EVERYDAY ETHICS CABOT CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY FROM THE LIBRARY OF PROFESSOR RALPH S. TARR 1864-1911 GIFT OF Russell Tarr 1939 olin.anx The original of tliis book is in tlie Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924031217874 EVERYDAY ETHICS BY ELLA LYMAN CABOT NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY Copyright 1806 «T HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY TO A. T. L. IN LOVING RECOGNITION OF HIS GENEROUS, SUSTAINING TRUST PREFACE A SUCCESSFUL book on methods of teaching ethics will ■ improve in the schoolroom the art of instruction in the most difficult province of study and practice. Ethics relates to all manner of deeds and habits of doing which concern one's fellow men, either as pri- vate individuals or as members of institutions — ^mem- bers of the social whole. One may conduct himself in such a manner as to obstruct the actions of his fellow men and thereby re- duce their labours and strivings to a nullity, more or less, according to his power and skill. Or, on the other hand, he may act in such a manner as to reen- force their labours and strivings and increase the net product of human endeavour. The fact that there are rational objects to be achieved by humanity — name them collectively as the conquest of nature for man's use and the peaceful combination of man with men to the end that each in- dividual may share in the experience of all individuals • — these objects ought to be the common aim of all rational beings : this fact furnishes the basis and norm of ethics. It makes evident the Source of Power. The individual who promotes the twofold end of civilisa- tion increases the aggregate power of mankind and at the same time shares in that power. His own help vi Preface of others is reflected back upon him. He gets in ex- change for the mite that he contributes, the right to participate in the positive outcome of the labours of all. This is a true source of power and it can be approached in only one sure way — ^by the adoption of ethical action as a habit, and by continuous growth in ethical insight. Human power consists in the control of nature and the ability to effect combinations with one's fellow men. Ethics is in the first place a matter of the will; it concerns the form of doing. Good breeding consists chiefly in correct habits of practice rather than in correct modes of thinking. And good behaviour is a bundle of good habits. All the habits that facilitate combination with one's fellow men in matters of common weal concern the will rather than the intellect. Thus in the school, behaviour is the first considera- tion. For it makes possible the concerted work — work in classes. The class work of the school is of an alto- gether higher order than mere individual study under a private tutor. For in the class the pupil sees the failures and successes of his schoolmates who are of the same grade of progress as himself; he measures his work by their work and discovers from day to day other ways of looking at the subject of the lesson. He gradually learns to reenforce his own insight by the insights of others. But the individual pursuing his work by himself under a tutor is not aided in this salutary way. His teacher is in another orbit and does not help him by emulation or vicarious experience — • the sight of others in the same plight as himself and Preface vii yet achieving success by one or another device of in- dustry and persistence. In order that the school may perfect its method of teaching the individual by the class, there are certain ethical habits necessary, regularity of attendance, of study, of concerted action — all pupils intent on the same thing. Next there is punctuality ; readiness and alertness, even more necessary than regularity in mak- ing the school with its class work effective. Then, thirdly, there is silence, a self-repression of tendencies to disorder, a subjugation of the animal proclivity to prate and chatter. Silence on the part of pupils en- ables them all to concentrate their attention on the exposition of the teacher; its opposite has the effect of producing distraction. The activity of each nullifies the activity of his fel- lows. The morbid desire to attract attention to one's self is repressed by the school virtue of silence; re- spect for the rights of others and for the triumph of the grand aim of the school takes its place. A fourth schoolroom virtue is industry in the form of work at the assigned task. It takes on one of two forms: first the individual absorption of each by himself in the prescribed study or investigation of the topic for to-day's lesson. This is an absorption in which the pupil goes from the external, first aspects of a subject to the secondary ones, deeper and higher. He learns to test and discard the superficial and to seize essentials. He learns to strive for insight into profound principles. The other side of school industry is the alert and viii Preface critical attention to the work of one's fellows under the review of the teacher in the class exercise. In the for- mer kind of industry the pupil is absorbed in his own work oblivious of the presence of teacher and fellow pupils. He is using his whole might to master his task. In the latter kind of industry the pupil is con- centrating his attention on the work of others. Each form of attention is essential to culture. In the lines of direct will-training the school is potent in building up good habits of cooperation with one's fellows. By effort and reiterated precept of the teacher good habits in respect to regularity, punc- tuality, silence and industry get formed and become a second nature, unconsciously a part of the personal make-up of each pupil. But because these are unconscious habits they have sunk below the strictly moral plane of action, for they are more or less mechanical. The truly moral must be connected with a world-view — a. theory of a moral order of the universe. There should be formed a habit of looking for the rational ground of each action — ^a habit of ethical thinking that amounts to conscientiousness. The bun- dle of practical habits results from mechanical obe- dience to the school order and although it serves great ends in that it makes possible cooperation with one's fellows, the pupil may not understand the rationale of his practical habits and they may have merely a conservative influence preserving the traditional use and wont that stands in the way of readjustment to higher ideals. Preface ix Thus it happens that the second way to ethical life belongs to the intellect rather than to the will di- rectly. It concerns a competent discussion of the grounds of conduct — the standards of morality. Along this second line of ethical theory and prac- tice — ^which is that chosen by Mrs. Cabot in this book — the somewhat advanced student is called away from ethical habit to the consideration of the moral grounds of all habit. It is especially the consideration to which the future leader of public opinion should give atten- tion in his own preparatory studies. It is moreover specially the line of ethical training needed by tht school teacher, although not to the exclusion of a care- ful study of the rationale of the discipline of school order and of unconscious habit in the elements of gootl breeding. The teacher should know the application of the high- est ethical principles and be able to bring them to the aid of the immature mind struggling to free itself in the presence of a conflict of duties. A careful training of the teacher in discriminating the motives of conduct is useful, not merely in the practical settlement of cases of discipline that arise, but — what is of even more importance — useful in getting an insight into all the studies of the school which have human nature as their content or subject; for example, literature, history, biography, economics, commerce, politics, and the like. Great stress is laid by the author on the choice o£ a special calling in life and on the moral support it ^ives to character. In fact it is made a ver^ impor^ X Preface tant norm for the decision of one's course in the presence of conflicting duties. Each activity of the soul, memory, imagination, courage, feeling, the sense of honour, has its moral aspect. It contributes to strengthen or to weaken the moral character. The discussion of details under this head forms one of the most valuable features of the present treatise and cannot fail to aid the teacher who gives it careful study. Care is taken by the author to avoid sentimental- ism on the one hand and on the other hand the ap- proach to unintelligible abstractions. The composition of the book is such that live questions are everywhere introduced and the interest of the reader is aroused at the outset and held firmly to the end. [William T. Harris. Washington, 1905. CONTENTS CHAPTER PAGE I. The Diffusion of Ethics I. Rise and Spread of Ethical Questions . . . . i II. Virtue the Condition of Success 3 III. AH Interests Lead to Ethics 7 IV. Ethics is one Outlook upon Everything in the World 9 V. What the Study of Ethics can Accomplish . . 10 II. Boundaries I. No Moral Responsibility without Choice . . . 17 II. The Boundary Line between Voluntary and In- voluntary Acts is often Difficult to Trace . 20 ni. We are Responsible for Preparing to become Non-Responsible 22 IV. We are Always Responsible for our Will . . .27 V. Necessity for Periods of Non-Responsibility . . 29 III. The Power of Purpose I. The Distinctive Qualities of a Ptirpose ... 32 II. The Moral Life is the Purposeful Life .... 35 lit Purpose Classifies Acts as Right or Wrong . . 37 IV Ethics is Concerned with all Acts which Embody a Purpose 40 V, A PtiriKJSe is a Sign and Source of Power ... 43 IV. Goodness, the Essence of Manhood I. Goodness is Fitness for a Chosen Purpose . . 46 II. Nothing is Forever Purposeless or Worthless . . 49 m. Goodness Involves Sacrifice for the Sake of Fulfihnent 51 IV. The Likeness between Goodness and Virtue . . 5^ V. The Difference between Goodness and Virtue . 55 iz c Contents V. How TO Judge Purposes I. To Judge any Act we must Know its Life History S9 II. The Good Purpose is Carefully Chosen and Loy- ally Followed 62 III. It Avoids both Inertia and Dissipation ... 70 IV. Virtue is the Control of Impulse by Purpose . • 74 ^ VI. The Darkness of Sin I. Sin is Avoidance of Light 77 II. It is our own Power Turned against Ourself . . 86 III. It is Wilful Abandonment of our Aim .... 90 VII. The Light of Conscience I. Conscience is the Sensible and Timely Will to Know the Right Act 93 II. It is Openness to the Light of Truth .... 97 III. We can be Overscrupulous, not Overconscien- tious 104 VIII. Conscience, Custom and Law I. The Conscience of the Past, as Expressed in Law f and Custom 108 • II. The Relation of Law to Morality 110 III. The Relation of Custom to Morality . . . .118 (a) The Significance of Custom . . . .119 (b) The Effect of Custom on the Sense of Guilt 122 IX. Interests as Life Givers and Life Savers 1. We See with our Interests, because they are Ourselves 125 II. The Distinction of an Interest from a Wish or a Liking 127 III. Interests as Reformers 129 IV. All Subjects may become of Interest . . . .135 V. By the Deepening Process of Work and of Insight 138 , X. The Choice of Interests I. The Common Nature of Interests 142 II. Classification of Types of Interest 144 III. Indications of the Right Choice of Interest • . 155 Contents xi XI. Effort, Sacrifice, and Drudger? I. The Relation of Growth to Effort 158 II. The Tests of Right Sacrifice 161 ni. Sacrifice ought always to be a Means to Self- Fulfilment 167 IV, The Permanent Need of Effort 169 XII. Selfishness I. Selfhood is Essential to Moral Life 173 II. My Self Consists of all with which I am Iden^ tified 177 III. Selfishness is Wilful Narrowness in Person^ Relations 179 rv. Every Unselfish Act Breaks its Shell of Narrow- ness 184 XIII. Sympathy ' I. Sympathy Expresses the Width of Selfhood . . 188 11. Perfected Sympathy is Realisation of the Truth . 191 III. And must Include Firmness and Common Sense . 194 IV. Sympathy Grows by Intimate Knowledge and Devotion 198 V. And becomes a Creative Force 200 XIV. Imagination ' I. The Meaning of Imagination 202 II. It is Essential to the Fulfilment of any Aim . . 204 III. Faults due to Lack of Imagination 209 XV. Memory I. Memory is Central in Human Life 215 II. By the Use of Memory we Overcome Temptation 217 ' III. The Cultivation of Memory 220 rvr. Exclusion is one Aspect of Memory .... 223 ^ V. To Remember is to Attain Integrity .... 325 XVL Courage I. The Difference between Courage and Fearlessness 228 n. Courage is the Effort to Control Fear .... 230 UL Suggestions for the Conquest of Fear .... 233 xii Contents XVII. Thought Aglow with Feeling I. The Inadequacy of Inarticulate Feeling . . . 240 IL Thought and Feeling Supplement one another . 243 III. Expression through Art 249 XVIII. Thought and Action I. Action without Evasion 253 II. Times when Thought should be Controlled . . 257 III. The Bliss of Ignorance is Alien to Growth . • 260 IV. Thought in the Presence of Temptation . . .262 XIX. Truth I. The Corrosion of Falsehood 265 II. Reasons for Truthfulness 267 m. Truthfulness is the Effort to Convey an Accurate Impression 270 rv. The Causes and Treatment of Lying .... 273 XX. Truth Speaking as a Fine Art I. Speaking the Truth in Love 281 II. The Acquirement of Skill in Truth Speaking . . 283 III. The Relation of Truth to Loyalty 289 IV. Truth as the Guardian of Character .... 293 XXI. Open-Mindedness and Prejudice I. Prejudice due to a Mistaken Idea of Loyalty . . 296 II. The Strength of Open-mindedness 298 III. Evils due to Prejudice 301 IV. The Attainment of Fair-mindedness .... 306 XXII. Self-Government L The Paradoxical Nature of Self-government . . 312 n. The Ascent from Servitude to a Chosen Obedience 313 III. Disobedience as an Aspect of Loyal Consecration 319 IV. The Value of Self-government 322 XXIII. The Use of Time I. The Meaning of Saving Time 325 n. Aimlessness and Disloyalty are the Thieves of Time 227 ni. The Moulding of Time to Our Ends . . . .333 IV. Virtue and Timeliness 337 Contents xiii TEACHERS' KEY 341 Introduction 343 Methods of Teaching 347 I. The Meaning of Ethics 351 II. The Moral and the Involuntary 355 III. The Power of a Purpose 360 IV. Goodness and Badness 364 V. Right and Wrong Judgments 367 VI. The Darkness of Wrong-Doing 370 VII. The Light of Conscience 373 vin. Conscience, Custom and Law 376 I IX. Interests as Life Givers and Life Savers . . 379 X. The Choice of Interests 381 XI. Sacrifice and Drudgery 385 XII. Selfishness 388 XIII. Sympathy 392 XIV. The Value of Imagination 395 XV. Memory 39S XVI. Courage 401 XVII. Quick Feeling and Steady Thought .... 406 XVIII. Thought and Action 409 XIX. Truth 413 XX. Truth Speaking as a Fine Art 417 XXI. Open-Mindedness and Prejudice 421 XXII. Obedience and Self-Government 425 XXIII. The Use of Time 429 INDEX . • 433 EVERYDAY ETHICS CHAPTER I^ THE DIFFUSION OF ETHICS " You can keep no men long, nor Scotchmen at all, off moral or theological discussion. . . . They are to all the world what law is to lawyers, they are every- body's technicalities, the medium through which all consider life and the dialect in which they express their judgment." ^ Moral questions are incessantly discussed by old and young. " It is a disgrace that Tillman was acquitted ! " " Mamma, Charlie ought not to knock down my card house." " Do you think it is right for me to spend so much on that silk waist? " " If you really want to learn the outer roll you should go skating every day that the ice will bear." Questions of right and wrong are woven into all conversation; they are as close to our life as the air we breathe ; but this is not surprising, for any- one who has any interests whatsoever is concerned with ethical problems. The careful study of these issues which we so often touch upon and glide away from is my task in this book. The study of right- 1 Robert Louis Stevenson, " Memories and Portraits," p. 153. 2 Everyday Ethics choosing and well-doing, — that is, of doing anything well, — is ethics ; it is the study of what to do and how to do it. No one begins his moral life by a deliberate choice. Before we know it we find ourselves standing knee- deep in the water of moral decisions and pulled this way and that by eddying currents, the opinions of par- ents and friends. We have been sent to school without being asked our opinion of its value, we have been told that it is babyish to cry, wicked to get dirty, and wrong to steal sugar ; and we have lived close to some wonder- ful, long-sufifering love which has influenced us far more than we begin to know. But sooner or later we are awakened by a decision of our own, great or small, and begin in a dim, fragmentary way to ponder ques- tions of right and wrong, — that is, to study ethics. For example, a boy finds himself possessed by a strong impulse to succeed in athletics or in some form of art, to become a great explorer, or to help the poor. If he wants to make a success in athletics, how ought he to go about it ? Two questions immediately arise : — What opportunities are there? What are his own powers? To make a sensible decision, he must know the situation and his own abilities. He must make his choice within the field of athletics by studying sensibly the situation about him. The country is suited to certain sports rather than to others. If there is a wide stretch of land, it gives an opportunity for golf, a small level patch is exactly fitted for tenni% but not nearly large enough for a golf course, — ^the lack of water near by makes rowing impracticable, and The Diffusion of Ethics 3 the remoteness from neighbours makes it difficult to organise a football eleven. Circumstances seem to favour his playing tennis, but before deciding he must consider also his own power. Is he strong enough for tennis, or has he a weak wrist? Which game is the most interesting, and for which has he most skill ? These questions must be answered before a wise decision can be made. On the whole he decides to play golf. How shall he learn? Mainly in three ways. He must have instruction, he must practise, he must study the play of others. II We come next to a point of special interest. It turns out that if one is to succeed in playing golf, he must acquire and exercise patience, industry, concen- tration, perseverance, pluck, and self-sacrifice. In fact to do what he wants to do really well he must develop a group of powers which are really virtues. But this is not peculiar to athletics. The successful musician must be energetic, persevering, industrious, must overcome fear, and resist allurements, must con- trol himself under provocation ; so also must the sailor, the motorman, the washerwoman, the nurse, the doc- tor, and the soldier. This means that it is our chosen work that is the best moral teacher. Though we aim only to be efficient, to make a success of what we undertake, no matter what it is, we find that in the process we develop what 4 Everyday Ethics people call " virtues." This point seems to me so im- portant as to need further illustration. The Freshman who aspires to play football next autumn has no intention of being virtuous. What he wants is to get on the team, but if he succeeds it will be because he has or acquires a set of powers which are just those which his best friends would want him to have. " If Jack would only put the same determination, the same perseverance, the same self-restraint and ambition into other things that he does into football, he would be perfect." In this part of his life he is all that they want him to be, and it is there that he is happiest, least con- strained, most expressed and on his mettle. The quali- ties he shows in football are as truly virtues as when they are displayed in war or engineering. It is true that a boy may show great self-control in the way he plays football and none at all in the way he spends his money, just as the sailor may show great courage in a storm and none in resisting the temptation to drink. A politician is often very unselfish in making sacrifices for his children, but utterly selfish toward the citizens whom he defrauds by putting in as super- intendent of streets a personal friend who is unfit. There are many people who show their good qualities only in a small fraction of their life, the part where their keen interest is aroused. Here they are fully alive and so are " good." When we study, as we do in ethics, the core of good action, we find it wher- ever anyone is doing his work well, whether he knows The Dififusion of Ethics 5 it to be his duty and calls it so, or whether he only feels it to be worth doing. The laws of ethics are the princi- ples which anyone must follow to attain success in any pursuit, and what are called virtues are the powers developed by and necessary to any efficient work. It is worth noticing here that it is through activity and efficiency that goodness is reached, not through avoidance of actions that might possibly be dangerous or disturbing. It is impressed upon us from childhood up that being good is the same as keeping quiet, sitting still, not getting dirty, and avoiding breakage of china. " Do as you're told. Come when you're bid. Shut the door softly And you'll never be chid." Now it is true that shutting the door softly and sit- iing still may at times and for some special reason be good acts, but in themselves they tend to stifle and dis- hearten the moral life which grows through activity. When the good characters in books are, like Owen Wister's Virginian, men of unquenchable purpose, the identification of good with stupid, and bad with interesting will lose its meaning. This fallacy still haunts many who are but half aware of it. So far I have taken up only the large, far-reach- ing decisions as to one's work — decisions such as are made only a few times in one's life, but no matter how small or great the decision, ethics is always con- cerned with what to do and how to do it. Making a moral decision always means trying to think fearlessly, 6 Everyday Ethics ' sensibly, and sympathetically about whatever we pro- pose to do. At the opening of the Spanish War, Commodore Dewey was confronted with the question whether or not he should enter Manila Bay and bombard the city. The weight of great responsibility hung over him. He had time to think carefully, as he was bound to think, without flinching from the consequences and without self-deceit. What did he need to consider in order to make the best decision? First of all he needed to reenforce in his memory the sense of his obligation — his contract to fulfil the duties of a commodore of the United States. Next he had to decide the question : Will it further the pur- pose for which I am here if I enter Manila Bay and bombard the city ? What will be the gain to the United States in case of success and the loss in case of failure ? He had to consider the danger, not as it affected him- self or his friends, but as it concerned the effective- ness of his fleet and the prestige of his country. The decision to take all necessary risks for himself and his men was made long before ; but he still needed to consider the fitness of his squadron for the task before it and to " size up " the whole situation. He needed, that is, to know all the relevant circumstances and the capacity of the group of men under his com- mand. The decision what to do once made, his next ques- tion was how to do it. " Shall the attack be made by night or by day ? How shall I best avoid the torpedoes in the harbour? At what point is the weakest defence The 7?if5fusion of Ethics 7 of the city? Is it an advantage or an added danger to cooperate with the insurgent Filipinos?" All pursuits have something in common, and the same principles are applicable to every one. A friend of mine, in doubt about his choice of a profession, visited many people who were following different lines of work — lawyers, doctors, business men, politicians, musicians— and asked of each : " What qualities do you need to succeed in your profession ? " Much to his surprise, each answered in almost the same words: " You need energy, perseverance, resource, good judgment, interest in your work, concentration, imag- ination." This is what we have found out in think- ing about different pursuits, and it is what makes the study of ethics, which deals with what is common to all aims, all work, all achievement, universally in- teresting and important.' Ill If you'are undertaking any work whatsoever, you are in so far interested in ethics. We can picture ethics as like a sun shooting out rays in eveiy direction. If you are interested in anything, the rays from ethics hit you. As it is only when you are a tramp without ties or aims that your citizenship becomes unreal, so it is only as you are a moral tramp with no stake in life anywhere that ethics cannot touch you. The tramp, as his name suggests, is always on the move, but yet going nowhere in particular. He will not settle down nor yet travel with any definite purpose. The moral tramp is out- 8 Everyday Ethics wardly respectable and usually covers less ground than his ragged brother of the road, but like all tramps he will not stick to anything, accumulate anything, or commit himself to anything. We may like or dislike him and he may like or dislike his beat; but duties he has none. He must first take a hand somewhere in the game of life ; hold some property, get a job, marry, or become an anarchist. As soon as he commits himself in any of these ways he is bound by duties on every side. Ethics is a real and living study only because it deals with the myriad interests of all who are taking a hand in the game of life, as citizenship is significant because it includes the myriad activities of all citizens. Wipe out all the pursuits and interests of its citizens and you have not the United States, but an absolute blank. So it is with ethics. Wipe out all the interests toward which ethics radiates, and ethics is nothing; it too is an absolute blank. This point is so important that we need to consider it carefully. Here is our Country to which we owe everything. What should we be without it ? Yet on the other hand without us, that is, without all the lives of its inhabitants, our country would be utterly meaningless. This does not mean that citizen- ship in the United States is but a name. No, it is the greatness of the country that it at the same time moulds and is moulded by the lives of all its citizens. So it is the strength, not the weakness, of ethics that, while concerned with all interests yet identical with none, it draws its life from the eager pursuits of which the Avprld is fijll. Wherever a human being strikes a job, The Diffusion of Ethics 9' there is ethical life, just as when the runner from a vine strikes the earth, there grows a root. Only those who are unrooted are outside of the grip of moral issues. IV It may easily seem that I am making ethics so central and all-pervasive a subject that it monopolises the world. The scientist may say : " You claim that ethics penetrates all human life, but science penetrates everything, human and non-human. Make room for science." The artist, too, and the lawyer finds material everywhere and will not be crowded out by ethics. There is no need that they should be. Ethics is one point of view from which to look at everything in the world, and science, art, and law are other points of view. The subject of marriage, for example, can be looked at from an ethical point of view. Ought any girl to marry a man who has consumption ? It can be looked at from an artistic point of view, as, in the love scenes of Romeo and Juliet. It can be looked at from a scientific point of view, as it is when the statis- tics of marriage and divorce are stated impartially and without reference to right and wrong or to the happi- ness and tragedy involved. Marriage can be looked at from a legal point of view. The law decides at what age a girl can marry without her parents' consent, what are the rights of a woman to her husband's prop- erty, what degree of ill-treatment is ground for annul- ling a marriage. Every subject may have these aspects and countless 10 Everyday Ethics ■others. I was once driving to a much-anticipated ball with a friend who, though also invited to the ball, had decided to go to a lecture which I thought very dull. As we drove along we had a hot discussion about the relative value and interest of these two ways of spend- ing the evening. As I was getting out at the house where the ball was to take place, our driver asked a question which brought home to us with a wholesome shock the difference between our point of view and his : " Where did you say," he inquired with a jerk of his head toward my friend in the carriage, " the other freight was to be unloaded ? " Everything in the world may be considered on its physical side, its aesthetic side, its legal side, and in countless other aspects. We are interested here in con- sidering everything from its ethical side. If we cut off from our present stu3y these other points of view and turn our undivided attention toward ethics we find at the outset an important ques- tion. Can the study of ethics make us good or show us what we ought to do? Only indirectly. A doctor can tell a young man that the use of opium is ruining his health. He can make this vivid by describing what the effect on his brain and his character will be. As a result the man may give up taking opium, but the doctor cannot make him give it up. Nevertheless it is the duty of the doctor to open the patient's eyes; then, if he chooses to go on, it is with his eyes open. The Diffusion of Ethics ill Ethics is like the doctor. It cannot force anyone to be good, but it can make us recognise that, just as small doses of opium gradually kill the body, so selfishness, indolence, falsehood, are suicide of the spiritual nature. It is important to realise, also, that ethics cannot touch us at all if we stand aloof from every aim and every interest. The great stream of active life, brimful of questions of right and wrong, flows along continu- ally, but we may sit on the bank and refuse to enter; we may dabble our hands in it and draw them out and let the shining drops slip through our fingers. " If you take small doses of morphine every day you will gradu- ally ruin your health and character," says the doctor. " Let them go," the infatuated man may answer. " If you want to go to college, you must study every even- ing." " I don't care whether I do or not," may be the baffling reply, baffling because the binding force of all these counsels depends on the word if, with which each begins, and if anyone denies his part in each and all of them, moral rules slip ofif him like water off a slanting roof. He is left to vegetate or become a brute as he will. Ethics cannot help us against our will ; it cannot help us when we have no will ; neither can it tell us the par- ticular steps we are to take. If you ask : " Does ethics show me what I ought to do?" the answer is again: " No." No book on ethics can tell you what you ought to do, because each life, and so the right choice in any life, is different from any that has been made before. A girl is trying to decide whether she ought to go to college or not. No book on ethics can say that she 12 Everyday Ethics ought to go to college, nor can it go so far as to say that all girls ought to go to college. She may be in duty bound to stay at home and take care of her blind father, and if it would be wrong for her to go, then it cannot be true that all girls should go, nor even that all girls who can afford it should go. It is the whole significance and joy of our lives that each one is dif- ferent and each decision new, like the first step in a field of unbroken snow. Ethics cannot direct the steps because no book or theory can anticipate our advance into the untrodden future. I said that ethics is the study of what to do and how to do it. I need to add at once that it gives the princi- ples or general rules for any act and never the par- ticular decision. We all follow the same principles when we carry out any plan, but we apply them dif- ferently. A glance at various careers will make this clearer. We have already seen that if you want to succeed in golf, medicine, society, or anything else you must know your subject thoroughly, know your own capacities, and apply steadily all your powers. The particular rule, however, is different in each case. The golfer says: Keep your eye on the ball. The doctor says: Keep your eye on the patient's lips. The politician says : Keep your eye on the State of New York. The music teacher says : Keep your eye on the notes. Ethics is concerned with what is called for in all these different directions, and that is among other things, attention, concentration, intentness. If you are going to do anything well you must look sharp. That The Diffusion of Ethics 13 is a universal rule of successful action, and so it is a law of ethics. The particular choice is unique, how- ever, your own and not another's, and so there can be no specific rule. Let us turn to the positive side. We already have had glimpses of what it is that ethics can do for us ; it is time to see more fully. Ethics helps us by giving us principles of action as tools for clearing away under- brush. Living is always making our way through an unexplored country, sometimes with dense woods to penetrate, sometimes with rushing rivers to navigate, and sometimes with open green fields where we are tempted to linger. The help ethics can give is very much like the help of having an axe with us on such a journey. The axe does not cut until we swing it, nor unless we keep it sharp ; nor does the axe decide for us what to cut. There are times when we hardly use it because our way is clear, but any day we may meet difficulties in which we should be utterly baffled with- out it. Many a moral question is as baffling and tangled as dense underbrush, and even where the decision is not in itself important it is often puzzling. My father and mother are away for a week when I wake up one morning with an uncomfortable cold. Ought I to go to school or not ? Of course, my mother would not want me to make my cold worse, nor, on the other hand, to miss school unnecessarily. At this stage of the question we have a deadlock. Either decision seems wrong. The first way in which the study of ethics would help me is to suggest that I must know the circumstances and my own nature better. How 14 Everyday Ethics bad is my cold? Am I feverish? Am I naturally strong? Have I had similar colds which vsrere not in- creased by going out? Is the schoolroom likely to be close or hot? If I dislike school, I am likely to find myself saying, " I may be feverish, and I might make my cold wrorse by going to school. Mamma would never want me to do that, and besides there is an examination in algebra to-day and if I go to-morrow I shall not have to take it." Ethics clears up this tangle in three ways. It helps us to see which facts are really relevant ; it helps us to clear away self-deceit; and it helps us to put in order our reasons, pro and con, so that instead of a jumble of mixed ideas we have a number of clear arguments on each side and can weigh and balance fairly. It is true that I have a cold, but I am naturally strong; I take my temperature and find I am not feverish; the sky is grey, but it hardly looks like a bad storm, and as for the examination, that has absolutely nothing to do with the question. It ought not to have the slightest weight. On the whole it is fairly clear that I ought to go, and if my cold is made worse I will take that into account another time. This last sentence suggests still further the help that careful thought about moral questions gives. It teaches us to glean from our past and from the past of others help that prevents our stumbling over recurring decis- ions or repeating old blunders. What should we think of a captain who went to sea in a ship whose seaworthiness he had never investigated? Yet our The Diffusion of Ethics 15 lives with their critical moral decisions are far more important than any boat, and we are the sole com- manders in them. We know it is blameworthy and foolhardy to sign papers whose contents we have not read. Is it not far more blameworthy and foolhardy to take upon ourselves the responsibilities of marriage or of the choice of a profession without all the foresight we can gain ? I A general of long experience can look over a be- wildering battle scene, see what is happening, and give the command for the best thing to be done. The smoke, the deafening noise, the masses of wounded, the scattered troops whose colours are so blurred that it is hard to tell friend from foe, are still there for him as for you ; but he has learned to see the important and put aside the irrelevant. He has a plan of battle which gives him a clue to guide his decision, he knows the principles of attack, he has gathered up the experience of other generals and of other battles. So in moral life if we are to be ready for experience we must learn to make our plan of battle and to formulate our princi- ples of attack through study, through practice, and through watching the career of others among us or before us on the field. The student of ethics has a rich mine of past expe- rience in which to dig. History shows certain recurring types of moral puzzles into which people fall again and again and which by hook or crook they finally conquer. We aim to anticipate these perils and, before the crisis comes, to avail ourselves of the experiences of the past in tackling these problems apd facing them with sys- 1 6 Everyday Ethics tern and deliberation instead of with the desperate courage born of necessity. We aim to pull the future into the present and so live more intensely and less at haphazard. We cannot take our morality on trust any more than our politics or religion; neither need we act as if no one had ever had such problems before, nor wait till the moment of temptation before we think out our principles. Sophistry or conventionalism is the result of not anticipating moral problems. Unless we think out our principles we are swayed by the sophistry of momentary desires, or we give up reasoning and accept old answers unquestioned. A boatman who canoes down a river frequently meets the problem of the eddy at corners. It has con- fronted thousands and upset hundreds. Similarly in ethics, there are certain whirlpools that come sooner or later in almost every life. They should be anticipated and their problems thought out. You may find a better solution than any hitherto discovered. Ethics does not prejudge the way of meeting the eddy. It suggests how the eddy has been and may be met, and stimulates you to realise the difficulty and to make an effort to find an ideal solution. Ethics is this systematic effort to anticipate and solve recurrent problems and to light up the new problems by fire kindled in the flame oit, past victories. CHAPTER II BOUNDARIES When a person buys a large piece of land, the first thing he does is to find out its boundaries. Otherwise he might waste time and get into trouble by cutting down trees or cultivating fields which did not belong to him. This is what we need to do before we go farther in the consideration of ethics. As I have said already, ethics is the study of right-choosing and well-doing, and anyone who is carrying out any plan whatsoever is concerned with it. But we need to make more definite the boundary lines between what is in the field of ethics, that is of moral life, and what is beyond it, Huxley's desire for a perfectly arranged clockwork life brings us at once in view of the whole question of moral responsibility : " I protest [he writes] that if some great power would agree to make me always think what is true and do what is right, on condition of being turned into a sort of clock and wound up every morning, I would instantly close with the offer." ^ Why is such a proposition utterly repugnant to us in spite of the freedom from sin, failure, doubt and effort which by Huxley's conditions are to go with the accept- »T. H. Huxley, "Lay Sermons." p. 3401 17 i8 Everyday Ethics ance of a clockwork life? We say that it is uninterest- ing, monotonous, dreary, that it would make people all alike, that it is too easy and leaves nothing to strive for ; but underlying all these answers is the deeper one that compulsion to do the right act wipes out the whole moral life which is the life of choice. We should not be ourselves if we were made to do right, we say,, and this is true, because if we did the right mechani-', cally we should lose the most characteristic part of our^ life as human beings, which is the power to choose what to do and how to do it. This realisation, that in spite of all the suffering, the disgrace, the struggle involved, we would rather be moral beings than perfect machines, is far-reaching in its significance. It takes away the bitterness even of sorrow, evil, and shame, because we recognise that they are a part of the life of morality, with all its eager outlook and all its possibility of growth. It is better to rise over difficulties than to have them smoothed away, better to resist evil and even to fail and be dis- graced than to live in the choiceless innocence of a violet or a crystal. Our reaction against Huxley's suggestion shows us that moral life is the life of choice. The non- responsible or machine-like life is beyond our con- trol. It may be absolutely beneficent in its results or it xnay be destructive of all that is good, but if beyond our control it is non-moral. A sleep-walker may go down stalls with a candle and set the curtains on fire, and the house may burn down. Her action is dis- astrous, but it is not sinful. She may, on the other Boundaries 19 hand, put out a fire in her sleep, but though useful, her deed is not praiseworthy. Moral life is voluntary, within our control, and we may choose half-heartedly, wilfully, carelessly, nar- rowly. Moral life, therefore, includes sin as well as virtue. The sleep-walker is at the time neither good nor sinful, but anyone who is morally responsible is free either to do right or to sin. When Pat, the office boy, is accused of doing wrong and feels that he is not guilty, he may assert this in various ways. He may say :, I was not myself when I did it; I was fast asleep; I was so absorbed that I forgot that you had forbidden it; I did not know it could do any harm; Charlie made me do it; I did it before I had time to think, or I \yas so frightened I could not help it. Here are six diiiferent excuses : unconsciousness, ab- sorption, ignorance, force, suddenness of impulse, fear. In each of them the appeal is made : " I was unable to choose, I had no control." Assuming that Pat is accurate in his statements, we can be sure that he is not responsible for the wrongdoing of which he has been accused. We are sure of this, because in the first three cases Pat was unconscious of his act or its con- sequences, while in the last three it was beyond his control, that is, involuntary. We can say then that an irresponsible act is one which is either unconscious or involuntary. I once knew a gentle and devoted servant who be- came insane and believed it her duty to murder a man whom she called James Dolan because I1& was about to 20 Everyday Ethics cause war between America and England, She was possessed by the idea, as we say; it controlled her instead of her controlling it ; and no matter how tragic the result of her act might have been, we should not call it sinful, because it was forced by an overmastering impulse. n This example of the non-moral is evident enough. The cases, however, in which people are not responsible shade off into cases where they might have done or known better. The non-moral shades into the moral as violet shades into blue in the rainbow, and though it is easy to mark off the violet of the rainbow from the red, as distinct and even sharply opposed in colour, it is very difficult to see just where the changes come. Many cases are " on the line," as we say in tennis, and we have got to get close and look very carefully before we can judge whether they are to be classified as responsible or not. The sleep-walker is not responsible for her deed, when she is wholly unconscious, but how shall we judge a case of entire oblivion, like that of Mag- gie Tulliver in " The Mill on the Floss," who caused the death of her brother's rabbits by forgetting to feed them? She was unconscious that she had, for- gotten the rabbits till too late to save them ; she would not have neglected them if she had thought of it, but the question is, could she have helped forgetting? To answer this we need to study Maggie's, character; Mrs. Tulliver gives us a description of Maggie that Boundaries 21 brings out vividly her dreamy temperament. "You talk of cuteness, Mr. Tulliver, but I'm sure the child's half an idiot in some things, for if I send her upstairs to fetch anything, she forgets what she's gone for, and perhaps 'ull sit down on the floor i' the sunshine an' plait her hair an' sing to herself like a Bedlam creatur', all the while I'm waiting for her downstairs. That never run i' my family, thank God, no more nor a brown skin as makes her look like a mulatter. I don't like to fly i' the face of Providence, but it seems hard as I should have but one gell and her so comical. There's Lucy Deane, she's such a good child you may set her on a stool and there she'll sit for an hour together and never offer to get off." ^ This dreaminess seems to have lain so deep in Mag- gie's nature that it really overwhelmed her remem- brance. She loved Tom intensely ; she meant to remem- ber the rabbits, but it all went out of her head. She was at the time non-responsible. ' Nor is such power of absorption wholly undesirable. When a girl becomes so absorbed in her music that she forgets a Latin lesson we have a somewhat similar result from a different cause. We all need to be con- centrated in our work; without concentration no first- rate work is done. Could this girl be at once deeply engrossed in her music and yet free enough to be aware when an hour had passed? We all know the type of practising in which the clock is consulted every few minutes that the proper limit may not be missed. We know, too, how slight is the gain « George Eliot, " The Mill on the Floss." 22 Everyday Ethics in musical ability which comes from such half-heafted work and how incapable of steady work the player soon becomes. " When you are practising you ought not to think of anything except your music," the teacher often says. If the girl followed this advice literally, and was wholly absorbed in reading the piano score of Lohengrin, she may have been in so deep a reverie at the time when she ought to have left the music and turned to the Latin lesson that she never once thought of the hour. Although her eyes are open, she is to all intents and purposes asleep, and no more responsible at the time than the sleep-walker. At the time, that is the central point. Unless it had never happened before, she was responsible for not remem- bering how easily she became absorbed in music and for not preparing for this, either by learning her lesson first or by asking someone to call her when the hour was over. Ill We are always responsible for preparing to become non-responsible. Even the sleep-walker, if she knew that she was in the habit of walking in her sleep, and was likely to do dangerous things, was responsible for not locking herself into her room and putting the matches where she could not reach them. In the same way Maggie Tulliver was responsible for promising impulsively to feed the rabbits, when a little thought would have recalled to her the probability of her for- getting all about it unless she asked someone to remind her of it. Yet Maggie Tulliver learned in her reveries Boundaries 23 much that Lucy Deane was never capable of knowing, and it is important to remember that it may be our highest, equally with our lowest, experiences which take us out of the moral sphere. It is often our duty to anticipate a period of irresponsibility. In Anne Gilchrist's "Life of Mary Lamb " there is a touching account of her periodic insanity. She felt the attacks coming on, and knew that she was going to become irresponsible. She knew she might kill her brother, as she had killed her mother. " Then would Mary as gently as possible prepare her brother for the duty he must perform. . . . On one occasion Mr. Charles Lloyd met them slowly pacing together a little footpath in Hoxton fields, both weeping bitterly, and found on joining them that they were taking their solemn way to the accustomed asylum." ^ This is a case of noble moral preparation for a non- moral state. In little ways the need of such prepara- tion comes up every day. If, while I am asleep some night, the sparks of my wood-fire fly out and burn the rug, I cannot say as an unanswerable excuse : " Oh, it wasn't my fault; I couldn't help it. I was fast asleep." I knew that I was about to go to sleep, that is, to get into an irresponsible or non-moral condition, and I ought to have prepared for it by covering the fire so thoroughly with ashes that the sparks could not fly out. Nearly as common as unconscious acts are acts done through ignorance; here, in judging moral respon- •Mary Lamb, by Anne Gilchj-ist, p. 97, 24 Everyday Ethics sibility, we have always to ask whether the ignorance was unavoidable. Many accidents are caused by cul- pable ignorance. The phrase, " I did not know it was loaded," is almost proverbial as a lame excuse for care- lessness. Yet acts which look apparently blameworthy shade imperceptibly into those that are non-moral. A boy is firing off cannon-crackers on the Fourth of July, and having experienced the joyful noise caused by the explosion of a small cracker under a tin can, he puts a cannon-cracker under the can and gets his brother to hold the can down with his foot. The result is a bad injury. Is the first boy responsible? The answer depends wholly on the decision whether he could have foreseen the disastrous effect of the large cracker. If not, he was not responsible. We reach here this general conclusion : No one who is practically or actually asleep, in any way not him- self, or necessarily ignorant of what the consequences of his act may be, is responsible for his acts, good or bad. He is responsible for making any preparation he might have made before he lost his control, or, in the case of ignorance, for thinking before he acted. . I have taken up so far cases on the border-line be- tween consciousness and unconsciousness, and shown that when we are unconscious, as in sleep, deep ab- sorption, or any other cause, we are at the time non- moral beings. I come now to a different type of non-responsibility, that brought about by suddenness of temptation. Take, for example, the case of a man of violent temper, who is so fired by a stinging insult Boundaries 25 that he instantly stabs his companion with a knife. If we ask him why he did it, he raphes that he could not help it His hand struck the blow before he could con- trol it. If this was true, if the act was as uncon- trollable as winking when we are hit, we can be sure that he was at the moment non-moral, unanswerable for the act his hand did. He was not himself at the time ; he was like an engine with no engineer to regu- late its speed. To be capable of morality you must be yourself. But if, as is highly probable, he had lost his temper at other times, and acted in ways he after- wards regretted, he was responsible for letting himself become irresponsible. To judge whether he was sinful, we should need to know what his inheritance and early training were, whether he could have rightly avoided the encounter which aroused his passion, and whether he could have dominated his anger in the early stages when it was only rumbling within him. But to know whether he was or was not responsible for this act we need only to know whether even an instant's glimmer of an alterna- tive action came to liim, or whether, on the contrary, the act of striking was as automatic as that of a clock when the hour and minute hands meet at twelve. Similar to temper, in its' sudden and often irresistible power, is the influence of fear. An official is se'/it by the government to the Yosemite with a large sum of money to pay the salaries of the soldiers sta- tioned there to protect the forests from fire. As the coach rounds a corner two masked highwaymen spring from behind the rocks and shout : " Hands up! " Up 26 Everyday Ethics go all hands automatically: "As if," the driver said afterward, " you'd done nothing else all your life." The oflficial messenger is covered by a pistol and robbed with the rest of the passengers. The question whether he was morally responsible rests wholly on the decision whether he had enough control of himself at the time to choose any alternative act. He may have lost his head completely; his, masterless body may have followed an irresistible impulse of self-protection. To throw up his hands was probably an unconscious act; and whether it was wise or foolish, it was in this case outside the sphere of morals. During the minutes that succeeded this act, while the passengers were being robbed of their money and watches, the official, unless wholly un- nerved, must have had time to think and he thereby became responsible for his next act, whether of sub- mission or of resistance. While not responsible for throwing up his hands, he was in all probability re- sponsible for the decision whether it was wise or fool- ish to take them down. In this case, as in the others we have discussed, though the moment's surprise may have swept away all self-control, the preparation for such an event may have been clearly his duty. At some point or other in the man's life there probably was an opportunity for thought on the risk of and the preparation needed for this work. Without opportunity for thought, either at the time or beforehand, there is no moral responsibility. Boundaries 27 IV The two cases last cottsidered were those in which dominant impulses of anger and fear apparently forced men to act contrary to what they really believed best. We take up next a more subtle case. As Dante passes through the lowest circle of Paradise he sees the Em- press Constance, whom he has often heard of as saintly in her conduct, but snatched by a cruel compulsion away from her convent and forced to marry and live in the world. Dante, in great surprise, inquires of Beatrice why such a holy and innocent person should not be in the highest circle of Paradise. Beatrice answers: " Though there be violence when he who suffers nowise consents to him who compels, these souls were not by reason of that excused. For will unless it wills is not quenched, but does as nature does in fire, though vio- lence a thousand times may wrest it. Wherefore, if it bends little or much it follows the force and thus these did, having power to return to the holy place." * 1 Constance is not re^onsible for her act. She is responsible for letting her will, which (as Dante believes) was within her control, yield itself to what to her was less noble than the life of her convent. Here we reach an important distinction. Moral responsibility means the opportunity for thought, and the facing of alternatives. Where that is present we are responsible because we are capable of desiring a right or wrong act, even though it may be physically impossible for us to carry out either course. When * " Paradise," Canto IV. lines 73-81, Norton's translation. 28 Everyday Ethics a stronger comrade seizes a younger boy and prevents him from going home, the small boy is still responsible for wishing to stay out or to go home. Physical force cannot control his vision of the right and wrong alter- native. It is only if the younger boy has no glimmer of an alternative that we can call him non-responsible.^, So Constance was within and not oufcside the sphere of morality. The apothecary in " Romeo and Juliet " " who, while selling the poison to Romeo, maintained that his poverty and not his will gave consent, is still more evidently within the sphere of responsibility. We know it, not only in spite of his asseveration : " My poverty, but not my will consents," but largely because of it. Shakspere's wonderful description of his pov- erty prepares us to face the question whether his hunger drove him beyond the power of self-control. " I do remember an apothecary. And hereabouts he dwells, whom late I noted. In tattered weeds, with overwhelming brows. Culling of simples, — meagre were his looks. Sharp misery had worn him to the bones." It seems at first as if suchTiunger and misery might well have made him irresponsible, yet in this case I think there is no doubt of his moral responsibility. We know this because : He was neither asleep, unconscious, nor insane; he clearly knew the law, and the effect of poison; no physical force nor intimidation were used; he had time to think; by his own statement he recog- nised a possible choice, 6 Act V, scene i. Eoundaries 29 Non-moral acts are those due to unconsciousness or to ignorance. They are automatic and without choice. The act of the apothecary was dehberate and free; hence, whether or no it was right or wrong, it was certainly his own act, and not compelled, as he claimed it to be. Through the study of many cases we have now' reached a clear definition of moral action. Such deeds 'must be deliberate, the acts of one who is awake and knows what he is doing, and they must be voluntary, that is, the actor must have at least the ghmmer of an alternative choice. It is at first startling to realise that every one of us ceases to be responsible during at least one-third of his entire life. In sleep we drop all responsibility and become for the time as passive as lumps of clay. And even during the hours when we call ourselves awake, a large proportion of what we do is a matter of pure habit and not within our control. Many of our habits are so ingrained that we are unaware of them. They are like the rhythmic swing of the right foot with the left arm in walking, so deep-rooted by repetition that change is almost impossible. Every one of us has acquired rigid habits ; everyone sleeps a large proportion of his life, spends more or less time in reverie, gets so absorbed in music or worship, in reading or the theatre, that he forgets everything else. We let ourselves become almost like plants, alive but totally unconscious and non-moral. Can this be 30 Everyday Ethics right? Surely, when it is done ioi the sake of greater power in active life. Without sleep we should soon become nervous wrecks, battered and unseaworthy. There is for all of us a corresponding need of regular habits. It is the steadying power of regular hours of rising and eating, work and recreation, the com- plete surrender of thought about trifles, that alone makes advance possible. The pianist who has to think about each note cannot play with freedom; his fingers must work automatically before his atten- tion can be free to receive and express the meaning of the music he is playing. If we were aware of every mouthful we ate, or chose freshly each night the hour of going to bed, our attention would be so engrossed by details that all our important work would be badly done or neglected. It is only by choos- ing for a part of our time, and in many of our acts to be non-moral, that we can accomplish anything. It is then right to become irresponsible in every instance where by so doing we gain on the whole in the power of fulfilling our purposes ; if we lose on the whole, it is wrong. There is some risk in this. It is a part of every moral life to take risks. The risk of our doing mischief while unconscious is usually not enough to balance the gain of sleep. If, however, I am driving an engine, it is immoral to let myself go to sleep, because the risk is too great. We take risks, for the sake of greater gain : in meditation which may only unfit us for work but ought to strengthen us with new insight , in worship, which may leave us Boundaries 31 overwrought and 'nervous, but should give us new vigour and impulse. Reverie, too, though a risk, is necessary to the finest moral life, necessary that purposes may not crowd, push and wear out their owner, but be brought into a single whole. I " We are too busy, too encumbered, too much occu- pied, too active. We must know how to put our occupa- tion aside ; which does not mean that we must be idle. In inaction which is meditative and attentive the wrinkles of the soul are smoothed away, and the soul itself spreads, unfolds and springs afresh, and, like the trodden grass of the roadside or the bruised leaf of a plant, repairs its injuries, becomes new, spontaneous, true and original. Reverie, like the rain of night, restores colour and force to thoughts which have been blanched and wearied by the heat of the day. With gentle fertilising power it awakens within us a thou- sand sleeping germs, and gathers round us materials for the future and images for the use of talents. Rev- erie is the Sunday of thought, and who knows which is the more important and fruitful for man, the labo- rious tension of the week or the life-giving repose of ■ the Sabbath ? It is like a bath which gives vigour and suppleness to the whole being, to the mind as well as to the body." ® There are then tracts of life wherein we are non- moral or non-responsible, but as long as this state is chosen because by so doing we can, on the whole, best , fulfil our purposes, it is not wrong, but right. « Amiel, "Journal Intime," Translated by Mrs. Humphry Ward, vol. i.. p. 43. CHAPTER III THE POWER OF PURPOSE In the last chapter we found that all who are uncon.'- scious of what they are doing and all who are acting involuntarily, that is, without any alternative before them, are not responsible for their actions, and so are excluded from the moral realm. We saw that if Pro- fessor Huxley's wish for a character incapable of wrongdoing had been granted, his choice of such a' character would have been his last moral act. With its fulfilment the whole field of responsible life would have been wiped out as the tide levels the castles we build upon the sand. Moral life is that part of our existence in which we are answerable, in which we choose. If a bricklayer, through no carelessness of his own, drops a hod of bricks from the roof and kills a man who is passing below, we say that he is not responsi- ble, because his act was involuntary. He could not help it, he was unconscious of the danger, he did not mean to hurt anyone, he did not do it on purpose. The common expression : " I did it on purpose," is an accurate one. The moral life is the life wherein we carry out our purposes. Since this is so, it becomes important to know just what we mean by a purpose. 32 The Power of Purpose 33 I will take up first the difference between a purpose and a fact. It is certainly different to say : " I am on the way to New York " and to say " I am planning to go to New York during the Christmas vacation." Evidently there is a kind of desire or hunger in the purpose that is not in the fact. The fact is, as it were, settled back comfortably in its chair, the purpose leans forward eagerly. The fact rests in the present, the purpose stretches into the future. The fact is at one with itself, the purpose is never at one with itself : it yearns toward what is not itself. A purpose, then, as contrasted with a fact, has desire in it. There is the same sort of contrast between a pur- pose and a day-dream. As we dream before the fire we are placid, content. We build with busy fingers our castles in the air. It is easy and delight- ful; but when dinner-time comes we wake to find not only that our castles have crumbled, but that their building has filled the hours we had planned for work. The difference between a dream and a purpose is that the former is passive and the latter active. The dreamer is content, the planner hungry for attainment. Wishes are hungry, too. " How I wish I were going to New York; I want to go dreadfully." There seems to be plenty of desire in the wish, but we begin to doubt its genuineness when we ask : " Well, have you taken any steps toward going ? " and are answered. " No, but I wish someone would pay my expenses." " Can't you earn or save the money?" "Well, I suppose I might, if I gave up going to the opera, but I don't 34 Everyday Ethics want to do that." The difference between a wish and a purpose seems to be this: When we purpose, we take the means to our eiid; when we wish, we wait for the end to come our way. Wishes often grow into purposes, but as long as they are nothing but , wishes they remain inactive. "If wishes were horses, J beggars would ride." Mr. C. P. Huntington, who died t lately and left many millions, started without a cent lin the world and won it all by his energy and intelli- igence. Here is a beggar who did ride, but it was because his wish was also a purpose. I do not admire his business standards, but I do admire his energy. The difference between a purpose and an impulse is that a purpose has thought in it. " Why did you go out skating?" "Oh, Helen was going, and I went along, too." She simply followed like a sheep who takes the same path as the rest of the flock. " Why did you go out skating?" I ask of another girl. " Because I've made up my mind that I am going to learn the outer roll before the winter is over." " Made up my mind " : we use this expression often, but we do not usually realise all that it means. A per- son who has not made up his mind is in a queer state. " I can't decide whether to go out to walk or to stay in the house." Now a little tug pulls me toward the door, " It doesn't seem to be raining much, I guess I'll go." Then another little tug comes in the other direction. "That new novel looks so interesting, I believe I won't go out. But then I always feel soggy and stupid if I don't," so I am tugged toward the door again. " Oh ! it's raining harder now and my hat is The Power of Purpose 35 trimmed with velvet." This state is close to that of my being two persons and so morally irresponsible. When on the contrary you have a clear purpose, you make up your mind what to do, quickly or slowly, according to the difficulty of the case, but once for all. " I have an engagement to give a music lesson at 3 o'clock. It is 2.35 now; of course I must go at once." The difference between a person who has a purpose and whose mind is therefore made up, and one who I is dreaming or vacillating, is so great that we can see it in the very way each walks down the street. The woman who has a definite aim walks straight and steadily; the one without an aim saunters, hesitates at corners and is lured by every shop windc 1. With- out an aim she has no rudder and therefore drifts about on the line of least resistance. By distinguishing purposes from facts, dreams, wishes, impulses and fancies, we learn this about the nature of a purpose. A purpose, to be a purpose truly, must have thought, foresight and will. A purpose is more and more distinguished from a whim or a "^dream in proportion as it is clearly chosen and per- sistently held. ri .There are a good many people who are moved by any impulse and have no steady purpose, nothing with which they are identified. Two girls of fifteen come to pass a fortnight with their aunt at the sea- shore. One plans from the start that she will learn 36 Everyday Ethics to swim well before the end of that visit. She sets out each day and without wasting any time or en- ergy in jumping about and splashing the water over her friends, she devotes herself to getting the stroke and forces herself to cut loose as soon as possible from supports and to become confident in the water. The other girl has no aim. When she goes down town the candy shops attract her, and every girl who drops in to call can make her change her occupa- tion. She picks up a magazine article, but does not find it worth finishing. She is excited for half an hour over the plan of getting up a play, but finds it too much trouble to learE her part, ajid abandons it. At the end of the fortnight, the first girl has become a good swimmer, the second has become thoroughly bored. Slft'^has sipped the cream off everything and is satiated but not nourished. This girl is for the time almost outside of morality. It is impossible to help her until she herself will take hold of some pur- pose and stick to it. Like an aimless June bug who is never still, she wearies herself and all those around her. Such a girl is hardly to be called sin- ful, because she has no purpose to which to be loyal ; she is far more like a cork tossed about by the waves. We cannot really tell whether she is either good or bad until we know whether she could hold to a purpose if she had one. Tennyson, in " The Lotus Eaters," pictures some sailors who have reached ah enchanted island and eaten of the lotus which brings forgetfulness. Every aim is slipping away from them; even the thought of The Power of Purpose 37 their wives and children far away at home is dim and unreal. " They sat them down upon the yellow sand, Between the sun and moon upon the shore. And sweet it was to dream of Fatherland, Of child and wife and slave, but evermore Most weary seemed the sea, weary the oar. Weary the wandering fields of barren foam. Then someone said: 'We will return no more,* And all at once they sang: ' Our Island home Is far beyond the wave; we will no longer roam.'" They seem to be acting in a dastardly way and to be neglecting every duty for the bliss of dreaming on this lovely island, and yet we cannot call them good or bad because they have no purpose. They were responsible for eating of the Lotus if they knew it would bring forgetfulness, but once its subtle influ- ence has taken possession of them, they drift over the border that divides the moral from the irresponsible. The moral life is the life of purpose and no one with a purpose can drift along in the Lotus Eaters' peace. Ill If we have a purpose it means that we want to do something and so to make something different from what it now is. I have set my heart on having a watch which costs fifty dollars. It is not simply a wish on my part, it is a definite purpose. Such a pur- pose immediately begins to affect both what I do and what I refuse to do. If I am to get a watch and if I 38 Everyday Ethics have no way of borrowing the money, I must earn it. If I am going to earn money I must become capable of doing well something that is needed, and I must put aside all that will interfere with my making and sav- ing the money till I have enough for my purpose. I decide to learn wood-carving well enough to earn fifty dollars by selling picture frames. I must work at it every afternoon and refuse all invitations and allure- ments. I am not going to spend any of my earnings until my end is attained. Theatres and magazines are good things in themselves, but they have become wrong for me because I have identified myself with a person who is earning a watch. As soon as I have undertaken my purpose some acts become wrong and others right for me. This is a very important point. It is only through relation to a purpose great or small that acts become either right or wrong. Any purpose at once classifies acts and separates the sheep from the goats. The moral life takes hold of us as soon as we begin to aim at any end which we think worth while. Our first impression may be that we have no purpose at all. " Why, I haven't any special end in life," one says, or again, " My purpose is only to make my fathei give me the cash to go to the Newport tournament." To one his purpose seems too indefinite and un- analysed, to the other, too concrete and small to be either moral or immoral. Nevertheless, all purposes are included in the moral realm, from the vague pur- pose of " doing good " to the concrete purpose of playing marbles; and by looking more attentively The Power of Purpose 39 than we usually do, we shall recognise purposes in ourselves. If you have no end in life, why are you living? The very fact of your living on suggests purpose. The fact of your getting up and dressing in the morning, unless it is pure habit or has no plan at all in it, shows that you are alive and responsible. If you have no purpose in life, why not lie still in bed ? Because it is lazy, because I have to take a music lesson, because I want to go skating. In each of these cases you have a plan, and it is this which prevents you from lying still like a log, or getting up merely from habit. You are planning to persuade your family to go to Newport at the time of the tennis tournament. This does not seem to be an important purpose, but it comes under the same head as every other chosen act, and can be judged as right or wrong. It is not the kind of purpose, but the fact that one has any purpose whatsoever that is the password to the moral sphere. Even if a person says, " I hate re- sponsibility ; I'm going to be just as irresponsible as I can," he becomes morally responsible through that purpose; for to resist all impulses toward steady work and to devote oneself to being an animal, is to carry out a difficult project and so to be subject to moral laws. No one can carry out a steady plan of being non-responsible, because he is constantly responsible for that plan and deliberately to choose and cling to a machine-like existence requires gre^t activity, persistency and resplutioij. 40 Everyday Ethics IV No matter how trivial our plan may be, it Is some- thing with which ethics is concerned. Spencer^ says that moraHty is not at all concerned with such a choice as whether we take our pleasure walk by the waterfall or along the seashore. He is not thinking of people too absorbed to be conscious of choice. He holds that there are many chosen acts which are yet perfectly indifferent. The pedestrian who says : " Shall I go by the waterfall or ramble along the seashore " is not unconscious, lost in reverie, or unaware of any alter- native. He can choose. Still, Spencer says, even when we are wide-awake, entirely ourselves, deliber- ately asking questions, there are many choices with which morality has no concern. With this view I differ. Morality, I maintain, is concerned with every choice we make, although of course many are unimportant, like the subor- dinate yet essential details of any work of art. In a great novel or picture, there are many pai'ts which are more prominent than others; the hero and heroine have to be described far more elaborately than the waiter or the distant cousin. But though the novelist will not dwell on these minor characters, we know that anything which comes into his scheme must be appropriately done. So it is with the rest of life. Ethics is concerned with every chosen act, but some are rightly much more prominent in con- sciousness than others. It is perfectly true that the choice between going by the waterfall or rambling * " Data of Ethics," chapter i, section 2. The Power of Purpose 41 along the seashore is usually unimportant, but it is the myriad small decisions which disintegrate or strengthen character, just as it is " the thousand name- less, unremembered acts of kindness and of love,"* which make up a good man's life. If we go back to what Spencer says we shall see why it sounds true, but is misleading. " Stirring. the fire or opening the window," he says, " are (as cur- rently conceived) acts with which morality has no concern." This is true when such acts are done unconsciously or without purpose, but not when chosen. We recognise this as soon as we come to a real case, a case in which we are told more of the circumstances. As you lie before the camp fire on a bitter cold night, very sleepy, but knowing that your companions are shivering, is it not a moral act to get up and stir the fire? Or if by opening the win- dow, overheated as you are, you are likely to catch a violent cold, is not that an immoral act? Every chosen act of anyone whose life is guided by its purpose is either right or wrong. Take one of the other cases of which Spencer speaks, " Reading the newspaper," he says, " is an act with which morality, as currently conceived, has no concern." How untrue this statement is when we examine it! Reading the newspaper may be right or it may be wrong, and it may be of little or of vast importance. For instance, we read the newspapers to get the information necessary to vote intelligently for the next President of the United States. Almost 2 Wordsworth, " Tintern Abbey." 42 Everyday Ethics all the information of the average man about poli- tics comes from the newspapers, and if nobody in the country read them, voting would be a farce. On the other hand, to read a newspaper may be absolutely sinful. Suppose I am left in charge of a baby near the edge of a pond. In my newspaper there is a fascinating article on Salvini's acting and I am tempted to neglect the baby in order to read it. This is clearly not an indifferent act. ' The difficulty in Spencer's position seems to be that he speaks of acts like opening a window, or reading a newspaper, as if they might be wholly severed from the rest of the actor's life. Taken out of their setting in this way they are non-moral because they are as meaningless as a single word cut out of a letter. But in reality a chosen act never is without some setting of purpose, and as soon as we are told what the pur- pose is, we see that the act is, like all acts of choice, right or wrong. There is, then, no conscious choice with which morality is unconcerned; though some choices should be made swiftly, and without hard thought, while others need long pondering and keen search for light on the situation. I ought usually to think little zibout the direction of my afternoon walk, and long and hard about my choice of a profession, but both decisions are moral whenever they are not purely impulsive. It is obviously wrong to think long on unimportant subjects or briefly on important ones. But what does " important " mean ? It means closely related to your burpqs^. The Power of Purpose 43 To have a plan, to be about something-, is then the distinguishing mark of the moral realm, and also the most characteristic trait of humanity. Man is an ani- mal who makes and carries out plans. Other animals seem not to look so far beyond the present moment. " Man looks before and after," and so aims at a new cotton-gin, a new symphony, a new kingdom, while animals build their nests, seek their food and repro- duce their species practically unchanged from century to century. If you see a starving cat standing before a bowl of milk, there is certainty as to the result, but if you see a man with a glass of water presented to his parching lips, you cannot predict the result without knowing him through and through. If he is a David, he may pour it on the ground as an offering to the Lord ; if he is a Sir Philip Sidney, he may give it to the dying soldier by his side. We see here strikingly how such men as David or Sidney are factors in their own destiny be- cause they can convert their impulse from a blind impelling force into an intended end. They make up their mind about it, make it theirs instead of being subservient to it; and this means that they take their impulsive desire out of its isolation and bring it into connection with the rest of their life. Just this differ- ence makes the capacity for a moral or an immoral life. The cat, if she is thirsty, drinks. No alternative seems present to her, but in a man, though just as thirsty, other impulses, other plans, other interests 44 Everyday Ethics come into play. He draws in other moments of his life, other ideals of himself, to compete with and withstand this domineering craving. Deeper than his parching thirst is his love of his neighbour ; he will not drink the water and see another die of thirst. The impulsive craving for something to satisfy his thirst, if it were his only want, would compel him to drink, but it is not alone, as it would be in an animal. He can think about his neighbour's thirst. It is thought that holds his different desires together, and makes him see what is most important. For thought draws his im- pulses in out of anarchy, out of chaos, and makes them his own, the act of the whole person. All the richness and nobility of human life, all man's heroism and genius are made possible by this fundamental tendency to gather up the past and the distant; to shape it into a plan and this plan into a new act. This is the power of purpose which makes man capable of freedom and of progress. This power to make a plan is far-reaching in its effects. Man grows with cumulative swiftness. Be- cause a cat acts necessarily on impulse, her wants and the range of her activities never grow. A year hence you will find her seeking the same ends that she seeks now. We talk about the ingenuity with which birds build their nests. Birds' nests look ingenious and complicated ; but each generation of birds builds its nest in practically the same way, no matter how exposed to danger it is, for birds learn little by experience. If man built birds' nests, he would long ago have had umbrella tops, wire doors and gratings for protection The Power of Purpose 45" against grey squirrels and cats. He would have added heaters and made provision for cleanliness. The difference between acting on impulse or in- stinct and acting from a purpose, is that impulses alone never enlarge the want, and purposes, carried out, always do. The cat, when she is hungry, snatches at the proffered food, and under like condi- tions always will, but to think about an impulse for food, means to control the unreasoned and momen- tary tendency to seize it. It means to think not only of that moment's impulse, but of other moments, and, as we grow more and more conscious, to think not only of moments, but of a whole lifetime; not only of our own life, but of our family or our country. What seems but a slight distinction, becomes an all-im- portant one. The cat feels hungry and eats. The man feds hungry, realises the necessity of the future supply of food, ploughs, sows seed and gathers into barns ; sends carloads of grain from West to East and over the sea and establishes commerce. The cat looks to the moment; man looks before and after, shapes his destiny and becomes capable of endless growth. CHAPTER IV GOODNESS THE ESSENCE OF MANHOOD* I SUPPOSE hardly an hour passes in the lives of most people without their hearing the words, " That's good," or " that's too bad." If a phonograph should i' report conversations held at the same time in different parts of a town it would resound with the conception of goodness. " Get me a good beefsteak." " I want a good piece of silk, one that will not wear out quickly." " Johnny, if you're not good, I shall have to send you upstairs." " I've had such a good time ! " " That's a good drive." " That balloon's no good ; it's all squashed." " That was a good speech of Roosevelt's." " I don't consider that a good policy." " I've got a good typhoid case for you." " Good for you ! " Such wide uses of " good " cannot but suggest to us that the goodness of man is part of a larger conception of goodness which runs through the universe. What is the common element in all good things? Take, for example, a poem: When we call a poem good, we mean that it is one in which all the parts are perfectly adjusted, so that each has its rightful place, large or small, as the case may be. We call a 1 In this chapter my indebtedness to George H. Palmer's "Nature of Goodness" (Houghton, Mifflin, 1903) is very great 46 Goodness the Essence of Manhood 47 train good with a similar significance. " That's a good train ; it ought to go to New York in five hours." Ought to, because that is what it is meant to do, what it is fitted for. Goodness seems to mean fulfilHng the purpose, doing what you were meant to do effi- ciently. Goodness is fitness and fitness for a purpose. ,,' We see at once, however, that we do not judge good- ness merely by fitness to any purpose whatsoever. , Kindling wood is good when it lights the fire quickly. But a poem of Kipling's is not proved good by the same test. I have read somewhere the story of an Indian, who, seeing John Lawrence with a newspaper, said: " Give me one, Sahib." Lawrence knew he could not read, and was surprised to see him staring for hours at the paper. Finally the Indian gave it up and pronounced it a bad paper. When asked for his rea- sons, he said : " I have held it up many hours and my eyes are as uncomfortable as before." The Indian thought of the paper as a cure for weak eyes, and hence bad if it did not fulfil that purpose. " What a bad day it is," says the tennis player. " What a good rain," says the farmer. They are speaking of the same day, but they have very different purposes in mind. Each is right from his own point of view. Anything is good when fitted for the purpose held in mind, and bad when not so fitted. In many cases we do not know in relation to what purpose an object should be judged. " Is that good ? " says the child, holding up a tin pan pierced with small holes. " Good for what? " I ask. "For a dipper? Most 48 Everyday Ethics decidedly not." Unless we clearly know the puipos.e of anything our judgment is as likely to be wrong as right, or rather we cannot judge at all; knowing the purpose means knowing what anything belongs to, what its relations are. I find a bit of steel and am tempted to throw it away, but my friend comes along and says : " Have you seen the cap that fits over the valve of my bicycle? Oh! I'm so glad; the machine is absolutely no good without it." Even a great work of art is of significance through the relation of its parts to a central purpose. No siiigle word of Hamlet's soliloquy, " To be or not to be," has any value by itself. Anybody can say "to" or "not" or "be." Yes; but the soliloquy is admirable because each word is a part of a complex whole, into which it fits and there fulfils its special purpose. The word or the bit of steel is not itself when out of its place. It is the servant of an end greater than itself, and without knowing the whole, of which it is a part, we cannot tell whether it is good or bad. We should at first say, for example, that to light a cigar with a hundred-dollar banknote would always be an outrageous use of money. There was once an occasion on which it was the best possible use of the money. During the war in Cuba one of the American generals was approached by an office-seeker. The general knew he was unfit and refused. As the appli- cant rose to go he insidiously slipped a one-hundred- dollar bill into the general's hand. " Please stay and smoke a cigar with me," said the general instantly, Goodness the Essence of Manhood 49 and he handed the visitor a cigar. Then he delib- erately took a match and lighting the one-hundred-dol- lar bill held it out to his guest so that he could light his cigar with it. When the bill was in ashes, the general turned again to his work and the dismayed office- seeker retired. The one hundred dollars had served the important purpose of utterly discouraging bribery. II It is another aspect of the essential relation between goodness and purpose that when an object has no pur- pose, or seems to have none, we cannot call it either good or bad.' We speak naturally of a good golf stick, a good knife, a good pudding, or a good horse, for we have their purpose clearly in mind, but it seems far-fetched to call a stone either good or bad. You would hardly call a sea-anemone or a snail good unless you were seeking specimens, and therefore had a dis- tinct purpose which you were ready to apply as a test. It is hard, however, to find examples of absolutely purposeless things, and the reason for this is interest- ing. It is because purpose is the key which man brings with him to unlock every closed door and he almost never leaves it behind. " What's that good for? " we ask, on seeing anything new or strange. We are at sea until we know. "You're a good-for-nothing vaga- bond," exclaims the irate housekeeper to the tramp.- " Good-for-nothing." That is the worst term of re- proach, more disheartening than the sharpest criticism. Here is the wide universe with its myriad opportuni- 50 Everyday Ethics ties, needs, and purposes, and you are good in no single one of them all. Yet even the tramp may be a good comrade, for it is hard to find anything that is strictly good for nothing. The very garbage of our city is a fertilizer which helps to beautify our fields. Those who are poorer or more ingenious than ourselves scour our ash heaps to find good things. The ship, after serving its purpose at sea, goes to pieces, water-logged. Has all the goodness gone from it? No, the artist finds it "an unusually good subject"; the buyer of driftwood is willing to pay extra for its saturation with copper, and the barnacles find on it a protecting home. " Dirt is matter in the wrong place," but in its right place, its goodness is preeminent. So many are the purposes of the world, so infinite the fertility of man's growing mind, that the purposeless, that which is " no good," is pushed steadily into lower and lower strata. "Imperial Caesar, dead and turn'd to clay. Might stop a hole to keep the wind away." "To what base uses we may return." Yes, our bodies return to less noble uses than to hold the con- quering mind of a Caesar or a Shakspere, but they do not become absolutely useless. Purpose is the centre of human life, and just in so far as a man is human, he recognises and constructs purposes. It is the mark of an active and cultivated mind that it sees use, pur- pose, goodness, where others see blankness or badness. . Goodness the Essence of Manhood 51 in Clearly the " good," is that which is fitted for some purpose. Is it then true that the more purposes any one thing fulfils, the better it is? I was fascinated as a child by an object in our dining-room described as follows: "Day's Patent Chimney Ornaments to represent Gothic architecture are so constructed that they may be used for Fire-screens, Flower or Scent Jars, Candlesticks, Timepiece cases. Candle shades, and various other useful purposes. The patent candle screen may be removed from the stand and used as a hand screen or fan." Of course, it might have been added that it would serve as a reading lesson, an example of elegant English and a paper-weight. That ornament, however, was never made useful. Here we can again advance a step. It seems that things are not necessarily better because they serve a great many purposes. The best razor is not the one which is also a knife. The best racing boat is not also the one which is safest for children. Some ends seem to be contradictory ; we have then to face the question of sacrifice. Goodness involves not being everything at once. The Jack of all trades is master of none. If then an object is not made good by the number or variety of the purposes for which it can be used, wherein does its goodness consist? What is it that makes a good friend good? A good friend is one who embodies in himself the very essence and flower of friendship. He is delicately adapted to that purpose, as the racehorse is bred to perfection for racing. 52 Everyday Ethics Sometimes we say of a very slow horse, " That horse is a cow." A bad horse is hardly to be called a horse, for he has not the characteristic qualities. The good umbrella is one that is well adapted to keep off the rain. The good man is he who has in full measure the qualities of a man. The supreme designation of human goodness is that which Hamlet applies to his father : Horatio: "1 saw him once, he was a goodly king.'* Hamlet: " He was a man, take him for all in all, I shall not look upon his like again." =^ IV When we compare the use of goodness as commonly applied to things with its use in relation to man's conscious ends, we find a great deal of likeness and several important differences. [We will begin with the likeness: Goodness means fitness whether we apply the word to the goodness of man or to the goodness of any thing. The good knife is fitted to cut well, that is what a knife is meant for. The good man is he who is fitted for manhood. The Latin word for virtue (virtus) means primarily manliness. The virtuous man is the man who is fully a man, or as we some^ times say, " humane." As the knife is not truly a knife if it has lost its power of cutting, so an im- moral man is hardly a man at all. He is a beast. He is less of a man than I thought him, we say. It is impoirtant to remember the oneness of virtue with 2" Hamlet," Act I. scene 2. Goodness the Essence of Manhood 53 manhood; for we have a curious way of using the word " virtue," as if it were something conventional and superficial, instead of the life of man when he is truly man. The outer bark of a tree is not essen- tial to its health, it may fall away without injuring ithe tree, but below there is living, growing wood, and '; if this dies, the tree, though it may stand for years, is (Uot alive. So virtue is the growing centre of man's I life, and in its death, he dies. We found that the goodness of anything means its fitness for a special purpose, not for the purpose of any other object. This is equally true of the goodness of man. It is not the goodness of anyone else which is our duty, but the goodness for which we are fitted. It is not the duty of St. Gaudens to be a good cook, nor of Edison tO' sell newspapers, nor of Worth to lead an orchestra. It is the duty of St. Gaudens to carry out his own purpose of embodying great national types of character in sculpture, and of Worth to carry out his own purpose of dressmaking. As we cannot estimate the worth of anything if we do not know the purpose it serves, so also we cannot estimate any man's act without knowing his purpose. We found in analysing good objects that if any object had and could have no purpose, it was not to be classed as either good or bad. That seems to apply equally to men and to things ; but with this difference, that the man with no purpose as a man sinks into a thing, and is generally far more troublesome than any inanimate object because he incessantly interferes with the pur- poses of others. 54 Everyday Ethics We found that it was not best for a piece of Gothic architecture to be also a scent jar and a fan. This is preeminently true of the goodness of man. The question has been admirably illustrated by Professor William James in his " Psychology." * " With most objects of desire, physical nature re- stricts our choice to but one of many represented goods. I am often confronted by the necessity of standing by one of my empirical selves and relinquish- ing the rest. Not that I would not if I could be both handsome and fat and well-dressed and a great athlete and make a million a year, be a bon vivant and a lady- killer as well as a philosopher, a philanthropist, states- man, warrior, and African explorer as well as a tone-poet and saint. But the thing is simply impossible. The millionaire's work would run counter to the saint's, the bon vivant and the philanthropist would trip each other up, the philosopher and the lady-killer could not well keep house in the same tenement of clay. Such different characters may conceivably be at the outset of life possible to a man. But to make any one of them actual, the rest must be more or less sup- pressed. So the seeker of his truest, strongest self, must review the list carefully and pick out the one on which to stake his salvation." It is important to remember that, in its fundamental idea, goodness is one throughout the vast range of its application from the beefsteak or the knife, to the washerwoman or the statesman. It means always fitness for one's end, fulfilment of what one is meant for. ' Wm. James, " Psychology," vol. i., p. 309. Goodness the Essence of Manhood 55 To this great substratum of the conception of good- ness, we must, however, add new qualifications when we rise to the goodness of man. We need therefore to notice the differences between the goodness of man and of things. " I've got such a good fountain pen. It flovre per- fectly." This sounds natural, but I cannot say, " I've gdt such a virtuous fountain pen." We do not use virtue as applied to things, because they have no choice. It is not the fault of the fountain pen that it is clogged. Virtue and sin are words reserved to ex- press chosen acts. When, therefore, we want to dis- tinguish the goodness characteristic of man from that of things, we call him virtuous. Virtus, — ^manliness, has its own qualities, and these qualities distinguish the goodness of man as man from that of man used as a thing, or even as an animal. Man may be used as a thing, as when in a boatrace a man is occasionally used as ballast and is shifted from side to side to adjust the weight. Here his value is simply his weight, and he is good in so far as he fulfils the purpose of ballast. Again man is an animal and may serve the purpose of an animal. In Italy one sees women harnessed to carts and taking the place of horses. They do it poorly, for they are not adapted to it; a horse or a donkey would do it better. But there is something in our feel- ing of surprise and pain at seeing them so harnessed that goes far deeper than the sense that the work is cruelly hard. We feel that these women are treated like 56 Everyday Ethics slaves, that they are not serving their own ends and so are not hving a human life. Slavery was an evil not so much because the work was hard or the treat- ment cruel as because forced labour tends to make men incapable of a life of their own. Slavery under Ameri- can civilisation was probably far better for the negroes than the degradation of African, freedom. Slavery may even have been necessary for a time. But all subserv- ient and incessant physical labour tends to dull the finer, more human part of people's nature. For this reason we want as far as is possible to have machine work done by things and brutish work by brutes, and to set men and women free for characteristically human tasks. This brings out a characteristic distinction between men and things. Man can serve his own ends, a thing will serve the end of anyone. The slave in the cotton field was, we sometimes say, a chattel ; the hireling who does the bidding of a crafty politician, is called his tool. These are accurate expressions, for such men have become like things, and are serving an end that is in no way their own end. Shakspere likens the subservient courtier to a sponge : Rosencrants : "Take you me for a sponge, my lord?" Hamlet: "Ay, sir; that soaks up the king's countenance, his rewards, his authorities. But such officers do the king best service in the end: he keeps them, like an ape doth nuts, in the corner of his jaw; first mouthed, to be at last swallowed: when he needs what you have gleaned, it is but squeezing you, and, sponge, you shall be dry again." * Contrast with this the wonderful scene where again speaking to Rosencrantz and Guildenstern, Hamlet * " Hamlet," Act IV. scene 2. Goodness the Essence of Manhood 57 compares playing upon a pipe with playing upon a man's soul. " Why, look you now, how unworthy a thing you make of me. You would play upon me; you would seem to know my stops; you would pluck out the heart of my mystery; you would sound me from my lowest note to the top of my compass: and there is much music, excellent voice, in this little organ; yet cannot you make it speak. S'blood: do you think that I am easier to be played on than a pipe? Call me what instrument you will, though you can fret me, you cannot play upon me." " It takes skill even to play a pipe, but a pipe will serve the ends of anyone who has sufficient skill, while Hamlet has his own ends to serve. There is another important difference between the nature of the goodness of man and that of things. Every time a man uses his mind he strengthens it. Every time a man uses his courage he makes it greater, but every time you use a pencil you make it smaller. We have to reverse our standard when we speak of the right usage of a man and of a thing. " Don't use that silk dress so often, you will wear it out," "If you never use your mind, you soon won't have any left." " Of course he can play whist well, he's done it so many times." " Of course the cards are worn out. We've used them so often." A man gains mentally every time he uses his mind, his love grows the more he gives out, his happiness is increased in proportion to the number of those who share it, his sympathy en- larges as he spreads it abroad. A thing then serves another's ends, and is worn out in so doing; a man = " Hamlet," Act III. scene 2. 58 Everyday Ethics serves his own ends, and grows more himself by eacK act of service. There are pursuits characteristic of man as man. The writing of Shai 54- Conscience, Custom, and Law 123 We are afraid of the unaccustomed, though it may be right. Ten years ago during a wali