/ ' ' THE GIFT OF .>/dl^...!o^^ .A.....H5... t +4.1. '....._... ?.?/£/.i2. Date Due Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924029078702 HUME'S TREATISE OF MORALS: AND SELECTIONS FROM THE TREATISE OF THE PASSIONS. WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY JAMES H. HYSLOP, Ph.D., Instructor in Logic, Ethics, and Psychology, Columbia College, New York. BOSTON, U.S.A.: PUBLISHED BY GINN & COMPANY. 1893. © The Philosophical Review EDITOR'S OFFICE l.;;.,i '■-■ iuJt> CORNELL UNIVERSITY Ithaca, IT. 7, rf Copyright, 1893, By GINN & COMPANY. All Rights Reserved. ©inn & Compang Gbe atbcnaeum press Boston EDITOR'S PROSPECTUS. The Ethical Series, of which this book on Hume's Ethics, by Dr. J. H. Hyslop, is the initial number, will consist of a number of small volumes, each of which will be devoted to the presentation of a leading system in the History of Modern Ethics, in selections or extracts from the original works. These selections will be accompanied by explana- tory and critical notes. They will also be introduced by a bibliography, a brief biographical sketch of the author of the system, a statement of the relation of the system to preceding ethical thought, and a brief explanation of the main features of the system and its influence on subsequent ethical thought. The volumes will be prepared by experi- enced teachers in the department of Ethics and with special reference to undergraduate instruction and study in colleges. The series at present will include six volumes as follows : Hobbes, Professor G. M. Duncan, Yale University ; Clarke, President F. L. Patton, Princeton University ; Locke, the Editor of the Series ; Hume, Dr. J. H. Hyslop, Columbia College ; Kant, Professor John Watson, Queen's University, Canada. Hegel, Professor J. Macbride Sterrett, Columbian University. The increasing interest in the study of Ethics and the consequent enlargement of the courses in college curricula, suggest to every teacher the need of better methods of teaching the subject than those which have quite generally EDITOR'S PROSPECTUS. prevailed in the past. Instruction in the History of Ethics, like instruction in the History of Philosophy, has largely been based on text-books or lectures giving expositions of, and information about, the various systems. Such methods, although serviceable, are not as stimulating and helpful as those which put the student in direct contact with the text of the author, enabling him to study the system itself rather than to study about the system. Undoubtedly the best plan would be to have the student read the entire work of the author, but all teachers will probably concede the impracticability of this in undergraduate work, if a num- ber of systems is to be studied, which is usually desirable. Only inferior, in my judgment, to the best, but impracticable plan, is the plan of the "Ethical Series," — to study selec- tions or extracts from the original works, embodying the substance of the system. The " Series " makes provision for such work in a convenient and comparatively inexpen- sive manner. That the plan of instruction on which the " Series " is based is in the interest of better scholarship, I am assured by my own experience, and by that of many other teachers in the leading colleges of the country, with whom I have communicated. It is with the earnest hope of facilitating instruction and study in the History of Ethics that this series is issued. E. HERSHEY SNEATH. Yale University, January 25, '93. TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGB Preface . , 3 Bibliography . . 4 Biographical Sketch 6 Introduction 13 Selections from Treatise of the Passions . 67 The Treatise of Morals . . . . 100 Index 273 PREFACE. The student will observe that the whole of Hume's original treatise on Morals has been included in the pres- ent volume and that the selections are taken only from his work on the " Passions." Portions of the latter have been included because of their importance to a correct understanding of Hume's ethical principles. The main portion of them consists in his discussion of "free will." The whole of the treatise on Morals has been included in order to prevent the volume from being fragmentary, or at least to prevent it from being more so than is necessary for an adequate conception of his system. I have chosen the original work rather than the revised form of 1751, because the later contains no essential changes of view. Hume himself, in a letter to Gilbert Elliott, says: "The philosophical principles are the same in both." Even if this confession had not been made, the judgment of T. H. Green would have sufficed to justify the course taken, since he pronounced the difference between them to be too small to create any obligations of a serious kind on the part of one performing the task here under- taken. JAMES H. HYSLOP. Columbia College. BIBLIOGRAPHY. Hume's Works. A Treatise of Human Nature. Being an attempt to intro- duce the experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects. 3 vols. London, 1739. Essays, Moral and Political. Vol. I., 1741; Vol. II., 1742. Philosophical Essays, 1748. Political Discourses, 1 75 1 . Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, 1 751. History of England. (The reigns of James I. and Charles I.), 1754; (Charles II. and James II.) 1756; (Early period of English History and down to James I.) 1762. Four Dissertations: The Natural History of Religion; of the Passions; of Tragedy; of the Standard of Taste, 1757. Two Essays: (On Suicide and the Immortality of the Soul), 1777- Dialogues concerning Natural Religion, 1779. BIOGRAPHICAL REFERENCES. My own Life. David Hume. (Preface to Editions of his works). Life and Correspondence of David Hume. By J. H. Burton. 2 vols. 1846. An Account of the Life and Writings of David Hume. By Thomas Edward Ritchie, 1807. Hume. By Thomas H. Huxley, 1879. Letters of David Hume to William Strahan. By G. Birbeck Hill, 1888. Hume. By William Knight. Blackwood's Philosophic Clas- sics, 1886. CRITICAL AND OTHER REFERENCES. Hume's Treatise of Human Nature, with an Introduction. By Thomas H. Green, 1882. Introduction to Hume's Philosophical Works. By Thomas H. Green. Philosophical Works, Vol. I. Hume's Treatise of Human Nature. By Selby-Bigge, 1888. Die Ethik David Hume's in ihrer geschichtlichen Stellung. By Georg von Gizycki, 1878. Hume-Studien. A. Meinong, 1877. Leben und Philosophie David Hume's. Jodl, 1872. Hume. Thomas H. Huxley, 1879. Outlines of the History of Ethics, Sidgwick, 1886. Geschichte der Ethik. Jodl, Band I, 1882. English Thought in the Eighteenth Century. Leslie Stephen, 1876. Hume. William Knight, Blackwood's Philosophic Classics, 1886. Grundprobleme in Hume. J. H. W. Stuckenberg, 1887. Eine Untersuchung iiber die Principien der Moral. Dr. G. Garrique Masaryk, 1883. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. David Hume was born at Edinburgh on the 26th of April (O. S.) 17 1 1. His family claimed aristocratic con- nections on both sides, and the fact of this connection was regarded very naturally with some pride by Hume himself. His father died when Hume was an infant, and hence the education of the son was left to the mother. Of his early life and education little is known. We might say almost nothing is known except what he himself stated in a very brief autobiography which was written shortly before his death and published in the next edition of his History of England. He appears to have entered the Greek class at the University of Edinburgh in 1723, but did not graduate. He very early acquired a passion for literature, which finally, after some vicissitudes of fortune, determined his choice of a career. It was probably this taste with the want of positive and aggressive elements in his character which led his mother to remark of him: "Our Davie's a fine, good-natured crater, but uncommon wake-minded." The former part of this judgment proved to be just and accurate, but Hume's subsequent fame and influence rather belied the second part of it. This trait was the opposite of the general characteristic in his race which is intellectually pugnacious and active, and it very probably explains his sceptical tendencies by referring them to a constitutional disposition to cautious and deliberate habits. In 1727, after leaving Edinburgh, Hume came to Nine- wells, the name of his father's estate, and here he was BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. 7 occupied with general reading and private study in his favor- ite way. The next year he began the study of the law, but soon abandoned it for work more congenial to his tastes. He spent the hours on Cicero and Vergil which others sup- posed were spent on Voet and Vinnius. After giving up the law he remained six years at Ninewells before attempt- ing to fix upon a definite career. In J834 he decided to enter upon a commercial life and went to Bristol for this purpose. But this undertaking proved as distasteful as the law and was in its turn abandoned. His fortune being too small to guarantee his independence in England, Hume resolved after the failure at Bristol to reside in France where he could prosecute his literary studies with the small income at his command. He first settled at Rheims and afterward at La Fleche in Anjou. Here he spent three years, carrying out the plan which he had formed while at the university, and returned to London in 1737 with a per- fect knowledge of the French language and the first two volumes of the Treatise on Hitman Nature, which he pub- lished the following year. The third volume appeared in 1740. The work, however, much to Hume's chagrin and disappointment, met with no favor. Of its reception, he himself says in his autobiography: "It fell dead born from the press, without reaching such distinction, as even to excite a murmur among the zealots." This latter part of the remark shows that he was quite conscious of the sceptical character of his work. But his sanguine tempera- ment soon overcame his disappointment, which at first seems to have been very keen, and we find him again at Ninewells carrying on his studies, mainly in the direction of politics and political economy. As a result of this, in 1 741 he published the first volume of his Essays, which met with some success and reanimated his hopes. A copy of the volume was sent to Bishop Butler, the famous author of the Analogy, and his high praise of the work made him a 8 BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. friend of Hume who entertained a very high respect for the Bishop in spite of the wide differences between them on matters of religious belief. In 1742 the second volume of the Essays was published and met with considerable suc- cess. By this time, both the man and his works were suffi- ciently known and respected to have him brought forward in 1744 as a candidate for the chair of Moral Philosophy in the University of Edinburgh. But "the zealots" seem now to have been apprised of the nature of his philosophy, and brought against him the charge of infidelity. The influence of his friends could avail nothing, and he was defeated by Mr. James Balfour, the man who had severely criticised Hume's Treatise on Human Nature. Perhaps Hume's revenge is found in the superior estimation which history has assigned him over his competitor. The grounds upon which he was rejected created a life-long bitterness in Hume against the Scottish clergy. But he ought to have had the sagacity to know either that the general tenor of his writings was out of sympathy with the religious spirit of his countrymen, or that the fanaticism of that time would not tolerate in an orthodox chair a voice so uncertain as his upon the theological questions then agitating the church. Huxley humorously reproaches him for failing to see the natural impropriety of his becoming " a Presbyterian teacher of Presbyterian youth." In 1745 he became guardian to the Marquis of Annan- dale, but this appointment proved unsatisfactory and the next year found him acting as secretary to General St. Clair who was commissioned upon an expedition to Canada and afterward in 1748 as ambassador to the court of Turin, whither Hume followed him in the same capacity as before. It was in this latter year that he published the " Philosophic Essays," or " Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding." He returned to London in 1749 and, soon after, his mother died. Between this time and 175 1 he resided with his BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. 9 brother and sister at Ninewells and occupied himself with the composition of his " Dialogues on Natural Religion," which were not published until after his death, the " In- quiry Concerning the Principles of Morals," and the " Political Discourses." The last two were published in 1 75 1, the Principles of Morals being a recast of the volume on that subject in the "Treatise." In the same year he again failed of election to a professor's chair, the chair of Logic at the University of Glasgow. At the end of the period of which we have just spoken, Hume returned to Edinburgh and took up his residence in the Townmarket, having acquired a sufficient fortune to give him a modest competence. A year afterward the Faculty of Advocates in that city elected him their libra- rian, but not without considerable opposition from religious zealots. Hume writes with some humor of this and other episodes of the incident, and expresses much satisfaction at the result. The salary was only forty pounds a year, but the resources of a large library compensated him in part for this meagre remuneration and he was delighted with the opportunities which the position offered him for continuing his literary pursuits. The duties of his office allowed him leisure to write the History of England, the first volume of which appeared in 1754, the second in 1756, and the last two in 1759. Hume seems to have entertained rather extravagant expectations of its success, and if we are to accept his disappointment as a measure of the results, we should have to record the work as a failure. But its recep- tion was much better than Hume's wounded vanity would seem to imply. For the sales were much larger than he would have us believe. About this time an incident took place which is of inter- est in estimating the influences affecting Hume's attitude towards religion. In 1754 the presentment by the grand jury of Middlesex against the philosophic works of Lord io BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. Bolinbroke led in the following year to the prosecution of Hume for heresy before the courts of the General Assembly of Scotland. After considerable discussion upon the ques- tions whether Hume was amenable to this court, whether he was a Christian, and whether there was any propriety in proceeding against him, the matter was dropped and came to nothing. The Presbytery dismissed the process and Hume thus fortunately escaped the dangerous conse- quences of a clerical inquisition. While the History was in process of publication Hume was active in other lines of literature. In 1757 appeared four dissertations, one on "The Natural History of Re- ligion," one on "Tragedy," one on "The Standard of Taste," and one on "The Passions," the last being a revision and modification of the second book of the "Treatise." In the meanwhile the bitterness which he had felt on account of the imagined failure of his History, assumed a violent form of animosity against the English whom he supposed to be in a conspiracy to hold the Scotch in contempt. As a consequence of these rancorous feelings toward the English, the second portion of his History became a mere party pamphlet in favor of the Tories and against the Whigs, and he even went so far as to purge the first volumes of all statements which might seem to savor of Whig sympathies. The fact is interesting as showing an underlying vein of dogmatism and bias in a man who has generally passed as the Coryphaeus of scepticism, and may explain certain features of his style in his philosophic works when first published. In 1763 Hume accepted the post of secretary to Lord Hertford who went as ambassador to France. Here he became acquainted with that brilliant coterie of French philosophers and literati of that time, including Montes- quieu, Helvetius, Diderot, Rousseau, and Turgot, with some of whom he had before exchanged correspondence. On BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. n his return from Paris in 1766 he was accompanied by Rousseau whose suspicious and ungrateful temper soon provoked a quarrel which separated them, although only after Hume had acquitted himself of all blame in the mat- ter. For two years after his return he remained in London as under-secretary to General Conway, and finally settled in 1769 at Edinburgh with an income increased to £1000 a year and with the determination of spending the remainder of his days in ease. His home in St. David's Street, which was so named because of a humorous and ironical allusion to Hume's religious beliefs by some one who chalked the name upon the wall, " was the centre of the accomplished and refined society which then distinguished Edinburgh." In the spring of 1775 he fell ill with the malady that had carried off his mother, and died on August 26th, 1776. He was buried on the eastern slope of Calton Hill. Hume very early showed traces of a predisposition to philosophy. A remarkable letter written at sixteen years of age shows unusual precocity of philosophic taste and ex- pression, although it indicates no more than his brooding over a vague and indistinct ideal which was an aspiration to realize the attainments he admired in the classic models of Greece and Rome. When he was eighteen he passed through an intellectual crisis which Mr. Huxley compares with a similar event in the life of John Stuart Mill. The comparison seems a little strained, but the incident is of interest because it turns upon the question of virtue and moral discipline, qualities which came in to divert Hume's attention from his philosophic dreaming, and to suggest another form of culture than that which at first attracted his imagination. For a while Hume gave himself up to serious reflections after the manner of ancient moralists. He lost during this period some of his native intellectual balance, but soon afterward he regained his natural robust health and with it recovered his former equability of temperament. 12 BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH. He had all his life a cheerful and complacent disposition and this characteristic fitted him for a literary life and for the sceptical pursuits which he chose to follow. He was equally disqualified by temperament, by circumstances, and by the company with which he associated, for the defence or advocacy of positive convictions upon the more abstruse subjects of philosophic speculation. This may or may not have been a merit. Which of the two it is not necessary to decide. The fact is referred to as indicating a constitu- tional quality which more or less determined the negative nature of his convictions on the more abstract questions of philosophy. To all who have gotten beyond the need of defending the peculiar philosophic and theological theories of that time, this mental poise and sceptical self-control over misdirected enthusiasm has much to admire in it. It must be confessed, however, that Hume did not sustain this attitude in an equal measure toward all subjects. His ex- perience with the clergy and religious problems generally sufficed to make him a sceptic always in this direction, but politics and disappointed vanity soured his temperament only to make him quite positive in his political beliefs after the doubts of his earlier years had been dispelled by maturer reflection and a larger experience. But in his first works we feel the force and example of a very cool and subtle judgment, and the irony of its passionless reflections very naturally annoys those who have a disposition for enthusiasm, and who must accept the first theory at hand, for the peculiar purposes of advocates. This characteristic he retained to the last in spite of his positive views in politics and economics. INTRODUCTION. Preliminary Observations on Hume's Scepticism. The task of correctly estimating the philosophy of Hume is incumbered with unusual difficulties. We have first to determine whether he really had a system or not; whether, in order to expose their contradictions, he was merely developing views for which he himself, claimed no personal responsibility, or whether he meant to present positive doc- trines in the place of the systems of Locke and Berkeley. We generally assume to know that a man is either a realist, an idealist, a sensationalist, a rationalist, a materialist, an empiricist, a transcendentalist, a sceptic, or what not. With this knowledge we have an opportunity to discuss his point of view accordingly, to estimate its agreement or dis- agreement with facts. We may defend it, or we may criticise it. But in all cases our method of treating a man' will be determined solely by the consideration whether we are deal- ing with his doctrine, or with his reasoning, or with both. If he is supposed to occupy a given position in philosophy we may defend or attack it in its relation to facts, or in its relation merely to logical reasoning. But if a man cannot be said to have any positive opinions of his own we are limited to the consideration of his reasoning. For instance, an idealist or a realist may be exposited, defended, or criti- cised. We may test his doctrine by its conformity or non- conformity with admitted truths. We may take him seriously to mean what his language implies. But if a man be a sceptic we have nothing to do with his private opinions, but only 14 INTRODUCTION. with his reasoning. A sceptic is a man who presumably has no opinions of his own upon the subject at hand, but assumes certain premises which others furnish him, and then merely deduces conclusions that flow from them. He claims no responsibility for the truth of the premises, nor for the conclusion, but only for the legitimacy of the process by which that conclusion is reached. Were processes of rea- soning infallible there would be no escape from his clutches. The strength of his position, however, lies in the superior security of logical processes as compared with the psycho- logical which are in the first instance, the originators of knowledge. Hence, inasmuch as he is not responsible for the data of his argument, he can be judged only at the bar of logic. He applies his method only in order to develop contradictions, or such disagreeable results as those who admit the premises are not disposed to accept. He is care- ful not to embarass himself with the duties of an advocate. A man of this kind is not subject to criticism for his opinions, but only for the character of his reasoning. It is probable also that he is chargeable with no other fallacy than an equivocation or a non sequitur. He is never exposed to the charge of a petitio principii which is the fallacy of a man who has opinions. But the possibility of an equivocation or a non sequitur is great enough to offer good opportunities for impeachment. Yet fallacies of this kind may be less frequent than errors of assumption, and hence the sceptic, not making any assumptions of his own, is exempt from so many liabilities which affect others that he is less vulnerable to attack, and not at all by the usual weapons of controversy. The ideal sceptic may not often be realized. He may alternate between dogmatism and scepticism as convenience requires, or he may be an imperfect master of his method. Again he may merely simulate scepticism on emergency for the sake of the immunity which it affords against criticism, INTRODUCTION. 15 or he may push the method to such extremities that it breaks down under its own weight. Such were the ancient sceptics among the Greeks. Their scepticism was so naive and ex- travagant that it was very ineffective against the convictions of common sense. This was mainly because it was directed against perception and not against reasoning. But modern sceptics have been much more secure against ridicule. They have enjoyed the immunity of impeaching doctrines and accepting facts while they appeared to be discrediting both of them. They have been shrewd enough to accept the facts of knowledge, and only to dispute the theories of it and to suggest its limitations. Consequently, wherever they appear they are the signal either for general assault, or for a more profound investigation of philosophical problems. Hume has always been regarded as a sceptic, and he him- self would probably not have cared to dispute this verdict. So general has this view of him been that it would be taken as presumption to qualify or to deny it, and it would open new possibilities to most students if they could be made to believe that Hume's reputation in this respect was a mis- taken one. For it would expose him to new methods of attack. It is not my purpose, however, to dispute the gen- eral correctness of the prevalent judgment, because it is not to be denied that Hume was a master of sceptical methods. But nevertheless I am disposed to qualify this opinion in order to explain certain characteristics in his writings and certain inconsistencies in those who regard him as a sceptic and yet speak of his philosophic system. Before doing so, however, it is well to remark the radical difference between two states of mind which go under the name of scepticism. They are religious scepticism and philosophic scepticism. ■ They are both alike in the respect that they represent a state of doubt. But the former is a doubt of certain facts and beliefs, and the other is a doubt of the grounds of them, or the theories explaining them. It 1 6 INTRODUCTION. is true that there are cases where the two forms of doubt coincide, and these are those in which theology and philos- ophy interpenetrate. But usually religious scepticism is a doubt of the validity and certitude of asserted facts which are assumed to attest the truth and authority of something else, while philosophic scepticism does not necessarily im- peach the value of any facts, but only the grounds on which they are assumed to rest; that is, the proof of them. The disbelief of a fact or an assumed truth may be felt without reference to any of its supposed grounds, and merely on the principle that it is opposed to experience, but the disbelief of a philosophic theory is not incompatible with the accept- ance of all that the theory endeavored to support, while it often has the effect of implying a distrust of facts on the frequently accepted but false assumption that unproved truths are inadmissible. Were it not for this advantage dogmatism might more easily triumph over its opponent. In regard to Hume there can be no doubt that he was a religious sceptic. His life and works leave this fact indubitable. It is quite as certain that he must be consid- ered a philosophic sceptic, but with a qualification. His reputation for being a sceptic comes from two considera- tions. The first is his emphatic repudiation of the main doctrines which characterized the religious mind of the time, and the second is his cautiousness about admitting anything for which he may be made responsible. The latter means that he had assumed his premises from pred-» ecessors and had drawn conclusions from these premises which were not agreeable to the defenders of the reigning philosophy. But there is a characteristic in the style of Hume which suggests a criticism of the loose habit of call- ing him a sceptic, because, although he is a sceptic quite frequently, he is not always one. This characteristic has two features in it. The first is the discussion of his subject in a manner to make most readers believe that he is enun- INTRODUCTION. 17 dating his own doctrines. Not only the air of seriousness, but the mode of expression would induce most persons to interpret him in this light. The second feature is the modification of the fundamental conceptions of Locke and Berkeley in such a way that, instead of seeming to argue from premises which he assumes neither to affirm nor deny, he appears to be stating views of his own. This character- istic is so strong that most readers would have to be told not to take him too seriously in order to realize that he is a sceptic. Undoubtedly we can suppose him assuming the premises of Locke and Berkeley, but the dogmatic style of his statements and his persistent silence about these two philosophers would generally prevent the suspicion of a purely sceptical motive. One writer tells us that there is no reason to suppose that Hume did not accept as true the principles from which he argued, and the same writer im- plies in his remarks that the hesitancy and doubt which gave rise to Hume's reputation for scepticism came from a real perplexity about the problems he was trying to solve, and not from any desire to evade responsibility for his premises. However this may be it is certain that his style is much more that of a dogmatist than of a sceptic. When Hume wrote the Treatise of Human Nature he was decidedly more sceptical than he was in his latter days. The age at which he wrote precluded the probability that he would be so assured in his convictions as to be wholly dogmatic and self-dependent, and it also rendered it unlikely that his mastery of philosophic method would be so complete as to prevent the betrayal of a style against which a trained sceptic would be secure. But there was an element in Hume's temperament and mental constitution which conflicted with perfectly sceptical deportment. He was not wholly indifferent about philosophic principles. He had too keen an insight into truth to be wholly the victim of that intellectual paralysis which is the mark of 18 INTRODUCTION. certain kinds of scepticism. A true philosophic sceptic is a man who either has no power to perceive truth and always doubts it for that reason, or effectively conceals his perception in order to discredit the arguments by which it is sought to be established. In other words he is a man who only sees, or only affects to see, a weakness in con- structive theories about things. Hume undoubtedly had many qualities of a genius for this task of breaking down theories. He had a well balanced judgment, and above all that freedom from bias which a healthy man always has, who does not allow himself to be frightened by ignorant fears about unlikely consequences, and who knows that truth is too often associated with ideas that have no neces- sary connection with it. His sceptical tendencies were supplemented by a native insight into the possibility or probability of what could not be demonstrated, and this gave him the consciousness of knowledge while he saw as clearly the weakness of the constructive theories which endeavored to import extrinsic and often irrelevant evi- dence into the support of truth. His intuitive insight was as good as his ratiocinative powers, and often led him to betray in his style the existence of opinions which an astute sceptic would effectually conceal. It is only a false em- phasis upon the value of theoretical and ratiocinative knowledge that ever leads to scepticism, and it does this by disparaging a natural trust in one's insight for the less exempted power of reason. Hume's scepticism thus came from a desire to see both capacities in harmony. He had no intellectual difficulties in seeing the truth, but he desired to enjoy the traditional security of seeing it put beyond question by a process of proof, and as he perceived the fallacies in existing arguments directed to that end he could appear only as a man questioning the validity of gen- eral beliefs. Others did not see the distinction which he drew or implied, and which Kant made emphatic, between INTRODUCTION. 19 the world of experience and the world of dialectic concep- tions, and hence they mistook the nature and scope of his scepticism, and failed as well to notice the element of dog- matism in his intuitive acceptance of empirical truths. Had Hume not longed too much to give these truths a ratiocinative basis he would have been more constructive in his methods, and would have escaped the imputation of scepticism along with Locke and Berkeley. But failing to distinguish between empirical and " transcendental " knowl- edge, he brought the former under the impeachment which his scepticism produced against the latter. And yet his native insight into truth is so clear and his sympathy with empirical and scientific knowledge is so strong, that he can- not evade the manners of a dogmatist in various emergen- cies of his speculations. He cannot always maintain the scoffing indifference of an ideal sceptic and hence it is almost impossible to avoid thinking that he has simulated this attitude merely to purchase the immunities which such a position confers. There are some interesting facts which confirm the view here taken of Hume. In the first place the third volume of the Treatise does not draw so distinctly from the philosophy of Locke and Berkely as does the first book. The same might be said of the second book which treats of the pas- sions, except that portion which treats of the freedom of the will. Unlike these two books also the third did not run counter to the generally accepted theory of ethics, except, perhaps, in the matter of the relation of " reason " to moral distinctions; and even this was in conflict only with a small school of thinkers, whom Mr. Martineau describes as " intel- lectualists," and who did not represent the prevalent theory of the day. Hume drew from other systems for his ethics what Locke and Berkeley did not directly supply for him. The consequence was that there were no reasons for sus- pecting scepticism in this part of his speculations, because 20 INTRODUCTION. they were in accord with the prevailing doctrines of the time. His evident sympathy with the position that moral conceptions were the product of a "moral sense," or a "sentiment," advocated by Hutcheson and Shaftesbury, allied him very closely with the schools who opposed the explanations of moral ideas by association, because this view eviscerated those ideas of their moral content. This is the more remarkable because, having made havoc in the first book of speculations about causal connection by means of the doctrine of association, it was open to him as a scep- tic to dissolve the moral systems of the day in the same manner, instead of accepting with them the appeal to a form of intuitive ideas. But his scepticism seems to extend no farther than metaphysics, while his ethics escapes its analysis. The conflict between theology and utilitarianism had not yet begun, and hence Hume could accept the position of Hutcheson and Shaftesbury without fear of controversy. A still more striking proof of the claim here made is the dogmatic tone of the "Principles of Morals," published in 1752. There is nothing in that edition to suggest a scep- tic. Its style is thoroughly dogmatic, — dogmatic in the sense that it represents positive convictions, and a well defined explanation of the nature and origin of moral dis- tinctions. Scepticism does not propose theories, but dis- putes them; it is occupied with the rcductio ad contradic- tionem and the rednctio ad absurdum of prevailing opinions upon any given subject. But there is not a trace of this method in the later work. Hume here proposes as definite and positive a system of ethics as any predecessor or suc- cessor ever conceived, and he does so without finding it necessary to set aside more than a few special doctrines. His work, too, is in the interest of a view which neither the school of Reid nor that of Benthan has any reason to dis- pute. The earlier work is less positive and assured in its tone, but it advocates the same doctrine. INTRODUCTION. 2 1 Hume's political bias as shown in his history and in his treatment of political doctrines is an indication of the dog- matic instinct in his mental constitution. We can readily admit that it may not have existed to the same extent in the earlier period of his literary activity, but it was there nevertheless, as might be inferred from his attempt to explain the idea of causal connection by association. As a sceptic he was under no obligation to explain this idea. He would have done all that a sceptic is called to do if he had thrown sufficient doubt upon the idea to discredit its validity. But so far from stopping with an exposure of the difficulties and contradictions involved in the Lockian and existing theories of that idea, he went out of his way to propose an explanation of the origin of it, which implied the existence of the very thing he had previously dis- credited. This is not the wisdom of a sceptic, but is the characteristic of a man who has too good an insight to be the victim of merely formal reasoning. The only difference between the dogmatism of this procedure and that displayed in his attitude toward political matters was in the amount of unreasoning prejudice which he showed in the latter and not in the philosophic method employed. It is not to be denied, however, that Hume had his thor- oughly sceptical moods, nor that the general influence of his philosophy has been sceptical. Only we must insist that this tendency is not exhibited in his system of morals, and hence the system must be treated as his express doc- trine, for the statements and consistency of which he may be held responsible. The sceptical nature of his general influence can be best represented by a comparison with Bishop Butler. Butler had a strong and judicious intellect. He was quite as dispassionate as Hume, and probably had a greater confidence than he in the ability and right of reason to solve the problems agitating the age in which he lived. It 22 INTRODUCTION. was this, no doubt, that prevented him from being a scep- tic. He was a man whom Hume himself respected however much he chose to differ from him. But he was firmly attached to the side of theology and yet he represented that cool, logical temperament which, while it assumes the need of a philosophy, is keenly sensible of the strength of scep- ticism. The nature of the philosophic and theological con- troversies of the time appears very clearly in the problems of Butler's Analogy. Those problems were the existence of God, miracles, immortality, and revelation. Butler's argu- ment was designed to show that the objections urged against the Christian system, which now passes under -the name of Theism, applied with equal force against the doc- trine of natural religion or Deism, as then accepted by the rationalists. This was only to say that objections which overthrew the Christian scheme overthrew Deism and necessitated the acceptance of Atheism which the deist opposed as heartily as the Christian. Or put in another way, it placed the deist between the alternatives of Atheism and Christianity. Such a statement of the case had its sceptical implications, because it did not prove the alterna- tive which men were to choose. It left every one free to accept the validity of the objections to Christianity or revealed religion and thus to force upon himself the con- clusion of dogmatic scepticism. This consequence was of course counteracted in Butler by his known belief that the Christian system was adequately supported, and he un- doubtedly relied upon the general religious consciousness of the time to adopt his side of the question. The deistic school also would have accepted the same conclusion if it had felt itself reduced to admit the disjunction implied by Butler, and there is no doubt that Butler made out a suffi- ciently strong case for the deists to feel compelled to modify their position, as subsequent developments have shown. Hume, however, had no interests to bind him to the theistic INTRODUCTION. 23 point of view, and having started with a doubt of the phil- osophic positions, upon which Theism was founded, he chose the sceptical alternative, which was only to say to Butler that he had been given the liberty of choosing Atheism, if he admitted the force of the argument against revealed religion, and that he did not find the evidence for this alternative to it so overwhelming as Butler had assumed. Butler was hardly prepared for this position. He had assumed the case against Atheism to be so plain that no rational mind would incline in that direction, and would have been at an entire loss to meet a man who admitted the argument against Deism. Hume therefore appears as endeavoring to prove that the sceptical attitude is quite as rational as the one advocated by Butler. He had a twofold ad hominem argument in his support. First, he had only to acftnit what the deist was not expected to admit ; namely, the cogency of the objections asserted by Butler to apply equally against natural and revealed religion. Second, he could assert that miracles, the existence of God, revelation, personal identity, causality, etc., were ideas not found in experience, according to the system of Locke, and hence were fictions, as all "complex ideas" were in that philos- ophy. This reasoning afforded a splendid destructive weapon at the time, at least so far as metaphysical and theological theories were concerned. But there was no ground for applying the method to ethics. Neither Locke nor Berkeley had said enough on this subject to involve them in sceptical controversies, nor was the subject connected with the problems of the time in a way to tempt a sceptic with a reductio ad absurdum of it. The same ethical principles were admitted by nearly all schools. Had Hume lived to see the doctrine of Evolution, or had he appreciated and sympathized with the principles of Hobbes, he might have turned scepticism upon moral principles with as much ingenuity and effect as upon the 24 INTRODUCTION. problems of metaphysics. But in addition to not being as cynical and pessimistic as Hobbes, there was no influence to lead him into a destructive policy regarding ethics. And more than this, the moral systems of contemporaries and predecessors were so in accord with the philosophy of Locke that the one point which Hume might have been disposed to attack was not present to tempt his antagonism. This was the opposition between the doctrine of an innate moral sense and the doctrine of utilitarianism. Until the time of Hartley, Bentham, and Mill these doctrines remained in perfect harmony. The systems of Hutcheson and Shaftes- bury, while advocating the theory of a " moral sense," did not pretend to advance this view with the object of opposing the theory of happiness or utilitarianism. On the contrary, they distinctly made this end the object of their "moral sense." Cudworth, Clarke, and Wollaston had advocated an intuitive and intellectual morality, but not in a way to oppose the doctrine of happiness. They were opposed only to the doctrines of conventionalism and of sensuous pleasure, or hedonism. Hume criticised the general position of these men when he denied that reason had any function in origi- nating moral distinctions. But the position of the intellect- ualists was never generally accepted, while the prevailing systems, such as they were then, were not more affiliated with theological doctrines than with scientific and political views. Indeed, as Mill astutely observes, in one of his essays, utilitarian principles were staunchly defended by theologians until they discovered that utilitarianism was the favorite theory of sceptics and atheists, when they suddenly changed their attitude. Hence Hume had no motive to apply scepticism to morals, for it was his dislike of theolog- ical doctrines that was the motive to all his scepticism. He could agree with his contemporaries on ethical matters in the main without compromising his free-thinking and without prejudicing his philosophy, or he could disagree with them INTRODUCTION. 25 without espousing the cause of the orthodox in any impor- tant respect. The consequence was that he accepted the prevailing tendencies to utilitarianism and adapted his theory to the psychology which had been borrowed with modifications from the philosophy of Locke. On this account, therefore, we feel bound to qualify the charge of strict scepticism against his system at large and to treat his ethics as we should that of any other writer belonging to that age. With this understanding of his position we can enter into an exposition and criticism of his doctrine. # Exposition and Criticism. Hume's conception of tffe field of moral philosophy was the same as that of his age. It was supposed to comprise the whole area of the sciences occupied with the life and action of men, history, political economy, psychology, aesthetics, metaphysics, and theology. To these were op- posed physics, chemistry, astronomy, etc., which were known as the natural sciences. This looser conception of moral science affected the treatment of the problems now passing under the notice of ethical theories, in that it prevented the present and current radical distinction between psychology and ethics. This fact will be apparent to all who examine the contents of the three parts of the Treatise. The first part, after the example of Locke, was on the Understanding, which concerned perception and reasoning, and the prob- lems of knowledge. The second was on the Passions, or as we should now denominate them, the Emotions, — a division which might be regarded as an anticipation on Hume's part of the threefold division of mental phenomena into intellect, feeling, and will, which is so often accredited to Kant. It of course only implies such a division by separating the treatment of the " passions " from that of moral principles 26 INTRODUCTION. generally. But the interesting feature of the system is that a problem which is quite universally regarded as an ethical problem, namely, the freedom of the will, is examined and discussed under the head of the passions instead of under the head of morals. The third part discusses the origin and nature of moral distinctions, both in general and in particu- lar. But why Hume does not consider the freedom of the will in this part of his work is inexplicable, unless we sup- pose either that he regarded it as a psychological question, or # that he very shrewdly excluded it from morals on the ground that a system of ethics could be constructed without reference to it. The latter can hardly be the true supposi- tion, because he himself, although affirming the doctrine of determinism, asserts the existence of free will in one sense of the term, in the only sense in'which, he says, it can be maintained to have a meaning at all, and because he also asserts that this freedom is a necessary condition of moral principles. He therefore probably regarded the question as psychological, and this supposition accords with his treat- ment of the matter under the passions. It is possible to maintain that he considered the problem of ethics to be exclusively occupied with a theory of the nature and origin of moral ideas, and as not concerned with any psychological conditions of their validity, and that the nature and functions of the will were assumed in all prob- lems of theoretical ethics. But in spite of this real or apparent separation of the two parts of the Treatise, the discussion of the passions is very closely connected with the principles of morals, because it deals with the ele- ments which have to be regarded as the motives of conduct, and with the doctrine of freedom which must be regarded as the condition of ethical speculation. On this account the passions must be subject to examination and criti- cism wherever Hume's theory of morals is a matter of consideration. INTRODUCTION. 27 Everywhere throughout the system of Hume one funda- mental distinction appears at its basis. It is Locke's dis- tinction between "simple" and "complex ideas," although somewhat modified in the adoption. In Locke there were " simple ideas," both of sensation and reflection, while reflection was also the source of "complex ideas." Reflec- tion thus does duty for perceptional, conceptional, and ratiocinative functions. But with Hume it seems that sen- sation was the proper source of " simple ideas " or " impres- sions," and reflection of "complex ideas." Still Hume is not clear or uniform in this matter, and we shall have to examine his usage a little more fully in order to make it clear. Locke uses the term " idea " to denote the objects of both perception and thought. Hume, however, remarking this perversion of its usage, chooses, in one passage at least, to limit it to the conceptions of the understanding, which, in his view, differ only in vivacity or degree from the impres- sions of sense. In consequence of this limitation of the term Hume uses the term "perception " to denote all mental states of the understanding, whether "simple" or "com- plex," and divides these perceptions into impressions and ideas. By " impressions " he means " all our sensations, passions, and emotions, as they make their first appearance in the soul." By " ideas " he means " the faint images of these (impressions) in thinking and reasoning." When he comes to treat of the passions he divides "impressions" into the "original" and the "secondary." The former include all the sensations and the feelings of pleasure and pain ; the latter are the feelings or emotions which " proceed from these original ones, either immediately or by the interposition of its idea," namely, of pleasure or pain. That is, the second- ary passions arise from experiences of pleasure and pain. It is to be remarked in this analysis that Hume does not regard pleasure and pain as passions : only those states 28 INTRODUCTION. which exercise a prompting influence upon the will are to be regarded as passions. Hume's division places pleasure and pain among the " impressions " of the understanding and not as impulsive feelings, which he considers the passions to be. In other words, in Hume, the passions are equated with the desires and aversions, and so express what later writers have meant by the term when considering them as impulsive emotions, or as the class of feelings which are on the one hand contrasted with the reflex feel- ings of pleasure and pain, these being the effects and con- comitants of action, and which on the other hand constitute the motives to volition, being in this case the causes of action. In this scheme it is apparent that Hume cannot regard pleasure and pain as motives to action, but only as reactions upon stimulus, or as concomitants of sensations which are such reactions. He would be obliged to distin- guish between pleasure and pain and the ideas of them. The consequences of his doctrine will be evident when we come to consider his treatment of freedom and the theory of utilitarianism. The divisions of the passions into the "calm" and the "violent," and again into the "direct" and the "indirect," have only a psychological interest. The classification of them under the first division is not carried out or completed. The meaning of the second division is made more clear. But since both divisions represent motives to action the distinction into "calm" and "violent," and "direct" and "indirect" is of no special importance in a theory of moral principles. The direct passions are " desire, aversion, grief, joy, hope, fear, despair, and security ; " the indirect are " pride, humility, ambition, vanity, love, hatred, envy, pity, malice, generosity, with their dependents." Both the direct and indirect passions are said to arise from pleasure and pain, only that the indirect are found " in conjunction with other qualities." " In conjunction with other quali- INTRODUCTION. 29 ties," means in Hume's parlance " concurrence with certain dormant principles of the human mind." But the nature and differences between the two classes are not further discussed by him and in fact have no special bearing upon his problem, although it probably became him to explain his mysterious allusion to " certain dormant principles of the human mind." It is in connection with the sections on the direct pas- sions that Hume discusses the freedom of the will. On this subject he is a pronounced determinist, although with qualifications. He admits that we are free agents in one sense of the term ; namely, in the sense that we can do as we desire, or that we can act according to our pleasure. But he denies that we can act without a motive. This position is asserted most distinctly in the revised account of the passions, published in the Essays in 1752, when Hume became convinced that some form of liberty must be assumed in order to have the first conditions of any moral principles at all. The doctrine is stated, however, in the first edition of the Treatise, where he draws the distinction between the " liberty of spontaneity " and the " liberty of indifference." He admits the former, but denies the latter. It is important always to remember this characteristic of Hume's doctrine before opposing it, because it must not be adjudged out of its relation to the ideas of the time. In fact, no theory of this question, or of any other, should be criticised until we ascertain the contemporary and ante- cedent views in relation to which the particular doctrine under consideration was conceived. Time generally intro- duces a change of relations and conceptions which very greatly modifies the import of a doctrine. In this way, to use an apt phrase of John Stuart Mill, what is true in one age may not be true in another, merely because a change of content may accompany a retention of the same language. It will be apparent to those who do not approach the theory 30 INTRODUCTION. of Hume from a purely abstract conception of it, as a doctrine of determinism, that it was conceived solely as a refutation of the so-called liberty of indifference, a position which has not been held by any respectable freedomist since that time. The speculation preceding Hume, and to some extent contemporaneous with him, was predominantly in sympathy with this doctrine. This conception implied motiveless volition, and this absence of determining motives was assumed to represent the proper condition of freedom. It was Hume's task to show that no such a state of things ever existed, and there is no reason to dispute his claim on this matter. Unless the freedom of the will can be sustained without assuming that conception of it which is illustrated by the story of the ass between the two bundles of hay, it must be frankly abandoned, and determinism adopted in its place. This Hume asserted in a very positive way by show- ing that there was nothing capricious, casual, or motiveless about human conduct ; that we act according to law ; that we are orderly and rational, and that expectations can be entertained regarding what we are likely to do with much the same certainty as we predict events in the physical world. His arguments on the matter, it should be remarked, were nothing more nor less than those with which disputants were familiar in his own time, and can be found fully stated in such writers as Hobbes and Collins. He was, therefore, not alone in the view he defended. But Hume, it must be remembered, had the advantage, first, of presenting his arguments sceptically, and, second, of defining the terms connected with the question in a way to involve his desired conclusion, while these terms represented by supposition the current notions of them. His own concessions to the freedomists were concealed by the want of emphasis upon them in order that they might not avail themselves of an ambiguity to parade in an apparent triumph over the determinist. Hume was shrewd enough to see and perhaps INTRODUCTION. 31 to appreciate, but not to advocate at length any other conception of the terms in the dispute than such as were necessary to refute the prevailing doctrine. He remarked that he would not pretend to argue with any one who assumed different conceptions of freedom to start with. This was his warning that he would confine himself in the argument to current conceptions of the problem and that he would relieve himself, as far as possible, of responsibility for his premises, or, at least, that he would put himself in a position to escape responsibility when necessary. He seems, however, to be accepting in good faith the data from which he argues, and it is this fact which gives his argument so much force. But whether he was serious in accepting his data may be a question, and upon the settlement of this depends the matter of his scepticism, and the method of criticising him. It is to be noticed that the form in which he presented the case for determinism is unusually clear and forcible ; the more so from the fact that Hume evidently does not propose to shrink from the consequences of his doctrine. He faces a paradox or a supposed absurdity with unblanched courage, and makes his reader feel that there is no way to evade the conclusion but to question the premises. That uncritical period was very slow to perceive this resource. Reid, however, did discover a way of escape, and set about a reconstruction of the problem all along the line, in the theory of morals as well as in the theory of knowledge ; and if we are to accept the judgment of Prof. Seth in the matter Reid was not far removed from Kant in his treatment of these questions. We have, therefore, an instance, as already intimated, where the treatment of Hume must be determined entirely by the manner in which we regard his position. If we assume that he is a sceptic, we cannot treat his arguments seriously as his own. We should be at liberty only to consider the character of his reasoning and to throw the 32 INTRODUCTION. responsibility for unacceptable conclusions upon those of his predecessors who had unwarily furnished him with such dangerous premises. If we regarded him as a dogmatist, we should be able to consider his problem on its merits and to dispute his*assumptions, as well as his reasoning, on the ground that he seriously accepted the data from which he argued. But in regard to the question of freedom we cannot regard him as wholly one or the other. He is sufficiently both to put himself in a position of limited liability. He reserves to himself, on the one hand, the right to throw his premises upon others' shoulders in order to escape an impeachment for a petitio principii , and on the other, he retains enough of positive conceptions in the liberty of spontaneity to protect his theory of morals. Hence his arguments may be considered as sceptical and negative against the liberty of indifference, but as irrelevant to any other conception of the problem. This circumstance makes it unfair to Hume to treat his views as opposed to the doctrine of freedom in general, and so we have to attack him always with a proviso. Again, if he could not take shelter in the privileges of a sceptic, and if he did not admit one form of free agency, we might accuse him of mis- conceiving the nature of the problem. But the perpetual immunity from criticism against his data, which his astute manner gives him, compels the student to throw the respon- sibility for error mainly upon his predecessors, while his one concession of free spontaneity secured moral science against the consequences of unconditional determinism. Hence the only resource left to those who do not like Hume's conclusions, and yet wish to hold him to account while they grant him the privileges of a sceptic, is to reproach the consistency of his reasoning. t\ There are two points, therefore, which can be brought I against him, which are of considerable force and which do ' not make him responsible for his premises. V\\The first is the INTRODUCTION. 33 contradiction involved in his treatment of the idea of necessity or necessary connection.^ The second is his ignorance of the manner in which previous philosophy had employed the term "reason" in connection with the doctrine of the will and the motivation of conduct. The latter exposes Hume to the charge of a misconception which leads to an inconsistency in his entire system of morals. In regard to the first of these considerations it is to be noted that Hume had disputed the existence of necessary or causal connection, when discussing the doctrine of Locke in the first part of the Treatise. There is a contradiction between this denial of necessity or causation, and the use of such a connection between phenomena to refute the doctrine of freedom. If motives and volitions, according to the empirical and associational theory, are connected only by co-existence or sequence, the former is not a cause of the latter, according to Hume's own conception of the case, because he disputes the very existence of causation. It is impossible to distinguish between uncaused and free volition. Indeed if Hume were to suppose that volition is thus uncaused, on the ground that all connection between phenomena is associative, he would be admittting the free- dom of indifference in a far worse sense than the advocates of that doctrine have ever maintained. He would actually be assuming a beginning of something without a cause, the very contradiction of natural science and of all the principles upon which scepticism is usually dependent. The defenders of the freedom of indifference never went so far as to maintain that a volition could originate without a cause. They assumed or affirmed that the cause was the intelligent ego, and that it was not the motive which caused or causes the volition. They merely claimed that in so far as the motive was related to volition the latter could exist without it, and hence the proper refutation of this position was to 34 INTRODUCTION. show that it could not so exist and that the act could not properly be a volition unless it had a motive. But to reduce all events to co-existences and sequences of phenomena and then, while excluding, in this way, all causal connection between them, to suppose that these events have an origin, each one having its beginning in the series, is to assume or assert a creatio ex nihilo. A volition thus originating would be not only motiveless, but causeless. Every event which comes into existence must do so of its own accord, or on account of some cause. If it be the former it is uncaused and spontaneous ; if it be caused, the argument would stand presumptively in favor of the determinists' claim, so far as the general law of causation can be said to do it at all, but it would be against the sceptical doctrine of Hume, discredit- ing, as it did, the existence of causal connection. Hume is reduced to the alternative of choosing between freedom and the existence of causality. There can be no doubt about the dilemma in which he is placed. On the one hand, the denial of necessary connection implies that events, and among them volitions, have no cause, are free spontaneous creations. On the other hand, to regard such events as caused is to grant the existence of more than mere co- existences and sequences and thus to surrender the sceptical conclusion to which his argument in the first book of the Treatise led. The whole force of his argument against freedom depends upon the validity of the idea of causation. This is not to say that freedom is denied, if causation is believed or proved to be true, but that the first condition of disproving freedom exists in the assumption of causal con- nection. But when that idea is impeached there is nothing left to prevent the supposition that volitions among other events are causeless, whether they be motiveless or not. The contradiction then in Hume is clear. The reply to this criticism, however, is evident, and it would be that the contradiction is not Hume's own ; that INTRODUCTION. 35 he is merely employing the methods of scepticism, and that he is responsible only for the ad hominem character of the argument. His defenders can say that in one place he is ■merely disproving Locke's right to the idea of necessary connections from the premises, and in the other he is showing that the same school cannot hold to the doctrine of liberty if they admit the causality of all events and yet include volitions among them. In this manner the apparent inconsistency of Hume is only his statement of the double inconsistency of the philosophy, of which he is giving a rednctio ad absurdum; namely, the inconsistency, on the one hand between its doctrine of experience and the conception of causality, and on the other between the motiveless and uncaused character of volition, and the causation of all events. There is no doubt that to thus regard Hume's position as purely sceptical acquits him of responsibility for the contra- diction we have indicated. But we have two rejoinders to this supposition of its sceptical nature. The first is that, granting Hume's scepticism, our argument applies with full force to all who dispute the existence of necessary connec- tion, and these include all who have taken Hume seriously upon the subject, among them the Positivists. They must choose between causality and freedom. They cannot deny both of them. The second rejoinder is that Hume cannot be properly regarded as wholly a sceptic in this matter. Had he been content merely to point out the inconsistencies of the philosophy of Locke, he might have been exempt from the charge of contradiction. But he did not stop with this criticism of Locke. He went on to propose a theory of his own, a procedure which took him wholly without the pale of scepticism and places him among the dogmatists. As a sceptic he should express no opinions about the idea of causality. He should merely have shown that Locke had no right to it in his system, and should have left the reader 36 INTRODUCTION. ignorant in regard to his own views. But- instead of this he produces an argument of his own to deny the existence of causality. He admitted that we have, as a fact, the idea of necessary connection other than mere co-existence and. sequence, but in order to show its illusory character he undertakes to explain its origin by the doctrine of associa- tion. He starts with the view of Locke that experience gives us co-existences and sequences, mere facts of con- nected occurrences, and concedes that causal connection is superadded to these. But in order to show that this superadded idea is only a mistaken co-existence or sequence, he shows the influence of long and frequent association in producing an idea of connection which we mistake for a necessary one. This is simply a reduction of the idea of necessary connection to association, and no one ever sup- posed that association contains the causal nexus, which is something in addition to it. Hume's own doctrine, there- fore, is a denial of causation and thus contradicts his attempt to set aside freedom on the ground of the law of c,ause and effect. To secure himself against this accusa- tion, Hume must give up his theory of the origin of our idea regarding necessary connection. If he had been content to show that the Lockians had no right to the idea of causality, as being excluded from the primary data of knowledge, and that with this idea they have no right to the doctrine of freedom, as long as freedom means indifference to motives, he would not have been disturbed in his argu- ment. But the moment he endeavors to prove that the idea of a causal nexus other than association is an illusion, he assumes a position which makes any other doctrine than freedom a most rank absurdity. Throwing aside Hume's inconsistency as a sceptic and admitting the law of causatigrj, the defence to which his argument is entitled is that" we must admit the causation of volitions and the invariable concomitancy of motives with INTRODUCTION. 37 them. This indisputably refutes the doctrine of indifference, and unless we can reconcile the theory of freedom with the caused character of volitions it must be abandoned. Hume's argument undoubtedly forces this conclusion upon us, because the only alternative to it is the assumption that volitions are not events or have no origin. But it may not be wholly and only to Hume's credit that the case is thus made out ; for the determinists who preceded him make the same conclusion quite as inevitable, although probably not quite so clear. It must also be said for the advocates of freedom that they were not all even apologists for that abused conception of it represented by the liberty of indifference. They were many of them careful to repudiate such a doctrine, and Hume may be suspected of insincerity or misrepresentation for not stating this fact instead of appearing to make us believe that the doctrine he attacked was the only one existing at the time. He can escape the suspicion only by pleading ignorance in regard to the history of philosophy. It is true that many persons have conceived the doctrine of freedom after the manner imputed to them by Hume, but they have not been so numerous as to justify a disregard of those who held a different view. Besides, Hume could not have had in mind a sceptical reduction of Locke's theory of freedom, because when we have eliminated the paradoxes of Locke's discussion of the problem we have a view precisely identical with that which Hume admits to be true ; namely the freedom of spontaneity. Hume could have been thinking only of the dogmatic philosophers and theologians for whom he felt a strong antagonism. He was ever ready to torment these adversaries with the conclusions from their own premises and delighted to see them writhe under the hopeless confu- sion in which their contradictions left them. It would be too charitable to Hume as well as false in fact to suppose that he was morally in earnest about either the truth or the 38 INTRODUCTION. value of his conclusions so eagerly demonstrated. He was bent on weakening the convictions of those who were willing to toy with philosophy as long as it did not under- mine their faith or threaten the integrity of their traditional dogmas. There was a disposition to mischief in Hume's nature which greatly qualifies his claim to sincerity and it is attested by his own moods of complete indifference, both moral and intellectual, in regard to the results of his speculations. In spite of some dogmatic feeling there was the malice of a sceptic in him and it was this trait which created distrust in the seriousness of his argument, and forfeited the respect that attached to the more radical but more earnest philosophy of contemporary Frenchmen. Diderot, Helvetius, and Condillac were quite as sceptical as Hume, so far as theology was concerned, but they were terribly in earnest about the doctrines which they wished would supplant those of tradition, and modern humanita- rianism may be said to have received its second birth at their hands. No such movement can trace its lineage to Hume's influence. Yet this fact should not be used too much to his discredit, nor should we because of certain moral defects in his temperament either unduly depreciate the merits of his philosophy or unfairly burden scepticism with the responsibility for the world's intellectual errors and practical ills. For the claim can be very justly made that quite as much good comes to the world from scepticism as from dogmatic and impulsive moral earnestness, because the latter is always in danger of becoming intolerant and overbearing. Both mental attitudes have their place. Scepticism is the antidote of intolerance. It is the mother of deliberative habits and deliberation is essential to all rational life and conduct. It is the only instrument which can enable us to get an adequate conception of the various conditions with which we have to deal in the intellectual and moral problems of the world. Without it we are dis- INTRODUCTION. 39 posed to assume a greater uniformity in the nature of men and of life than actually exists. What we require is a knowledge of the diversities of nature and circumstance under which men think and act, and we can expect to attain it only under the impulse of a certain amount of change in the ideas of our earlier periods of belief. On the other hand, moral earnestness is the condition of all noble action. Yet it must be wisely cultivated and applied. But it is necessary to counteract the paralyzing influence of doubt and hesitation, which if left to themselves result in inaction. The two functions require to be judiciously combined, the one to prevent unadjusted life, and the other to prevent inertia. In purely speculative philosophy, however, they may often be separated to a great advantage. Here we are concerned only with the naked truth of things apart from the personal interests with which our feelings, even those of the loftiest nature, may become associated, and in order to assure the judicial calmness necessary to estimate abstract truth rightly, we require often to divest ourselves of every impulse attaching us to preconceived opinions and purposes. Hume possessed this characteristic of intel- lectual self-control and poise to a very marked degree and it was a source of great strength to his philosophy. He undoubtedly had an eye to mischief when any theological doctrines were concerned. But this fact, while it might justify some suspicion of his disinterestedness, must not weigh in estimating the nature and value of his reasoning. Bad motives will not nullify the force of good logic ; and hence we are compelled to test his philosophy by other than moral criteria. The second peculiarity of Hume's treatment of the will is his denial that " reason " alone can influence it as a motive power, or that " men are only so far virtuous as they con- form themselves to its dictates." The first temptation of most students of philosophy would be to oppose Hume's 4° INTRODUCTION. position, and yet a little examination might show that after all the doctrine is not so far removed from that of Kant and common sense as might be imagined. For both agree that the "good will" is an indispensable factor in virtue, and it may be claimed that Hume's is only a negative statement of this view. In the discussion of this question the student must be careful not to misunderstand or to misrepresent the real position of Hume. He is often said, or thought, to have denied all influence of "reason" upon the will, and his argument lends much color to this view, because of his in- complete exposition of the functions of reason, and because of the vast amount of negative argument on his part to show the inability of " reason " to furnish motive power. It is true that the impression left by his general language is that "reason" is excluded from all relation and influence upon volition, and it appears that the occasional use of the term " alone " or its equivalent is the only resource for defence which his apologists can produce. This is important and conclusive, but it would have conduced more to clearness had so important a qualification been more conspicuous in the general discussion. Hume's position is saved by his distinct assertion that " reason alone* can never be a motive to any action of the will," and this is his real point of view in spite of apparent argument to the contrary. The general drift of his discussion undoubtedly favors the separation of " reason " and will, or volition, and justifies a measure of criticism in order to counteract its influence or to correct the very natural misunderstanding occasioned by it. Were he defending the entire independence of volition from the in- fluence of reason there is an ad homincm argument which would be absolutely conclusive against him. It is the fact that he distinctly places pleasure and pain among the " im- pressions," which are not " passions," but data of the under- * Italics are our own. INTRODUCTION. 41 standing or reason, although the passions may arise from or upon the occasion of impressions. The passions are the only motives to action which Hume recognizes, and as pleasure and pain, according to his view, are not passions, they cannot be motives. And yet Hume founds his utilita- rianism upon the supposition that pleasure and happiness are the motives of conduct, But since pleasures and pains are "impressions," or data of the understanding, and are not passions, and since the passions are the only motives to volition, Hume must either have given up his utilitarianism and with it the assumed motivation of pleasure and pain, or he must have admitted the motivation of the understanding or reason, as pleasure and pain, in his view, are among its. functions. Again, inasmuch as it is not pleasure and painjb considered as present states, that are assumed to be motives^ but the ideas of them that are the real motives, it might be/ said that " reason " is thus necessarily implicated in volition,/ as a motive power to it, for ideas have no other source thai* reason. This fact is conclusive in the case. But it does not militate against the real position of Hume as qualified by his inconspicuous admission. It in fact illustrates the positive view which it was his duty to have constructed after having implied that reason was in some way related to voli- tion. The criticism, however, has been necessary for several reasons. First, it was necessary to make clear the inconsistency of any system which virtually denied the motive nature of pleasure and pain, and affirmed the theory of utilitarianism while regarding them as products of the understanding, and not as passions. Second, the case offered a good opportunity for explaining the real relation between volition and pleasure and pain, and between reason and volition, which is that ideas are as much motives as pas- sions, — a position, which, although not made clear by Hume, is distinctly anticipated by him in the admission, on the one hand, that reason has some relation to conduct, and in the 42 INTRODUCTION. assertion, on the other, that conduct is not virtuous solely on the ground of its conformity to reason. And again it was necessary to exhibit the proper proportions of apology and criticism belonging to his view. These considerations, even if they do not take the shape of a refutation, justify our animadversions, on the ground that every student should be put on guard against misrepresentation of Hume, and against deductions from his doctrine which have ignored the important concessions already mentioned. There is a farther consideration of Hume's view, which partakes of the nature of both a criticism and an apology. We may first remark that he is disposed to beg the question of the relation between reason and volition by using the term " reason " in its ratiocinative sense. It is indisputably true that ratiocinative reason can never produce a motive to volition. Logical processes are not motives, and no philosopher was ever careless enough to suppose that they were. The ambiguities of language in the Platonic system and its traditions might have lent some color to such a mis- understanding, but responsible thinkers have not given any ground to suppose that they would defend such a view. Hence it creates some surprise to see Hume insinuating by his treatment of the question that they had taught such a doctrine. In fact there is reason to charge Hume either with ignorance or with disingenuousness in the matter. He either did not know adequately the history of philosophy, or he wished to avail himself of a manifest but ambiguous truth in order to impeach the intellectualists of the day. If he was resorting consciously to an equivocation to support his cause he forfeits all respect for his argument. This view of him, however, is, we are convinced, not the true one. It is an accusation which it would be hard to prove, and can be nothing more than a presumption taken from his known sympathy with the cause of scepticism. Besides his sympathy with the doctrine of a moral sense acquits him of INTRODUCTION. 43 disingenuousness, as it indicates a desire on his part not so much to play the sceptic with the school of Cudworth and Clarke as to prepare a way for his doctrine of moral senti- ment. But we have a right to assert that Hume does not seem sufficiently acquainted with the history of the term to understand what the intellectualists meant by the motivation of reason in volition. We shall have occasion to refer to this question again when considering his moral theory in its more special character. It is referred to here for two pur- poses ; first in order to understand the peculiar nature of his doctrine of the will, and second in order to illustrate the difficulties in dealing with him merely as a sceptic, or as one who had not recognized in any form a relation between reason and volition. Were we to assume that he denied all relations between the two, we could better understand the feeling which the freedomists of that day would entertain toward him. Accustomed as they were to connect freedom with rational as opposed to instinctive or passionate action, they would very naturally resent in strong language any attempt to widen the distance between reason and will by disregarding the established language and distinctions of philosophy, or to diminish the influence of reason upon conduct by giving morals over to the sentiments ; because turning the will over exclusively to the passions and instincts was, in the well defined conceptions of the day, as in Plato and his school, to make all conduct non-moral by regarding it as the result of mechanical motives or unconscious and irrational impulses. It may be that motive force has other elements than mere perceptive and ratiocinative ideas, but volition can never be truly moral until it is qualified by the rational element ; that is, until ideas of the intellect inform the motives to action. These ideas need not be those of the reflective stage of life. It is sufficient that they represent the consciousness of an end, although the reflective type may 44 INTRODUCTION. be the higher of the two. But in the general thought of his own and previous ages "reason " represented a motive opposed to blind instinct, and one which was opposed to the pure emotions. The term was taken in its broad sense of mind, and not of logical processes. It was this fact which Hume seems to have wholly ignored and he is reproachable for some lack of insight in not apprehending the true meaning of his contemporaries and predecessors. It was a strange oversight on his part. For no kind of freedom, not even that of spontaneity, which Hume admits, could be possible under the supposition that reason had no relation to volition, taking that term to denote the general power of consciousness. What he did, without being conscious of it, was to place conduct entirely under the agency of instinct or passion, in so far as his system separated reason and the will. This was effected by his failure to distinguish between " motives " as merely efficient causes of volition, and as final causes of it, or final and efficient causes together. In much of the traditional philosophy instinct and instinctive impulses were considered as efficient causes of conduct in which the agent was not supposed to be intelligent ; and where only efficient causes operated, they being always regarded as external. Because the instinct was an impulse or influence outside of conscious- ness, the action could in no way be taken as the agent's own voluntary effort, and hence was not considered spontaneous or free. Such " motives " are mechanical in their nature, or are analogous to mechanical forces, so far as their relation to Jvolition is concerned. But a true "motive " to action must be a state of consciousness, an idea of an end, in order to imake the action moral at all. It also requires impulsive force, and it is true that this motive efficiency does not come from it as an idea, but from the desire that is coupled with it. But, nevertheless, it will not be a true " motive " unless it contains the element of consciousness, or the consciousness INTRODUCTION. 45 of an end, because the act cannot be a volition without this accompaniment. Hence Hume's general tendencies are toward a determinism which contradicts his admission of spontaneity. He interprets " motive " to mean causal efficiency and denies this power to reason, so that volition, not coming from reason, but from the passions, can in no sense be intelligent, or coincide with his conception of free spontaneity. His error is, therefore, either in his mis- conception of the term "motive," which leads to the contradiction just mentioned, or in his denial of reason as a motive power while making pleasure and pain, its products, the motives to conduct. In either case there is a contra- diction involved, both of them involving his theory of determinism, because as long as the assumptions of his own system include at least the concomitant motivation of reason in every volition, this fact and the freedom of spontaneity appear to offset the conclusions based upon a purely mechanical conception of the term " motive." There are passages also which show that Hume does not, and cannot escape the influence of traditional usage in his employment of the term "reason." This appears in some of his references where it denotes perceptive as well as ratioc- inative processes, and as he could not question its function to supply ideas of ends involved in every volition this usage, perhaps an unwitting concession on his part, either impli- cates him in the very doctrine which the whole spirit of his discussion has the effect of denying, as usually interpreted by the general reader, or it furnishes data for reproaching him with a surprising failure to apprehend correctly the teaching of the history of philosophy. A man of his insight and knowledge, in order to evade the accusation either of ignorapce or of equivocation, should have seen that " reason " was, in general parlance, a term for all the intellectual energies, whether intuitive or ratiocinative. The possession of the first of these qualifications was sufficient to connect 46 INTRODUCTION. it with the will much more closely than the general spirit of his argument would indicate. The next subject for consideration is Hume's theory of moral principles . We have already alluH'ed to the separa- tion which he makes between the doctrine of freedom and the theory of morals, and to the fact that he probably regarded that doctrine as a psychological question. We must remark farther that he was probably wiser than he knew at the time. His discussion of the will in connection with the passions made it necessary to abandon all psycho- logical matters when he came to the problem of morals. This was a great gain, and students will hardly fail to perceive how it was, consciously or unconsciously, an anticipation of Kant's method, which aimed to present the deduction not the historical genesis of moral ideas and principles. Hume begins an entirely new system and method with his third book, although in one important respect he is still linked to the past. It is in regard to his doctrine of a " moral sense." i With Locke and the contemporaries of Hume the problem was mainly genetic. This is to say that it was concerned with the origin of moral distinctions. But there are two kinds of "origin," quite distinct in their nature, and yet usually complicated with each other in the same questions. They are the psychological and the historical origin of ideas. Both are quite different from the logical deduction of prin- ciples, and all three constitute as many distinct problems for philosophy. The psychological "origin" of ideas properly concerns their mental source and the mental elements constituting them. Their historical "origin" is a question of the time they come into existence and of the circumstances which elicit them into consciousness. . Their deduction is occupied with a determination of the general principles upon which particular moral ideas rest for their meaning and authority, and this investigation can be carried INTRODUCTION. 47 on without any reference to the "origin," a priori or em- pirical, of moral ideas. Now Locke's polemic against "innate ideas" committed him to the view that moral con- ceptions were not a part of the original constitution of the mind, or of a simple faculty, but were the product of experience. He treated them as "complex ideas," which, although their elements might have a natural source in the mind, were themselves derived, as subsequent thinkers expressed it, by association. Hence he did not raise or discuss the question in regard to the special mental source of these ideas. He was occupied mainly with their histori- cal genesis. But his system assumed, with the general belief of the age, that moral distinctions were purely intellectual, if it did not directly assert the fact. Scepticism is in a peculiar situation here. It can hardly attack Locke's empiricism without strengthening the doctrine of " innate I ideas," which would make scepticism appear rather un- natural, to say the least. Hence it must appeal to another resource in order to attain its object. Hume's sceptical tendency, therefore, on the one hand, and his sympathy with the doctrine of a "moral sense," on the other, permit him only one resort. He departs from Locke and the intellectualists so far as to consider whether moral distinc- tions are intellectual or " sentimental " in their source. This mode of discussion enables him to avoid implicating his scepticism in an indirect defence of "innate ideas," while he can support the naturalness or nativity of moral principles and avail himself of the difference between reason and passion to refute intellectualism, on the one hand, and to prepare the way for emphasizing the motive element of morality, on the other. Hence Hume's first step is to deny that "reason" is the source of moral distinctions, and to affirm that it is "sentiment." His grounds for this position are the same as those by which he limited the influence of reason upon the will. Morals, he asserts, have to do with 48 INTRODUCTION. fthe distribution of praise and blame, and as these cannot apply to ideas, which are the products of reason, he thinks that reason cannot be the source of the distinction we make [between vice and virtue. It is difficult to criticise Hume's position on this ques- tion. There is so much truth in his point of view when correctly understood, and so much that is worthy in the object at which he aims, that criticism against him may appear to be dictated by a general dislike of his philosophy. It is easy to make his reputation among the orthodox a text for a homily against scepticism. But such a policy directed against his morals would be a grave mistake. Hume is not so sceptical in this part of his work as in the book on the understanding. He is not aiming to destroy certain views out of sheer mischief, nor to merely expose the difficulties of existing beliefs. All this we have previously explained. On the contrary, the only negative criticism he indulges is done in order to prepare the way for a constructive theory of morals on the lines of Hutcheson, Shaftesbury and Reid. We should never lose sight of this fact in estimating his doctrine. He attacks the intellectualists of the day, not in behalf of scepticism, but in the interest of a doctrine of " moral sense," which, although it was founded in the sen- timents rather than in the understanding, preserved all that was valuable in the theory of "innate ideas" and suggested an element in moral principles and conduct not properly recognized by that view. Students of the history of ethics will easily remark that Hume, when opposing intellectualism, has in mind the rather erratic doctrines of Clarke and Wollaston, and there is much in their views to justify his criticism of them. In fact it is an apology for Hume to know what the views of the extreme intellectualists were. And yet he did not fully appreciate the basis and the spirit of their doctrine, and in some cases misrepresented it, though perhaps unconsciously. INTRODUCTION. 49 The reason for this is his misunderstanding of the term "reason " in the history of morals. He still seems to think that it denotes only a ratiocinative power and that previous writers regarded " morality, like truth, to be discerned merely by ideas and by their juxtaposition and comparison." But this supposition represents an entire misunderstanding of the case. Previous writers had no intention of affirming that moral principles had a ratiocinative origin. What they intended was to assert a derivation independent of blind instincts, in order both to vindicate the freedom of the will and to contrast what we call rational with impulsive conduct. At the risk of some repetition we must refer again to the history of this term. The original antithesis which Plato wished to establish was that between conscious and uncon- scious conduct ; or perhaps better, between intentional and unintentional conduct. He did this by distinguishing between " reason " (voBs) and impulse or passion (l-mdv^ia and #v/x,os). His system assumed that passion acted without reference to a conscious purpose, or idea of an end to be intentionally realized. Although psychology in the course of its development has changed its conception of the passions in this respect, gradually coming to regard them as conscious, but non-deliberative, it still retained the old antithesis between reason and impulse or passion, while the term " reason " was also doing service for both the percep- tive (vovs) and the ratiocinative (Aoyos) function of the mind. There were tendencies at the time of Hume to limit reason to its ratiocinative import, as is evinced by the threefold division of the mind into "sense," "understanding," and "reason." The understanding was the faculty of concep- tions and judgments, and reason the logical faculty. In this view the more comprehensive conception of the term was forgotten. This whole tendency is quite as apparent in Kant as in Hume and others ; and it created a very natural 5° INTRODUCTION. resource for those who felt the difference between " specu- lative " and " practical " thought. Now when in the later psychology the passions came to be regarded as conscious influences upon the will, they absorbed all that Plato had meant by reason, and hence nothing was left of his antithesis except such as clings by tradition to the forms of language, and the irremovable difference between ratiocinative and impulsive functions. It was clear that the purely contemplative and perceptive exercise of reason could not be a " motive " to volition in the same manner as the passions, and hence upon this transparent fact, while unconscious of the equivocal addition made to the functions of the passions, and assuming the traditional import of the term that they were the motive efficients of the will, an easy argument was constructed both for determinism and against the motivation of reason. vBut here it was that Hume forgot or ignored the synthetic, Ithat is to say, complex character of "motives." They must ponsist of ideas of ends and motive impulses, the former derived from reason, in the comprehensive sense, and the latter from desire, as has already been remarked. In this way he might have seen what current usage meant by the term and have qualified his criticism. By such a course he would have discovered that the motivation of reason was 1 not opposed, but really at the basis of his own doctrine of a "moral sense." This, we think, can be made out from a statement that represents the doctrine of Hume in a nutshell. "Actions," he says, " may be laudable or blamable, but they cannot be reasonable or unreasonable : laudable or blamable, there- fore, are not the same with reasonable or unreasonable." Nothing can be truer than this if we mean that volitions cannot be like logical or perceptive processes ; and if historical writers had intended that they should be so considered, Hume's position could not be contested. But INTRODUCTION. 51 his limitation of the terms "reasonable" and "unreason- able" is a distortion of both their original and their traditional import, and it is amazing to find Hume either unaware of the fact, or resorting to a transparent equivoca- tion for the sake of a temporary logical triumph. His own position gets its cogency only by making the most of an obliquity which is entirely of his own producing. He cannot find it as a concession of the intellectualists. The only excuse he might be entitled to use would be an inference from the logical distinction between understand- ing and reason. But what he would gain by this expedient would be lost by accepting " sense " instead of understand ing as the source of moral principles, because the elimina- tion of intellectual elements with the understanding would result only in either the absurdity of making all moral ideas sensuous and more definite and uniform in conception than their actual relativity and Hume's appeal to this fact would justify, or in using the term " sense " as a real equivalent of understanding and reason, internal perception, which was evidently the import intended by Hutcheson and Shaftes- bury. Looked at in this light his contention seems no better than a logomachy. "Reasonable" and "unreason- able " as applied to morals in Hume's own time were intended to express conformity and non-conformity to the laws determined by consciousness as opposed to blind instinct, and not to denote merely ratiocinative processes. There was nothing, therefore, out of the way in the common view, unless some stickler for logical usage chose to misin- terpret or misrepresent accepted language. In spite of this, however, there is a very important truth in Hume's position, which ought, perhaps, to exempt him from unqualified censure. His distinction between the" functions of reason and passion in relation to morality calls attention anew to the fact that there is no necessary , connection between knowledge and virtue ; that morality is/ 52 INTRODUCTION. not the perception of right, but the willing of it. Only, Hume should not have used language which implied that moral distinctions arose outside of reason. That which he really emphasized, in spite of his misrepresentation of the matter, was what may be called the moral as compared with the intellectual side of conduct. The distinction he had in mind was the same as that of Aristotle between the "natural" and the "acquired virtues." To urge this was I only to say that the distinctive characteristic of morality is la quality of will, and to recognize this fact was to anticipate the analysis which Kant worked out without involving him- self in the paradox of excluding "reason" from a prominent influence upon morality. Moral action, said Kant, consists first in the "good will," which was not a "speculative," but a "practical" function of "reason." Knowledge (conditioned, but did not constitute moral conduct, accord- ing to him. Hume's real view is not far enough removed from this to criticise it unqualifiedly. As a practical moralist he saw that in dealing with men the problem was to move their wills less than it was to convince their intellects, and hence their characters were to be estimated and their wills moved by other elements than mere knowledge. There is a just criticism, nevertheless, which can be pro- duced against Hume at this point. He puts forward as his problem the origin and foundation of moral principles, and in discussing it he confuses two distinct questions. Instead of discussing only the way in which moral rlisrmrriT ms originatedlhe enters into the question of what it is that makes an action mor al. In this way he fails to distinguish between the psycho-gonic question and what may be called the deductive or psycho-derivative question. The former has to do with the genesis of moral distinctions, ideas, or principles, and the other with the coefficients of moral action. Had Hume recognized the difference between the INTRODUCTION. 53 two problems he would not have entered the controversy about the relation of reason to the will, and could have sustained his intended position with better success and less difficulty. Moral principles originate in ideas, but they are realized by motive agencies superadded to them and having their efficiency in the passions or emotions. The emphasis of the latter factor was the merit of Hume's position, but unfortunately he made it in language which put the matter at the expense of the relation between reason and the will. In the first edition of his Morals Hume does not define his relation to utilitarianism so distinctly as in the edition of 1752. After stating the case in favor of a "moral sense" and the import of the terms " natural " and " artificial," by which he expects to describe moral principles in general, he proceeds to discuss the origin of the ideas of justice and injustice. Justice he seems to regard as the fundamental conception out of which all other moral principles arise. Hence he does not begin, as Plato and moralists generally would have done, with an investigation of the summum bonum. This is simply assumed to be pleasure. "Tn the later edition he uses the term utility to define this good, and thereby indicates more clearly the point of view from which his principles of morals are to be judged. It is not necessary here to enter into a general discussion of utilitarianism in order to determine either the merits or demerits of Hume's special doctrine. We are interested only in the extent to which Hume could support his doctrine from the premises assumed. In general, we regard the doctrine of utilitarians as possessing sufficient merits to secure it against unqualified criticism. It requires only to be modified, although this modification may be radical, in order to be commended to general acceptance. Like most other one-sided theories it is liable to misapplication and abuse. But in so far as Hume is concerned this liability is not so great, for the simple reason that he did not develop 54 INTRODUCTION. the doctrine after the manner of Bentham and Mill. He was too much bound by the genetic conception of the moral problem, after Locke's example, to devote himself wholly to the deductive question as it appeared to them. Yet his position on the matter is open to a unique criticism which weakens his utilitarianism, although we may find in his psychological analysis a very interesting conception of the matter which may modify the force of the criticism, or suggest to the utilitarian a very effective defence of his theory ; a defence also which will not antagonize the opposing doctrine. We know that utilitarianism requires pleasure to be the ultimate end of conduct. The defenders of the theory assert that pleasure and pain are the motives of all action. It would be unfair to them to say that this expresses exactly what they mean. They intend to say that it is either the idea or the desire of pleasure and aversion to pain, perhaps both the idea and the desire, that form the motive to con- duct. Certainly this is the only defensible meaning that can be advanced. A double difficulty is, therefore, suggested by Hume's position on the matter.(\)In the first place, assuming as he does that all action is for pleasure or to avoid pain, he cannot allow them to be motives to volition, because he excludes them from the passions and places them among the impressions of sense and reflection. Even if pleasure and pain as present states could be regarded as motives in the ordinary theory of utilitarianism they could not be so considered in Hume's conception of the problem, because of the above mentioned psychological analysis. He would, therefore, be compelled either to abandon his utili- tarianism or to modify his view of the relation between pleasure and pain, and the will. But these alternatives are forced upon him only because he had denied or greatly disparaged the common view about the motivation of reason in volition^ In the second place, having maintained that INTRODUCTION. 55 ideas and impressions could not be motives to volition, and having classed pleasure and pain among them, Hume virtually excluded the latter from a place among the ends of conduct. But utilitarianism has no right to existence unless it can claim pleasure to be the ultimate end of action, and in so far as Hume makes it impossible so to regard pleasure he cuts away the foundations of his theory. He may be right about the fact that pleasure is such an end, but his classification of it among the impressions and ideas nullifies his claim to that assertion. Hume's psychological position, however, suggests a very interesting analysis of the ethical problem. In his discus- sion on the origin of the idea of justice he shows very clearly his peculiar conception of the term " motive," to denote merely an impulse to volition, and an impulse that cannot properly be regarded as representing a preconceived idea. It is merely the efficient cause of volition without the mnal. For instance, he asserts in italics, the summary of a long discussion, "that no action can be virtuous, or morally good, unless there be in human nature some motive to produce it, distinct from the sense of its morality." We do not care at this point of the discussion to dispute this view. But we wish only to call attention to the conception of the term "motive," which, as in his illustration of benevolence being moral without the conscious recognition of its good- ness, must denote a blind instinct, and this conclusion is enforced by his exclusion of " reason " from a determination of morality. The " motive " of action is thus not only a mere efficient cause, but it is also different from the end of conduct, and from the idea of that end. Accepting for the moment this conception of the case we have three distinct elements recognized, at least by implication, in Hume's position. They are the motive, the end, and the " sense of morality." Two interesting facts can be deduced from this view. First, Hume clearly distinguishes between the mor- 56 INTRODUCTION. ality of conduct and the sense of its morality. This distinction can be reduced to that between instinctive or unreflective, and conscious or reflective morality, which is quite an important one to make in discussing the theory of ethics. Instinctive morality is conduct which we can call good on the ground that the end sought is approvable and the agent has the disposition to seek it without a temptation to do otherwise. In this form, morality has not reached its rational stage. Conscious or reflective morality is the con- duct of a man who knows that what he is doing is right, and so has a sense of its worth and binding character. Here morality is rational. But Hume was shut out of developing his doctrine up to this point by his exclusion of reason from a part in it, and yet his analysis requires that the doctrine be developed in this very way. I In the second place, if the development of the theory of ethics goes so far beyond Hume's restriction of the term " motive " to mere desire, independent of " ideas " or consciousness, as to admit the accompaniment of the "sense of morality," there will be the basis for an interesting reconciliation between utilitari- anism and Kantianism, in which the categorical imperative is the only spring of true morality. For by combining the "motive" and the "sense of morality," as modern moralists do in regarding the "motive " as a synthesis of an idea and 1 an impulse, we have only to distinguish between the motive \ and the consequent in order to see that the good sought \may be one thing and the motive to it represent an entirely \distinct element of consciousness. That is, utility or Pleasure might be the summum Ionian, while the pursuit of it would get its moral character, not from the fact that man had an impulse in that direction blindly considered, but from the fact that he sought it rationally or under the sense of duty. In this way we might hold that "the sense of morality" was the formal, and utility the material element of virtue, a position which after all is not only that of Kant INTRODUCTION. 57 as reflected in his recognition of "universal happiness' as the end of moral action, but is also quite in keeping with Hume, who makes the virtue of conduct to consist wholly in the motive. The strangest thing in the case is, that Hume should have admitted, as he did, that " the sense of morality " should motivate volition and yet not give it moral charac- ter. This was no better than making morality a matter of pure, blind instinct. It might be consistent with the denial of the motivation of the will by reason, but this consistency was purchased at the expense of everything which elevated man's conduct above that of the animal. Hence, the mo- ment that " the sense of morality " was recognized by philosophers as both a motive to volition and a determinant of high merit in it, Hume's doctrine that the " motive " only could moralize conduct, was transformed into Kant's theory of the "good will." There are some very paradoxical remarks by Hume in his treatment of justice, and since he is here dealing with the fundamental principles of morals, they require some con- sideration. The first most interesting fa%t to be noticed is his conception of justice. He does not define it clearly, but only indicates the class of phenomena to which it belongs and whose essential nature it shares. In the first part of the book he had discussed the relation of moral principles to "nature," and after recognizing three different meanings for the term decides that moral principles are "artificial." In this latter class he places justice. "There are some virtues," he says, "that produce pleasure and approbation by means of an artifice or contrivance, which arises from the circumstances and necessity of mankind. Of this kind I assert justice to be." The first criticism which this observation would instigate, would be, especially if Cudworth had an opportunity to attack it, that it is the old conventionalism of the sophists 58 INTRODUCTION. and sceptics rejuvenated. The language unmistakably suggests this view, but the criticism nevertheless misrepre- sents the real and true position of Hume. For he is careful to say that although justice is conventional in its origin it is not arbitrary, and he enforces this remark by the farther assertion that the framers of moral rules always had to rely upon some ultimate principles in the constitution of man. " The utmost politicians can perform," he says, " is to extend the natural sentiments beyond their original bounds ; but still nature must furnish the materials, and give us some notion of moral distinctions.'' This effectually sets aside the old doctrine of relativity and of convention- alism, although- it may not make his own view so intelligible as is desired. But previous to his investigation into the nature of this " artifice " by which ideas of justice came into existence, Hume ventures upon a short, and, he thinks, convincing proof of his position. It consists of an analysis of moral action, to some features of which we have already alluded. " The external performance," says Hume, " has no merit. We must look witfiirt to find the moral quality." He then affirms that this quality is found in the motive, but as this cannot be directly ascertained in others the actions have to be regarded as the signs of the motives. In this way, he concludes that " all virtuous actions derive their merit only from virtuous motives," and adds farther that "the first virtuous motive, which bestows a merit on any action, can never be a regard to the virtue of that action, but must be some other natural motive or principle." But Hume has to face the question whether " the sense of morality or duty " may not motivate volition without the existence of any other "natural motive or principle," and he answers it by saying : " Though, on some occasions, a person may per- form an action merely out of regard to its moral obligation, yet still this supposes in human nature some distinct INTRODUCTION. 59 principles, which are capable of producing the action and whose moral beauty renders the action meritorious." Hume's doctrine of morality may possibly be tested by this last remark. He admits that sometimes volition may be motivated by the sense of duty, and we may ask how he can reconcile with this admission the assertion that it " sup- poses in human nature some distinct principles which are capable of producing the action." It may be a fact that there are such " principles," but Hume mistakes a connec- tion of fact for a connection of implication. The existence of other motives to action is not implied by the existence of the sense of duty, although in fact we may find them invariably associated. Again, if "the sense of morality or duty " alone may produce an action, how can it consist with this to suppose other motives as necessarily operative and implied ? But not to urge this contradiction, which may be due to mere carelessness, we may still ask how it is possible for the action to be a sign of the motive if both " the sense of morality " and some " natural motive or principle " may either separately or together motivate volition ? According to Hume the " natural motive " determines the merits of conduct, and if so, to which motive does the act as a sign testify? If it attests only the "natural motive," there is no circumstance in which the existence of " the sense of morality " can be proved. But if it attests " the sense of morality " in any case, according to Hume, the act could not be moral for the lack of the accompanying "natural motive." If it attests the existence of both motives there is no reason for distinguishing their sanctifying power. In fact, Hume has not provided for those cases in which there is a struggle between duty* and interest, although the differ- ence which he assumes between " the sense of morality " and " natural motives " requires him to do so. Where that struggle exists and the motive of duty is obeyed, we have evidence of the sole motivation of "the sense of morality," 60 INTRODUCTION. so that the establishment of this fact would bring upon Hume's position all the criticisms we have advanced. Again, to make virtue consist in action from a motive other than a regard to its morality is to affiliate his doctrine with that which makes virtue purely a matter of instinct, in the narrower sense of the term. This is consistent enough in Hume after depreciating the influence of reason upon conduct, and although we may not be able to reproach him with an inconsistency here, probably so bold a statement of his position or of what it implies will expose its inherent weakness. But we have this object much less in view than to call attention to an omission on his part which led him into his paradoxical assertions and exposed him to the redudio ad absurdum just mentioned. It was his failure to distinguish between naive or unreflective, and conscious or reflective morality. His view that the virtue of an act con- sisted solely in the character of the motive did not permit him to distinguish between internal and external morality. To him all morality had to be internal ; that is, representa- tive of character, not of a physical order in the world. But he could have distinguished between instinctive or natural and conscious or rational morality. We may say that the differences between them are in kind or in degree, just as we are pleased to state the case, but they are not opposed to each other. Hume's failure, however, to recognize this double character of conduct, which we approve as "moral," involved him in two difficulties : first, in making virtue dependent on impulses which have generally been regarded as non-moral, on the ground that they were purely instinctive, while affirming that the motive was the sole source of virtue, and second, in assuming that "the sense of morality" c;ave no merit to conduct, while he could hardly have denied that the consciousness of obligation greatly increased the indi- vidual's responsibility. The trouble is that Hume had no means of solving the. problem in the comparison between INTRODUCTION. 61 those who have no temptations and those who resist them. Only those without temptations could be moral or immoral in his system. What Hume was seeking to show, however, in the para- doxical position, that all virtuous conduct must be derived from motives "distinct from the sense of morality," was the fact that "the sense of morality" is an "artificial" product of man's necessity and circumstances. Here we have the true motive to his doctrine, and in it we may trace very clearly the lineage of the theories of Bentham, Mill, Spencer, and evolutionists generally. We know how it has been developed by these writers and do not require more than to recognize its historical relations. Hume takes the matter up in the section on "the Origin of Justice and Property." hat the position amounts to, on general principles, is, that 1 the ideas passing current among traditional moralists as representative of rational morality are conventional in their irigin, but not arbitrary, as Hume would say. This is to ay that the sense of duty, or the categorical imperative, is ot among the natural endowments of man. We shall enter neither into the statement of his doctrine nor into a criticism of his argument on this particular point. To treat the matter with due exhaustiveness we should be obliged to go into the complicated theories of the associa- tionists and evolutionists. It must suffice for the present merely to indicate this general direction of his speculation. To say that morality is conventional is to reanimate the old controversy of the sophists, except that Hume saves himself from the imputation of their shallowness, by admitting a natural element at the same time as the basis of the con- vention. But in asserting a place and influence for convention at all, he merely stated in more traditional language Bentham's doctrine of "political sanctions," and Herbert Spencer's theory of "political restraint" or "con- trol," and these views are the true descendants of Hume's. 62 INTRODUCTION. The error in all of them lies less in the assertion that political influences and conventions affect our current moral ideas than in the implication usually understood, perhaps wrongly, that these agencies create morality instead of merely making it effective or eliciting it into consciousness. It may be said that Hume's admission of a natural element at the foundation of convention involves this view of the case, and we grant that it does. Only Hume had not dis- tinguished between the ratio fiendi of moral ideas and the ratio fiendi of morality, a mistake, however, which was very general in that age. What he ought to have remarked was the fact that convention and law can only give motive efficiency to moral conceptions already existent, instead of using language which implies that the quality of conduct was a matter of creation by government. In spite of this criticism, however, it is always possible for a defender of Hume to say that his admission of "natural" principles at the basis of convention was a recognition of this view, and even if we do not accord him the credit of consciously proposing this distinction it is there as a greater or less tribute to his understanding and as a concession to the opponents of pure empiricism. And yet in making this concession Hume may have been a victim of the equivoca- tions which he himself had exposed in the use of the term "natural." But if this be so, it is hardly possible to make anything intelligible out of his system. Besides, we cannot so easily explain the inconsistency between affirming that "moral distinctions are derived from a moral sense," which must be natural if anything, and affirming that they are the creations of convention or "artifice." Hume's only escape from this criticism would be to maintain that the "moral sense" and "the sense of morality or duty" were the same and that both were products of experience. But he seems nowhere to make this claim, while the only rational implica- tions of his statements are that the "moral sense" is a INTRODUCTION. 63 natural endowment and that "the sense of morality or duty" is an empirical product, a conclusion which either establishes a contradiction in Hume's system or indicates that the controversy between the apriorist and empiricist represents an entirely false conception of the true ethical problem. It is also a pertinent question to ask a sceptic who, like Hume, cherishes considerable animosity toward theology, whether the view that conscience or "the sense of morality" is not a natural endowment of man, does not leave the whole field of ethics open to the theologian ? Certainly a purely negative conclusion like this would do so. But Hume's escape from such an imputation lies in his positive view that "the sense of morality" is a conventional product •of social life and its necessities. This asserts a human as opposed to a divine origin of the moral law. But it is not apparent in this doctrine that human convention and "artifice" are any better sources of morality than the arbitrary enactments of the divine will. Indeed it would puzzle any mind to tell the difference. Hume here lost his opportunity to show that the theologian was the real em- piricist and that his doctrine defining morality as a creation of the divine will was in conflict with its a priori origin in reason. Hume might, in this contingency, have made a strong ad hominem argument in favor of his theory of a moral sense, by using the theologian's prejudice against empiricism to refute the created character of moral dis- tinctions. As it is, however, the assertion that convention can originate morality is a tacit admission of the theologian's point of view ; namely, the created nature of morality. Again, it may be a question whether Hume would have a right to appeal to the conception of a conventional origin of moral distinctions as a refutation of theological and intuitive views, because, after his radical distinction between "natural motives" to volition and "the sense of morality," 64 INTRODUCTION. asserting that the latter is an "artificial" product and that it cannot confer any merit upon conduct, he is left without a shred of ground upon which to base a theory of empiri- cism. If "the sense of morality" were, in Hume's view, a modification of "natural" impulses, it could confer merit upon conduct ; but since it cannot confer this merit, accord- ing to his statements, it cannot have the moral character- istics of "natural motives," and it is the motive, in Hume's view, that determines the character of the act. Hence it is apparent that the origin of "the sense of morality" by con- vention is in no way the origin of a moral impulse, so that Hume's empiricism can in no respect legitimately antagonize the theories of apriorism in so far as they maintain the naturalness of moral principles. A rather conclusive con- firmation of this, also, is Hume's own statement near the close of Section II., where he is discussing the origin of justice and property. "Any artifice of politicians," he says, " may assist nature in the producing of those sentiments which she suggests to us, and may even, on some occasions, produce alone an approbation or esteem for any particular action ; but 'tis impossible it should be the sole cause of the distinction we make betwixt vice and virtue. For if nature did not aid us in this particular, 't would be in vain for politicians to talk of honorable or dishonorable, praise- worthy or blameable. These words would be perfectly unintelligible, and would no more have any idea annexed to them, than if they were a tongue perfectly unknown to us. The utmost politicians can perform, is, to extend the natural sentiments beyond their original bounds ; but still nature must furnish the materials, and give us some notion of moral distinctions." This remarkable concession very greatly limits the area of "artificial" moral conceptions, and it would have been well for the empirical successors of Hume if they could have granted as much. It is not a little interesting to note that, INTRODUCTION. 65 while claiming him as the father of modern empiricism, barring the claim of Locke, they systematically ignore the ineradicable limitations he puts upon that doctrine. Hume himself also seems unaware of the fact that his position in this passage practically admits the unique and original nature of "the sense of morality," since the passage limits the function of convention merely to extending moral principles and conceptions already in existence. But in spite of the inconsistency which, in one conception of the terms, can be charged upon Hume for these and other statements, there is so much truth in his position, when we distinguish, as he did not, between the origin of the intension and the origin of the extension of moral ideas, that it is an ungrateful task to criticise him severely. We should rather quote him to show that modern empiricists have departed from their much vaunted master in their efforts to make morality wholly conventional. The proper criticism against Hume is that, in common with the moralists of his age, he treated the subject as if the problem was the origin and not rather the ground and validity of morality. The empiricists of to-day have not fully learned this fact, owing, no doubt, to their failure to appreciate the work of Kant. They simply adopted one half of Hume's principles and shunned Kant as they would Augustine or Aquinas, and as a consequence treat the whole problem of Ethics as if it were natural history. Hume saw better than this, and had he extricated himself from the confusion of treating the question as a controversy between natural and conventional morality ; that is, as a problem of the ratio fiendi rather than the ratio essendi of moral principles, he might have contested with Kant the palm of philosophic honors. As it is he simply comes short of that result and leaves the student in perpet- ual fear of doing him injustice, if the system is criticised without qualification, and of ignoring one half his theory if he is represented as a pure empiricist. In fact, Hume 66 INTRODUCTION. simply marks a transition, and his Ethics show all the instability and incompleteness of analysis which character- izes a transitional period. It remained for subsequent schools to cut a better path into the wilderness. Their success is still sub judicc. But they represent two distinct tendencies, the empirical or evolutionistic and the transcen- dental or Kanto-Hegelian, both properly tracing their lineage to Hume. JAMES H. HYSLOP. Columbia College. BOOK II. OF THE PASSIONS. PART I. OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY. SECTION I. Division of the Subject. As all the perceptions of the mind may be divided into impressions and ideas, so the impressions admit of another division into original and secondary. This division of the im- pressions is the same with that which 1 I formerly made use of when I distinguish'd them into impressions of sensation and reflection. Original impressions or impressions of sen- sation are such as without any antecedent perception arise in the soul, from the constitution of the body, from the animal spirits, or from the application of objects to the external organs. Secondary, or reflective impressions are such as proceed from some of these original ones, either immediately or by the interposition of its idea. Of the first kind are all the impressions of the senses, and all bodily pains and pleasures : Of the second are the passions, and other emotions resembling them. 'Tis certain, that the mind, in its perceptions, must begin somewhere ; and that since the impressions precede their correspondent ideas, there must be some impressions, which without any introduction make their appearance in the soul. As these depend upon natural and physical causes, the examination of them wou'd lead me too far from my present subject, into the sciences of anatomy and natural philosophy. 1 Book I. Part I. sect. 2. 68 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. For this reason I shall here confine myself to those other impressions, which I have call'd secondary and reflective, as arising either from the original impressions, or from their ideas. Bodily pains and pleasures are the source of many passions, both when felt and consider'd by the mind; but arise originally in the soul, or in the body, whichever you please to call it, without any preceding thought or percep- tion. A fit of the gout produces a long train of passions, as grief, hope, fear; but is not deriv'd immediately from any affection or idea. The reflective impressions may be divided into two kinds, viz., the calm and the violent. Of the first kind is the sense of beauty and deformity in action, composition, and exter- nal objects. Of the second are the passions of love and hatred, grief and joy, pride and humility. This division is far from being exact. The raptures of poetry and music frequently rise to the greatest height; while those other impressions, properly called passions, may decay into so soft an emotion, as to become, in a manner, imperceptible. But as in general the passions are more violent than the emotions arising from beauty and deformity, these impres- sions have been commonly distinguished from each other. The subject of the human mind being so copious and vari- ous, I shall here take advantage of this vulgar and specious division, that I may proceed with the greater order; and having said all I thought necessary concerning our ideas, shall now explain those violent emotions or passions, their nature, origin, causes, and effects. When we take a survey of the passions, there occurs a division of them into direct and indirect. By direct passions I understand such as arise immediately from good or evil, from pain or pleasure. By indirect such as proceed from the same principles, but by the conjunction of other qual- ities. This distinction I cannot at present justify or explain any farther. I can only observe in general, that under the Book II. OF THE PASSfONS. 69 indirect passions I comprehend pride, humility, ambition, vanity, love, hatred, envy, pity, malice, generosity, with their dependants. And under the direct passions, desire, aver- sion, grief, joy, hope, fear, despair and security. I shall begin with the former. [Hume then proceeds to give the " objects " and " causes " of pride and humility, both of which conceptions he takes in a very broad sense. "The object," he says, "is self, or that succession of related ideas and impressions, of which we have an intimate memory and consciousness." He does not think it possible, however, that the cause can be the same as their object. Hence he says : "Pride and humility, being once rais'd, immediately turn our attention to ourself, and regard that as their ultimate and final object ; but there is something farther requisite in order to raise them : some- thing which is peculiar to one of the passions, and produces not both in the very same degree. The first idea, that is presented to the mind, is that of the cause or productive principles. This excites the passion connected with it ; and that passion, when excited, turns our view to another idea, which is that of self. Here then is a passion plac'd betwixt two ideas, of which the one produces it, and the other is produced by it. The first idea, therefore, represents the cause, the second the object of the passion." The causes of pride and humility are then enumerated and are made to consist of a great variety of " subjects," as Hume chooses to call them, as distinguished from the " objects " of the pas- sion. They are "every quality of mind, whether of the imagination, judgment, memory, or disposition ; wit, good sense, learning, courage, justice, integrity; all these are the causes of pride ; and their opposites, of humility." Further causes, to go beyond merely mental qualities are, " beauty strength, agility, good mien, address in dancing, riding, fencing, and of his dexterity in any manual business or 7° A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. manufacture." But these are not all. " Country, family, children, relations, riches, houses, gardens, horses, dogs, clothes ; any of these may become a cause of either pride or of humility." In regard to the causes Hume farther dis- tinguishes between the "quality which operates and the subject on which it is plac'd." In the case of a beautiful house considered as the cause of a passion, the beauty is the quality, and the house is the subject. The next section takes up the derivation of the causes and objects of the two passions. Hume's purpose is to find what it is that connects them with the passions. He main- tains that their influence " proceeds from an original quality or primary impulse " of the individual who has the passions, and that it is the distinguishing characteristic of these pas- sions to be natural. But in order to explain how it is that such a variety of causes and objects is connected with the same effect ; that is, how such different " causes " as a house and wit may be sources of pride, Hume proceeds to show " that 'tis from natural principles this variety of causes excite pride and humility, and that 'tis not by a different principle each different cause is adapted to its passion," and this is accomplished by referring to the law of association of ideas, as enabling different "subjects" to affect the individual in the same way. It is the manner in which they concur to produce pleasure and pain that links them with the same end, and as " all agreeable objects, related to ourselves, by an association of ideas and of im- pressions, produce pride, and disagreeable ones humility," we may find in this concurrence the unity of the principle affecting the passions concerned. Hume admits five limita- tions to his principle, but they do not affect the main dis- tinctions in question according to his view. His next task is then to show how the various "causes " including "vice and virtue," "beauty and deformity," "external advantages and disadvantages," " property and riches," and "the love of fame " affect pride and humility. Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 71 Part II. on the Passions gives the same treatment of "love and hatred " as is given to pride and humility. Hume distinguishes in the same manner as before between the "causes" and the "objects" of them. As in pride and humility the "object" is self, so in love and hatred the " object " is others. The " causes '' are diversified as be- fore, but are related to a thinking being, and are such qualities as " virtue, knowledge, wit, good sense, good humour." Physical objects do not awaken them. The remainder of this section is occupied with special cases of influence upon the two passions. A separate and peculiar treatment is given to " benevo- lence and anger." They are not regarded as forms, but only as accompaniments, of love and hatred. The last two passions, therefore, entail desire and aversion. " Pride and humility are pure emotions in the soul unattended with any desire, and not immediately exciting us to action. But love and hatred are not completed within themselves, nor rest in- that emotion which they produce, but carry the mind to something further." Love and hatred have not only a cause and object, but also an end, which they reach through desire and aversion. Benevolence and anger are the accompany- ing agents or means to this end. The discussion of com- passion, of malice and envy, and of mixed emotions is only a consideration of modified forms and circumstances of the second general class of emotions and passions which Hume regards as preliminary to his examination of the desires and the will. In them he means to define the mental excite- ments expressing the various manifestations of pleasure and pain, and so to indicate the causes and objects of the states of mind affecting self and others as the conditions of all the movements of the will. It is interesting to remark that his analysis and classification excludes from them all impulsive characteristics. They have "objects," but not ends unless they become complicated with the desires and aversions. 72 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. The matter, however, has mainly a psychological interest, and requires notice only in order to understand Hume's dis- cussion in this connection of the freedom of the will, which, although more properly appearing as a part of the required ethical postulates, is examined as a part of the psychology of the emotions. This is part third of his chapters on the passions.] PART III. OF THE WILL AND DIRECT PASSIONS. SECTION I. Of liberty and necessity. We come now to explain the direct passions, or the im- pressions, which arise immediately from good or evil, from pain or pleasure. Of this kind are, desire and aversion, grief and joy, hope and fear. Of all the immediate effects of pain and pleasure, there is none more remarkable than the will ; and tho', properly speaking, it be not comprehended among the passions, yet as the full understanding of its nature and properties, is necessary to the explanation of them, we shall here make it the subject of our enquiry. I desire it may be observ'd, that by the will, I mean nothing but the internal impression we feel and are conscious of, when we knowingly give rise to any new motion of our body, or new perception of our mind. This impression, like the preceding ones of pride and humil- ity, love and hatred, ' tis impossible to define, and needless to describe any farther ; for which reason we shall cut off all those definitions and distinctions, with which philosophers are wont to perplex rather than clear up this question ; and entering at first upon the subject, shall examine that long disputed question concerning liberty and necessity ; which occurs so naturally in treating of the will. Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 73 ' Tis universally acknowledg'd, that the operations of ex- ternal bodies are necessary, and that in the communication of their motion, in their attraction, and mutual cohesion, there are not the least traces of indifference or liberty. Every object is determin'd by an absolute fate to a certain degree and direction of its motion, and can no more depart from that precise line, in which it moves, than it can convert itself into an angel, or spirit, or any superior substance. The actions, therefore, of matter are to be regarded as in- stances of necessary actions ; and whatever is in this respect on the same footing with matter, must be acknowledg'd to be necessary. That we may know whether this be the case with the actions of the mind, we shall begin with examining matter, and considering on what the idea of a necessity in its operations are founded, and why we conclude one body or action to be the infallible cause of another. It has been observ'd already, that in no single instance the ultimate connexion of any objects is discoverable, either by our senses or reason, and that we can never penetrate so far into the essence and construction of bodies, as to perceive the principle, on which their mutual influence depends. ' Tis their constant union alone, with which we are acquainted ; and ' tis from the constant union the necessity arises. If objects had not an uniform and regular conjunction with each other, we shou'd never arrive at any idea of cause and effect ; and even after all, the necessity, which enters into that idea, is nothing but a determination of the mind to pass from one object to its usual attendant, and infer the existence of one from that of the other. Here then are two particulars, which we are to consider as essential to necessity, viz. the constant union and the inference of the mind ; and wherever we discover these we must acknowledge a necessity. As the actions of matter have no necessity, but what is deriv'd from these circumstances, and it is not by any insight into the essence of bodies we discover their connexion, the absence of 74 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. this insight, while the union and inference remain, will never in any case, remove the necessity. ' Tis the observa- tion of the union, which produces the inference ; for which reason it might be thought sufficient, if we prove a constant union in the actions of the mind, in order to establish the inference, along with the necessity of these actions. But that I may bestow a greater force on my reasoning, I shall examine these particulars apart, and shall first prove from experience, that our actions have a constant union with our motives, tempers, and circumstances, before I consider the inferences we draw from it. To this end a very slight and general view of the com- mon course of human affairs will be sufficient. There is no light, in which we can take them, that does not confirm this principle. Whether we consider mankind according to the difference of sexes, ages, governments, conditions, or methods of education; the same uniformity and regular operation of natural principles are discernible. Like causes still produce like effects; in the same manner as in the mutual action of the elements and powers of nature. There are different trees, which regularly produce fruit, whose relish is different from each other; and this regularity will be admitted as an instance of necessity and causes in external bodies. But are the products of Guioinc and of Champagne more regularly different than the- sentiments, actions, and passions of the two sexes, of which the one are distinguish'd by their force and maturity, the other by their delicacy and softness ? Are the changes of our body from infancy to old age more regular and certain than those of our mind and con- duct ? And wou'd a man be more ridiculous, who wou'd expect that an infant of four years old will raise a weight of three hundred pound, than one, who from a person of the same age, wou'd look for a philosophical reasoning, or a prudent and well-concerted action ? Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 75 We must certainly allow, that the cohesion of the parts of matter arises from natural and necessary principles, whatever difficulty we may find in explaining them: And for a like reason we must allow, that human society is founded on like principles; and our reason in the latter case, is better than even that in the former; because we not only observe, that men always seek society, but can also explain the principles, on which this universal propen- sity is founded. For is it more certain, that two flat pieces of marble will unite together, than that two young savages of different sexes will copulate ? Do the children arise from this copulation more uniformly, than does the parents care for their safety and perservation ? And after they have arriv'd at years of discretion by the care of their parents, are the inconveniencies attending their separation more certain than their foresight of these inconveniencies, and their care of avoiding them by a close union and con- federacy ? The skin, poras, muscles, and nerves of a day-labourer are different from those of a man of quality : So are his senti- ments, actions a»d manners. The different stations of life influence the whole fabric, external and internal ; and these different stations arise necessarily, because uniformly, from the necessary and uniform principles of human nature. Men cannot live without society, and cannot be associated without government. Government makes a distinction of property, and establishes the different ranks of men. This produces industry, traffic, manufactures, law-suits, war, leagues, alliances, voyages, travels, cities, fleets, ports, and all those other actions and objects, which cause such a diversity, and at the same time maintain such an uniformity in human life. Shou'd a traveller, returning from a far country, tell us, that he had seen a climate in the fiftieth degree of northern latitude, where all the fruits ripen and come to perfection in the winter, and decay in the summer, after the same manner 76 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. as in England they are produc'd and decay in the contrary seasons, he wou'd find few so credulous as to believe him. I am apt to think a traveller wou'd meet with as little credit, who shou'd inform us of people exactly of the same character with those in Plata's republic on the one hand, or those in Hobbes's Leviathan on the other. There is a general course of nature in human actions, as well as in the operations of the sun and the climate. There are also characters peculiar to different nations and particular persons, as well as com- mon to mankind. The knowledge of these characters is founded on the observation of an uniformity in the actions, that flow from them ; and this uniformity forms the very essence of necessity. I can imagine only one way of eluding this argument, which is by denying that uniformity of human actions, on which it is founded. As long as actions have a constant union and connexion with the situation and temper of the agent, how- ever we may in words refuse to acknowledge the necessity, we really allow the thing. Now some may, perhaps, find a pretext to deny this regular union and connexion. For what is more capricious than human actions ? What more inconstant than the desires of man ? And what creature departs more widely, not only from right reason, but from his own character and disposition ? An hour, a moment is sufficient to make him change from one extreme to another, and overturn what cost the greatest pain and labour to establish. Necessity is regular and certain. Human con- duct is irregular and uncertain. The one, therefore, proceeds not from the other. To this I reply, that in judging of the actions of men we must proceed upon the same maxims, as when we reason concerning external objects. When any phenomena are constantly and invariably conjoin'd together, thev acquire such a connexion in the imagination, that it passes from one to the other, without any doubt or hesitation. But below Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 77 this there are many inferior degrees of evidence and prob- ability, nor does one single contrariety of experiment entirely destroy all our reasoning. The mind ballances the contrary experiments, and deducting the inferior from the superior, proceeds with that degree of assurance or evidence, which remains. Even when these contrary experiments are entirely equal, we remove not the notion of causes and necessity ; but supposing that the usual contrariety proceeds from the operation of contrary and conceal'd causes, we conclude, that the chance or indifference lies only in our judgment on account of our imperfect knowledge, not in the things themselves, which are in every case equally necessary, tho' to appearance not equally constant or certain. No union can be more constant and certain, than that of some actions with some motives and characters ; and if in other cases the union is uncertain, 'tis no more than what happens in the operations of body, nor can we conclude any thing from the one irregularity, which will not follow equally from the other. 'Tis commonly allow'd that mad-men have no liberty. But were we to judge by their actions, these have less regu- larity and constancy than the actions of wise-men, and consequently are farther remov'd. from necessity. Our way of thinking in this particular is, therefore, absolutely incon- sistent ; but is a natural consequence of these confus'd ideas and undefin'd terms, which we so commonly make use of in our reasonings, especially on the present subject. We must now shew, that as the union betwixt motives and actions has the same constancy, as that in any natural operations, so its influence on the understanding is also the same, in determining us to infer the existence of one from that of another. If this shall appear, there is no known circumstance, that enters into the connexion and production of the actions of matter, that is not to be found in all the operations of the mind ; and consequently we cannot, 7& A TREATISE OF HUMAN XATURE. without a manifest absurdity, attribute necessity to the one and refuse it to the other. There is no philosopher, whose judgment is so riveted to this fantastical system of liberty, as not to acknowledge the force of moral evidence, and both in speculation and practice proceed upon it, as upon a reasonable foundation. Now moral evidence is nothing but a conclusion concerning the actions of men, deriv'd from the consideration of their motives, temper and situation. Thus when we see certain characters or figures describ'd upon paper, we infer that the person, who produe'd them, would affirm such facts, the death of Cesar, the success of Augustus, the cruelty of Nero ; and remembring many other concurrent testimonies we conclude, that those facts were once really existent, and that so many men, without any interest, wou'd never con- spire to deceive us ; especially since they must, in the attempt, expose themselves to the derision of all their contemporaries, when these facts were asserted to be recent and universally known. The same kind of reasoning runs thro' politics, war, commerce, oeconomy, and indeed mixes itself so entirely in human life, that 'tis impossible to act or subsist a moment without having recourse to it. A prince, who imposes a tax upon his subjects, expects their com- pliance. A general, who conducts an army, makes account of a certain degree of courage. A merchant looks for fidelity and skill in his factor or super-cargo. A man, who gives orders for his dinner, doubts not of the obedience of his servants. In short, as nothing more nearly interests us than our own actions and those of others, the greatest part of our reasonings is employ'd in judgments concerning them. Now I assert, that whoever reasons after this manner, does ipso facto believe the actions of the will to arise from necessity, and that he knows not what he means, when he denies it. Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 79 All those objects, of which we call the one cause and the other effect, consider'd in themselves, are as distinct and separate from each other, as any two things in nature, nor can we ever, by the most accurate survey of them, infer the existence of the one from that of the other. 'Tis only from experience and the observation of their constant union, that we are able to form this inference ; and even after all, the inference is nothing but the effects of custom on the imagina- tion. We must not here be content with saying, that the idea of cause and effect arises from objects constantly united ; but must affirm, that 'tis the very same with the idea of these objects, and that the necessary connexion is not discover'd by a conclusion of the understanding, but is merely a perception of the mind. Wherever, therefore, we observe the same union, and wherever the union operates in the same manner upon the belief and opinion, we have the idea of causes and necessity, tho' perhaps we may avoid those expressions. Motion in one body in all past instances, that have fallen under our observation, is follow'd upon impulse by motion in another. 'Tis impossible for the mind to penetrate farther. From this constant union it forms the idea of cause and effect, and by its influence feels the necessity. As there is the same constancy, and the same influence in what we call moral evidence, I ask no more. What remains can only be a dispute of words. And indeed, when we consider how aptly natural and moral evidence cement together, and form only one chain of argument betwixt them, we shall make no scruple to allow, that they are of the same nature, and deriv'd from the same principles. A prisoner, who has neither money nor interest discovers the impossibility of his escape, as well from the obstinacy of the gaoler, as from the walls and bars with which he is surrounded ; and in all attempts for his freedom chuses rather to work upon the stone and iron of the one, than upon the inflexible nature of the other. The same 80 A TREATISE OF HUM A A' NATURE. prisoner, when conducted to the scaffold, forsees his death as certainly from the constancy and fidelity of his guards as from the operation of the ax or wheel. His mind runs along a certain train of ideas : The refusal of the soldiers to consent to his escape, the action of the excutioner ; the separation of the head and body ; bleeding, convulsive motions, and death. Here is a connected chain of natural causes and voluntary actions ; but the mind feels no differ- ence betwixt them in passing from one link to another ; nor is less certain of the future event than if it were connected with the present impressions of the memory and senses by a train of causes cemented together by what we are pleas'd to call a physical necessity. The same experiene'd union has the same effect on the mind, whether the united objects be motives, volitions and actions ; or figure and motion. We may change the names of things ; but their nature and their operation on the understanding never change. I dare be positive no one will ever endeavour to refute these reasonings otherwise than by altering my definitions, and assigning a different meaning to the terms of cause, and effect, and necessity, and liberty, and chance. According to my definitions, necessity makes an essential part of causation ; and consequently liberty, by removing necessity, removes also causes, and is the very same thing with chance. As chance is commonly thought to imply a contradiction, and is at least directly contrary to experience, there are always the same arguments against liberty or free-will. If any one alters the definitions, I cannot pretend to argue with him, 'till I know the meaning he assigns to these terms. SECTION II. The same subject continued. I believe we may assign the three following reasons for the prevalence of the doctrine of liberty, however absurd it Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 81 may be in one sense, and unintelligible in any other. First, After we have perform'd any action ; tho' we confess we were influenc'd by particular views and motives; 'tis difficult for us to perswade ourselves we were govern'd by necessity, and that 'twas utterly impossible for us to have acted other- wise ; the idea of necessity seeming to imply something of force, and violence, and constraint, of which we are not sensible. Few are capable of distinguishing betwixt the liberty of spontaniety, as it is call'd in the schools, and the liberty of indifference; betwixt that which is oppos'd to violence, and that which means a negation of necessity and causes. The first is even the most common sense of the word ; and as 'tis only that species of liberty, which it con- cerns us to preserve, our thoughts have been principally turn'd towards it, and have almost universally confounded it with the other. Secondly, there is a false sensation or experie?ice even of the liberty of indifference ; which is regarded as an argu- ment for its real existence. The necessity of any action, whether of matter or of the mind, is not properly a quality in the agent, but in any thinking or intelligent being, who may consider the action, and consists in the determination of his thought to infer its existence from some preceding objects • As liberty or chance, on the other hand, is nothing but the want of that determination, and a certain looseness, which we feel in passing or not passing from the idea of one to that of the other. Now we may observe, that tho' in reflecting on human actions we seldom feel such a looseness or indifference, yet it very commonly happens, that in per- forming the actions themselves we are sensible of something like it : And as all related or resembling objects are readily taken for each other, this has been employ'd as a demon- strative or even an intuitive proof of human liberty. We feel that our actions are subject to our will on most occa- sions, and imagine we feel that the will itself is subject to 82 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. nothing ; because when by a denial of it we are provok'd to try, we feel that it moves easily every way, and produces an image of itself even on that side, on which it did not settle. This image or faint motion, we perswade ourselves, cou'd have been compleated into the thing itself ; because, shou'd that be deny'd, we find, upon a second trial, that it can. But these efforts are all in vain ; and whatever capricious and irregular actions we may perform ; as the desire of showing our liberty is the sole motive of our actions ; we can never free ourselves from the bonds of necessity. We may imagine we feel a liberty within ourselves ; but a spec- tator can commonly infer our actions from our motives and character ; /and even where he cannot, he concludes in general, that he might, were he perfectly acquainted with every circumstance of our situation and temper, and the most secret springs of our complexion and disposition. Now this is the very essence of necessity, according to the foregoing doctrine. A third reason why the doctrine of liberty has generally been better receiv'd in the world, than its antagonist, pro- ceeds from religion, which has been very unnecessarily interested in this question. There is no method of reason- ing more common, and yet none more blameable, than in philosophical debates to endeavour to refute any hypothesis by a pretext of its dangerous consequences to religion and morality. When any opinion leads us into absurdities, 'tis certainly false ; but 'tis not certain an opinion is false, because 'tis of dangerous consequence. Such topics, there- fore, ought entirely to be foreborn, as serving nothing to the discovery of truth, but only to make the person of an antagonist odious. This I observe in general, without pre- tending to draw any advantage from it. I submit myself frankly to an examination of this kind, and dare venture to affirm, that the doctrine of necessity, according to my Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 83 explication of it, is not only innocent, but even advantageous to religion and morality. I define necessity two ways, conformable to the two defi- nitions of cause, of which it makes an essential part. I place it either in the constant union and conjunction of like objects, or in the inference of the mind from the one to the other. Now necessity, in both these senses, has univers- ally, tho' tacitely, in the schools, in the pulpit, and in common life, been allow'd to belong to the will of man, and no one has ever pretended to deny, that we can draw infer- ences concerning human actions, and that those inferences are founded on the experienc'd union of like actions with like motives and circumstances. The only particular in which any one can differ from me, is either, that perhaps he will refuse to call this necessity. But as long as the mean- ing is understood, I hope the word can do no harm. Or that he will maintain there is something else in the opera- tions of the matter. Now whether it be so or not is of no consequence to religion, whatever it may be to natural philosophy. I may be mistaken in asserting, that we have no idea of any other connexion in the actions of body, and shall be glad to be farther instructed on that head : But sure I am, I ascribe nothing to the actions of the mind, but what must readily be allow'd of. Let no one, therefore, put an invidious construction on my words, by saying simply, that I assert the necessity of human actions, and place them on the same footing with the operations of senseless matter. I do not ascribe to the will that unintelligible necessity, which is suppos'd to lie in matter. But I ascribe to matter, that intelligible quality, call it necessity or not, which the most rigorous orthodoxy does or must allow to belong to the will. I change, therefore, nothing in the receiv'd systems, with regard to the will, but only with regard to material objects. 84 A TREA TISE OF HUMAN NA TURE. Nay I shall go farther, and assert, that this kind of necessity is so essential to religion and morality, that with- out it there must ensue an absolute subversion of both, and that every other supposition is entirely destructive to all laws both divine and human. Tis indeed certain, that as all human laws are founded on rewards and punishments, 'tis suppos'd as a fundamental principle, that these motives have an influence on the mind, and both produce the good and prevent the evil actions. We may give to this influence what name we please ; but as 'tis usually conjoin'd with the action, common sense requires it shou'd be esteem'd a cause, and be look'd upon as an instance of that necessity, which I wou'd establish. This reasoning is equally solid, when apply'd to divine laws, so far as the deity is consider'd as a legislator, and is suppos'd to inflict punishment and bestow rewards with a design to produce obedience. But I also maintain, that even where he acts not in his magisterial capacity, but is regarded as the avenger of crimes merely on account of their odiousness and deformity, not only 'tis impossible, without the necessary connexion of cause and effect in human actions, that punishments cou'd be inflicted compat- ible with justice and moral equity ; but also that it cou'd ever enter into the thoughts of any reasonable being to inflict them. The constant and universal object of hatred or anger is a person or creature endow'd with thought and consciousness ; and when any criminal or injurious actions excite that passion, 'tis only by their relation to the person or connexion with him. But according to the doctrine of liberty or chance, this connexion is reduc'd to nothing, nor are men more accountable for those actions, which are design'd and premeditated, than for such as are the most casual and accidental. Actions are by their very nature temporary and perishing ; and where they proceed not from some cause in the characters and disposition of the person, Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 85 who perform'd them, they infix not themselves upon him, and can neither redound to his honour, if good, nor infamy, if evil. The action itself may be blameable ; it may be contrary to all the rules of morality and religion : But the person is not responsible for it ; and as it proceeded from nothing in him, that is durable or constant, and leaves nothing of that nature behind it, 'tis impossible he can, upon its account, become the object of punishment or vengeance. According to the hypothesis of liberty, therefore, a man is as pure and untainted, after having committed the most horrid crimes, as at the first moment of his birth, nor is his character any way concern'd in his actions ; since they are not deriv'd from it, and the wickedness of the one can never be us'd as a proof of the depravity of the other. 'Tis only upon the principles of necessity, that a person acquires any merit or demerit from his actions, however the common opinion may incline to the contrary. But so inconsistent are men with themselves, that tho' they often assert, that necessity utterly destroys all merit and demerit either towards mankind or superior powers, yet they continue still to reason upon these very principles of necessity in all their judgments concerning this matter. Men are not blam'd for such evil actions as they perform ignorantly and casually, whatever may be their consequences. Why? but because the causes of these actions are only momentary, and terminate in them alone. Men are less blam'd for such evil actions, as they perform hastily and unpremeditately, than for such as proceed from thought and deliberation. For what reason ? but because a hasty temper, tho' a constant cause in the mind, operates only by intervals, and infects not the whole character. Again, repentance wipes off every crime, especially if attended with an evident reformation of life and manners. How is this to be accounted for? But by asserting that actions render a person criminal, merely as they are proofs of criminal 86 A TREATISE OF HUM AX NATURE. passions or principles in the mind ; and when by any alteration of these principles they cease to be just proofs, they likewise cease to be criminal. But according to the doctrine of liberty or chance they never were just proofs, and consequently never were criminal. Here then I turn to my adversary, and desire him to free his own system from these odious consequences before he charge them upon others. Or if he rather chuses, that this question shou'd be decided by fair arguments before philoso- phers, than by declamations before the people, let him return to what I have advanc'd to prove that liberty and chance are synonimous ; and concerning the nature of moral evidence and the regularity of human actions. Upon a review of these reasonings, I cannot doubt of an entire victory ; and therefore having prov'd, that all actions of the will have particular causes, I proceed to explain what these causes are, and how they operate. SECTION III. Of the influencing motives of the will. Nothing is more usual in philosophy, and even in common life, than to talk of the combat of passion and reason, to give the preference to reason, and to assert that men are only so far virtuous as they conform themselves to its dictates. Every rational creature, 'tis said, is oblig'd to regulate his actions by reason ; and if any other motive or principle challenge the direction of his conduct, he ought to oppose it, 'till it be entirely subdu'd, or at least brought to a conformity with that superior principle. On this method of thinking the greatest part of moral philosophy, ancient and modern, seems to be founded ; nor is there an ampler field, as well for metaphysical arguments, as popular'declamations, than this suppos'd pre-eminence of reason above passion. The eternity, invariableness, and divine origin of the former Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 87 have been display'd to the best advantage : The blindness, unconstancy, and deceitfulness of the latter have been as strongly insisted on. In order to shew the fallacy of all this philosophy, I shall endeavour to ■prove first, that reason alone can never be a motive to any action of the will ; and secondly, that it can never oppose passion in the direction of the will. The understanding exerts itself after two different ways, as it judges from demonstration or probability ; as it regards the abstract relations of our ideas, or those relations of objects, of which experience only gives us information. I believe it scarce will be asserted, that the first species of reasoning alone is ever the cause of any action. As it's proper province is the world of ideas, and as the will always places us in that of realities, demonstration and volition seem, upon that account, to be totally remov'd, from each other. Mathematics, indeed, are useful in all mechanical operations, and arithmetic in almost every art and profes- sion : But 'tis not of themselves they have any influence. Mechanics are the art of regulating the motions of bodies to some design' d end or purpose ; and the reason why we employ arithmetic in fixing the proportions of numbers, is only that we may discover the proportions of their influence and operation. A merchant is desirous of knowing the sum total of his accounts with any person : Why ? but that he may learn what sum will have the same effects in paying his debt, and going to market, as all the particular articles taken together. Abstract or demonstrative reasoning, therefore, never influences any of our actions, but only as it directs our judgment concerning causes and effects ; which leads us to the second operation of the understanding. 'Tis obvious, that when we have the prospect of pain or pleasure from any object, we feel a consequent emotion of aversion or propensity, and are carry'd to avoid or embrace what will give us this uneasiness or satisfaction. 'Tis also 88 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. obvious, that this emotion rests not here, but making us cast our view on every side, comprehends whatever objects are connected with its original one by the relation of cause and effect. Here then reasoning takes place to discover this relation ; and according as our reasoning varies, our actions receive a subsequent variation. But 'tis evident in this case, that the impulse arises not from reason, but is only directed by it. 'Tis from the prospect of pain or pleasure that the aversion or propensity arises towards any object : And these emotions extend themselves to the causes and effects of that object, as they are pointed out to us by reason and experi- ence. It can never in the least concern us to know, that such objects are causes, and such others effects, if both the causes and effects be indifferent to us. Where the objects themselves do not affect us, their connexion can never give them any influence ; and 'tis plain, that as reason is noth- ing but the discovery of this connexion, it cannot be by its means that the objects are able to affect us. Since reason alone can never produce any action, or give rise to volition, I infer, that the same faculty is as incapable of preventing volition, or of disputing the preference with any passion or emotion. This consequence is necessary. 'Tis impossible reason cou'd have the latter effect of pre- venting volition, but by giving an impulse in a contrary direction to our passion ; and that impulse, had it operated alone, wou'd have been able to produce volition. Nothing can oppose or retard the impulse of passion, but a contrary impulse ; and if this contrary impulse ever arises from reason, that latter faculty must have an original influence on the will, and must be able to cause, as well as hinder any act of volition. But if reason has no original influence, 'tis impossible it can withstand any principle, which has such an efficacy, or ever keep the mind in suspense a moment. Thus it appears, that the principle, which opposes our passion, cannot be the same with reason and Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 89 is only call'd so in an improper sense. We speak not strictly and philosophically when we talk of the combat of passion and of reason. Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey them. As this opinion may appear somewhat extraordinary, it may not be improper to confirm it by some other considerations. A passion is an original existence, or if you will, modi- fication of existence, and contains not any representative quality, which renders it a copy of any other existence or modification. When I am angry, I am actually possest with the passion, and in that emotion have no more a reference to any other object, than when I am thirsty, or sick, or more than five foot high. ' Tis impossible, therefore, that this passion can be oppos'd by, or be contradictory to truth and reason ; since this contradiction consists in the disagreement of ideas, consider'd as copies, with those objects, which they represent. What may at first occur on this head, is, that as nothing can be contrary to truth or reason, except what has a reference to it, and as the judgments of our understanding only have this reference, it must follow, that passions can be contrary to reason only so far as they are accompany' d with some judgment or opinion. According to this principle, which is so obvious and natural, ' tis only in two senses, that any affection can be call'd unreasonable. First, When a passion, such as hope or fear, grief or joy, despair or security, is founded on the supposition of the existence of objects, which really do not exist. Secondly, When in exerting any passion in action, we chuse means insufficient for the design'd end, and deceive ourselves in our judgment of causes and effects. Where a passion is neither founded on false suppositions, nor chuses means insufficient for the end, the understanding can neither justify nor condemn it. ' Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the 9° A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. whole world to the scratching of my finger. ' Tis not con- trary to reason for me to chuse my total ruin, to prevent the least uneasiness of an Indian or person wholly unknown to me. ' Tis as little contrary to reason to prefer even my own acknowledg'd lesser good to my greater, and have a more ardent affection for the former than the latter. A trivial good may, from certain circumstances, produce a desire superior to what arises from the greatest and most valuable enjoy- ment ; nor is there anything more extraordinary in this, than in mechanics to see one pound weight raise up a hundred by the advantage of its situation. In short, a passion must be accompany'd with some false judgment, in order to its being unreasonable ; and even then ' tis not the passion, properly speaking, which is unreasonable, but the judgment. The consequences are evident. Since a passion can never, in any sense, be call'd unreasonable, but when founded on a false supposition, or when it chuses means insufficient for the design'd end, ' tis impossible, that reason and passion can ever oppose each other, or dispute for the government of the will and actions. The moment we per- ceive the falshood of any supposition, or the insufficiency of any means our passions yield to our reason without any opposition. I may desire any fruit of an excellent relish ; but whenever you convince me of my mistake, my longing ceases. I may will the performance of certain actions as means of obtaining any desir'd good ; but as my willing of these actions is only secondary, and founded on the supposi- tion, that they are causes of the propos'd effect ; as soon as I discover the falshood of that supposition, they must become indifferent to me. 'Tis natural for one, that does not examine objects with a strict philosophic eye, to imagine, that those actions of the mind are entirely the same, which produce not a different sensation, and are not immediately distinguishable to the feeling and perception. Reason, for instance, exerts itself Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 91 without producing any sensible emotion ; and except in the more sublime disquisitions of philosophy, or in the frivolous subtilties of the schools, scarce ever conveys any pleasure or uneasiness. Hence it proceeds, that every action of the mind, which operates with the same calmness and tran- quillity, is confounded with reason by all those, who judge of things from the first view and appearance. Now 'tis certain, there are certain calm desires and tendencies, which, tho' they be real passions, produce little emotion in the mind, and are more known by their effects than by the immediate feeling or sensation. These desires are of two kinds ; either certain instincts originally implanted in our natures, such as benevolence and resentment, the love of life, and kindness to children ; or the general appetite to good, and aversion to evil, consider'd merely as such. When any of these passions are calm, and cause no disorder in the soul, they are very readily taken for the determina- tions of reason, and are suppos'd to proceed from the same faculty, with that, which judges of truth and falshood. Their nature and principles have been supposed the same, because their sensations are not evidently different. Beside these calm passions, which often determine the will, there are certain violent emotions of the same kind, which have likewise a great influence on that faculty. When I receive any injury from another, I often feel a violent passion of resentment, which makes me desire his evil and punishment, independent of all considerations of pleasure and advantage to myself. When I am immediately threaten'd with any grievous ill, my fears, apprehensions, and aversions rise to a great height, and produce a sensible emotion. The common error of metaphysicians has lain in ascribing the direction of the will entirely to one of these principles, and supposing the other to have no influence. Men often act knowingly against their interest : For which reason the 92 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. view of the greatest possible good does not always influence them. Men often counter-act a violent passion in prosecu- tion of their interests and designs: Tis not therefore the present uneasiness alone, which determines them. In general we may observe, that both these principles operate on the will ; and where they are contrary, that either of them prevails, according to the general character or present disposition of the person. What we call strength of mind, implies the prevalence of the calm passions above the violent ; tho' we may easily observe, there is no man so constantly possess'd of this virtue, as never on any occasion to yield to the solicitations of passion and desire. From these variations of temper proceeds the great difficulty of deciding concerning the actions and resolutions of men, where there is any contrariety of motives and passions. SECTION IV. Of the causes of the violent passions. There is not in philosophy a subject of more nice speculation than this of the different causes and effects of the calm and violent passions. 'Tis evident passions in- fluence not the will in proportion to their violence, or the disorder they occasion in the temper ; but on the contrary, that when a passion has once become a settled principle of action, and is the predominant inclination of the soul, it commonly produces no longer any sensible agitation. As repeated custom and its own force have made every thing yield to it, it directs the actions and conduct without that opposition and emotion, which so naturally attend every momentary gust of passion. We must, therefore, distinguish betwixt a calm and a weak passion ; betwixt a violent and a strong one. But notwithstanding this, 'tis certain, that when we wou'd govern a man, and push him to any action, Book II. OF THE PASS/ONS. 93 'twill commonly be better policy to work upon the violent than the calm passions, and rather take him by his inclina- tion, than what is vulgarly call'd his reason. We ought to place the object in such particular situations as are proper to encrease the violence of the passion. For we may observe, that all depends upon the situation of the object, and that a variation in this particular will be able to change the calm and the violent passions into each other. Both these kinds of passions pursue good, and avoid evil ; and both of them are encreas'd or diminish'd by the encrease or diminution of the good or evil. But herein lies the differ- ence betwixt them : The same good, when near, will cause a violent passion, which, when remote, produces only a calm one. As this subject belongs very properly to the present question concerning the will, we shall here examine it to the bottom, and shall consider some of those circumstances and situations of objects, which render a passion either calm or violent. 'Tis a remarkable property of human nature, that any emotion, which attends a passion, is easily converted into it, tho' in their natures they be originally different from, and even contrary to each other. 'Tis true ; in order to make a perfect union among passions, there is always requir'd a double relation of impressions and ideas ; nor is one relation sufficient for that purpose. But tho' this be con- firm'd by undoubted experience, we must understand it with its proper limitations, and must regard the double relation, as requisite only to make one passion produce another. When two passions are already produc'd by their separate causes, and are both present in the mind, they readily mingle and unite, tho' they have but one relation, and sometimes without any. The predominant passion swallows up the inferior, and converts it into itself. The spirits, when once excited, easily receive a change in their direction ; and 'tis natural to imagine this change will come 94 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. from the prevailing affection. The connextion is in many respects closer betwixt any two passions, than betwixt any passion and indifference. When a person is once heartily in love, the little faults and caprice of his mistress, the jealousies and quarrels, to which that commerce is so subject ; however unpleasant and related to anger and hatred ; are yet found to give additional force to the prevailing passion. Tis a common artifice of politicians, when they wou'd affect any person very much by a matter of fact, of which they intend to inform him, first to excite his curiosity ; delay as long as possible the satisfying it ; and by that means raise his anxiety and impatience to the utmost, before they give him a full insight into the busi- ness. They know that his curiosity will precipitate him into the passion they design to raise, and assist the object in its influence on the mind. A soldier advancing to the battle, is naturally inspir'd with courage and confidence, when he thinks on his friends and fellow-soldiers ; and is struck with fear and terror, when he reflects on the enemy. Whatever new emotion, therefore, proceeds from the former naturally encreases the courage ; as the same emotion, proceeding from the latter, augments the fear ; by the relation of ideas, and the conversion of the inferior emotion into the predomi- nant. Hence it is that in martial discipline, the uniformity and lustre of our habit, the regularity of our figures and motions, with all the pomp and majesty of war, encourage ourselves and allies ; while the same objects in the enemy strike terror into us, tho' agreeable and beautiful in them- selves. Since passions, however independent, are naturally trans- fus'd into each other, if they are both present at the same time ; it follows, that when good or evil is plac'd in such a situation, as, to cause any particular emotion, beside its direct passion of desire or aversion, that latter passion must acquire new force and violence. Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 95 This happens, among other cases, whenever any object excites contrary passions. For 'tis observable that an opposition of passions commonly causes a new emotion in the spirits, and produces more disorder, than the concur- rence of any two affections of equal force. This new emotion is easily converted into the predominant passion, and encreases its violence, beyond the pitch it wou'd have ariv'd at had it met with no opposition. Hence we natur- ally desire what is forbid, and take a pleasure in performing actions, merely because they are unlawful. The notion of duty, when opposite to the passions, is seldom able to over- come them ; and when it fails of that effect, is apt rather to encrease them, by producing an opposition in our motives and principles. The same effect follows whether the opposition arises from internal motives or external obstacles. The passion commonly acquires new force and violence in both cases. The efforts, which the mind makes to surmount the obsta- cle, excite the spirits and enliven the passion. Uncertainty has the same influence as opposition. The agitation of the thought ; the quick turns it makes from one view to another ; the variety of passions, which succeed each other, according to the different views : All these produce an agitation in the mind, and transfuse themselves into the predominant passion. There is not in my opinion any other natural cause, why security diminishes the passions, than because it removes that uncertainty, which encreases them. The mind, when left to itself, immediately languishes ; and in order to preserve its ardour, must be every moment supported by a new flow of passion. For the same reason, despair, tho' contrary to security, has a like influence. ' Tis certain nothing more powerfully animates any affec- tion, than to conceal some part of its object by throwing it into a kind of shade, which at the same time that it shews 9 6 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. enough to pre-possess us in favour of the object, leaves still some work for the imagination. Besides that obscurity is always attended with a kind of uncertainty ; the effort, which the fancy makes to compleat the idea, rouzes the spirits, and gives an additional force to the passion. As despair and security, tho' contrary to each other, produce the same effects ; so absence is observ'd to have contrary effects, and in different circumstances either en- creases or diminishes our affections. The Due de la Roche- foucault has very well observ'd, that absence destroys weak passions, but encreases strong ; as the wind extinguishes a candle, but blows up a fire. Long absence naturally weakens our idea, and diminishes the passion : But where the idea is so strong and lively as to support itself, the uneasiness, arising from absence, encreases the passion, and gives it new force and violence. SECTION V. Of the effects of custom. But nothing has a greater effect both to encrease and diminish our passions, to convert pleasure into pain, and pain into pleasure, than custom and repetition. Custom has two original effects upon the mind, in bestowing a facility in the performance of any action or the conception of any object ; and afterwards a tendency or inclination towards it ; and from these we may account for all its other effects, however extraordinary. When the soul applies itself to the performance of any action, or the conception of any object, to which it is not accustom'd, there is a certain unpliableness in the faculties, and a difficulty of the spirit's moving in their new direction. As this difficulty excites the spirits, ' tis the source of wonder, surprise, and of all the emotions, which arise from Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 97 novelty ; and is in itself very agreeable, like every thing, which inlivens the mind to a moderate degree. But tho' surprize be agreeable in itself, yet as it puts the spirits in agitation, it not only augments our agreeable affections, but also our painful, according to the foregoing principle, thai every emotion, which precedes or attends a passion, is easily converted into it. Hence every thing, that is new, is most affecting, and gives us either more pleasure or pain, than what, strictly speaking, naturally belongs to it. When it often returns upon us, the novelty wears off ; the passions subside ; the hurry of the spirits is over ; and we survey the objects with greater tranquillity. By degrees the repetition produces a facility, which is another very powerful principle of the human mind, and an infallible source of pleasure, where the facility goes not beyond a certain degree. «And here ' tis remarkable that the pleasure, which arises from a moderate facility, has not the same tendency with that which arises from novelty, to augment the painful, as well as the agreeable affections, The pleasure of facility does not so much consist in any ferment of the spirits, as in their orderly motion ; which will sometimes be so powerful as even to convert pain into pleasure, and give us a relish in time for what at first was most harsh and disagreeable. But again, as facility converts pain into pleasure, so it often converts pleasure into pain, when it is too great, and renders the actions of the mind so faint and languid, that they are no longer able to interest and support it. And indeed, scarce any other objects become disagreeable thro' custom ; but such as are naturally attended with some emotion or affection, which is destroy'd by the too frequent repetition. One can consider the clouds, and heavens, and trees, and stones, however frequently repeated, without ever feeling any aversion. But when the fair sex, or music, or good cheer, or any thing, that naturally ought to be agree- 98 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. able, becomes indifferent, it easily produces the opposite affection. But custom not only gives a facility to perform any action, but likewise an inclination and tendency towards it, where it is not entirely disagreeable, and can never be the object of inclination. And this is the reason why custom encreases all active habits, but diminishes passive, according to the observation of a late eminent philosopher. The facility takes off from the force of the passive habits by rendering the motion of the spirits faint and languid. But as in the active, the spirits are sufficiently supported of themselves, the tendency of the mind gives them new force, and bends them more strongly to the action. [Section VI., which is a very short one, examines the in- fluence of the imagination on the passions. The general view advanced is that an idea of particular pleasures exer- cises a stronger influence than a general idea. " Any pleasure, with which we are acquainted, affects us more than any other, which we own to be superior, but of whose nature we are wholly ignorant. Of the one we can form a particular and determinate idea : the other we conceive under the general notion of pleasure ; and 'tis certain, that the more general and universal any of our ideas are, the less influence they have upon the imagination," and hence have less upon the passions and the will. " Contiguity and distance in space and time," as charac- teristic of objects of the mind show the same difference of influence as " particular " and " general " ideas. Objects at a distance which if present would move our desires are more or less ineffective, and those remote in time have the same effect, past time being less influential than the present. " Contiguous objects must have an influence much superior to the distant and remote. Accordingly we find -in common life, that men are principally concern'd about those objects, Book II. OF THE PASSIONS. 99 which are not much removed in space or time, enjoying the present and leaving what is afar off to the care of chance and fortune. Talk to a man of his condition thirty years hence, and he will not regard you. Speak of what is to happen to-morrow, and he will lend you attention. The breaking of a mirror gives us more concern when at home, than the burning of a house when abroad, and some hun- dred leagues distant." This difference of attractive and stimulating effect avails to influence the imagination and the passions according to the same law, and hence the will is influenced in a way to show which is the stronger motive to volition. The ninth section is a consideration of the direct passions grief and sorrow, fear and hope, desire and aversion, which had been mentioned and discussed briefly when treating of the will. But nothing is remarked of any importance either to the free will controversy or having any bearing upon sub- sequent questions. Hume himself remarks of them : "None of the direct affections seem to merit our particular atten- tion, except hope and fear, which we shall here endeavor to account for." He regards them both as mixtures of joy and grief, their difference being determined by the different pro- portions in which they are combined, or by the degree of probability connected with a prospective event. They affect the will according to their intensity. The last section treats of " curiosity or the love of truth " as a passion. The only interest which attaches to his treat- ment of it is his comparison of it to the passion of hunting. It affects the will merely as all other passions.] BOOK III. OF MORALS. PART I. OF VIRTUE AND VICE IN GENERAL. SECTION I. Moral Distinctions not deriv'd from Reason. There is an inconvenience which attends all abstruse reasoning, that it may silence, without convincing an an- tagonist, and requires the same intense study to make us sensible of its force, that was at first requisite for its inven- tion. When we leave our closet, and engage in the common affairs of life, its conclusions seem to vanish, like the phan- toms of the night on the appearance of the morning ; and 'tis difficult for us to retain even that conviction, which we had attain'd with difficulty. This is still more conspicuous in a long chain of reasoning, where we must preserve to the end the evidence of the first propositions, and where we often lose sight of all the most receiv'd maxims, either of philosophy or common life. I am not, however, without hopes, that the present system of philosophy will acquire new force as it advances ; and that our reasonings concerning morals will corroborate whatever has been said concerning the understanding and the passions. Morality is a subject that interests us above all others We fancy the peace of society to be at stake in every decision concerning it ; and 'tis evident, that this concern must make our specula- tions appear more real and solid, than where the subject is, in a great measure, indifferent to us. What affects us, we Book III. OF MORALS. 101 conclude can never be a chimera ; and as our passion is engag'd on the one side or the other, we naturally think that the question lies within human comprehension ; which, in other cases of this nature, we are apt to entertain some doubt of. Without this advantage I never should have ven- tur'd upon a third volume of such abstruse philosophy, in an age, wherein the greatest part of men seem agreed to con- vert reading into an amusement, and to reject every thing that requires any considerable degree of attention to be comprehended. It has been observ'd, that nothing is ever present to the mind but its perceptions ; and that all the actions of seeing, hearing, judging, loving, hating, and thinking, fall under this denomination. The mind can never exert itself in any action, which we may not comprehend under the term of perception; and consequently that term is no less applicable to those judgments, by which we distinguish moral good and evil, than to every other operation of the mind. To approve of one character, to condemn another, are only so many different perceptions. Now as perceptions resolve themselves into two kinds, viz., impressions and ideas, this distinction gives rise to a question, with which we shall open up our present enquiry concerning morals, Whether 'tis by means of our ideas or im- pressions we distinguish betwixt vice and virtue, and pronounce an action blameable or praise-worthy 1 This will immediately cut off all loose discourses and declamations, and reduce us to something precise and exact on the present subject. Those who affirm that virtue is nothing but a conformity to reason ; that there are eternal fitnesses and unfitnesses of things, which are the same to every rational being that considers them ; that the immutable measures of right and wrong impose an obligation, not only on human creatures, but. also on the Deity himself : All these systems concur in 102 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. the opinion, that morality, like truth, is discern'd merely by ideas, and by their juxta-position and comparison. In order, therefore, to judge of these systems, we need only consider, whether it be possible, from reason alone, to distinguish betwixt moral good and evil, or whether there must concur some other principles to enable us to make that distinc- tion. If morality had naturally no influence on human passions and actions, 'twere in vain to take such pains to inculcate it ; and nothing wou'd be more fruitless than that multitude of rules and precepts, with which all moralists abound. Philo- sophy is commonly divided into speculative and practical ; and as morality is always comprehended under the latter division, 'tis supposed to influence our passions and actions, and to go beyond the calm and indolent judgments of the understanding. And this is confirm'd by common experi- ence, which informs us, that men are often govern'd by their duties, and are deter'd from some actions by the opinion of injustice, and impell'd to others by that of obligation. Since morals, therefore, have an influence on the actions and affections, it follows, that they cannot be deriv'd from reason ; and that because reason alone, as we have already prov'd, can never have any such influence. Morals excite passions, and produce or prevent actions. Reason of itself is utterly impotent in this particular. The rules of morality, therefore, are not conclusions of our reason. No one, I believe, will deny the justness of this inference ; nor is there any other means of evading it, than by denying that principle, on which it is founded. As long as it is allow'd, that reason has no influence on our passions and actions, 'tis in vain to pretend, that morality is discover'd only by a deduction of reason. An active principle can never be founded on an inactive ; and if reason be inactive in itself, it must remain so in all its shapes and appearances, whether it exerts itself in natural or moral subjects, whether Book III. OF MORALS. 103 it considers the powers of external bodies, or the actions of rational beings. It would be tedious to repeat all the arguments, by which I have prov'd 1 , that reason is perfectly inert, and can never either prevent or produce any action or affection. 'Twill be easy to recollect what has been said upon that subject. I shall only recal on this occasion one of these arguments, which I shall endeavour to render still more conclusive, and more applicable to the present subject. Reason is the discovery of truth or falsehood. Truth or falsehood consists in an agreement or disagreement either to the real relations of ideas, or to real existence and matter of fact. Whatever, therefore, is not susceptible of this agree- ment or disagreement, is incapable of being true or false, and can never be an object of our reason. Now 'tis evident our passions, volitions, and actions, are not susceptible of any such agreement or disagreement ; being original facts and realities, compleat in themselves, and implying no refer- ence to other passions, volitions, and actions. 'Tis impossible, therefore, they can be pronounced either true or false, and be either contrary or comformable to reason. This argument is of double advantage to our present purpose. For it proves directly, that actions do not derive their merit from a conformity to reason, nor their blame from a contrariety to it ; and it proves the same truth more indirectly, by shewing us, that as reason can never imme- diately prevent or produce any action by contradicting or approving of it, it cannot be the source of moral good and evil, which are found to have that influence. Actions may be laudable or blameable ; but they cannot be reasonable or unreasonable : Laudable or blameable, therefore, are not the same with reasonable or unreasonable. The merit and demerit of actions frequently contradict, and sometimes con- 1 Book II. Part III. sect. 1. 104 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. troul our natural propensities. But reason has no such influence. Moral distinctions, therefore, are not the offspring of reason. Reason is wholly inactive, and can never be the source of so active a principle as conscience, or a sense of morals. But perhaps it may be said, that tho' no will or action can be immediately contradictory to reason, yet we may find such a contradiction in some of the attendants of the action, that is, in its causes or effects. The action may cause a judgment, or may be obliquely caus'd by one, when the judgment concurs with a passion ; and by an abusive way of speaking, which philosophy will scarce allow of, the same contrariety may, upon that account, be ascrib'd to the action. How far this truth or falshood may be the source of morals, ' twill now be proper to consider. It has been observ'd, that reason, in a strict and philo- sophical sense, can have an influence on our conduct only after two ways : Either when it excites a passion by informing us of the existence of something which is a proper object of it ; or when it discovers the connexion of causes and effects, so as to afford us means of exerting any passion. These are the only kinds of judgment, which can accompany our actions, or can be said to produce them in any manner ; and it must be allow'd, that these judgments may often be false and erroneous. A person may be affected with passion, by supposing a pain or pleasure to lie in an object, which has no tendency to produce either of these sensations, or which produces the contrary to what is imagin'd. A person may also take false measures for the attaining his end, and may retard, by his foolish conduct, instead of forwarding the execution of any project. These false judgments may be thought to affect the passions and actions, which are con- nected with them, and may be said to render them unreason- able, in a figurative and improper way of speaking. But tho' this be acknowledged, ' tis easy to observe, that these errors Book III. OF MORALS. 105 are so far from being the source of all immorality, that they are commonly very innocent, and draw no manner of guilt upon the person who is so unfortunate as to fall into them. They extend not beyond a mistake of fact, which moralists have not generally suppos'd criminal, as being perfectly involuntary. I am more to be lamented than blam'd if I am mistaken with regard to the influence of objects in pro- ducing pain or pleasure, or if I know not the proper means of satisfying my desires. No one can ever regard such errors as a defect in my moral character. A fruit, for instance, that is really disagreeable, appears to me at a distance, and thro ' mistake I fancy it to be pleasant and delicious. Here is one error. I choose certain means of reaching this fruit, which are not proper for my end. Here is a second error ; nor is there any third one, which can ever possibly enter into our reasonings concerning actions. I ask, therefore, if a man, in this situation, and guilty of these two errors, is to be regarded as vicious and criminal, how- ever unavoidable they might have been ? Or if it be possible to imagine, that such errors are the sources of all immorality? And here it may be proper to observe, that if moral distinc- tions be deriv'd from the truth or falshood of those judg- ments, they must take place wherever we form the judg- ments ; nor will there be any difference, whether the question be concerning an apple or a kingdom, or whether the error be avoidable or unavoidable. For as the very essence of morality is suppos'd to consist in an agreement or disagree- ment to reason, the other circumstances are entirely arbitrary, and can never either bestow on any action the character of virtuous or vicious, or deprive it of that char- acter. To which we may add, that this agreement or dis- agreement, not admitting of degrees, all virtues and vices wou'd of course be equal. Shou'd it be pretended, that tho' a mistake of fact be not criminal, yet a mistake of right often is ; and that this may 106 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. be the source of immorality : I would answer, that ' tis impos- sible such a mistake can ever be the original source of immorality, since it supposes a real right and wrong ; that is, a real distinction in morals, independent of these judgments. A mistake, therefore, of right may become a species of immorality; but 'tis only a secondary one, and is founded on some other, antecedent to it. As to those judgments which are the effects of our actions, and which, when false, give occasion to pronounce the actions contrary to truth and reason ; we may observe, that our actions never cause any judgment, either true or false, in ourselves, and that 'tis only on others they have such an influence. 'Tis certain, that an action, on many occasions, may give rise to false conclusions in others ; and that a per- son, who thro' a window sees any lewd behaviour of mine with my neighbour's wife, may be so simple as to imagine she is certainly my own. In this respect my action resem- bles somewhat a lye or falshood ; only with this difference, which is material, that I perform not the action with any intention of giving rise to a false judgment in another, but merely to satisfy my lust and passion. It causes, however, a mistake and false judgment by accident ; and the falshood of its effects may be ascribed, by some odd figurative way of speaking, to the action itself. But still I can see no pretext of reason for asserting, that the tendency to cause such an error is the first spring or original source of all immorality '. 1 One might think it were entirely superfluous to prove this, if a late author [Wollaston], who has had the good fortune to obtain some rep- utation, had not seriously affirmed, that such a falshood is the founda- tion of all guilt and moral deformity. That we may discover the fallacy of his hypothesis, we need only consider, that a false conclusion is drawn from an action, only by means of an obscurity of natural princi- ples, which makes a cause be secretly interrupted in its operation, by contrary causes, and renders the connection betwixt two objects uncer- tain and variable. Now, as a like uncertainty and variety of causes take place, even in natural objects, and produce a like error in our judgment, if that tendency to produce error were the very essence of vice and Book III. OF MORALS. 107 Thus upon the whole, 'tis impossible, that the distinction betwixt moral good and evil, can be made by reason ; since that distinction has an influence upon our actions, of which reason alone is incapable. Reason and judgment may, in- deed, be the mediate cause of an action, by prompting, or by directing a passion : But it is not pretended, that a judg- ment of this kind, either in its truth or falshood, is attended with virtue or vice. And as to the judgments which are caused by our judgments, they can still less bestow those moral qualities on the actions, which are their causes. But to be more particular, and to shew, that those eternal immutable fitnesses and unfitnesses of things cannot be defended by sound philosophy, we may weigh the following considerations. If the thought and understanding were alone capable of fixing the boundaries of right and wrong, the character of immorality, it shou'd follow, that even inanimate objects might be vicious and immoral. 'Tis in vain to urge, that inanimate objects act without liberty and choice. For as liberty and choice are not necessary to make an action produce in us an erroneous conclusion, they can be, in no respect, essential to morality ; and I do not readily perceive, upon this system, how they can ever come to be regarded by it. If the tendency to cause error be the origin of immorality, that tendency and immorality wou'd in every case be inseparable. Add to this, that if I had used the precaution of shutting the windows, while I indulg'd myself in those liberties with my neighbour's wife, I should have been guilty of no immorality ; and that because my action, being perfectly conceal'd, wou'd have had no tendency to produce any false conclusion. For the same reason, a thief, who steals in by a ladder at a window, and takes all imaginable care to cause no disturbance, is in no respect criminal. For either he will not be perceiv'd, or if he be, 'tis impossible he can produce any error, nor will anyone, from these circumstances, take him to be other than what he really is. 'Tis well known, that those who are squint-sighted, do very readily cause mistakes in others, and that we imagine they salute or are talking to one person, while they address themselves to another. Are they therefore, upon that account, immoral ? Besides, we may easily observe, that in all those arguments there is an evident reasoning in a circle. A person who takes possession of another's goods, and uses them as his own, in a manner declares them 108 A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. virtuous and vicious either must lie in some relations of objects, or must be a matter of fact, which is discovered by our reasoning. This consequence is evident. As the operations of human understanding divide themselves into two kinds, the comparing of ideas, and the inferring of matter of fact ; were virtue discover'd by the understanding ; it must be an object of one of these operations, nor is there any third operation of the understanding, which can discover it. There has been an opinion very industriously propa- gated by certain philosophers, that morality is susceptible of demonstration ; and tho' no one has ever been able to advance a single step in those demonstrations ; yet 'tis taken for granted, that this science may be brought to an equal certainty with geometry or algebra. Upon this supposition, vice and virtue must consist in some relations ; since 'tis allow'd on all hands, that no matter of fact is to be his own ; and this falshood is the source of the immorality of in- justice. But is property, or right, or obligation, intelligible, without an antecedent morality ? A man that is ungrateful to his benefactor, in a manner affirms, that he never received any favours from him. But in what manner ? Is it because 'tis his duty to be grateful ? But this supposes, that there is some antecedent rule of duty and morals. Is it because human nature is generally grateful, and makes us conclude, that a man who does any harm never received any favour from the person he harm'd ? But human nature is not so generally grateful, as to justify such a conclu- sion. Or if it were, is an exception to a general rule in every case criminal, for no other reason than because it is an exception ? But what may suffice entirely to destroy this whimsical system is, that it leaves us under the same difficulty to give a reason why truth is virtu- ous and falshood vicious, as to account for the merit or turpitude of any other action. I shall allow, if you please, that all immorality is derived from this supposed falsehood in action, provided you can give me any plausible reason, why such a falshood is immoral. If you con- sider rightly of the matter, you will find yourself in the same difficulty as at the beginning. This last argument is very conclusive ; because, if there be not an evident merit or turpitude annex'd to this species of truth or falshood, it can never have any influence upon our actions. For, who ever thought of forbearing any action, because others might possibly draw false conclusions from it ? Or, who ever perform'd any, that he might give rise to true conclusions ? Book III. OF MORALS. 109 capable of being demonstrated. Let us, therefore, begin with examining this hypothesis, and endeavour, if possible, to fix those moral qualities, which have been so long the objects of our fruitless researches. Point out distinctly the relations, which ■ constitute morality or obligation, that we may know wherein they consist, and after what manner we must judge of them. If you assert that vice and virtue consist in relations susceptible of certainty and demonstration, you must confine yourself to those four relations, which alone admit of that degree of evidence ; and in that case you run into absurdi- ties, from which you will never be able to extricate yourself. For as you make the very essence of morality to lie in the relations, and as there is no one of these relations but what is applicable, not only to an irrational, but also to an inanimate object ; it follows, that even such objects must be susceptible of merit or demerit. Resemblance, contrariety, degrees in quality, and proportions in quantity and number , all these relations belong as properly to matter, as to our actions, passions, and volitions. 'Tis unquestionable, there- fore, that morality lies not in any of these relations, nor the sense of it in their discovery. 1 1 As a proof, how confus'd our way of thinking on this subject commonly is, we may observe, that those who assert, that morality is demonstrable, do not say, that morality lies in the relations, and that the relations are distinguishable by reason. They only say, that reason can discover such an action, in such relations, to be virtuous, and such another vicious. It seems they thought it sufficient, if they cou'd bring the word, Relation, into the proposition, without troubling themselves whether it was to the purpose or not. But here, I think, is plain argument. Demonstrative reason discovers only relations. But that reason, according to this hypothesis, discovers also vice and virtue. These moral qualities, therefore, must be relations. When we blame any action, in any situation, the whole complicated object, of action and situation, must form certain relations, wherein the essence of vice consists. This hypothesis is not otherwise intelligible. For what does reason discover, when it pronounces any action vicious ? Does it discover a relation or a matter of fact ? These questions are decisive, and must not be eluded. no A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. Shou'd it be asserted, that the sense of morality consists in the discovery of some relation, distinct from these, and that our enumeration was not compleat, when we compre- hended all demonstrable relations under four general heads : To this I know not what to reply, till some one be so good as to point out to me this new relation. 'Tis impossible to refute a system, which has never yet been explain'd. In such a manner of fighting in the dark, a man loses his blows in the air, and often places them where the enemy is not present. - I must, therefore, on this occasion, rest contented with requiring the two following conditions of any one that wou'd undertake to clear up this system. First, As moral good and evil belong only to the actions of the mind, and are deriv'd from our situation with regard to external objects, the relations from which these moral distinctions arise, must lie only betwixt internal actions, and external objects, and must not be applicable either to internal actions, compared among themselves, or to external objects, when placed in opposition to other external objects. For as morality is supposed to attend certain relations, if these relations cou'd belong to internal actions consider'd singly, it wou'd follow, that we might be guilty of crimes in, ourselves, and indepen- dent of our situation, with respect to the universe : And in like manner, if these moral relations cou'd be apply'd to external objects, it would follow, that even inanimate beings wou'd be susceptible of moral beauty and deformity. Now it seems difficult to imagine, that any relation can be discover'd betwixt our passions, volitions and actions, compared to external objects, which relation might not belong either to these passions and volitions, or to these external objects, compar'd among themselves. But it will be still more difficult to fulfil the second con- dition, requisite to justify this system. According to the principles of those who maintain an abstract rational differ- Book III. OF MORALS. 1 1 1 ence betwixt moral good and evil, and a natural fitness and unfitness of things, 'tis not only suppos'd, that these relations, being eternal and immutable, are the same, when consider'd by every rational creature, but their effects are also suppos'd to be necessarily the same ; and 'tis concluded they have no less, or rather a greater, influence in directing the will of the diety, than in governing the rational and virtuous of our own species. These two particulars are evidently distinct. 'Tis one thing to know virtue, and another to conform the will to it. In order, therefore, to prove, that the measures of right and wrong are eternal laws, obligatory on every rational mind, 'tis not sufficient to shew the relations upon which they are founded : We must also point out the connexion betwixt the relation, and the will ; and must prove that this connexion is so necessary, that in every well-disposed mind, it must take place and have its influence ; tho' the difference betwixt these minds be in other respects immense and infinite. Now besides what I have already prov'd, that even in human nature no relation can ever alone produce any action ; besides this, I say, it has been shewn, in treating of the understanding, that there is no connexion of cause and effect, such as this is suppos'd to be, which is discoverable otherwise than by experience, and of which we can pretend to have any security by the simple consideration of the objects. All beings in the universe, consider'd in them- selves, appear entirely loose and independent of each other. 'Tis only by experience we learn their influence and connexion ; and this influence we ought never to extend beyond experience. Thus it will be impossible to fulfil the first condition required to the system of eternal rational measures of right and wrong ; because it is impossible to shew those relations, upon which such a distinction may be founded : And 'tis as impossible to fulfil the second condition ; because we cannot prove a priori, that these relations, if they really H2 A TREA TISE OF HUMAN NA TURE. existed and were perceiv'd, wou'd be universally forcible and obligatory. But to make these general reflections more clear and convincing, we may illustrate them by some particular instances, wherein this character of moral good or evil is the most universally acknowledged. Of all crimes that human creatures are capable of committing, the most horrid and unnatural is ingratitude, especially when it is committed against parents, and appears in the more flagrant instances of wounds and death. This is acknowledg'd by all mankind, philosophers as well as the people ; the question only arises among philosophers, whether the guilt or moral deformity of this action be discover'd by demonstrative reasoning, or be felt by an internal sense, and by means of some sentiment, which the reflecting on such an action naturally occasions. This question will soon be decided against the former opinion, if we can shew the same relations in other objects, without the notion of any guilt or iniquity attending them. Reason or science is nothing but the comparing of ideas, and the discovery of their relations ; and if the same relations have different characters, it must evidently follow, that those characters are not discover'd merely by reason. To put the affair, therefore, to this trial, let us chuse any inanimate object, such as an oak or elm ; and let us suppose, that by the dropping of its seed, it produces a sapling below it, which springing up by degrees, at last overtops and destroys the parent tree : f ask, if in this instance there be wanting any relation, which is discoverable in parricide or ingratitude ? Is not the one tree the cause of the other's existence ; and the latter the cause of the destruction of the former, in the same manner as when a child murders his parents ? 'Tis not sufficient to reply, that a choice or will is wanting. For in the case of parricide, a will does not give rise to any different relations, but is only the cause from which the action is deriv'd ; and consequently produces the same relations, that Book III. OF MORALS. 113 in the oak or elm arise from some other principles. 'Tis a will or choice, that determines a man to kill his parent ; and they are the laws of matter and motion, that determine a sapling to destroy the oak, from which it sprung. Here then the same relations have different causes ; but still the relations are the same . And as their discovery is not in both cases attended with a notion of immorality, it follows, that that notion does not arise from such a discovery. But to chuse an instance, still more resembling ; I would fain ask any one, why incest in the human species is crimi- nal, and why the very same action, and the same relations in animals have not the smallest moral turpitude and deformity? If it be answer'd, that this action is innocent in animals, because they have not reason sufficient to dis- cover its turpitude ; but that man, being endow'd with that faculty, which ought to restrain him to his duty, the same action instantly becomes criminal to him ; should this be said, I would reply, that this is evidently arguing in a circle. For before reason can perceive this turpitude, the turpitude must exist ; and consequently is independent of the de- cisions of our reason, and is their object more properly than their effect. According to this system, then, every animal, that has sense, and appetite, and will ; that is, every animal must be susceptible of all the same virtues and vices, for which we ascribe praise and blame to human creatures. All the difference is, that our superior reason may serve to discover the vice or virtue, and by that means may augment the blame or praise : But still this discovery supposes a separate being in these moral distinctions, and a being, which depends only on the will and appetite, and which, both in thought and reality, may be distinguish'd from the reason. Animals are susceptible of the same relations, with respect to each other, as the human species, and therefore wou'd also be susceptible of the same morality, if the essence of morality consisted in these relations. Their H4 A TREA TISE OF HUMAN NA TURE. want of a sufficient degree of reason may hinder them from perceiving the duties and obligations of morality, but can never hinder these duties from existing ; since they must antecedently exist, in order to their being perceiv'd. Reason must find them, and can never produce them. This argu- ment deserves to be weigh'd, as being, in my opinion, entirely decisive. Nor does this reasoning only prove, that morality consists not in any relations, that are the objects of science ; but if examin'd, will prove with equal certainty, that it consists, not in any matter of fact, which can be discover'd by the understanding. This is the second part £>f our argument ; and if it can be made evident, we may conclude, that moral- ity is not an object of reason. But can there be any diffi- culty in proving, that vice and virtue are not matters of fact, whose existence we can infer by reason ? Take any action allowed to be vicious : Wilful murder, for instance. Exam- ine it in all lights, and see if you can find that matter of fact, or real existence, which you call vice. In which-ever way you take it, you find only certain passions, motives, , volitions and thoughts. There is no other matter of fact in the case. The vice entirely escapes you, as long as you consider the object. You never can find it, till you turn your reflection into your own breast, and find a sentiment of disapprobation, which arises in you, towards this action. Here is a matter of fact ; but ' tis the object of feeling, not , r 216. Necessity, and liberty of will, 29- 39, 7^-86. Obligation, 108 n., m, 163-164, 170-171. and interest, 144, 163-172, 19S-199. of allegiance, 189 f. of promises, 162-172. Occupation and property, 151 f. Ought, 115. INDEX. 275 Passions defined, 89. indirect, 68 ; of the will and . direct passions, 72-99 ; calm, 91, 93 ; direct, 68 ; relations of, 128-129, 133, 165, 179. Patriarchal government, 188. Perception, 27, 101. Pity, 137. Pleasure, 72, 117, 222-223, 2 4 a Political artifice, 1 46-181. Possession, 148, 151, 152 ; of gov- ernment, 204-205. Prescription and property, 1 54. Pride and humility, 69, 118, 223, 241, 245-250. Private and public duties, 194. Promises, 162-172, 189. Property, 107 n., 129-147, 147-162. Prudence, 259. Public and private duties, 194. Punishment, 84-85. Reason, 39-45, 49, 102, 103, 107- 115, 232, 238. Reflection, impressions of, 27. Reid, 48. Relation, 108 f. Religion, 119. Responsibility, 84-85. Right, 136. Scepticism, 13 f. Selfishness, 124, 132 f., 140. Shaftesbury, 20, 24, 48. Society, 130, 131, 189. Spontaneity, liberty of, 81. Succession, of property, 151, 160; of government, 1 60, 207 f . Sympathy, 145, 226, 227, 235, 241, 254, 268. Understanding, 139. Usual, 129, 197. Virtue. See Moral. Volitions. See Will. Will, 72-92 ; relation of to natural abilities, 257-258. Wollaston, 48, 106 n. ADVERTISEMENTS. PHILOSOPHY. Empirical Psychology ; or, The Human Mind as Given in Consciousness. By Laurens P. Hickok, D.D., LL.D. Revised with the eo-operation of Julius H. Seelye, D.D., LL.D., Ex-Prest. of Amherst College. 12mo. 300 pages. Mailing Price, 81.25; Introduction, $1.12; Allowance, 40 cents. rpHE publishers believe that this book will be found to be re- markably comprehensive, and at the same time compact and clear. It gives a complete outline of the science, concisely pre- sented, and in precise and plain terms. It has proved of special value to teachers, as is evidenced by its recent adoption for several Reading Circles. John Bascom, formerly Pres. Univ. of Wisconsin, Madison : It is an ex- cellent book. It has done much good service, and, as 1 revised by President Seelye, is prepared to do much more. (Feb. 3, 1882.) I. W. Andrews, Prof, of Intellec- tual Philosophy, Marietta College, 0. : This new edition may be confi- dently recommended as presenting i delineation of the mental faculties so clear and accurate that the careful student will hardly fail to recognize its truth in his own experience. (April 6, 1882.) Hickok's Moral Science. By Laurens P. Hickok, D.D., LL.D. Revised with the co-operation of Julius H. Seelye, D.D., LL.D., Ex-Prest. of Amherst Collego. 12mo. Cloth. 288 pages. Mailing Price, $1.25; Introduction, $1.12; Allowance, 40 cents. \ S revised by Dr. Seelye, it is believed that this work will be ■^ found unsurpassed in systematic rigor and scientific precision, and at the same time remarkably clear and simple in style. G. P. Fisher, Prof, of Church His- tory, Tale College ■■ The style is so perspicuous, and at the same time so concise, that the work is eminently J3S adapted to serve as a text-book in colleges and higher schools. In mat- ter and manner it is a capital book, and I wish it God speed. PHILOSOPHY. 139 Lotze's Philosophical Outlines. T Dictated Portions of the Latest Lectures (at Gottingen and Berlin) of Hermann Lotze. Translated and edited by George T. Ladd, Pro- fessor of Philosophy in Yale University. 12mo. Cloth. About 180 pages in each volume. Mailing price per volume, $1.00 ; for introduc- tion, 80 cents. HE German from which the translations are made consists of the dictated portions of his latest lectures (at Gottingen, and for a few months at Berlin) as formulated by Lotze himself, recorded in the notes of his hearers, and subjected to the most competent and thorough revision of Professor Rehnisch of Got- tingen. The Outlines give, therefore, a mature and trustworthy statement, in language selected by this teacher of philosophy him- self, of what may be considered as his final opinions upon a wide range of subjects. They have met with no little favor in Germany. These translations have been undertaken with the kind permis- sion of the German publisher, Herr S. Hirzel, of Leipsic. Outlines of Metaphysic. This contains the scientific treatment of those assumptions which enter into all our cognition of Reality. It consists of three parts, — Ontology, Cosmology, Phenomenology. The first part contains chapters on the Con- ception of Being, the Content of the Existent, Reality, Change, and Causa- tion ; the second treats of Space, Time, Motion, Matter, and the Coherency of Natural Events ; the third, of the Subjectivity and Objectivity of Cog- nition. The Metaphysic of Lotze gives the key to his entire philosophical system. Outlines of the Philosophy of Religion. Lotze here seeks " to ascertain how much of the Content of Religion may be discovered, proved, or at least confirmed, agreeably to reason." He discusses the Proof for the Existence of God, the Attributes and Personality of the Absolute, the Conceptions of the Creation, the Preservation, and the Government, of the World, and of the World-time. The book closes with brief discussions of Religion and Morality, and Dogmas and Confessions. Outlines of Practical Philosophy. This contains a discussion of Ethical Principles, Moral Ideals, and the Freedom of the Will, and then an application of the theory to the Indi- vidual, to Marriage, to Society, and to the State. Many interesting remarks on Divorce, Socialism, Representative Government, etc., abound throughout the volume. Its style is more popular than that of the other works of Lotze, and it will doubtless be widely read. Outlines of Psychology. The Outlines of Psychology treats of Simple Sensations, the Course of Representative Ideas, of Attention and Inference, of Intuitions, of Objects as in Space, of the Apprehension of the External World by the Senses, of Errors of the Senses, of Feelings, and of Bodily Motions. Its second part is " theoretical," and discusses the nature, position, and changeable states of the Soul, its relations to time, and the reciprocal action of Soul and Body. It closes with a chapter on the "Kingdom of Souls." Lotze is peculiarly rich and suggestive in the discussion of Psychology. 140 PHILOSOPHY. Outlines of /Esthetics. The Outlines of ^Esthetics treats of the theory of the Beautifu± and of Phantasy, and of the Realization and Different Species of the Beautiful. Then follow brief chapters on Music, Architecture, Plastic Art, Painting, and Poetry. This, like the other volumes, has a full index. Outlines of Logic. This discusses both pure and applied Logic. The Logic is followed by a brief treatise on the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, in which are set forth the definition and method of Theoretical Philosophy, of Practical Phi- losophy, and of the Philosophy of Religion. This volume is about one-fifth larger than the others, aad makes an admirable brief textbook in Logic. Kind, London, Eny. : No words are needed to commend such an en- terprise, now that Lotze's importance as a thinker is so well understood. The translation is careful and pains- taking. The Philosophical Review. A Bi-monthly Journal of General Philosophy. Edited by J. G. Schurman, Dean of the Sage School of Philosophy in Cornell University. Subscription price, $3.00. Single copy, 75 cents. Foreign Agents : Great Britain, Edward Arnold, London ; Germany, Mayer & Miiller, Berlin; France, E. Leroux, Paris; Italy, E. Loescher, Rome. Volume I. began with January, 1892. rpHE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW is intended as an organ for the publication of the results of investigation in every branch of Philosophy. It is made up of original articles, reviews of books, and classified summaries of periodical literature. The Review will not enter into competition with those special- ized or technical journals which are already engaged in the minute cultivation of particular branches of Philosophy. Its domain is the still unoccupied field of General Philosophy : that whole which includes, along with the older subjects of Logic, Metaphysics, and Ethics, the newer subjects of Psychology, ^Esthetics, Pedagogy, and Epistemology, both in their systematic form and in their his- torical development. Its field is as broad as mind. And it will be an open forum alike for those who increase the stock of positive data and for those who strive to see new facts in their bearings and relations, and to trace them up to their ultimate speculative implications. With the generality of its scope, the Review aims to combine an impartiality and catholicity of tone and spirit. It will not be the organ of any institution, or of any sect, or of any interest. It will maintain the same objectivity of attitude as a journal of Math- ematics or Philology. All articles will be signed, and the writers alone will be responsible for their contents. PHILOSOPHY. 141 A Brief History of Greek Philosophy. By B. C. Burt, M.A., formerly Docent of Philosophy, Clark University. 12mo. Cloth. xiv + 296 pages. Mailing price, $1.25 ; for introd., $1.12. rpHIS work attempts to give a concise but comprehensive account of Greek Philosophy on its native soil and in Rome. It is critical and interpretative, as well as purely historical, its para- graphs of criticism and interpretation, however, being, as a rule, distinct from those devoted to biography and exposition. The wants of the reader or student who desires to comprehend, rather than merely to inform himself, have particularly been in the mind of the author, whose aim has been to let the subject unfold itself as far as possible. The volume contains a full topical table of con- ' tents, a brief bibliography of the subject it treats, and numerous foot-notes embracing references to original authorities and assist- ing the student towards a real contact with the Greek thinkers themselves. G. Stanley Hall, Pres. Clark Uni- versity : His book is the best of its kind upon the snbject. Geo. S. Morris, late Prof, of Phil- osophy in Michigan University ; What Professor Burt has done is to collect in compendious form what is most characteristic and of most essential significance in these results of philosophical investigation, and then to re-interpret or re-exhibit them in the light of the more mature fruits of modern inquiry. This is the best and most serviceable kind of originality. W. T. Harris, Editor Jour. of Spec- ulative Philosophy : I have found this work in philosophy to possess high merit. His grasp of the history of the subject is rare and trustworthy. The ModalJSt ; or. The Laws of national Conviction. A Text-Book in Formal or General Logic. By Edward John Hamiij- ton, D.D., Albert Barnes Professor of Intellectual Philosophy, Ham- ilton College, N.Y. 8vo. Cloth. 337 pages. Price, by mail, $1.40; for introduction, $1.25. rpHIS book, which the publishers believe a noteworthy one, is called Tlve Modalist, because it restores modal propositions and modal syllogisms to the place of importance which they occu- pied in the Logic of Aristotle. The author thinks that universal and particular categorical propositions cannot be understood, as principles of reasoning, and as employed in " mediate inference," unless the one be regarded as expressing a necessary and the other a contingent sequence. Therefore, also, he explains the pure syl- 142 PHILOSOPHY. logism by the modal. Moreover, there are modes of reasoning which can be formulated only in modal syllogisms. Logic is the science, not of thought simply as such, but of thought as the instrument of rational conviction, and therefore of thought in its relation to metaphysics, which is the science of the nature and laws of things. Some radical modifications of logical doctrine have resulted from the thorough-going application of this principle, and these, it is believed, have added greatly to the intel- ligibility of the science. Mechanism and Personality. By Francis A. Shoup, D.D., Professor of Analytical Physics, Univer- sity of the South. 12mo. Cloth, xvi + 341 pages. Price by mail, $1.30 ; for introduction, $1.20. rpHIS book is an outline of Philosophy in the light of the latest scientific research. It deals candidly and simply with the "burning questions" of the day, the object being to help the general reader and students of Philosophy find their way to some- thing like definite standing-ground among the uncertainties of science and metaphysics. It begins with physiological psychology, treats of the development of the several modes of personality, passes on into metaphysic, and ends in ethics, following, in a general way, the thought of Lotze. It is strictly in line with the remark of Professor Huxley, that "the reconciliation of physics and metaphysics lies in the acknowledgment of faults upon both sides; in the confession by physics that all the phenomena of nature are, in their ultimate analysis, known to us only as facts of consciousness ; in the admission by metaphysics that the facts of consciousness are, practically, interpretable only by the methods and the formulas of physics." George Trumbull Ladd, Prof, of Philosophy, Yale University : I find Dr. Shoup's " Mechanism and Per- sonality" an interesting and stimu- lating little hook. Written, as it is, by one whose points of view are somewhat outside of those taken by professional students of philosophy, it is the fresher and more suggestive on that account. At the same time, the author has kept himself from straying too far away from the con- clusions legitimate to disciplined students of the subject, by a some- what close adherence to Lotze, and by a considerable breadth of philo- sophical reading. THE B EST HIST ORIES. MYERS'S Eastern Nations and Greece. — Introduction price, $1.00. With full maps, illustrations, and chronological summaries. "Far more interesting and useful than any other epitome of the kind which I have seen." — Professor Beckwith, Trinity College. ALLEN'S Short History of the Roman People. — Introduction price, $1.00. With full maps, illustrations, and chronological synopsis. "An admirable piece of work." — Professor Bourne, Adelbert College. MYERS AND ALLEN'S Ancient History for Schools and Colleges. — Introduction price, #1.50. This consists of Myers's Eastern Nations and Greece and Allen's Rome bound together. MYERS'S History of Rome. — Introd. price, $1.00. With full maps, illustrations, tables, and chronological summaries. This, bound with Myers's East- ern Nations and Greece, is Myers's Ancient History. Price, $1.50. MYERS'S Medieval and Modern History. — Introduction price, $1.50. With a full series of colored maps. " Sure to be liked by teachers and pupils and by the general reader." — Professor Snow. Washington University. MYERS'S General History. — Introduction price, #1.50. With full maps, illustra- tions, tables, and summaries. " The best text-book in universal history for beginners that we are acquainted with." — Professor Stearns, University of Wisconsin. , MONTGOMERY'S Leading Facts of English History. — Introduction price, $1.12. With full maps and tables. " I have never seen anything at all equal to it for the niche it was intended to 611." — Professor Perry, Williams College. MONTGOMERY'S Leading Facts of French History. — Introduction price, $1.12. With full maps and tables. " It is a marked advance on any available work of its scope." — The Nation. MONTGOMERY'S Leading Facts of American History. — Introduction price, $1 .00. With full maps, illustrations, summaries of dates, topical analyses, tables, etc. "The best school history that has yet appeared." — Principal Rupert, Boys' High School, Pottstown, Pa. EMERTON'S Introduction to the Study of the Middle Ages. — Introduction price, $1.12. With colored maps, original and adapted. " An admirable guide to both teachers and pupils in the tangled period of which it treats." — Professor Fisher, Yale College. And many other valuable historical books. GINN & COMPANY, Publishers, Boston. New York, Chicago, and London. Cornell University Library B1493 .T7 1893 Treatise of morals: and selections from olin 1924 029 078 702