-^35 65 SMITH JURISPRUDENCE . (5ornf U IGaui Btl^anl ICibtary HERBERT D. LAUaE K 235.865'°'"^" ""'"^'^'fy Library JURISPRUDENCE BY MUNROE SMITH FKOFESSOR OF BOMAN LAW AND COMPAKATIVE JUKISPHUDENCK COLUMBIA tTNIVERSITT THE COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY PRESS 1909 Cornell University Library The original of tiiis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924017121645 JURISPRUDENCE A LECTURE DELIVERED AT COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY IN THE SERIES ON SCIENCE, PHILOSOPHY AND ART FEBRUARY 19, 1908 COPYKIGHT, 1908, By THE COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY PRESS. Set up, and published May, 1908. JURISPRUDENCE BY MUNROE SMITH PROFESSOR OF ROMAIT LAW AND COMPARATIVE JURISPRUDENCE COLUMBIA UjnVEHSITT THE COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY PRESS 1909 K JURISPRUDENCE OuE lives are controlled, to an extent which we do not measure without eflPort, by rules of conduct which are im- posed upon us by our environment and which we may not contravene without endangering our existence, our welfare or oiu- happiness. We do not ordinarily realize the multi- plicity of these rules or their coercive operation, because our acceptance of them is largely unconscious and om- obedi- ence to them, the leading of a normal or regular life, is largely automatic. When, however, we force ourselves to consider all these rules, and when we attempt to classify them, we see that some of them, such as the rules of health- ful living, represent primarily the adaptation of our con- duct to our physical environment ; others, such as the rules of thrift, adaptation to what may conveniently be termed our physical-social environment, that is, to those conditions which result from the interaction and reciprocal modifica- tion of human society and its environment; while a third group of rules, which may be termed social, seems to be im- posed upon us by the sentiments or the will of our fellow- men. When rules which we assign to the physical or to the physical-social group appear also, as they often do, in the distinctively social group — when, for example, we find that violations of the rules of health or of thrift are denounced as immoral and are in some instances penalized by law — it still remains true that these rules are not primarily social. They do not originate in social opinion, and disregard of 5 them is attended by risks which society has not created. They receive the additional sanctions of morals and of law because human interests are so solidary that the individual cannot live or die or prosper or suffer for himself alone. It may of course be queried whether we have any right to consider human society as a thing distinct from its physical environment, acting independently upon that environment and imposing upon us, as individuals, rules of conduct which are purely social. In the constitution of human so- ciety, indeed, there is much that seems arbitrary, and in its action there is much that is incalculable; but it is possible that our inability to forecast social action is due solely to the complexity of the phenomena, and that our impression that society determines in any degree its own constitution and conduct is an illusion. These questions, however, lie outside of the field of jurisprudence. L The law with which our science has to do assumes the existence of individual wills and bases its authority upon a social will.J^ .Whether the individual will is in any sense free; whether the social will is the resultant of free individual wills or a direct and independent product of the social life ; in what degree the social life is itself controlled by forces which men do not create and cannot control — these are questions which the jurist gladly leaves to the psychologist, the sociologist and the philosopher.^ Legal rules, even when they are assignable, by virtue of their origin, to the physical or to the physical-social group, belong, as regards their legal quality, in the group of social rules. In the same group we find a second body of rules which we call moral; and in addition to legal rules and moral rules we are aware of a third body of more or less heterogeneous rules which you will permit me, for con- venience, to call manners. IWhat now is the characteristic which differentiates law from manners and morals?: Obviously not the field in 6 which it operates, not the flatters with which it deals. Law has indeed a field, or a number of fields, in which it operates alone. Law has created institutions of its own; and the rules which shape these institutions and govern their opera- tion had no previous existence in manners or in morals. To a large extent, however, manners, morals and law cover the same field. To knock a man down, for example, or to wrest from him portable valuables is, in most instances, at once unmannerly, immoral and illegal. Especially large is the field which is common to law and to morals— so large, indeed, that many time-honored definitions of law assume a complete correspondence of law with morals, and it has been possible to say, although erroneously, that law is sim- ply applied morals. It is equally impossible to find the distinguishing char- acteristic of law in its purpose or end. The primary pur- pose of law is the maintenance of the social order ; but this purpose is also subserved, in large measure, by morals and by manners. The graver disturbances of the established social order are usually stigmatized as immoral. The ex- istence, in the various fields of human effort, of accepted and regular modes of activity does much to lessen the fric- tion of social life ; and the established forms of social inter- course, manners in the narrowest sense of the word, take out of the struggle for existence much of its bitterness and perhaps do more than either morals or law to prevent breaches of the peace. iThe ultimate purpose of the law, indeed, is not the main- tenance of the social order but the assurance of the condi- tions of social progress. That man shall obtain increasing control over his physical environment ; that the relations of men shall become more and more kindly; that human life shall be more and more worth living— these are the final objects of the law. To attain these ends individual effort must not only remain worth while, it must be increasingly 7 encouraged; in other words, competition must continue; and yet anti-social activities must be increasingly re- strained and there must be increasing cooperation. ^The fundamental and eternal problem of human civilization is the reconcihation of individual with social interests^; Such progress as has thus far been made towards the solution of this problem has been achieved by raising the plane of com- petition and by increasing the range of cooperation. In the methods of competition craft has replaced brute force, and fair play is replacing craft. The objects of competi- tion have become and are becoming less and less material: honor is sought rather than wealth, and higher honor is ac- corded for social service than for personal success. The cooperation of the horde has been replaced by that of the class and, in many fields, by that of the nation; interna- tional cooperation exists and is increasing. All these ends, however, are moral as well as legal ends, and higher ethical ideals indicate lines of legal progress. We gain our first glimpse of the distinguishing charac- teristic of law, and perhaps of that of morals also, when we note the different results that attach to the disregard or violation of different rules of social conduct. If the rule infringed be one of manners simply, there is usually a so- cial reaction of surprise, attended commonly by ridicule of the offender. If the rule infringed be one of morals, the social reaction is more energetic: it is more than a surprise, it is a shock, and it is attended by more or less heated dis- approval, which may range from contempt through scorn to loathing. In the mind of the offender himself there is a reflex of the social disapproval; there is the prick of con- science, the sense of shame; and if he be a religious man and his offense be one that his religion brands as a sin, there will be a sense of divine displeasure. J' Arnold defined relig- ion as morality touched with emotion^ but there is a marked element of emotion in morality itself, independent of 8 religion. All these reactions, it will be noted, are purely psychical, and the penalties which follow breaches of manners and morals operate upon the offender's feelings. ^Law, on the other hand, encourages cer- tain courses of conduct by the assurance of advantages and discourages other courses of conduct by imposing dis- advantages or penalties which aif ect the property or the person; and these purely legal consequences may be. en- forced, in case of need, by the entire physical power of the community.J We note further, and this brings us to a second differ- entia of law, that the advantages which follow the obser- vance of legal rules and the disadvantages or penalties which attend the disregard or violation of such rules do not attach solely by virtue of the social sentiment or opinion, but by virtue of the social will. In civilized communities this social will is formulated through special processes and usually by special organs. The processes are mainly polit- ical and the organs are for the most part governmental. In constitutions adopted by the people, in acts passed by representative bodies, in orders of administrative officers and in decisions of courts we find, authoritatively stated, the rules of law, the advantages which attach to their ob- servance, the disadvantages or penalties which follow their disregard or violation. The rules of manners and of mor- als, on the other hand, are not stated in any such authori- tative form. In early society, indeed, authority over the entire field of conduct is usually accorded to priests, and in later stages of social development this authority frequently persists in the field of morals ; but in an advanced civiliza- tion it tends to disappear. It may still be asserted, and it may long command extensive recognition; but the recog- nition becomes less and less general, and morals, like man- ners, tend to rest directly upon social sentiment and opin- ion. They are matters of usage. 9 To affirm that law is formulated through special pro- cesses, and chiefly by special organs of the community, is not to deny that its rules are largely determined by social sentiment. 4 Manners and morals are, to a large extent, antecedent to law, and social usage has always furnished much of the material of which law has been made. In the earliest stages of legal development usage apparently fxu"- nishes all the material ; it is converted into law simply by adding the support of social force; and in every state of social progress new law is made by the recognition and en- forcement of established customs. Manners, morals and law, all appear to rest ultimately upon social utility. The conversion of usage into law, the decision whether any particular rule of conduct shall be supported by the physi- cal power of the community, is clearly a question of social expediency. Social utility or expediency is determined, in the whole field of conduct, by the social judgment, and so- cial force can be exercised only by virtue of the social wilLX The social judgment, however, is usually inarticulate ; it re- veals itself as sentiment. In the matters with which the law deals, we call this sentiment the sense of justice. The so- cial will, likewise, is, in most instances, liot aimless indeed, but only vaguely aware of its true aim ; it manifests itself as impulse to do something, to sweep aside or crush some- thing that is felt to be alien and hostile. As it is the pri- mary function of practical ethics to interpret moral emo- tion and to give articulate form to the moral sentiment, so 5^ it is the primary function of practical jurisprudence to in- terpret the sense of justice and to formulate in legal rules those ends toward which the social will is blindly groping^ Ulpian's "nomen iuris a iustitia" although indefensible from the philological point of view, is good philosophy, t In the interpretation of the social sentiment and the social will judges and legislatures have indeed an authority which no men or bodies of men possess in the fields of manners and 10 morals: even when they misinterpret the general sense of justice and thwart the general will, the rules which they lay down are law. Such law, however, has no root, and, if it be not formally abrogated or superseded, it becomes a dead letter. In the long run, general sentiment and opin- ion control not only the finding and making of law, but also its enforcement..^ Persistent disregard of general sentiment on the part of lawfinders or lawmakers is exceptional; in the democratic state it is almost impossible. I Conflicts between general sentiment and positive law arise, as a rule, only when so- cial changes have made the established legal rules unsatis- factory.* Such conflicts take the form of agitation for the reform of the law, and they cease when the law is suitably amended. Conflicts between sectional or local or class sen- timent and the general law arise, on the contrary, in every type of state, and such conflicts are practically incessant. •Powerless, as a rule, to control lawfinding or lawmaking, adverse minority sentiment makes itself felt in resistance to the enforcement of the law ; and under favoring circum- stances the resistance may result in the nullification of the law. From such results it is sometimes inferred that the physical sanctions of the law are less coercive than the psy- chical sanction of opinion, even when the opinion is that of a portion of the community only, of a locality or of a social group. It should be noted, however, that when the law is worsted in these conflicts it does not put forth its full power. It is defeated because it binds its own hands. Laws are nullified, for example, because local administra- tive authorities are legally independent of the central ad- ministration, or because juries are permitted by the law to interpret the law as they see fit. It may not be advisable to destroy or seriously to limit local self-government because Sunday-closing laws are locally nullified, or to empower judges to set aside verdicts in criminal cases because busi- 11 ness or labor interests make it difficult to punish illegal combinations ; but these or similar changes in the law can be made if such be the general will. 5; Z The strength of the law lies in the fact that its physical sanctions operate, or can be made to operate, with equal force throughout the entire area of a state and among all classes. The weakness of general opinion lies in the fact that it operates less strongly on men's minds than does the opinion of their locality and that of their class.*^ Especially strong is the influence of group opinion, and it is strongest in the smallest and most homogeneous groups. The pressure of social opinion seems to vary inversely as the square of the social distance. Hence the tendency of all usage to variation and to particularism; hence the lusty growth, at all times, of group morals— morals of the class, of the profession, of the business, of the gang. Left to it- self, enforcing itself only by the pressure of social opinion, our existing morality would tend to revert to its primitive form, the usage of the horde. The higher social utilities which the rules of general morals represent could never have prevailed over the interests of the horde or of the tribe or of the class through any appeal to reason or to individual interest ; for feeling is stronger than reason and group feel- ing is stronger than self-interest. The agencies which in the past have slowly subordinated group morals to general morals, and by which general morals were perhaps first formulated, are religion and law. Every religion that has developed beyond the stage of a clan cult has, on the whole, lent its psychical sanction to the more general morals ; and the religious sanction, like the legal, can be made to operate with equal force over indefinite areas and upon all social classes. The law, in so far as it has had to deal with moral questions, has likewise put its special sanction, that of physical force, behind general morals. In the early stages of civilization, religion apparently played the more im- 12 portant part in formulating the rules of general morals and in securing their triumph ; in later periods and at the present time law has possibly become the more efficient agency. Rehgion influences the believer only; law coerces even the anarchist. Confessions are divided into sects, and churches are organized, in some instances, along the lines of class cleavage; states grow larger by conquest or by federation, and modern states are becoming increasingly democratic. J Our analysis of social rules and of their operation upon the individual is not complete without a word regarding constraints that are neither purely psychical nor purely physical but economic.^ A religious association, possessing at the outset no means of securing obedience except those which are purely psychical, may come to exercise so gen- eral an influence over the minds of men that individuals cast out from its communion are completely boycotted and can obtain none of the necessities of life. A relatively small number of persons, united by ties of class interest, may so monopolize land or other means of production that no one can live by his labor except upon the terms which the group prescribes. A larger number of persons, similarly united by the ties of class interest, may so monopolize the labor market that no one outside of their association can obtain regular employment and that the production of goods be- comes impossible except upon the terms which they dictate. There have been periods in which such associations or groups have become states, or at least governments. This was the case in the middle ages with the Christian church, the feudal nobility and some of the city guilds; and the rules established by these associations became law in the strictest sense of the word, since they were generally ac- cepted and were supported by physical force. In the dem- ocratic state, however, with monarchic or representative government, such associations are not permitted to exercise 13 permanently an economic constraint which parallels and possibly neutralizes the constraints imposed by the general will and applied through governmental organs. If the ends which such associations pursue are approved by the social judgment, the constraints are legalized, but the asso- ciations are brought under legal control. Otherwise, their efforts to exercise an irresistible extra-legal constraint are repressed as illegal conspiracies. The democratic state is rightly jealous of its monopoly of coercion, for its govern- ment alone can be trusted to exercise coercion in the in- terests of liberty. By way of summing up the results thus far reached, I suggest, with all deference to the superior authority of the specialists in ethics, that ^morals is that part of the social order which is supported by social opinion, touched with more or less emotion ; and, with more confidence, I describe law as that part of the social order which by virtue of the social will may be supported by physical f orce4 » Law is in part found, in part made ; that is, it is estab- lished partly by decisions and partly by legislation. Of these processes the decision is not only the older but the more important and the more persistent. A decision is not alone the termination of a pending controversy, it is also a precedent for future decisions. To us, to-day, the word suggests primarily a judicial decision ;;^but^here were de- cisions before there were courts, and decisions that make law are still rendered to-day outside of the courts. The primitive himian community resembles those lowest forms of animal life which exercise with the whole body a num- ber of functions which the higher animals exercise only through special organs. The primitive decision is a com- munity-decision, and its earliest form is the lynching or running-out of the individual who has violated one of the rules of conduct which the community feels to be f unda- 14 mental,! In somewhat more advanced communities there is another very important form of community-decision. When a man has slain another in self-defence or in rightful vengeance, the community may intervene to protect him from blood-feud, just as to-day the community, acting through special organs, absolves from responsibility the individual who has shot a burglar at night in his bedroom. In both cases the slaying of the wrongdoer precedes the de- cision that he has been rightfully slain ; but in both cases the decision in favor of the man who has taken the law into his own hands recognizes that what he has taken into his own hands is law. t After the establishment of courts, community-decisions tend to disappear in that part of the law with which the coiu-ts are competent to deal. In those parts of the law, however, in which the courts are not competent, in political law, for example, community-decisions have continued to establish law in modern times. All unwritten constitutions rest on precedents, and constitutional precedents are set whenever acts of power are supported or accepted by the whole community. And in the international community the only rules that are strictly legal are those which have been enforced in the past, and will therefore presumably be enforced in the future, by the international community, the concert of powers. The rest of what we call international law is as yet only international morals and manners. The processes by which early society develops judicial and legislative organization have only recently begun to be understood. As regards European communities, we can now say with confidence that neither lawfinding nor lawmaking has any historical connection with the authority of a patriarch to settle disputes of his descendants and to lay down rules for their future conduct. In general, it may be said that the more light we get on the conditions prevailing in really primitive human society, the less we see 15 of anything resembling a patriarch. Ages seem to have been necessary for the establishment of marital and pater- nal authority, and ages more for the development of the patriarch ; nor is any patriarchate so complete as that of the Romans known to have existed among any other European people. The earliest European court was not patriarchal but popular. In it the community still acted collectively, but it acted not as a mob but as an orderly assembly. The assembly court had from the outset special lawfinding or- gans; it gradually developed special organs of decision; and the modification, rearrangement or combination of those organs have produced every type of modern court. C Legislation, as we know it, has two historical roots: for- mal agreement of the community (which originally, it seems, had to be unanimous) and the order issued by the war-lord to the people under arms. From the power of the military leader to issue orders to his men was derived, when temporary leadership grew into permanent kingship, the power to issue orders in time of peace J Among European peoples, however, such orders were not originally regarded as laws in any proper sense, but merely as administrative measures ; and neither among the Germans nor among the Romans could such orders be enforced, originally, by any means other than a fine, legally limited in amount. I Only in proportion as a king gained power by conquest did his ordinance power expand into anything like legislative power; and it amounted to general legislative power only when the king became an absolute monarchy. In the modern state the executive order has shrunk into something like its original dimensions, while the general power of the people to legislate by agreement is still ex- ercised directly or through representatives. I Even in the earliest stages of legal development, when the social will manifests itself directly in social action— in 16 lynchings, for example— there are experts to tell the com- munity why it acts as it does. These experts are not law- yers only; they belong to the single undifferentiated profession from which have emerged all the professions of civilized life; they are experts in all matters natural, human and divine; they formulate the rules of health, of thrift, of manners and of morals. All this knowledge is one body of wisdom, and aU these rules are part of the re- ligion of which these men are the priests. In their undiffer- entiated activity we are nevertheless able to recognize spe- cial fields of legal action.J They define not only the cases in which individuals may rightly be slain or be thrust out into the deserts or forests, but also the cases in which clan feud may be rightly raised or private vengeance rightly taken. They also devise the earliest methods of deciding doubtful cases and of terminating controversy. Among the early Romans the legal activity of the priests had be- come so highly specialized that not only was there a class of priests whose business was chiefly legal, but there were three boards of these priests: one for interstate relations, another for the public law of Rome, and a third for the private law. After courts of justice were established, the priestly law- finder was succeeded and displaced, in European legal de- velopment, by the secular lawfinder, whom the Romans described as the jurisprudent or jurisognsjilt, the Germans as the Wiseman or lawspeaker. ^.These lawfinders were un- official persons : they were neither elected by the assembly nor appointed by king or magistrate. They emerged from the body of the people by a natural selection; they were en- titled to declare the law because they knew the law. Con- clusive, of course, as to the authority of a new lawspeaker was the general opinion of the older and recognized law- speakers. These experts were not judges in our sense, nor did they directly decide controversies. In the early Euro- ir pean court a governmental chairman heard the pleadings of the parties, but he was not necessarily a lawyer. The decision was rendered originally by the whole body of the freemen, as among the Germans ; in a more advanced stage of development it was rendered, as in Greece and repub- lican Rome, by a larger or smaller body of citizens, or by a single citizen ; but even when, as at Rome, the decision on the law and the facts was rendered by a single citizen, he was not necessarily learned in the law. The naturally selected unofficial experts informed the chairman of the court whether the pleadings were regular; and it was from such experts that the people or their representatives learned the rules of law which should govern their decisions. Out- side of court these experts gave legal advice to individuals. They accordingly combined the functions of the modern lawfinding judge and of the modern counselor. The modern type of court with which we are all familiar was constructed at Rome in the early Empire, and was con- structed again a thousand years later in Norman England, by the simple expedient of selecting a jurist or wiseman for chairman of the court. This change substituted for the naturally selected unofficial lawfinder an artificially se- lected official lawfinder. In the English type of court pop- ular cooperation in the administration of justice reappears in the jury ; but, as the decision of the people in the earliest European court was guided by the instruction of the ex- pert, so the decision of the modern jury is guided by the learned judge. After the judges were taken out of the general body of experts, the remainder of the legal profession (includ- ing certain elements which were not historically derived from the lawspeaking or jurist class) was organized either, as in England, in the two groups of barristers and solicitors or, as in imperial Rome and in the United States, in a single undifferentiated body of practising lawyers. 18 When we say that law is established by decisions, we do not mean that the condemnation or acquittal of a person accused of crime or the rendering of a judgment for the plaintiff or for the defendant in a civil case establishes the law. tit is in the determination of the legal question at issue, by the recognition and formulation of the legal rule which governs the case, that the law is established. This, as we have seen, has always been the work of experts. That part of the law which the Romans described as the custom- ary or unwritten law, which we describe as common law or case-law, is, in reality, §jinply expert opinion. The un- written law of Rome consisted, in the republican period, of the "responses" of the unofficial jurists, in the imperial period of the responses of the jurists who were authorized to respond and who, for the most part, were imperial judges. Old German tribal law was found in the "wis- doms" or "dooms" of the wisemen or lawspeakers ; English and American common law consists of the opinions ren- dered in court by learned judges, 'i These experts, it should be noted, have always been men engaged in the practical application of the law; and their opinions have always been given in connection with cases actually in litigation and in view of the facts of each spe- cial case. Lit should be noted, further, that the unsup- ported opinions of single experts have rarely been regarded as authoritative. The response of the single jurist at Rome, the wisdom of the single lawspeaker among the Germans, was regarded as establishing the law only in so far as it was accepted by the whole body of legal experts. Similarly, in the latest stage of legal development, the opinions which are cited as authoritative are those rendered on appeal by courts of final instance. It should be added that the dodejgj bench always depends largely on the bar to cast light on all sides of a difficult legal question, and that, in the English and American practice, the authority 19 of a decided case may always be impugned on the ground that it was not fully argued. To make owe description of unAvritten or case-law completely accurate, we should therefore say that it is deliberate and accordant expert opinion. ;( u While the expert lawfinders have always claimed that they were following precedents and abiding by the rules laid down in decided cases, they have always exercised great freedoi|i in the interpretation of earlier decisions. In the development of the customary or unwritten law it has always been assumed that the law which is found in decided cases existed somewhere before the cases were decided. One of the oldest German words for law is ewa, that which has always been. Of this eternal law the wis- dom or dooms pronounced by the wisemen were simply the accepted statements. This is still the orthodox doctrine of all courts of justice.j^TFrom it is derived the very im- portant inference that the form in which a rule has been stated in earlier cases is not binding ; it is always admissible to re-examine the cases and to restate the rule. The pos- sibilities of change and development inherent in such a theory are obviously very great; they have been sufficient to enable the coiuis to meet, by constant re-interpretation, most of the needs of a progressive society.^! It was in fact mainly by interprejation that the Roman law and the Eng- lish law were developed from rude customs into the stately fabrics beneath whose shelter all civilized peoples except the Chinese and the Mohammedans are now living.:; In connection with the development of the rules of the unwritten law there also gradually appears a set of more general rules described as principles. These present them- selves as propositions of which the ordinary rules are merely corollaries ; and from these principles are frequently derived, in case of need, entirely new rules. The eternal existence of these principles is asserted with even ^eater 20 energy and persistence than is the eternal existence of the special rules ; but here also it is recognized that no partic- ular statement of a principle is definitive. When we make abstraction from the time-honored fic- tions of the lawfinders, and consider what European legal experts, priests, lawspeakers and judges have actually been doing in the twenty-three hundred years over which our observation extends, it is impossible, I think, to deny that their methods have been scientific — far more scientific than their own description of their methods. I The fun- ;J( damental assumptions upon which all their work has been based are obviously these: that law exists for the protec- tion of social interests, and that social interests are more truly reflected in social feeling, in the general sense of jus- tice, than in any reasoned theories. In their effort to give to the social sense of justice articulate expression in rules and in principles, the method of the lawfinding experts has always been experimental. The rules and principles of case-law have never been treated as :^q^ ^M^JS ^^* ^s working hypotheses, continually retested in those great laboratories of the law, the courts of justice. Every new case is an experiment ; and if the accepted rule which seems applicable yields a result which is felt to be unjust, the rule is reconsidered. It may not be modified at once, for the attempt to do absolute justice in every single case would make the development and maintenance of general rules impossible ; but if a rule continues to work injustice, it will eventually be reformulated. The principles them- selves are continually retested ; for if the rules derived from a principle do not work well, the principle itself must ulti- mately be re-examined.it The further this process is carried, the more does the conscious recognition of social utility become the real, al- though unavowed, basis of decisions— "the secret root," as Holmes says in his Common Law, "from which the law 21 draws all the juices of life." Iln novel eases, however, espe- cially when their novelty is due to changed social conditions —in cases, that is, in which the sense of social utility has not yet attained its reasoned justification — the finding of new law is always controlled by feeling rather than by reason.! LThat legal experts have not generally described their methods as experimental and inductive is probably due to the fact that the scientific character of such methods has not been generally recognized until modern times. Through the ages in which deduction from unquestioned premises was regarded as the only scientific mode of thought, the lawyers not unnaturally endeavored to rep- resent their premises as absolute and unchanging and their method as purely deductive.^ J^ Great as are the possibilities of the development, by interpretation, of law which has no objective existence ex- cept in its interpretation, these possibilities are not unlim- ited. In all law, and most of all in law established by decis- ions, there is a tendency to persistence, a resistance to change. This is true of all law, because society demands not only that the rules of law be just, but also that they be certain. It is especially true of case-law, because the development of this law is wholly in the hands of lawyers, who are gen- erally more conservative than laymen. Their conservatism is rational, because they xmderstand, better than laymen, the meaning and the value of the accepted principles and rules of the unwritten law ^ and it is valuable to society, because these principles and rules represent the abiding sense of justice, as against momentary gusts of popular feeling, and the accumulated experience of centuries, as against impressions derived from situations which are ex- ceptional and which may be transitory. 1 Legal conser- vatism, however, is a constant impediment to necessary 22 changes ; if it cannot prevent, it delays them; and the delay which it causes is most constant in case-law. j{ A current of decisions may be diverted, but it cannot well be made to flow backward ; and if its direction is to be seriously modi- fied, it will not turn abruptly but will sweep round slowly in a very long curve. Accordingly, in periods of rapid social change, law is made by other processes than those which we have been considering. One of these processes is that by which the j^i^torian Igvj^ was developed at Rome and ^uity in England, tin both instances new law was made and enforced by executive or administrative authority, and in both instances this new law was developed experimentally in the administration of justice between litigants. J It was thus substantially the same process by which the older law had been developed; but the old precedents were disregarded and a fresh start was made. Both at Rome and in England the new law was framed by experts: at Rome by the jurists who sat in the councils of the praetors, in England by a special court with its own bar. In both instances admirable results were achieved ; but in both instances the production of new law through these administrative agencies ceased when the social needs which had set them in motion were satisfied. The praetors and chancellors began to adhere with increas- ing strictness to the precedents established by their prede- cessors ; the new law became relatively stable ; and the en- suing legal development proceeded along the old fines of interpretation until legislation became active. In modern times, however, the making of law by the decisions of administrative authorities is reappearing. On the continent of Europe there are regular administrative courts, and their decisions not only control the working of the administrative machinery, but affect the interests of in- dividuals. In our coimtry administrative tribunals are multiplying in the form of federal and state commissions, 23 which are clothed with quasi- judicial as well as with quasi- legislative powers and which are meeting new social ex- igencies by decisions as well as by administrative orders. When, as is the case both in Europe and in the United States, certain matters fall exclusively within the jurisdic- tion of these administrative authorities, their decisions create new law, t In Europe it is recognized that adminis- trative judges should be experts alike in administration and in law. In the United States, where administrative tribunals are comparatively new and their importance is imperfectly realized, this double qualification is not as yet demanded.! u Legislation is confined, in early stages of legal develop- ment, to matters of policy and is chiefly employed for the adoption of temporary measures in the face of special ex- igencies4 The abiding social order, the ancient law, is too sacred a thing to be changed consciously and openly. tWhen early legislation touches the field of general law it is usually declaratory, that is, it simply affirms the law already recognized and enforced in the decision of contro- versies. Such declaratory legislation first appears, in many communities, in connection with early attempts to set forth the law as a whole, that its provisions may be better known^lThe use of legislation, whether popular, royal or representative, as a means of changing the gen- eral law comes late in European political life. The idea that the law stands in need of constant change and that the necessary changes are normally to be accomplished by legislation is an idea that appears only in a very advanced civilization^ In the Roman Empire it appeared only in the period of decline and decay. In the West Gothic and Frankish Empires legislation was fairly frequent because of the persistence of late Roman traditions. In mediaeval Eui'ope, after the ninth century, there was little legislation except in church councils and in the free cities ; and in the 24 HERBERT D. LAUl cities legislation was active only when they had attained a high degree of economic and political development, t In the modern European states there was little reformatory legislation before the eighteenth century, nor did statutory law gain anything like its modern volume before the nine- teenth century, jj u The increasing part played by legislation in late periods of legal development is due in some measure to the in- creased rapidity of social Qhange, in some measure to an exaggerated faith in the power of law to modify social con- ditions and to remedy social evils, but in the main, ap- parently, to the fact that there are certain portions of the law which courts are wholly unable to develop and certain other portions in which judge-made law is less satisfactory than enacted law.^ Political law, constitutional and ad- ministrative, is usually beyond the competence of courts. This part of the law, developed during long stretches of time by commiuiity-decisions, is at last embodied in stat- utes and in written constitutions. Again, that part of the law which expresses interests which are primarily social tends always, and particularly in a democratic society, to be formulated by the direct assertion of the general will. Finally,*there is a considerable part of the law which is distinctly arbitrary. Here also there must be rules; but from the point of view of justice it seems immaterial what the rules shall be. Here certainty, not justice, is the im perative social demand, and here the movement toward legislation begins at a very early periodJ[ After ceding all these fields to legislation, a large do- main may yet be reserved for the tentative development of law by the courts. J To the courts may be left that part of the law which primarily subserves the interests of indi- viduals, which accordingly grants to individuals a large measure of liberty, and which, for this reason, has to deal with extremely varied and highly complex relations. In 25 this part of the law the demand for justice is more im- perative than the demand for certainty. This part of the law, roughly speaking, is the law of personal property, of contracts and of torts. To the very end of the Roman Empire this part of the law remained embodied in decided cases, and the same is true to-day among all Enghsh- speaking peoples. 1 The belief, so generally held to-day, that in a really advanced civilization legislation must cover the whole field of the law, that the finding of law by coiu-ts is a remnant of archaic conditions destined gradually to disappear — this belief has no basis except in the conditions existing to-day in continental Europe and in those coun- tries which have derived their institutions from continental Europe. But in continental Europe, from the dissolution of the Prankish Empire until the estabhshment of national states, the political and legal development was abnormal. In the Roman Empire, and in England after the Norman conquest, there were at all times organs capable of finding general law as well as organs capable of making such law, and there was always a central authority able to subor- dinate local law to general law. Both in the Roman and in the English legal development, accordingly, it was pos- sible to create general or common law by decisions as well as by legislation. In continental Europe the national state developed much later than in England: in Germany and in Italy it was not organized until the nineteenth century. Until it was organized there were no efficient organs for finding or making national law. When it was organized, the existing law was in the main provincial or local; and the provincial and local laws were so firmly estabhshed that national law could be produced only by legislation, and a complete body of national law could be created only by codification. iThe work of the legislator is akin to the work of the judge, in that it is his business to express the social will in 26 the form of rules. In the work of the legislator a higher degree of skill is required than in the work of the courts, because rules laid down in statutes are less easily amended than rules laid down in decisions. A representative leg- islature, in particular, is a cumbrous piece of political ma- chinery, not easily set in motion; and if a law be ill-con- sidered or badly drawn, it will do much harm before it arouses enough resentment to secure its amendment or repeaLS In modern European countries, including Great [Britain, these considerations have led to the development of a class of legislative experts, men who are primarily trained lawyers but who are also trained legal draftsmen, and who hold permanent appointments in the govern- mental service. These experts not only draw all bills which are introduced by the government, but they examine bills introduced by private members of the legislative body ; and it is usually impossible for a private member to secure the adoption of a bill unless it be put in such form as the governmental experts deem satisfactory. Under the in- fluence of this body of legislative experts, a scientific theory of legislation has obtained general acceptance, tit is rec- ognized that no finite intelligence can anticipate the vari- ous situations to which a proposed law may become ap- pUcable or the varying conditions under which it may be applied. A modern European statute accordingly lays down the principles that are to be applied or indicates the ends that are to be attained, and leaves the detailed rules which shall give effect to the legislative purpose to be formulated in administrative orders or to be worked out in decisions. 4 In the United States the legislative expert is only beginning to appear and is still in the unofficial stage of development. Under these conditions it is not sur- prising that our theory of legislation is that of a past age. Our legislators try to do too much, and by attempting to provide for all contingencies they not only embarrass the 27 administration and the courts, but in many cases they; defeat their own piu-poses. *The making of a code, especially of a civil code, which sets forth the rules of the private law, that is, the law of property, of contracts, of family and of inheritance, is the most difficult work in the field of legal science. The suc- cessful solution of this problem presupposes a large and well reasoned body of case-law and numerous well digested systematic treatises. No single expert has ever con- structed a satisfactory civil code: the work must be done, as it has been done in modern European states, by a com- mission of experts.^ The most scientific process which has ever been employed in the work of codification is that which was employed in the German Empire in the construction of the existing civil code. A committee on plan and method was appointed in the spring of 1874. In the autumn of the same year, in accordance with the recommendation of this first committee, a commission of eleven eminent jm-ists was constituted, with the chief justice of the highest im- perial court as its president. In the year 1887 a complete first draft was presented to the government. In 1888 this was published, with five volumes of "motives." An enor- mous amount of expert criticism appeared in this and the ensuing years. All this criticism was carefully digested by governmental experts. Their digest was arranged in the order of the sections of the draft code and was pub- lished in 1894. With the aid of this digest a second com- mission revised the draft of 1887, and a greatly improved second draft was published in 1895. After further slight revision by a committee of the Imperial Diet, the code was adopted in 1896, and it went into force in 1900. The occupation of any portion of the legal field by writ- ten law, constitutional or statutory, in no wise terminates the activity of the courts in that field ; it does not even ter- 28 minate their lawfinding power. Z Scientific legislation recognizes fully that the detailed rules which are needed to give effect to a legislative pohcy musit be worked out partly or wholly by the courts^ .Unscientific legislation requires from the courts something more than this sub- sidiary lawfinding; it requires corrective interpretation. The same is true of the most thoroughly considered and most carefully drawn laws, when the social conditions to which they must be applied have undergone serious changes, f According to the theory of the separation of powers, the covu^s should not use their power of inter- pretation for the purpose of correcting or amending legis- lation; they should apply the written law as it is written, leaving to the legislatures the task of improving it. Prac- tically, however, this course would result in so much incon- venience and injustice as to arouse public resentment, not against the legislatures but against the courts. The gen- eral purpose of the law, it would be said, is evident; why do the courts not endeavor to realize that purpose? This accordingly is what the courts try to do. For more than two thousand years it has been an accepted legal principle that, in interpreting the written law, effect should be given, as far as possible, to the spirit and intent of the law. Here again the possibihties of lawfinding under cover of inter- pretation are very great.;i jl distinguished German jurist, Windscheid, has remarked that in interpreting legislation modern courts may and habitually do "think over again the thought which the legislator was trying to express," but that the Roman jurist went further and "thought out the thought which the legislator was trying to think. "4 Of this freer mode of interpretation Windscheid might have found modern examples. ^The president of the highest French court, M. Ballot-Beaupre, explained, a few years ago, that the provisions of the Napoleonic legislation had been adapted to modern conditions by a judicial inter- 29 pretation in "le sens evolutif." "We do not inquire," he said, "what the legislator willed a century ago, but what he would have willed if he had known what oiu* present conditions would be.'ljf In English-speaking countries this freer mode of interpretation has always been applied to the unwritten or common law, and it is usually applied to the written law with a degree of boldness which is very closely proportioned to the difficulty of securing formal amend- ment. Thus![the rigidity of our federal constitution has constrained the Supreme Court of the United States to push the interpreting power to its furthest limits. This tribunal not only thinks out the thoughts which the Fathers were trying to think one hundred and twenty years ago, but it undertakes to determine what they would have thought if they could have foreseen the changed conditions and the novel problems of the present day. It has con- strued and reconstrued the constitution in "the evolutive sense," until in some respects that instrument has been re- constructed. Jl t Every science classifies the phenomena with which it deals. In the law classification is especially necessary be- cause, without classification of persons, of acts and of rela- tions, it would obviously be impossible to lay down any general rules^ In the early stages of legal development classification is crude : persons are either fully capable and responsible or completely incapable and irresponsible ; acts by which property may be transferred or debt created are limited in number, and such acts are valid or invalid ac- cording as certain forms are or are not rigidly observed. I In early law certainty is far more important than equity. In the later stages of legal development classification be- comes increasingly refined, and, correspondingly, the law becomes more and more equitable ; for equity, in last analy- sis, means discrimination. To this process, however, 30 there are necessary limits. In its most advanced develop- ment the law necessarily deals with typical persons, typical acts and typical relations ; for if it should attempt to deal specially with variations from the normal type it would lose all certainty. In becoming absolute equity it would cease to be law.JjDModern society, however, provides spe- cial organs of discrimination, in such institutions, for ex- ample, as the pardoning power and the jury. The great social advantage of the jury is that it can bend the law in hard cases without creating authoritative precedents.! t Every science, again, analyzes the phenomena with which it has to deal. J In the law every act is resolved into its inward and its outward elements: crime becomes a combination of wrongful intent and illegal conduct; con- tract becomes a meeting of two corresponding wills in cor- responding declarations. Every legal relation is resolved into its constituent powers or rights; and in spite of the very great variety of legal relations, the variety of legal rights is seen to be limited. ^ The conception of the legal right is to-day so famihar, and it seems so simple, that we can hardly realize with what difficulty it was attained. But as early law was wholly remedial and the substantive legal order which the rem- edies supported was only slowly recognized, so the legal right long lay concealed behind the correlative and essen- tially ethical notion of the duty. 3 Brunner tells us that in the Germanic languages the word RecM, whether used in the sense of right or of law, is clearly younger than the other words for law; and Hozumi assures us that the Japanese language had no expression for the legal right until 1868, when a word was coined by a Japanese writer who had studied European law at Leyden. Andjonly in our own time has it been clearly perceived that' the legal right, pre- viously regarded as the atom of all legal relations, is itself a combination of a definite interest and a limited power.3 31 and that these two elements are separable. LThis was one of Jhering's great contributions to jurisprudenee.^ Coup- ling this analysis with Burgess's sharp distinction between state and government, we see that it is in no sense inexact, as has been frequently asserted, to speak of public legal rights. Of course limited powers can not be attributed to the state, because the state is legally omnipotent; but limited powers may properly be attributed to any organ of government, and our public rights are in fact a combina- tion of definite public interests with limited governmental powers. The possible developments of this line of thought in private and in public law are as yet imperfectly reahzed. i The final task of legal science is the orderly and conve- nient arrangement of all the institutions and rules of the law, public and private, substantive and remedial, in a logical system.^ The difficulties of this problem are very great, because of the innumerable points at which each part of the law touches every other part. Interrelations so com- plicated that the mind must work in a fourth dimension to apprehend them cannot be satisfactorily exhibited along the single line of a topical arrangement. I have already indicated that[Jbhe formulation of legal rules and principles has been, in the main, the work of practical jurists, men actively engaged in the administra- tion of justice. The same statement may be made as re- gards legal classification and analysis, both in Roman and in English law. Not only has most of this work been done in the judicial laboratory, in connection with the discussion and decision of concrete cases, but the results obtained are largely embodied in judicial opinions. Moreover, the liter- ature in which these results are presented has for the most part been produced by practical jurists. Nearly all the juristic writers of the Roman Empire were imperial judges (a few only were law professors) , and their writings were substantially digests of the practice of the imperial su- 32 preme coiirt. In English-speaking countries the legal literature has been less important; in these countries legal classification and analysis, like the rules of the law, are for the most part to be sought in the law reports ; but in these countries, as at Rome, the most valuable contributions in these fields of legal science have been made by practical lawyers, by judges or by members of the bar.i| In this re- spect, again, the continental European development, dur- ing the middle ages and in modern times, has been differ- ent. In consequence of the arrested development of national law, recourse was had to the compilations of Jus- tinian ; because of the antiquity of these compilations their study centered in the universities; andjfrom the eleventh century down to the present time nearly all the legal litera- ture was written by professors. These writers were, in- deed, by no means out of touch with the administration of justice. Not only were some of them judges, but until comparatively recent times university law faculties were frequently called upon to decide difficult cases. The rela- tion between legal literature and applied law was, how- ever, fundamentally different from that which existed in the most productive period of Roman jurisprudence and exists in English-speaking countries. It was a relation not of dependence but of control^! The constructive work of the academic writers was based chiefly on that part of the Roman legal literature which is preserved in the Digest of Justinian. In this literature they had at their disposal a rich and admirably reasoned body of case-law. The de- centralized administration of justice in the secular courts was producing no case-law comparable with the Roman in range or in quality. For all these reasons, legal literature obtained, and it still in a measure retains, a direct influence upon the decisions of the continental European courts which it did not exercise in the ancient Roman world until the period of legal decadence in the fourth and following 33 centuries, and which it has seldom exercised in the countries of the English law. On the other hand,;attempts to present the law or large parts of the law in systematic treatises have always been made under academic influences. Gains, who wrote his Institutes of Roman law in the second century, and whose arrangement was generally followed, even in English- speaking countries, until the nineteenth century, seems to have been a law professor. The most important systematic works produced in France prior to the nineteenth century were those of Donellus and Pothier, both professors, al- though Pothier was also a judge. The modern German arrangement (Pandektensystem) , which is replacing that of Gains, was developed in university lectures ; and a series of academic writers, from Savigny to Windscheid, have given us one of the most admirable bodies of systematic literature that has ever been produced in the field of private law. In England, the attempt to present the whole law systematically was made but once before the time of Black- stone, namely, by Bracton. Bracton was a judge, but he borrowed the whole framework of his treatise from Azo, an Italian law professor. Blackstone was a university professor, and his commentaries were prepared as lectures. In this country the systematic treatise of Story and of Kent grew out of academic instruction/f I Philosophical theories of law demand our attention only in so far as they have strongly influenced or are strongly influencing the movement of law or of politics.^ If The life of man, the Stoics said, is but a part of the uni- versal order. For the individual and for the state there are eternal and immutable natural laws with which human conduct and human laws should be in harmony. As re- gards himian law, it will be noticed that this theory bears a singular resemblance to the orthodox judicial doctrine, 34 according to which every rule of law laid down in a judicial decision existed before it was discovered and enunciated.^ t The natural-law theory gives to this eternal law, if not an objective basis or a demonstrable source, at least a name. The jurist-judges of the Roman Empire accepted the Stoic theory and used the name ; and when a new rule was needed for the decision of a novel case, they drew from natural law the rule that seemed to them desirable. The mediaeval church accepted the natural-law theory, adding the explanation that the natural order was simply a part of the divine order, so that when divine revelation was lack- ing the divine will was discernible as natural law.2 In the Roman Church as in the Roman Empire the discovery and the interpretation of the natural law were wholly in the hands of authorized experts. Sporadically discernible in the ancient world is a theory that natural law is something more than a reservoir from which supplementary rules may be drawn when needed, that it is a superior law, and that human law that is not in harmony with natural law is of no authority. No Roman lawyer entertained this essentially anarchic theory. It re- ceived no countenance from the mediaeval church as re- garded ecclesiastical law; but it was accepted by the church as regarded secular law. Such law was void not only when it was contrary to the revealed will of God as interpreted by the church, but also when it was contrary to natural law as interpreted by the same authority. When in the six- teenth and following centuries it came to be generally held that neither church nor state had exclusive authority to in- terpret the divine will or the natural law, the theory that natural law was superior to positive law developed all its latent dynamic qualities. / Natural-law theories were em- ployed to legitimize revolution. "Is and ought to be" was the revolutionary formula for the assertion of every pre- viously imrecognized right.J 35 1 The reaction in favor of constituted authority produced both the positivist and the historical theories of law, or at least led to their more precise formulation.? The positivist theory, as formulated by Hobbes, was a direct result of the English revolt against the crown. Hobbes did not deny the existence of natural law, but he asserted that it was not "law proper." The law of nature, he neatly remarked, "is become of all laws the most obscure, and has consequently the greatest need of able interpretation." Only the sover- eign or the judges to whom he delegates authority are com- petent interpreters. This of course is the theory which was implicit in the Roman jurisprudence, but Hobbes was the first to make it q^xplicit. iThe historical theory was formulated in the reaction against the French revolution. The historical school found its antidote to the natm-al-law theory, not in the will of the sovereign, but in the authority of the past. Accord- ing to this theory, presented in the field of public law by Burke, formulated as applicable to all law by Savigny, law is not made, it grows. The judge who declares it, the legislator who seems to make it, are simply interpreters of the national sense of right; and this in its turn is a product of the nation's entire historical existence, m; To a certain extent the historical school also represents, at least in English-speaking countries, a reaction against the positivist school; less indeed against the theories set forth by Hobbes than against those formulated by the so- called "analytical" jurists. Confusing, as did Hobbes himself, the state with the government and finding sover- eignty not in the croAvn, as did Hobbes, but in Parliament, the analytical jurists have always been inclined to regard legislation as the normal source of "law proper." 1 Maine and other English adherents of the historical school have not only rehabilitated judge-made law, but they have re- stored custom to its ancient (and perhaps unduly exalted) dignity and importance. ^ 36 ^Whether it is admissible to speak of a comparative school of jurisprudence, in the sense in which we speak of the natural-law school or of the historical school, may perhaps be disputed.^ It may be urged that comparative juris- prudence has produced no distinct theory of law. I In the writings of Jhering, however, we find an interesting and, I think, typical reaction against the historical theory as formulated by Savigny. Without for an instant denying that law is a historical phenomenon, Jhering insists that it is not wholly nor even mainly a national product. Even national law is in the main a world product. The history of law, like the history of civilization, is a history of bor- rowings and of assimilations. Further, Jhering vehe- mently denies that law grows and asserts that it is and always has been made. It is a product of conscious and in- creasingly determinate human will. In this last assertion Jhering approaches the position of the positivists, but he lays less stress than they on the authority by which the rule is established, emphasizing as essential to the concept of law the possibility of enforcement, t Noting the assertion of a contemporary writer that a certain custom was really law, only it was not enforced, Jhering replies: "We might as well say: This is fire, only it does not bum." 3 I Each of these theories represents a partial truth. Many of the contradictions disappear when we realize that the natural-law theorists and the historical jurists are pri- marily interested in the substance of legal rules, the ana- lytical jurists and the other positivists in the legal quality of the rules. 4 I The historical study of law did not originate in the his- torical school of jurisprudence, nor were the laws of differ- ent peoples first compared when the comparative school formulated its theories. The extent to which law has always rested on precedents has always made it necessary for the lawyer to look back; and he has always been ready, 37 if he could not find a satisfactory precedent in the near past, to look back as far as any existing record or tradition has made retrospect possible. The use of the historical method in legal literature is also very old j and even that type of history which was recently described, in the non- technical lecture on history, as "morphogenetic" is dis- tinctly visible in the Institutes of Gaius, written for the use of first-year law-students more than seventeen hundred years ago. Resuscitated by Cujacius in the sixteenth cen- tury, imbued with a due sense of its own importance by Savigny in the nineteenth century, morphogenetic history has been as assiduously cultivated by lawyers as by any other body of scientific men. I The comparative method is, if anything, older than the historical. The story that, in the fifth century before Christ, when the Romans were thinking of putting their own laws into written form, they sent to Greece for a transcript of the laws of Solon, may not be true; but the fact that the story was believed in Rome in the early Empire is significant. In fact the Roman lawyers were actively engaged, in the last two cen- turies of the Republic, in studying and comparing the laws and customs of all the Mediterranean peoples, in order to establish a uniform commercial law— a problem which they solved with such success that the commerce of the world has ever since been governed, in the main, by the rules which they then formulated. Historical and comparative study of the law is prosecuted to-day on a more extensive scale and by more scientific methods than in any previous period, but these studies are new things only in the spirit in which they are being carried on and in the way in which they are now combined.^ !. Legal history is being studied not only for the elucida- tion of existing law but for its own sake. It has become a part of general history, and one of the most essential parts JSt In political history its importance has long been recognized ; 38 in social history its significance is still imperfectly appre- ciated. tFor many obscure periods of history, the legal material is the fullest that we possess and by far the most trustworthy. The interpretation of the legal material re- quires special training, but the results to be gained are well worth the labor. In course of time the synthetic historian will become aware that the legal material is that which he can least afford to neglect; that without the law of prop- erty and of contract, of family and of inheritance, of crimes and of torts, social history is as invertebrate and flabby as is political history without constitutional law.;t ^ Comparative legal study also is carried on to-day, not only for the practical suggestions which the legislator may derive from the accimiulated and digested experience of other nations, but for its own sake. It has become a branch of the new science of society, and one of the sturdiest and most fruitful branchesjt New also — an invention of our time — is the combination of the historical with the comparative method ; and the re- sults in every field of social science have been surprisingly rich. !^he comparative study of early institutions has been actively prosecuted during the last two generations, phi- lologists and jurists, anthropologists and ethnologists, working side by side ; and it is not too much to say that our conceptions of the beginnings of civilization have been rev- olutionized. Comparative work in the later stages of legal development promises a rich harvest^ These lines of study have carried the jurist far away from the practical tasks of interpreting and developing the law of his own time and his own people; and yet we are beginning to see that some of the results attained are of practical value. A vantage ground is being gained from which the existing law of each nation may be objectively examined and criticized. S,It is becoming more and more possible to see how much of any existing legal system is 39 dead or moribund, how much is vital.Jl It is also becoming possible to see in what respects the law of each nation is in advance of other systems, and in what respects it is suffer- ing from retarded development. These studies, moreover, are preparing us to meet the great problem of the future— that of establishing world order and assuring the conditions of world progress. Even in the most progressive nations there are many xmsolved social problems; but the world problem is forcing itself more and more insistently upon our attention; it will not be evaded or postponed. The problems of world order and world progress can not be solved by international morals alone. In the inter- national community, the law of the diminishing pressure of widening opinion is conspicuously verified ; the influence of world opinion upon the rulers and peoples of the single states is very much weaker than the influence of national opinion; and the triumph of world morals over national morals can be secured only through international law. Rudimentary as this law is, it has already secured impor- tant gains. It has suppressed the slave-trade ; it has forced the opening of all doors to world commerce; it has estab- lished the freedom of the open and the narrow seas ; it has secured to all men the free use of the great navigable rivers of the world. Civilization is being carried into the backward portions of the world through the agency of the single national states, but international law is beginning to define the powers and duties of the states which under- take this mission. I In spite of the highly refined character of many of its rules, international law has as yet hardly reached the stage of development which Em-opean tribal law had reached in a prehistoric period ; but the development is in rapid prog- ress. In international arbitration the world has taken the 40 first steps towards international adjudication, but arbitra- tors have as yet no greater authority than is given them by the voluntary submission of the parties. World legis- lation is still in the contractual stage of development; it comes into existence only by unanimous agreement i^ an international congress is a Polish diet with the liberum veto. International conventions between great groups of states are, however, becoming increasingly numerous and important, and these conventions are reaching more and more into the field of commercial relations ; besides the pub- lic law of nations a conventional private law of the world is in process of construction. tThe social force which is nec- essary to transform international law from a body of usages and agreements, supported only by moral senti- ment, into "law proper" exists in the concert of the powers. This force has been exercised, thus far, only against back- ward or feeble states ; but every case in which it is exercised establishes a precedent. All the essential agencies of legal development exist ; they are becoming increasingly active ; and it can hardly be doubted that the development will be more rapid in the next three generations than in the last three centuries.3 At a similar stage in the development of tribal law the task of interpreting and guiding the social will was every- where in the hands of priests ; it was at a later period that the task was transferred to secular lawfinders. The world of to-day has many religions; it will listen to the secular jurist alone. It has been listening to him, largely accept- ing his rulings and his instructions, since the time of Gro- tius, the first of the world-lawspeakers. In the court of the Hague it is now replacing the natm-ally selected unofficial expert by the artificially selected official expert, the learned judge. In this new laboratory of world-law the bench will require the constant assistance of a learned international bar, and bench and bar will need all the help they can se- 41 cure from international legal literature. For centuries to come, perhaps during the whole future existence of the human race, there will be ample fields for juristic activity within the single nations; but the great task of the juris- prudence of the future will be to interpret the social will of federated humanity and to express in increasingly accu- rate and logical form the universal sentiment of justice. 42 A SERIES of twenty-one lectures descriptive in non-technicdl,|langug;ge of. the achievements in Science, Philosophy ^lid Art, and indicating the present ' status of tjiesesutjects as concepts of human knowledge, were delivejfedat Colum- bia Unilversi^iy, during the academic year igq/r'igoS; by various jprqfe5sprsch6?en to represerit the several departments of instru'ctio^. ' ,' > ' '' MATHEMATICS, by Cassius {jiacfcsbn Keyser, Adrain Professor of Mathe-. PHYSICS, by Ernest Fox Nichols, Professor of Eiepefitniinfal Physics. " ASTROT!iOMy,hy Harold Ja.cohy,Rutherfiird Professor of Astronomy. ' 'GEOLOGY, by James Furman Kemp, Professor of Geology. BIQLOGY, by Edmund B. Wilson, Professor, 6f Zoology., , , PHYSIOLOGY, by Frederic S. Lee, Professor. qfiPhysioloiy. ).'" BOTANy,-by Herbert Maule Richards, Professor of Botany. ZOOLOGY, by Henry E. Crampton, Professor of Zoology. ANTHROPOLOGY, by Franz BoasjPro/eMor of ^Mttro^oZogy. - ARCHAEOLOGY, by James Rignall Wheeler, Professor ofQreek Archaeolagyi -, and Art. ^ ..,'. ,_:■'■ ■" '';. ; ', ./ HISTpRY, by James Harvey Robinson, P»-o/esio»-o/fliitory. ,i ECONOMICS, by Henry Rogers Seager* Professor of PoUUcal Economy.' ^} 70lAi:icS,hyCh3,xle^ A. 'Bea.Td, Adjunct Professor of PoUtics. \ :' JURISPRUDENCE, by Munroe Smith, Professor of Roman Law and Com- parative Jurisprudence. ' SOCIOLOGY, by Franklin Henry Giddiijgs, Professor of Sociology. sr PHILOSOPHY, by Nicholas Murray Butfer, President of the Uiiiver^ity.i PSYCHOLOGY, by Robert S. Woodwprth, A djunct Professor of Psychology. metaphysics; by Frederick J. E. Woodbridge, Johnsonian Prdfesfor of Philosophy. j^ ,-,•; ^ < , / , / ' , , ETHICS,by]obnDey^e^, Professor of PhUosophy..', PHILOLOGY, By A. V. W. Jackson, Professor of ItldoTlranian LatigUageSi literature, by.Harry Thurston Peck, Anthon Professor of the Latin Lan- guage and Literature. - The^e, lectures are published by the GolHmbia University Press separately in pamphlet form, at the uniform price of twenty-^five cents, b^ jnaiil t?retlty:eight' cents. " Orders will be taken for the separate pamphlets, or for the whole series.' Also to be, had in one volume, blue-cloth, at $5.00 net; by mail, $S-27- ' " / Addreu THE COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY PRESS Colombia Uuhrersitr, New York DATE DUE -v^f^^c^ T~ i ^ - GAYLORO PRINTED IN U.S.A