•p. BOUGHT WITH THB INCOME PROM THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OP mimtu ^^ Sage 1S91 AhMAlH ^h.:Ln^ m-^mt M f ^^ -^-h^ij: ±3- PRINTED IN U.S.A. Cornell University Library p 121.M94W62 The original of tliis book is in tlie Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924026441364 MAX MtlLBER AND THB MAX MULLER AND fan Science of Language: A CRITICISM, BY William Dwight Whitney,- Professor in Yale University. NEW YORK : D. APPIvETON AND COMPANY, 1892. Copyright by WlI,I Greek and Latin didlionaries, in which men of sci- ence, from metaphysicians to badleriologists, go and rummage when they wish to get their new concep- tions so clad as to be presentable in society ?), it fol- lows that they cannot have been brought from any where and put upon the people that wear them ; and hence, again, that people were born with them on, and could never have existed in a naked state. And we may add in our turn that, with a true view of what expression is to thought, this argument is no mere joke, but precisely as good as our author's. To clinch the latter, he appends a pair of illustrations : " If we never find skins except as the teguments of animals, we may safely conclude that animals cannot exist without skins [so all the earlier editions read, as the connedlion demands]. If color cannot exist by itself, it follows that neither can anything that is col- ored exist without color." Now of the second illus- The Body of Language. 7 tration the conclusion is unquestionable, as much so as that nothing that is shaped can exist without shape, nor anything that is numbered without number. It does not, however, follow from the premise stated, but from this very different premise : that nothing is found by us to exist, or conceivable as existing, without (in the light) possessing color, as without shape or num- ber. Our author's argument, as he uses it, would have been just as good in this form : if the color red cannot exist by itself, it follows that nothing can exist without being red. That this is a non-seguitur would probably be perceptible even to him ; but it is not really more plainly so than his other illustration con- cerning skins, the quality of which he might have tested by varying it thus : if we never find horns and tails except as the appendages of animals, we may safely conclude that animals cannot exist without horns and tails. In fadl, this test of the quality of the reasoning involved was applied to it, some time since ;* and, for once, he appears to have seen the point, and been led, not to omit the unfortunate sen- tence altogether, but to change slightly its conclud- ing words, which in this finally revised text read ' ' we may safely conclude that skins cannot exist without animals. ' ' This is a very harmless statement ; though "if we found" and "we might conclude" would be yet safer, because it would probably puzzle our author to show that apples and potatoes, for example, are not as properly said to have ' ' skins ' ' as animals. But the alteration, though it has spoiled the sentence as a * North American Review, vol. cxiii., 0(9;., 1871, pp. 439-40. 8 Muller' s Science of Langtiage. quotation for the chapter on fallacies in a treatise of logic, has at the same time destroyed its value as a part of the author's argument ; it goes now to show only that words cannot exist without conceptions, not that conceptions cannot exist without words, and is quite out of conne<5lion with what precedes and fol- lows. It is not possible to support the doctrine that conceptions and words are one and indivisible by pointing out that the skins of animals cannot exist without the animals to which they belong. In some respedls it is unfair to begin our review with a discussion of this passage, because it is per- haps (there are others that run it hard) the weakest in the two volumes. It is more than weak ; it is inane (what a German would call albern). But it is one of the passages to which, in a finally and thor- oughly revised edition, one who knows the work can- not help first turning, in order to see what the qual- ity of the revision has been. Moreover, it is not in its charadler an exceptional case, but rather the acme of the author's method ; this is the kind of ratiocina- tion by which, on no small scale, he arrives at unten- able conclusions from misunderstood or half-under- stood premises. Yet again, it concerns a matter, the relation of expression to thought, which is of the most central and fundamental importance in linguistic philosophy, respedling which if any one goes wrong he is liable to fail at every point. The false views here involved ramify very widely through our author's whole work, and it may be well for us to go on and follow them out as they show themselves elsewhere in his reasonings. Meaning of Conventional. g WHAT DOES " CONVBNTIONAI< " MEAN? We may note first his assumption, clearly made in these pages, that, if words and ideas (we may well enough use these terms in their popular sense, instead of seeking others more exadl) were not confessed to be identical, or at least eternally joined and insepa- rable, we should have to believe that an array of ar- ticulate signs was produced in advance, and then by deliberate and formal agreement added to or imposed upon a like array of ideas that had been waiting for signs. That is our author's view of what is involved in the dodlrine that the signs which make up lan- guage are "conventional." I^et us see how he ex- presses himself in regard to it throughout his two volumes. At i. 29, speaking of certain erring modern phi- losophers, he describes them as holding ' ' that the varieties of human speech arose from different na- tions agreeing on different sounds as the most appro- priate signs of their different ideas ;" and so it is not difficult for him to point out, a little later (i. 32), that " no one has yet explained how, without language, a discussion, however imperfedl, on the merits of each word, such as must needs have preceded a mutual agreement, could have been carried on." Again, at i. 94 : "when, as we are told by some persons, the first men, as yet speechless, came together in order to invent speech, and to discuss the most appropriate names that should be given to the perceptions of the senses and the abstradlions of the mind. ' ' Yet again, at i. 329, the idea is repudiated of " a congress for settling the proper exponents of such relations as lo Muller's Science of Language. nominative, genitive," etc. Once more, at ii. 432, he asserts that I