. _>aWII— WliWKIllllim ■ :a4<^.aMfc.>. " J i WWM"i i!!i | i ' i li iiiiiii . ii rii. — »^ ■-- — " BJ 1 0( I BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME ' FROM THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF 1891 /i,.XJ.sc>M..Z- Z.f./Jo ..Jjt^.o.pi 7673-2 blJN UBRARY-CIRCUIATIOH' TDATE DUE rmt P I lASED DEI ERIQRATIQN IRA2\LE UOliS NOT cmcuip t— ti PRINTEOINU.S.A. rilrart*--.'' ',^* •■■»■'> ^^ ►ii^sf^-^j: FRAGILE PAPER Please handle this book with care, as the paper is brittle. 1 )ES NOT COBNELL UNIVEHSm; jj«^^^^^^ no^ 3 1924 092 294 564 Cornell University Library The original of tiiis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924092294564 BY THE SAME AUTHOR THE UNIVERSITIES OF EUROPE IN THE MIDDLE AGES 1895 DOCTRINE AND DEVELOPMENT - 1898 NEW COLLEGE, in 'College Histories' Series (with R. S. Rait) 1901 THE ULTIMATE BASIS OF THEISM, in 'Contentio Veritatis, by six Oxford Tutors ' 1903 PERSONALITY HUMAN AND DIVINE, in 'Personalldealism'; edited by H. C. Sturt 1902 CHRISTUS IN ECCLESIA 1904 THE THEORY OF GOOD AND EVIL A TREATISE ON MORAL PHILOSOPHY BV HASTINGS RASHDALL D.LITT. (oxford), HON. D.C.L. (dUHHAm) FELLOW AND TUTOR OF NEW COLLEGE, OXFORD VOLUME I OXFORD AT THE CLARENDON PRESS 1907 / V It I/'/ ■ ' ' HENRY PROWDE, M.A. FUBLISHEB TO THE UNIVKRSITTr OF OZroBD LONDON, EDINBURGH NEW YORK AND TORONTO TO THE MEMORY OF MY TEACHERS THOMAS HILL GREEN AND HENRY SIDGWICK PREFACE The scope of the present work is perhaps made sufficiently obvious by the title-page. It is an attempt to deal with the chief topics usually discussed in books bearing the title ' Moral Philosophy ' or ' Ethics.' It is on a rather larger scale than the books generally described as ' Textbooks,' or ' Introductions,' and is occupied to some extent with difficulties and controversies which can hardly be called ' elementary.' Still, I have in writ- ing it had chiefly before my mind the wants of undergraduate students in Philosophy. I have endeavoured, as far as possible, to assume no previous acquaintance either with ethical or with general Philosophy : but it has not, in aU parts of the work, been possible to avoid alluding to the arguments and objections of writers whose systems cannot be fuUy explained or examined in a book like the present. That is especially the case in Book II, which is largely occupied with replies to objections and with the criticism of views more or less opposed to my own. Even there I have endeavoured to make the drift of my argument intelligible to readers who have not read the works criticized. But those who want a short and fairly elementary treatment of the subject might perhaps read Book I by itself, or pass at once from Book I to Book III. That book deals in part with metaphysical questions which do not admit of an altogether ' popular ' treatment ; this section of the work would no doubt be better understood by a student who has read enough to know in a general way the meaning of the metaphysical problem, but I hope it will not be found wholly unintelligible to those who may make their first acquaintance with it in these pages. Advanced students are more likely to complain that I have touched upon many great questions, not specially belong- ing to the ethical branch of Philosophy, in a way which must appear unsatisfying to those who are well versed in them, and dogmatic to those who do not agree with me. I would venture vi PREFACE in reply to such a criticism to plead that the necessity of touch- ing upon difficult questions without getting to the bottom of them is to some extent inseparable from any treatment of Ethics which does not form part of a complete course or system of Philosophy: and the difficulty is increased when one wishes to avoid allusiveness and technicality of a kind which would necessarily render the book perplexing and uninstructive to a student beginning the subject, or to the general reader who may take some interest in the ethical and religious aspects of Philosophy without wishing to embark upon an elaborate course of Logic, Psychology, and Metaphysic. The idea prevails among some Philosophers that Moral Philo- sophy is a particularly ' easy ' branch of Philosophy. I believe that it is easier than other branches of Philosophy in the sense that its more elementary problems can be discussed with less technicality, and can be understood more readily at a first read- ing by persons of ordinary ability and education. For this reason it seems to me a peculiarly good subject for the student of Philosophy to begin upon, although logically it might well be considered to come rather at the end than at the beginning of a philosophical course. But, though the controversies which range round the words ' Utilitarianism ' and ' Intuitionism ' can be understood and discussed almost without reference to meta- physical problems, the ultimate question of Moral Philosophy — the meaning and nature of the ideas ' good,' ' right,' ' duty ' — is after all the ultimate question of all Philosophy, and involves all the others. I am very far from thinking that I have got to the bottom of all the difficulties involved in that fundamental problem: upon some of them I am aware that I have hardly touched in these pages. Nor is there anything very original in such a solution of them as I have been able to offer : and yet I am not aware that, in English at any rate, there is any syste- matic treatment of them, written from anything like my own point of view, to which I could point as altogether meeting the wants of the class of readers for whom this book is chiefly intended. Neither of the great writers to whom I feel I owe most in the special department of Ethics — the late Professor Sidgwick, and the late Professor T. H. Green whose lectures and PREFACE vii private classes I used to attend as an undergraduate — can well be regarded as having said the last word upon the subject by students of a generation later who ha^je profited not merely by the criticism which each of them supplies upon the other, but by the general progress of Philosophy since the first appear- ance of Sidgwick's Methods of Ethics (1874) and of Green's Prolegomena to Ethics (1883). Since the last-mentioned date the supposed easiness of this branch of Philosophy, or the superior attractiveness of Logic and Metaphysic, has led perhaps to a certain unwillingness to write separate treatises on Ethics, at least among those who take what one may call a constructive view of the subject *. But the period — almost a quarter of a century — which has elapsed since the death of Green has been a period of great philosophical activity, and (I venture to think) of great philosophical progress, and there has been much incidental treatment of ethical questions in the works both of English and of foreign Philosophers. There seems therefore room for a fresh systematic treatment of the main problems of Moral Philosophy in what I will venture to call (in spite of great difierences both of opinion and of temperament) the spirit which animated both of them. Among more recent writers I have learned most perhaps from those from whom I differ most. I have so frequently criticized the writings of Mr. F. H. Bradley that I should like to say that, fundamentally as I dissent from his ultimate position, I believe that no one has a deeper sense than myself of personal obligation to his brilliant writings, or a deeper appreciation of the stimulus which he has given to philosophical progress, not only in his own ' I should wish to speak with respect of three short English textbooks — Professor Muirhead's Elements of Ethics, Professor Mackenzie's Introduction to Moral Philosophy, and Bishop d'Arcy's Short Study of Ethics ; but none of them can be said to represent exactly my own point of view. I feel more sympathy on the purely ethical, though not on the metaphysical, side with a quite recent work — Mr. Moore's very powerful essay, Principia Ethica, which appeared when my own work was practically finished. Professor Paulsen's System of Ethics is an admirable and very attractive book, which represents on the whole a point of view not unlike my own, but it hardly touches upon many difficulties which have attracted much attention in England. viii PREFACE University of Oxford, but throughout the English-speaking world and beyond it. Unfortunately, Ethics seems to me pre- cisely the side of Philosophy on which his influence has been least salutary. I trust that, while criticizing him with freedom, I have not failed in the respect that is due to perhaps the most original of contemporary thinkers. With regard to my criticism of the able work of Professor A. E. Taylor {The Problem of Conduct), I should wish to explain that the recent number of the Philosophical Review in which he withdraws his view about the merely ' apparent ' character of evil did not come into my hands till the whole of my criticism was printed and some of it had been finally passed for the press, though I had not failed to notice the change of tone already traceable in his Elements of Metaphysics. I can only therefore express my regret for having devoted so much space to the criticism of a position which its author has abandoned. It is useless for an author to offer apologies for the defects of a book which he is not compelled to write. In explanation of such deficiencies of the present work as may arise from the absence of a more exhaustive knowledge of the literature bearing upon this and cognate subjects, I may, however, be allowed to plead, for the information of persons unacquainted with our English system of University teaching, that Oxford College Tutors are very far from possessing 'the leisure of a German or an American Professor, and that they have to choose between publishing imperfect work and not publishing at all. They may perhaps console themselves with the reflection that the method of individual teaching by means of essays and conversation gives them opportunities of appreciating the real wants of students which are hardly accessible to teachers who see their pupils only in the lecture-room. I have a strong feeling that the progress of knowledge, especially in the region of Philosophy, is often retarded by an excessive shrinking from criticism, and by an indefinite postponement of publication in the hope of more completely satisfying an author's ideal. The following articles which have already appeared in various periodicals have been freely made use of with the kind per- mission of their editors : — ' Professor Sidgwick's Utilitarianism ' PREFACE ix {Mind, 1885) ; 'Dr. Martineau and the Theory of Vocation' [Mind, 1 888) ; ' The Theory of Punishment ' (The International Journal of Ethics, 1 891); 'The Limits of Casjjistry' {International Journal of Ethics, 1894); 'Justice' {The Economic Review, 1 891, 189a); 'Can there be a Sum of Pleasures?' {Mind, 1899); ' The Ethics of Forgiveness ' {International Journal of Ethics, 1900); 'The Commensurability of all Values' {Mind, 1902). Some of the earlier articles have been largely re- written : others are reprinted with little change. Dr. McTaggart of Trinity College, Cambridge, has kindly read through the whole of my proofs, and I am much indebted to his criticisms and suggestions. For assistance and advice in dealing with parts of the work I am similarly indebted to Mr. C. C. J. Webb of Magdalen College, Oxford, and several other friends, nor must I omit to mention the help of my wife in the final revision. H. RASHDALL. ANALYTICAL TABLE aF CONTENTS VOLUME I BOOK I. THE MORAL CKITERION CHAPTER I. INTRODUCTORY PAGE The exact scope and object of a Science is only arrived at gradually, as the Science itself progresses. This applies to Philosophy and its branches i And the individual student of Philosophy has to discover its meaning gradually 2 Hence no attempt will be made at an exact definition of the scope of Moral Philosophy beyond saying that we are investigating the meaning and application of the terms ' right ' and ' wrong ' : plan of the work explained 3 CHAPTER II. PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISS^ ^'"' J. Bentham's view that nothing but pleasure can possibly be desired 7 Its plausibility depends upon a confusion between three possible interpretations : (i) that I always do that which it gives me most pleasure at the moment to do ; (2) that the motive of an action is always some future pleasure ; (3) that the motive is always to get the greatest pleasure on the whole. It is clear that people often do things which they once knew would not secure most pleasure on the whole 8 If it be said that at the moment they persuade themselves that such things will do so, this by itself implies a bias in favour of immediate pleasure : this involves rejection of the third view 9 Nor can it be said that I always do what is pleasantest at the moment, for people often choose painful things for the sake of some- thing future n This again implies that the nearer pleasure is more attractive 12 But the superior attractiveness of some pleasures over others can- not be explained merely by (i) expected intensity and (a) proximity : e. g. in case of anger 13 If not pleasure but a particular kind of pleasure is desired, this really implies that something is desired besides pleasure ... 14 The hedonistic Psychology involves a hysteron-proteron : in many cases the pleasure can only be accounted for by pre-existent desire . 15 Few pleasures, chiefly sensual and aesthetic, can be explained without admitting ' disinterested desires ' 15 xii ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE II. If it were admitted that Altruism grew out of Egoism, this would not prove the hedonistic Psychology, but such a theory is inconsistent with all that is known about instinct .... 20 Some instincts are race-preserving, even in animals ... 22 In men such instincts gradually pass into desires .... 23 III. J. S. Mill's admission of differences of quality in pleasure abandons psychological Hedonism : to desire a superior quality in pleasure is not to desire pleasure ''25; Pleasures differ in kind, if by a pleasure is meant not abstract — pleasantness but a pleasant state of consciousness .... 26 IV. The difficulties of psychological Hedonism illustrated by the possibility of desiring objects that vidll not be realized till after death 27 Case of the atheistic Martyr 28 The pains and pleasures of Conscience cannot be included in the calculus, for they imply the existence of desire for something besides pleasure 29 V. Elements of truth in psychological Hedonism : — (1) The gratification of every desire gives pleasure ... 31 (2) Pictured or experienced pleasantness strengthens desire . 33 (3) Especially in the case of bad or indifferent desires, which may be disinterested as well as good ones, but not in quite the same sense or degree 33 (4) Not all desires are ' disinterested ' : there is such a thing as desire of pleasure 36 (5) Nor need the possibility of desiring a ' sum of pleasures ' be denied (see below. Book II, Ch. i) 37 (6) The ' paradox of Hedonism ' (' if you aim at pleasure you will not get it ') has some truth in it, but is often exaggerated . . 37 VI. The theory that in every desire self-satisfaction is sought involves the same hysteron-proteron as the hedonistic Psychology : if I regard the satisfaction of a desire for my neighbour's good as my good, this implies that I first desired it apart from its tendency to promote my good 38 CHAPTER III. RATIONALISTIC UTILITARIANISM I. If it is possible to desire other objects than one's own pleasure, the question remains whether it is rational to do so . . . . 44 Even the Egoistic Hedonist contends that his end of action is in- trinsically more reasonable than another's ; and if so, no reason can be given why one person's pleasure should be desired more than another's 44 The recognition of this leads us from Egoistic to Universalistic Hedonism 46 ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS xiii PAGE And this involves the recognition of an ' ought ' .... 48 IL The late Prof. Henry Sidgwick's Rationalistic Utilitarianism : his position compared with Mill's ...*.... h* Sidgvirick admits the existence of disinterested desires, and holds that it is ' right ' or our duty to pursue the greatest pleasure of Society on the whole, though such virtuous conduct is not in itself a good gj Objections to Sidgwick's position : (i) It practically admits that it is reasonable for A to promote B's pleasure ; yet it treats S as a being who may reasonably pursue nothing but his own pleasure : if such conduct is reasonable for A, why not for £? If ^ is to promote B'a happiness only so far as is consistent with £'s promoting the general pleasure, this seems to make virtue part of the end . . . . c. (a) The Dualism of the Practical Reason admitted by Sidgwick is untenable -5. (3) If the Egoist is pronounced reasonable in desiring his own good, and the Altruist in desiring general good, ' reasonable ' must be used in different senses eg (4) If to act rationally is not itself a good, why should I be rational ? cy (5) Sidgwick admits that he cannot fully establish the reason- ableness of right conduct without the postulates of Grod and Immor- tality, but his Hedonism undermines the principal ground for these beliefs g^ This criticism suggests that a rationalist Ethic cannot be hedonistic, but must treat Virtue or character (i.e. at least the disposition to pro- mote the general good) as itself part of the good to be promoted . 63 III. Reply to Sidgwick's objections to making character an end- in-itself : they seem to imply forgetfulness that there are other ele- ments in consciousness besides feeling, i. e. will and knowledge, and that these may have value 63 The final objection is that the Moral Consciousness does pronounce moral goodness to have value 69 IV. We have thus arrived at Kant's position that there are two rational ends — Virtue and Happiness 71 And this will remove most of the practical objections to Hedonism 72 But the Moral Consciousness does not favour the theory that nothing but pleasure and Virtue (in the sense of disposition to pro- mote pleasure) is intrinsically good : it includes other elements in the good, e. g. Culture. The true good consists in certain states, not merely of Feeling, but of Thought and of Volition .... 73 V. The relation of Thought, Feeling, and Will to each other : use of these and other terms explained 76 xiv ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER IV. INTUITIONISM PAOE I. By Intuitionism is meant the theory that the moral faculty pro- nounces either particular acts (unphiloBOphical Intuitionism) or rules of action to be morally binding without reference to consequences . 80 Unphilosophical Intuitionism seems to reduce Morality to mere caprice, unless it is held that the isolated judgements imply some principle .81 To philosophical Intuitionism the following objections may be made : — (i) Granted the existence of an intuitive impulse to condemn acts without reference to consequences, can such judgements be regarded as rational or valid ? 83 ., (ii) Variations of moral judgements in different races, ages, and individuals : but this objection is not final, for self-evident truths may not be evident to everybody 84 (iii) The rule which seems intuitively recognized is often incapable of exact definition, and admits of exceptions about which there are no clear intuitions 85 (iv) The rule generally involves a tacit reference to consequences : some consequences are included in our conception of the act . . 87 (v) Some alleged intuitions contradict others : the requirements of Benevolence may collide with those of Veracity .... 89 (vi) The only intuitions which really commend themselves upon reflection are precisely those upon which Utilitarianism is based — the axioms of Prudence, Rational Benevolence, and Equity . . 90 II. We are thus driven to accept the principle that actions are to be judged by their tendency to promote a universal Well-being. We have in the last resort to appeal to intuitions or judgements of value, but these relate not to acts but to ends 91 This position allows us to recognize that acts may have a value as well as consequences, for to the Non-hedonist the means are often part of the end g6 Some pleasures are bad g8 III. The moral judgement is thus a judgement of value — ' this is good,' not (immediately) ' this is right ' loo CHAPTER V. THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE I. Our moral judgements involve an ultimate unanalysable idea — ' ought ' or duty. Utilitarianism requires such an ' ought ' as much as any other system, as has been recognized by Sidgwick . . . 10a Kant is thus (by Sidgwick's admission) right in making Morality a ' categorical imperative ' in so far as this means that ' rightness ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS xv PAQE is perceived immediately by Reason, and that the lightness of any act supplies a motive for doing it 106 He is also right in recognizing that the perfornlance of duty is the agent's highest good 107 II. But Eant was wrong in supposing that the bare notion of a Categorical Imperative will enable us, without any appeal to experience, to decide what in detail it ia right to do . . . . 108 Experience cannot tell us what is good, but neither can we say what is good without experience 109 No content for the Moral Law can be got from Kant's first rule, ' Act as if the law of thy action were to become by thy will law universal' 110 Eant confused two senses of the word ' categorical ' : a categorical rule (in one sense) does not exclude exceptions 116 III. The principle of ' duty for duty's sake ' did not (as Eant supposed) imply that no other motive can give moral value to conduct 119 Eant made the same mistake as the hedonistic Psychologists . 122 IV. The 'sense of duty' must not be treated as unnecessary or belonging to an imperfect Morality 124 The true moral motive is the rational love of persons (including in due measure one's self) and of the things which constitute their true good 128 Schopenhauer's criticism of Eant 129 V. When it is recognized that other ends or objects of desire are good besides (i) Virtue and (2) Happiness, the sharp Dualism of the Kantian* Ethics disappears 130 VI. No content for Morality can be got out of Kant's second rule, ' Use Humanity always as an end, never as a means only ' . . . 131 VII. Eant's third rule, ' Act as member of a kingdom of ends,' is more rational, but insufficient : ambiguity of all his formulae . . 133 VTII. The idea of ' good ' is logically prior to the idea of ' right,' though each implies the other 135 ' Value ' the fundamental idea in Morality 137 CHAPTER VI. REASON AND FEELING I. It is implied in what precedes that the moral faculty is Reason, not any kind of feeling or emotion 138 This does not imply that the reasonableness of a moral act causes it to be done without desire 14° Moral judgements are normally accompanied by emotion . . 14.1 II. The Moral Sense theory of Ethics a reaction against an exaggera- tive Rationalism 142 xvi ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGB But if the Moral Sense be only a feeling of approbation, whence its superiority to other feelings ? . . 143 Such feelings can have no universal or objective validity . 145 III. Such ethical maxims as those of Prudence, Rational Benevo- lence, and Equity are indeed self-evident, but their resemblance to niathematical axioms may be exaggerated, or rather they are nothing but mathematical axioms applied to conduct, and cannot give a con- tent to Morality apart from the judgement ' this or that is good ' . 147 And such judgements have not the precision or exactness of mathematical judgements 149 They are more like aesthetic judgements, if these are recognized as possessing objective validity 149 IV. Further elements of truth in the Moral Sense view . . . 151 The moral judgement is ultimately a judgement upon the value of some state of consciousness, and this always includes feeling . . 152 We could hardly pronounce knowledge or even goodness to have value for a consciousness which was incapable of deriving any kind of satisfaction from them 153 Sometimes the feeling to which value is assigned may be merely a feeling of pleasure or pain, but in other cases it may be some emotion connected with particular kinds of conduct, in the absence of which Reason could not pronounce the act good or bad . . . .154 But the judgement that the emotion is good is not the same thing as the emotion itself 155 It must be remembered (i) that these emotions, in which the value of an act often lies, are not arbitrarily selected, but are closely con- nected with our whole ideal of human good . . . . _ . 157 (2) That we cannot (as some Rationalists attempt to do) pronounce what is good for man without experience of his actual sensitive, aesthetic, and emotional nature 159 (3) Such judgements often require an experience which is beyond the reach of a single individual : hence the importance of Authority in Ethics 160 The above considerations are often forgotten by pure Utilitarians, as well as by ultra-Rationalists, e. g. Plato 161 V. Martineau"s view that Conscience is neither feeling nor Reason is scarcely intelligible . ., 164 Gizycki's objections to ethical Rationalism turn upon misunder- standing 166 VI. Examination of the view that, though moral judgements are '■-Rational, they are inseparable from a certain specific emotion in the absence of which they could not be made 168 In popular language Conscience implies not merely the judgement that this is right or wrong, but the feelings and desires which are ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS xvii PAGE presupposed by such judgements and which prompt to the doing of the actions judged right 175 Note on the Aesthetic Judgement . . * . . . . 177 CHAPTER VII. IDEAL UTILITARIANISM I. Our view that acts are right or wrong according as they tend or do not tend to promote a Well-being or tuSai/iotia or good consist- ing of various elements, the relative value of which is intuitively discerned, may be called Ideal Utilitarianism ..... 184 Importance of the three axioms of Prudence, Benevolence, and Equity 184 Benevolence must be regulated by Justice 185 Popular uses of the term Justice all imply impartiality in the treat- ment of individuals upon the basis of some established system of distribution: ultimate Justice would mean the distribution of the true good in accordance with the principle that one man's good is of as much intrinsic value as the like good of another's . . , . 183 All virtues may be included in Benevolence regulated by Justice, but it is convenient to give distinctive names to special kinds of contribu- tion to social good 187 II. Eventhe virtues which are most obviously altruistic have a value of their own greater than that of the pleasure which they produce, e. g. Humanity or the social affections 189. The ground on which we condemn Infanticide .... 189 III. Value of knowledge, culture, aesthetic and intellectual activity, and the accompanying emotions 191 Veracity and love of truth 193 IV. Purity 197 Temperance 202 V. Humility 204 VX. The prohibition of Suicide 207 VII. Duty towards the lower animals 213 VIII. Difficulty of finding a suitable name for an Ethic which is teleological but not hedonistic. Such a view widely held . . . 216 IX. When Morality, pleasure, and other things are pronounced good, they must not be thought of as lying side by side without affect- ing or modifying one another : they are all parts, elements, or aspects of an ideally good life which it is the duty of each to promote for all 219 CHAPTER VIII. JUSTICE I. No ethical question can be answered without deciding the ques- tion ' Whose good is to be promoted ? ' 222 There are two competing ideals of Justice : (l) Equality, and (2) Just recompense or reward 223 SASHDALL 1 b xviii ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE II. Examination of the Benthamite maxim, ' Every one to count for one, nobody for more than one '........ 223 Abstractly considered, the maxim seems rational .... 224 But what if an equal distribution diminishes the amount of good to be distributed ? 225 Equality of consideration is the only equality which is always right, and this may often demand an unequal distribution .... 226 No unconditional rights except the right to consideration . . 227 Moreover men's capacity for enjoying good varies .... 228 ' Equality of opportunity ' would bear too hardly on the weak . 230 Some Liberty is a condition of Well-being, and this always involves some inequality . . ■ 233 III. Does superior capacity constitute a claim to superior con- sideration ? 234 In most cases such superior consideration is in the interests of all ; but, even where this is not the case, we must admit that higher Well- being is of more value than lower, and those who are capable of it are therefore entitled to superior consideration 235 We can therefore accept the Benthamite maxim only in the sense ' Caeteris paribus every one to count for one,' or ' Every man's good to count as equal to the like good of every other ' 240 Final collisions between the higher good of few and the lower good of many rarely occur, especially if the good of the future be duly remembered 240 Summary of conclusions 241 IV. The theory of Reward assumes two forms — 'to every man according to his merit,' and ' to every man according to his work ' . 243 The two views would work out very differently .... 243 To say that Justice means paying each man in proportion to his work involves forgetfulness of the fact that economic value is relative : if competition be excluded, there is no means of fixing values . . 244 To equate the amount of different kinds of work is equally im- possible 247 Nor is the superior dignity — moral, aesthetic, or intellectual — of different kinds of labour a ground for differential remuneration . . 249 Nor yet the difference of natural capacity 250 It is true that the man of higher faculty may require exceptionally favourable external conditions for the realization of his higher capacities, and Justice requires that he should have them . . . 253 Should superior merit, in the sense of superior Morality or devotion to the general good, be differentially rewarded ? .... 255 As a matter of abstract right, the answer is ' No,' and at all events there is no way of rewarding superior virtue without rewarding superior capacity; yet it is true that the good ought to be made ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS xix PAGE happy, but the proper reward is the pleasure which results from the exercise of the superior capacity under favourable external con- ditions * . . . . 257 A limit to the material reward of virtue will be set by the con- sideration that beyond a certain point such reward might be un- favourable to the virtue itself 259 Hence, practically, abstract merit must be put aside as a canon of distributive Justice, and reward for work must be determined by considerations of social expediency 259 Reward will always be necessary, but may become increasingly non- material 260 V. We have found that each of our competing ideals, (i) Equality (2) Reward, is true only in the sense in which it is the equivalent of the other, i. e. every one's good is equally valuable with the like good of another, but superior good is woi-th more than inferior, and the man of superior capacity should therefore receive proportionately greater consideration 262 VI. But what if there be a final collision between Benevolence, i. e. the promotion of good on the whole, and Justice, i. e. the fairest possible distribution of the good in proportion to capacity ? In prac- tice we should deem it rational to sacrifice a little good on the whole to a great increase of Justice in its distribution, and vice versa, but not to sacrifice much good for a little nearer approach to just distribution of it 264 The two principles might be brought together by treating Equality or Justice in distribution as itself a good, but it is difficult to regard such an abstraction as a good 266 But, if we regard Morality as a good-in-itself, we may treat Justice in distribution as part of the good enjoyed by the just individual or society, and so there will be no real loss of good by the society which sacrifices some lower good for the sake of juster distribution . . 267 VII. Justice represents an ideal which cannot be immediately realized 269 Justice as the immediate duty of the individual consists in (i) seek- ing to promote a nearer approach in social arrangements to the ideal of equality of consideration, (2) observing the principle in private relations so far as is immediately practicable, (3) respecting the existing social and political order so far as it cannot be immediately changed for the better 273 VIII. The rights of property depend upon considerations of social expediency, including their effects on character .... 274 IX. Reply to the objection that such a view of Justice is incon- sistent with ' organic character of human society ' . . . . 277 Note on Rbnouvieb's Idea of Justice 282 XX ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER IX. PUNISHMENT AND FORGIVENESS PAGE I. The theory of retributive Justice as expounded by Kant and others 284 Such a theory does not commend itself to the moral consciousness . 286 Difficulties of the theory illustrated by Mr. Bradley's attempted modification of it 286 Yet the retributive theory possesses elements of truth : (i) Psychological or historical truth. Punishment originated in Vengeance 291 (2) Punishment is reformatory as well as deterrent . . . 293 (3) The theory represents the idea that the State has spiritual or moral ends 295 The educative effect of the criminal law 296 II. The theory that ' the promotion of Morality by force is a self- contradiction ' is an exaggeration of the truth that some liberty is a condition of the highest Morality 298 III. It cannot be right to inflict pain or other evil except as a means to good . 300 This does not imply disrespect for personality 303 The expression by punishment of indignation at wrong is good for individuals and for societies, but should be controlled by Reason: Love is better than Revenge ......... 304; The retributive theory mistakes a natural, and valuable, emotion for a judgement of the Practical Reason 305 IV. The retributive theory can give no reasonable account of forgiveness 306 But we rightly hold that resentment and forgiveness are alike applications of the general duty of promoting social welfare, and that social considerations determine the measure of both . . . 307 The moral effects of forgiveness 310 This view of punishment must be applied to Theology . . .311 THE THEOEY OF GOOD AND EVIL BOOK I THE MORAL CRITERION CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY A CLEAR and adequate conception of the scope and object-matter of a Science and of its relations to other Sciences is usually arrived at only at a tolerably advanced stage in the development of the Science itself. It is impossible to start with clear con- ceptions of such matters as Heat, Light, Electricity, and Mag- netism ; for the attainment of such conceptions is precisely the goal of the Sciences which deal with these matters, and is even yet not fully reached. Science starts with some roughly defined department of common experience, and works towards clearer and more adequate conceptions of it. In the course of scientific progress, it sometimes turns out that a supposed Science deals with really non-existent objects, or is directed towards aims impossible of attainment, or that it is really identical with some Science hitherto supposed to be distinct, or is a branch of some Science the very possibility of which was previously unsuspected. Sciences fuse, subdivide, transform themselves, or disappear altogether; new Sciences make their appearance and new groupings of old Sciences. Thus the greatest service which Astrology ever rendered to the world was its own ex- tinction : while it was only at a tolerably advanced stage of its development that the Science of Electricity was discovered to be identical with that of Magnetism, and not identical with the closely related but still distinguishable Sciences of Heat and Light. And, if that is the case even with the various depart- ments of physical Science, each of which studies some group EASBDALI. I , B a INTRODUCTORY [Book I or some aspect of tangible and visible things, it is pre-eminently the case with Philosophy in general and its various branches. It is only gradually that Philosophy has clearly differentiated itself from the special Sciences, and particularly from the most general of those Sciences. The older Metaphysicians were also Physicists. It is only at a comparatively recent date that Meta- physicians have abandoned the attempt to decide by the methods of Metaphysics what were really questions of empirical Natural Science, and that Physicists have ceased to dogmatize about metaphysical questions, if indeed a well-defined conception of the relation between the two spheres can be said to have been arrived at even now : while the exact relations between the various Sciences included in or closely connected with Philosophy, such as Logic, Metaphysic, and Psychology, are still avowedly matters of dispute among Philosophers. To a certain extent every student of a Science has to go through in the course of his own studies the same process which the human mind has followed in reaching the present level of scientific attainment. In the Physical Sciences this necessity is to some extent avoided by the fact that certain results of Physical Science rapidly become matters of common knowledge or social inheritance, and so are accepted unconsciously on authority even before the age at which formal scientific teaching begins. Though the results of philosophical enquiry are far from contributing nothing to the common stock of socially transmitted ideas, they pass far more slowly and incompletely into general circulation. A teacher of Astronomy does not find it necessary to begin by refuting the hypothesis that the motions of the heavenly bodies exercise a profound influence upon the life-history of individual men. In the region of Philosophy ideas of the same order cannot always be assumed to be non- existent. The very nature and meaning of Philosophy, and still more the lines of demarcation between its various branches, must be left slowly to dawn upon the student in the course of his study of Philosophy itself. Philosophy is like learning to swim. A man does not really discover what it is until he finds himself already somewhat out of his depth. He must plunge in boldly, and discover what he has been at later on. Chap.i] PLAN OF WOEK 3 For these reasons I shall make no formal attempt to mark out beforehand the relation of our subject to Philosophy in general or to its other branches. I shall begin by assuming only that we are concerned with the study of human conduct, that we are investigating the meaning of the ideas ' right ' and ' wrong ' with the object both of arriving at a clearer conception of those ideas in general, and of determining in a more precise manner than is done by ordinary persons in common life what things in particular are right and what are wrong. How far and in what sense such an aim is attainable is one of the things which must be left to appear in the course of our enquiry. And in my treatment of the subject I shall endeavour to follow what is, not indeed always but very frequently, the Hne of development taken by the mind of students. When first the attempt is made to think out clearly the unanalysed, more or less confused and incon- sistent ideas about human conduct with which we all start, the student is very likely to be caught by a theory of extreme simplicity and apparently great scientific completeness and attractiveness — a theory which, as a matter of fiact, has always made its appearance at the beginning of every serious historical effort to grapple with the ethical problem. H© is very likely to be bitten by the theory which traces all human conduct to the operation of a single motive, the desire of pleasure. If this theory be true, it foUows as a matter of course that the only meaning which can be given to the term right is ' conducive to pleasure,' and to the term wrong ' unconducive to pleasure or productive of its opposite, pain.' The commonly received ideas about right and wrong, in so far as they are upon such a view capable of scientific justification at all, have then to be explained by showing that the acts commonly regarded as right are produc- tive of pleasure on the whole to the individual, while the actions commonly accounted wrong are conducive on the whole to pain or loss of pleasure. To examine this theory, known as psycho- logical Hedonism, will be the starting-point of our investigation and will be dealt with in the next chapter. If satisfied that pleasure is not always the motive of the individual's own action, the student may still very probably be attracted by other forms of the theory that pleasure in the last resort, either to the individual B 3 4 INTRODUCTORY [Book I or to others, is the sole true and ultunate criterion of human action. Utilitarianism disconnected from psychological Hedonism will be the subject of our third chapter. From the Utilitarian group of ethical theories I shall turn to their extreme opposite, the theory which asserts in the most uncompromising and un- analysed way the authority, perhaps even the infallibility, of the individual Conscience and of the judgements about particular questions of right and wrong which the ordinary Conscience pro- nounces — the theory commonly known as Intuitionism. I shall then try to bring together the various elements of truth con- tained in the conflicting theories, and to arrive at a view which will embrace and harmonize them, while avoiding the mistakes and exaggerations which each, taken by itself, can be shown to involve. I sk&ll then go on to examine more in detail some of the chief questions of right conduct, the chief commonly recog- nized virtues and duties or groups of duties, and to show how they can be explained and co-ordinated, with whatever correction of popular notions may turn out to be necessary, upon the basis of the theory which will be adopted. To arrive at a clearer and more definite conception of the Moral Criterion — a clearer and more definite answer than is contained in that common moral consciousness from which we must all start to the question ' What ought I to do, and why ought I to do it ? ' will be the object of our first book. In the second book I shall enter at greater length into some of the current controversies connected with our subject, by the exam- ination of which I shall hope further to elucidate and define the results arrived at in the first book. Most of these con- troversies may be said to centre round the question of the relation of the individual and the individual's good to society and a wider social good. I have therefore styled the book ' The Individual and the Society.' In the third book I shall deal with some of those wider philosophical issues which are ultimately in- volved in any attempt to think out fully and adequately the meaning of the words 'right and wrong,' 'good and evil' — in other words with the relation of Morals and Moral Philosophy to our theory of the Universe in general, to Metaphysic and Religion, to the theory of Free-will, to the facts of Evolution Chap, i] METAPHYSIC AND ETHICS 5 and theories of Evolution, and finally to practical life. The subject of this section may be described generally as 'Man and the Universe.' In postponing thase more general con- siderations to the end of our enquiry instead of making them our starting-point, I am once more abandoning what may perhaps be thought the logical order ; and adopting the order which will, I hope, be most advantageous for purposes of exposition and dialectical defence, and which will be most convenient for those who may read this book with no previous acquaintance with technical Philosophy or with any of its branches. With regard to the relations between Metaphysic and Moral Philosophy it wiU be enough to premise this much — that Metaphysic is an enquiry into the ultimate nature of Reality and our knowledge of it ; while Moral Philosophy is an enquiry into a particular, though very general and important, department of our knowledge, our ideas of right and wrong ', that is to say into one particular though very fundamental aspect of Reality, the aspect which is expressed by our moral judgments. To attain some clearer con- ception as to the relation of these ideas to other ideas, of this aspect of Reality to other aspects, will be one object of our investigation. But, whatever answer may be given to this last problem, it must be possible at least to begin the enquiry as to what we mean by saying that an act is right or wrong, and why we call some actions right and others wrong, without presupposing any more than is presupposed in our common unscientific thinking about the world in general and man's place in it. At a very early stage of our enquiry it may, indeed, be found that we cannot give a satisfactory answer to that question without assuming particular answers to other and more general questions about human know- ledge and about the ultimate nature of things — answers which from various philosophical points of view have sometimes been implicitly or explicitly denied. But I shall endeavour, for the ^ The relation of this question to the wider question ' What is good ? ' win be dealt with in the sequel ; but in modem times Moral Philosophy has grown out of an attempt to answer the question ' What is right ? ' rather than the question ' What is good ? ' And this is the essentially ethical ques- tion, since, by general admission, Ethics starts with the problem of human conduct, even though it may soon be discovered that that problem involves a wider problem about values in general. 6 INTRODUCTORY [Book I reasons already indicated, to make the first part of our enquiry as purely ethical as possible. If and in so far as it shall be found that to take a particular view about the ideal of human conduct, a view to which we are led purely by the investigation of the actual contents of our ethical consciousness, logically involves us in wider conclusions as to the nature of the Universe and man's place in it, that will be the best way of defending those wider conclusions, and so of exhibiting the true relation between that ethical Science which is the subject of this book and that wider Science of Reality which will be dealt with in these pages only in so far as may be necessary for the purpose of attaining clear ideas about the meaning and end of human life. CHAPTER II PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM In the writings of Bentham^ and his followers the ethical doctrine that actions are right or wrong according as they do or do not tend to produce maximum pleasure is founded upon the psychological theory that as a matter of fact nothing is or can be desired except pleasure. The most fundamental of aU distinctions between ethical systems turns upon the attitude which they adopt towards this theory. It is of course possible for a Moral Philosopher to reject the hedonistic Psycho- logy and still to remain a Hedonist. He may hold that it is, as a matter of psychological fact, possible to desire other things besides pleasure, but that pleasure is the only proper or rational object of desire. It is possible to contend that I may, as a matter of psychological fact, desire other things, but that, if I do so, I am a fool for my pains. On the other hand it is clear that if nothing but pleasure can be desired, it is useless, and indeed meaningless, to maintain that something other than pleasure ought to be desired. It will be . well, therefore, to clear the ground by facing the psychological problem before we attack the ethical questions which depend, to a large extent, upon our answer to that problem, ^ And earlier of Hobbes, with this difference— that Hobbes defines plea- sure in terms of desire (' Whatsoever is the object of any man's appetite or desire, that is it which he for his part calleth good,' Leviathan, ch. vi), and then proceeds to define pleasure as 'the apparance or sense of good.' Bentham assumes that we already know what pleasure is, and then proceeds to argue that we desire that and nothing else. The difference might be more important than it is if Hobbes had always remembered it himself. When he identifies the ' iucundum ' with ' good in effect, as the end desired,' he practically adopts the position of Bentham. 8 PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book T The plausibility of the doctrine that nothing but pleasure can be the object of desire depends mainly upon a confusion between three different senses in which it may be vmderstood. The proposition that the motive of every action is pleasure may mean : — (i) That I always do that which it gives me most pleasure at the fnoment to do ; (2) That the motive of every action is somQ future pleasure, although that future pleasure is not necessarily the most intense (it being for instance possible to choose the nearer but smaller pleasure in preference to one greater but more remote) : (3) That the motive of every act is always to get the greatest quantum, of pleasure upon the whole. Now the doctrine explicitly maintained by psychological Hedonists is usually the last of these three positions : while its plausibility arises chiefly from its confusion with one or both of the former. The last proposition is, indeed, one of those which would hardly obtain a moment's acceptance but for the supposed consequences of denying it. Let us assume for the moment that nothing ever is desired except pleasure, and ask whether it is always the prospect of thfi greatest pleasure that moves us. That men do not always do that which will as a matter of fact bring them most pleasure will readily be admitted : need we hesitate to assert that the world would be a much better place if they did ^ ? Nor will it be denied that people often do actions which, before the time of acting, they know very well to be contrary to their real interest, understood in the most purely hedonistic sense. The drunkard — the poor drunkard at all events, who suffers from his vices in other than purely physiological ways — knows very well in the morning that he gets more pain than pleasure from his drink : he craves to get rid of the habit, and yet, as a matter of fact, he drinks on. That will be acknowledged, ' ' The thing to be lamented is, not that men have so great regard to their own good or interest in the present world, for they have not enough ; but that they have so little to the good of others.' Bp. Butler, Preface to Fifteen Sermons. Chap, ii, § i] PLEASUEE AND DESIRE 9 but it may be urged perhaps that atjtke moment of action such a man has always persuaded himself that the drink will produce a balance of pleasure on- the vjhole. Admit, if you like, that he has. The question remains : how, on the assump- tions of psychological Hedonism, is it possible to account for such a persuasion ? Granted that at the time he acts he does not know that the thing is bad for him, how can a man who once knew that a thing was bad for himself come, however momentarily, to believe the contrary? Such conduct as that of the drunkard will hardly be accounted for by mere intellectual error, mere involuntary lapse of memory. H a man who in the morning knew that to drink a whole bottle of gin was not for his good, comes in the evening to believe the contrary, his ignorance must be to some extent voluntary: he must, as we say, have ' persuaded himself ' that it will do him no harm. And this voluntary ignorance, this bias in his judgement, has to be accounted for: and on the hedonistic theory (in^the form in which it is now before us), it can be accounted for only in one way. On that theory there is only one desire or emotion that can ever affect the will, and so exercise a distorting influence upon the judgement, viz. desire for one's greatest pleasure on the whole. In the case supposed then desire for his greatest pleasure on the whole, steadily operating throughout the day, must somehow have changed the conviction that the man's greatest pleasure lies in abstinence or moderation into a conviction that his greatest pleasure lies in drunkenness. Is this an in- telligible piece of Psychology ? '^■■ Perhaps the matter "may Tse made plainer by a slightly difierent illustration. If there is a certain piece of hedonistic calculus in the world, it is that the pleasure of eating something very bad for one is not worth the indigestion which it causes. The pleasure, unlike that of quantitative or qualitative errors in drinking, is slight and almost momentary: the pain may be continuous and severe. Ask a man with a delicate digestion whether the wise dyspeptic Hedonist will eat lobster salad. Ask him in the morning, ask him the moment before dinner, ask him while he is actually tasting his soup, and he will say emphatically ' No. It has almost always disagreed with me ; lo PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I it certainly is not worth the risk of temporary indigestion and the danger of bringing back that chronic indigestion which it took me so long to get over a year ago.' Yet it may be that, as the dinner proceeds and conversation flows and spirits rise, the lobster salad comes round, and he eats. Now I admit that in cases like that it is scarcely possible to account for the man's action without supposing at least a momentary intellectual vacillation. Very likely he does say to himself, ' After all the consequences are not certain : I have upon occasion taken lobster salad without suffering much. I am better now than when I ate it last,' and so on. But the question remains, ' Why should he seek in this way to deceive himself?' Do not these efforts at self-deception imply that the man is not, as the theory supposes him to be, an absolutely impartial judge between the pleasure of the next moment and the pleasure of the next morning or the next week 1 Were he unbiassed by desire of lobster salad, or of the pleasure attending its consumption, he would un- questionably have retained his well-grounded conviction as to the inadvisability of eating it. Supposing, at the very moment before he took the fatal resolution, he were to be consulted by a no less dyspeptic neighbour, he would have no hesitation whatever about the matter. 'By no means eat lobster salad,' he would have said. And when in his own case he acts differ- ently, it is evident that at that moment he cares more for present pleasure (in so far as his desire is really a desire for pleasure at all) than for his pleasure on the whole. There is a bias in his judgement — a bias derived from desire — which prevents him from correctly balancing present against future pains. He has, in short, other desires besides a desire for the greatest quantum of pleasure, though it may be (for anything we have seen so far) that he still cares about nothing but pleasure. At all events, the nearer pleasure exercises more attractive power than the more remote. We have seen reason to reject the third interpretation of the hedonistic formula ; now let us look at the first. It undoubtedly sounds plausible to say that, if I do a thing, I do it because it pleases me to do it ; and from this it does not seem a large step to the admission that, if I prefer one alternative to another, Chap, ii, §i] PLEASURE AND DESIRE ii it is because it pleases me more, and from that to the admission that I always do that which pleases me most. It might be enough to point out that we are really misled Jby an ambiguity of language. ' It pleases me to do it,' ' it is my pleasure (placet) that it shall be done,' means merely ' I wiU that it should be done': as to why I will it, the phrase tells us nothing. But let us admit that we are justified in interpreting this ' placet ' by ' It gives me at this moment more pleasure to do this than to do anything else ^.' The question still remains ' Why does this course of action give me so much momentary pleasure as to determine my will to adopt it ? ' It certainly cannot always be the pleasure resulting at the moment of action that moves me to do it. For the most selfish people clearly do many things which are. painful at the time for the sake of some future end. Granted that it always gives me most pleasure to do what I have made up my mind to do, the question remains 'What leads me to make up my mind ? ' And this certainly cannot be the mere momentary pleasure involved in the act itself. If I thought only of my own momentary sensations while preparing for a bath on a very cold morning, I certainly should not take it. Still less, should I go to the dentist when my tooth is not actually aching. If I do these unpleasant things, it must be for the sake of something — a feeling of my own or otherwise — which lies beyond that moment. That brings us to the second possible sense of the psychological-hedonist doctrine — that I ^ This seems to be very muck the position of Sigwart : ' Bach end must, if I am on the whole to will it and to be able to devote my powers to its attain- ment, be such a one that the attainment of it promises some kind or other of satisfaction {Befriedigung) for me, the thought of which so affects my feeling, that the expectation of its attainment affords me joy, the fear of the opposite causes me pain ' (Sigwart, Vorfragen der Ethik, p. 5). This state- ment (with others in this remarkably clear and able little work) seems to me to be not actually erroneous, but to suggest the fallacies of psycho- logical Hedonism, inasmuch as it is not made clear whether the thought of the action is now pleasant because it will produce in the agent the greatest possible maximum of pleasant feeling, or because he desires the end and consequently will find satisfaction in its future accomplishment and in work- ing for its accomplishment in the present. The word ' Gefuhl ' seems to be used by Sigwart sometimes in the sense of ' desire,' sometimes of anticipated pleasure. 13 PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I always act for the sake of some future pleasure^, though not necessarily for the sake of the greatest quantum of pleasure on the whole. Why then should one pleasure or sum of pleasures attract me more than another, apart from its being greater in amount ? It may be said that I am more attracted by the nearer than by the remoter pleasure. That is intelligible, and it was admitted by Bentham, who did not see that the admission was fatal to the doctrine, implied if not expressed in the writings of himself and his followers, that what is desired is always the greatest pro- spective sum of pleasures. Of course in so far as remoteness mvolves uncertainty, that may logically be taken into account by the hedonistic calculus. But in so far as a remote pleasure is practically just as certain as a nearer one, it ought on Benthamite principles to prove equally attractive. And yet it is matter of experience that it very often does not. And this involves the admission that what I desire in such cases is not pleasure, but immediate pleasure. The pleasure in_the ha nd is treated as if it were worth two in tibe bush, even when the pleasure in the bush is as certain as that in the hand. This admission by itself makes a very large inroad into the apparently logical and coherent system of the hedonistic Psychology. Ethically it is of little importance, so long as the only characteristic which can give to one foreseen pleasure an increased attractiveness as compared with some other foreseen pleasure is supposed to be its greater proximity. But the admission may perhaps prepare the way for the recognition of the fact that there are other sources of (so to speak) differ- ential attractiveness in pleasures besides (i) expected intensity and (a) proximity. Let us emphasize the admission that has so far been made. It is admitted, we may assume, that foreseen greater intensity of pleasure does not always carry with it greater constraining power over the will. The human mind is not the mere impartial calculating machine which it is represented to be by the hedonistic Psychology in its most logical form. We have in fact recognized the existence of passion in the ' Not of course excluding the pleasure of the immediate act which in some cases is obviously the prominent element. Chap, ii, §i] PASSION 13 human soul, though at present we may be disposed to interpret passion as a mere liability to be more affected by a nearer than by a remoter pleasure. But is that a j)ossible explanation of the extraordinary motive power possessed at certain moments by one pleasure as compared with another which, upon a calm review, would be recognized as being of far greater intensity ? Take the case of an angry man. On a calm review of the pleasure of avenging some trifling or imagined slight (at the cost perhaps of some serious and clearly foreseen penalty), the man himself would usually be disposed to admit that the game was not worth the candle. The pleasure, he would admit, would not be worth the sacrifice of even a week's freedom and ordinary enjoyment of life. ' Yes,' it will be said, ' but then the prospect of this pleasure is near, its more clearly perceived intensity triumphs over a chaos of remote, indefinite, and indistinctly envisaged enjoyments such as might be pur- chased by self-restraint.' Well, at that rate, the offer of some other pleasure more intense and equally near should at once hold back the uplifted hand, and transform the angry counte- nance. Once assume that the attraction lies wholly in pleasure — that the man is indifferent to the kind of pleasure, except so far as ' kind of pleasure ' implies to him a difference of intensity — and this consequence must follow. But does it 1 The average wife-beating ruffian would probably admit on reflection that the pleasure of beating his wife on one particular occasion was not worth a pot of beer. But tender him the pot of beer when he is angry, and will the uplifted hand inevitably be lowered to grasp it ? ' No,' it will be said, ' this is what he would do if he calmly reflected ; but at such a moment he does not reflect ; his mind is so concentrated upon that one imagined pleasure that the other fails to obtain an entrance.' But why does he not reflect? The determination to reflect or not to reflect is just as much a voluntary action as the determination to strike or not to strike. And, if the hedonistic Psychology is right, this action must be itself determined by a calculation as to the greater pleasantness of reflection or non-reflection. If then a man gets angry and so fails to reflect upon the consequences of what he is doing, that must be, it would seem, 14 PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I because he has come to the conclusion that (in this particular case) non-reflection will be the pleasanter course. But what should lead him to such a conclusion? Experience? Are we then really prepared to say that a hot-tempered man is one who has been taught by experience to believe that at certain moments non-reflection upon the relative value of pleasures, necessarily involving the choice of pleasures which calm reflection would show to be of less intensity, is itself conducive to ob- taining the greatest amount of pleasure or at least of immediate pleasure ? If any one is really prepared to admit this analysis of passion, there is no more to be said. If he is not, he must concede that, even if we allow the object of choice to be always a pleasure, there is something which causes a man at times to prefer one pleasure rather than another, irrespective of its greater nearness or greater intensity. What is this something ? I know of no better way of expressing it than to say that the man desires one pleasure (assuming for the moment that it really; is pleasure which is desired) rather than another^. It is an ultimate fact that one desire is stronger than another^. The strength of the desire does not depend whoUy upon the intensity of the imagined pleasure. And in so far as it does not depend upon such imagined intensity, it is not really a desire for pleasure qua pleasure. If all that is desired is pleasure — as much of it as possible, and for as long as possible — it must be a matter of indifference to the man in what form (so to speak) his pleasure is served up to him, so long as he gets enough of it. But the existence of such passions as we have alluded to is by itself a sufficient proof that it is not pleasure in general but some particular kind of pleasure that is desired in such pases. Now ^ In so far, that is, as his impulses are sufficiently reflected upon to become desires. A large part of our habitual bodily movements are of course due to impulses which cannot be so described. The actions are voluntary only because they can be at once inhibited when any conflicting desire presents itself. Movements which are not voluntary even to this extent are not acts. ^ Of course the cause may lie in the man's physical constitution or in external influences ; but, as ex hypothesi we are dealing with voluntary actions, these causes lying outside consciousness can only influence him by producing an impulse to act within consciousness, i. e. a desire. Chap.ii,§i] THE GREAT HYSTERON-PROTERON 15 it seems clear that desire for a particular kind of pleasure is not really desire for pleasure and nothing else. Even if we supposed that pleasure was always part of his object, we should have to admit that the man desires not only pleasure but also a particular sort of pleasure, not necessarily thought of as more intense than other pleasures. Desire of pleasure then is not the only motive which is capable of inspiring action. And having got so far, we may be prepared to go a step further and admit that the desire of pleasure need not really be present at all. At least there need be no desire for anything which would be a pleasure apart from the fact that it is desired- The fact that a thing is desired no doubt implies that the satisfaction of the desire will necessarily bring pleasure. There is undoubtedly pleasure in the satisfaction of all desire. But that is a very different thing from asserting that the object is desired because it is thought of as pleasant, and in proportion as it is thought of as pleasant. The hedonistic Psychology involves, according to the stock phrase, a ' hysteron-proteron ' ; it puts the cart before the horse. In reality, the imagined pleasantness is created by the desire, not the desire by the imagined pleasantness. The truth is that to deny the existence of ' disinterested ' desires, i. e. desiresJoiLabieets, otker_Hiaa..g^ateat .aat iciBated ^leasure-i, destroys the possibility of accounting for nearly all our interests except those of a purely sensual character^. It is admitted on all hands that different people get different amounts of pleasure from the same external sources. Why so ? In the case of mere physical sensation we can account for the difference between man and man by differences of physical constitution. Whether a man likes port or champagne depends upon the ^ The phrase may also be used to mean desires for objects other ihan (^tip.'h own good, however understood, but I am here arguing with those who would idenffiy good and pleasure. It will be seen below that I regard the Psy- chology that is egoistic without being hedonistic as open to the same objections as the latter. ' Many even of these, as pointed out below, are not originally desires for pleasure, but they may be treated as such for ethical purposes in so far as the impulses or appetites are deliberately acted upon from a conviction of the pleasantness of indulgence. i6 PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I constitution, as modified by education, of his palate and nervous system. It has nothing to do with the strength of any pre-existing impulse towards the one or the other. His preference is not, in any direct and immediate way, determined by his character. Apart from the anticipated pleasure, he is perfectly impartial or unbiassed in his decision between the two wines. Nothing but experience of their comparative pleasantness determines his judgement as to which of them he will take, so far as no considerations of health, or economy, or the like may dictate the choice of one rather than the other ^. Suppose a glass of champagne to be administered to a life-long teetotaller and called a glass of lemonade. He may have been wholly innocent of a desire for champagne ; he may have habitually denounced it as liquid poison; all his anticipations may have been confined to the unexhilarating lemonade. And yet, given the requisite nervous organization, he will probably exclaim, ' Why, this is the very best lemonade that I have ever tasted in the whole course of my life I ' On the other hand, when we turn to moral, intellectual, or other ideal pleasures ^, we find that their attractiveness depends entirely upon their appealing to some pre- existing desire, though no doubt some accidental and undesired experience may sometimes awaken a desire not previously felt. To the mind that does not desire knowledge, knowledge is not pleasant ; knowledge compulsorily admitted is often found to be productive of anything but pleasure. Benevolence does not give pleasure to people who are not benevolent. The psycho- logical Hedonist analyses Benevolence into a liking for benevolent * Of course he might be moved by curiosity to desire a wine which he had never tasted ; but the pleasure which he got from gratifying his curiosiiy would be distinguishable from the physical pleasure of drinking. The former would be undiminished should the wine fail to commend itself to his palate. " I am of course far from attempting to draw an absolute line of de- marcation between the two classes of pleasure. Pursuits involving a high degree of intellectual activity may often owe some of their pleasantness to some suggestion of sensuous gratification : the desire for power may become fused with the desire for the sensual gratifications secured by power, &c., &c. And on the other hand the sensuous pleasure may be a condition of many others which are not sensuous. Coleridge, for instance, pronounced tea- drinking to be the most intellectual of sensual pleasures. Chap, ii, §i] DISINTERESTED DESIRES 17 pleasure. No doubt to the benevolent man Benevolence does give pleasure, but it gives him pleasure only because he has previously desired the good of this or that person, or of mankind at large. Where there is no such desire, benevolent conduct is not found to give pleasure. And so with many bad pleasures : for it is extremely important to insist that disinterested desires are not necessarily good desires ^. If I have set my heart upon the death of an enemy, it will give me pleasure to kill him. Apart from such a desire, there is nothing in the mere physical process which could possibly account for the pleasure. It would be no pleasure at all to kill some other person by precisely the same means^ unless indeed my desire is not a desire for vengeance but a disinterested malevolence towards humanity in general ^. In all such cases it is a certain idea which is pleasant, the idea of an object which is or may be something quite different from my own sensations, whether of a purely physical character or of any more exalted kind which a hedonistic Psychology may be able to recognize. It is not the representation of my being pleased in the future which makes the idea of the sick man relieved or of the wrong avenged pleasant to me, and so moves my will ; my desire is that the actual objective result shall be achieved. Of course if I am to be influenced by such a desire, I must, as we say, 'take an interest' in the desired object. So far every, desire might no doubt be called an ' interested ' desire. But the ^ The observation of this fact was Bishop Butler's most original contribu- tion to moral Psychology. Aristotle admits that there are desires for objects other than pleasure, but he assumes that these objects are always good objects— Knowledge, Beauty, Virtue, and the like, and thus ultimately admits only two motives, desire of to koKov and of to ^Sii. " The pleasure of sheer cruelty is no doubt less purely ' ideal ' than that of vengeance, and may be more correctly represented as a mere desire for a particular kind of physical excitement, which gives pleasure just like any otber sensation. It may best be treated as a primitive instinct, just like the impulses commonly described as appetites — a survival in human nature of the brute, in which such an instinct was conducive to survival. But, like these appetites, cruelty of course becomes something different in a man who deliberately makes the satisfaction of the impulse his end. A beast is not capable (strictly speaking) of cruelty any more than it is capable of licentiousness. When deliberately indulged, the impulse or appetite becomes a desire. BASBDALI. X t8 psychological HEDONISM [Book I question at issue is just this— whether I am capable of taking an interest in other things besides my own sensations, actual in the present or imagined as being enjoyed by me in the future. To deny that I am capable of taking such an interest would make it scarcely possible to explain how anything could please me except purely physical sensations, an interest in which is, so to speak, compulsory. The pleasantness may no doubt be stimulated by an eflFort of voluntary attention, or diminished by a voluntary efiFort of abstraction, which will usually take the form of voluntary attention to something else. But it does not rest with us — it does not depend upon our will, or our character, or our desires — whether we shall or shall not feel the sensations and feel them to be pleasant. It is extremely important to insist upon the full extent of ground covered by this class of ' disinterested desires.' A pre- judice is sometimes created against the doctrine of disinterested desires just on account of its ethical import. The greater part of our desires are assumed to be ' interested,' and in asserting some few of them to be 'disinterested,' we are suspected of trying to introduce questionable exceptions in the interests of edification. It is, therefore, desirable to insist that the possi- bility of being 'interested' in something besides our own sensations is as distinctly implied by the momentary absorption in the plot of a novel, or the most evanescent and morally in- difierent sympathy with its characters, as by the most sublime heroism or the most systematic philanthropy. The spectator of a tragedy who had no ' disinterested desires ' would simply exclaim, ' What is Hecuba to me, or I to Hecuba, that I should weep for her 1 Prove to me that my own future pleasures are somehow involved in the fate of Hecuba, and then I shall begin to be interested in her story, but not till then.' No pleasures in short are explicable on the hypothesis of psychological Hedonism except those of a purely sensual character, and I may add, aesthetic pleasures, which after all have a purely sensuous basis, however many higher intellectual activities and sympathies may be involved in them. When a beautiful landscape bursts upon us unexpectedly, the enjoyment of it is not dimmed by the fact that we were not craving for it beforehand. Nor does it appear Chap.ii, §i] AESTHETIC PLEASUKES 19 that a craving for beauty in general precedes or is implied in the first development of the aesthetic faculties ; it is rather experience of their pleasantness which begets the love of beauty. For, although beauty is not merely a particular kind of pleasure, the pleasure is certainly an inseparable element of the beauty, and this pleasure does not seem to imply any previous desire ^. But directly Art begins to involve anything more than the con- templation of immediately beautiful form and colour and sound ^, it interests us only by appealing to desires or interests which are not merely desires for pleasure. A man who cared about nothing but his own sensations might derive pleasure from a beautiful sunset, but he could hardly appreciate a beautiful character or a beautiful plot, and even the appreciation of physical beauty probably has its roots to some extent in a kind of sympathy, however strongly we may repudiate Hume's attempt to analyse away our appre- ^ There is much truth in Schopenhauer's doctrine that the satisfaction afforded by Art is due (I should say, partly due) to the absorption in mere contemplation which it involves, and so in the temporary suspension of desires. ^ And even these could not be desired unless they had previously been experienced. There would indeed be a shorter way with psychological Hedonism if we could assume with Prof. A. B. Taylor that ' an appeal to intro- spection will show . . . that it is impossible to have a representative image or idea of pleasure or pain ' {Problem of Conduct, p. 113). So far as I have been able to ascertain, Prof. Taylor appears to be alone in this peculiar incapacity for imaging past pleasures and pains. The theory implies so extreme an abstraction of the content of the pleasant consciousness from its pleasantness that it hardly requires explicit experience to refute it. If Prof. Taylor cannot remember what the displeasure was like which it gave him to look upon his neighbour's ugly wall-paper, how can he remember even what the paper itself was like ? How can he have an idea of the colour and pattern without an idea of its ugliness, and what is an idea of ugliness which does not include unpleasantness ? The reason why the more acute physical pains are (fortu- nately) less capable of being represented with distinctness in imagination seems to be that, though assuredly not without content, they have (so to speak) very little content. There are comparatively few distinct kinds of qualities of pain, and still fewer have names ; so that the distinction of intensity plays the chief part in our idea of them, and intensity is just the element in which imagination most fails, accurately or fully, to reproduce past sensations, though it reproduces them quite sufficiently to enable a boy to pronounce (when the difference was considerable) which of two floggings hurt most. This is of course quite a different thing from supposing (with Hume) that an ' idea ' differs from an ' impression ' only in liveliness. C 3 ao PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I ciation of the elegance of a swan's long neck into sympathy with its utility to the swan. Any further analysis of aesthetic pleasure would here be out of place. I merely note that the aesthetic pleasures, or an element in them, seem to be the most prominent case of pleasure, not in the ordinary sense purely sensual, which does not necessarily imply desire for anything besides the pleasure itself^. II I have so far confined myself to the motives operating upon the consciousness of adult human beings at an advanced stage of development. I shall hereafter have to consider how far the facts of Evolution can throw any light upon our ethical ideas ; and it is of the last importance to keep questions of psychological fact distinct from questions of psychological origin. The starting- point of any enquiry into the origin or history or explanation of our ideas, desires, motives or any other facts of consciousness must be a clear comprehension of what these facts are now in that developed human consciousness which alone is accessible to direct observation. Into questions of origin and history, there- fore, I do not propose to enter now in any detail. But it is hardly possible to deal efiectively with the theory of psychological Hedonism without noticing that its plausibility lies for many minds in a certain confusion between the question of origin and the question of actual present fact. It is constantly assumed as a sort of axiom that ' Altruism ' must have in some way been evolved out of Egoism ; and this assumption often carries with it the further implication that in some sense Altruism is thereby shown to be Egoism after all, only more or less disguised. It is not surprising that pre-evolutionary individualists like John Stuart Mill should have supposed that primitive men and the lower animals were pure Egoists. But it is amazing to discover the same delusion more or less underlying the treatment of this subject by the very writer who, whatever may be thought of his system as a whole, has at least the merit ^ I do not mean to imply that the value of aesthetic pleasures is to be estimated merely by their intensity, or that the desire for aesthetic pleasures (when once aroused) is merely a desire for pleasure as such. Chap, ii, §ii] PRIMITIVE MAN NOT AN EGOIST 21 of having been the first among Darwin's disciples to suspect that Darwinian ideas might throw important light upon many psychological and sociological phenomena ^* If there is one thing which the Darwinian doctrine of Evolution has emphasized in the psychological region, it is the existence in animals and in primitive men of tendencies, impulses, instincts, of whose self- preserving or race-preserving efficacy they themselves are quite unconscious. We have hitherto sought our illustrations of impulses that are not mere desires of pleasure in desires which might be considered as, in a sense, above the moral or at least above the intellectual level of pleasure-seeking. It is quite equally certain that there are in animals, in primitive men, and in infants at an advanced stage of social development (to say nothing of adults), impulses that are below that level ^. The human or other infant does not suck because experience has convinced it that sucking is a source of pleasure. It does not first suck by accident, and then repeat the action because it has found sucking pleasant, though this last discovery may no doubt aid in inducing it to suck in the right place. It sucks simply because it has an impulse to suck. The Physiologist may know why it sucks ; but the child does not. The young bird does not tap the inside of its shell because it has calculated that the breaking of that shell is a con- dition precedent to the enjoyment of wider pleasures than are possible to it in the limited sphere of its early experiences; it taps for no other reason than that it has an impulse to tap. The beaver that has been in the habit of collecting sticks to build its habitation wiU go on collecting sticks when its house is ready built for it. The young elephant does not attack the aggressor because experience has convinced it that that is the best way of avoiding aggression, and the painful consequences of aggression, in the future ; it attacks because it is angry. No doubt in all these cases the gratification of the impulse does in fact give ^ The assumption is nowhere distinctly formulated, but it seems to under- lie the argument of Mr. Herbert Spencer's Psychology, Pt. II, ch. ix, and Data 0/ Ethics, ch. V sq. * For a fuller refutation of the theory that the lower animals or primitive men or human infants act or behave on egoistic Hedonist principles the reader may be referred to the whole later part of Wundt's Ethics and to Prof. James's chapter on 'Instinct' in his Principles of Psychology (ch. xxiv.). 2% PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I pleasure, or at least the resistance to the impulse would be found painful. And the experienced pleasure or relief from pain undoubtedly stimulates the animal to the continued performance of the acts. Moreover, in some cases the impulses which are now blind and unreflecting may have originally in some remote ancestor been .purposeful ; but the fact remains that the actual stimulu^to the present act is not a mere anticipation of pleasure: the pleasure only comes because there is a pre-existing impulse. Striving of some kind or other is as primitive a factor in all consciousness as feeling^. It is quite true that normally not only is the satisfaction of the impulse itself a pleasure, but the instincts of an animal tend for the most part to prompt actions which are pleasurable on the whole. An instinct which brought immediate pain would tend to disappear, and an animal whose instincts on the whole did not bring it pleasure would tennd to disappear also. But these tendencies are by no means always realized, and require to be stated with many qualifications. The moth would no doubt find it painful to resist the impulse which draws it to the candle : but still it is probable that on the whole it does not find it pleasant to be burned alive. The instinct does not tend to promote survival, and yet the moth survives. Many of the instincts or impulses of animals are not self- preserving but race-preserving, and these are often sources of immediate pain and danger to the animal itself. The most obvious instance is the maternal instinct which often leads an animal to brave obvious pain or danger for the sake of its young. And among the higher and more gregarious animals there are often found not merely the blind impulses of anger and aggression ^ Some Psychologists would say more primitive. But I see no advantage in attempting to identify conscious impulses with unconscious tendencies towards an end such as may exist in plants, however decidedly these may differ from merely mechanical processes. Even Mr. Spencer does recog- nize that race-preserving actions not conducive to the pleasure of the in(£- vidual are as primitive as individual-preserving actions. That admission cuts away the ground of his assumption that individual-preserving actions are always prompted by a desire of pleasure. To identify ' cravings ' with ' dis- comforts ' which inspire a desire for their- removal {Principles of Psy- chology, § 123) tends to disguise the hysterotirproteron of the Pleaaure- psyohology. Chap, ii, § ii] INSTINCT 23 which do actually preserve individual and race alike, but instincts which lead them to face easily avoidable perils and pains in defence of the herd. How far these instiijcts are due to ' lapsed intelligence,' how far to natural selection, how far to direct adaptation, how far they may require the hypothesis of a final causality which resists further physiological explanation, are questions with which we are not now concerned. , The only point that has here to be emphasized is that the conscious actions of infants or animals are as little explicable by the theory of psychological Hedonism as those of the hero or the saint. The impulses are not desires for a particular imagined pleasure, still less for a greatest possible quantum of pleasure upon the whole. This last aim would imply a power of reflection and abstraction wholly beyond what we have any reason to believe to be possible in an animal or even a not very primitive man. The theory of psychological Hedonism is therefore not entitled to any advantage which it might derive from presenting us with a true account of the historical origin of our present human experience. Altruism was not developed out of Egoism ; though, if it were, that would not disprove the existence of Altruism now. Men and animals have always had both race-preserving and self-preserving in- stincts. Altruism in the developed human beings is evolved out of social and race-preserving instincts : Egoism out of self -pre- serving instincts. Both in their human form involve an intellectual development of which the lower animals are incapable. The question may be raised whether these instincts or impulses which we have distinguished from ' disinterested desires ' in the stricter sense do not exist even in developed humanity ? They certainly exist in the human infant : do they in the adult man ? The answer seems to be that these impulses do certainly exist. It is perhaps better not to follow Bishop Butler in classing hunger with such disinterested desires as Benevolence or even Vengeance '. Hunger is neither a desire for the pleasure of eating, nor (in its less acute forms) a desire to avoid the pains of ^ Sidgwick follows him in this view {Methods of Ethics, 6th Ed., p. 45). Prof. Mackenzie seems to me right in distinguishing appetites from desires {Manual of Ethics, 4th Ed., p. 46). See also the chapter in James's Psychology already referred to (above, p. 21, note). 24 PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I inanition : but it is not quite the same thing as a disinterested desire of food for food's sake. It is simply an impulse to eat. But then the human being has a power which the animal has not, or a greater power than the animal possesses, of reflecting on these impulses of his, and presenting their satisfaction to himself as an object of thought and of encouraging them or resisting them accordingly. So long as the impulse is a physically irresistible impulse, as when a man closes his eyes or ducks his head to avoid an unexpected missile, that is mere ' reflex action ' ; that is to say, the act is not in the moral sense of the word an act at all. The impulse is not, properly speaking, a ' motive.' But in so far as the impulse can be inhibited, in so far as the impulse is reflected on and its object deliberately conceived by the understanding and adopted by the will, the mere instinct or impulse passes into what we ordinarily call a desire, and (in so far as the desire is not merely a desire for the imagined pleasure of satisfaction) a ' disinterested desire.' And therefore from an ethical point of view the distinction between appetites and instinctive desires or 'desires of objects' becomes of comparatively little importance — of com.paratively little importance, though it may for some purpose be important to remember that an action prompted by impulse or appetite or instinct, even where not actually involuntary, may be far less voluntary than one which flows from the conscious and deliberate desire for an object clearly presented to the mind. There are no hard and fast lines to be drawn in this matter. In the developing race and in the growing child reflex action passes by imperceptible gradations into instinctive action, and instinct into voluntary action motived by desire. So in the adult human individual there is every stage between the purely reflex action and the fully premeditated and deliberate act; but it would seem that, though there are instincts, there are here no purely instinctive acts in the strict sense of the word except those which are wholly involuntary. The instinct which has been reflected on and has not been inhibited, may be treated as a desire— for pleasure or some other object, as the case may be, and the resulting act is no longer in the strict sense of the word merely instinctive. Chap, ii, § iii] DOCTRINE OF MILL 35 III The course of our argument has already touched upon the question of diflferences in quality among pleasures. We have already seen that, even upon the assumption that what is desired is always pleasure, it is in many cases clear enough that it is not pleasure in general that is desired but some particular kind of pleasure, and we have already attempted to show that such an admission really surrenders the whole hedonistic doctrine. If people do as a matter of fact desire pleasures for other reasons than their greater intensity, it is clearly possible that the superior ethical quality or rank or dignity of the pleasure may be one of the determining factors in their choice. That this is so has often been admitted by high-minded Hedonists who have not seen how fatal is the admission to the whole doctrine that what they desire is always pleasure as such. We may take for instance the well- known passage of John Stuart Mill : — ' It is quite compatible with the principle of utility to recognise the fact, that some kinds of pleasure are more desirable and more valuable than others. It would be absurd that while, in estimating all other things, quality is to be considered as well as quantity, the estimation of pleasures should be supposed to depend on quantity alone. 'If I am asked, what I mean by difference of quality in pleasures, or what makes one pleasure more valuable than another, merely as a pleasure, except its being greater in amount, there is but one possible answer. Of two pleasures, if there be one to which all or almost all who have experience of both give a decided preference, irrespective of any feeling of moral obliga- tion to prefer it, that is the more desirable pleasure. If one of the two is, by' those who are competently acquainted with both, placed so far above the other that they prefer it, even though knowing it to be attended with a greater amount of discontent, and would not resign it for any amount of the other pleasure which their nature is capable of, we are justified in ascribing to the preferred enjoyment a superiority in quality, so far outweigh- ing quantity, as to render it, in comparison, of small account ^,' ' Utilitarianism, pp. 11, 12. a6 PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I Mill's psychological analysis here leaves little to be desired, bufc_^ he failed ta^ee that a desire for superior quality of pleasure is not really^a desire for pleasure. If I drink a particular wine for the sake of pleasure, I of course care for the quality of the wine — its taste, bouquet, body, exhilarating properties and the like, in so far as these conduce to pleasure. But so far only. I should give it up the moment that I found a pleasanter wine at the same price and with equally hygienic properties, except in so far as oc- casional variety may be itself a source of pleasure. If, therefore, I care about philanthropic pleasure merely as pleasure, I should necessarily give it up and take to the pleasures of an animal if I were only satisfied of their superior pleasantness. This is just what, according to Mill, the wise man will not do : ' few human creatures would consent to be changed into any of the lower animals, for a promise of the fullest allowance of a beast's pleasures ^.' He admits therefore that such a man desires some- thing other than pleasure. What makes him think the pleasures of the intellect superior to those of a beast is not their intensity as pleasures but their superior nobleness or moral elevation. And that is a consideration which can only appeal to a man who cares about nobleness or moral elevation. Strictly speaking, pleasures do not diflFer in quality, but only in quantity. Or, to be entirety accurate, pleasure varies only in quantity. In ordinary language we mean by a pleasure a total state of consciousness which is pleasant. But no man's conscious- ness at any one moment can be full of pleasure and nothing else. There must be something there — a taste or a smell, a perception or a thought, an emotion or a volition — to be pleasant. A man who should for a single instant have nothing in his mind but pleasure would be an impossible variety of idiot: for this would imply that he was pleased at nothing at all. The pleasure then of this or that moment of consciousness is an abstraction ; it can never exist by itself so long as pleasure is understood to mean the mere quality of pleasing. Very different contents of consciousness — the most purely animal sensation or the loftiest moral purpose — may have this common quality of pleasing ; but, so long as they are compared merely in respect of this one ' 1. 0., p. 12. Chap, ii, § iv] AMBIGUITIES 27 characteristic, they can only differ in one way — in respect of the intensity or quantity of this pleasingness ; the pleasure varies in degree, not in kind. All this tends to 8ho\f haw completely the admission of qualitative differences in pleasure abandons the hedonistic point of view. As a popular mode of expression, the doctrine that pleasures differ in kind is a true and useful formula ; but it should be recognized that this is not Hedonism. For it means precisely this — that we ascribe value or worth to states of consciousness for other reasons than their pleasantness, although a certain measure of pleasantness might be a character- istic of all states of consciousness which are capable of being desired. IV It should be distinctly . understood that the question with which we are at present concerned is a purely psychological one. It is a mere question of fact, and can only be answered by each man for ^himself after careful observation and analysis of what ' goes on in his own mind, aided by observation of what goes on in other people's minds, in so far as that is revealed by word and act. All that any writer can do towards helping another person to perform this process is (a) to state the question clearly and to warn him against the ambiguities of language which are the main source of error upon such subjects ; (b) to remind him of some of the facts which the hedonistic theory has got to explain, and to ask him whether that explanation is adequate ; and (c) to state clearly and fully the elements of truth which that theory holds in solution, and to show that a recognition of such elements of truth does not carry with it the inferences which the Hedonist draws from them. I have already attempted to perform the first of these tasks, and have made some siiggestions towards the second. But before proceeding to the third, I should like to call attention to some of the more extreme cases of disinterested desire which the theory before us has got to explain away, though I have already tried to show that its failure is quite as apparent in the case of very ordinary impulses to action which are of no special significance from an ethical point of view. The palmary instance of this failure may perhaps be found in 38 PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I cases where a man labours to accomplish a result which he knows cannot be achieved till he is dead and no longer able to enjoy it. Such instances occur not only in the ease of heroic self-sacrifice for a political or religious faith, or the less heroic but no less altruistic efforts of parents to provide for their children, but in the case of many desires which in the ordinary, ethical sense of the word would commonly be described as selfish enough. How is the hedonistic Psychologist to explain the vulgarest desire on the part of some recently ennobled brewer to ' found a family,' or the desire of posthumous fame — say for instance, the kind of literary vanity or ambition which has had so large a share in inspiring the life-work even of men like Hume and Gibbon ? i It will be urged that the man who is influenced by such motives ( acts as he does because the thought of being talked about afterl his death gives him pleasure now. Exactly so ; the thought of it gives him pleasure ! But that is just what the hedonistic Psychology declares to be an impossibility. According to this system nothing that is present merely in thought can give pleasure except the thought of a future pleasant state of the man's own consciousness. Being talked about after my death is not a future state of my own consciousness ^ ; and therefore the thought of it can, according to the theory, give me no pleasure now. Once again we have the old hysteron-proteron — the cart before the horse. The hedonistic Psychology explains the desire by the pleasure, whereas in fact the pleasure owes its existence entirely to the desire. The difficulty reaches its climax in the case of an atheistic martyr, who, with no belief in a future life, dies in furtherance of an object which cannot be realized till he will (according to his own view) no longer be able to enjoy it. Or, if we choose (however illogically ^) to explain his conduct by the desire of enjoying the moments of triumph which may elapse between his ^ In such cases we may ignore the belief in Immortality. Even where such a belief is strong and influential, it probably does not occur to a man to think of himself as hereafter enjoying the contemplation of his great- grandchildren seated on the red benches of the House of Lords, or smiling down upon his own statue in the market-place of his native town. " Since this sense of triumph really implies that he is capable of looking forward with satisfaction to a result other than his own pleasure. Chap.ii, §iv] PLEASURES OF MARTYRDOM 29 resolution to die and the execution of his sentence, we may put a case where this interval is non-existent. Supposing a con- demned man, disbelieving in a future lif e^ to be told that by holding up his finger just before the guillotine fell he would save the life of a dearly loved child or confer some inestimable benefit on the whole human race. On the hedonistic theory even such a minimum degree of benevolence would be a psychological impossibility. For one who knew that the act would be syn- chronous with the termination of his own consciousness, there would be no future consciousness the imagined pleasantness of which could possibly supply a motive for the present act. If it be contended that the moment of consciousness in which the act is performed is itself pleasant, the whole point is conceded. For it is admitted that volitions are rendered pleasant to us in con- templation, and so are called into actual being, on account of future effects other than a pleasant state of one's own conscious- ness. The only way of escape would be to contend that the act of lifting up a finger would have seemed pleasant to the man apart from the efiects which it was to have after his death. But in normal circumstances the holding up of a finger would give no pleasure at all. One last skulking-place of psychological Hedonism may be briefly noticed, though this represents a form of the error which rarely imposes upon any but very young students of Ethics. At a certain stage of reflection egoistic Hedonism is often made to present itself in an extremely amiable and even edifying light by including among the pains and pleasures which determine the morality of an action the pains and pleasures of Conscience. Nothing can be more beautiful, it is suggested, than to do my duty simply because I like it. There can be no more efiicient sanction and guarantee of Morality than the happiness which experience shows invariably to follow in its train. I will not here examine whether the pains and pleasures of Conscience are as a matter of psychological fact so intense as Moralists have sometimes found it convenient to assume. It is probable that, as regards minor kinds of wrong-doing, in persons of average conscientiousness, the pains of Conscience have been greatly exaggerated. If moral obligation were to be based solely upon 3° PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I this ground, the cynical advice to make one's moral standard as low as possible in order that one may occasionally enjoy the luxury of living up to it would have something to be said for it. But, be this as it may, be the pleasure of right-doing and the pains of wrong-doing great or small, these pleasures and pains are only explicable on the assumption of the existence now or in the past, in the man himself or in others, of desires for something besides pleasure. When the pleasure arises from the person's own purely introspective satisfaction in his own morality or victory over temptation or the like, we have simply another case of the pleasure attending the satisfaction of all desire. The attempt to explain this away is another instance of the old hysteron-proteron. In other cases there may, indeed, be no desire — at least in any conscious and explicit form — for the performance of duty or the happiness of others for its own sake in the individual himself, and yet the doing of the right act may be a source of pleasure or more probably the doing of the wrong one a source of pain. The pleasure in the act, or the pain in its omission, may be due to a habit formed under the influence of other motives. Or pleasure may have come to be associated with the act, and pain with its omission, through the influence of a public opinion which is itself based upon an approval or disapproval not arising from any hedonistic calculus, and which influences the individual quite apart from any anticipated con- sequences of the public feeling. To attempt to justify (on hedonistic principles) the performance of certain acts commonly called moral by their pleasantness, and then to explain their pleasantness by assuming that they are moral and so sources of conscientious pleasure or means of avoiding conscientious pain, is to argue in a circle. The pleasantness of the act is explained by its morality, and its morality is explained by its pleasantness. It is admitted that the act is often such as could not produce the attainable maximum of pleasure apart from its being regarded as moral ; but, according to the hedonistic Psychology, it could never have come to be regarded as moral except through an experience which showed that apart from the opinion of its morality it was already the way to obtain the greatest maximum of pleasure. The consciousness which can take pleasure in an Chap, ii, §v] ELEMENTS OF TRUTH 31 action because it is right is not a consciousness that cares about nothing but pleasure. If it has not risen to the level of a dis- interested love of duty, or of tribe or family gr individual person, it must at least be capable of being affected by a desire of social approbation, or other social impulses and interests, which are just as difl&cult to account for on the hypothesis of egoistic Hedonism as the love of duty for its own sake, and which generally imply more definitely 'disinterested' desires on the part of the com- munity by which the opinion that the act is right has been created. Even if the community is supposed to approve or disapprove merely from self-interest, the community's disappro- bation would bring no loss of pleasure to a consciousness that cared not for disapprobation ^. Moralists like Mandeville, and in a more refined way Hume, have a tendency to reduce the motive of moral conduct to a kind of vanity. But vanity is as good an instance as could be found of a disinterested desire, when it rises above the level of that gregarious instinct which is shared by the lower animals, and which after all is equally proof against the hedonistic analysis. I shall now attempt, even at the risk of some repetition, to state what appear to me the elements of truth contained in the theory of psychological Hedonism, and to guard against some of the exaggerations on the other side which have sometimes helped to secure acceptance for that position. (i) The gratification of every desire necessarily gives pleasure in actual fact, and is consequently conceived of as pleasant in idea before the desire is accomplished. That is the truth which lies at the bottom of all the exaggerations and misrepresentations of the hedonistic Psychology. The psychological Hedonist ex- plains the martyr's death by a taste for the pleasures of martyr- dom. Undoubtedly a martyr must derive pleasure from the thought of dying for a holy cause, and even in the midst of the flames the thought that he is doing something for that cause * Of course, when any ulterior consequence of social approbation is to be feared, we should not speak of the person as acting from purely conscien- tious motives at all. 3% PSYCHOLOGICAL HEDONISM [Book I must, presumably, so long as it actually remains in his conscious- ness, give him some pleasure. But you cannot account for his action by that pleasure (waiving for the moment our objection to the hysteron-proteron), unless you contend that the pleasure involved in the gratification of the desire is greater in amount than the pains involved, and foreseen to be involved, in the process of achieving that gratification. The thought of the purpose accomplished or the cause assisted may no doubt, even in the moment of martyrdom, when abstracted from everything else in the man's consciousness, be pleasant ; but that is a very different thing from saying that the process of being burned alive, taken as a whole, is a pleasant one, and that the man suffers martyrdom because, upon a calm and impartial review, he thinks that the pleasure will predominate over the pain. His conduct implies that the thought of serving his cause must have had some peculiar attraction for him over and above the pleasant- ness which it shared with the rejected attractions of a happy and tranquil existence. Had it ever occurred to him to make the calculation, a man totally indifferent to the source or moral character of his pleasures would surely have found that the pleasures of living were greater than those of martyrdom ^ Aristotle saw this with peculiar clearness. The brave man, he tells us, finds pleasure in the exercise of courage ; yet the pleasure is so small in amount, when compared with the attendant pains, that the popular mind hardly notices that there is any pleasure at all in the dying warrior's last moments. On the whole, such a death seems painful, like the experience of the athlete fighting in the arena, though there too the contemplation of the prize and the glory to be achieved are no doubt sources of pleasure ^. ' We may here ignore the question of the nearness of the pleasure : for experience seems to show that, even if we gi'ant the delightfubiess of looking forward to heing burned alive, the prospect does not at all gain in attractive- ness when one comes closer to it. ^ Ethic. Nicomach. III. ix. 3 (p. 1117) Oi /n^v ciKKa ho^nev hv clvai to Kara Trjv avSpiiav rcXoy f)8v, irrA tS>v kv/cXo) &' a(j>aviiev(rei.) — that it is in short a delusion, not a reality ; and with that belief in the intrinsic value of goodness will go the theological beliefs that were based upon it. IV Let us see then exactly to what point the course of our argument has carried us. We have felt compelled by the very considerations that led us to regard the preference of other people's well-being to our own as rational, to treat such a preference on our part as intrinsically better even for our- selves. We have in fact (with Kant) recognized the existence of two prima facie rational ends — Virtue and Happiness, the latter being treated as part of the true well-being of man only in so far as is consistent with the predominance of Virtue. It has been objected, indeed, to such a position, both by Professor Sidgwick himself and by others, that such a position involves the admission of two heterogeneous and ' incommensur- 72 KATIONALISTIC UTILITAEIANISM [Book I able ' ends — Virtue and happiness. To this we may reply that the very ground on which we have felt bound to recognize Virtue as an end in itself compels us to regard it as an end superior in value to pleasure. Keason pronounces that there is an end which all human acts should aim at promoting, i. e. the general good, and that no state of a rational will can be regarded by Reason as good which is not directed towards that end ; and a will which did not regard the choice of the right as of superior value to pleasure would not be a will directed to that supreme end. The man who acted upon the hypothesis that his own virtue and his own pleasure possessed equal intrinsic value would not really be virtuous at all. The hypothesis is there- fore one which contradicts itself. And the principle that the will directed towards the good must be regarded as of more value than the agent's pleasure will equally compel us to regard the pleasure of others as an intrinsically valuable end only in so far as it is consistent with the like preference of the good to the pleasant in those others. In other words, pleasure can only be regarded as intrinsically valuable in so far as it is consistent with Morality. No doubt the ' dualism,' the absolute antagonism between the two ends, the impossibility of fusing them into a harmonious whole in which the sharp contrast between them is lost (so long as all pleasure is put on the same level and is regarded as something which Virtue must simply limit from the outside without modifying and transform- ing), may be a reason for suspecting that we have not yet reached an adequate and complete view of the elements con- tained in 'the good.' But there is no absolute logical contra- diction involved in such a position ; it is not open to the charge that the two ends or elements of the end are ' incommensurable.' Now, practically, the introduction of this principle — the principle that Virtue must be regarded as an element, and as the dominant element, in the good — will by itself do much to bring our view of the ethical criterion into harmony with ordinarily accepted moral ideas, and to remove some of the more glaring of the difficulties of Utilitarianism as commonly understood. For (i) the most glaring of all the inconsistencies between Utilitarianism and the deliverances of the ordinary. Chap, iii, § iv] QUALITY OF PLEASURE 73 unsophisticated moral consciousness, lies precisely in its refusal to recognize the intrinsic goodness of Virtue, (a) The inclusion of Virtue (which for the present we take to mean rational Benevolence ^} in our conception of the end allows us to exclude frora it excessive indulgence in the pleasures which we recognize as good in themselves, and also all pleasures which are incon- sistent with the predominance of Benevolence, e. g. the pleasures of cruelty. We shall not merely disallow them on account of their ' infelicific' effects, but we shall regard them as intrinsically worthless or bad, because they imply an indifference to the good: we shall condemn the man who voluntarily indulges his taste for them, even though accidentally (as in an arena, for instance, in which the combatants were condemned criminals) he might be able to indulge them in a way not immediately inconsistent with the public interest. (3) We shall attach a high intrinsic value to such pleasures as actually include a benevolent element, and a lower degree of intrinsic superiority to such pleasures as are actually conducive to the public good, though the public good may be no part of the motive of the person indulging in them. Under the first head we should include the actual pleasures of Benevolence or personal affection, and even to some small extent the pleasures of sociability and friendship in so far as these imply some degree of unselfish good-will to others. Under the second we should include the pleasures of ambition or emulation and the whole range of aesthetic and intellectual pleasures. In this way it would probably be possible to justify, on the whole, that preference for what are commonly called higher pleasures which is so clear an element of the ordinary moral consciousness; since it will be generally admitted that in the long run indulgence in social and intellectual pleasures is more beneficial in its indirect social effects than indulgence in mere sensual gratification or unintellectual amusement. But so far we have interpreted Virtue as including nothing but Benevolence, or rather Benevolence and (in due subordination thereto) Pru- dence ; we have admitted no ground for ascribing superior moral ^ In the sense of ' desire to promote pleasure on the whole, not excluding one's own pleasure in due proportion.' 74 RATIONALISTIC UTILITARIANISM [Book I value to one pleasure over another except its direct or indirect influence on the pleasure of others. It is now time to ask whether this limitation really corresponds to the deliverances of the moral consciousness. Is there no element in conscious- ness to which we should upon reflection ascribe intrinsic value except (i) Virtue in the sense of simple Benevolence and (a) Pleasure with a preference for social useful pleasures ? Is our conception of the sumimmi bonum, for a rational being limited to these two elements ? If his will invariably prefers (in case of collision) other people's pleasure to his own and if he enjoys as much pleasure as possible, should we say that a human being has all that it is reasonable for him to want ? Would a com- munity of simple people enjoying material plenty and inno- cent amusements in the utmost degree that is consistent with the predominance of the most intense and most universal love — the life for instance of some rude Moravian Mission Settlement — beautiful and noble as such a life might be, realize to the full our highest ideal of human life ? Would a community devoid of Letters, of Art, of Learning, of any intellectual cultivation beyond that low elementary school standard which might be regarded as absolutely necessary to Virtue and the enjoyable filling up of leisure — would such a state of society realize our ideal ? If it were certain (a by no means extreme supposition) that the communities which have approximated most nearly to this pattern have actually realized a higher average of enjoy- ment than has ever been attained in more ambitious societies, should we thereupon think it right to adopt an obscurantist policy, to burn down libraries and museums and picture galleries, and to repress all desires for knowledge and beauty which should soar above the standard indicated ? Do we not rather judge that such desires ought to be gratified, that in their gratification — nay, in the efibrt to satisfy desires which grow stronger with every partial satisfaction — lies one large element of true human good, one large source of its nobleness and its value ? And can such a conviction be based upon the extremely dubious calcula- tion that the pleasures resulting from such pursuits or produced by them in others are invariably intenser, when due allowance is made for the increasing susceptibility to pain which they Chap.iii, §iv] GOODS OF THOUGHT AND WILL 75 bring with them, than those attainable by the healthy and moderate pursuit of more animal satisfactions in due subordina- tion to the activities of social Morality 1 Should we really be prepared to condemn any study, say that of pure Mathematics, which could be shown to be less 'felicific' than Sciences and Arts of more immediate and obvious ' utility ' ? To all these questions I can only answer for myself, ' No.' Argument on questions of ultimate ends is impossible. All that I can do is to trace the further modifications which this admission of other ends besides Virtue and happiness will compel us to make in the system of rationalistic Utilitarianism, from which we have already diverged by making Virtue as well as happi- ness into an element, and the more important element, in our con- ception of the ultimate end. The view to which we have been led may be briefly expressed as follows. The human soul is a trinity. Consciousness includes three elements or aspects or distinguishable activities — Thought, Feeling, and Volition or (to use a more general term) Conation, each of which is unintel- ligible in entire abstraction or separation from the rest. There is a good state and a bad state of intellect, of feeling, and of will. The good consists in a certain state of all three of them. It may be true in a certain rough and popular sense that in thought and perhaps even in the good will, taken in absolute abstraction from the two others, we could discover no value at all, while in pleasure we could find such a value ^. That is the assumption upon which all Hedonism is based; and the assumption might perhaps be admitted, though we might refuse to admit the inferences based upon it, if we could attach any meaning to pleasure taken absolutely by itself. But it is often forgotten that there is no such thing as pleasure without a content, and this content, which makes the state of conscious- ness pleasant or unpleasant, is, at least in rational beings, dependent upon the other two aspects of consciousness. It is no doubt possible by an effort of abstraction to think only of the intensity of our pleasurable feelings without thinking of their content, and to make their value depend upon that intensity, but there is no ground whatever for assuming that 1 Cf. below, pp. 78, 153. 76 RATIONALISTIC UTILITARIANISM- [Book I we actually do so or ought to do so. In judging of the ultimate value of any state of consciousness we think of its content — of the state of desire and of will on the one hand and of intellect on the other, as well as of feeling, and of the content of feeling as well as of its intensity. Sometimes we pronounce a less pleasant state of consciousness to be more valuable than a more pleasant one because it involves an activity of the higher intellectual faculties, or because it represents the direction of the will to a higher good. Sometimes, no doubt, the dififerent parts of our nature represented by the trinity of thought, feeling, and will cannot all obtain equal satisfaction by the same course of action, and then we have to choose between a course which will satisfy one part of our nature and that which will satisfy the other; but the ideal good of men would include all three. It would include truth and activity of thought, pleasantness of feeling, and goodness of will. In what relation the goods predominantly connected with each of these elements of our nature stand to each other, we shall in some general way consider hereafter ^. It will be enough to say here that we have already recognized the supreme value of the good will, i. e. of the devotion of the will towards that which the moral consciousness recognizes as the good for humanity at large, that in the abstract we recognize the superior value of intellectual activities to mere pleasant feeling, while the superiority of certain states of pleasant feeling to others is largely due to their arising to a greater extent than others from the activity of the. two higher elements in our nature, the activity of the good will or of the intellect, or both. If we were to enter at greater length into the relation between the different parts or elements or activities of our nature, with which we have just been dealing, we should find ourselves involved in many difficult and important matters of psychological ' It -will be fully recognized that no one of them can actually exist in entire abstraction from the other. The good will, for instance, must include some pleasant feeling and some knowledge. Chap, iii, §v] PSYCHOLOGY OF ETHICS 77 controversy. Such psychological problems I wish in the present work to avoid in so far as their solution is not directly and immediately necessary for the purpose of Ethics. But by way of explaining my use of them, a few remarks may be added. I do not adopt the usage of those Psychologists who make feeling equivalent merely to pleasure and pain. Such a usage seems to imply an abstraction of the pleasure from its content, which is not what we really mean when we talk about feeling, and which tends to encourage the idea that we are interested in nothing but the hedonistic intensity of our consciousness apart from its content. By Thought or Reason I do not mean merely discursive thought to the exclusion of immediate perception, but the whole intellectual side of our consciousness ; I include in it every kind of awareness. Desire I regard as belonging to the conative or striving side of our nature, though it implies also, and cannot exist apart from, both the intellectual and the feeling side of it : we must know in some measure what we desire, and the desire is itself a state of feeling, though it is more. An emotion is simply a name for a kind of feeling, but the term is usually and properly reserved for those states of feeling which are not, and do not immediately arise from, physical sensations, but imply the existence of ideas and of those higher desires which are directed towards ideal objects. It is obvious that in these distinctions we are concerned with aspects of consciousness rather than with distinct and separable things or facts or 'states.' In some cases the distinction between them is clear and capable by an easy abstraction of a pretty sharp differentia- tion in our thought: in other cases they are simply the same thing looked at from a slightly different point of view. We have no difficulty for instance in distinguishing processes of mathematical calculation from the pleasant feeling by which they are accompanied in the mathematical mind, or the unpleasant feeling which those processes create in the unmathematical. On the other hand a simple perception of colour must be treated as an intellectual activity when we think of the recognized relation between the person or subject and his object, as a state of feeling when we think of it merely as a state of the subject and from the point of view of his interest in it. Similarly one 78 RATIONALISTIC UTILITARIANISM [Book I and the same desire may be looked upon simply as a particular state of the subject and so as feeling, or as involving the intel- lectual idea of an end, or again as a conative activity tending to realize that end. Further to illustrate both the distinctions between, and the inter-dependence of, these fundamental aspects of consciousness does not seem necessary to enable us to proceed with our ethical enquiry. All that need here be emphasized is that the value which we recognize in consciousness is not depen- dent upon any one of these aspects taken in absolute abstraction from another. The extremest Hedonist will find it impossible to attach a clear meaning to the idea of pleasure taken apart from all awareness that one is pleased, or of what one is pleased at ; the extremest Rigorist would find it difficult to say what would be the value of a good will which did not know what it willed and did not care whether it willed it or not. And the moral consciousness does not encourage us to approximate to any such feats of abstraction, even in so far as this may be possible. It pronounces its judgement upon the value of consciousness as a whole. For the purpose of weighing one good against another and choosing between them in cases of collision, it may often have to attempt a relatively complete abstraction of one aspect from another; but it does not pronounce that any aspect has exclusive value, or that the value of one aspect is to be estimated entirely without reference to the others, or that the good can be conceived of under any one of them. The man is Reason, Feeling, Will ; and the ideal state for man is an ideal state of all three elements in his nature in their ideal relation to one another. At this point it is probable that the reader who is inclined to utilitarian ways of thinking will be disposed to ask ' How do you know that knowledge is good, or (if you like so to express it) that the pleasures attending its pursuit and attainment are intrinsically superior to those of eating and drinking ? ' The answer must be, ' I do as a matter of fact so judge : I judge it immediately, and, so far, a priori : my Reason so pronounces : judgements of value are ultimate, and no ethical position, utilitarian or other, can rest on anything but judgements of value.' What is this, the reader is likely to exclaim, but sheer Intuitionism ? How far Chap, iii, §v] IS EGOISM RATIONAL? 79 I am prepared to accept this identification will appear from the next chapter ^. ' Tlie logical contradiction involved in Egoism has been powerfully argued by von Hartmann in his criticism of Nietzsche and Max Stirner (Ethische Studien, pp. 33-90). More recently Mr. Moore has incisively expressed the difficulty as follows : ' What Egoism holds, therefore, is that each man's happiness is the sole good— that a number of diflferent things are each of them the only good thing there is— an absolute contradiction ! No more complete and thorough refutation of any theory could be desired. Yet Professor Sidgwick holds that Egoism is rational,' a conclusion which he proceeds to characterize as ' absurd ' (Principia Ethica, 1903, p. 99). I should agree with him that the position is self-contradictory in a sense in which universalistic Hedonism is not, and that with all his subtlety Sidgwick failed altogether to escape what was really an inconsistency in- thought, even if he escaped an actual or formal contradiction. But to point out this logical contradiction does not seem to me quite so easy and final a way of refuting Sidgwick's position as it does to Mr. Moore for these reasons : (i) The Egoist with whom Professor Sidgwick is arguing would probably not accept Mr. Moore's (and my own) conception of an absolute objective good, though I should admit and have contended in this chapter that if he fully thought out what is implied in his own contention that his conduct is ' reasonable ' he would be led to that conception. (2) Sidgwick only admitted that the Egoist was reasonable from one point of view — reasonable as far as he goes, i. e. when he refuses to ask whether his judgements are consistent with what he cannot help recognizing as the rational judgements of other men, and limits himself to asking whether he can make his own judgements consistent with themselves from his own point of view. No doubt Sidgwick ought to have gone on to admit that this imperfectly reasonable point of view was not really reasonable at all, and to some extent he has done this in his last Edition. And (3) after all, even if we admit that the Egoist is unreasonable, there remains the question 'Why should he care to be reasonable?' It was largely the difficulty of answering this question on universalistic Hedonist principle which drove Professor Sidgwick to admit a ' dualism of the Practical Reason,' and I am not sure that the question has been very satisfactorily answered by Mr. Moore who, though he is no Hedonist, appears to be unwilling to give the good will the highest place in his scale of goods. CHAPTER lY INTUITIONISM By Intuitionism is usually understood the theory that actions are pronounced right or wrong a priori without reference to their consequences. According to one view it is supposed that Conscience, or whatever else the moral faculty may be called, pronounces on the morality of particular courses of conduct at the moment of action. This form of the doctrine has been styled by Professor Sidgwick unphilosophical Intuitionism, while he gives the name philosophical Intuitionism to the doctrine that what is intuitively judged to be right or wrong is always some general rule of conduct, from which the morality or immorality of this or that particular course of action must be deduced. According to the first view, Conscience is an ever-present dictator issuing detailed injunctions to meet particular cases as they arise : according to the second, Con- science is a legislator, whose enactments have to be applied to particular cases by the same intellectual process as is employed by a judge in administering an act of Parliament ^. Intuitionists ^ It is probable that many ' Intuitionists ' would hold a position mid- way between these extreme views. They would hold that some rules are intuitively discerned to be of absolute obligation, while in other cases the decision must be left to the intuitive judgement of the moment. It may be asked where we are to find examples of the Intuitionist presupposed by the Utilitarian polemics. To a large extent no doubt he is a man of straw set up to be knocked down again. It will generally be found that most of the writers usually associated with the name make larger admissions than the popular exponents or assailants of this view recognize as to the necessity of considering consequences and the paramount duty of promoting the general good properly understood. But it cannot be denied that Bishop Butler (especially in the Dissertation of Virtue) and Reid have approximated to this position. The writer who seems specially to have introduced the term ' intui- Chap.iv, §i] UNPHILOSOPHICAL INTUITIONISM 8i may further be divided into two classes according to the view which they take as to the nature of the faculty by which these a priori judgements are pronounced. 5y some Intuitionists this faculty is supposed to be Reason, by others a ' Moral Sense.' But the nature of the faculty involved in our moral judgements is one which can best be discussed when we have answered the easier preliminary question — ''Do we in practice, or can we reasonably, pronounce actions to be right or wrong without regard to their consequences, in so far as such consequences can be foreseen ? ' The belief described as unphilosophical Intuitionism in its wildest form is one which can hardly claim serious refutation. If it is supposed that the injunctions of the moral faculty are so wholly arbitrary that they proceed upon no general or rational principle whatever, if it is supposed that I may to-day in one set of circumstances feel bound by an inexplicable impulse within me to act in one way, while to-morrow I may be directed or direct myself to act differently under circumstances in no way distinguishable from the former, then moral judgements are reduced to an arbitrary caprice which is scarcely compatible with the belief in any objective standard of duty ; for it will hardly be denied that, if right and wrong are not the same for (the same individual on dififerent but precisely similar occasions, they can still less be the same for different persons, and all idea of an objective moral law disappears. It may of course be alleged that the circumstances of no two acts are precisely alike, but they may certainly be alike in all relevant respects. If it be said that Conscience will vary its judgement in accordance with the circumstances of the case, and that other men's Consciences in proportion to their en- lightenment will always pronounce the same judgements under tion ' as the note of a School is Eichard Price, but that -writer's admissions are so ample that he ends by virtually resolving all duties into Benevolence, understood in a non-hedonistic sense, and Justice. His Review of the princi- pal Questions and Difficulties in Morals (1769) I regard as the best work published on Ethics till quite recent times. It contains the gist of the Kantian doctrine without Kant's confusions. In this chapter it must be understood that I am criticizing a type of opinion and not any particular writer. RABHDALL 1 Gc 8 a INTUITIONISM [Book I similar circumstances, there must be some rule or principle by which it must be possible to distinguish between circumstances which do and circumstances which do not alter our duty, however little this rule or principle may be present in an abstract form to the moral consciousness of the individual. Granted, therefore, that the moral judgements may as a matter of psychological fact reveal themselves first and most clearly in particular cases (just as we pronounce judgements about particular spaces and distances long before we have consciously put geometrical prin- ciples into the form of general axioms), it must still, it would seem, be possible by analysis of our particular moral judgements to discover the general principles upon which they proceed. Analytical thought and philosophical language may be inade- quate for the accurate expression of the delicate shades and gradations of circumstance upon which, in complicated cases, our moral judgements actually depend ; but some approximation to this, some rough rules or principles of ethical judgement, ought, one would think, to be capable of being elicited from a wide comparative survey of one's own and other people's actual judgements. If this be denied, moral instruction must be treated as absolutely impossible. Now it may be quite true that in many ways ' example is better than precept,' not only on account of its emotional eflFect but even on account of the intellectual illumination supplied by a good man's conduct in presence of varying practical difficulties. It is true that the contemplation in actual fact or in recorded history of a good life may suggest ideals which no mere system of precepts, abstracted from particular applications, can adequately embody. A general rule is often best embodied in a concrete, typical case. The parable of the Good Samaritan has taught the true meaning of Charity more clearly as well as more persuasively than any direct precept that could be culled from the writings of Seneca or even from the Sermon on the Mount. But still there is a consensus among reasonable men that moral instruction of some kind — however vague, general, and inadequate to the complexities of actual life — is possible, desirable, and necessary. We do not say to a child who asks whether he may pick a flower in somebody else's garden, ' My good child, that depends Chap. iv,§i] CONSIDERATION OF CONSEQUENCES 83 entirely upon the circumstances of the particular case : to lay down any general rule on the subject would be a piece of unwarrantable dogmatism on my part : consult your own Con- science, as each case arises, and all will be well.' On the contrary, we say at once : ' You must not pick the flower : because that would be stealing,, and stealing is wrong.' Make any reserves you please as to the inadequacy of the rule, its want of definiteness, its inability to meet many problems of life, the necessity for exceptions and the like ; yet it must be admitted that if there be any one point about Morality as to which there is a consensus alike among all plain men and nearly all Philosophers ^ it is surely this — that general rules of conduct do exist. Morality cannot be reduced to copy-book headings, but copy-book headings we do and must have. Now, in proportion as all this is admitted, unphilosophical Intuitionism tends to pass into the philosophical variety of the Intuitionist creed and may be subjected to the same criticism. The strongest part of Sidgwiek's great work consists in its analysis of common-sense Morality. The loose statements of Intuitionists as to the clearness, certainty, adequacy, and self- evidence of the ordinarily received rules of conduct have never been subjected to so searching, so exhaustive, and so illuminating an examination. That task has been done once for all, and need not in detail be done over again. It will be enough in this place to exhibit in the barest outline the difiiculties which this mode of ethical thought has to confront : — (i) Granted the existence of intuitive tendencies to approve action of particular kinds, we may still ask why we should trust to blind unreasoning impulses which refuse to give any rational account of themselves. Granted the existence of such judgements as a matter of psychological fact, whence comes their validity 1 If it be said ' they are deliverances of moral Reason,' we may ask whether it can be really rational to act without some consideration of consequences ? What does rational conduct mean but acting with a clear conception of our ultimate ^ Some of Mr. Bradley's utterances in Ethical Studies and elsewhere seem to constitute the only exception known to me. This position will be further discussed in the last chapter of this work. 02 84 INTUITIONISM [Book I purpose or aim, and taking the means which seem best adapted to attain that end ? ' Look before you leap ' seems to be one of the clearest of all practical axioms : to act in obedience to every subjective impulse, even if it be prima facie an impulse arising from the higher part of our nature, would seem very like adopting as our maxim ' Leap before you look.' Of course there may be circumstances in which we have to leap after a very hurried and imperfect survey of the situation under penalty of being too late to leap at all, but some looking before leaping is as necessary in the most unexpected and agonizing crisis of the battle-field or the hunting field as in the leisured pomp and circumstance of formal athletic sports. (ii) The moral notions which have seemed equally innate, self-evident, and authoritative to those who held them have varied enormously with different races, different ages, different individuals — even with the same individuals at different periods of life. It will be unnecessary to illustrate at length the varia- tions of moral sentiment which have formed the main stock-in- trade of utilitarian writers from the days of John Locke to those of Herbert Spencer. We have been taught to honour our fathers and mothers : there have been races which deemed it sacred duty to eat them. Average Greek public opinion looked with favour, or at least indulgence, upon acts which are crimes in most civilized modern communities. Pious and educated Puritans could see no harm in kidnapping negroes or shooting Irishmen. The eminent evangelical clergyman John Newton pronounced the hours which he passed in the captain's cabin of a slaver, separated by a plank or two from a squalid mass of human misery of which he was the cause, to have been sweeter hours of divine communion than he had ever elsewhere known. Some virtues seem to be of very late development even among civilized races — religious toleration, for instance, and humanity towards animals. And so on, and so on. To beginners in Moral Philosophy these objections to In- tuitionism will usually present themselves as the strongest and most unanswerable. In truth perhaps they are the weakest. Neither the slow development of the moral faculty nor its unequal development in different individuals at the same level Chap, iv, §i] OBJECTIONS TO INTUITIONISM 85 of social culture forms any objection to the a priori character of moral judgements. We do not doubt either the axioms of Mathematics or the rules of reasoning, <43ecause some savages cannot count more than five ^, or because some highly educated classical scholars are incapable of understanding the fifth propo- sition of Euclid's first book. Some of us will even refuse to allow our belief in the objectivity of aesthetic judgements to be shaken because a Zulu will hold a picture upside down, because an uneducated bargee will often prefer some gaudy sign-board to an old Master, because the taste which pronounced Queen's College the only really satisfactory piece of Oxford architecture does not commend itself to that of the twentieth century, or because even among the most cultivated art critics of the present day there exist considerable differences of opinion. Intuitionists have no doubt shown a tendency to claim infalli- bility as well as authority for the moral judgements of the individual: but such a claim is by no means necessary to the extremest view of the arbitrary, unconsequential, isolated character of moral judgements. We may admit the validity of the principles of reasoning and of the axioms of Mathe=~ matics, although many men reason badly, and some cannot even count. Men's moral judgements may be intuitive, but they need not be infallible. Self-evident truths are not truths which are evident to everybody. There are degrees of moral illumination just as there are degrees of musical sensibility or of mathematical acuteness. Taken by themselves, the variations of moral judgement form a less serious objection to the intuitional mode of thought than those which follow, although it may be certainly contended that Intuitionism of the cruder kind cannot adequately account for these variations. (iii) Even when a certain intuition is actually found in all or most men of a certain race and age, the moral rule which it enjoins usually turns out upon examination to be incapable of exact definition. All, or nearly all, detailed moral rules have some exceptions, except indeed when the rule laid down tacitly excludes such exceptional cases. The rule 'Thou shalt do no * Assuming such to be the fact, as is sometimes alleged, though the truth may be that they have no words or other signs for higher numbers. 86 INTUITIONISM [Book I murder ' presents itself no doubt at first sight as a moral rule admitting of no exception ; but that is only because murder means 'killing except under those exceptional circumstances under which it is right to kill.' Now, even where there seems to be the fullest agreement, at least among men of developed moral nature, as to the main rules, it is frequently found to disappear as soon as we come to discuss the exceptions ; while even the same individual will often find that at this point his intuitions become indistinct or fail him altogether. And in practice it will nearly always turn out that the exception has been introduced from some consideration of consequences. Those who are most positive in maintaining a particular moral rule to be of self-evident and universal obligation independently of consequences, will generally shrink from applying it in certain extreme cases. Set forth to the Intuitionist in sufficient detail the appalling consequences of applying his rule, pile up the agony sufficiently, and there will almost always come a point at which he begins to be doubtful as to whether the rule applies, and a further point at which he is certain that it does not. ' Thou shalt do no murder ' ; but most men will admit that there are exceptional cases in which killing is no murder, and perhaps a very large majority would be got to declare that their intuitions were clear in excepting self-defence, war or at least lawful war, and judicial execution. But ask at what point killing in self-defence becomes lawful, what consti- tutes war or what constitutes lawful war, for what offences we may lawfully inflict death, at what point it becomes the duty of the individual to refuse to take part in an unrighteous campaign or to carry out an iniquitous sentence — and we find ourselves once again in a chaos of uncertainties. And observe exactly the point of the uncertainty: the uncertainty lies exactly in this — that no clear intuitions are forthcoming as to the exact moment at which it begins to be legitimate to take account of consequences. 'Thou shalt not kill except in self-defence, or by judicial sentence.' So much may perhaps be pronounced to be self-evident without reference to conse- quences. But if the established government absolutely refuses to protect person, property, or Morality, shall we never reach Chap, iv, § i] CONSEQUENCES 87 a state of anarchy such as will warrant the intervention of an extra-legal committee of public safety or vigilance association, and the summary execution of its sentences ? If only the foreseen consequences are bad enough, no one but an advocate of absolute non-resistance will fail to relax his severity, and the advocate of unlimited non-resistance is certainly not in a position to claim any general consensus in his favour. Now, if there be any point at which an apparent intuition has to give way before clearly foreseen ill consequences, how can we logically say that it can ever be right to exclude consideration of conse- quences ? We must at least examine the probable consequences of an act sufficiently to feel reasonably sure that it will have none of those extreme results which, it is admitted, would have the effect of suspending the moral rule upon which it is proposed to act. The only people who have really carried out the doctrine that apparently self-evident moral rules cannot be modified by the consequences, however socially disastrous, of disobeying them to anything like its logical results, are those who (like Count Leo Tolstoi) preach the doctrine of unlimited submission to force, unlimited giving to mendicants and the like. And here common-sense Intuitionism decidedly declines to follow. (iv) The above considerations may probably lead on to the reflection that after all some reference to consequences is really included in every moral rule. Indeed, you cannot really distinguish an act from its present or foreseeable consequences. The consequences, in so far as they can be foreseen, are actually part of the act. You cannot carry out any rule whatever without some consideration of consequences. You cannot obey the rule of Benevolence without asking whether giving money in the street really is Benevolence; and that depends upon whether it will actually have the effect of doing ultimate good to those to whom you give and others who may be affected by the expectation of similar assistance which your act creates. You cannot obey the command ' Thou shalt not kill ' without considering whether the trigger that you pull will actually discharge a bullet, how far the bullet is likely to travel, what it will meet with on the way, and (if it is likely to hit any one) 88 INTUITIONISM [Book I whether that person is on the point of shooting somebody else, or is a peaceable and inoffensive fellow-citizen. What would be the meaning of asking whether drunkenness would be wrong if it did not make a man incoherent in his talk, irrational in his judgements, unsteady in his gait, and irresponsible in his behaviour ? Drunkenness taken apart from all its consequences would not be drunkenness. Once admit that consequences must be considered at all, and it is arbitrary to stop at any particular point in the calculus of social effects. You are not really in a position to pronounce upon the morality of the act until you have the completest view that circumstances enable you to take of the whole train of events which will be started by your contemplated volition. Until you have formed that estimate of consequences, you do not really know what you are doing: at any point in the vast orbit of changes which spreads from every human action, like the widening ripple that radiates from a stone dropped into smooth water, it is always theoretically possible that some circumstance may be discovered which may remove the case from the category to which your moral rule refers. No doubt in practice it is often imperative that we should act without this elaborate investigation : but the very enquiry ' how long ought I to deliberate before I act ? ' is precisely one of those questions upon which it is impossible to discover any intuitive rule, containing no reference to the probable consequences — the consequences, that is to say, on the one hand of deliberating too much, and on the other of not deliberating enough. If there are cases in which our moral consciousness clearly bids us do something or other at once without thinking of consequences, it will be found that these cases are precisely those in which excessive deliberation would be likely to lead to harmful results. To stay and reflect upon all the consequences which might be expected to flow from obeying or resisting the impulse to plunge into the water after a drowning man would very rapidly place the former alternative out of the question ; to encourage the habit of prolonged deliberation in such cases would be to make gallant attempts at rescues few, and successful rescues fewer. It is therefore considered enough to justify the attempt that Chap, iv, §i] INCONSISTENT INTUITIONS 89 a man knows he is a good swimmer, that the sea is not ex- ceptionally rough, and that it is not certain that the attempt wiU fail. There are, of course, scores of»cases in which it is right to act on short deliberation : but it will probably be found, on analysis, that it is some consequence of allowing people to deliberate upon which the judgement is ultimately based. It is a commonplace of utilitarian Ethics that many things must be avoided altogether which might in exceptional cases have good eiFects just because exceptions, if admitted at all, would have a tendency to become too numerous ^. (v) Still more obviously does the existence of contradictory moral intuitions compel an appeal to consequences. When the duty of Benevolence collides with the duty of Veracity, or the claim of one individual to immediate relief with the duty of doing what is best for society on the whole, how shall we determine which rule is to take precedence ? It is no use to say with Dr. Martineau ' Act in obedience to the highest motive ^ ' ; for it is impossible to pronounce one motive higher than another in the abstract, without reference to circumstances. If I were ' It is therefore quite reasonable to hold that some acts may properly be forbidden by Morality, just as others are forbidden by law, because (though often harmless) there is a probable balance of harm in allowing the practice at all. Law forbids my crossing the line except by the bridge (although the practice is quite safe for an able-bodied man in full possession of all his faculties) because my indulging in it has a tendency to encourage imitation in the feeble, the elderly, and the deaf, who are likely to be run over. It is quite reasonable to urge that even moderate gambling ought to be forbidden by public opinion on much the same grounds. Until public opinion has forbidden it, I am not, indeed, at liberty to treat the man who plays whist for sixpences as a moral offender. But, if I think that society would do well to adopt as its rule the total condemnation of gambling, it is my duty under ordinary circumstances to abstain from it myself, and to do what in me lies (short of censoriously condemning individuals who differ from me) to bring about the adoption of this rule. Those who will not under any possible circum- stances admit that 'abusus toUit usum ' would find it difficult to justify a whole host of accepted moral rules which rest on this principle. The whole social code which restricts the time, place, and circumstances of social inter- course between the sexes is based on this principle. Acts in themselves harmless are forbidden altogether because experience shows that they are liable to lead to bad consequences in some cases. * This doctrine is developed in the first part of the second volume of Types of Ethical Theory. 90 INTUITIONISM [Book I to pronounce Veracity invariably a higher motive than Bene- volence, I could never tell a lie or employ a detective to tell one for me, to avoid the extremest social disaster. If, on the other hand, I pronounce Benevolence higher than Veracity and every other possible motive, I have practically adopted the utilitarian principle, and Veracity would have always to give way to Benevolence, wherever there was the slightest collision between them. But neither solution of the problem seems to satisfy the demands of our moral consciousness. The first view strikes us as too rigorous, the last as too lax. What our actual moral judgement seems to say is, that in such collisions it is the amount of the unveracity or the amount of the inhumanity that will have to determine which rule is to give way. And this cannot be ascertained without a calculation of consequences. If once it be admitted that under any possible combination of circumstances I may tell a lie (however strongly one may feel the practical inexpediency of entering upon such a calculation in all ordinary cases), I must still feel bound to examine the cir- cumstances sufficiently to be pretty sure that there is no proba- bility of this turning out to be one of those extreme or exceptional cases in which the lie would be warranted. In general, of course, this hasty survey of the consequences is so instantaneously performed as to escape notice altogether. A truthful man acts at once on the general rule unless he detects something in the circumstances which seems to call for further con- sideration. (vi) While the foregoing objections may be urged against many of the alleged intuitions to which intuitional Moralists appeal, there are some which do submit to the tests which have been found fatal to the claim for absolute and final validity on the part of the rest. The axioms of Prudence, Rational Benevolence, and Equity do possess the clearness and definiteness and freedom from self-contradiction which other alleged intuitions so conspicuously lack. It does on reflection strike us as self-evident that I ought to promote my own good on the whole (where no one else's good is affected), that I ought to regard a larger good for society in general as of more intrinsic value than a smaller good, and that one man's good is (other Chap, iv, §ii] INTUITIONS RELATE TO ENDS 91 things being equal) of as much intrinsic value as any other man's. But these axioms, so far from throwing any doubt upon the truth of Utilitarianism, are precisely the maxims upon which Utilitarianism itself is founded for those who attempt to base the duty of promoting pleasure upon its intrinsic Tightness or reasonableness. In the acceptance of those maxims as genuine moral axioms, Sidgwick has, as we have seen, laid the foun- dations for a reconciliation between Intuitionism and Utili- tarianism. But the acceptance of these axioms does not make in favour of the kind of Intuitionism which it is the object of this chapter to examine; for these are precisely the axioms upon which Utilitarianism itself is based. Such intuitions do not forbid us — on the contrary they expressly require and compel us — to attend to the consequences of actions, and to make our judgement about them depend upon their tendency to promote a universal good. II It is perhaps unnecessary to multiply objections to that sort of Intuitionism which declares that certain rules of action are to be followed irrespectively of consequences. It is irrational to judge of the morality of an action without tracing its bearing upon human Well-being as a whole. We are compelled to accept the utilitarian formula in so far as it asserts that conduct is good or bad only in proportion as it tends to promote the Well- being of human society on the whole. But we have already seen reasons for rejecting the utilitarian identification of greatest good with greatest pleasure; and we have seen that in the judgements as to the value of different kinds of good we encounter a 'priori or immediate deliverances of the moral con- sciousness of precisely that kind to which the term Intuition is commonly applied. What then is the diflference between the intuitions which we have rejected and the intuitions which we have felt ourselves compelled to accept ? The intuitions of the Intuitionist are supposed to lay down invariable rviles of conduct; the a priori or immediate judgements which we have admitted relate to ends, to the relative value of different elements in human Well-being or ivhai\t.ovia. In other words the intuitions 92 INTUITIONISM [Book I of the Intuitionist disregard consequences ; ours relate precisely to the value of different kinds of consequence. The Intuitionist pronounces intuitive judgement upon acts ; our intuitions relate to ends ; his take the form ' this is right,' ours always the form ' this is good.' A few illustrations will make the contrast plain. The old intuitive rule of Veracity is supposed to say, 'Do not lie under any circumstances whatever ' : our judgement of value gives us only ' Truth-speaking is good ; lying is bad.' And the moment the intuitive or a priori truth is put in this new form, the irrationality and unworkableness of the old intuitional system disappears. We are not forbidden to calculate consequences. Certainly we must trace the bearing of an act upon universal Well-being ; but in our evbaiixovCa truth-speaking, or rather the truth-speaking and truth-loving character, finds a place. Suppos- ing the speaking of the truth will in this particular case involve such and such evils, the question is ' Which is the worse — these evils or the evil involved in the lie ; so much suffering, and suffer- ing caused by my voluntary act, or so much untruthfulness?' It is impossible, of course, to set forth in detail all the circum- stances upon which a right decision of such cases may depend. But it would be generally agreed that to tell a lie to save some- body from hearing an unpleasant remark, or to save him from some trifling injury to his pride or self-esteem, would be to choose the greater of two evils instead of the less. On the other hand, to save a friend's life at the cost of concealing bad news by a lie would be a less evil than the voluntary causing of . his death by speaking the truth. Of course, if any one disputes such a view of the case, we have nothing to say. As in all questions of ultimate ends, argument is impossible : but so in this particular case the vast majority of conscientious people judge and act. And be it observed that on this principle our moral judgements can never contradict one another. It remains true that truth is good, and speaking an untruth an evil; but like other goods, truth may have to give way to greater goods ; lying is always an evil, but it may be the less of two evils. It is evil even when the justification for the lie is palpable and incontestable. Where the circumstances are such that the isolated act does not Chap, iv, § ii] EXCEPTIONS 93 evidence or encourage an untruthful hahit or character, the evil may be very small ; but we cannot always secure that the evil shall be a small one. Lying in detectives i% necessary and right, but, like some other professional duties, it may not always be good for the character of the person who practises it. It is often necessary to do things which are right for us, but which are liable to be imitated by those for whom it is wrong. If the evil of the anticipated imitation be great enough, this may no doubt be a sufficient reason for abstinence, but no sensible man would forbid a father to smoke because the example may fire his youthful son with the ambition to do likewise. The general result then of our discussion, taken in connexion with preceding chapters, is that the true criterion of Morality is the tendency of an act to promote a Well-being or ivbaifiovia which includes many other good things besides pleasure, among which Virtue is the greatest. The value of these elements in human life is determined by the Practical Reason intuitively, immediately, or (if we like to say so) a priori ^. All moral judgements are ultimately judgements as to the intrinsic worth or value of some element in consciousness or life. And we may go one step further than this in recognition of the partial truth of Intuitionism. The great objection in many minds to the utilitarian view of Ethics is the element of calculation which it involves. When this objection is made into a plea for acting without regard to consequences, it is (as I have en- deavoured to show) completely irrational. But all the same the directness and immediacy which appear to characterize our clearest moral perceptions do seem at first sight an objection to the doctrine that I cannot decide whether a thing is right or wrong until I have worked out all its probable consequences upon so remote and intangible a thing as universal Well-being. And the ' I wish for the present to avoid as far as possible metaphysical discussion, and therefore content myself with saying that by a priori I mean merely that the judgement is immediate — not obtained by inference or deduction from something else in the way in which the Utilitarian supposes his judgements to be deductions from rules got by generalization from experience (though, as I have explained, he always assumes the ultimate major premiss ' Pleasure is good')- That in another sense judgements of value are not independent of experience, I shall hereafter strongly insist, especially in the next chapter. 94 INTUITIONISM [Book I difficulty is not fully met by insisting on the fact that on most of the ethical difficulties of common life the moral consciousness of the community has already laid down rules which the in- dividual has only to apply to the matter in hand. For there are no moral judgements which probably strike those who make them as more authoritative and self-evident than those by which a certain act is judged to be wrong in spite of an overwhelming weightof custom and tradition. Suchajudgement was pronounced, for instance, when a solitary monk declared that the gladiatorial combat was a barbarous brutality, though the tradition of ages and a whole circus-full of professedly Christian spectators pro- nounced it right, and by a public protest, which cost him his life, sealed the doom of the whole institution. And there is no reason why we should not fully recognize the validity of such judgements without any surrender of the principles which we have adopted. For this indefinable Well-being or evbainovCa, which our moral Reason pronounces to be the ultimate end of all human conduct, is itself made up of elements of consciousness — feelings, volitions, emotions, thoughts, activities — each of which is itself an object of moral valuation. If these elements were not each of them by itself^ the object of a judgement of value, there could be no judgement of value upon the whole. Every one would recognize this as regards acts which cause immediate pleasure or pain. Nobody supposes that, when I see a man sticking a knife into another, it is necessary for me to calculate the effect of the act upon the lives of all human beings, present and future, before I condemn the proceeding. I say at once, ' This pain is bad : therefore the infliction of it is wrong ' ; and, if I am not a Hedonist, I may add, 'the character or disposition which this act shows is worse than the pain which it causes.' And it is equally so in many cases where the act has no such immediate and obvious bearing upon the welfare of human society. That a rational being should use his intellect to make things appear to his brother man otherwise than as they are strikes me at once * I speak of course in a rough and relative sense. We could form no judgement upon the worth of an act or a state of mind without some general knowledge of its relation to life as a whole. The illustrations wUl, I trust, BufSciently explain my meaning. Chap, iv, §ii] THE RIGHT AND THE GOOD 95 as irrational and evil. I do not want to trace out all the effects of lying upon human society before I say, ' this is a lie and there- fore bad.' It is not the existence or even ijje relative and partial validity of such judgements that is disputed, so much as their finality. In many cases it is practically apparent at the first glance that no possible circumstances could make this act — the cutting or the lying — result in an overplus of good to human society. In many more cases there is a great improbability that any circumstance at present unknown to me will disclose a prospect of beneficial consequences which would reverse my prima facie judgement. But, unless I know all the circum- stances, it is always possible that further knowledge might reveal such a tendency. The man sticking a knife into his fellow with apparently heartless brutality may turn out to be a surgeon per- forming a salutary operation. The lie which I put down to mere indifference to truth may turn out to be part of a detective's scheme for the capture of a murderer or the protection of an innocent man. It is not always practically necessary to look to the ultimate end before we judge, and act upon our judge- ment: but, until we have done so, we are never sure that we have reached one of those ultimate moral judgements which represent an immediate deliverance of Reason, and which no further knowledge of facts and no demonstration of con- sequences can possibly shake. There would be little objection to the claims which the Intuitionist makes for his intuitions, if only he would admit that they are subject to appeal, though it is only an appeal to the same tribunal which pronounced the original judgements — an appeal (to borrow an old legal phrase) a conscientia male inforviata ad conscientiam, Tnelius in- formandam. So long as the intuitive judgement runs in the form, ' This is right,' it is always liable to be reversed on a wider survey of consequences. If it be turned into the form, ' This is good,' it cannot possibly be reversed (supposing that the man's ethical ideal be a true one), though the resulting duty may appear different when this isolated judgement is brought into comparison with other moral judgements affirming the superior goodness of some other end '. In Morality, as in other matters, ' This point has been well put by Dr. McTaggart. ' But is a moral 96 INTUITIONISM [Book I our judgements require to be correlated and corrected by reference to one another. Only the judgements that are based upon complete knowledge are final. The ideal moral judgement implies a conception of the ideal good for society as a whole, but we could have no ideal of what is good for society as a whole unless we had a power of pronouncing that this or that particular moment of conscious life is good or bad. Our conception of the moral ideal as a whole is built up out of particular judgements of value, though particular judgements of value have to be pro- gressively corrected by our growing conception of the moral ideal as a whole, just as our conception of the laws of nature is built up out of particular perceptions, though when that knowledge is once attained it reacts upon and alters the per- ceptions themselves. And by expressing the moral judgement as a judgement of Value we get this further advantage. We emphasize the fact which eudaemonistic systems of Ethics are apt to overlook — that acts are the objects of moral judgements as well as consequences. Because no act can be good or bad without reference to con- sequences, it does not follow that its morality depends wholly upon those consequences. To the Hedonist, of course, such a dis- tinction would be meaningless. For him nothing about an act is of any value or importance besides the consequences. Whether a poor family economize by infanticide or by curtailing their expenditure is simply a question of profit and loss. If the sum criterion,' he asks, 'wanted at all? It might be maintained that it was not. It would only be wanted, it might be said, if we decided our actions by general rules, which we do not. Our moral action depends on particular judgements that A is better than B, which we recognize with comparative immediacy, in the same way that we recognize that one plate is hotter than another, or one picture more beautiful than another. It is on these particular intuitive judgements of value, and not on general rules, that our moral action is based. ' This seems to me a dangerous exaggeration of an important truth. It is quite true that, if we did not begin with such judgements, we should have neither morality nor ethics. But it is equally true that we should have neither morality nor ethics if we stopped, where we must begin, with these judge- ments, and treated them as decisive and closing discussion. For our moral judgements are hopelessly contradictory of one another.' (Studies in Hegelian Cosmology, p. 97.) Chap, iv, §ii] ACT AND CONSEQUENCES 97 of pleasure would be equal in the two cases, it would be a matter of perfect indifference by which machinery the requisite cor- respondence between food and eaters shall be effected. The inhumanity of the act, the want of self-control which it implies, the temper or character which it expresses and fosters are matters of no importance except in so far as they may result upon the whole in an actual diminution of pleasure or increase of suffering. But, when once it is admitted that the end includes a certain ideal of human character, then the deliberate extinction of children deliberately brought into the world with the intention of so disposing of them will seem a vastly greater evil, to the individuals concerned and to the society which tolerates their conduct, than much poverty with all its physical hardships and privations. From this non-hedonistic point of view we can no longer recognize an absolute distinction between means and ends. Some means may no doubt have no value beyond that of conducing to a further end ; but many, nay most, of the acts which do conduce to further ends have a value (positive or negative) of their own; and this value must be taken into account in estimating the rightness or wrongness of the acts. It is on this principle that we must deal with most of the privna facie collisions between our ordinary moral judgements and the results of eudaemonistic calculation. Nothing but consciousness has value, but volitions and desires, emotions and aspirations and imaginations, are elements in aU our consciousness as well as mere pleasures and pains. There are acts so intrinsically re- pulsive that it strikes us as, on the face of it, impossible that any pleasure which they might yield could be worth the evil which they involve. In this way most people would condemn without further examination proposals for the abolition of marriage or the permission of promiscuous infanticide. But still even in such cases it is not speculatively admissible to say, ' we will not look at the consequences.' Practically, of course, it may often be right to refuse to argue some proposed moral innovation: that must depend upon circumstances. But, if we do argue, if we do want speculatively to get to the bottom of an ethical question, we are bound to look at all the consequences, and BASHDALI. I 98 INTUITIONISM [Book I pronounce whether, given such and such probable results, they are worth the evil involved in the means taken to gain them. In many cases — where the consequence on the strength of which it is proposed to do some questionable act is not some remote effect but some immediate pleasure — it is convenient to discuss the question as one of higher versus lower pleasure, though in strictness this means, according to our view, that the getting pleasure from one source is better than getting it from another, that one kind of pleasant consciousness is intrinsically better than another, though not more pleasant. And, if we treat one pleasure as intrinsically better than another, there is no logical objection to our regarding some pleasures (i.e. the getting pleasure from some things) as intrinsically bad. It is clear to my mind that there do exist pleasures which are intrinsically bad. On strictly hedonistic principles I fail to understand why we should object to the Spanish or Southern- French bull-fight, to the German students' face-slashing duels, to the coursing and pigeon-shooting which the higher public opinion is beginning to condemn among ourselves, to the wild- beast fights of the Roman amphitheatre, or perhaps even to the gladiatorial combats themselves, at least if the gladiators were justly condemned criminals. Hedonism is not bound to object to all infliction of pain, but only to insist that the pain inflicted shall yield a sufiicient overplus of pleasure on the whole. There is no more difficult ethical question than the question of the negative value to be attributed to pain as compared with the positive value to be attributed to pleasure. There is no question assuredly upon which people's actual judgements would differ more. Which would you rather have — some particularly longed for treat, the holiday or the travel that you have set your heart upon + a painful operation without chloroform, or no treat and no operation? Different men would answer such questions very differently ^. But, to return to our bull-fight, upon any rational ' It is an extremely difficult question to say hew far in such matters Hedonism would be bound to accept the verdict of the persons themselves. For we often deceive ourselves a« to the pleasurableness of pleasures not immediately present, even when we have some experience to go upon, and yet such false estimates are causes of further pleasures and pains —pleasures Chap.iv, §ii] BAD PLEASURES 99 or intelligible view of the comparative values of pleasure and pain, the intense pleasure which such spectacles give to thousands of beholders must surely outweigh the jftiin inflicted on a few dozen animals or even a few dozen criminals. If ten thousand spectators would not be sufficient to readjust the balance, suppose them multiplied tenfold or one-hundredfold. A humane man would condemn the spectacle all the same. He will pronounce such pleasures of inhumanity bad, quite apart from the some- what dubious calculation that the encouragement of inhumanity in one direction tends to callousness in another. Experience does not seem to show that persons habituated to the infliction of pain in one direction sanctioned by custom are less humane than other men in other directions. It is possible to question the morality of many forms of sport without accusing the average country gentleman of exceptional inhumanity, or doubt- ing the sincerity of the indignation with which he sends a labourer's boy to prison for setting his dog at the domestic cat. Another good instance of intrinsically bad pleasures is supplied by drunkenness. The pleasures of drunkenness strike the healthily constituted mind as intrinsically degrading and dis- gusting, though it is probable that occasional acts of drunkenness are physically less injurious than a course of ordinary dinner- parties ; and we should think the man's conduct in getting drunk worse instead of better if he had carefully taken pre- cautions which would prevent the possibility of his doing mischief or causing annoyance to others while under the influence of his premeditated debauch. Of course in all such cases, where we pronounce a particular kind of pleasure bad, we must remember what was said in dealing with the distinction between higher and lower pleasures. The pleasure taken by itself — in abstraction from the total content of the consciousness enjoying it — cannot possibly have anything bad about it. In the night all cows are black ; when we have made abstraction of all that differentiates one pleasure from another, the abstract remainder must obviously be identical from a moral as from every other point of view. It is really the getting pleasure from such and such things that or pains of expectation, imagination, or retrospect — which must themselves come into the calculus. H a lOo INTUITIONISM [Book I is pronounced bad in such cases. It is good to be pleased, but not at everything, or under all circumstances, or at all costs. Ill Our examination of the traditional Intuitionism has thus brought us round to the same position which we arrived at by a criticism of the traditional hedonistic Utilitarianism. We found that the Utilitarians were right in saying that actions are right or wrong according as they tend to promote or to diminish universal Well-being, but we found that they were wrong in thinking that the Well-being of a rational creature consists simply in pleasure, and pleasure measured quantitatively. We saw reason to believe that the very choice of the right and rational course for its own sake was itself a good and the greatest of all goods, and that it is impossible logically to establish the duty of preferring the general pleasure to our own without recognizing the intrinsic value of such a preference of universal good both for ourselves and for others. We saw further that besides this preference of the truly good in conduct or character there were many other elements in the ideal state of a human soul besides the Altruism of its volitions and the pleasantness of its sensations ; and when we faced the question, how we know these things to be good in various degrees, we were obliged to answer ' We know it intuitively or immediately ; we can give no reason why it should be so except that we see it so to be.' So far we were obliged to admit that the Intuitionists were right. We found, however, that the Intuitionists were mistaken in supposing that the moral Reason on which they rightly base our ethical judge- ments either lays down fixed and exceptionless laws of conduct, or issues isolated, arbitrary, disconnected decrees pro re nata without reference to probable results. We saw that fundamentally these moral judgements were judgements of value: they decide what is good, not immediately and directly what is right. Since prima facie it is always right to follow the good, these judge- ments may often in practice condemn this or that kind of conduct so emphatically that we feel sure that no calculation of con- sequences is likely to prevent our turning the judgement 'this is Chap, iv, § iii] THE MORAL CRITERION loi good ' into a judgement 'this is right' : but we saw that theo- retically no single judgement of value can form the basis of a rule of conduct which admits of no axceptions. For moral Reason bids us not only seek to realize the good but to realize as much good as possible, and (if I may anticipate a point which we have not yet estabhshed) to distribute that good justly or impartially between the various persons who may be affected by our actions. We have seen reason, while accepting the intuitional view of the imperativeness of duty and the supreme value of moral goodness, to hold that the law of duty itself requires us to consider the consequences of our actions and to seek to promote for all mankind a fvSaiij,ovCa or Well-being which shall include in itself all the various elements to which moral Reason ascribes value; and include them in such wise that each is accorded its due value and no more than that value. So far we have decided nothing as to what these elements are except that Virtue is the most important of them, that culture or knowledge is another, and that pleasure has a place among them, although some pleasures are bad and the relative value of others has to be determined by a non-hedonistic standard. We have begun our study of Ethics with the question of the moral criterion. Logically it might seem that we should have discussed the theory of duty in general before attacking the question how we find out what particular acts or classes of acts are duties. I have adopted the former course because it seemed the best way of showing how impossible it is for the most thorough-going Utilitarian to avoid admitting that this simple, unanalysable notion of duty or the reasonable in conduct does exist, and of illustrating the impossibility of constructing a logically coherent system of Ethics without the assumption that the reasonableness of an act is a sufficient ground for its being done. Before we go further, however, it may be well to dwell at some greater length upon the nature of this fundamental idea ; and the best way of doing so will be by a brief examina- tion of the classical exposition of it contained in the system of Immanuel Kant. CHAPTER V THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE We have seen that there is implied in every ethical judgement the idea that there is something which is intrinsically good, which it is reasonable to do, which is right, which ought to be done. These different modes of expression I regard as alter- native ways of expressing the same unanalysable idea which is involved in all ethical judgements — as much in the Utilitarian's judgement that he ought to promote the greatest happiness of the greatest number as in the Idealist's judgement ' I ought to aim at the greatest Virtue or Perfection for myself or for others.' If any one questions the existence of this idea of rightness, no argument can do more than remove some of the misconceptions which may prevent his explicitly recognizing what is really implied in the workings of his own mind. To attempt this task will be the object of the present chapter. If any one denies the authority or validity (as distinct from the existence) of this idea of duty, such a vindication of its validity as it is possible to give belongs to Metaphysic. The relation of Morals to Metaphysic is a subject on which something must be said hereafter : and yet all that even Metaphysic can do in this connexion is to develope the extravagant consequences in which a man becomes involved if he denies the validity of his own thought. To deny the deliver- ances of our own Reason is to deprive ourselves of any ground for believing in anything whatever. To admit that our Reason assures us that there are some things which it is right to do, and yet to ask why we should believe that those things ought to be done, is to ask why we should believe what we see to be true. Sidgwick's account of this idea of duty is so clear and so entirely dissociated from any metaphysical assumptions which CKap. V, §i] THE IDEA OF DUTY 103 to some minds might seem difficult or questionable, that I cannot do better than quote him at length : — ' It seems then that the notion of " ought ",ov " moral obHgation " as used in our common moral judgements, does not merely import (i) that there exists in the mind of the person judging a specific emotion (whether complicated or not by sympathetic representation of similar emotions in other minds) ; nor (a) that certain rules of conduct are supported by penalties which will follow on their violation (whether such penalties result from the general liking or aversion felt for the conduct prescribed or forbidden, or from some other source). What then, it may be asked, does it import ? What definition can we give of " ought," " right," and other terms expressing the same fundamental notion ? To this I should answer that the notion which these terms have in common is too elementary to admit of any formal definition The notion we have been examining, as it now exists ^ in our thought, cannot be resolved into any more simple notions : it can only be made clearer by determining as precisely as possible its relation to other notions with which it is connected in ordinary thought, especially to those with which it is liable to be confounded. 'In performing this process it is important to note and dis- tinguish two difierent impUcations with which the word " ought " is used ; in the narrowest ethical sense what we judge " ought to be" done, is always thought capable of being brought about by the volition of any individual to whom the judgement applies. I cannot conceive that I " ought " to do anything which at the same time I judge that I cannot do. In a wider sense, however, — which cannot conveniently be discarded — I sometimes judge that I " ought " to know what a wiser man would know, or feel as a better man would feel, in my place, though I may know that I could not directly produce in myself such knowledge or feeling by any effort of will. In this case the word merely implies an ideal or pattern which I " ought " — in the stricter sense — to seek to imitate as far as possible. And this wider sense seems to be that in which the word is normally used in the precepts of Art generally, and in political judgements: when ' In the sentences omitted the writer explains that he does not exclude the possibility that the notion has been gradually developed. I04 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I I judge that the laws and constitution of my country "ought to be " other than they are, I do not of course imply that ray own or any other individual's single volition can directly bring about the change. In either case, however, I imply that what ought to be is a possible object of knowledge : i. e. that what I judge ought to be must, unless I am in error, be similarly judged by all rational beings who judge truly of the matter ^. ' In referring such judgements to the " Reason," I do not mean to prejudge the question whether valid moral judgements are normally attained by a process of reasoning from universal prin- ciples or axioms, or by direct intuition of the particular duties of individuals. It is not uncommonly held that the moral faculty deals primarily with individual cases as they arise, applying directly to each case the general notion of duty, and deciding in- tuitively what ought to be done by this person in these particular circumstances. And I admit that on this view the apprehension of moral truth is more analogous to Sense-perception than to Rational Intuition (as commonly understood) : and hence the term Moral Sense might seem more appropriate. But the term Sense suggests a capacity for feelings which may vary from A and B without either being in error, rather than a faculty of cognition: and it appears to me fundamentally important to avoid this suggestion. I have therefore thought it better to use the term Reason with the explanation above given, to denote the faculty of moral cognition V In claiming for the idea of duty not merely existence but authority, we have implied that the recognition that some- thing is our duty supplies us with what we recognize upon reflection as a sufficient motive for doing it, a motive on which it is psychologically possible to act. The recognition of the thing as right is capable of producing an impulse to the doing of it. This impulse need not be strong enough to override other motives, nor need we enter here upon the question in what sense (if any) the choice between this motive of duty and other desires ^ Ab a representation of the present ■writer's views this statement of the unanalysable character of the right must be taken to be qualified by what follows (below, pp. 137, 138) as to the relation between this notion and the wider concept of ' good.' ^ Methods 0/ Ethics, 6th ed., pp. 31-34. Chap. V, §i] DICTATES OF REASON 105 or impulses must be held to depend upon the undetermined choice of the individual at the moment of action. It is enough for our present purpose that on reflection we recognize that the seeing a thing to be right is a reason for doing it, and that in some men at some moments the desire to do what is reasonable or right as such causes the actions to be done. Once again I may quote Sidgwiek : — 'Further, when I speak of the cognition or judgement that " X ought to be done " — in the stricter ethical sense of the term ought — as a " dictate " or " precept " of reason to the persons to whom it relates; I imply that in rational beings as such this cognition gives an impulse or motive to action : though in human beings, of course, this is only one motive among others which are liable to conflict with it, and is not always — perhaps not usually — a predominant motive. In fact, this possible conflict of motives seems to be connoted by the term "dictate" or "imperative"; which describes the relation of Reason to mere inclinations or non-rational impulses by comparing it to the relation between the will of a superior and the wills of his subordinates. This conflict seems also to be implied in the terms " ought," " duty," "moral obligation," as used in ordinary moral discourse: and hence these terms cannot be applied to the actions of rational beings to whom we cannot attribute impulses conflicting with reason. We may, however, say of such beings that their actions are "reasonable," or (in an absolute sense) "right." ' I am aware that some persons will be disposed to answer all the preceding argument by a simple denial that they can find in their consciousness any such unconditional or categorical impera- tive as I have been trying to exhibit. If this is really the final result of self-examination in any case, there is no more to be said. I, at least, do not know how to impart the notion of moral obligation to any one who is entirely devoid of it. I think, how- ever, that many of those who give this denial only mean to deny that they have any consciousness of moral obligation to actions without reference to their consequences ; and would not really deny that they recognise some universal end or ends — whether it be the general happiness, or well-being otherwise understood — as that at which it is ultimately reasonable to aim. . . . But in this io6 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I view, as I have before said, the unconditional imperative plainly comes in as regards the end, which is — explicitly or implicitly — recognised as an end at which all men " ought " to aim ; and it can hardly be denied that the recognition of an end as ultimately reasonable involves the recognition of an obligation to do such acts as most conduce to the end ^.' These two positions (i) that the rightness of actions is per- ceived immediately by the Reason, (a) that this rightness ought to be and is capable of becoming a motive to the Will, are embodied by Kant in the two famous phrases, the categorical imperative and the autonomy of the will. Duty is a categorical imperative because when a thing is seen to be right, we feel commanded to do it categorically, absolutely, as a means to no end beyond itself. If duty meant merely ' Do this if you want to be happy, or to be perfect, or to go to heaven,' it would be merely a hypothetical imperative: its obligation would depend on our happening to desire the end to which we saw the action in question to be a means. As it is, we feel that the rightness of doing what we see to be our duty is in no way dependent on the presence or absence of any desire or inclination towards what is commanded. It is true that the action cannot be done imless there is an impulse to do what is right or reasonable on our part, but such a desire may be created by the Reason which recognizes the rightness : we desire to do the act commanded (in so far as we do desire it) because it is commanded ; we do not judge that we are commanded to do the act simply because we chance to desire it ^. When then we do a thing because it is right, the will ' Methods of Ethics, 6tli ed., pp. 34-5. ' It was partly to avoid this implication that Kant refused to speak of a desire to do one's duty, and partly because, as pointed out below, he erroneously assumed that every desire was a desire for pleasure. He therefore spoke of the ' interest ' of Reason in the Moral Law or ' respect ' for the Moral Law as the subjective motive of right conduct. But in his eagerness to assert that Reason immediately moves the will, he has at times the appearance of forgetting (what Aristotle urges against Plato) that bare thought does not initiate action (Sicii/oia avrt] oidiv Kivil) : that moral choice {Ttpoaipia-ts) involves a desire (ope^is) for the end as well as the intellectual perception that an act will promote the end. As von Hartmann puts it, ' Das Pflichtgefuhl ist selbst eine Neigung ' (Das sittl. Bewusstsein, p. 254). Moreover, this habit of speak- ing as if Reason stepped in (so to speak) and worked the human body without Chap. V, §i] MORALITY A GOOD 107 is autonomous: it is a 'law to itself.' Though the man feels commanded to do the act whether he likes it or not, it is never- theless the man himself — his own Reason, tie highest part of his nature — which issues the command or makes the law. Hence in the highest sense he is most free when most completely the slave of duty '. The two positions in which we have taken Sidgwick as a peculiarly lucid exponent of Kant are in the Philosopher's own writings associated with a third in which his utilitarian disciple does not follow him. To Kant the performance of duty is not merely 'right'; it is the highest 'good' of the agent. Here we have already found reason to believe that Kant is right, and can only refer the sceptic to the testimony of his own con- sciousness. If he denies that he finds in his own consciousness the judgement 'goodness of conduct possesses a higher worth than anything else in the world,' the only way to argue with him would be to try to show that his own actions, or at least his judgements of himself and other men, really imply that he thinks so ; that his approval of himself when he does right and disapproval when he does wrong are quite inexplicable upon the assumption that bad conduct is merely conduct which is irrational from the point of view of Society though wholly rational from his own private point of view. For the man who believes it, the judgement ' Morality is good and the greatest of goods ' or ' the good will is the most important element in the good ' is as much a simple and ultimate deliverance of the moral consciousness as the judgement ' It is right to promote the general good.' the intervention of any subjective motive, involved him in much unneces- sarily mysterious language about the Autonomy of the Will. When Kant said that the will is a 'law to itself he meant that in right action Reason is a law to the will ; in fact, according to Kant, the will is Reason, at least when the will is rightly directed. Wrong acts, it would appear, can only be said to be willed, and so to be free, according to Kant, in so far as Reason might have intervened to stop them and did not. But the Psychology of wrong action is one on which Kant is as vague as he is unsatisfactory. ^ No doubt in Kant's own view this use of the term ' free ' (in which it can only be applied to right acts) implies also the opposite of ' determined ' or ' necessitated ' (see below, Book III, ch. iii, § i). The double sense in which Kant used the term ' free ' is very clearly pointed out by Prof. Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, Book I, ch. v and Appendix. io8 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I II So far we may regard Kant as having laid down in the most impressive way the principles which must form the basis of every constructive ethical system^. But in Kant's own view these positions are associated with two other doctrines which require further examination. In the first place he assumed that out of this bare idea of a categorical imperative, without any appeal to experience, he could extract a moral criterion, i.e. that he could ascertain what is the actual content of the Moral Law, what in detail it is right to do. Secondly, he assumed that, so far as an act is not determined by pure respect for the Moral Law, it possesses no moral value whatever. Let us examine each of these positions in turn. The value of Kant's work consisted very largely in supplying a metaphysical basis for Ethics. So long as it is assumed that all our ordinary knowledge of matters of fact comes from experi- ence of an ' external world,' there is always a sort of suspicion that any kind of knowledge which cannot point to such an origin must be in some sense unsubstantial or delusive. The Critique of Pure Reason demonstrates that in all our knowledge there is an element which is not derived from experience : all knowledge implies ' forms of perception ' and 'forms of understanding' which are a priori, part of the constitution of the mind itself, not supplied to it from without. The matter of sensation is from without, but sense by itself is not thought. I cannot judge of the size and distance of particular objects without a matter supplied by sensible perception : but 1 could not build up these data into the conception of a square table of a certain size unless I had already notions of space, of spacial and causal relations, of ' Eant was no doubt wrong in supposing that all other systems but his own were based upon ' heteronomy of the Will.' This is not true of Plato and Aristotle (to say nothing of other ancient writers) whom Kant's education had not qualified him to understand, nor of the Cambridge Platonists and other English Rationalists of whom he appears to have known little or nothing. It was not true of them unless the doctrine of the categorical imperative is distorted into the precept ' Do your duty without considering whether what you are doing is good for any one or not,' and in that sense the idea of Autonomy is, as contended below, indefensible and absurd Chap.v, §ii] KANT'S MOKAL CRITEEION 109 substance and accident and the like which do not come from experience ^. In all actual knowledge there must be a matter supplied by experience and a formal element which is a 'priori. But in Morality — in the idea of duty — we are presented with a form which needs no filling up from experience, a form which is (so to speak) its own content, since it is a matter of immediate con- sciousness that this a priori concept of duty can supply a motive to the will. Now in this position a very important truth is (as is almost universally admitted by the most Kantian of modem Moralists) confused with a very serious error. That no experience can prove an act to be right, that no accumulation of knowledge as to what is can possibly give us an ought, is a truth which can only be denied by asserting that there is no meaning in duty or in Morality. Experience of the past may tell us what has been or what wiU be: it cannot possibly tell us what ought to be. That which ought to be is ex vi termini something which as yet is not and which may conceivably never be. In that sense our moral judgements are undoubtedly a priori or independent of experience. But that without any appeal to experience we can get at the content as well as the form of the moral law, can easily be shown to be a pure delusion. Let us see how Kant made the attempt. The rules of action which the categorical imperative is sup- posed to give us are the following : — (i) 'So act as if the law of thine action were to become by thy will law universal.' (a) ' Regard humanity whether in thine own person or in that of any one else always as an end and never as a means only.' (3) ' Act as a member of a kingdom of ends ^.' ' This is a very inadequate and popular statement, nor do I mean to assent to Kant's idea of a form derived from the mind and a matter derived from some source outside the mind. I have merely endeavoured to explain for the benefit of any one to whom it is unfamiliar Kant's use of the terms ' form ' and ' matter ' so far as is necessary for the comprehension of his ethical position. '' Kant nowhere explains the relation in which the three rules are sup. posed to stand towards one another, nor does he ever bring them into close contact with one another ; but in different parts of his ethical writings each one of them is treated as the fundamental principle of Morality. In practice no THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I Let us examine the first of these rules — ' Act as if the law of thy action were to become by thy will law universal.' Now it is quite true that it does follow from the very idea of there being something which it is right to do irrespectively of inclination that this course must, in the same circumstances, be binding upon every one else. And therefore in a sense it is true that no action can be really a moral rule the principle of which could not be universalized. It is good practical advice to urge that when we have to pronounce upon the morality of a proposed act we should ask ourselves whether it represents a principle which we should think it rational to will as a universal rule of conduct. But this is by itself a merely negative test. It gives us no definite information until we have made up our minds as to what it is which makes conduct rational or irrational. We can, indeed, with a little ingenuity extract from it the all-important axioms of Benevolence and Equity : for, if there is something which it is intrinsically right to do, what is right for me would be right for any one else in the same circumstances ^ : hence it must be right for me to treat every other man as it would be right for him to treat me under similar circumstances. If my good is recognized as something which it is intrinsically right for others to promote, the good of each other individual must also be treated as an end the promotion of which I must look upon as incumbent upon me: hence I am bound to promote the greatest good of humanity collectively (the maxim of rational Benevolence), and to treat each individual's good as of equal value with the good of every other (the maxim of Equity). But these rules by themselves will give us no practical guidance till we know what that good is which ought to be promoted by every rational being for every other. The Kantian maxim, properly interpreted, thus occupies in he uses one or the other of them just as may be most convenient for the pur- pose of proving the particular duty with which he is dealing. ' This principle seems to me to require some qualification (see below, p. ii6 note) ; and it is obvious that we have not really got this rule out of the form, for without knowing what sort of being the ' other ' is, and what ' good ' he is capable of, we cannot say what that good is worth — unless, indeed, we make it mean simply an individual's good must be of as much value as the like good of any other individual. Chap. V, §ii] INADEQUACY OF KANT'S EXILE iii Ethics the same position which the law of contradiction holds in Logic ^. The law of contradiction is a negative test of truth : it tells us that two judgements which contradict one another cannot both be true, but as to which judgements in particular are true, it will give us no information : only, when I know that judgement A is true, it will tell me that judgement B, being inconsistent there- with, cannot also be true. In the same way the Kantian rule tells us that a genuine ultimate rule of conduct must not only be logically consistent with itself, but also be such as that all its prescriptions shall be consistent with all other ethical rules. The supreme ethical precept must consist of an harmonious and self- consistent system of precepts. It need hardly be said that this by itself is a most important negative test of ethical truth. It gives us the principle upon which alone inference or reasoning (as distinct from immediate judgements of Reason) is possible in Ethics. The fact that something is a part of the true ethical rule supplies, if we assume this principle to be self-evident, a demonstrative proof that some precept inconsistent with it cannot be a part of it^. But as to what rule of action in particular is reasonable, it gives us no information whatever. If we interpret the rule of acting on a principle fit for law universal as equivalent to Sidgwick's three ethical axioms — of ^ This interpretation of Kant is well insisted on by Sigwart [Logic, E. T., ii. p. 543 seq.). Sigwart would call the principle in question a postulate : I should venture to regard it as both a postulate and an axiom. It ought not to be denied by any one who is not prepared to question the validity of all thinking. Mr. Bradley is so far consistent that he accuses thought as well as Morality of internal inconsistency. Some of his followers (in Ethics) have been less logical. Mr. Bradley is only following out his own principle to its logical conclusion when, in his frequent polemics against Casuistry, he denies apparently the possibility of any inference whatever in the ethical sphere (see below, Bk. Ill, ch. vi). It is enough for our present purpose to insist that the self-evident axioms of Ethics and the inferences based upon them have as much validity as any other parts of our thinking. ^ It will be observed that I am speaking of elements in the supreme ethical rule, not elements of the end. The end itself must not contain intrinsically incompatible elements, but in particular circumstances ele- ments of the end are often incompatible : but the ethical rule says ' in that case promote the good which is of most intrinsic value.' Even the good may, and obviously does, contain elements which cannot all be enjoyed by the same persons. iia THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I Benevolence, Equity and Prudence — we shall get rules for the promotion and distribution of the good or ultimate end, but no information as to what particular things are good : and, until we know that, we cannot get any principles from which we can deduce the right course of conduct in any one single case. If with Sidgwick (who could quote much in Kant himself to support this interpretation) we made ' good ' in this connexion equivalent to ' pleasure,' and interpreted our rule to mean ' pro- mote universal pleasure and distribute it equally,' we should obviously have gone beyond the mere a priori formal rule. We should have appealed to experience — an appeal which our categorical imperative was intended by Kant to exclude. The judgement ' Happiness ought to be promoted ' is no doubt in a sense a priori, but not in the sense that no information derived from experience is necessary to its being made. Kant himself admits that the concept of happiness is of empirical origin i. Experience must tell us what happiness is before we can judge happiness to be good. Still more obviously experience is wanted to tell us what particular goods constitute happiness, or what are the means to procure those goods. It might be thought that Kant could get a content for the Moral Law by holding that the true good of man is simply Morality, a concept which might be said to be of purely a priori origin, and that we should find out what particular actions are right by considering what actions would promote universal Morality. But here again, if the concept of the end is in a sense purely a priori, experience is needed to tell us the means ; and Kant has incapacitated himself from adopting this solution of the problem by the exaggerated Libertarianism which made him pronounce an action due to another's influence to be not truly ' free,' and therefore without moral value ^. Consequently, he pronounced that it was im- ' ' All the elements wliich belong to the notion of happiness are altogether empirical, i.e. they must be borrowed from experience' (Grundlegung zur Met. d. Sitten, § 2, translated by Abbot in Kant's Theory of Ethics, 4th ed., 1889, p. 35). '^ Meiaph.Anfangsgi'unde d. Tugendlehre, Einleitung, § iy seq. (Abbot, p. 296). But this is qualified (hardly consistently) by the admission of a negative duty towards the moral well-being of others, i. e. not to create temptations (Abbot, p. 304). Chap.v, §ii] FITNESS FOR LAW UNIVERSAL 113 possible for one man to make another's moral good his end. Hence if Virtue is by itself to constitute the end, it must be the man's own virtue that he must treat .as his end. To tell a man to make his own virtue an end will not tell him what to do until he knows what acts it is virtuous to perform, and as to this the formula that what is right for him is right for others wiU give him no information whatever. How then did Kant attempt to extract out of the bare form of the Moral Law a knowledge of the particular actions which are right or wrong? It is impossible to maintain that Kant gives a clear and con- sistent meaning to his own dictum. Sometimes the irrationality of willing the universal adoption of the immoral course appears to turn simply upon the fact that the social consequences to which the adoption of such a will would lead are consequences which no rational man could regard as good. We cannot will universal promise-breaking because in that case no promises would be made, and at times the irrationality of willing such a consequence seems to turn upon its injurious social eiFects. Still more clearly when Kant pronounces that we cannot rationally will the non-development of our faculties, the irra- tionality of such a course is made to depend simply upon the fact that the rational man actually regards this non-development as bad and their development as good^. Here the appeal to ' ' A third ' [the first two cases are suicide and breach of promise] ' finds in himself a talent which with the help of some culture might make him a useful man in many respects. But he finds himself in comfortable circum- stances, and prefers to indulge in pleasure rather than to take pains in enlarging and improving his happy natural capacities. He asks, however, whether his maxim of neglect of his natural gifts, besides agreeing with his inclination to indulgence, agrees also with what is called duty. He sees then that a system of nature could indeed subsist with such a universal law although men (like the South Sea islanders) should let their talents rust, and resolve to devote their lives merely to idleness, amusement, and propagation of their species — in a word, to enjoyment ; but he cannot possibly will that this should be a universal law of nature, or be implanted in us as such by a natural instinct. For, as a rational being, he necessarily wills that his faculties be developed, since they serve him, and have been given him, for all sorts of possible purposes ' (Grundlegung, § 4 : Abbot, p. 40). I pass over the objections (i) that elsewhere the development of faculties is not regarded by Kant as an ultimate good, the only ultimate goods being Virtue and Happiness ; (2) that Kant relies upon teleological assumptions BABHDALL t I 114 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I consequences which can only be known by experience is scarcely disguised : the a priori judgement relates simply to the goodness or badness of the end. But Kant was able to conceal from him- self the necessity of this appeal to experience, because in certain carefully selected instances he was able to point to the appear- ance of internal contradiction in the reverse of the accepted rule^ We cannot rationally will that men shall break their promises, because in that case no promises would be made ; and we cannot rationally will something to be done which will make it impossible to observe the very rule which we will. In a society in which there were no promises, it would no longer be possible to observe our proposed rule of universal promise-breaking ; if no promises are made, none can be broken. Now even here it is evident that Kant falls back upon his experience of human nature to tell him what will be the consequences of his act: but still he might maintain that, given this much experience, the contradiction is self-evident. Yet it is easy to show that absence of contradiction, in this sense, would be a very irrational test of conduct. Kant himself appears to concede that there would be no internal contradiction in willing that all men should leave their faculties undeveloped. Nor would there be any internal contradiction in adopting as our rule of action the promotion of universal misery, or at least of the maximum of misery which should be consistent with the continued survival of the human race. That is, indeed, according to some Pessimists, precisely the end which is actually realized in the world as we know it. And, just as we hold many acts to be wrong which involve no internal contradiction, so there are many things which we pro- nounce right in spite of such contradiction. Kant tells us that we cannot rationally will universal promise-breaking, because the universal adoption of such a rule would lead to a state of things in which the rule ' Break your promises ' could no longer be observed. We must not commit suicide, because if every to which he was not entitled: he had no right (from his point of view), to assume that our faculties were ' given ' us for any reason whatever. ' It is true that even in the selected cases the contradiction is not really internal. It is the actual structure of human society which makes the suggested rule unworkable. Chap. v,§ii] TEST OF NON-CONTEADICTION 115 one did so, there would soon be nobody left to practise the virtue of suicide. Then are we, it may be asked, to deny that Philanthropy is a duty because the uiliversal practice of a reasonable Philanthropy would lead to a state of things in which there would be no poor upon whom to practise that virtue? Shall we refuse to bless the peacemaker, because if every one shared his disposition, there would be no quarrels to adjust? And then, again, how unreasonable is the alternative with which we are presented — either to will universal suicide and universal lying, or to forbid each of these practices in any circumstances whatever ! As reasonably might we pronounce Kant's own celibacy a crime because universal celibacy would rapidly extinguish the human race and (consequently) the practice of celibacy. It is true that the emergence of an internal contradiction (in Kant's sense) in any suggested moral rule does show that we have not reached an ultimate principle of conduct. We can, indeed, put such rules as ' Give to the poor ' into a universal form by making them hypothetical : ' So long as there are any poor, relieve them ; ' but so might we say, ' So long as there are any human beings alive, let them commit suicide.' Still, the fact that the rule is only applicable to a particular set of cir- cumstances does show that we have not reached an ultiimate principle. The rule, 'Be charitably disposed,' may, indeed, be universally willed : but then Kant's object in applying his test of fitness for law universal is to supply a guide for the details of outward conduct, not for mere dispositions and intentions, and this purpose is not served by such generalities as these. And even in this case there is really a reference to the physical constitution of human beings which is known to us only from experience. We might interpret charity to mean ' a disposition to promote good,' but the absence of internal contradiction will not tell us what good is. Moreover, as has already been pointed out, although an ultimate moral principle must be free from internal contradiction, it is impossible to deny that many im- moral principles might very well be universalized without leading to any such contradiction. The structure of the Universe and of human nature is quite as consistent with the non-development I 3 ii6 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I as with the development of human faculties. And if the criterion is not of universal application, how are we to know when to apply it, and when not ? The fact is that Kant appears to have confused two distinct senses of the term ' categorical.' When he sets forth that it is of the essence of every moral law to be categorical, he means that it must admit of no exception due to the subjective dis- inclination of the individual for the course of action which it prescribes. We must not say, ' I admit Temperance or Veracity to be right in a general way : only I personally happen to have such a rooted antipathy to Temperance or Veracity, or whatever it be, that I must regard myself as an exception to the general rule.' To talk in that way no doubt destroys the very nature of a Moral Law. It is an essential characteristic of the Moral Law that whatever is right for me must be right for every man in precisely the same circumstances ^. But when Kant tries to make out this mere unconditionality of a rule an absolute test of its reasonableness, he has to assume that the categorical character of an imperative excludes the possibility of an ex- ception based not on the mere subjective disinclination of the individual, but on the nature of the case. He does not see that the rule ' Do this except in such and such circumstances ' is just as ' categorical ' and just as little ' hypothetical ' as the rule ' Do this under all circumstances whatever,' so long as the exceptions are recognized as no less universal in their applica- tion, no less based upon the reason and nature of things, than the original rule. Kant in fact confuses the inclusion of an exception in a moral rule with the admission of an exception to a moral rule. He does not recognize that the difference between a rule with an exception and a grammatically categorical rule is often a purely verbal one. The precept ' Do no murder ' admits of no exceptions, because ' murder ' means ' killing except in such and such circumstances.' The rule 'Thou shalt not kill' hfis exceptions. So the rule ' Lie not ' could be represented as equally ' That we can only hold this principle by including in the ' circumstances ' the man's own character and disposition (other than an indisposition to perform what has once been proved to be his duty), I have contended below in the chapter on ' Vocation ' (vol. ii, oh. iv). Chap. V, §ii] QUESTION OF EXCEPTIONS 117 'categorical' if there were as clear a usage in favour of the proposition that a legitimate untruth is no lie, as there is in favour of the proposition that in certain aircumstances killing is no murder. We are obliged sometimes to express a moral rule in the form of a general command with an exception simply because the enumeration of the circumstances to which the rule is inapplicable is shorter and more convenient than an exhaustive enumeration of all the cases to which it is applicable. And it is clear that every rule, however general, implies some set of circumstances in which alone it is capable of being applied. The duty of not committing adultery is only applicable to the relations between two persons of whom one at least has a lawful spouse, and it is obvious that this term ' lawful ' postulates a larger number of highly complicated social arrangements, about which there is by no means a universal consensus, and which the most enthusiastic Kantian could hardly attempt to determine on any a priori principle. Either, then, we must say that every possible rule really involves a hypothesis under which alone it is applicable; or we may say that every moral law excludes all exception if only you put it into a sufficiently general, and a sufficiently internal, form, 'Kill not' has exceptions: ' Thou shalt love thy neighbour as thyself ' (properly understood) has none ^. But, in whichever way it is put, it is plain that we can get no criterion of Morality out of the presence or absence of exceptions. ' Kill not ' has exceptions, and yet (subject to the exceptions) is accounted a good moral principle. On the other hand, ' Thou shalt love thy friend and hate thine enemy ' does not appeal to us as the highest morality, in spite of its being quite as categorical as the Christian precept. Kant's attempt to extract an ethical criterion out of the bare form of the Moral Law is the more remarkable, because he did not hold (as he is sometimes supposed to do) that there is no other rational end of action except the bare performance of duty. • ' The Moral Law, we may say, has to be expressed in the form, " Be this," not in the form, " Do this." The possibility of expressing any rule in this form may be regarded as deciding whether it can or cannot have a dis- tinctively moral character. Christianity gave prominence to the doctrine that the true moral law says "hate not," instead of "kill not'" (Leslie Stephen, Science of Ethics, 1882, p. 155). ii8 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I Had he held that view, it would have become fairly impossible for him even to have persuaded himself that he had discovered in the bare form of the law any content for the idea of duty ^. If a man is to perform his duty, he must know what that duty is ; and the mere knowledge that, when he has discovered what his duty is, it is a thing categorically commanded does not help to find out what it is. It is impossible, in short, to show the rationality of one course of action rather than another until we have admitted that something else besides the performance of duty — some objective good other than the state of the will — is a rational end of action or possesses value ^. And Kant did admit that there is such another rational end of action — which ^ Dr. Lipps {Die ethischen Orundfragen, 1899, p. 158 seq.) has attempted to clear Eant of the imputation that his categorical imperative has no content by suggesting that the content is supplied by all our natural desires and in- clinations : the moral law simply prescribes the way and extent to which they should be indulged. I believe that this is very largely the explanation of Kant's own view of the matter, but it is open to the objection that it allows all actual tendencies of human nature ('aller moglichen menschlichen Zwecke ') to be indulged in proportion to their actual strength, except in so far as their indulgence interferes with the indulgence of other such ten- dencies in ourselves and in other individuals. It is obvious that we should have to appeal to experience to know what is the relative strength of these tendencies ; and, after all, it supplies us with a very unsatisfactory test of their relative value. If only the tendency to opium-smoking were sufiSoiently strong in a whole community, the Kantian principle (as interpreted by Dr. Lipps) would make universal opium-smoking a categorical imperative. ^ Lotze, the last man in the world to sanction vulgar Hedonism, has said : ' There is nothing at all in the world, which would have any value until it has produced some pleasure in some being or other capable of enjoyment. Everything antecedent to this is naught but an indifferent kind of fact, to which a value of its own can be ascribed only in an anticipatory way, and with reference to some pleasure that is to originate from it' (Practical Philosophy, Eng. Trans, by Ladd, p. 19). I believe this statement might be defended, since (a) pleasure is an element in all ultimate good. (6) Lotze has not said that the value lies exclusively in the pleasure abstracted from the other elements of consciousness, or that it is to be measured by the amount of that pleasure. But his statement seems to me liable to mis- understanding. On the other hand, it is surprising to find Lotze admitting that ' the effort to hold fast pleasure, or to regain it, and to avoid pain, are the only springs of all practical activity ' {Microcosmus, E. T., i. p. 688), but here again the taint of Hedonism is removed by a recognition of differences in the quality of the pleasure. Chap. v,§m] DUTY FOR DUTY'S SAKE 119 possesses worth, not indeed ' absolutely and unconditionally,' but on one condition — that it does not interfere with Virtue. And that other end is Happiness. From this p^ition it would seem logically to follow that the true criterion would be the tendency of an action to promote for all mankind Happiness in so far as is compatible with Virtue. This would supply us with a quite intelligible and workable view of the moral criterion, and it would correspond roughly with the actual deliverances of the moral consciousness. That it is an inadequate view of the ultimate end of human life, I have already attempted to show ; and its deficiencies will be further illustrated when we pass on to the other mistaken assumption, from which I am anxious to dissociate Kant's fundamental doctrine of a categorical im- perative. Ill That duty should be done for duty's sake we have seen to be really implied in the very notion of there being such a thing as duty. But it does not follow that the desire to do one's duty must always be the sole and exclusive motive of right conduct, or that conduct not consciously inspired by respect for the Moral Law as such must possess no moral value at all. Yet such was the assumption of Kant himself. To Kant the most unselfish ^ devotion to wife or child, the most ardent patriotism, the most comprehensive philanthropy, possessed no more moral value than the purest avarice or the most unmitigated selfishness. Unless the man loves, or rather behaves as though he loved (since love, he holds, cannot be commanded) wife, or country, or humanity simply from an actual, conscious respect for the Moral Law, his conduct is worthless — not necessarily wrong (for it is not a crime to promote one's own happiness when duty does not forbid), but entirely without moral value. The will that wills from pure love of the brethren is morally on a level with the will that wills from pure love of self. It is of no more value than the ' I speak popularly: to Kant there could be no such thing as an ' unselfish ' love of anything except duty, and even that could only be ' respected,' not ' loved.' To Kant (in his stricter moments), as to Bentham, Benevolence not inspired by pure sense of duty was merely a love of benevolent pleasure. lao THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I behaviour of an animal. Such is the revolting and inhuman Stoicism to which Kant's ideal logically leads. It is, as Schopen- hauer puts it, the ' apotheosis of lovelessness, the exact opposite, as it is, of the Christian doctrine of Morals^.' In well-known lines the poet Schiller makes the disciple of Kant complain : Gladly, I serve my friends, but alas I do it with pleasure. Hence I am plagued -with the doubt that I am not a virtuous person: in reply to which the answer given is : Sure, your only resource is to try to despise them entirely, And then with aversion to do what your duty enjoins you''. Nor can it be alleged that Kant has any desire to conceal this result. He holds ex professo that all desire is bad. 'The in- clinations themselves being sources of want, are so far from having an absolute worth for which they should be desired, that on the contrary it must be the universal wish of every rational being to be wholly free from them ^,' We might ask in what, according to Kant, happiness is to consist? Happiness, as we know it, arises entirely from the satisfaction of desires*, and happiness is admitted to be a rational end of action ; how then can the desires be consistently treated as a mere encumbrance which the rational man would fain be without? But it is enough to point out the utter discrepancy between the Kantian dogma and the strongest moral convictions of mankind. The ' common-sense ' philosophy of Bishop Butler is here a far better exponent of the moral consciousness. Insisting as strongly as Kant upon the claims of Conscience, he yet recognizes that Conscience does not prescribe this total suppression of all other ' passions, propensions, or affections.' It rather pronounces that some of the desires ought to be encouraged, some suppressed, others moderated or controlled, and all subordinated to Benevo- lence and self-love — the two great rational impulses which make for the good of ourselves and our fellow men ^, And in ' Ueber die Grundlage der Moral, § 6 {The Basis of Morality, trans, by A. B. Bullock, 1903, p. 49). He goes on to call it a piece of ' stupid moral pedantry ' {taktlosen moralischen Pedantismus). ^ From Die Philosophen. ' Grundlegung, § 2 (Abbot, p. 46). * Including the desire of pleasure. " I do not mean to accept this as a fuUy adequate account of the matter. Chap.v, §iii] THE MOEAL MOTIVE 121 this teaching Butler was only developing the principles of Aristotle who (amid many retrogressions) advanced beyond Plato just by his recognition of the faat that desire is as essential an element of human nature as Reason ; that the raw material (so to speak) of the sublimest virtues and of the coarsest vices is the same, that natural impulses are good or evil just according as they are or are not controlled by the ideals which Reason sets up \ Granted fully that an act may be done from the bare sense of duty, from a desire which is created solely by our conviction that a certain course is intrinsically right or reasonable, this is not in most cases an adequate analysis of a good man's motives. In most of his acts the good man is doing something towards which he has some inclination apart from the consideration that it is his duty. He works for wife and children because he loves them : he speaks the truth because he feels an instinctive repulsion for a lie : he relieves suffering because ' he cannot bear ' to see another man in pain. It is rather in the selection of the right one from among the many impulses by which his will is from time to time solicited, and in the reinforcement of it when it is absolutely or relatively too weak, that the ' sense of duty ' need come into play ^. It is only perhaps at rare crises in the moral life, when duty calls for some great sacrifice or commands resistance to some great temptation, that the ' sense of duty ' becomes the one all- sufficient motive present to the consciousness. It is no doubt eminently desirable that the sense of duty should be always present in the background or, as the Psychologists have called it, the ' fringe ' of consciousness * ; that Reason should be (so to speak) a consenting party to all our actions, however strongly prompted by natural impulses, and be ready to inhibit even the noblest and most generous of them when it threatens to oppose unless tlie idea of Benevolence and that of self-love have been understood in a non-hedonistic sense. ' Cf. below, p. 153 sq. " Dr. Martineau's Ethics have the merit of developing this idea : but he exaggerates when he denies that the love of duty or desire ' to do what is right and reasonable as such,' can ever be a ' spring of action ' at all {Types of Ethical Theory, 3rd ed., ii. p. 279 sq.), ' Cf. James, Psychology, i. 258 sq., 471 sq., &c. 123 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I itself to duty's call. But, even when this is not the case, even when in a particular act or in the general tenour of a man's life conscious and deliberate respect for the Moral Law as such cannot be said to occupy this paramount and predominant position, we do not in fact regard the act or the character of such a man as entirely destitute of moral value. We may regard his defective sense of duty as a moral defect or shortcoming, but we do not regard him as on a level with the selfish pleasure-seeker. It would be a violent perversion of psycho- logical fact to represent that every man who works hard and resists temptations to self-indulgence from love for his wife and children, or from a zeal for his profession, is inspired by pure respect for the abstract Moral Law; it would be a perversion of moral fact (attested in the only way in which moral fact can be attested, by the evidence of consciousness) to say that such conduct is morally worthless i. To do so would involve the denial of moral value not only to much of the normally good conduct of average civilized men, and to all the more elementary morality of children or savages (to whom the idea of a Moral Law or an abstract ' duty ' can hardly be said to have occurred), but also to some of the very noblest acts of generous but one- sided and imperfect characters. The source of Kant's ethical mistake must be sought in his defective Psychology. He assumed, as completely as Hobbes or Locke, that the motive of every action is pleasure except in one case. Reason had, he thought, the power of arbitrarily inter- posing, and acting directly upon the man's will, by laying upon him a categorical command to do this or abstain from that : but, except when and in so far as the man was influenced by pure respect for such injunctions, his will was always under the influence of pleasure and pain. Apart from the power of inter- position accorded to this deus ex machina, the categorical ^ It would perhaps be consistent with Kantian principles to say that the act possesses some moral value because there is some respect for the moral law ; but this explanation does not really express the facts. The man is possibly not thinking of the Moral Law as such at all (I have explained below that he may nevertheless recognize that there is something intrinsically good in his love for wife and children), and yet we do recognize that the disinterested aflfection by itself gives the act moral value. Chap.v, §iii] KANT'S PSYCHOLOGY 123 imperative, Kant was a psychological Hedonist. Moreover, he assumed that an action determined by self-interest was com- pletely 'natural,' that the motives of the Calculating pleasure- seeker were the same in kind as the mere animal impulses of the savage or even the beast. He would probably have explained the behaviour of animals as due to the pursuit of pleasure. He did not recognize the high degree of abstraction, the high intel- lectual and moral development, which is implied in the deliberate pursuit of so ideal an object as ' maximum pleasure ' or ' happi- ness ' in general. Kegarding all desire as desire for pleasure, and the desire of pleasure as merely ' natural,' he was obviously unable to recognize any difference in moral value between one kind of desire and another. Benevolence and malevolence were simply different forms of pleasure-seeking. From the point of view which we have adopted we are able to recognize that the value of the desire depends upon the nature of the objects desired. We can pronounce, and as a matter of fact the moral conscious- ness does pronounce, that devotion to the family or the tribe is a higher and nobler motive of action than devotion to one's own good, love of knowledge better than love of sensual indul- gence, indignation against cruelty or injustice better than resent- ment provoked by jealousy. We may, therefore, ascribe moral value to a man's acts in proportion as they are inspired by a desire of objects which Reason pronounces intrinsically good, although the man may not pursue them consciously because Reason pronounces those objects to be good — still less because Reason pronounces the acts to be right apart from their tendency to gratify a desire for the objects. In proportion as the moral consciousness is developed, or at all events in proportion as the man's intellectual development allows his morality to become self-conscious and reflective, the intrinsic value of the objects which he pursues is recognized with increasing distinctness and abstract- ness ; and this recognition brings with it reinforcement of the higher impulse as against the competing desires which might otherwise take its place. Some degree of this consciousness of value is no doubt necessary to make it a motive which can fairly be described as a higher desire at all. The most rudimen- tary family affection implies a certain consciousness (wholly 124 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I unanalysed no doubt) of the claims or rights or intrinsic worth of other persons, and of the consequent superiority of such an impulse to mere sensual desire — a consciousness -which is not present in the maternal impulses of the lower animals, in which naturalistic writers have seen realized their highest ideal of conr duct. But even in highly developed moral natures, and in some of the highest actions of such natures, it is often impossible to discover the conscious presence in any high degree of respect for the abstract idea of duty or the Moral Law as such. The philanthropist is carried away by an enthusiasm of humanity which does not stop to ask whether to relieve suffering or to fight against oppression is or is not contained in the categorical imperative of Reason. And such zeal for the things contained in the law we certainly pronounce morally good, however little conscious reference there may be to the law which contains them. IV And from this point of view the thought may occur to us : ' if good conduct implies only desire for objects which Reason can recognize as good, why do we need the " sense of duty " or the categorical imperative at all?' May we not say with Aristotle that a man is not really good unless he likes the things that another may recognize as constituting his duty, or even go beyond Aristotle (who did insist that in developed Morality there should be a conscious recognition that the things desired were good), and say 'It is nobler to be so fired by the thought of tyranny and injustice and suffering, so to feel others' wrongs as though they were one's own, that the question never arises at all whether it is a duty to fight against them, or even whether it be Kakov to do so ? Would it not show a positive defect in the man's character if he should decline to make a sacrifice which the good of his family demanded till he had calmly reflected that it was a dutiful or a beautiful thing for him to do ? Is it not better to be socially useful because one loves one's neighbours as oneself than to regard them with indifference, and yet to feed or serve them only because it is one's duty ? ' We are here in the presence of something like an antinomy. Chap.v, §iv] THE MORAL MOTIVE 125 On the one hand, it does seem nobler to love the things contained in the law than to do good things unwillingly because we feel bound to obey the law as such. On the |)ther hand, it seems diiBeult to admit that there can be any nobler motive than devotion to duty as such, or that there can be a perfect character, or even a perfect act, in the inspiration of which such devotion has no place. The solution of our difficulty seems to lie in a consideration which we have hitherto neglected. It is quite true that an action may be good which is done from the love of some good object. The poor man who shares his scanty dinner with a still poorer friend has certainly done an act possessing moral worth. The scholar who ' scorns delights, and lives laborious days ' from sheer love of Learning is not to be treated as on a level with the mere sensualist because he is not habitually inspired by reflection on the duty of research, or even because he may be seriously wanting in devotion to many kinds of social good. But love of any particular good object is always liable to interfere with the promotion of some other, and, it may be, more important good. Love of Learning is good, but the scholar in whom that passion extinguishes all others may become selfish and inhuman, if all social impulses are stifled in its pursuit. Nero's love of Art was a redeeming feature in his character, but the fact (if it be a fact) that he ' fiddled while Rome was burning ' was rather an aggravation than an extenuation of his callous indifierence to human sufiering. Enthusiasm for some particular cause is good, if the cause be a righteous one ; but the root of all fanaticism lies in a devotion to some single good which extinguishes all scruple or respect for rules no less essential to human Well-being than Temperance or the influence of the Church or even the con- version of sinners. Unselfish affection or loyalty to particular persons or societies is good ; but the morality of the man who surrenders himself to it without restraint may degenerate into mere honour among thieves. Family afiection may steel the heart against the claims of a wider humanity. Even a genuine Patriotism may produce absolute blindness to the plainest dic- tates of Humanity or international Justice. And so on. Now duty means, as we have seen, precisely devotion to the various ia6 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I kinds of good in proportion to their relative value and impor- tance. No one then can be trusted at all times and in all circumstances to attribute to each good precisely its proper degree of worth in whom there is not strong devotion to that supreme good in which all others are summed up. It is not necessary that a man should make the sense of duty the sole motive of all his conduct, provided it is always ready to inhibit an action the moment he sees any reason for believing that it is contrary to his duty. The conscientious man will not seek actually to substitute the sense of duty for other motives of con- duct, because he will recognize that many of the commonplace actions of life are better performed from some other impulse, and that the cultivation of altruistic or ideal impulses is actually a part of that ideal of human character which duty bids him promote in himself as in others. He will eat his breakfast from force of habit or because he is hungry ; the sense of duty will only be ready, in the background of consciousness, so to speak ', to stimulate him when appetite fails or to inhibit him when some call of duty demands the suspension or omission of that meal on a particular morning. He will select things to eat and drink because he likes them, provided that he is always ready to modify his choice when there is reason to believe that what he likes is unwholesome or too expensive. He will labour for the good of his family because he cares about it as much or more than he does for his own good, but the sense of duty will always be ready to remind him of the claims of the workmen or the ' There is considerable ethical importance in the modem Psychologist's recognition that we do not think of one thing or ' idea ' at a time, but that while the centre of consciousness may be occupied by some idea, there is a ' fringe ' of other ideas present with various degrees of clearness and dis- tinctness (like the object lying on the outside of the fringe of vision, e. g. persons of whose presence we are conscious without actually looking at them sufficiently to know who they are). An idea present in the ' fringe ' of consciousness can always become the central object of the mental vision when occasion arises for it. The good man will always have the sense of duty somewhere in the fringe of his consciousness. This view is not inconsistent with the doctrine strongly insisted on by many Psychologists that we can only attend to one 'object ' at a time ; but at all events such an ' object ' may in- clude many 'ideas' (in James's sense) which maybe the object of different degrees and kinds of attention. Chap. V, §iv] THE MORAL MOTIVE 127 customers whom his methods of business may prejudice. He will throw himself into the work of a profession, because he likes it, because he is ambitious of success, recognition, oppor- tunities of more interesting or more important work and the like ; but he will be ready to listen to the faintest whisper of a suspicion arising in his mind that the path of ambition and the path of real social duty have begun to diverge. The Priest will devote himself heart and soul to the good of his parish simply because he wants to see his flock happier and better. He will do his work all the more efiectively the more completely he identifies their well-being with his own, the more he takes delight in his occupation ; but the sense of duty will always be ready to press upon his attention the more disagreeable or the more unpopular duty, to suggest the claims of study to the un- studious, the claims of his poor to the man whose heart is in books, the claims of rest or reflection or devotion when absorp- tion in work threatens to dry up the foundations of thought and of feeling. In proportion as a man's habitual desires or 'interests' are identifled with some wider form or element of human good, the danger of collisions between various forms of good — the difference, so to speak, between devotion to a par- ticular end and devotion to the good in general — may tend to disappear. The sense of duty may be less needed as check or as spur to the man of ardent temperament, absorbed in self-denying philanthropy, than it is to the average man whose habitual energies are divided by a remunerative profession and an affectionate family. But it is unnecessary to illustrate the possibilities of moral aberration which attend upon devotion to every form of good less than the whole. And where there is devotion to the whole of human good, to the ' matter ' of the Moral Law, to every kind of good object in due proportion to its intrinsic worth, need there then be any thought of the ' form ' at all 1 Is the idea of ' duty for duty's sake ' part of the highest ideal of character or is it always a note of imperfection? The question is not an easy one, for every term that we use in speaking of such matters is a more or less ambiguous one : but I would suggest the following outline of an answer: — 128 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I (i) Goodness in the narrower moral sense — the right direction of the will — is itself the greatest of goods, and must always be paramount in the ideal man; but the ideal man will care about many other things besides the right direction of his own and other people's wills — knowledge, beauty, particular persons, social intercourse, various pleasures in proportion to their intrinsic value. It is scarcely possible that he should acquire this habitual right direction of the will without more or less consciously thinking of it ; but, in so far as he does come to love the things prescribed by Reason, respect for duty as such will tend to pass into a sense of the relative value of the goods which he loves, and to lose that abstractness, and also that sense of constraint and obligation, which are elements in the sense of duty as understood by Kant and his followers. At bottom the sense of duty is the due appreciation of the proportionate objective value of ends. In this sense alone is the ' feeling of obligation ' an ultimate and indispensable element of the moral consciousness ^. (2) Since the various ends the promotion of which constitutes the content of the Moral Law are all resolvable into some state of conscious beings, it may be said that an ideal love of mankind would supersede all sense of duty as such, provided that this love of persons be taken to include a desire of various goods for them in proportion to their relative value, and in particular a pre- dominant desire for their moral Well-being. In this sense it may be said that ' perfect love casteth out fear ' — even of the Moral Law — and constitutes by itself, in the strictest possible sense, ' the fulfilment of the law.' At its highest the sense of duty is identical with the rational love of persons (including in due measure self-love), and the things which constitute their true good. (3) For a mind which believes in the existence of a Person whose will is absolutely directed towards the true good, the love of such a Person, the conscious direction of the will towards the end which He wills, absorbs into itself the sense of duty. The love of God is the love of duty with the added intensity both of intellectual clearness and of emotional strength which arises from ^ ' Une conscience morale n'aboutit pas a la formula : je dots faire ceci, mais k la formule : ceci est & faire ' (Bauh, L'Expirience morale, p. 32), Chap. V, § v] SCHOPENHAUER'S CRITICISM 139 the conviction that an ideal is also already real. How far and in what sense the belief in such a Person must be considered as involved or implied in the idea of an objective Morality, is a question which must be considered hereafter. Meanwhile I notice merely as a psychological fact that in the religious consciousness the idea of Duty may lose those aspects and associations which often cause a revolt against the idea of a categorical imperative. Kant's categorical imperative has been justly (in some of its aspects) ridiculed by Schopenhauer as a mere survival from the lowest form of the ' servile ' theological Morality which he professed to have abandoned. 'Whether he calls his fetich categorical imperative or Fitziputzli,' makes no difference 1. It was the survival of the drill-sergeant Theology of eighteenth- century Prussia with the drill-sergeant turned into an abstraction. In depersonalizing his imperative and cutting it adrift from its connexion with the real world as a whole, life as a whole, good as a whole, he reduced it to something arbitrary, abstract, almost inhuman. Repersonalize it, regard it as the reflex in the human soul of the Will which wills the supreme good of humanity, and the categorical imperative loses aU those features which tend to present it as an emotion incompatible with and inferior to the other impulses or emotions which may inspire men to right con- duct. To the Christian or the Theist with a worthy idea of God the love of goodness is no longer distinguishable from the love of the concrete good which forms the content of the divine Will as of aU good human wills. How far the love of goodness, whether or not embodied in a Person, can supersede in the actual conditions of human life the sense of effort, of struggle, of sacrifice commonly associated with the aspect of Morality embodied in the term Duty, is another question to which we must return hereafter. If the sense of duty be really the sense of the relative value of ends, it is obvious that some sense of constraint or ' obligation ' must always be connected with the idea of duty, so long as any of * Grwndlage der Moral, § 6 (E.T., p. 50). RABUDA1.L 1 K I30 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I the ends which we rationally desire are incompatible with the attainment of any other such ends which we either desire or feel that we ought to desire. Meanwhile, I may notice the close connexion between the two great defects in the Kantian ethical system which have been pointed out — the harsh ' dualism ' of his view of human good and his erroneous doctrine as to the motives of moral conduct. The ethical criterion to which the Kantian system logically points, and which Kant at moments seems on the verge of deliberately adopting, is the tendency of actions to promote a Well-being or evbaiiiovCa in which there are two elements, (i) Virtue or the performance of duty, (a) Happiness conceived of as mere pleasure. This view has been criticized as inadequate, and it might be possible to enlarge upon the harsh psychological dualism which it involves. It cuts human nature into two halves which have no connexion with, or relation to, or influence on one another. Between these two elements in the ideal human life there seems to be nothing in common : nay, there is at least the appearance of actual irreconcilability between them. In so far as a man succeeds in finding happiness in his work, his Virtue, it might seem, must suffer ('but alas! with pleasure I do it ') ; in so far as he lives for duty, considered as something opposed to his inclinations, he will tend to be unhappy^. Happiness, according to Kant, has value, but no moral value : the work of Virtue on the other hand seems to consist precisely in its tendency to thwart those natural impulses in the satisfaction of which ordinary happiness consists. Now the moment it is recognized that other desires exist besides the respect for the Moral Law on the one hand and pleasure on the other, that these desires may have very various degrees of moral value, that Reason does not condemn or supersede but only regulates desire, that pleasure is good or bad according to the nature of the desire from the gratification of which it springs, — both the inadequacy and the dualism disappear. Virtue no longer seems to consist in thwarting all the other impulses of our nature: happiness is no longer destitute of moral value when it arises from the satisfaction in due degree of all the desires which possess an intrinsic worth of their own, a value which may often be superior ■ No doubt Kant often repudiates this deduction from his principles. Chap.v, §vi] USE HUMANITY AS AN END 131 to the value which they possess as mere sources of pleasure. The conditions of human life may prevent the actual attainment of this ideal reconciliation, but there is no necessary or invariable antagonism between the two ends ; they tend to pass into a single, internally harmonious and self -consistent, ideal of life. VI It may be desirable to add a word about the second of the three moral criteria put forward by Kant — the rule 'Use humanity whether in thine own person or in that of any other always as an end, never as a means only.' It is the principle less frequently insisted on in Kant's own writings, and its relation to the other is not very precisely determined. He uses it chiefly to prove the immorality of suicide and of sexual transgression. There can be no question of the deep moral significance of the principle, but it is too vague to be really of any use as a moral criterion without knowledge of a kind which cannot be extracted out of the formula itself. "We must know what is the true end of human life before we can tell whether a certain course of conduct does or does not involve treating humanity only as a means. Now Kant (as we have seen) only recognizes two ends in human life — one primary, i. e. Morality, the other secondary, l e. happiness. On Kant's view of Free-will it is impossible to make another man immoral or less moral. Hence it would seem that he has no right to condemn conduct towards another for any other reason than its interference with his other end — happiness. And this is clearly not always done by the kind of conduct which he has in mind. Nor, even if this consideration be waived, can he show that the conduct which he condemns involves using the body of another, or one's own, as a means, any more than much conduct which no one could describe as immoral. I am using a porter's body as a means when I employ him to carry trunks for me, and there is nothing immoral in my doing so. I am not using him ordy as a means, if I pay him for his work and treat him as a moral being no less entitled to a share in all the true goods of life than myself. Kant never said anything so absurd (though he is constantly cited as doing so) as that we should never use K a 132 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I humanity as a means, but only that we should never use it as a means without using it also as an end, and it is impossible (apart from some conception of a concrete end or good of human life) to show that sexual immorality might not be equally compatible with a like recognition of others' claims. We should only have to insist on just and considerate treatment of those who have been called the 'priestesses of humanity^.' The one kind of exchange of services is, on Kant's premisses, exactly on a level with the other. Kant's real feeling was no doubt that the conduct in question was inconsistent with a true ideal of the relations between man and woman, but it was impossible for him to prove that inconsistency so long as he narrowed his conception of the ideal human life down to the performance of social duty on the one hand and the indiscriminate enjoyment of pleasure on the other. It is not the treating of humanity as a means that strikes us as wrong (for that might quite well be compatible with recognizing it also as an end), but the treating of humanity as a means in this particular way, as a means to such and such a kind of sensual pleasure, to such and such an end in which Reason can find no value. It is only because we have judged already that such treatment is a degrada- tion of humanity that we pronounce it to be using humanity ' only as a means.' Once again, we see the impossibility of reducing moral judgements to a merely intellectual, non-moral principle; of getting a criterion out of mere formal conceptions, which take no account of the content or intended consequences on which depends all the morality or the immorality of our actions. Mere universality or freedom of contradiction is no test of goodness or badness. The judgement of value cannot be reduced to any other sort of judgement — a judgement of formal consistency or a judgement as to the relation between ends and means, which takes no account of the character of those ends. It ' Eant has specially in mind the case of certain other kinds of sexual vice, and there his contention would be still more hopeless, if -we assume that happiness (= pleasure) is the only end except duty considered simply as the promotion of pleasure for others {Tugendlehre, Th. I. § 7, Semple's Translation, 3rd ed., 1871, p. 240). Chap, V, §vii] THE KINGDOM OF ENDS 133 is only in estimating the value of an end that the moral Reason really comes into play. Abstract the form of the law from the matter of it, and there is nothing left on .which a judgement of value can be passed. A rule of action is not moral because it is consistent, unless it consistently conduces to an end in which Peason can recognize value ; neither is the making of humanity a means immoral unless the end to which it is a means be one which Reason refuses to recognize as part of the true end for man. The non-recognition of this principle involved Kant in the absurdity of gravely questioning whether it was lawful to cut one's hair, and of solemnly pronouncing the conduct of a woman who cuts off her hair to sell it — irrespectively of the motives for which she wants money — not ' altogether devoid of blame ^.' Such a verdict will probably fail to commend itself to readers of Mr. Marion Crawford's touching 'Cigarette-maker's Romance.' VII It has generally been recognized that the best expression of Kant's fundamental ethical principle is to be found in his third rule — ' Act as a member of a kingdom of ends ' : that is to say 'Act in such a way as to treat thyself and every other human being as of equal intrinsic value ; behave as a member of a society in which each regards the good of each other as of equal value with its own, and is so treated by the rest,' in which each is both end and means, in which each realizes his own good in promoting that of others. That such an ideal of human Society must, as far gjs it goes, be approved by the moral con- sciousness, follows from what has been already said : but, considered as a guide to the details of conduct, it suffers from the same fatal ambiguity as the preceding formulae. There is no sufficient definition or explanation of this good of others which we are to promote. We have still got nothing but a ' form ' without any content. If we fill up the deficiency from other parts of Kant's system, and interpret each man's end as ' goodness + happiness,' that (as has been explained) gives us an intelligible, but a rough and inadequate, criterion of Morality : and on that 1 Tmgendlehre, Th. I. § 6 (Semple, p. 239 sj.). 134 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I interpretation, which in many passages would appear to be Kant's own ^, we must cast to the winds the whole of his elaborate attempt to get at the details of conduct without appeal to experience or calculation of consequences, and to ex- hibit that good will as actuated by the mere form of a universal law without any regard to the content or matter of it. In truth there run through the whole of Kant's ethical teach- ing two inconsistent and irreconcilable lines of thought — one of which is the basis (though only the basis) of all sound ethical theory ; while the other has proved the fruitful parent of every extravagance, superstition, and absurdity by which the scientific study of Ethics has been, and still is, impeded. Every formula of Kant's may be interpreted, and at times appears to be interpreted by himself, in each of these opposite ways. 'Duty is a categorical imperative.' That may mean 'there is a right course of action which is intrinsically right and reasonable for every man whether he Ukes it or not,' and that is simply an analysis of what duty means to any one to whom it means anything at all. Or it may mean 'there are certain acts which we recognize as being right to do without thinking of the ends (social or otherwise) which they will tend to realize,' than which no better definition could be given of the irrational in conduct. ' Duty for duty's sake ' may mean that ' we should pursue the good or intrinsically valuable end just because it is good,' or it may mean that we should act without reference to an end at all. 'Act on a principle fit for law universal ' may mean ' Pursue the ends which Reason 1 ' The realization of the summum honum in the ■world is the necessary object of a will determinable by the Moral Law' (Kritik d. prahtischen Vemunft, Dialektik, Pt. II, § 4, p. 262, and Abbot, p. 218). ' Now inasmuch as virtue and happiness together constitute the possession of the summum bonum in a person, and the distribution of happiness in exact proportion to morality . . . constitutes the summum bonum of a possible world ; hence this summum bonum expresses the whole, the perfect good' (Dialektik, Pt. II, Abbot, p. 206). Of course, in so far as Eant did not recognize that the good will means the will that wills the promotion and just distribution of happiness, he was still liable to the criticism that he has provided no means of determining what will is moral : but on the whole it would seem that in such passages as the above he meant to define virtue as the willing of acts tending to promote happiness and the just distribution of it. Chap. V, § viii] GOOD AND RIGHT 135 pronounces to be intrinsically valuable for others no less than for thyself,' or it may mean ' Make the avoidance of internal inconsistency the criterion of thy conduct.'* ' Treat humanity as an end and never merely as means ' inay mean ' Regard the true Well-being of every man as possessing an intrinsic worth,' or it may mean ' Regard it as beneath thy dignity to be of use to the society in which thou livest, and indulge in phantastic scruples about things which do no real harm to thyself or anybody else.' The ' kingdom of ends ' represents simply a com- bination of the two last maxims, and is liable to the same charge of ambiguity ; though of all the formulae employed by Kant it is the one which lends itself most readily to the more rational interpretation. VIII One more way of expressing our criticism upon the Kantian system shall be attempted, because it will supply a convenient opportunity of giving a definite answer to an ethical question of fundamental importance — the question which is the logically prior conception, the idea of ' good ' or the idea of ' right.' Kant never thoroughly made up his mind about this question. He always started with the idea of ' right ' ; and all his difficulties arose from the attempt to give a meaning to, and to find a content for, this idea of 'right' without appealing to the idea of ' good.' In our view the idea of ' good ' or ' value ' is logically the primary conception, though psychologically the idea of ' right ' may often in modem men be the more early developed. That action is right which tends to bring about the good. There is no attempt here to get rid of the ultimate unanalysable 'ought.' The good is that which 'ought' to be'. ' Such a statement is in no way inconsistent with the doctrine which I fully accept, that the word ' good ' is indefinable : we can only biing out the real meaning of the idea by the use of words which equally imply the notion. ' Good,' ' Ought ' (when applied to ends), ' Value,' ' the End ' I regard as synonymous terms. Mr. Moore, in his recent Principia Ethica, has done well to emphasize in a very striking manner that ' good is indefinable ' ; but when he goes on to say (p. 17) ' and yet, so far as I know, there is only one ethical writer, Prof. Henry Sidgwick, who has clearly recognized and stated this fact,' I cannot admit the historical accuracy of his statement. To say t I 136 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I The difference between the two terms is this : that the term ' right ' is applicable only to voluntary actions ; the term ' good ' is applicable to many things besides acts. Entirely apart from the question, ' who caused such things 1 ' I judge that pain or discordant music or ugly pictures (i.e. of course the enduring of pain by conscious beings, the listening to discords or the contemplation of bad pictures by conscious beings) are bad things. They seem to me bad whether they arise from chance or necessity or voluntary action. Only because I have so judged is there any ground for the judgement ' it is right, in so far as it is possible to get rid of these things ' ; but, whether they can be got rid of or not, they are equally bad ^. The will that nothing of writers who (hke Mr. Moore and myself) learned the doctrine largely from Sidgwick, I should contend that it was taught with sufficient distinctness by Plato (whatever may be thought of his further attempt to show that only the good has real existence), Aristotle, and a host of modern writers who have studied in their school— by no one more emphatically than by Cudworth. The only criticism which I should make upon Mr. Moore's exposition of it is that he ignores the other ways in which the same notion may be expressed, and in particular the correlative notion of 'right' or ' ought.' He is so possessed with this idea that the ' good ' is indefinable that he will not even trouble to expound and illustrate it in such ways as are possible in the case of ultimate ideas. ' The non-recognition of this principle (so fully admitted, as we have seen, by Lotze) is to my mind the leading defect in the Bishop of Clogher's in many respects admirable Short Study of Ethics (2nd ed., 1901). Bishop d'Arcy fully appreciates the defects of Kant's ' formalism,' and of the attempt to pronounce acts right or wrong without regard to consequences known to us from experience : yet we find him asserting ' the end, or good, of man is man doing, the concretion of man and the world. This concrete activity is the only thing which can be called good in itself (pp. 16&-9), and 'the only true good is to be good in the sense of performing the good act ' (p. 277). Such statements seem to me to imply a reversion to Kant's attempt to say that to cause toothache is wrong without having first decided whether tooth- ache (however caused) is or is not a bad thing. And it goes beyond Kant in pronouncing that nothing but a moral act is good at all. Wundt seems to me equally open to criticism, when he talks about happiness as being ' not an end in itself, but a by-product of moral effort ' (Ethics, Eng. Trans., iii. p. 90), or about an ' objectively worthless sum of individual happinesses ' (ib., p. 83). It is curious that so modem and ' scientific ' a Moralist as Wundt should be almost the only living thinker of high eminence who out- kants Kant in his view of the exclusive value of a moral end, which, how- ever, is to him not so much the perfection of individual wills as a vague and impersonal ' progress of humanity.' Chap. V, § viii] THE IDEA OF VALUE 137 deliberately causes or refuses to fight against such things may be, and I believe is, a worse evil than the pain or the bad music or the ugly pictures. But unless these ftiings were evils, the will that refused to remove them would not be evil either ; its acts would not be acts of a wrongly directed will. Kant generally ends by coming round to this view — that the right or rational act is the act which wills the good. Unfortunately he did not see that with that admission his attempt to avoid the appeal to experience completely breaks down. It is possible, though it is irrational, to will particular acts without attending to the consequences which experience shows likely to result from them ' ; it is impossible to pronounce that something is good until one knows what it is. No experience will tell us what is good unless we include in our idea of ' experience ' an un- avowed judgement of value ; but without experience of what a thing is it is impossible to say whether it is good or not. It is obvious that this necessity of experience for sound ethical judgements goes a long way to explain the actual divergences of moral codes. When the Caliph Omar (if the story be not a myth) ordered the Alexandrian library to be burned, it is probable that he knew very imperfectly what the Alexandrian library or any other library really was. I do not deny that there might be fanatics who knowing a good deal about the contents of these books would still have ordered them to be burnt ; but it is probable that a more extensive acquaintance with their contents would have modified the Caliph's judgement. The consistent Kantian, i. e. a disciple of Kant in his most logical but least rational movements, ought to be able to say whether they should be burned without knowing what sort of books they were or even that they were books at all. Our moral judgements are ultimately judgements of Value. The fundamental idea in Morality is the idea of Value, in which the idea of ' ought ' is implicitly contained. The advantage in- volved in the use of the term ' value ' lies in its freedom from * Strictly no doubt there must be some feature in the act known to us to account for our choosing it, but the motive might be the simple desire to act without further reflection— the 'pure cussedness' from which, indeed, it is so hard to distinguish the motive of the ideal Kantian, when Kantism is understood on its irrational side. 138 THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE [Book I many of the exaggerations and mystifications which have some- times created a prejudice against the term ' ought,' even in minds which have no prejudice against the reality which it signifies. The idea of ' good ' and the idea of ' right ' are, as it seems to me, correlative terms. It is implied in the idea of ' good ' that it ought to be promoted ; the idea of ' right ' is meaningless apart from a ' good ' which right actions tend to promote. If, finally, we ask what is the relation of the idea of value to the idea of ' moral ' value, I should answer that all that has value has moral value, in the sense that it must be moral, in due proportion to the amount of that value, to promote it ; but by moral value we generally mean the particular kind of value which we assign to a good character. That value is, as I believe, the greatest of all values. Pleasure is a good, and it is right for a man to promote it in himself as in others. We assign value to the pleasure, but we do not assign any particular value to the acts or to the characters from which it springs, since this promotion of private pleasure does not necessarily indicate a good character, and even the promotion of the highest ends may have no moral value when the promotion of such ends forms no part of the man's motive; only when we recognize a man's conduct as exhibiting the preference of the good because it is the good or the preference of some higher to some lower good for its own sake do we assign to it the peculiar kind and degree of value which we usually term moral value ^ ' I have in this chapter for the most part avoided all criticism of sides of the Kantian Ethics which could not be discussed without reference to the defects of the metaphysical system with which they are so closely con- nected. Even Kant's purely ethical position I have only examined so far as seemed desirable as a means of helping forward my own argument. CHAPTER yi REASON AND FEELING In the preceding chapters I have assumed that Kant is right in making Morality to be essentially rational, in holding that moral approval is a judgement of the Intellect, not a feeling or an emotion. This position seems now to require some further justification than it has yet received, and this justification may perhaps best take the form of a reply to the objections which are commonly made to it. The reply will be one which may be thought to involve considerable qualifications of the creed known as ethical Rationalism as represented by such men as Clarke in the seventeenth century and by Kant and other modern Idealists. The most obvious form which objections are likely to take will be something of this kind: Does not common opinion recognize that Morality is an aflfair, not of the head, but of the heart? Are not our moral perceptions attended with a glow and warmth of feeling which is entirely absent from our perception (say) of a mathematical truth ^? Are not good men very often stupid and bad men often intellectual ? If we admit that there is an intellectual element in what is commonly called Conscience, must we not at least say with Bishop Butler that Conscience is neither merely ' a sentiment of the under- standing ' nor ' a perception of the heart,' but ' partakes of the nature of both ^ ' ? ' Cf. the passage quoted from Martineau, Types of Ethical Theory, below, p. 165. ' Dissertation of Virtue. This change from the more rationalistic position of the Sermons was perhaps due to the influence of Hutcheson. He now uses the term ' moral sense ' as a synonym for Conscience. 140 REASON AND FEELING [Book I The common objections seem to imply several misconceptions — misconceptions, however, for which the exaggerations of Kant and other ethical Rationalists are, it must be admitted, largely responsible. In the first place, when it is held that moral judgements are given by Reason, we do not imply that their rationality is the sole reason for the acts being done. Un- doubtedly it is possible to see that an act is right with absolute clearness and not to do it — nay, to feel practically little or no disposition to do it. Even when an act is done out of pure ' respect ' for a recognized duty, there must at least be present a ' desire for what is right and reasonable as such ' (to use Professor Sidgwick's phrase) or the duty will not be done. And we have seen reason to hold that Kant was wrong in insisting that this rational desire is or ought to be the sole motive which impels us to the performance of good actions. It has been admitted that normally the ends prescribed by the Practical Reason are objects of desire for their own sake, that actions directed towards such ends may possess moral value even when the thought of an abstract law does not enter into the agent's consciousness at all ; and that even the best actions of the best men are commonly influenced by other desires besides bare respect for duty. Now when Conscience presents itself as partly an ' emotion of the heart,' the term is probably used to include not merely the perception of what is right but also the impulses which cause what is right to be done — to include at least the ' respect ' or love for the good and perhaps also the whole of those benevolent or other higher afiections and emotions which are approved by the moral Reason as motives to action^; while the question at issue between ethical Rationalists and their opponents is simply the question ' by what faculty or part of our nature do we discover that an act ought to be done ? ' It may further be admitted that the judgements of Practical ^ ' The single act of conscience may be a feeling, an emotion, an impulse or a judgment ' (Wundt, Ethics, Eng. Trans., vol. iii, p. 60). Wundt is surely wrong in making Conscience or avveiSrjtTis mean originally a ' knowing with God,' instead of an ' inner ' or ' self-knowledge.' The word, it is signifi- cant to observe, is first found in the generation immediately after Aristotle — a period of great progress both in ethical feeling and ethical theory. Chap, vi, §i] THE MORAL FACULTY 141 Reason normally create a more or less powerful impulse towards the performance of what they enjoin; and, in those who are powerfully influenced by such judgements, they are undoubtedly accompanied by an emotion of a kind which is wholly absent from mere mathematical judgements. Still, it is possible to distinguish between the judgement that the act is right and the emotions by which that judgement is accompanied. It will perhaps be contended that in some persons who would commonly be described as very good men emotion of one kind or another is so obviously the main inspirer of their conduct that it is difficult to detect any intellectual judgement at all. And it may be admitted that as a matter of psychological fact the process by which many people come to attach the idea o'f rightness to particular kinds of conduct is almost entirely an emotional one : but still I should contend that, in so far as the idea of goodness or rightness forms the object of that emotion, the intellectual judgement must necessarily be there. This liability to be influenced or even wholly determined by emotional causes is no peculiarity of ethical judgements. All sorts of psychological causes may be at work in inducing a man to accept a particular theory as to the causes of the French Revolution; but the most prejudiced and passionate view of the matter and the most calm and scientific would be alike impossible to a man whose consciousness did not contain the intellectual concept or category of Causality. Nobody would ever dream of describing such a historical judgement as itself a mere emotion. Just in the same way, emotion may inspire particular judgements of right and wrong, but it could not create the idea of ' right ' or of ' good.' Even in those cases where the actual motive is most clearly emotional, some per- ception of the goodness of the act may be said to enter into the exciting cause of the emotion, or the emotion may be said to be accompanied by a judgement of its own value. A man may devote himself enthusiastically to some philanthropic object, from a passion excited by the abstract idea of Justice, or he may be moved by a pure love of humanity which is nevertheless accompanied by the judgement that it is good to feel such a love. In some cases one, in others the other may seem to be the more 143 REASON AND FEELING [Book I appropriate mode o£ statement, but the two kinds of judgement — the judgement which ascribes value to the emotion and the judgement which ascribes value to an object and by so doing excites the emotion which leads to action — run into one another. All that is necessary to contend for at present is that judge- ment and emotion are logically distinguishable, and that the judgement of value does more than merely record the fact of the emotion being felt. II When the popular unwillingness to recognize the rational character of our moral perceptions assumes the form of a philo- sophical theory, it tends to pass either into the theory of a 'moral sense' or into the theory of a moral 'faculty called Conscience ' which is represented as wholly sui generis — distinct alike from intellectual judgement and from any kind of feeling or emotion. Let us briefly examine each of these views. In the writings of John Locke the Rationalism of Cumberland and the Cambridge Platonists had degenerated into mere theo- logical Utilitarianism. Locke continued to use the old language about Morality being rational ; but in him that language had come to mean almost the opposite of what it was originally intended to mean. The appeal to Reason was intended as an answer to Hobbes, and now Reason was used in a sense in which Hobbes himself would have had no objection to base Morality upon it. By Reason was no longer meant a faculty which originates the idea of something intrinsically good in itself, and which pronounces what things are intrinsically good, but merely the faculty which connects ends and means ^. ' Exception may be taken in some quarters to the use of the word ' faculty ' at all in this connexion. The word has fallen into disfavour partly because by a certain school it has been used to suggest the idea of a definite number of mental activities sharply distinguishable from and independent of each other — planted, as Plato would have said, as it were ' in a wooden horse,' to the ignoring of the unity of self-consciousness, and partly because the invention of a specific faculty has often taken the place of logical or psychological analysis of complicated mental processes. I hope I have sufBciently guarded myself against these mistakes. But to prescribe altogether the use of the word ' faculty ' is to fall into the very superstition which the denouncers of it have in view. Whatever we do, there must be Chap, vi, §ii] THE MORAL SENSE THEORY 143 To Locke Virtue was rational because it could be demonstrated that without it a man will infallibly go to Hell. Hence in men like Shaftesbury and Hutcheson we find a recoil from a way of thinking which seemed to make Morality a mere matter of selfish calculation. It was thought that Morality would be all the safer if it were removed altogether from the jurisdiction of the intellect, and placed under the control of 'the heart.' Moreover, these men shared, or at least had in- completely shaken ofi", the metaphysical presuppositions of the Master against whose Ethics they had revolted. Experience, by which was practically meant sensation, was regarded as the sole source of knowledge. If, therefore, Morality was to be shown to be something real, it must, it seemed, be revealed to us by some kind of feeling or sensation. Yet to base Morality upon the deliverances of the ordinary sensibility, upon the pleasures and pains of the bodily senses, meant of course Hedonism pure and simple. To avoid this consequence they invented a special sense which was to be the source of our moral know- ledge, just as sight is the source of our colour-perceptions and hearing of our sound-perceptions. Morality was made to rest (like aU our knowledge) upon a kind of feeling; only it was a specific feeling. Moral approbation was a feeling wholly sui generis, arising from the contemplation of good acts; dis- approbation a feeling similarly arising from the contemplation of bad acts. Not to insist on the complete want of analogy between the bodily senses and this organless sense of Morality, all such schemes are open to one insuperable objection. If moral approbation is a mere feeling, how can it claim any superiority over other feelings? Granted that it gives me a pleasant feeling to do a kind action, and that it causes me a particular kind of discomfort to tell a lie, that may be a very good reason under normal circumstances for my doing the one and avoiding the other. But supposing I do not happen to be sensitive to this particular kind of feeling, or supposing I am so constituted that a violation of some social conventionality a faculty or capacity (Simius) of doing it. In asking what is the moral faculty, I mean only to ask by which of the distinguishable activities of the single self-conscious self our ideas of right and wrong are to be referred. 144 REASON AND FEELING [Book I shocks me more than a moral offence^, why shoTild I attach any paramount importance to this particular feeling of moral disapprobation ? I may have a certain capacity for the pleasures of whist, but I do not feel bound to play it if I like reading a novel better. If we grant that immorality does normally cause me mental or emotional distress and discomfort of a particular kind ; still under particular circumstances Morality may cause me more pain and discomfort of another kind. I may dislike the pains of Conscience much, but I may dislike the thumbscrew more. Why am I bound, if threatened with torture for refusing to reveal a secret which I am bound to keep, or falsely to accuse an innocent man, to prefer the pleasures of an easy conscience to those of a whole skin and easy nerves ? To insist on the specific character of the feeling in question is nothing to the point; the pleasures of whist-playing are different from those of touch or taste, but they are not necessarily superior to them. The taste of port is specifically different from that of sherry, but it is not necessarily superior to it. If it be said ' Oh 1 but you are inwardly conscious that these pleasures are superior in kind, and not merely in quality, to those of sense, that they ought to be attended to more than others,' is not that really admitting that we have to do with something more than a mere feeling, with a dictate of Reason or a judge- ment of value ? It is not the feeling which claims obedience, but the judgement which assigns a value to that feeling. Moreover, not only does a Moral Sense theory fail to supply any reason why the individual should accord to his own moral perceptions a primacy among the feelings and emotions of which his nature is capable, but it is totally unable to assign any ^ ' The not taking into consideration this authority, which is implied in the idea of reflex of approbation or disapprobation, seems a material deficiency or omission in Lord Shaftesbury's Inquiry concerning Virtue. He has shewn beyond all contradiction that virtue is naturally the interest or happiness, and vice the misery of such a creature as man, placed in the circumstances which we are in this world. But suppose there are particular exceptions ; a case which the author was unwilling to put. ... Or suppose a case which he has put and determined, that of a sceptick not convinced of this happy tendency of virtue or being of a contrary opinion. His determination is, that it would be leithout remedy' (Butler, Pref. to F^een Sermons). Chap, vi, § ii] OBJECTIVITY OF MORAL JUDGEMENT 145 universal validity to such moral perceptions. Inconsistent or contradictory feelings, qua feelings, are equally true and valid for those who feel them. When the cololfr-blind man calls the red light green or grey, it really is green or grey to him ; his judgement is as true as that of the man who pronounces it red. Feelings as feelings are not ' true ' or ' false ' at all ; while as to the judgements based upon them, the judgement of A that he sees red and of B that he sees green, these no doubt possess objective validity, but such statements as to what two men actually feel are perfectly compatible with one another. Now, if a good act means simply an act which causes me to experience a particular kind of feeling which I call moral approbation, it is undeniable that such feelings are occasioned in different men by different, and even opposite, kinds of conduct. The pious fraud may occasion no less pleasure to the man brought up to regard such acts as right than a sacrifice made in the cause of truth will cause in the heart of another differently educated. A Spanish bull-fight excites feelings of enthusiastic approval in the minds of most Spaniards and feelings of lively dis- approval in most Englishmen. Observe exactly where the difficulty lies. It is not the practical difficulty of ascertaining moral truth. Every ethical system has to admit that the Conscience of the individual is not infallible, that men's ethical judgements do as a matter of fact contradict one another. How- ever strongly I feel that a certain course of conduct is right, I may make a mistake, just as I may make a mistake about a scientific or historical theory to which I may be no less passionately attached. The objectivity of the moral judge- ment does not mean the infallibility of the individual, or even of a general consensus of individuals at a particular time and place. What is meant is that if I am, right in my approbation of this conduct, then, if you disapprove of it, you must be wrong. If Morality be a matter of objective truth or falsity, then the Moral Law remains unaffected, though you and I — nay, the whole human race in its present stage of moral development — may have erroneously conceived some of its provisions. But, if the goodness of an act means simply that the act occasions a specific emotion in particular men, then the same BABHDAIiL Z 146 REASON AND FEELING [Book I act may be at one and the same time good and bad. Moral feelings will have no more objective truth or validity than any other feelings which vary in their nature or intensity with the varying sensibility of different men's skins or sensory nerves. The bull-fight will be neither right nor wrong, but simply right to some people, wrong to others, just as mustard is neither objectively nice nor objectively nasty, but simply nice to some people, nasty to others ^. It may perhaps be replied, ' These feelings are not what make things right or wrong; they are merely the subjective index by which we recognize the presence of an actual quality in the world of objective fact.' This is no doubt what was really meant by the doctrine of Moral Sense in the hands of con- structive Moralists like Hutcheson. A full reply to the objection would involve a discussion of the metaphysical system which it presupposes. No doubt if knowledge of any kind could be explained by mere feeling, Morality so explained would at least possess as much objectivity as the rest of our knowledge. Moral Sense theories are no more fatal to Morality than Sensationalism is to Science. I can only point out here that, just as all knowledge implies something more than feeling, so, if Morality is to possess any universal truth or validity, moral perceptions must be regarded as judgements. The specific moral feeling can be at most merely the occasion or index by which we are enabled to make the judgement, it cannot be its sole source ; just as I cannot actually make the judgement that this triangle is larger than that without sensible experience, though there is more in the judgement than mere sense. The essential idea of ' good ' cannot come from feeling, though feeling may some- times be psychologically the cause or occasion of my pro- nouncing this or that particular act to be right or good, III It has been the practice of ethical Rationalists to compare the moral faculty with the faculty by which we immediately appre- ' It may indeed be contended that there is an aesthetic, and therefore an objective, element even in gastronomic matters. If so, we must substitute some pleasure of a still more purely sensuous type. Chap, vi, § iii] THE MATHEMATICAL ANALOGY 147 hend mathematical axioms or the laws of thought. I have myself contended that it is possible to discover moral axioms, the truth of which appeals to us very much in the Same way as the truth of the axioms 'If equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal ' or 'Two straight lines cannot enclose a space.' Such ethical axioms are the three great laws of Prudence, Rational Benevolence, and Equity, which Professor Sidgwick regards as the ultimate basis of Ethics. And I have fully admitted the validity and importance of these axioms. But this comparison of moral to mathematical axioms may be overdone. It may be insisted on in a way which ignores some of the characteristic features of our ethical judge- ments, and its palpable failure to represent the facts may lead to a reaction against the whole idea of rational Morality. Rationalistic Moralists have not always observed that in them- selves there is nothing ethical about these axioms of Prudence, Benevolence, and Equity except the bare formal notion or category of 'the good' which they involve. The axiom of Equity, 'one man's good is of as much intrinsic worth as the like good of another ^,' may, indeed, be reduced to the form of a merely analytical judgement. That which I recognize as having value in one man I must recognize as having the same value in another, provided it is really the same thing that is implied in the assertion that it has value. And the two other axioms — those of Benevolence and Prudence — simply assert that more good is always more valuable than less good. They are not merely comparable to the axioms of Mathematics ; they are simply particular applications of those axioms. The judgement that the value of the good of all is greater than of any one man's may be treated as a mere case of the mathematical axiom that the whole is greater than its part. But so far there is nothing really ethical about the judgement except in so far as it involves the ethical proposition that value or good is one of the things which have quantity. Yet, after all, such a way of representing the matter is really superficial ; for it is in the conception of value that the whole meaning of the judgement lies. And that conception of value cannot be analysed away ^ This qualification of the axiom (not recognized by Utilitarians like Bentham or Sidgwick) I shall explain and defend in Chap, viii of this Book. La 148 REASON AND FEELING [Book I into the mere statement of an emotional fact. Considered as a mere statement of psychological fact, no assertion could well be more false than that my feeling towards one man, the emotion which I experience in knowing that he is benefited or that he is injured, is the same as that which I should experience in the case of any other. The ethical Rationalists are, it appears to me, quite right in treating these judgements as genuine axioms which are to some extent analogous to the axioms of mathematics; but such axioms are by themselves quite incapable of solving any concrete ethical problem. The really ethical element in them is contained simply in the con- ception of 'value' or 'good,' and we cannot use them till we have pronounced some concrete thing or experience to be good. They resemble the axioms of Mathematics just because they are purely formal. All that they can do is to direct us as to the way we are to distribute ' the good ' when we know what it is. The really ethical judgement lies in the pronovmcement that this or that is good. And, when we come to the judgement which pronounces that this or that is good or has value, the judgement assumes a form which seems psychologically much less like the mathematical, and much more like the aesthetic, judgement — a form consequently in which it can with much more plausibility be compared to a mere emotion or even a mere sensation. I can give no reason why I judge this pleasure to be higher than that — the pleasure of Shakespeare to the pleasure of champagne — except that I see it to be so, just as I can give no reason why I know this to be beautiful or that to be square, except that I see that they are so. We naturally express our judgement by saying ' I feel it to be so,' rather than ' I know it to be so.' And that is one reason why they have so often been supposed to be mere feelings. Very often probably this immediacy is all that is meant by those who insist on treat- ing them as feelings of a supposed 'Moral Sense.' But only a Sensationalist can suppose that the expression 'I feel tliat A is £' represents a mere feeling. ' I feel ' is here merely a loose popular synonym for 'I judge.' Propositions cannot be felt. Another fact which has favoured the theory is the impossibility Chap, vi, § iii] THE AESTHETIC ANALOGY 149 of expressing our real and concrete ethical judgements, as distinct from the merely formal and abstract axioms just con- sidered, with the scientific accuracy and definiteness characteristic of other self-evident truths. Although the judgement ' pleasure is good but not so good as Virtue ' is an immediate judgement, and so far resembles a mathematical axiom, it is one which does not admit of being expressed with the same precision aa mathe- matical judgements. And still more when we come to particular applications of our idea of value, when we ask what is the relative value of this as compared with that pleasure, or what is the comparative importance for an individual or a nation of a definite kind of artistic sensibility and of social feeling, we do not find that consensus among all who barely understand the meaning of the terms employed which can be claimed for the axioms of mathematics. And the essence of the really ethical judgement lies not in general axioms of the type suggested above but in the concrete judgement ' this particular pleasure or this kind of knowledge is good or valuable,' ' that kind of pleasure is bad ' ; here the immediacy seems to be much more like the immediacy of the aesthetic appreciation, or even that of a mere judgement of perception, ' this is green.' All these characteristics of the ethical judgement tend to win acceptance for the Moral Sense theory of moral apprehension. How far the analogy between aesthetic judgements and ethical can be admitted, must depend upon the view which we take of the aesthetic judgement itself. The Moral Sense writers have usually assumed that aesthetic approval is merely a particular kind of subjective feeling. The judgement ' this picture is beautiful ' means to them merely ' I get from the contemplation of this picture a particular kind of pleasant feeling.' And, if that were the case, the relegation of the moral judgement to the same category as aesthetic appreciation would be fatal to that authority or universality which we divine to be of its essence. On the other hand we may be prepared to deny that the judgement of one man on matters of Art or Poetry is as good as another, as would undeniably be the case if the aesthetic judgement were nothing but a matter of feeling. We may maintain that there is a right and wrong in matters of aesthetic appreciation as well 150 REASON AND FEELING [Book I as in matters of conduct. We may claim for the aesthetic judgement a certain objectivity, and consequently a partly rational character. But Aesthetics is a much more difficult Science than Ethics. The objectivity of aesthetic appreciation is much more difficult to defend, the relation between the rational or intellectual and the merely sensuous or emotional elements in it much more difficult to determine, than is the case with the moral judgement. At all events, the theory of an absolute standard of aesthetic value could not be defended without a more elaborate treatment of the whole subject than would be here in place. Consequently, I dispense myself from any further attempt to define the relations between aesthetic and moral value, and will only point out that the analogy between aesthetic perception and moral may be admitted without giving up the position that there is an element in the moral judgement which cannot be reduced to mere subjective feeling or emotion and which must be regarded as belonging to the rational or intellectual part of our nature. And when once the rational and objective character of the aesthetic judgement is admitted, we may with great advantage insist upon this rather than upon the mathematical analogy, because the comparison avoids a suggestion which is apt to cleave to the mathematical analogy — the suggestion that these judgements of value can be made prior to and independent of experience ^, The judgement ' this view is beautiful ' no doubt (in so far as it claims that the man who does not think so makes a mistake) asserts something which is not given in experience, but no one contends that it can be made without looking at the view, or even without the experience of other views and pictures by which the man's aesthetic sensibility has been cultivated. Even the ordinary judgement of perception (' this is a square object ') involves, for those who have learnt the lesson of Kant's Critique, much besides mere sensation — the forms of space and ' It is of course admitted by Eant that even the mathematical axioms in point of time are not prior to experience ; his contention is that, when once there has been experience of space or number in general, their truth is seen independently of any particular fact or facts of experience — that the universal truth of the principle is implied or presupposed in each particular judgement about space or number. Chap. vi,§iv] NEED OF EXPEKIENCE 151 time, the categories of substance and accident, quantity, &c. And so the judgement 'this act of charity is good' involves no doubt experience, for we cannot pronounce that it is good without knowing what it is, an admission which was, as we have seen, never explicitly made by Kant himself. But it remains true (i) that the judgement of value is an immediate judgement of the Practical Keason, not a mere feeling; (3) that the essence of the judgement — the idea of value — is a distinct intellectual concept or category ; and (3) that the moral judge- ment possesses a universality or objectivity which cannot be ascribed to mere sensations or to the judgements of perception founded upon them^. So much is involved in the very idea of Morality or duty or moral obligation. The very heart of our moral conviction is that there is something which every rational being, in so far as he is rational, must recognize as intrinsically right, that that something must be the same for all persons under the same conditions, and cannot be dependent upon the subjective caprice of particular persons. The Moral Sense theoiy, duly realized and thought out, necessarily involves the admission that that conviction on our part is a delusion. There is, therefore, no real analogy between an ethical ' perception ' (if the word is to be allowed) and the sensations, perceptions, or emotions with which they are compared by the Moral Sense school. So far then ethical Rationalism is right, when once we have got rid of Kant's attempt to make out that the ethical judgement is not merely not derived from experience but does not require as its condition knowledge derived from experience ^. IV But there are further elements of truth in the Moral Sense position to which we have not yet done justice. ^ Of course there is an objectivity even in the judgement of perception. My toothache as a feeling is purely subjective in the sense that I alone feel it. But my judgement ' I have a toothache ' claims objectivity. I mean that the man who denies is in error. ^ By experience is here meant of course experience in the sense of the Empiricists— mere sensible experience. There is no objection to saying that moral judgements are derived from experience if we include in the term ' experience ' the whole of our intellectual as well as our other psychical activities. 153 REASON AND FEELING [Book I In the first place we must emphasize what is already implied in the admission that experience is necessary to the ethical judgement. This admission implies that the ethical judgement is invariably based upon some fact of feeling ; since experience, though it includes more than feeling, does always involve feeling. The ethical judgement pronounces that something has value, and we do not on reflection pronounce that anything can have value except some state of consciousness. I do not, indeed, believe that feeling represents the only element in, or aspect of, con- sciousness which has value ; but feeling is always an element in every state of consciousness, and an inseparable element. And no judgement can be pronounced as to whether a state of con- sciousness is good without taking the feeling-aspect of it into account. Feeling is therefore always part of the ground on which an ethical judgement is based. This represents the true element in Hedonism. The mfetake of Hedonism lies in trying to abstract the feeling side of consciousness from its other sides, and making the whole value of the consciousness to lie in that feeling-aspect, the cognitive and conative elements being deliber- ately put out of sight ; while the value of feeling is supposed to reside in the mere abstract pleasantness in respect of which all pleasures are qualitatively alike, and not in the total content which is pleasant. We have already accepted the position that knowledge and goodness are intrinsically valuable elements of consciousness. Yet these things taken apart from feeling are as much abstractions as feeling when taken apart from knowledge and volition. And it is impossible to say what value we should assign to the latter, if they were capable of actually existing apart from the feeling by which they are necessarily and inevit- ably accompanied. I can, indeed, intelligibly say that knowledge and goodness, even when accompanied by bodily pain, are good ; but, even when the pursuit of knowledge or the doing of a good action brings with it a measure of pain, some measure of pleasant feeling normally accompanies those intellectual or volitional states. When I say that the state is on the whole painful, I mean that its pleasantness simply as pleasantness is outweighed by pains of another kind, and yet I may think that it possesses more value than many states which on the whole are pleasant. Chap. vi,§iv] PLEASURE IN ALL GOOD 153 We may, indeed, attach value to knowledge even for a con- sciousness which does not find pleasure in its possession ; but, if so, we must do so either for its uses or effects or propter spem, as a step to an enjoyment of which the man is capable but to which he has not yet attained. In a consciousness which was for ever incapable of feeling the smallest pleasure or interest in what it knew, it would be difficult to say that knowledge could be an end-in-itself. Indeed, the very idea of an ' end ' implies the existence of beings with tendencies, desires, or impulses for which some kind of satisfaction can be found in that end. This satisfaction is not the same thing as pleasure, but there can be no satisfaction without some (however low a degree) of pleasure. ' The good ' is an intellectual category, but it is a category which would be meaningless in a purely knowing consciousness. Hence it may be doubted whether we could rationally attach any value even to the good will in a consciousness which not only did not derive, but was intrinsically and for ever incapable of deriving, any pleasure or satisfaction from its goodness. We may, indeed, recognize that the good will has a value, and ought consequently to be cultivated, in those who, as a matter of present fact, do not care about goodness and derive no pleasure from it. But then we should say that they ought to care about it. In so far as it is possible for a man to do his duty without liking the dutiful action taken by itself (apart from the pains incidentally involved in it), we should say that that was because he is not good enough. The value of goodness does not mean merely its actual pleasurableness to the agent at this or that moment ; but still I can as little conceive it psychologically possible for a man to say 'My whole will is completely devoted to and concentrated upon the good, but it gives me not the smallest pleasure or satisfaction to be good ' as I could attach any meaning to the statement ' I recognize indeed the exquisite beauty of that land- scape, but, as far as my own pleasure goes, I would just as soon gaze at a blank wall ' ; though I can quite intelligibly say ' This picture gives me more pleasure than that other which I acknow- ledge to be more beautiful.' Beauty is more than pleasure, but it is unintelligible without it. Value is not a feeling, but it cannot be recognized as attributable to anything in consciousness 154 REASON AND FEELING [Book I which can excite no feeling of pleasure in its possessor. The fallacy of Hedonism lies in the attempt to estimate the value of the feeling element in abstraction from the other elements of consciousness. Knowing, feeling, willing are, for us at least, the three inseparable aspects of consciousness. It is upon conscious- ness taken as a whole that we pronounce our ultimate judge- ments of value; the nature of its knowledge and its will must necessarily colour and determine the value of the feeling by which in any consciousness they are accompanied. Invariably, then, moral judgements imply facts of feeling as part of their ground — that is to say either feelings actually experienced or desires which imply feeling in the present as well as feeling in their subsequent satisfaction ^. Those feelings need not be the feelings of the person making the judgement, and in many cases there is nothing specifically moral about them. I judge that it is wrong for me or any one else to stick pins into a human being, simply because it hurts. If I did not know that it hurts, if I did not know what pain is, I could not judge it to be a bad thing, or the act of causing it wrong. Given that knowledge, I can pronounce the act wrong, quite apart from any sympathetic or other feeling which the act may excite in myself. But sometimes we can recognize a far less superficial truth in the Moral Sense position than this. The actual ground of my judgement may be simply an emotion ; and, although an emotion to which I assign value must be to some extent pleasant, I may assign it a value which is not measured by its pleasantness. I may approve of an act not merely on account of the pleasure or pain which it causes, but also on account of the emotion which it excites, the emotion from which it proceeds, or the emotion by which it is accompanied. I may approve of maternal afiection not merely on account of the benefit arising to the babe and to society, but for its own sake ; and that emotion, though it is a source of pleasure, is assuredly one which also causes much pain. Yet the value which we ascribe to it is certainly not smallest in those cases in which the pain is greatest. Still more closely do we approach to a recogni- ' What we usually call a desire I take to be a state of feeling and a certain state of -will or conation combined. Chap, vi, §iv] MORAL EMOTION 155 tion of the specific emotion which the Moral Sense theory wishes to make the beginning and end of the ethical judgement when we take into consideration the feeliftgs which the mere contemplation of some acts excites in a well-regulated mind, whether the mind be the agent's or that of some ' disinterested spectator ^ ' — say for instance the disgust which is experienced at an isolated act of otherwise practically harmless drunkenness, or our feeling about acts of impurity. It is in cases of this sort that we can least of all ignore the fact that not merely ordinary feelings of pleasure but certain specific kinds of higher emotion do form part of the ground on which our moral judgements are based. They are part of what the moral judgement pronounces to have value. And they are judgements which could not really be pronounced by a consciousness which could not experience those emotions, which knew only on the one hand the data supplied by the senses and on the other hand the abstract axioms of the Practical Reason. But this recognition of the absolute indispensability of certain specific emotions (in many cases) to our moral judgement does not in the least invalidate what has already been said as to the intellectual, rational, objective character of the judgement of value. The judgement that a certain emotion has value is a different thing from the mere emotion itself^. Without the ^ ' For, if we once suppose tlie general physical basis of animal life to be seriously altered, it is impossible to say to what extent the types of senti- ment and action which, under present conditions, approve themselves as life-preserving and beneficial to the individual and the species would be still in place ' (Taylor, The Problem of Conduct, p. 41). Prof. Taylor's insistence that the details of duty would be different in different surroundings is quite justified, but he seems to me to think that this proves more than it does — that it altogether upsets any claim for objective validity or a ' rational ' character in our moral judgements. But (i) it is true that I may recognize that the ferocity of the tiger is as life-preserving and beneficial to its species as the charity of the Saint ; yet I need not pronounce that it has the same in- trinsic value : and (2) though the judgements as to right and wrong for human nature would be different if our physical constitution were altered, that does not show that every rational intelligence, in proportion as it is rational, would not pronounce the same course of conduct to be right for man as he is. And this is what we mean by treating the moral judgement as objective. " ' Notre vrai guide n'est ni I'instinct, ni une pensee transcendante, c'est la reflexion sur I'instinct ' (Bauh, L' Experience morale, p. 96). 156 REASON AND FEELING [Book I a priori and purely intellectual idea of value we could never pass from the judgement .' I feel such and such an emotion ' to ' it is right for me and others to do the act which excites in me this emotion ' ; though the judgement could equally little be pro- nounced by a person incapable of experiencing the emotion, or at least of understanding and respecting its existence in others through the analogy of something more or less similar in his own experience. It is not the existence of the feeling but our judgement that that feeling is good that enables us to say that the act which excites it is right or wrong. It is not merely because it is a feeling excited by conduct that it can claim any pre-eminence over other feelings. If that were so, it would have no validity except for the persons naturally disposed to feel it. But our judgement that certain conduct is wrong does not dis- appear because as a matter of fact we may know that it excites no such feeling of disgust or repulsion in the person guilty of it. There are doubtless individuals who really do feel no disgust whatever at isolated or even habitual acts of drunkenness (though they are probably fewer than those who merely pretend to feel none) : but we do not say that on that account drunkenness is right for such men. On the. contrary we say that, if a man has not got such feelings, so much the worse for him : they are feel- ings which he ought to have. He falls short of the ideal of manhood if he has them not^. There are other cases where natural feelings of disgust at particular kinds of conduct are pronounced on reflection to have no value whatever — e.g. the young medical student's sensations on first entering a dissecting room. We pronounce that such feelings should simply be got over as quickly as possible. The ultimate truth then which the Moral Sense school distorts is that in some cases a state of feel- ing is judged to have an absolute value, which, though more or less pleasant, is not measured merely by its pleasantness, and that such states of feeling form in and for themselves, entirely ' Cf. Aristotle, Ethic. Nicomach. III. i. § 13 (p. mo 6) "O yap ludiav I) opyi^ofievos ov boKtl 81 ayvoiav nparreiv . . . ayvoei fiev ovv iras 6 poxfirjpos & 8ti Trpdrrcw Koi &v aeKTeov, Koi Sia Trjv ToiavTrjV ipapriav SSiicoi Kai oXa>f Kaxo'i ytvovToi' TO 6' aKovaiov ^ovXerai XtyeirOai ovk €i ris ayvoft to 6apTiKri ap}(ljt, " I cannot call to mind any printed expression of this doctrine, though it is taught by high authorities in Oxford— a fact which must be my apology for quoting a private letter. Chap, vi, § vi] FEELING AND JUDGEMENT 169 the other. The judgement " this is right " is not a moral judge- ment unless one has, more or less, the moral emotion (for in the judgement " this is right," when the ground-is any authority, the moral emotion and the judgment proper fall upon the authority, not strictly upon the particular point), nor is it a moral emotion unless it claims universality. This, I think, is the same view as yours, but perhaps you might more carefully avoid the use of language which suggests juxtaposition (reason + feeling); which is surely unsatisfactory, and leads to what one finds inadequate in the language of Hume on one side and Kant on another.' To such a line of criticism I should reply as follows : (i) With regard to the suggestion about mere 'juxtaposition,' I have very definitely admitted that in all cases some feeling is, in part, the ground of the judgement. That being so, the judge- ment could not be made without the feeling, but the feeling which is the ground of a moral judgement is, in my view, not always any specifically moral or 'higher' kind of feeling. In some cases the judgement implies a particular kind of ' higher ' emotion, but not in all. In some cases the only feeling which is implied as the ground of the judgement is simple pleasure and pain, not in ourselves but in others, though without some experience of them in ourselves we should not know what they are in others. To know that this act causes pain in others is all that I want to enable me to condemn it. That pain is the negation of good, and that the good ought to be promoted, are self-evident truths perceivable by the intellect. How far in actual fact there exist persons so constituted as to be capable of seeing that truth without experiencing the smallest emotional repulsion against causing pain, or the smallest inclination to avoid it themselves, is a question of empirical Psychology on which I should not like to pronounce a decided opinion. But I see nothing self-con- tradictory in the supposition that there may be such persons. There certainly seem to be persons who do make this judge- ment, but in whom ethical emotion and ethical inclination are so small as in no way to account for the judgement being made. (3) And even in persons who are not altogether incapable of moral emotion, some moral judgements are not as a matter of I70 REASON AND FEELING [Book I fact accompanied by any emotion at all, though the same judge- ment may on other occasions call forth emotion of great strength. The proposition that pleasure is good and pain bad — or that some particular trifling pleasure of my own is good and conduct which interferes with it wrong in myself or in another — is one that can be assented to without any emotion whatever ; and yet that proposition is the ultimate ground for my condemnation of some act of cruelty which might excite in me feelings of warm indignation. And I regard it as a matter of great theoretical importance to insist that the intellectual categories of good and right are as distinctly present in the cool and calculating judge- ment that it is unreasonable to throw away a large pleasure for a smaller one (no matter whose that pleasure be), as in our enthusiastic approval of some heroic act of self-sacrifice. (3) Of course we can, if we choose, include in our idea of good and evil, right and wrong, the emotion which they excite in normally constituted persons, or even all the varieties of emotion that they may excite in abnormally constituted persons. On the principle that we do not know a thing fully till we know all its relations, it may no doubt be said that we do not fully under- stand the meaning of right and wrong unless we do take into account these facts of our emotional nature. To a person incapable of any such emotion the terms would no doubt not mean all that they mean to one who is capable of it. But I am not prepared to admit that it would mean nothing to him. Not only would it mean something to him, but that something is, I should hold, the very essence of the moral judgement, con- sidered simply as a judgement. The ideas of good and evil, right and wrong, seem to be as distinguishable in thought from any emotion accompanying them as the idea of a circle is froin the aesthetic feeling which may perhaps be in fact its inseparable accompaniment. To insist upon the greater practical importance of the feeling attending the moral judgement would be wholly beside the point. (4) The contention that the term ' right' means nothing apart from the emotions by which moral judgements at the higher levels of moral experience are usually accompanied seems to me open to a further objection. I am unable to recognize the Chap, vi, §vi] NO SPECIFIC MORAL FEELING 171 existence of any one particular specifically ' moral ' emotion ' . An intellectual category must be one and the same for all intelligences, though there may be a greater or less degree «f clearness, explicit- ness, and adequacy in the apprehension of it at differenir stages of intellectual development. But emotion is essentially a variable and subjective thing. And the emotion excited by good or bad conduct, and by the judgements of moral approbation or dis- approbation which they call forth, are no exception to the rule. These emotions are difierent in the case of different races, different individuals, different periods of life. Even in the same individual they vary from day to day with our changing moods and circumstances. The emotions which different kinds of good or bad conduct excite are very different, even when the intellectual approval or disapproval is the same. Few people approve an act of commonplace Justice with the warmth which they bestow on an act of Generosity, and yet Justice is quite as important as Generosity. When I judge a massacre to be wrong, my judgement is exactly the same whether it has been committed by Englishmen on Englishmen in the streets of London, or by Chinamen on Chinamen in the streets of Pekin, but my emotion would probably be very different both in kind and. intensity. Even with characters of exceptional moral earnestness, there is every reason to suppose that the emotion accompanying their ethical thinking must be of very different kinds. It is im- probable that a mind of John Wesley's severity could ever have felt the tender humanity of St. Francis of Assisi, or that in a man of sympathetic nature like John Stuart Mill the sense of duty assumed the emotional tone with which it was invested in the Philosopher whose personal character has stamped itself for ever upon the doctrine of the ' categorical imperative.' To say that the category of value or of duty was present in the mind of Mill as much as in that of Kant, however little the Metaphysic of the former may have recognized its presence, is an assertion which I understand and accept. Whether the emotional accom- ' ' Es giebt demnach nicht ein bestimmtesGefuhl, welches als moralisches Gefulil von alien anderen Gefuhlen verschieden ware, sondem jedes Gefuhl entspricht in seiner Tendenz mehr oder minder sittliclien Aufgaben, oder es widersprieht denselben in hoberem oder geringerem Grade ' (Hartmann, Das sittl. Beumsstsein, p. 148). T7a EEASON AND FEELING [Book I paniments of their judgements were the same is a psychological question which it would be a piece of the most unwarrantable dogmatism to determine a priori. If, therefore, the assertion that a moral emotion claims universality means that the same emotion must be present in all moral persons, I see no ground for the assumption. Nor, indeed, in strictness can I understand the meaning of asserting that any emotion whatever ' claims universality.' That, when I recognize a value in a certain emotion, my judgement claims universality I admit ; but I recognize the probability that many different kinds of moral emotion may possess a high degree of intrinsic worth, and I see no reason for selecting one particular type of it as the one and only 'moral emotion,' in the absence of which the judgement could not be moral at all. It may no doubt be urged that the ideal man would feel exactly the same kind of emotion on the same occasions. That would be a somewhat difficult contention, inasmuch as a certain limitation, and therefore a certain indi- viduality, seems essential to a nature that is to be truly human. But, whatever may be thought of this point, the assertion supplies no ground for saying that the judgement is not in thought quite distinguishable from the emotion. The ideal man might be unable to think of universal gravitation without profound 'cosmic emotion,' but that supplies no reason for declaring that a Physicist who has never felt a moment's ' cosmic emotion ' in his life must be ignorant of universal gravitation. (5) It is only, as I have already pointed out, in the case of certain particular ethical judgements (not in all) that they simply cannot be made by a consciousness incapable of certain emotions : here where that is so, the judgements turn upon the actual value of the emotions as elements in human life. A consciousness which was entirely lacking in all the higher feelings — aesthetic, intellec- tual, social, moral — to which the developed moral consciousness assigns value, would assuredly have a limited and distorted moral ideal, but it does not follow that it would attach no meaning at all to the ideas of right and wrong, or be unable to pronounce correctly upon simple problems of elementary Morality. It might still for instance be able to recognize the wrongnesB of the individual deliberately preferring his own Chap, vi, §vi] INFLUENCE OF INTEREST 173 interest to that of the community, and to apply that judgement to many particular cases. (6) It may even be admitted that those judgements which do not psychologically depend upon the presence of emotion are not very likely ever to be made — to say nothing of the respect paid to them — by a mind totally destitute of the emotions which naturally accompany them. If the human mind could ever be a passionless thinking machine, it might indeed be contended that the emotionless man would be a particularly good judge of right and wrong in respect of those questions — questions for instance of Justice in the distribution of pleasure — which lay within its range. But no mind can ever be a passion- less mirror of Reality. In the mind which is (relatively or absolutely) devoid of moral or social feeling, the place of such feelings is sure to be taken by other feelings, emotions, and desires, which must necessarily distort the moral judgement or totally prevent its exercise. Even our most abstract thinking is dominated by purpose or interest of some kind. Minds which take no interest in Morality do not think about it at all. I see no reason why for instance a person incapable of moral emotion should not be able to recognize the injustice of slavery, though he might have felt no inclination to agitate for its abolition. But we know that as a matter of fact the minds which first pronounced slavery to be wrong were minds dominated by a passion for Justice and an ardent love of Humanity. In minds which have no such passion, indiflference may prevent any judgement whatever upon the problem; interest may suggest wrong judgements. This doctrine of the inseparability of the moral judgement from one particular kind of emotion seems to me not only unwarrantable in itself, but dangerous in its theoretical ten- dency : for it obscures the fact that the judgement of value by which we recognize that my own pleasure is a reasonable end of pursuit is exactly the same in its intellectual character as our recognition of an intrinsic value in heroism or saintliness, although the emotional accompaniments of the two judgements may be very different. It is true no doubt that the amount of value which we recognize in the former case is much smaller 174 REASON AND FEELING [Book I than that which we recognize in the latter. To the pleasure which it is right to pursue we assign value: but we do not attribute much intrinsic value to the will which wills that pleasure unless the preference of the pleasure implies devotion to some higher kind of good, or to the good as such, on the part of the agent ; and this is commonly the case only when the pleasure aimed at is not the agent's own, since only in this case is there usually present any strong temptation to pursue some other end, though we may ascribe some small value to the preference even of private interest to mere brute passion. Conduct directed towards the good is right whether it implies Virtue on the part of the agent or not : but such conduct need not possess value in any appreciable degree. The value may often lie in the end or consequences, not in the act itself. And the term moral value is commonly reserved for the value that we attribute to character — to the good will or at least to inclinations and dispositions, desires and emotions, which we recognize as conducive to or resulting from a settled bent of the will towards the good^. It is important no doubt to insist on the superior value which we ascribe to such preference for the good. But the two kinds of value are not absolutely incommensurable. However much superior the value of a good act may be to that of a transitory pleasure, we still use the term ' value ' of both, and we use it in the same sense : the two kinds of value differ as being at the top and the bottom of the same scale, not as representing two totally incommensurable scales. There can be only one ultimate scale of values, however heterogeneous the objects which we appraise by that scale. Thus to the actual relief of pain and healing of wounds which resulted to the man fallen among thieves from the act of the good Samaritan • we assign value. If it were not good for wounds to be healed, it would not have been right for the good Samaritan to heal them; but we should not call the injured * Prof. Taylor seems to me to forget this use of the term ' moral value ' when he declares, without qualification, that ' it is quite impossible, after the fashion of popular philosophy, to draw a line between qualities that are moral and qualities that are not so. Whatever is felt by men to be wortJi having at all has, eo ipso, moral value, or rather, moral value is a tautologous expression ' {Problem of Conduct, p. 297). Chap, vi, § vi] CONSCIENCE 175 man's feeling morally good. On the other hand, to the good Samaritan's act we assign ' moral value,' and we may even assign moral value to the emotion which promptad, or to the pleasure which resulted from the act, even though the emotion and the pleasure may not have been under the immediate control of the will, because it would be an indication of character or of a settled bent of the will. Such is the ordinary usage of language. The distinction between ' moral value ' and ' value ' is no doubt one of great practical importance, inasmuch as it implies a conviction of the supreme and unique value of a rightly directed will. But there is not the absolute disparity between them that is suggested by the idea of a distinctively moral emotion in the absence of which our judgements as to the value of this or that element of human life could not be moral judgements at all. It has been contended in this chapter that ' the moral faculty ' is essentially Reason. By that is meant that the ideas of Right and Wrong, Good and Evil, are intellectual concepts or categories which cannot be reduced to any kind or sort of mere feeling. But it has been fully admitted that practically the power of deciding between right and wrong involves many emotional elements, and these are certainly included in what is popularly spoken of as Conscience. Conscience or (to speak more scientifically) the moral consciousness may be held to include not merely the capacity of pronouncing moral judgements, but the whole body of instincts, feelings, emotions, desires which are presupposed by and which influence these judgements, as well as those which prompt to the doing of the actions which they prescribe^. No more accurate definition can be given, because the 'moral faculty' cannot actually exist apart from the other elements of self-consciousness. The Practical Reason implies all the other activities of Reason and would be impossible without them ; and it implies also, not a mere single specific feeling or emotion, but a whole complex of feelings and ^ Another element in what is commonly called Conscience is simply the individual's consciousness of the fact that he is or is not doing what he himself believes to be right. ' It perceives whether those [actions] it judges right, or those it judges wrong, are actually adopted ' (Shadworth Hodgson, Philosophy 0/ Experience, vol. IV, p. 86). 176 REASON AND FEELING [Book I emotions upon the value of which the Practical Reason has to pronounce. ' Conscience ' or the moral consciousness is a name for a particular aspect of the single self which is thought and feeling and will. Morality would be impossible and meaningless, or at least defective and one-sided, for a being in whom any one of these elements were wanting ^. ^ It may be broadly stated that all recent moralists who approach the sub- ject from a purely psychological point of view tend to agree with the Moral Sense position in making Morality ultimately to rest upon feeling, though they may be less clear about the specific and distinctive character of the feel- ing. To Hoffding for instance the value-judgement is simply a feeling, arising largely from Sympathy {Ethik, pp. 41, 72, &c.) ; the categorical imperative is ' an instinct' (ib., p. 55). Though quite aware that this position involves the sacrifice of all objective character for moral judgements, he seems to me constantly to use language and to express ideas which imply such an objec- tivity. Simmel insists strongly on the fact that the ' ought ' is an ultimate and unanalysable category of our thought, but makes the whole content of the ' ought ' come from feeling (Einleitung in die Moralwissenschaft, Berlin, 1892, I, pp. 23 sq., 54, 239, &c.). But it is difficult to see how it is possible to assert the validity of a category (and if it is a category of thought its validity can hardly be denied) without any power to apply it to a matter or to give it a content. Such an assertion would seem to be like maintaining that we have indeed a category of quantity or number, but are quite incapable of counting. Granted that our judgements in detail are liable to be influenced by all sorts of psychological considerations, just as subjective motives con- stantly lead to numerical miscalculations (e. g. of the numbers present at a meeting in which we are interested), it is difficult to see how there can be a category which we cannot validly use at all. After all the category of ought in general is simply an abstraction got by comparing together actual judgements of value. If what is contended is that we do think values but that such judgements possess no objective validity, the reply to it must simply be the general metaphysical reply to all Scepticism. Much of Simmel's polemic against Rationalism in Ethics seems to turn upon the old confusion between Reason and reasoning (e. g. in Einleitung, I, pp. 98-99) ; at the same time he has done a service by pointing out with much acuteness and vivacity some of the psychological causes which as a matter of fact do largely determine our actual moral judgements, e. g. our tendency to assume that the usual or normal conduct of our society is the right course. But it is perhaps a mistake to take Simmel's use of the term ' category ' too seriously. It appears that ultimately the category of ' end ' (practically identical with that of ' ought ') is a merely ' subjective ' category (II, p. 347, &c.) which would seem to mean that we have a confused idea of an ' ought ' which we take to mean something, but which is of no more objective signifi- cance than the idea of ' Kismet ' or that of a Centaur, though (like those ideas) it may influence human conduct. But the admission that as a matter Chap, vi, note] THE AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT 177 of psychological fact these ideas of ' ought,' ' end,' ' the good,' &c., do exist, and cannot be resolved into something else, represents a great advance on the crude Psychology which simply explained them as ' fear of tribal ven- geance,' or the like. When writers like Simmel deny their objective validity, they do so as sceptical or sensationalistic metaphysicians, not as observers of psychological fact. These admissions become particularly valuable when we turn to the philosophical fireworks of such a writer as Guyau (Esquisse d'une Morale sans obligation ni sanction), whose original discovery seems to be that any factor of our consciousness which he cannot explain on the assumptions of his own Philosophy may be got rid of by the simple device of calling it ' mystical.' NOTE ON THE AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT A chapter on the relation between the moral and the aesthetic judge- ment might have formed a natural and desirable sequel to the treatment of ' Reason and Feeling ' in Ethics, but I do not feel that my acquaintance with Aesthetic Philosophy enables me to undertake it. A few remarks on the subject may, however, be useful with a view to clearing up what has been said in the preceding chapter, and to prevent misunderstanding. (1) I distinctly recognize an objective element in our aesthetic judge- ments. That is implied in our strong conviction that there is a right and a wrong about such judgements. They too, like moral judgements, are in a sense judgements of value. But I do not say that they are ' objective ' in exactly the same sense and to the same extent as the ethical judgement. For they seem to be more closely connected with the variable physiological organization of individuals than ethical judgements. It has been suggested, for instance, that the restful feeling of green for human beings is due to effects on the human eye and nerves of its frequency in Nature — especially for our arboreal ancestors; while the effect of red ('like the sound of a trumpet,' to quote the famous remark of a man blind from his birth) is due to its infrequency in Nature. By beings with a different evolutionary history, therefore, a red landscape with a few touches of green would, it may be contended, be pronounced as beautiful, and beautiful in the same way, as we think a landscape of predominant green with a few touches of red. So again the beauty of a Gothic window as compared with a square one may plausibly be connected with the frequency of the Gothic arch in woods and the rarity of square arches in Nature. Even if such theories are well founded, they do not destroy the existence of an objective element in our aesthetic judgements. The perfect intelligence might still pronounce the aesthetic feeling which we experience good, though in beings otherwise constituted other aesthetic experiences might be good also. It may be contended that we have something parallel to this in the moral laws which are obviously applicable only to beings constituted like man, though the good for such beings may be something in which every rational intelli- gence would recognize value. But then I for one should contend that the BA8HDA1.L I IT 178 REASON AND FEELING [Book I more ultimate of our moral judgements, such as that which recognizes the value of love, are independent of such differences in the structure of individuals or of society (see Bk. IIIj chap, iii), and represent not merely what all rational beings would pronounce valuable in us, but an element of experience which must exist and have value in all higher minds and in God. It may be that we might say the same of aesthetic judgements — that the value which may be recognized in aesthetic judgements which differ and even contradict one another in detail, might all be referable to some higher principles of aesthetic judgement which would explain them all ; but we can form a less distinct conception of such principles than we can of the fundamental moral laws. I cannot undertake to discuss the matter here, but will only notice that aesthetic judgements (as we know them in human beings) do seem to be more intimately connected with, and inseparable from, sensations which presuppose a particular physiological organization than the most fundamental moral judgements, although I do not regard that fact as any reason for denying that they are in a true sense objective. (2) If the moral judgement is essentially a judgement of value, its sphere must be absolutely all-embracing. There can be no department of human life, no kind of human consciousness or experience, upon which the moral Reason may not pronounce its judgements of value. People in whom aesthetic interests are stronger than ethical interests frequently attempt to set up a sphere of Art to which Morality is supposed to have no relation whatever. Such persons simply show that they have too narrow a view of what Morality is. What they really mean, or ought to mean, is that aesthetic activities or enjoyments have a high value quite apart from any further effects upon conduct in the narrower sense — that it may be morally right to paint and look at pictures which have no tendency to make the artist or the beholder go away and perform his social duties better. That artistic enjoyment has this high value and forms an important element in true human good, I have strongly contended. Our aesthetic objector may, however, mean more than this. He may mean that any amount of aesthetic enjoyment, and all kinds of it, are right, and right in all circumstances. Such a proposition is so extravagant that it could hardly be made by anybody who really contemplated the full consequences of his assertion ; but, whether the proposition be true or false, it represents an ethical judgement — as much so as the proposition that the interests of Art must sometimes give way to the claims of social duty, and that there are in the world plays not devoid of aesthetic value which it was morally wrong to write, and which the State is right in not allowing to be acted. The question what kinds of Art it is good to produce, how much time it is right for such and such persons to spend in producing them or in con- templating them, within what limits the aesthetic indulgence should be restrained in the interests of wholesome moral feeling — these and such-like questions are moral questions. Morality deals with ultimate ends or elements in the end. No indulgence which does not form part of the true ultimate end can possibly be justified. Chap, vi, note] ART AND BEAUTY 179 (3) The question may then be raised ' what is the relation between the moral and the aesthetic judgement ? ' The moral judgement is a judgement of vaUie ; but is not, it may be asked, the aesthetic judgement also a judgement of value — at least for those who recognize its objective character and refuse to reduce it to the judgement 'this gives me a particular kind of pleasure'? When I pro- nounce that a thing is aesthetically ' good,' does not that imply that it is an end which ought to be pursued ? Up to a certain point there can be little diflBculty in answering the question. We may say that the moral judgement is in all cases the final one, but that the moral judgement mi^st use the data supplied by the aesthetic judgement. The aesthetic judgement tells us ' this is beautiful.' The moral judgement goes on to say ' Beauty, or this particular kind of beauty, has an intrinsic worth, and consequently ought to be pursued.' We may even say that for a consciousness which recognizes the intrinsic value of Beauty, the judgement ' this picture is aesthetically good' practically implies and includes the judgement 'the contemplation of this picture has a certain intrinsic worth,' though other and purely moral judgements will be required to determine its relative worth as compared with other goods. (4) But what if the moral judgement and the aesthetic judgement actually contradict one another? In ordinary cases of what may be superficially called coUisiona between the moral and the aesthetic judge- ments no real diflSculty arises. When I say 'this play is aesthetically a good one, but on this particular evening it would be wrong for me to go and see it,' this is merely an ordinary case of the collision between goods. The judgement ' the contemplation of this play has a certain worth ' is not rendered untrue by the judgement ' What I should do with my time and money if I did not go to see this play, has a greater worth, and it is my duty not only to seek the good but the greatest good. Hence it would be morally wrong to see the play.' The real difficulty arises, not when we pronounce merely that what is aesthetically good is yet a good which for certain persons in certain circum- stances ought to be surrendered in favour of a greater good, but when we pronounce it to be from a moral point of view actually bad. In some cases it may be possible to isolate and separate the good element from the bad. We may approve a novel as a work of Art, and yet condemn the moral tendency of incidental reflections or remarks by the author, or of certain disgusting episodes which (even if not actually irrelevant to the plot as it stands, as is often the case) may still be regarded as contributing nothing to the aesthetic effect of the piece which could not equally be secured by a somewhat different plot. Here we may say ' the work of Art as such is good ; but a novel ought not merely to be artistic but to be decent. What I pronounce morally bad forms no part of what I pronounce aesthetically good.' But in other cases the immoral tendency may be too intimately allied with the artistic effect of the piece to be treated in this way. The particular kind of Art in question may be aesthetically good, and yet by its very nature appeal to passions which had better (from a moral N a i8o REASON AND FEELING point of view) not be excited, at least in this way and in this intensity. This is particularly the case, I should judge, with certain kinds of Music in their effect upon highly musical natures. But even here is not the case after all only a case of the comparison of values ? If we condemn the piece — that is to say, if we judge that it ought not to have been written, or that it ought not to be performed, or that particular persons should not hear it, or that it should not be listened to frequently — we judge that, though the worth which it possesses qua work of Art is a real worth, that worth is not so great as the worth of properly regulated passions, and that, if and in so far as the former kind of good cannot be enjoyed without the loss of the latter, that good is one which we should do without. Of course I need hardly say that we may condemn the moral tendency of a book or a piece of music without necessarily saying that nobody should under any circumstances read the book or hear the music. The good may still— for particular persons and in particular circumstances — outweigh the evil. But that in some circumstances it is a moral duty to abstain from enjoyments which are aesthetically admirable cannot be doubted. In the great majority of cases — at least as regards Literature — the important thing is the relative proportion which the morally stimulating and the morally depressing in our reading bear to each other. Ruskin has remarked that the important thing is not so much what we don't read as what we do read. The properly nourished mind may for a sufficient purpose read, without injury and even with advantage, much which in itself has an immoral tendency, just as the properly nourished physical frame can swallow many germs of disease without deleterious effects. The principle must apply to a greater or less extent to other branches of Art. (5) Another way of putting the matter is to say that, when we pronounce a particular experience aesthetically good but morally bad, we mean that it appeals to and satisfies a part of our nature, and a part which, when we look at it in abstraction from our nature as a whole, we pronounce good : but that, when compared with our ideal of human nature as a whole, this particular indulgence fails to be approved. To indulge in it — for certain persons, in certain circumstances, or beyond a certain point, or in some cases to indulge in it at all — would be to attach disproportionate value to this side of our nature as compared with others. The case of an aesthetic indulgence given up in deference to moral considerations differs from the case of a banquet condemned and abstained from as too costly or luxurious only in the fact that the value of the good surrendered is, when taken in abstraction from our ideal of human life as a whole, a higher or more valuable good than the pleasures of good eating and drinking. (6) From the point of view which has now been reached it may be possible to make a further step towards the solution of the difficulties presented by the problem of objectivity in the aesthetic judgement. The difficulty with which we are confronted is that (a) we are unwilling to admit that the judgement (say) of a certain Australian Minister of Educa- tion who solemnly pronounced that he had himself examined the works of William Shakespeare and could discover nothing in them but profanity Chap, vi, note] OBJECTIVITY OF BEAUTY i8i and obscenity, and that he should therefore discourage their use in schools, is objectively as good as that of the cultivated critics of all nations who regard Shakespeare as the greatest dramatic genius that the world has produced ; and yet that (6) so many of our aesthetic judgements are so obviously connected with features of our particular human (sometimes even our local or racial) experience which we can perfectly well imagine to be different in another planet. Take for instance the undeniable tendency to regard the usual or normal or typical form of man or any other animal as the more beautiful, and to regard any considerable deviation from it as ugly — even when the individual thereby approximates to a type which in another animal we should think beautiful. We do not like a human face which approximates to the shape which in a horse or a mouse we should think beautiful enough. May it be possible to admit that the question what particular forms or colours give us aesthetic pleasure is largely dependent upon physiological constitution, use and wont, environment, accidental association ; but that the objectivity of the aesthetic judgement lies not in the judgement which states the fact that we experience such and such a feeling but in the judgement which ascribes a value to this feeling — that in truth it is not the strictly aesthetic judgement that is objective, but the judgement of value which is pronounced on such and such an aesthetic experience ? From this point of view we can admit that aesthetic pleasure is often given to different persons by different experiences ; and yet that in certain cases there may be no more value in the one state of consciousness than in the other. The pleasure which red trees and a green sunset might give to the inhabitants of another planet might be just as ' true ' or ' high ' a pleasure as we derive from green trees and red sunset. In a differently constituted planet square arches might suggest feelings of awe and solemnity closely analogous to those which we derive from a Gothic cathedral, and both kinds of emotion might have their value. The negro's ideal of human beauty may include a broader nose and a different shape of head from a European's, but the resulting pleasure might to a perfectly disinterested intelligence appear to possess precisely the same value. But, though this might be so with those particular elements in the aesthetic consciousness which are in this way due to accidental circumstances, it need not be so with all. The Australian statesman mentioned above might have derived some pleasui-e from the poetry (say) of Longfellow or Mr. Kipling, and the disinterested intelli- gence would pronounce that that pleasure would have some value, but it would ascribe a higher value to the different pleasure which a more cultivated person would derive from Longfellow or Mr. Kipling, and a still higher value to the pleasure which Longfellow or Mr. Kipling have presumably derived from Shakespeare, but which the illiterate Minister of Education would be incapable of feeling at all. For the different estimate pronounced upon the poets in question would depend not upon mere accidents of physical organization or environment but upon general mental cultivation, upon qualities of intellect and character which to an impartial intelligence would appear to possess very different values, i8a REASON AND FEELING Here it is not the same pleasure that is caused by different kinds of poetry to different men, but a quite different pleasure. It is true that the capacity for aesthetic appreciation may be dependent upon a delicacy of eye and ear which is purely physical. An unmusical poet may through the structure of his nervous system be incapacitated from deriving pleasure from music without being a man of lower intellect or character than the musician who derives exquisite pleasure from the same sounds, or rather from sounds caused by the same instruments, though they are sounds which the unmusical poet simply does not hear. When the unmusical poet pronounces the music not to be beautiful, his judgement may in a sense possess strictly objective truth : for not only is he right in saying that he gets no aesthetic pleasure from the music, but he is right in saying that no high objective value attaches to what he actually hears— to the sensations, ideas, and emotions which the music actually produces in him. Could the musician share that experience, he would agree with the poet as to its low intrinsic value. The poet is only in error if he denies the objective value of the emotion which the music sets up in souls that possess the musical capacity which has been denied him ; or when he supposes that the elementary musical pleasure which he does himself derive from a simple hymn or song is of equal intrinsic worth with the pleasure which Beethoven or Bach give to the musical. Even where a pleasure is given to some people by what appears to the more cultivated critic absolutely ugly, there may be a worth in the pleasure, though we may say that the uncultivated man is wrong, in a sense, in feeling it because his enjoyment of it implies incapacity for something much better worth enjoying. If we say more than this, if we say that he ought not to go on indulging in his low aesthetic pleasures (even if he cannot school himself into enjoying what the cultivated man enjoys), our judgement is clearly a moral judgement, and not an aesthetic one at all. To distin- guish more in detail between the elements of aesthetic appreciation which are due to merely accidental circumstances and which might conceivably vary in differently constituted beings without either of them being in error, and those which are accounted for by incapacities in some beings for kinds of consciousness the value of which could not be denied by any intelligence without error, would involve a treatise on Aesthetic Philosophy which I have no intention of attempting. I merely throw out the suggestion that the really objective element in the aesthetic judgement is the judgement of value which it implies. The judgement of value implied in aesthetic judgement differs from ordinary judgements of value merely in being a judgement as to the value of a particular class or aspect of human experience which requires to be looked at in relation to a whole complex of other judgements of value before it can form a ground for making the avowedly and professedly moral judgement ' this kind of experience ought to be indulged in by ^ or B or promoted by ^ or £ in C ov D at such and such a time and in such and such circumstances.' (7) The result of this analysis — or mere suggestion of a possible analysis — is not to deny the objectivity of many of our aesthetic judgements, but Chap, vl, note] COMPARISON OF VALUES 183 to bring the objective element in them into closer connexion with our ordinary judgements of value— the judgements which we usually call dis- tinctively moral judgements. The judgement '^his is beautiful' claims objective validity in the sense that it asserts (a) that in the ideally consti- tuted consciousness, it will produce such and such an aesthetic experience, and (3) that this aesthetic experience possesses such and such a value. There may be cases in which a man might derive an equally valuable aesthetic experience from other external objects, just as one man likes one kind of food and another another without there being any difference of intrinsic value between the two kinds of pleasure : but that is not so always. In other cases the consciousness that thought such and such things beautiful would be pronounced by an omniscient mind to be inferior to the consciousness to which it appeared ugly. At the same time, though aesthetic judgements are (or include) judgements of value, they are value-judgements of a very distinctive and special kind. There will always be this much difference between them and what we usually call moral judgements, (o) that to judge well of the value of various kinds of aesthetic experience requires a different kind of mental capacity from that which is required to judge well of other values, and (6) that the judgement ' this has aesthetic value ' cannot pass into a moral judgement, on which any one can be called upon to act, until the value of the aesthetic experience has been compared with the value of other kinds of experience — the value for instance of Love in ourselves and of the pleasure produced by a socially useful action in others, and it is this estimate of comparative values which we usually call in a distinctive sense the moral judgement. Many may have a good aesthetic judgement, i. e. are capable of the higher aesthetic experiences and judge rightly of their value, who may have a bad moral judgement, i. e. be incapable of appreciating other kinds of experience at their true value when compared with the higher aesthetic experiences ; others may have a good moral judgement in general, i. e. rightly estimate (say) the superior value of Love and rightly balance the value of other people's pleasure against their own, but may make mistakes in particular cases from want of a developed aesthetic conscientiousness, i. e. because they do not see that Shakespeare is beautiful or underestimate the true value of the sense of beauty. CHAPTEE VII IDEAL UTILITARIANISM In previous chapters I have sought to show that the way to find out whether an action is right or wrong, when we are forced to consider such a question for ourselves without reference to some established rule^, is to consider whether it will tend to produce for society in general a Well-being or eiibainovia or good which includes many elements possessing diflFerent values, which values are intuitively discerned and compared with one another by the moral or practical Reason. The right action ie always that which (so far as the agent has the means of knowing) will produce the greatest amount of good upon the whole. This position implies that all goods or elements of the good are in some sense and for some purposes commensurable. Some of the objections which may be taken to this position I shall consider hereafter. In the present chapter I shall aim at illustrating how the moral judgements implied by the special virtues, and in particular by those which are prima facie most unutilitarian, are explainable upon the supposition that all moral judgements are ultimately judgements as to the value of ends. This view of Ethics, which combines the utilitarian principle that Ethics must be teleological with a non-hedonistic view of the ethical end, I propose to call Ideal Utilitarianism. According to this view actions are right or wrong according as they tend to produce for all mankind an ideal end or good, which includes, but is not limited to, pleasure. A paramount position among our moral judgements is (as we have seen) occupied by the three axioms of Prudence, Benevo- ' When we ougtt to enter upon such a consideration is a question which I have discussed in Book II, chap. v. Chap.vii,§i] BENEVOLENCE AND JUSTICE 185 lence, and Equity. It is self-evident to me that I ought (where it does not collide with the greater good of another) to promote my own greatest good, that I ought to prefer a greater good on the whole to a lesser, and that I ought to regard the good of one man as of equal intrinsic value with the like good of any one else. This last assumption will be further defended and explained in the Chapter on Justice. Meanwhile, it may be assumed that the ultimate meaning of absolute Justice is to be sought in this equal distribution of good. Such is the meaning, I take it, of ultimate social Justice. Justice in this absolute sense prescribes the principle, whatever it be, upon which the good is to be distributed, while Benevo- lence is taken to mean the promotion of maximum social good without reference to the question of its distribution. In this sense even the hedonistic Utilitarian must admit the necessity of recognizing that Virtue cannot be altogether resolved into Benevolence, unless the meaning of Benevolence is narrowed down to a Benevolence which is consistent with Justice. But it must be admitted that there are many senses of the word Justice, as popularly used, which do not seem priima facie to have any reference to the question of the distribution of Well-being or ultimate good. When we say that it is unjust to punish a man without hearing his defence, or to compel a man to give evidence against himself, or to punish a man twice for the same offence, or to make an ex post facto law, or to decide a civil action in favour of the poorer or the more deserving litigant who has nevertheless the worse case — in all such cases there seems no obvious or immediate reference to any principle for the ultimate distribution either of ultimate Well-being or of its material conditions. In Aristotelian lan- guage 'regulative' Justice^ — the Justice of the law-courts — seems to be a different virtue from ' distributive ' Justice. But in all these heterogeneous uses of the term Justice there seems ^ The same may be said of his Commercial Justice, or Justice of Exchange. It assumes the justice of the principle of private property and free barter in exchange, which a Socialist might regard as intrinsically unjust on account of the advantage which it gives to the possessor of unearned capital. 1 86 IDEAL UTILITARIANISM [Book I to be this much in common ; they all prescribe impartiality in the treatment of individuals ; they forbid inequality, or rather arbitrary inequality — inequality not justified by the require- ments of social Well-being, or some other general and rational principle — in the treatment of individuals. They all involve the application of some general rule or principle without respect of persons to particular cases. The question of the justice of this rule is not, in common discourse, brought into question. We call a judge unjust who refuses to apply the law impartially, though we ourselves disapprove of the law and regard it as essentially unjust. Thus we may say that the word, as used in ordinary parlance, always denotes impartiality in distribution upon some condition — assuming some established principle or rule of the actual social order, which must itself no doubt rest upon some principle of absolute Justice if it is to be capable of ultimate justification, but the justice of which is for the moment assumed. Thus we say that it is unjust to punish one man more severely than another for the same oflFence and under precisely similar circumstances, because here no consideration of social expediency (that is to say, at bottom no conflicting claims of other men) can interfere with the general principle that one man should be treated in exactly the same way as another under exactly the same circumstances. The principles of absolute Justice cannot require such unequal treatment : if they did, that would constitute such a difference of circumstance as might justify the unequal treatment. But we do not regard it as unjust for the judge to decide a case in a way which will enrich an already rich man and beggar a poor man, because we assume the justice of the laws of property, and regard it as the duty of the judge simply to administer that law impartially ; as unjust that a naval officer should receive more prize-money than a common sailor, because on other grounds we assume that social Well-being demands the adoption of an unequal s.cale of remuneration for officers and men, while we should regard it as unjust to give more to one man than to another of the same rank. It is unnecessary to multiply illustrations : in all cases the popular usages of the term Justice, in so far as they are capable of defence, may be held to imply the due regard of the claim of individuals — ^not Chap, vii, § i] PARTICULAR VIRTUES 187 their intrinsic merit or ultimate claims to Well-being, but their claim according to some established or recognized law or prin- ciple of distribution. Varied as are the usee of the term Justice in common language, the underlying idea of all of them seems to be that our accepted principles of social conduct, whatever they may be, should be applied impartially as between different individuals or classes. Sometimes of course when an act or a custom or an institution is pronounced unjust, it is meant that the established principle itself is one which cannot be defended upon any ground of social expediency, that it violates the fundamental principle that the ultimate value of one man's good is equal to that of the like good of another. But this question of absolute Justice raises so many difficult and intricate questions that further explanations must be reserved for a separate chapter. Subject to due regulation by the rule of Justice or Equity ^ it might seem to follow from the principles which we have hitherto adopted that all virtues could be explained as ultimately resolv- able into rational Benevolence or Love. But even the Hedonist must recognize that special names are in practice given to various special kinds of conduct, which are supposed to be conducive in definite and distinguishable ways to human good ; such kinds of conduct, or rather the dispositions to perform them, are called particular virtues. On the view which judges of the ultimate value of goods by other than a hedonistic standard we are able to establish a sharper and clearer distinction between the different duties or the dispositions which lead to their performance, since we can recognize not merely a distinction between different kinds of conduct all ultimately conducive to a single good, but also a real and important distinction between the kinds of good which they tend to promote. Thus even from the hedonistic point of view it is clearly convenient to have a distinctive name for the disposition to observe the rule of truth-speaking, though ' Which includes Prudence, or the recognition of the due claims of self. That due recognition of the claims of self is a duty is well put by Hsffding {Ethik, p. 119): 'It follows from the principle of Welfare [or Utility] that the individual is only one among many, but it follows also therefrom that the individual really is one among many." i88 IDEAL UTILITAEIANISM [Book I to the Utilitarian truth-speaking is simply one of the particular rules which the supreme and all-inclusive duty of promoting human pleasure imposes upon mankind. From the point of view of ideal Utilitarianism we may no doubt recognize that devotion to true human good will include all other virtues, Veracity among the number: but we shall be disposed to insist more strongly upon this and other special or particular virtues, because to us truthfulness of character, in ourselves and others, is a part of the end or ideal life which the virtuous man will seek to pro- mote, and not merely a means to a good other than itself. We shall be less disposed to acquiesce in the disposition to reduce all the virtues to Benevolence, since in practice ethical teaching of this kind is pretty sure to obscure or slur over the fact that the end which the benevolent man is to promote must include many other kinds of good besides pleasure, many dispositions, emotions, activities, states of consciousness which are valued for their own sakes and not merely as a means to some further good. I do not intend in the present work to attempt any exhaustive enumeration or description of the particular kinds of conduct, the particular duties or virtues, which are included in the dis- position to promote true human good, or of the various ends or elements in that good with which these various duties or virtues are specially concerned. I shall not attempt to show elaborately in what ways virtues such as Honesty, Industry, Family Affection, Kindliness, Compassion, Loyalty (to the State or other social institutions), Orderliness, Courage (physical and moral) are con- ducive to the general good. That they are so is common ground between the hedonistic and the ideal Utilitarian, though no doubt it will be possible to find in connexion with all of them casuistical questions which might have to be differently answered by those who take and by those who refuse to take a hedonistic view of human good. Descriptions or classifications of duties or virtues are apt to be tedious and useless, unless the details of duty are discussed with much greater fullness than is compatible with the scope of the present work. I propose, therefore, to confine myself in this chapter to some remarks upon those duties or virtues which seem at first sight most difficult to reconcile with the view that all virtue consists ultimately in the promotion Chap, vii, § ii] HUMANITY 1 89 of true social good, and which really are (as it appears to me) in- capable of being reconciled with that doctrine, so long as social good is understood in a purely hedonistic sense. II In the first place, I must observe that even those virtues which are most obviously altruistic in their tendency are, according to our view, also ends in themselves — having a value independent of, and in some cases much greater than, the mere pleasure which they cause in others. Hence it becomes rational to encourage the cultivation and exercise of these virtues even in ways which cannot always be shown to produce a net gain in pleasure on the whole. I have already illustrated this in the case of Humanity to men and animals. The high value which we assign to all natural kindliness of feeling and to parental affection in particular is, I believe, one of the main grounds for our condemnation of infanticide. The same consideration forbids the extinction of life in the case of the old or the sick or the insane, and generally speaking, persons whose existence is a burden to the community, even should they be willing to consent to the sacrifice. If it be assumed that their lives are a burden even to themselves, then of course the question is complicated with another, the lawfulness of suicide, to which we shall return later on. It is no doubt quite compatible with this high estimate of the social affections to urge that in certain directions Christian sentiment has been carried to extremes. But here it is important to bear in mind a principle on which we shall have frequently to insist — that we must take into consideration the actual psycho- logical constitution of human nature, and the impossibility of modifying it exactly in the way and to the extent to which we please. It might be difficult without this principle to justify our absolute condemnation of the extinction of extremely mis- shapen infants. It would be difficult, that is, to maintain a priori that it would not be a gain to society to eliminate the infants most grossly and obviously unfitted for life, were it not for the fact of the horror which the idea actually excites in humane persons. The moral reformer who should feel inclined 190 IDEAL UTILITARIANISM [Book I to suggest some modification of the existing custom will, however, reflect on the extreme value of the feelings which such a sugges- tion would shock, the extreme difficulty of drawing the line between the permitted and the unpermitted elimination, and the impossibility of securing that interference with spontaneous emotions shall stop just where he wants it to stop. He will remember the ease with which the kindly inhibition of an unhappy life might degenerate (in individual parents and in society at large) into a mere selfish repudiation of trouble, privation or anxiety, and the encouragement which any extension of the practice would give to materialistic and hedonistic views of life. We condemn infanticide, because we consider the feelings which the prohibition cultivates to be of more intrinsic worth than the good which it secures. Given the actual psychological constitution of human nature, we may even judge it best that such questions should not be raised at all : but, if they are raised, there is no principle upon which they can be decided but this of the comparative worth of the sentiments and type of character encouraged by that prohibition and of the social advan- tages which might accrue from its relaxation. While I have no doubt that on the whole the established rule is right, it is possible that in certain extreme cases the Christian sentiment has been pushed too far, and that in the case of actual monsters or beings entirely destitute of human intelligence, in which it is possible to draw a fairly definite line, and in which the life that is preserved is as valueless from a moral as it is from a hedonistic point of view, an exception might be made'. ' It appears that this was the recognized doctrine both for Church and State in Christian countries in the seventeenth century : see constant allu- sions to it in connexion with the difficulty of defining the term ' man ' in the works of Leibniz. In ' Some Remarks on Punishment ' in the Inter- natiwml Journal of Ethics (vol. iv, 1893-4, p. 269 «g.), Mr. Bradley assumes the whole of the modem aversion to infanticide to be due to what he would regard as a pure superstition about the taking of human life. That the feeling of the sanctity of life, assumed to be prescribed by direct divine revelation, has historically exercised some influence in this direction can hardly be denied ; but that so deeply-seated and widely-spread an ethical change should be due entirely to ' superstition ' or to merely theological ideas (reasonable or unreasonable) is a view which will probably commend itself only to anti-Christian fanaticism. The Buddhistic feeling against the taking Chap, vii, § iii] DUTY OF SELF-CULTURE 191 Another possible case in which a valuable sentiment has been indulged to an exaggerated extent may perhaps be found in the practice of preserving, at immense risk to» warders and doctors, the lives of homicidal maniacs. Ill I pass on to consider some other of the less obviously utilitarian virtues and duties. Through all of them there seems to run the general principle that a higher value should be attributed to the exercise and cultivation of the higher — that is to say, of the intellectual, sesthetic, and emotional — faculties than to the indulgence of the merely animal and sensual part of our nature. We regard knowledge, culture, enjoyment of beauty, intellectual activity of all kinds, and the emotions connected with these things, as having a higher value than the pleasures arising from the gratification of the mere animal propensities to eating and drinking or physical exercise or the like ^. What of life, ho-wever little in its exaggeration capable of rational defence, is at all events sufBcient to show that the sentiment with which we have to deal is not the mere influence of a supposed divine command inherited by Chris- tianity from Judaism. Moreover, it is worthy of note that the practice advocated by Mr. Bradley was condemned by the best pagans. Even Plato, to whom Mr. Bradley appeals, did not approve of the deliberate bringing into existence of children expressly designed for the slaughter-house ; he sanctioned infanticide only in case of children born of parents who had passed the prescribed age ; while Aristotle condemned infanticide for the mere purpose of reducing population, and allowed it only in the case of misshapen infants. For a sanction to ' social surgery ' of the wholesale type advocated by Mr. Bradley we must descend below the level of the ' higher Paganism.' ^ We may legitimately attribute a higher value to athletic enjoyment than to mere gratification of the senses because (o) athletic exercises (especially in the form of games) in moderation are as conducive to the due activity of the intellect as in excess (an excess very soon reached) they are detrimental to it, (&) because (especially in men of small moral or intellectual capacities) they supply a useful antidote to still more animal propensities, (c) because they do cultivate some moral and intellectual qualities. I might say more on this side of the matter if it were not for the enormous exaggera- tion of the moral value of athletics which is popular at the present moment, and which is threatening the higher life of the nation no less than the prestige of our commerce and the efficiency of our army. The fallacy of the arguments commonly used by those schoolmasters who encourage the 192 IDEAL UTILITARIANISM [Book I is the relative value of these things as compared with activities of a directly social character, is a question on which we may have to say something hereafter. It is not necessary to deny that the encouragement even of such intellectual pursuits as are of the least direct and obvious social utility does lead to an increase of pleasure on the whole, but our feeling about them is not based upon any such doubtful calculations : and assuredly there are many cases where an individual would find it difficult to justify the devotion of his whole time to pursuits which bring pleasure only to himself, and perhaps a very small circle of other people, when it might be bestowed upon work which would undoubtedly bring pleasure or a saving of pain to large numbers, if he thought that all pleasure was of equal worth, that nothing was of any value but pleasure, and that conduct was right only in so far as it tends to increase of pleasure. This general principle of the superiority of certain parts of our nature to others — the more purely human to the more animal — is the root of two sets of virtues : — 1. Of those virtues (though modems are not much in the habit of thinking of them as virtues at all) which consist in the exercise of the higher intellectual and aesthetic faculties : 2. Of the virtues which consist in the due control or sub- ordination of the lower or more animal impulses. Of the first we need not speak more at length, except in one connexion. This seems to be the place to say a word about the source of our respect for Truth. Granted the great social utility of being able to take a man's word (say in com- mercial transactions), it is obvious, to my mind, that upon hedonistic assumptions the exceptions would be much more numerous than would commend themselves at least to a well- brought-up Englishman. There would be no reason why we should resist that tendency to say (in matters of no importance), exaggerations of Athleticism seems to lie chiefly in assuming (i) that the qualities undoubtedly cultivated by games cannot be cultivated in any other way, (2) that the resource, initiative, self-control, habit of co-operation, prompt action, &c., cultivated in one particular way will transfer themselves to other spheres. Experience does not seem to favour either assumption. A football player who excels in ' combination ' is quite as likely as other men to play for his own hand in real life. Chap, vii, § iii] VERACITY 193 at any expense to Truth, what would be agreeable to the hearer which is, indeed, almost sanctioned by the current morality of some civilized nations. It is of course possible to enumerate many inconveniences — particularly what we may call moral inconveniences, loss of any opportunities of learning our defects and the like — which result from such a toleration of minor lying. But, entirely apart from all such considerations, I believe that we do on reflection recognize something intrinsically fitting in the rule which prescribes that a rational being, endowed with faculties which enable him to pursue, to communicate, and to love the truth, should use those faculties in that way rather than for the purpose of making things appear otherwise than as they are. So much appears to me to be the clear result of introspection, and to be implied in the strongest moral convictions of other men. But, it is equally easy to show that to erect the principle of Veracity into a hard and fast rule admitting of no exceptions is out of harmony with the belief and the practice of the most conscientious persons. Where some conventional use of language is sufficiently recognized, formal untruths may no doubt be removed from the category of lies proper by the principle that words must be taken to mean what they are commonly understood to mean. In this way we may defend the formal ' not at home,' the usual forms of social and epistolary salutation, the hyperboles of courtly compliment, though in proportion as these latter pass beyond the minimum of fixed convention their justification becomes more precarious. But this principle is inapplicable to the actual deception practised by detectives, or by private persons towards a brigand inquiring the whereabouts of his victim, or to the denial of bad news to sick persons, or to lies told for the preservation of important secrets, or to the employment of ancient formulae (a political oath, a declaration imposed by some ancient Statute, or a confession of faith ^), which nobody takes quite literally, but with respect to which the limits of per- missible latitude are not definitely fixed by universally under- ^ I have discussed this particular application of the principle in an article in the International Journal of Ethics, 'Prof. Sidgwick on Religious Con- formity,' vol. Ill (Jan. 1897), BASHDALL 1 194 IDEAL UTILITARIANISM [Book I stood and accepted custom. Of course, in proportion as these exceptions to the rule of truth-speaking are generally recognized, part of the moral objection to them disappears. Though they in some cases deceive for the moment the particular person to whom they are addressed, they do not to any important extent tend to weaken respect for truth, the habit of telling the truth, and the general confidence in other people's statements. It is no doubt much to be desired that a general under- standing should be arrived at about such matters. But as a matter of fact no such general understanding does exist, and the absence of such an understanding forms an insuperable objection to finding even in the case of Veracity — the stronghold of popular Intuitionism — the case of an intuitively discerned rule of conduct, universally binding without any consideration of consequences. From our point of view we have no diflBculty in reconciling the ' intuitive ' basis of the virtue with the occur- rence of exceptions based upon consideration of consequences. Truth-speaking is a good, and so (still more) is that inward love of truth of which truth-speaking is the expression and the guarantee. It is almost invariably right to speak the truth, because it is morally good both for ourselves to speak it and for others to hear it, even when it is unpleasant to both parties. But there are other goods besides truth-speaking and truth-loving: and sometimes Truth must be sacrificed to the more imperative claims of Humanity or of Justice. In each case we must decide which is of the greatest worth — the speaking of truth and the habit of speaking it which my lie would tend to discourage, or the life which my lie will save, the injustice that it will prevent, the practical good which it will enable me to do, the greater truth which it will enable me to difiuse. There are even cases in which a lie has to be told in the interests of Truth itself. An untrue statement must be made to one man in order to keep a secret which one has promised to respect ; a statement literally untrue must be made that a higher truth may be taught or real liberty of thought and speech advanced ^. ' This is admirably put by HefFding (Ethik, p. 178) : ' The duty of speaking the truth amounts to this, the duty of promoting the supremacy of the truth Chap, vii, § iii] TRUTH-SEEKING 195 It will be observed that I have drawn no hard and fast distinction between the duty of Veracity and the duty towards Truth in a wider and more speculative 'sense. And it seems to me of great practical importance to insist that the social duty of Veracity and the duty of scientific enquiry ultimately spring from the same root, though in the case of Veracity the duty is more directly and immediately dependent upon our social relations. We ought not to lie one to another (as was recognized by St. Paul), because we are ' members one of another,' because we do not like to hear lies told to ourselves, and ought not to like them even when they are pleasant. Deception implies want of respect for the personality of others. But, after all, the distinction is only one of degree, for there is some social reference even in the duty of seeking speculative truth. It is under ordinary circumstances best for ourselves and for others that we should seek and make known the truth in matters of Religion and of Science as well as about the facts of common life. It is important to insist upon the close connexion between a very practical duty and one which is intimately associated with the highest intellectual aspirations for two reasons. It emphasizes the fact that the social duty is not confined to the mere abstinence from false statements (though of course the negative rule is capable of more exact definition and admits of fewer legitimate exceptions than the (" die Wahrheit zur Herrschaft zu bringen ") : the end may, however, often be interfered with by speaking the truth.' So Sir Leslie Stephen : ' The rule, " Lie not," is the external rule, and corresponds approximately to the internal rule, " Be trustworthy." . . . Truthfulness is the rule because in the vast majority of cases we trust a man in so far as he speaks the truth : in the exceptional cases the mutual confidence would be violated when the truth, not when the lie, is spoken ' {A Study of Ethics, p. 208). So the insistence upon a strict and literal interpretation of political or religious formulae is- often opposed to the interests of Truth. The man too scrupulous to join a party, some part of whose programme does not express his real mind, or to subscribe a creed details of which are obsolete, often does less than he might do to propagate the truth. Such protests often have their value, but it is perhaps the tendency of conscientious persons to over-estimate this negative devotion to Truth. In the case of the actual ' pious fraud ' or yfvvcuov ^cvSos it is most commonly the minor, not the major premiss of the moral syllogism which is questionable. Such fi-auds would be justifiable if (when all their consequences are considered) they were socially beneficiaL a 196 IDEAL UTILITAKIANISM [Book I positive), and it further illustrates how the admission of ex- ceptions is compatible with the fullest recognition of an 'intuitive' basis for the duty. It may be recognized as a general principle that it is a duty to seek for and to reveal the truth in spite of the fact that its discovery often seems to weaken or to shatter beliefs, institutions, habits, traditions of high social utility. Even in the most modem times I believe that this duty is inadequately recognized, at least by those who are in the habit of attaching most value to what are commonly called moral considerations in the narrower sense of the word. There is probably, in this country at least, too much, not too little, unwillingness to communicate to the ignorant and the young the results of Science or of scientific Theology, for fear they should weaken the reverence and the Morality which have in the past been associated with beliefs no longer tenable. And yet those who put the duty highest acknowledge that it has at times to give way to others more imperative still. No one but a fanatic thinks it a duty to proclaim the truth on every subject, at all times and under all circumstances — in omnibuses and railway trains, before old and young, simple and learned, on suitable occasions and unsuitable — with equal openness and equal insistence. Some respect we all recognize it as right to show to the known convictions, the sympathies, the limitations, the prejudices of our hearers; to the social convenience of the principle that there is a time and place for all things ; to a host of conventions, traditions, and under- standings. The principle that all moral judgements are judge- ments of value, while all value is comparative, supplies us with an unfailing means of reconciling the highest reverence for Truth with the limitations which all sensible and right- feeling persons recognize to the duty of actively proclaiming it ; although it does not (any more than any other ethical principle) supply us with an infallible mode of discerning what is right in difficult cases of ' conflicting duties \' ' Of course in the strictest sense there can be no ' conflict of duties.' It is no doubt true that the duty only begins when the conflict of traditional rules or of real moral principles has been decided. If one supposed 'duty' is overruled by another, the former is not really a duty. But the expression is a natural and convenient one. Chap, vii, § iv] PURITY 197 IV The due subordination of the appetitesf their control in such a way as is most favourable to the activity of the higher part of our nature, constitutes the virtue of Temperance in that wider sense indicated by the Greek