(^atmll IttitterBitg Cibtatg Strata, ISiax Qarb THE GIFT OF The original of tiiis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924092288202 SUBJECT AND OBJECT BY REV. JOHNSTON ESTEP WALTER Author of "The Perception of Space and Matter," "The Principles of Knowledge," and "Nature and Cognition of Space and Time." JOHNSTON AND PENNEY WEST NEWTON PA. 1915 Copyright, 191S, by JOHNSTON ESTEP WALTER J. F. TAPLEY CO. NEW YORK CONTENTS CHAPTER I PAGE The Subject oe Sotjl 1 I. Theories of the Soul — Hume's theory of the mind as the broken succession of our perceptions or thoughts without subject or substance — His doctrine of the knowable relations among the separately existing perceptions composing mind — His explanation of the knowable relations by foisting in a second mind of a peculiar nature — ^The theory self-contra- dictory and baseless, and involves a return to. the theory of substance — The later form of the theory, in which mind is regarded as, not a disconnected, but a connected, succession of thoughts, a stream — Professor James' exposition — It is chargeable with similar inconsistency and errors to those of Hume's — Its grave faults especially as an account of memory and the sense of personal identity — Making a mind of the permanent and extended brain — ^11. The Soul maintained as a permanent and identical reality — ^Relation of soul and body — ^Mind as the producer of the conscious modes — Re- lation of the conscious affections and the producing mind — What do we really know of mind, and how? — Knowledge of the Succession of mind — Of its Permanence — ^Memory as a mode of mediate knowledge — ^Knowledge of the mind superior to knowl- edge of the brain and every other physical object — ^Knowledge of personal identity — Knowledge of the mind our supreme knowledge, as being the most direct and certain and the basis of the knowledge of all else. CHAPTER II Subject and Object in theie Relation 75 Subject and Object discriminated — The two sorts of objects, Subject-Objects and Object-Objects — (1) Relation of subject and subject-object — Subject-objects constitute a distinct internal procession and system — (2) Relation of object- objects to subject and subject-objects — Possible cognition of object-objects — ^The cognition is inferential — Comparison with CONTENTS PAGE the "window" theory of perception — ^Projection of sensations and percepts — ^The immediate materials of both mental science and physical science are the same — Mental science and phys- ical science distinguished — The two worlds, the internal and the external, and their correspondence — Does the knowledge of self require the knowledge of other selves? — Does the knowl- edge of physical objects require the knowledge of other per- sons? — ^The view that "what science finds in Nature is the mind's own latent wealth" — ^Dualistic realism since Locke. CHAPTER III The Nature and otte Perception of Mattee .... . 109 Nature of Matter — Reality and nature of atoms — ^Perception of matter to be treated with special reference to the Berkeleian immaterialism — Relation of Berkeley to Lod£e — ^Berkeley's rea- soning against the knowableness and the reality of external matter — His doctrine of the relation of spatial extension to the so called Secondary Qualities, as color — His doctrine of causation within mind — ^In his teachings respecting subjective extension and subjective causation, Berkeley states and ad- vocates principles which constitute a substantial basis for a true representative knowledge of matter; and which, there- fore, turn about, so to speak, and serve as means of his own refutation — Berkeley's place in the historical development of the science of external perception. CHAPTER IV Truth .... 151 Truth objective and subjective; or truth as fact or reality, and as correspondence of thought to reality — ^In this essay truth is taken as entirely subjective — ^The correspondence of thought to its object or to reality — Four sorts of truth or correspondence of thought: (1) Correspondence to the sub- stantial mind; (2) to other thought; (3) to past events; (4) to external objects — ^Truth and knowledge compared — Antago- nism of idealists to truth defined as correspondence of thought to objects external to mind — The same as Berkeley's main opposition to the doctrine of the representative cognition of external matter — ^Possibility of correspondence, and known correspondence, of thought to external things — ^Truth a mat- ter of progression — 1. How far do we make truth? — ^The "cognitive making" of reality — ^Reality as determined by our wishes — The making of truth by our thinking and wishing — CONTENTS PAGE The intellect as conditioned in the making of truth by the original and indispensable materials and forms given to it — Nature of the sense-materials supplied to the intellect — De- pendence of intellect also upon the action of external objects. — 2. Stability of truth — It results from the constancy of the in- ternal and the external conditions of knowledge — 3. Utility as the criterion of truth — ^The real as the useful — All things use- ful to us because of the systematic unity and imiformity of nature — Neither reality nor truth, though inseparable from utility, is identical with it; they are more, they have a primacy — The conception of God considered as beneficial and as a "working hypothesis" — ^The truth of our knowledge of God. SUBJECT AND OBJECT CHAPTER I THE SUBJECT OR SOUL, "To write a chapter for the purpose of showing that nothing is known, or can he known, of the suh- ject which the title of the chapter indicates, will he thought strange." These are the words with which Mr, H. Spencer opens the chapter in his Psychology on the "Suhstance of Mind."^ The present discus- sion has its occasion in the conviction that the human mind is a permanent entity or substance, which can be and is known; and the primary purpose of the dis- cussion is to expound and defend that conception. This statement is made for the convenience of the reader, that at the very beginning he may know clearly and certainly the point of view and aim of the essay; and it is hoped he will not be repelled by the frank avowal. But this purpose, it must be admitted, goes against what seems to be the main psychological tendency of the time. It is the contention of many that "the ex- planation of psychic life demands the complete elimi- nation of the concept of substance"; and that the con- cept prevails only among "unreflective minds." Some of the most zealous opponents deride mental substance as an "accursed idol." 1 Psychology, I, p. 145. 2 SUBJECT AND OBJECT It might be supposed that, of all realities, the Mind, Soul, Self, Ego, should be the most directly and cer- tainly known ; and that there should be complete agree- ment among men in all their main tenets and decisions regarding its nature and functions. Eespectiug agree- ment in doctrine, the truth is just the contrary. Hardly a wider variety and opposition of theories are found on any other subject than on what for us, as some would say, is the immediate centre and focus of all reality and knowledge — the Self. The theory of mind now most prevalent apparently among professional psychologists is, that mind is the stream, flux, process, of our thoughts, feelings or con- scious states. The process-mind is conceived to be purely successive, purely temporal. It is the flow of the rapidly rising and perishing thoughts. It has no relation to a real or knowable permanent spiritual sub- ject or substratum, or to one entitled to consideration in psychology. Hume is the most distinguished repre- sentative of this hypothesis of mind. He is the chief protagonist for modem times of psychology without a soul. Another theory defines mind as the permanent pos- sibihty of feeling — of sensation, idea, volition — or as consisting of the present feeling and the permanent possibility of other feelings. Its most distinguished advocate is J. S. Mill, who has expounded it especially in the chapter on the "Psychological Theory of Mind," in his Examination of Sir W. Hamilton's Philosophy. An important question regarding the theory is as to what we are to understand by a "permanent possibil- ity," or as to what a "permanent possibility" is when yet in its unrealized state or before actualization, or after feeling ceases. Mr. Mill does not furnish a clear THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 3 answer to this question. He tells us what the per- manent possibility is not, rather than what it is."^ It appears to be an abstract, non-substantial capability or potentiality suspended in the void, having no rest for the soles of its feet. If this be its character, then we must admit the conception is one of the most cun- ningly devised and elusive ever fabricated by the hu- man intellect. It is scepticism respecting mental sub- stance developed to the limit. We remark further now only on this specific point, namely, that, whatever mind may be as a possibility of feelings, it is, according to this theory, not a pure succession or stream; for per- manence is postulated of the ultimate possibility; and identity, time, and memory are thus apparently con- ceived as supported by permanence, and not only by a pure flow of momentary and perishing experiences.^ - He says of the permanent possibility of sensation [Matter] : "But though the sensations cease, the possibilities remain in existence; they are independent of our will, our presence, and everything which belongs to us." {Exam,. Hamilton, I. p. 241.) The permanent possibilities are not supposed to be, or to be in, a universal mind that embraces or governs the particular finite minds and is the immediate author of all their conscious experiences. 2 Mr. Mill makes some statements respecting memory and the uncon- scious which are worthy of note. In speaking of "stored-up knowl- edge," he denies that it is an unconscious state or action of mind. "It is not a mental state, but a capability of being put into a mental state. When I am not thinking of a thing it is not present to mind at all." (Exam. Hamilton, II. p. 7.) He says again of latent mem- ory: "It is not the mental impressions that are latent, but the power of reproducing them. Every one admits, without any apparatus of proof, that we have powers and susceptibilities of which we are not conscious; but these are the capabilities of being affected, not actual affections" (p. 9). He remarks also: "I am myself inclined to agree with Sir W. Hamilton, and to admit his unconscious mental modifications, in the only shape in which I can attach any very distinct meaning to them, namely unconscious modifications of the nerves" (p. 22). Mill here seems to favor the theory that the capabilities or possibilities of memories, and probably of all other mental states, are wholly in the permanent nervous matter. But it will be remembered that matter itself he defines as the permanent possibility of sensation; by which definition, 4 SUBJECT AND OBJECT A third hypothesis declares that mind and body con- stitute one reality, a psycho-physical organism; and that a mental change and a bodily or nervous change are phases of the same event. There is no interaction between mind and body, because they are one ; but there is an established parallelism between conscious states and nervous motions. The theory of psycho-physical unity and parallelism often ends in giving great su- premacy to the physical side of the organism, or in making it the "whole thing." The mental modes are treated as if products or creations of the physical mo- tions. The latter have not a reciprocal like depend- ence upon the former. An older and long popular theory holds that mind or soul is a substance distinct from the body, and that the human constitution is a duality of mental and ma- terial substances. Mind, in its essence a permanent and identical entity, is the producer of the procession of the various conscious phenomena. It is supposed to be the permanent support or subject of the proces- sion, just as a material body is generally regarded as the permanent subject of its own successive and tran- sient motions. Though mind is substantially distinct from body, it is united with body in a close relation of interdependence and interaction. With this theory is commonly combined the belief that the soul survives in its integrity, with its memories and identity, the disso- lution of the body. It is our purpose now to return to the theory of the process-mind, the mind of the pure temporal series of feelings without substrate, that is, the mind of Hume and his followers, and to subject it to a more full and with these other statements, we are at length involved in an almost bewildering maze. THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 5 particular examination. There is no force in present- day psychology more potent than that of Hume; and some careful consideration of the mala principles of his hypothesis of mind will therefore be especially ap- propriate. It will also serve as a convenient prepara- tion for our own independent treatment of mind which is to follow. According to Hume's formal definition, mind is a pure abstract collection or succession of perceptions. He says : "What we call a mind is nothing but a heap or collection of different perceptions."^ Again: "They are the successive perceptions only that con- stitute the mind" (I 313). Perceptions is Hume's gen- eral term for "impressions and ideas"; and these are the two great classes into which all the phenomena or contents of the mind are divided. He observes : "All the perceptions of the human mind resolve themselves into two distinct kinds, which I shall call impressions and ideas" (15). These two kinds of "perceptions" correspond to what are often called in the later psychology presentations and representations. They differ only in "force and liveliness." Impressions are vivid perceptions; ideas are faint perceptions. All ideas are effects and copies of precedent impressions. Hume notes three main characteristics of the suc- cession of perceptions which alone constitute mind. The first of these is, that the perceptions rapidly pass and vanish. He says: "All impressions are internal and perishing" (245) ; perceptions have no "continued existence" (265); they "succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity" (312). The two other char- acteristics Hume repeatedly distinguishes and empha- ^ Philosophical Works, 4 vols., Boston, 1854. (Edinburgh 1825.) I. p. 260. 6 SUBJECT AND OBJECT sizes as of the greatest importance. The one is, that the successive and transient perceptions forming mind "exist separately," are perfectly isolated from one another. The other is, that certain relations are cog- nizable among the isolated perceptions; namely, the relation of resemblance, relation in space and time, and the relation of cause and effect. The isolation of the successive perceptions composing the mind is aflfirmed by Hume in the most express and decided terms. He says: "All our perceptions are different from each other and from everything else in the universe, they are also distinct and separable, and may be considered as separately existent" (290). "Our perceptions are all really different, and separable, and distinguishable from each other, and from every- thing else which we can imagine; and therefore it is impossible to conceive how they can be the action or abstract mode of any substance" (304). "Every dis- tinct perception which enters into the composition of the mind, is a distinct existence, and is different, and distinguishable, and separable from every other per- ception, either contemporary or successive" (320). "There is no known [real] connection among objects [perceptions] " (278). "All events seem entirely loose and separate. One event follows another, but we never can observe any tie between them. They seem con- joined but never connected" (IV 84). Mind, according to these and other like declarations frequently made by Hume, is a collection or succession of perceptions di- vided from one another by absolutely void intervals. It is like a flock of birds on the wing, or a stream of leaves in the wind, the individuals of which are sepa- rated by empty spaces. In his repeated and vehement assertions that there THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 7 is no real tie, bond, or connection among the percep- tions composing mind, Hume generally has in view, and wishes to oppose, Locke's doctrine of mental sub- stance. Locke held to the existence of mental sub- stance, the "subject" or "substratum" in which it is supposed ideas "inhere," "subsist," are "united," to which they "belong," by which they are "supported." But he yet held also that though the mental substance exists, it is unknown. He affirms : "The substance of spirits is unknown to us ; and so is the substance of body equally unknown to us." ^ "All our ideas of the sev- eral sorts of substances are nothing but collections of simple ideas, with a supposition of something to which they belong, and in which they subsist ; though of this supposed something we have no clear distinct idea at all. ' ' ^ Hume takes a very important step beyond Locke and antagonizes him, in asserting that mental substance is not only unknown, but does not exist ; that the mind is a collection of ideas without any supporting subject or substratum whatever, but self-sustained. He says explicitly: Perceptions are distinct and separable "and have no need of anything else to sup- port their existence" (I 290). "We have no idea of a substance. . . . Nothing appears requisite to support the existence of a perception. We have therefore no idea of inhesion" (291). "The understanding never observes any real connection among objects [percep- tions] " (330). "Objects exist distinct and independ- ent, without any common simple substance or subject of inhesion" (II 549). It may be remarked that Hume thus exceeds Berkeley, the nearer successor of Locke, by a very distinct advance. Berkeley rejected ma- 1 Essay, II. xxiii. 30. 2 76., 37. 8 SUBJECT AND OBJECT terial, but admitted mental, substance. Hume emphat- ically rejects both. But, as above remarked, one of the most frequently and forcibly asserted principles of Hume's psychology is the doctrine that among the collected perceptions composing mind — ^which are separated from one an- other and are never connected by a real bond or tie, by a medium or substance — certain significant relations are cognized ; namely, the relations of resemblance, con- tiguity in space and in time, and cause and ejffect. He says of these perceivable relations: "To me there appear to be only three principles of connection among ideas, namely. Resemblance, Contiguity in time or place, and Cause or Efect" (IV 23) . " The three con- necting principles of aU ideas, are the relations of re- semblance, contiguity, and causation" (29). "We have already observed that nature has established con- nections among particular ideas, and that no sooner one idea occurs to our thoughts than it introduces its correlative, and carries our attention toward it, by a gentle and insensible movement. These principles of connection or association we have reduced to three, namely. Resemblance, Contiguity, and Causation; which are the only bonds that unite our thoughts to- gether" (58). Hume expressly observes that these re- lations are not real connections among perceptions, and are not based upon or made possible by real connec- tions; but are only relations which the separate per- ceptions have in our "thought," "fancy," "imagina- tion." "When we say that one object is connected with another, we mean only that they have acquired a connection in our thought" (86). "The only qualities that can give ideas a union in the imagination are these three relations above mentioned. These are the uniting THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 9 principles in the ideal world" (I 321). "We only feel a connection or determination of the thought to pass from one object to another" (II 551). "Events . . . seem conjoined, but never connected"; that is, they are conjoined in thought but have no "tie" in reality, no "real bond " or " real connection. ' ' Particularly, per- ceptions are not connected by the being of a unitary owner, subject or substratum. By a moment's consideration of this doctrine of cog- nizable relations, it becomes quite obvious that Hume is here introducing a principle that is entirely incon- sistent with the character of mind described as a collec- tion of separately existing, and never really connected, perceptions. To a mind so defined the cognition of such relations would evidently be impossible. The separation of the elements of mind carries with it the impracticability of perceiving the relations. What is it that will perceive the relations? Where is there any provision for any combining cognition of the collected perceptions "which constitute a thinking mind"? Hume posits no arch-perception, analogous to the "arch-monad" of Leibnitz, which might supervise the other perceptions and discern their relations. There is no thinking factor in mind other than each of the separately existing perceptions. These are the whole of mind. What imaginable means, then, can there be for any knowledge of the relations of the associated but isolated perceptions? If each perception may know itself, yet its severance from all others clearly makes impossible to it any knowledge of its relations to them. It cannot be supposed to leap the gulfs between itself and the others, and thus ascertain its resemblance to them, and measure the distance of its position from theirs in space and in time. That would require at 10 SUB,TECT AND OBJECT least that each separate perception should be a soul, a person, capable of visiting his fellows, of coming into immediate real connection with them and embracing them. The two great principles of Hume's psychology (1) that the mind is a collection of separately existing per- ceptions, and (2) that there are important relations cognized among the perceptions — the relations of re- semblance, coexistence and separation in space, and succession — certainly seem to be, and certainly are, in- compatible with one another, even mutually contradic- tory. In the defined and avowed mind there is no acknowledged knowing factor beside the severed per- ceptions; there is not the slightest place or provision with them or among them for any sort of knower; and their separation absolutely forbids the cognizability of the relations. A cognized relation between the con- stituent perceptions would be possible only on the con- dition of a real connection. The positive denial of a real connection necessitates the denial of a perceivable relation. Yet, as Hume constantly and confidently affirms the actual cognition of these relations, it be- comes interesting and important to consider how he construes in his own mind the feasibility of the cog- nition. This he does by blandly supposing and employing, over and above the avowed mind of the separately existing perceptions, what is in reality a second mind possessing a peculiar and remarkable character. This second mind is variously denominated "mind," "thought," "imagination," "we," "I"; and is repre- sented as, like an outside observer, surveying the suc- cession and mass of our perceptions, as moving among them, as combining and commanding them. It is THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 11 noticeable that Hume makes this assumption with the utmost ease and serenity, without the slightest concern, as if it were a postulate which no one should ever think of questioning or condemning as inconsistent with any- other of his tenets. In the following passages this surprising conception of an extra mind is made clear and unmistakable. Speaking of ' ' the mind, ' ' Hume says : * ' The qualities ... by which the mind is conveyed from one idea to another are these three, viz., resemblance," etc. (I 26). "The thinking of any object readily transports the mind to what is contiguous" (133). "The relation facilitates the transition of the mind from one object [perception] to another, and renders its passage as smooth as if it contemplated one continued object" (314). "The mind has the command over all its ideas, and can separate, unite, mix, and vary them, as it pleases" (II 544). Similar and the same functions are attributed to "thought" and "imagination": "Our notions of personal identity proceed entirely from the smooth and uninterrupted progress of the thought along a train of connected ideas" (I 321). "A deter- mination of the thought to pass from one object to another" (II 551). "When one idea is present to the imagination, any other united by these relations nat- urally follows it, and enters with more facility by means of that introduction" (13). "The imagination has the command over all its ideas" (IV 57). "Our imagination runs easily from one idea to any other that resembles it"; and runs "along the parts of space and time in conceiving its objects" (I 26). Ideas have a "union in the imagination" (321). Likewise, in very- many instances, "we" and "I" are represented as observing, uniting, controlling, remembering, the sep- 12 SUBJECT AND OBJECT arately existing ideas, objects, perceptions. Thus under these different names, and with these various representations, Hume very clearly introduces an extra mind which has no recognition or place whatever in the avowed mind of the collection, bundle, train, suc- cession, of perceptions. But, in view of the fact that Hume defines mind to the last as a collection of loose, unconnected, isolated perceptions, this quiet foisting in of a second mind as the observer, possessor, combiner and master of the perceptions is undeniably one of the most obtuse or, if not that, then one of the most un- scrupulous and flagitious surreptions and self-contra- dictions in the annals of mental philosophy, and on account of it he deserves to be. everlastingly chas- tised. Hume's interpolation of an extra mind is essentially a bringing back of the spiritual subject of Locke and the substantialists which he had decidedly rejected. Locke had taught, as before remarked, that "our spe- cific ideas of substances are nothing else but a collec- tion of a certain number of simple ideas, considered as united in one thing. "^ He variously speaks of this "one thing" or substance as something to which ideas belong, in which they inhere, subsist, are united, by which they are supported. But Hume would maintain against Locke that the only mind and all of mind is the collection of ideas; and that they do not have and do not need anything to support them; that they subsist without any real or substantial connection, upholding themselves in perfect reciprocal isolation in the void; that we cannot form any idea of what a substance or inhesion is. The introduction of a second mind, how- ever, undoes all this; it constitutes a glaring self-con- I Essay, II. xxiii. 14. THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 13 tradiction; it is a complete recantation; it is a clear re- call of the repudiated and excluded substance. In these many instances in which Hume declares of the second mind that it possesses, combines, commands, ideas and perceptions, it is evidently made essentially identical with Locke 's uniting, owning, supporting sub- ject. Locke's connecting of ideas in one thing Hume emphatically rejected ; but here he freely accepts what amounts to the same connecting. Locke's doctrine of the inhesion or subsistence of ideas in a common sub- ject he held to be unintelligible; but here he treats a nearly or quite identical inherence or subsistence as if it were perfectly intelligible. There is obvious in this procedure the singular turn in Hume's speculation, that the extra mind which he tacitly foists in comes to hold the chief place and to be the supreme mind; and that the separately existing perceptions, which by them- selves, with nothing else whatever, compose the ex- pressly avowed and defined mind, are made objects which it observes, unites, controls. Further, the inter- polated mind is made to give all plausibility to the often asserted cognition of the relations, among the isolated perceptions, of resemblance, space and time. This interjection of a second mind by Hume must be denounced as an inconsistency and self-contradiction of the most flagrant sort. But it had more causes than Hume's love of paradox and dilemma, or delight in acting the sceptic. It is in part a demonstration of Tiow an important fact, which has been arbitrarily excluded from the theory of mind and ignored and denied, will at times force itself forward into recognition, compel respect, and accuse and retaliate its unjust exclusion. There was more in Hume's experience of mind than was embraced in his theory; and his full experience there- 14 SUBJECT AND OBJECT fore spontaneously and necessarily came into conflict with Ms theory. As iUustrating and tending to confirm some of the main points that have just been dwelt on, we shall yet produce a familiar declaration of Hume, which has often been quoted as being a particularly clear and com- pact statement of what is most distinctive in his psy- chology. Its maiQ doctrine has been by many regarded as embodying very important truth, and dominates much of the psychology of our time. "For my part," says Hume, "when I enter most intimately into what I call myself, I always stumble on some particular per- ception or other, of heat or cold, light or shade, love or hate, pain or pleasure. I never can catch myself at any time without a perception, and never can observe anything but the perception. ' ' He soon adds, that men "are nothing but a bundle or collection of different per- ceptions, which succeed each other with an inconceiv- able rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and move- ment" (I 312). In here saying that he never can observe anything but the perceptions, or flux of differ- ent isolated perceptions, he means especially that he cannot observe, in addition to the perceptions, any con- necting substance among them, any single, permanent, identical, subject or support for them. This passage then is a very plain and direct affirma- tion of psychology without a soul, in opposition to the substantialists. It is also a further clear exhibition of the profound self-contradiction within Hume's hypoth- esis of the nature and cognition of mind. No one will wish to question in the least the truth of Hume's as- severation, that when entering into the most intimate examination of himself he always stumbled upon some particular perception or perceptions ; for it is undeni- THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 15 able that, universally, mind is known or knows itself only in its conscious modes; but Hume is cbargeable with a gross self-contradiction in asserting tbat he observed nothing more than the perceptions. He ob- served something more in the very act of denying it. The something more is in this "I," this "self," this permanent, identical, unitary, remembering being, which, as he says, always "stumbles," etc., never "ob- serves," etc.; and must therefore be something more than the inconceivably rapid flow of the perishing iso- lated perceptions ; must be something which stores up memories of perceptions that it experienced in the past, holding thus in the unity of knowledge both the present and the past, and certainly being capable of doing this only because it did not perish with the past perceptions but survives in its sameness to the present. Hume's theory of mind as a flux of unconnected perceptions in- volves the indubitable corollary that if, in his closest self -inspection, he never observed aught but the isolated perceptions, then he never observed even the percep- tions. He must catch more than the perceptions, or there is no possibility of catching even them, or catch- ing any one of them in any relation to others. We have been dwelling upon the two fundamental, but inconsistent and contradictory, principles of Hume 's psychology : first, that the mind is a succession of severed perceptions, without a single subject or any- thing to connect and support them ; and, secondly, that the relations of resemblance, space, time, and causa- tion, are constantly perceived among the severed per- ceptions. We have considered also his flagrant sur- reption of an extra mind which is supposed to survey the isolated perceptions, to observe the relations among them, to possess, unite and command them. It will re- 16 SUBJECT AND OBJECT ward us if we now turn back to consider further and attentively what Hume's original mind, defined as a succession of separately existing perceptions, is in and by itself, or what it is capable and incapable of knowing by itself, expelling entirely from the view the inter- jected second mind. We should note especially what the successive mind can know of time, personal identity and causation, or of the alleged primary relations of its swiftly passing constituent terms. First, it is obvious that the successive mind cannot know succession, cannot know its own succession. A succession of separately existing perceptions evidently does not implicate in itself alone the knowledge of suc- cession. The succession's knowledge of its own suc- cession is impossible, because, owing to the mutual iso- lation of the perceptions by void intervals, not one of them can know itself as the predecessor or successor of another. A perception cannot know its position in the succession, and therefore cannot even be cognizant that it belongs to a succession or that there is a succession. This manifest impossibility of the abstract mental suc- cession's being aware of itself as a succession and of any succession at all, should have convinced Hume, and forced him to the open and honest acknowledgment, that the mind must be something more than a train of isolated terms ; that the idea of succession imperatively requires a more adequate reason, a far more competent cause and support. Secondly, the impossibility of the abstract successive mind's knowing its own succession, makes certain the impossibility of its possessing memory and the sense of permanent identity. As a perception, because of its isolation, can have no knowledge of any predecessor. THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 17 it can have no remembrance of any. It can not retain a knowledge of what it never did and never could know. And where there is no memory it is also evident there cannot be the thought of permanence and identity. The present passing perception could not know any- thing beyond its own momentary existence, if it could know that; and it could not have any thought of per- manence, because there is no real permanence from which the thought could rise and upon which it could rest. Induced probably by the manifest incompatibility between the ordinary idea of identity and his concep- tion of the pure succession-mind, Hume attempts to force the idea of identity into conformity with this con- ception. He would have us believe that the idea of identity is a fiction, or a mistake for what is really but the idea of diversity and of succession. The occasion of the mistake is the ease and rapidity of the transition of our thought along the train of our ideas. The dif- ferent ideas are taken, in the facile and quick survey, for one and the same; and their succession for per- manence. The essence of Hume's doctrine is couched in the following extracts: "The relation [of succes- sion] facilitates the transition of the mind from one object [idea] to another, and renders its passage as smooth as if it contemplated one continued object" (I 314). "Our notions of personal identity proceed en- tirely from the smooth and uninterrupted progress of the thought along a train of connected ideas" (321). Identity is a fictitious notion which we entertain by mis- take for what is really the idea of a succession of dif- ferent objects or perceptions. The easy passage of the thought along the successive perceptions we erro- 18 SUBJECT AND OBJECT neously imagine is the contemplation of the same object. We substitute invariability for diversity, identity for succession. A conspicuous fault of Hume's account of personal identity is the gross surreption of a second mind, which we have already considered. He says there is a "tran- sition of the mind from one object to another," a "prog- ress of thought along a train of connected ideas." But the separately existing ideas or perceptions that are said to compose mind admit of no such transition or progress. The perceptions are "islands without bridges and without boats, ' ' and intercommunication is impossible. There cannot be a mind or thought pass- ing from one perception to another, and perceiving and remembering any relation between them; for there is no mind or thought distinct from the separate percep- tions themselves to compass them and think of them as in any conjunction. We need not dwell on Hume's sinister introduction and use of a second mind. He virtually assumes the existence of a real permanent and identical mind in the very sentences in which he de- nies it. Instead of striving to force the idea of personal iden- tity into consistency with his successive serial mind, Hume should have franMy fashioned mind into con- sistency with the idea. The clear, persistent and uni- versal idea of permanent identity, which is certainly not the idea of succession, but of sameness lasting through succession, should have proved to him that there must be something more of mind than a temporal series of severed perceptions; that within mind there must be, in addition, a permanent element as the neces- sary occasion and foundation of the idea of permanence and even as indispensable to the idea of succession. THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 19 Hume's adored idol of the successive mind imperiously excluded from his thought all facts of experience, how- ever strong and certain, that would not do obeisance to it. Thirdly, the abstract succession-mind of Hume could never be cognizant of causation, power, or succession with power. Since not any of the separate perceptions composing mind could know itself as preceding, or as simultaneous with, another perception, it necessarily could not know itself as exerting power on or affecting another perception. Inability to know perceptions as successive or simultaneous, involves the inability to know them as cause and effect. But Hume attempts to make the idea of causation consistent with his theory of the succession-mind, by falsifying it as he falsified the idea of identity. He argues with much elaboration that the idea of causation is really only the idea of a mode of succession, as the idea of identity is but a mode of the idea of succession. Causation is but a customary succession of ideas. He asserts: "We have no other notion of cause and effect, but that of certain objects which have been always conjoined together, and which in all past instances have been found inseparable" (I 124) ; and, ' ' The union of cause and effect, when strictly examined, resolves itself into a customary association of ideas" (321). The result of his teaching is that causation is only constant or customary succession without involving any power whatever. The idea of power is a fiction or phantom; the word is "absolutely without any meaning." Hume contends that the idea of power is not true of real, because there is no impression, or direct, vivid, original experience, of power from which it should be derived. Here is one of his most arbitrary denials of 20 SUBJECT AND OBJECT fact. We have in trutli original and certain conscious- ness of power, in the voluntary command of the mind over its activities, or when one act of mind determines another. This experience is clear and sure, and per- fectly distinct from that of pure succession. Succes- sion of experiences without power, and succession with power, must be regarded as an original and primordial difference. They are both first facts of experience and reality, and neither can be rightly reduced to the other. It was then wholly perverse in Hume to attempt to represent causation as pure succession, and thus to make it consistent with his conception of the character of mind. He should exactly have reversed his action here, as he should have done in the case of identity, and made the character of mind consistent with the genuine experience. Just as the real experience of identity should have led him to perceive and acknowledge that there is more in mind than succession, namely, a per- manent and identical element as the necessary ground of the cognized succession and conviction of identity; so the real experience of causation should have per- suaded him that there is a real connection of power or determination within the mental succession, that is, be- tween mental cause and mental effect, as the indis- pensable source and foundation of the conscious ex- perience — a quality or factor upon which the experience is grounded and to which it corresponds. The final animadversion is justifiable, that hardly anything can be more wanton and false than Hume's juvenile con- jectures as to the nature and conditions of the ideas of mental identity and mental power or causation. We have dwelt at some length and with some minute- ness, possibly with excess, upon the nature of mind as understood by Hume and upon the extent of its capa- THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 21 bility especially as to knowledge, and shall bring our survey to a close. Enough has been seen to prove that his theory of mind is, in its main or most distinctive propositions, a scheme of misrepresentation and in- ternal discord and falsity. Hereafter we shall see some- thing of the baneful influence it has exercised upon the later psychology. Hume has had and continues to have many to follow him in advocating psychology without a soul, or the doc- trine that mind is a pure succession of perceptions, ideas, thoughts, and in positively denying the cogniza- bility and reality of a permanent mental subject or substratum, or in denying at least that such a subject has any scientific value in psychology. But there is an important difference between Hume's conception of mind and that of most of his present-day followers. These maintain that the successive serial mind is, not as Hume taught, a succession of separately existing per- ceptions, of perceptions with empty intervals or abso- lute breaches among them, but a continuous, unbroken, succession, a flow or stream. With this meaning they speak of the "process" of the mental affections or phe- nomena, "the stream of thought," the "stream of con- sciousness," etc. The conception of continuity or un- broken flow they suppose is a truer knowledge of mind than the conception of the broken, and not liable to the grave accusations that may be made against the latter. This supposed superiority of continuity of the mental succession over discontinuity deserves the most careful consideration, a much more careful consideration than has been generally given to it ; especially respecting its accord with, and competency to account for, the near, persistent and confident knowledge and conviction we 22 SUBJECT AND OBJECT have of succession, time, personal identity, and mental power or causation. The connecting points of the closely successive terms of the abstract mental stream are too often made the habitat of surreption and fallacy. In our treatment of the later form of the theory of the successive mind, we propose to give somewhat special and exclusive attention to Professor W. James' discussion of it in his Psychology, because his discus- sion is one of the latest and most complete and capable. This course will probably serve the interests of brevity and be found otherwise advantageous. Let us first consider attentively Professor James' description of the nature of mind, and his conception of the matter and scope of scientific psychology. He defines mind as the stream of thought or thoughts. He represents it as a stream of a unique kind in the decla- ration, that it is a " succession of perishing thoughts. ' ' The stream consists at any moment of only the one thin "section," namely, the present thought. The upper part of the stream, all its past, has perished ; the lower part, the future, has not yet come. Further, the stream of thoughts is conceived of as existing by itself, as ab- stract or detached, or as having no relation to or support in a real, or necessary, or at any rate known, soul or mental substance. Moreover, as the only part of the stream that exists at any one moment is the present thought, then the only mind and the whole of mind ever immediately known, the only "verifiable thinker," is the present passing thought.^ If there is 1 "The passing Thought itself is the only verifiaMe thinker." ( Psy- chology, I. p. 346. ) The I "is a Thought, at each moment different from that of the last moment, but appropriative of the latter, together with all that the latter called its own" (p. 401). "// the passing thought he the directly verifiaile existent which no . school has hitherto doubted it to be, then that thought is itself the thinker, and psychology need not look beyond" (p. 401). THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 23 anything else in or known of mind, it can be known only mediately, by memory or by inference.^ Snob is Professor James' conception of mind. Mind is the ab- stract continuous succession or stream of the perishing thoughts. But all of the stream that exists at any moment, and can be immediately known, is the present thought. All we ever certainly know of mind in any way, is the present thought and the ideal stream to which it belongs. We pass on to Professor James ' notion of the content and scope of scientific psychology. First, he resolutely excludes the soul from the proper matter of psychology. He does not positively deny the existence of the soul ; he will allow us to believe in it if we care to do so ; but he is emphatic in declaring its inaccessibility to direct knowledge and its "superfluity for scientific purposes" (p. 350). The only thing of a mental nature that rightly comes into the science of psychology is the ab- stract stream of thoughts. If our psychology should embrace the soul, then it would embrace something that is not immediately known, and is of doubtful existence ; it would become metaphysical, and lose the character of strict and pure scientific psychology. But in addition to the only proper mental matter. Professor James introduces into psychology some very significant things that are not mental. Of this addi- tional content are the physical motions, the nervous molecular processes, that accompany and parallel the mental processes. The correlation of states of con- sciousness and states of brain requires that states of 1 "The bare Phenomenon, however, the Immediately Known thing which on the mental side is in apposition with the entire broA/n-process, is the state of consciousness and not the soul itself. Many of the atanch- est believers in the soul admit that we know it only as an inference from experiencing its states" (p. 182). 24 SUBJECT AND OBJECT brain shall have place and consideration in psychology as well as states of consciousness. Our author asks: "Whether, after all, the ascertainment of a blank un- mediated correspondence, term for term, of the succes- sion of states of consciousness with the succession of total brain-processes, be not the simplest psycho-physic formula, and the last word of a psychology which con- tents itself with verifiable laws, and seeks only to be clear, and to avoid unsafe hypotheses" (p. 182). He says also : ' ' Psychology when she has ascertained the empirical correlation of the various sorts of thought or feeling with definite conditions of the brain, can go no farther, — can go no farther, that is, as a natural science. If she goes farther she becomes metaphysical. ... I have therefore treated our passing thoughts as integers, and regarded the mere laws of their coexistence with brain-states as the ultimate laws for our science" (pp. vi, vii). It is worthy of express remark that Professor James does not treat the brain-processes as if they were abstracted from the brain itself, but as belonging to the brain and as inseparable from it. The brain is always regarded as the owner and immediate bearer of the processes, and as abiding through their transiency. It is therefore perfectly obvious that he introduces into psychology the permanent and extended brain with its molecular processes or motions. According to this view, then, the succession of thoughts, and the brain- processes occurring with and corresponding to them, together with the permanent and extended brain which is inseparable from the processes, constitute the whole of the materials of scientific psychology. One or two observations pertinent to this conception of the science of psychology should here be made. Professor James' apparent implication, that the brain- THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 25 motions are as directly and certainly known as the states of consciousness, and that, for this reason at least, they are as fully entitled to a place in psychology as the related states of consciousness, should be re- garded as one of the gravest epistemological errors ever countenanced by psychologists. Another error of like significant character is the apparent tacit assumption that the permanent and extended brain is known more directly and certainly than the permanent mental sub- stance or soul, and therefore should be included in psy- chology, while the soul should be shut out. We are not wishing to be understood as advocating the exclusion of the brain and its processes from the science of psy- chology; but only as decidedly opposing the inclusion of these processes upon the supposition that they are as immediately and certainly known as the mental affec- tions, and opposing also the exclusion of the soul upon the supposition that it is not as immediately and cer- tainly known as is the brain. We shall hope to show hereafter that our contention is not without justifica- tion. It may be noted further, respecting the contamina- tion of psychology with metaphysics, that Professor James seems to be involved in a serious self-contradic- tion. He annuls his own proposition against mixing metaphysics with psychology; for, though he excludes from psychology mental substance and its metaphysics, yet in bringing in a material mass, the permanent and extended brain, he gives the readiest and warmest wel- come to the metaphysics of matter. Now we come to the most important question that can be asked respecting Professor James' theory of the nature of mind. The question is crucial, and it is this : What account does the theory give of Memory and the 26 SUBJECT AND OBJECT conviction of Personal Identity, and what is the worth of the account? The best testing demand upon the theory of the soulless stream of perishing thoughts is for it to show how the experiences of memory and identity are consistent with or possible to the hypo- thetical mind. The theory seems to break down utterly under this demand. First, of Memory. Professor James very confidently claims memory, both retention and reproduction, for the abstract stream of perishing thoughts. He ex- plains the possibility and reality of memory by the postulate, that each thought transmits to its successor the record of its own individual experience and its recollections, or that each successor "appropriates," "adopts," its predecessor and all its contents. The sinking thought hands on to its rising successor its ex- perience and mnemonic stores; the rising thought re- ceives them. "Each pulse," it is affirmed, "of cogni- tive consciousness, each Thought, dies away and is re- placed by another. The other among the things it knows, knows its own predecessor. . . . Each Thought is thus born an owner, and dies owned, transmitting whatever it realized as its Self to its own later pro- prietor" (p. 339). It is said also, that the nascent thought immediately takes up the expiring thought and adopts it with all it contains ; and, again, that no other agent need be supposed than "a succession of perishing thoughts endowed with the functions of appropriation and rejection" (p. 342). It should be observed, by the way, that Professor James does not make quite clear what he conceives to be the ontologic relation between two immediately connected thoughts in the succession. Does a thought perish or die away by melting itself into, or becoming, its own successor, and thus carry along THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 27 all it possesses including its memories ? Is the relation in a peculiar way causal? In what respect are the suc- cessive thoughts distinct or different from one another? These questions are not clearly answered. It should he explicitly remarked of this hypothesis of a thought's transmitting its mnemonic stock to its suc- cessor, that memory is thus conceived as if it were en- tirely mental, as if the successive transmitting and re- ceiving thoughts were independent of relationship, for instance, with cerebral processes and substance. All that is distinctly recognized as concerned is the pure succession of perishing thoughts, the pure stream- mind. The present thought remembers, because it has received the experiences of its predecessor by imme- diate impartation or appropriation. It retains and re- produces, because of the direct gifts from its dying foreruimer in the stream of thoughts.^ Professor James begins his theory of the memory of the stream-mind with an assumption of superlative im- portance, which deserves to be closely considered. He assumes as if it were an elementary and self-evident fact, that the present thought knows its predecessor as a predecessor, and holds implicated in that the knowl- edge of time, of the past, of succession. But in this 1 Elsewhere Professor James expresses himself in this manner : "In radical empiricism there is no bedding [no substance connecting our thoughts] ; it is as if the pieces clung together by their edges, the tran- sitions experienced between them forming their cement. . . . The meta- phor serves to symbolize the fact that Experience itself, taken at large, can grow by its edges. That one moment of it proliferates into the next by transitions which, whether conjunctive or disjimctive, continue the experiential tissue, cannot, I contend, be denied." {Radical E'mpiricism, pp. 86, 87.) "In the same act by which I feel that this passing minute is a new pulse of life, I feel that the old life continues into it, and the feeling of continuance in no wise jars upon the simultaneous feeling of a novelty." {11., p. 95.) 28 SUBJECT AND OBJECT assumption he obviously begs the whole question. The most important problem, the problem above aU other problems for the stream-mind respecting memory, is to explain, or show the possibility of, the present thought knowing past thoughts as having been past — knowing itself as a successor — ^knowing that there is any succes- sion at all or that there was a past. The only "verifi- able thinker," he admits, is the present passing thought ; and the question before all others then is, how can this transitory thinker have any acquaintance with the past of which he has no irmnediate knowledge, how can he even dream of a predecessor or of the past? The two main principles of Professor James' theory of mental-memory are these: First, a thought trans- mits to its successor its possessions, including its mem- ories ; or a thought adopts the possessions of its prede- cessor. Secondly, a thought knows its predecessor as a predecessor; and it knows the memories which it has appropriated from its predecessor, not only as its own present experiences but also as memories, as represen- tations of the past. The direct transference by a thought of its posses- sions to its succeeding thought in the mental stream is a sufficiently conjectural and mysterious transaction. Yet it is not the greatest difficulty for this theory of memory. Granting that the transference takes place, it does not help or warrant the second principle just noted. The very grave question yet remains: How can the present solitary thought, which is only for the present, and whose whole inherited content is for itself only in the present and for the present, know any element of this content, or anything whatever within itself, as having come from the past or as representing the pastt The possibility of such knowledge is in no THE SUBJECT OB SOUL 29 wise made credible. There is no ground whatever for supposing that a thinker which never had a past itself, but has its only and total existence in the present mo- ment, can know, or can even imagine, any possession of its own, or anything else, as having had a past, or as having come down from the past, or as in any wise related to the past ; or can know that it is itself a mem- ber of a succession, or be aware of succession at all. There can be no actual, but only a fancied dove-tailing of thoughts, or "clinging together" by their edges. For there is but one verifiable piece, the present thought ; all other pieces have perished. Also there is but one edge, the edge of the present thought ; all other edges are gone. The edge of the present thought touches or clings to nothing; it subsists in the void with no correlate. What result might foUow for memory if past thoughts perished not, or perished not quickly, and remained to form at every moment a temporal stream of some length, we shall not undertake to say; but it seems manifest that, if one of its experiences be felt by the hypothetical present transient thought as different from another in quality, yet it cannot be felt as differ- ent in time, as having a predecessor or as being a suc- cessor, as forming a new experience in comparison with an old. If it be cognizant of simultaneity, it cannot be also cognizant of succession. It would appear, finally, that if the present thought have the conviction of the past, the conviction can be only an effect which the thought produces at the moment in order to entertain itself with a fiction; or be only the arbitrary effect of creative evolution. The thought cannot know any- thing as having existed before itself, but at the farthest know only itself and the present production or creation. It is quite evident of Hume's serial mind, in which 30 SUBJECT AND OBJECT the successive thoughts are discontinuous, are sepa- rated from one another by absolute breaches, that one thought cannot have any knowledge of its temporal, or of any other kind of relation, with a predecessor. The void intervals between the thoughts permit to any one of them at the utmost only a knowledge of its own being and momentary duration. The series cannot be aware of itself as a series. No thought can know that it is a member of, or has a place in, a series. It cannot have any memory of an antecedent, or of the past, or of suc- cession. By the most unscrupulous presumption Hume claims for his serial mind a knowledge of temporal and other relations of the terms which is manifestly im- possible. It is just as evident that the serial mind of the later psychologists, the mind of the continuous suc- cession, is as incapable of memory, of the knowledge of the past and of succession, as the broken serial mind. For all of the continuous mind existing at one moment is the present passing thought. This is the only mind and all of mind. It is divided from its predecessors by all the profound abyss, so to speak, subsisting between a thing that exists and things that do not exist; and there is no basis or possibility of the knowledge of the past as past, or the knowledge of any part of its pos- sessions as having existed before itself and having come from the past. It can know itself at the best, not as an heir, but solely as a present possessor of what is in its hand without its knowing whence. It is to be remembered that the stream of thoughts, the stream-mind, is supposed to be a pure abstract succession. Now many psychologists maintain as a fundamental principle, that a succession of thoughts is not the thought of succession; that a succession of thoughts, in and of itself, is not aware of itself as a sue- THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 31 cession and does not possess memory. They hold that there must be a permanent element or factor by asso- ciation and contrast with which the succession or stream is known, or knows itself, as a succession or stream. They follow Kant's teaching, that the permanent "must always be coexistent with succession." ^ But where is there a permanent element or factor in or with the ab- stract stream of thoughts? The hypothesis indeed claims, as we must recognize, one permanent element; namely, in the identical mnemonic stock that passes along the stream of thoughts, being handed down by each thought to its successor and constantly receiving accretions. "The identity," says Professor James, "which the I discovers . . . can only be a relative identity, that of a slow shifting in which there is al- ways some common ingredient retained. The com- monest element of all, the most uniform, is the posses- sion of the same memories. However different the man may be from the youth, both look back on the same childhood, and call it their own" (p. 372). The ques- tion inevitably occurs here, is this identical body of memories a person or soul? If it be, then we would seem after all our wanderings to have gotten back into the company of the substantialists. But yet it is a soul of a very peculiar character : it passes through the suc- cessive thoughts, instead of having the successive thoughts pass through it ; or it belongs to them, instead of their belonging to it. We cannot be required to admit that the permanent stock of memories (if we should grant for the time its own possibility), which glides along the stream of thoughts, affords a permanence adequate to the work of inaking known by comparison the stream as a stream, ''■Kritik d. r. V. (Hartenstein), p. 77. 32 SUBJECT AND OBJECT the succession as a succession. Succession certainly is known only by association with permanence; but the permanence must be of a more real and stable sort than that of the transient common mnemonic store. The inadequacy of the identical and moving stock of memories, in its permanency, to make possible to a suc- cession of thoughts the thought of succession implying memory, and of the whole theory of memory as be- longing to the pure stream of thoughts without a per- manent soul, seems indisputable. And Professor James himself in a surprising manner tacitly acknowl- edges the inadequacy and unsatisfactoriness of the theory. He does this by introducing a very important, a genuine permanent, reality in association with the stream of thoughts and the transitive mnemonic store. This reality is the permanent brain. To the permanent brain he now assigns the whole function of retention and the permanent possibilities of recollections. The retention and reproduction which he seemed to hold as belonging to the pure rapid stream of thoughts in itself, because each thought by melting itself into, or when "hugged" by, its successor, hands over its memories directly to it, are now assigned to the permanent sub- stance and paths of the brain. According to the men- tal theory of memory, "each thought is born an owner and dies owned"; the nascent thought immediately takes up the expiring thought and appropriates its con- tents; each "section" of the stream of consciousness knows and adopts all those that went before it (p. 340) ; memory is possible because the successive thoughts "cling together by their edges." A thought gets its memories thus directly from the preceding thought, not from the retention of the brain alone. It is just like one man bequeathing a herd of cattle to another and the THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 33 same cattle being thus possessed in succession by dif- ferent men. But according to tMs additional, that is, this cerebral, theory of memory, the tendency to think an experience again has its permanent ground in the ' ' organized neural paths. ' ' Moreover, retention of ex- perience is "neither more nor less than the brain-paths which associate the experience with the occasion and cue of the recall. When slumbering, these paths are the condition of retention; when active, they are the condi- tion of recall" (p. 655). It is also expressly averred that retention "is not a fact of the mental order at all. It is a purely physical phenomenon, a morphological feature, the presence of these 'paths,' namely, in the finest recesses of the brain's tissue" (p. 655). The present thought gets its memories from the brain, the enduring and only retainer, and not directly from the preceding thought as was supposed in the account of mental memory. Retention, which seems to have been treated before as wholly a mental fact, is now said to be not a mental fact at all. In fine, not the passing thought, but the permanent brain, appears here to be made the real thinker and agent of conservation and re- call. Professor James' bringing in, to the side of the mind of the pure stream of thoughts, the brain as the one es- sential foundation and organ of memory, is a pro- cedure, quite analogous to, and forcibly recalls, Hume's introduction of the permanent extra mind as reviewing, owning, controlling, and remembering, the successive but separately existing perceptions constituting his only explicitly avowed mind. He does not, as should be kept in mind, treat the brain as if it were only a succession of motions, a succession of motions occa- sioning a succession of states of consciousness ; but as 34 SUBJECT AND OBJECT a permanent something enduring through motions, and the bed of permanent possibilities of states of conscious- ness. It seems evident, therefore, when we consider our author's emphatic rejection of the permanent soul of the spiritualists as a "superfluity," and the com- plete capability he ascribes to the abstract stream of thoughts of remembering and knowing succession and time, through direct communication of thought to thought, through the thoughts clinging together "by their edges," that his adoption and employment of the brain as the permanent and supreme organ of mem- ory, are hardly superior in their method to the sur- reption and sophistry by which Hume introduces the extra mind and gives it in fact a place as the permanent, ruling and remembering mind, over the mind of the pure discontinuous succession. Professor James also has his two minds; namely, the stream of conscious- ness or stream-mind, and what is not a stream — ^the permanent and retentive brain. The course of Hume in bringing in the permanent extra mind, and of James in bringing in the permanent brain with its permanent and related paths, are both clear and impressive revelations of the great difficulty, we may say the impossibility, of remaining constant to the mind of the abstract succession, in the explana- tion of memory and the known relation of succession. Their addition and use of these notable permanent realities was but the result of the profound necessity felt by them for something permanent, something en- during in sameness, beside the mind of the rapid suc- cession of perceptions and thoughts, to make possible memory and the knowledge of succession and time; and thereby each contradicts and condemns his the- oretic mind as being quite insufficient. It should be THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 35 remarked furthermore, that Professor James may easily and confidently dispense with the permanent soul of the spiritualists and declare that the "soul-theory is a complete superfluity," etc. (p. 348), if he may in- troduce into its place the permanent and identical brain regarded as endowed with capabilities and func- tions usually ascribed to the soul. Certainly, if the brain be supposed to be the permanent and unitary producer, retainer, and reproducer of thought, it is supposed to be a permanent soul of the greatest po- tentialities. We have been considering the possibility of the stream-mind's knowing succession and remembering. Now we go on to consider briefly the possibility of its having the conviction of personal identity. The two facts of memory and the sense of personal identity are closely related; the former is necessary to the latter; and much that was said of memory will apply also to the other. If it is proved that memory is impossible to the stream-mind, the same is proved of the sense of personal identity. According to Professor James, the sense of personal identity is a feeling of resemblance, continuity, and intimacy or "warmth," among the successive selves or thoughts. He remarks : ' ' The past and present selves [thoughts, feelings] compared are the same just so far as they are the same, and no farther. A uniform feeling of 'warmth,' of bodily existence (or an equally uniform feeling of pure psychic energy?) pervades them all; and this is what gives them a generic unity, and makes them the same in kind" (p. 335). Our author accounts for the sense of personal iden- tity by the same mode of supplementation by which he accounts for memory; namely, by bringing in to 36 SUBJECT AND OBJECT the side of the stream of consciousness a permanent and identical reality — the brain. The supplementa- tion becomes quite evident by a comparison of various statements in which the experience of personal identity is supposed to be fuUy possible to the pure succession of perishing thoughts alone, with statements in which the basis of conscious personality is conceived to be the existence and motions of the brain or body, which is not a perishing succession, but a permanent reality enduring through the mental and the bodily succes- sions. The unusual supremacy attributed by Professor James to cephalic and certain other bodily motions, in our sense of personality, or as constituents of self, is pronounced. He thinks he finds the "central nucleus of the Self" in "some bodily process for the most part taking place in the head" (p. 300). He says: "The 'Self of selves' when carefully examined is found to consist mainly of the collection of these peculiar m,o- tions in the head or between the head and throat," as in breathing. "These cephalic motions are the por- tions of my innermost activity of which I am most dis- tinctly aware" (p. 301). "The part of the innermost Self which is most vividly felt turns out to consist for the most part of a collection of cephalic movements of 'adjustments' which, for want of attention and reflec- tion, usually fail to be perceived and classed as what they are" (p. 305). "The nucleus of the 'me' is al- ways the bodily existence felt to be present at the time" (p. 400). "We feel the whole cubic mass of our body all the while, it gives us an unceasing sense of personal existence" (p. 333). It should be observed that the body, head, encephalon, is treated in these citations and elsewhere not only as having or as being THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 37 processes or a stream of motions, corresponding to the stream of consciousness, but also, unequivocally, as being much, more than a stream of motions, namely, an extended reality which possesses and supports the motions and endures after them. There is here also the complete confusion of the stream of consciousness, sensations, with the concomitant physical processes. By cephalic motions are meant, not less than the material motions, the sensations that accompany them. Though what Professor James here confounds, he at other places clearly distinguishes, as in these propositions: "Psychology . . . assumes as its data (1) thoughts and feelings, and (2) a physical world in time and space with which they coexist and which (3) they know" (p. vi) ; "Mental and physical events are, on all hands, admitted to present the strongest contrast in the entire field of being. The chasm which yawns between them is less easily bridged over by the mind than any interval we know" (p. 134). It must spe- cially be deemed a failure of the gravest sort when the commonly acknowledged difference between the modes of cognizing the two kinds of events is entirely ignored. We have immediate knowledge of mental events; we have never immediate knowledge of physical events.^ This important contrast must not be disregarded. But we shall not dwell longer upon what seems to be the fundamental postulate of Professor James' doc- trine of personality, namely, that we have the convic- 1 "The ordinary man is first aware of his conscious experiences, and only very remotely aware of his nervous system." (Judd, Psychology, p. 59.) "The sensation of 'muskiness' is known immediately . . . The knowl- edge of any object or material cause of the sensation is mediate." (Huxley, Hume, p. 302.) "Our mental states are known immediately; external things indi- rectly or inferentially." (Sully, Human Mind, II., p. 369.) 38 SUBJECT AND OBJECT tion of personal identity because we have a permanent and identical brain or body; that the conviction has its foundation, not in the stream of consciousness alone, as sometimes seems to be supposed it might have, but has its deeper and real foundation in what is not a stream, that is, the permanent corporeal organism. This at least appears clear, that the theory which adds to the subjective stream of consciousness the permanent brain, something very different from a stream and en- dowed with notable soul-power, cannot have much that is worthful to say against the theory which accepts with the stream of consciousness the permanent soul. Their employment of the permanent brain is in fact the decisive testimony of the advocates of the pure stream-mind or stream-self to the total inadequacy of the latter to account for the conviction of personal identity, and is virtually a retreat to the position of the substantialists. The two parties agree in the im- phcit conclusion that the pure abstract stream of con- sciousness, having nothing but temporal progression, is in no wise sufficient in itself for memory and the sense of identity, but absolutely needs the adjunction of a permanent and indentical reality. One party re- gards that reality as spirit; the other supposes it to be cerebral matter capable of spiritual functions. Before concluding we should notice more fully a fundamental position of Professor James, which was noticed above, namely, the tacit assumption that the permanent and extended brain is known more directly and certainly than the soul, and therefore that it should be received into the science of psychology, and the soul excluded. He is full of confidence as to the existence and nature of the brain, but full of doubt as to the soul. He says respecting the knowledge of THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 39 the soul: "If with the Spiritualists, one contend for a substantial soul . . . one can give no positive ac- count of what that may be" (p. 330). The soul is sup- posed to be inaccessible to direct or to any other sort of knowledge. But it is presumed of the brain that it is easily accessible to our knowledge, and that we have clear and certain cognition of its nature — of its permanence and extension, its permanent paths of mo- tion — and may confidently accept the occurrence of re- peated motions along the identical paths. When we consider the extensive and apparently im- mediate knowledge of the brain claimed by Professor James, and the great readiness with which he admits the brain into the science of psychology, it appears a very grave failure in him not to have shown at the same time with some fulness and minuteness, how he succeeded in attaining such a knowledge, in amount and certainty, of the brain; particularly, how by the stream-mind, a pure succession, the perception of such a different thing as a permanent material object is possible; or how, since by the hypothesis mentality is wholly successive, he ever happened even to think or dream of such a permanent material reality as he represents the brain to be.^ The passage from mental succession to corporeal permanence is quite unex- plained. We must contend that this assumption of the direct and certain knowledge of the brain, of a knowledge deemed altogether superior to the knowledge of the 1 It is an important point not to be lost sight of in a review of the uses some make of the brain in psychology, that what may appear to be the crassest cerebralism or materialism may however be, curiously enough, in fact, the most refined idealism; for by brain, head, matter, may be meant only a group of muscular and other sensations, or the mere in- substantial permanent possibility of them. 40 SUBJECT AND OBJECT permanent soul, is a psychological error of the most serious character. It must be maintained further that to the stream-mind, the mind of the pure abstract succession or temporal procession, the knowledge or even the idea of a permanent and extended object is an impossibility. It seems to be a demonstrable propo- sition, that the knowledge of the permanent soul has a priority over the knowledge of the permanent brain, and is the foundation, the indispensable condition, of the knowledge of the latter and of every other extra- mental permanent reality. The policy of "explaining mind by body" requires the most careful definition and limitation. It is clear and undeniable that to some extent mind must be ex- plained by body. For instance, the first rise of sensa- tions is dependent upon corporeal motion or stimula- tion. Sensations do not spring up spontaneously in mind, without the objective excitement. And it is evi- dent that characteristics of sensations, feelings, per- cepts — as their particular intensity, duration, exten- sion — depend upon corporeal qualities and conditions. But on the other hand, it cannot be said that bodily substance or its vibrations generate or create con- sciousness or the conscious modes. Again, knowledge of the body does not precede knowledge of the conscious modes, or condition knowledge of these. Knowledge of the material is primitively not even concurrent with the knowledge of the mental, but succeeds it; and is not the same in kind or equal in directness and cer- tainty. The two knowledges are separated by the sharpest and most assured demarkation; we may be clearly cognizant of sensation in the head, without any knowledge whatever of the cerebral matter and mo- tions. The cognitions are quite different in kind. We THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 41 have iminediate knowledge or consciousness of the mental modes. We are never conscious of the bodily substance or properties, but know them only medi- ately, inf erentiaUy ; and the media of our knowledge are always the previously, the immediately and inde- pendently, known mental modes. As to manner of knowledge, body and mind are thus separated in the most thorough-going fashion. This division, as to pri- ority and nearness of knowledge, may be a true indica- tion of an ontological division. The question, Where does the mind end and the body begin? might be an- swered in general thus : at the line dividing immediate from inferential knowledge. We shall endeavor to justify these positions of the priority and nearness of the soul in knowledge, espe- cially the priority of the knowledge of the soul to the knowledge of the body, in the attempt, to which we shall now proceed, to present a positive doctrine of the soul. After so much criticism and negation the reader will likely be gratified with the proposal to offer now for his consideration something positive and construc- tive, a substitute especially for the theory of the ab- stract stream-mind; and may perhaps also anticipate some entertainment for himself in the opportunity of detecting the possible surreptions, paradoxes, defects, of the positive theory to be outlined. Our main en- deavor will be to maintain the existence, and trust- worthy knowledge, of the Soul regarded as a per- manent and identical reality capable of a stream of processes of conscious modes. There are two important facts pertaining to the re- lation of mind or soul and body which deserve some 42 SUBJECT AND OBJECT notice at the outset. Of these facts, one is the inti- macy of the relation between soul and body, or between thought and nervous motion; the other is the very great disparity, the very manifest ineomparability, be- tween thought — sensation, passion, volition — and every known and imaginable mode of material motion and arrangement. The intimate relation of body and mind, and great dependence of mind upon body, are indisputable. The bodily conditions of development, nourishment, waste, age, undoubtedly affect the mind. Drugs, fevers, neural derangement, produce marked results in mind. A stroke on the head, by causing some disorder of the brain, may cause a suspension of consciousness. Prom the evident influence of body upon mind, some draw the grave conclusion in effect that mind or the mental phenomena are but products of body. Some derive the far-reaching deduction that, as a temporary de- rangement of the brain may cause a temporary cessa- tion of consciousness, a permanent derangement, or the disintegration, of the brain may cause the per- manent cessation, or may destroy the possibility, of consciousness. Because of the close association of body and mind, it is common to call them in their union the "psycho- physical organism." But psychologists are seldom careful and precise to tell what part of the composite organism is psychical and what part physical, or what either is as distinguished from the other. As was be- fore remarked, great superiority is frequently given to the physical portion, it being regarded as, through its molecular motions and groupings, the generator of the psychical. All that is permanent is physical; the THE SUBJECT OB SOUL 43 psychical is a fleeting process, with nothing perma- nent. Unquestionable as is the very considerable influence of body upon mind, yet directly over against this fact stands the no less evident and certain fact of the im- mense disparity or the incommensurability between material motion and every mode of thought or con- sciousness. This thorough incommensurability, and the distinguished character of the mental experiences and of our knowledge of them, require the conclusion that material motion and conscious mode cannot be the same; that such great unlikeness of nature makes it impossible for them to be but distinct phases of the same fact or event, and makes it impossible for the material to be the cause or generator of the conscious. Cerebral elements whose sole efficiency is assumed to be in their movements and changes of relative spatial position can never originate the vivid modes of con- sciousness. Matter in motion is not mind. These facts favor the affirmative postulations, that the mental phenomena have their ground and source in an entity distinct from and superior to the physical; an entity which has as real permanence as the physical, and which combines within itself the peculiar capabilities of producing presentations, conserving experiences or their effects, and producing memories, — of presenta- tion, retention, and reminiscence, — ^yet not without the support and stimulation of the physical organism. Though the disparity between the physical and men- tal is very great, it cannot be maintained to be total or absolute. If it were absolute, that should appar- ently make any intercourse or interaction between them impossible. But while the obvious disparity seems to 44 SUBJECT AND OBJECT render the generation of the mental by the physical impossible, it does not require us to believe that the physical cannot in some manner act on mind and ex- cite it to activity and production of conscious modes; or that there cannot be reciprocal excitation without generation or creation of activity by either for the other. Particular note may be made of some mani- fest correspondences between mental activity, especially sensation, and the accompanying physical process : the duration of a sensation answers in many instances to the duration of the physical impression; its extension to the extension of the impression; and its vividness and intensity to the force of the impression. It further appears, however, that because of the great unlikeness between the mental and physical, in essence and ac- tivity, especially between mental and physical energy, interaction between them must be governed by a dif- ferent law from that which governs the interaction of material objects — a different law which is as yet un- discovered and unknown. The principle of the conser- vation of physical energy as this principle regulates the interaction of physical realities, does not seem to per- tain to the reciprocity of mind and body. We come now to the cardinal question. How ought we to define and describe mind considered in itself, without regard to its relation to the physical organism or to any external reality? This question may be fitly answered as follows: Mind is an entity or substance that contains in itself, as original or constitutive ele- ments, the permanent possibilities of the different species of conscious modes — of sensations, emotions, volitions. The permanent possibilities are potentiali- ties; or they are capabilities of producing the various modes of consciousness. The modes of consciousness THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 45 are the realizations of the permanent constitutive po- tentialities. Again, the potentialities, or the mind as consisting of them, is an entity or substance ; it is not an undmg or an airy indescribable thing such as J. S. Mill's "permanent possibility of feeling" seems to be. The mind is more than abstract activity, as the brain is more than abstract motion. The mind is some- thing that thinks, as the brain is something that moves. It is as reasonable to ask what the mind is more than its activity, as to ask what a revolving wheel is after it has stopped. Activity seems to require an agent, as motion requires a body. In fine, consciousness is not the realization of a permanent nothing, but of a permanent something. The mind as a substance holds in potentia all the phenomena of consciousness; and, as thus understood, it is an active and living, not an inert and dead, substance. It should be further re- marked, that the potentialities of consciousness should not be supposed to "inhere" in mind. They rather constitute the substance of mind, they are its struc- tural elements. As constantly related to each other and mutually dependent, they form one single mind. The mind is a real unit, consisting of the closely bound and interdependent potentialities; and capable of ex- periences that are various but yet unitary, or of a collective consciousness. To reverse the order of statement, this unity of consciousness, or "synthetic linity of apperception," is certainly far more than a mere appearance or abstract fonn; it requires and in- volves a unitary reality. Mind as the producer of the conscious affections, precedes consciousness. It is not made by, or depend- ent upon, consciousness; consciousness is dependent upon it. When consciousness arises, it is the identical 46 SUBJECT AND OBJECT mind passing from an unconscious to a conscious state. The mind may be said to precede and to produce or generate consciousness, just as it is said that poten- tiality precedes actualization; or as it is said by the materialists that brain precedes, and by preceding, gen- erates thoughts; or as is affirmed or implied by some that a permanent possibility of sensation precedes sen- sation. Actual consciousness is no more necessary to the existence of mind than rolling or flying is necessary to the existence of a billiard-ball. The mind is the sole cause of the phenomena of con- sciousness ; that is, it is the sole source of the content of these phenomena. They are wholly the actualiza- tion of the potential energy of the mind. The rise of consciousness is the soul's transformation of itself from an unconscious into a conscious entity. But the self-transformation is not the spontaneous activity of the mind ; it is at first excited or occasioned by the neu- ral processes. Hence, in the generation of conscious- ness, the mind is not only active, but is also passive. It is not the sole cause, for the neural motion is also a cause. But the mind is the sole cause, it is the only actor, in the production of the matter of consciousness. The neural motion is a cause only as a stimulant or agitator; it contributes absolutely nothing to the con- tent of the conscious modes which it excites the mind to produce. Eespecting the production of consciousness or thoughts, we here note this remark of Professor James: The bald fact is "that when the hrain acts, a thought occurs. The spiritualistic formulation says that the brain-processes knock the thought, so to speak, out of a Soul which stands there to receive their influ- ence. The simpler formulation says that the thought THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 47 simply comes. But what positive meaning has the Soul, when scrutinized, but the ground of possibility of the thought? And what is the 'knocking' but the determining of the possibility to actuality f" (p. 345.) The spiritualist holds that the brain-processes excite the soul to engender the thought ; that the whole activ- ity or causation of the brain is stimulation, that it in no way generates, as it is incapable of generating, any of the matter of consciousness. He maintains also that the soul has full constitutional rights to existence ; that it is not the mere serf of the brain, but is greatly superior to it as a cause. "The simpler formation," declares Professor James, "says that the thought sim- ply comes." But no one can rest content without ask- ing the question. Comes from whence? Does it come from something, or from nothing? Does it come from the brain, does the brain hold in itself alone the possi- bility of the thought and the whole power of actualiza- tion! Peradventure, it comes from a "permanent pos- sibility" which is not a constitutional property of the brain. Or are we expected to adopt the conception of Lotze, that the soul-activity is a "new creation pro- duced by the one encompassing and universally de- termining Reality from its own nature as the supple- ment of its physical activity"?^ The spiritualist an- swers, that the thought comes from the soul ; that it is produced by the soul; that the possibility of it, as to its contents, is in the soul alone; and that the soul is a permanent reality possessing in itself, as constitutional attributes or elements, the possibilities or potentiali- ties of all forms of consciousness. The efficiency of the soul for the production of spiritual effects is unique and most intimately related to the effects ; and is neces- 1 MetaphysiG, p. 442. 48 SUBJECT AND OBJECT sarily far superior to any efficiency that can be prop- erly attributed to the motions and collocations of cere- bral matter. The self-knowing, self -remembering ego, carrying a constant and irrepressible conviction of per- manent identity, and having as one mode or grade of its energy what we are all familiar with in voluntary self-control and experience, must, as a cause of thought, be superior to its physical associate. Especially as to the origination of our thoughts, Pro- fessor James himself says: "Thoughts accompany the brain's workings, and those thoughts are cognitive of realities. The whole relation is one which we can only write down empirically, confessing that no glim- mer of explanation of it is yet in sight. That brains should give rise to a knowing consciousness at all, this is the one mystery which returns, no matter of what sort the consciousness and what sort the knowledge may be" (p. 687) ; but at another place proposes the following conception: "For my own part I confess that the moment I become metaphysical and try to define the more, I find the notion of some sort of an anima mundi thinking in all of us to be a more promis- ing hypothesis, in spite of all its difficulties, than that of a lot of absolutely individual souls" (p. 346). It is hard to see a necessity for assuming any other soul as the immediate cause of the stream of thoughts, includ- ing presentations and memories, than the permanent finite soul which is in most intimate relation with our permanent nervous organism and entirely inside our epidermis, and of which we have a knowledge certainly not less direct and sure than our knowledge of an anima mundi. Eegarding the profound question of the exact rela- tion of conscious affections, or thoughts, to the engen- THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 49 dering soul, realistic psychologists have made various representations. They have said that thoughts, ideas, "inhere" in mind; are "supported" by mind; are the changing possessions of the unchanging mind that is "behind" them; "point" to mind as something over and above themselves. According to Locke and Kant, ideas are appearances attached to an unknown mind or reality. Berkeley treated the mind as if it were a re- ceptacle for ideas, into which and out of which they flow ; ideas being quite distinct from the mind. Ideas cannot properly be said to inhere in, or to be supported by, mind, if there is implied the assumption that the mind is yet in some manner distinct from them, being back of them or under them. Ideas are in the mind, and the mind is in ideas; there is no sort of separation, that is, when ideas are existing. Mind is not an "it" to which consciousness adheres. Their relation is more intimate than adherence. Conscious- ness lives in the mind, and cannot live apart from it; and the mind lives in consciousness. Mind is no more apart from ideas than the brain is apart from its processes or motions. Mind is in its ideas as the brain is in its motions. It should be repeated and emphasized, that mind has no knowledge of itself outside or independently of its conscious modes. They cannot exist without it, and it cannot know itself without them. The unactualized po- tentialities of mind are not self -known. We may here use the language of Hume, and much more fitly than he himself used it: "When I enter most intimately into what I caU myself, I always stumble on some particular perception or other. ... I never can catch myself at any time without a perception." A man catches him- self only in his perceptions; only in his perceptions, 50 SUBJECT AND OBJECT and not behind them, or under them, or in anywise apart from them. Perceptions and self are imme- diately together, there is no interval or division of any kind between them. Yet it remains true, that the mind exists when it has no perceptions, or when perceptions have ceased. The mind exists when it does not know its existence. Knowledge of itself is not indispensable to its existence. It subsists with its potentialities, be- fore consciousness, and when consciousness is inter- rupted. Consciousness is no more necessary to the elementary being or substance of the mind, than motion is necessary to the substance of the brain. As brain may conceivably remain when motion ceases, so mind remains when consciousness ceases. From the definition and the general account of mind, we may now proceed in an open pathway to particular inquiries, and especially to consider the two profound- est questions for us pertaining to mind ; namely, First, What do we really know of mind, or what does mind really know of itself? and, Secondly, What is the actual character or species of this knowledge? is it immediate, or mediate, or inferential, or a combination of different modes ? But before proceeding with these particular and direct inquests, it will probably prove advantageous to give brief consideration to a specific assumption, al- ready taken note of, which is made by many psycholo- gists; namely, the assumption that the brain or body and external material objects are definite, and clearly and certainly known, realities, but that the supposed soul is no such reality; that the physicist deals with objects of precise form and magnitude and permanence, but that the psychologist deals with no analogous ob- THE: SUBJECT OB SOUL 51 ject; that a flower in the hand of a botanist, or a frag- ment of rock in the hand of a geologist, or a bone in the hand of an anatomist, is a thing of easy, exact and continued inspection, but that the psychologist has no such object in the changing and fleeting phenomena which he observes. Some who emphasize the existence and the clear knowledge of material objects ask sar- castically, "What do we know of the essence of the soul?" Already the remark of Professor James has been cited: "If, with the Spiritualists, one contend for a substantial soul, or transcendental principle of unity, one can give no positive account of what that may be." He constantly admits the possibility of giving a positive account of the brain or body or other material object, as a thing of definite form, size, structure, per- manence, but questions and denies any analogous ac- count of the soul. We again earnestly insist that in this assumption of superiority in our knowledge of the physical object over the knowledge of the soul, psychologists are sub- ject to a very serious delusion. When a geologist is scanning a specimen of rock, unquestionably the only object immediately known is his own subjective percept projected upon the specimen. The color perceived is altogether the color of the projected percept. The only spatial extension immediately cognized is the ex- tension of the percept. The color and extension are coexistent subjective attributes. Of the extension of the real external specimen in the hand, he has only mediate knowledge through the immediately known extension of the subjective percept serving as a repre- sentation. The like of what is here said of color and extension may be said of permanence. The perma- nence originally and more directly cognized in every act 52 SUBJECT AND OBJECT of external perception is wholly that of the mind. The percept itself has a quasi-permanence in being con- stantly renewed by the constant impression of the ex- ternal object; or the constant renewal serves as real permanence. Further, there is not only apparent per- manence of percept caused by continual renewal, but there is real permanence which is perceived by means of the renewed percept. This is the permanence and identity of the mind itself revealed by memory of the successive exactly similar percepts. Again, not only is the permanence of the mind the first and most directly perceived, but it is the necessary ground of the per- ception of the permanence of any and every other reality. Our cognition of the permanence of an extra- mental object is in every instance an inference from the mind's own permanence previously known by the re- peated impressions made upon the mind by the object. We conclude that the object possesses a permanence like that of the mind, because of the very similar impres- sions successively made by the object upon the mind, or of the very similar sensations occasioned by them. The impressions or sensations are both known as successive and inferred to be made by a permanent object, on the indispensable condition of the mind's own known per- manence. In these statements we suppose we are giv- ing expression to the real facts ; and therefore contend that psychologists are quite wrong in the postulate that we have a better knowledge of the brain, body, extra- corporeal object, than of the mind. The truth is that in every act of external perception, the color, extension, permanence, unity, directly known are properties of the mind's sensations and substance, and that we can know an extra-mental object only by representation and in- ference through the properties of the mind. There is THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 53 then involved, that we have a more intimate, real, cer- tain and full knowledge of the mind than of any other reality in existence. From these preliminary general observations let us proceed to a more direct and special ascertainment of what is known of mind. First. We know the Succession of mind ; that is, the succession of its conscious modes — of its thoughts, feel- ings, affections. These constitute a temporal continu- ous series, a stream, a process or aggregate of proc- esses. As to the knowledge of the succession of mind, psychologists are generally agreed. Many teach that we certainly know the temporal series of thoughts, but nothing more; for, as they contend, there is nothing more of mind to know. Within the knowledge of the succession of thoughts is involved the knowledge of the temporal unity of the mind. In apprehending the past and present thoughts, in holding them together in one knowledge, the mind is cognizant of unity, of its own unity in time. Further, in the aggregate of present passing thoughts the mind knows also simultaneity ; it is conscious of the unity of the simultaneous. Here it may be noted also that, in simultaneous spatially separated sensations, the mind is conscious of spatial unity, of its own spatial unity. Again, it is to be remarked that spatially separated sen- sations are not in and of themselves the sensation of spatial, separation ; just as a succession of sensations is not in and of itself the sensation of succession. There is more involved in either case than pure abstract sen- sations. Moreover, in all the cognitions of the succes- sive, the simultaneous, the spatially severed, the mind has a peculiar sense of the unity of possession or owner- ship. It knows in the one moment, and in the one com- 54 SUBJECT AND OBJECT prehensive cognitive act, that it owns the present thought and owned the past thoughts of the succession; that it owns the simultaneous thoughts, including the simultaneous thoughts or sensations that have spatial intervals between them. In the discussion of the mind's knowledge of its own succession and temporal unity, the most penetrating question is, What is the nature of this knowledge? Most psychologists hold that we have immediate knowl- edge of only the present thought or thoughts. Votaries of the stream-mind, the mind of the pure abstract suc- cession without substrate, would maintain that the only mind and the whole of mind at any moment is the pres- ent passing thought. We have found Professor James asserting, that "the passing Thought is itself the only verifiable thinker" (p. 346); by which we suppose he means the only verifiable thinker particularly as com- pared with the ' ' soul, ' ' and as alone known with abso- lute directness and certainty. If now we have imme- diate knowledge of the present thought only, if it is the sole thought known with absolute inamediacy and cer- tainty, what then is the character of our knowledge of the past thoughts of the mental succession? It is answered, that we know the past thoughts by memory. But there still remains the pressing inquiry, what sort of knowledge is memory? It cannot be an immediate knowledge of the past. Memory is rather, as Sir W. Hamilton has defined it, an immediate knowledge of the present and a belief of the past. The one present re- membering act is known as present, and is also believed to represent a past act. But what kind of knowledge is the belief of the past? What is it compared with the immediate knowledge of the present? How does it differ from the latter? Here we are brought to face THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 55 one of the most profound problems in the epistemology of mind ; namely, How does our knowledge ever get be- yond the immediately known present thought? or how come we ever to know a past thought, since it is outside the sphere of immediate knowledge? We shall pursue this problem farther in the discussion of the second great fact in our knowledge of mind, to which we now pass. Secondly. We know the Permanence of the mind. This we know simultaneously, and in the closest asso- ciation, with its succession. But here we enter upon disputed territory, and come into direct conflict with the votaries of the mind of the pure succession. They ad- mit the knowledge of the mind's succession, as they hold that the mind itself is only the pure succession of the perishing thoughts; but deny the knowledge and reality of permanence. Many of them explicitly assert that "Modem psychology knows nothing of a perma- nent mind"; and that "Psychology deals only with processes." "Mind is pure activity." To these dec- larations we would make the prefatory reply, that if modem psychology knows nothing of a permanent mind, this lack of knowledge is decisive proof of the defectiveness of modern psychology; if it deals only with the processes or succession of mind, it is far from dealing with mind in the fulness of its real and known character. Psychology must find place for the perma- nence of mind as well as for its succession, or it is de- ficient and false. For, in the first place, permanence is as well, as clearly and certainly, known as succession. The knowl- edge is essentially the same in both cases. It is a mix- ture of immediate knowledge and belief. As already remarked, we have not immediate knowledge of a sue- 56 SUBJECT AND OBJECT cession — of a succession of thoughts. We have im- mediate knowledge of only the present term of the suc- cession, the present thought ; of the past terms, the past thoughts, we have not immediate knowledge ; we cannot have, for they have died away, they are gone. We have only the memory or the belief of their existence. Our knowledge then of the succession of thoughts is a fusion of immediate knowledge and belief. The same is true of our knowledge of the permanence of the mind. By permanence, we mean continued existence from the past to the present; the mind did not perish in the past as its thoughts did, but has endured, has been maintained in existence, to the present. But as we cannot have im- mediate knowledge of anything outside the present, we cannot have immediate knowledge of the past and per- manence of the mind. We have immediate knowledge only of its present existence as the one owner of the momentary simultaneous affections which are different in quality and in some instances spatially separated. The past existence of the mind we know only by mem- ory, by belief. Our knowledge of the permanence of the mind, therefore, like that of the succession of its experiences, is a combination of immediate knowledge and belief. But the belief of the permanence is as dis- tinct, certain, constant, persistent, as that of the suc- cession; we have the very strongest conviction that we existed in past days and past years and have endured to the present time ; and for that reason the permanence of the mind is as well entitled to recognition and place in psychology as the succession. To exclude it is quite unscientific and arbitrary. It is shutting out a part of the mental data which is as verifiable, as well attested, as the succession. Again. Not only is the permanence of the mind as THE SUBJECT OB SOUL 57 well known as the succession, but it is itself necessary to the knowledge of the succession. Without the knowledge of the permanence, the knowledge of the suc- cession would be impossible. I have already dwelt upon the important fact, very widely admitted, that a succession of thoughts is not in itself the thought of succession. A permanent element is necessary in mind, or a permanent something, as is generally maintained, by means of which, by association and comparison with which, the succession of thoughts is known as a suc- cession. Kant's well known declaration has been quoted, that the permanent is always coexistent with succession. We have before contended that a knowledge of suc- cession, or a knowledge of the past, is certainly im- possible to the stream-mind, the mind of the pure tem- poral series. For the whole of this mind at any mo- ment, the only thinker, is the present fleeting thought. But how is it possible for this thinker to know any- thing that preceded itself? How can it grasp anything beyond its momentary self, or know dead thoughts as having been in the past I It was never in the past itself, how then can it have any knowledge of the past, or know anything as having existed in the past, or know anything as an effect of the past? We must insist that it cannot know anything outside the present, and cannot know the present else than as present, else than as without any relation to the past ; that memory, the knowledge of succession and of the past, is mani- festly impossible to it. We have observed how the devotees of the mind of the pure succession get on in the absence of the permanence in mind necessary for the knowledge of succession. Hume makes the out- rageous surreption of an extra mind which he treats as 58 SUBJECT AND OBJECT the permanent surveyor, possessor and controller of the bundle of successive perceptions constituting his original and only avowed mind. By this permanent extra mind he would show how the relation of succes- sion is known. Also we have seen Professor James, after excluding in so facile a manner the permanent soul as a superfluity in the science of psychology; bring- ing in the permanent and extended brain, and making a soul of it, or spiritualizing it at least to the degree of imputing to it alone the mnemonic function of reten- tion and the possibility of recollection. What is im- possible to the pure stream-mind is at last made pos- sible by introducing the permanent brain which is adopted as the sole foundation of memory and then implicitly of all knowledge of succession and time. Thus the succession and the permanence of the mind are known together. But, as was above noted, the knowledge of either is not an immediate knowledge, but a belief. What account now can be given of this belief? How may we suppose it to originate? Upon this pro- found matter we may contend for this much, that the thought and belief in both cases are the manifestation, the expression, of the reality ; that is, if there were not real succession and real permanence, there could never be the thought or belief of them. This is our alterna- tive against the groundless hypothesis, that a dura- tionless mind, or a mere passing thought, can know permanence. Such a mind could not know mental per- manence, for there would be none to know. It could not even imagine or surmise its existence. Such a mind cannot create permanence for itself, or know it by cre- ating it; for there is no evidence whatever that finite mind possesses a power of so great creative efficiency. Rejecting for this reason the hypothesis of creation, we THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 59 are justified in the view that the best course for us, in- deed the only course, is to take these beliefs as they are and for what they are, until they are proved to be fictitious. We may conclude, at any rate, that our sense of the time or permanence of the mind has its neces- sary source and support in the mind's real tinie. The thought is the revelation of the reality ; if it were not for the reality there would be no thought. Memory and all conviction of the mind's time, all belief of its suc- cessive experiences and permanence of existence, have their indispensable basis in the actual permanence of the mind. The mind existed in the past and has en- dured to the present, and for that reason alone it can think of the past. Above we have accepted the principle that the suc- cession of our thoughts can be known as a succession only in association with permanence; and have been making the specific assumption that the primary per- manence necessary to the knowledge of the succession of thoughts is the permanence, not of the brain or any material or external object, but of the mind itself. This latter proposition undoubtedly runs counter to the doc- trine advanced by many psychologists. Kant held that the mental succession can be known only in association with permanence, but apparently teaches that the per- manence must be, not that of the mind itself, but of mat- ter; and his teaching has had a very potent influence on the later psychology. In the notable section of his Kritik d. r. Vernimft entitled "The Refutation of Idealism," he says: "I am conscious of my existence as determined in time. All time-determination pre- supposes something permanent in perception. But this permanent something cannot be anything in me; just for the reason that my existence in time can itself be 60 SUBJECT AND OBJECT determined only through this permanent something. Therefore is the perception of this permanent some- thing possible only through a thing outside of me and not through the mere representation of a thing outside of me. . . . Consciousness in time is necessarily com- bined with the consciousness of the possibility of this time-determination; therefore is it also necessarily combined with the existence of things outside of me, as the condition of time-determination. That is, the consciousness of my own existence is at the same time an immediate consciousness of the existence of other things outside of me." ^ At another place he observes: "All change, in order to be perceived as change, presupposes something permanent in percep- tion; but in the inner sense no permanent perception is to be found. " ^ In the following statement, he refers especially to "matter" as an external something pos- sessing the required permanence: "If, for example, we take the pure notions of relation, we find (1) that in order to give to the notion of substance something per- manent in perception corresponding to it (and thereby to demonstrate the objective reality of this notion), we need a perception in space (of matter), because space alone determines with permanence, while time (with all, consequently, that is in the inner sense) constantly flows. "^ But we must hold that Kant's dogma, if here rightly understood, is an error of the first significance ; it seems just the reverse of the truth. The mind knows itself as in time, or knows the succession of its states, first by means of its own permanence. Both mental succession iKritik d. r. V., p. 198. 2 lb., 207. 3 Ih., 207. THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 61 and mental permanence are cognized by the inner sense, and are cognized with equal directness and certainty. Moreover, instead of the mind being known by external permanence, the permanence of every external object is kaown primitively by the permanence of the mind. The latter is known first and most directly, and is the necessary provision for any knowledge of external per- manence. No doubt, the knowledge of the permanence and other properties of the not-self help to our ad- vanced knowledge of self; but it seems incontrovertible that we have an original empirical knowledge of self and its attributes which precedes and is entirely inde- pendent of any external knowledge, upon which external knowledge itself is entirely dependent. We should maintain the general principle, that in our knowledge we move out from the mind. The mind is our starting- place, our centre and necessary basis and object of im- mediate knowledge. The knowledge of things distinct from the mind is mediate, and the indispensable ground of the mediate knowledge, the indispensable medium, is the immediate knowledge of the mind itself or its properties. Accordingly, we must know a permanent mind, before we can know a permanent brain or a per- manent anything else. We must know subjective per- manence, before we can know objective permanence or even be able to form any conception of it. We must find permanence within mind, before we can ever find it without.^ 1 It should be remarked that the external permanence, the permanence of space or matter, which Kant affirms as necessary to the knowledge of the mind's succession or time, is, according to the fundamental prin- ciples of his epistemology, really not external, but internal, — the per- manence of the mind itself. For, in his central conception, space and all its contents, including matter, are entirely of the mind and within the mind. Their permanence must therefore necessarily be the permanence of the mind that produces and contains them. If any permanent thing 62 SUBJECT AND OBJECT When considering above the particular character of the mind's knowledge of its past and permanence, it was affirmed that this knowledge is a belief. Memory, it was said, is a union of the immediate knowledge of the present with a belief of the past ; and it was noted that one of the most urgent and important questions pertaining to our subject is, What sort of knowledge is this belief? We return to this question. Some have answered, that the belief is inferential knowledge. For instance, Mr. F. H. Bradley writes: "My past self is arrived at only by a process of inference, and by a proc- ess which also itself is fallible." ^ He says again: A direct experience "can supply us with no reality beyond that of the moment" (p. 248). We have already admitted that the mind's knowledge of its past is not immediate. Memory is not immediate knowledge of the past, because an immediate knowledge is possible only of what is present. The mind's knowledge of its past is then necessarily a mode of me- diate or indirect knowledge. But it cannot be prop- erly called inferential. For there is in it neither in- duction nor deduction, neither reasoning from particu- lar facts nor from a general principle. There is no discoverable logical process of any kind. There is cer- tainly no conscious inference, and not the slightest evidence of unconscious. Our knowledge of all external things is inferential. My knowledge of this solid rubber ball is of that charac- ter. The ball impresses my sense, and I infer the ex- istence of the ball as a cause. I reason from internal effect to external cause. But the mind's knowledge of exist outside the mind, it is, at any rate, unknowable; and hence cannot help to the knowledge of the time of the mind. 1 Appewrwnoe and Reality, p. 255. THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 63 its past, though, like that of external realities, not an immediate knowledge, is not of the same sort of in- direct knowledge, it is not inferential. The severance between the present mind and its past experience is quite different from the severance between the mind and an external object. The two breaches are entirely unlike, and they are spanned by modes of knowledge that must be unlike. The past event pertained to the mind, belonged to the mind; it belonged to the same mind to which the present recollection belongs ; the past experience and the present remembrance are affections of the one permanent and identical mind. But there is nothing like this true of an external object and the mind. This rubber ball which I am perceiving does not belong to my mind now, and never did. It has always been outside. The ball then being outside the mind, and so outside the range of immediate knowledge or conscious- ness, can be known only by inference. But the past event of mind, because it was an event of mind, was once thus an internal possession of mind, while it can- not be known immediately since it is outside the pres- ent, is not known by any act that can be called infer- ential. The mind's knowledge of its past and permanence is a unique conviction or belief. It is the belief in the present experience that it represents a past experience. We can give no further account of it than the fact that the mind itself was in the past and has endured from the past experience to the present. The past experience, which we know, is gone, and therefore cannot be known directly. But the mind which had the experience is not gone, it abides; and the abiding, permanent, identical mind, because it is such a mind, introduces into con- sciousness, by a distinctive and extraordinary means 64 SUBJECT AND OBJECT and process quite unknown to us, the belief of the past — ^makes a present thought also a recollection. The knowledge of our past experience is a more certain knowledge than the knowledge of external objects, be- cause of the intimate relation the past experience had to us, in being our internal possession. The mind had a closer hold on its past than it ever has on any external object; and because of this closer hold, it continues to maintain by memory a closer enduring hold on its past than is its inferential hold on any outside object. It is the common opinion respecting memory that thoughts do not remain stored up in the subconscious repertories of the mind, and that recollections are not the rise of the identical thoughts again into conscious- ness. All thoughts are supposed to perish; but in perishing to leave vestiges or residual effects of them- selves which have the potency of recollections. These produce recollections upon the stimulation of neural processes, just as the original experiences were pro- duced upon excitation by like processes. Recollections are new productions representing former experiences. But very many psychologists hold that the only vestiges or residua left by our thoughts are physical, modifica- tions of the brain ; that there are not any of a mental nature. It is usual to assert: "In all ideation, in every process of thought, the record of the conscious stream may be registered and conserved in the corre- lated neural process. ' ' ^ Such declarations are often made without any surmise whatever of a possible men- tal registration of thoughts. Sometimes a mental registration is expressly denied ; retention, it is said, is "not a fact of the mental order at all," but is wholly physical. I Prince, The Sutconscious, p. 121. THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 65 But we may well inquire, why should it be supposed that retention is incompatible with the nature of a soul or impossible to it ; that thoughts cannot produce in the mind itself modifications which should be permanent registers and the necessary grounds of reminiscences'? Physiologists ask us to believe too much when they aflSrm that a modification of cerebral matter alone con- tains the possibility of the conscious vision of a past event. The product seems altogether too unlike and too great for the conditions. Surely more of a cause is needed for recollections, as more is needed for presen- tations. It appears to be tacitly assumed that the brain is the necessary and sole basis of memories because of the extraordinary multiplicity of its elements and their interconnections. The millions of the cells and fibres and their conjunctions are thought to correspond to the countless memories and their associations, and to be the proper permanent grounds for them. It is sup- posed that a soul or mental substance must be of a chaotic character, undifferentiated, without minuteness and definiteness of organization, unfit as a basis for our numberless distinct and discriminated memories or ex- periences ; that it has no such perceptible multifarious- ness and fineness and completeness of structure as the brain is known to have. We would reply, that modem psychology is burdened with too many such gratuitous postulates. The mind cannot have less wealth of at- tributes and a less varied and perfect structure than any material object which it knows. All things, includ- ing the brain, are to us what we know them to be ; and we know them only representatively by the attributes of our own mind and by abstractions and inferences from these. In looking at a brain all one sees imme- 66 SUBJECT AND OBJECT diately of its diverse parts and of its whole formation is in one's own imaging percepts. The perceiving mind cannot be less rich and complete in its properties and functions than the brain it perceives. By the variety of its own properties and experiences the mind is capable of thus knowing all sorts of material objects ; and is capable of more than this — ^it has experiences, as those of pleasure and pain, over and above what it ever perceives in or imputes to material objects. Giv- ing precedence to brain or body over mind as to or- ganization and in knowledge, is but an instance of one of the most powerful and habitual of human tendencies, namely, the disposition, which begins in the earliest years, to forget or disregard self when cognizing the not-self or the external. For the above reasons it should be maintained that mind is not primarily ex- plained by nervous organism, but nervous organism by mind. To reverse this order is to deny the real order of knowledge. We hold it then further to be a reason able proposition, that our thoughts may leave traces or residual effects in the richly endowed and organized mind itself, as really as they may occasion correspond- ing effects in the brain; that the persistent mental ef- fects may be an indispensable condition of memories; and such facts as that repetition of experience strength- ens recollection, and the near is remembered better than the remote, may result in part at least from the charac- ter of the mind and its permanent changes. The mind may be regarded as the prime agent in retention or prime holder of the potentialities of memories. The mind should produce memories as well as presentations. It should reproduce because it retains. It should com- bine in itself the possibilities and functions of presen- tation, retention and reproduction. THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 67 Furthermore. If there is a soul, and if it has the capability of retention, it may be supposed to have also the capabilities of habit and heredity. Why should not the soul be able to acquire and possess habits? Why should it not be capable of inheriting and of bequeath- ing characteristics, including possibly the effects of use? Some psychologists there are who seemingly do not deny the existence of the soul, yet impute to it little or nothing of these capabilities. They tacitly assume that a spiritual substance must be lacking in them, or that it cannot have a real and indispensable and neces- sarily recognized share in habit and heredity with the body. But in what has just been said of the mind as possess- ing the capabilities of retention, habit and heredity, we have not desired to disregard or deny the offices of the physical organism in relation to these possibilities and functions. The influence upon retention and re- production, for instance, of bodily circumstances of nu- trition, waste, excitation by diseases and drugs, and age, we hold to be indisputable. What we would main- tain is, that the mind is the primary, the innermost, nearest and perpetual, ground of memory, habit and heredity. The body is a basis or support for the mind, and influences its processes; but the processes have their primary, their nearest and by far most important ground and cause in the mind, not in the body. With the knowledge of the permanence of the mind is closely associated the knowledge of its sameness. These properties may indeed be said to be one and in- separable. We are cognizant of them together in our sense of "personal identity." Our conviction of per- manent and identical existence, of being the same to-day that we were yesterday, and last month, and last year. 68 SUBJECT AND OBJECT is one of the most constant and potent convictions of the soul. How should we account for the existence of this conviction? The conviction must arise from the reality, that is, from the fact of the mind's actual iden- tity. We are convinced of permanent sameness be- cause the mind in its being is in truth the same from day to day and from year to year. The conviction arises from, is produced by, is the revelation of, real identical self -hood. It can not arise from, or be attached to, a stream or pure succession of dying thoughts, or to a momentary thought or group of thoughts. Perhaps the most important question for us at the present regarding the permanent identity of the mind, is the question of its extent or degree. Is the identity of the mind entire or partial? Is the mind in its suc- cessive and varying experiences the same always? Some have spoken of the changing experiences of the changeless mind. Some have supposed that mind must be changeless to be immortal. There are various curious facts regarding what has been called split-con- sciousness, divided self, or divided identity and ex- perience, that have drawn much recent attention. Respecting the above question, we may hold that the mind perserves sameness, but not absolute sameness. The constitutional potentialities which in their union form the one mind having normally one stream of ex- periences, maintain much identity throughout the whole course of life. But the potentialities cannot be sup- posed to remain in themselves entirely unchanged. They change by their own exercises or realizations. They produce effects within themselves. They produce effects which afterwards continually influence them and affect their actualizations. They may be supposed to undergo an evolution. Every stage contains what was THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 69 in the preceding; but yet there is change. There is sameness ; but there is also difference. It may be diffi- cult to draw the line in mind between change and con- tinuous sameness ; but there are yet decisive proofs of a considerable extent of sameness. These proofs are chiefly in the identity in character of the conscious prod- ucts — of the sensations, emotions, and volitions. Many of our sensations remain much the same through life. The same permanent external objects excite in us the same sensations. The face of a friend is readily recog- nized after years of absence. Likewise many of our emotions continue nearly the same — ^the same in them- selves and in their physical expression. The anger of the man is very much like the anger of the boy. There is constant sameness in the character of volition, and in its relation to preceding thought and feeling. Further, every man's memory carries an identical store from youth to age. These identities in our experiences prove identity in the permanent capabilities or potentialities of the mind. There is a phase of personal identity deserving notice, which may be called our moral identity. It is manifested in the feeling of guilt or responsibility for past intentions and actions. The sense of blame for a blunder or act of meanness or wrong, committed in youth, will cling to a man like a burr to the last days of his life. Here is the clear experience of life-long moral identity. With the approval of the whole community a man is hanged for a crime committed many years be- fore. This is a clear recognition of his personal same- ness enduring from the far past to the present. The present conviction or self -imputation of responsibility for past purposes, volitions and overt actions, is a dis- tinct and positive knowledge of the permanence and 70 SUBJECT AND OBJECT identity of the mind. It is possible only to a mind of such attributes. The past guilty designs and volitions are gone, are extinct ; but the agent that had them is not extinct, he survives, he has continued to the present; and in his permanent substance and permanent dis- positions and potentialities, is the bearer of guilt from the past down to the present. A mind consisting of a pure succession of thoughts, or of a present fleeting thought, would seem to be entirely incapable of such moral experiences. It is incredible that a dying thought should pass on its guilt to its successor, or that a present thought should feel responsible for a past thought that has perished. As there could be no con- viction at all of the past, there could be none of past wrong-doing. The descent of guilt seems impossible for the abstract stream of thoughts; unless the asso- ciate brain, by the permanence and identity of its sub- stance, should bear guilt along for the mental stream. Thirdly. Another primary property known of mind is Power. We are cognizant of this, for example, in the voluntary direction of the attention, and in striving to moderate or suppress a passion. Thus by volition the mind knowingly acts upon itself, or produces effects in itself. One of the great principles of Hume 's scepticism, and one of his most flagrant misrepresentations of mind, is the denial of mental power. He holds, as we have al- ready noted, that our conception of mental power or causal connection in mind is quite fictitious ; that what we take for causal connection is a pure succession of perceptions with absolutely no power, but yet a suc- cession of a special sort, namely, a customary succes- sion. Our sense of power is but the feeling arising from a constant or invariable succession. He denies THE SUBJECT OR SOUL 71 the existence of power or real causation as well inside the mind as outside. The advocates of the process- mind or stream-mind in many instances give very in- adequate recognition to the real character of volition and the exertion of mental power in it. They consider attentively the succession of our thoughts, but often bestow little or no consideration upon the actual causal relation within mind, upon the power of the mind in- volved in the action of thought upon thought. Among our primary and most certain experiences are indis- putably both succession and succession with power. The consciousness of power in volition is the revelation and representation of a real power in the mind. The thought of power has its source and basis in the reality, and has a likeness to the reality. We have claimed a direct knowledge of mind, — of its unity, ownership, power, amidst its varied simultaneous affections; and also a knowledge of the permanence and sameness of mind, which is not entirely a direct knowledge (for it involves a knowledge of the past), but is in part a belief, a mediate or indirect knowledge. But a very important question is here to be considered : Is the knowledge we thus have of mind a complete knowledge? is this knowledge coextensive with the mind's being? We cannot maintain that it is so; but must admit that there are elements, structure, proc- esses, of mind which are not reached by it, are uncon- scious, subliminal, and which, so far as they are known, are known only by obscure inference. For instance, we know nothing, save by conjecture, of the elements and structure in the mind which are the ground of the mnemonic functions of retention and reproduction. Some, as observed before, suppose that we have much more full and certain knowledge of the corporeal con- 72 SUBJECT AND OBJECT ditions of memory — of the elements and motion-paths of the brain. But this seems to be a fundamental error. It is opposed to the priority and greater nearness and certainty of the knowledge of the mind over the knowl- edge of everything else. Our knowledge of mind may be compared with our ordinary knowledge of a material object — as this rubber ball; but, as preliminary to the comparison, a question of the first consequence to be considered is. What do we really know of such an object? We certainly know the magnitude and shape of the baU. We certainly know its permanence and sameness. But we have very little knowledge indeed of its ultimate elements and inner- most structure. If the ball were divided to its last particles, we know not what these particles would be found in essence to be, whether ethereal, or electrical, or of some other sort. Something like this is true also of our knowledge of mind. We know the succession, per- manent identity, power, unity and ownership, of the mind, — very much more than could ever be known of the mind of the pure succession of thoughts, the stream- mind, or than the stream-mind could ever know of itself, and very much more than mere abstract activity, — ^but we cognize not the lowest depths of mind, its final es- sence, its innermost formation. But this ignorance no more proves that we do not know the permanent iden- tity and power of the mind, than ignorance of the final elements of a material object proves that we do not know the object's permanence and extension. We remark in general, and in conclusion, that the knowledge the mind has of itself is its supreme knowl- edge ; supreme in the sense of being its most direct and certain knowledge, and the ground and the means of the THE SUBJECT OE SOUL 73 knowledge of all other reality. The only immediate knowledge the mind has is its knowledge of itself. It certainly has much other knowledge ; it knows many things which are not present in time and space ; it has knowledge of objects that are greater than itself, — objects of longer duration, larger extension, and of superiority in every attribute ; — ^but only by a mode of cognition less direct and less certain. The mind has immediate and most certain knowledge of itself because the thing known and the knowing are in the closest pos- sible relationship ; the thing known is in the knowing ; the knowing is in the thing known. But such knowl- edge the mind has solely of itself; all other things are known only mediately, by inference and representation. No other thing whatever has so close relation to the knowing act or state as the mind itself ; everything ex- cept the mind is severed from the cognition of itself by an ontological breach, or by separation in time and space. The division, which is of the highest signifi- cance, of immediate and mediate knowledge, corre- sponds to and indicates a division of reality — a division between soul and body, or between soul and every other object animate and inanimate. It may be remarked further explicitly, that the mind always, if not neces- sarily, knows itself in comparison and contrast with other realities, especially other finite realities. But the comparison in every instance is based upon, or made possible by, the combination of two modes of knowledge — the immediate knowledge of self, and the mediate or inferential knowledge of the not-self. The means of our knowledge of outer realities, it should be expressly noted, are not media distinct from the mind, are not third things coming in between the mind and the outer objects, but the pure conscious 74 SUBJECT AND OBJECT modes of the mind itself. These modes are the grounds for inference ; they are the means of representation and depicture. Therefore the mind has, in the same cog- nitive modes, both an immediate knowledge of itself and a mediate knowledge of other things ; just as, but in a different manner, it has, in the same present mode, a knowledge of both the present and the past. Our me- diate or inferential knowledge, which constitutes the great hulk of our knowledge, thus stands upon the nar- row foundation of our immediate knowledge of mind. This foundation is indeed narrow; but it is yet alto- gether firm, safe and sufficient, because it is a direct knowledge and therefore also certain, and because, though contracted, it is still in itself rich. CHAPTEE II SUBJECT AND OBJECT IN THEIK BBLATION One of the most common and important topics in psy- chology is that of the correlation in existence and knowledge of Subject and Object. Subject is usually defined as the thinker, the knower; and Object, as the thing thought of, the thing known. But, unfortunately, many discussions of this great topic are notable for in- definiteness and vagueness. This is true especially of the discussions of idealists. There is frequent failure to describe clearly the characters of Subject and Object; to show what either is as distinguished from the other, and the real nature of their relation to one another. In treating of subject and object it is of the first moment to consider that there are two primary kinds of objects, and that these kinds are very different. The one kind is of objects that are internal, within the mind or consciousness, mental objects, very properly called subject-objects. The other is of objects outside the mind and independent of it, quite fitly called object- objects. In their treatment of the objects of thought, idealists altogether neglect and ignore object-objects. This is consistent for them ; since their greatest denial is, that objects external to and independent of the mind or consciousness do not exist. Many distinguish subject and object in this wise: object is the aggregate of the vivid states of conscious- ness; and subject the aggregate of the faint states. The difference between the vivid and the faint states 75 76 SUBJECT AND OBJECT of consciousness, between presentations and represen- tations, is manifest and permanent ; but while the two sorts of states generally differ clearly in vivacity, they are yet, at the same time, alike in being entirely sub- jective, pure subject-objects, pure states of the one real subject. A percept in itself is no more objective, and no less subjective, than a memory or any faint state of consciousness. To divide them as if they were not both alike wholly subjective, and as if the one was objective as the other was not, is a great error in dis- crimination, and a grave misuse of language. Subject and object are distinguished by many others as coordinates resulting from the differentiation of a unit — of one idea or thought or experience. Object is, by a mode of negativity, set over in opposition to sub- ject. But the antithesis is yet really only appearance. Subject and object are both in fact absolutely subjec- tive. There is but an apparent division of what is al- ways really one and indivisible; or an apparent ob- jectivization of what is never else than subjective.^ 1 Here follow from several authors Illustrative passages; which will serve also for reflection hereafter: "That though, within certain limits, we oppose the subject to the object, the consciousness to that of which it is conscious, yet that from a higher point of view this antagonism is within consciousness," etc. "The self exists as one self only as it opposes itself, as object, to itself, as subject, and immediately denies and transcends that opposition." (Oaird, Begel, p. 123 and p. 169.) "Since subject and object only exist in the unity of experience, the one is not determined by the other, but icith the other." (Baillie, Idealistic Construction of Experience, p. 198.) "All is indeed one life, one being, one thought, which only exists as it opposes itself within itself, sets itself apart from itself . . . and yet retains and carries out the power of reuniting itself." (Wallace, Logic of Hegel, 2nd ed., p. 165.) "The reality of everything lies in its pointing beyond itself to some- thing else; in other words, the real is always something which is itself and not itself in one, a unity in difference, or differentiated unity." (Nettleship for T. H. Green, Memoir, p. 110.) SUBJECT AND OBJECT 77 1. We proceed to consider, first, the true nature, but more especially the correlation, of Subject and Sub- ject-Object. Subject is the permanent and indentical Ego, Self, Soul. It is not an idea or thought, or a phase or division of thought; it is not a current of thoughts ; but an entity which exists with, and yet may exist without, thought or consciousness, and is known as identical and enduring. Subject-objects are all properties or modes of the subject — its sensations, percepts, images, memories. The more conspicuous and frequently considered sub- ject-objects are percepts, that is, our ideas of external things. Subject-objects are entirely subjective or men- tal in their nature; they are pure conscious modes of the subject or mind, having no element or property from any source outside or different from the mind; they are one with mind. For illustration, take the percept of an apple. This percept includes color and extension. Color is reckoned among the "secondary" qualities of objects; extension, among the "primary." But both the color and extension of the percept, both the secondary and primary qualities, are purely men- tal. The color is not alone mental, and the extension non-mental or extra-mental. The extension is not communicated to the mind from without and then by the mind combined with the subjective color. Both color and extension are in the mind and of the mind, are equally and altogether mental. In fact, the color "We start then with this duality of subject and object in the unity of experience. What a subject without objects, or what objects without a subject, would be, is indeed, as we are often told, unknowable; for in truth the knowledge of either apart is a contradiction." (Ward, Naturalism and Agnosticism,, II. p. 112.) "What we find is not a dualism of mind and matter, but a duality of subject and object in the unity of experience." (/6., p. 97.) 78 SUBJECT AND OBJECT and extension are not two, but one; that is, they are the inseparable original properties of one sensation. Color is in itself extended; extension is its constitu- tional attribute. Therefore, as forming a unitary and indivisible sensation, both properties must be in the same place; the extension must be in and of the mind as much and as certainly as the color. As to subject-object and subject in their relation and contrast, it should be expressly remarked, that they are not alike in nature or in function, they are not coordinate relatives or opposites, they are not equals in antithesis and synthesis. The subject-object is the transitory mode of the permanent subject, and may be either "vivid" or "faint." It is the pure product of the subject, generated from a permanent potentiality in the subject. Thus it is dependent upon the sub- ject, and the subject independent of it. But the rela- tion of the two is of the closest from first to last. The subject produces subject-objects, but never actually separates itself from them, or them from itself; it is one with them and knows itself in them. They are the conscious modes or states of the subject, mysteri- ously produced by the subject, always ontologicaUy inseparable from, and always embracing the knowl- edge of, the subject. Subject-object cannot exist with- out and apart from subject; subject does not know itself apart from and independently of subject-object. They are together in existence and inseparable in knowledge. Subject-objects are known immediately or in con- sciousness; and are the only objects so known by the mind. They are known immediately, because they are immediate to the mind, "given," present; present in the sense of existing within the mind and being modes SUBJECT AND OBJECT 79 of mind. For the same reason we are properly said to be conscious of subject-objects only. The light of consciousness is wholly produced by the mind and is wholly within the mind; and therefore only objects that are in the mind are in that light, all other objects are outside of it. If, and so far as, other objects are known, they are known without the light of conscious- ness, or, so to speak, in the dark. Subject-objects form a distinct procession and sys- tem, we may say a distinct world — ^the colored and luminous world, the internal conscious world. This world, in its whole content and structure, is formed by the mind, or by the constructive power of the mind, the intellect. It is quite distinct from the objective or external world, and owes not the least of its content to the latter. It is entirely the result of the produc- tive and constructive processes of the mind; although in these functions the mind may owe much to the ex- citation of external things. Unquestionably, subjective objects come to appear as if outside of us, of our mind and body, and far away, as also entirely independent of us. In other words, we objectivize them. In this manner, it may be truly said, ' ' the mind sets itself in antithesis to itself." But this very remarkable fact of objectivization or projection is appearance alto- gether. All the colors and light which so certainly seem to be outside of us and to be attributes of ex- ternal things, are reaUy within the mind, are pure in- ternal sensations, attributes of subject-objects; in no wise the real, but only the apparent, attributes of ex- ternal objects. Real subjectivity, and phenomenal ob- jectivity, have been generally understood and admitted of the colors and other "secondary" qualities of sub- ject-objects ; but they are as true of their primary qual- 80 SUBJECT AND OBJECT ity of extension. As above remarked, color is itself extended, extension is its inseparable attribute; and when color is projected, its extension must go with it. It should be further observed that the procession and world of subject-objects, this mental world, this in- ternal Nature, has its remarkable character and laws as a system. It has its regular coexistences, sequences, and causal connections. Its various and multitudinous objects occur together, and succeed one another, many successions being causal or consisting of cause and effect, with multiplied uniformities. These facts all manifest the wonderful productivity and constructive- ness of the subject. So much for the relation of sub- ject and subject-objects in existence and in knowledge. 2. Let us go on to consider next the relation, alike interesting and important, of objiect-objects to subject and subject-objects. Already we have defined object- objects as things outside the mind and independent of it or its thinking or consciousness. That such things exist is the fundamental doctrine of the dualistic real- ists. It is believed and defended by them as ardently as it is denied and derided by idealists. The latter contend that the existence of objects out of mind or thought and independent is altogether impossible ; that the real is the rational; that to exist is to be thought; that a division or cleft or space between mind and ob- jects, which puts objects over against mind as inde- pendent realities, is not to be considered. It is all self-contradictory and absurd. The realists main- tain in opposition that, however they may have come to exist, there are certainly objects external to and independent of our mind or thought. They adduce the existence of other men as a capital instance. The fact of other men, and their invincible antagonism to being SUBJECT AND OBJECT 81 regarded as our pure subject-objects, or as only prod- ucts or modes of our mind, they maintain, doom ideal- istic monism to an eternal overthrow. Realists hold that what idealists say of objects is indeed largely true of subject-objects ; but flagrantly untrue of object- objects. In asserting that there are objects external to and in- pendent of mind or thought, we have meant the finite, the human, mind or thought. But when idealistic monists deny the possibility of objects existing outside and independent of mind, they mean, or often mean, "aU mind"; not the human only, but both the human and the Divine. This is in consequence of their iden- tifying the human and Divine minds. They declare that the human mind, self, consciousness, experience, is but a "fragment" or "limited mode" of the Divine mind, self, consciousness, experience. There is unity or identity, not duality. But there appear to be the strongest reasons for rejecting the hypothesis of iden- tity, and for maintaining that the human and Divine are two minds. The human and the Divine are evi- dently divided in this wise: that there is immediate knowledge of the human, and nothing but an inferential knowledge of the Divine. This clear difference of knowledge must be supposed to be dependent upon a separation or duality of existence. But the great ques- tion of the relation of the human and Divine minds cannot be fully discussed here. There seems, however, to be warrant for believing in a genuine duality, and therefore for holding in regard to the relation of ob- ject-objects to mind, that there are two distinct ques- tions which may and should be treated separately; namely, the question of their relation to the human mind, and that of their relation to the Divine mind. 82 SUBJECT AND OBJECT Of the former relation we may claim to have some definite knowledge; of the latter we have very little knowledge. We may suppose that, in respect to ob- ject-objects and also all other reality, God is both im- manent and transcendent ; but we must admit that these contradictories are not easily reconciled or held to- gether. In our further discussion of the relation of object-objects to mind, we shall have in view the human mind alone. We have been contending that there are objects ex- ternal to and independent of the mind or conscious- ness ; and also that they are knowable. It must be ac- knowledged that the question of the knowableness of such objects possesses a priority; since we can claim existence only for what we know. How idealists confidently and persistently declaim against the possibility of cognizing external objects, is well known and need not be dwelt upon here. As be- fore in part noted, they argue that such knowledge is self -contradictory and impossible ; that to know a thing is necessarily to have it within mind or consciousness ; that an object exists for the subject only in being ap- prehended by it, and that "thought can never go be- yond itself" ; that the "physical thing and our idea of it are one object," a creation of the mind; etc., etc. Vig- orously opposed to the positions of the idealists have been various sects of realists who have sought to main- tain such directly antagonistic positions as the fol- lowing : that, with the consciousness of an act of knowl- edge, there goes the consciousness of the external ob- ject to which the act is relative; that there is a native or necessary and certain belief of external realities, which is universal in men; that our knowledge of the external is a belief of which the negative is incon- SUBJECT AND OBJECT 83 ceivable ; that with the consciousness of muscular sen- sations of resistance, or of voluntary energy opposed, there is combined the consciousness of external resist- ing objects ; that, in thinking of its own limits, the mind inevitably transcends them, and becomes cognizant of other finite beings, even of the Infinite. The Scottish school of philosophy, in their theory of external perception, contend for an immediate knowl- edge of extra-mental objects. This knowledge they define as an invincible and certain belief which is con- stitutional or natural to men.^ But this school, for- merly so numerous and influential in this country, un- doubtedly failed to maintain their theory, and have suffered a great loss of prestige. Their theory has been largely displaced in our institutions of learning by hypotheses composed of English and German ideal- ism — the idealism of Berkeley and Hume and that of Kant and his followers. The Scottish philosophers failed in not exhibiting a scientific warrant or justifica- tion for the avowed necessary belief in external things. They did not sufficiently consider that the belief must have evidence or a basis in knowledge. As to the per- ception of the external, we cannot rightly stop with 1 "That our sensations of touch indicate something external, extended, figured, hard and soft, is not a deduction of reason, but a, natural prin- ciple. The belief of it, and the very conception of it, are equally parts of our constitution." (Reid, Works, Hamilton's edition, p. 130.) "If asked . . . how we know that what we apprehend in sensible per- ception is, as consciousness assures us, an object, external, extended, and numerically different from the conscious subject? — ^how we know that this object is not a mere mode of mind, illusively presented to us as a mode of matter ? — then indeed we must reply that we do not in pro- priety know that what we are compelled to perceive as not-self, is not a perception of self, and that we can only on reflection Relieve such to be the case, in reliance on the original necessity of so believing, imposed on us by our nature." (Sir W. Hamilton, 76., p. 750.) According to these philosophers, then, the perception of an external object is essentially a natural and necessary belief. 84 SUBJECT AND OBJECT belief however potent or self-assured it may be; but must yet ascertain some ground for the belief in our possibilities of perception, or find that the belief in- volves, or is supported by, a genuine process of empiri- cal cognition. Object-objects, we have been saying, are knowable; and it should be further said that they are knowable by a knowledge that must be something more than a nat- ural or innate or necessary belief. The next step for us, then, is to ascertain the mode and process of this knowledge. In attempting this we shall here study brevity and confine ourselves to the more general facts ; reserving a somewhat more detailed treatment for the next chapter, in which will be considered the cognition of a particular object-object, namely, matter. First, it is to be remarked that our knowledge of object-objects cannot be immediate as is that of sub- ject-objects; because they are not present to the mind as are the latter. It must be some mode of mediate or representative or inferential knowledge. We have immediate knowledge of our percepts of external ob- jects, since they are pure mod6s of mind, and there- fore one with and inseparable from mind ; but not of the objects themselves. Our knowledge of the percepts is immediate; that of the objects mediate. Again, in other words, we cannot be said to be conscious of ob- ject-objects as we are of subject-objects ; since they do not come into the bright sphere of consciousness as do the others, but subsist in outer darkness. We may be conscious of an act of knowledge without being con- scious of the external object to which the act is relative. Many realists, in claiming an immediate knowledge or consciousness of external realities, are certainly in error. They mistakingly pretend to what in fact they SUBJECT AND OBJECT 85 do not have and what is impossible ; and by so doing weaken the case of realism. If our knowledge of object-objects is wholly inferen- tial or mediate, the first move is to endeavor to show what are the media of the knowledge, i. e., the means by which the object comes into relation to the subject, and the subject to the object and apprehends it. These media are not tertia quaedam, numerically different from both the mind and the objects, and en- tering between them; but are pure subject-objects, the pure internal sensations and percepts. By these media, modes of the subject itself and immediately known, we attain a knowledge of objects not immedi- ately known. By modes of consciousness, as the indis- pensable means or ground, we acquire a knowledge of things outside of consciousness. According to these statements, the relation of the media to the subject knowing obviously must be very different from their relation to the objects known. The media are modes of the subject, are immediate to it, are one with it. But they are quite distinct and apart from the ob- jects; they can be at best only distant representations, to some extent copies, of the objects. They may be said then to stand between us and objects; but the conclusion cannot be rightly deduced that they hide objects from us, or that a true knowledge of objects, of objects as they are in themselves, is not possible through them as distant representations. Berkeley's reasoning against the possibility of a representative knowledge of external sensible things is in no wise de- cisive or final. We have been all along speaking of and postulating spatial outsidedness or externality. "We are bound be- fore proceeding farther to give some account of it and 86 SUBJECT AND OBJECT of our assumption. The first and fundamental cogni- tion of spatial externality is of the externality of one point in an extended sensation to another, and of the externality of one sensation to another. This experi- ence of reciprocal externality within the sphere of the pure subjective sensibility, seems to be an indispen- sable condition of our cognition of the reciprocal ex- ternality of mind and the extra-mental. Our knowledge of external objects is, primitively and fundamentally, our inference of them as the causes or occasions of our sensations and percepts. But how does the subjective thought make the inference of the external cause? What excites and guides it to this remarkable leap? We have first, in the interaction of our sensitive organs, as hands and arms, and of our moving organs and trunk, experience of their recipro- cal production in themselves of sensations. One organ excites sensation in another, and has sensation ex- cited in itself by that other. When, after some ex- perience, though it be yet vague, of this reciprocity of our sensitive parts and organs, we have experience in one organ of such tactual and muscular sensations as we have felt when the organ was impressed or re- sisted by another organ, but have not concurrent sim- ilar sensations in another organ, — i. e., when we have a single set of sensations and not a double, or sensations only on the one side, — ^we jump to the inference of an external resisting object as the cause of the sensations, as a cause operating like the resisting sensitive organ and cause we have known. We conclude in particular that the external resisting object is extended, from the extension of the sensations it excites. In such a man- ner as this, stated thus with much brevity and general- SUBJECT AND OBJECT 87 ity, we infer external objects as causes ; so we pass from the internal known to the external unknown. Accordingly, our knowledge of external objects is en- tirely inferential. They are never immediately known, they are never directly seen, they never really appear. The only objects immediately known, or directly seen, or really appearing, are subject-objects. By means of these latter, however, as indispensable media, we reach object-objects through inference alone, but through in- ference that is true ; we represent them as they are in themselves, in their most important properties and re- lations, namely, their real durations, spatial extensions, motions, interactions, successions. The general result therefore is a doctrine directly contrary to that of the Scottish school. They contend that our perception of external extended things is "not a deduction of rea- son," but a natural and necessary belief. Here it is maintained that the perception is a deduction of reason or an inference, and is not a natural and necessary be- Hef. It will probably contribute to distinctness, if we shall compare the above theory of the perception of external objects with what is called the "window" theory of per- ception and so often ridiculed by idealists. In the "window" theory, which in important elements is Locke's theory, the mind is thought of as an empty room into which outside things introduce a knowledge of themselves through the senses which are likened to windows. The mind is represented, not as productive and synthetic, but as passive and receptive only. Knowledge, as if ready-made, is presented by objects, and received into itself by the mind. The "window" hypothesis mistakes fatally in con- 88 SUBJECT AND OBJECT ceiving the mind as only passive and receptive in the knowledge of the external, and in quite overlooking its generative and constructive activity. All our cognitive states or modes referring to the external — our sensa- tions, percepts, images — are products of the mind itself and are wholly internal and mental. The mind sup- plies from within itself all the materials of percepts, and is their sole architect. External objects communi- cate nothing like ready-made knowledge of themselves to the entirely passive mind ; they impart not the least portion of the materials that enter into a knowledge of themselves. They are indeed not entirely inactive re- specting our knowledge of them; but their activity is particular and limited — it is only stimulation and a certain amount of regulation. They stir the mind to produce sensations and percepts representative of themselves, and exercise some control over the produc- tion ; but the mind yet furnishes from within itself all the materials of percepts, and is the sole framer of them. But though the activity of external things respecting our perception of them is of this simple and restricted character, still the importance of it must be recognized as being very considerable. We notice particularly the importance of its regulative influence upon the activity of the mind. In the production of inferences and rep- resentations of external objects, the mind does not act capriciously, irregularly, and arbitrarily, in total inde- pendence of the external objects ; but is in a degree gov- erned by the objects. Objects impart no cognitions or materials of cognitions to the mind ; these, as just said, are whoUy produced by the mind itself ; but they to an extent determine the mind in its productivity. For in- stance, the intensity, duration, and extension of sensa- SUBJECT AND OBJECT 89 tions and percepts are not the result entirely of the spontaneous, wholly independent and wayward purpose and action of mind; but are determined in a measure by the force, duration, and extension of the impressions made by particular objects on our sense-organs. The duration and extension of a sensation or percept are thus made like those of the impressing face of an ex- ternal object. Therefore while the mind is so fully active and productive in its perceptions of outer ob- jects, it is yet to this important degree passive and de- pendent; and while objects are so fully passive in our cognition of them, they are yet at the same time, to a significant degree, regulatively active. The most peculiar and remarkable fact pertaining to our knowledge of the external world is the involuntary projection into it of our sensations, percepts, subject- objects. So potent becomes the tendency, so com- pletely established the habit, even in the earliest life (on account to some extent probably of inherited incli- nation), of projecting the mental modifications or states, that they do not at all seem to belong to us, but to be distinct and remote objects or qualities of them. For example, colors appear to be the properties of dis- tant and independent objects. Sound appears to inhere in or to be at a distant object, as a bell. My percept of a tree seems to be a tree far off. Certainly, then, we ordinarily conceive ourselves clearly to see colored material objects and illuminated space, as if outside the mind. There are indeed outside extended objects and space, but we do not really see them, that is, we are not immediately cognizant, or conscious, of them. We only see, or are immediately cognizant of, our pure internal colored percepts which we project upon the external colorless realities. Our conscious percepts are thrown 90 SUBJECT AND OBJECT out upon the extended objects wMcli are inferred, and serve as representations of them. The really internal and small percept, as a visual image, serves as a sign and representation of vastly extended external reality, and appears as externalized. Accordingly, knowledge, instead of being received into the mind from the outside world, is rather projected from the mind upon the out- side world. As a painter depicts his ideal upon the canvas, so the mind projects and overspreads its light and percepts upon the external extended world as its canvas or screen. We must not, however, fail duly to recognize the im- portance of the stimulation from the actual external extended reality in the rise of sensations and percep- tual material and the production and projection of per- cepts. If there were no external extended objects to occasion the production of the pure subjective percepts, there would be no apparent projection of percepts from the mind. If external realities made upon the sense no impressions of definite extensions, definite dura- tions, and definite strengths, there would not arise, as far as we can know, any definite percepts and any thought of existence outside of mind. The mind would not, of its pure spontaneity, produce such percepts, or dream of anything as external to itself. The greatest aberrations of idealists have relation to this phenomenon of projection. They suppose that the only objects in existence are the projected subject-ob- jects. When they speak of Subject and Object, they mean by outer object the externalized subject-object. According to the Hegelian idealism, as before indicated, the mind or thought is at first entirely subjective, or neither subjective nor objective. It proceeds from its own initiation to differentiate itself into subject and SUBJECT AND OBJECT 91 projected object; and then again identifies subject and object. There is first antithesis, which is followed by synthesis ; but the procedure and results are yet wholly within and of the unitary consciousness or thought. The Hegelian idealism may be described briefly, in its totality, as the hypothesis of the single world-thought developing by triadic self-evolution — evolution, wholly self-originated and self -continued, by thesis, antithesis, and synthesis. It is a supreme error of idealism, that the mind pro- jects subject-objects by its own self-originated motion. No doubt, projection is wholly the activity, the invol- untary activity, of the mind; but not of its self -initi- ated, or self-occasioned, or internally originated, activ- ity. There never would be the phenomenal projection of subject-objects, if there were not object-objects, real external and independent things, to move the mind to the action. Before externalization takes place and is possible to mind, the mind must have some knowledge, some inferential knowledge, of real external objects. This knowledge it acquires by means of the tactual and muscular sensations primarily, in such a manner as was above summarily described. The mind then first pro- jects sensations to particular places, because of its pre- vious knowledge of real external objects existing at those places and occasioning the sensations. If there were not the previous knowledge of external objects as causes of sensations, there would never be the projec- tion of sensations. In our external perception, there is a singular com- bination or fusion, so to speak, of projected subject- objects and object-objects— of what is in consciousness, with what is outside^ — of what we know immediately, with what we know only inferentially and representa- 92 SUBJECT AND OBJECT tively — ^which epistemologists have not considered. For example, in my cognition of a man standing near me on the street, there is embraced my colored and ex- tended percept projected upon him, and his own ex- tended body which is truly external to and independent of me. I have immediate knowledge, I am conscious, of the percept, for it is a pure subject-object, a pure mode of mind ; but I am not immediately cognizant, or conscious, of the body of the man. I only infer its ex- istence at the place whither I project my percept. I am conscious of the reference of my percept to the body, or I am conscious of my inference of the body; but not of the body itself. The latter I know only by inference and representation through the percept of which I am conscious. In other words, in seeing an- other person we have both mediate and immediate sight. Our vision of the person is only and altogether mediate sight, and the medium is our own pure visual percept. But of the percept itself we have immediate sight. The person is altogether outside our conscious- ness, and is not and cannot be immediately seen. He is seen only by representation in our conscious, or imme- diately known, or immediately experienced, percept. But the representative knowledge is genuine knowl- edge ; it is true to the real external and extended body. Not merely the bare existence of the body is known, but also the primary qualities of size and figure. Only the hardihood of idealism that hath no fear of solip- sism before its eyes can assert that there is no other object cognized than our percept, the pure subject- object; and that the supposed body of the man, or the whole man, is identical with the subject-object, is there- fore a pure mode of our consciousness, or has no exist- SUBJECT AND OBJECT 93 ence whatever as a reality outside and independently of our mind. The same statements are applicable in general to the cognition of any other external object. In my per- ception of the tree I was viewing through my window a moment ago, there were combined in the same single cognition the immediate knowledge of my green and extended percept and the representative knowledge of the extended and permanent tree which is really ex- ternal to and independent of me, and upon which I pro- jected the percept. The perception unites the con- sciousness of the percept and the consciousness of the percept as a representation of an object outside of con- sciousness; it unites the knowledge of what is really inside of mind with the knowledge of what is really outside; just as memory unites in the same mode of mind an immediate knowledge of the present and a representative knowledge of the past. Our eye illu- minates and adorns outer objects with its extended col- ors ; or it may be said in general that the mind, in its cognition of the external world, floods it with its own internal light, — as the head lamp of a railroad engine, the iron cyclops, pours its light far along the track in front, or as the search-light of a war-ship (to em- ploy again an illustration used before) illumines a wide expanse of sea. An important conclusion involved in the facts and principles just enunciated is, that all the materials im- mediately dealt with by all the sciences, both mental and physical, are identical, namely, the pure subject- objects or the pure phenomena of mind.^ But the 1 Similar assertions are made by idealistic psychologists : "The phases of experience dealt with in the natural sciences and in psychology 94 SUBJECT AND OBJECT modes of handling tlie common materials are clearly different. Psychology treats the materials, the sub- ject-objects, especially as they are in themselves, or in their relation to the mind and their relations to one another. Physical science treats them in their rela- tion to external material objects, or as representations of such objects; or, what comes to the same, it treats external objects as represented by the pure sub- jective experiences. The main concern of physical science is with external material objects, its proper ob- jects. These objects, however, are not, and cannot be, immediately known; they are known only mediately through the pure modes of the mind. Physics then, like psychology, deals directly only with the subjective modes; while its primary interest is not, like that of psychology, in the directly known internal experiences, but in the external realities mediately known through them. In correspondence with the above view, it must be admitted that there is a certain measure of truth in such general declarations of idealists as, that "the field of science is the contents of the mind"; for, un- doubtedly, the only immediate facts or contents in every sort of scientific thought and research are the pure mental percepts or experiences. But while in science we deal immediately only with mental con- tents, yet, at the same time, we deal also mediately, are nothing but phases of one experience regarded from different points of view." (Wundt, Psychology (Judd), p. 361.) "If it is true that all the sciences have the same sort of subject- matter, there can be no essential difference between the raw materials of physics and the raw materials of psychology." "Physics and psychology deal with the same stuff, the same material." {Titchener, Text-Book of Psychology, p. 6 and p. 8.) These declarations indubitably express important truth; still they do not by any means sustain the idealistic premise of the writers. SUBJECT AND OBJECT 95 through, the mental contents, with realities that are not contained in the mind but are distinct and apart from it; as our fellow-men, material objects, and others. In the scientific treatment of matter, we handle di- rectly only the pure mental percept; but at the same time mediately, through the percept as a representa- tion, we truly deal with real external, matter or its properties — its real extension, permanence, and mo- tion or activity. The remark has been made, that "when we classify plants by their resemblances, we classify the plants and not the impressions." This is true; yet it must be acknowledged that the only re- semblances immediately known and dealt with are the resemblances of the impressions or percepts. The re- semblances of the external plants which are indeed the primary concern, are yet cognized only through those of the percepts. We may observe further upon the notable declaration with which Schopenhauer begins his principal work, and which is of similar import to the assertion respecting the field of science just quoted above, — Die Welt ist meine Vorstellung, — that this declaration includes and excludes the same measure of truth as the other. The world we immediately know is, doubtless, the internal world of our representations ; but we also mediately know, by these representations, an external world of extended and permanent realities. Schopenhauer's saying would be much nearer the truth if it could be rendered. My knowledge of the world is my representation. It is necessary to recognize the existence of two worlds or two Natures, the internal and the external, the subjective and the objective. Each of these, as we have been postulating, is a system or cosmos, possess- ing its own great multitude and variety of peculiar ob- 96 SUBiJECT AND OBJECT jects with their laws — ^their regular coexistences, se- quences, and causal connections. First, there is the internal world of our thoughts, feelings and volitions — subject-objects — ^with the laws of their occurrence. Secondly, there is the world of animate and inanimate realities — of extended, enduring and moving reali- ties — wholly outside and independent of the world of subject-objects, ruled by their own laws, or corre- lated in uniform sequences, spatial coexistences, and interactions. But while the objective world is wholly independent, in its objects and laws, of the subjective, it is wholly dependent upon the latter in making itself known. The objective, in its individuals, laws, and systemic oneness, is known only mediately through the subjective. The properties of its objects and the co- existences, successions, and causal connections, are known by like properties and relations of the sub- jective objects ; and known truly, known as they are in themselves. Without such internal representative properties and relations, the properties and relations of external realities would not be known.^ Both sorts of objects are known by the same identical cognitive mode, the one immediately, the other mediately. Still, though the mind wholly of itself furnishes the materi- als, and all the constructive labor, in its cognition of the external world, it is not active only, but is to some de- gree passive and dependent upon the outside realities. The constant and habitual relations of subject-objects are dependent to some extent upon the uniform rela- tions of external objects as these impress themselves 1 In that sense, we may accept the declaration, that "in self -conscious- ness are implicitly contained all the categories by which science and philosophy attempt to make the world intelligible." (Caird, Hegel, p. 150.) In that sense, but only in it, is the mind "legislative" over nature. SUBJECT AND OBJECT 97 upon the mind. The external objects and their rela- tions in no manner generate the internal ; for the mind generates them itself; hut they certainly influence the mind in the production of its representative objects and relations. These several principles, it may be briefly observed further and finally, are exemplified by the action of the mind in every science. The science of astronomy is indisputably a systematic construction of the human intellect; but, we may contend, there would not be a science of astronomy, if there were not a great system of external celestial moving realities, and if these had not influenced the constructive processes, and deter- mined the product, of the intellect. The intellect em- braces both the internal and external worlds simul- taneously, in the same science ; a result of the fact that both worlds are known by the same cognitions, though differently. The two worlds are indeed distinct; but they are combined by the unity of knowledge — ^by the unity of knowledge that is both immediate and medi- ate. The same cognitive mode is in itself both a sub- ject-object and the representation of an object-object. Hence both subject-objects and object-objects can be handled by the intellect in scientific thought, and are comprehended by it in the same science. We may now fitly turn to consider the specific doc- trines of many psychologists, that the knowledge of subject or self requires the knowledge of other selves ; and that our knowledge of external inanimate nature depends upon our knowledge of other persons. They say that we know self in knowing other people ; ^ and t "The Self of any man eomes to consciousness only in contact with other selves." (Eoyce, Psychology, p. 297.) "A vague belief in the ex- istence of our fellows seems to antedate, to a considerable extent, the 98 SUBJECT AND OBJECT know outer physical things because we know that other people know them.^ Some define the subjective as that which is "special to me"; and the objective, as that which is "common to all." This teaching appears extravagant and unwarrant- able. No doubt it comes to pass that the knowledge of the self is always united with or involves the knowl- edge of other selves ; for the reason, that we are always closely associated in life with others. Constantly with us and constantly affecting us, they are constantly rec- ognized with our knowledge of self. But there is a primitive, a first, it may be only an inchoate or rudi- mentary, knowledge of self which precedes our knowl- edge of other selves and is wholly independent of it. This view is in agreement with important principles expounded above. Our knowledge of self is immedi- ate and it is our sole immediate knowledge; (all other definite formation of any consciousness of ourselves.'' {The World