OLIN HB 501 .M39 L34 ISSSai 1 ^OHNM.^\ OLIN g 3 1924 074 296 330 In compliance with current copyright law, Cornell University- Library produced this replacement volume on paper that meets the ANSI Standard Z39. ■^8-1984 to replace the irreparably deteriorated original. 1993 KARL MARX AN ESSAY By HAROLD J. LASKI London ; THE FABIAN SOCIETY 25, TothiU Street, Westminster, S. W. 1 and ALLEN & UN WIN LIMITED 40, Musieum Street, London, W.C.I ONE SHILLING ^r0i^^. '^.-^.^ TO H. G. WELLS. >y sal { L^^ This work has been published at the expense of the TuUoch and Barr Publishing Fund, instituted as a Memorial of Lieut. William Tulloch and Capt. Hugh Barr, M.B., R.A.M.C., two members of the Fabian Society who lost their lives in the Great War. ^7 7/ 73-/3 a 3? X KARL MARX AN ESSAY NO name in the history of social ideas occupies a place more remarkable than that of Karl Marx. Save Machiavelli and Rousseau, no thinker has been the subject of a condemnation so unsparing, and, like Rousseau, it has been his fortune to preside after death over a revolution conceived in his name. His books have received from a chosen band a scrutiny as earnest as ever the Bible or the Digest have obtained. Yet the precise grounds of the position he occupies among Socialists is a more complex problem than is usually assumed. His theory of value is no more than a formid- able adaptation of a concept already worked out in full by a group of English" pfedecessors. TSIennike HaHing' ton and James Madison realized, hardly l ess clearly than he, the significance of the materialist interpretation of history. His appreciation of the fact of class antagonism had been anticipated in detail by Saint-Simon. Even his passionate sympathy with the inarticulate aspirations of the working class was no more profound than that of Charles Hall and Owen and John Stuart Mill. His position, indeed, cannot be appreciated unless it is seen in its historical perspective. Born between two revolutions, he utilized the method produced by the re- action from the excesses of France to the service of its fundamental principles. The disciple of Hegel, he was the first of those who felt his master's influence to apply his dialectic to the analysis of social facts. Hardly less important was the material of which he made use. Be- ginning to write when the full implications of capitalism were becoming visible, he utilized its own description of its economic consequences as the proof of its moral inadequacy. The evidence was impressive and complete ; and the induction therefrom of a social order at once new and inevitable, suited to a nicety the yearnings of his generation. 4 KARL MARX The main result of the Hegelian movement was to lend a new sanction to philosophic conservatism. The impact of the revolutionary wars seems to have turned the mind of its founder towards the justification of estab- lished order. In that sense, Hegel is a chief of reac- tionary romanticism, and his affinity to men like Burke and Savigny is obvious. Yet the essence of Hegelianism is, at the same time, the idea of evolution, and, to an age which, as with de Maistre, was chiefly concerned with finding the basis of a permanent social scheme the notion of evolution was a definitely radical one. For Hegel insists on the impermanence of institutions. Each age is its predecessor with a difference. There is a change of tone and outlook, a tendency to emphasize the anti- thesis of what has been characteristic of the earlier period. To the period of religious intensity there suc- ceeds the age of religious indifference; Bossuet begets Voltaire, as Lord Eldon implies the reforming zeal of Henry Brougham. The law of life is the warring of contradictions, with growth as its consequence. This process, which Hegel called dialectic, is, as it were, a kind of rhythm which moves from the concrete hardness of some definite idea to its opposite ; from that repulsion it shifts towards a synthesis in which the two first stages interpenetrate each other to form a new concept by their union. This notion is the ruling method of Marxian thought. Obviously enough, it provides a means whereby the foundations of any given social system may be criticized at their base. For if we can be certain that any inter- prtrtation of a period is necessarily a partial view, we have only to emphasize its antithesis to call forth the possibility of a new standpoint. Hegelianism, for example, might insist on the moral adequacy of the Prussian State. But under its very banner. Young Germany might make protest against its rigorous im- permeability to freedom. Where Hegelian doctrine had empliasized birth and position, Young Germany could point to the frustration of talent and the tragedies of the poor. Where it insisted on the value of religion, the newer thinkers might question the very foundation's of faith. The disciples of Hegel, in fact, turned the weap ins of their master to the service of a cause he had KARL MARX 5 denied. Straus s and Feuerbach, Bruno Bauer and Heine are essentially a part of the same generaltendericy of which Marx is the representative in social ideas. They are the heralds of revolt against the reaction. Their| difference from Marx consists in their failure to see the! political implications of their position. Marx grasped them from the outset ; and the Hegelian dialectic in his hands is an effort at the overthrow of the existing social order. The time, indeed, was singularly fitted for the ideas of which he was the protagonist. The shadow of two French Revolutions bestrode Europe like a colossus; and the very reaction they had provoked was compelled to make grudging concessions to ensure even its tem- porary survival. The mood of the people was every- where bitter and discontented; and the criticism of exist- ing institutions secured a widespread and eager welcome. In France, the work of Saint-Simon and Fourier and Enfantin had shown how prolific of novelty the revolu- tion remained ; and its influence was hardly less apparent in the new liberalism of Sismondi and the Catholic experiments of Lamennais. England was in the throes of a convulsion not the less profound because it was silent. Bentham had at last come into his own; and, under the stress of his urgent protests English institu- tions were being transformed into the organs of a middle- class state. The refics of feudalism had at last submitted to the assaults of Ricardo and his school ; and the new- born industrialism, even if, to an observant eye, it seemed but the grim doctrines of Calvin translated to an economic sphere, completely altered the atmosphere of social life. The revolution, indeed, did not achieve its purpose without suffering. As early as 1805, Charles Hall had uttered a remarkable protest against the implications of the new civilization and that half-forgotten school of economists who form a link between the individualism of Bentham and the co-operation of Owen, were riddling its protective armour in the name of social justice. The masses had regarded the Reform Act of 1832 as the prelude to the greatest happiness of the greatest number; and their disappointment expressed itself in the revolu- tionary activity of the trade unions and the formation of 6 KARL MARX the Chartist movement. Thinkers like William Thomp- son and J. F. Bray, noble-minded agitators like Francis Place and William Lovett, are every whit as indicative of the new capitalism as the great merchants and the in- credible machines of Lancashire and Yorkshire. The Industrial Revolution reaped what it had sown. It ground a whole generation into intolerable despair, and dreams of its destruction were the sole refuge of its victims. Those dreams were the background which made possible the emergence of Karl Marx. They gave him the foundation of his social philosophy. II. Karl MaTX was born at Treves on May 5th, 1818, of Jewish parents who were descended on both sides from rabbinic ancestors. Neither his father, whowas a lawyer, nor his mother seems to have had any special ability ; and Marx himself was the only one of several children who attained intellectual distinction. When he was six years old, the family was converted to Christianity, not, it appears, from any desire to avoid the stigma then attached to the Jewish faith, but' as a result of that romantic idealizing of Christianity of which Chateau- briand was the most famous representative. It is not easy to measure exactly what influence this change had upon Marx. If it later opened to him avenues that would otherwise have been closed, he never availed him- self of them. To the end of his life he remained some- thing of an anti-Semite ; but this does not seem traceable to any emotion of iapostasy\ Marx's childhood was passed in the normal atmosphere of a patriotic lawyer's life. His father was a zealous Prussian, to whom the defeat of Napoleon offered the opportunity, of which his son did not take advantage, of a lyrical hymri to Prussian victory. He went to the grammar school of his native town, where his ability was immediately marked by his teachers. There, too, he was intimate with the Privy Councillor, von West- phalen, whose house was a kind of salon for the intel- lectual youth of Treves. At least Marx learned there a love of literature, and the dedication of his doctor's thesis is testimony to his grateful regard for his future father-in-law. For even before his departure, in 1835, KARL MARX 7 to Bonn University, he had become secretly engaged to Jenny von Westphalen, whose beauty and strength of mind had awakened in him an affection which did not diminish through life. Marx remained a year in Bonn, studying jurispru- dence ; but he seems to have devoted himself to the more convivial side of the University, and it was not until his removal to Berlin, in 1836, that he threw himself into intellectual work. Berlin was then at the very height of its reputation ; and the influence of Hegel was still para- mount in its instruction. No sort of learning seems to have come amiss to Marx. History and philosophy, geography and jurisprudence, literature and aesthetic, all of them aroused in him the typical enthusiasm of an undergraduate in search of omniscience. Nor — it is a grateful thought — did he fail to write poetry ; and if his verses are a fair index to his state of mind, he was full of a restless insatiability for knowledge, and a zealous desire to solve the problems of the universe, from which at least there must have been derived many hours of happy work. He tried his hand at composing philo- sophic systems. He attempted to compile an outline of jurisprudence. He went hardly at all into society, and it was not until the winter of 1837 that his experiments resolved themselves into a settled system. He surren- dered the neo-idealism of Kant and took refuge in a complete acceptance of Hegelian metaphysic. That this change represented for him a very real mental crisis is evident from the passionate, if turgid, letter to his father of November loth, 1837. There he summarizes the in- tense struggle through which he had passed, the desire " to dive into the deeps of the ocean . . . bringing up chaste pearls into the sunlight." He was ill and troubled. His poems^and short stories were burned; he sought escape from the seductions of Hegel in discussion at the Graduates' Club, only to find himself the more securely enmeshed therein. It is the typical intellectual history of an ardent mind, conscious of great powers, and eager to secure a foothold from which to survey the universe. Not unnaturally, it greatly disturbed his father. He, good man, was anxious above all to see Karl at work in a lawyer's office, or, even better, in Government service. 8 KARL MARX Why did he not do as other students, attend his lectures, meet the right people, and embark upon his future career ? He did not understand this mental torment save to see that it involved physical ill-health and a good deal of miscellaneous reading totally unconnected with the law. But Marx's ideals had already passed beyond so pedes- trian an existence; and his father seems to have reconciled himself to the new ambitions. Marx determined upon a University post, and for that purpose devoted himself to the study of philosophic jurisprudence. With friends like Bruno Bauer and Friedrich Koppen, he buried him- self in study and discussion. A thesis was written on the philosophical systems of Democritus and Epicurus, and in 1841 Marx became a doctor of the University of Jena. He rejoined Bauer at Bonn and awaited the oEFer of a lectureship in the University. Had that offer come, the history of European Socialism might have been very different. But the Prussian educational system did not look with affection upon eager young men whose views did not square with orthodox teaching. The post did not arrive, and it was shortly enough obvious that it was not likely to arrive. An academic career being thus im- possible, Marx set to work to find a living in journalism, and in 1842 an opportunity of an attractive kind presented itself. The first number of the Rheinische Zeitung was pub- lished on January ist, 1842, and Marx was a warm friend of the editor, who had met him at the Graduates' Club in Berlin. Invited to assist, he wrote philosophical articles which not only brought him to the notice of a wider circle, among whom were men like Feuerbach and Moses Hess, but also secured for him the direction of the journal on the retirement of its first editor in the next October. Thereby Marx was compelled to deal, and for the first time, with immediate political issues'. He came into contact with French and German Social- ism, then in their Utopian stage. The agrarian problem m the Rhme provinces and the discussion of the tariff gave him " the first stimulus " to investigate economic questions. French socialist ideas were already beinff discussed in the paper, but Marx, as always, determined upon a thorough grasp of the issue, did not as yet pro- nounce upon their worth. An editor who takes time to KARL MARX 9 make up his mind is obviously lost ; and the directors of the paper decided to make a change in its management. Marx, who had just married, seems to have resigned without regret, and to have buried himself for the next two years in those economic studies from which he emerged a Socialist. Of the inner history of those years Ave know practically nothing. Certain alone it is that as early as May, 1843, he detected within society " a breach which the old system cannot heal ' ' ; and it was not long before he showed in his letters an intimate knowledge of Fourier, Proudhon and Cabet. Already he had done with Utopias; the problem was "to explain the struggles and yearnings of the time." In the winter of 184;^, when he had settled with his wife in Paris, he wrote the introducJ tion to Hegel's ^^i^2££^^J:L_£i_L2H' which remains,! perhaps, his profoundestpiece of technical criti cism. ' Already he^"was~fhmkmg~tir'teinis--of-TBVC)1trrron, and insisting that the task of the proletariat was to free itself from the existing social order. Poverty he viewed, thus early, as the artificial product of a bourgeois society ; and the denial of the right to private property had become for him the fundamental avenue of release. But we catch glimpses only of this time. All that can be said with certainty is the fact that reflection had made him a Socialist. He had realized, too, the inadequacies of the abstract remoteness of French Socialism . He had seen that the political state was, at any given time, tjie reflec- tion in structur e of the idea s of that epoch . ~He had realized that the main need was to make plain to the mass of men the implications of the state, and the end to which their half-conscious struggle should lead them. His thought, indeed, was abstract enough, and still fettered within the^jTarrow^waJb__ofjtheJHegelian djalec But at least it was moving forward. Meanwhile, the problem of how to live had still to be solved. He had gone to Paris in October, 1843, to become editor of the Franco-German Year Books. But that periodical lasted only for a single issue, and, for Marx, its chief importance was the appearance therein of a long and, frankly, bad article by Friedrich En^els , on political economy. The article led to correspondence between them, and in the autumn of 1844, Engels went lo KARL MARX to Paris to visit Marx. That visit was the commence- ment of a friendship which even death did not terminate. Friedrich Engels was the son of a rich manufacturer in the Rhineland. His father owned a cotton mill near Manchester, to which, in 1842, Engels had been sent to study English business conditions. He was already an eager critic of social conditions, and how carefully he observed the life about him, his Condition of the Work- ing Classes in England in 1844, which he published in 1845, bears witness. A sympathizer with the Chartist Movement, and a contributor to Owen's New Moral \World, he was exactly in the frame of mind to be recep- tive to Marx's ideas. And his personal qualities admirably fitted him to be the complement of Marx. Thoroughly loyal, without an atom of personal ambition, generous, and self-effacing, practical and energetic, he brought to Marx all the necessarj' characteristics of a Fidus Achates. His unstinting literary assistance hardly less than his constant financial aid were the materials which determined Marx's future career. It is, indeed, almost impossible to disentangle the labours of the twol Clearl}' enough, it was to Engels that Marx owed both his knowledge of English blue-books as a source of economic theorj?^, and his introduction to the work of the English socialist school. Without Engels, too, it would have been difficult for Marx to undertake the research to which the first volume of the Capital bears witness; and the posthumous publication of the two latter volumes was the tribute that Engels paid to the memory of his master. That Marx would have been an important figure without Engels is clear enough ; but the aid ren- dered by the latter made all the difference between the comparative calm of London and the restless wanderings of which hapless exiles like Bakunin were the miserable victims. The sudden end of the Franco-German Year Books made Marx turn to more solid production. The Holy Family (1845) is important, not only because it contains the fijst clgar^utline o f the materiali stic conceptinn^nf histog^ but aliSlDecause its attack on Bruno Bauer is evidence that Marx had already broken with the youncr Hegelians. He had come to place all his faith in the significance of mass-movements, where Bauer believed KARL MARX n that the ideas by which mankind is moved cannot hope for mdrethan superKcial understangi ngTrom the mass a nd" depend for the i r success upon t he^ettojJalfit . great ^^ men. Simultaneously, alsoTTie was answering Ruge's'l attacks upon the German proletariat with an impassioned defence of socialism and revolution. Weitling is held up as proof of proletarian virtue against the mediocrity of the political literature of the German bourgeoisie. And in the polemic against Riige it is insisted that thei time for political revolution, the only revolution of which! the German bourgeoisie is capable, had passed; thel capacity of Germany is the capacity of its workers, and ' it is to a social revolution that Marx directs attention, j This Paris period is important not only for the advent of Engels. Mingling with the German workers then living in Paris, Marx naturally met those who were already in sympathy with his own views. From them to Proud- hon was a natural step, for Proudhon was already the dominant socialist influence in France. Proudhon was interested in the Hegelian dialectic, and he and Marx spent countless hours in discussing its application to social science. But this fruitful intercourse was inter- rupted by his expulsion from France (January, 1845) at the demand of the Prussian Government. Marx went from Paris to Brussels, where he remained, but for short intervals, until the outbreak of the I'evolution of 1848. Engels gave him a selection of his library and ' Marx devoted himself to the composition of his singu- larly able and unpl easant criticism of Proudhon. This was published iTrT§47, and it may be said to mark his transition to the full vigour of his matured philosophy. Proudhon's reputation as-a social philosopher has undergone an interesting reconstruction -in our own day.' As an economist he has hardly survived the analysis of Marx. A self-taught man, originally a printer, he came into prominence by the publication, in 1840, of his prize essay. What is Property? in which, with much brilliance of style and no small genius for paradox, he repeated in the economic sphere the sub- stance of those criticisms of social organization which ' See A. Berthod, Proudhon et la Propriiti; C. Bougie, La Sociologie de Proudhon; G. Pirou, Proudhon et Syndicalisme Rdvolutionnaire ; " les Amis de Proudlion," Proudhon et Ses Temps. y 12 KARL MARX Rousseau had expressed in a prize essay not less famous. But Proudhon's aspirations were not limited by his knowledge. With undoubted ability and with a real gift of social insight, he yet lacked that rigorous training in the method of intellectual inquiry without which the pro- duction of a logical system is rarely possible. Discover- ing the work of Hegel, he^alt«n£tedjinjntergretati^n_qf_ social life in terms of the dialectic. It is, broadly, a mass of"ilPaTfTaTrgsa*^argon with sonie brilliant asides. But the work was written while in contact with Marx, and. the Philosophie de la Misere is the exposition of exactly that type of Utopia-mongering which aroused Marx's anger. It depended for its success mainly upon the unconscious ease with which it determines the most complex economic problems, and the reckless certitude of its own conclusions. It is, indeed, at the same time, a very attractive book. Proudhon realized, not less keenly than Marx, the evils of capitalism, and he was not less anxious to point the way to an economic order of which the motives were freedom and justice. In the Dm Principe Federatif and the Justice dans la Revolu- tion, indeed, he outlined a type of federalism of which the suggestiveness is immense ; and it would be legitimate to argue that not the least significant source of the ancestry of Guild Socialism could be traced to his writings. But the conflict between Marx and Proudhon was an inevitable one. At_bottoin,Jh e ideals of P roudhon were those lof a peasant soc iaBsm, ilTwhich the authority of a central state was reduced to a minimum ; he was re- formist in outlook, despite the vigour of his phrases, land his economic views were always subordinate to certain ethical assumptions. Marx was the typical representative of the new industrialism, and the source jof change for him was solely to be traced to develop- ;ments in industrial technique. Authoritarian and !materialist in both outlook and temper;, there was no real contact between Proudhon and himself. Marx more- over, was a trained scholar, to whom the luxuriance of Proudhon's speculations was never an adequate sub- stitute for fact. He was able without difficulty to show that Proudhon understood neither the theory of value nor the process of production. At bottom, as' he insists KARL MARX 13 Proudhon had done little more than urge, first that labour was the source of value, and next that riches and poverty co-exist. Proudhon could see that the source of economic injustice lay somewhere within the system of production, but he could not, with any clarity, explain its development. Marx overwhelmed him with ridicule, abuse, and sarcasm, and it must be admitted that from the standpoint of an economist, right is on his side. And Marx's answer, the Poverty of Philosophy, is note-j worthy also for its firm grasp of the economic processes', of history and for his insistence upon the part that an I oppressed class has always played in the development of any system founded upon class antagonism. But tlie main value of the book consists less in any positive doctrine that ft annoiIricS^tian~ln~the~jrtTtlospKere~By' wKIch it is permeated. It is definitely revolutionary, and it is revolutiohar)' because it is historical. Its lesson is the argument that social evolution implies economic revolution. That was a new note to strike in the history of European Socialism. III. The controversy with Proudhon was the natural pre- lude to the Communist Manifesto. It had been evident to Marx, for several years before 1848, that Europe was on the verge of revolt. England was passing through a period of intense agitation. Socialism was growing in Germany by leaps and bounds; and the lyrical falsi- fications of Lamartine seemed to the Paris workmen in- finitely preferable to the mediocre corruption of Guizot and Louis Philippe. Marx, indeed, did not see that the political situation was far too complex to admit of an interpretation in uniform terms. Democratic nation- alism like that of -Mazzini, individualist republicanism like that of Ledru-Rollin, such hostility to dynastic oppression as Kossuth embodied, ,state socialism as typified by Louis Blanc — the forces of upheaval were too various and incompatible to admit of any continuous co-operation. Bitterly as the worker might resent the: consequences of industrialism, he had not yet reached the stage where the seizure of political power for) economic ends seemed to him the one ideal worthy ofl attainment. And he was, to no small degree, still 14 KARL MARX attracted by the kind of unrealistic thinking of which Robert Owen was so prolific, the sense that the diffi- culties of , the time might be evaded by extra-political organization. Marx realized that this attitude was definitely unconstructive. The seizure of the State was to him the starting point of successful effort, and when Frederic William IV summoned the United Assembly in Februar}', 1847, it was not unnatural for him to assume that the hour for action was at hand. From the outset of his life in Brussels, Marx had mingled with the German socialist residents there. He had come into contact with the League of the Just, an organization of German workers with branches in the chief European towns. This society, founded in 1836, had in 1840 moved its headquarters to London, pro- bably to escape the unwelcome attention s^jpf the political police. The attention of the London gjoi^p had been drawn to Marx by the members in Parl^teiid Brussels. The London branch commissioned inquiries to be made about him, and when the first Congress of the League was held in London in the summer of 1847, Engels and Wilhelm Wolff, the latter, through Engels, a disciple of Marx, were present at its deliberations. Engels had spent the year in efforts at revolutionarj'- propaganda in Paris and the Rhineland; and it is probably due, in the main, to him that the League of the Just was trans- formed into the Communist League. The ground was thus prepared for Marx, who appeared at the second Congress, also in London, in December, 1847. Engels had already conferred with him as to the ground to be taken there; and he had sent Marx the outline of a programme to be offered to the Congress for acceptance. Engel's outline contains the substance of the famous manifesto; but it lacks the ringing challenge and firm grasp of its successor. At the Congress, Marx and Engels were commissioned to draw up a programme. They were prepared for the effort; and the'Cerman edition of the Communist Manifesto appeared a few ..^ays before the outbreak of the Paris revolution. : It is not easy to over estimate the significance of the ; Manifesto. It gave direction and a philosophy to what : had been before little more than an inchoate protest against injustice. It began the long process of weldincr KARL MARX 15 together the scattered groups of the disinherited into an organized and influential party. It freed SociaUsm from its earlier situation of a doctrine cherished by conspira- tors in defiance of government and gave to it a ^ once a purpose and an historic background. It almost created a proletarian consciousness by giving, and for the first time, to the workers at once a high sense of their historic mission. and a realization of the dignity implicit in their task. It destroyed at a stroke both the belief that Socialism could triumph without long preparation, and the hope that any form of economic organization was possible save that which was implicit in the facts of the time. It insisted upon no natural rights. It did not lay down any metaphysic. It was, on the contrary, a careful and critical historic survey of the institutional process regarded as a whole. To insia|^iBon its epoch-making character is not to. regard it^^p^n original or definitive document or to; suggest that it is free from inconsistencies. It qwesi much, clearly, tojDqn_siderantls_J£am/ejfM_d£_Ja-j3e«io- cratie which M^as published four years before.' There Have been Utopian socialisms in despite of Marx; and we are doubtless not at the end of them. The belief in natural rights revives with every age of discontent, and it would be possible to prove that the idea of natural rights is necessarily implicit in the juridical structure' of Socialism. Nor is its treatment of the middle class at all adequate. At one point it is subject to a vitupera- tion so scathing and relentless, as to make it seem the nurse of all social evil. At another its great historic achievements are exalted beyond all praise. Its immediate programme of action is borrowed in almost everyi particular from those earlier Socialists who are so un-i sparingly condemned. Nor can Marx's claim that he substituted " a critical insight into the facts, progress and general results of the actual social movement "for the systems of his predecessors, be entirely accepted;! for, after all, it is not the least merit of Fourier and' Saint-Simon that they had described with not less sober accuracy than that of Marx the economic conditions of their time. Even the use of the class-war as the key to ' But Considerant, though his picture of the economic situation is lilcc that of Marx, rejects revolutionary communism. i6 KARL MARX history was brilliantly anticipated in the Gene.van Letters of Saint-Simon. ' Yet the general superiority of the Manifesto to previous Socialist writing is incontestable. It contains, broadly speaking, four definite groups of ideas. Be- ginning with a history of the growth of the middle class, it recounts its victory over feudal privilege, its emer- gence into the full development of capitalistic enterprise, and its necessary result in a revolutionary proletariat. A second section deals with the philosophic interpreta- tion of this history. It argues that the doctrine of the class struggle, the necessary and inevitable conflict between the bourgeoisie and the proletariat, with the consequent revolutionary role that is assigned to the latter, are the plain deductions to be drawn. Ways and means are then discussed, the main object of which is to bring within the ambit of state control the whole economic life of the people. There then follows a criticism of previous Socialist literature of which it must be said that, forcible and eloquent as it is, much of it is inaccurate and the whole unfair. No description can do justice to the brilliant vigour of the whole. Every phrase of it is a challenge, and much of it has the same moving passion that distinguishes the exordium of the Social Contract or, in a very different type of polemic, the Paroles d'un Croyant of Lamennais. It is the book of men who have viewed the whole process of history from an eminence and discovered therein an inescapable lesson. It is at once an epilogue and a prophecy — an epilogue to the deception from which the workers suffered in the Revolution of 1789, and a prophecy of the land of promise they may still hope to enter. A movement that could produce a challenge so profound came hardly less to fulfil than to destroy. It had hardly appeared before the .Revolution broke out in Paris, and Marx, as a precautionary measure, was banished from Brussels by the Belgian Government. " Tyranny has banished you," wrote the French Pro- visional Government, " but a free France opens her gates to you." Marx proceeded to Paris, but remained there only a short time. Germany was already seething with revolt, and the natural vantage-ground for him was obviously the Rhineland. Gathering about him KARL MARX 17 the members of the Communist League, Marx went to Cologne where the editorship of the revolutionary paper, the Neue Rheinische Zeitimg, was entrusted to him. Brief as was its life, its substance was not merely- brilliant but of great significance as an indication of the Marxian tactic. Engels and Wilhelm Wolff were its chief contributors, and Freiligrath and Lassalle sent poems and essays. Mehring has published a selection of the chief articles of Marx in this paper. Dominantly, they insist upon three ideas : the disarming of the bourgeoisie, the erection of a revolutionary terror " 10 abridge and concentrate the hideous death agonies of society," and the creation of a revolutionary army. Th ^ere is no room in Marx's_thouglit, save perhaps asj an ultimate, tor any d em ocratic system] Revoliltion opposes counter-revolution, and a reign of terror is the' path to triumph. Liberty is dismissed as a purely! bourgeois ideal, which impedes proletarian advance to! its goal. The idea of a general upheaval, Russia link- ing hands with France, Berlin uniting with Vienna, is emphasized, though it should be added that Marx had no full realization either of the difficulties the Revolu- tion would encounter, or the speediness of its destruc- tion. The paper hardly lived for a year, when troubles with the censorship put an end to its existence, Marx left Cologne and returned to Paris, but only to witness the bloody suppression of the days of June. Banished by the French Government in July, 1849, to a remote corner of Brittany, he decided to move to London. Thither he went with his family, and he remained in England, with one or two brief intervals, for the rest of his life. IV. ,1 Marx's London period is, creatively, the most im- portant .part df^j.s career ; but it was a difficult and tragic struggle fof: existence, and his work was accom- plished only by heroic effort. For the first ten years, the famify was hardly over the verge of starvation, and Marx had even to pawn his clothes for necessary ex- penses. Nor was his intellectual environment easy. The disappointed maker^ of a revolution are never com- fortable neighbours;, and his pamphlet, Herr Vogt i8 KARL MARX (i860) is proof that German Communists did not differ from their fellows of France or Russia. For ten years (1851-60) Marx acted as European correspondent of the New York Tribune, a post which was the sole source of any continuous income. It w-as, however, very poorly paid, and if the selection of his articles therein published by Eleanor Marx after his death is at all representative, it is clear that the taste of the American I reader has changed in remarkable fashion since the 'sixties. For Marx does not abate one iota of his con- victions in his correspondence; and the manner of inter- pretation is that of the philosopher rather than the journalist. That income apart, Marx had no consistent means of livelihood during his first ten years in London. Then came one or two family legacies, and a generous tribute from Wilhelm WolfT; later, Engels was able from his own means to allow Marx some three hundred and fifty pounds a year. Yet, with all their penury, these were not unhappy years. His wife seems to have had a real genius for deriving contentment from misfortune; judges like Heine and Paul Lafargue paid her the tribute of profound admiration. His children were growing up, and Marx was passionately fond of his children. Their nurse, Helene Demuth, was a source of infinite help and comfort, and there was always the sure knowledge of the inevitable triumph of the revolu- tionary cause. For Marx did not share in the sense of depression which fell upon Liberals after the failure of 1848. He shut himself in the British Museum and, sometimes viforking sixteen hours a day, set himself to the composi- tion of a socialist economics. One or two minor pamph- lets were written, as the unsparing denunciation of the coup d'etat of 1851, which he called the Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (1852) and the Critique of Political Economy (1859) which is important, in part because it is the groundwork of the Capital itself and in part because of the valuable light it throws upon his own conception of his method. But outside^ his rela tions with the international, it was to the Capital that these years were devoted. And they were years of un remitting and devoted service. He was at the Museum KARL MARX 19 as it opened and never left until the attendants turned him out. A chosen band of helpers, all fellow-exiles, used to accompany him and aid in the researches he conducted ; though it should perhaps be added that they were not admitted as assistants until they had shown their agreement with Marx and passed certain craniological tests. Phrenologj- was not typical merely of the Utopian period of Socialism. Marx, moreover, never considered the exchange of conviction for com- fort; offers of position came to him, as when Buchar sounded him, possibly on Bismarck's behalf ; but he never dreamed of desertion. There is certainly no more remarkable instance of great sacrifice for intellectual discovery than that of which I^Iarx's life is a record. Darwin, it is true, devoted twenty years to the testing of his hypotheses, but he had ample means at his com- mand. Marx was surrounded by difficulties, of which not the least was the knowledge that his self-imposed task condemned his wife and family to profound suffer- ing. Neither he nor they seemed to have flinched from the consequences, and one may judge not unfairly that their pride in his work was for Marx his happiest achievement. Of Marx's intellectual environment in London, we know all too little. Men like John Stuart Mill he never met, though he was on friendly terms with the leading trade unionists as Odger and Applegarth. With the latter, however, he had no intimate political relations, and in the contemporary history of English labour, his name has no large place. That, perhaps, was natural enough ; for English trade unionism was then a system of compromises with which Marx's revolutionary dogmas had little connection. For the most part his affiliations were with Engels and the German exiles in London, though only the former seems to have enjoyed his full confidence. He had, moreover, a close relation- ship with that mysterious figure, half-fanatic and half- knight-errant, David Urquhart, whose loathing of Russia Marx seems fully to have shared. Both of them saw spies at every street corner, and at one time or another, in each case without a shadow of justification, Marx was able to convince himself that Herwegh and Bakunin were government emissaries. It is, of course. 20 KARL MARX sufficiently intelligible that an exile who had himself been the object of police attentions should live in an atmosphere of nervous suspicion ; but it is a regrettable corollary of Marx's accusations that both Herwegh and Bakunin belonged to different sections of the Socialist party. Marx never welcomed opposition or rivalry ; and he was too prone to assume that a doubt of his right- ness was a doubt also of his opponent's integrity. Yet it must be counted to his great credit in these years that he is in no small degree responsible for the sympathy shown to the North by the working class during the American Civil War. It was Marx who advised the union of the labour leaders with Cobden and Bright to arouse the enthusiasm of the trade unions ; and it was Marx who proposed in the General Council of the Inter- national, that a vote of congratulation be sent to Lincoln, on his re-election as President of the United States. Marx played some part also in arousing the trade unions to protest against the brutal suppression by Russia of the Polish revolt of 1863. But, apart from the preparation of Capital, Marx's chief occupation in London was with the early stages of the First International. In 1862 a group of Paris workmen paid a visit to the London Exhibition of that year. A trade union committee received them and a joint international Council was founded. When the Polish rebellion of 1863 broke out, it was this Council which prepared the gigantic protest meetings against Russian barbarity which represented the first interven- tion, failure though it was, of British labour in foreign politics. It was in connection with this campaign that Odger, a member of the Junta, suggested that the needs of the working class involved the holding of regular international meetings. The idea was taken up with enthusiasm and a great meeting was held in London in September, 1864, to organize the movement. Marx, who had held rather aloof from the initial stao-es, was present at the meeting, and joined the Founders' Com- mittee that was created. He perceived at once the significance of the new movement, and, though he seems to have had little but contempt for its leaders, he was appomted to draw up the inaugural address. The Com- mittee had given him a basis prepared by the French KARL MARX 21 delegates and accepted by it as adequate. Marx, characteristically enough, destroyed the basis, and pro- duced instead an address of his own detailing the pro- gress of the working class in England during the past thirty years, and insisting that its meaning must be read in terms only of his own theories. It is, in fact, a new edition of the Communist Manifesto, with the revolutionary period of trade unionism as the basis of Its deductions instead of universal history. The special interest of the address, however, lies in Marx's use of the history of the Factory Acts as a proof of the value of working-class agitation. " In the bright sunlight of day," he said, " the bourgeois political economy was here vanquished for the first time by the political economy of the working class." The Factory Acts were, indeed, revolutionary in the sense that they were a direct admission of the inadequacy of laissez-faire; but their passage was hardly due to the type of influence Marx had in mind. At least in other moods he would not have called Lord Shaftesbury a revolutionary Com- munist. Marx henceforward devoted much energy to the International, and as he hurried it forth from its cradle, so he may be said to have hastened it towards the grave. Its origin began in dissension — the struggle between the idealist nationalism of Mazzini and the revolution- ary and class-conscious aggressiveness of Marx. On the latter's victory Mazzini withdrew, though with characteristic selflessness he advised his followers to continue their support. Marx henceforth dominated the organization, though he waged a continuous war- fare to maintain his supremacy. To him, the movement was essentially an effort to propag*;e the ideas of the Com,munist Manifesto and thus to prepare the way for the revolution. But to the English members the Inter- national was essentially an organ for promoting trade unionism ; and when Odger perceived, in the Commune of 1871 and Marx's defence of it, the real drift of its purpose, he resigned from the organization. The Eng- lish section always remained aloof from the directorate; for it was that special brand of Radicalism of which William Lovett was perhaps the finest representative that they were really conc'erned to foster. Nor was the 22 KARL MARX English section the only difficulty. For the first two years, the followers of Proudhon were notable rivals, and they had no sympathy with Marx's idea of a direct and immediate political revolution. They were, more- over, hostile to Communism; and racial differences played their part. Even when the Proudhoniens had been defeated, Bakunin and his followers remained. They were anarchists and bitterly opposed to the cen- tralized dictatorship of which Marx was the exponent; and there were grave differences between them on the degree to which property was to be confiscated. Bakunin, it must be admitted, was as difficult as Marx himself in colleagueship. He founded a rival organization and did much intriguing against Marx when he was readmitted on its abandonment. By 1872 his influence had so increased that a frontal attack upon him was impossible. In the Hague Congress of that year, Marx therefore proposed the removal of the headquarters to New York. The motion was carried ; but it was obviously impossible to direct European Socialism from a position three thousand miles away. By 1875 the International was extinct; and hostile as were the attentions given to it by the Governments of Europe, it rather perished of internal dissension, the struggle between two powerful and antithetic personalities, than from external attack. Not, however, before it had rendered one great ser- vice. The Second Empire perished in the defeat of Sedan, and the provisional government created by Thiers was not merely hostile to a democratic re-organ- ization, but even looked forward to the building of a new monarchy. The working men of Paris had no sympathy with these ideas ; and the Commune was their answer to them. The effort lasted only seven weeks, when it was overthrown amid scenes of unexampled butchery. Marx had been definitely hostile to its incep- tion. For him the essential function of the workers was to strengthen their own organizations and to prepare themselves thereby for their coming freedom. But when the Communards perished in their heroic folly, and were pursued, as even more modern history has pursued them, by a campaign of virulent and lying attack, Marx came to their defence in what is, the Com- munist Manifesto apart, the m ost brilliant pamphlet KARL MARX 23 be^ver_wrQi£^^ The Civil __W_q£_inJ'rance, published as an official statement of the International, is, of course, a partial and incomplete view of the complicated events it narrates ; but nothing that has been written since so admirably depicts the ideas and sentiments by which, the Communards were inspired, or more energetically displays the savage brutality with which they were treated. The defence was the more generous when Marx's low opinion of the French Socialist movement is remembered, as also his conviction that Sedan was the just price of Bonapartist imperialism. Yet even in the hour of a victory he welcomed, Marx addressed the German workers in a manifesto which demanded a fair and honourable place for the vanquished. Meanwhile, the great labour of his life had been partially completed by the publication, in 1867, of the first volume of the Capital. It cannot be said to have received the welcome it deserved. Written, of course, as it was in a German particularly cumbrous and in- volved in structure, it was necessarily caviare to the multitude. The Saturday Review perceived the value of the material of which it made use ; though not even Professor Beesly's persuasiveness could induce George Henry Lewes to insert a long notice from Engels in the Fortnightly. Russian and French translations soon followed; and in Russia, particularly, the book soon made its way to that position of commanding influence it has never lost. Marx, it must be remembered, was already well-known in Russia. Belinsky had already praised the Franco-German Year Books; Annenkov had published a long critique from Marx on Proudhon ; and his relations with Herzen and Bakunin had made him a notable figure among international Socialists. In Ger- many the book seems to have made its way but slowly ; and the second edition (1873) contains a long protest by Marx against what he deemed an organized con- spiracy of silence. It had, of course, presently to under- go the inevitable attack incidental to all learned German controversy — on the ground that its doctrines had been anticipated ; and Marx was ludicrously assumed to have stolen his thunder from Rodbertus. But within five years from its publication Capital had become the pivotal part of German Socialist literature, and his 24 KARL MARX name assumed the position from which all other social- isms might be surveyed. Marx, was not, however, destined to complete it. The long struggle against poverty had left its mark upon his frame, and the last twelve years of his life were an incessant fight against pain and disease. Asthma and infiainmation of the lungs left him little chance of con- tinuous work, though typically enough, he devoted his rest to the study of the Russian language that he might speak the more authoritatively upon its agriculture, and to such recreations as physiology and advanced mathe- matics. He wrote, too, in 1875, his Criticism of the Gotha Frogramme, which contains, perhaps, the clearest statement of his attitude towards the transition to Socialism. He was able, further, in 1877-8, to do something towards preparing the second volume of Capital for the press. But visits to Karlsbad and Algiers did not improve his shattered health ; and he did not lift his head again after the death of his wife on December 2nd, 1881. To her, Marx had intended, as Engels has told us, to dedicate the completed structure of his work. He had no strength for the effort. On March 14th, 1883, he died peacefully, after a slight hcemorrhage of the lungs. His old nurse, Helene, and Engels were present at his death; and three days later he was laid to rest in the cemetery at Highgate. Engels and Wilhelm Liebknecht spoke at his graveside ; and the former devoted the remaining twelve years of his life to completing the unfinished edifice of his master. Marx would have wished no other wreath upon his tomb. V. _ Marx's personality is no easy one to dissect. There is no trace of the rebel in his inheritance; and his early education would have fitted him for any career rather than the one he chose. If he became the head and centre of the destructive forces of Europe, that was the inevitable outcome of the reactionary regime into which he was born; and he would doubtless have countered that description by insisting that destruction is the parent of creativeness. His work dealt with the historic foundations of the permanent source of revolution, and KARL MARX 25 the only weapon, as he realized, for flesh that has morti- fied is the knife. The view that makes of him the com- peer of Darwin, the discoverer of the universal law of economic evolution, has not a little truth in it; but it is less true than that which places him alongside of Rousseau and Carlyle, as one of the great prophets of the human race. For it is essentially by the qualities of th e prop het t hat he is distinguishe B^ He was unnToved'Tjy oracles other than his own. Impatient of difference, as with Proudhon and Bakunin, contemptuous, as his corre- spondence with Engels shows, of all who did not think exactly in his fashion, he never learned the essential art of colleagueship. He was too prone to regard a hostile view as proof of moral crime. He had not a little of that zest for priority he was so unwilling to recognize in the discoveries of others. He was rarely generous in his recognition of intellectual stimulus. With Marx, to enter a movement was to dominate it; and he was incapable of taking the second place. " Hatred," wrote Mazzini of him, " outweighs love in his heart, which is not" right even if the hatred may in itself have foundation." There is a penetrating truth in that criticism. Marx's absorption in the wrongs of the dis- inherited undoubtedly blinded him to the universality of human nature. He had brooded so long over the method of their redress, that he became incapable of weighing the value of alternative channels. He never realized how partial and incomplete were the views upon which he based his conclusions ; and vast and patient as were the researches he undertook, he was not always exact in his measurement of evidence. He is, in fact, a noble, but not an attractive figure. -That there was a Marx eminently lovable in himself, the testimony of friends makes certain ; but it was not the Marx of public life. There is something unhealthy in the venom with which he assails early friends like Bruno Bauer, or not less ardent seekers after light like Proudhon. His accusations against Proudhon, even when the temptation to destroy is remembered, were singularly ungenerous. Learned, courageous, capable of profound sympathy with the mass of men, he was never able to grasp the secret of dealing with individuals. 26 KARL MARX Much, doubtless, is to be pardoned to an exile who never enjoyed comfort, and had often risked his personal safety ; but Mazzini was able to emerge from trials not less diffi- cult with a sweetness unembittered. Nor could Marx accustom himself to the necessary compromises of political life. One is tempted to feel that Marx confined his introspection to other men, and never attempted that sober examination of self which is often the beginning of political wisdom. That effort, after all, is fundamental. The unstated assumptions of a thinker's personality are the more urgent because they do not appear in the printed word. Every great philosophic interpretation is at bottom a spiritual autobiography, and Marx never realized how greatly his work is a palimpsest within which one can read the history of his personal experience. It is signi- ficant for his books that his early radicalism should have proved a barrier to his university career. It is significant also that he should have known the pains and penalties of exile. Nor is it irrelevant that, after thirty years in London, he was still, at the end, a Ger- man stranger testing facts and constructing theories in terms quite alien from the circumstances around him. The impalpable penumbra of his thought never im- pressed him, even while it remained the subconscious touchstone by which he judged the thought and acts of other men. Thus, while he wrote with superb pro- fundity about the material environment of men's lives, he rarely penetrated into the inner substance of those lives. With such tracts of experience — religion for example — as were alien from his own knowledge he could neither sympathize, nor understand. He wrote a philosophy which expresses in the mass the aspirations of men ; but it is not a philosophy, like that of Rousseau, which, with all its defects, springs directly from their deepest emotions. In a sense, that is to say, the seem- ing logic of his attitude is deceptive, for it in part rests upon a failure to test his own assumptions, and in part upon an abstract view of human nature with which the totality of facts is in direct contradiction. v f Marx's doctrines may be divided into five different ' parts which, though they are brought into connection in his writings, hayejnj-ealijtyno necessary dependence KARL MARX 27 upon each other. Their central economic position is a theory of_value, by which he endeavoured to explain Oie methods^Hy which the workers are exploited under capitalism ; and as a corollary, a view of the increasing concentration of capital from which he derived^ im- portant consequences in his prophecy of the future. Historically it is an attempt to explain the growth of movements and institutions entirely in economic terms.; Predominantly, Marx insists, the antagonism of classes is the motive-power which underlies the historic process ; and it is to the impulses which are at work in the satis- faction of economic demand that all changes are to be traced. Philosophically, this view results in a purely materialistic view of human nature — a view, be it noted, which has obvious and important connections with the general attitude of the Benthamite school. Politically, the doctrines of Marx resolve themselves into a defence of revolution as the method by which the workers are to attain to power, and dictatorship as the method by which they so consolidate it as ultimately to secure a condition of general freedom. ^ Upon_Mani^ theory of value it is not necessary to. spend much time. It has "not stood the test of critidsm,; IT is out'oF'fiarmony with the facts, and it isTar from self-consistent. It represents essentially a narrow inter- pretation of some loose sentences of Ricardo. The latter had argued, with certain qualifications, that the value of any commodity is to be measured by the quantity of labour which goes to its production. Marx, however, ignored the qualifications, and the proof he offered of the thesis is essentially different from that of Ricardo. Exchange value, he argued, is not the singular quality of the commodity in which it inheres. Exchange value is the quality which it possesses alike with all other qualities for which it can be exchanged. Since human labour is the only quality which all commodities possess in common, human labour must be the measure of ex- change value. And, be it noted, _by huma n labour is meant " undiffere ntiated human labour," 11 is 'a. quanti - tative and n ot a qualitative equation, it is a measur e siniply ot efCort in time and not of effort in result "o r quality ot result. Labour is paid differently simply in relatton to the-Sifferent amount of labour " congealed " 28 KARL MARX in any given commodity produced. That which will suffice to produce the necessaries of life for the labourer is therefore th^_price_ol labour power. Wages, as it clearly follows7are"the value of the' worker's necessaries of life. But the worker produces in a day more than suffices for his necessaries of life. If we assume that by working six hours each day the worker can produce his necessaries, while his working day is eight hours long, then the value of what he produces is as eight hours is to six, is, that is to say, one-third greater. Marx termed this extra-production surplus-value, and he assumed that the capitalist, taking his surplus as his profit, robbed the worker of it. For by buying labour- power at its market price, the capitalist at once grows rich and exploits his workers. And in any capitalistic society, especially where there is free competition, this is bound to be the case; from which it of course follows that only by the abolition of capitalism can we stop the exploitation of labour. It is unnecessary to dwell at any length upon the fallacies implicit in this analysis. As a matter of logic, Marx had no right to assume that the quality of labour is, other differences being subtracted, the common basis of measurement. N,oiidjd.hejnention_ that, in addition tqjab our, all com modities to havevajue must, have this a t least m com moiT7TIi"at""t"Rey satisfy some need. Utilit y, iji_other^wordSj_i_s_a._neces.^s.a it wcmld be impossible to produce aeroplanes except" upon the assumption that some people wanted to fly in them. Nor can " undifferentiated human labour " be taken as a measure of value. It is an economic platitude that differences in wages are not merely due to differences in the effort in time of production. It costs no less to produce a bad carpenter than a good one, but the guahty of a good_car£enter'^ w-ork_has a value quite apart from cost as effort; inkslTieTypFof value which the economists^ call a quasi-rent, and this quasi-rent appears in the value-in-exchange of the product. Nor is this all. Wherever there is a type of produc- tion the phenomena of which result in rent, the measure- ment of value is not the mean cost of production but the marginal cost of production. Marx failed to note this limitation, with the result that he cannot under- KARL MARX 29 stand the nature of rent and was led into obvious con- tradictions." And he fails also to take any account of; the fluctuating character of demand. He seems to have? regarded demand as purely static, and falls, as a con-' sequence, into all the difficulties Avhich Bohm-Bawerk and the Austrian school have emphasized. To say, moreover, with Marx that the " cost of a labourer is the socially necessary cost," the lowest cost, that is, at which he can be produced, is immediately to bring within purview tests of his hypothesis which he entirely failed to apply. For if wages represent the cost of necessaries, 'the existence of a proletariat whose wages are above the bare cost of necessaries clearly invalidates the whole process. And, in fact, the question of a wages level is an historical problem in which logical considerations do not play the whole part. Social conscience, for example, as with the Trade Boards, may insist upon a rate of wages historically above " the socially necessary cost," and trade unions may by the combined strength they represent, lead to the same result. If a state, even though it be a capitalistic state, chose to adopt a policy of a minimum basis of civilized life, in which a wage- standard was fixed, the iron law of wages, which Marx deduced from his theory of value, would immediately be obsolete. It must not be forgotten, moreover, that in thel Marxian analysis whatever does not appear as wages,! is always regarded as unearned profit. Of rent and in-| terest this is, perhaps, no unfair account, but it is out- side the evidence of facts to argue that the taskof-^irect- ing;^ busijiess, the '^'of^ci^^iii^entre^T^^Qr, is""not to count as labour and"3oe"s not jcreate value. Even when a suspiCfffn' ofTihrsTmpossib'iIity dawned upon Marx, he dismissed the earnings of direction simply as cunning," and argued that all profits contain an element of surplus value which differs from interest, wages and payment to the entrepreneur. But if profits are not a payment for work then it should surely follow that. the capitalist must take it also ; otherwise he is gifted with a quality of moderation with which Marx does not normally endow him. ' See Das Kapital, Vol. Ill, pp. i8o-i and 192, for an example of two quite different theories of rent within a dozen pages. = Vol. Ill (German edition) Part I, p. 343 ff- 30 KARL MARX In such a general background, the Marxian theory of value seems clearly untenable not less on theoretic grounds than from an analysis of the facts of business. Yet it_is equallj_jjndeniable jdiat.31arxls_ view has obtamed~lTTe'^sentJ2la3vli)le_^ c>^^ _soclety__to ,its t£uA; and'TtIs, therefore, worth while for a moment to inquire exactly what magic it possesses from which its strengthening hold is derived. That, it may be sug- gested, is simple enough. For the technical economist, the difference between profits and rent was fundamental. Men like Ricardo and Nassau Senior saw a natural distinc- tion in source of origin which manufacturers like Bright embodied in the legitimate earnings of a hardworking mill- owner, whatever his wealth, and the illegitimate because unearned income of a land-owning duke. They saw it the more clearly when, as in the period of Marx's own maturity, they were struggling to free his business from the environment of a hostile squirearchy. But to the labourer, as Marx clearly saw, such a distinction was for practical purposes irrelevant. The world was divided for him into those who lived by wages and those who did not. Those who lived by wages were poor, those who did not live by wages were rich. Assume, as Marx assumed, that the surplus theory of value is true, and the riches of those who do not live by wages are due to the poverty of those who do. The worker was able to see that he was poor; he saw also that he produced more than he could consume, and that his surplus production was divided among a relatively small class of rich, and often idle, men. A theory such as Marx's inevitably appealed to him as the natural ex- planation of his oppressed condition. He clung to it, not by virtue of any logical estimation of its theoretic adequacy, but because it summarized the most poignant experience he knew. The Marxian law of wages, more- over, will, from its very nature, win new adherents at every period of commercial depression. At any moment when there is a decline in the effective demand for com- modities, or' when the strength of trade union resistance is at a low ebb, the impact of capitalism upon the M-ao-e- earner will closely resemble what Marx insisted is Its normal relation ; for few business men have imao-ination enough to realize that there are other ways to the re KARL MARX 31 habilitation of markets than the reduction of price by means of lower wages. Inevitably, therefore, the worker will move from the acceptance of surplus value to the philosophy which Marx constructed as its natural environment. The law of the concentration of capital stands upon] firmer ground. The greater the degree of complexity involved in the productive process, argues Marx, the fewer will be the number of persons controlling its instruments. Everything contributes to the intensifica- tion of this process. New means of communication are established, the problems of which are beyond the solu- tion of the small capitalist. Important mechanical inventions are beyond his financial means. Territorial consolidation destroys the local market in which he was once a privileged person. The process, indeed, is neither immediate nor direct. It took the bourgeoisie' three centuries to expropriate the artisan and create the proletariat. But once the process had begun, the development was inexorable. Over production created a new army of reserve workers. The substitution of pasture for arable farming concentrated a large rural population in the towns. The economies of large scale production forced hitherto^ independent producers into the ranks of the wage-earners. The capitalistic system moves from a national to an international character; its market becomes the world. Its nature involves increasing centralization, until the control of the forces of production reaches a point where its further develop- ment in private hands is impossible. For alongside the development of accumulation is the increase of the pro- letariat. The workers cannot any longer endure the misery that is involved in the capitalist regime. They have learned discipline from the training that is. neces- sitated by the mechanism of the process of which they are the victims. "The knell of capitalist private pro- perty then sounds. The expropriators are expro- priated." To the great capitalist there succeeds the state, which is captured by the workers for their own purpose. The result of capita lism is^Jn^fact^ its own destruction. It produces, in Hegelian fashion,, its own antithesis. The very condition of its growth is that it should involve the laws which imply its inevitable ruin. 32 KARL MARX We need not accept the conclusion of the argument to insist on the important truth that it contains. The wastage of competition in large scale enterprise is a commonplace of modern business, and the trust or cartel is the characteristic symptom of industrial de- velopment. There are, indeed, certain important limi- •tations to the simplicity of the Marxian view. The igrowth of joint stock enterprise distributes over a wider Icircle the number of those interested in the receipt of profits, even while it limits those who actually control the industrial process itself; while there are many minor industries, of which photography and the repair of motor-cars are examples, in which the tendency is to the increase of small firms rather than to the develop- ment of great ones. But parallel with this evolution has gone a very striking centralization of credit which concentrates in continuously fewer hands the finances of the community. Agriculture, indeed, despite the large-scale farming of Western America, and the de- velopment of agrarian co-operation, remains persistently individualist in temper.' Yet, on the balance of inquiry, it is impossible to deny the emergence of an increasingly collectivist spirit. And its reaction upon industry is the more important because it leads, without question, to the demand by the workers of certain nominal standards from the state which are increasingly insisted upon as the condition of business enterprise. Nor is that all. It becomes obvious that certain industries are, from their very nature, too vital in their results to be left to the chaotic possibilities of private effort. If the expropriators are not actually expropriated, there comes, as with mines and railways, a demand for some form of nationalization, and just as the investigations of the / 'thirties and 'forties produced the Factory Acts, so it is legitimate to argue that the results of inquiries like the Coal Commission of 1919, and the Dockers' Inquiry of 1920, are likely to put a term to the continuance of private enterprise. Capitalism, in fact, prepares mono- polies which immediately affect the community towards some form of state administration. So regarded, of course, this view does not involve the theory of revolution which Marx regarded as the inevit- ' Cf. Herman Levy, Lart^c and small lioldings (191 1). KARL MARX 33 able corollary of capitalistic concentration. It need not, indeed, involve a transition towards a socialistic state, at all. All that would seem to be implied would be the, removal of industries essential to the welfare of the community from the danger of exploitation by private interests. The logic of a necessary conflict resultant upon the concentration of capital is derived by Marx from other sources. It is the corollary of his interpre- tation, of history. That, broadly speaking, may be summarized by saying that all the phenomena of history are the result of economic motives. To them are trace-i able legal and social institutions not less than the religion and philosophy of each age. The system of production is the ultimate factor, in short, by which the mass of human relationships is determined. Pro- testantism, Engels wrote, is " essentially a bourgeois religion " ; so too, in a feudal period we should expect the legislation to reflect not general ideas of right, but those ideas of right which are compatible with the main- tenance of feudalism. But ideas change, and in Marx's view, the source of change is to be discovered in the transformation of one economic system into another. A new external world produces new internal ideas. Let womerf enter industry ii^ the mass and, as Mr. Bertrand Russell has pointed out, ideas which not even the logic of Plato and Stuart Mill could make obvious, become accepted without question. Two hundred years ago, it was unthinkable that a peer should go into the city; to-day, finance has enmeshed political life within its fold, so that no company prospectus is complete until the peerage is represented there. No one can doubt the very large measure of truth in this outlook. No one can write the history of English Puritanism, of the struggle for toleration, or of the American Revolution, without making the defence of an economic incentive fundamental to their explanation. But it is equally clear that the insistence upon an economic background as the whole explanation is radic- ally false. No , economic motive , cajX..explaiii„lJi.e.&uIcidal nationalism ^JheJBalkans. The, war of 1914 may have BSH^Targely due"to"conHicting commercial imperial- isms ; but there was also a competition of national ideas which was at no point economic. Historically, too, the 34 KARL MARX nail played by religion in the determination of social butlook was, until at least the peace of Westphalia, as important as that played by material conditions. Luther represents something more th^n a protest against the financial exacdons_of Rome— The impulses of men, in fact^are' never referable to any single source. The love of power, herd-instinct, rivalry, the desire of display, all these are hardly less vital than the acquisitiveness which explains the strength of material environment. Engels, indeed, seems to have realized the narrowness of the orthodox view, for in the later years of his life he insisted that the dominant part ascribed by Marx to the economic motive was due mainly to its neglect by his opponents, " and there was not always time, place and opportunity to do justice to the other considera- tions." *-■ But with Marx the economic motive is not only final, it is final in a particular way. " The only durable source of faction," said Madison, " is property," and, for Marx, the emergence of private property in history is the beginning of the class struggle. Immediately society can be divided into those who do, and those who do not, possess private property, a power is released |which explains the changes of history. For the class iwhich possesses property moulds the civilization of that society in the service of its own interests. It controls the government, it makes the laws, it builds the social institutions of the commonwealth in accordance with its own desires. Slave and free man, master and ser- vant, these have been the eternal antitheses of history. With the advent of capitalism the struggle is at once simplified, and made more intense. Thenceforward, the final stage of the class-war, the struggle between bourgeoisie and proletariat, emerges. And just as each social order of the past has secreted within its womb the germ of its successor, as for example, feudalism produced capitalism, so does the latter contain within ^Itself the germ of its communist successor. " Capital- ism," said Marx, "produces its own gravedigger." The conflict, in his view, was an inevitable and a bitter one, and it was Sound to result in the victory of the proletariat. " The bourgeoisie," he wrote in the Com- munist Manifesto, " is incapable of continuing in power KARL MARX 35 because it is incapable of securing a bare subsistence to its slaves "; and the result is a growing sense of revolt in the worker who ultimately, by a revolutionary act, assumes the reins of power. In a large sense, it is obvious that the substance of this interpretation is accurate. The fact of the class- struggle, as Marx himself pointed out, is a common- place of historians and economists ; and it may be added that to deny its importance is to make history unin- telligible. Where Marx parted company with his pre- decessors was in the deductions he drew from his per- ception of its significance. For whereas with men like Madison and Guizot, the fact of conflict produced a sense of horror at its implications, and a search for a^ technique that its dangers might be obviated, with Marx the conflict was fundamental and both its method and ultimate outcome were to him alike obvious. Whereas with Madison there is an ever present uncertainty whether a just victory may not suffer betrayal, or a wrong object be pursued, with Marx the process is pre- determined and, save for a brief period in 1870, no hesitation seems to have crossed his mind. The method by which the proletariat was to securei| power lies at the very root of Marx's doctrine ; and it ; has been in our own day, perhaps, the main source of his influence. The method was revolution, and a dicta- torship of iron rigour would consolidate the new system until the period of transition had been effectively; bridged. Marx did not blind himself to what all thiS' implied. The history of capitalism was the history of a relentless defence of each phase of the rights of pro- perty. They were maintained by methods at each point unconnected with ethical demands. If -the conflict was extreme as in the days of June, 1848, or with the Com- mune of Paris, the last ounce of misery was wrung from its opponents, that capitalism might be secure. A period of comparative quiescence may produce the con- cession of social reform, but this is merely deception. Once a really vital point is touched by the workers' de-' mands, they are met by armed resistance. That means, of course, that only by conscious violent intervention can communism be realized. The proletariat must seize a propitious moment for the revolution; but until it 36 KARL MARX comes, they must do all in their power to disturb the existing regime. Even if minor successes have been achieved by the aid of the liberal-minded bourgeoisie " from the first hour of victory, the workers must level their distrust against their former allies." They must create a working-class organization of their own, workers' committees, local workers' councils, to oppose proletarian institutions and their influence to those of the middle-class state. The Communists must arm the proletariat and do all they can to cut down the army of the State as the chief weapon of defence possessed by the bourgeoisie. Where the workers are in the militia, they must form within it a secret organization to obtain its control. They must form their own independent, if hidden, military force and acquire arms by every method. Influential democrats to whose word the work- ing class seems to respond, must be discredited. The old social order, in fact, must be attacked at every point. Communists have two functions only, to prepare for the ■revolution, and to consolidate it successfully when it has been prepared. They must think of themselves not as realizing an ideal, but only as setting free the ele- ments of a new societ}^ concealed within the womb of the old. The period of consolidation, moreover, must be a period of iron dictatorship. Marx had no illusions about the possibility of a democratic governance in such an hour. The ideals of freedom were impossible to maintain until the ground so conquered had been made secure. Revolution provokes counter-revolution ; and a victorious proletariat must be on its guard against reaction. Revolution, in fact, demands of the revolution- ary class that it secure its purpose by every method at its disposal. It has neither time nor opportunity for compassion or remorse. Its business is to terrorize its opponents into acquiescence. It must disarm antagon- ism by execution, imprisonment, forced labour, control of the press. For as it cannot allow any effort at the violent overthrow of what it has established, so must it stamp out such criticism as might be the prelude to further attack. Revolution is war, and war is founded (upon terror. The methods of capitalism must be used ;for the extinction of capitalism. For as capitalism has KARL MARX 37 made of life itself the cheapest of commodities, there need be no repining at its sacrifice, and the result, in any case, is worth the cost, since it destroys the possi- bility of future sale. It would have been a wanton be- trayal of trust, said Marx of the Paris Commune, to observe the traditional forms of liberalism. The end, in fact, is too great to be nice about the means employed. 7; Nor can we expect that a. peaceful revolution is pos- jsible. While Marx had certain doubts of England, on the whole he was certain that a violent . struggle was inevitable. The workers might capture Parliament at the polls ; but political power of that kind is in any cas& a shadow, and werelFused for ah assa'ult liporTpropefty;' iTwould i nevitably~prowke' an ~anned~re indeed7~weh1t fiir'tTier anSTwas openly conternptuous of democracy. It was a bourgeois invention unrelated to the real, and used only to deceive the people. Again' and again the proletariat is betrayed ; and throughouF Marx's writings there is the assumption that reliance must be placed upon a class-conscious minority. For in his view there is no place in history for the majority principle; the record of States is the clash between determined minorities, contending for the seat of power. To introduce considerations of consent, to wait on in the belief that the obvious tightness of communist doc- trine will ultimately persuade men to its acceptance, is entirely to ignore reality. The mass of men will always] acquiesce in, or be indifferent to, whatever solutions arel afforded. Communists must proceed upon the assump- tion that nothing matters save the enforcement of their will. " ^ Upon the end this revolution is to serve, the forms its purpose will adopt, Marx has written but little. Obviously, with justice on his side ; for speculation in distant historical futures is the worst form of gambling. It was with the destruction of capitalism an^ the period of transition therefrom that he was mainly concerned. A new productive system was bound to involve new institutions which no man could foresee. That the Com- munist maxim, " From each according to his powers, to each according to his wants," would become operative was, of course, obvious to him ; that performance would be measured in terms of labour-time (a possibly incon- 38 KARL MARX sistent hypothesis) he took for granted. But he was always emphatic that the future must settle itself. He insisted that the measure of distribution would be neces- sarily unequal in the period of transition. You may, as he saw, destroy by catastrophe, but creation is not an immediate and spontaneous process. So that he nowhere set limits to the duration of this interrnediate period. It was necessary to wait until the habits en- gendered by a new productive system created a psycho- logy in which the dogma of equality superseded the bourgeois hypothesis of individual rights. The main thing was the destruction of a regime in which class- distinction made possible the servitude of the many. It was possible to have confidence in an order in which the whole force of social effort was deliberately placed at the disposal of the common welfare. VI. A generation which has seen this doctrine supported by machine-guns and bayonets is unlikely to belittle its importance. Nor can it be denied that not a little of /social evolution has taken the course Marx predicted. Anyone who reads the history of the industrial struggle in Colorado or West Virginia will find it difficult to discover a limit of unreason which capitalism is not willing consistently to overpass. The treatment of communists in Hungary and Finland ^as exactly the characteristics he foretold. An isolated community like the miners of South Wales becomes, naturally, commun- ist in the background of incompetence and ill-treatment from their employers. And representative government, at least in its classical form, seems unlikely to justify the high hopes of its Benthamite exponents. Every country in the world that has experimented with univer- sal suffrage has experienced a sense of disillusion. It is even commonplace to argue that reason has little place in political struggle, and to pin faith to an irrational impulse which seeks no more than the satisfaction of individual desire. If there has been an improvement in the general standard of civilization, an increasing unwillingness, for example, to inflict unnecessary pain, there are no signs of the- mitigation of the class-conflict'. On the contrary, the events of the last decade point KARL MARX 39 directly to its exacerbation; and we have obviously entered upon a period in whicli the rights of property- are challenged at their foundation. Certainly it is un-t questionable that the purchase-price of capitalist sur- vival is the offer of concessions which a generation ago would have seemed not less unnecessary than unthink- able. Yet the approximation of the general atmosphere to the condition Marx had in view hardly justifies the prin- ciples upon which he placed his reliance. To begin with, the preparation for revolution is a qualitatively different problem from what it was in the days of the Paris barricades. It is possible in a mood of defeat for a civilian population to destroy a regime which the army and navy no longer uphold, and, as was .demonstrated long ago. by Cromwell, a military force which is dis- satisfied with its civilian superiors can without difficulty become. their master. But for a party of men in the position of communists in the modern State, the situa- tion is very different. Unless they are the majority and, consequently, the government, the hostility of the army and navy is certain. Nor can they obtain, on any large scale, the necessary equipment for insurrection. They would have to obtain control of the national arsenals; and that would mean the dispersion of forces in any case small by hypothesis. They would have to meet in the people at large at least a mood of acquies- cence. They would have to guarantee a supply of food, which, in any but a dominantly agricultural society, would be practically impossible if international credit was seriously impaired by the revolution. Even if we regard a general strike as tantamount, in the conditions of modern industry, to a revolution the difficulties are overwhelming. A general strike might well succeed as a protest against war, for its penumbra might, in the future, arouse emotions of determination that would be irresistible. But upon any less dramatic issue, it seems tolerably certain that once again, the army and navy must be in the control of the strikers if success is to be assured. For a modern army can supply all services connected with transportation ; it can secure the distribu- tion of food, and the problem of fuel is becoming less and less a matter of mining coal. The Marxian view 40 KARL MARX iof a secretly armed minority assuming power at a single Istroke is unthinkable in the modern state. It would have to imply either the existence of a government so weak that it had practically ceased to be a government at all, or, what is perhaps, an equivalent, a population actively sympathetic to the revolutionary minority. The iresources of publicity in modern civilization make im- jpossible the private preparation of the gigantic effort iassOmed by the Marxian hypothesis. But this is only the beginning of the difficulty. Marx assumed throughout his analysis a system of compact states the life of which was mainly determined by economic considerations, and each relatively indepen- dent of its neighbours. Each of these assumptions is only partially true of the modern world. A State like England, which is wholly dependent on foreign trade, could not undergo a successful revolution except upon the assumption that her neighbours viewed its results with benevolence. Such an attitude on the part, for instance, of America is very unlikely, and the rupture of Anglo-American trade would be fatal to any revolu- tion in this country. Nor is that all. It is quite clear that the division a revolution would imply must, in its workings, be very partially determined by economic considerations. In a country like America, for example, there would be at least three other factors of vital im- portance. An American communist revolution would have to cope with problems of distance which would probably render it abortive at a very early stage. It would not, as in France, be a matter of the immense im- pact of the capital on the life of the nation ; Washington is relatively insignificant in the perspective of America. To control the whole continent would involve control- ling the most complicated railway system in the world. And even if that difficulty could be surmounted, a com- plex of nationalist differences would have to be assuaged German, French, English, Irish, Polish, these have their special characteristics which the American capital- ist has been able to exploit to their common dis- advantage; it is difficult to see how an appeal to a communist minority of each would result in the trans- cendence of these differences. Even then, the religious problem remains ; and the hold of the churches upon the KARL MARX 41 mind, particularly, of the Latin peoples would not be easy to loosen. For Marx, insisting only upon the! economic motive, it is easy to ignore these difficulties, j but it is far too narrow an outlook not to realize at the' outset that appeal can be made to other incentives every! whit as strong. And even if it were argued that Marx; could in our own time assume that the day of such pre- judice as nationality and religion engender is passing (which is doubtful), and that the barriers built by economic difference are now alone important, his con- clusions would not follow. For in a period of universal suffrage, it ought then to be possible to capture the seat of power at the polls, and throw upon the capitalist the'onus of revolting against a socialist demo- cracy. There are, however, other approaches to the problem! which Marx did not adequately consider. There is, in the first place, the general result upon society of the practice of violence, particularly when the destructive nature of modern warfare is borne in mind ; and, in the^ second, there is the special psychological result upon the agents of the opposing forces in such a regime. Marx did not consider these possibilities, in part because he judged that, in any case, the conflict was inevitable, and also because he was convinced that whatever sacri- fices had to be made would be ultimately justified by the, result. Such an attitude is, of course, simply an instance! of his general failure to weigh sufficiently the substance j of a political psychology. In part, also, it is the corol-' lary of a determinism which the facts in issue at no point, justify. For it is obvious that if revolution, with its attendant violence, is justified for any cause in which you happen to believe profoundly, no modern state can hope for either security and order. The war has shown clearly that the impulses of savagery which are checked by peace are, when loosed, utterly destructive of the foundations of a decent existence. If life became an organized and continuous jacquerie, civilization could quite easily be reduced to the state where, as in Mr. •Wells's imaginary but far from impossible picture, some aged survivor may tell of an organized Europe as a legend which his grandchildren cannot hope to under- stand. Violence, on the grand scale, in fact, so far from 42 KARL MARX proving an avenue to communism, would be the one kind of existence in which the impulses demanded by a communist state had no hope of emergence. For the condition of communism is the restraint of exactly those appetites which violence releases; and Marx has nowhere indicated how this difficulty could be met. Even beyond this issue, a further point must be raised. Marx has assumed the seizure of power, and a period of rigorous control until the people are prepared for com- munism. But he has not shown what approximate length that period is to be, nor what certainty we have that those who act as controllers of the dictatorship will be willing to surrender their power at the proper time. It is a commonplace of history that power is poisonous to those 'who exercise it; there is no reason to assume that the Marxian dictator will in this respect be different from other men. And, ex hypothesi, it will be more difficult to defeat his malevolence since his regime will have excluded the possibility of opposition. No group of men who exercise the powers of a despot can ever retain the habit of democratic responsibility. That is obvious, for instance, in the case of men like Sir Henry Maine and Fitzjames Stephen, who, having learned in India the habit of autocratic government, become impatient on their return to England of the slow process of persuasion which democracy implies. To sit continuously in the seat of office is inevitably to become separated from the mind and wants of those over whom you govern. For the governing class acquires an interest of its own, a desire for permanence, a wish, perhaps, to retain the dignity and importance which belong to their function ; and they will make an effort to secure them. That, after all, is only to insist that every system of government breeds a system of habits ; and to argue as a corollary therefrom that the Marxian dictatorship would breed habits fatal to the emergence of the regime Marx had ultimately in view. The special vice of every historic system of government has been its inevitable tendency to identify its own private good with the gublic welfare. To suggest that communists might do the same is no more than to postulate their humanity. And it may be added that if they surrendered power at a reasonable time, the grounds for so doing, being obviously in their KARL MARX 43 nature non-economic, would thereby vitiate the truth of the materialistic interpretation of history. All this, it is worth noting, is to omit from considera- tion the ethical problems that are involved. It is obvious, for example, that it involves the complete erosion of the whole historic process. But the erosion of responsi- bility in the governing class is the destruction of per- sonality in their subjects. In such a regime notions of liberty and equality are out of place. Yet it is obvious that the two main defects of capitalism are its failure to produce liberty and equality for the mass of humble men and women. Marx, that is to say, contemplated a condition which reproduces exactly the chief vices of capitalism without offering any solid proof of their ulti- mate extinction. For, after all, the chief effort that is worth making is towards a civilization in which what Mr. Graham Wallas has termed, " the capacity of con- tinuous initiative," is implied iR the fact of citizenship. It is clear enough that the possibility upon which the existence of that capacity turns is a wide distribution of power. A man whose thought and acts are at the dis- posal of other men is deprived of his personality, and that deprivation is implied in the rigorous centralization to which Marx looked forward. Unquestionably, he was right in his insistence that the distribution of economic power in a capitalist state makes the enjoyment of such personality impossible to most ; but it does not seem any more likely to emerge in the successor to it that he contemplated. We may go further and argue that it is impossible in any state where the main purpose of, and motive to, effort, is the increase of material wealth. No society can realize itself in any full sense of the word until the mainspring of its existence is a capacity to value things of the mind as more precious than material com- modities. That involves a sociology in which the economic motive which Marx emphasized is appraised at a low level. Obviously, to achieve the condition in which that appraisal is possible, involves an educational system far different, both in scope and purpose, from what we now have. It involves a complete transforma- tion of values, in which things like the wider apprecia- tion of art, the study of science and philosophy, the release, in short, of the creative energies of men from 44 KARL MARX their present bondage, are regarded as the main and immediate effort of political organization. Yet, if historic experience is to count for anything — and Marx's philosophy is nothing if not the interpreta- tion of historical experience — it is exactly this trans- formation of values which cannot take place in the development Marx had in view. The barbarian invasions of Rome did not produce a great art and a great culture, they produced the dark ages. The Thirty Years' War im- peded constructive effort in Germany until the threshold of the nineteenth century. Nor has our own experience been different. The idealism of 1914 has perished before the greater strength of the purely destructive forces released in the struggle. What we have realized is how tenuous and fragile are the bonds of civilization, how little likely they are to be reinforced by any effort save that of peace. In such a background, the conflict that Marx envisaged looms before us as the harbinger of precisely those evils from which we are seeking release. It emphasizes in men the impulses against which civili- zation is a protest. That wrong can be wiped out with wrong, that we are to regard ourselves as the victims of blind and impersonal forces against which it is useless to strive, that the ix>ssessive impulses of men cannot be transcended by creative effort — these and things like these are a gospel of impossible despair. In that aspect, surely, the older socialists were right who made the basis of their creed a doctrine of right and fraternity and justice. For right and fraternity and justice imply love as their foundation; they do not spring, even at the last vain striving, from a doctrine founded upon hate. VII. The real power and influence of Marx lie in a direction essentially different from what is generally assumed. He was the first thinker to expose in all its hoUowness the moral inadequacy of a commercial civilization. He showed that in any society where the main effort is the attainment of wealth, the qualities that are basically noble cannot acquire their full vigour. He did, in fact, for the economic relationships of peoples what Grotius did for their international relationships. He founded both a science and an ideal. For he made finally impossible KARL MARX 45 any economic system which makes the volume of trade the test of national well-being; and he put in the fore- front of social discussion the ultimate question of the condition of the people. And he performed the incal- culable service to his generation of bringing to it a message of hope in an epoch where men seemed to them- selves to have become the hapless victims of a misery from which there was no release. In every country of the world where men have set themselves to the task of social improvement, Marx has been always the source of inspiration and prophecy. His weaknesses, of course, are obvious and important.! " He diagnoses a disease admirably," says Mr. Wells, in an excellent phrase, " and then suggests rather an! incantation than a remedy." Yet the diagnosis is an essential part of the cure. No one can read unmoved the picture he drew of the results of the Industrial Re- volution. Massive in its outline, convincing in its detail, it was an indictment such as neither Carlyle nor Ruskin had power or strength to draw. It is relatively unim- portant that his explanations of the phenomena he depicted have not stood the test of criticism. What is| vital in the whole was his perception that a society' dominated by business men and organized for the pro- sperity of business men had become intolerable. Hardly less splendid was his insistence that no social order is adequate in which the collective energies of men are not devoted to their common life. It does not matter that such perception had been given to others, that such insistence was not new. No thinker of the nineteenth century drove home the lesson with force so irresistible or with urgency so profound. Even his advocacy of catastrophic revolution has this much of truth in it, that a point is reached in the development of any social system where men will refuse to accept any longer a burden they find too great to bear; and, in that moment, if they cannot mitigate, they will become determined to 1 destroy. The condition, in fact, upon which a state may hope to endure is its capacity for making freedom in each generation more widespread and more intense. Where Marx was wrong was in his belief that the catas- trophe was, in itself, worthy of attainment and in his emphasis upon its ultimate benefit. But where he was, 46 KARL MARX also, irresistibly right was in his prophecy that the civilization of his epoch was built upon sand. And even the faults of his prophecy may be pardoned to an agitator in exile to whom the cause of the oppressed was dearer than his own welfare. At bottom, the main passion by which he was moved was the passion for justice. He may have hated too strongly, he was jealous, and he was proud. But the mainspring of his life was the desire to take from the shoulders of the people the burden by which it was oppressed. He realized that what, in all varieties of time and place, has caused the downfall of a governing class, has never been some accidental or superficial event. The real cause of revolution is the unworthiness of those who controlled the destinies of a people. Indifference to suffering, selfishness, lack of moral elevation, it was for those defects that he indicted the class from which he sprang. He transformed the fears of the workers into hopes, he translated their effort from interest in political mechanisms to interest in social foundations. He did not trust in the working of laws, he sought always for the spirit that lay behind the order of which they were the expression. He was often wrong, he was rarely generous, he was always bitter; yet when the roll of those to whom the emancipation of the people is dvie comes to be called, few will have a more honourable, and none a more eminent place. GARDEN CITV PRESS, PRINTERS, LETCHWORTH, ENGLAND. BY THE SAME AUTHOR. The Problem of Sovereignty. Authority in the Modern State. Selected Letters of Edmund Burke, edited with an Intro- duction. (The above are pubHshed by the Oxford University Press.) Political Thought in England from Locke to Bentham (Williams & Nor gate). The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (Allen & Unwin). THE FABIAN SOCIETY 25, TOTHILL STREET, WESTMINSTER, LONDON, S.W.i. Those willing to join the Labour Party, or desirous of obtaining information about Its Programme and Principles, are invited to communicate with the Secretary of the Fabian Society. The Fabian Sqciety has been, from the outset, a constituent body of the Labour Party ; and membership of the Society carries with it full membership of the Labour Party, eligibility for nomination to all Conferences and Offices, and qualification for Labour Party candidatures for Parliament and Local Authorities, without obligation to belong ]to any other organization. The Society welcomes as members any persons, men or women, wherever resident, who subscribe to its Basis (set forth below), and who will co-operate in its work accord- tag to 'their |opportumties. BASIS OF THE FABIAN SOCIETY. (To BE SIGNED BY ALL MEMBERS.) (Adopted May s^rd, 1919.) The Fabian Society consists of Socialists. It therefore aims at the reorganization of Society by the emancipation of Land and Industrial Capital from individual ownership, and the vestiag of them in the com- munity for the general benefit. In this way only can the natural and acqmred advantages of the country be equitably shared by the whole people. The Society accordingly works for the extinction of private property in land, with equitable consideration of established expectations, and due provision as to the tenure of the home and the homestead ; for the. transfer to the commtmity, by con- stitutional methods, of all such industries as can be conducted socially ; and for the establishment, as the governing consideration in the regulation of production, distri- bution and service, of the common good instead of private profit. The Society is a constituent of the Labour Party and of the International Socialist Congress ; but it takes part freely in all constitutional movements, social, economic and political, which can be guided towards its own objects. Its direct business is (a) the propaganda of Socialism in its application to current problems ; (6) investigation and discovery in social, industrial, political and economic relations ; (c) the working out of Socialist principles in legislation and administrative reconstruction ; {d) the publication of the results of its investigations and their practical lessons. . The Society, believing iu equal citizenship of men and women in the fullest sense, is open to persons irrespective of sex, race or creed, who commit themselves to its aims and purposes as stated above, and tmdertake to promote its work. The Society includes: — >.,.■,;, -, I. Members, who must sign the Basis and be elected by the Committee. Their Subscriptions are not fixed ; each is expected to subscribe annually according to his means. They control the Society through the Executive Committee (elected annually- by ballot through a postal vote), and at its annual and other business meetings. ,, , - . - ' II. Associates, who sign a form expressing only general sympathy with the objects of the Society and pay not less than 10s. a year. They can attend all except the exclusively members' meet- ings, but have no control over the Society aiid its pohcy.T' -^ / "~ ^ ' ■ ' ' '- III, Subscribers, who must pay at least '5s./ a. year, and ^ho, can attend the Society's Ordinary ■Lectures. -, _ -- . \ .''<<■ . -,■ \ »-,. ' ^: ', \ - ' '■■ '- .-, ■',''," The monthly-paper, Fabian NeiBsi and the Tracts from time to time published in the well-known Fabian Series, are posted to all these; classes. There are convenient Common Rooms, where light refreshiuents can. be obtained, with an extensive library for the free -use of members only. ;-- ■ '? . ' ~ , ■ ■■_■■. Among the Society's activities (in which it places its services unreservedly at the. disposal of the Labour Party and the Local Labour Parties all over the covmtry, the Trade Unions and Trades Cotmcils, and aU other Labour and Socialist organizations), may be mentioned : .!, 1 ,. ' , ■ ■> ' (i ) Free lectures by its members and oiBcers ; ; ' '' ,.,' • ' / ^. ■ ' ■ ' ,. ' (ii.) The well-known Fabian Book-boxes, each containing about three dozen of the best boots od Economics, Politics and Social Problems, which can be obtained by any organization of men or women for 15s. per annum, covering an exchange of books every three months ; (iii.) Answers. to Questions from Members of Local Authorities and othera on legal, technical or pohtical mattersof Local Government, etc. ;v. ■'^,i..:V' . , '.-',■;',■*' ' 'r ■ - (iv.) Special subscription courses of lectures on iiew developments m thought ; .' - (v.) Economic and social investigation and research, and publication of the results. - Lists of Publications, Annoal Report, Form ol Application as Member or Associate, and any other information can be obtained on application personally or by letter to the Secretary at the above address. FABIAN PUBLICATIONS TABIAN ESSAYS. (1920 Edition.) 2s. 6d. ; postage 3d. WHAT TO BEAD on Social and Economic Subjects, is. net ; postage 3d. TOWARDS SOCIAL DEMOCRACY P By Sidney Webb. is. net; postage 2d. FROM PATRONAGE TO PROFICIENCY IN THE PUBUC SERVICE. By W. A. ^ ROBSON. IS. net ; postage ad. THIS MISEBY OF BOOTS. By H. G. Wells. 6d. ; post free, 7d. FABIAN TRACTS and LEAFLETS. Tracts, each 16 to 52 pp., price id., or gd. per doi., unless othenvise sUUeJ. Leaflets, 4 pp. each, price id. for three copies, as. per 100, or 20s. per 1000. The Set o£ 74, 7s. 6d. ; post free, 83. 6d. Bound in buckram, 123. 6d.; post free, 138..6d. I. — General Socialism in its various aspects. Tracts. — 192. Quild Socialism. By G. D. Cole, MA. 180. The Piiilosopliy of Socialism. By A. Cltjtton Brock. 169. The Socialist Movement in Germanj'. By W. Stephen Sanders. 2d. 159. The Necessary Basis of Society. By Sidney Webb. 151. The Point of Honour. By Ruth C. Bentinck. 147. Capital and Compensation. By E. R. Pease. 146. Socialism and Superior Brains. By Bernard Shaw. id. 142. Bent and Value. 138. Municipal Trading. 121. Public Service t). Private Eipenditure. By Sir Oliver Lodge. 2d. 107. Social- iam for Millionaires. By Bernard Shaw. 139. Socialism and the Churches.^By Rev. John Clifford. D.D. 133. Socialism and Christianity. By Rev. Percy Dearmer. 2d. 78. Socialism and the Teaching 0! Clirist. By Dr. J. Clifford. 4a. Christian Socialism. By Rev. S. D. Headlam. 79. A Word ol Remembrance and Caiition to the Rich. By John Woolman. 72. The Moral Aspects of Socialism. By SidneV Ball. ad. 69. Difficulties ol Individual'pm. By Sidnev Webb. 31. Socialism: True and False. By Sidney Webb. 45. The Impossibilities ol Anarchism. By G. B. Shaw. ad. 7. Capital and Land. 5. Facts for Socialists. 3d. Leaflets. — 13. What Socialism Is.^ i. Why are the Many PoorP II. — Applications of Socialism to Particular Problems. Tracts. — -196. The Root 0! Labour Unrest. By Sidney Webb. 2d. 195. The Scandal of the Poor Law. By C. M. Lloyd. 2d. 194. Taxes, Rates and Local Income Tax. By Robert Jones. D. So. ad. 1 88. National Finance and a Levy on Capital. By Sidney Webb. ad. 1 87. The Teacher in Politics. By Sidney Webb. 2d. 186. Central Africa and the League ol Nations. By R. C. Hawtoit. ad. 183. The Reform of the House of Lords. By Sidney Webb. 181. When Peace Comes — the Way ol Indnstrial Reconstruction. By Sidney Webb. ad. 178. The War ; Women ; and Unemployment. 2d. 177. Socialism and ttie' Arts of Use. By A. Clutton Brock. 175. The Economic Foundations ol the' Women's Movement. 2d. 173. Public v. Private Electricity Supply. 170. Profit- Sharing and Co-partnership : a Fraud and Failure ? 164. Gold and State Banking. 162. Family Life on a Pound a Week. By Mrs. Reeves, ad. i6i. Afforestation and Unemployment. i55- The Case against the Referendum. 154. The Case tor School Clinics. 152. Our Taxes as they are and as they ought to be. 2d. j 145. The. Case for School Nurseries. 140. Child Labor under Capitalism. 136. lie Village and the Landlord. By Edw. Carpenter. 144. TBachinery : -its Masters, and Servants. 122. Municipal Milk and Public Sealth. 123. Municipalization by Provinces. 124. State Control ol Trusts. 1 Leaflet.— 104. Hovr Trade Unidnz benefit Workmen. •. '■,'-,,.-.•,;--,,-- . •, ' - -.--'f..': ■ -'-^ •■ ■,-■-';■'''■"'■'¥ III.— Local Government Powers: How to use theta. ? ' Vv>' /' Tracts. — 189. Metropolitan Borough Councils: Their Constitution, Powers and Duties. By C. R. Attlee, M.A; zd. . 191. Borough Councils : Their Constitution,-: Powers and Duties. By C. R. Attlee, M.A. 2d, 193. Housing. By C. M. Lloyd, M.A. 3d. 189. Urban District Councils. By C: M. Lloyd, M.A. 2d. 62. Parish and District Councils. (Revised 1919.) 2d. 137. Parish Councils and Village Life. Leaflets. — 134. Small Holdings. 68. The Tenant's Sanitary Catechism^ 71. Ditto for London. , i . .' .;.j:' IV.— General Politics and Fabian Policy. " > /,t- ; Tracts.— 158. The Case against the C.O.S. By IUxs.Townshknd. 41. The Fabian Society: its Early History. By Bernard Shaw. , >^' ,f _ = .' V. — Biographical Series. - In portrait covers, 2d. and 3d. '. . ,- '■;■-_- i8a. Robert Owen, Idealist. By C. E. M. Joad. 179. John Buskin and Social Ethics. By Prof. Edith Moeley.-. 165. Francis Place. .By St. John G. Ervink. 3d. 166. Robert Owen, Social Reformer. By Miss B. L. Hutchins. 167. William Morris and the Communist Ideal. By Mrs. To\vnshend. 3d. 168. John Stuart Mill. By Julius West. 3d. 174. Charles Kingsley and Christian Socialism, By C. E. VULLIAMY.