be free from all. subjection, save that to which they have consented. A short statement of Locke's ethical opinions will not be out of place, as it will shew the way in which the first great apostle of the Rights of Man obtained the premises of his politics. Things are called good and evil only in reference to pleasure and pain I What is apt to produce pleasure in us we call good, for no other reason than because it is apt to produce pleasure'. Moral good is the con- formity of our voluntary actions to some law whereby good is drawn on us by the will of the law-giver'. The only true touchstone of rectitude is the law of God, whereby He directs us to what is best : this law bearing sanctions not only in a future life, but in this life also. This law we discover by the light of nature and by revelation'. Apart from revelation, it is reason ^ On Govt. II, 4, ^ Hum. Under, ii. xx. 2. ' 11. xxi. 42. * 11 xxviii. 5. ' II. xxviii. 8-11. 3—2 Digitized by Microsoft® 36 Political Philosophy in England which discovers this law ; in fact, reason is the law of nature\ The laws of God can be deduced with demon- strative certainty from our idea of a Supreme Being, infinite in power, goodness, and wisdom, on whom we depend, and the idea of ourselves as understanding, rational beings. Our knowledge of the Supreme Being is derived from our intuitive knowledge of our own existence, and our knowledge that there must be some eternal cause of our existence, power, and knowledge ^ Of the ethical propositions which can be thus deduced with demonstrative certainty, he gives two examples — "Where there is no property there is no injustice," and "No government allows absolute liberty^" (Very true, but very useless.) It requires study and reasoning to discover this divine law, but it is easily intelligible and plain to all, for men are furnished with the same faculties". The sum of this is : Men ought to obey the laws of God, deduced by reason from the knowledge we have of God and of ourselves ; such obedience being good because it brings us pleasure. But here is a difficulty. Such obedience may be good, but how are we to say that the laws or their Maker are good ? Locke calls God good, though he does not, when formally proving the existence of a Supreme Being, prove that goodness is one of His attributes. He should shew that these laws are themselves fitted to secure the pleasure of mankind, or how can he, with his definition of goodness, call them or their Maker good ? It is certain, however, that Locke regarded our duties as set us by the laws of God, which can be deduced by ' On Govt. n. 6. ^ Hum. Under, iv. x. " IV. iii. 18. ''On Govt. 11. 4, 6, 12. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 3-7 reason, and, when laying down a maxim as such a law, he does not make a calculation of consequences, but appeals to the law as discoverable from our knowledge of God. And indeed he held that a man who does not believe in a God cannot know of any moral duties', and thus morality is merged in natural religion. I believe however that Locke would not have objected to saying that the laws of God direct us to those actions which most conduce to the greatest happiness of the greatest number, and it is probably to this fact that he would have appealed if asked to shew that God is good. But he attempts to transcend utilitarianism by deducing moral laws from our idea of God. In short, his poHtics are as " meta-political " (to use Coleridge's happy phrase) of those of Kant himself. What therefore Locke has to do is to deduce the right of every man to be under no government to which he has not consented, from the ideas of God as infinitely wise, good, and powerful, and of ourselves as understanding, rational creatures. He proceeds to shew that men being the workmanship of God, and being His property whose workmanship they are, have no right to destroy themselves or others. They must preserve themselves and not quit their station wilfully, and, when their own preservation comes not into com- petition, they must preserve the liberty, health, limbs, and goods of others". We have however a right to punish offenders ; we may retribute to them what is proportionate to their transgressions, which is so much as niay serve for reparation and restraint^ But what ' First Letter on Toleration. ^ On Govt. n. 6. * ii. 8. Digitized by Microsoft® 38 Political Philosophy in England are the offences which we may punish ? Apparently any breaches of the laws of nature, the particulars of which laws it would, Locke thinks, be beside his pur- pose to enter into\ The highest crime of which a man can be guilty is the attempt to get another man into his absolute power, for it may reasonably be concluded that he who would get me into his power without my consent would destroy me if he had a fancy to it^ Hence we ought to be free from all absolute power to which we have not given our consent '. Such is the argument by which Locke would deduce the conventional theory from our ideas of God and of ourselves. We are God's property, not our own, there- fore we may not destroy ourselves or each other ; he who attempts to assume the sovereignty without the consent of the ruled, must be supposed to be intent on destroying them, and therefore commits the greatest of all sins against the law of nature. Government therefore ought to rest upon the con- sent of the governed, and the consent of every man is equally valuable. But what are we to consent to ? It is of the greatest importance that we should have an exact answer. Unfortunately, Locke here assumes the place of the historian, and begins to tell us what men have done ; he allows fictitious history to intrude upon ethics. But we must take the doctrine as we find it. We are told that when any number of men have by the consent of every individual made a community, they have thereby made the community one body with power to act as one body, which is only by the will and deter- ^ Oil Govt. II. 7-12. ^ II. 17-21. * II. 22. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 30 mination of the majority. So when once the state is formed, the whole body is to be concluded by the majority. This assertion of the divine right of majori- ties is most important, and here is the reasoning on which it is based. That which acts any community, being only the consent of the individuals of it, and it being necessary for that which is one body to move one way, it is necessary for that which is one body to move that way whither the great force carries it, which is the consent of the majority : or else it is impossible to act or continue one body, one community, which the consent of every individual united into it agreed that it should, and so every one is bound by that consent to be concluded by the majority'. At first this looks like a piece of Social Mechanics, this talk about necessity seems to imply that we are to take a fatalist view of the matter, and say that a body politic will always move as the majority of citizens would have it move. Even here the physical analogy breaks down ; a body acted on by two unequal opposite forces does not move as if the lesser force did not exist. This however is not what Locke meant, he is not really speaking of what must happen, but of what ought to happen, and doubtless it is his opinion that men's faculties are equal, which makes him see in the principle that a majority can bind a minority the one possible principle of just government. But how about after generations .-" Does the con- sent of the fathers bind the children to be concluded by the majority ? Burke tries to shew that the original contract binds posterity, but Locke resolutely answers ^ On Govt. II. 95, 96. Digitized by Microsoft® 40 Political Philosophy in England that the son is altogether as free as the father. At this point however in Locke's argument, there is a little vacillation. At first we are told that every citizen enters into the covenant when he comes of age. But, it is argued, no government can permit any part of its dominions to be enjoyed by those who do not belong to the community. The original contract is thus sup- posed "to run with the land," to use a lawyer's phrase. Every person who has possession or enjoyment of any land within the dominions of the government has given his consent to its laws. So far the idea is that, the land being bound by the covenant, every one who has possession or enjoyment of the land gives a tacit consent to the government^ " by becoming a member of the society^." But in a few lines all is changed. These tacit covenantors are not members of the society, their obligation begins and ends with the enjoyment of the land", and we are introduced to a fresh set of covenantors who, by actual agreement and express declaration, have given their consent to be of the commonwealth, and are perpetually and indispensably obliged to be and remain unalterably subjects to it : and nothing can make a man a member of the common- wealth but his actually entering into it, by positive engagement and express promise and compact*. Thus having been told that the son becomes a member of the society by merely enjoying the possessions of his father, we now learn that he is not a member of the community unless he has entered into it by express promise and compact. I have dwelt at some length on this point because ^ On Govt.u. 116-119. ^ II. 117. * II. 120. * II. 121. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 41 I would shew the exact steps by which the conventional theory leads us to democracy. If men can bind their posterity, then the conventional theory may be perfectly conservative, but then how are we to say that all men are born free ? If we are prepared to reject natural freedom we have no need of the conventional theory. If we will not do this, we must say with Locke, that the son is born as free as the father. Then Locke finds a momentary resting-place in the notion of a covenant which binds, not posterity, but the land which posterity occupies. But this will not do, for even if our ethics were bounded by Real Property Law we should admit that not all conditions with which a man may try to burden his successors in title are valid. The moralist would go at least as far as the lawyer in abhorring a perpetuity. Locke tells us that the earth has been given to men in common, and shall one generation be able to deprive its successors of the use of it ? So Locke surrenders this doctrine, and seems to think it only necessary as accounting for the way in which alien residents become subject to our laws ; and then he boldly proclaims that nothing can make any man a subject or member of the commonwealth but his actually entering into it, by positive agreement, and express promise and compact. One barrier still remains between us and democracy. The majority may institute some legislative body, and surrender certain of the natural rights of the people to this body. It may even give the power to one man\ After this grant of power the legislator or prince may have certain rights. He holds his power under an ' On Govt. II. 132. Digitized by Microsoft® 42 Political Philosophy in England agreement, and apparently cannot be cashiered as long as he performs his part of the agreement. I take the following words of Dr Hutcheson to be a correct account of the proceedings at the Original Convention, as imagined by Locke : " To constitute a state or civil polity in a regular manner these three deeds are necessary — First, a contract of each one with all that they should unite into one society to be governed by one counsel ; and next, a decree or ordinance of the people concerning the plan of government, and the nomination of governors ; and lastly, another covenant or contract between these governors and the people, binding the rulers to a faithful administration of their trust and the people to obedience'." Here is some little defence against democracy, for by this latter covenant the people are obliged to obedience as long as the rulers do not break their half of the engagement, and it is admitted that the power may have been granted to the rulers for ever. Even Hobbes is not excluded. He could still say that all rights have been surrendered for ever, and that the rulers have on their part made no covenant at all. But Locke is not going to permit the revival of such pretensions. We can learn the conditions of the contract between the rulers and the ruled by considering why it was that men left the state of nature for the social state. It was because they wanted — (i) a known and settled law to decide their controversies; (2) known and indifferent judges; (3) power to enforce the law against criminals^ But It is with the intention the better to preserve himself, ' Hutcheson's Introduction to Mor. Phil. in. 5. ^ On Govt. II. 124. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 43 his life, liberty, and property, that every man consents to enter the society, and therefore the power of the society ought never to be supposed to extend further than the common good, and is obliged to secure to every man his property {i.e., life, liberty, and estate) by guarding against those defects in the state of nature which induced men to form communities'. Hence it follows that the legislative body instituted by the majority of the community — (i) must govern by estab- lished laws, (2) must design its laws for no other end ultimately but the good {i.e., pleasure) of the people, (3) must not raise taxes without the consent of the people, for it must not take from any one his property without "his own consent, i.e., the consent of the majority^" \ (4) must not delegate its legislative powers But supposing that there is a dispute between the prince and the people as to whether these conditions have been broken (and surely there well may be such a dispute, for men are not apt to agree as to whether a prince's laws are designed for no other end but the good of the people), who is to decide ? " Who shall be judge whether the prince or legislative act contrary to their trust ? To this I reply, the people shall be judge^" Thus just when the conventional theory might have been appealed to on the Conservative side, Locke practically abandons it and falls back on Utilitarianism. One of the conditions of their tenure of office is that the rulers shall make laws for no other end ultimately but the good of the people, and if the rulers break this condition, they have no further rights under the ' On Govt. II. 123-131. ^ II. 140. * II. 134-141. " II. 240; Digitized by Microsoft® 44 Political Philosophy in England contract. This is to go nearly as far as Hutcheson, who, though he also admits a contract between rulers and ruled, says outright that if greater and more lasting mischiefs are likely to arise from the continuance of a government than from a violent effort to change it, such an effort is both lawful and honourable. Rousseau, we shall see, manages the matter more cleverly, for he admits of no contract between the rulers and the ruled. But at any rate, the barrier between Locke and democracy is a very weak one. Though Locke comes with a system of rights to liberty and equality deduced from the very idea of God, there runs throughout his politics a tendency to admit that the Utilitarian measure of right and wrong is the true one. " The end of government is the good of mankind\" " The public good is the rule and measure of all law-making^" And good is pleasure. Locke resembles Hobbes^ in this respect. He requires his sovereign to be a utilitarian, but holds that we can decide who ought to be sovereign by some surer and readier method than by considering who will make the best laws. Now it is by no means evident that " the end of government " will be attained, or the " measure of all law-making" satisfied, when the governors are appointed by the majority of the people. Thus we may have to say that the only right government (that is, one established by a majority of the people) is not the one best suited to attain the end for which all governments are instituted. Of course, the laws of morality may not be harmonious among themselves, but this is a conclusion which we can scarcely come to, ^ On Govt. II. 229. ^ First Letter on Toleration. ' Op. Cit. 111. ^22. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 45 if we look upon these laws as deduced from the idea of a Being infinite in power, goodness, and wisdom. Burke has vehemently asserted that the French Libert^ was not the Liberty for which our own Whig patriarchs pleaded'; but Burke would have found it difficult to show that there was any single article in the Declaration of the Rights of Man for which ample authority could not be found in the writings of the most popular of all English philosophers. It is surprising how little Rousseau added to the essential part of the conventional theory as it was delivered to him by Locke. Of course there is a great external difference between the writings of the cautious, candid English- man, and those of the brilliant French romance writer, but the difference is external. In Locke we find a constant desire not to "go beyond his brief," while Rousseau will at all hazard turn out a perfectly neat and logical piece of work ; but Locke had been obliged to proclaim principles which covered not only his own case, but also the case of Rousseau. The chief improvements which Rousseau introduced into the conventional theory must be shortly noticed. Locke, we have seen, emphatically asserts that a father cannot alienate the liberty of his children''; Rousseau agrees, " un tel don est contraire aux fins de la nature, et passe les droits de la paternit6^" But Locke holds that the land being bound by the contract, occupation of the land must be taken as evidence of a tacit consent to the government. He however wavers, and requires an express consent in order that a man ^ Reflections on tru Revolution, etc. ^ Civ. Govt. n. u6. ' Du Contrat Social, i. iv. Digitized by Microsoft® 46 Political Philosophy in England may become a subject of the State, Rousseau is at one with him. Unanimity is necessary for the contrat social, if any one will not consent he remains outside the State; but, "quand I'Etat est institud le consente- ment est dans la residence ; habiter le territoire c'est se soumettre a la souverainet6'." This doctrine however would allow that tyranny may become rightful by pre- scription, so a very characteristic note is added'': "Ceci doit toujours s'entendre d'un Etat libre ; car d'ailleurs la famille, les biens, le defaut d'asyle, la necessity, la violence, peuvent retenir un habitant dans le pays malgr^ lui, et alors son sejour seul ne suppose plus son consentement au contrat, ou a la violation du contrat." This ingenuity is beyond Locke, who, when speaking of residence as a tacit consent, does not make it applic- able only to the case of a "free" state; but then he elsewhere does what is almost equivalent, for he will not allow that an usurper — one who obtains power by other ways than those which the laws of the community have prescribed — can have any authority until he has obtained the actual consent of the people'. But Rousseau's grand improvement on Locke is that he gets rid of the third of Hutcheson's "three deeds " ; he will have no contract between the rulers and the ruled. The first deed, the contract of associa- tion, is the only social contract*. Here Rousseau is at one with Hobbes, who, though for a very different reason, will have no contract between the sovereign and the subjects. Hobbes' account of the proceeding is that the subjects covenant among themselves, the ' Cont. Soc. V. ii. ^ ibid. note. ' Civ. Govt. II. 198. * Cont. Soc. iv. 16. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 47 sovereign not being a party'. From this we should expect that the sovereign can have no rights under the covenant, and that the covenantors could by mutual agreement annul the contract. But this was not at all what Hobbes wanted, so he imagines, not a contract between rulers and ruled, but a grant to the ruler^ Rousseau does not admit the contract or the grant ; the rulers hold their power not only by, but also during the will of the sovereign people. Now this is a great improvement in the theory : there can be no question as to whether the rulers have kept their part of the engagement. If they be not wanted they may go. After all, however, Locke had gone nearly as far as this, for the rulers may be sent about their business if they make laws for any other end but the good of the people, and Hutcheson had gone quite as far. In fact, with the latter the " third deed " is a mere survival ; it is not useful, and must drop off in time. But Rousseau, in his practical application, does go much further towards democracy than Locke did. "Toute loi," he says, "qui le peuple en personne n'a pas ratifi^e est nulle ; ce n'est point une loi. Le peuple Anglais pense ^tre libre ; il se trompe fort, il ne I'est que durant I'election des membres du Parlement ; si-tot qu'ils sont ^lus il est esclave, il n'est rien." How, let us ask, would Locke have answered this ? He would probably have said that undoubtedly the people of England have a God-given right to make their own laws, but that they do not think it expedient to insist on this right : they cannot, however, lose the right by lapse of time ; if they choose to insist on it no one can 1 Op. at. III. 161. '- Op. at. II. 91. Digitized by Microsoft® 48 Political Philosophy in England rightfully object. But though he might make use of an appeal to expediency to stop democracy in practice, he cannot use it to resist the theory that all men have a right which they may enforce if they please, to be under no laws save those to which they have consented. It will be noticed that Locke does not admit that the consent of our representatives is all that we can insist on, for a representative assembly he thinks may (though it probably will not) infringe the natural rights of the people, e.g., by raising taxes without their consent^ We have seen how Locke gets over the difficulty of identifying the consent of the majority with the consent of the whole ; we must have agreed to be concluded by the majority because a body politic must move in one way. And when speaking of taxation he says that a man's property may not be taken without "his own consent, i.e., the consent of the majority^' This simple id est is too clumsy for Rousseau : he rises to the occasion, and produces a splendid sophism, which I quote at length, because it shows the difficulty of hiding the weak point of the conventional theory : — Mais" on demande comment un homme peut 6tre libre, et force de se conformer a des volontes qui ne sent pas las siennes. Com- ment les opposans sont-ils libres et soumis &. des loix auxquelles ils n'ont pas consenti ? Je reponds que la question est mal posee. Le citoyen consent a toutes les loix, meme a celles qu'on passe malgre lui, et meme a celles qui le punissent quand il ose en violer quel- qu'une. La volontd constante de tous les membres de I'^tat est la volontd g^n^rale ; c'est par elle qu'ils sont citoyens et libres. Quand on propose une loi dans I'assemblde du peuple, ce qu'on leur demande n'est pas precisdment s'ils approuvent la proposition ou s'ils la rejettent; mais si elle est conforme ou non a la volontd ' Civ. Govt. II. 138. ^ II. 140. ^ Cont. Soc. v. ii. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 49 gendrale qui est la leur; cbacun en donnarit son suffrage, dit son avis la-dessus, et du calcul des voix se tire la declaration de la volenti generale. Quand done I'avis contraire au mien I'emporte, cela ne preuve autre chose sinon que je m'etois trompe et que ce que j'estimois Stre la volonte generale, ne I'etoit pas. Si mon avis particulier I'eut eniporte, j'aurois fait autre chose que ce que favois voulu, c'est alors que je n'aurois pas eti libre. Now when Sydney says that civil liberty is an exemption from all laws to which we have not con- sented, this sounds plausible. Liberty is absence of restraint imposed upon us by other men, and it is plausible to say that we cannot require a liberty from self-imposed restraint. But when Rousseau tells us that a man is not free, though he be under no restraints whatsoever, unless the majority of the people wish that ' he should be under no restraint, we seem to have wandered far out of the right road. The question must force itself upon us, Have we not been pursuing an object which constantly retires before us ? We say that men should be under no laws save those to which they have given their consent ; we say that Hobbes' fictitious consent will not do. Consent must be real — - it must be the consent of all, and, trying to make the consent real and universal, we land ourselves in demo- cracy ; and yet we find that an individual may still be under many restraints to which only an ingenious sophistry can say that he has consented. If what we want be freedom from all restraint not strictly self- imposed, democracy cannot be the ultimate ideal of the conventional theory. Even in Rousseau we already see rising an opinion that democracy does not give us any security for that M. 4 Digitized by Microsoft® 50 Political Philosophy in England liberty which is valuable, or else what is the meaning of his eulogy on the state of nature, the state in which there were no laws ? But the world could only be convinced that democracy is not necessarily a security for that liberty which men desire, by a great practical experiment. We must now return to England, and we notice that during the quiet time which succeeded our Revo- lution the conventional theory is put away, and even falls into discredit. One of the first blows struck at the Original Contract came from Locke's pupil Shaftes- bury, who, looking at the interests of mankind as harmonious, and constantly dwelling on our social instincts, thought that civil societies might well arise and continue without any contract. Ascribing the perception of moral differences to a sense, or taste, rather than to reason, he opposes that tendency of "rational" moralists to resolve all our duties into truth- fulness or fidelity, which tendency had added force to the conventional theory. " The natural knave," he says, " has the same reason to be a civil one, and may dispense with his politic capacity as oft as he sees occasion. 'Tis only his word stands in his way. A man is obliged to keep his word. Why ? Because he has given his word to keep it. Is not this a notable account of the original of moral justice and the rise of civil government and allegiance' ! " Again, Shaftesbury was brought by another road to resist the principles of Locke, for Locke derived our political rights from the idea of God, and this founding of morality on religion Shaftesbury condemned with unusual asperity, it throws ^ Freedom of Wit and Humour, Pt. 3, Sec. i. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 51 " all order and virtue out of the worlds" His aesthetic ethics were much less likely to lead to inalienable, in- defeasible rights than the jural, religious, semi- Puritan ethics of his master. But in no book is the reaction against the politics which give Divine rights to kings or to majorities more marked than in the Essay on Man. That reaction must have been at its height when Pope wrote — For forms of government let fools contest : Whate'er is best administer'd is best. It is the prevailing optimism of the time, the optimism so well illustrated by Shaftesbury and Pope, which led to this contempt of political speculation. Good government appears to these optimists a matter of no great difficulty. After all, governments can do but little towards making men happy or unhappy. Virtue, thinks Pope, alone gives the best happiness ; external goods, the only goods which governments can provide, are comparatively worthless. This optimism I believe to be a great exaggeration. That true self-love and social are the same, requires more proof than has yet been given of it, and Shaftesbury's attempt to find such a proof is to this day one of the best as well as the most ingenious. But it was high time that the social part of our nature should be brought into prominence, and that we should be shewn to have other motives leading us to civil intercourse, besides our sense of a duty owed to God, and our fear of God, and our fellow-men. The harmony of the time was broken by Mande- 1 Letter to a Student^ vii. 4—2 Digitized by Microsoft® 52 Political Philosophy in England ville's assertion that civil society is far from an unmixed good, that crafty politicians have for their own purposes induced men to subject themselves to laws. Thus Mandeville assisted Rousseau in setting up a state in which there is no civil government as an ideal. Men, said Rousseau and Mandeville, have been coerced, or cozened into submitting to law, and the question arises as to whether civil society is not a mistake. It was this line of thought which did much towards proving that the ultimate ideal of those who would free men from all restraints not strictly self-imposed is not to be found in democracy. Burke makes use of arguments with which Mandeville had familiarized the world when he insists against Bolingbroke that all that can be said for natural as against revealed religion, can equally well be said for natural as against civil society. " Shew me an absurdity in religion, and I will under- take to shew you a hundred for one in political laws and institutions'." Now, so well did Burke put the arguments against civil society, that there were some who thought that he spent his whole life in vainly attempting to answer them. Such an one was Godwin, the author of the Political Justice, a book, now chiefly known as the exciting cause of Malthus on Population, but one of the best productions of English democracy. Godwin expressly accepts Burke's reductio ad absurdum of Bolingbroke as a really sound argument^ This, coupled with the doctrine of the perfectibility of man, due to the fact that his voluntary actions spring from opinion and that he is rapidly attaining true opinion, ' Burke, Vindication of Natural Society. ^ Political Justice, B, i. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 53 led Godwin to look upon democracy as merely a stage on the road to liberty — a road which will end in the complete abolition of government. I have said this in order to shew how the teaching of Mandeville and Rousseau, that men made an error in letting them- selves be deprived of their natural liberty, affected that stream of thought which, starting from our common- wealthsmen and Locke, at first takes its course towards democracy. Before we speak of Hume, who fitly closes that period of our Political Philosophy which lies between the two revolutions, we must refer shortly to the course of ethical speculation in England. During the time of civil strife our political philosophers were too eager to find some answer to the question, "Who ought to rule ? " They tried to supply the place of an answer to the more fundamental question, " What ought a ruler to do ? " by some piece of fictitious history, a direct grant from God to some man and his heirs, or an original contract. But we can scarcely hope to answer this latter question until we have settled what is to be the supreme principle of ethics. For if there be some one supreme principle according to which all men ought always to act (and our philosophers, Bentham no less than those whom he ridicules, always assume that this is the case), then the answer to the fundamental question of ethics, what ought men to do, must be, or include an answer to the fundamental question of politics, how ought men to act in their civil relations. " Le but de I'association, quelque nombreuse quelle soit, ne pent etre essentiellement autre que le but de chacun des ^tres associ^s ; et la loi supreme de Digitized by Microsoft® 54 Political Philosophy in England I'individu sera la loi supreme de r6tat\" Hence, for the progress of political philosophy, it was necessary that the various possible answers to the question of ethics should be unravelled and distinguished. Whether we get any nearer to a settlement of this question may be doubted, but it is certainly more possible to understand what the exact issue is in these days than it was when Hobbes opened the controversy. Hobbes found the orthodox unprepared. He startled the world by his proclamation of " glory " and " sensuality " as our only motives, and of the will of the sovereign as the only standard of right, and his opponents caught up the first weapons which came to their hand without being nice in their choice. It was retorted that there is a difference between right and wrong, independent of all positive law, a difference pointed to by Revealed and Natural Religion, Reason, Conscience, the interest of mankind, and even enlightened Selfishness, and an indiscriminate use was made of these as a defence for morality, and civil liberty. Political writers like Clarendon, found no difficulty in withstanding Hobbes by appealing to numerous principles, which the moralist sees are not necessarily compatible with each other. In the first place it became necessary to exclude revealed religion from the coalition. Both Cumber- land and Clarke keep religious considerations out of sight when setting up their criteria of right action ; for the truth of religion can scarcely be proved without the help of some independent standard of right. Again, the difficulty of calling God good — if His will be the measure of goodness — made the establishment of a ^ Saint-Hilaire, Politique d'Aristote, p. xi. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 55 moral system based on natural religion seem to most men illegitimate ; Locke is here an exception. But a further disruption was necessary. Clarke held that "the good of the universal creation does always coincide with the necessary truth and reason of things," and that, were we in possession of an infinite understanding, all morality might be founded on " considerations of public utility'." But Butler on the one hand, and Hume on the other, made a lasting breach between the morality of conscience and the morality of general utility. To Hume fairly belongs the credit, or blame, of being the founder of modern Utilitarianism. It is true that the opposition to Utilitarianism was roused, not so much by his writings as by those of Paley and Bentham. This was likely to be the case, for Hume approached ethics much more in the spirit of Aristotle than in that of a moral preacher. Morality was an existing fact, to be explained if possible. He scarcely draws any distinction between what ought to be and what Tnen think ought to be ; for, as he says, with regard to morals, general opinion is the only standard by which controversy can be decided I It was because he took this view of the matter that his attack on the conventional theory did not produce so great an effect as the attacks of Paley and Bentham. Still there can be no doubt that both Paley and Bentham owed their conception of morality to Hume. And when they make their attempts to shew that the ordinary rules of morality really aim at utility, they can only follow Hume, and follow him at a considerable distance. The 1 Evidences, p. 223. ^ Essays, 11. xii. Digitized by Microsoft® 56 Political Philosophy in England Benthamites have been rather ungrateful to Hume, apparently because he differed from them on the purely psychological question of the origin of the moral sense\ but the fact remains that all that can be called a "proof" of Utilitarianism is due to the suggestions of Hume, and that in this line of argument he has never been surpassed. Directly Utilitarianism has fairly separated itself from other moral systems it begins its attack on the original contract. Hutcheson can scarcely be called an Utilitarian in ethics, but when he comes to politics he becomes distinctly Utilitarian. " The end of all civil power is acknowledged by all to be the safety and happiness of the whole body ; any power not naturally conducive to that end is unjust^" He still maintains that there ought to be an original contract with its "three deeds," but this has become a mere fiction. When we turn to Hume's works we can see the gradual process by which he freed himself from the conven- tional theory. We have two editions of his ethical opinions. A change, if not in his views, at least in his language, is discoverable as we pass from the one to the other. In the Treatise on Human Nature, though he expressly states that our political duties do not and cannot depend on promises, he uses words only fitted to express the old theory of the original contract. Thus, when considering the duty of justice, he speaks of "a convention entered into by all the members of the society to bestow stability on the ' E.g., James Mill, Fragment on Mackintosh (ed. 1870), p. 264. J. S. Mill, Dissert, and Discuss. (2nd ed.), vol. n. p. 455. ^ Introduction to Moral Philosophy. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 57 possession of external goods," &c. — the old phrases lingering on after their meaning has vanished \ But these expressions are not to be found in the Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals. He had pub- lished an essay on the original contract^ which puts forward the arguments afterwards used by Paley^ and Bentham* in their most telling form. Hume had not yet made the acquaintance of Rousseau, he only knew of the conventional theory as a piece of Whiggism, for since Locke's time the theory had been asleep in England. But the argument is equally fitted to meet the democratic doctrine, and the conservative imitation of it. From Hume's day we may date the rise of a definite philosophical antagonism to the conventional theory. Such an antagonism had never before existed, for since Filmer and Mackenzie (who can scarcely be called philosophers) had been conquered by Locke and Sydney, the only choice for the politician had been between different forms of the conventional theory. Doubtless there had been many men who had seen through the pretensions of this theory (Shaftesbury had), but they had not provided a substitute, and Utilitarianism is a substitute. One more word as to Hume. He proclaimed that politics might be made a science". This was no new assertion, for Hobbes and Locke had gone this length. But Hobbes and Locke thought that geometry should be the model for politics. Neither the one nor the other had shewn the least appreciation of the use of ' Treatise, etc., ni. ii. ^ Essays, ii. xii. ^ Mor. and Pol. Phil., vi. iii. ^ Fragment on Govt., i. xxxvi., and note. ^ Essays, i. iii. Digitized by Microsoft® 58 Political Philosophy in England history. Like their contemporaries, they looked upon history not as an account of certain general streams of tendency, but as a collection of anecdotes from which apt illustrations of a priori theories might now and then be gleaned. We might describe Hobbes' method, in Mill's language, as the deduction of ethology from psychology, without a verification from history. The seventeenth century revolt against Aristotle is often looked upon as the revolt of induction against deduc- tion. But however true this may be of metaphysics it is wholly untrue of politics. The deductive mind of Hobbes revolted against the cautious induction of Aristotle. Hallam^ notwithstanding, there is no philo- sopher who has shewn so little appreciation of the inductive method as Hobbes^ In Hume we see the first beginnings (if we except the remarkable work of Harrington) of a scientific use of history. Psychology and history provide evidence for a science of politics. We cannot afford to neglect either ; we cannot afford to neglect history with Hobbes, or to plead for the pure Baconian method with Macaulay^ Hume, in his short Essays on Politics, tries to use both kinds of evidence, and, though without any parade of system, follows that method which John Mill has described as the proper one for social and political investigations. To return. At last there appears that outcome of the conventional theory, the Declaration of the Rights of Man. It has often been said that there should have been a Declaration of the Duties of Man as well. ^ Hist. Lit., vol. ni. ch. iii. ^ Hobbes describes his own method, Op. Cit., ni. xi.-xii. ^ Utilitarian Theory of Government. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 59 The reply that the one implies the other is obvious, but unsatisfactory. There are many good reasons why a political philosopher should concern himself with duties and not with rights. (i) It is certain that the rights of Man are not legal rights. They must be what are called moral rights. But supposing that we can attach any definite meaning to the phrase "moral rights," nothing that we can do will ever deprive the word " rights " of its legal savour. We have seen how the expression " laws of nature" may lead to anarchy, but the word "rights" is far more positive than even the word "laws." (2) But if we rigorously exclude the idea of positive legal rights, we have still a whole bundle of ambiguities. An example will shew this. We say that A has a moral right to receive ;^5 from B. We may mean simply that it is B's duty to pay that sum. Or that if A chooses to force B to pay, no one ought to prevent him. Or that other people ought to force B to pay, and this they ought to do either by the force of law, or by the force of public opinion. Let me for a moment invent a term or two. If we merely mean that B ought to pay, then A has a moral claim. If we mean that if A forces B to pay, no one ought to interfere, or that other people ought to force B to pay by the sanction of popular opinion, then A has a moral right. If we mean that third parties ought to oblige B to pay by making some law to that effect, then A has an ideal legal right. This analysis is not complete but must suffice. (3) Our moral claims and moral rights depend in some measure on positive law. We say that A has a Digitized by Microsoft® 6o Political Philosophy in England moral right to ;i^5 from B. We may mean that B ought to pay, and pubHc opinion ought to make him pay, the law of the land being what it is ; or that B ought to pay, and public opinion ought to make him pay, whatever may be the law of the land. For all these reasons " rights " should be left to their proper owners, the lawyers. If the rights of man mean anything definite, they can be translated into terms of duty, and it is very advisable that this should be done. Let us take an actual case. Locke and Rousseau would agree in saying that men have a right to be equal. Now this may mean that no one ought to do anything tending to inequality ; or that public opinion ought to prevent anyone from doing anything tending to inequality; or that a law ought to be made to punish those who do anything tending to inequality. Again, it may mean that the first, or the first and second of these propositions are true, law being xvhat it is, or are true whatever law may be. This is extremely brief and incomplete, the am- biguities of "moral rights" are not exhausted, they are scarcely exhaustible ; but enough has been said to shew that we should look on a philosophy of rights _ with suspicion. We must now consider what were the philosophic weapons which Englishmen had to oppose , to the Rights of Man. It would be unfair to say that Burke used any one weapon, for he used all, and Coleridge is right in saying that he was not very consistent in his use of them. He could be a maintainer of inalienable rights against the calculators, a reckoner of expediency against the preachers of inalienable rights. But Burke Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 6i has, and has justly, the reputation of being a great philosophic statesman ; he shews a desire to get to first principles, and this is the desire of the philosopher. So we may fairly dissect his theories as if they were but the theories of a system-maker. Now, throughout his works on the Revolution, the two most successful lines of argument are the religious and the utilitarian. He could easily shew that the revolution was opposed to Christianity. He could shew that a great deal of unhappiness resulted from the subversion of the old social order. But he tried to do more than this. Like Hobbes he tried to wrest the conventional theory out of his adversaries' hands. In his Reflections on the Revolution, he takes pains to prove, as against Dr Price, that the rights of choosing our governors, and of cashiering them for misconduct, were not claimed by this nation in 1688. Again, in the Appeal to the old Whigs, he would shew that the party to which he still professed to belong was not committed to the principles of 1789. To a certain extent he was successful. He could shew that Somers in drawing the Bill of Rights was careful to base the English Revolution on necessity. He could say that he did not wish to be a better Whig than Somers, who held that the revolt against James could only be justified by a privilegium, and privilegiwm non transit in exemplum. He could shew that the managers of Sacheverell's trial had been at pains to accuse the Doctor on special, not on general grounds ; it was not Revolution, but the Revolution of 1688 which was justifiable. But then this proves litde. Somers had to scrape together a majority, he wanted (as Macaulay Digitized by Microsoft® 62 Political Philosophy in England says) not to frame a valid syllogism, but to secure 200 votes by his major and 200 more by his conclusion^ That James had broken the original contract, that he had abdicated, that he had left the country, were all put forward as reasons for calling in William. Besides, as Mackintosh shews^ Somers and Maynard, when pressed by the Tory Lords, admitted that William was an elected king. Nor was it likely that Walpole and Jekyl would argue for sweeping principles when all they wanted was a conviction. More than this is required if Burke would convince us of the thorough novelty of the French doctrines. We may not wish to be better Whig statesmen than Somers, we cannot hope to be more truly Whig philosophers than Somers' friend Locke. Coleridge was far more right than Burke, he knew that the French doctrines of liberty and equality were of no sudden growth. Even Cole- ridge does not trace these doctrines to their source. Coleridge's friend Sydney had gone nearly as far as Coleridge's enemy Locke. Locke did not invent many new political doctrines, his materials were ready to hand ; he did but define them more sharply, systematize them more accurately, and reject all that was incon- sistent with them. Burke is really much hampered by this notion that he is attacking principles of mushroom growth, the fancies of a few atheistic "garreteers"; this prevents his striking at the real root of the doctrines he hated. He will not break loose from the original contract. Like Hobbes, he will try to shew that we have surrendered some parts of our natural liberty once for all. Only he will find a historic ^ Hist. Engl. ^ Vindicia Gallica. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 63 support for this theory. The original contract was confirmed at the Revolution, and was reconfirmed by the Acts of Settlement. And here is a real fact to rest upon, Parliament did profess to bind themselves their heirs and posterities for ever, therefore we are for ever bound \ Hume had answered this argument some thirty years in advance : " Let not the establishment of the Revolution deceive us.... It was only the majority of seven hundred who determined that change for near ten millions. I doubt not, indeed, but the bulk of these ten millions acquiesced willingly in the deter- mination, but was the matter left in the least to their choice^ ? " Burke, of course, would reply that the majority of seven hundred was constitutionally com- petent to bind the rest. But how came this about ? Why were they constitutionally competent to do this ? The only answer that the conventional theory can supply is, that they were so under the terms of some older compact. So at last we get back to the original contract, for obviously no subsequent ratification which is only binding because made under the terms of that contract can add any force to our original obligation. So Burke must hold that previous to any social contract the father can bind the son, or else the original contract and all proceedings founded thereon are not obligatory on us. Burke said that he was a Whig ; but here he is at issue with the great apostle of Whiggism, who states with emphasis that the father cannot bind the son. Now Hobbes, in trying to make the con- ventional theory Conservative artfully slurs over this ^ Reflections, etc. ^ Essays, ii. xii. Digitized by Microsoft® 64 Political Philosophy in England point, managing to speak as if the covenant had been made once for all, and at the same time as if it was made by each successive generation. But Burke dis- tinctly holds that the father can bind the son, thinking however that this is the result of the original contract, which, as I say, it cannot be. The power of binding posterity must be independent of the dontract, or else the contract itself has no force. We must now face this difficulty : " Can a father bind his posterity by his contracts ? " Burke and Dr Whewell say " Yes," Locke and the Utilitarians say " No." Let us see what popular opinion says. That a father can bind his children to the full extent of what they receive from him by bequest or inheritance is a principle of law which has generally, though not always, the support of positive morality. But that a father can bind his children beyond this extent could never be made law. A covenants to build a school, and, his children being otherwise provided for, be- queaths all his property to a hospital, leaving his covenant unfulfilled. Popular opinion would sanction a law obliging the hospital trustees to build the school, but it would certainly not sanction a law obliging the children to build the school, nor would it consider it morally obligatory on them to do so, even if the hospital trustees evaded their obligation. Common morality does not require the son to keep his father's covenants qua son, but qua heir, devisee, or legatee. And it will be noticed that in Dr Whewell's argument against Paley the cases of hereditary obligation chosen are cases in which the ancestor's property has passed to his descendants. So if popular opinion allow the Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 65 force of these lasting covenants, it is only when they " run with " the possession of property. This is the straw at which Locke catches, just before he makes up his mind to require an express consent from every citizen. But what says the English law ? Any number of lives in being twenty-one years and a few months, that is the limit to your power over real property. But it may be said that this is the outcome of the contract, and is not prior thereto. But will popular morality go further than the English law ? Certainly not at present ; if the length of time for which settle- ments are valid is altered, it will not be lengthened. For centuries the law has abhorred a perpetuity. And why .? Because it is "contrary to public policy." Are we then to believe that it is not contrary to public policy that we should be bound by a contract made by our ancestors when they first left that state of nature which they probably were never in ? I must repeat that any subsequent proceeding of those who, under the original contract had power to settle the govern- ment of this country, cannot be binding on us, unless the contract under which they held the power could be binding on us. Paine perhaps exaggerates when he says, " There never did, there never will, and there never can exist a Parliament, or any description of men, or any generation of men, in any country, possessed of the right or the power of binding posterity 'to the end of time.'... and therefore all such clauses, acts, or declarations by which the makers attempt to do what they have neither the right nor the power to do, nor the power to execute, are themselves null M. 5 Digitized by Microsoft® 66 Political Philosophy in England and void\" We should probably add these words — " if they do not conduce to the good, the happiness, or the morality of the nation." Such clauses are rather "voidable" than "void." But Paine is far nearer common sense than Burke is ; those "primary morals," "untaught feehngs unvitiated by pedantry," to which Burke appeals are quite against him. No man really conceives that his duty to obey the Queen or the laws depends even in the least degree on the fact that some ancestor of his may possibly have promised that he should do so. But Burke himself was not satisfied with this, and falls back into a sort of scepticism. To this he had always been prone. In his first work we see its germ in a distrust of human reason, which can easily " make the wisdom and power of God in his creation appear to many no better than foolishness^" This germ developes, until we find him railing against philosophy, appealing to "prejudices cherished all the more because they are prejudices," describing the heart of the meta- physician as pure, unmixed, defecated, dephlegmated eviP. But this strain of language, this assertion that in morals and politics, reason should yield to prejudice, is not natural to Burke. When he describes his own reforms, we do not hear that they were dictated by untaught feeling. No, "I have," he says, "ever abhorred... all the operations of opinion, fancy, inclina- tion, and will in the affairs of government, where only a sovereign reason, paramount to all forms of legisla- tion, should dictate^" The passage from which this ' Rights of Man. " Vindication, etc. ^ Letter to a Noble Lord. ^ Ibid. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 67 is quoted was written near the close of his life, it shews Burke still proud of having been a philosophic reformer, still proud that great and learned economists (probably including Adam Smith) had communicated to him upon some points of "their immortal works," works not dictated by " cherished prejudices." But Burke was like Reid, he thought that he could play the plain man among philosophers, and the philo- sopher among plain men. Why, we must ask, did Burke in arguing against the friends of the Jacobins descend- from principles to prejudices ? Burke has defended himself against the charge of quitting his party, but we do not need this apology to shew us how thorough a Whig he was to the last. No perception of the badness of its results could bring him to abandon the conventional theory. His scepticism is the result ; he will neither give up the old doctrine, that all rightful government must rest on the consent of the ruled, nor accept the only legitimate deduction from this principle. So hiding his meaning in a cloud of words, he in effect repeats over and over again that the doctrine of the rights of man is true in theory but false in practice. Here is a specimen of his philosophy. " The pre- tended rights of these theorists are all extremes ; and in proportion as they are metaphysically true, they are morally and politically false. The rights of men are in a sort of middle, incapable of definition, but not impossible to be discerned. .. .Political reason is a computing principle, adding, subtracting, multiplying, and dividing morally and not metaphysically or mathe- matically true moral denominations \" Some examples ' Reflections, etc. 5—2 Digitized by Microsoft® 68 Political Philosophy in England of principles metaphysically true, but morally and politically false, of moral as opposed to mathematical and metaphysical addition, would not have been thrown away. But what this and many other similar passages really mean is, that Burke will not surrender the premises but will reject the conclusion. If Burke could but have brought himself to deny that these "metaphysic rights" have any existence, he would have struck the French philosophy the heaviest blow it ever received. But for a really convincing argument against the conventional theory we must turn from Burke to Bentham. Bentham's Anarchical Fallacies'^ is one of his best works. It was written before he, perhaps influenced by James Mill, took that peculiar view of human nature which made him think democracy the only form of government tolerable by the Utilitarian. Bentham hated the claim of "meta- physic rights" no less than Burke did, and bolder than Burke, he denied their existence. He insists on having every word in the French declaration explained. What is a right? Are you using "can," "is," and " ought to be " as synonyms ? Such and such like questions he showers down, questions which Sieyes would have found it difficult to answer. The Third Article of the Declaration was a statement of the con- ventional theory. " The principle of every sovereignty resides essentially in the nation. No body of men, no single individual can exercise authority which does not expressly issue from thence." If this had been presented as a naked proposition, I believe that Locke, Sydney, Milton, and even Hooker would have accepted ^ Bentham's Works, ii. 491. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 69 it. Bentham replies, — The first sentence is perfectly- true, perfectly harmless, where there is no obedience there is no government. When we come to the second clause, we meet "the ambiguous and envenomed 'can." Can not rulers exercise more power than has been expressly committed to them by the nation ? They do. This is not the meaning. It must mean that all laws hitherto made are void. What are you going to do to prevent laws being void ? The whole nation must consent — women, children, all. If women and children are not part of the nation, ^ivhat are they ? Cattle? " Indeed, how can a single soul be excluded when all men, all human creatures, are, and are to be equal in regard to rights, in regard to all such rights, without exception or reserve." There is much more of such argument, obvious perhaps, but tending to shew how unsatisfactory a support the rights of man afford for human happiness. The whole argument might be summed up in the question — If the assertion of these rights of man does not lead to human happi- ness, are you right in asserting them ? If it is not right to assert them, in what sense can they be called rights ? Of course, it is in many ways absurd to compare Bentham with Burke, but Bentham supplies just the one thing which always seems wanting in Burke's denunciations of Jacobinism. Burke always feared lest in rooting up revolutionary principles he would root up the principles for which he and his forerunners had contended. It may be added that this exposure of Anarchical Fallacies was intended as a pendent to the Book of Digitized by Microsoft® 7o Political Philosophy in England Fallacies, for if the two be read together it will be seen that there is Httle justice in either of the contra- dictory accusations that have lately been made against Bentham ; (i) that he made law the measure of justice, (2) that in advocating law reforms of secondary im- portance he sacrificed what was of primary importance — respect for law. The doctrine of the rights of man returned from France to England with all the latest improvements. We must once more refer to the argument on which it is based. Locke says in effect that God has made all men equal, and that this must be taken as evidence of God's intention that there should be no subordination among them save such as results from consent. Now there is much plausibility in this argument, and it was open to Locke and to Rousseau. But it was scarcely one which some of their followers could use, for the best of reasons, namely, that they did not believe that God had made man at all. Tom Paine could only use it by substituting "nature" for "God," and when this is done the argument ceases to be plausible. If we cease to believe that the original equality of man was produced by a Being infinite in goodness and wisdom, there seems to be no reason for treating men as equals when they have become unequals. The defence of the doctrine in Mackintosh's answer to Burke is interesting, because it is a piece of philosophy in the transitional style ; it wavers between Locke and Hume. Mackintosh argues^ that Burke admits the existence of natural equal rights in all men. Some of these we surrender, but as each surrenders an ' VindicicR GalliccE. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 71 equal portion, the remaining portions of all must be equal. All men have an equal right to share in the government. But then he turns round— he must have read Hume, and may have read Bentham's Fragment. He would leave out " prope " in the line, " Ipsa utilitas justi prope mater et sequi." "Justice is expediency," but he adds, " it is expediency speaking by general maxims into which reason has consecrated the ex- perience of mankind. Every general principle of justice is demonstrably expedient, and it is utility alone that confers on us a moral obligation." But though these rights arise from expediency, " the moment the moral edifice is reared its basis is hid from the eye for ever."..." It then becomes the perfection of virtue to consider not whether an action be useful, but whether it be right." He then proceeds to argue in the familiar way that the expedience philosophy does not require us to always calculate the expedience of an action, such calculation being itself inexpedient. But this will not do. The rule forbidding calcula- tion is not a rule for the philosopher laying down his middle axioms ; it is a rule for the practical man who has to act in a hurry, and will very likely count himself for more than one. The principle of equality is a principle of justice. " Every principle of justice is demonstrably expedient." Then why not demonstrate the expedience of equality ? Because that men should be equal is a maxim into which reason has consecrated the experience of mankind ? Surely not. We cannot, at all events, take so important a principle upon trust as being that basis of the moral edifice which is hidden from the eye for ever. If Utilitarianism be once Digitized by Microsoft® 72 Political Philosophy in England allowed to be at the base of the rights of man, Burke's reply would be crushing. Mackintosh, it may be noticed, afterwards surrendered both Utilitarianism and democracy. But while the conventional theory was falling into discredit among English philosophers it was proclaimed as a necessary truth by no less a person than Kant. The key-stone of his jurisprudence is the idea of free- dom. Law ought to minimize the external restraints to free action^ We however meet with another notion of freedom, and this a familiar one. " Frei- heit...ist die Befugniss, keinen aiisseren Gesetzen zu gehorchen, als zu denen ich meine Beistimmung habe geben konnen^" Kant was a republican. The republican constitution is, he thinks, "die einzige, welche aus der Idee des urspriinglichen Vertrags hervorgeht auf der alle rechtliche Gesetzgebung eines Volks gegriindet sein muss." But by republicanism he does not mean democracy. " Der Republicanism us ist das Staatsprincip der Absonderung der ausfiihrenden Gewalt (der Regierung) von der gesetzgebenden," What exactly Kant meant by saying that all right laws must be grounded on the idea of an Original Contract, and that we are free when under no laws to which we could not have given our consent, must here be left undetermined. But doubtless it was in imita- tion of Kant that Coleridge refused to give up the conventional theory. Coleridge has elaborately ex- posed that " metapolitical " system which attempts to evolve an idea of government out of the pure reason. His attack is directed against Rousseau, but is still ^ Rechtslehre. ^ Entwurf zum ewigen Frieden. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 73 more applicable to Kant. He himself is in politics a Utilitarian, a zealous advocate for deriving the various forms and modes of government from human prudence, and of deeming that just which experience has found to be expedient'. This being so he does what we should expect, he throws over the original contract. But he cannot give up the last fragment of the conventional theory. He introduces an "ever- originating contract " between the subjects and the sovereign. "If there be any difference between a government and a band of robbers, an act of consent must be supposed on the part of the people governed ^" Supposed ! What would Coleridge have said if he had caught Paley affirming that the difference between right and wrong depends upon a supposition ? If we are not going — and Coleridge most certainly was not — to require an actual consent, why ever should we re- quire a supposed consent? Coleridge's sole support for this teaching is an argument addressed to Paley, namely, that whatever Hume might do, a clergyman ought to know that God has authorized the con- ventional theory by his own example : the relation of mankind as a body spiritual to the Saviour at its head is styled a covenant. But this is trifling. Christians believe that God has actually made promises to them, and that they have actually made promises to God. Are we to say that these promises are " supposed " .-" Lastly, Dr Whewell espoused the cause of an " ever-originating " contract. He thinks " the social compact... expresses in one phrase the mutual relations ' The Friend, Essay in. ^ Essay ii. Digitized by Microsoft® 74 Political Philosophy in England of the governors and governed, and of all classes one with another ; the reciprocal character of their rights ; the possibility of the obligations of one party ceasing, in consequence of some act done by another party; the duty of fidelity. and respect to the Constitu- tion ; and the condemnation of those who violate or disregard such duties'." This is true, but the expres- sion "social compact" impHes much more than this, it implies that the duties of the governors and the governed depend upon the existence of some agree- ment ; it implies that had there not been some social agreement, men's duties would not have been what they now are. The social compact is quite unneces- sary to Dr Whewell's system, for he admits a special duty of Order ; and this, not the duty of keeping promises, is the origin of our duty to respect the Constitution. And indeed he expressly says that " Government has rights which no contract among the subjects could give^" This being so, the consent of the subjects not being required in order to make a government rightful, it is surely a mistake to use an expression which was intended to imply, and does still imply, that men have " a right " to be under no govern- ment save one which exists by consent. It is also advisable that anti-Utilitarian moralists should cease to use a phrase which points to a defect in the systems of their predecessors, of which their own systems are not guilty. Hitherto the attacks on the conventional theory have come from professed Utilitarians, while their opponents have only surrendered the doctrine which bases the duty of obedience to civil law on the duty of ' Elements, % 849. ^ § 828. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 75 keeping promises, with great reluctance. It would certainly be well that the anti-Utilitarians should clear themselves from the charge of not being able to give any account of our political duties, without falling back upon a principle which either lands us in democracy or has to be turned aside from its natural course by some fiction. It was not unnatural, we repeat, that the conventional theory should have found advocates among moralists who yet were no friends to de- mocracy ; for (i) many moralists have been accustomed to see in the duty of keeping promises the duty most directly and obviously dictated by reason, and (2) those who take the jural view of morality, and include all duties in the general duty of obeying law (i.e., divine or natural law), may easily omit to find a place for the special duty of obeying the law of the land. But Dr Whewell has admitted a special duty of Order^ — a duty of obeying civil law as civil law, and only clings to the social compact because it is an apt phrase. Again, when Dr Whewell says, " the social-compact is the constitution," surely this is misleading. It implies that Englishmen have consented to this constitution. Now this can only be true if their continued residence in this country be taken as evidence of consent, and residence can only be evidence of consent to one part of our law, if it be evidence of consent to all parts. We have only consented to the fundamental laws of the constitution if we have consented to every statute on the books. If our consent bar our repealing the one, it bars our repealing the other ; and yet there are some statutes which we may certainly have a duty to repeal. There cannot be any real danger to Digitized by Microsoft® 76 Political Philosophy in England the great principles of our Constitution in admitting the fact that they do not depend upon consent. We do not wish to be better Whigs than Lord Macaulay, and he treated the original contract with contempt. There is much of truth in what another Whig, Samuel Johnson (Coleridge's " Cobbett-Burke ") said : " To establish the throne upon a notorious untruth is to establish it upon Mr Milton's Vacuum, where it must fall ten thousand fathoms deep, and know no end of falling'." But turning from the conventional theory as it is in Coleridge, a self-convicted fiction, a supposition, to the great principle which Locke took from Hooker, and Rousseau from Locke, we have yet to ask how far the ideal government of those who profess this theory can be called "free." It is certain that the gradual de- velopment of the conventional theory in the direction of democracy was perfectly logical ; that is, that if Hooker would controvert the doctrines of Locke, he must modify some passages in his own writings, notably that passage which I have quoted ; that if Locke would resist Rousseau and Tom Paine, he must contract some of his most essential propositions. Democracy seems a necessary point through which we must pass in attempting to make the consent of the governed more and more of a reality. Since the French Revolution, the conventional theory has fallen into some discredit. Looking back now, we may say that the anti-democratic panic which Burke did much to create, was not wholly reasonable, that to it were due some of the revolutionary excesses ; ^ Abrogation of King James by the People of England, etc. Digitized by Microsoft® Liberty 77 but below this temporary reaction there was a reason- able feeling, that the French Liberie was not a good ideal for state action. " The liberty to which Mr Burke declared himself attached was not French Liberty'," and even when it puts out of sight the horrors and absurdities of Jacobinism, English opinion is at one with Mr Burke. The tyranny of the majority, of which De Tocqueville set the example of speaking, has become an object of dread. But still the conven- tional theory is popular, it crops up when men become excited ; it appeared in 1832 and in 1866, it appears when any clqss desires to acquire a share in the govern- ment. The principal influence with which it has to contend is the influence of certain other ideals of liberty, with which it is maintained to be incompatible — for instance, religious liberty, or commercial liberty. That there is something very plausible in calling a popular government a " free government " is certain. It has been so-called through ages. It is into the reasons for this that we must now enquire. Aristotle says — uird^ecrts [i-h) ovv ttjs SyjfjiOKpaTLKT]<; TroXireias ikevdepta. tovto yap Xdyeiv eicidacrLV, ws iv p.6vr) rrj TToXiTeCa ravTrj )u,€Tej(ovras iXevdepia