BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME FROM TB[E SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF fietirg W, Sage 1891 fi.A^.'^iSJ.I.. ^^^.4/A//..* 6896-1 Cornell University Library R 133.M81 The relation of medicine to philosophy, 3 1924 011 949 835 Cornell University Library The original of tiiis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924011949835 THE RELATION OF xMEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY THE RELATION OF MEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY BY .R. O. MOON, M.A., M.D.OxoN., F.R.C.P. PHYSICIAN TO THE NATIONAL HOSPITAL FOR DISEASES OF THE HEART ASSISTANT PHYSICIAN TO THE ROYAL WATERLOO HOSPITAL LONGMANS, GREEN AND CO. 39 PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON NEW YORK, BOMBAY, AND CALCUTTA 1909 All right^tXeserved La Philosophie apr^s avoir renferm^ dans son sein toutes les sciences naissantes, a dfl'les voir se s^parer d'elle, aussitol qu'elles sont arrives k un degrd suffisant de d^veloppement. Viendra-t-il un jour ou elles y rentreront, non pas avec la masse de leurs details, mais avec leurs rdsultats g^neraux ; un jour oil la philosophie sera moins une science k part qu'une face de toutes les sciences, une sorte de centre lumineux ou toutes connaissances humaines se ren- contreront par leur sommet en divergeant k mesure qu'elles descendront aux details ? Ren AN, DAvenir de la Science. Le vice radical des histoires de la mddecine et qui les frappe presque toutes de sterility, c'est qu'on y consid^re notre science, dans son ensemble ou dans ses details, comme une creation isolde, sans relations ni pariente avec les autres creations de I'esprit humain : " Proles sine matre creata." Daremberg, Histoire des Sciences Midicales. PREFACE This little book, of which the first three chap- ters have already appeared in the British Medical Journal, and which I am allowed here to reproduce, by the kind permission of the Editor, does not profess in any sense to be a History of Medicine. With that we are already furnished, on a large scale in the shape of Haeser's encyclopaedic work, and on a smaller scale in Withington's most illuminating History of Medicine from the Earliest Times. To both of these works I am very largely indebted, as also to Kurt Sprengel's History of Medicine, the references to which are taken from the French trans- lation by Jourdan (1815). Its object is rather to show, by taking various important epochs in the history of the world, how intimately medicine has been bound up with the current thought and philosophy of the day ; . how medicine no more than art can work away by itself, uninfluenced by the intellectual milieu in which it finds itself. We shall thus see why some epochs have been peculiarly favourable to the progress of medicine, others as markedly the reverse. Speaking generally, medicine has advanced in periods of great intellectual activity, and remained in a state of stagna- viii PREFACE tion during times of intellectual torpor ; though this rule must not be taken too absolutely, as there have been times of great intellectual awakening which have given an unbridled licence to the imagination, and this has almost invariably led medicine off on a false track. It seems to me that this way of looking at the history of medicine may not be unhelpful in the practice of our profession, enabling us perhaps to come to the study and observation of disease with a broader outlook. The rise and fall of so many systems and methods of treatment, while inculcating a prudent scepticism, need not make us despair. The great advantage which truth possesses over error is that it may be discovered again. The study of the history of medicine has this advantage over that of art, that it is progressive, for " II n'y a pas pr6cise- ment de progres pour I'art ; il y a variation dans I'id^al. Presque toutes les literatures ont a leur origine le modHe de leur perfection. La science, au contraire, avance par des proc^d^s tout opposes." ^ Thus, though we are rightly and reasonably proud of the achievements of medicine in the nineteenth century, which it has shared with science generally, we feel that we may make one further demand of it : What is the result of all this progress ? is it really the amelioration of the human lot, or is it only the setting of a larger number of ingenious puzzles — knowledge for the sake of knowledge, art for art's sake — is that the conclu- sion of the whole matter ? Happily, no. Knowledge * Renan, L'Avenir de la Science. PREFACE ix is for the sake of life. The end of Hfe is living — not indeed to t^v, but to e5 f^v. That the progress of medical science has enor- mously reduced the death-rate no one can possibly deny. The cry occasionally heard, that there is a vast increase in diseases which were never heard of before, is purely absurd ; this increase of disease is merely increase in the differentiation of disease. Because at one time the word fever served to cover almost every affection in which the pulse and respiration were quickened and the skin hot, the sum total of disease has not been increased by giving different names to the various fevers. To take a more techni- cal instance, the disease of the nervous system called " Disseminated Sclerosis " will almost undoubtedly be divided up with increasing knowledge into several diseases of the spinal cord, but the sum total of diseases will not be larger. There is, however, just this much truth in the outcry, that as man's life has become more complex with advancing civilisation, so the possibility of minor oscillations from complete adjustment to the environment becomes increasingly great ; it is more difficult to be perfectly healthy, because a higher standard of health is required by modern life. This is particularly seen in the case of insanity ; for civilisation, by increasing the number of social and moral rules to be observed, increases the possibility of their infraction. Modern medicine has been so much engaged in tracking out the minutiae of disease, that it has failed X PREFACE to give as much attention to health in general as was the case in bygone days. Former epochs of medicine, with their vast generalisations, co-extensive with the whole of life, had not got enough positive knowledge about the human organism to justify such generalisa- tions. Just as the French Revolutionists thought that society could be reconstructed de novo from first principles in accordance with reason, without having any knowledge of the laws of the historic growth of society, so the system makers of medicine en- deavoured to lay down laws for human life without having any sufficient knowledge of the mechanism of the human organism. Plain living and high thinking must ever be the rule of the wise, but the attempt to return to the simplicity of the savage, or even to the elementary life of a more primitive people, is neither possible nor desirable ; the plain living of many nations, who are called blessed because they have no history, is associated with very jejune thinking, or with no thought at all. No members of the great nations of the West can wish to return to such a condition of things : the increasing complexity of thought and feeling should rather be welcomed as differentiating man further and further from the brutes that perish ; yet, on the other hand, the increasing complexity of his physical or animal life is just what should at all hazards be avoided. Here he may wisely imitate the savage, for thus he will have the strongest basis on which his intellectual and moral life may develop ; for PREFACE xi surely the object of life is to combine the simplicity of the savage with the subtlety of the sage. Medicine, therefore, in order to take its proper place in the social organism, must embrace the whole of life and be prepared to suggest the type of intellectual as well as other activity suitable to any given patient, just as it would prescribe for a bodily ailment. To some extent this method was practised by the Jesuits ; but with them the object was to produce a special kind of character with a view to a highly definite end, whereas in our case it would simply be the endeavour to enable each individual to make the best of his life. To preserve life must ever be the honour and duty of the physician, but to make life livable should be his aim also. . If life has lost its savour, how is it to be lived ? In a too exclusive pursuit of health, may we not lose the object of life, " et propter vitam vivendi perdere causas " ? The function of the _poet, Goethe tells us somewhere, is so to represent things that we may find life tolerable ; and the physician, in providing for the health of the body as a sort of indispensable prerequisite, must ever have before his mind that wider outlook which shall enable him to cope with the tcedium vitce, Weltschmerz, maladie de Finfini, or by whatever name we like to call those ills which seem inseparable from the travail of an advanced civilisation struggling to a new birth. CONTENTS CHAP. TAOE I. THE RELATION OF EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY TO EARLY GREEK MEDICINE .... I II. POST-HIPPOCRATIC SCHOOLS OF MEDICINE IN RE- LATION TO CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY . 1 6 III.. THE RELATION OF GALEN TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF HIS TIME 35 IV. INFLUENCE OF EARLY CHRISTIANITY ON MEDICINE 50 V. ARAB MEDICINE AND ARAB PHILOSOPHY . . 67 VI. VARIOUS INFLUENCES AFFECTING MEDICINE IN THE MIDDLE AGES 83 VII. MEDICINE AND THE RENAISSANCE . . . 106 VIII. PARACELSUS AND THE MEDICINE OF HIS TIME . 125 IX. THE EFFECT OF PHILOSOPHY ON MEDICINE IN THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY. . . -144 X. THE INFLUENCE OF PHILOSOPHY ON MEDICINE IN THE EARLY PART OF THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY . 170 xiv CONTENTS CHAP. JPAGE XI. INFLUENCE OF CONTEMPORARY THOUGHT ON MEDICINE IN THE SECOND HALF OF THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY 1 89 [XII. INFLUENCE OF CONTEMPORARY THOUGHT ON MEDICINE IN THE NINETEENTH CENTURY . 207 THE RELATION OF MEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY CHAPTER I THE RELATION OF EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY TO EARLY GREEK MEDICINE The tendency of modern civilisation towards a minute and elaborate specialisation is apt to make us forget that there was a time when such important branches of human activity as religion, philosophy, and medi- cine were hardly separated from one another. In the earliest days of ancient Greece the mind ranged with equal energy over every field of human knowledge ; priests, philosophers, and doctors had not yet become differentiated into their several castes. To map out, divide, and to some extent isolate the several provinces of the human mind was therefore an important prob- lem for the early Greek thinkers. In the world of art a somewhat similar state of things existed, for we find music, dancing, poetry, painting, sculpture, and archi- tecture inextricably blended together, so as to form one harmonious whole. All these several arts, in accordance with the Spencerian doctrine of a prog- A 2 RELATION OF MEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY ress from homogeneity to heterogeneity, have gradu- ally become separated, and have developed along their own individual lines to some extent independently. Hence it has resulted that, in considering a picture or a statue, it scarcely occurs to us to regard the propriety of the architecture of the room or gallery in which it is exhibited, any more than, in listening to a great singer, it has been customary to give particular heed to the words of the song. In this region of art, however, Wagner, some fifty years ago, undoubtedly effected a vast revolution, and attempted, with what amount of success the annual pilgrimages to Baireuth bear witness, to reintegrate the several arts and to bring them all harmoniously to the service of his emotional expression. On this very account he has been stigmatised by Dr. Max Nordau as a degenerate of a particularly evil type. The most enthusiastic Wagnerian and keen advo- cate of this reintegration and co-ordination of the arts would probably admit that music, dancing, poetry, painting, &c., had derived the greatest benefit from their long period of isolated development, and con- sequently-had been able to rise to a far higher pitch of excellence than would have been possible had the differentiation never taken place. If this be true in the sphere of the arts it is surely not less so in that of medicine, philosophy, and re- ligion, and it is interesting to consider how far medi- cine was attaining to an independent and separate existence in the early days of Greek civilisation. GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MEDICINE 3 The close connection of medicine with religion has been characteristic of all primitive races, and the Greek formed no exception to the rule. The earliest records of Hellenic life show that the power of healing was an attribute of all the gods, though possessed in a pre-eminent degree by Apollo, Artemis, and Pallas. Rather later, in post-Homeric times, the gods had begun to specialise, and Asclepius appears" as the sole god of healing, \yhile medicine was practised by the priests of his temples, who were known as "ascle- piads," The astonishing intellectual activity of this gifted race is shown by the way in which medicine emancipated itself from the trammels of religious formalism and superstitious belief at a very early stage of its development. When compared with Egyptians, Indians, or Babylonians, the contrast is the more striking. That the Greeks were as pro- foundly susceptible to religious mysticism as the Orientals, the strange society of Eleusis amply tes- tifies ; but they differed from the Orientals in the natural force and versatility of their intellect, which made them impatient of truths sanctioned only by external authority. This emancipation of medicine from religion was due largely to the speculations of the pre-Socratic philosophers, but their usefulness to medicine has perhaps been rather undervalued owing to other evils which they brought in their train, and more particularly the excessive employment of the deduc- tive method. Their tendency to be for ever finding 4 RELATION OF MEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY the general in the particular, and then making most sweeping deductions, was doubtless inimical to a sober and steady pursuit of medicine. On the other hand, though the conclusions to which this method led were only too often fanciful and absurd, yet it was certainly better than having no method at all, as was the case with the other nations of antiquity. At all events, it furnished a strong stimulus to intellectual activity, which is an essential pre-requisite to any sound progress, whether in art or science. One of the earliest signs of interest in medical, or rather physiological, matters is the saying of Anaxi- menes that the world breathes. He considered that just as man is kept alive by drawing in draughts of air, so the world is kept going by the draughts of air which it inhales from the infinite mass beyond the heavens. This philosopher, who flourished 550 B.C., believed that air was the ultimate substance out of which the whole world was made, just as Thales had held water to be the primary substance. In this instance, we have an argument from the micro- cosm to the macrocosm, and Anaximenes utilises his physiological observation of breathing to support his cosmological theory. Heracleitus of Ephesus {fl, 500 B.C.) exercised a great influence upon succeeding philosophers, and even upon Plato, who was a Heracleitean in his youth. Medicine, too, was affected by his doctrines, as we gather from various passages in the De Diceta of Hippo- crates. His leading ideas are well known ; thus : — GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MEDICINE 5 "All things are in constant flux, and nothing has permanence; man cannot descend twice into the same stream, everything is continually passing over into something else, and this proves that it is one nature which assumes the most opposite forms, and pervades the most various conditions ... all comes from One, and One from All." ^ To this philosopher the world was an eternally living fire, certain measures of which were always being kindled, while like measures were always being extinguished, and so the constant flux of things was kept going, and yet the world in appearance was relatively stable. This theory of the cosmos was applied by Heracleitus to man, who, like the macro- cosm, is made of fire, water, and earth ; but as in the case of the world the fire is the only important element, and is identified with the one wisdom, so in the microcosm fire alone is conscious. When it has left the body, the remainder, the mere earth and water, is altogether worthless. The fire which ani- mates man is subject to the " upward and downward path," just as much as the fire of the world ; and again, we read in the De DicBta that " all things are passing, both human and divine, upwards and down- wards." We are just as much in perpetual flux as anything else in the world. We are not the same for two consecutive instants. The fire in us is perpetually becoming water, and the water earth ; but as the opposite process goes on simultaneously we appear > Zeller, Outlines of Greek Philosophy. 6 RELATION OF MEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY to remain the same. Man, like the world, is subject to a certain oscillation in his " measures " of fire and water, which gives rise to the alternations of sleeping and waking, life and death. Sleep was produced by the encroachment of moist, dark exhalations from the water in the body which causes the fire to burn low. In a soul where the fire and water were evenly balanced, the equilibrium would be restored in the morning by an equal encroachment of the fire on the water. The Heracleitean idea that the " unseen harmony " of the universe and man was maintained by the strife of opposites not unnaturally gave rise to some strange views on dietetics and medical treatment. , Pythagoras (Jl. 550 B.C.) was the most famous of all these early thinkers, and his influence upon medicine has certainly been the greatest. Strictly speaking, his position is not quite analogous to that of the other Ionian philosophers ; for he was not only a philo- sopher but also a religious leader, the founder of a brotherhood and teacher of a "way of life." His position is rather more comparable with that of Con- fucius and Laotsze in China, with whom, indeed, he was contemporary. The fame of Pythagoras has been kept alive rather by his religious and moral teachings than by the remarkable speculations on number, although at present we are more immediately concerned with these. This Pythagorean doctrine of number has often been misunderstood. When Pytha- goras said "things are numbers," he was making an attempt to explain the sensible world from a sensible GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MEDICINE 7 origin, it was not an idealistic hypothesis. Numbers to Pythagoras were not abstract as they are with us, though it is difficult for us to think of them as being anything else. Aristotle tells us that these numbers were intended to be mathematical numbers, but that " they were not separated from the objects of sense " ; they could not, therefore, be mathematical numbers in the ordinary sense of the term, inasmuch as bodies were made up of them. In reality these numbers of Pythagoras were spatial numbers — that is, their points had magnitude, their lines breadth, and their surfaces thickness. Thus, while a modern geometer regards a line as having only one dimension, the Pythagoreans identified it with the number two. They considered that numbers were built up of geometrical figures, that they were portions of space cut off and limited in a variety of ways. The properties of number wei-e studied by means of geometrical constructions. The Pythagoreans spoke of square and oblong numbers, and they called odd numbers "gnomons." ^ Being unable to distinguish ideal or intelligible numbers from sensible or materialised numbers, they were forced to identify with magnitudes purely ideal things, such as justice, which was described as an equal number multiplied by an equal — that is, one of the first two square numbers, four and nine — because it returns equal for equal. Medicine was undoubtedly influenced by this doc- trine of the importance of number, and from it origi- 1 Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy. 8 RELATION OF MEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY nated the medical teaching of " critical days." It is worth noting, also, that Empedocles, who was in- fluenced by Pythagorean teaching, speaks of the fetus being formed in the womb on the thirty-sixth day, and completed on the forty-ninth, and was probably led into this speculation by the fact that these numbers are the squares of 6 and 7 respectively. To this number 7 Pythagoras and his disciples attached a special importance ; perhaps their medical studies had led them to observe that the second teeth came out at the seventh year, puberty synchronised with the fourteenth, and the beard appears at the twenty- first. In the matter of practice the Pythagoreans in- fluenced medicine in the direction of diet and gym- nastic treatment; their school used poultices and salves very little, still less internal medicaments, and least of all the knife and cautery. Many physicians gave in their adherence to this school of thought, of whom the best known is Alcmaeon of Croton. Empedocles of Agrigentum {fl. 460 B.C.), in addition to being a philosopher, was also a practical physician, and Galen ascribes to him the foundation of the Italian school of medicine. Certainly some of his doctrines were more favourable to the scientific study of medi- cine than those of his predecessors. For instance, "we must not attempt to construct a theory of the universe offhand, instead of simply trying to under- stand each thing we come across in the way in which it is clear." GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MEDICINE 9 " We must not reject the assistance of the senses, for they are the only channels through which know- ledge can enter our minds at all ; we must make use of them all, and neglect the testimony of none, not even that of taste." Here, indeed, we seem to breathe for a moment something of the atmosphere of modern science. Various physiological or quasi-medical speculations have come down to us from Empedocles. Thus, with regard to respiration, he said, "We breathe through all the pores of the skin, not merely through the organs of respiration. " Alternate inspiration and expiration of the breath are caused by the movement of the blood from the heart to the surface of the body and back again, "All things draw breath and breathe it out again. All have bloodless tubes of flesh extended over the surface of their bodies, and at the mouths of these the uttermost surface of the skin is perforated all over with pores closely packed together, so as to keep in the blood while a free passage is cut for the air to pass through. Then, when the yielding blood recedes from these, the bubbling air i-ushes in with an impetuous surge, and when the blood runs back it is breathed out again." Tears and sweat arise from a disturbance which curdles the blood; they are, so to speak, the whey of the blood. Again, perception is caused by the meeting of an element in us with the same element outside ; our knowledge varies with the varying con- lo RELATION OF MEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY dition of our bodies. To his views as to the dates of the formation of the fetus we have already referred in discussing Pythagoras, but in this connection may be mentioned his curious description of the secretion of milk : " On the tenth day of the eighth month the white pus (ttvov) arises," which clearly means the mammary secTttion. He discovered the labyrinth of the ear by dis- secting goats ; he also perceived that in plants two sexes are combined, but thought that they came into being in an imperfect state of the universe, and that the distinction of the sexes was the result of the gradual differentiation brought about by the entrance of hate into the world. He further held that love was the principle which was capable of bringing the four elements into union, but he regarded it from an entirely physiological standpoint, and so considered that it was the same impulse to union as is implanted in human bodies. Here, again, we have an instance of a physiological observation being employed in the explanation of the cosmos. With Anaxagoras of Clazomenae (_/?. 450 B.C.) we come to the end of the pre-Socratic philosophers. He occupies among them a most honourable position ; he was the teacher of Pericles, and Aristotle speaks of him as "the only sober man amongst drunkards." It was he who introduced the idea of mind (1/0O9) as the cause of motion among the elements, and has therefore been credited with the introduction of the suprasensible into philosophy. This, however, may GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MEDICINE ii be going too far, and there is some ground for supposing that the vov<; of Anaxagoras was only a highly differentiated kind of matter ; that, in fact, he conceived of it as a body, and substituted it for the love and hate of Empedocles, which had been intro- duced in order to explain the source of motion in the world. Whatever may have been the precise meaning which Anaxagoras attached to mind, he certainly considered that it was the same in all living creatures, both in the animal and vegetable kingdoms, and that the different grades of intelligence depended entirely on the structure of the body. Plants he regarded as animals fixed in the earth. His interest in physiology is shown by his theory that sensation implies pain, for all unlike things produce pain by their contact, and this pain is made perceptible by the long con- tinuance or by the excess of a sensation. In man even sensible perception is the work of mind, but as it. is effected by means of the bodily organs it is therefore inadequate. Such were some of the random philosophical specu- lations which affected the development of Greek medicine prior to the advent of the master mind which was to bring some kind of order out of this heterogeneous collection of generalisations. Hippocrates, as we all know, stands in the same relation to medicine as Homer does to poetry and Herodotus to history. His title to this proud position was earned not so much by any special observations, 12 RELATION OF MEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY valuable as some of these undoubtedly were, far less by any such epoch-making discovery as distinguished our English Harvey, but because, in the words of Celsus, he separated medicine from philosophy.* He continued the emancipation from religion which had already been in part accomplished by the dissolving influence of the sixth-century philosophers, saying that one disease is no more divine or human than another, but that each occurs in accordance with Nature (Kara vai,v). But, above all, he was the first to start medicine on an independent Hne of its own and to free it from the somewhat crude speculations of these early Ionian philosophers on the one hand and the sterile theories of the Eclectics on the other — sterile for all purposes of immediate medical advancement, but fruitful indeed for the birth of metaphysics in the future. For here it may be well to point out that by philosophy in this connection we are not meaning metaphysics, for they, in the strict sense of the term, hardly existed before the time of Plato and Aristotle. The latter tells us that the pre-Socratic thinkers had no conception of reality except as cognisable by the senses {Uepl fiev T&v SvTcov rr/v oKrjdeiav iaKo-rrovv, ra S^Sptu vTriXa^ov etvai TO, alaOrjTo. fiovov). Their philosophy could not be of much direct assistance to medicine in its early stages before anatomy, and still less physiology, had been seriously ' Primus quidetn ex omnibus memoria dignis ab studio sapienticC disci- plinam banc separavit. GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MEDICINE 13 studied, while on the other hand the influence of medicine on philosophy was certainly at times far from favourable. Thus, from the time of Thales to that' of Plato and Aristotle, philosophy, with many ups and downs, had gradually advanced to the foundation of a stable metaphysics, in which it was recognised that there may be realities of which the senses could never conceivably take cognisance. For the purpose of this kind of progress the mere accumu- lation and observation of facts can be of little use, however beneficial for the advance of medicine. In fact, the influence of medicine was sometimes directly harmful to advance in metaphysics ; thus, at a time when all philosophic progress was necessarily in the direction of pluralism, which culminated in the atomic theory of Leucippus, the medical theorisers of the day opposed this, believing that a monistic foundation of the universe was required by medicine, as otherwise it would be impossible to understand how one thing could do good or harm to another. Hippocrates was considerably influenced by all these speculations, nor did he brush them aside as useless, but he showed that the observation of in- dividual facts was the only method of proceeding in order to obtain any real progress in medicine. It seems not unnatural to inquire how it came' about that medicine, having once been set upon the right line of progress by Hippocrates, did not con- tinue steadily upon this more scientific course. One reason would seem to be that Hippocrates perhaps 14 RELATION OF MEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY hardly realised the importance of his own work on its theoretical side. He had been led to a careful observation of facts by the naturally practical bent of his genius, and not because he fully comprehended the importance of the inductive method for the study of medicine. Then, too, being a practising physician, and actually busied with technical matters and the collection of facts, he had not time or occasion fully to set forth the theory of his method as a logical instrument for the purpose of scientific progress. Bacon, on the other hand, when, nearly two thousand years later, he forged anew the weapon of inductive reasoning, lent the whole weight of his genius to the formulation of his method ; so that though to some extent he busied himself with the practicalities of science, we cannot say that there are any special observations of value made by him, or that he bene- fited any one science in particular. Another reason which prevented the method of Hippocrates from being carried out by his medical successors was the growth and development of meta- physics under the inspiration of Plato and Aristotle. Their highly imaginative philosophy drew away to itself many of the ablest minds in Greece, so that the more prosaic inductive method, whether as applied to medicine or anything else, fell more and more into the background. Then came the gradual decay of Greece, and the decadence of all philosophic forms of thought. With the advent of Galen {fl. i6o A.D.) came an immense stimulus to the study of medicine. GREEK PHILOSOPHY AND MEDICINE 15 He was a man of vast erudition and immense medical knowledge, and to some extent he revived the Hip- pocratic tradition. But, in addition to the great contributions which he certainly made to medicine, he also wrote extensively on philosophy, and en- deavoured to unite medicine with the metaphysics of Plato. This unfortunate move arrested the further progress of medicine for more than a thousand years. The system of Galen was taken as a gospel by the Arabian physicians, and the extraordinary reverence for external authority in matters intellectual character- istic of this people, combined with the growing powers and influence of the Church, stifled all independent thought, and consequently all medical progress, until the dawn of the Renaissance. The aim of Galen was praiseworthy enough, but it was premature, for medicine at that time had not been working long enough in isolation to render fruitful such a union with religion or philosophy. As in all ages, however, the contemporary religious and philosophic thought of the day has had an influence at least unconscious upon medical practice, the question arises whether the time may not now have arrived for making the relationship more definitely conscious, and effecting for medicine that co-ordina- tion with religion and philosophy which Wagner accomplished for music with the sister arts. CHAPTER II POST-HIPPOCRATIC SCHOOLS OF MEDICINE IN RELA- TION TO CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY In the last chapter we attempted to explain the relation of early Greek philosophy to early Greek medicine. Continuing the same line of inquiry, we now propose to see how far the schools of medicine immediately succeeding Hippocrates were dominated by the philosophic influences of the time, and were indeed the expression of them. Goethe says some- where that there is a certain logic in the actions of men and women which enabled him in his youth to write correctly about things of which he had no experience, but which, on growing older, he found out to be true. Similarly, in reflecting on the history of the art of heahng, we are led to conclude that there is a logical bond between the various activities of the human mind, so that a subject such as medicine, independent as it may seem, does not grow up and develop in isolation, separated off from the other creations of mental energy, but is of necessity connected with the pre- vailing philosophic theories of the day. Periods of constructive medicine are the outcome of periods of constructive thought, so that we must not POST-HIPPOCRATIC SCHOOLS OF MEDICINE 17 expect any serious advances in the former when the latter is in a state of stagnation. The death of Hippocrates (357 B.C.) coincided with the decadence of philosophy and the cor- ruption of morals which ensued after the battles of Leuctra and Mantinea, when Greece fell into a general condition of intellectual flabbiness and moral laxity. From this mental paralysis medicine assuredly did not escape. Instead of advancing soberly along the path traced out for her by Hippocrates, she embraced wild theories and absurd practices. During the five hundred years which elapsed between the death of the great physician of Cos and the advent of Galen it would seem that medical knowledge was in the trough of the wave. No striking discoveries were made or illuminating principles enunciated during that period ; men either lost themselves among the hill-tops of speculation or were engulfed in the quagmires of doubt. The lack of intellectual fibre so charac- teristic of this epoch was reflected in the medical schools, for when one department of a nation's mental life suffers, the whole is apt to suffer with it. The first of the medical schools of this period to become famous was that of the Dogmatists. The name is not very happily chosen, but it was given to them by Galen, and has been followed by subsequent writers, so that it must be adopted for the sake of convenience. Roughly speaking, they 1 8 RELATION OF MEDICINE TO PHILOSOPHY occupy the century from the death of Hippocrates to the estabHshment of medical schools at Alexandria (357-264). The earlier representatives of this school, ? namely, Dioxippus and Praxagoras of Cos, followed I closely the doctrines of their master Hippocrates ; ' they accepted his medical teaching without, how- ever, in the least imbibing his spirit of sober scientific observation. Thus they adopted his humoral pathology and made it a most essential part of their system. According to this theory, all diseases are explained by a mixture of humours which are four in number, namely (i) blood, (2) yellow bile found in the liver, (3) mucus in the head, (4) black bile in the spleen. The medical treatment based upon this was that medicines work upon the predominating cardinal humours, some expelling mucus, others removing bile, &c. This theory controlled medicine for more than ten centuries, and eventually only gave way to the most modern views. Far more important for this school, however, was the influence of the Platonic philosophy. Having taken as their motto the saying of Hippocrates that " the physician who is also a philosopher is Godlike," ^ they proceeded with commendable zeal to try and earn this title by a careful study of the Timceus. This famous dialogue of Plato became their text-book of philosophy, and with disastrous results, for this work, though described by Jowett as obscure and 1 'I))Tp4! 7*/) 0(\6(ra0os liriOeos. Hippocrates, Uepi tiirxw<>