Ipillilillp '',><. I ! I it lORMELL LAW LlBU. Kf H5'75' C^3 CORNELL UNIVERSrTY LIBRARY 924 065 504 254 Cforn^U Ham ^rljool 2Itbrat:g DATE DUE s^^ kM^ 4^ Lrcy^ ^i^^ S^!5t ■ i f CAYLONO CfllNTCDINO.».A. Cornell University Library The original of tiiis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/cletails/cu31924065504254 The Doctrine of Judicial Review ITS LEGAL AND HISTORICAL BASIS AND OTHER ESSAYS EDWARD S.^'CORWIN Of the Department of History and Politics, Princeton University "The history of lanu must be a history of Ideas." — Maitland PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS PRINCETON LONDON: HUMPHREY MILFORD OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 1914 Copyright, 1914, by Princeton University Press Published October, 1914 1915 A. To My Wife PREFACE In the preparation of another volume, not yet pub- lished, I have encountered a number of questions involving controversies important to the student of American Constitutional History, an extended con- sideration of which however in those pages I felt to be out place. The following studies present my conclusions with regard to these questions, and the grounds of them. In the principal essay, I have en- deavored to present judicial review as the outcome of a view of legislative power which arose in consequence of the astonishing abuse of their pov/ers by the early State legislatures but which was first appreciated for its full worth by the Convention that framed the Con- stitution of the United States. Incidentally I have, I trust, laid to rest that most inconclusive "explana- tion" of judicial review which dwells on the idea that a legislative measure contrary to the constitution is not law and never was. The alleged explanation totally ignores the crucial question, which is. Why is it the judicial view of the constitution that legislative measures have to conform to? The article on the Dred Scott Decision treats of the most dramatic epi- sode in the history of judicial review, though one that is by no means the best illustrative of the spirit of the institution. The study entitled "We, the People," ap- proaches the time-honored controversy over Secession and Nullification from what is shown to be, I submit, vi PREFACE the point of view of 1787. But the verdict arrived at with reference to the rights of the States in rela- tion to the Constitution is not without import for some present-day issues, as is shown in the paper on Some Possibihties of Treaty-Making. The paper on the Pelatiah Webster Myth deals with a question of less practical significance, but yet one of real ethical im- portance. For if history has any function to perform it is that of endeavoring at least to make correct assess- ment of the motives and services of men. In the preparation of this little volume I have be- come the debtor of Professor Evans Holbrook, editor of the Michigan Law Review, for valuable editorial as- sistance in putting the first study into final shape. My especial thanks are also due to Mr. Walter Cottrell of the Princeton University Library stafif and Mr. B. A. Finney of the University of Michigan Library for numberless courtesies. I should also take this occasion to point out to the reader that when the word "constitution" is capi- talized in the following pages it refers to the national Constitution, but that at other times it refers to this or that State constitution or signifies constitution in the generic sense. The distinction becomes at times of some importance. Edward S. Corwin. Ypsilanti, Michigan Sept. II, 1914 CONTENTS PACE 1. MARBURY V. MADISON AND THE DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW i II. "WE, THE PEOPLE" 8i III. THE PELATIAH WEBSTER MYTH iii IV. THE DRED SCOTT DECISION leg V. SOME POSSIBILITIES IN THE WAY OF TREATY-MAKING i6i MARBURY V. MADISON AND THE DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW MARBURY V. MADISON AND THE DOC- TRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW* What is the exact legal basis of the power of the Supreme Court to pass upon the constitutionality of acts of Congress? Recent Hterature on the subject reveals a considerable variety of opinion. There are radicals who hold that the power owes its existence to an act of sheer usurpation by the Supreme Court itself, in the decision of Marbury v. Madison.''- There * The principal historical studies on this subject are the fol- lowing: W. M. Meigs, The Relation of the Judiciary to the Constitution, 19 Am. Law Rev. 175-203 (1885); C. B. Elliott, The Legislatures and the Courts, 5 Pol. Sc. Qtly. 224-58 (1890) ; Brinton Coxe, Judicial Power and Unconstitutional Legislation (Phila., 1893) ; J. B. Thayer, The American Doctrine of Con- stitutional Law, 7 Harv. Law Rev. 129-56 ( 1894) ; E. S. Corwin, The Rise and Establishment of Judicial Review, 9 Mich. Law Rev. 102-25, 284-316 (1910-11) ; C. A. Beard, The Supreme Court and the Constitution (N. Y. 1912) ; J. H. Dougherty, Power of the Federal Judiciary over Legislation (N. Y., 1912) ; A. C. McLaughlin, The Courts, the Constitution, and Parties (Chicago, 1912) ; C. H. Burr, Unconstitutional Law and the Federal Judicial Power, 60 Univ. of Pa. Law Rev. and Am. Law Reg. 624-43 (1912) ; H. Pope, The Fundamental Law and the Courts, 27 Harv. Law Rev. 45-67 (1913) ; H. A. Davis, An- nulment of Tegislation by the SuipTeme Court, 7 Am. Pol. Sc. Rev. 541-87 (1913) ; C. G. Haines, The Am. Doctrine of Ju- dicial Supremacy ('N. Y., 1914) ; F. E. Melvin, The Judicial Bulwark of the Constitution, 8 Am. Pol. Sc. Rev. 167-203 (1914)- *See for example, H. L. Boudin in 26 Pol. Sc. Qtly. 238, or J. B. McDonough, Usurpation of Power by Federal Courts, 46 Am. Law Rev. 45. I 2 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW are conservatives who point to clauses of the Consti- tution which, they assure us, specifically confer the power.^ There are legal writers who refuse to go back of Marbury v. Madison, content in the ratification which, they assert, subsequent events have given the doctrine of that decision.* There are historical writers who show that a considerable portion of the member- ship of the body that framed the Constitution are on record as having personally favored judicial review at one time or another, either before, during, or after the Convention.* Finally, there are other historical writers who represent judicial review as the natural outgrowth of ideas that were common property in the period when the Constitution was established.' Both these last views I find to be in themselves correct enough, but with the result of disclosing some more fundamental problems. For the question is not, what did the framers of the Constitution hope or desire with refer- ence to judicial review, but what did they do with reference to it; and before ideas contemporary with the framing of the Constitution can be regarded as furnishing the legal basis of judicial review, it must be shown that they were, by contemporary understand- ' Brinton Coxe and J. H. Dougherty, above. ' This seems to 'be the position, for example, of Prof. James Parker Hall, in his Constitutional Law and of Mr. Cotton in his Introduction to his Decisions of John Marshall. ' Meigs, Elliott, Beard, Burr, MeMn, above. Mr. Melvin's researches into this subject are the most thorough. His arti- cle is also valuable for the account it gives of the growth in the Convention of the articles of the Constitution touching judicial power. ° The present writer in above cited articles and McLaughlin, The Courts, etc. MARBURY V. MADISON 3 ing, incorporated in the Constitution for that purpos^ and that they were logically sufficient for it. To in- vestigate these questions is the purpose of the study to follow. The position of those who are content to rest the power of the Supreme Court over acts of Congress upon Marbury v. Madison'^ is plainly illogical. For either that decision was based upon the Consititution or it was not. In the former case, however, it is the Constitution that is the real basis of the power, while in the latter the decision was erroneous by the court's own premises. Still it is urged that whatever the defects of the original decision, these have long since been cured by popular acquiescence and later decisions. Let me then begin this article by showing some diffi- culties in the way of this view. The case of Marbury v. Madison arose upon an ap- plication by plaintiff to the Supreme Court for a writ of mandamus to the Secretary of State to compel him to deliver a commission authorizing plaintiff to exer- cise the functions of an office to which be had been duly appointed. The court, reversing the usual order of procedure,®" went first into the merits of the ques- "i Cr. 137 (1803). '" "As the first question which this motion presents is one of the jurisdiction and power of this court to grant the writ prayed for in this case, it will be following the rule estab- lished to consider it first; a rule which ought never to be dis- regarded where a question of power arises": J. Baldwin in 5 Pet. 190, 200, citing i Cr. 91, 3 Cr. 172, 5 Cr. 221, 9 Wheat. 816, ID Wheat. 20. 4 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW tion and from its review of these came to the con- clusion that a mandamus, had it been sought in a tribunal having jurisdiction of the case, would un- doubtedly have been the proper remedy. But this, it contended, had not been done. For though § 13 of the Act of 1789 purported to authorize the Supreme Court to issue "writs of mandamus in cases war- ranted by the principles and usages of law to . . . persons holding office under the authority of the United States,"'^ this provision transgressed Article III, § 2, par. 2, of the Constitution, the words of which describing the original jurisdiction of the Supreme Court must be interpreted as negativing any further power of the same order. Thereupon the court pro- nounced §13 null and void, and dismissed the case for want of jurisdiction. Inevitably, the first question raised by Marshall's decision is as to the correctness of his construction of Article III, § 2, par. 2. In support of his position the Chief Justice might have quoted, had he chosen, the Federalist,* but against him were: first, the im- portant evidence of the legislative provision over- turned, showing congressional opinion practically contemporaneous with the Constitution; secondly, the fact that anterior to Marbury v. Madison the court itself had repeatedly taken jurisdiction of cases brought under that provision;" and thirdly, the fact that in other connections affirmative words of grant 'For the Act of 1789, see i Statutes at Large 85 ffg. (24 Sept. 1789, c. 20). 'Federalist No. 81 (Lodge's Ed., p. 507). ° See argument of counsel in i Cr. 137-53. MARBURY V. MADISON 5 in the Constitution had not been deemed to infer a correlative negative. Thus, were the rule laid down in Marbury v. Madison to be followed, Congress would have power to enact penalties against only the crimes of counterfeiting, treason, and piracy and of- fences against the Law of Nations, whereas in fact it had, even as early as 1790, enacted penalties against many other acts, by viftue of its general authority under the "necessary and proper" clause.^" Yet it must be admitted that the rule of exclusive- ness does often apply to cases of affirmative enumer- ation, so that the only question is whether Article III, § 2, par. 2, furnished such a case. Speaking to this point, the Chief Justice said: "A negative or ex- clusive sense musit be given them [the words of the paragraph in question] or they have no operation at all."^^ But this is simply not so. For though given only their affirmative value, these words still place the cases enumerated by them beyond the reach of Con- gress, — surely no negligible matter. Nor does the Chief Justice's attempt to draw support from the fur- ther words of the same paragraph fare better upon investigation. "In all other cases," he quotes, the Supreme Court is given appellate jurisdiction, that is, as he would have it, merely appellate jurisdiction. Unfortunately for this argumtot the words thus pointed to are followed by the words — which the Chief Justice fails to quote — "with such exceptions ... as the Congress shall make." Why, then, should not the exceptions thus allowed to the appellate juris- '"i Stat. L. 112 ffg. (Apr. 30, 1790). " I Cr. 174. 6 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW diction of the Supreme Court have been intended to take the form, if Congress so willed, of giving the court original jurisdiction of the cases covered by them? Moreover, the time was to come when Marshall himself was to abandon the reasoning underlying the rule laid down in Marbury v. Madison. This rule, to repeat, was that the Supreme Court's original juris- diction is confined by the Constitution to the cases specifically enumerated in Article III, § 2, par. 2, and — though this was only dictum — that the court's appellate jurisdiction is confined "to all other cases." But now it must be noted that jurisdiction is always either original or appellate, — that there is, in other words, no third sort. The rule laid down in Marbury V. Madison becomes therefore the logical equivalent of the proposition that ithe Supreme Court had only orig- inal jurisdiction of the cases enumerated in Article III, § 2, par. 2. In Cohens v. Virginia^'^ nevertheless the court took jurisdiction on appeal of a case which had arisen "under this Constitution," but was also a case to which a State was party, on the basis of the rule, as stated by the Chief Justice, that "Where the words admit of appellate jurisdiction the power to take cognizance of the suit originally does not neces- sarily negative the power to decide upon it on an ap- peal, if it may originate in a different court."^^ And in further illustration of this rule, the Chief Justice instanced the right of the Supreme Court to take jurisdiction on appeal of certain cases which foreign ^=6 Wheat. 264 (1821). '"lb- 395-402. MARBURY V. MADISON 7 consuls were allowed to institute in the lower federal courts." He also insisted, and quite warrantably, upon the necessity of the rule in question to major purposes of the Constitution. Yet obviously if the rule is to be harmonized with that laid down in Mar- bury V. Madison, it must be by eliminating the word "all" from the opening clause of Article III, § 2, par. 2, and by inserting qualifying words in front of the word "those" of the same clause. Otherwise the line of reasoning taken in Marbury v. Madison is aban- doned and the precise decision there left hanging in mid-air. ^^ Suppose however, we concede Marshall his con- struction of Article III, is his decision absolved of error thereby? By no means. This decision rests upon the assumption that it was the intention and necessary operation of § 13 of the Act of 1789 to enlarge the original jurisdiction of the Supreme Court, and this cannot be allowed. To begin with, in Com- mon Law practice, in the light of which § 13 was framed, the writ of mandamus was not, ordinarily at least, an instrument of obtaining jurisdiction by a court, even upon appeal, but like the writs of habeas corpus and injunction, was a remedy available from a " The validity of such appeals was considefSn by C. J. Taney in Gittings v. Crawford, Federal Cases, 5,465. Referring to the precise clause, under discussion in Marbury v. Madison, Taney said : "In the clause in question there is nothing but mere affirmative words of grant, and none that import a design to exclude the subordinate jurisdiction of other courts of the United States on the same subject-matter." See also C. J. Waite's language in Ames v. Kansas, ill U. S. 449. ^° The precise precedent in Marbury v. Madison has been applied several times. See 5 How. 176, i Wall. 243, 8 Wall. 85. 8 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW court in the exercise of its standing jurisdiction. This being the case, however, why may it not have been the intention of Congress in enacting § 13, not to enlarge the Supreme Court's jurisdiction, but simply to enable the court to issue the writ of man- damus to civil officers of the United States as auxiliary to the original jurisdiction which the Con- stitution conferred upon it? It is certain that the court has more than once entertained motions by original suitors for injunctions to such officers,^® and it is apparent thait, so far as the question here dis- cussed is concerned, an application for a writ of man- damus must rest on the same footing.^''' Furthermore, the proposition that the writ of man- damus is not to be regarded ordinarily as a means of obtaining jurisdiction, but only of exercising it, was recognized and applied by the Supreme Court itself a few years later, in a case the exact parallel of Marbury v. Madison. By § 14 of the Act of 1789 the circuit courts of the United States were given the power, in words substantially 'the same as those em- ployed in § 13, to issue certain writs "in cases author- ized by the principles and usages of law." Yet in Mclntire v. Wood,^^ where the issue was the validity of a writ of mandamus to a person holding office '"Mifj. V. Johnson, 4 Wall. 47s; Ga. v. Stanton, 6 Wall. 50. The grounds on which these cases were dismissed do not affect the view urged in the text. " Suppose Congress should transfer the business of interstate extradition to federal commissioners, as it would be within its power to do, there would be plenty of occasions when the Su- preme Court would be asked for writs of mandamus to civil officers of the United States. See Ky. v. Dennison, 24 How. 65. ''7 Cr. S04 (1813). MARBURY V. MADISON 9 under the authority of the United States the Supreme Court ruled that before a circuit court could utilize the power given it in § 14 in a case, it must have jurisdiction of the case on independent grounds, and the same rule was later reiterated in McClung v. Silli- man}^ But clearly, had the court followed this line of reasoning in Marbury v. Madison, it could not have questioned the validity of § 13. Indeed, had it but followed the, today at any rate, well-known maxim of Constitutional Law that of two possible interpreta- tions of a statute, the one harmonious with the Con- stitution, the other at variance with it, the former must be preferred,^° it could not have challenged the legislation in question. \ By its view of Article III, § 2, par. 2, it must still doubtless have declined juris- diction of the case, but the ground of its action would have been, not the error of Congress, but the error of plaintifif. In short there was no valid occasion in Marbury v. Madison for any inquiry by the court into its preroga- tive in relation to acts of Congress. Why then, it will be asked, did the court make such an inquiry? In part the answer to this question will appear later, but in part it may be answered now. To speak quite frankly, this decision bears many of the earmarks of a deliberate partisan coup. The court was bent on reading the President a lecture on his legal and moral duty to recent Federahst appointees to judicial office, whose commissions the last Administration had not "6 Wheat. 598 (1821). ="For a rather far-fetched application of this rule see the "Commodities Clause" Case, 213 U. S. 366 (igo8). 10 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEiW had time to deliver, but at the same time hesitated to invite a snub by actually asserting jurisdiction of the matter. It therefore took the engaging position of declining to exercise power which the Constitution withheld from it, by making the occasion an oppor- tunity to assert a far more transcendent power. II But from Marbury v. Madison we proceed to the question whether, and in what yray, the Constitution itself sanctions judicial review, fl have already indi- cated my opinion that no clause was inserted in the Constitution for the specific purpose of bestowing this power on courts, but that the power rests upon certain general principles thought by its framers to have been embodied in the Constitution. I shall now endeavor to justify this opinionr) That the members of the Convention of 1787 thought the Constitution secured to courts in the United States the right to pass on the validity of acts of Congress under it cannot be reasonably doubted. Confining ourselves simply to the available evidence that is strictly contemporaneous with the framing and ratifying of the Constitution, as I think it only proper to do, we find the following members of the Conven- tion that framed the Constitution definitely asserting that this would be the case: Gerry and King of Massachusetts, Wilson and Gouverneur Morris of Pennsylvania, Martin of Maryland, Randolph, Madi- son, and Mason of Virginia, Dickinson of Delaware, Yates and Hamilton of New York, Rutledge and Charles Pinckney of South Carolina, Davie and Wil- MARBURY V. MADISON ii liamson of North Carolina, Sherman and Ellsworth of Connecticut.^^ True these are only seventeen names out of a possible fifty-five, but let it be con- sidered whose names they are. They designate fully three-fourths of the leaders of the Convention, four of the five members of the Committee of Detail which drafted the Constitution,^^ and four of the five mem- bers of the Committee of Style which gave the Con- stitution final form.^* The entries under these names, in the Index to Farrand's Records occupy fully thirty columns, as compared with fewer than half as many ^ Max Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention (Yale Univ. Press, 1913) ; I, 97 (Gerry), log (King) ; II, 73 (Wilson), 76 (Martin), 78 (Mason), 299 (Dickinson and Morris), 428 (Rutledge), 248 (Pinckney), zi^ (Williamson), 28 (Sherman, 93 (Madison); III, 220 (Martin, in "Genuine Information"). The Federalist: Nos. 39 and 44 (Madison), No. 78 (Hamilton). Elliot's Debates (Ed. of 1836); II, 1898-9 (Ellsworth), 417 and 4S4 (Wilson), 336-7 (Hamilton); III, 197, 208, 431 (Randolph), 441 (Mason), 484-S (Madison); IV, i6s (Davie). P. L. Ford, Pamphlets on the Constitution, 184 (Dickinson, in "Letters of Fabius")- Ford, Essays on the Constitution, 295 (Yates, writing as "Brutus"). Pinckney later, in 1799, denounced the idea of judicial review, thus : "On no subject am I more convinced than that it is an unsafe and dangerous doctrine in a republic ever to suppose that a judge ought to possess the right of questioning or deciding upon the constitutionality of treaties, laws, or any act of the legislature. It is placing the opinion of an individual, or two, or three, above that of both branches of Congress, a doctrine which is not warranted by the Constitution, and will not, I hope, long have any advocates in this country"; quoted from Wharton's State Trials, 412, by Mr. Horace A. Davis in Am. Polit. Sc. Rev., 551. Madison's later views are considered infra. ^Gorham, Rutledge, Randolph, Ellsworth, and Wilson. The argument is from Professor Beard's Supreme Court, etc. ^Johnson, Hamilton, Morris, Madison, and King. 12 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW columns under the names of the remaining members. We have in this list, in other words, the names of men who expressed themselves on the subject of judicial review because they also expressed themselves on all other subjects before the Convention. They were the leaders of that body and its articulate members. And against them are to be pitted, in reference to the ques- tion under discussion, only Mercer of Maryland, Bed- ford of Delaware, and Spaight of North CaroHna, the record in each of whose cases turns out to be upon inspection of doubtful implication. For while Spaight, for instance, undoubtedly expressed himself, during the period of the Convention, as strongly ad- verse to the theory of judicial review,^* yet he later heard the idea expounded both on the floor of the Philadelphia Convention and the North Carolina con- vention without protest. The words of Bedford which are relied upon in this connection are his declaration that he was "opposed to every check on the legisla- ture." But these words were spoken with reference, not to judicial review, but to the proposition to estab- lish a council O'f legislative revision.^^ Mercer of Mai-yland did not sign the Constitution and opposed its adoption. It is by no means impossible that one of the grounds of his opposition was recognition of the fact that the Constitution established judicial review.^® Altogether it seems a warrantable assertion that on no other feature of the Constitution with reference ^■See McRee, Life and Correspondence of James Iredell, II, 169-76. ^ Farrand, I, 100, 106, '"/&. II, 298, MARBURY V. MADISON 13 to which there has been any considerable debate is the view of the Convention itself better attested. Yet it must be admitted that, if we assume that the Convention did not finally incorporate its view in specific provisions of the Constitution, a difficulty that at first seems formidable opposes itself to the thesis that this view was secured by certain general princi- ples thought to be embodied in the Constitution. The source of the difficulty I allude to is Article VI, par. 2, of the Constitution. This paragraph first announces the supremacy of the Constitution, the acts of Con- gress in pursuance thereof, and treaties made under the authority of the United States, as law of the land, and then proceeds to impose a specific mandate upon State judges to enforce this supreme law, anything in the law or constitution of any State to the contrary notwithstanding. The question therefore arises, Why did the Convention, if it believed general principles sufficient to secure judicial review of acts of Congress, deem it necessary to order the State judges to prefer what was described as supreme law of the land to subordinate law? Any doctrine of judicial review must rest in part upon the idea of one law superior to another, and if, to repeat the question just put, the fact of superiority of national law to State law fur- nished, in the estimation of the Convention, an insuffi- cient security of the former as against the latter, why should not the analogous superiority of the Constitu- tion itself to acts of Congress be similarly insufficient? But the answer to this question is, after all, plain enough: The judges to whom the mandate of Article V'l is addressed are State judges, that is, judges of 14 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW an independent jurisdiction. Their duty to talurpose, in the quaint words of Sir Benjamin Rudyard, "to make that good old, decrepid law of Magna Carta, which hath so long been kept in and bed-ridden, as it were, to walk again."*^ Coke took the position that there was no such thing as sovereign power in England, even for Parliament ; for, said he : "Magna Carta is such a fellow that he will have no sovereign." His famous dictum in Dr. Bonham's Case*^ that an act of Parliament "contrary to common right and reason" would be "void," was therefore quite in harmony with his whole propaganda. At the same time, it would be the height of absurdity to sup- "F. W. Maitland, Constitutional History, 255. Maitland ex- presses the emphatic opinion that the law-making power of Crown and Parliament was from an early date unlimited. "■ Cobbett, Parliamentary History, II, col. 335 ; the remark quoted below is from the same debate, col. 357. "8 Reps. 107, 118 (1612). MARBURY V. MADISON 29 pose that these words spell out anything like judicial review. They undoubtedly indicate Coke's belief that the principles of "common right and reason," being part of the Common Law, were cognizable by the judges while interpreting acts of Parhament. For the rest, however, they must be read along with Coke's characterization of Parliament as the "Supreme Court" of the realm. Being a court, Parliament was necessarily bound by the law, even as it declared and elaborated it; but being the highest court, its interpre- tations of the law necessarily bound all other courts. As he plainly indicated, both by his words, in his In- stitutes, and practically, by his connection with the framing of the Petition of Right, Coke regarded Parliament itself as the final interpreter of the law by which both it, the King, and the judges were bound.*^ The inaugural event in the history of American Constitutional Law, however, was the argument made by James Otis at Boston in Februaiy 1761, in the Writs of Assistance Case. The question at issue was whether the British customs ofificials, one Paxton in particular, should be furnished with general search warrants enabling them to search for smuggled goods. The application was opposed for the Boston mer- chants by Thacher and Otis. Thacher contented him- self with denying that such a writ as was asked for was warranted by any act of Paidiament and, more particularly, that the court to whom the application '" See note at the end of this article on The True Meaning of Coke's Dictum. 30 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW had been made had authority in the premises. Otis, on the other hand, plunged at once into the most fundamental issues. His argument was, that whether such writs were warranted by act of Parliament or not, was a matter of indifference, since such act of Parliament would be "against the constitution" and "against natural equity" and therefore void. "///'' he accordingly concluded, "an act of Parliament should he made in the very words of this petition, it would be void. The executive courts must pass such acts into disuse."** Was there then any warrant in law for this con- clusion? No. The proposition that an act of Par- liament contrary to "common right and reason" was "void" had indeed been repeated obiter by Coke's con- temporary, Hobart, and later by Holt, and had found its way into some of the abridgments and commen- taries,— works which are apt to be more comprehen- sive than critical, — but with it hitherto had never been joined the proposition that an inferior court might override the will of Parliament if this were unmistakably expressed.*^ On the contrary, in Captain Streater's Case, in which, in 1653, Otis' argument had been anticipated, the idea had been specifically re- jected. "Mr. Streater," said the judge in that case, "one must be above another and the inferior must submit to the superior, and in all justice an inferior " See Quincy, Early Mass. Reps., note to Paxton's Case, pp. 469-85; also, John Adams, Life and Works, II, 521-5. " See note to Paxton's Case, Quincy, pp. 521-30 and notes, with references to Bacon's Abridgment (1735), Viner's Abridg- ment (1741-51), Comyn's Digest (1762-67). Hobart's dictum MARBURY V. MADISON 31 court cannot control what Parliament does. If Par- liament should do one thing and we do the contrary here, things would run round. We must submit to the legislative power."*® Nevertheless, having been formulated at the mo- ment when Americans were beginning to lay about them for weapons with which to resist the pretensions of ParHament, Otis' doctrine met with a degree of success, — enough at least to make it a permanent memory with the men of the time. Otis himself, it is true, soon abandoned his own offspring, while his reporter John Adams, in arguing a second case in- volving the question of the right of Parliament to authorize writs of assistance, maintained a significant silence on the doctrine. In Virginia, on the other hand, the supreme court of the colony, having been put the question, early in 1766, whether officers of occurs in Savadge v. Day, Hob. 85 (1615) ; Holt's dictum oc- curs in City of London v. Wood, 12 Mod. 669 (1701). "Coke Lyttleton," wrote Jefferson, with reference to the period when he was a law student, "was the universal book of students and a sounder Whig never wrote nor one of profounder learning in the orthodox doctrines of the British Constitution or what is called British rights.'' Writing in 1759, Cadwallader Colden makes casual references to a "judicial power of declaring them [laws] void": N. Y. Hist'l Soc. Cols. H, 204. In his study on Colonial Common Law, Professor Reinsch refers to the case of Giddings v. Brown in which a Mass. magistrate (aipparently in the 17th century) pronounced a town resolve voting taxes to build the minister a house "against fundamental law," and void : Select Essays in Anglo-Am. Legal Hist., I, 376. For further instances of the influence of the doctrine under dis- cussion, see Chalmers, Political Annals, N. Y. Hist'l Soc. Cols., I, 81 ; and Chalmers, Colonial Opinions, 373-82. "St. Trials, II, 196 fjfg. 32 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW the law would incur a penalty if they did not use stamped paper in conformance with the prescriptions of the Stamp Act, answered that that act did not bind the inhabitants of Virginia, "inasmuch as they con- ceived" it "to be unconstitutional" ; while six years later, George Mason, whose argument was reported by Jefferson, contended in behalf of chents that the same doctrine was applicable to the case of local legislation that was "contrary to natural right." And thence the theory returned to its place of origin. On the very eve of the Declaration of Independence, Judge Gush- ing, la:ter one of the original bench of the Supreme Gourt of the United States charged a Massachusetts juiy to ignore certain acts oi Parliament as "void" and "inoperative." It was a true case of "judicial review" by virtue of the right of revolution.*^ Meanwhile, however, a new element had entered American political thinking,' — the notion of legislative sovereignty, from the pages of Blackstone. The grand result of this notion was eventually the establishment of the distinction between "natural law," in the broad general sense of the moral law, and "civil law" and the confinement of civil obligation in the last analy- sis to the latter. Blackstone himself is enough of a conservative to treat "natural law," "divine law," and the like, as in some sense "law," but it is not law, he finally admits, potent to control the will of the "The opinion of the Va. judges on the Stamp Act (Feb. 1766) is described by McMaster, Hist., V, 394. Mason's argu- ment in Robin v. Hardaway is to be found in Jefferson's (Va.) Reps., 109 ffg. Adam's argument in the Advocate-General v. Hancock is to be found in Quiincy, loc. cit., 459-62. MARBURY V. MADISON 33 legislature. Considering, therefore, the statement "that acts of Parliament contrary to reason are void," he says : "But if the Parliament will positively enact a thing to be done which is unreasonable, I know of no power in the ordinary forms of the constitution that is vested with authority to control it; and the examples usually alleged in support of the rule do none O'f them prove that where the main object of the statute is unreasonable the judges are at liberty to reject it; for, that were to set the judicial power above that of the legislature, which would be subversive of all government." The only acts of Parliament, accordingly, which the judges could ignore were acts "impossible to be performed."*® Strange it is that this exception, which indeed is in the nature of a self-identical proposition, should have furnished the entering wedge for judicial re- view in this country after the establishment of In- dependence. Yet such is the fact. The most in- fluential case in which judicial review was broached before the Convention of 1787 was that of Trevett v. Weeden, in which, in 1786, the Rhode Island judges " Comms. I, 91. "Sovereignty and legislative power are in- deed convertible terms ; one cannot subsist without the other" : ib., 46. According to Chancellor Kent, 2,500 copies of the commentaries had been sold in America before the outbreak of the Revolution. Jefferson testifies that many young lawyers, "seduced by the honeyed Mansfieldism of Blackstone, began to slide into Toryism." But the Patriots themselves felt the in- fluence. Their final position was no longer one of reliance on the "British Constitution" and "fundamental law," but to oppose the claim of the colonial assemblies as local parlia- ments to that of the imperial Parliament : See Jefferson's own Summary View. 34 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW refused enforcement to a rag-money law on account of its alleged repugnancy, that is, self -contradictory character. Coming, then, to the early State constitutions, we find cooperating with the influence of Blackstone, to exclude judicial review from them, two other circum- stances ; first, uncertainty whether these constitutions possessed the force of law and, secondly, the actual organization of legislative power in them. That the fundamental principles of right and reason invoked by Coke were known to the judges and enforceable by them, at least as principles of interpretation in ap- plying statute law, there could of course be no doubt. For even Blackstone conceded that. But the early State constitutions were of a different stamp, — they were acts of revolution, social compacts, sprung from the pages of Locke rather than of Coke. Undoubtedly they illustrated and realized the doctrine that all just government rests upon the consent of the governed. Yet it was a corollary from this doctrine, that a gov- ernment established upon this foundation had the right to govern, and that this was recoverable by the people only by another act of revolution. The power of enacting laws, however, was a function of government. How, then, could constitutions, bills of rights, frames of government, the work of the people themselves, be regarded as laws in the strict sense of the term? Their moral supremacy none doubted, nor yet that a breach of them by government destroyed its right to be, but until the people should be regarded as having an enacting power, exercisable directly and without MARBURY V. MADISON 35 the intervention of their legislative representatives, the supremacy of constitutions was a real barrier to their legality^^ But the second difficulty was even more formidable. A majority of the early State constitutions contained statements, sometimes in very round terms, of Montes- quieu's doctrine of the separation of powers; and as against executive power, a supposed monarchical ten- dency in which was feared, this principle was given detailed application/'" Not so, however, as against legislative power.^^ In the first place, all through colonial times, the legislature had stood for the local interest as against the imperial interest, which had in turn been represented by the governors and the judges. In the second place, the legislative department was supposed to stand nearest to the peoi>le. Finally, legislative power was undefined power. As applied against the legislative department, accordingly, all that the principle of the separation of powers originally *' On a constitution as an act of revolution, see the remarks of the judges in Kamper v. Hawkins, Va. Cases 20, fifg. ; also, Marshall in Marbury v. Madison; also, Tucker's Blackstone, I, App. p. 91. On the lodgment of the function of governing ex- clusively with the government, see Luther Martin's remarks in his "Genuine Information" (quoted at close of following essay) ; also, Dr. Benjamin Rush's remarks in his "Address to the People of the United States" (1787) iri Niles' Principles and Acts of the Revolution, 234-36. The idea, indeed, is funda- mental to the concept of representative government. °° See data in Federalist -Nos. 47 and 48. °' The position of the legislature in the early State constitu- tions is described at length by Morey, in Annals of the Am. Acad, of Soc. and Polit. Sc, IX, 398 fifg.; also by Davis, "American Constitutions" in Johns Hopkins University Studies, 3rd Series. 36 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW meant was that those who held seats in the legislature should not at the same time hold office in either of the other departments.^^ But the legislature itself, like the British Parliament and like the colonial legisla- tures before it, exercised all kinds of power, and par- ticularly did it exercise the power of interpreting the standing law and interfering with the course of justice as administered in the ordinary courts ;^^ and the only test of its acts deemed available was that they should be passed in the usual form.°* In short, as both Madi- °^ The doctrine of the separation of powers receives recog-, nition in the body of the first Virginia constitution in the fol- lowing words : "That the legislative, executive, and judiciary departments shall he distinct; so that neither exercise the powers properly belonging to the other ; nor shall any person exercise the powers of more than one of them at the same time," etc. See also the first New Jersey Constitution, Art. XX ; the original North Carolina Constitution, Arts. XXVIII- XXX ; the first Pennsylvania Constitution, Sec. 23 ; the first South Carolina Constitution, Art. X : Thorpe, Am. Charters, Constitutions, etc. '" See note at close of this article on Mingling of Legislative and Judicial Powers. " Consider, for example, Jefferson's words in his "Virginia Notes" (cited above) : It is needless for the executive or the judiciary to attempt to oppose the legislature, he says, for then "they put their proceedings into the form of acts of assembly, which will render them obligatory on the other branches." Consider also C. J. Pendleton's words in Com. v. Caton, 4 Call. 5, 17 (Va., 1782) : "How far this court, in whom the judiciary powers may in some sort be said to be concentrated, shall have power to declare the nullity of a law passed in its forms by the legislative power without exercising the power of that branch, contrary to the plain terms of the constitution, is in- deed a deep, important, and I will add, a tremendous question the decision of which might involve consequences to which gentlemen may not have extended their ideas." MARBURY V. MADTSON 37 son and Jefferson put tlie matter later, legislative power was the vortex into which all other powers tended to be drawn. Obviously so long as this re- mained the case, there could be nothing like judicial review. The period 1 780-1 787, however, was a period of "constitutional reaction," which mounting gradually till the outbreak of Shays' Rebellion in Massachusetts in the latter part of 1786, then leaped suddenly to its climax in the Philadelphia Convention. The reaction embraced two phases, that of nationalism against State sovereignty, that of private rights against uncontrolled legislative power; but the point of attack in both in- stances was the State legislature.^" Yet it should not be imagined for a moment that those who discerned the central fault of "the American political system" gave themselves over merely to idle lamentation. For- tunately no one contended at that date that the exist- ing American constitutions, wrought out as they had ""See criticisms passed in the Convention on the notion that the States were sovereign under the Articles of Confederation, in Farrand I, 313-33, 437-79. See also the present writer's National Supremacy, ch. Ill (Holt & Co., 1913). For the revolt against legislative oppression of private (property) rights, see the elaborate criticism of the recent product of the State legislatures by Madison in 1786, Writings (Hunt Ed.), H, 338 ffg. Also, see his statement on the floor of the Convention, June 6, and afterwards repeated by him elsewhere, that "the necessity of providing more effectually for the security of pri- vate rights and the steady dispensation of justice'' was one of the objects of the Convention. "Interferences with these," he declared, "were evils vvhich had, more perhaps than anything else, produced this Convention. Was it to be supposed that re- publican liberty could long exist under the abuses of it practised in some of the States?" See also Federalist Nos. 10 and 44. 38 DOCTRIXE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW been under the stress and urgency of a state of war- fare, were impossible of improvement.^" Fortunately, too, American political inventiveness had by no means exhausted itself in its first efforts at constitution- building. Upon this latent talent the problems of the times acted as incentive and stimulant, eliciting from it suggestion after suggestion which it needed but the ripe occasion to erect into institutions composing a harmonious whole. Some of these suggestions it is l>ertinent to enumerate : ( i ) from Massachusetts and New Hampshire came the idea of an ordered and regular procedure for making constitutions, with the result inevita:bly of furthering the idea of an enacting power in the people at large and that of the legal character of the constitution;'^^ (2) from New Jersey, Connecticut, Virginia, Rhode Island and perhaps New Hampshire came the idea of judicial review, partly on the basis of the doctrine of the right of revolution and partly on the basis of the doctrine of certain principles fundamental to the Common Law that had found rec- ognition in the State constitutions;^^ (3) from North "" See Jefferson's apologia in his Virginia Notes, above cited ; also Rush's "Address" in Principles and Acts, 234-36. "' On the making of the revolutionary State constitutions, see Davis in Johns Hopkins University Studies, 3rd Series, pp. 516 ffg. The legal character of the Massachusetts constitution of 1780 was recognized and enforced by the supreme court of the State in a series of decisions, in 1780-81, pronouncing slavery unconstitutional. See G. H. Moore, History of Slavery in Massachusetts, pip. 200-23. A futile attempt was made to have the legislature order rehearings in some of these cases. The petitioners state the grounds of the decisions, ib. 217-8. °' See note at close of this article on Alleged Precedents for Judicial Review antedating the Convention of 1787. MARBURY V. MADISON 39 Carolina, just as the Philadelphia Convention was as- sembling, came the idea of judicial review based squarely on the written constitution and the principle of the separation of powers;''" (4) from various sources came the idea that legislative power, instead of being governmental power in general, is a peculiar kind of power f° (5) from various sources came the idea that judicial power, exercised as it habitually was under the guiding influence of Common Law prin- '^° Bayard v. Singleton, i Martin 42. See note 24, above. Mr. W. S. Carpenter finds from the contemporary newspapers that this case was decided in May, several days before the Phila- delphia Convention had actually come together. The attorneys in the case who argued the unconstitutionality of the legisla- tive act were Wm. R. Davie, a N. C. delegate to the Phila. Convention, and James Iredell, later a member of the first bench of the U. S. Sup. Ct. '" See especially Madison's words in Fed. No. 47 and Hamil- ton's in No. 81. The latter are quoted infra. See also the Reports of the Pennsylvania Censors, referred to in the note on the Mingling of Legislative and Judicial Powers at the end of this study. The earliest 'Statement of the respective limits of legislative and judicial powers came from the royal governors, in an effort to check the former. See, for example, the message of Gov. Fletcher to the New York Assembly, Apr. 13, 1695 : "Laws are to be interpreted by the judges," ». e., the judges alone : Messages from the Governors (of New York) (Lin- coln, Ed.), I, 55. For later gubernatorial messages on the same subject, see ib. II, 250 (Apr. 27, 1786), and IV, 532 ffg. (Apr. 10, 1850). For some early judicial statements of the notion, see Bayard v. Singleton; also Ogden v. Witherspoon and Ogden V. Blackledge, discussed below. Some later cases on the point are S Cow. (N. Y.) 346; 16 N. Y. 432; 99 N. Y. 463; 159 N. Y. 362. But the classic judicial statements of the established doc- trine are in the cases of Dash v. Van Kleeck, 7 Johns. (N. Y.) 477, 488-93, 498, 508-9 (1811) ; and Merrill v. Sherburne, 1 N. H. 199-217 (1817). See also Cooley, Constitutional Limitations (2nd Ed.), 173-5- 40 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW ciples, was naturally conservative of private rights;"^ (6) from various sources came the idea that the ju- diciary must be put in a position to defend its pre- rogative against the legislative tendency to absorb all powers, and this idea was connected with the idea of judicial review both in the relation of means and of endf^ (7) from the Congress of the Confederation °' The reception accorded Trevett v. Weeden has just been referred to. At this same time Wm. Plumer was writing (1786) : "The aspect of public affairs in this State is gloomy . . . Yet even in these degenerate days, our courts of law are firm" ■ Life of Wm. Plumer, p. 166. It was at this time that the worship of the judiciary began, which was later to become so conspicuous a feature of the Federalist regime, leading indeed to the belief on the part of the judges them- selves, that they were meant to be the moral guardians of so- ciety. See Henry Jones Ford, Rise and Growth of American Politics, 112-13. Even Jefferson participated in the general feeling to a certain extent. Writing Madison in 1789, he said: 'The judiciary, if rendered independent and kept strictly to their own department, merits great confidence for their learn- ing and integrity": Writings (Ford's Ed.) V, 81. Again in 1793, he wrote : "The courts of justice exercise the sovereignty of this country in judiciary matters, are supreme in these, and liable neither to control nor opposition from any other branch of the government": ib. VI, 421. Yet in 1805 he approved the ffg. sentiment, expressed in complaint of Congress' lack of power to remove judges : "From this defect in the Constitu- tion arise these evil consequences, that many wrongs are daily done by the courts, to humble, obscure, or poor suitors. . . . It is a prodigious monster in a free government to see a class of men set apart, not simply to administer the laws, but who exercise a legislative and even an executive power, directly in defiance and contempt of the Constitution'' : Phila. Aurora, Jan. 28, 1805. '^ See the criticism by the Pennsylvania Council of Censors (Nov., 1783) against the existing State Constitution: "Because if the assembly should pass an tmconstitutional law and the MARBURY V. MADISON 41 came the idea that the Articles of Confederation and treaties made under them were rightfully to be re- garded as part and parcel of the law of every State, paramount, moreover, to conflicting acts of the State legislatures and enforceable by the State courts.''^ Probably no one public man of the time shared all these ideas when the Philadelphia Convention met. But the able memibership of that famous body was in a position to compare views drawn from every sec- tion of the country. Slowly, by process of discussion and conversation, these men, most of them trained in the legal way of thinking, discovered the intrinsic harmony of the ideas just passed in review; discov- ered, in other words, that the acceptance of one of them more or less constrained the acceptance of the others also, that each implied a system embracing all. The Virginia Plan, introduced into the Convention at its outset, jjrovided for the three departments of government. None the less, the same plan gave evidence that its authors had but imperfect recogni- tion of the implications of the doctrine of the sepa- ration of powers, for it associated members of the judiciary in a council with the executive to revise measures of the national legislature and it left to the judges have the virtue to disobey it, the same could instantly remove them'' : loc cit., p. 70. See also, Hamilton in Federalist Nos. 78 and 80; also infra on the debate of 1802. Madison's anxiety for judicial independence of legislative influence was extreme: Farrand II, 44-5. "^Secret Journals of Congress (1821), IV, 18S-.287; Journals of Congress (1801), XII, under dates of Mar. 21 and Apr. 13, 1787. See also, Bayard v. Smgleton (supra) and Writings of Jefferson (Mem. Ed.), VI, 98. 42 DOCTRIXE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW national legislature the task of keeping State legis- lation subordinate to national powers. The first im- portant step in the clarification of the Convention's ideas with reference to the doctrine of judicial review is marked, therefore, by its rejection of the Council of Revision idea on the basis of the principle stated perhaps most precisely by Strong of Massachusetts, "That the power of making ought to be kept distinct from that of expounding the laws." "No maxim," Strong added, "was better established," and the utter- ances of other members bear out his words.®* For, in one form or another, the notion of legislative power as inherently limited power, distinct from and exclusive of the power of interpreting the standing law, was reiterated again and again and was never contra- dicted. When, therefore, the Convention adopted Article III of the Constitution vesting "the judicial power of the United States in one Supreme Court and such inferior courts as Congress shall from time to time establish," it must be regarded as having ex- pressed the intention of excluding Congress from the business of law-interpreting altogether. But a not less important step toward the final result was taken when the idea of a congressional veto of State laws was dropped and for it was substituted the Small State proposition of giving the Constitution the character of supreme law within the individual States enforceable by the several State judiciaries."^ "Farrand II, 73-80. "' Note particularly the significance of Sherman's words with reference to congressional veto : "Such a power involves a wrong principle, to wit, that a law of a State contrary to the MARBURY V. MADISON 43 Thus it was settled that as against State legislation at any rate the Constitution should be legally supreme. Why not then as against national legislation as well ? When it was decided that the Constitution should be referred for ratification to conventions within the States, the question was probably determined for the majority of the members. Said Madison : "A law violating a constitution established by the people them- selves would be considered by the judges as null and void."*^® Later the Convention proceeded to insert in the Constitution prohibitions upon congressional power in the same terms as some of those already im- posed upon State legislative power. ^'^ The conclusion is unescapable that when Article VI, par. 2, designates the Constitution as law of the land in the same terms as it does acts of Congress made in pursuance of it, it does so by virtue of no inadvertence or inattention on the part of its framers. Moreover, as noted before, the same paragraph recognizes State constitutions as known to and enforceable by State courts. But then was it upon the premises thus provided that the Convention did actually base its belief in ju- dicial review of acts of Congress ? The answer to this question is indicated in part by the fact that the func- Articles of Union would, if not negatived, be valid and oper- ative." Yet as late as Aug. 23, John Langdon of New Hamp- shire said: "He considered it [the question of a Congressional veto] resolvable into the question whether the extent of the National Constitution was to be judged of by the State gov- ernments": Farrand H, 391. The "arising" clause was adopted Aug. 27. "Farrand, H, 93. "' Cf. sections 9 and 10 of Art. I. 44 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW tion of judicial review is almost invariably related by the members of the Convention to the power of the judges as "expositors of the law." But a better rounded and a more satisfactory answer is furnished by Hamilton's argument in Federalist 78 : "The in- terpretation of the laws is the proper and peculiar promnce of the courts. A constitution is in fact, and must he regarded by the judges, as a fundamental law. It therefore belongs to them to ascertain its meaning as 7C'r// as the meaning of any particidar act proceed- ing from the legislative body, and, in case of irrecon- cilable difference between the tzvo, to prefer the will of the people declared in the cotistitution to thai of the legislature as e.rpressed in statute." It cannot be reasonably doubted that Hamilton was here, as at other points, endeavoring to reproduce the matured conclusions of the Convention itself.®^ And not less certain is it that he was thus notifying those to whom the Constitution had been referred for ratification of the grounds upon which its framers and supporters based the case for judicial review. " Note also the words of James Wilson in his "Lectures" (1792), where lie presents judicial review as "the necessary result of the distribution of power made by the Constitution between the legislative and the judicial departments" : Works (Andrews' Ed.), I, 416-7. Note, too, the words with which Hamilton introduces his discussion of the grounds of judicial review : "As this doctrine is of great importance in all the Am. constitutions, a brief discussion of the grounds on which it rests cannot be unacceptable." There is, in other words, no peculiar foundation for the power in the U. S. Constitution. MARBURY V. MADISON 45 V Our demonstration, however, of the views of the framers with reference to the basis of judicial review may also be profitably extended to the period between the adoption of the Constitution and the decision in Marbury v. Madison. For this was the period when the new system was set going, not only in the still un- dimmed light of the views of its authors, but for the most part under their personal supervision. But the interest of the period also arises in part from the real paradox which judicial review has always presented in our system from the outset, the paradox namely of try- ing to keep a government based on public opinion within the metes and bounds of a formally unchange- able law. The dilemma thus created did not at first press, but with the rise of political opposition it became grave enough, and when this opposition finally tri- umphed, not only judicial review but even judicial independence was for the moment in peril. But, indeed, the difficulty at the time of the adop- tion of the Constitution was hardly a new one, for some such objection had been earlier forthcoming to judicial review within the States themselves, where however, the judges were generally much less secure of independence than under the United States Constitu- tion,^^" and where, as we have seen, the legislature still fredy directed the course -of judicial proceedings. Furthermore, as I have already indicated, judicial re- view as at first proposed for the States had rested upon a logic which put it in the light of a highly extra- ""' See the data given in Annals of Congress, I, col. 844. 46 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW ordinary, quasi-revolutionary remedy, and gave it sway w^ithin the very limited area marking the intersection, so to speak, of the written constitution with funda- mental principles oi the Common Law. It is hardly surprising, then, to find Hamilton turning from his work of planting judicial review squarely within the Constitution and of rendering its field of operation co-extensive with the four corners of that instrument, to consider certain objections, which he recites as follows : "The authority of the proposed Supreme Court of the United States, which is to be a separate and inde- pendent body, will be superior to that of the legislature. The power of construing the laws according to the spirit of the Constitution will enable that court to mould them into whatever shape it may think proper; especially as its decisions will not be in any manner subject to the revision or correction of the legislative body. This is as unprecedented as it is dangerous. . . . The Parliament of Great Britain and the legislatures of the several States can at any time rectify by law the exceptionable decisions of their respective courts. But the errors and usurpations of the Supreme Court of the United States will be uncontrollable and remediless." Hamilton met these objections by flatly denying that the principle of the separation of powers permitted even a State legislature to reverse a judicial decree. Said he: "Neither the theory of the British nor the State constitutions authorizes the revisal of a judicial sentence by a legislative act.""^ Madison, on the other hand, responded — character- istically — to the views of the alarmists more pro- ™ Federalist No. 8i. Hamilton also pointed to impeachment as an available remedy for an abuse of power by the judges. MARBURY V. MADISON 47 nouncedly. ^ On the floor of the Convention, as we have just seen, he had espoused the doctrine of judicial review in unmistakable terms!] Again in the Feder- alist he had described the Supreme Court as the tribunal which was "ultimately to decide" the ques- tions that would necessarily arise between the State and national jurisdictions. ''*' And in the Virginia con- vention his point of view had still been the same: the National Government was to be the final judge of its own powers through the Supreme Court. ''^ Yet within six months he was writing a correspondent in Kentucky that neither the federal nor State consti- tutions made any provision "for the case of a dis- agreement in expounding them" and that the attempt of the courts to stamp a law "with its final character" "by refusing or not refusing to execute it" made "the judicial department paramount in fact to the legis- lative, which was never intended and can never be proper."''^ Still Madison was reluctant to abandon judicial re- view outright. What he really desired was a principle which, while saving to judicial interpretations of the Constitution their finality in certain instances, in ™ No. 39. "Elliot, III, 484-S. '^Note 35, supra. Madison, like many other Virginians of prominence, was angered at this time by the pedantic attitude taken by the State court of appeals toward an act of the legis- lature imposing new duties on them without increasing their salaries. See the Case of the Judges, 4 Call. 139, ffg. (1788). The case gave rise to a vigorous debate in the Virginia assembly. See Monroe to Madison, Nov. 22, 1788: "Letters to Madison," MSS., Library of Congress. 48 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW others clad those of Congress with a like finality. He soon had an opportunity to attempt the formulation of such a principle. The bill introduced into the first Congress creating the Department of Foreign Affairs contained the clause, with reference to the Secretary of State, "to be removable from office by the Presi- dent of the United States." The clause was at once attacked by Smith of South Carolina in the following words : "What authority has this house to explain the law ? . . . Sir, it is the duty of the legislature to make laws; your judges are to expound them." Madison sprang to the defense of the clause. He admitted that it represented an attempt by Congress to construe the Constitution fin-ally at the point involved, but he as- serted that it was within Congress' power to do this very thing in a case where the Constitution was silent and the question raised concerned an apportionment of power among departments. In other words, an as- sumed incompleteness at points was to give Congress its opportunity. But, rejoined Gerry of Massachusetts, "I would ask, gentlemen, if the Constitution has given us the the power to make declaratory acts, where is the necessity of inserting the Fifth Article for the purpose of obtaining amendments ? The word amendment implies a defect, a declaratory act conceives one. Where then is the difference between an amendment and a declaratory act?" The protest against an "attempt to construe the Con- stitution" was also voiced by Sherman of Connecticut, Page and White of Virginia, and Benson of New York, with the result that eventually Madison himself joined in support of a motion striking out the excep- MARBURY V. MADISON 49 tionable clause and substituting for it phraseology merely inferring that the President would exercise the power of removal and making provision for the event.''* A little later the House passed the Judiciary Act almost without comment upon the 25tli section of it, which recognizes the judicial prerogative in rela- tion to the written constitution in the most explicit fashion.''^ " For this debate, see Annals of Congress, I, col. 473 ffg. '* The following are the names of those who attended the Philadelphia Convention and later supported the Act of 1789: Ellsworth, Paterson, Strong, Bassett , and Few — all of whom were on the Senate Committee that drafted the act; Robert Mprris- and Read , also Senators; and Madison , Baldwin , and SliSHcan in We House. Professor Beard in his Supreme Court, etc., assumes that all these men must have favored judicial review in 1787. The argument must be taken with considerable allowance, for judicial review was a rapidly spread- ing idea during this period. On the floor of the Convention itself there were several converts. Read, for example, in this connection the exact statements of Gerry, Wilson, and Dickin- son, as reported by Madison. Compare Dickinson in his "Let- ters of Fabius." Compare Morris' words in 1785: Sparks, Life of Gouverneur Morris, III, 438. Mr. Horace Davis in the November, 1913, Am. Polit. Sc. Rev. seeks to prove, on the other hand, that those who supported the Act of 1789 thereby showed that they did not believe in the power of the Supreme Court to pass upon the validity of acts of Congress, except as the question was raised in cases coming up from the State courts. If Mr. Davis had turned to the debate, just reviewed, on the establish- ment of the Department of Foreign Affairs, he would have found at least half a dozen men championing the notion of judicial review who later voted for the Act of 1789. Also, I should like to ask where the State courts get their power to pass on the validity of acts of Congress save as it is intrinsic to judicial power under a constitution regarded as law. The argument would, however, have considerable force if the Su- preme Court got its power from the clause "cases arising under so DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW From this time on for nearly a decade, the juristic view of the Constitution passed substantially without challenge. It is true that when in the first Hayburn case the judges of the Middle Circuit refused to en- force the Pension Act of 1792 on the ground of its unconstitutionahty, some "high-fliers in and out of Congress" raised the cry of impeachment; but they were speedily silenced. Upon the objections of the judges to the act being filed with the President, the latter forwarded them to Congress, which proceeded promptly to bring the act into conformity with the judicial view of constitutional requirements.''® Four this Constitution," considered in the light of Hamilton's in- terpretation of it in Fed. 80. For some further references in the first Congress to judicial review, see Annals, I, cols. 457, l(>li, 767-8; II, cols. 1978 and 1988. '° The materials for this account of the "Pension Case" are drawn from 2 Dall. 409 ; Am. St. Papers, Misc. I, 49-52 ; Annals of Cong., HI, cols, 556-7; Annals of Cong., XI (7th Cong., ist sess'n), cols. 921-5; XJ. S. v. Ferreira, 13 How. 40 (note). The statement with reference to the threat of impeachment is based on the following extract from Bache's General Advertiser (Camden, N. J. for Apr. 20, 1792) : "Never was the word 'impeachment' so hackneyed as it has been since the spirited sentence passed by our judges on an unconstitutional law. The high-fliers, in and out of Congress, and the very humblest of their humble retainers, talk of nothing but impeachment! impeachment ! impeachment ! as if forsooth Congress were wrapped up in the cloak of infallibility, which has been torn from the shoulders of the Pope; and that it was damnable heresy and sacrilege to doubt the constitutional orthodoxy of any decision of theirs, once written on calf skin 1 But if a Secretary of War can suspend or reverse the decision of the Circuit Judges,, why may not a drill sergeant or a black drummer reverse the decisions of a jury? Why not abolish at once all our Courts, except the court martial? and burn all our laws, except the articles of war . . ?" "But when those MARBURY V. MADISON 51 years later occurred the case of United States v. Hylton,''^ which is instructive of the estabHshed doc- trine in a number of ways. The only question argued before the court was that of the constitution- ality of the act of Congress involved. In the argu- ment for the United States, the Attorney General was assisted by Alexander Hamilton, for whose services Congress appropriated a special fund. Neither side challenged the power of the court in the premises.'^'' The court's decision upholding the act was based purely upon the merits of the case. Madison was plainly disappointed at the act's not being disallowed. '^^ And meantime, judicial review was also advancing within the States, and what is an even more significant development, was being transferred from the earlier basis of fundamental principles to the written consti- impeachment mongers are asked how any law is to be declared unconstitutional, they tell us that nothing less than a general convention is adequate to pass sentence on it; as if a general convention could be assembled with as much ease as a party of stock jobbers.'' And to like effect is a paragraph in Fre- neau's National Gazette for Apr. 16, 1792. I am indebted for these references to my friend, Mr. W. S. Carpenter, who is preparing a volume on Judicial Tenure in the United States. "3 Dall. 171 (1796)- "Annals, XI, cols. 925-6. "It was also during this period that, in 1793, the Supreme Court refused Washington's request to advise him with refer- ence to the operation of the treaties of 1778 with France, basing its refusal upon the strictly judicial character of their office : Baldwin, American Judiciary, 33. In the debate on the De- partment of Foreign Affairs in 1789, Gerry had expressed the idea that the President could require opinions of the judges on constitutional questions and that these would be binding on Congress: loc. cit. col. 524. 52 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW tiition. Two illustrative cases are Bowman v. Mid- dleton,''° and Kamper v. Hawkins.'^'* In the former, decided in 1792, the South Carolina supreme court pronounced an early colonial statute to have been void ab initio as contrary to "common right" and "Magna Carta." In the latter, four years later, the Virginia court of appeals pronounced an act of the State legis- lature void as in conflict with the letter and spirit of the Virginia constitution, which was described as an ordinance of the people themselves and therefore su- perior to an ordinary statute, but as nonetheless a source of rules determinative of the rights of individuals.®^ One thing that retarded the growth of judicial re- view in the States was the continuing influence of Blackstone, with his notion of parliamentary sover- eignty,^^ but a not less potent factor was the '" I Bay (S. C.) 252. Earlier than this, in the case of Ham v. McClaws, loc. cit., 93 (1789), the S. C. court, following Coke's dictum, gave a statute a very restricted meaning to bring it into conformity with "rules of common right and justice." "Statutes made against natural equity," said the court, "are void, and so also are statutes made against Magna Carta." ™Va. Cases, 20. '' Note J. Nelson's words, p. 131 of the volume : For the legis- lature to decide whether its own act is void or not would be unconstitutional, "since to decide whether the plaintifif or de- fendant under the existing law have a right is a judicial act." '" For an illustration of the Blackstonian influence, see Zephaniah Swift, The System of Laws of Connecticut (179s). pp. 16-7, 34-S, 52-3. Also, in the same connection, see argu- ments of attorneys in 4 Halstead (N. J.) 427 and i Binney (Pa.) 416. For a decidedly disingenuous and somewhat amus- ing attempt to explain Blackstone's words away, see Works of James Wilson (Andrews' Ed.), II, 415. Note also, Marshall's MARBURY V. MADISON . 53 retention of the doctrine that legislative power ex- tended to the interpretation of the standing law. Thus as late as 1798 we find Justice Chase of the United States Supreme Court declaring that only in the Massachusetts constitution were the powers of gov- ernment distributed; and two years later the same judge announced his opinion that the mere statement of the general principle of the separation of powers in a State constitution did not serve to restrict the legis- lative powers, that such general principles were "not to be regarded as rules to fetter and control, but as matter merely declaratory and directory."^^ But in Ogden V. Witherspoon,^*' which was a North Carolina case falling within federal jurisdiction because of the diverse citizenship of the parties to it, and in which therefore the federal court stood in the same relation to the State constitution that the State court would have, Chief Justice Marshall on circuit reversed this position; and in Ogden v. Blackledge the Supreme Court itself sustained his course. In the latter case the question at issue was whether a North Carolina words, as attorney in Ware v. Hylton, 3 Dall. 199, 211 : "The judicial authority have no right to question the validity of a law unless such a jurisdiction is given expressly by the constitution." ^'The cases referred to are Calder v. Bull, 3 Dall. 386, and Cooper V. Telfair, 4 Dall. 13. Justice Chase indicates by his remarks in these cases, significantly, reluctance to admit judicial review save on the hasis of natural rights and the social com- pact. His remarks in the latter case, however, contain inter- esting testimony as to the unanimity of opinion on the subject among bench and bar, both in 1800 and at the time of the adop- tion of the Constitution. ^3 N. C. 404 (1802). 54 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW statute of limitations, passed in 171 5, had been re- pealed in 1789, the State legislature having declared in 1799 that it had not been. Said attorney for plaintiff : "To declare what the law is or has been is a judicial power, to declare what it shall be is legislative. One of the fundamental principles of all our governments is that the legislative power shall be separated from the judicial."^" The court stopped counsel and decided that, "under all the circumstances stated, the act in question had been repealed in 1789." The service thus rendered the cause of judicial review under the State constitutions by the federal courts acting in their vicarious capacity cannot be overesti- mated. By 1820, the spread of the juristic interpre- tation of the principle of the separation of powers had effected the establishment of judicial review on the basis of the written constitution in every State in the Union save only Rhode Island, which exception moreover only proves the rule, since it is explained by the fact that till 1842 Rhode Island continued its colonial charter as a constitution and that by this in- strument legislative power remained undefined. None- theless, even today. State judges in exercising this power sometimes place their right to it upon a some- what precarious basis.®" VI But lastly we turn to consider the challenge made to the finality of the Supreme Court's interpretation ^2 Cr. 272, 276 (1805). ™ See the note at the dose of this study on the Establishment of Judicial Review in the States. MARBURY V. MADISON 55 of the Constitution in relation to acts of Congress l>y Jefferson and his more radical followers in the years 1798-1802. The matter most immediately demanding explanation is evident. It is the entire failure of this challenge even while its authors were borne into higher office by an overwhelming political triumph. The debate and vote on the Judiciary Act of 1789 prove that originally the advocates of State rights — for they existed from the beginning — were nothing loath to accept the Supreme Court's view of the Con- stitution as final, both in relation to national and to State power. When, however, the federal judges showed themselves disposed to uphold and enforce the Alien and Sedition Laws of 1798, and some of them indeed to entertain prosecutiions for sedition under a supposed Common Law of the United States,*®" the State-rights champions began to appreciate for the first time the added sanction given to national authority by judicial decision. The Virginia and Kentucky Resolutions of 1798 and 1799 were framed primarily with the design of breaking through this subtle control, on the warrant of the propositions, first that the Constitution was a compact of sovereign States and, second, that the organ of sovereignty within a State was its legislature, from which propositions the conclusion was drawn that the final word in con- struing the national Constitution lay with the indi- "'" On the question of whether the federal courts enjoy a Common Law jurisdiction independently of statute, see U. S. v. Worrall, 2 Dall. 384 ; U. S. v. Hudson et al., 7 Cr. 32 ; U. S. V. Coolidge, i jSall. 488. \ S6 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW vidual State legislatures.^'' But the outcome of the propaganda thus undertaken was not merely a further vindication of the prerogative of the Supreme Court of the United States, but of all courts. Thus having been forwarded to the other legislatures, the resolutions elicited from the seven Northern of them unequivocal declarations of the right of the "Supreme Court of the United States ultimately" to decide "on the constitutionality of any act" of Congress.^^ In his famous Report of 1799 to the Virginia legislature, Madison endeavored at first to meet these responses by reiterating the doctrine of the original resolutions, but even in so doing he admitted the finality of judi- cial constructions of the Constitution as against the other branches of the National Government, and in the end he abandoned his case completely.®^ The Resolutions, he contended, taking a defensive tone, were entirely proper, since they were designed merely "to excite reflection," whereas, he added, decisions of the judiciary, "are carried into immediate effect by force." It would be hard to imagine a more complete retreat. The probability is that he and those for whom he spoke had begun to realize that to make the State legislature the final interpreter of the National "MacDonald, Select Documents, 148-60; Elliot, IV., 528-32, 540-45. It should be noted that Jefferson did not deny judicial review outright in 1798. Writing Rowan, Sept. 26, 1798, he said : "The laws of the land, administered by upright judges would protect you from any exercise of power unauthorized by ihe Constitution of the U. S." : Writings (Ford, Ed.), VII, 281. "* H. V. Ames, State Documents on Federal Relations, 16-26. '"Writings (Hunt's Ed.), VI, 341-406. MARBURY V. MADISON S7 Constitution was also to make it the final interpreter of the State constitution, which in turn meant either the setting up of a legally uncontrolled power within the State itself or — what practically would have been the same thing — return to the idea, now rapidly be- coming obsolete, of a legislative function of jvus dicere. Two years later, nevertheless, the question of the finality of the judicial view of the Constitution was again to the front, though on a somewhat altered foot- ing. By the election of 1800 the Republicans had captured the Presidency and both Houses of Congress, but the judiciary still withstood them. Now, at the very moment of retiring from power the Federalists proceeded by the Act of February, 1801, substantially to double the number of inferior federal courts, while President Adams at once set to work, with the co- operation of the Senate, to fill the newly created offices with Federalists. The federal judiciary, exclaimed Randolph wrathfully, has become "a hospital of de- cayed politicians!" Jefferson's concern went deeper. Writing Dickinson he said: "They have retired into the judiciary, from which stronghold they will batter down all the works of Republicanism." Naturally the first step attempted was the repeal of the Act of 1801, but from the point of view of a possible larger program of definitely subordinating the judiciary to the pohtical branches of the govern- ment, the repeal voted was indeed a Pyrrhic victory.®" "Jefferson and Giles were originally of the opinion that the act was irrepealable. They were converted to their later view by the dialectic of Joha Taylor of Caroline. These statements are based on documents from the Breckenridge MSS. which S8 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW In the debate on the question the Federalists speedily developed the argument that, inasmuch as the Consti- tution designed the judiciary to act as a check upon Congress, the latter was under constitutional obliga- tion not to weaken the independence of the former in any way. To meet this argument Breckenridge of Kentucky, the Republican leader in the Senate — and one of the authors O'f the Kentucky Resolutions — brought forward the theory of the equal right of the three departments, when acting within their respective fields, to construe the Constitution for themselves, and from it deduce the exclusive right of the legislature "to interpret the Constitution in what regards the law- making power" and the obligation of the judges "to execute what laws they make." In other words, as we noted earlier, the notion of a departmental right of con- stitutional construction takes its rise not from the effort to establish judicial review but from an attempt to over- throw it. But the feeble disguise which this doctrine afifords legislative sovereignty made it little attractive even to Republicans, who for the most part either plainly indicated their adherence to the juristic view of the Constitution, or following a hint by Giles of Virginia, kept silent on the subject. The Federalists on the other hand were unanimous on the main question, though of divergent opinions as to the grounds on which judicial review was to be legally based, some grounding it on the "arising" and "pursuant" clauses, some on the precedents of the Pension and Carriage are given in Mr. W. S. Carpenter's thesis on Judicial Tenure in the United States. MARBURY V, MADISON 59 cases, some on the nature of the Constitution and of the judicial office, some on "the contemporary use of terms" and "the undisputed practice under the Con- stitution" "of all constitutional authorities." And un- doubtedly, by this date, all these grounds were fairly available save the first. For the rest, said the Feder- alist orators, judicial review was expedient, since the judiciary had control of neither the purse nor the sword; it was the substitute offered by political wis- dom for the destructive right of revolution ; "to have established this principle of constitutional security," "a novelty in the history of nations," was "the peculiar glory of the American people;" the contrary doctrine was "monstrous and unheard of."''^ "'Annals of Cong., XI, cols. 26-184 (iSenate), cols. 510-985 (House). Breckenridge of Kentucky did not at first attack judicial review, loc. cit. 92-9; but was> finally prodded to it, ib. 178-80. In the Senate two advocates of repeal attacked judicial review (Breckenridge and Stone of North Carolina), while two (Jackson of Georgia and Wright of Maryland) accepted it. In the House, three advocates of repeal attacked judicial re- view (Randolph of Virginia, Williams of North Carolina, and Thompson of Virginia) ; two endeavored to discover a compro- mise position, along the line of the doctrine of departmental equality (Davis of Kentucky and Bacon of Massachusetts) ; but five, impliedly at least, accepted judicial review without making such qualifications (Smith of Vermont, Nicholson of Maryland, Gregg of Pennsylvania, Holland of North Carolina, and Varnum of Massachusetts). Their remarks can be easily located through the Index. Those of Randolph and Bacon are most instructive. In the Senate, seven opponents of repeal championed judicial review (see, especially, the speeches of Morris of New York, and Chipman of Vermont). In the House, fifteen of the same party performed this service. The remarks quoted in the text are from the speeches of Stanly and Henderson of North Carolina, Rutledge of South Carolina, and 6o DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW A few months later occurred the decision in Mar- bury V. Madison, which against this background as- sumes its true color. Yet Marshall's performance is by no means to be regarded as a work of supereroga- tion. In the first place, vested as it was with the ap- parent authority of a judicial decision, it brought to an end a discussion which, for all that it had been highly favorable to judicial review, might in the end have proved unsettling. Again, it threw the emphasis once more upon the great essential considerations of the character of the Constitution, as "fundamental and paramount law" and "the province and duty of the judicial department to say what the law is." Finally, in the very process of vindicating judicial review, it admitted to a degree the principle that had thus far been contended for only by opponents of judicial re- view. Thus, discussing the amenability of the Presi- dent and his agents to mandamus, the Chief Justice says: "By the Constitution of the United States the President is vested with certain important political powers in the exercise of which he is to use his own discretion and is accountable only to his country in Dana of Connecticut: Cols. 529-30, 542-3, 547-6, 754-5, 920, 932. Other notable speeches were those of Goddard and Griswold of Connecticut, and Hemphill of Pennsylvania. Giles' case is in- teresting. In the debate on the first Bank, 1791, he had answered an argument in behalf of the proposition, that was drawn from the fact that the Congress of the Confederacy had chartered "the Bank of North America" thus : "The act itself was never confiTtned by a judicial decision.'' In other words, adjudication is made the final test of constitutionality. But in 1804, we find him holding that Congress might impeach a judge for declaring one of its acts unconstitutional : J. Q. Adams, Memoirs, I, 321 flfg. MARBURY V. MADISON 6i his political character and to his own conscience."''^ Later of course, this doctrine, which we may call the doctrine of departmental discretion, was supplemented by the doctrine that the powers of Congress must be liberally construed,^* and later still by the doctrine of the immunity of the President from judicial process.®* All these doctrines may be readily harmonized with the theory of judicial review.®^ At the same time, they are not constrained by that theory, but are plainly concessions to the necessity of making the Constitu- tion flexible and adaptable while still keeping it legal. They prove therefore that "the spirit of accommoda- tion" with which Professor McLaughlin credits the political departments has at least been met by a similar spirit on the part of the judiciary. * =K * * Judicial Review originally offered itself on the basis of the notion of Fundamental Law, but could not establish itself on that basis because legislative power was still undefined, approximating indeed to all governmental power viewed in the light of its exercise by a particular organ of government. Later the emergence of the distinction between law as an act of revelation, like the Common Law, and law as an act of authority, like statute law, suggested the "i Cr. 165-6. "McCulloch V. Md., 4 Wheat. 316 (i8ip). "'Miss. V. Johnson, 4 Wall. 475 (1867). °° The theory, however, of the immunity of the President from jurisdiction for his personal and private acts, so long as he remains in office, has no reasonable foundation. See in this connection Countryman, The Supreme Court and its Appellate Jurisdiction, pp. 230 fifg. (Albany, 1913). 62 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW requisite differentiation of "legislative" and "judicial" powers; but this distinction was accompanied by the notion of legislative sovereignty, and so judicial re- view was once again postponed.*® But in democratic America the attribute of sovereignty was presently a;bsorbed by the People, — first, in its passive sense of the source of governing power, and later in its active sense of the highest governing power; and the result of the latter development was to impart to the con- stitution the character, not simply of an act of revo- lution, but of law, in the true sense of the term of a source of rules enforceable by the courts. Until the Convention of 1787, judicial review as a workable institution was still in ovo. One of the main motives however that had brought the Conven- tion together was a general disgust at the recent antics of the State legislatures. To curtail legislative power as it existed in the State constitutions in the inter- est, first, of an adequate national power and, secondly, in the interest of private rights, was therefore one of the main problems before that body. From some of the States, the tentative hint of judicial review was available, and when the notion of a congressional veto on State laws was rejected, was gladly turned to. But this outcome had in fact been substantially " Note in this general connection that James Otis maintained in his Rights of the British Colonists Asserted and Proved (1764) that, "The supreme power in a state is jus dicere only; jus dare, strictly speaking, belongs only to God" : McLaughlin, The Courts, etc., p. 70. With Otis' contention, on the other hand, compare Bacon's significant warning in his Essay on Judicature, that the judges ought to be "lions, but lions under the throne" and not to "interfere with points of sovereignty." MARBURY V. MADISON 63 guaranteed from the first by the Convention's grow- ing comprehension of the principle of the separation of powers in relation to a written constitution re- garded as lazv; and by the same token, judicial re- view of acts of Congress was also assured from an early date a place in the projected system. From time to time, various other arguments than the one just reiterated have been urged in support of judicial review, even by judges, particularly of the State courts; but they are all invalid as assuming the very point in dispute. The judges do not exercise a revolutionary function in pronouncing acts of the legislature void, but an official function. Their con- stitutional ecjuality with the other departments se- cures them in the possession of their rightful powers but does not enlarge those powers. Their oath of fidelity to the constitution does not oblige them to ex- ercise other than their constitutional powers in its defense. Furthermore, the notion of an equal au- thority in all departments and officers to determine the meaning of the constitution for themselves was origi- nally brought forward with a view to checking judicial review. And thus much by way of summary. In the last analysis, the doctrine of judicial review involves "an act of Faith," to wit, the belief that the judges really know the standing law and that they alone know it.®'^ "' Says Montesquieu : "Judges are no more than the mouth that pronounces the words of the law." Mr. Pope in his article in the Harv. Law Rev., cited above, insists upon the belief in 1787 that the judges knew the law, while all others had only opinions about it. 64 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW This act of faith was easy for the popular mind under the regime of the Common Law. To-day, however, through the activity of legislatures in the- prosecution of Reform, law comes to be looked upon more and more as something made rather than as something discovered,' — as an act of authority rather than as an act of knowledge. The result is that the possibility of an automatic declaration of the law by the judges comes to be regarded with scepticism; and it comes to be said that the judges in interpreting the law really change it and in interpreting the constitution really change that. To these views a large measure of truth must be conceded. Meantime, fortunately, the philosophy of Evolution has introduced a distinction of palpable serviceability to our constitutional theory in its pres- ent exigency, the distinction between growth by. grad- ual accretion and change by leaps and bounds. The concept of an automatic declaration of the law is there- fore no longer necessary to the doctrine of the separa- tion of powers. The judges change the law, it is true, but they go about the business in a vastly different way than the legislature does. The legislature acts simply upon considerations of expediency. The judges are controlled by precedent, logic, the sensible meaning of words, and their perception of moral con- sequences.®^ Also, as it happens, our courts are to-day in a position in construing the constitution to avail them- °° See generally Prof. Vinogradoff's illuminating little volume on Common Sense in Law (Home Univ. Library Series, Holt & Co. N. Y., 1914). MARBURY V. MADISON 65 selves of the modern flexible view of law as some- thing inherently developing, in a way never before possible to them. All constitutional limitations set- ting the bounds between the rights of the community and the rights of the individual have tended of recent years to be absorbed into the constitutional require- ment of "due process of law" and this requirement, in turn, has come to take on the general meaning of "reasonable law."®^ So far as constitutional theory itself is concerned there is small ground for the com- plaints levelled by reformers at judicial i-eview. When, however, one turns to the more concrete matter of the fitness of particular judges for the great responsi- bility vested in them by the constitution, there is, of course, often room for discussion. Notes I — Judicial Review in the State Ratifying Conven- tions : The power that the courts would have with reference to unconstitutional acts of 0>ngress was ex- pounded at length in the Pa. convention by Wilson: Elliot, Debates, II, 417, 454 (Edition of 1836) ; also by Ellsworth in the Conn, convention, ib. 198-9. It was referred to directly by Hamilton in the N. Y. convention, ib. 336-7. Several references occur to it in the N. C. convention that failed to ratify; loc. cit. IV, 87, 93-4, 152, 165, 167, 192. The report of the debate in the Mass. Convention on the judiciary appears in only very abbreviated form on account of the illness of the reporter at this stage of the proceedings. But Samuel Adams made a direct allusion to the power of judicial review affecting acts of Congress ; loc. cit. II, 142 ; and other speakers used language showing their recognition of some such power in courts; see ib. 97-8, 100-6, iio-ii, 138, 154, 167, 171-4. In the Va. convention, judicial °° See the present writer in 7 Mich. Law Rev., 543 ffg. 66 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW review was referred to, either as touching acts of Con- gress or in more general terms, no fewer than twelve times: loc. cit. Ill, 182 and 309 (Henry) ; 197, 208, and 431 (Randolph) ; 287 and 498 (Pendleton) ; 409 (Nicholas) ; 441 (Mason) ; 484-5 (Madison) ; 503 (Marshall); 514 (Granger). Much of this and further evidence is presented by Mr. Horace Davis in his article in the Am. Pol. Sc. Rev. Mr. Davis himself, however, endeavors to reject the obvious verdict of this evidence. The explanation of his attitude is that he confuses the question of whether judicial review of acts of Congress was believed to be a feature of the new system with the question whether it was expected to prove an effective limitation upon Congress. The absence of a Bill of Rights and the presence of the "general welfare" and "necessary and proper" clauses caused opponents of the Constitution to charge that the judges would never be able to stamp any act of Congress as invalid, that Con- gress' power was practically unlimited to begin with. See Elliot, I, 545; H, 314-15, 318, 321-2; IV, 175; also, McMaster and Stone, Pennsylvania and the Federal Con- stitution, 467, 611; also, Ford, Pamphlets, 312; also and especially. Federalist No. 33. Said Whitehill in the Pa. convention : "Laws may be made in pursuance of the Constitution, though not agreeably to it; the laws may be unconstitutional" : McMaster and Stone, loc. cit. 780. II — The Doctrine of Departmental Construction of the Constitution. There is an early hint of this doctrine in Jefferson's Va. Notes, which is criticized by Madison in Fed. No. 49. A much more explicit statement of the doctrine is that of Abraham Baldwin in the U. S. Senate, Jan. 23, 1800: Farrand, III, 383. For Jefferson's view formulated late in life, see his Writings (Mem. Ed.), XV, 212 ffg. Madison as President took the position that he had no discretion in the matter of enforcing, not only decisions of the judiciary, but acts of Congress : Am. St. Papers, Misc., II, 12 (1809). Professor McLaughlin, on the other hand, refers approvingly to old Gideon Welles' attempt "to make General Grant see that he was not under constitutional obligation to obey an act if that act MARBURY V. MADISON 67 was unconstitutional. Grant maintained that he was under obligations to obey a law until the Supreme Court declared it unconstitutional. Such is the natural po- sition of the layman." But even Welles had no idea of maintaining that the President would not be bound by a decision of the Supreme Court: Diary of Gideon Welles, III, 176-80. Furthermore, on the precise ques- tion in issue between Welles and Grant, I must express a preference for the views of the latter. Obedience to the mandates of the legislature till they are proved to be void is one of the risks of office under our system. The contrary view leads to irresponsibility and disorder. Lincoln's views expressed in criticism of the Dred Scott ^decision reveal some contradictions: see Haines, 265-9. ^Lincoln himself virtually admitted that, in disobeying the Thandate of the court in Merryman's case he had violated the Constitution in one particular, but pleaded the neces- sity he had been under to do so in order to save it as a whole.! But then, is the President always bound to take the^ measure of his powers from the Supreme Court? The answer is, that by the Supreme Court's own view of the Constitution many of the powers vested by it in the President are to be exercised at his discre- tion : Martin v. Mott, 12 wheat. 19. One such power is doubtless the veto power. On the other hand, the Presi- dent can exercise only his constitutional powers, cannot in other words, in the guise of exercising his discretion, transcend their limits. Another question relevant to the general matter under discussion is as to the application of the doctrine of stare decisis in constitutional cases. There can be no doubt that the doctrine applies in such cases : Story i Comms. §§ 377-8. On the other hand, however, the doctrine is in nowise necessary to the theory of judicial review itself. jThe Supreme Court is not bound by its own erroneous decisions : Genessee Chief V. Fitzhugh, 12 How. 456; the Legal Tender Cases, 12 Wall. 457. IBut the court alone can authoritatively pronounce its decisions erroneous, and anyone else who presumes to ignore the precedents does so at his risk. Also, as said above, executive officers, save where con- stitutionally vested with a discretion, must follow the 68 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW decisions as they find them, and also the acts of the legis- lature. Such is the nature of the executive office. For further discussion of the applicability of the doctrine of stare decisis in constitutional cases, see Dorr v. U. S., 195 U. S. 138, 154; 58 Cent. L. J. 29; 3 Harv. Law Rev. 125 ; 3 Mich. Law Rev. 89, ffg. The argument for judi- cial review based on the official oath is of course an ar- gument for departmental construction of the constitution. It was well answered by J. Gibson in his famous dissient in Eakin v. Raub, in the following words : "The official oath . . . relates only to the official conduct of the officer, and does not prove that he ought to stray from the path of his ordinary business to search for violations of duty in the business of others ; nor does it, as supposed, define the powers of the officer": 12 Serg. and Rawle (Pa.) 330, 353. Marshall cites the oath taken by the judges to uphold the constitution apparently in support of his contention that the constitution is law. Ill — The True Meaning of Coke's Dictum : Coke was what to-day would be called a "political judge" ; and it is possible that there was a period when, the King and Parliament being at loggerheads and legislation accord- ingly impossible, he dreamed of giving the law to both. His final and matured views on the power of Parliament, however, are those stated in the Fourth Book of his Insti- tutes, in the following passages : "And it is to be known that the lords in their house have power of judicature and the commons in their house have power of judica- ture, and both houses together have power of judicature (p. 23). . . . Of acts of Parliament, some be introduc- tory of a new law [n.b.] and some be declaratory of the ancient law and some be of both kinds (p. 25). . . . Of the power and jurisdiction of the Parliament for making of laws in proceeding by bill, it is so transcendent and absolute as it cannot be confined either for causes or persons within any bounds (p. 36). . . . Yet some ex- amples are desired : . . . To attaint a man of treason after his death. ... It may bastard a child that by law is legitimate. ... To legitimate one that is illegitimate" (ib.). His ideas of "common right and reason" were MARBURY V. MADISON 69 therefore not very rigorous. Returning to Bonham's Case, we find him citing in support of his dictum a case arising in the manor of Dales, where it was held that an act of Parliament conferring in general terms upon a specific person the jurisdiction of cases arising in the manor did not apply to a case to which that person was an interested party: 8 Rep. 118-20. Judged by this in- stance all that he means by the word "void," as applied to an act of Parliament, is "inoperative in the particular case when interpreted by Common Law standards." With the dictum should be compared his much later words on p. 37 of the Fourth Book of the Institutes : "I had it of Sir Thos. Gawdye, Knight, a grave and reverend judge of the King's bench, who lived at that time, that Henry VIII commanded him to attend the chief justices and to know whether a man that was forthcoming might be at- tainted for high treason by Parliamient and never called to his answer. The judges answered that it was a dangerous question, and that the High Court of Parliament ought to give examples to inferior courts for proceeding according to justice, and no inferior court could do the like, and they thought that the High Court of Parliament would never do it. But being by the express commandment of the King and pressed by the said earl to give a direct answer, they said that if he he attainted by Parliament, it could not come in question afterwards, whether he were called or not to answer. And albeit their opinion was according to law, yet might they have made a better answer, for by the statutes of Magna Carta, Cap. 29, 5 Edw. Ill Cap. 9, and 28 Edw. HI Cap. 5, no man ought to be condemned . without answer, etc., which they might have certified but facta tenent multa quae fieri prohiben- tur; the act of attainder being passed by Parliament did bind, as they resolved." The position is substantially identical with that afterward taken by Blackstone. See text. See also 4 Mass. 529. IV — Mingling of Legislative and Judicial Powers : For Parliament's relation to the standing law in the 17th century, see the instructive pages in Mcllwain, High Court of Parliament, etc., ch. Ill, especially pp. 109-66. 70 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW Said Harrington in his Oceana : "Wherever the power of making law is, there only is the power of interpreting the law so made" ; loc. cit. 163. See also Blackstone, I Comms. 160. For the case of the colonial legislatures, see Works of James Wilson (Andrews' Ed.), II, 50; Minot, History of Massachusetts, I, 29 ; Hutchinson, History of Massachusetts, etc., I, 30, II, 250, 414; 15 Harvard Law Rev. 208-18; Massachusetts Acts and Re- solves (to 1780), passim; Journal of Virginia House of Burgesses, passim. For the case of the early State legis- latures, see Federalist Nos. 48 and 81, the latter of which is quoted infra on this subject. See also Jefferson's "Virginia Notes" in Works (Mem. Ed.) II, 160-78; also the Reports of the Pennsylvania Council of Censors of their sessions of Nov. 10, 1783, and June i, 1784, in The Proceedings Relative to the Calling of the Conventions of 1776 and 1790, etc. (Harrisburg, 1825), pp. 66-128; also, Tucker's Blackstone, I, app. 81-3, 1 19-21, 125-6. See also Langdon of New Hampshire's letters complain- ing of acts of the State legislature annulling judgments, in New Hampshire State Papers, XI, 812, 815, and XXII, 749, 756, (June, 1790). For a concrete case in N. H., as late as 1791, see the Am. Hist'l Rev. XII, 348- 50, and Prof. W. F. Dodd's remarks concerning it. For concrete instances in Massachusetts under the consti- tution of 1780, see Acts and Resolves under following dates: 1780, May 5, June 9, Sept. 19; 1781, Feb. 12, Apr. 28, Oct. 10; 1782, Feb. 13, 22, Mar. 5, 7, May 6, 7, June 7, 18, Sept. 11, Oct. 4, Nov. 2; 1783, Feb. 4, 25; Mar. 17, Oct. 11; 1784, Feb. 3; 1785, Feb. 28, Mar. 17; 1786, June 27, July 5; 1787, Feb. 26, Mar. 7, July 7; 1790, Feb. 25, 26, Mar. 9; 1791, Feb. 24. See also Kil- ham V. Ward et al., 2 Mass. 240, 251 ; also. Proceedings of the Massachusetts Historical Society, for 1893, p. 231 ; also Story's Commentaries, § 1367. Further testi- mony will be found in a speech by Roger Sherman in his contemporary essays on the Constitution ; Moore's History of North Carolina ; Jeremiah Mason's Memories ; Plumer's Life of Wm. Plumer; various judicial his- tories of Rhode Island, where the practice continued till 1842. The published Index to Rhode Island legislation MARBURY V. MADISON 71 to 1842 is immensely instructive in this connection. For the case of Pa., see Roscoe Pound in 14 Col. Law Rev. 8 (footnote), citing Debates of Pa. Const'l Conv. (1873) III, s-20. See also such cases as Rep. v. Buffington, 1 Dall. 61 ; Calder v. Bull, 3 Dall. 386 ; Watson v. Mercer, 8 Pet. 88; Satterlee v. Matthewson, 2 Pet. 380; Wilkin- son v. Leland, ib. 657. The overturn of this practice through a new interpretation of the principle of the separation of powers is traced infra. See also my article on the Doctrine of Vested Rights in 12 Mich. Law Rev. 247-276. V — Alleged Precedents for Judicial Review, antedat- ing the Convention of 1787: The earliest "precedent" . claimed for judicial review is the Va. case of Josiah I Philips (1778), but the claim is without any basis in fact. The origin of the claim is to be found in the following passage on page 293 of the appendix to the first volume of Tucker's Blackstone (1803) : "In May 1778, an act passed in Va. to attaint one Josiah Philips unless he should render himself to justice within a limited time. He was taken after the time expired, and was brought before the general court to receive sentence of execution pursuant to the direction of the act. But the court refused to pass the sentence and he was put upon his trial according to the ordinary course of law. This is a decisive proof of the importance of the separation of the powers of government and of the independence of the judiciary. A dependent judiciary might have exe- cuted the law whilst they execrated the principles upon which it was founded." Tucker, a zealous champion of judicial review, is here seeking to create a precedent out of hand. The myda is elaborated in an ingenious series of conjectures byj Professor W. P. Trent in the Am. Hist'l Rev. I, 444K'g. The recollection in the Va. rati- fying convention ^eems to have been that Philips was executed under the attainder: Elliot III, 66-7, 140, 298-9. This however is wrong. In a letter to Wm. Wirt of Aug. 15, 1815, Jefferson says: "I remember the case, and took my part in it. Philips was a mere robber, who availing himself of the troubles of the times, collected a banditti, retired to the Dismal Swamp, and from thence 72 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW sallied forth, plundering and maltreating the neighbor- ing inhabitants, and covering himself, without authority, under the name of a British subject. Mr. Henry, then governor, communicated the case to me. We both thought the best proceeding would be by bill of attainder, unless he deHvered himself up for trial within a given time. Philips was afterwards taken; and Mr. Randolph being Attorney General and apprehending he would plead that he was a British subject, taken in arms in support of his lawful sovereign, and as a prisoner of war entitled to the protection of the law of nations, he thought the safest proceeding would be to indict him as a felon and a robber. Against this, I believe. Philips urged the same plea; but was overruled and found guilty." This letter was communicated to me from the Jefferson MSS. by my friend Mr. W. S. Carpenter, but it or letters to the same effect will be found in Jeffer- son's published works. In his article entitled A Phantom Precedent, 48 Am. Law Rev. 321-44, Mr. Jesse Turner also brings forward strong evidence to show that, con- trary to Tucker's statement that Philips "was taken after the time [set by the act] expired," he was taken before that time. Certainly it is a strange idea that a court would, in 1778, have pronounced a bill of attainder un- constitutional when every legislature in the country was passing such acts, and especially in view of the fact that as late as 1800 the Supreme Court of the U. S. itself held that to pass such acts was within legislative power: 4 Dall. 13. — The second "precedent" brought forward for judicial review before the convention of 1787 is the N. J. case of Holmes v. Walton (1780): Austin Scott in Am. Hist'l Rev. IV, 456 ffg. The case dealt with the question of trial by jury and affords a clear instance of the court's refusing to carry out the will of the legislature on the ground that it transgressed the constitution. The attitude of the court drew forth much unfavorable comment, and though the legislature amended the objectionable act, it met the views of the court only in part. The case is referred to by Gouver- neur Morris of Pa. five years later. He did not however, he said, want the judges in Pa. to exercise any such MARBURY V. MADISON 73 power: Sparks, Life of Gouverneur Morris, III, 438. C. J. Brearley of the N. J. court that decided Holmes v. Walton was a member of the Convention of 1787. — The third "precedent," the Va. case of Com. v. Caton, 4 Call 5 (1782), is brought forward merely for its dicta. Chan- cellor Wythe and Judge Blair both asserted the right of the court to resist an unconstitutional act of the legisla- ture, on semi-revolutionary grounds. C. J. Pendleton was doubtful ; see note 54, supra. Wythe and Blair were both members of the Convention of 1787 and Blair was one of the first bench of the Supreme Court of the U. S. — The fourth "precedent," a municipal court easel from N. Y. City (1783) called Rutgers v. Waddington, is urged with even less justification than the Philips case. It was a marked triumph for the notion of legislative sovereignty: see my article in 9 Mich. Law Rev. 115-16. — The fifth "precedent" is from Conn., the Symsbury Case: Kirby, 444 iJg. (1785). In this case a legislative act making a land grdnt was given a restricted construc- tion so as to prevent its invading a previous grant. The court invoked fundamental principles, and altogether the case |may be regarded as a somewhat bold application of Coke's dictumj The decision of the court stood — if it stood — only because the legislature did not choose to review it: cf. Calder v. Bull, 3 Dall. 386. — The sixth "precedent," from N. H., is vouched for by Mr. Meigs in 47 Am. Law Rev., 684, on the strength of the follow- ing passage from Plumer's Life of William Plumer (P- 59) '■ "I entered my protest singly and alone against the bill for the recovery of small debts in an expeditious way and manner, principally on the ground that it was unconstitutional. The courts so pronounced it, and the succeeding legislature repealed the law." These words were apparently written by Plumer himself of the year 1785 or 1786, but several years later. If this is the case referred to by Jeremiah Mason in his Memoirs (p. 26), its claim to be considered a true case of judicial review is very doubtful. I strongly suspect that this is an- other instance of precedents made to order. For a true case of judicial review in N. H. in 1791, invoking the principle of the separation of powers, see Professor 74 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW W. F. Dodd in Am. Hist'l Rev. XII, 348-50.— The seventh "precedent" is offered on the strength of a let- ter by one Cutting to Jefferson in 1788, in which it is asserted that the Mass. court had recently declared an act of the legislature unconstitutional and that the legis- lature had in consequence repealed the act. A thorough search however fails to reveal any such case or act of repeal: A. C. Goddell, 7 Harv. Law Rev. 415 ffg. The case was probably one in which the court had ruled the act of the legislature involved to be repugnant to the treaty of 1783 with Great Britain. The Mass. legislature had repealed all such acts April 20, 1787, by gen- eral description, in conformity with the demand of Con- gress: See my National Supremacy, ch. Ill (1913). The only question for the court, therefore, was whether the act before it had been repealed or not. — The eighth "precedent" is the R. I. case of Trevett v. Weeden, al- ready referred to. In this case, as Coxe points out, the statute was "repelled," but on the ground allowed by Blackstone, that it was self-contradictory and impossi- ble to be performed, since it required that those violating it be tried nnthout a jury but in accordance with the "Law of the Land." (Nonetheless the case passed as a true constitutional case and met with wide-spread ap- proval: McMaster, History, I, 338 ffg. It is clearly the case that was foremost in the minds of the members of the Convention of 1787 at the opening of the Con- vention. Far more important than the opinions of the judges was Varnum's argument for defendant, in which' the written constitution is thrown about certain funda-l mental principles of the Common Law and the line is drawn between "legislative" and "judicial" power. To the former alone, Varnum contends, belongs the power of amending or altering the laws, to the latter "the sole power of judging^ of the laws" : see the excerpt from the argument in Haines, p. 90. The argument is given in extenso in Coxe. — Finally reference should be made to the early case of Winthrop v. Lechmere in which, in 1727, the British Privy Coucil "held that an act of the colony of Conn, relating to the division of the property of an intestate among his children was 'null and void MARBURY V. MADISON 75 as being contrary to the law of the realm, unreasonable, and against the tenor of their character, and conse- quently the province had no power to make such a law' " : Haines, p. 65. Professor Thayer urges truly that this decree was a judicial decree: Cases on Constitu- tional Law, 39-40. It was argued before the Council as a case at law: see C. M. Andrews in Select Essays in Anglo-Am. Legal Hist., I, 445. But this fact does not make it a precedent for judicial review. The provincial legislatures were in law mere corporations possessed of the powers of legislation of municipal councils. Such bodies to this day, as a general proposition, must not exer- cise their powers "unreasonably" nor to the transgression of the Common Law : see the following Mass. cases : 3 Pick. 462, 6 ib. 187, 1 1 ib. 168, 16 ib. 121. The problem of judicial review arises, however, in the first instance, be- cause the legislature was supposed to possess supreme judicial powers, but latterly because of the attribution to the legislature of sovereignty. The application of the idea of sovereignty to the State legislatures creates an absolutely impossible gulf between such alleged prece- dents as Winthrop v. Leckmere and the institution of judicial review in the U. S. Moreover, these cases are never referred to by those who developed the argument for judicial review. VI — -The Establishment of Judicial Review in the States : By 1803, the following States had either been definitely committed to the doctrine of judicial review by judicial decision or practically so by judicial dicta : North Carolina (1787), New Hampshire (1791), South Caro- lina (1792), Virginia (1788, 1793), Pennsylvania (1793, 1799), New Jersey (1796), Kentucky (1801), Maryland (1802). The Kentucky Constitution of 1792, Art. XII, p. 28, says : "All laws contrary ... to this Constitution shall be void." Prof. Thayer, in his study in 7 Har- vard Law Rev., 129 ffg., contended that this article specifically authorized judicial review; but the Pennsyl- vania constitution of 1776 and the Massachusetts consti- tution of 1780 contained equivalent provisions without producing judicial review. Of interest in this connection is the opinion of the judges of the Pa. Supreme Court, of 76 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW Dec. 22, 1790, to Gov. Mifflin holding that certain offices had been vacated by the new constitution. The ground of the opinion is indicated by the ffg. words: "We think the constitution to be paramount [to] the acts of the legislature": Pa. Archives, ist Ser., XII, 36. In Pa. however, because of the persistence of the power of the legislature in the matter of private bill legislation, judicial review continued on a precarious basis till a late date. In Emerick v. Harris, i Binn. 418 ffg. (1809), though reference is made to Marshall's argument in Marbury v. Madison, the court's reliance seems to be chiefly on the duty of the -judge by his oath of office and the equality of the judiciary with the other departments, both of which arguments, as we saw above, are quite inadequate. In his famous dissent in Bakin V. Raub, 12 S. and R. 330 ffg. (1825), Justice Gibson (later chief justice), defining the constitution as an act of "extraordinary legislation", and contending that the courts had under it only their Common Law powers of administering the ordinary law, rejected judicial re- view as "a professional dogma," held "rather as a mat- ter of faith than of reason." The power of keeping the legislature within its constitutional bounds, he contended, belonged to the People, its authors. Subsequently as chief justice, Gibson changed his opinion "from exper- ience of the necessity of the case" : Harris v. Clymer, 2 Barr (Pa.) 277, 281. In N. Y., where judicial review was destined to receive its final form, the first judicial claim to the power was made in Dash v. Van Kleeck, 7 Johns. 477 fiEg. (181 1). In Gardner v. Newburgh, 2 Johns. Ch. 162 ffg., five years later, Kent enjoined the enforcement of an act of the legislature on the ground of its invalidity. For the persistence of the idea of judicial review on the basis of fundamental law, apart from the written constitution, see my article in 12 Mich. Law Rev. 247 ffg. ; also, C. J. Chase in the License Tax Cases, 5 Wall. 469. The first R. I. case under the con- stitution of 1842, Taylor v. Place, 4 R. I. 339, states the doctrine of the separation of powers at length. An in- teresting Mass. case showing the effect of the doctrine of departmental equality upon judicial logic is that of MARBURY V. MADISON ^^ Wellington et al., Petitioners, i6 Pick. 87 (1834). Here we find C. J. Shaw, after first stating the correct doctrine of judicial review as flowing from the nature of judicial power in relation to the standing law, then introducing the notion of three coordinate departments, whereupon he proceeds as follows (p. 96) : "Perhaps ... it may well be doubted whether a formal act of legislation can ever, with strict legal propriety, be said to be void; it seems more consistent with the nature of the subject ... to treat it 'as voidable'." In 24 Pick. 352 (1837), he abandons this refinement. The history of judicial re- view in the States may be, generally speaking, divided into the following periods: 1-1780-87, its tentative sug- gestion; 2-1787-1800, its rapid advance, under Federal- istic influence; 3-1800-1810, its temporary check, under Jefifersonian influence; 4-1810-1825, its more aggressive exercise, under the influence of Marshall and Kent and of the doctrine of "vested rights"; 5-1825-45, its general recognition, but rare use, on account of the influence of the Jacksonian Democracy and the rise of the notion of the "police power"; 6-1845-1857, a period of diversity, rise of new doctrines of Constitutional Law, conserva- tism of the N. Y. courts in sharp contrast at the close of the period to more democratic tendencies in many other States, protests against "judicial despotism" from certain courts brought to a climax in criticism of the Dred Scott decision; 7-1857-1890, judicial review generally used very moderately, under the influence of the doctrine of the "police power" as developed by the U. S. Sup. Ct. ; 8-1890-1910, a tremendous expansion of judicial review in all jurisdictions, under the influence of the modern definitions of "liberty," "property," and "due process of law"; to-day, reaction in favor of legislative discretion, under the leadership of the U. S. Sup. Ct. Throughout, the practice of judicial review in two States, New York and Massachusetts, has been of leading importance from the point of view of the history of Constitutional Law, but the North Carolina, Tennessee, New Hampshire, Vermont, Pennsylvania, Illinois, and Iowa courts have also made influential contributions from time to time. It may be safely said, I think, that more statutes were 78 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW invalidated in New York before the Civil War than in any two other States together. On the other hand, in Virginia, where judicial review was at first so strongly asserted, only two acts of the legislature were pro- nounced void by the court of appeals between 1793 and i860, and one of these had been repealed some years earlier. During the same period, however, about twenty- five cases were brought before that court in which the constitutional question was raised. "WE, THE PEOPLE "WE, THE PEOPLE" In the Webster-Hayne debate the South Carolinian set out from the following premises, taken from the Kentucky Resolutions of 1798: "Resolved that the several States comprising the United States of America ... by a compact under the style and title of a Constitution for the United States and of amendments thereto . . . constituted a general government for specific purposes, reserving each State to itself the residuary mass of right to its own self- government . . .; that to this compact each State ac- ceded as a State . . . ; that as in all other cases of compact among parties having no common judge, each party has an equal right to judge for itself, as well of in- fractions as of the measures of redress."^ This position Webster met with the contention that the Constitution is not a- compact among States but, 'Writings of Thomas Jefferson (Ford Ed.) VII, 289. The third of the Va. resolutions of the same year reads as follows : "Resolved . . that this assembly doth explicitly and peremp- torily declare that it views the powers of the Federal govern- ment as resulting from the compact to which the States are parties . . and that in case of a deliberate, palpable, and dan- gerous exercise [by the Federal government] of . . . powers not granted by the said compact, the States who are parties thereto, have the right and are in duty bound to interpose for arresting the progress of the evil and for maintaining within their re- spective limits, the authorities, rights and liberties appertaining to them": Writings of James Madison (Hunt lEd.) VI, 326. Note that Madison does not say that the States are the parties (i. e. the only parties) to the compact, but simply that they are ■'parties." This ambiguous position, however, he abandons in his Report of 1799- 81 82 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW by its own declaration, a law ordained by the people. But, rejoined Calhoun, by what people ? and answered : The people of the several States, acting as so many sovereign political communities, since in the first place, it is only a sovereign political community that can enact law and since, in the second place, the States were in 1787 the only sovereign political communi- ties on the continent. The Constitution is then, he proceeded, law within the several States by their own ordination, and may be repealed by them at any time, since sovereignty is inalienable. But even before this position was completely thought out. Story had argued in his Commentaries that the language of the Preamble of the Constitution was to be taken literally, and that the Constitution was ordained and estab- lished, not by the people of the several States, but by the people of the United States, acting as one people, though within the several States. In his first Inaugu- ral Lincoln adopted this argument and contended fur- ther that, far from the States being the only political communities at hand in 1787, the Union was older than the States. The great historical difficulty in the way of Cal- houn's theory of the nature of the Union and the Con- stitution, once at any rate it is indicated, is obvious enough. It consists in the inversion it effects of the relation between governments and people that is stated by the Declaration of Independence, that all just gov- ernments rest on the consent of the governed. Even Calhoun admitted, what indeed would have been undeniable by the hardiest theorizer, that the govern- "WE, THE PEOPLE" 83 ment of the United States is a government over in- dividuals.- Yet he contended that this government did not rest upon the consent of these individuals, but was foisted upon them by the several States. True, the Articles of Confederation rested upon the consent of the States merely, but then, that was not a govern- ment over individuals. And the difficulty in question is certainly not lessened by the dogma that inalienable sovereignty was in 1787 a property of the States as political entities. For either this dogma assumes to interpose an absolute veto upon the right of the people to revolutionize their governments or it does not. If ' The following is an excellent statement of this principle by Ellsworth in the Connecticut convention : "We see how neces- sary for union is a coercive principle. No man pretends to the contrary : We all feel and see this necessity. The only question is, shall it be a coercion of law or a coercion of arms? There is no other possible alternative. Where will those who oppose a coercion of law come out? Where will they end? A neces- sary consequence of their principles is a war of the States one against the other. I am for coercion by law, — that coercion which acts only upon delinquent individuals. This Constitution does not attempt to coerce our sovereign bodies. States, in their political capacity. No coercion is applicable to such bodies but that of an armed force. . . But this legal coercion singles out the guilty individual and punishes him for breaking the law of the Union" : Elliot, II, 197 (The edition used in preparing this article is the Phila. edition of 1881). Ellsworth, however, some- what exaggerates the immunity of the States from direct con- trol by the National Government. As Madison points out in Federalist No. 39, "In several cases . . . they must be viewed and proceeded against in their collective political capacities only": pp. 237-8 (Lodge's Ed.). The contrast between the Con- federation as a government over States in their corporate capacities and the government proposed by the Constitution as one over individuals is made with great effect by Hamilton in Fed. No. IS- 84 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW it does not, however, then the theory of which the dogma just recited is an essential part does not effec- tively contradict the contention that the establishment of the Constitution of 1787 was an act of popular revolution; while if it does, it absolutely contradicts the most fundamental article of the political creed upon which all American governments are founded. The truth is that, in the estimation of the men of 1787, the establishment of the Constitution was an act of popular revolution, which not only overturned the Articles of Confederation, but broke through the State constitutions also at essential points. The con- ventions that ratified the Constitution of 1787 were in no case provided for by the existing State consti- tutions. In some cases indeed these constitutions for- bade their alteration or amendment for stated terms of years. But the adoption of the Constitution of 1787 did nevertheless alter every one of these instru- ments of government in the most radical fashion.^ ' Note the following passage from the debate of Aug. 31, in the Convention, touching the method of ratification : "Madi- son : . . . The people were in fact the fountain of all power, and by resorting to them all difficulties were got over . . . Mr. King observed that the constitution of Mass. was made un- alterable till the year 1790, yet this was no difficulty with him. The State must have contemplated a recurrence to first prin- ciples before they sent deputies to this Convention" : Farrand, II, 476-7. See also Madison's words on the floor of the Convention June 19: "A majority would have the right to bind the rest, and even to form a new Constitution for the whole." This idea was brought forward to meet the argument that the Con- vention had no right to cast the Arts, of Confed. aside, since they comprised a social compact among the States. But the idea itself plainly represents Madison's own theory of the rights of individuals under the social compact. Note also Wil- "WE, THE PEOPLE" 85 All this, however, is but introductory. The main purpose of this article is to set forth the most import- ant evidence bearing on the question of the historical validity of the venerable antithesis: The People of the United States vs. the People of the States. This evidence falls into two parts : that drawn from dis- cussions in the State ratifying conventions of the opening phrase of the Constitution, and therefore immediately antedating the establishment of the Con- stitution; and that drawn from the congressional de- bates of 1789 on certain propositions of amendment to the Constitution, and therefore immediately sub- sequent to the establishment of the Constitution. It will be best, I think, to give this evidence first and then the conclusions which it suggests afterward. I — The evidence from the ratifying conventions, then, is as follows : King in the Massachusetts convention: "The intro- duction to this Constitution is in these words : 'We, the people' etc. The language of the Confederation is, 'We, the States' etc. The latter is a mere federal govern- ment of States. Those therefore that assemble under it have no power to make laws to apply to the individuals of the States confederated."* son's words on the floor of the Convention, Aug. 30: "We must, in this 'Case [that is the ratification of the Constitution], go to the original powers of society. The house on fire must be extinguished without a scrupulous regard to ordinary rights" : Farrand, II, 468-9. But see especially the Federalist, Nos. 40, 43, and 45, quoted infra. * Elliot, II, SS. Note that the contrast is between States and People, and that nothing is made of the phrase "of the United States." The same rule holds for the ensuing quotations. I may add here that the evidence given in the text is, to my belief, substantially complete for the State conventions on the subject discussed. 86 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW Wilson in tlie Pennsylvania convention: "In this Constitution all authority is derived from the people. . . . The leading principle in politics and that which pervades the American constitutions is that the supreme power resides in the people. This Constitution . . . opens with a solemn and practical recognition of that principle : 'We the people of the United States, in order etc. do ordain and establish this Constitution for the United States of America'. It is announced in their name — it receives its political existence from their authority. . . . What is the necessary consequence? Those who ordain and establish have the power, if they think proper, to repeal and annul. "= And again : "The secret is now disclosed, and it is discovered to be a dread that the boasted State sover- eignties will, under this system, be disrobed of part of their power. . . . Upon what principle is it contended that the sovereign power resides in the State govern- ments? The honorable gentleman has said truly that there can be no subordinate sovereignty. Now if there cannot, my position is, that the sovereignty resides in the people; they have not parted with it; they have only dispensed with such portions of power as were conceived necessary for the public welfare. This Con- stitution stands upon this broad principle. I know very well, sir, that the people have hitherto been shut out of the Federal Government, but it is not meant that they should any longer be dispossessed of their rights. In order to recognize this leading principle, the proposed system sets out with the declaration that its existence depends upon the supreme authority of the people alone. . . When the principle is once settled that the people are the source of authority, the consequence is, that they may take from the subordinate governments powers with which they have hitherto trusted them and placed those powers in the General Government, if it is thought that there they will be productive of good. They can distribute one portion of power to the more contracted circle called State governments. They can 'lb. 434-S. "WE, THE PEOPLE" 87 furnish another proportion to the government of the United States."" And again: "The truth is that the supreme, absolute, and uncontrollable authority remains with the people. . . . His [Findley's] position is, that the supreme power resides in the States, as governments; and mine is, that it resides in the people, as the fountain of government. ... I consider the people of the United States as form- ing one great community; and I consider the people of the different States as forming communities again on a lesser scale. . . . Unless the people are considered in these two views, we shall never be able tO' understand the principle on which this system was constructed. I view the States as made for the people, as well as by them, and not the people as made for the States. The people therefore have a right, whilst enjoying the un- deniable powers of society, to form either a general government or State governments, in what manner they please, or to accommodate, them to one another and by this means preserve them all. . . . 'Governments are in- stituted among men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed.' '"' And again: "There can be no compact unless there are more parties than one. . . . 'The Convention were forming compacts!' With whom? ... I am unable to conceive who the parties could be. The State govern- ments make a bargain with one another; that is the doctrine that is endeavored to be established by gentle- men in opposition; their State sovereignties wish to be represented ! But far other were the ideas of this Con- vention, and far other are those conveyed in the sys- tem itself."' Henry in the Virginia convention: "What right had °Ib. 443-4. Note the equivalent use of the terms States and governments. Compare Hamilton in Fed. No. 1$: "The great and radical vice in the construction of the existing confedera- tion is in the principle of legislation for States or governments^ in their corporate or collective capacities": p. 86 (Lodge). ' Loc. cit. AZ6-7. 'lb. A97- 88 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW they to say 'We the people' . . . instead of 'We the States'? States are the characteristic and soul of a confederation. If the States be not the agents of this compact it must be one great consolidated, national gov- ernment of the people of all the States. . . . The people gave them no power to use their name. That they ex- ceeded their power is perfectly clear. "^ And again: "Have they said, We the States? ... If they had, this would be a confederation. It is other- wise, most clearly, a consolidated government. The question turns, sir, on a poor little thing, — the expres- sion, We the people, instead of the States of America. . . . Here is a resolution as radical as that which sepa- rated us from Great Britain."^" Randolph in the Virginia convention : "The gentle- man then proceeds and inquires why we assumed the language of 'We the people'? I ask, why not? The government is for the people ; and the misfortune was that the people had no agency in the government before."" Pendleton in the Virginia convention : "We the people, possessing all power, form a government, such as we think will secure happiness. . . . But an objection is made to the form : the expression. We the people, IS thought improper. Permit me to ask the gentleman who made this objection, who but the people can dele- gate powers? Who but the people have a right to form government? ... If the objection be, that the Union ought to be not of the people, but of the State govern- ments, then I think the choice of the former very happy and proper. "^^ Lee of Westmoreland in the Virginia convention : "He [Henry] then adverted to the style of the govern- ment and asked what authority they had to use the ex- " Elliot, III, 22-3. Note that Heniry, who was opposing adoption, does not find fault with "We, the People of the U. S." but with "We, the People." '"lb- 44. "/&. 28. "/6. 35. "WE, THE PEOPLE" 89 pression 'We the people,' and not. We the States. This expression was introduced into that paper with great propriety. This system is submitted to the people for their consideration, because on them it is to operate, if adopted. ... It is now submitted to the people of Vir- ginia. . . . Suppose it was found proper for our adop- tion, and becoming the government of the people of Vir- ginia, by what style should it be done?"^' Madison in the Virginia convention: "Who are the parties to it? The people — but not the people as com- posing one great body; but the people as composmg thirteen sovereignties. Were it, as the gentleman as- serts, a consolidated government, the assent of a ma- jority of the people would be sufficient for its establishment. . . . But, sir, no State is bound by it, as it is, without its own consent. Should all the States adopt it, it will be then a government established by the thirteen States of America, not through the intervention of the legislatures, but by the people at large. . . . The existing system has been derived from the dependent, derivative, authority of the legislatures of the States; whereas this is derived fi'om the superior power of the people."^* Corbin in the Virginia convention: "I expected no such objection as this. Ought not the people, sir, to judge of that government whereby they are to be ruled ?"^^ Iredell in the North Carolina convention: The Con- stitution is not a compact between the rulers and the ruled. This principle is inapplicable "to a government where the people are avowedly the fountain of all power.''^" Caldwell in the North Carolina convention: "Mr. Chairman, if they mean. We the people, — the people at "/&. 42. "7&. 94- "J&. 104. ^"Elliot, IV, II. A little later, Iredell added: "We, People, was not to be applied to the members themselves [of the Phila. convention], but was to be the style of the Constitution when it should be ratified in their respective States" : *. 23. go DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW large, — I conceive the expression is improper. Were they who framed this Constitution the representatives of the legislatures of the different States? In my opin- ion, they had no power, from the people at large, to use their name, or to act for them. They were not delegated for that purpose."^^ Maclaine in the North Carolina convention: "The reverend gentleman has told us that the expression. We the people, is wrong, because the gentlemen who framed it were not the representatives of the people. I readily grant that they were delegated by States. But they did not think that they were the people, but intended it for the people at a future day. The sanction of the State legislature was in some degree necessary. It was to be submitted by the legislatures to the people ; so that when it is adapted, it is the act of the people. When it is the act of the people, their name is certainly proper. This is very obvious and plain to any capacity."^^ Spencer in the North Carolina convention: "The States do not act in their political capacities, but the government is proposed for individuals. The very cap- tion of the Constitution shows that this is the case. The expression. We the people of the United States, shows that this government is intended for individuals."^" Luther Martin in his Genuine Information : "It is, in its very introduction, declared to be a compact between the people of the United States, as individuals ; and it is to be ratified by the people at large in their capacity as individuals; all which . . . would be quite right and proper if there were no State governments, if all the people of this continent were in a state of nature, and we were forming one national government for them as individuals; and is nearly the same as was done in most of the States when they formed their governments over the people who composed them,"^° Hamilton in Federalist 22 : "It has not a little con- tributed to the infirmities of the existing federal system, '"lb. 15-6. Caldwell opposed adoption. "76. 16. "76. 153. Spencer opposed adoption. ""§30: Farrand, Til, 193. The emphasis is ftom the original. "WE, THE PEOPLE" gi that it never had a ratification by the people. Resting on no better foundation than the consent of the several legislatures, it has been exposed to frequent and intricate questions concerning the vaHdity of its powers, and has, in some instances, given birth to the enormous doctrine of a right of legislative repeal. Owing its ratification to the law of a State, it has been contended that the same authority might repeal the law by which it was ratified. However gross a heresy it may be to maintain that a party to a compact has a right to revoke that compact, the doctrine itself has had respectable advocates. The possibility of a question of this nature proves the ne- cessity of laying the foundations of our national govern- ment deeper than in the mere sanction of delegated authority. The fabric of American empire ought to rest on the solid basis of THE CONSENT OF THE PEOPLE. The streams of national power ought to flow immediately from that pure, original fountain of all legitimate authority. "^^ Madison in Federalist 39: "It appears', on one hand, that the Constitution is to be founded on the assent and ratification of the people of America, given by deputies elected for the special purpose; but, on the other, that this assent and ratification is to be given by the people, not as individuals composing one entire nation, but as composing the distinct and independent States to which they respectively belong. It is to be the assent and ratification of the several States, derived from the su- preme authority in each State, — the authority of the people themselves. The act, therefore, establishing the Constitution, will not be a national, but a federal act. Were the people regarded in this transaction as forming one nation, the will of the majority of the whole people of the United States would bind the mi- nority, in the same manner as the majority in each State must bind the minority; and the will of the majority must be determined either by a comparison of the in- dividual votes, or by considering the will of the ma- jority of the States as evidence of the will of a "Lodge's edition is used. This and the following .passages will be found on pp. I3S, 236, 241-2, 246, 275-6. 92 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW majority of the people of the United States. Neither of these rules has been adopted. Each State, in ratifying the Constitution, is considered as a sovereign body, in- dependent of all others, and only ta be bound by its own voluntary act. In this relation, then, the new Constitu- tion will, if established, be a federal, and not a national constitution."^^ Same in Federalist 40: "Let the most scrupulous expositors of delegated powers . . . declare, whether it was of most importance to the happiness of the people of America, that the articles of Confederation should be disregarded, and an adequate government be provided, and the Union preserved ; or that an adequate govern- ment should be omitted, and the articles of Confeder- ation preserved. . . " (On the other hand) "let us view the ground on which the Convention stood. . . . They must have reflected, that in all great changes of established governments, forms ought to give way to substance ; that a rigid adherence in such cases to the former, would render nominal and nugatory the tran- scendent and precious right of the people to 'abolish or alter their governments as to them shall seem most likely to effect their safety and happiness'." Same in Federalist 43 : " 'The ratification of the conventions of nine States shall be sufficient for the establishment of this Constitution between the States, ratifying the same.' This article speaks for itself. The ^/6. p. 236. The advocates of State rights have sometimes ventured to quote portions of this passage in support of their thesis. A careful examination of the terms used however shows that Madison has it in mind to emphasize two points : I — that the existing States are recognized to the extent that the Constitution, by its own specific provision, is to go into effect only in those whose people ratify it; 2 — that in the States ratifying it, it will be the act of the people, acting as individuals. Also, the State rights advocates do not attempt to reconcile their interpretation of Fed. No. 39 with the further language used by Madison in Fed. Nos. 40, 43, and 45, quoted infya. See also the passage quoted infra, from his Report of 1799- "WE, THE PEOPLE" 93 express authority of the people alone could give due validity to the Constitution. To have required the unanimous ratification of the thirteen States, would have subjected the essential interests of the whole to the caprice or corruption of a single member. It would have marked a want of foresight in the Convention, which our own experience would have rendered inex- cusable. Two questions of a very delicate nature present themselves on this occasion: i. On what principle the Confederation, which stands in the solemn form of a compact among the States, can be superseded without the unanimous consent of the parties to it ? 2. What re- lation is to subsist between the nine or more States rati- fying the Constitution, and the remaining few who do not become parties to it? The first question is answered at once by recurring to the absolute necessity of the case ; to the great principle of self-preservation ; to the transcendent law of nature and of nature's God, which declares that the safety and happiness of society are the objects at which all political institutions aim, and to which all such institutions must be sacrificed." II — The evidence drawn from the proceedings in Congress in 1789, on the proposed amendments, falls into four groups: i — Speeches made on Sherman's motion, which was eventually adopted, not to incorpo- rate the proposed amendments in the Constitution, as had been intended by the committee that formulated them, but to append them to it as separate and dis- tinct articles; 2 — Speeches made on a proposition, which was eventually lost, to insert in the Preamble of the Constitution a formal declaration of the prin- ciple that "governments rest on the consent of the governed"; 3 — Speeches made on a proposed amend- ment, which was also lost, asserting the right of the people to instruct their representatives in Congress; 4 — The Tenth Amendment. In no case, of course, are 94 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW the speeches quoted below given for their discussion of the topics immediately in debate, but for the light they shed upon the historicity of the, today, current antithesis between "People of the United States" and "People of the States." I — From the debate on Sherman's motion: "Mr. Sherman : If I had looked upon this question as mere matter of form, I should not have brought it for- ward or troubled the committee with such a lengthy dis- cussion. But, sir, I contend that amendments made in the way proposed by the committee are void. ... I would desire gentlemen to consider the authorities upon which the two constitutions are to stand. The original was established by the people at large, by conventions chosen by them for the express purpose. The preamble to the Constitution declares the act : but will it be a truth in ratifying the next constitution, which is to be done perhaps by the State Legislatures, and not conventions chosen for the purpose? Will gentlemen say it is "We the people" in this case? Certainly they cannot; for, by the present Constitution, we, nor all the legislatures in the Union together, do not possess the power of re- pealing it. All that is granted us by the Fifth Article is, that whenever we shall think it necessary, we may pro- pose amendments to the Constitution ; not' that we may propose to repeal the old, and substitute a new one."-^ "Mr. Gerry: The honorable gentleman from Con- necticut, if I understand him right, says that the words 'We the people' cannot be retained, if Congress should propose amendments, and they be ratified by the State legislatures. Now, if this is a fact, we ought most un- doubtedly to adopt his motion; because if we do not, we cannot obtain any amendment whatever. But upon what ground does the gentleman's position stand? The Con- stitution of the United States was proposed by a Conven- tion met at Philadelphia; but, with all its importance, it ^Annals of Cong., I, col. 742. For the entire proceedings on the motion, see ib., cols. 734-44, 795. "WE, THE PEOPLE" 95 did not possess as high authority as the President, Sen- ate, and House of Representatives of the Union. For that Convention was not convened in consequence of any express will of the people, but an implied one, through their members in the State legislatures. The Consti- tution derived no authority from the first Convention; it was concurred in by conventions of the people, and that concurrence armed it with power and invested it with dignity. Now the Congress of the United States are expressly authorized by the sovereign and uncon- trollable voice of the people, to propose amendments whenever two-thirds of both Houses shall think fit. Now, if this is the fact, the propositions of amendment will be found to originate with a higher authority than the original system. The conventions of the States, re- spectively, have agreed for the people, that the State legislatures shall be authorized to decide upon these amendments in the manner of a convention. If these acts of the State legislatures are not good, because they are not specifically instructed by their constituents, neither were the acts calling the first and subsequent conventions."^* 2 — From the debate on the proposed amendment to the Preamble : "Mr. Tucker replied, that the words 'We the people do ordain and establish this constitution for the United States of America,' were a declaration of their action ; this being performed. Congress have nothing to do with it. Bttt if it was necessary to retain the principle, it might come in at some other place."-' "Mr. Page thought the Preamble no part of the Con- stitution ; but if it was, it stood in no need of amend- ment; the words 'We the people,' had the neatness and simplicity, while its expression was the most forcible of any he had ever seen prefixed to any constitution. He did not doubt the truth of the proposition brought for- ""/&. cols. 743-4- ■'lb. col. 74S- 96 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW ward by the committee, but he doubted its necessity in this place."^'* "Mr. Madison: If it be a truth, and so self-evident that it cannot be denied ; if it be recognised, as is the fact in many of the State constitutions ; and if it be desired by three important States, to be added to this, I think they must collectively offer a strong inducement to the mind desirous of promoting harmony, to acquiesce with the report; at least, some strong arguments should be brought forward to show the reason why it is improper."^" "Mr. Sherman thought they ought not to come in in this place. The People of the United States have given their reasons for doing a certain act. Here we propose to come in and give them a right to do what they did on motives which appeared to them sufficient to warrant their determination; to let them know that they had a right to exercise a natural and inherent privilege, which they have asserted in a solemn ordination and establish- ment of the Constitution. Now, if this right is indefeas- ible, and the people have recognised it in practice, the truth is better asserted than it can be by any words what- ever. The words "We the people" in the original Con- stitution, are as copious and expressive as possible ; any addition will only drag out the sentence without illumi- nating it ; for these reasons, it may be hoped the com- mittee will reject the proposed amendment."^" 3 — From the debate on the proposed amendment asserting the right of instruction : "Mr. Gerry : . . . The friends and patrons of this Constitution have always declared that the sovereignty resides in the people, and that they do not part with it on any occasion; to say the sovereignty vests in the people, and that they have not a right to instruct and control their representatives, is absurd to the last degree. . . ."^^ ="/&. col. 746. "/6. col. 765. The entire debate on the subject runs from col. 761 to 776. The motion was rejected by a vote of 41 to 10. "WE, THE PEOPLE" 97 "Mr. Madison: . . . The honorable gentleman from Massachusetts asks if the soivereignty is not with the people at large. Does he infer that the people can, in detached bodies, contravene an act established by the whole people ? My idea of the sovereignty of the people is, that the people can change the Constitution if they please ; but while the Constitution exists, they must con- form themselves to its dictates. But I do not believe that the inhabitants of any district can speak the voice of the people; so far from it, their ideas may contradict the sense of the whole people; hence the consequence that instructions are binding on the representative is of a doubtful, if not of a dangerous nature. I do not con- ceive, therefore, that it is necessary to agree to the prop- osition now made; so far as any real good is to arise from it, so far that real good is provided for; so far as it is of a doubtful nature, so far it obliges us to run the risk of losing the whole system. . . ."-* "Mr. Livermore was not very anxious whether the words were inserted or not, but he had a great deal of doubt on the meaning of this whole amendment; it pro- vides that the people may meet and consult for the com- mon good. Does this mean a part of the people in a township or district, or does it mean the representatives in the State legislatures? If it means the latter, there is no occasion for a provision that the legislature may instruct the members of this body. . . ."^' "Mr. Sedgwick opposed the idea of the gentleman from New Hampshire, that the State legislature had the power of instructing the members of this House; he looked upon it as a subordination of the rights of the people to admit such an authority. We stand not here, said he, the representatives of the State legislatures, as under the former Congress, but as the representatives of the great body of the people. The sovereignty, the independence, and the rights of the States are intended to be guarded by the Senate; if we are to be viewed in any other light, the greatest security the people have for their rights and privileges is destroyed. . . ." "lb. col. 7^- "lb. col. 770. 98 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW [Mr. Livermore said that the gentleman misunder- stood him, that what he had said respected only the in- fluence that legislative instructions would have on his private judgment.]^" "Mr. Page: ... It was strictly compatible with the spirit and the nature of the Govermnent; all power vests in the people of the United States ; it is, therefore, a Government of the people, a democracy. "'"^ 4 — The Tenth Amendment : "The powers not dele- gated to the United States by the Constitution or pro- hibited by it to the States are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people."^^ This evidence, drawn as it is from eveiy variety of political opinion contemporary with it, sustains, it is submitted, the following deductions : That in 1 787 the terms "People of the States" and "People of the United States" were not antagonistic terms; that the terms opposed by the men of that day were States and People, or more generally Governments and People ; that the political science of the day afforded no intermediate term; that governments were universally regarded as properly the creations of the people gov- erned by them; that the States were regarded as re- spectively the creations of the people politically organized under them; that the term People meant any designated aggregation of individuals endowed with the rights of men under the social compact and especially the right to determine their forms of gov- ernment; that the Constitution was universally recog- ^"/&. cols. 771-2. °'/&. col. 772. "^Thd antithesis is still between States and people: he. cit. col. 797- "WE, THE PEOPLE" 99 nized as proposing a government over individuals; that though the existing organization of the American people into States was recognized to the extent of a specific provision in the Constitution that it was to go into efifect only "between the States" ratifying it, as to those States it was to rest upon an act of popular ratification; that the establishment of the Constitution was regarded contemporaneously as representing a fresh manifestation of the inexhaustible, inalienable right of the people to govern themselves. ^^ '"Further evidence confirming that given in the text is avail- able from the comparison so frequently made of the House of Representatives and the Senate : "The House of Representatives will derive its powers from the people of America. . . . The Senate, on the other hand, will derive its powers from the States, as political and coequal societies'' : Fed, No. 39, p. 237 (Lodge Ed.). I do not, of course, deny that the Constitution is frequently spoken of as being "ratified by the States," for in colloquial use the term "States" had several meanings: see pas- sage quoted infra from Madison's Report of 1799. See also King's language in the Convention, June 19 ; and again, John- son's June 29 : Gentlemen were using the term "States" in two senses, "those on one side considering the States as districts of people composing one political society ; those on the other, con- sidering them as so many societies" : Farrand, I, 461. What is insisted upon in the text is, first, that neither the term "of States" nor the term "of United States" added anything in 1787 to the intrinsic force of the term "People"; and secondly, that 'when used in contradistinction to the term "People," the term "States" signified simply certain governmental creations of the People. The views urged in the text are also supported by the language of all the judges in Chisholm v. Ga. 2 Dall. 419 (1793) ; by J. Story's language in Martin v. Hunter's Lessee, I Wheat. 304, 324-S (1816) ; and by C. J. Marshall's language in McCulloch V. Md. 4 Wheat. 316, 402-s (1819). Note particu- larly the following passage from Marshall's opinion: "It has been said that the people had already surrendered their powers 100 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW And from these conclusions two others necessarily follow: First, that it is a matter of entire indiffer- ence, legally speaking, whether the United States was a nation before the Constitution was adopted or not, since the Constitution obtains its entire force and effi- cacy, not from the fact that it was ratified by a pre- existent political community or communities — for it was not — but from the fact that it was established by the people to be governed by it.^^" Secondly, that the States have no outstanding rights against the Constitu- tion, that their rights with respect to the Constitution are defined in it, that whether they are in any particu- lar superior to or subordinate to the National Govern- ment depends entirely on the terms of the Constitution itself until this is overthrown. Secession therefore and nullification as alleged constitutional rights go a-glim- mering. The only fundamental outstanding right supe- rior to the Constitution is, in other words, that right of the people to the exercise of which it owes its existence, namely, the right of revolution. Confronted with the question in the Federalist as to what would be the to the State sovereignties and had nothing more to give. But surely, the question whether they may resume and modify the powers granted to government does not remain to be settled in this country. Much more might the legitimacy of the Gen- eral Government be doubted had it been created by the States. The powers delegated to the State sovereignties were to be exercised by themselves, not by a distinct and independent sov- ereignty created by themselves." ^'^ Nor is this to say that the Constitution made the U. S. a nation. All the factors of nationality were already present to the American People save organization under a real govern- ment. That, of course, the Constitution supplied for the first time. "WE, THE PEOPLE'\ \ ' "" '^ /a, ip'i > Mk/ , '-'^'^''/' consequence if Congress should atteiTf]5t- -to'tlsurp power, Madison answered : "The same ... as if the State legislatures should violate their respective constitutional authorities," though he further pointed out, that as a matter of fact, popular resistance to encroachments upon liberty by the National Govern- ment would be easier than resistance to like encroach- ments by the State governments, since the machinery of the latter, indi'Spensable as it is at any number of points to the working of the former, would often- times be in the hands of the resisters.^* And not less explicit is the answer returned to the same question by the Virginia ratifying convention. That body adopted the following declaration: "We, the dele- gates of the people of Virginia, ... do in the name and in behalf of the people of Virginia declare and make known that the powers granted under the Con- stitution being derived from the people of the United States, may be resumed by them whensoever the same shall be perverted to their injui-y or oppression."*" To cite this declaration as an assertion of the right of secession or indeed of any kind of State intervention is simply absurd. It is a plain statement of the doc- trine of the right of revolution, which is a right not of governments but of the governed.*"" "No. 44, p. 283 (Lodge). See also Nos. 45 and 46; and Hamil- ton in No. 28. ^Elliot, in, 656. °'"' Said Robert E. Lee, in a letter to his brother, written in Jan. 1861 : "Secession is nothing but revolution. ... It is idle to talk of isecession. Anarchy would have been established, and not a government, by Washington, Hamilton, Jefferson, Madi- son, and other patriots of the Revolution": Bradford, Lee the 102 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW The tinderlying fallacy of Calhounism is, then, clear once more. It consists in an attempt to appro- priate to political entities, called States, rights which properly belong only to populations. As is well known, this fallacy made its first appearance in the Virginia and Kentucky Resolutions of 1798,^" but it is further illumined by some instructive passages in Madison's famous Report to the Virginia legislature the year following in defence of the Resolutions. American, p. 35. It is a tenable thesis, I believe, that Cal- hounism has been more influential with Southern apologists for secession, 'since the war, than it ever was with the promoters of secession before the war. "" It is to be noted, however, that even the Va. and Ky. Reso- lutions confirm the thesis set forth in the text to this extent, that the State legislature is still regarded as the highest organ of the State as a political entity. The intermediate term, in other words, between State, in the sense of government, and the people of the State in their revolutionary capacity, had not yet been found. Madison indeed saw the difiiculty that this fact opposed to the doctrine of the resolutions. Thus, on Dec. 29, 1798, he wrote Jefferson thus : "Have you ever considered thor- oughly the distinction between the power of the State and that of the legislature on questions relating to the federal pact? On the supposition that the former is clearly the ultimate judge of infractions, it does not follow that the latter is the legitimate organ ; especially as the convention was the organ by which the compact was made": Writings (Hunt Ed.) VI, 328 fn. The hint thus given was followed by Calhoun : see infra. Madison's discussion of this question throws a curious light on his later attempts to escape the log'ical consequences of the Resolutions : See letter in Writings, IX, 495 ffg. This was written in Jan. 1833, after the Nullification menace had become serious. In his letter to Cabell of Aug. 16, 1829, Madi'son virtually admits that the difference between South Carolina's doctrine and that of Virginia in 1798 was merely one of degree: loc cit., IX, 343-4- "WE, THE PEOPLE" 103 Reiterating the doctrine that the Constitution is a compact of sovereign States, and for that reason ulti- mately subject to the construction given it by the States, Madison writes: "It is indeed true that the term 'States' is sometimes used in a vague sense, and sometimes in different senses, according to the subject to which it is applied. Thus it sometimes means the separate sections of terri- tory occupied by the political societies within each; sometimes the particular governments established by those societies ; sometimes those societies as organized into those particular governments; and lastly, it means the people composing those political societies in their high- est political capacity. ... In the present instance, what- ever different construction of the term 'States' in the resolution may have been entertained, all will at least concur in that last mentioned; because in that sense the Constitution was submitted to the 'States' ; in that sense the 'States' ratified it; and in that sense of the term 'States' they are consequently parties to the compact from which the powers of the Federal Government re- sult. . . . The Constitution of the United States was formed by the sanction of the States, given by each in its sovereign capacity. . . . The States then, being the parties to the constitutional compact, and in thcii- sover- eign capacity, it follows of necessity that there can be no tribunal above their authority to decide."-'^ In other words, what is at the outset characterized as the highest political capacity of the people of the States is finally transmuted by verbal legerdemain into the highest political capacity of the States themselves ! The argument reduces itself to a mere pun on the word "States," which is dexterously concealed by an elaborate pretence at definition. Later in the report occurs this sentiment: "The authority of constitu- " Writings, VI, 348-9- 104 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW tions over governments and of the sovereignty of the people over constitutions" are truths that cannot be enough emphasized.^® Very good. But if it was the purport of the Resolutions merely to assert the ulti- mate control of the people of the United States over the Constitution, why all the jargon about "a compact of sovereign States" ? But in the end, as I pointed out in the previous article, Madison abandoned his entire case for State "interposition." "A declaration," he writes, "that proceedings of the Federal Government are not warranted by the Constitu- tion is a novelty neither among the citizens nor among the legislatures of the States, . . . nor can the declara- tions of either, whether affirming or denying the con- stitutionality of measures of the Federal Government, be deemed, in any point of view an assumption of the office of judge. The declarations in such cases are ex- pressions of opinion, unaccompanied with any other ef- fect than what they may produce on opinion by exciting reflection."^^ Rather a lame conclusion to so much fulminationl The boasted right of the sovereign State to insert it- self between its citizens and the National Government on such occasions as it deemed the latter to be ex- ceeding its powers dangerously comes down in the last analysis to a mere right on the part of its legislature to vote resolutions expressive of opinion, resolutions which are admitted to be no more authori- tative than any ebullition of opinion on the part of private citizens. On the other hand, it must not be concluded that Calhounism is absolutely without justification from ="/&. 352. "lb. 402. "WE, THE PEOPLE" 105 the point of view of the history of American political theory. For one thing, even in 1787, there was some difficulty in admitting in the same breath the idea of the Constitution as law and the idea of it as a direct act of the people. Government was representative, and until they were unseated, the people's representa- tives alone had the right to govern, and, therefore, to enact laws.*" To use the words of Ellsworth on a closely related matter, "a new set of ideas was creeping in." They had not, however, as yet, established them- selves so generally but that at this point the Conven- tion of 1787 must be held to have broken with the dominant tradition. But again, while by Calhoun's time, the idea of a constitution as law was well enough established, yet the agency by which constitutions are nowadays drawn up, namely, constitutional conven- tions, had become such usual phenomena as to have been substantially assimilated to the machinery of organised government, so that one looking back to the State conventions that had in 1787 ratified the Con- stitution found it natural to regard them as organs of existing political societies, rather than as directly rep- resentative of the individuals back of those societies. But lastly, Calhounism may be regarded as an effort to restore the somewhat tarnished reputation of the Right of Revolution. A very vital right this was in 1787. Nor was it a merely moral right, for the hne between morals and law was as yet but faintly drawn, as evidence of which is the fact that judges them- selves claimed power to pass on the validity of laws *° See the quotation from Luther Martin's Genuine informa- tion immediately below. io6 DOCTRIXE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW under principles of the social compact.*^ By 1830 however, with the extension of the notion that it was the sovereignty of the people, and nothing else, that gave constitutions their legal character, this line had become distinctly delineated and the right of revolu- tion confined to the field of moral rights. Well, then, some right as good as the right of revolution had been must be provided — hence the theory of the right of secession as a constitutional right. But the general subject under discussion has yet another aspect that deserves brief mention. It is the habit of a certain school of writers nowadays to ring the changes on the assertion that the Convention of 1787 was "undemocratic," and there is undoubtedly some poorly defined truth to the charge. Nonetheless, this "undemocratic" body made the most audacious and altogether unqualified appeal to the notion of popular sovereignty and majority rule that had ever yet been made, even in America. For while some of the State constitutions had also been referred for popular ratification by the bodies which formulated them, even these were not at their inception regarded as law, while the national Constitution was. The fact of the matter is, that so far as prerogative and democracy are antagonistic ideas, the opponents of democracy in 1787 were also the opponents of the Constitution. In this connection let the reader turn to Luther Martin's attack in his Genuine Information*- upon the supporters of the Constitution for their re- " See the language of Justice Chase in Colder v. Bull, 3 Dall. 386 (1798). "§§ 104-6, as printed in Volume III of Farrand's Records. "WE, THE PEOPLE" 107 jection of the Articles of Confederation and for the inroads they proposed upon the existing State consti- tutions, and then to the premises upon which this at- tack was avowedly based : "Nor do these positions," Martin proceeds, "in the least interfere with the principle that all power originates from the people, because when once the people have exercised their power in establishing and forming themselves into a State government, it never devolves back to them, nor have they a right to resume or again to exercise that power, until such events take place as will amount to a dissolution of their State governments." The reference of the Constitution to the people, there- fore, had "a tendency to set the State governments and their subjects at variance with each other, to lessen the obligations of govermnent, to weaken the bonds of so- ciety, to introduce anarchy and confusion and to light the torch of discord and civil war throughout this continent."*^ This standpat argument was met by Madison in Federalist 45 in the following words : "Was then," he there inquires, "the American Revolu- tion effected, was the American Confederacy formed, was the precious blood of thousands spilt, and the hard- earned substance of millions lavished, not that the people of America should enjoy peace, liberty, and safety, but that the government of the individual States, that par- ticular municipal establishments, might enjoy a certain extent of power, and be arrayed with certain dignities and attributes of sovereignty? We have heard of the impious doctrine in the Old World, that the people were made for kings, not kings for the people. Is the same doctrine to be revived in the New, in another shape — that the solid happiness of the people is to be sacrificed to the views of political institutions of a different form? It is too early for politicians to presume on our for- "^ lb. § 106, Farrand, III, 230. The emphasis is from the original. io8 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW getting that the public good, the real welfare of the great body of the people, is the supreme object to be pursued; and that no form of government whatever has any other value than as it may be fitted for the attain- ment of this object. Were the plan of the Convention adverse to the public happiness, my voice would be, Re- ject the plan. Were the Union itself inconsistent with the public happiness, it would be, Abolish the Union. In like manner, as far as the sovereignty of the States cannot be reconciled to the happiness of the people, the voice of every good citizen must be, Let the former be sacrificed to the latter." In short, government rests upon the consent of the governed and may be remodelled by them at will to suit their utility, all previous govermxifints, states, confederations, constitutions, to the contrary notwith- standing. What more could one demand of the spirit of liberalism in an age when the "social problem" had not yet emerged?** " The question at issue between Martin and Madison was really as to the proper scope of the Right of Revolution. Mar- tin's view was that this right (not power) was available only against oppression. Madison and the supporters of the Consti- tution, on the other hand, took the position that it was available whenever its exercise would prove beneficial. This view is un- doubtedly sanctioned by the Declaration of Independence, a somewhat radical interpretation of the teachings of which in this reference is that given in a speech by Benj. Hichborn of Boston early in 1777 : Civil liberty, said he, was "not a 'govern- ment by laws,' made agreeable to charters, bills of rights, or compacts, but a power existing in the people at large, at any time, for any cause, or for no cause but their own sovereign pleasure, to alter or annihilate both the mode and essence of any former government and adopt a new one in its stead" : Niles, Principles and Acts, 146-7. Martin's view, however, was the older one. Developing it on the floor of the Convention he had cited in its support Locke, Vattel and others : see Madi- son's Notes for June 27. Jefferson's idea that there ought to be actual blood-letting about every nineteen years is familiar. THE PELATIAH WEBSTER MYTH THE PELATIAH WEBSTER MYTH* For several years Mr. Hannis Taylor has been en- deavoring to persuade the American public that the Constitution, instead of being the work of the Conven- tion of 1787, acting under the guidance of men like Madison, Hamilton, Pinckney, Patterson, Ellsworth, and others of similar caliber, was really the invention of a single individual, Pelatiah Webster by name, whose fame, till Mr. Taylor's resurrection of it in The North American Review for August, 1907, had dropped quite out of historical notice. Since this first publication of his discovery, — I think it was the first, — • Mr. Taylor has returned to the attack time and time again, now in a memorial to Congress urging some sort of national recognition of Webster's services, now in a volume on Jurisprudence, again in an impos- ing work on The Origin and Growth of the American Constitution, and more recently, and compendiously, in the New York Evening Post of January 10, 1912, where he attempts to answer Mr. Gaillard Hunt's very pointed criticism in an earlier issue (December 30, 191 1 ) of the same journal, of his method of handling historical evidence in one or two instances. Certainly if asseveration and reiteration could establish the truth of history, Mr. Taylor would by this time have put his thesis beyond all question. But has he in fact suc- ceeded in doing so? This is the subject of our inquiry. * The greater portion of this article appeared in the Michigan Law Review for June, 1912. Ill 112 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW First, a word as to the documents involved. For the most part, I shall quote from Mr. Taylor's latest statement of his case, in the Evening Post article. But this case in turn is based upon a document. For, as Mr. Taylor reminds us, in the language of M. Langlois : "History is studied from documents. . . . There is no substitute for documents; no documents, . no history." Accordingly, between pages 23 and 49 of Mr. Taylor's memorial to Congress, which is avail- able to everybody as Senate Document No. 461 of the 60th Congress, ist session, will be found, to quote its editor, "the epoch-making document of February 16, 1783, in which is embodied the first draft of the exist- ing Constitution of the United States," the document which entitles its author, Pelatiah Webster, to be re- garded as "the architect of our Federal Constitution." Further along Mr. Taylor adds : "Strange indeed it is that the most important document connected with our constitutional history should now be presented to the jurists and statesmen of the United States as if it were a papyrus from Egypt or Herculaneum." Sketched in outline, Mr. Taylor's case for Webster is as follows : The United States is a federal govern- ment, but a federal government of a unique sort, in that it operates directly upon the individuals subject to it instead of through the governmental machinery of its component States. Originally the United States, as organized under the Articles of Confederation, was itself of the usual type of federal government, being dependent even for its revenue upon State action. This system, however, soon proved inadec[uate, and THE PELATIAH WEBSTER MYTH 113 particularly on its financial side. Now as it chanced, Pelatiah Webster of Philadelphia was a student of finance. Approaching the subject of the deficiencies of the Confederation from the angle afforded by his favorite studies, Webster was able to make an almost unparalleled contribution to the science of government. The system of State requisitions had failed. The central government must therefore have a revenue of its own, to be levied by its own legislature and to be collected by its own agents. For financial purposes at least, then, the central government must act directly on the people, and not indirectly through the States. Thus at one leap was the tremendous barrier that de- marks the American system from all other federal systems surmounted. For this great feat achieved, all the rest was easy enough for the mind that had achieved it. Not only was Webster the first to sug- gest a federal revenue, but he was the first to outline the entire system embodied in the Constitution of lySf. But now is it true that Webster was the first to pro- pose that the Federal Govei'nment should have "the independent power to tax," that before him "no one had dreamed of a federal state with the independent power of taxation," that this proposition "made all possible," involving "the creating of a distinct and self-sustaining federal government such as had never existed" ? Webster's proposition to invest "the supreme authority" of the Union with "power of taxation," meaning by that the power to levy import duties, which he urged should be particularly heavy upon 114 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW articles "consumed by the rich or prodigal part of the community," occurs on page 26 of Senate Document Number 461. On that very page Webster himself refers to the recent action of Rhode Island in rejecting an amendment to the Articles of Confederation by which Congress was to be given the power to levy a 5 per cent import duty! This amendment was first proposed in February, 1781, and so antedates Web- ster's pamphlet an even two years. Even earlier was Hamilton's famous letter of September 3, 1780, to James Duane urging a "solid coercive union," a power- ful executive consisting of few heads, a federal reve- nue, a tax in kind, and a national bank. Mr. Taylor is quite aware of this letter of Hamilton's but sets it down as of "no importance" on account of its alleged private character. "It was not a pubhc act, not even a public declaration," he says. But is this a valid line of argu- ment? The letter, whether it be regarded as public or private, still comprises an index to its author's gen- eral interests and conversation, as well as of the group in which he moved. This is proved by the very sen- tence with which it opens : "Agreeably to your re- quest and my promise, I sit down to give you my ideas of the defects of the present system and the changes necessary to save us from ruin." But the fact is that the letter was, in a very true sense of the term, a public one, though it was not at the time published through the press. Its author was the private secre- tary of the Commander-in-chief of the Continental Army. Its recipient was a member of Congress. The topic it dealt with was one of public interest. Its THE PEL ATI AH WEBSTER MYTH ns dimensions were those of a pamphlet. Finally, one of the specific proposals contained in it resulted in the plan from the congressional committee of which Duane was a member, establishing a Department of Foreign Affairs with a Secretary. This occurred in January 1781, many months before Webster had con- ceived his pamphlet.^ But indeed, not even Hamilton is entitled to the credit of first suggesting, the idea of a federal sys- tem the central authority of which should be vested with an independent power of taxation. More than a quarter of a century before the letter to Duane was written, three years before its author had yet seen the light of day, Benjamin Franklin had proposed a fed- eral government for the British Colonies of North America, "for their mutual defense and security." This was the so-called "Albany Plan of Union" of 1754. The governing body of the Union was to be a "Grand Council" composed of forty-eight members, apportioned among the colonies in a way to recog- nize, to some extent, their relative population and importance. But the central feature of the scheme was the grant of power to the Grand Council. They were to regulate all trade with the Indians, to make new settlements, to govern these till the crown should ^For the Duane letter, see Writings of Alexander Hamilton (Lodge, Ed.) I, 213 ffg. It is worth noting, in view of Mr. Taylor's insistence on the importance of the printed word that Hamilton did in fact publish a series of papers in one of which, bearing date of Aug. 30, 1787, he repeated his recommendation of a tax to be "granted to the Federal Government in per- petuity, and, if Congress think proper, to be levied by its own collectors": 25 Harv. Law Rev. 748. ii6 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW "form them into particular governments," to "raise and pay soldiers," "build forts," "equip vessels of force to guard the coast and protect the trade on the ocean, lakes, or great rivers," and for these purposes, to "have the power to make laws and lay and levy such general duties, imports, or taxes, as to them shall appear most equal and just, considering the ability and other circumstances of the inhabitants in the several colonies, and such as may be collected with the least inconvenience to the people, rather discouraging luxury, than loading industry with unnecessary burdens." It is true that the Plan does not state specifically whether the collectors of the federal revenue were to be appointed by the Grand Council or the colo- nial governments, but at least the intervention of the colonial legislatures in the levying of federal taxes, which was the major cause of the failure of the Arti- cles of Confederation, was avoided.^" But not only does the Albany Plan, to this extent at least, anticipate both Hamilton and Webster in their suggestion of a federal government with an indepen- dent revenue, but it also suggests the question whether Mr. Taylor has not exaggerated somewhat the diffi- culty in the way, in the year 1783, of conceiving of a federal government acting upon individuals. In this connection the testimony of Madison in the Federalist is most instructive and it is, moreover, testimony which must be very persuasive with Mr. Taylor. Thus writ- ing in Federalist 40, Madison compares the scheme " For the Albany Plan, see Wm. MacDonald, Select Charters, 253 ffg. See also Mrs. Lois K. Matthews' interesting study in The Am. PoIit'I Sc. Rev., VIII, 393 ffg. THE PELATIAH WEBSTER MYTH 117 proposed by the new Constitution with that organized by the Articles of Confederation thus : "In some instances, as has been shown, the powers of the new government will act on the States in their col- lective characters. In some instances, also, those of the existing government act immediately on individuals. In cases of capture, of piracy, of the post-office, of coins, weights, and measures, of trade with the Indians, of claims under grants of land by different States, and, above all, in the case of trials by court-martial in the army and navy, by which death may be inflicted without the intervention of a jury, or even of a civil magistrate; — in all these cases, the powers of the Confederation oper- ate immediately on the persons and interests of individual citizens. . . . The truth is, that the great principles of the Constitution proposed by the Conven- tion may be considered less as absolutely new, than as the expansion of principles which are found in the Articles of Confederation." Yet Madison himself admits in the end that "the new system" had "the aspect of an entire transforma- tion of the old," so that the question of originality is still before us, even though in tones somewhat sub- dued. Also, it must be conceded that, while Webster was plainly no pioneer in urging an import duty for the government of the Confederation, he may still have been the originator of other not less important features of the Constitution of 1787. In other words, it is possible that, while Mr. Taylor is mistaken as to the exact road by which Webster approached the great discoveries in government attributed to him, he may still be right in crediting him with those discoveries. We thus return to Mr. Taylor's claims for his hero, with a view to comparing them with the hero's actual performance. ii8 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW Mr. Taylor's second claim for Webster is, then, that he first proposed the extension to the Federal Govern- ment of the principle of checks and balances and the separation of powers. His language is as follows : "No one had dreamed of a federal legislature di- vided into two chambers; no one had dreamed of a federal state divided into three departments; execu- tive, legislative and judicial." The answer to this claim is twofold. In the first place, what Mr. Taylor asserts "no one had dreamed of," had been apparently a matter of discussion and de- liberation, and that at the very foundation of the Union. Ultimately however, John Adams informs us, the prin- ciple of the separation of powers was not extended to "the United States in their federal capacity," be- cause "the people of America and their delegates in Congress were of opinion that a single assembly was in every way adequate to the management of all their federal concerns"; and he adds that this was a rea- sonable decision, "because Congress is not a legislative assembly . . . but only a diplomatic assembly."- But now, it is worth noting, as bearing on the whole ques- tion of Webster's merits as a political thinker, that, while he did indeed propose to divide Congress into two houses,^ it never occurred to him to touch the real source of mischief, namely Congress's appointment by and responsibility to the States. In other words. Con- gress is still to remain a diplomatic assembly in which the States shall be represented, precisely as under the Articles of Confederation, by delegates "appointed by '■ Life and Works IV, 579. See also ib. 208. ^ Senate Document No. 461, 60th Congress, p. 33. THE PELATIAH WEBSTER MYTH iig the States in any manner they please" and subject to recall by the States "as often as they please."^ But in the second place, aside from this anomalous proposition to divide a diplomatic body into two cham- bers, which, in the case of their being unable to agree in the face of a crisis, were to bestow all their powers upon a dictator after the Roman model,^ Webster had not the faintest idea of ^.pplying the principle of checks and balances to the Federal Government. True, like Hamilton before him, he would have a collegiate executive, a "Council of State," but this council was to be appointed, certainly in part, probably in entirety, by Congress,^ to which moreover "all and singular of them" were to be "ever accountable." As to the part that this council was to have in legislation, Webster writes thus : "/ do not mean to give these great min- isters of State a negative on Congress, but I mean to oblige Congress to receive their advices before they pass their bills, and that every act shall be void that is not passed with these forms. "'^ In view of this very specific language how remarkable that Mr. Taylor should write thus : "Under Webster's plan, now in force, federal legislation is enacted by three bodies — the executive, the House of Representatives and the Senate. The President of the United States is a part of the law-making power. Tlmt is what Webster said, no more, no less" ! But Mr. Taylor's third claim in his hero's behalf is */&. p. 27. "76. p. 42. °Ih. p. 43. 'lb. p. 37- 120 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW even more preposterous. Stated in his own language it runs thus: "He outhned the Supreme Court with jurisdiction both original and appellate," he anticipated "the splendid conception of the Supreme Court as it now exists," he "provided for the complete supremacy of federal law" and "paved the way for Marshall's great judgment in Cohens v. Virginia." What is the basis for these sweeping assertions? It is supplied by the following passage from Web- ster's pamphlet : "That the supreme authority should be vested with powers to terminate and finally decide controversies arising between different States, I take it, will be universally admitted, but I humbly appre- hend that an appeal from the first instance of trial ought to be admitted in causes of great moment, on the same reasons that such appeals are admitted in all the states of Europe."^ The important point to be made clear in this refer- ence is the meaning of the term "the supreme author- ity." Obviously, it is the same "supreme authority" for which already Webster has urged the right to levy a customs duty® ; again it is the same "supreme authority" for which in the paragraph immediately following the one just quoted from he claims the "power of peace and war, and forming treaties" : it is, in short, Congress}'^ But also, it should be ob- served, Webster himself claims no credit for origi- nality in urging that Congress should have power to terminate "controversies arising between different "lb. p. 31. "lb. p. 26. "/&. p. 33. THE PELATIAH WEBSTER MYTH 121 States," and his modesty in this respect is most be- coming, since by Article IX of the Articles of Con- federation, Congress was ah'eady possessed of this power. Yet it is certain that the Articles of Con- federation did not produce a Cohens v. Virginia. But not only would Mr. Taylor have it that Webster proposed the Supreme Court with its present jurisdic- tion, but also that he prevised the entire federal ju- dicial system. Thus on page 18 of the memorial to Congress he writes as follows : "After an elaborate discussion of the qualifications of members of Con- gress ... he proceeded to define a part of the origi- nal jurisdiction of the Supreme Court of the United States by saying 'that the supreme authority should be vested with power to terminate and finally decide con- troversies between different States.' He also said 'to these I would add judges of law and chancery.' Thus the entire federal judicial system was distinctly outlined." Mr. Taylor's endeavor to identify Webster's "su- preme authority" with the present Supreme Court has been already disposed of. Our interest at this point is in the second one of the sentences just quoted. What is the significance of the word "these" in this sentence, to whom does it refer? Mr. Taylor's ob- vious intention is to convey the impression that it refers to the "supreme authority," that is, as he would have it, the Supreme Court. As a matter of fact, however, when we turn to Webster's pamphlet we find "these" separated from the antecedent which Mr. Taylor provides for it by more than five pages, ^^ and "7&. pp. 31 and 36. 122 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW that the antecedent which Webster suppHes has noth- ing to do with the "supreme authority," but refers to those Ministers of State who were to constitute his council of legislative revision. "To these," he writes, "I would add judges of law and chancery, but I fear they will not be very soon appointed." In other words, the very sentence from which Mr. Taylor pre- sumes to quote in support of his proposition that Webster foresaw the federal judicial system, proves precisely the contrary. And with Webster's federal judiciary thus vanish- ing in the thin air of illusion, what becomes of the further claim that he conceived the idea of a "supreme law of the land" enforceable by that judiciary? The fact is of course that Webster never even distantly approached such a conception. It is true that he would give the "supreme authority" "sufficient powers to enforce the obedience of all subjects of the United States" to its treaties^^ and "to punish all transgressors in all these respects, "^^ but what is the method he relies upon for making good these powers of enforce- ment? He sets it forth on page 45 of the published pamphlet thus : "I therefore propose, that every per- son whatever, whether in public or private character, who shall, by public vote or overt act, disobey the su- preme authority, shall be amenable to Congress, shall be summoned and compelled to appear before Con- gress, and, on due conviction, suffer such fine, impris- onment, or other punishment, as the supreme authority shall judge requisite." This, from "the Architect of ''lb. p. 31. "76. p. 32. THE PELATIAH WEBSTER MYTH 123 the Federal Constitution," who, according to Mr. Tay- lor, "proposed the division of a Federal State into three departments, executive, legislative, and judicial, the organization of each of which he worked out" ! However, we must look at this proposition of Web- ster's from another point of view, namely, as a pro- posal to make the federal power operative upon individuals, without the intervention of the States, which, according to Mr. Taylor, was yet another, in- deed the most important of Webster's discoveries. Thus, in his letter memoriaHzing Congress "in behalf of the Architect of our Federal Constitution," Mr. Taylor writes : "Having thus defined his fundamental concept of a federal government operating directly on the citizen, the great one boldly accepted the inevitable corollary that such a government must be strictly or- ganized and equipped with ... all the usual appara- tus of a government, all bearing directly upon every citizen of the United States without any reference to the government of the several States."^'^ But now what is the fact of the matter? It is that Webster had not the least idea of dispensing with the State govern- ments as the usual intermediaries between the govern- ment of the Union and its subjects. Thus, while vesting Congress with a customs revenue, he still retains State requisitions.^^ Again, his notion of hail- ing persons before Congress for transgressing the acts of the Union is devised principally, it seems plain, with the idea of punishing members of the State legis- latures for voting measures opposed to the "supreme "/&. p. 16. " lb. pp. 30, 43- 124 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW authority." But finally, it is upon State coercion that he relies principally for securing the authority of the Federal Government. Thus he writes: "There re- mains one very important article still to be discussed, namely, what methods the Constitution shall point out to enforce the acts and requisitions through the several States; and how the States which refuse or delay obedience to such acts and requisitions shall be treated." And again : "to leave all the States at liberty to obey" the acts of Congress "or not with impunity, is, in every view, the grossest absurdity." And again: "every State in the Union is under the highest obliga- tion to obey the supreme authority of the whole." And again : "I cannot therefore admit, that the great ends of our Union shall lie at the mercy of a single State, or that the energy of our government should be checked by a single disobedience." What he pro- posed, accordingly, was this : first, that any State might petition Congress for the repeal of any law or decision, and that if a majority of the States did so propose, the law or decision in question should be re- pealed, but secondly, that "if the execution of any act or order of the supreme authority shall be opposed by force in any of the States ... it shall be lawful for Congress to send into such State a sufficient force to suppress it."^® In other words, under Webster's scheme, as under the Articles of Confederation, the States still re- mained the essential units of the Federal Government, and the supremacy of the federal authority was to be '"lb. pp. 43-7- THE PELATIAH WEBSTER MYTH 125 secured by State coercion. But with reference to State coercion, there are just these two facts to be re- membered: first, that the idea was not original with Webster, having been proposed as early as March 1 78 1, by a committee of Congress itself, the spokes- man of which was Madison; secondly, that the idea was utterly repudiated by the Convention that framed the Constitution, as impracticable and destructive and, under the system before the Convention, unnecessary. And yet Mr. Taylor asserts that Webster's pamphlet furnished the Convention of 1787 "the basis of its proceedings" ! One point further. In his recent book on The Ori- gin and Growth of the American Constitution, as earlier, Mr. Taylor has endeavored to secure for Web- ster the credit for a pamphlet written in 1781 in which, Hamilton's letter to Duane aside, the proposition of a continental convention for the purpose of enlarging the powers of Congress was first broached. Mr. Taylor bases this claim upon the testimony of Madi- son, given late in life. This testimony, however, the historian Bancroft specifically rejects : first, because, when at a later period Webster collected his pamphlets in a volume, he did not incltide the pamphlet in ques- tion; secondly, because the style of the pamphlet is totally unlike that of the rest of Webster's writings; thirdly, because the bill for the printing of the pamphlet was made out to one William Barton; fourthly, because "Barton from time to time wrote pamphlets, of which on a careful comparison, the style, language and forms of expression are found to corre- spond to this pamphlet published in 1781." Notwith- 126 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW Standing this convincing array of reasons, Mr. Taylor has the hardihood in a footnote^'' to write thus : "No attention should be paid to Bancroft's vain attempt to discredit Madison's statement . . . Madison was on the ground and knew the facts; Bancroft's inference is based on flimsy hearsay nearly a century after the event" ! Altogether, it becomes quite clear that Mr. Taylor's efforts to enroll Pelatiah Webster with the world's great lawgivers have failed, — although, of course, one could never predict what a cipher might yet reveal! But indeed Mr. Taylor should have better assessed the difficulties of his enterprise. For while rural churchyards may now and then shelter "some mute, inglorious Milton," it seems most unlikely that a period in which both the minds of men and the print- ing press fairly teemed with schemes of constitutional reform, — when politics was the intellectual interest, — would have relegated a really superior thinker along these lines to an undeserved oblivion. Rather it would have provided genius with platform and pedestal — as in truth it did in the case of both Hamilton and Madison. The author of the pamphlet of February i6, 1783, was, however, no genius. Madison, on the basis of his recollection of him, even hesitated to credit him with ability. For having described him as "an able citizen of Philadelphia," he later struck out the adjective. No doubt to have been a citizen of Philadelphia was not without merit, but after all, it hardly entitles one of itself to a place with Moses and Lycurgus. " See The Origin and Growth of the American Constitution, p. 27. THE DRED SCOTT DECISION THE DRED SCOTT DECISION^ The purpose of the following study is to consider the Dred Scott decision^ in the light of legal doctrine contemporary with it, in the view particularly of re- assessing the pronouncement therein of unconstitu- tionality upon the Missouri Compromise.* The main facts leading up to and attending this famous case may be summarized as follows :* Dred, a slave belonging to an army officer named Emerson, was taken by his master from the home State, Mis- souri, first into the free State of Illinois and thence into that portion of the national territory in which, by the eighth section of the Missouri Compromise, slavery had been "forever prohibited." Here master and slave remained two years before returning to Missouri, the latter in the meantime marrying with his master's consent. In 1852 Dred sued his master for ^ In substance this paper was read before the American His- torical Association at its annual meeting of December, 1910, and was later published in more extended form in the Am. Hist'I Rev., XVII, No. I. ' ig Howard 393-633 (cited below as "Rep.")- " For the conventional view of Scott v. Sanford, see James Ford Rhodes, History of the United States, II, 251 ffg. ; James Schouler, History of the United States, V. 377 ffg. ; Nicolay and Hay, Abraham Lincoln, II., ch. 4; Theodore Clarke Smith, Parties and Slavery, ch. 14. * The agreed statement of facts is to be found. Rep. 397-399, 129 130 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW freedom in one of the lower State courts and won the action, but upon appeal the decision was reversed by the supreme court of the State, upon the ground that appellee's status at home was fixed by State law regard- less of what it had been abroad — a decision which plainly ran counter to the whole trend of decision by the same court for the previous generation. There- upon the case was remanded to the inferior court for retrial, but Dred, having in the meantime become the property of one Sanford, a citizen of New York, now decided to bring a totally new action in the United States circuit court for the Missouri district, under section ii of the Act of 1789. In order to bring this action Dred had of course to aver his citizenship of Missouri, which averment was traversed by his ad- versary in what is known as a plea in abatement, deny- ing the jurisdiction of the court upon the ground that plaintiff was the descendant of African slaves and had been born in slavery. The plea in abatement the circuit court overruled, but then proceeded to find the law on the merits of the case for the defendant; and from this decision Dred appealed to the United States Supreme Court. Scott V. Sanford was first argued before the Su- preme Court in the December term of 1855. From a letter of Justice Curtis we learn that in the view the court then took of the case, it would find it unneces- sary to canvass the question of the constitutionality of the Missouri Compromise.^ And indeed it was evi- dently of a mind to evade even the question of juris- " Curtis to Ticknor, April 8, 1856: George Ticlcnor Curtis, Life of Benjamin Robbins Curtis, I, 80. THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 131 diction, had it not been for the fact, as it presently- developed, that Justice McLean, who aspired to the Republican presidential nomination, had determined to make political capital of the controversy by writing a dissenting opinion, reviewing at length the history of African slavery in the United States from the Free Soil point of view." McLean's intention naturally produced some uneasiness among his brethren and particularly such as came from slave States, three of whom now began demanding reargument of the ques- tions raised by the plea in abatement. This demand being acceded to, the case came on for reargument in the December term of 1856, that is, after the presi- dential election was past. Yet even now it was origi- nally the purpose of the court to confine its attention to the question of law raised by the circuit court's de- cision, which rested upon the same ground as the State supreme court's earlier decision, and Justice Nelson was commissioned to write an opinion sustaining the circuit court. '^ "Ashley of Ohio's positive testimony, on the basis of report current at the time Scott v. Sanford was pending, supplies the explanation needed of the demand for reargument, since the final disposition of the case would be precisely the same whether the circuit court were held to have erred in taking jurisdiction or, having rightfully taken jurisdiction, to have properly decided the case on its merits : Congressional Globe, 40th Cong., 3d sess., App., p. 211. Ashley's testimony is moreover confirmed by that of Justice Grier in the letter cited below in note 9. See also McLean's opinion, Rep. 529-564, and Curtis's animadver- sions on the same, ih., 620. ' Rep. 529-564. The fact that Nelson was commissioned to write an opinion stistaining the lower court again shows that intrinsically the question of the lower court's jurisdiction was regarded as unimportant. 133 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW But with the defeat of Fremont, and Buchanan's election, the advantage of position now lay with the pro-slavery contingent of the court. Two of this group, accordingly, Wayne of Georgia and Catron of Tennessee, soon began urging the notion that, as ex- pressed in Wayne's very frank opinion, "the peace and harmony of the country required the settlement . . . by judicial decision" of the "constitutional principles" involved in the case.* From Daniel of Virginia and Campbell of Georgia, the two agitators apparently en- countered little opposition; indeed, their well-founded apprehension seems to have been that these two justices would seize the occasion to "throw out" "some extreme views." The aged Chief Justice proved at first more difficult, but he too at last yielded and consented to write what in the Report is absurdly labelled "the Opinion of the Court," covering all issues that had been raised by counsel's argument. It now only re- mained to align one of the Northern justices with the majority, since otherwise the sectional and partisan character of the decision would appear too palpable. On February 19, 1857, Catron, whose own efforts to this end had thus far proved unavailing, appealed to the President-elect to persuade his fellow Pennsyl- vanian, Grier, to join "the majority of his brethren" in a broad gauge decision of the entire question of Congress' power in the territories, instead of taking, as he seemed disposed to do, "the smooth handle for the sake of repose." Buchanan, at once wrote Grier as he was bid, and Grier promptly responded with the 'Rep. 4S4-S- THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 133 desired promise. In his inaugural address, a few days later, Buchanan, again taking his orders from Catron, referred to the pending decision, indicated the scope it would take, and bespoke the acquiescence of all good citizens in it, "whatever it might be" !® II Hostile criticism of the Dred Scott decision, natur- ally, has always found its principal target in the Chief Justice's opinion, and the gravamen of such criticism has always been that the portion of it dealing with the Missouri Compromise, was obiter dictum. I do not, however, concur with this criticism, for reasons which I shall now endeavor to make plain. To begin with, it ought to be clearly apprehended what difficulty attaches to a charge of this sort against a deliberate utterance of the Supreme Court of the United States, evidently intended by it to have the force and operation of law, and for the reason that the ultimate test of what is law for the United States is, and at the time of the Dred Scott decision was, the opinion of the Supreme Court. On the other hand, the Supreme Court is not a legally irresponsible body : by the very theory that makes it final judge of the laws and the Constitution it is bound by these ; as by virtue " Catron's and Grier's letters will be found in the Works of James Buchanan (J. B. Moore Ed.) X, 106-8 fn. Grier's answer of Feb. 23 to Buchanan's note gave the President-elect complete information as to the alignment of the Court. A. H. Stephens was aware of the scope the decision was to take as early as Jan. 1857 : Rhodes, II, 253. And to know the scope of the decision was, in view of the make^ip of the court, to know its purport. 134 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW of its character as court it is bound by the lex curiae, that is to say, is bound to make consistent appHcation of the results of its own reasoning, and to honor the precedents of its own creation unless it is able to stig- matize them as erroneous. What the charge of obiter dictum amounts to then is this : first, that the action of the Chief Justice in passing upon the constitution- ality of the eighth section of the Missouri Compromise was illogical, as being inconsistent with the earlier part of his opinion, the purport of which, it is alleged, was to remove from the court's consideration the rec- ord of the case in the lower court and, with it, any basis for a pronouncement upon the constitutional question; and secondly, that it was in disregard of precedent, which, it is contended, exacted that the court should not pass upon issues other than those its decision of which was strictly necessary to the deter- mination of the case before it, and particularly that it should not unnecessarily pronounce a legislative enactment unconstitutional. Let us consider these two points in order. As already indicated, the primary question before the court upon the reargument was what disposition to make of the plea in abatement which the circuit court had overruled, thereby taking jurisdiction of the case,^" and upon this point a majority of the court, including both Chief Justice Taney and Justice Curtis, ruled decisively both that the plea in abatement was before it and that the decision of the circuit court as to its jurisdiction was subject to review by the Su- " Supreme Court Reports, Lawyer's Edition, Bk. xv., 694, 697. THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 135 preme Court." Evidently the charge of illogicahty lies against only those judges of the above-mentioned majority who, after sustaining the plea in abatement and so pronouncing against the jurisdiction of the circuit court upon the grounds therein set forth, passed to consider the further record of the case, by which the constitutional issue was raised. But was such pro- ceeding necessarily illogical? Upon this point ob- viously the pertinent thing is to consider Taney's own theory of what he was doing, which he states in sub- stantially the following language at the conclusion of his argument on the question of plaintiff's citizen- ship : But waiving, he says, the question as to whether the plea in abatement is before the court on the writ of error, yet the question of jurisdiction still remains on the face of the bill of exceptions taken by plain- tiff in which he admits that he was born a slave but contends that he has since become free; for if he has not become free, "he is still a slave and certainly incapable of suing in the character of a citizen."^^ In other words, the Chief Justice's theory was, not that he was canvassing the case on its merits, which he could have done with propriety only had he chosen to ignore the question of jurisdiction, but that he was "This majority consisted of the Chief Justice and Justices Wayne, Daniel, Campbell, and Curtis. Grier considered it sufficient to canvass the question of the lower court's jurisdiction on the basis of the facts stated in the bill of exceptions. Nelson did not consider the question of jurisdiction. Catron and McLean did not deem the question of jurisdiction to be before the court. " Rep. 427. Note also the Chief Justice's statement of the issue at the opening of his opinion, Rep. 400. 130 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW fortifying his decision upon this matter of jurisdiction by reviewing the issues raised in the bill of exceptions, as well as those raised by the plea in abatement; in other words that he was canvassing the matter of jurisdiction afresh. The question of the validity of the Chief Justice's way of proceeding then comes down to this question : Is it allowable for a court to base a decision upon more than one ground and if it does so, does the auxiliary part of the decision become obiter dictum f On the general question of what constitutes dictum we find the writer in the American and English Encyclopedia of Law indicating the existence of two views among Common Law courts. By one of these views none of a judicial opinion is decision save only such part as was absolutely necessary to the determination of the rights of the parties to the action. By the other view, on the contrary, all of an opinion is decision which represents a deliberate application of the judicial mind to questions legitimately raised in argument. ^^ But on the precise question just stated the above-mentioned writer speaks as follows : "Where the record presents two or more points, any one of which, if sustained, would determine the case, and the court decides them all, the decision upon any one of the points cannot be regarded as abiter. Nor can it be said that a case is not authority on a point because, though that point was properly presented and decided in the regular course of the consideration of the case, another point was found in the end which disposed Oif the whole matter. The decision on such a question is as "Encyc. (2d ed.), "Dictura," IX, 452-453; "Stare Decisis," XXVI, 168-169. Cf. Carroll v. Carroll's Lessee, 16 How. 275, 287, and Alexander v. Worthimgton, 5 Md. 471, 487. THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 137 much a part of the judgment of the court as is that on any other of the matters on which the case as a whole depends. The fact that the decision might have been placed upon a different ground existing in the case does not render a question expressly decided by the court a dictum."" In support of this view are cited cases which ante- date the Dred Scott decision and others which, though, of later date, plainly purport to set forth long stand- ing and established doctrine. ^^ But logic too supports the same view of the matter. For the contrary view, by keeping open a choice by interested parties between the diverse grounds of decisions, would leave the law unsettled precisely in proportion as the courts had presumed to settle it. Still it is urged that constitutional questions com- prise a peculiar class of questions which should be left undecided if possible. To quote Justice Curtis's protest against the Chief Justice's opinion : "A great question of constitutional law, deeply affecting the peace and welfare of the country, is not ... a fit subject to be thus reached"; such is the argument.^® So far, however, is this alleged exception from being justified by the history of the matter, that it would be far nearer the truth to say that, if constitutional cases comprise a class by themselves in this reference, they warrant an exceptionally broad view of the legal value "lb., 171. I am indebted for this reference to Albert W. R. Ewing's Legal and Historical Status of the Dred Scott Decision (Washington, 1909). ^See C. J. Waite in R. R. Cos. v. Schutte, 103 U. S. 118, cited with approval in Union Pacific R. R. Co. v. Mason City, etc., R. R. Co., igg U. S. 160. "Rep. 590. 138 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW of judicial opinion. Let us consider as an example in this connection Chief Justice Marshall's decision in Cohens v. Virginia.^'' In that case the plaintiff in error had been indicted and put to trial and penalty under a Virginia statute for selling tickets for a lottery which Congress had chartered for the District of Columbia. As in the Dred Scott case, the primary question before the court was one of jurisdiction, though in this case the Su- preme Court's own jurisdiction, which counsel for Vir- ginia denied upon the ground, among others, that a State was defendant contrary to the Eleventh Amend- ment. This objection Marshall met in the following terms : "It is, then, the opinion of the court, that the defendant who removes a judgment rendered against him by a State court into this court, for the purpose of examining the question whether that judgment be in violation of the Constitution or laws of the United States, does not commence or prosecute a suit against the State."^® This utterance has from that day to the present been regarded as establishing the law on the point with which it deals, — and a vastly important point it plainly is.^* Yet by the test set up by the critics of Chief Justice Taney's opinion in Scott v. Sanford, the utterance is not decisive; for its author continues thus : "But should we in this be mistakeUj the error does not affect the case now before the conrt," since plaintiff in error is not "a citizen of an- "6 Wheat. 264. "/&. 411-12. " See, for example, Holmes v. Jennison, 14 Pet. 624 and Prigg V. Pa., 16 Pet. 539; also, Ableman v. Booth, 21 How. 506. THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 139 Other State" nor the "subject of any foreign State," but a citizen of Virginia herself.^" In short, the critics of Chief Justice Taney take their view of the proper scope of judicial decisions from a particular line of Common Law precedents rather than from American Constitutional Law. Altogether, the only feasible definition, historically, of obiter dictum in the field of American Constitutional Law would seem to be, a more or less casual utterance by a court or members thereof upon some point not deemed by the court itself to be strictly before it and not necessary to decide, as preliminary to the deter- mination of the controversy before it. Such an utter- ance, for example, is that of Chief Justice Marshall at the close of his decision in Brown v. Maryland, where he says that he "supposes" that the principles he has just applied to a case arising in connection with for- eign commerce would also apply in a case of commerce among the States. ^^ This pronouncement is obviously an aside upon a point not argued before the Court and it is quite justifiably ignored by Chief Justice Taney in his opinion in the License Cases,^^ whereas the rest of Marshall's opinion in Brown- v. Maryland Taney treats as law, though the entire second portion of it, dealing with the "commerce" clause, was unnecessary, since the immediate issue before the court had already been disposed of under Article I, § 10, of the Constitution. Chief Justice Taney had therefore, it appears, a clear right to canvass the question of Dred's servitude =° See note 18. ^' 12 Wheat, 419, 449- ^5 How. 504, 574-578; see also J. McLean, ib. 594. 140 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW in support of his decision that Dred was not a citizen of the United States, and he had the same right to canvass the question of the constitutionality of the Missouri Compromise in support of his decision that Dred was a slave. To all these points his attention was invited by arguments of counsel and to all of them he might cast it with propriety by a well-estab- lished view of the scope of judicial inquiry in such matters. If then the decision rendered by six of the nine judges on the bench, that the Missouri Compro- mise was unconstitutional, is to be stigmatized as un- warrantable, which is all that the court of history can do with it, it is not by pronouncing it to have been obiter dictum but by discrediting, from the standpoint of the history of Constitutional Law antedating the decision, the principles upon which it was rested. Ill Turning then to consider the constitutional decision directly, we find our task simplified to this extent: that the entire court, majority and dissenting minority alike, are in unanimous agreement upon the proposi- tion that, whatever the source of its power, whether Article IV, § 3 of the Constitution or the right to acquire territory and therefore to govern it. Con- gress in governing territory is controlled by the Con- stitution — a proposition to which the court has always adhered, though there has been latterly some alter- ation of opinion as to what provisions of the Consti- tution are applicable in this connection. And this was the question that troubled the majority in the Dred Scott case. The Missouri Compromise was unconsti- THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 141 tutional, that was certain ; but just why — that was im- mensely uncertain. The extremest position of all was taken by Justice Campbell, whose doctrine was that the only power Congress had in the territories, in addition to its powers as the legislature of the United States, was the power to make rules and regulations of a conservatory character "for the preservation of the public domain, and its preparation for sale or disposition." From this it was held to follow that whatever the Constitu- tion and laws of the States "validly determine to be property, it is the duty of the Federal Government, through the domain of jurisdiction merely federal, to recognize to be property."^^ This of course was the extremest Calhounism, from which it came later to be deduced, with perfect logic, that it was the duty of the Federal Government, not only to admit slavery into the territory, but to protect it there. But, as Benton showed in his famous Examination of the Dred Scott Case, this particular phase of Calhounism was, at the date of the Dred Scott decision, less than ten years old. But now it is a common view with historians, a view obviously traceable to Benton, that this decision rested exclusively upon Calhounist premises. Nothing could be farther from the fact. For though Justice Daniel of Virginia went almost as far as Justice Campbell in representing the power of Congress in governing the territories as a simple proprietary power of supervision, yet even he rejected Campbell's notion that Congress was the mere trustee of the States; ^ Rep. 509-517; the quotations are from pp. 514 and 515. 142 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW while Justices Catron of Tennessee, an old Jacksonian Democrat, Grier of Pennsylvania and of similar tradi- tions, Wayne, a Southern Whig, and the Chief Justice himself, could by no means consent thus to read the Constitution through the spectacles of the prophet of nullification. Upon what grounds then were these judges to rest their pronouncement of the unconstitu- tionality of the Compromise ? Let us first take up the case of Catron and then turn to that of the Chief Justice, who spoke upon this point for himself, for Grier and Wayne, and to some extent for Daniel. Catron paid his respects to the Calhounist point of view in the following words : "It is due to myself to say, that it is asking much of a judge, who has for nearly twenty years been exercising jurisdiction, from the western Missouri line to the Rocky Mountains, and, on this understanding of the Constitution," namely that Congress has power really to govern the territories, "inflicting the extreme penalty of death for crimes committed where the direct legislation of Con- gress was the only rule, to agree that he had been all the while acting in mistake, and as an usurper." Set- ting out from this extremely personal point of view, Catron found that Congress possessed sovereignty over its territory, limited however in this case by the treaty with France, with which the anti-slavery article of the Missouri Compromise was, he held, incom- patible, and always by the "spirit" of the Constitution, which stipulates for the citizens of each State "the privileges and immunities of citizens m the several States."^* ^'Rep. 522-527. THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 143 A more extravagant line of reasoning it would be difficult to conceive. It is true that, at this date, the Supreme Court had not itself as yet had occasion to determine finally the legal effect of a congressional enactment in conflict with an earlier treaty, but the generally recognized doctrine was clearly that the treaty-making power could not prejudice Congress in the exercise of its granted powers; and this view had registered itself in reputable judicial decision only a few years before the Dred Scott decision, while to- day, of course, it is established law.^^ But the appeal to Article IV, § 2, of the Constitution, significantly vague as it was, was even less warrantable. All that this section of the Constitution was ever supposed to require was that no State should deny citizens of another State sojourning within its boundaries the personal rights of its own citizens, — personal rights, that is, as distinguished from political rights.^® Yet Catron seeks, not only to extend this provision to the powers of Congress, but also to make it guarantee citizens of States the rights enjoyed by them in their home States in every other State and territory of the Union ! One of Lincoln's criticisms of Scott v. San- ford was that logically it prohibited even the States from forbidding slavery within their respective limits. Restricted to Catron's opinion the criticism was valid. But the most strongly nationalistic, or more precisely ^° See the writer's National Supremacy (N. Y. 1913), 9-12 and references. The decision referred to was Taylor v. Morton, 2 Curt. 454 (i8ss). The law today is laid down in 112 U. S. 580 (1884), 122 ib. 116 (1887), 124 ib. 190 (1888), 130 ib. 581 (1889), 149 ib- 698 (1893). '"See Federalist No. 42, pp. 264-6 (Lodge's Ed.). 144 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW federalistic, of all the opinions upon the constitutional question was that of the Chief Justice, who, again following Marshall, traced the power of Congress to govern territories to its power to acquire them. Upon what ground then was he to rest his condemnation of the Missouri Compromise ? In one or two passages Taney speaks of Congress as "trustee," but it is as trustee of the "whole people of the Union" and for all its powers. The limitations upon the power of Congress must therefore, in this case as in all cases, be sought in the Constitution, "from which it derives its own existence, and by virtue of which alone it continues to exist and act as a government and sov- ereignty." From this it follows that when Congress enters a territory of the United States it cannot "put off its character and assume discretionary or despotic powers which the Constitution has denied to it" : it is still bound by the Constitution.^'^ Therefore Con- gress can make no law for the territories with respect to establishing a religion, nor deny trial by jury therein, nor compel anyone to be a witness against himself in a criminal proceeding. "And," the Chief Justice continues, "The rights of private property have been guarded with equal care." They "are united with the rights of persons '' Rep. 448-9. The italics are mine. Taney develops the doctrine that the U. S. can acquire territory only for the pur- pose of ultimately making States of it. This doctrine exactly reverses the argument, regarded sympathetically by Jefferson himself, against the validity of the La. Purchase : Henry Adams, History, II, chs. 4 and 5. Taney's opinion at this point was probably drawn in part from J. McKinley's opinion in Pollard's Lessee v. Hagan, 3 How. 212 (1845). THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 145 and placed on the same ground by the Fifth Amendment to the Constitution, which provides that no person shall be deprived of life, liberty and property without due process of law. And an act of Congress which deprived a citizen of the United States of his liberty or property merely because he came himself or brought his property into a particular territory of the United States, and who had committed no offense against the laws, could hardly be dignified with the name of due process of law. . . . The powers over person and property of which we speak are not only not granted to Congress, but are in express terms denied. . . . And this prohibition is not confined to the States, but the words are general and extend to the whole territory over which the Constitution gives it power to legislate. ... It is a total absence of power everywhere within the dominions of the United States, and places the citizens of a territory, so far as these rights are concerned, on the same footing with citizens of the States. . . . And no word can be found in the Consti- tution which gives Congress a greater power over slave property, or which entitles property of that kind to less protection than property of any other description. The only power conferred is the power coupled with the duty of guarding and protecting the owner in his rights. "^^ Undoubtedly it must be conceded at the outset that in asserting for slave property a position within the Constitution equal to that of any other kind of prop- erty, the Chief Justice was entirely in the right, his Free Soil and Republican critics to the contrary not- withstanding. Their position, which was represented for the nonce in Justice McLean's dissenting opinion, was that there was a difference between slave property and other kinds of property arising from the alleged fact that slavery was contraiy to natural law, and that consequently, while the Constitution recognized prop- =^Rep. 450-1- 146 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW erty in slaves within the States where slavery was permitted, it did not recognize it within the terri- tories. The argument was both erroneous and beside the point. Under our system of government title is acquired to property in nine cases out of ten under the jurisdiction of particular States and in accordance with the laws thereof, but once it has been so acquired, the subject-matter, whatever it be, is recognized by the Constitution as the property of its owner and his right to it as entitled to the protection of the Constitution. But does this concession warrant the final sentence just quoted from the Chief Justice's opinion : "The only power conferred is the power coupled with the duty of guarding and protecting the owner in his rights" ? Plainly not, unless, first. Congress must always assume a protective attitude toward all prop- erty in the exercise of all of its powers, or secondly, slave property occupied in 1857, not simply a position of equality with other property in the Constitution, but one of superiority. In behalf of the latter inter- pretation of his position, however, the Chief Justice offers not a word of proof. On the contrary, his whole argument is an implied disavowal of such an interpretation. Considering his repeated assertion that Congress is a sovereign legislature in the exercise of what powers belong to it, it seems clear that we can do his argument full justice only by treating it as tantamount to the proposition that Congress in the exercise of its powers has the same control of property, of whatever description, that any government would THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 147 have in the exercise of the same powers, limited by the prohibitions of the Constitution in protection of property. But what provision of the Constitution protective of the property right does the Chief Justice rely upon in this instance? As we have just seen, the "duey' process of law" clause of the Fifth Amendment. This, he recites, "provides that no person shall be deprived of life, liberty, and property, without due process of law. And," he comments, "an act of Congress which deprives a citizen of the United States of his liberty or propeity merely because he came himself or brought his property into a particular territory of the United States, and who had committed no offence against the laws could hardly be dignified with the name of due jM'ocess of law." At first approach there are two striking features to this argument, first, its apparent irrelevancy and sec- ondly, its apparent begging of the question. It is ad- mitted that property may be taken for "an offense against the laws," but it is implied that there has been no such offense. But this implication assumes the very point to be proved, namely, the unconstitution- ality of the act of Congress under review. For if this was constitutional it was law, and an attempt to take slaves into a territory in contravention of it was "an offense against the laws." And not less striking is the matter of irrelevancy. For to the lay mind the term "due process" suggests simply correct procedure, and in the Dred Scott case no question of procedure was involved, the antagonists of the Missouri Com- 148 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW promise being opposed, not to the method of its en- forcement but to its enforcement at all, not to the mode of its operation but to its substance. However, once we consult the Constitutional Law of the period, both these difificulties disappear and the question of the historical validity of Chief Justice Taney's argument stands before us on its merits.^® Throughout the States in 1857, it was a generally acknowledged principle that there were certain limits beyond which legislative power was inherently in- capable of proceeding in control of an owner's right to his property, that what the law once recognized to be property legislative power could not invade unduly. By the same date moreover, in some of the States, this principle had become established upon the "due process of law" and "law of the land" clauses of their respective' constitutions. And thus much for the sup- posed irrelevancy of the Chief Justice's argument. But by the same line of reasoning, the petitio principii pointed out therein also vanishes. For if the due process clause prohibits legislation bearing with undue severity upon existing property rights, then all new legislation affecting such rights must be compared in this reference with the law which already defined those rights. In other words, the term "laws" comes to mean the law as it stood before the new legislation was enacted; and "offenses against the laws" means offenses against the law thus defined. What, then, in 1857, was that undue severity against ^ For a fuller consideration of the subjects treated immedi- ately below, see my articles in 24 Harv. Law Rev., 366 flfg., 460 ffg. THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 149 existing property rights which automatically con- signed legislative acts to the wastebasket? To begin with, every court in the country acknowledged that private property could be taken by government for only public uses, and further, that it could be so taken only upon just compensation to the owner. But at this point agreement ceased. In the years immediately preceding the Dred Scott decision, many States passed anti-liquor acts which, generally speaking, prohibited not only the sale of intoxicating liquors save for medi- cinal purposes and by licensed chemists, but also the keeping of them, when not designed for this purpose, elsewhere than in the dwelling of the owner; and such acts applied equally to liquors in existence at the mo- ment of their going into effect and to liquors to be acquired in the future. In objection to them, accord- ingly, the argument soon began to be shaped, that though they did not purpose to transfer to the State outright the title to existing stocks of liquor, they were in fact, in relation to these, equivalent to acts of confiscation and void as such. Yet in twelve States statutes of this description were upheld as plainly within legislative power. Only in New York in the case of Wynehamer v. the People,^" was the act of the legislature disallowed as contrary to the con- stitutional requirement of due process. Now it is an interesting circumstance that the pub- lished briefs of counsel in Scott v. Sanford make no reference to the Fifth Amendment.^^ And connected with this circumstance is another not less interesting, ■"13 N. Y. 378 (1856). ='See Lawyer's Edition, Bk. XV, 691-8. ISO DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW namely, that Wynehamer v. the People was decided by the New York court of appeals at the very close of the interval between the first and second argument of Scott V. Sanford. All things consideixd, there can be little doubt that Chief Justice Taney took his doctrine from the New York court of appeals. v/ Does then Wynehamer v. the People furnish a precedent for Scott V. Sanford? Unquestionably it does, if %ve as- sume that there was already slave property in the territory governed by the eighth section of the Mis- souri Compromise at the date of its enactment. But this, the Chief Justice does not attempt to show, nor indeed, does he mention the point. Also this consider- ation would not, necessarily certainly, have affected the validity of the Compromise as to slave property brought into the territory at a later date. But finally, even if we give this precedent its widest possible oper- ation, yet it represented the doctrine of a single State and was in fiat conflict with the doctrine of a fidl dozen other States. But now let us recall once more the acknowledged purpose of the court in entering upon the constitu- tional question in Scott v. Sanford. It was to settle the question of Congress' power over slavery in the territories, — which meant, however, not Congress' power over slavery actually existing in the territories, but its power to prevent slaves from being brought into the territories henceforth. And on this question the New York precedent throws not the least light. Two of the judges in the Wynehamer case expressed the opinion that the withdrawal of the right of sale THE DRED SCOTT DECISION 151 from subsisting owners would alone suffice to invali- date a legislative act, but the other judges gave no countenance to this doctrine, and the court itself later formally disavowed it. The decision in the case is based solely on the proposition that the total effect of the act before the court was the destruction of certain existing property. But for the Chief Justice to have contended that the prohibition by Congress of slavery in the territories effected anything like a destruction of existing slave property outside the territories would have been absurd in the extreme, nor in fact does he venture to hint such a notion. The only purpose of the Missouri Compromise and of later acts of Congress of the same character, and their only effect, was to withdraw from owners out- side the territories governed by them the right to enter there with their slaves. Viewed in this light there can be no doubt that so far as available Constitutional Law stood in 1857, these acts were entirely valid under the Fifth Amendment. Otherwise, as Justice Curtis inquired in his dissenting opinion, what was to be said of the Ordinance of 1787, which Virginia and other States had ratified notwithstanding the presence of similar clauses in their constitutions? What again was to be said, upon that hypothesis, of the act of Virginia herself, passed in 1778, which prohibited the further importation of slaves? What was to be said of numerous decisions in which this and analogous laws had been upheld and enforced by the courts of Maryland and Virginia, against their own citizens who had purchased slaves abroad, and that without IS2 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW anyone's thinking to question the validity of such laws on the ground that they were not law of the land or due process of law? What was to be said of the act of Congress of 1808 prohibiting the slave trade and the assumption of the Constitution that Congress would have that power without its being specifically bestowed, but simply as an item of its power to regu- late commerce? What finally, if the scope of con- gressional authority to legislate was thus limited by the Fifth Amendment, was to be said of the Embargo Act, which had borne with peculiar severity upon the people of the New England States, but the constitu- tionality of which had been recently asserted by the court in argument in the roundest terms.^^ Nonetheless, subsequent developments in our con- stitutional jurisprudence prove that Taney chose his ground in Scott v. Sanford with some prescience. In- deed, even before the War, the Republican ci-itics of the decision, instead of utilizing Curtis's very effective ^ Rep. 626-627 ; the Virginia cases cited are S Call 425 and i Leigh 172, and the Maryland case is 5 Harr. and J. 107. The learned justice might have added 2 Munf. (Va.) 393. The case in which the Embargo Act was adverted to was U. S. v. Mari- gold, g How. 560, in which the court upheld an act of Congress prohibiting the importation of fraudulent coins. Justice Curtis should also have inquired how, upon the Chief Justice's argu- ment, Congress had power to exclude goods purchased by Ameri- can citizens abroad "merely because" the duty had not been paid on them. See also C. J. Marshall in Gibbons v. Ogden, 9 Wheat. I, 196-7 (1821), where the doctrine is stated that the only limi- tations to the power of Congress is regulating foreign and in- terstate commerce are the purely political limitations which arise from the responsibility of Congress to its constituents. See also Fed. Nos. 23 and 33, for similar doctrine as to some other powers of Congress. & THE DRED SCOTT DECISION IS3 dissent at this point, themselves pounced upon the Fifth Amendment and by emphasizing the word "liberty" in it, instead of the word "property," based upon it the dogma that Congress could not allow slavery in the territories.^* After the Civil War Taney's Republican successor, Chase, invoked the Amendment in his opinion in Hepburn v. Griswold in the same sense in which Taney had invoked it, but only as a limitation upon the implied powers of Con- gress.*'' This doctrine was flatly rejected by the court itself, speaking through Justice Strong, in Knox v. Lee?^ Yet a few years later, Strong too was elaborat- ing the Taney-Chase point of view in his dissenting opinion in the Sinking Fund cases,*® and connect- ing it with the early New York and North Carolina precedents. But of course, the most noteworthy applications of the doctrine of Due Process of Law have been made by the courts in their interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment, the terms "liberty" and "property" in ^ See the Republican Platform of i860, par. 8. At this point the Republicans followed McLean's opinion rather than Curtis's. Xote the significance in this connection of the discussion as to whether slavery was recognized by the Constitution ; and also of the discussion as to whether it was recognized by natural law. ^'S Wall. 603, 624; see J. Miller's cogent answer, ib. 637-638. Also, see the Chief Justice's own decision in Veazie Batik v. Fenno in the same volume of reports, 533 ffg. ^ 12 Wall. 457, SSI. C. J. Chase elaborates upon his earlier argument under the Fifth Amendment at 580-582. "'99 U. S. 700, 737-739. See also the various justices in the Northern Securities Company case, 193 U. S. 197, 332, 362, 397-400. See also J. Harlan in Adair v. United States, 208 U. S. 161, 172-174; cf. J. McKenna, ib. 180-190, and J. Holmes, 191. IS4 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW which are to-day given a very extended significance. This development, however, has been matched by the pari passu development of the doctrine that legislative power extends, generally speaking, to the enactment of all reasonable laws and that such laws are "due process." The legislative stagnation that the earlier doctrine logically imported has thus been obviated. But at the same time, we have to give the Dred Scott case a place in the line of precedents from which has finally emerged one of the most fruitful doctrines of modern Constitutional Law.^^ IV But there is one other topic worth our brief con- sideration before closing this paper, namely, the char- acter of the issue between Chief Justice Taney and Justice Curtis upon the question of citizenship raised by Dred's attempt to sue in the federal courts. | The usual view of the issue referred to is that it resolved itself into a dispute as to whether negroes were in any case capable of citizenship at the time of the adoption of the Constitution. This account of the matter is inaccurate.^ A careful comparison of Chief Justice Taney's opinion with that of Justice Curtis reveals the fact that the fundamental issue between the two, though it is not very specifically joined, is not whether there may not have been negro citizens of States in 1787 who upon the adoption of the Constitution be- came citizens of the United States, but from what source citizenship within the recognition of the Consti- " See. the present writer in 7 Mich. Law Rev. 642 ffg. THE DRED SCOTT DECISION iSS tution was supposed to flow thenceforth. UiX)n this point, Curtis's view was that citizenship within the recognition of the Constitution in the case of persons born within the United States was through the States, while Taney's view was that a "citizen of the United States," to use his frequent phrase, always, unless de- scended from those who became citizens at the time of the adoption of the Constitution, owed his character as such to some intervention of national authority — was, in short, a product of the National Government.^^ Curtis's theory, it can hardly be doubted, was that of the framers of the Constitution, wherefore Taney's pretense of carrying out not only the spirit but the very letter of the Constitution as it came from the framers, becomes at this point particularly hollow.^'* On the other hand, Taney's view is a very logical, and indeed inevitable, deduction from his whole body of doctrine with reference to the dual nature of the federal system: the States independent and sovereign within their sphere and the National Government within its. This theory Taney had voiced from the beginning of his judicial career, so that, at this point he was at least acting consistently with his past. Also, without doubt, the doctrine in question was pretty well ^ Taney states his position on this point at pp. 404-406 and 417-422 of the Report, and Curtis states his at p. 581. ^ Taney translates the "'citizens of each State" clause of the Constitution as "citizens of the United States," but the deriva- tion of this clause from the Articles of Confederation forbids any such notion. The original source of the Chief Justice's argument on the citizenship question is to be found in Reports of Committees, No. 80, 27th Congress, 3rd session, a very in- structive document. 156 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW established by 1857, both in judicial decision and in political thinking.*" To summarize : I conclude, first, that the Dred Scott decision was not obiter dictum within any defi- nition of obiter dictum obtainable from a fair review of the practice of the Supreme Court, particularly under Marshall, in constitutional cases; secondly, that it was not based by the majority of those entering into it upon Calhounist premises; and thirdly, that Justice Curtis's supposed refutation of Taney's argument upon the question of Dred's title to a prima fa^ie citizenship within the recognition of the Constitution is a fiction. None of these results, however, goes far to relieve that decision of its discreditable character as a judicial ut- terance. When, as in this case, the student finds six judges arriving at precisely the same result by three distinct processes of reasoning, he is naturally dis- posed to surmise that! the result may possibly have induced the processes rather than that the processes compelled the result,\\ though of course such surmise is not necessarily sound; but when he discovers fur- ther that the processes themselves were most deficient in that regard for history and precedent in which judicial reasoning is supposed to abound, his surmise becomes suspicion; and finally when he finds that be- yond reasoning defectively upon the matter before " For a good statement of this doctrine, see Taney's opinion in Ableman v. Booth, cited supra in note 19. It should he noted in passing that this elucidation of the real is^e between Taney and Curtis on the citizenship question throws additional light on the close relation existing in Taney's mind between the ques- tion of Dred's seniitudc and that of his citizenship. THiE -DRED SCOTT DECISION IS7 them, the same judges deliberately gloss over material distinctions (as for example, in this case, the dis- tinction between sojourn and domicile) and ignore precedents that they have themselves created (as for example, in this case, the decisions regarding the operation of State decisions upon questions of comity) his suspicion becomes conviction. The Dred Scott decision cannot be, with accuracy, written down as usurpation, but it can and must be written down as a gross abuse of trust by the body which rendered it. The results from that abuse of trust were moreover momentous. During neither the Civil War nor the period of Reconstruction did the Supreme Court play anything like its due role of supervision, with the re- sult that during the one period the military powers of the President underwent undue expansion, and dur- ing the other the legislative powers of Congress. The court itself was conscious of its weakness, yet not- withstanding its prudent disposition to remain in the background, at no time since Jefferson's first admin- istration has its independence been in greater jeopardy than in the decade between i860 and 1870; so slow and laborious was its task of recuperating its shat- tered reputation. SOME POSSIBILITIES IN THE WAY OF TREATY-MAKING SO'ME POSSIBILITIES IN THE WAY OF TREATY-MAKING ^ Under date of September 26, 1906, seven European nations entered into a treaty by which they agreed to prohibit within their respective dominions night work for women, and into another treaty by which they similarly agreed to prohibit the use of white phos- phorus in the manufacture of matches. These same countries have also entered into treaties with regard to the insurance of workmen against industrial acci- dents. Lastly, proposals which have already been formulated are to be submitted in September of the present year for an international agreement prohibit- ing the night work of young persons and fixing the maximum working day for women and young per- sons. The question arises, why, if other countries may enter into and carry into effect such engage- ments, may not the United States? The powers of the National Government, though enumerated, are each of them sovereign powers and keep pace in their development with the enlargement of the subject-matter amenable to them. Said the court in South Carolina v. the United States: "The Constitution is a written instrument. As such its meaning does not alter, and what it meant when adopted it means now. Being a grant of powers to a government, '^The following paper was read at the 20th annual tneeting of the Lake Mohawk Conference on International Arbitration, May 28, 1914- 161 i62 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW its language is general, and as changes come in social and political life, it embraces in its grasp all new con- ditions which are within the scope of the powers in terms conferred. In other words, while the powers granted do not change, they apply from generation to generation to all things to which they are in their nature applicable."^ With the growth of international trade relations, immigration, and other forms of international inter- course, the conditions of life within particular nations become of ever increasing concern to their neighbors, with the result that treaty-making among the inde- pendent states of the world tends to extend to matters earlier deemed to lie quite without its sphere. In this general development the United States must and does participate and for the resultant legal responsi- bilities the powers of the National Government are, if we adhere to the historically settled canons of Constitutional Law bearing on the subject, entirely adequate. In the words of Chief Justice Marshall: "The Constitution [was] intended to endure for ages and consequently to be adapted to the various crises of human affairs."^ ^ 199 U. S. 437, 448-9. See also J. Moody in ///. Cent. R. R. Co. V. Howard., 207 U. S. 463, 520: "It is said that Congress has never before enacted legislation of this nature for the government of interstate commerce by land . . The funda- mental fallacy of this argument is that it misunderstands the nature of the Constitution . . . and forgets that its unchanging provisions are adaptable to the infinite variety of the changing conditions of our national life." C. J. Waite's wrell-known ut- terance in the Pensacola Tel. Co. v. the Western Un. Tel. Co. 96 U. S. I, should also be recalled in this connection. ^4 Wheat. 316, 415. Note also his words in the same place, p. 407 : "We cannot comprehend the train of reasoning which would maintain that the extent of power granted by the people TREATY-MAKING 163 But it will be objected that the regulation of the hours and conditions of labor falls in the United States to what is called the "police powers" of the States. This is true, but that fact does not withdraw the same subject from regulation by the National Government in the bona fide exercise of its powers. The National Government has only certain enumerated powers, but it may exercise these powers for all the legitimate purposes of government that events may bring within their reach. A like objection to the one just recited was made to the recent Mann Act forbidding the trans- portation of women from one State to another for immoral purposes. This, said the objectors, did not regulate commerce among the States for commercial purposes, but for moral purposes, and so invaded the power of the States to regulate the public morals. But Justice McKenna, speaking for the unanimous Court, replied : "Our dual form of government has its perplexities. State and Nation having different spheres of jurisdiction, but it must be kept in mind that we are one people ; and the powers reserved to the States and those conferred on the Nation are adapted to be exercised, whether inde- pendently or concurrently, to promote the general wel- fare, material and moral."* is to be ascertained, not by the nature and terms of the grant, but by its date." Note also the words of J. Story in Martin v. Hunter's Lessee, i Wheat. 304, 326: "The Constitution una- voidably deals in general language. . . . The instrument was not intended to provide merely for the exigencies of a few years, but was to endure through a long lapse of ages, the events of which were locked up in the inscrutable purposes of Providence." These words are quoted less as stating a rule of law however, than as indicating the point of view from which the Constitution must be construed if it is to last. *227 U. S. 308, 322. i64 DOCTRINE O'F JUDICIAL REVIEW The utterance is in the very spirit of the words of the Preamble of the Constitution. Suppose, however, that the action taken by the National Government conflicts with that taken by the State with reference to the same subject-matter? The pertinent provision of the Constitution is undoubtedly Art. VI, par. 2 : "This Constitution, the acts of Congress in pursuance thereof, and the treaties made or which shall be made under the authority of the United States, are the supreme law of the land; and the judges of each State shall be bound thereby, anything in the constitution or laws of any State to the contrary notwithstanding." Words could not be plainer than these, especially when they are given their historical setting. The Convention of 1787 desired nothing so much as to get rid of that State intervention which had wrecked the Articles of Confederation. This it ac- complished in four ways : i — By referring the Con- stitution to the People ; 2 — By providing the National Government with executive machinery of its own; 3 — By making the national Supreme Court the final interpreter of the Constitution; 4. — By providing for the supremacy in all cases of national authority as defined by the Constitution over conflicting State authority. The point of view of the Convention was voiced by Wilson thus : "With respect to the province and object of the General Government they [the States] should be considered as having no existence."^ '' See Madison's Notes, under date of June 25. Equally to the point was Read of Delaware's earlier objection to a proposition that the U. S. should guarantee the several States in their territory: "It abetted the idea of distinct States, which would TREATY-MAKING 165 Later a motion was offered in the Convention pro- hibiting the National Government "to interfere with the government of the individual States in any mat- ter of internal police which respects the government of such State only and wherein the general welfare of the United States is not concerned." Despite the careful language in which it was couched the motion was voted down by eight States to two.® The view that the reserved powers of the States comprise an independent limitation on national power probably found expression for the first time in the debate on Hamilton's Bank Project of 1791. Op- posed as he was to the Bank, Madison pronounced the argument fallacious : "Interference with the powers of the States," said he, "was no constitutional criterion of the power of Congress. If the power was not given, Congress could not exercise it; if given, they might exercise it, although it should interfere with the laws or even the constitution of the States."''^ Nevertheless, a generation later the same notion was again afoot. "It has been contended," recites Chief Justice Marshall in his opinion in Gibbons v. Ogden, "that if a law passed by a State in the exercise of its acknowledged sovereignty comes into conflict with a law passed by Congress in pursuance of the Constitu- be a perpetual source of discord." The proposition was then altered to the present guaranty of "'a republican form of gov- ernment" and was agreed to, nem. con.: ib. under date of June II. Considering the fact that territorial cessions so often fur- nish the purpose of treaties, the refusal of the Convention to make the guarantee in question is particularly significant. 'Loc. cit. under date of July 17. ' Annals of Cong. II, col. 1891. The emphasis is mine. i66 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW tion, they affect the subject and each other hke equal and opposing powers." "But," the Chief-Justice answered, J "The framers of our Constitution foresaw this state of things and provided for it, by declaring the supremacy not only of itself but of the laws made in pursuance of it. The nullity of any act inconsistent with the Consti- tution is produced by the declaration that the Constitu- tion is the supreme law. The appropriate application of that part of the clause which confers the same supremacy on laws and treaties is to such acts of Sta,te legislatures as do not transcend their powers, but, though enacted in the execution of acknowledged State powers, interfere with, or are contrary to the laws of Congress made in pursuance of the Constitution, or some treaty made un- der the authority of the United States. In every such case, the act of Congress or the treaty is supreme; and the law of the State, though enacted in the exercise of powers not controverted, must yield to it."* I admit that with the advance of the dissolving theories of the Great NuUifier, in the period between the death of Marshall and the Civil War, the doctrine of Gibbons v. Ogden was temporarily abandoned for the view that State power comprised of itself a limi- tation upon national power. Indeed, this view is, after all, but a particular form of Calhoun's doctrine. For while the actual business of nullifying national author- ity is farmed out, so to say, with the Supreme Court, the pretended basis of the power, namely, the vast, undefined powers of the States, remains the same. But th€ crucial fact is that the Supreme Court has to-day i-eturned to first principles. Of this such deci- sions as those in Henderson v. New York,^ in re '9 Wheat. I, 210-11 (1824). The emphasis is mine. "92 U. S. 279 (187s). TREATY-MAKING 167 Rahrer,^^ the recent Employers' Liability Cases/^ and Minnesota Rate Cases,^^ furnish proof positive, to say nothing of a host of dicta. Thtis in the Employers' Liabihty Cases, the court was confronted with the now notorious decision of Chief Justice Baldwin of the Connecticut supreme court in the Hoxie case, in which enforcement had been refused the act of Congress on the ground of its disharmony with "the policy of the State." Strangely unaware as the Connecticut court showed itself to be of the established canons of Constitutional Law, its view must after all be admitted to have been the in- evitable one if the reserved powers of the States limit national power. But, as I say, the Supreme Court of the United States no longer subscribes to this doc- trine. The theory of the Connecticut court was ac- cordingly swept aside, in the following words taken from the court's earlier opinion in Smith v. Alabama: "The grant of power to Congress to regulate com- merce ... is paramount over all legislative powers wrhich, in consequence of not having been granted to Congress, are resented to the States. It follows that any legislation of a State, although in pursuance of an ac- knowledged power reserved to it, which conflicts with the actual exercise of the power of Congress over the sub- ject of commerce, must give way before the supremacy of the national authority."" In the Minnesota Rate Cases the Court invited Con- •°I42U. S. 545 (1891)- "^Mondou V. N. Y., N. H., and H. R. R. Co v. U. S. 223 U. S. ^Simpson v. Shephard 230 U. S. 352. '•■124 U. S. 465, 473 (if i68 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW gress to take over the business of regulating infra- State rates so far as might be necessary and proper to make effective its regulation of inter-State rates." And, as Marshall's words just quoted, indicate, the principles that determine the relation of Congress' power to State power also determine the relation of the national treaty-making power to State power. Certainly, no power falls more distinctly within the reserved powers of the States than the power to regu- late the tenure of real property. In this connection, note the language of Justice Field in United States v. Fox: "The power of the State to regulate the tenure of real property within her limits, and the modes of its acqui- sition and transfer, and the rules of its descent, and the extent to which testamentary disposition of it may be exercised by its owner, is undoubted."^" And again the language of Justice Washington in McCormick v. Sullivant: "The title and modes of disposition of real property within the States, whether inter vivos or testamentary, are not matters placed under the control of federal authority."^* Yet the same judges, with one exception, who decided the McCormick case also decided Chirac v. Chirac^''; the same judges, with one exception, who decided United States v. Fox also decided Hauenstein v. Lynham^^ ; and the judge who wrote the opinion in " See especially J. Hughes' language at p. 399 of the Report. "94 U. S. 31S, 320. ^° 10 Wheat. 192, 202. "2 Wheat. 2S9 (1817). "100 U. S. 483 (1879). TREATY-MAKING 169 the United States v. Fox again spoke for the court in Gcofroy v. Riggs}^ In each of these three cases the issue was the same; it lay between claimants to real estate whose right to the property involved was ad- mitted to be perfect under the local law and other claimants who asserted the right to claim the same property as heirs to it upon the basis of certain treaty provisions. In each case the decision of the United States Supreme Court, given unanimously, was in favor of the latter claimants; and the basis of the decision was in each case announced to be Article VI, par. 2. Later, reviewing these and similar deci- sions, Attorney-General Griggs stated the rule that they unmistakably establish : "The fact that a treaty provision anrmls and supersedes the law of a particu- lar State upon the same subject is no objection to the validity of the treaty."^'' In a word, what powers the States possess is a mat- ter of the utmost indi£ference in determining the scope of the treaty-making power of the United States. Or to put it otherwise, the United States has exactly the same range of power in making treaties that it would have if the States did not exist.^^ Let a matter arise that is of genuine international concern and the na- >"i33 U. S. 2S8 (1890). ^22 Opins. Atty. Gen'l 214. ^^ Of course the U. S. cannot, in view of its obligation to guarantee the States "a republican form of government" assume to control and direct the actual machinery of government within the States indefinitely. But that fact does not detract from the force of the statement in the text. For if there were no States, there would be no such machinery of government to control and direct to any extent. 170 DOCTRINE OF JUDICIAL REVIEW tional power to negotiate treaties with rejeretice to it and to give those treaties the force and effect of law of the land becomes perfected. At the present moment, I am informed from re- liable sources, an agreement is in process of negotiation with the Dominion of Canada which will have for its purpose the extension of the provisions of the recent Weeks-McLean Migratory Bird Law to the case of birds passing from Canada. It would be difficult to distinguish such a treaty in principle from one of the sort mentioned at the opening of this paper, for the State's police power with reference to its wild game is well settled.^^ The precedent will be the more precious from its origin with a State-rights Administration. ^ See e.g., Geer v. Conn. i6i U. S. 519. Mr. Henry Chase in his recent volume on Game Protection seems to think that while the Weeks-McLean Act is possibly unconstitutional as invading the police powers of the States, a treaty covering the same matter would not be open to this objection. That is a great mistake. If the reserved powers of the States restrict Congress in the exercise of its powers, then also do they restrict the national treaty-making power in its capacity to make "law of the land". My own belief is that the Weeks-McLean Act is perfectly constitutional as an act "necessary and proper" to protect the federal timber reserves. The act is analogous to congressional legislation intended to repress crime within districts subject to Congress' exclusive power of legislation. The authors of crimes committed within such dis- tricts, forts, arsenals, etc., are often tried outside them, within State territory. But if a resident of a State should attempt to rescue the culprit in such a case he would be subject to federal law. Likewise, if a resident of a State should withhold informa- tion with reference to a crime committed within a district subject to Congress' exclusive power, he would be guilty, under the act of Congress, of misprision of felony, and punishable there- for. And examples might be multiplied : Cohens v. Va. 6 TREATY-MAKING 171 The whole question, then, is wrapped up in the phrase "genuine international concern," and this, as I have indicated, is a thing ever advancing and de- veloping. What with cable, steamship, wireless tele- graphy, and inter-oceanic canals, the world to-day is astonishingly small and the consequence is that the nations can no longer live unto themselves in the way that was earlier possible. The rise of an international police power and of an international power of eminent domain, exercisable by the fitter members in the Family of Nations, is a development clear and palpable before our eyes. The development of uniform national legis- lation of social character, in pursuance of international agreement, is but another phase of the broader devel- opment of international solidarity. And it is the fundamental contention of this paper that the United States is competent to march abreast of this development.^^ Wheat. 264, 424-30. Congress, whatever of its powers it hap- pens to be exercising at any particular moment, is always the national legislature, and capable as such of giving its acts na- tion-wide operation, — so that they be passed in exercise of its constitutional powers. The only question with reference to the Migratory Bird Act is, then, whether its nation-wide oper- ation is a necessary and proper measure for the protection of national property of great value. Certainly, there can be no idispute about that. The efforts of the advocates of the law, however, to bring it within the "commerce" clause seem to me rather far-fetched. ^ For further discussion of the questions above considered, see the writer's National Supremacy (Holt and Co., N. Y., 1913) ; also, his article on the Treaty-Making Power in the North Am. Rev. for June, 1914. INDEX (The list of cases indexed is incomplete.) Acts of Congress : Alien and Sedition Laws, S6 j Judiciary Act of 1801, 57; Mann "White Slave" Act, 163; Weeks-McLean Migratory Bird Act, 170-1. See Judiciary Act of 1789. Adams, John : Characterizes the Congress of the Confederation "a diplomatic body," 118; see Writs of Assistance Case. Articles of Confederation : Declared to be paramount to State laws, 40-1 ; character of government under, 83, 112-24 passim. Baldwin, C. J. (Conn.) : Doctrine of, in the Hoxie case, 167. Bancroft, Geo. H. : Note by, on Barton's pamphlet, 125-6. Barton, Wm. : Urges a continental convention (1781), 125. Benton, Th. H. : Influence of his Examination of the Dred Scott case, 141. Blackstone, Sir Wm. : Doctrine of Parliamentary Sovereignty, 32-4, 52. Breckenridge, Sen. Jno. : States doctrine of departmental con- struction of the Constitution (1802), 58. Buchanan, Pres. : Participation of, in the Dred Scott decision, 132-3. Calhoun, Jno. C. : Theory of the Union and the Constitution, 82-4, 100-6; effect of doctrines on Constitutional Law, 166. Campbell, J.: Calhounist doctrines of, in Scott v. Sanford, 141. Cases: Ableman v. Booth, IS- Bayard v. Singleton, 39. Bow- man v. Middleton, 52. Brown v. Maryland, 139. Caldcr v. Bull, 53. Captain Streater's Case, 30-1 Chirac v. Chirac, 168-9. Chisholm v. Georgia, gg. Commonwealth v. Caton, 73. Cohens v. Virginia, 6, 7, 138-9. Cooper v. Telfair, 53. Dr. Bon- ham's Case, 28-30, 68-9. Eakin v. Raub 68, 76. Employers' Lia- bility Cases, 166-7. Geofroy v. Riggs 169. Gibbons v. Ogden, 165-6. Hauenstein v. Lynham, 168-9. Heyburn's Case, 50. Henderson v. New York, 166-7. Hepburn v. Griswold, 153. Holmes v. Walton, 72-3. Josiah Philips' Case, 71-2. Kam- per V. Hawkins, 52. Knox v. Lee, 153. McClung v. Silliman, 8-9. McCormick v. Swllivant, 68. McCulloch v. Maryland, 99, 161-2. Mclntire v. Wood, 173, 8-9. Marbwy v. Madison, i-io, 173 174 INDEX 60-1. Martin v. Hunter's Lessee, 99, 161-2. Martin v. Mott, 67, Ogden v. Blackledge, 53-4 Ogden v. Witherspoon, 53- -WJM- nesota Rate Cases, 166-7. Rahrer, in re, 166-7. Rutgers v. Waddington, 7Z- Scott v. Sanford, see article on Dred Scott Decision. Sinking Fund Cases, 153. Smith v. Alabama, 166-7. South Carolina v. United States, 161-2. ^jiwJ&Mry Caj^, 73. Trevett v. Weeden, 33-4, 74. United States v. Fo;ir, 168. C/m'- f^d States v. Hylton, 51. Winthrop v. Lechmere, 74-S- Writs of Assistance Case, 29-32. Wynehamer v. People, 149-51. Chase, C. J. : See Hepburn v. Griswold Chase, J. : Regards principle of separation of powers as merely "declaratory," 53. Catron, J. : Action in procuring the decision in S'foii v. ^aji- /orrf, 132 ; opinion of, in that case, 142-3. Citizenship: Source of, under the Constitution (1857), IS4-S- Coke, Sir Edw. : Theory of Fundamental Law and of Parlia- ment's power in relation thereto, 27-9; see Dr. Bonham's Case. Common Law : As a source of national jurisdiction, 55. Congress : Debates in, respecting the establishment of the De- partment of Foreign Affairs (1789), 48-9; debate and pro- ceeding in, on the act repealing the Judiciary Act of i8or, 57-9; debate in, on the first ten Amendments, 93-8; power of, in governing territories, 140-1 ; see Acts of Congress. Constitution of the United States : Art. Ill, § 2, 4-7, 14-5, 42 ; Art. IV, § 2, 143; same, § 3, 140; Art. VI, par. 2, 13-4, 43, 164-8; considered as an act of popular revolution, 84-S, 98-9, 106-8; canons of the liberal construction of, 161-2; see Pre- amble and Fifth Amendment. Constitutional Reaction (1780-87) : Phases and characteristic ideas of, 37-41. Constitutions : Basis of, in revolution, 34-5. Convention of 1787: Purposes of, 37-8, 164; see Judicial Review and Separation of Powers. Curtis, J.. Dissenting opinion of, in Scott v. Sanford, 151-2, IS4-S. Departmental Construction of the Constitution : Doctrine of, reviewed and criticized, 18-26, 66-8. Departmental Discretion: Doctrine of, 6o-i, 67. Dred Scott Case: Statement of facts in, 129-30; before the INDEX 175 Supreme Court, 130-3; alleged dictum in, 133-40; the consti- tutional question in, 140-53; citizenship question in, 153-5; effect of decision in, 156-7. Dual Sovereignty : Theory of, stated, 155-6. Due Process of Law : Modern doctrine of, 65, 153-4. Field, J. . See Geofroy v. Riggs and United States v. Fox. Fifth Amendment: Its operation as a general limitation on the powers of Congress, 147-54, passim. Franklin, Benj.: Albany Plan of, 115-6. Fundamental Law : Notion of, in relation to Parliament's power, see Coke. Grier, J. : Compliance of, in the Dred Scott case, 132. Griggs, Atty-Gen'l : On the supremacy of treaties, 169. Hamilton, Alex. : Argues for judicial review in the FederaHst, 44; on ratification of the Constitution, 90-1 ; letter of, to Duane (Sept. 3, 1780), 114-5, 125. Hayne, Sen. : His view of the Constitution, in debate with Webster (1830), 81. Hobart, J. (Eng.) . Reiterates Coke's dictum in Dr. Bonham's Case, 30. Holt, C. J. (Eng.) : See Hobart. Instruction: Doctrine of, debated in Congress (1789), 97. Jackson, Pres. : Veto Message of, stating doctrine of depart- mental construction (July 10, 1832), 21. Jefferson, Pres.: Fears the federal judiciary (1801), 57. Judicial Independence: Rise of demand for (1783-87), 40. Judicial Law-Making : Considerations governing, 64. Judicial Review : Bibliographical note on, i ; various grounds assigned for, in relation to acts of Congress, 1-2; action of Convention of 1787 respecting, 9-17, 42-4; logical basis of, 18-27, 63 ; general history of the idea before the adoption of the - Constitution, 27-44, 61-2; alleged precedents for, before 1787, 71-5 ; reception of the idea in the State ratifying con- ventions, 65-6; establishment of, in relation to acts of Con- gress (1787-1803), 45-61; history of, in the States, 75-7; a paradox in representative government, 45; objections to, in 1787, 46; Madison's vacillations respecting, 46-9, 55-7; Feder- alist support of (1802), 58-9; flexible basis of, today, 64-5 ; see Marbury v. Madison. Judiciary Act of 1789: Debate in Congress on, 55; Signifi- cance of 2Sth section of, 49; § 13, 4, 7-9; § 14, 8-9; § 11, 130. 176 INDEX Legislative Power: Early broad view of, 36-7; mingled with judicial power, 69-71 ; rise of a more restiricted view of, 37-9. Lincoln, Abr. : Theory of the Union, 82; criticism of the Dred Scott decision, 66, 143. McKenna, J. : On purposes of national power, 163. McLaughlin, Prof. A. C. : Explanation given by, of judicial re- view, 18-24, passim. McLean, J.: Makes political capital of the Dred Scott case, 131- Madison, Jas. : Report of, to the Virginia legislature (1799), 56, 103-4; on ratification of the Constitution, 89., 91-3, 107-8; compares Articles of Confederation and Constitution, 117; canon of constitutional construction respecting the relation of national to State power (1791), 165; see Judicial Review, Instruction, State Interposition, State Coercion, "State". Marshall, C. J. : Maxim of, for flexibile construction of the Constitution, 161 -2; construction by, of Art. VI, par. 2, of the Constitution, 166; see Marbury v. Madison, Ogden v. W'th- erspoon, Ogden v. Blackledge, Cohens v. Virginia, Gibbons v. Ogden, McCulloch v. Maryland. Martin, Luther : Genuine Information of, on the ratification of the Constitution, 90, 107. Mason, Geo. : See Writs of Assistance Case. Missouri Compromise: Eighth section of, 129; see Dred Scott Decision. National Power: Origin of, in the matter of taxation, 113-6; in relation to State power, 164-70. Nullification : See Secession, Calhoun. Obiter Dictum: Meaning of the term, especially in Constitu- tional Law, 123-9. Otis, Jas. : See Writs of Assistance Case. Parliament : See Coke, Blackstone, Smith. "People": Significance of term for Political Science (1787), 34-S, 98-9; see article on "We, the People". PoHce Power : See National Power. Preamble : No part of the Constitution, 95 ; as a clue to constitutional interpretation, 163-4. President: Doctrine of the immunity of, from jurisdiction, 61. Property: Position of, in Constitutional Law before the Civil War, 148-50. Revolution: Theory of the right of (1787), loi, 106-8. INDEX 177 Secession : No right of, under the original theory of the Con- stitution, loo-i. Separation of Powers: Place and meaning of the principle in the early State constitutions, 3S-7; relation of, to judicial re- view, 7, 8, 39; view taken of in the Convention of 1787, 41-2; recognized to be a legal principle, S3-4. Slaves: Recognized and protected as property by the Consti- tution, 145-6. Smith, Sir Th. : Theory of Parliament's power, 28. Stare Decisions: Application of, to constitutional decisions, 67-8. "State": Significance of term (1787-99), 98-9, 103. State Coercion : Urged by Madison and Pelatiah Webster, 123- S; rejected by the Convention of 1787, 125. State Interposition: Doctrine of, 81, 104. State Power : See National Power. Story, J.: Theory of the Constitution, 82; see Martin v. Hun- ter's Lessee. Strong, J. : See Knox v. Lee. Taney, C. J.: Opinion of, in Scott v. Sanford, criticized, 144-53. Taylor, Mr. Hannis : See article on Pelatiah Webster Myth. Treaties : Scope of national power in making, see article on Some Possibilities in the Way of Treaty-Making; some European conventions of a social character, 160. Virginia and Kentucky Resolutions (1798-99) : Doctrines of, 55-6, 81 ; underlying fallacy of, 102-4. Virginia Plan (1787) : Not harmonious with the principle of the separation of powers, 41-2. Washington, J. : See McCormick v. Sullivant. Wayne, J. : Activity in procuring the Dred Scott decision, 132. Webster, Sen. D. : Refutes doctrine of departmental construc- tion (1832), 21-2; theory of, regarding the Constitution (1830), 81. Webster, P. : Claims of, to be considered the originator of the Constitution considered, see article on The Pelatiah Webster Myth. "We, the People'' : Significance of phrase as used in the Con- stitution (1787), see article under this title. Wilson, Jas. : Theory of nature of the Constitution, 86-7; canon of constitutional construction (1787), 164. Date Due APIMJ5.2&. A^A'. ^^n**<"x<(ni mmmmmim '3 -4^^^-^ »i^*..S^ 1