BOUGHT WITH THE l»COME OF THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF 1891 B-.^a.S'i^aBk 3,.4^::': THE SHIFTING OF LITERARY VALUES BY ALBERT MORDELL THE INTERNATIONAL 236 Chestnut Street Philadelphia, Pa. Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/cletails/cu31924026939672 Cornell University Library PN 45.M83 Shifting of literary values. 3 1924 026 939 672 THE SHIFTING OF LITERARY VALUES BY ALBERT MORDELL THE INTERNATIONAL 236 Chestnut Street PhiUdelphla, Pa. 1912 COPYRIGHT, 1912 by Albert Mordell CONTENTS. Chapter. Page. Peefacb ,. . . 3 I. LiTEBAEY Values Change 6 II. Some Overestimated Classics . . ., 21 III. The Eeroes of Literary Criticism 34 IV. Literature Progresses Like Science 42 V. Ideas More Important Than Form 51 VT. Historical Criticism and The Classics 59 VII. The Causes op Liteeary Fame 68 VIII. The Dangerous Influence of Some Classics 79 PEEFACE. The author of the following essay has undertaken to establish that changes in morality must affect lit- erary values, that some of the classics idealize views of life now obsolete, that these books are therefore responsible for the existence of some of our moral and intellectual stagnancy, and that a new critical outlook upon them is called for. This essay is not the result of a mere desire to dethrone literary idols, but has been the product of a conviction fortified by years of ex- tensive reading and careful deliberation, that litera- ture, having been the depository of men's thoughts in the past, must wane in artistic value, after the world has discovered that these ideas were false. The author has purposely endeavored not to allow himself to be influenced by the grand eulogies that have heretofore been pronounced upon these classics; he has resolved not to be daunted even when the oldest and most famous books are involved. But while differ- ing from the doctrines of life taught by them, he has tried to maintain the utmost respect for both book and author. For instance, while he shares the opinions of Taine and Johnson in regard to Paradise Lost, he most ardently admires the personality of Milton. Though he confesses to have been bored by the Iliad and be- lieves that it has been too extravagantly praised, he is greatly moved by the speeches in the sixth, twenty-sec- ond and twenty-fourth books. He has also remembered that it is best not to ad- vance one's views in too polemic a spirit ; that an undig- nified defense of the truth itself may displease the reader more than a subdued defense of falsehood. He therefore requests the reader 's indulgence for any por- tions of the essay where the author 's feelings have got- ten the better of his judgment and self-restraint. He (3) does not wish to make any unwilling converts to Ms views and has tried not to shock any one's sensibilities. He merely requests an impartial and critical considera- tion of the principles laid down. It will be noticed that the author attacks chiefly those books whose morality is rigorous, crabbed and narrow. He believes that men must be taken as they are, that too much must not be demanded of them ; they must be given a certain measure of liberty. They can- not live in accordance with the doctrines taught by Seneca, Plato, Marcus Aurelius and Epictetus of the Pagans, and a Kempis, St. Augustine, Bunyan and Pascal of the Christians. These authors, while often embodying good precepts, also incorporate the most fallacious views of stoicism and monasticism. They decry our instincts and set up abstract theories of con- duct not founded either on experience or human nature. Aristotle long ago deprecated that philosophy which taught that pleasure was bad with the object of draw- ing men towards a possible mean. But he understood that a contrary result is often attained. "In matters relating to men's feelings and actions," he said, "theories are less convincing than facts. Whenever, therefore, they are found conflicting with actual experience, they not only are despised, but involve the truth in their fall. ' ' The author has also made objects of his attack — and he admits it with reluctance rather than arrogance — some of the world's greatest poets. He believes that they have corrupted their poetry by too close an ad- herence to the errors of their religion. They did not ally themselves with the more progressive element, did not foresee the triumph of more rational and liberal views. Pindar and Aeschylus championed the gods and the superstitions of traditional religion ; they have not the broadness of vision that we find in the Age of Peri- cles. It is well known and admitted by students of Dante that he was not moved by the richest ideas of the Ren- aissance, while Tasso was too eager to become the poet of Medieval Christianity to concern himself with the more humanistic ideas of the time previous to his. Similarly, Spenser and Milton had been trying to ser- monize in support of their faiths, and as a result we do not get that more wholesome view of life had they thought more of their art and less of th6ir religion. If the author has been too harsh with these writers he hopes that he makes amends by his enthusiasm for those other classics, just as famous and often admitted to be greater, where the authors are broader in their outlook upon life and were not too closely tied down to traditional religious errors. He is second to none in his admiration for writers like Aristotle, Thucydides, Plutarch, Lucian, Lucretius, Tacitus, Horace, Machia- veUi, Montaigne, Chaucer, Bacon, Spinoza, Cervantes, Moliere, Fielding, Sterne, Voltaire, Diderot, Goethe, etc. The author also wishes to state that he has lighted upon the germ of the ideas in this essay in writers, so different as Shaw and Balfour, Maeterlinck and Al- den, the Editor of Harper's Magazine. He must also record his debt of gratitude to those three authors, now dead, but typical of the spirit of the age — Nietzsche, Whitman and Ibsen, and to that greatest liv- ing critic — George Brandes. Albebt Moedell. Philadelphia, July, 1912. CHAPTER I. LITERARY VAIUES CHANGE. 1. There are several hundred universally famous books that have come down to us approved by the voice of the past. There is here and there a dissenting opin- ion in regard to the merits of some of these works, but on the whole the place that they have taken is pretty well established. Mankind seems to be very reluctant in attacking their greatness. Yet one may be permitted to ask, Is it not possible that out of these, let us say two or three hundred vol- umes, there may not be a score or even two score of books whose fame is due to other causes than intrinsic literary merit? May not some embody a philosophy of life that is absolutely false and may it not also be couched in a form that is obsolete in our time? May not some be usurpers in the shrine of literary fame and have deserved their reputation much less than more worthy claimants? Is it not rather striking that, dif- fering as we do in our ideas as to what constitutes beauty and truth from the people of past ages, that we should still be agreed with them as to what are the most beautiful books? Views of life change; why then should not our attitude towards books, which are only views of life, also change ? Our notion as to what are beautiful forms and truthful ideas alter ; why not our criticism of books which incorporate these forms and ideas ? The central idea of modern literature is self-devel- opment as opposed to the hitherto central idea of lit- erature which was self-sacrifice. Modern literature like that of Ibsen is strongly individualistic; it advo- cates self-realization, attacks blind worship of custom, points out the evils of some of our institutions, treats the body with proper respect and allows the pursuit of (6) worldly goods. It is usually conceded that these ideas are saner than those that ruled of old, which taught that the pursuit of happiness was sinful, the develop- ment of one's individuality, a heresy, the martyring of one's self by torturing the body, a virtue. If then the idea of self -development is the true idea and self-sac- rifice the false one, literature founded upon the latter idea must be the inferior. Many of the classics are based on this falser idea. Yet we worship them though we are opposed to all the ideas that they idealize. We are told that just that literature which burns incense before an unreasonable ascetic ideal possesses the high- est merit. Many of the books undeservedly famous today are those in which the leading character or hero is some one who follows out all the mandates of puritan- ism or monastic morality, who pays most homage to conventional duty. We are told to admire the ideas of Ibsen and at the same time those books the ideas of which are antagonized by him. As a matter of fact these famous books must have less literary value for us, if we discard the notion of self-sacrifice. No matter how old or sacred they are, they become from our point of view immoral and bad art. In past literature we often find fashioned theories of life which are not only inappropriate, but actually harmful to us. We find in past literature the formula- tion of worn out and obsolete ethical maxims. We find what we, at least, consider confusion reigning as to what is right and wrong, truth and falsehood, as to what is good and bad, beautiful and ugly. If all these ideas are repugnant to us, our critical attitude towards the books expounding them must change. Whenever moral ideas change the result is a new outlook upon life and hence a new view or criticism of literature which is that outlook upon life. It must be shown that litera- 8 ture which advocates these worn out doctrines has ebhed in value for us. It might be asserted that the great masterpieces are not affected by the changes in ideas. But it is chiefly they that are most affected. The ancient sec- ondary literature was merely concerned with the aesthetic presentation of truisms that never change despite the revolutions in ideas. But it is in the master- pieces in which are crystallized the tendencies of an age that has gone, the ideas of a people which no longer sway mankind, the aspirations and false illusions that have even become the laughing stock of our world. Pre- cisely the classics, particularly the classics of monastic- ism and Puritanism lose in force, for here above all are reflected in every possible manner the various phases of movements that seethed with the errors of mankind. Just those books that were most representative of their age, that most focussed the tendencies of a movement that has disappeared, have lost in artistic value >i for us. When ideas which have been an ancient people 's reality have become for us but a memory, when ideals which were the staff of yesterday have become the stum- bling block of our time, the literature in which these are embodied cannot be our spiritual guides. "It is not without deep pain," says Nietzsche, "that we acknowledge the fact that in their loftiest soar- ings, artists of all ages have exalted and divinely trans- figured precisely those ideas which we now recognize as false; they are the glorifiers of humanity's religious and philosophical errors ; and they could not have been this without belief in the absolute truth, of these errors. ' ' "We might add that the more sincere the artist was in his convictions and the more he represented the spirit of his times, the more fanatical would his art appear to us. The greater his art was esteemed in his day, the more probably he embodied the chief errors of his age. The more truthful the utterances appeared to him and his admirers, the more false they are likely to be to us. Past literature is a large mausoleum in which lieC_ the eflBgies of the old movements that are dead beyond resurrection. Ethics hampered by absolute standards that did not consider the facts of human nature, dying religions fettered with articles of faith now destroyed by the simplest scientific principles, groundless philo- sophical speculations losing themselves in metaphysical mazes, — 'these are in back of the ideas of life and no- tions of beauty entertained by some of the most promi- nent authors of the past. These errors should be allowed to slumber instead of being revived by worshiping the books in which they are incorporated. If monasticism, feudalism, Puritanism and other forms of asceticism, are gradu- ally losing their hold upon the moral and intellectual forces in mankind, one sees no reason why we should enter into the spirit of these movements, by worshiping the books to which they have given birth. These books have a historical value, but they should not be forced upon us when they teach us views of life that it is to the world's interest to let repose in oblivion. Where an ancient author has praised is often for us the signal for awakening our deepest hatred ; where he has lavished the most glorious outbursts, is often where we should direct our most malignant venom. If we agree with Ibsen, who shows us that many of the duties that we believe we owe to society are imaginary ones, are merely the result of hide-bound customs, ham- per our spiritual life and are stumbling blocks in our progress, why should we go into raptures over old works of art which strictly enjoin upon us the per- formance of these imaginary duties? We cannot bow down to that which sings of the healthiness of an idea which we perceive to be wrong. 10 Old classics have cast a halo about duties that superstitious authors thought we owed to the church or the king or the public. If to-day no one thinks that these obligations should be required of him, why this deference to books, that exalt these duties and treat a neglect of their performance, as an odious crime? If a book has been written which treats as a heresy an act which we regard as noble, or condemns a good act or thought as a blasphemous one, or depicts a really worthy character as a base one, we cannot accept it as a great book. If the author allows the characters to be mouthpieces for his own pernicious doctrines and approves of conduct that ought to be censured, his work is artistically affected. The fact that we are outgrowing some of the old notions. of morality must necessarily make us less en- raptured with books where these notions are idealized. Since our ideas in art and morality are being modified and often reversed, it would be most extraordinary if we saw in these classics all the merits that the ancients saw therein. Moreover, we should not try to appre- ciate these books lest we descend to the intellectual level of our ancestors. The real value of the literary productions of the past should be proportional to the intellectual strength therein. It should depend upon the truth of their cen- tral ideas, upon the soundness of their philosophy of life. That literature which was most thoroughly per- meated with the spirit of an ancient age is now bad art, if that spirit was all wrong. Wherever dogma has reigned, it has moulded art to conform to it. Wherever false creeds have pre- vailed, the arts have been corrupted by them. The books that were most impregnated with emotions connected with these false dogmas and creeds are the ones that should not be placed in the list of the world's best books. 11 2. If art and literature are to teach us what is beautiful, we might reply that many ancient books and art works cannot do this because our conceptions of beauty change. We canot be expected to go to the books of the monastic and puritan ages to teach us anything about beauty. Authors who taught that we should stifle our instincts, not think of sexual matters, and who decried our bodies, cannot be authorities on what is beauty, for a well-developed masculine body is beautiful and our perception of beauty is wrapped up with our sexual instincts. Those books which call upon us not to think of this earth but only of heaven, to hate color, form, scented odors, harmonious sounds, cannot give us the true conception of beauty, when they deprecate all that constitutes it. Literature has always described man's attitude towards women, his conception of love and his mode of love-making. But all these change in different ages and the books which describe and defend the old views must lose in artistic value. We cannot approve of those books that treat of love as being nothing more than lust affiliated with none of the finer qualities in human nature. On the other hand, we believe that it is falsely delineated where it is treated only as a gal- lant feeling not in the least tinged with sexual interest. An ignorant person will do his courting in an en- tirely different manner from an intelligent one. At one time force was the only means of courting ; at another time a woman was purchased. The world changes its ways of love-making, and literature, which approvingly depicts an obsolete fashion of courting, cannot mean for us what it formerly meant. We do not believe woman to be the immaculate, pale, soulful, useless creature that the age of chivalry regarded her; we do not think she was the vile and cursed person that the monks considered her; we do not look upon her as the mere servant of man as the 12 ancient Greeks did ; we do not think of her simply as an object to satisfy man's desires, as some of the profli- gate Eomans did. In all those books where women are treated from these viewpoints, we do not find our con- ception of women, and hence these books are false to us. Taste changes because human nature changes. What was sublime to one age becomes ridiculous to another age. We do with approval things which would have shocked the sensibilities of our forefathers. We look composedly at spectacles over which they would have wept, we are repelled by deeds which it was the height of their ambition to achieve. Other habits and desires have taken hold upon us and we are not the same kind of people as they were. ^ 3. Every new philosophic school, every great scien- tific discovery makes some change in our ethical be- liefs, and hence in our literary judgments. When the modern school of philosophy with Des- cartes, Spinoza and Baeoli at their head dealt the death blow to scholastic philosophy, literary opinions that held sway during the ages when scholastic philos- ophy ruled, changed. Many hitherto famous authors were forgotten and obscure ones came into prominence. ^The philosophical principles to which a man adheres largely determines his moral and literary views. A disciple of Kant will in all probability adopt the theory of the Categorical Imperative in morals, namely, to do that which would do no harm if every one else did the same thing. A pupil of Bacon would be very much inclined to attach himself to a morality of expediency. The literature that the former would prefer would be the kind that insists sternly on duty to the exclusion of happiness. The books that the latter would care for would be those where some rein is given to the joyous instincts of mankind. 13 Discoveries in science must also affect our criti- cism of books. Our attitude towards life and hence art, must be affected by a discovery which teaches man that this planet is but one insignificant world in an in- finite number, instead of being the one for which all the rest have been created; or by a discovery which shows us that we are but one of the myriads of infinite organisms and that the same forces that have governed their growth have evolved us, instead of our being specially brought forth as we are, with all other living creatures placed particularly for our use. If science has taught us that there never was an original state of perfection from which there was a fall but, on the contrary, a gradual rise, if she has shown us that our . morality, intellect, feelings and our most sacred insti- tutions have been made what they are by circum- stances and environment without divine interference; if it has been proven to us that the laws of nature are the same in the remotest corner of the universe as they are on this earth ; how can we be enraptured with liter- ature which teaches us the ideas that man believed when he held the opposite beliefs ? "Where the ideas of morality and decency alter from one age to another," Hume points out in an essay on the standard of taste, "and where vicious manners are described without the proper character of blame and disapprobation, this must be allowed to disfigure the poem, and to be a real deformity. * * * We are dis- pleased to find the limits of vice and virtue so much confounded: and whatever indulgence we may give to the writer on account of his prejudices, we cannot pre- vail on ourselves to enter into his sentiments, or bear an affection to characters which we plainly discover to be blamable." But are we not asked to enter into the sentiments of these characters which we find blamable, if we are asked to worship the book? One cannot really admire 14 the book witliout accepting the leading ideas of the book. If manners are described in such a way that it is apparent that the author stamps them as exemplary, we cannot approve of those manners if they are vicious or in bad taste ; hence we cannot love the work where those manners are upheld. If, as Hume says, the limits of vice and virtue are confounded, if that which is permissible or justifiable is described as an enor- mous vice, if that which is blind custom or rank stu- pidity is depicted as a great virtue, we cannot accept the author's notions of art and morality; nor can we worship at the shrine of a book filled with these errors. The literature of ancient times after all could do nothing more than to express the then commonly ac- cepted ideas. It did not, as a rule, rise above the in- tellectual level of the age. It conformed to certain standards above which it did not rise, it embodied what it regarded as the highest ethical and sesthetical views of the time. If the ideals of the time were shallow, the litera- ture produced was of an inferior order. If wrong con- ceptions of what is beautiful and true prevailed, the literary performances of the age were immoral and inartistic. If the ideas of the time were tainted by a blind worship of custom and an unreasonable clinging to dogma, if the people entertained superstitious views in morality and religion, we cannot expect the prevail- !>ing literature to have ranked very high. As water can- not rise above its own level so the art of a nation cannot go beyond the intellectual level of the times. If the people were ignorant, their ignorance will be seen in their books. Many of the books that we fondly revere because they mirror the spirit of their times — times which were periods of mental sloth — are unworthy of our worship. In his Romantic School Heine gives only a qualified approval to the doctrines of Goethe's dis- 15 ciples who held that art must be independent of morality, which changes often; and that although re- ligion and morality change, our conception of art should not. ' ' If art were to be judged, ' ' they thought, * ' by the (^ standard of current morality, each generation would interdict all previous works of art as immoral." (The sentence is from Heine.) That is just what each generation should do. c Whether their criticism of a past work of art is just, will depend upon the correctness of their moral views. So the chaste monks, who, as Heine says, gave Aph- rodite an apron, were really acting consistently; they followed out their system of ethics into art criticism; but it was their ethical theories that were wrong and gave rise to their poor artistic taste. There is no doubt that had a Kempis or Bunyan «, produced their works in the Age of Pericles if possible, their books would have been looked upon as very poor art. One could not expect a nation worshiping the human body to admire books where the body was dis- credited. A nation can only be expected to allow its moral ideas to influence its art views. It is absurd to say that art is independent of morality. An ascetic nation cannot really worship works of art teeming with love of beauty and the body, any more than a pagan people can really appreciate ascetic art works. Art finds its material in the ethical views that prevail; if these views are untrue, the art presenting them ought to be considered great at least by those who maintain these views. There are but few writers who rise above the morality of their times and for this reason ordinary critics do not at first recognize them. Art is judged then by the standard of morality that prevails and if this standard changes so must our opinion of art. Each generation is bound to criti- cise art of the past in proportion as morality has changed. If the morality improves so does the art and vice versa. 16 In short, to sum up, -whatever functions literature may have it is bound to do one of several things: to depict what is beautiful, to teach what is good and evil in conduct and character and to distinguish between intellectual truth and falsehood. Now, it is generally conceded that to a certain extent, our ideas of beauty, goodness and truth alter in different ages, and in many cases improve for the better. If literature be regarded as something whose chief importance is in delineating ideas rather than in cultivating mere style, that past literature which has taught these no longer tenable views should have historical rather than artistic value. If literature represents our outlook upon life and this outlook is constantly changing, can we go to those old books which represent that false outlook upon life, for our aBsthetic and spiritual sustenance? If a past book lavished arguments upon proving that a virtue, which we find a vice poisoning the founts of society ; if an old poet sang the praises of an institu- tion that has been overthrown as deteriorated; if the exhibition of beauty in an old art work appears to us nothing more than a gaudy display, something like a discarded fashion; if a false dogma is embellished to wear the trappings of truth ; if a character was drawn as exemplary whom it would be the height of folly to admire and imitate, can we look upon these works as embodying spiritual truths for us, can we worship them as supreme works of art? 4. To show how the conception of character changes, the story of Griselda, one of the most popular of medieval stories, as told by Boccaccio, will serve well. Boccaccio was free from the asceticism of the times, but in this particular story he gives us the medieval conception of woman in all its hideousness. The story was also used by Chaucer in his Canterbury Tales. 17 In her day Griselda was the type of the model wife and mother, and women strove to emulate her. Her patience was a by-word, her servility to her hus- band a virtue. She is the willing sufferer of the most outrageous indignities, the victim uncomplaining of the most startling cruelties. She is, it is true, of low birth, and is married to a lord. She agrees to appear naked at the wedding ceremonies. After marriage she even consents to be put away to see her lord satisfied. She allows him to take her two children to be killed because he so desires it, and is even ready to let the servant leave the child to be devoured by the beasts and birds, if her husband commands it. Under the impression that the children are dead she mourns, but says nothing. On being put away she is ready to receive the ladies at the new wedding and make everything comfortable for the new wife. But the new "wife" happens to be her own daughter, and Jier husband had merely been trying her patience. He embraced her saying that he had done all this "Avishing to teach you to be a wife" and to teach the rest of the people "to know how to take and keep one. ' ' The impudence of it ! Griselda is without one spark of individuality, utterly without a sentiment of self-respect and an equally guilty party with her husband in the murder of their children, had he really killed them. She is an insult to womanhood. Let us rather have the Nora of Ibsen than a type like hers. In these days when women are seeking suffrage, her type is but the relic of ancient days. We wisely despise her, yet admire the story that tells of her follies. The artist has nearly always been prone to be de- pendent upon some one for his views. He usually adopted the views of the most popular philosopher of his time. He cringed before the political powers that happened to rule, he was subservient to the established church. Instead of creating ideas he took those already 18 accepted and put them in artistic form. He served as a means of propagating errors, of casting abroad and popularizing views that were beneficial to the few in power. It was literature that kept England in dark- ness till the time of Henry VIII; there was not a great independent thinker among the English writers before his time, except Chaucer. Authors were formerly connected with some court or followed in the footsteps of some patron. It was not good policy to go counter to the interests of those from whom one derived his success and the authors were usually faithful. A poet had to defend his patron's politics and religion. Yet although those things upon which literature one time leaned for support have fallen, we still tried to keep it propped up. The patron has gone with his politics and religion, but we still peruse and admire the books in which these found expression. We look to these books for independent views although they were the result of cringing. As Nietzsche says of artists: "They were at all times the chamberlains of some morality or philosophy or religion * * * they always stood in need of a safe- guard, a backing, some firmly established authority; artists never stand alone; they have a deep, and in- stinctive aversion to standing alone." When Nietzsche advocated a change in our ethical notions, a transvaluation of our moral values, he under- stood that this also meant a revolution in our sestheti- cal values. He saw that our attitude towards books must be affected by our altered conception as regards I truth and justice. He marvelled that we should take our ideas of art from books written by authors who believed literally in a hell, in oracles, in the devil, in miracles, in insane religious maniacs, in witches, in persecution. He was sensitive to the changes going on in the 19 world in all things, particularly in human taste. Hence he could not admire many of the most famous writers. He was especially hostile to the most famous poet of the medieval times — Dante, whom he called a "hyena c poetizing in the tombs," a quotation that is becoming as famous as Walpole's characterization of Dante as a "Methodist parson in Bedlam." The philosopher c that he disliked intensely was Plato, no doubt because of the many resemblances that Plato's morality bears to that of Christianity, a fact attested to by the great admiration accorded to him by many of the Fathers and the medieval ages. Another author, Landor, has also registered his dislike for Plato and Dante. Nietzsche was bound from his views to think also that Seneca, that favorite of the Fathers, was a "toreador of virtue." "We are not surprised that he could not hold The Imitation of Christ without feeling a physi- ological resistance. It was natural for him to prefer those sceptical authors with intellects as great as his own, men like Machiavelli, Thucydides, Montaigne, La Eouche- foucauld, La Bruyere, Stendhal, Goethe and Heine. His attitude towards many of the great writers of the nineteenth century was unjust, no doubt, but we should not nevertheless overlook his services in the field of literary criticism. It is true that there are certain ideas that are never changed by the influences that make their way felt in the world. The thoughts that we all have in regard to the brevity of life, the sadness of the parting of lovers, the beauty of natural scenery, the mutability of human affairs, the charm of domestic relations, the pain of death— these are the same in all peoples and in all times. The literature that has expressed these thoughts pleases us whether written by ancients or moderns, pagans or Christians. Such literature may be written by those who have no intellect and its 20 quality will rather depend upon the form than the sub- stance. But on the whole our tastes and literary judg- ments have been pre-ordained for us. We shrink from dissenting from the literary criticisms of our fathers although we hold different and reverse opinions on the most vital subjects. Although other artistic and ethical demands have taken hold upon us, we hesitate to sweep away some of their literary conclusions. We must, however, renovate literary criticism and slacken the bonds by which it is held to ancient stand- ards. Other phases of intellectual activity are being transformed. Religious dogmas and moral tenets have been exploded, constant changes are going on in the economical and political world; these facts must affect literature and yet we assume that stationary attitude in our criticism of it. If moral values are being shifted, so are art values. Aesthetics is no more proof against change than morality. We must remember that the most long-lived canons of taste have passed out of existence. We have deservedly forgotten many books that were always classified with the first literary per- formances. Why should we not inquire into the pos- sibility of a transvaluation of many of our literary classics? What is there to prevent us from thinking that many of our masterpieces will not some day be doomed, that what has happened yesterday will not occur tomorrow and on a far larger scale? We mould our tastes upon an old taste which we do not admire. We endeavor to persist in the same artistic conclusions although our mental scope has widened and altered. We try to become individuals of past ages instead of our own. We must demand how- ever a satisfaction of our own tastes ; we must resent that cowardly attitude before literary shrines; we must assert our aesthetic claims irrespective of the conclusions of centuries. CHAPTER II. SOME OVERESTIMATED CLASSICS. 1. All great movements, whether moral, social or religious, have fully permeated the great books that have been written in the times when these movements held complete sway. The ebb and flow in the tide of human affairs has left many of these movements stranded like shipwrecks, but the books themselves are held up to us like beacons. The spirit of an ancient institution may have long since fled, but the book most suffused with it is presumed to be throbbing with life for us. The ideals of a departed state of society may have been pointed out as reeking with error, but the art works hallowing these ideals are still thrust upon us. These movements have been chiefly developments of an ascetic ideal and are really related to one another. They are Stoicism, Monasticism, Feudalism and Puri- tanism. They have their representative poets and mor- alists, and the most mystifying thing is the influence of these authors upon a society which has outgrown their art and ideals. The two most read works of ancient stoical writ- ers are The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius and The Discourses of Epictetus. They are always reprinted in cheap editions and included in the lists of best books. While many of their precepts are pure in their moral outlook, and it is particularly commendable that a Icing and a slave should arrive at many of the same noble ethical ideals, yet careful examination of these pre- cepts will show us that they are often untrue to human nature, that the conception of life is narrow, that the ideals are unworthy of being followed and that the proposed consolations fall flat. "We worship these two authors because they are the least pagan of ancient (21) 22 authors and largely approach, the morality of ascetic Christianity. Two other ancient moralists, who were great favor- ites of the Christian world because they were rich in passages that looked as if they might have been gleaned from the New Testament, were Seneca and Plato. Monasticism, like stoicism, is practically dead. The remnants of it have been modified by many of the new ideas that have made their way into the world. Yet the most famous poem of Christendom, the most popular collection of maxims and the most noted auto- biography imbued with monastic doctrines are as much read and admired today as though they contained all that man needed to know in order to live properly. "^Every one is forced by the opinion of the public and the critics to think highly of the Divine Comedy of Dante, of the Imitation of Christ of a Kempis and the Confessions of St. Augustine. There is, no doubt, much in these authors that is great in spite of their monasti- cism, that appeals to our human instincts, but in these works are also idealized some of the most pernicious views that ever ruled the world. Boethius' Consolation of Philosophy was more read in former times than today, and, next to the works of St. Augustine, is probably the most known monastic work of the Fathers in literature. It was translated by King Alfred and also by Chaucer. The most famous classic (outside of those of medi- eval times) of monasticism has no doubt been Pascal's Thoughts. It is absolutely devoid of any of the healthy pagan spirit we find in other writers of his century. It is an overrated book; even liberal thinkers have been attracted to it. The wi-iters of the days preceding the French Revolution would compose short books whose ideas consisted of many of Pascal's Thoughts reversed. Voltaire himself did this. 23 Two other seventeenth century authors, who are still held to be among the greatest writers of France, were Bossuet and Fenelon, both of them authors of many works fairly reeking wilh the errors of monasti- cism. They have not been sb extensively read in the English speaking world as in France. Then there are the French tragedians, Corneille, whose Polyeucte, and Racine, whose Athalie refle^ct their authors' monastic views. / The English epic poera of Feudalism is Spenser's < Faery Queen, a book mor^ valuabTe for its form and language than its ideas. l^Eany of Shakespeare 's plays are imbued with the feudal spirit and he is really great in proportion to its absence. We find much of the feudal spirit in many of the works of modern times, but it is best seen in works that were composed when its influence was strong, as in Malory's Morte Darthur and the Niebelungen Lied. What an influence these two books have exerted can be seen from the fact that Wag- ner based his famous opera on the latter and Tennyson his Idyls of the King chiefly upon Malory. Tasso also based his famous poem, Jerusalem De- livered, upon feudal ideas. The last of the movements is typically English and American; namely, Puritanism. We are as enthusias- tic as ever about MUton and Bunyan. Although our Puritanism is not so virulent as theirs, we still speak of Paradise Lost as the greatest English epic poem, c and of the Pilgrim's Progress as the greatest English allegory. Then there are such famous books of English theol- ogy, that may be mentioned here, as Butler's Analogy, Taylor's Holy Living and Dying and Baxter's Saint's Rest. The above-mentioned writers and books may in the future not occupy as high a place as they do today. They will always be known, but there are many less 24 known authors who will be ranked above them by posterity. Most of the authors of Christian nations who are full of the errors of their times were chiefly those who were too much imbued with the spirit of piety, who thought only of justifying the ways of God to man by ^arguments taken from popular sermons. The more the author thought of his religion, the less value did his art have. Literature is not a vehicle for theology. The more ethical precepts that the poet derived from the church, the more ascetic and unpractical did his poetry become. Similarly in ancient Grreek and Roman literature, those authors who were most pious and thought pri- marily of the gods, are not on an artistic or intellectual or moral level with those ancient writers who based their conclusions on the facts of life itself. Though the spirit of beauty entered into ancient art more than in that of medieval times, and there was a certain healthy pantheism about ancient paganism, neverthe- less there was cruelty and superstition in ancient reli- gion as well. "We have instances of persecution in the cases of Socrates, Euripides, Aristotle, Anaxagoras, Pericles and others. In the poems of the three most famous of the Greek poets, Homer, Pindar and Aeschylus, we find all the evil effects of their authors' extreme piety. Their art suffered; their views are not those we mean when we speak of the noble Greek ideals. Their ideas are alien to the true spirit of Greek art and are not in accord with those held by the more famous thinkers. These poets were most famous in their day because the re- ligion they stood for was the popular religion. Xen- ophanes had, however, severely criticised Homer and Epicurus tried to discredit Greek piety. Aristophanes was another author who hated progress in religion or morals and the merit of his own works is thus effected. 25 Virgil is the chief Roman poet who was extremely pious, and what interests us in his poems are the human parts, like the story of Dido. 2. Most of the above authors have been criticised by competent critics, and a few of these criticisms are brought together here. No one will deny that the opin- ions of Symonds, Professors Mahaffy and Jebb, our best critics on Greek literature, are entitled to respect ; nor that the conclusions of English literary historians like Ambassador Jusserand and Professor Courthope deserve consideration when an English author is in question. The criticisms of writers like Landor, Taine, Macaulay, Heine, Nietzsche, Poe and Leigh Hunt always command our attention. Of Pindar, Mahaffy says: "He lived a somewhat sacerdotal life, laboring in honour of the gods and seek- ing to spread a reverence for old traditional beliefs." Though Symonds admires him and did not con- sider him credulous or superstitious, he says : ' ' Accept- ing the religious traditions of his ancestors with simple faith, he adds more of spiritual severity and of mystical morality than we find in Homer. ' ' Speaking of Aeschylus 's doctrine of retribution. Professor Jebb writes: "Aeschylus put some strain on the facts of human experience, but at any rate he saved the justice of Zeus." Symonds declares: "Much of elder superstition clings about his ethics, and an awful sense of guilt and doom attaches to acts in themselves apparently indif- ferent. ' ' Of Aristophanes, Symonds says: "The poet, we fear, was very far behind his age. * * * We, who read the history of Athens by the light of our Grote * * * know now how very perverse and unadvanced the poet was." The following is from Heine : "He hated the poets, the representatives, as it were, of modern life, of a 26 life as different from the preceding epoch of Greek gods, heroes and kings, as the present time is from the times of medieval feudalism. ' ' Landor was very hostile to Plato. The following is a typical comment: "Politics will gain nothing of the practical from him, philosophy nothing of what is applicable to morals, to science, to the arts or the con- duct of life." Nietzsche disliked Plato. He wrote: "Plato is tiresome. In the end my distrust of Plato goes deeper than the surface; I find him strayed from all funda- mental instincts of the Hellenes * * * that I should prefer to employ the hard expression 'superior cheat- ery' with reference to the whole phenomenon of Plato * * * rather than any other term." Macaulay did not express himself enthusiastically of Plato. "The more I read, the more I admire his style, and the less I admire his reasonings." Of St. Augustine in the Confessions, Macaulay says: "He expresses himself in the style of a field preacher. ' ' Of Seneca, he writes : "I have read through Seneca and an affected, empty scribbler he is. ' ' Of Dante, Leigh Hunt said : ' ' Such a vision as that of his poem (in a theological point of view) seems no better than the dream of an hypochondriacal savage, and his nutshell a rottenness to be spit out of the mouth. ' ' ' ' It would be difficult, ' ' said Landor, ' ' to form an idea of a poem into which so many personages are introduced, containing so few delineations of charac- ter, so few touches that excite sympathy, so few ele- mentary signs for our instruction, so few topics for our delight, so few excursions for our recreation." Goethe and Voltaire did not like Dante. Of Paradise Lost, Poe said: "The fact is, if the Paradise Lost were written today (assuming that it 27 had never been written when it was), not even its emi- nent, although overestimated merits, would counter- balance, either in the public view, or in the opinion of any critic at once intelligent and honest, the multitudi- nous incongruities that are part and parcel of its plot. ' ' Taine wrote thus: "He gives us correct solemn discourse, and gives us nothing more; his characters are speeches, and in their sentiments we find only heaps of puerilities and contradictions." Of the Pilgrim's Progress, Taine wrote in a letter: "It is a nursery tale, a blood-curdling allegory, show- ing the terrible inner mind of one of those fanatics; groans, invasions of the spirit, the belief in damnation, visions of the devil, scruples, etc." Francis Thompson said of it : " We have searched the book in vain for a single scene with a single master- touch of delineation, and the result has been thoroughly to convince us that the man was incapable of such a thing ; he knew himself incapable, and therefore instinc- tively shirked description. ' ' Ambassador Jusserand speaks as follows of the Faery Queene ; ' ' But we, unfortunate beings, who, for our merits, doubtless, have not been touched by grace, dazzled as we are by these wondrous sights and de- lighted by the music of the verse, but fatigued by so many inconsistencies, by the mixture of bacchanals and sermons, with so little allowed for true human tender- ness, we feel as we could not breathe; * * * Ten lines of Langland's Visions are worth more than all the moral in 'grave moral Spenser's' seventy- two cantos. ' ' Professor Courthope, the historian of English poetry, ranks Spenser below Chaucer. Speaking of Spenser's doctrines taken from the scholastic theology, he says : ' ' Mixed up as these things are with the action of a romantic fable, they have lost that spirit of uni- versal truth which animates them in the verse of the 28 older poets. * * * The Eeformation has brought into England a new mode of Seriptural interpretation, and with its arrival the old genius of allegoric interpre- tation has departed." 3. These authors may all ,have their literary merit, but the reader should only be made to remember that they have all been surpassed by other more broad- minded artists. Today Moliere and La Fontaine rank higher than the classical writers of the Age of Louis XIV. St. Beuve places them above Eacine and Boileau. Speaking of Moliere, he says : "He entered into no re- action, religious or literary, as did Bossuet, Eacine, Boileau and three-fourths of Louis XIV 's century." In our own day most critics prefer Moliere and the writers with a similar philosophy of life, like Eabelais, Montaigne and La Fontaine, to Pascal, Eacine, Bos- suet, Corneille and Fenelon. The cultured reader will see nothing heterodoxical in a taste which prefers Thucydides, Machiavelli, Spi- noza and Hume to Plato, Seneca, Epictetus and St. Augustine. Are not Nietzsche, Taine and Pater greater moralists and stylists than Marcus Aurelius, Bunyan and aKempis? Goethe, Ibsen, Balzac and Byron are really greater than Milton, Aeschylus, Spen- ser and Tasso. These opinions are endorsed by many of our best critics. It would be extraordinary that authors who are often considered the greatest novelists, dramatists, poets and moralists of the nineteenth century should not stand higher than writers who have given expres- sion to medieval views. Our authors were greater geniuses and profited by the new discoveries in the realms of thought. It does not, however, follow that authors who are imbued with piety and even superstition, are not there- fore great writers. On many subjects we will find that 29 utterly irreligious writers and religious ones are re- lated to one another in their ideas. Blake may call himself a Christian, and Nietzsche an atheist, but their views on morality are very much alike. A man's real creed is not necessarily derived from the religion to which he attaches himself. Many a Christian author was pagan in his moral beliefs. The morality in Balzac's novels is surely not the same as that of the Sermon on the Mount. He worships all the things that are there condemned. Milton was as great a Puritan as Balzac was a Catholic, but his ideas on divorce are very modern and liberal, and anything but Puritan. The inner nature and experiences of these two authors forced them to entertain moral views not sanctioned by their religions. There are so many ideas we may have and feel- ings that we may be subject to irrespective of our re- ligions. In the work of pious authors we come across beautiful and even liberal passages; we find ideas about whose truth there is no question, as for example, Cardinal Newman's Idea of a University. We will thus be able to understand why in works like the Sonnets of Petrarch and the Elegies of TibuUus, though the authors introduced many of the errors and superstitions of their respective religions, yet there are transcripts of genuine feeling felt by all of us. Nevertheless we will find that where the poet 's love is subdued entirely by his religion, there is less literary value for us. 4. As an illustration of our main theory let us ex- amine two of the most typical of the above mentioned works— TTie Meditations and the Imitation of Christ. We do not admire the Stoic philosophy and yet we all join in pronouncing The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius a great classic. Let us see whether the ideas there are still true in our day. 30 We find that the artificial remedies to alleviate our sorrows do not console us. When we labor Tinder a great misfortune or are in the toils of a strong pas- sion, illogical appeals to our reason do not help us. Whatever emotion possesses us, there is some physical change in the body. The normal condition cannot be restored by false philosophical mediation. We are all bundles of nerves; all our feelings are registered in our brain; after we think we have subdued our emotions a slight cause can evoke the most dormant pain. We are the victims of moods and our emotions are mobile and fickle. Marcus Aurelius tells us that if we have a very great misfortune we will be rid of our woes if we reflect that we are part of a whole, that what is well for the whole is also well for the part and can not be injurious to the part ; that if we remember all this we shall be content with whatever happens. (Bk. X, 6.) But a man lives and feels as a part. If he is bereaved of some member of his family, how can we tell him that in the scheme of the universe at large it does not mat- ter that some are cut off in their prime? For in his calamity he feels as a husband or father or son and not as a citizen of the universe. He does not believe that their death is beneficial to the universe. He feels his pain keenly, and by reflecting that what is good for the whole is also good for the part (which he does not believe) he will not be made content with what- ever happens. A favorite precept of the Emperor is to tell the reader to forget his surroundings and retire within himself. He thinks that the only space we occupy in the world is in our soul and that this is never affected by external circumstances. Would we retire to the country or seashore ; it is folly ; retire within yourself. (Bk. IV, 3.) A discontented mind can derive all con- solation from within. The sea breeze and mountain 31 air are nothing compared to reason. Imagine that you are at the shore. "The religious, impassable ocean," says Maeterlinck, speaking of ijie Emperor in his Mystery of Justice, "that excused and protected the retreat into himself of the sage and the man of good, now only exists as a vague recollection. ' ' Would we delight ourselves, we are told to reflect that some of our friends are possessed of certain virtues. (Bk. VI, 48.) But if we have not those virtues ourselves we will derive no special pleasure by re- membering that our friends possess them; very likely we will feel rather envious. Then what does the reader think of consoling a person who is stricken with an incurable disease from which he will shortly die by telling him that since he has no desire to increase his weight he should have none to increase his length of days (Bk. VI, 49), or that since a few days make little difference as to the time of dying, so should a few years! What a false analogy between the desire to increase one's weight which does not give one material pleasure and the desire to in- crease one's days, which is satisfying our strongest instinct, the will to live. Innumerable maxims can be gathered from The Meditations that are stale, flat and unprofitable, such as "It is the power of the soul to maintain its own serenity and tranquillity and not to think that pain is an evil," "Does any one do wrong? It is to him- self that he does wrong." He constantly tells us to live according to Nature, but gives us suggestions that are entirely opposed to the promptings of Nature. For instance, he asks us to pray that we should not be afraid to lose our son rather than pray that he live. One begins to weary of these hopeless consolations that do not consider the simplest elements of human nature. Philosophy and particularly Stoic philosophy 32 can do little for us. As Cardinal Newman asked, "Did philosophy support Cicero under the disfavor of the fickle populace or nerve Seneca to oppose an imperial tyrant?" The Imitation of Christ sums up the principles of monastic morality as Marcus Aurelius' Meditations does those of Stoic morality. We, at heart, no more believe that a Kempis ' precepts can govern our life than can the Meditations. Yet we affect to admire the book. The book insists upon our renouncing our will, upon our suppressing our individuality, upon our stifling our abilities. We suffer many of our mis- fortunes because we cannot will, because we cannot bravely assert our personalities. Yet the criticism of our times sees fit to lavish praises upon a book that encourages us in our weakness in developing our will power. It may no doubt be prudent to crush our will for that which is beyond our power, but to ask us to root out our desires for things that we can attain by a slight exertion, is unfair. We are creatures of flesh and blood and in us have been planted certain instincts, like that of love for knowledge, art, honor, riches and beauty, and it is useless to tell us that we should have contempt for all the things of this world in order to tend towards the Kingdom of Heaven. We will only become the most affected hypocrites pretend- ing to despise what we will be secretly doing. The book preaches everything that is opposed to the best in Greek and modern authors. It tells us that the more we can get out of ourselves, the more divine will we be; they tell us that the more we can be our- selves the more will we approach the divine. The Imitation maintains that the less we rely on ourselves and the more we adopt the ideas of others, the nobler will we be. Greek and modern literature recognize that we can only cultivate the best that is in us by trust- 33 ing solely in ourselves. aKempis repeatedly asserts human nature to be vile, man to be full of sin, not "worth comfort or consolation. Greater authors and deeper thinkers and higher moralists teach us that human nature is not vile, that man is to be treated as dignified. Our day has no sympathy with these tirades against the body, against ambition, against pride, ' ' The scheme of the book," said Thackeray, "if carried out would make the world a wretched dreary place of sojourn. There would be no manhood, no love, no tender ties of mother and child, no use of intellect, no trade or science, a set of selfish beings crawling about avoiding one another, and howling a perpetual miserere. The author goes so far as to say that even after we have given everything of ourselves, completely re- nounced all the pleasures of this world and entirely suppressed our own individualities, even then we have done nothing. It is at a point like this one loses patience with the philosophy of life laid down and critical examination must stop. CHAPTEE III. THE EEBORS OF L.ITEEARY CEITICISM:. 1. Walt Whttman has pointed out to us that we ought not to set up as literary ideals for America, the pagan and religious and feudal classics which teem with ideas utterly hostile to our theories of life. He saw that conditions and beliefs different entirely from our own caused these works to bloom forth and that hence these can not serve for our spiritual sustenance. Many of them sprouted in castles and temples and monasteries ; hence they are opposed to that spirit of independence and individualism characteristic of democracy. Whitman pays these authors the greatest homage and acknowledges their services, but he sees that they give us conceptions of character which we can not fol- low ; he perceives that their notions of beauty are per- verted and can not form a criterion for us. He felt that this constant worship of the classics was a hind- rance to the birth of a literature that would represent our time. He was doubtful as to what evil results might not be produced by the ever-constant harping upon the names of the great poets of the past, fearing that our own poetic channels would be clogged. He has no doubt made his mistakes, but he teaches us a healthy spirit of independence. We see a man who does not grovel before great names and who candidly contests the validity of established reputations, who questions the authority of the world's most famous poets — Homer, Virgil, Aeschylus, Dante, Spenser, Shakespeare and Milton. He thinks that their fame rests more on the "mountain-high growth of associa- tions ' ' connected with their poems, and that the bases on which these were built have become "vacuums." If these classics built on the ideas of monasticism, Puritanism, etc., have themselves not been attacked very often by name, at least the ideas on which they (34) 35 are based have been severely criticized. An onslaught upon stoical ideas or a defence of epicurean views is really a criticism of those books where the stoical ideas find expression. If we reproach an author of our day for his monastic views we are also rebuking the classics of monasticism. He has simply put their ideas in another and sometimes better form. We do not have the courage to criticize the master because of the prestige of his name, but we have really attacked him through the channel of some obscurer author. So all along those critics who have dealt severely with feudalistic, puritan, monastic and stoical ideas; who have reviled obscure authors imbued with these ideas; who have based their own essays on the doctrines of a modified paganism or a refined epicureanism, have written against Marcus Aurelius, Pascal, a Kempis, Bunyan, etc. Montaigne tells us how he incorporated ideas and quotations from other authors without naming them, so that the critics would be censuring them when they thought they were attacking him. ' ' I would have them give Plutarch a fillip on my nose, and put themselves in a heat with railing against Seneca, when they think they rail at me. ' ' Let us level our criticism where it is due, at those classics from which the minor works of our own day draw their life-blood. The fact that in our own compositions we often de- part entirely from some of the forms and ideas of ancient authors signifies that these writers are not sufficient for our own day. If these ideas were always true all that literature would have to do would be to repeat them in another style. If in addition the old forms were still beautiful, literature would then be an art of imitation, of retelling to mankind the old views in the old forms. But literature is always creating new forms and taking up ideas rarely or not at all dealt with by older writers. Does this not mean that they are insufficient 36 for our demands and that in all probability those older authors, had they been living in our day would have written like our own writers'? Probably those who wrote epic poems about war and religion would have given us novels and prose dramas treating of import- ant psychological, moral and sociological questions. A new departure in form and thought is always then a tacit criticism of an old book. If the disciple is superior to and hence breaks away from the master, there must be some deficiencies in the master's literary productions. And as a rule it is necessity rather than the desire for novelty that forces the breaking up of the old traditions. The more our writers deviate from the old, the less literary merit the latter must possess. 2. To judge the literature of the past we should forget all the panegyrics written and criticise the works anew. We should free ourselves from the opinions we have held about ancient authors and take note of the appeal made to us. We would surely discover that we had been deluded into insincere rhapsodic eulogies. It does seem strange to see critics pick out the same names to represent the highest achievements in literature. Had the weight of past centuries not borne down upon the critics, other names would have been chosen to represent these achievements. Had Homer been forgotten and then suddenly discovered he would not then be ranked as high as he is today by the critics. The critic, if he has studied history and literature, sees what an immense influence Homer has had, he dis- covers how many great men cared for the Iliad; he reads it himself, is bored by many parts but he then comes to the really passionate speeches in some of the books and he concludes that Homer is one of the first poets ; so he joins in the universal chorus and is flat- tered that his own voice has been re-echoed by past traditions. Had he come across the identical passages 37 in obscure authors — and as a matter of fact he does — he would not be so extravagant in his eulogy. Le Bon, in his The Crowd, calls attention to the tremendous influence that the prestige of an author has upon us. The mob instinct — that instinct to do col- lectively through the hypnotic influence of the crowd what we would not do individually— alone governs us in judging books. Our worship of great names is a sort of craze with us that acts upon us very much like a religious revival. We join in, whether we believe or not. Just as the mob consciousness influences respectable law-abiding citi- zens to join in lynching mobs or criminals to enlist themselves in philanthropic movements, so we all join in the frenzied worship of authors whom we, at most, think passable. It is not intellect that plays a great part in the worship of ' ' great" authors. We are swept into the admiring crowd whether we possess intellect or not, whether we admire or not. Even our greatest geniuses are infected by this tendency. Some of our most liberal thinkers cling to the most obsolete dogmas and worship the most effete classics, just as Newton and Locke did. Some of our best authors admire the most famous books in spite of the fact that these are poor. Similarly we may possess no intellect and join in the most intellectual movements, drifting along with what is in the air. If the theory of evolution has made such strides it is not necessarily because of the growing love of truth; if morality spread in the first century after Christ it was not because of the growing good- ness; if the worship of art was a feature of the Eenaissance, it was not because of the increasing love of beauty. Darwin and Spencer, Jesus and St. Paul, Michael Angelo and Leonardo da Vinci exerted a hypnotism that was irresistible and the epidemic spread. The most ignorant may attach themselves to a great cause and welcome a profound, idea though they 38 do not understand these. It did not follow that when the ideas of such intellects like Spinoza and Montaigne and Hobbes and Diderot were spread broadcast during the French Eevolution that every peasant and gamin who embraced them were men of advanced intelligence. So the mob consciousness may make us follow writers who are below us and also worship those who are too far above us to understand them. It is not the possession of intellect that makes us worship the truth any more than the lack of it that makes us follow false- hood. 3. The difficulty with some of the so-called classics is that they are far removed from life as we find it to- day. Old writers bemoaned calamities that do not af- flict us, they found joy in the realization of ideals that no longer exist for us. If they despaired because they did not see means of fulfilling their whole duty toward God, we are in agony because we cannot perform our duties towards ourselves or those we love. What are the groans of Bunyan, Dante and Pascal to the business man harassed by incessant worry? How can you call upon a man to invent some imaginary grievances about , the state of his soul when he is entangled in some domes- tic woes or is suffering from some painful disease, or is engaged in some drudgery that scarcely gives him a living? The epigrams of Marcus Aurelius do not console us when we are the victim of some injustice, a Kempis does not help us in quenching a passion we feel, and in spite of him we all are interested in glory, wealth or power. We are concerned about our futures or the futures of our children; why call upon us to take a deep interest in false philosophy. Only that literature can be vital which touches on our own needs and, although many of these classics depict struggles that we ourselves undergo, between 39 good and evil, between the passions and the reason, and between the flesh and the spirit, we do not have the same conception of these things as they did, and hence our struggles are different. We often try to seek as a goal what they struggled to avoid. Men of our own time with moral and aesthetic notions superior to those found in the classics, with a wider range of knowledge and a more keenly developed intellect, are told nevertheless to learn what is truth and beauty from authors with limited intellects and limited experience. An average educated man has a better mind and a greater insight into life than some of our old authors, and yet he is urged to learn from authors than whom he is better informed. No one would think of telling a man who has mas- tered the works of a Goethe or a Taine, or a Balzac or a Spencer, or a Brandes, to go off into some obscure haunt where no ideas have made any incursions in centuries, and to learn morality from their most able parson or author. "We would scorn to get ideas of life from people who have had less culture and experience than ourselves. It is just as presumptuous to ask a man who has imbibed the best ideas of our thinkers to learn his morality from Bunyan. As a matter of fact a man may have a powerful intellect, a keen sense of literary values, and a highly educated moral sense without having read the classics of stoicism, monasticism and puritanism. They are not necessary for our intellectual, artistic or moral devel- opment ; we are acquainted with their ideas as soon as we think for ourselves. Intuitively we take up the best that is in them, for they have become part of the world's way of thinking. We may read a few of our nineteenth century authors and be men of culture for these embody the best that is in the old classics and also the fruit of modern thought. 40 4. In the times wJieii the church and the state were very powerful and sowed errors and heaped abuses upon the community, just that literature was consid- ered greatest which fostered these errors and condoned or rather urged these wrongs upon the public. The healthiest literature was, under despotic regimes, that which justified evils committed for the personal grati- fication of a few tyrants. When the doctrine of the divine right of kings held sway, the best books were those that attacked any tendencies in the people to- wards democracy or to assert their individuality. When the church was supreme and all its doctrines held divine, only those books were excellent that were composed under the shadows of its altars and had the support of its misguided priests. Literary criticism fell into the hands of the cour- tier and the patrons of the established church, or at least authors strongly subject to their influence. Natur- ally only that literature was praised which upheld the corrupt institutions in power and which looked after the interests of the privileged few. The influence of this criticism has come down to our own day. We hold practically the same opinions about these books that supported injustice as the an- cient critics, although we hold entirely different polit- ical views, and in many cases the extreme opposite religious views. Our tendency to worship books with whose ideas we do not agree can be remedied simply by making our judgment conform to our opinions. No change in our ideas themselves are necessary. But we often admire old books with wrong views, because our own views are false, and find in those classics authorities to corroborate us. These books have lived just because they cherished the errors man- kind has believed in ; because they have kept alive the conventions that the world has approved. Mediocre minds worship those books in which their mediocrity is 41 reflected. Those whose ideas in religion, morality and art are tainted with falsehood, will consider those books the greatest which cast a halo about these false views. Literature has often been the weapon wherewith to fight truth and justice, and to keep old traditions still ruling over the world. Books have been the bul- warks behind which ignorance and superstition have shielded themselves. It stands to reason that in a country where the religion is strongly ascetic, the best literature will be that which constantly advocates the doctrine of self -mutilation and self-sacrifice. Before we can change our opinions of these books, we must change our ideas altogether, and this is what the pioneers of liberal ideas in our day our trying to do. Mankind is not born with all the emotions that they are subject to later in life. Conventional criticism with its insistence upon our worship of certain classics only is nothing more than a plea to us to cultivate only those feelings that are considered proper by society. The classics are praised because it is desired that they inspire us with reverence for that which our religion has taught us is sacred ; to exult in the punishment of transgressors of our old ethical beliefs ; to hate those who sin against the old traditions and institutions. We certainly were not born with our feelings thus directed, but have been brought up so. Max Stirner, in his The Ego and His Own, recognized that a large part of our education was really to teach us to feel the emotions that society deems respectable. Criticism has attempted to stifle the admiration for authors who sought to impart feelings to us that society thought improper, no matter how noble they really were. It permitted literature to depict emotions that mediocrity felt, and not those experienced by the great- est people. It would not allow us to lavish our love and hatred where most fitting, but would force us to approve what was countenanced by society. CHAPTER IV. LITEBATUEE PEOGBESSES LIKE SCIENCE. 1. Theories have been advanced to prove that art and literature are not progressive like science, and that great poets are never surpassed. Hazlitt, Macaulay and Hugo indorsed the views that the great ages of art were the periods of their infancy, that in those times the range of ideas was exhausted in some perfect form, and all that we could do was to give new forms to these ideas. According to these critics the early poets had the advantage of being the first to embody ideas that were stUl fresh. On the contrary, those authors who live later have the advantage. They can free themselves from the artistic and moral errors that the earlier writer could not recognize as errors. Our later authors can give us both improved technique and truer ideas; they can make use of the heritages bequeathed to them by earlier ages. Since taste and human nature change, our con- ceptions of truth and beauty improve and our style and ideas grow purer ; why should our art works also not be better? If the plane of intellect is higher than it formerly was and we are free from many of the superstitions and dogmas to which our ancestors were subject, if our imagination no longer goes about con- ceiving the most monstrous and ridiculous happenings, why should we say that our literature will not be favor- ably affected by these improvements in ourselves ? Our authors must necessarily create nobler ideals, more adapted, indeed necessitated, by the age in which we live. It is held that as the intellect improves, the imag- ination declines ; that as our judgment becomes better, our literary and poetical performances deteriorate; in short, that a great critical age such as ours is not com- (42) 43 patible with a poetic age. Macaulay has developed these ideas m his essay on Milton, but more fully and brilliantly in his essay on Dryden. Because mankind has developed intellectually it does not by any means follow that he has lost the fac- ulty of feeling and expressing his emotions. As a mat- ter of fact, we are more sensitive because our nerves have become more highly developed. The increase of neurasthenia and other nervous diseases shows this. We are more stirred than ever the ancients were by great passions. We become obsessed by some over- whelming emotion that rules us and we feel our pains more keenly and experience our pleasures with greater delights. The characters of Balzac are engrossed in their passions more intensely than the characters of Homer, in spite of the fact that Balzac possessed greater judgment and intellect than Homer. As the power to think does not choke up the emo- tions, so does it not corrupt the imagination. Our intellects do not permit the imagination to go off into insane flights, to create the most unconceivable alle- gories, to wander about in search of ridiculous solu- tions to natural phenomena. Our imaginative perform- ances are fully alive to the realities of nature and are in awe at the stupendous scientific discoveries. The great writer may avail himself of the researches in psychology and of moral discoveries; he may let his imagination revel over the mysteries of human nature and his book will not suffer because he understands them better. It is contended that the spirit of analysis is hostile to poetry and literature. But this spirit teaches us to understand character better, and the true delineation of character is one of the very highest functions of literature. And the more critical and intellectual we become the better are we able to describe character. 44 The fact that there have been several epic poems composed in primitive times has given rise to this doctrine that the most poetical ages are the ages of barbarism, and that civilization and science are hostile to poetry and literature. Because savage people are easily moved by a song or speak in figurative language is no proof that they produce greater poems than us. The greatest literature is produced at the zenith of a nation's civilization. It is then that men have the greatest thoughts and experience the deepest emotions and express themselves most nobly. Life is more com- plex and gives rise to more numerous and complicated situations. It is then that most moral and intellectual forces are brought into play and literature rises to give expression to these new struggles. Civilization is synonymous with the march of great ideas. It will be noticed that the great periods of the world's literature were those in which civilization was at its height ; when philosophic speculation was prolific and scientific discoveries were numerous. The ages of Pericles, Augustus, Lorenzo de Medici, Elizabeth, Louis XIV and Voltaire, etc., were the great ages of literature and not the times when the countries were uncultivated. The literatures of Eussia and Scandi- navia only became great in our times, when these coun- tries took up the fruit of the culture of modern Europe. Previously these countries did not possess great litera- tures. In the works of primitive times we find that those portions are best where civilization has made itself felt. Take Homer and observe that where there is apparent the influence of culture we find more refinement of feeling, more humanity of treatment. The fact that we become more critical does not im- pair our poetical and literary performances. This is apparent from observing that great novelties, drama- tists and poets have also been great critics. And a 45 really great critic is always a poet whether he writes in verse or not. Surely Pater and Ruskin were poets or they could never have given us those wonderful pas- sages in some of their books. Both Poe and Coleridge, Heine and Goethe, were poets and critics and it is still a debatable question in which department they excelled. It is, however, particularly in French literature that we see the combination of the critical and imagina- tive faculties in the same authors. Nearly all the great French authors, whether poets, novelists or dramatists, have left us excellent work in literary criticism. Voltaire and Diderot, Stendhal and the Goncourts, Baudelaire and Gautier were all excellent critics. These instances are not exceptions but rather ex- amples of the rule that the imaginative and critical faculties are usually combined instead of being di- vested. Is not that great work of genius, the Don Quixote, certainly a work of the imagination, really a piece of literary criticism directed against the literary of chivalry? And who that has read Tom Jones does not remember those delightful excursions in criticism par- ticularly at the opening chapters, which linger in the mind when the fighting episodes are forgotten? Macaulay thought that the poetry of an author would not be affected whether he believed in a moral sense like Shaftesbury or whether he referred all human actions to self-interest like Helvetius or whether he never thought about the matter at all. But it is just because a poet has a certain moral creed that real value is given to his poetry. If he believes that moral laws are the same in all ages and that they are of divine origin his poetry will differ from the poems where the author's beliefs are influenced by Epicurean or Sceptic moral views. And the greatness of his poem 46 will depend upon the truth of these moral views. If Macaulay's view were true as regards poetry it would also apply to dramas and essays ; it would matter little what moral views the dramatist or essayist enter- tained ; and we might as well say that it matters little what moral notions are entertained by writers like Marcus Aurelius and La Eouchefoucauld, the Maxims and the Meditations will not be affected by the author's beliefs — ^an assumption too absurd to discuss. Or con- ceive of Ibsen writing his plays had he never given a thought to the question whether moral ideas are not the products of environment, self-interest and expediency. If a poet believes that our actions may be traced to self-interest he will very likely write poems singing the joys of satisfying one's instincts, of the evils of convention which hinder the development of one's in- dividuality, if he believes strongly in a moral sense he will probably insist upon the performance of duty at all costs even if it is an imaginary duty. Dante and Groethe differ from one another just 'because of their difference in moral theories. If the author writes fiction it depends on his moral views whether he will be a Eichardson or a Fielding, a Malory or a Eabelais. Let us not be deceived into believing that igno- rance and poetic literature go together because un- educated authors like Bunyan and Burns have given us famous compositions. Any one who has read Burns ' letters can see that his mind was ripe and that he had wonderful intuitive power. He was intellectual but not educated. Yet a man may be able to write good lyrics without an education just as he may write fair alle- gories. But this does not alter the fact that his poetry would be greater if it contained the fruits of the author's intellect as in the case of Byron and Shelley. 47 2. It is true a nation may progress intellectually and yet its moral sense may have deteriorated, and its sense of beauty may have declined. A nation whose authors are not intellectually high may give us essays sound in their morality and poems of artistic beauty. But it is safe to say that these compositions cannot be- long to the highest realm of art though their excellence may be unquestioned. They will probably be lacking in originality and will confine themselves to commonplace thoughts and feelings. If these performances point out errors in our social life, it will be because innumerable predecessors have done so. If the author sings of cer- tain emotions it will be of those which the world sanc- tions. He will never give us something that we have not known or felt before. He will not produce a work into which can be gathered the essence of the highest beauty and the drawing of the noblest character — that type which practises a morality that is pure but not yet sanctioned by convention. But if with the progress of the intellectual there is a corresponding improvement in the sense of beauty and justice then we get the highest form of art. Dur- ing the Age of Pericles and the Eenaissance, the in- tellectual and artistic qualities were blended in most of the artists and writers. And although it is true that morality was not exceedingly high in these ages in the sense that Christianity looks upon morality, it is nevertheless the rule that the greater the intellect a man possesses the better he is prepared for knowing what is right and wrong. The question of the practise of morality has often very little to do with one's theories. It is rather the rule than the exception that the more intellectual the author the greater the sense of beauty and morality that one finds in his works. Goethe and Ibsen are examples to the point. Literature is concerned with ideas as science is 48 with facts. The literary man discovers new ideas in the same sense that the scientist does new facts. Time shows us that many of the literary ideas were wrong as it does that many of the scientific facts were false. Our later works of art then become more beautiful as our later scientific works become more truthful. The ad- vanced ethical and artistic ideas of our day are superior to those entertained under monasticism as the Copernican system is truer than the Ptolemaic system. Some day the Paradise Lost with the exceptions of a few passages may be as obsolete as literature as New- ton's Principia is as science. An old scientific treatise lives if its principles are true ; when these are discovered to be wrong the work dies and a new and improved book replaces it. Why should the same thing not happen in literature? Why do we say that literature does not improve simply be- cause in the old poem we may find a few beautiful pas- sages? Do we not find in the old scientific treatise many truths still true and the basis of our science? Nevertheless we do not deny that science improves. Hugo, in his Shakespeare, remarks that no one can go above Homer or Dante, for here literature has reached its climax and that no one can surpass these poets because art is not progressive. There are several great works of literature in the nineteenth century that are a living refutation of his thesis. He is under the impression that the ideal which is the basis of literature never changes and he emphasizes this fact but it needs very little to convince one that if any- thing does change, it is the ideals of man. It would be folly to say that the ideals of a Kempis were the same as those of Epicurus. "Pascal, the servant," says Hugo, "is outrun. Pascal, the writer, is not." On the contrary Pascal's ideas are often absurd; his scientific discoveries are still true. 49 3. Chateaubriand, in his Genie du Christicmism re- viving in the nineteenth century the old quarrel between the ancient and modern authors, maintained that the Christian religion and morality being truer than that of the ancient, therefore Christian literature and art were superior. He derived the greatness of Racine, Tasso and Milton from the fact that they were Christ- ians. There is no doubt that in those phases of morality where Christianity does surpass Paganism, Christian literature based on these particular phases will be the greater. But there are many pagan ideas that are nobler than some of the Christian ideas; literature grounded on those ideas will rank higher. Chateaubriand does not or will not realize that the great period of art and literature in the Eenaissance was due to the flourishing of pagan ideas. The moral of his book is that the more infidelity there is in an age the poorer will be its literature. But the Ages of Pericles and of Lorenzo de Medici were periods of scepticism. Chateaubriand at least realized that literature was progressive and that a change in our moral ideas will have an influence upon our passions and hence upon our art. But his premises that all the ethical ideas of Christianity are purer than those of Paganism are false. He was at least consistent, and though his con- clusions about the books of Christian literature being always superior to those of pagan literature is wrong, his main idea about the progressiveness of art is correct. Madame Be Stael's book. Literature (1800), shows that she also strongly believed in the progress of literature. She held that literature is nothing more than the transcript of the social ideas of the time and as she believed in human perfectibility and that later times always gave us the truer ideas, she concluded that modern literature is the superior. Except for 50 the fact that ideas sometimes are falser in a later age than in an earlier one, her main ideas are correct. She does not, like Chateaubriand, base her conclusions on religious grounds. But that there are periods of decline in the in- tellectual development of humanity there can be no doubt. Much ancient literature is certainly greater than some of our modern English literature. The period known as the Catholic Reaction is artistically and intellectually inferior to the Renaissance which preceded it. The literature of Madame De Stael's OAvn age is below that of the time of Voltaire. Time is not necessarily an important factor in considering the development of intellect and literature. We often find that the older writer is far ahead of us intellectually and that our age is behind him. "We may be deservedly proud of the literature of the last cen- tury but we must not forget the ancients. With thinkers like Aristotle, Thucydides, Tacitus, Cicero, Plutarch, Lucian ; with poets like Sophocles, Euripides, Ovid, Horace, Lucretius, Catullus, not to speak of the innumerable lost works of the ancient poets and philo- sophers, we need not pride ourselves too much upon our superiority to antiquity. Modern times, it is true, may have produced writers greater than any one of these; our own generation may have done so but the sentiments of these authors still move us and their ideas are still fresh to us. CHAPTER V. IDEAS MOBE IMPOETANT THAN FORM. 1. It has been maintained that the theology and politics of a poet have no effect upon his art ; that ar- tistic merit may be present in spite of false moral and social ideas; that the creed and dogma may be lost sight of in pondering upon a splendid imaginative product; that, in short, it is the form in a great poem that counts. But form can do little to save works of art when the life of the matter is gone. Poetry, like other forms of literature, must derive its chief greatness from the ideas rather than the form. Poetry speculates on the great human problems and there is no reason for con- sidering these of secondary importance because they are in verse. All the rhetoric in the world cannot res- cue a false idea. We are too thirsty for real beauty to be cheated out of it by being told that falsehood, garbed in allegory, is beauty. The great poets have lived, not because of their form, but because they were the deepest and truest thinkers, because they summed up the intellectual and moral products of a whole age. If their truth is no longer true, if their moral lessons are false, beautiful phrases cannot avail them. Dante and Homer, Milton and Spenser have lived because the world always believed that they gave the most complete expression to the moral truths of monasticism, pagan- ism, puritanism and feudalism. In our own time the poems that we most admire, like Faust and Peer Gynt, are rich in ethical lessons; they are the fruits of modern thought. "We are not en- raptured because of the form or the style, for many an inferior poem excels these in this matter, but because they present some intellectual problem, some universal situation. They, like the old poems, are valuable be- cause they treat of the struggles between good and evil, (51) 52 right and -wrong, but they do not suffer from false religious and moral views, as the older epics. Pater was certainly one of the greatest stylists we have had and though he recognizes the importance of style in determining good art, yet he maintained that it was the substance that decided what was great art. He gives illustrations in the Paradise Lost and Divine Comedy of works he considers great because of the importance of the underlying ideas. According to Pater, the greatness of literary art depends "on the quality of the matter it informs or controls, its compass, its variety, its alliance to. great ends, or the depth of the note of revolt, or the largeness of hope in it." His theory is correct, but his examples are given in defer- ence to established literary opinion. If the hope held out by a classic is now seen to have been based upon illusions, or the great ends to be at- tained are not in harmony with our ideals, the great- ness of the work is a figment. The objection to Dante or Milton is not the presence of the Ptolemaic system of astronomy or even the machinery of Christian and Pagan theology and mythology ; or the introduction of absurd allegory or hopeless pedantry, but that the un- derlying central ideas in regard to life and conduct are often utterly false. And it was the supposed greatness of these central ideas that made the reputation of these poems, and not the form. The greatness of art depends, then, upon the vast- ness and truth of the subject-matter, and if this turns out trivial and false, there must be a decline in the greatness of the work in question. We can not appreciate to its full extent a poem like Lucretius' Be Rerum Natura unless we are somewhat epicurean in our own beliefs. It is absurd to admire the poem enthusiastically and not believe at all in its philosophy of life. Similarly, we can not love a work like Tasso's Jerusalem Delivered, with its piety and monasticism, unless we are ourselves pious. It all de- 53 pends which is the truer philosophy of life in deciding which is the greater poem. We can not expect people to agree in their literary opinions if they differ in the fundamental views of morality and religion. Critics should not argue about the literary merits of books without discussing the truth of the ideas which form the groundwork of these books. Critics can not expect to agree in secondary matters when they differ in fun- damental principles. One can not expect readers who have pantheistic or agnostic views to admire religious and sacred poetry. If the cardinal principles of the poet's philosophy are crystallized in the poem and this philosophy is religious or monastic, the free-thinking critic can not justly go into raptures over the poem, even though he finds some beautiful passages. To appreciate such fime poems like Watson's The Unknown God and The Hope of the World, or David- son's Ballad in Blank Verse or The Man Forbid, we must be sceptical like the authors. If these poems mock some beliefs that we entertain, it is folly to say that nevertheless we can worship these poems. If the ideas in these poems are correct, then the pious man can not appreciate this poetry, for the chief pleasure of poetry consists in contemplating sympathetically the poet's ideas. If we merely value the poetry for the execution and craftsmanship, it might as well contain ideas held by illiterate people. 2. A work of art should awaken the reader 's mind as well as his emotions. The book should subdue his beliefs to those of its author; it should suffuse him entirely with its character, bring out his complete in- tellectual sympathy and win him over almost uncom- promisingly to its central ideas. When the reader finds that the struggles and ideals of the character are precisely his own, when he believes in nearly all the views of the author, then the book really appeals to him. 54 Every great writer has put into his book his whole philosophy of life, his whole raoral outlook upon life. All his intellectual sympathies, his psychology and mental attitude lie sealed therein. The artist must make his readers feel that his truth is the truth, that his philosophy is unimpeachable, that his moral out- look is absolutely correct. It is not enough that the readers be thrilled with the craftsmanship. Now, if the book contains ideas which the reader, as a whole, does not sympathize with, it does not capti- vate him by those ideas the expression of which really was the object of writing the book. It does not fulfil the first condition of artistic appeal which is the utter assimilation of the reader's soul to the author's. The ideas of reader and author are entirely opposed to one another ; their sublimest intentions do not coincide, their conceptions of beauty are not identical. There should be a challenge which the reader finds acceptable. There must be a message which is found irresistible. We must be made to enter into the au- thor's spirit and accept his gospel. It is the message above all that the author bears for us that determines his greatness. If this is no longer true, it is folly to worship the book as a supreme masterpiece on ac- count of the form. It is often held in defense of books that are spiritual autobiographies like the Confession of St. Augustine and Bunyan's Pilgrim's Progress that what we are primarily interested in are the struggles of a peculiar personality without concerning ourselves about his ideas. But in order that these books be great to the reader, he too must have felt those mental crises, undergone the same moral struggles and deliberated on similar questions. He too must arrive at the same conclusions, strive for the same ideals, be in anxiety about the same problems and solve them in the same way. Otherwise the books must have for us a value 55 akin to that which they have for the historian, the antiquarian, the theologian or the psychologist. For example, if the reader feels that he is never troubled by a consciousness of sin, that he has other duties in life than to pry constantly into his soul to find undiscovered crimes; if he feels that this world was not created merely to give us an opportunity to haunt ourselves with conceptions of sin; if he believes that the body is sacred, that ambition, beauty, art, power, are allowable pursuits; how can you expect him to love books where the authors are gnashing their teeth because they are always reminded of their sins and where they consider as errors what he deems virtues? If we love something we can not admire a book that decries it. If we are agnostics or sceptics we can not admire a book where the author describes his triumph over doubt and his conversion to faith. The book has in it nothing of ourselves. We may like the style, comment upon the sincerity of the author, and be otherwise in- terested. But it is not the history of our struggles, it is not the development of our souls. We are not in ac- cordance with the general spirit of the book and it will never have the real literary value for us, namely, of appealing to us by the intellectual and moral views entertained. 3. It is apparent that we can not admire the ancient books for their form and style alone from the fact that we can find many books in our own day that are much superior in this respect. We have poems per- fect in technique, stories and essays in majestic and faultless styles, but we do not consider them great litera- ture. There are newspaper editorials and magazine book-reviews written in flawless style which for diction, lucidity, ease, sublimity, power and other qualities are unsurpassed by many of the best prose writers of old. As Cardinal Newman says: "In point of mere 56 style, I suppose many an article in the 'Times' news- paper, or 'Edinburgh Eeview,' is superior to a preface of Dryden's, or a Spectator, or a pamphlet of Swift's, or one of South's sermons." As a matter of f-act in prose essays particularly, it is the style that is of secondary importance. What raises the literary value of the essay is the greatness and truth of the ideas. The quantity and quality of the truths, the profundity of intellect, the capacity for moral and psychological insight are the chief factors in determining literary merit. What the author says rather than how he says it is of most importance. We are so absorbed in finding great books that we forgive the author for paying less attention to his art. Every one can learn how to express an ordinary thought well ; only an original and gifted mind can utter an un- discerned truth. Who thinks of the style in reading Aristotle or Spinoza? These authors are so profound and original that no matter how they speak we are only too eager to grasp what they have to say. What is true of essays should also apply to fiction. There are many novels written in our day that far excel the style of Balzac or Stendhal, that have not the tedious descriptions of the former and the unadorned cut and dried style of the latter. There are best- sellers that preserve the laws of unity and keep up the interest of the reader more than Fielding or Sterne. Even the works of those novelists like Gautier and Flaubert, who held that literature was nothing more than form, live because of their ideas rather than their style. Surely the greatness of Mademoiselle de Maupin and Madame Bovary depends rather upon the character and ideas than the form, beautiful as that is. A novelist, like an essayist, becomes soulless when he is destitute of intellectual faculties. It is because ideas are more important than form in the novel that the psychological novel, the novel of character, is superior 57 to the novel of adventure or the novel of manners. Hence, French and Eussian fiction are as a whole superior to English fiction. Scott and Thackeray are not as great as Stendhal or Dostoievsky. Novels like Red and Black and Crime and Punishment are not at all remarkable for style and yet they are among the greatest literary productions the world has ever seen. Those two great fiction writers — Eabelais and Cervantes — live on account of their ideas solely. One can scarcely find two other writers more deficient in the qualities of literary form. Their outrages upon probability, the ridiculousness of the incidents, the lack of a sense of proportion, the absurdity of the adven- tures, the lack of unity and the irrelevant and dull chapters, would have been fatal to an ordinary work. But Eabelais' work and the Don Quixote are in- tellectual performances of universal interest. They are probably the two greatest criticisms of monasticism and feudalism that we have ever had. The moral ideas entertained by monks and knights were exposed by ridicule, the overwhelming influence of theology and mythology were given staggering blows. These works hastened the departure of the medieval ages and are still fresh, for the ideas that they combated still rule us. They contain philosophies of life that we have not yet grasped; their humor still evokes outbursts of laughter ; the very identical problems that faced their heroes still besiege us. We see ourselves described; the character studies in these books are character studies of ourselves. It is the substance then rather than the style in these works that have kept them alive. The impoverished periods of the world 's literature were those in which the language itself was the end rather than the thought. Eenan, in his Apostles, has shown us how in that period of Eoman literature from the death of Augustus to the accession of Trajan, liter- ature was mediocre because destitute of ideas. The result of ornament for the sake of ornament was that 58 no permanent literature was produced in that period. Where brilliancy and rhetoric usurp art the age is a barren one. In a similar manner and for a like reason, as Symonds has pointed out in his Renaissance studies, the Humanists of the Renaissance have been forgotten. The stress upon form and the aim after rhetoric have covered their ethical treatises and histories with dust in the libraries. Those authors like Machiavelli, who created new ideas entirely instead of adorning in pretty phrases the views of the ancients, survived. It will be noticed that wherever there was an age of darkness it was because man laid more stress on form than matter, that no ideas came into prominence because people were too much absorbed in giving re- peated expression to the old commonplace views. And a new age only dawned when importance was again laid upon ideas. The age between Chaucer and Shake- speare was an age in which allegory and metaphor were the goal of all writers. When new ideas burst upon England in the latter part of the reign of Eliza- beth, English literature was re-born. It is in aphorisms and reported conversations of great men that one can more readily see that it is the substance that counts rather than the style. Here we immediately look for the ideas expressed. Any man with an original and profound intellect might have a stenographer take down his sayings, and the result might be literature without any change in the form. The aphorisms of La Rouchefoucauld and Guicciardini are chiefly valuable because of the intellect behind them. The conversations and table-talk of Goethe, Johnson, Napoleon, Northcote and Coleridge are chiefly interesting because of what is said, and not how it is said. No doubt the aphorisms and conversations have some sort of style and their form is colored by the authors' personalities. But many journalistic products are better written and yet are not great, be- cause there is no intellect behind them. CHAPTER VI. HISTOEICAL CEITICISM AND THE CLASSICS. 1. In judging the works of former times, we are told that we should not govern ourselves by the stand- ards of our own time. We are told that we should con- sider the ages in which these books were produced and place ourselves in those times, and forget the span of centuries separating us from those books. We pride ourselves on the fact that we have invented historical literary criticism. But when we read a book of the past as literature, we read it for amusement, or its art or its ideas on moral and social subjects. It does not help us to tell us that if we try to have the viewpoint of the olden times we will appreciate their books. For their viewpoint may have been all wrong, and why should we try to cultivate it in order to sympathize with wrong ideas ? When we read a book of the past, it is not for those purposes in which historical criticism might be of value ; we do not read to study the manners and morals of an age through the medium of its literary produc- tions, or to discover the peculiarities and characteris- tics of a whole people in some representative literary type. The great Taine was mistaken in considering these the objects of the study of past literature. We seek in old books just what we want in the new-^truth and beauty. We seek to know how much of ourselves, of our noblest feelings and profoundest ideas are incorporated in those books. We seek in the works of antiquity for the faintest echo even of a note warbled by our own throats, for a response to the emo- tions awakened in our own hearts. We look for char- acters who are akin to ourselves, for descriptions of conduct and methods of thinking that we approve of. We wish to know the highest ideals entertained of (59) 60 character and justice, and we read ancient books to discover them and not because we find the wrong ideals interesting. In his Future of Science, Eenan admits that we do not find our ideal in many of the old masterpieces, but he does not think that this affects their value. He admires the works of Pascal and Bossuet only as works of the seventeenth century. He concedes that if they were to appear today they would scarcely deserve atten- tion. But there were other works of the seventeenth century, in which we do find our ideal, which are as advanced as the greatest books of our own time. These would have attracted attention if published in our own day on account of the advanced views therein. Authors like Moliere, La Eouchefoucauld, Hobbes, Spinoza are not tainted with the errors of their times, as were Mil- ton, Bunyan, Eacine and Pascal. The same circum- stances, the same environment surrounded them, the same religious, philosophic and social errors prevailed when these authors produced their most notable works in the last half of the seventeenth century. Yet we do not read the former as works of the seventeenth cen- tury, and we do not have to make any allowances for the errors of their age for them. It is poor policy to blame the intellectual poverty and moral errors of an author upon his country and his time. As a great author he is presumed to be above his time and to teach his country the truth instead of being influenced by its wrong ideas. All old authors should be judged in the same way. If their ideas are false, then they are poor writers, and we should not judge them in connection with their age, but with ours. If we can judge Spinoza by our age, why not Pascal! If the ideas of and old book can stand the test by being compared with those of a great book of our time, why should we look upon another old book produced at the same time only from the viewpoint of that age? 61 In his Plato and Platonism, Pater tells us that in reading Plato 's Republic, we should neither agree nor disagree with its ideas, but merely follow the course of the philosopher's mind, and that we should study the book in the conditions in which it was produced. But why should we admire the book if we don't agree with most of its views? If we seek for true ideas on edu- cation or poetry or marriage and we think that those of Plato were wrong, it consoles us little to know that they are wrong because of his age. If Plato tries to prove by bad logic something that is false, it is folly to tell us neither to agree with him nor disagree. There is much in Plato that is still true, and we can read those parts of his works and judge them by our own standards. In the works of Thucydides, Aristotle, Lucretius, Plutarch and Lucian, of the ancients, we find much that is as true for our own day as the best in our own writ- ers. We do not look upon them as literary curiosities, but as living books. We must restore the two methods of literary crit- icism which Pater says are now obsolete, but the uncon- scious use of which raises his own criticisms to the rank of a creative art. These are the dogmatic and the eclec- tic methods. The dogmatic method consists in admiring those authors with whose ideas one agrees. It condemns that ultra broad-minded fashion of growing enthusiastic about books with none of whose ideas one agrees. It is based on the most natural way of criticising a book which is to let our own views influence us in our judg- ments. It does not necessarily follow that if we adopt this method that we will not give due credit to books that ably defend a wrong cause; nor that we will ex- pect ancient writers to anticipate all our modern ideas. We can always bear in mind that new conditions give rise to new ideas and that these ideas could not have been brought forth because our conditions did not then D3 exist. This method is perfectly rational. It is only to be expected that a man with one range of views should not love books with the opposite views. It would have been absurd for Nietzsche to have admired The Imitation of Christ or Plato. The other method, the eclectic method, at first seems opposed to the dogmatic method, but it is really complementary to it. It consists in admiring only those books or parts of books whose ideas are true, irrespec- tive of the creed or school of philosophy to which its author belongs. It can see truths in Nietzsche and Plato, but it will in that case choose some common point of agreement between them. It accepts ideas that are true from the most conflicting sources. This method does not destroy our originality, but rather cultivates . it. Historical criticism has one great fatality; it at- tempts to reduce our minds to the level of those whom we have outgrown. It aims to deprive us of the fruits of culture that have bloomed between bur time and the book that we judge. It encourages us to embrace cer- tain superstitions and abandon valuable truths. It is a dangerous playing with falsehood; the artificial courtesy towards falsehood may make us a slave to it. We may begin to think altogether like the inferior peo- ple whose books we judge. We soon begin to enjoy every form of beauty indis- criminately, and we lose our capacity to enjoy the high- est kind. We appreciate every idea and we are no longer able to separate the important frora tne trivial, the true from the false. We enter into every viewpoint until we have none of our own. We lose the distinction between health and disease, between psychology and pathology. We become enamored of the imperfections and errors of the past. The final result is, as Nietzsche points out, that our instincts run back in all directions and we become a kind of chaos, and we finally can not appreciate the highest culture. 63 Professor Jowett, on writing upon the methods of interpreting the Scriptures, came to a very simple con- clusion, and that was that it should be interpreted like any other book. In criticising a great classic, the only rule to guide us is a similar one, and that is to criticise a past great book as we would a new book. We seek to know how much truth the book holds and not how much of what was held to be true by our fathers. We look for the best ideas and not only the best Christian views, but also for the best Pagan views. We wish to see life interpreted as we feel and experience it, and not accord- ing to its conformity with some past ideal. We want the old classic to be so eternal that intellectually and morally it is at least as high as the greatest work of our own time. In speaking of Milton's poem in connec- tion with Goethe's, for instance, we are forced to deny the seventeenth century poet the intellectual powers of the nineteenth century poet. And although Milton does show intellectual qualities in a work like his tract on divorce, yet it is not displayed in the Paradise Lost. But when one speaks of a contemporary of Milton like Spinoza, although not a poet, in connection with Groethe, we find that Goethe came to Spinoza for intellectual nourishment. The Ethics is a classic which has im- proved with time, as we find that many of the psycho- logical and moral discoveries of the nineteenth century have been anticipated there. As for Paradise Lost, we find that its intellectual value has deteriorated with time. The only question, then, in determining the value of a book is whether it is still true. Does it still give voice to our longings and desires ? Has its value been materially affected by the changes in religion and morality? Are the consolations that it offers and the social remedies it lays down genuine? Is the picture of life presented imbued with the spirit of a discerning 64 and intelligent mind? Are the passions that are burst- ing forth those we feel and the struggles encountered those we undergo ? The truths delineated must be the gleanings of the best elements in Paganism and Chrisiantity, in democ- racy and aristocracy. Both unbounded individualism and unreasonable self-sacrifice must be kept in check; the taste for beauty must be reconciled with the call to duty; there must be a harmony between the body and the soul. The books of the past should remain valuable only on condition that they incorporate the moral views entertained by those of our thinkers who are still ahead of our times. One might almost say that the greatness of a past book depends upon how much of the ethics of the future it contains. If the ethical lessons taught by men like Pater, Whitman, Ibsen, Brandes, Nietzsche, or Goethe are those that are in advance of the ethics of our own time and will be the ethics of tomorrow, surely those classics of the past that contain these same ethical lessons are the ones that above all deserve fame. Those classics that presented an ethical code that is obsolete and that our age is trying to get rid of, are the ones that should be consigned to obscurity. If the lost works of Pyrrho, Epicurus and some other of the Greek philosophers could be found, we would probably have a list of books greater than many of our most famous Christian classics. 2. Literature must not be read with the eye of an antiquarian. It must not be regarded as a scrap heap where all useless and curious ideas have been flung. If an old classic appears to us nothing more than a de- pository for the obsolete views of the world it is no longer literature and in that case does have an an- tiquarian interest for us. But if the old classic has a large residue of truths that are still profound, we must look upon it as though the water of life flowed from it. 65 It will often follow that the same book will appeal to us both from the antiquarian and literary point of view. It will contain ideas utterly absurd side by side with those that are advanced. A book like this must naturally still possess literary value. But the real difficulty with our literary criticism is that we often regard books from a literary point of view when they should be looked upon as possessing chiefly antiquarian interest. Works like The Holy Living and Dying, and The Saint's Rest, belong to this class. And we often look upon books from the anti- quarian's side when they should be looked upon as literature like the undeservedly forgotten works of Charron, Sextus Empiricus, La Mothe le Vayer, Bayle, Gassendi, St. Evremond, Sanchez, Naude, and other now obscure great authors who have anticipated the most advanced ideas of our time. It is not necessary in order to judge past books that we put ourselves in the author's age and into the place and mind of the reader of that age. We must remain — indeed we can not avoid it — children of the twentieth century. Anatole France with his usual irony has laughed at these attempts on our part to go out of ourselves. Innumerable causes have made us what we are and we can not really adopt a former gen- eration's attitude and way of thinking. It is impossible for one with a healthy pagan view of life, say like Gautier's, to try to have the consciousness of sin and the torturing anxiety to be saved as Pascal or a Kempis. For in the next instant he is breaking forth, "I am a man of the Homeric Age. For me Christ has never come," etc. There is something admirable in the position main- tained by criticism in the eighteenth century against authors like Homer, Milton, Spenser, Bunyan, Shakes- peare and Pascal. There was none of that divine superstitious reverence felt for them that exists in our DO own day. These writers were judged like any other author and did not occupy a too exalted place. We are willing to read the works of all obsolete authors, of mystics and alchemists and monks pro- vided that we are not compelled to renounce the heritages of our intellect. We can learn much from the idiosyncrasies of their personalities, truth from their errors, health from their diseases. But we can not say to ourselves that we are one moment denizens of the twentieth century, then of the twelfth and then of the first century. Had Cervantes cultivated the historical sense he would have been able to appreciate all the absurd romances of chivalry and in that case he assuredly could not have written Don Quixote. All literary criticism is really subjective. Our critical estimate of a book depends upon our prejudices and beliefs, upon our past experience, upon our phy- sical and psychological constitution. Matthew Arnold complained that our personal affinities and likings and circumstances swayed us in our estimate of books. But it is just because we are constituted with such a tem- perament, because we entertain such an idea and be- lief, that must be the determining factor in forming our critical belief. If our temperament is unhealthy or our beliefs wrong, then our literary judgment will be incorrect. In that case we must change both our temperament and our ideas. Our criticism is based on all our private beliefs; it represents the convictions that our past training and the bygone events of our lives have forced upon us. If a man has been the victim of public opinion it is only fair to assume that his faith in democracy might be shaken and in that case he is bound to be partial to- wards literature that exalts the ideal of aristocracy of intellect. A woman may have been the martyred scapegoat for the errors of the marriage institution 67 or the prevailing code of sexual morality. She can not be blamed for letting her sufferings influence her in admiring that literature where the marriage in- stitution or the prevailing code of sexual morality is attacked. There may be the real truth in this aristo- cratic and iconoclastic literature. As Oscar Wilde said: "A critic can not be fair in the ordinary sense of the word. ' ' Literary criticism is not a fixed science and can not become such. Our opinions about books depend upon our religious and moral views and these are diverse in different men. As long as it is uncertain which ideas are the best ones — and this will always be a matter of doubt — ^we will never be agreed as to our criticisms of books. The present standard that pre- vails is naturally from the standpoint of Christian morality. According to this standard only those are the really great books which are pervaded with this morality; nevertheless the critics have been broad enough to admit the classics of Eome and Greece and also many modern works conceived in a pagan spirit. Those who do not accept many of the precepts of Christian morality but have been influenced by the ideas of beauty held by the Greeks and the revolu- tions inaugurated by philosophic and scientific dis- coveries of the last century, judge books from a stand- point that might even be called anti-Christian. The more Christian, or rather the more ascetic a book is in spirit the more objectionable will they find it ; although they may also be broad-minded enough to see greatness in many works ascetic in spirit. It is not after all an affection to admire both the works of Voltaire and Bossuet, Lucretius and Tasso, Machiavelli and Pascal, Stendhal and Bunyan, Ibsben and Corneille. The ideas of these authors are utterly opposed to one another ; the former are pagan and the latter are Christian, and one's beliefs must influence him in his preferences for these authors. CHAPTER VII. THE CAUSES OF LITEEABY FAME. 1. Anatole France tells how an unsigned passage from Michelet at his best, given in a test as dictation, was ridiculed by the critics, one of whom was a great admirer of Michelet; unfortunately, he did not know that the passage was taken from Michelet. Very likely many good passages from the most famous authors might be similarly harshly dealt with, if the names of the authors were not furnished the critics. On the other hand, we might get critics to admire passages from unknown authors, which they are apt to ignore, if we pretend that these passages were written by great writers. Editors and college professors have often been the victims of tricks played upon them by people who signed their names to literary master- pieces, to have their work rejected or mercilessly criti- cised. France further tells us that Cousin discovered sublimities in Pascal, which have been since recognized as errors due to a copyist. It only illustrates the tendency of the author's reputation to make us eulogis- tic over that which we might otherwise pass by or even condemn. It is true that nearly every author has writ- ten some works for which the world does not care, in spite of his fame. But the particular works which made his fame are full of passages that we love, be- cause we are in a way hypnotized by the author him- self rather than because of the greatness of these passages. We pick out for our recitations, speeches in Shakespeare which are commonplace and do not represent Shakespeare at his best, but there are many passages in less known authors that are greater than the passage about the seven ages of man or "Wolsley's farewell to his greatness, or even Hamlet's famous soliloquy. (68) 69 ' ' Do you think, ' ' asks France in his Garden of Epi- curus, "there is much freedom of judgment in the approbation we accord the classics, Greek and Latin, or even the French classics ? Even the predilection we display, as a matter of taste, for such and such con- temporary production and our repugnance for another, are these really free and unbiased judgments ? Are they not determined by a host of circumstances foreign to the contents of the work under question, the chief being the spirit of imitation, which is so powerful in man and animals?" Many of the books published today and then for- gotten would, if published several generations or cen- turies ago, have attracted considerable attention, created an epoch and have lived today as literature. The converse is true that many books that once aroused a furore and are still looked upon as literature, would have been ignored if published in our own day. We worship a book often only because of our gratitude to it, for the changes that it has introduced. In its day it inaugurated a departure, destroyed some conventional methods and hence was conspicuous; it made literary history and as the result of this rather than real liter- ary merit does its fame come down to us. Many a book and author is famous because of the part they played in history, because of the good that they really did, rather than because they are still great today. As Lessing says, "A work of art may deserve all possible approbation without affording any special renown to the artist. On the other hand, an artist may justly demand our admiration even though his works do not afford us full satisfaction. ' ' We should learn to distinguish the book which lives because of its literary merit, from that which lives because of historical reasons. A work that has not created an epoch, but is rich in those qualities that make a book great, deserves to be called literature more than one which moulded the taste of its age. No doubt 70 many novels and dramas of the nineteentli century, which attracted less attention than Waverly and Eer- nani, are greater than these, and yet are not consid- ered to be equal in merit. The historical novel and the French Romantic School date from the years 1814 and 1830, when these works appeared. But there is nothing to be connected with many other greater novels and plays beyond the mere fact that they have certain merit. 2. Among the chief mistakes in neglecting great books, none are more conspicuous than the fate of Car- lyle's Sartor Resartus and Thoreau's WeeJc on the Con- cord and Merrimac Rivers. Here were books that were highly original, in a unique and good forceful style, brimming with the most sagacious remarks. They made not the slightest ripple in the literary world. Today there are many critics that maintain that these are their authors' masterpieces, while everyone concedes that they are at least among the very highest of their authors' achievements. Suppose Thoreau and Carlyle had each died be- fore Walden and The French Revolution were written. It was these two books that made the fame of their authors and drew attention to the earlier written works above mentioned. Can we be so sure that we would to- day be ranking Sartor and The Week as high as we do? Might we not have remained in utter ignorance about them? Who knows how many great books there are in the world that have never become known, because their authors did not later in life create a sensation by an- other book that drew the world's attention to his earlier one? Probably the names of the greatest books have never passed our lips. Probably a list of the best books might be formed from books of which we have never heard. Fame is not always the reward of merit. It is often the result of the appreciation of a solitary fam- ous critic, who has endorsed the book. He may not be 71 on hand when he is needed or may never have fallen across the pathway of the book. Emerson, for instance, helped to make Whitman's fame by his famous letter, which Whitman quoted. Mill helped to make Carlyle's fame by his review of The French Revolution. Octave Mirbeau made Maeterlinck famous by the title of the Belgian Shakespeare. Many other instances might be cited of one famous review, bringing an author fame. Had these particular critics not possessed themselves the power to sway opinion, or had they not been on hand or never read the book, and if the authors them- selves had then ceased their writing, the world would have remained possessed of at least one masterpiece in each case of which it would have known little. And that we are in ignorance of many such masterpieces because the right critic was absent, there can be no doubt. Had Hume died immediately after his Treatise on Human Nature appeared, that is before his Essays brought him his fame, can we be certain that we would today be ranking the Treatise as one of the greatest achievements in the history of the world's intellectual progress? It fell stillborn from the press and atten- tion was only drawn to it by the essays. Similarly with Schopenhauer's World As Will and Idea. It was ignored when published and attracted attention only after Schopenhauer became famous by his Essays. It is then due to the fact that both Schopenhauer and Hume continued to live after they had produced their masterpieces and popularized their views in essay form, that made the reputation of these authors. One might wonder how many other masterpieces were also published that fell stillborn from the press and because their authors either died or did not re- produce their ideas in a popular form, they never be- came known to us. "How many admirable men," asked La Bruyere, "and fine geniuses are dead without ever being talked 72 of? And how many are there living, who neither now nor ever will be talked of?" We often can not blame critics for misjudging their contemporaries but they have often been mistaken in their opinions of authors for many years after the deaths of these authors. The history of the fame of men like Richardson and Macpherson shows us the instability and uncer- tainty of fame and the length of time it sometimes takes the world to realize its critical errors. No one today reads Eichardson or Macpherson. The former is con- sidered narrow, prudish and verbose; the latter is hysterical, affected and forced. Yet, Ossian was once ranked with Homer ; Hazlitt included him in the list of the four great world poets ; G-oethe quoted long sections in his Werther although later he modified his opinion of it ; and Napoleon was an admirer of Ossian. It was imi- tated by Byron and its fame spread throughout Europe and lived for over a half century after its production. Richardson was considered the world's greatest novelist ; his influence in France was particularly great and curiously enough upon the free-thinkers. The eulogy of Diderot is well known. Johnson thought there was more knowledge of the heart in one letter of Eichardson than in all Tom Jones. Usually when an age makes a mistake in regard to its estimate of a poet, it makes amends after his death, as in the case of Keats and Shelley. But here were two authors who were admired extensively and extra- vagantly not only by the greatest men of their time but long after. If the opinion in which Richardson's novels and Ossian are held today is the correct one, and if for fifty years after their death the world was grossly mis- taken, we are led to reflect as to the number of other authors we have been mistaken ; and if we can be mis- taken for fifty years why not for a hundred or a hun- dred and fifty years and possibly more ? The history of the fame of authors like Blake and 73 Stendhal is a travesty upon human judgment. Very few today deny that these authors possessed wonderful genius, that they were men of great power. It is due to the fact that they were too much allied to the twentieth century that their fame was delayed into our own time, so long after their death. Even today, how- ever, they are not popular. But in their own time many an author with less art and thought stood higher than them, in the opinion of the public and of the leading critics. No man would have dared to rank Stendhal higher than Madame De Stael or Chateaubriand or even Sue or Dumas. Cowper and Crabbe, Rogers and Camp- bell stood higher than Blake. Today each name stands for all that is highest in literature in their respective countries. Around the names of Stendhal and Blake have rallied the greatest literary movements. The Pre-Eaphaelites, the Celtic and the Symbolistic schools, represented by great poets like Swinburne, Yeats and Symons who wrote excellent essays about him, looked with veneration to- wards Blake. Around the name of Stendhal all modernism and psychology in France rallied. Although Goethe and Balzac and our own Hazlitt admired him in his day, his fame rose in the year in which he himself predicted it would come — about 1880. Even so different a writer from him in every respect like Tolstoi has registered his debt to Stendhal. Taine, Merimee, Bourget and Brandes are a gorgeous galaxy of disciples. But it is to Nietzsche that these two authors are nearest. To him Stendhal was the greatest psycholo- gist of the nineteenth century. While Blake is now looked upon as a precursor of Nietzsche and Symons in his Blake has shown the similarity of their ideas. Are there not authors in our own day who are as little known as Stendhal and Blake were in their day and who will not be known for generations hence and will to posterity rank higher than some of our literary 74 idols? The future may rally around authors whom today we have amidst us and of whom we know little. 3. Literary reputations then are made by so many other causes besides the possession of real literary merit. There may be some controversy going on and some book lends its aid to the cause of the party in power or finally victorious. As a result immortality is achieved by a work like Butler's Analogy or Pas- cal's Provincial Letters. These books if produced at another time might not have won the fame they possess. A book may appear great because the literature of the age is on a low level, and slight merit will make it tower above the best books of the age. Augustiue's City of God and Boethius's Consolation of Philosophy very likely would not have attracted unusual attention in the Victorian Age. A book may be considered great because it is needed at a particular moment, and if it appears and checks what is considered an evil at the time, it receives everlasting recognition. To this class belong some of the works of Berkley and Chateaubriand who appeared when the times were weary of scepticism and sought some author to stem its tide. There are so many causes that enter into making the fame of a book apart from its literary merit. Asso- ciations cling to it; it becomes bound up with the his- tory of a country; it is carefully analyzed by scholars and is the subject of commentaries. Mysteries of authorship often revolve about it and it forms the sub- ject of controversies of all kinds. It may have been the favorite of several of the world's great men; it may have been brought into fame by a censorship; it may have been inspired by a certain movement. But when we criticize the book today we should look upon it aside of the memorie? that cling to it, and if it is still good art, then its fame is truly deserved. How often in reading an essay in some periodical 75 or some prose work, we can say to ourselves that we are reading something that we think better than Epictetus or Pascal; how often do we take up good novels and poems and plays that we are certain excel The Faery Queen and The Aeneidf Many of our writers have given us greater thought, finer descrip- tions and more interesting and passionate scenes than some of our classics, but we fear to express too high a eulogy upon them, as we have as yet not the endorse- ments of ages and sages. 4. Literary forgeries have done much to shake our confidence in the world's literary opinions. The detec- tion of these forgeries has been chiefly due to the pres- ence of archaeological errors, historical mistakes, modern idioms or illusions to latter events. The forg- ery as a rule was not discovered on account of lack of literary merit or intellectual vigor. Indeed some of the forgeries were as rich, and in some cases richer, than the original in these qualities. Had scholars not exposed the forgeries we might today be as eulogistic about them as about the original. For instance, there have been forgeries of Petro- nius that were thought to be genuine until in one case the bad Latin and in another the confession of the forger undeceived the scholars. In the case of the former, a story had been concocted by the forger, Francois Nodot, by which he could not be called upon to produce the original manuscript. In the case of the latter, Marchena, who did not produce a complete Petronius as the former did, the only objection was that he could not produce the original manuscript. The conclusion that one is led to is that a really gifted work of forgery should be great after its ex- posure as before. Eenan once said that it was only the discovery that Ossian was a forgery of Macpher- son that took away its literary value. But this dis- covery should not have made it a less work of art in our eyes. The merit of Chatterton's work was not 76 affected by the discovery that they were forgeries. If the forger is a genius himself we should consider his forgeries as good literature. If Shakespeare had forged some of the lost plays of Sophocles, or Gibbon some of the lost books of Tacitus, the forgeries might have been greater than the original. Had these forg- eries been exposed, their literary value would not have deteriorated. If any one today pretended he had found a lost novel of Balzac's and it was as good as Balzac's best, the discovery of the forgery should not affect its literary value. To be a great forger requires genius. What a genius he would be who could repro- duce works as good as the lost books of the Greek philosophers ! 5. Who knows but that some day the great poets of the Elizabethan Age will no longer be Shakespeare and Spenser, but some of their contemporaries. Charles Lamb, for instance, preferred Marlowe, Dray- ton, Drummond and Cowley to Shakespeare. Then there were such great intellectual poets like Sir John Bavies, whose Nosce Te Ipsum Was very famous in its day and reminds one of Lucretius, although a belief in immortality mingles with its agnosticism. Then higher still was Fulke Greville, Lord Brooke, whose works teem with the most advanced ideas. His plays and his treatises on Fame and Glory, on Religion and others show him a true disciple of the Eenaissance, a man much higher than Spenser. Then there were Donne, Chapman, Jonson, Beaumont and Fletcher and other of the playwrights of the age. Nor must we forget the love poets from Wyatt and Surrey to Her- rick and Suckling. It is doubtful if since that time we have had such beautiful love sonnets and lyrics as the Elizabethan Age has given us. Going back further than the Elizabethan Age we find poets who were great social reformers like Lang- land, Robert Lyndsay and John Skelton: poets who boldly attacked the vices of the church and the state, 77 who were on a higher plane intellectually than their age, although subject to many of its errors. Nearly all of these names are obscure to us except those who have made a specialty of early English poetry, but we can scarcely have any idea of the great repute in which they were held in their day. They were most of them cultured liberal thinkers at the same time that they were genuine poets. They have always had admirers, and even today we find attempts made to revive men like Langland by Jusserand who prefers him to Spenser; and we get editions of Davies and Lord Brooke by such an enthusiastic scholar as Gros- sart. Then there are authors who were very famous in their own day, but who have been forgotten because their ideas were too advanced and the world was not willing that they shake the repose of its more secure \'iews. But today when views similar to those enter- tained by these forgotten authors are gaining in the world, we must resurrect those authors. If we admire Nietzsche, why should we not again take up Mane- vUle's Fable of the Bees? for the ideas of both authors are similar. Then is it not absurd to neglect Helvetius' Mind while admiring his chief master, La Eouchefou- cauld, and a leading disciple like Stendhal? If we have been influenced by the sane Epicureanism preached by Pater, why should we not again read those famous Epi- curean philosophers of the seventeenth century like St. Evremond and Gassendi, the teacher of Moliere? "Why admire Montaigne and forget a man like Char- ron, who is probably as great? Why revere Voltaire and forget Bayle, from whom he learned much? There are many of the French sceptical writers who were very famous in their day, authors with the most advanced views. We often endorse these views when presented by our contemporaries, but ignore them when presented by Naude, Patin, Huet, Bodin, La Mo the le Vayer, Vauvenarges, Chamfort, Fon- tenelle, La Mettrie, Sanchez, etc. 78 The critics have allowed these authors to die and given us instead Pascal, Bossuet, Fenelon and other writers whose ideas are not dangerous. But the real curiosity of literary criticism is seen in the fact that the critics have also let live authors like Eahelais, Montaigne, Moliere, La Rouchefoucauld, Voltaire, Diderot and others, although their ideas are similar to those entertained by the forgotten authors and are not even couched in better or more beautiful form. But it was only by the greatest effort that these authors have been preserved for us, for they were bitterly attacked in their own day and thereafter, particularly by the clergy, who are still hostile to them. No doubt the future will entertain many critical judgments that will be more correct than our own. Charron's essays on Wisdom may hold a higher place than Pascal's Thoughts, La Mothe le Vayer and Bayle may be ranked higher than Bossuet and Fenelon. Sex- tus Empiricus may be read and admired more than Marcus Aurelius. But what, however, really appals the critics is the idea that some poet could rank higher than one of the great epic poets or another dramatist than the three or four that the world has recognized as being supreme. The critics can not reconcile themselves to the sugges- tion that some one has written greater plays than Shakespeare, Aeschylus or Eacine, or greater poems than those of Homer, Dante or Milton. Of course, we may find portions of the works of these poets, that taken together in each case will still leave the poet occupy a very prominent part in the list of the world's great singers. These epic poems and the few others we know may be placed below some of the great novels of the nineteenth century. What we today regard as the freakish opinion of some of our critics who place both Balzac and Ibsen above Shakespeare may be the verdict of posterity. CHAPTEE VIII. THE DANGEROUS INFLTJENCB OF SOME CLASSICS. 1. Many classics besides often being bad art are immoral and have an evil influence upon society. They are often responsible, directly or indirectly, for much of our social misery. The false ideas that sow error and misery among us are idealized in many classics; the glamor of art conceals the trappings of falsehood. When a book is all wrong in its conceptions of truth and falsehood, right and wrong, good and bad, and these are made attractive by setting them in a back- ground of poetry, romance and religion, these wrong notions will entwine their roots deep in the social soil. If conventional ideas and the blind worship of custom are suffocating us spiritually, the cause lies in our standard of criticism, which prostrates itself before that literature which eulogizes these conventions. The classics are the more dangerous because no one questions their authority. An evil brewing doc- trine in a great book has its baleful power doubled and trebled because of the prestige of the author. If many of the erroneous notions that exist today had not received the sanction of some great philosopher, if many works of art which embody these would not be looked upon with awe, the world might have been spared much of its actual wretchedness. It is par- ticularly the ascetic and pious classics that have been the source of immorality, for they cast a halo about ideas which misled men entirely in their outlook upon life. If we keep up our unreasonable enthusiasm for the classics, we constantly keep the false ideas before us. If we still are enthusiastic about books that were written to defend the conventional notions of chastity and monogamy, we are encouraging the miseries that the marriage institution and the misconceptions of (79) 80 chastity have wrought in the world. If we still admire the books written in servile patronage of the court or the church, we take part in the evils that these insti- tutions have inflicted upon the world. The classics have often written in defense of religious superstitions and implanted in the people a fear for imaginary sins. The unjust past persecu- tions of those who embraced alleged heretical ideas are the fruits of the influence of the classics. Eeligious persecutors have been made the heroes of literature. Those who omitted to follow the so-called duties to- wards God, which were homage to hideous customs, were depicted as sinners and were put in hell. The antagonism towards original thinkers and their mar- tyrdom, in the past and today, also were the results of the teachings of our classics. It might be a painful truth that a few books distilling the spirit of intolera- tion led to the deaths of Socrates and Bruno. Works of art have been responsible for whole- sale religious persecutions and for stirring up wars for false causes. The Spanish Inquisition, the Massacre of St. Bartholomew, the Edict of Nantes and the Crusades were partly, at least, the products of literature. The spirit that pervaded these movements was breathed into them by ascetic and feudalistic literature. Sismondi calls Calderon the true poet of the inquisition and mentions his play The Devotion to the Cross, whose teaching is that a religious life will exonerate one from the consequences of great crimes. Homer and the romances and poems current in the medieval ages have caused many of the wars that the world has seen. One might find it possible to trace some of the world's wars back to the influences of the stories about Achilles, Caesar, Alexander, The Cid and Charlemagne. One might also show how the false doctrine of philosophers like Socrates and Seneca inculcated in 81 pupils like Alcibiades and Nero were responsible for the terrible calamities that these monsters inflicted upon their countries. Both philosophers personally taught their disciples and had the full opportunity of insisting upon the importance of conforming to ab- stract theories of virtue, and the result of this unnat- ural teaching was that the pupils went in the opposite direction. There can be no doubt that the writings of the fathers and the chief works of monastic philosophy in the medieval ages were responsible for the igno- rance, darkness and misery that were prevalent in those times. And the works of St. Augustine, a Kempis and Dante in particular, by being worshiped so much in our own day have wafted many of the abuses and errors of medievalism into our own times. Spenser, Milton and Bunyan are largely to blame for the Puri- tanism that infects our morality and our art. "What an interesting task it would be for the his- torian to show how the ulcers in our social life, the outcasts of society, the hatred dividing different religions, classes and races are all partly, at least, due to the influences of some famous books. Books have done much to hinder the world's progress. Probably the above authors would have retarded the world's civilization more had Eabelais, Cervantes and Bacon and Montaigne not counteracted them. The fact is that one famous book can do much to spread misery, and what must be the result when there are a hundred or more of such books? It is no mere fantastic idea to trace many of the corruptions and woes of the world in the past, and also the present, to the influence of certain literary tastes and the apotheosis of some classic. In his chapter on the "Burning of Eome" in his Anti-Christ, Eenan has pointed out how the canon- ization of a certain species of literature caused the 82 degeneration in the time of Nero. Seneca no doubt incurs much, of the blame for the inhuman persecution of the early Christians ; and yet many of his own teach- ings were Christian in spirit. He created a false taste by teaching mankind to affect one feeling when experi- encing another, to reason directly contrary to one's instincts. The aim after rhetoric and pseudo virtue destroyed the taste of the times and corrupted the morality. His essays and dialogues were forced and artificial and genuine feeling departed from the age, and a love for cruelty spread. Eenan also shows how Seneca's Tragedies and the Lacoon introduced a love for counterfeit pathos and the expression of the gigantic in art and literature. People began as a consequence to experience a desire to see the myths acted and the tragic catastrophes enacted by living people who were torn by wild beasts and burnt alive, soaked in oil. Eousseau tried to prove that our troubles in this world were due to the progress of thought in the realms of art and science. Though this view is no longer seriously entertained, he caught a glimmer of the idea that books in which are incorporated pernicious and artificial ideas are among the chief causes of the misery infecting our social and spiritual life. True civilization may not, as Eousseau thought, be the cause of man's sufferings, but books in which obsolete and false bygone civilizations live over again may be the source of the woes of mankind. 2. Eeverence for some of the classics prevents us from appreciating the really good books that do appear. It delays the proper estimate of the real mas- terpieces of today. It will be found in most cases that a new genius is usually welcomed by critics who are not blind worshipers of the classics. The classics are made authorities for our taste, which constantly 83 alters. They hinder it from developing and compel the laws derived from them to govern us in judging new works. Admiration for these classics hinders the march of ideas. It tends to keep life and art at a standstill; it is the enemy of the expansion of the individuality. It militates against independent thought and would consider ideas different from those expounded in the classics as erroneous. The fact that many of the famous literary critics could not understand the great authors of their day may lie in a too eager application to some classics. As Addington Symonds shows us, the Elizabethan Age was the great period of writers, chiefly because it was an age of individualism in art ; an age where there existed freedom from the influences of preceding authors. Great names were not flaunted into the eyes of the poets to compel them to walk in the beaten path. The laws of art as formulated by critics from past works of art did not exert a tyrannical influence. The Elizabethan dramatists did not write tragedies with Seneca and Aeschylus before them. Bacon became a great philosopher because he overthrew the authority of Plato and Aristotle. The poets, although they were admirers of some of the ancient and Italian writers, nevertheless looked into their own hearts and wrote. Authors of great repute influence mankind into developing bad literary taste. They are praised both for their faults and virtues indiscriminately, and the distinction as to which is which is soon lost. Every great author is also instrumental in ruining the moral and intellectual development of his country. His man- nerisms are adopted and his bigoted ideas gain enor- mous popularity. His weaknesses are admired as his strong points ; he gathers about him a host of imitators and rules of art formed from his works are strictly followed. There is no question, for instance, that Pope 84 was largely responsible for the decline of English poetry in the eighteenth century. The law of poetry was laid down as something that was written in heroic couplets and was correct, artificial and commonplace. Scott is largely to blame for the trashy novels of adven- ture that all Europe began producing after his death. Had he never lived, probably the psychological novel and the novel of character and idea would have been in the ascendant sooner. Chaucer left a host of imitators, and as a result a barren period in English poetry after his death. ' ' After the praise of refining the taste of a nation, ' ' says Adam Smith, "the highest eulogy perhaps, which can be bestowed upon an author, is to say that he cor- rupted it. ' ' We should fear the influence of our great authors, be on everlasting watch whether we are not admiring them for defects. We should not pride ourselves on the fact that we are always discovering new beauties in the classics. We may be preparing thus the age of artistic corruption. To remain on a level with the classics and under their sway is to neglect the richer and more intellectual side of our own nature, to kill our originality, suspend our judgment and retard the progress of our own minds.