FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE MSmPHYSlC OF ETHICS EMMANUEL iK ANT T.K. ABBOTT. z^ M3 CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY FROM The Philosophical Review DATE DUE ^PR^BIfcF=^^ ^ 4k^M*Tim^^ PniNTCOINU.SA. « Cornell University B Library The original of tliis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924029021546 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES THE METAPHYSIC OF ETHICS, ,,,ji/'.A«,\JV>,.^j_^ BY THE SAME AUTHOR. SIGHT AND TOTTCH, 8vo. 51. 6d. iOut of Print. ^ KANT'S CEITIQTTE OF FBACTICAL BDASON, and other Works on the Theory of Ethics. Fourth Edition. 8vo. I2J. dd. KANT'S INTRODUOTION TO LOGIC. 8vo. ts. ELEMENTAET THEORT OF THE TIDES. 2i. OUB. ABC. id. CHWOLSON ON THE VOWEL LETTERS IN ANCIENT HEBREW ORTHOGRAPHY. Translated. 2s. EVANGELIA ANTEHEERONTMIANA. 8vo. 2 vols. 21J. CODEX RESCRIFTUS DTIBLINENSIS. 4to. 211. ESSAYS CHIEFLY ON THE ORIGINAL TEXTS OF THE OLD AND NEW TESTAMENTS. 8vo. loj. bd. • I DO THIS IN BEICEUBRANCE OF JIE": A Reply to Criticisms. 8vo. -ls. SHOBT NOTES ON ST. PAUL'S EPISTLES TO THE EOIIANS, CORINTHIANS, GALATIANS, EPHE- SIANS, PHILIPPIANS. 8vo. (Dublin University Press Series.) ap. FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES lETAPHYSIC OF ETHICS. BY IMMANUEL KANT. TRANSLATED BY THOMAS KINGSMILL ABBOTT, B.D., Litt.D., FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, DUBLIN. [EXTRACTED FROM "KANT'S CRITIQUE OF PRACTICAL REASON AND OTHER WORKS ON THE THEORY OF ETHICS."'\ LONDON: LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. AND NEW YORK: 15, EAST iS" STREET. 1895. KANT'S CRITIQ^M OF PRACTICAL REASON AND OTHER WORKS ON THE THEORY OF ETHICS. First Edition^ 1813, Second Edition [enlarged), iSfq. Third Edition {further enlarged) ^ i8t Fourth Edition, z88g. Note. — The numbers in the text are those of the pages in Rosenkranz and Schubert's Edition of the original. Notes in square brackets are by the Translator. Printed at THE UNIVERSITY PRESS, Dublin. PREFACE, Ancient Greek Philosophy was divided into three sciences : Physics, Ethics, and Logic. This division is perfectly suitable to the nature of the thing, and the only improvement that can be made in it is to add the principle on which it is based, so that we may both satisfy ourselves of its completeness, and also be able to determine correctly the necessary subdivisions. All rational knowledge is either material or formal : the former considers some object, the latter is con- cerned only with the form of the understanding and of the reason itself, and with the universal laws of thought in general without distinction of its objects. Formal philosophy is called Logic. Material philo- sophy, however, which has to do with determinate objects and the laws to which they are subject, is again two-fold ; for these laws are either laws of nature or of freedom. The science of the former is Physics, that of the latter, Ethics ; they are also called natural philosophy and moral philosophy respectively. Logic cannot have any empirical part; that is, a part in which the universal and necessary laws of thought should rest on grounds taken from experience ; 2 PREFACE TO THE FUNDAMENTAL [4] Otherwise it would not be logic, i.e. a canon for the understanding or the reason, valid for all thought, and capable of demonstration (4). Natural and moral philosophy, on the contrary, can each have their empi- rical part, since the former has to determine the laws of nature as an object of experience ; the latter the laws of the human will, so far as it is affected by nature: the former, however, being laws according to which everything does happen ; the latter, laws' according to which everything ought to happen. Ethics, however, must also consider the conditions under which what ought to happen frequently does not. We may call all philosophy empirical, so far as it is based on grounds of experience : on the other hand, that which delivers its doctrines from a /non principles alone we may call pure philosophy. When the latter is merely formal it is logic ; if it is restricted to definite objects of the understanding it is metaphysic. In this way there arises the id^a of a two-fold metaphysic — a metaphysic of nature and a metaphysic of morals. Physics will thus have an empirical and also a rational part. It is the same with Ethics ; but her^ the empirical part might have the special name of practical anthropology, the name morality being appro- priated to the rational part. All trades, arts, and handiworks have gained by diwsion of labour, namely, when, instead of one man 1 [The word ' law ' is here used in two different senses, on whiclP see Whatelj''s Logic, Appendix, Art. ' Law.'] [S] PRINCIPLES— METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 3 doing everything, ^ach confines himself to a certain kind of work distinct from others in the treatment it requires, so as to be able to perform it with greater facility and in the greatest perfection. Where the different kinds of work are not so distinguished and divided, where everyone is a jack-of-all-trades, there manufactures remain still in the greatest barbarism. It might deserve to be considered whether pure philo- sophy in all its parts does not require a man specially devoted to it, and whether it would not be better for the whole business of science if those who, to please the tastes of the public, are ^/wont to blend the rational and empirical elements together, mixed in all sorts of proportions unknown to themselves (5), and who call themselves independent thinkers, giving the name of minute philosophers to those who apply themselves to the rational part only — if these, I say, were warned not to carry on two employments together which differ widely in the treatment they demand, for each of which perhaps a special talent is required, and the combination of which in one person only produces bunglers. But 1 only ask here whether the nature of science does not require that we should always carefully separate the empirical from the rational part, and prefix to Physics proper (or empirical physics) a metaphysic of nature, and to practical anthropology a metaphysic of morals, which must be carefully cleared of everything empirical, so that we may know how much can be accomplished '''by pure reason in both cases, and from what sources it draws this its a priori teaching, and that whether the 4 PREFACE TO THE FUNDAMENTAL [6] latter inquiry is conducted by all moralists (whose name is legion), or only by some who feel a calling thereto. As my concern here is with moral philosophy, I limit the question suggested to this : Whether it is not of t h£ utmost necessity to construct aj^rejngr^ philosophy, perfectjyqieared of everything vchichjs only empirical,_ and which belongs to anthropology ? for that such a philosophy must be possible is evident from the common idea of duty and of the moral laws. Every- one must admit that ifa law is to have moral force, I.e. to be the basis of an obligation, it must carry with jt absolute necessity : that, for example, the precept, ' Thou shalt not lie,' is not valid for men alone, as if other rational beings had no need to observe it ; and so with all the other moral laws properly so called ; that, therefore, the basis of obligation must not be sought in the nature of man, or in the circumstances in the world in which he is placed, but a priori simply in the conceptions of (6) pure reason ; and although any other precept which is founded on principles of mere experience may be in certain respects universal, yet, in as far as it rest/even in the least degree on an empirical basis, perhaps only as to a motive, such a: precept, while it may be a practical rule, can never be called^jmoraljavs:. ~ " Thus not only are moral laws with their principles es- sentially distinguished from every other kind of practical knowledge in which there is anything empirical, but all moral philosophy rests wholly on its pure part. When applied to man, it dotes not borrow the least thing from [7] PRINCIPLES— METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 5 the knowledge of man himself (anthropology), but gives laws a priori to him as a rational being. No doubt these laws require a judgment sharpened by experience, in ordev on the one hand to distinguish in what cases they are applicable, and on the other to procure for them access to the will of the man, and effectual influence on conduct ; since man is acted on by so many inclinations that, though capable of the idea of a practical pure reason, he is .not so easily able to make it effective in concreto in his life. A metaphysic of morals is therefore indispensably necessary, not merely for speculative reasons, in order to investigate the sources of the practical principles which are to be found a priori in our reason, but also because morals themselves are liable to all sorts of corruption, as long as we are without that clue and supreme canon by which to estimate them correctly. For, in order that an action should be morally good, it is not enough that it conform to the moral law, but it must also be dione for the sake of the law, otherwise that conformity is only very contingent and uncertain ; since a principle which is not moral, although it may now and then produce actions conformable to the law, will also often produce actions which contradict it (7). Now it is only in a pure philosophy that we can look for the moral law in its purity and genuineness (and, in a practical matter, this is of the utmost consequence) : we must, therefore, begin with pure philosophy (meta- physic), and without it there cannot be any moral philosophy at all. That which mingles these pure 6 PREFACE TO THE FUNDAMENTAL [7] principles with the empirical does not deserve the name of philosophy (for what distinguishes philosophy from common rational knowledge is, that it treats in separate sciences what the latter only comprehends confusedly) ; much less does it deserve that of moral philosophy, since by this confusion it even spoils the purity of morals themselves, and counteracts its own end. Let it not be thought, however, that what is here demanded is already extant in the propaedeutic prefixed by the celebrated WolP to his moral philosophy, namely, his so-called general practical philosophy, and that, therefore, we have not to strike into an entirely new field. Just because it was to be a general practical philosophy, it has not taken into consideration a will of any particular kind — say one which should be determined solely from a priori principles without any empirical motives, and which we might call a pure will, but volition in general, with all the actions and condi- tions which belong to it in this general signification. By this it is distinguished from a metaphysic of morals, just as general logic, which treats of the acts an4 canons of thought in general, is distinguished from transcendental philosophy, which treats of the parti- cular acts and canons of pure thought, i.e. that whose cognitions are altogether a priori. For the metaphysic 1 [Johann Christian Von Wolf (1679-1728) was the author of treatises on philosophy, mathematics, &c., which were for a long time the standard text -books in the German Universities. His philosophy was founded on that of Leibnitz.] [8] PRIJTCIPLES— METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 7 of morals has to examine the idea and the principles of a possible pure will, and not the acts and conditions of human volition generally, which for the most part are drawn from psychology (8). It is true that moral laws and duty are spoken of in the general practical philosophy (contrary indeed to all fitness). But this is no objection, for in this respect also the authors of that science remain true to their idea of it ; they do not distinguish the motives which are prescribed as such by reason alone altogether a priori, and which are properly moral, from the empirical motives which the under- standing raises to general conceptions merely by com- parison of experiences ; but without noticing the difference of their sources, and looking on them all as homogeneous, they consider only their greater or less amount. It is in this way they frame their notion of obligation, which, though anything but moral, is all that can be asked for in a philosophy which passes no judgment at all on the origin of all possible practical concepts, whether they are a. priori, or only a poste- riori. Jntending to publish hereafter a metaphysic of morals, I issue in the first instance these fundamental principles. Indeed there is properly no other foundation for it than the critical examination of a pure practical reason ; just as that of metaphysics is the critical examination of the pure speculative reason, already published. But in the first place the former is not so absolutely necessary as the latter, because in moral concerns human reason can easily be brought to a high degree of correctness and 8 PREFACE TO THE FUNDAMENTAL [9] completeness, even in the commonest understanding, while on the contrary in its theoretic but pure use it is wholly dialectical ; and in the second place if the cri- tique of a pure practical reason is to be complete, it must be possible at the same time to show its identity with the speculative reason in a common principle, for it can ultimately be only one and the same reason which has to be distinguished merely in its application. I could not, however, bring it to such ccfmpleteness here, without introducing considerations of a wholly different kind, which would be perplexing to the reader (9). On this account I have adopted the title of Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals, instead of that of a Critical Examination of the pure practical Reason. But in the third place, since a metaphysic of morals, in spite of the discouraging title, is yet capable of being presented in a popular form, and one adapted to the common understanding, I find it useful to separate from it this preliminary treatise on its fundamental principles, in order that I may not hereafter have need to introduce these necessarily subtle discussions into a book of a. more simple character. The present treatise is, however, nothing more than the investigation and establishment oi the supreme prin- ciple of morality, and this alone constitutes a study com- plete in itself,' and one which ought to be kept apart from every other moral investigation. No doubt my con- clusions on this weighty question, which has hitherto been very unsatisfactorily examined, would receive much light from the application of the same principle [lo] PRINCIPLES— METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 9 to the whole system, and would be greatly confirmed by the adequacy which it exhibits throughout ; but I must forego this advantage, which indeed would be after all more gratifying than useful, since the easy applicability of a principle and its apparent adequacy give no very certain proof of its soundness, but rather inspire a certain partiality, which prevents us from examining and estimating it strictly in itself, and without regard to consequences. I have adopted in this work the method which I think most suitable, proceeding analytically from common knowledge to the determination of its ultimate principle, and again descending synthetically from the examination of this principle and its sources to the common know- ledge in which we find it employed. The division will, therefore, be as follows (lo) : — 1 . First section. — Transition from the common rational knowledge of morality to the philosophical, f 2. Second section, — Transition from popular moral philosophy to the metaphysic of morals. 3. Third section. — Final step from the metaphysic of morals to the critique of the pure practical 10 P'UNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [12] FIRST SECTION. TRANSITION FROM THE COMMON RATIONAL KNOWLEDGE OF MORALITY TO THE PHILOSOPHICAL. Nothing can possibly be conceived in the world, or even out of it, which can be called good without^ qualification, except a Good Will. Intelligence, wif, judgment, and the other talents of the mind, however they may be named, or courage, resolution, perseve- rance, as qualities of temperament, are undoubtedly good and desirable in many respects ; but these gifts of nature may also become extremely bad and mischie-- vous if the will which is to make use of them, and which, therefore, constitutes what is called character, is not good. y It is the same with the gifts of fortune. Power, riches, honour, even health, and the general well-being and contentment with one's condition which is called happiness, inspire pride, and often presumption, if there is not a good will to correct the influence of these on the mind, and with this also to rectify the whole principle of acting, . and adapt it to its end. The sight of a being who is not adorned with a single feature of 'a pure and good will, enjoying unbroken prosperity, can never give' pleasure to an impartial rational spectator (12). Thus a good^wdll_ appears to constitute J^he indispensabl£_condition_even_oflbeiii^ worthy of hap^pmess. ~ There are even some qualities which are of service to this good will itself, and may facilitate its action, yet [13] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. U which have no int rinsic unconditional value , but always presuppose a good will, and this qualifies the esteem that we justly have for them, and does not permit us to regard them as ' absolutely good . Moderation in the affections and passions, self-control and calm delibera- tion are not only good in many respects, but even seem to constitute part of the intrinsic worth "of the person ; but they are far from deserving to be called good without qual ification , although they have been so unconditionally praised by the ancients. For without the principles of a good will, they may become ex- tremely bad, and the coolness of a villain not only makes him f^r more dangerous, but also directly makes him more abominable in our eyes than he would have been without it. A good will is good not because of what it performs or effects, not by its aptness for the attainment of some proposed end, but sijapJ^by xirtu£_QLthe_iQlition, that ~ is, it is good in itself , and considered by itself is to be esteemed much higher than all that can be brought about by it in favour of any inclination, nay, even of the sum total of all inclinations. Even if it should happen that, owing to special disfavour of fortune, or the niggardly provision of a step-motherly nature, this will should wholly lack power to accomplish its purpose, if with its greatest efforts it should yet achieve nothing, and there should remain only the good will (not, to be sure, a mere wish, but the summoning of all means in our power), then, like a jewel, it would still shine by its own light, as a thing which has its whole value in itself (13)- Its usefulness or fruitlessness can neither add to nor take away anything from this value. It would be, as it were, only the setting to enable us to handle it the more conveniently in common commerce. 12 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [14] or to attract to it the attention of those who are not yet connoisseurs, but not to recommend it to true connoisseurs, or to determine its value. There is, however, something so strange in this idea of the "absolute value of the mere will , in which no account is taken of its utility, that notwithstanding the thorough assent of even common reason to the idea, yet a suspicion must arise that it may perhaps really be the product of mere high-flown fancy, and that we may have misunderstood the purpose of nature in assigning reason as the governor of our will. Therefore we will examine this idea from this point of view. In the physical constitution of an organized being, that is, a being adapted suitably to the purposes of life, we assume it as a fundamental principle that no organ for any purpose will be found but what is also the fittest and best adapted for that purpose. Now in a being which has reason and a will, if the proper object of nature were its conservation, its welfare, in a word, its happiness, then nature would have hit upon a very, bad arrangement in selecting the reason of the creature to carry out this purpose. For all the actions which the creature has to perform with a view to this purpose, and the whole rule of its conduct, would be far more surely prescribed to it by instinct, and that end would have been attained thereby much more certainly than it ever can be by reason. Should reason have been communi- cated to this favoured creature over and above, it must only have served it to contemplate the happy constitu- tion of its nature (14), to admire it, to congratulate itself thereon, and to feel thankful for it to the bene- ficent cause, but not that it should Subject its desires to that weak and delusive guidance, and meddle bunglingly with the purpose of nature. In a word, [15] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 13 nature would have taken care that reason should not break forth into practical exercise, nor have the presump- tion, with its weak insight, to think out for itself the plan of happiness, and of the means of attaining it. Nature would not only have taken on herself the choice of the ends, but also of the means, and with wise fore- sight would have entrusted both to instinct. And, in fact, we find that the more a cultivated reason applies itself with deliberate purpose to the enjoyment of life and happiness, so much the more does the man fail of true sa.tisfaction. And from this circumstance there arises in many, if they are candid enough to confess it, a certain degree of misology, that is, hatred of reason, especially in the case of those who are most experienced in the use of it, because after calculating all the advantages they derive, I do not say from the invention of all the arts of common luxury, but even from the sciences (which seem to them to be after all only a luxury of the understanding), they find that they have, in fact, only trought more trouble on."" their shoulders, rather than gained in happiness ; and they end by envying, rather than despising, the more common stamp of men who keep closer to the guidance of mere instinct, and do not allow their reason much influence on their conduct. And this we must admit, that the judgment of those who would very much lower ' the lofty eulogies of the advantages which reason gives t' us in regard to the happiness and satisfaction of life, or _ who would even reduce" them below zero, is by no means morose or ungrateful to the goodness with' which the world is governed, but that there lies at the root of these judgments the idea (15) that our existence"^ has a different and tar nobler end, for which, and not for happiness, reason is properly intended, and which 14 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [i6] must, therefore, be regarded as the supreme condition to which the private ends of man must, for the most part, be postponed. For as reason is not competent to guide the will with certainty in regard to its objects and the satisfaction of all our wants (which it to some extent even multiplies), this being an end to which an implanted instinct would have led with much greater certainty ; and since, nevertheless, reason is imparted to us as a practical faculty, i. e. as one which is to have influence on the > ■will, therefore, admitting that nature generally in the i distribution of her capacities has adapted the means to the end, its true destination must be to produce a will, not mer ely good as a means to something els e, b ut good in i tself, for which reason was absolutely necessary. This will then, though not indeed the sole and complete good, must be the supreme good and the condition of every other, even of the desire of happi- ness. Under these circumstances, there is nothing inconsistent with the wisdom of nature in the fact that the cultivation of the reason, which is requisite for the first and unconditional purpose, does in many ways interfere, at least in this life, with the attainment of the second, which is always conditional, namely, happiness. Nay, it may even reduce it to nothing, without nature thereby failing of her purpose. For reason recognises the establishment of a good will as its highest practical destination, .and in attaining this purpose is capable only of a satisfaction of its own proper kind, namely, that from the attainment of an end, -which end again is determined by reason only, notwithstanding that this may involve many a disappointment to the ends of inclination (i6). We have then to develop the notion of a will which [i6] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 15 deserves to be highly esteemed for itself, and is good without a view to anything further, a notion whk ib exists already i n the soundjaturaLjmderstaiiiiag, requiring rather ivo be cleared ji^thgn to be taught, and which in estimating the value of our actions always takes the first place, and constitutes the condition of all the rest. In order to do this we will take the notion of duty, which includes that of a good will, although implying certain subjective restrictions and hindrances. These, however, far from concealing it, or rendering it unrecognisable, rather bring it out by contrast, and make it shine forth so much the brighter. I omit here all actions which are already recognised as inconsistent with duty, although they may be useful for this or that purpose, for with these the question whether they are done from duty cannot arise at all, since they even conflict with it. I also set aside those actions which really conform to duty, but to which men have no direct z«c/z«a/zb«, performing them because they are impelled thereto by some other inclination. For in this case we can readily distinguish whether the action which agrees with duty is done from duty, or from a selfish view. It is much harder to make this distinction when the action accords with duty, and the subject has besides a direct inclination to it. For example, it is always a matter of duty that a dealer should not over- charge an inexperienced purchaser, and wherever there is much commerce the prudent tradesman does not overcharge, but keeps a fixed price for everyone, so that a child buys of him as well as any other. Men are thus honestly served ; but this is not enough to make us believe that the tradesman has so acted from duty and from principles of honesty : his own advantage required it ; it is out of the question in this case to suppose that 16 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [17] he might besides have a direct inclination in favour of the buyers, so that (17), as it were, from love he should give no advantage to one over another. Accordingly the action was done neither from duty nor from direct inclination, but merely with a selfish view. On the other hand, it is a duty to maintain- one's life ; and, in addition, every one has also a direct inclination to do so. But on this account the often anxious care which most men take for it has no intrinsic worth, and their maxim has no moral import. They preserve their life as duty requires, no doubt, but not because duty requires. On the other hand, if adversity and hopeless sorrow have completely taken away the relish for life ; if the unfortunate one, strong in mind, indignant at his fate rather than desponding or dejected, wishes for death, and yet preserves his life without loving it — not from inclination or fear, but from duty — then his maxim has a moral worth. To be beneficent when we can is a duty ; and besides this, there are many minds so sympathetically constituted that, without any other motive of vanity or self-interest, they find a pleasure in spreading joy around them, and can take delight in the satisfaction of others so far as it is their own work. But I maintain that in such a case an action of this kind, however proper, however amiable it may be, has nevertheless no true moral worth, but is on a level with other inclinations, e.g. the inclination to honour, which, if it is happily directed to that which is in fact of public utility and accordant with duty, and consequently honourable, deserves praise and encou- ragement, but not esteem. For the maxim lacks the moral import, namely, that such actions be done from duty, not from inclination. Put the case that the mind of that philanthropist were clouded by sorrow of his ■[18] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 17 own (18), extinguishing all sympathy with the lot of others, and that while he still has the power to benefit others in distress, he is not touched by their trouble because he is absorbed with his own; and now suppose that he tears himself out of this dead insensibility, and performs the action without any inclination to it, but simply from duty, then first has his action its, genuine moral worth. Further Still; if nature has put little sympathy in the heart of this or that man ; if he, supposed to be an upright man, is by temperament cold and indifferent to the sufferings of others, perhaps because in respect of his own he is provided with the special gift of patience and fortitude, and supposes, or even requires, that others should have the same — and such a man would certainly not be the meanest product of nature — but if nature had not specially framed him for a philanthropist, would he not still find in himself a source from whence to give himself a far higher worth than that of a good-natured temperament could be } Unquestionably. It is just in this that the moral worth of the character is brought out which is incomparably the highest of all, namely, that he is beneficent, not from inclination, but from duty. To secure one's own happiness is a duty, at least indirectly; for discontent with one's condition, under a pressure of many anxieties and amidst unsatisfied wants, might easily become a great temptation to trans- gression of duty. But here again, without looking to duty, all men have already the strongest and most inti- mate inclination to happiness, because it is just in this idea that all inclinations are combined in one total. But the precept of happiness is often of such a sort that it greatly interferes with some inclinations, and yet a man cannot form any definite and certain conception c 18 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [19} of the sum of satisfaction of all of them which is called happiness (19). It is not then to be wondered at that a single inclination, definite both as to what it promises and as to the time within which it can be gratified, is often able to overcome such a fluctuating idea, and that a gouty patient, for instance, can choose to enjoy what he likes, and to suffer what he may, since, according to his calculation, on this occasion at least, he has [only] not sacrificed the enjoyment of the present moment to a possibly mistaken expectation of a happiness which is supposed to be found in health. But even in this case, if the general desire for happiness did not influence his will, and supposing that in his particular case health was not a necessary element in this calculation, there yet remains in this, as in all other cases, this law, namely, that he should proniote his happiness not from inclination but from duty, and byTKirwouid his conduct iSrst acquire true moral worths It is in this manner, undoubtedly, that we are to understand those passages of Scripture also in which we are commanded to love our neighbour, even our enemy. For love, as an aff'ection, cannot be com- manded, but beneficence for duty's sake may ; even though we are not impelled to it by any inclination — nay, are even repelled by a natural and unconquerable aver- sion. This \s practical love, and not/aMo/o^zfgfc^a^love which is seated m the will, and not in the propensions of sense — in principles oi action and not oF tender sympathy ; and it is this love alone which can be com- manded. TKe¥econd' proposition is : That an action done from duty derives its moral worth, not from the purpose which ' [The first proposition was that, to have moral worth, an action must be done from duty.] [2o] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 19 is to be attained by it, but from the maxim by which it is determined, and therefore does not depend on the realization of the dbject of the action, but merely on the principle of volition by which the action has taken place, without regard to any object of desire (20). It is clear from what precedes that the purposes „which we rnay have in view in our actions, or their effects regarded- as ends andTpringT^the will, cannpt give to actions any uncon ditional or moral worth. In what, then, can their worth lie, it it is not to consist in the will and in refe- rence to its expected effect '^ It cannot lie anywhere but in ih^ principle of the z£jz7/ without regard to the ends which can be attained by the action. For the will stands between its a /n'orf principle, which is formal, and its a posteriori spring, which is material, as between two roads, and as it must be determined by something, it follows that it must be determined by the formal prin- Iciple of volition when an action is done from duty, in which case every material principle has been withdrawn from it. The third proposition, which is a consequence of the two preceding, I would express thus : Duty is the necessity of acting from respect for the law. I may have inclination for an object as the effect of my proposed action, but I cannot have respect for it, just for this reason, that it is an effect and not an energy of will. Similarly, I cannot have respect for inclination, whether my own or another's; I can at most, if my own, approve it; if another's, sometimes even love it ; i. e. look on it as favourable to my own interest. It is only what is con- nected with my will as a principle, by no means as an effect — what does not subserve my inclination, but over- powers it, or at least in case of choice excludes it from its calculation — in other words, simply the law of itself, c 2 20 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [22] which can be an object of respect, and hence a command. Now an action done from duty must wholly exclude the influence of inclination, and with it every object of the will, so that nothing remains which can determine the will except objectively the law, and subjectively pure respect (21) for this practical law, and consequently the maxim^ that I should follow this law even to the thwart- ing of all my inclinations. Thus the moral worth of an action does not lie in the effect expected from it, nor in any principle of action which requires to borrow its motive from this expected effect. For all these effects — agreeableness of one's condition, and even the promotion of the happiness of others — could have been also brought about by other causes, so that for this there would have been no need of the vdlUof..a,. rational _being_; whereas it is in this a[one tha.t the supreme an d unc onditional good.ca a.bfi fouixd.. The pre-eminent good which we call moral can therefore consist in nothing else than the conception of law in itself, which certainly is only possible in a rational being, in so far as this conception, and not the expected effect, determines the will. This is a good which is already present in the person who acts accordingly, and we have not to wait for it to appear first in the result (22). ' A maxim is the subjective principle of volition. The objective principle (i.e. that which would also serve subjectively as a practical principle to all rational beings if reason had full power over the faculty of desire) is the practical law. ' It might be here objected to me that I take refuge behind the word respect in an obscure feeling, instead of giving a distinct solu- tion of the question by a concept of fhe reason. But although respect is a feeling, it is not a feeling received through influence, but is self-wrought by a rational concept, and, therefore, is speci- fically distinct from all feelings of the former kind, which may be referred either to inclination or fear. What I recognise immediatelv [22] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 21 But what sort of law can that be, the conception of which must determine the will, even without paying any regard to the effect expected from it, in order that this will may be called good absolutely and without qualification ? As I have deprived the will of every im- pulse which could arise to it from obedience to any law, there remains nothing but the universal conformity of its actions to law in general, which alone is to serve the will as a principle, i, e. I am never to act otherwise than so that I could also will that my maxim should become a universal law. Here now, it is the simple conformity to law in general, without assuming any particular law applicable to certain actions, that serves the will as its principle, and must so serve it, if duty is not to be a vain delusion and a chimerical notion. The common reason of men in its practical judgments perfectly coincides with this, and always has in view the principle here suggested. Let the question be, for example : May as a law for itie, I recognise with respect. This merely signifies the consciousness that my will is subordinate to a law, without the intervention of other influences on my sense. The immediate determination of the will by the law, and the consciousness of this is called respect, so that this is regarded as an effect of the law on the subject, and not as the cause of it. Respect is properly the (22) conception of a worth which thwarts my splf-love. Accordingly it is something which is considered neither as an object of inclination nor of fear, although it has something analo- gous to both. The object of respect is the law only, and that, the law which we impose on ourselves, and yet recognise as necessary in itself. As a law, we are subjected to it without consulting self- love ; as imposed by us on ourselves, it is a result of our will. In the former aspect it has an analogy to fear, in the latter to incli- nation. Respect for a person is properly only respect for the law (of honesty, &c.), of which he gives us an example. Since we also look on the improvement of our talents as a duty, we consider that we see in a person of talents, as it were, the example of a law (viz. to become hlie him in this by exercise), and this constitutes our respect. AU so-called moral interest consists simply in respect for the law. 22 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [23] I when in distress make a promise with the intention not to keep it? I readily distinguish here between the two significations which the question may have : Whether it is prudent (23), or whether it is right, to make a false promise. The former may undoubtedly often be the case. I see clearly indeed that it is not enough to extricate myself from a present difficulty by means of this subterfuge, but it must be well considered whether there may not hereafter spring from this lie much greater inconvenience than that from which I now free myself, and as, with all my supposed cunning, the consequences cannot be so easily foreseen but that credit once lost may be much more injurious to me than any mischief which I seek to avoid at present, it should be considered whether it would not be more prudent to act herein according to a universal maxim, and to make it a habit to promise nothing except with the intention of keeping it. But it is soon clear to me that such a maxim will still only be based on the fear of conse- quences. Now it is a wholly different thing to be truth- ful from duty, and to be so from apprehension of in- jurious consequences. In the first case, the very notion of the action already implies a law for me ; in the second case, I must first look about elsewhere to see what results may be combined with it which would affect myself. For to deviate from the principle of duty is beyond all doubt wicked; but to be unfaithful to my maxim of prudence may often be very advantageous to me, al- though to abide by it is certainly safer. The shortest way, however, and an unerring one, to discover the answer to this question whether a lying promise is consis- tent with duty, is to ask myself. Should I be content that my maxim (to extricate myself from difficulty by a false promise) should hold good as a universal law, for myself [24] METAPHrSSIC OF MORALS. 23 as well as for others ? and should I be able to say to myself, "Every one may make a deceitful promise when he finds himself in a difficulty from which he can- - not otherwise extricate himself" ? (24) Then I presently become aware that while I can will the lie, I can by no means will that lying should be a universal law. For with such a law there would be no promises at all, since it would be in vain to allege my intention in regard to my future actions to those who would not believe this allegation,- or if they over-hastily did so would pay me back in my own coin. Hence my maxim, as soon as it should be made a universal law, would necessarily destroy itself. I do not, therefore, need any far-reaching penetration to discern what I have to do in order that my will may be morally good. Inexperienced in the course of the world, incapable of being prepared for all its contin- gencies, I only ask myself: Canst thou also will that thy maxim should be a universal law 7 If not, then it must be rejected, and that not because of a disad- vantage accruing from it to myself or even to others, but because it cannot enter as a principle into a possible universal legislation, and reason extorts from me immediate respect for such legislation. I do not indeed as yet discern on what this respect is based (this| the philosopher may inquire), but at least I understand this, that it is an estimation of the worth which far outweighs all worth of what is recommended by incli nation, and that_Uie_jnecessity of acting from /«r« respect for Jhe. practical law is what constitutes duty, to~which every other motive must give place, because it is the condition of a will being good in itself, and the] worth of such a will is above everything. Thus, then, without quilting the moral knowledge of 24 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [25) common human reason, we have arrived at its principle. And although, no doubt, common men do not conceive it in such an abstract and universal form, yet they always have it really before their eyes, and use it as the standard of their decision. Here it would be easy t& show how, with this compass in hand (25), men are well able to distinguish, in every case that occurs, what is good, what bad, conformably to duty or inconsistent with it, if, without in the least teaching them anything new, we only, like Socrates, direct their attention to the principle they themselves employ ; and that therefore we do not need science and philosophy to know what we should do -to be honest and good, yea, even wise and virtuous. Indeed we might well have conjectured beforehand that the knowledge of what every man is bound to do, and therefore also to know, would be within the reach of every man, even the commonest."- Here we cannot forbear admiration when we see how great an advantage the practical judgment has over the theoretical in the common understanding of men. In the latter, if common reason ventures to depart from the laws of experience and from tKe perceptions of the senses it falls into mere inconceivabilities and self- contradictions, at least into a chaos of uncertainty, obscurity, and instability. But in the practical sphere it is just when the common understanding excludes all sensible springs from practical laws that its power of judgment begins to show itself to advantage. It then becomes even subtle, whether it be that it chicanes with its own conscience or with other claims respecting 1 [Compare the note to the Preface to the Critique of the Practical Reason in I'heory of Ethics, p. III. A specimen of Kant's pro- posed application of the Socratic method may be found in Mr. Semple's translation of the Metaphysic of Ethics^ p. 290.] [26] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 25 what is to be called right, or whether it desires for its own instruction to determine honestly the worth of actions; and, in the latter case, it may even have as good a hope of hitting the mark as any philosopher what- ever can promise himself. Nay, it is almost more sure of doing so, because the philosopher cannot have any other principle, while he may easily perplex his judg- ment by a multitude of considerations foreign to the matter, and so turn aside from the right way. Would it not therefore be wiser in moral concerns to acquiesce in the judgment of common reason (26), or at most only to call in philosophy for the purpose of rendering the system of morals more complete and intelligible, and its rules more convenient for use (especially for disputation), but not so as to draw off the common understanding from its happy simplicity, or to bring it by means of philosophy into a new path of inquiry and instruction ? Innocence is indeed a glorious thing, only, on the other hand, it is very sad that it cannot well maintain itself, and is easily seduced. On this account even wisdom — -which otherwise consists more in conduct than in knowledge — yet has need of science, not in order to learn from it, but to secure for its 'precepts admission and permanence. Against all the commands of duty which reason represents to man as so deserving of respect, he feels in himself a powerful counterpoise in his wants and inclinations, the entire satisfaction of which he sums up under the name of happiness. Now reason issues its commands unyieldingly, without promising anything to the inclinations, and, as it were, with disregard and contempt for these claims, which are so impetuous, and at the same time so plausible, and which will not allow themselves to be suppressed 26 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [27] by any command. Hence there arises a natural dialectic, i. e. a disposition to argue against these strict laws of duty and to question their validity, or at least their purity and strictness ; and, if possible, to make them more accordant with our wishes and inclinations, that is to say, to corrupt them at their very source, and entirely to destroy" their worth — a thing which even common practical reason cannot ultimately call good. Thus is the common reason of man compelled to go out of its sphere, and to take a step into the field of a practical philosophy, not to satisfy any speculative want (which never occurs to it as long as it is content to be mere sound reason), but even on practical grounds (27), in order to attain in it information and clear instruction respecting the source of its principle, and the correct determination of it in opposition to the maxims which are based on wants and inclinations, so that it may escape from the perplexity of opposite claims, and not run the risk of losing all genuine moral principles through the equivocation into which it easily falls. Thus, when practical reason cultivates itself, there insensibly arises in it a dialectic which forces it to seek aid in philosophy, just as happens to it in its theoretic use ; and in this case, therefore, as well as in the other, it will find rest nowhere but in a thorough critical examination of our reason. [29] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 27 SECOND SECTION. TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY T0 THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. If we have hitherto drawn our notion of duty from the common use of our practical reason, it is by no means to be inferred that we have treated it as an empirical notion. On the contrary, if we attend to the experience of men's conduct, we meet frequent and, as we ourselves allow, just complaints that one cannot find a single certain example of the disposition to act from pure duty. Although many things are done in conformity with what duty prescribes, it is nevertheless always doubtful whether they are done strictly /rom duty, so as to have a moral worth. Hence there have, at all times, been philosophers who have altogether denied that this dis- position actually exists at all in human actions, and have ascribed everything to a more or less refined self-love. Not that they have on that account questioned the soundness of the conception of morality ; on the con- trary, they spoke with sincere regret of the frailty and corruption of human nature, which though noble enough to take as its rule an idea so worthy of respect, is yet too weak to follow it, and employs reason, which ought to give it the" law (29) only for the purpose of providing for the interest of the inclinations, whether singly or at the best in the greatest possible harmony with one another^ In fact, it is absolutely impossible to make out by experience with complete certainty a single case in which 23 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [30] the maxim of an action, however right in itself, rested simply on moral grounds and on the conception of duty. .Sometimes it happens that with the sharpest self-exami- ' nation we can find nothing beside the moral principlel . of duty which could have been powerful enough to move us to this or that action and to so great a sacrifice ; yet| we cannot from this infer with certainty that it was not really some secret impulse ..of self-love, under the false appearance of duty, that was the actual determining cause of the will. We like then to flatter ourselves by falsely taking credit for a more noble motive ; whereas in fact we can never, even by the strictest examination, get completely behind the secret springs of action ; since when the question is of moral worth, it is not with the actions which we see that we are concerned, but with those inward principles of them which we do not see. Moreover, we cannot better serve the wishes of those' who ridicule all morality as a mer e chimera of human imagination overstepping itself from vanity, than by conceding to them that notions of duty must be drawn only from experience (as, from indolence, people are ready to think is also the case with all other notions) ; for this is to prepare for them a certain triumph. I am willing to admit out of love of humanity that even most of our actions are correct, but if we look closer at them we everywhere come upon the dear self which is always prominent, and it is this they have in view, and not the strict command of duty which would often require self- denial (30). Without being an enemy of virtue, a cool observer, one that does not mistake the wish for good, however lively, for its reality, may sometimes doubt whether true virtue is actually found anywhere in the world, and this especially as years increase and the judgment is partly made wiser by experience, and partly [31] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 29 also more acute in observation. This being so, nothing can secure us from falling away altogether from our ideas of duty, or maintain in the soul a well-grounded respect for its law, but the clear conviction that although there should never have been actions which really sprang from such pure sources, yet whether this or that takes place is not at all the question ; but that reason of itself, inde- pendent on all experience,, ordains what ought to take place, that accordingly actions of which perhaps the world has hitherto never given an example, the feasi- bility even of which might be very much doubted by one i who founds everything on experience, are nevertheless inflexibly commanded by reason ; that, ex. gr. even ' though there might never yet have been a sincere friend,'' yet not a whit the less is pure sincerity in friendship required of every man, because, prior to all experience, this duty is involved as duty in the idea of a reason determining the will by a /mn principles. When we add further that, unless we deny that the' notion of morality has any truth or reference to any possible object, we must admit that its law must be valid, not merely for men, but for all rational creatures generally, not merely under certain contingent conditions or with exceptions, \ivXwithalsolute necessity, i^^Tiit is clear that no experience could enable us to infer even the possi- bility of such apodictic laws (31)- For with what right could we bring into unbounded respect as a universal precept for every rational nature that which perhaps holds only under the contingent conditions of humanity ?, Or how could laws of the determination of our will be regarded as laws of the determination of the will of rational beings generally, and for us only as such, if they were merely empirical, and did not take their origin wholly a priori from pure but practical reason } 30 FXJNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [32] Nor could anything be more fatal to morality than that we should wish to derive it from examples. For every example of it that is set before me must be first itself tested by principles of morality, whether it is worthy to serve as an original example, i.e. as a pattern, but by no means can it authoritatively furnish the con- ception of morality. Even the Holy One of the Gospels must first be compared with our ideal of moral perfec- tion before we can recognise Him as such ; and so He says of Himself, " Why call ye Me (whom you see) good ; none is good (the model of good) but God only (whom ye do not see) ? " But whence have we the conception of God as the supreme good } Simply from the idea of moral perfection, which reason frames a priori, and connects inseparably with the notion of a free-will. Imitation finds no place at all in morality, and examples serve only for encouragement, i. e. they put beyond doubt the feasibility of what the law com- mands, they make visible that which the practical rule expresses more generally, but they can never authorize us to set aside the true original which lies in reason, and to guide ourselves by examples. If then there is no genuine supreme principle of morality but what must rest simply on pure reason, independent on all experience, I think it is not neces- sary even to put the question, whether it is good (32) to exhibit these concepts in their generality {in abstracto) as they are established a /mn along with the principles belonging to them, if our knowledge is to be distin- guished from the vulgar, and to be called philosophical. In our times indeed this might perhaps be necessary ; for if we collected votes, whether pure rational know- ledge separated from everything empirical, that is to say, metaphysic of morals, or whether popular practical [33] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 31 philosophy is to be preferred, it is easy to guess which side would preponderate. This descending to popular notions is certainly very commendable, if the ascent to the principles of pure reason has first taken place and been satisfactorily accomplished. This implies that we first found Ethics on Metaphysics, and then, when it is firmly established, procure a hearing for it by giving it a popular character. But it is quite absurd to try to be popular in the first inquiry, on which the soundness of the principles depends. It is not only that this proceeding can never lay claim to the very rare merit of a true philo- sophical popularity, since there is no art in being intelli- gible if one renounces all thoroughness of insight ; but also it produces a disgusting medley of compiled obser- vations and half-reasoned principles. Shallow pates enjoy this because it can be used for every-day chat, but the sagacious find in it only confusion, and beingv unsatisfied and unable to help themselves, they turn away their eyes, while philosophers, who see quite well ' through this delusion, are little listened to when they( call men off for a time from this pretended popularity, \ in order that they might be rightfully popular after they have attained a definite insight. We need only look at the attempts of moralists in that favourite fashion, and we shall find at one time the special constitution of human nature (33) (including, however, the idea of a rational nature generally), at one time perfection, at another happiness, here moral sense, there fear of God, a little of this, and a little of that, in marvellous mixture without its occurring to them to ask whether the principles of morality are to be sought in the knowledge of human nature at all (which we can have only from experience) ; and, if this is not so, if 32 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [34] these principles are to be found altogether a priori free from everything empirical, in pure rational concepts only, and nowhere else, not even in the smallest degree ; then rather to adopt the method of making this a separate inquiry, as pure practical philosophy, or (if one may use a name so decried) as metaphysic of morals,! to bring it by itself to completeness, and to require the public, which wishes for popular treatment, to await the issue of this undertaking. Such a metaphysic of morals, completely isolated, not mixed with any anthropology, theology, physics, or hyperphysics, and still less with occult qualities (which we might call hypophysical), is not only an indispens- able substratum of all sound theoretical knowledge of duties, but is at the same time a desideratum of the highest importance to the actual fulfilment of their precepts. For the pure conception of duty, unmixed with any foreign addition of empirical attractions (34), and, in a word, the conception of the moral law, exercises on the human heart, by way of reason alone (which first becomes aware with this that it can of itself be practical), an influence so much more powerful than all other springs'' which may be derived from the ' Just as pure mathematics are distinguished from applied, pure logic from applied, so if we choose we may also distinguish pure philosophy of morals (metaphysic) from applied (viz. applied to human nature). By this designation we are also at once reminded that moral principles are not based on properties of human nature, but must subsist a /nbrz' of themselves, whil^from such principles practical rules must be capable of being deduced for every rational nature, and accordingly for that of man. 2 1 have a letter from the late excellent Sulzer, in which he asks me what can be the reason that moral instruction, although containing much that is convincing for the reason, yet accom- plishes so little .' My answer was postponed in order that I might make it complete. But it is simply this, that the teachers them- [35] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 33 field of experience, that in the consciou'sness of its worth, it despises the latter, and can by degrees become their master ; whereas a mixed ethics, compounded partly of motives drawn from feelings and inclinations, and partly also of conceptions of reason, must make^ the mind waver between motives which cannot be brought under any principle, which lead to good only by mere accident, and very often also to evil. From what has been said, it is clear that all moral conceptions ha yg__their seat and QrigirL£Qffi2letel£,J_ p riori \t\. th e reason, and that, moreover, in the com- rnonest reason just as truly as in that which is in the highest degree speculative ; that they canno t be ob- Jainedby abstraction Jrom_anj^empirical, and therefore merely contingent kaQBd_edj;e ; tha t it is just this purit y^ ofjifiir origin that makes thgin worthy jtjD.jerve as, our suprerne pract ical principle (ii;\ and that just iii_EEa- por tion as we add anything empirical, we detract from their genuine influence, anJTrmn tlie absolu te va lue of actions"; that it is not' only of the greatest necessity, in a_gurely speculative point of view, but is also of the greatest practical importance to derive these notions and laws from pure reason, to present them pure and selves have not got their own notions clear, and when they en- deavour to make up for this by raking up motives of moral good- ness from every quarter, trying to make their physic right strong, they spoil it. For the commonest understanding shows that if we imagine, on the one hand, an act of honesty done with steadfast mind, apart from every *iew to advantage of any kind in this world or another, and even under the greatest temptations of necessity or allurement, and, on the other hand, a similar act which was affected, in however low a degree, by a foreign motive, the former leaves far behind and eclipses the second; it elevates the soul, and inspires the wish to be able to act in like manner oneself. Even moderately young children feel this impression, and one should never represent duties to them in any other light. 34 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [36] unmixed, and even to determine the compass of this practical or pure rational knowledge, i.e. to determine the whole faculty of pure practical reason ; and, in doing so, we must not make its principles dependent on the particular nature of human reason, though in speculative philosophy this may be permitted, or may even at times be necessary ; but ^nce moral laws ought to hold good for every rational creature, we must derive them from the general concept of a^ratipnal^being. In this way, aTEKoiigFTor Its'Sppltcation to man morality has need of 1 anthropology, yet, in the first instance, we must treat it independently as pure philosophy, i.e. as metaphysic, complete in itself (a thing which in such distinct branches of science is easily done) ; knowing well that unless we are in possession of this, it would not only be vain to determine the moral element of duty in right actions for purposes of speculative criticism, but it would be impossible to base morals on their genuine principles, even for common practical purposes, espe- cially of moral instruction, so as to produce pure moral dispositions, and to engraft them on men's minds to the promotion of the greatest possible good in the world. But in order that in this study we may not merely advance by the natural steps from the common moral judgment (in this case very worthy of respect) to the philosophical, as has been already done, but also from a popular philosophy, which goes no further than it can reach by groping with the help of examples, to meta- physic (which does not allow itself to be checked by anything empirical (36), and as it must measure the whole extent of this kind of rational knowledge, goes as far as ideal conceptions, where even examples fail us), we must follow and clearly describe the practical [37] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 36 faculty of reason, from the general rules of its deter- mination to the point where the notion of duty springs from it. Everything in nature works according to laws. Ra- tional beings alone. have .the facultyof_acting according to the conception oi laws,, that _ia-_a.ccording_to^_priiiciples, i.e. have_ a will. Since the deduction of actions from principles requires reason fX\i& will is nothing but prac-l ..tical ..reason. If reason infallibly determines the will, then the actions of such a being which are recognised as objectively necessary are subjectively necessary also, i.e. t he will is a facul ty-to choose that only which reason independent on inclination recognises as practically necessary, i.e. as good. But if reason of itself does not sufficiently determine the will, if the latter is subject also to subjective conditions (particular impulses) which do not always coincide with the objective conditions V in a word, if t he will_does hot in z'^ JZaaaplfitely^accord with reason (which is actually the case with iiien), then/ the actions which objectively are recognised as neces- sary are subjectively contingent, and tlie determination of such a will according to objective Javsrs is obligation^ , that is to say, the relation of the objective laws to a will that is not thoroughly good is conceived as the determination of the "will of a rational being by prin- ciples of reason-, but which the will from its nature does not of necessity follow. The conception of an objective principle, in so far as it is obligatory for a will, is called a command (of reason), and the formula of the command is called an Imperative. All imperatives are expressed by the word ought [or shall], and thereby indicate the relation of an objective law (37) of reason to a will, which from its subjective D2 36 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [38] constitution is not necessarily determined by it (an obli- gation). They say that something would be good to do or to forbear, but they say it to a will which does not always do a thing because it is conceived to be good to do it. That is practically ^ot(^, however, which determines the will by means of the conceptions of reason, and consequently not from subjective causes, but objectively, that is on principles which are valid for every rational being as such. It is distinguished from the pleasant, as that which influences the will only by means of sensation from merely subjective causes, valid only for the sense of this or that one, and not as a principle of reason, which holds for every one.^ A perfectly good will would therefore be equally subject to objective laws (viz. laws of good), but could not be conceived as obliged thereby to act lawfully, because of itself from its subjective constitution it can only be determined by the conception of good (38). Therefore no imperatives hold for the Divine will, or in general for a holy will ; ought is here out of place, because the 1 The dependence of the desires on sensations is called inclination, and this accordingly always indicates a want. The dependence of a contingently determinable will on principles of reason is called an interest. This therefore is found only in the case of a dependent ■will, which does not always of itself conform to reason ; in the Divine will we cannot conceive any interest. But the human will can also take an interest in a thing without therefore acting from z}iierest. The former signifies the practical interest in the action, the latter ihe pathological in the object of the action. The former indicates only dependence of the will on principles of reason in themselves ; the second, dependence on principles of reason for the sake of inclination, reason supplying only the practical rules how the requirement of the inclination may be satisfied. In the first case the action interests me ; in the second the object of the action (because it is pleasant to me). We have seen in the first section that in an action done from duty we must look not to the interest in the object, but only to that in the action itself, and in its rational principle (viz. the law). [39] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 37 volition is alreadyof itself necessarily in unison with the law. Therefore i mperative s are only formulae to express^ the relati on of objective laws of all volition to the sub- jective imperfeclion of the will "oT this "or that rational^ being", e.g. the human will. Now all imperatives command either hypallisticallx. or j£ategorical^. The former represent the practical necessity of a possible action ^smeans_to. something else that is willed (or at least "wBich one might possibly willj. The categorical imperative would be that which represented an action as necessar;^of itself_without refe- rence to another end, i.e. as objectively necessary. Since every practical law represents a possible action as good, and on this account, for a subject who is practi- cally determinable by reason, necessary, all imperatives are formulae determining an action which is necessary according to the principle ofa will good in some respects. If now the action is good only as a means _/o something else, then the imperative is Ay^o/^g/z"fa/; if jt is conceived . as good in itself aiid. c on sequently a s_being necessarily the principle of a will which of itself conforms to reason, then i t is categorical { Thus the imperative declares what action possible by me would be good, and presents the practical rule in relation to a will which does not forthwith perform an action simply because it is good, whether because the subject does not always know that it is good, or because, even if it know this, yet its maxims might be opposed to the objective principles of practical reason. Accordingly the hypothetical imperative only says that the action is good for some purpose, possible or actual (39). In the first case it is a Problematical, in the second an Assertorial practical principle. The categori- cal imperative which declares an action to be objectively 38 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [40] necessary in itself without reference to any purpose, i.e. without any other end, is valid as a (practical) Apodictic principle. Whatever is possible only by the power of some rational being may also be conceived as a possible purpose of some will ; and therefore the principles of action as regards the means necessary to attain some possible purpose are in fact infinitely numerous. All sciences have a practical part, consisting of problems expressing that some end is possible for us, and of imperatives directing how it niay be attained'. These may, therefore, be called in general imperatives of skill. Here there is no question whether the end is rational and godd, but only what one must do in order to attain it. The precepts for the physician to make his patient thoroughly healthy, and for a poisoner to ensure certain death, are of equal value in this respect, that each serves to effect its purpose perfectly. Since in early youth it cannot be known what ends are likely to occur to us in the course of life, parents seek to have their children taught a great many things, and provide for their skill in the use of means for all sorts of arbitrary ends, of none of which can they determine whether it may not perhaps hereafter be an object to their pupil, but which it is at all events possible that he might aim at ; and this anxiety is so great that they comrrionly neglect to form and correct their judgment on the value of the things which may be chosen as ends (40). There is one end, hewsvety which may be assumed to be actually such to all rational beings (so far as impera- tives apply to them, viz. as dependent beings), and therefore, one purpose which they not merely may have, but which we may with certainty assume that they all actually have by a natural necessity, and this is happiness. [41] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 39 The hypothetical imperative which expresses the practi- cal necessity of an action as means totheadvancemsjll; _oniap2ifless_is .4aS£rtQ£Lal. We are notto"present it as necessary for an uncertain and merely possible purpose, but for a purpose which we may presuppose with certainty and a priori in every man, because it belongs ' to his being. Now skill in the choice of means to his own great well-bemg may be called prudence,'^ in the narrowest sense. And thus the imperative which refers to the choice of means to one's own happiness, i. e. the precept of prudence, is still always hypothetical; the action is not commanded absolutely, but only as means to another purpose. Finally, there is an imperative which commands a certain conduct immediately, without having as its condition any other purpose to be attained by^it. This imperative is Categorical. It concerns not the matter of the action, or its intended result, but its form and the principle of which it is itself a result (41) ; and what is essentially good in it consists in the mental disposition, let the consequence be what it may. This imperative may be called that of Morality./ There is a marked distinction also between the volitions on these three* sorts of principles in the dissimilarity of the obligation of the will. In order to ^ The word prudence is taken in two senses : in the one it may bear the name of knowledge of the world, in the other that of private prudence. The former is a man's ability to influence others so as to use them for his own purposes. The latter is the sagacity to combine all these purposes for his own lasting benefit. This latter is properly that to which the value even of the former is re- duced, and when a man is prudent in t"he former sense, but not in the latter, we might better say of him that he is clever and cunning, but, on the whole, imprudent. [Compare on the diflference between klug axt-Agescheu here alluded to, Anthropologie, § 45, ed. Schubert, p. no.] 40 FUNDAMENTAL- PRINCIPLES OF THE [42] mark this difference more clearly, I think they would be most suitably named in their order if we said they are either rules of skill, or counsels of prudence, or commands {laws) of morality. For it is law only that involves the conception of an unconditional and objective necessity, which is consequently universally valid ; and commands are laws which must be obeyed, that is, must be followed, even in opposition to inclination. Counsels, indeed, involve necessity, but one which can only hold under a contingent subjective condition, viz. they depend on "whether this or that man reckons this or that as part of his happiness ; the categorical imperative, on the con- trary, is not limited by any condition, and as being absolutely, although practically, necessary, may be quite properly called a command. We might also call the first kind of imperatives technical (belonging to art), the second pragmatic^ (to welfare), the third moral (belonging to free conduct generally, that is, to morals). Now arises the question, how are all these imperatives possible } This question' does not seek to know how we can conceive the accomplishment of the action which the imperative ordains, but merely how we can conceive the obligation of the will (42) which the imperative ex- presses. No special explanation is needed to show how an imperative of skill is possible. Whoever wills the end, wills also (so far as reason decides his conduct) the ' It seems to me that the proper signification of the yt or A fragmaiic may be most accurately defined in this way. For sanctions [see Cr. ofPract. iSifflu-., p. 271] are called pragmatic which flow properly not from the law of the states as necessary enactments, but from precaution for the general welfare. A history is composed prag- matically when it teaches prudence, i.e. instructs the world how it can provide for its interests better, or at least as well, as the men of former time. [43] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 41 means in his power which are indispensably necessary thereto. This proposition is, as regards the voKtion, analytical ; for, in willing an object as my effect, there" is already thought the causality of myself as an acting cause, that is to say, the use of the means ; aiji-tbe imperative educes from the conception of volition of a n end ttie conception of actions- necessary to this end. Synthetical propositions must no dojibt be employed in defining the means to a proposed end ; but they do not concern the principle, the act of the will, but the object and its realization. Ex. gr., that in order to bisect a line on an unerring principle I must draw from its extremities two intersecting arcs ; this no doubt is taught by mathematics only in synthetical propositions ; but if I know that it is only by this process that the intended operation can be performed, then to say that if I fully will the operation, I also will the action required for it, is an analytical proposition ; for it is one and the same thing to conceive something as an effect which I can produce in a certain way, and to conceive myself as acting in this way. If it were only equally easy to give a definite concep- tion of happiness, the imperatives of prudence would correspond exactly with those of skill, and would like- wise be analytical. For in this case as in that, it could be said, whoever wills the end, wills also (according tO' the dictate of reason necessarily) the indispensable means thereto which are in :his power. But, unfortu- nately, the notion of happiness is so indefinite that' although every man wishes to attain it, yet he never can say definitely and consistently what it is that he really wishes and wills (43). The reason of this is that all the elements which belong to the notion of happiness are altogether empirical, i. e. they must be borrowed 42 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [44] 'from experience, and nevertheless the idea of happiness requires an absolute whole, a maximum of welfare in my present and all future circumstances. Now it is impossible that the most clear-sighted, and at the same time most powerful being (supposed finite) should frame to himself a definite conception of what he really wills in this. Does he will riches, how much anxiety, envy, and snares might he not thereby draw upon his shoulders ? Does he will knowledge and discernment, perhaps it might prove to be only an eye ,so much the sharper to show him so much the more fearfully the evils that are now concealed from him and that cannot be avoided, or to impose more wants on his desires, which already give him concern enough. Would he have long life, who guarantees to him that it would not be a long misery ? Would he at least have health .'' how often has uneasiness of the body restrained from excesses into which perfect health would have allowed one to fall ? and so on. In short he is unable, on any principle, to determine with certainty^ what would make him truly happy ; because to do so he would need to be omniscient. We cannot therefore act_jon_ai}y dafijyte^grinciples to secure_ happiness, but only on emjurical ^counsels, exTgr. of regimen, fruga- lity, courtesy, reserve, &c., which experience teaches do, on the average, most promote well-being. Hence it follows that the jjnj^rativjes^of -prudence do not, strictly speaking, command at all, that is, they cannot present actions objectively as practically necessary ; that they are ratlier,tg_be regarded as counsels {consilia) than precepts {pmcepta) of reason, that the probleji to determine^jcertainly and universally (44) what aption would promote the hap_piness of a rational being.Js, •completely insolublej_and consequently no imperative [45] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 43 respecting it is possible which should, in the strict sense, command to do what makes happy ; because Jiappiness is_not an ideal of reason but of imagination, £estingsolely_on^ empirical grounds, and it is vain to ^expecFthat these should define an action by which one i could attain the totality of a series of consequences which is really endless. This imperative of prudence^ would however be an analytical proposition if we [ ass ume that the means to happiness could_be' certainly assigned/; for it is distinguished from the imperative of skill only by this, that in the latter the end is merely possible, in the former it is given ; as howeve r/^^otR ) only ^ordain the means to that which we suppose to be willed as an endj it follows that the i mperative which ordains the willing of the means to hinj who wills the end is in both cases analytical. Thus there is nol difficulty in~Fegafd"td the possibility of an imperative of this kind either. p On the other hand the questio n, how the imperative of morality is possible, is undoubtedly one, the only one, demanding a solution, as this is not at all hypothetical, and the objective necessity which it presents cannot rest on any hypothesis, as is the case with the hypothe- tical imperatives. Only here we must never leave out of consideration that we cannot make out ly any example, in 5ther words empirically, whether there is such an imperative at all ; but it is rather to be feared that all those which seem to be categorical may yet be at bottom hypothetical. For instance, when the precept is : Thou shalt not promise deceitfully ; and it is assumed that the necessity of this is not a mere counsel to avoid some other evil, so that it should mean : thou shalt not make a lying promise, lest if it become known thou shouldst destroy thy credit (45), but that an action 44 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [46] of this kind must be regarded as evil in itself, so that the imperative of the prohibition is categorical ; then we cannot show with certainty in any example that the will was determined merely by the law, without any other spring of action, although it may appear to be so. For it is always possible that fear of disgrace, perhaps also obscure dread of other dangers, may have a secret influence on the will. Who can prove by experience the non-existence of a cause when all that experience tells us is that we do not perceive it .'' But in such a case the so-called moral imperative, which as such appears to be categorical and unconditional, would in reality be only a pragmatic precept, drawing our atten- tion to our own interests, and merely teaching us to take these into consideration. We shall therefore have to investigate a priori the possibility of a categorical imperative, as we have not in this case the advantage of its reality being given in experience, so that [the elucidation of] its possibility should be requisite only for its explanation, not for its establishment. In the meantime it may be discerned beforehand that the categorical imperative alone has the purport of a practical law : all the rest may indeed be called principles of the will but not laws, since whatever is only necessary for the attainment of some arbitrary purpose may be considered as in itself contingent, and we can at any time be free from the precept if we give up the purpose : on the contrary, the unconditional command leaves the will no liberty to choose the opposite; consequently it alone carries with it that"" necessity which we require in a law. Secondly, in the case of this categorical imperative or law of morality, the difficulty (of discerning its possibility) is a very profound one (46). It is an a [46] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 45 priori synthetical practical proposition ;' and as there is so much difficulty in discerning the possibility of speculative propositions of this kind, it may readily be supposed that the difficulty will be no less with the practical. In this problem we will first inquire whether the mere conception of a categorical imperative may not perhaps supply us also with the formula of it, containing the proposition which alone can be a categorical imperative ; for even if we know the tenor of such an absolute command, yet how it is possible will require further special and laborious study, which we postpone to the last section. When I conceive a hypothetical imperative in general I do not know beforehand what it will contain until I am given the condition. But when I conceive a cate- gorical imperative I know at once what it contains.^ For as the imperative contains besides the law only the necessity that the maxims^ shall conform to this law, while the law contains no conditions restricting it, there remains nothing but the general statement that the maxim of the action should conform to a universal ' I connect the act with the will without presupposing any con- dition resulting from any inclination, but ^ priori, and therefore necessarily (though only objectively, i. e. assuming the idea of a reason possessing full power over all subjective motives). This is accordingly a practical proposition which does not deduce the will- ing of an action by mere analysis from another already presupposed (for we have not such a perfect will), but connects it immediately with the conception of the wiU of a rationar being, as something not contained in it. 2 A MAXIM is a subjective principle of action, and must be distin- guished from the objective principle, namely, practical law. The former contains the practical rule set by reason according to the conditions of the subject (often its ignorance or its inclinations), so that it is the principle on which the subject acts ; but the law is the objective principle valid for every rational being, and is the principle on which it ought to act, that is, an imperative. 46 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [48] law (47), and it is this conformity alone that the impe- rative properly represents as necessary.^ There is therefore but one categorical imperative, namely this : Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should become a universal law. Now if all imperatives of duty can be deduced from this one imperative as from their principle, then, although it should remain undecided whether what is called duty is not merely a vain notion, yet at least we shall be able to show what we understand by it and what this notion means. Since the universality of the law according to which effects are produced constitutes what is properly called nature in the most general sense (as to form), that is, the existence of things so far as it is determined by general laws, the imperative of duty may be expressed thus : Act as if the maxim of thy action were to become by thy will a Universal Law of Nature. We will now enumerate a few duties, adopting the usual division of them into duties to ourselves and to others, and into perfect and imperfect duties'* (48). ' [I have no doubt that ' den' in the original before 'Imperativ' is a misprint for ' der,' and have translated accordingly. Mr. Semple has done the same. The editions that I have seen agree in reading ' den,' and M. Barni so translates. With this reacSng, it is the conformity that presents the imperative as necessary.] ^ It must be noted here that I reserve the division of duties for a future metaphysic of morals ; so that I give it here only as an arbi- trary one (in order to arrange my examples). For the rest, I under- stand by a perfect duty one that admits no exception in favour of inclination, and then I have not merely external, but also internal perfect duties. This is contrary to the use of the word adopted in the schools ; but I do not intend to justify it here, as it is all one for my purpose whether it is admitted or not. [Perfect duties are usually understood to be those which can be enforced by external law ; imperfect, those which cannot be enforced. They are also called respectively determinate and indeterminate, officio juris and officia virtutis."] [48] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 4T T/< A man reduced to despair by a series of misfortunes feels wearied of life, but is still so far in possession of his reason that he can ask himself whether it would not be contrary to his duty to himself to take his own life^ Now he inquires whether the maxim of his action could become a universal law of nature. His maxim is : From- self-love I adopt it as a principle to shorten my life when its longer duration is likely to bring more evil than- satisfaction. It is asked then simply whether this principle founded on self-love can become a universal law of nature. Now we see at once that a system of nature of which it should be a law to destroy life by means of the very feeling whose special nature it is to- impel to the improvement of life would contradict itself, and therefore could not exist as a system of nature ;. hence that maxim cannot possibly exist as a universal law of nature, and consequently would be wholly incon- sistent with the supreme principle of all duty.' zXAnother finds himself forced by necessity to borrow money. He knows that he will not be able to repay it, but sees also that nothing will be lent to him, unless he- promises stoutly to repay it in a definite time. He desires to make this promise, but he has still so much conscience as to ask himself: Is it not unlawful and inconsistent with duty to get out of a difficulty in this way ? Suppose however that he resolves to do sp, then the maxim of his action would be expressed thus: When I think myself in want of money, I will borrow money and promise to repay it, although I know that I never can do so. Now this principle of self-love or of one's own advantage may perhaps be consistent with my whole future welfare; but the question now is, is it [On suicide cf. further Metaphysik der Sitten, p. 274.] 48 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [49] right ? I change then the suggestion of self-love into a universal law, and state the question thus (49) : How would it be if my maxim were a universal law ? Then I see at once that it could never hold as a universal law of nature but would necessarily contradict itself. For supposing it to be a universal law that everyone when he thinks himself in a difficulty should be able to promise whatever he pleases, with the purpose of not keeping his promise, the promise itself would become impossible, as well as the end that one might have in view in it, since no one would consider that anything was promised to him, but would ridicule all such statements as vain pretences. wA third finds in himself a talent which with the help of some culture might make him a useful man in many respects. But he finds himself in comfortable circumstances, and prefers to indulge in pleasure rather than to take pains in enlarging and improving his happy natural capacities. He asks, however, whether his maxim of neglect of his natural gifts, besides agreeing with his inclination to indulgence, agrees also with what is called duty. He sees then that a system of nature could indeed subsist with such a universal law although men (like the South Sea islanders) should let their talents rust, and resolve to devote their lives merely to idleness, amusement, and propagation of their species — in a word, to enjoyment; but he cannot possibly wt'll that this should be a universal law of nature, or be implanted in us as such by a natural instinct. For, as a rational being, he necessarily wills that his faculties be developed, since they serve him, and have been given him, for all sorts of possible purposes, 4^A fourth, who is in prosperity, while he sees that others have to contend with great wretchedness and that [so] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 49 he could help them, thinks : What concern is it of mine ? Let everyone be as happy (50) as heaven pleases, or as ' he can make himself; I will take nothing from him nor even envy him, only I do not wish to contribute anything to his welfare or to his assistance in distress ! Now no doubt if such a mode of thinking were a universal law, the human race might very well subsist, and doubtless even better than in a state in which every one talks of sympathy and good-will, or even takes care occasionally to put it into practice, but on the other side, also cheats when he can, betrays the rights of men, or otherwise violates them. But although it is possible that a univer- sal law of nature might exist in accordance with that maxim, it is impossible to jwill that such a principle should have the universal validity of a law of nature. For a will which resolved this would contradict itself,' inasmuch as many cases might occur in which one would have need of the love and sympathy of others, and in which, by such a law of nature, sprung from his own will, he would deprive himself of all hope of the aid he desires. These are a few of the many actual duties, or at least what we regard as such, which obviously fall into two classes on the one principle that we have laid down. We rnngt ViP nhu fQfmU thaf a maxim of our action should be a unirorsal law. This is the canon of the moral appreciation of the action generally. Q Some actions are of such a character that their maxim cannot without contradiction be^ ^v^" rqp.reiypd as a universal law of nature, far from it being possible that we should will that it should be so. In others this intrinsic impossibility ig_ not found, but still it is impossible to will that their maxim should be raised to the universality of a law of nature, since , such a_ ffiilIjEQ]]ld contradict_itsglf. It is E so FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [51] easily seen that, the former violate strict or rigorous (inflexible) duty (51); the latter only laxer (meritorious) duty. Thus it has been completely shown by these examples ho w all_duties ^p&nd-asj£gaiiis.tho.. nature nf e-th£_obligatiQn (not the object of the^actiqn) o n the s ame principle. IFnow we attend to ourselves on occasion of any transgression of duty, we shall fi nd that we in fact do not will that our maxim should^ be a universal law, for that is impossible for us; on the contrary we will that the opposite should remain a unjyersal law, only we assume the liberty of making an exception^. ia our own favour or (just for this time only) in Javour-of our incli- nation. Consequently if we considered all cases from one and the same point of view, namely, that of reason, we should find a contradiction in our own will, namely, that a certain principle should be objectively necessary as a universal law, and yet subjectively should not be I universal, but admit of exceptions. As however we at one moment regard our action from the point of view of a will wholly conformed to reason, and then again look at the same action from the point of view of a will afi"ected by inclination, there is not really any contradic- tion, but an antagonism of inclination to the precept of reason, whereby the universality of the principle is changed into a mere generality, so that the practical principle of reason shall meet the maxim half way. Now, although this cannot be justified in our own impartial judgment, yet it proves that we do really recognise the validity of the categorical imperative and (with all respect for it) only allow ourselves a few exceptions, which we think unimportant and forced from us. We have thus established at least this much, that if [52] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. SI duty i s a conception which is to have any import and real legislative authority for our actions (52), i t can only be expresagji in;categprica,l, and not at all in hypothiatj- _cal imperatiyes. We have also, which is of great impor- tance, exhibited clearly and definitely for every practical application the content of the categorical imperative, 1 which must contain the principle of all duty if there is such a thing at all. We have not yet, however, advanced so far as to prove a priori that there actually is such an imperative, that there is a practical law which commands ' absolutely of itself, and without any other impulse, and that the following of this law is duty. With the view of attaining to this it is of extreme importance to remember that we niust not allow pur- selves to think of_deducing the reality of this principle: from the particMlat attribuMs m/ human nature. For duty is to be a practical, unconditional necessity of action ; it must therefore hold ^or all rational beings (to whom an imperative can apply at all) and for this reason only be also a law for all human wills. On the contrary, whatever is deduced from the particular natural charac- .teristics of humanity, from certain feelings and propen- sions,' nay even, if possible, from any particular tendepcy proper to human reason, and which need not necessarily hold for the will of every rational being ; this may indeed supply us with a maxim, but not with a law ; with a subjective principle on which we may have [^ Kant distinguishes ' Hang (^ropensio) ' from ' Neigung {fncUnatioY as follows : — "'Hang' is a predisposition to the desire of some enjoyment; in other words, it is the subjective possibility of excitement of a certain desire, which precedes the conception of its object. When the enjoyment has been experienced, it produces a ' Neigung ' (inclination) to it, which accordingly is defined ' habitual sensible desire.' " — Anthropologie, §§ 72, 79 ; Religion, p. 31.] E 2 52 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [S3] a propension and inclination to act, but not with an objective principle on which we should be enjoined to act, even though all our propensions, inclinations, and natural dispositions were opposed to it. In fact the sublimity and intrinsic dignity of the command in duty are so much the more evident, the less the subjective impulses favour it and the more they oppose it, without being able in the slightest degree to weaken the obliga- tion of the law or to diminish its validity (53). Here then we see philosophy brought to a critical position, since it has to be firmly fixed, notwithstanding that it has nothing to support it either in heaven or earth. Here it must show its purity as absolute dictator of its own laws, not the herald of those which are whispered to it by an implanted sense or who knows what tutelary nature. Although these may be better than nothing, yet they can never afford principles dic- tated by reason, which must have their source wholly d priori, and thence their commanding authority, expect- ing everything from the supremacy of the law and the due respect for it, nothing from inclination, or else condemn- ing the man to self-contempt and inward abhorrence. Thus every em£irical_elemeiit_is. not only quite in- capable of being an aid to t he principle of mora lity, but is even highly prejudicial to the purity of morals, for the p roper and i nestimable worth of an absolutely good will consists just in this, that the principle of action is tree fr^ m all influence of cnntinfypnt g-rniinTs7 which alone experience can furni sh. We cannot too much or tod often repeat our warning against this lax and even mean habit of thought which seeks for its principle amongst empirical motives and laws ; for human reason in its weariness is glad to rest on this pillow, and in a dream of sweet illusions (in which. [54] MEI:aPHYSIC of morals. S3 instead of Juno, it embraces a cloud) it substitutes for morality a bastard patched up from limbs of various derivation, which looks like anything one chooses to see in it ; only not like virtue to one who has once beheld her in her true form.' (S4) The question then is this : Is it a necessary law for all rational beings that they should always judge of their actions by maxims of which they can themselves will that they should serve as universal laws ? If it is so, then it must be connected (altogether a priori) with the very conception of the will of a rational beingi generally. But in order to discover this connexion we must, however reluctantly, take a step into metaphysic, although into a domain of it which is distinct from speculative philosophy, namely, the metaphysic of morals. In a practical philosophy, where it is not the reasons of what happens that we have to ascertain, but the laws, of what OK^A/ /o happen^&iGa. although it never does, i. e. objective practical laws, there it is not neces- sary to inquire into the reasons why anything pleases or displeases, how the pleasure of mere sensation differs from taste, and whether the latter is distinct from a general satisfaction of reason ; on what the feeling of pleasure or pain rests, and how from it desires and inclinations arise, and from these again maxims by the co-operation of reason : for all this belongs to an empi- rical psychology, which would constitute the second part of physics, if we regard physics as the philosophy 1 To behold virtue in her proper form is nothing else but t6 contemplate morality stripped of all admixture "^I'^Jgi^l^ thingSi (54) and of every spurious ornament of reward or sen-love. How much she then eclipses everything else that appears charming to the affections, every one may readily perceive with the least exer- tion of his reason, if it be not wholly spoiled for abstraction. 54 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [SS] of nature, so far as it is based on empirical laws. But here we are concerned with objective practical laws, and consequently with the relation of the will to itself so far as it is determined by reason alone, in which case whatever has reference to anything empirical is necessarily excluded ; siQce_2f__J22^2^ °f ^^^^V olone determmes _t_he_conduct (55) (and it is the possibility of thS~that we are now investigating), it must necessjrily ^o so a priori. The will is conceived as a faculty of determining oneself to action in accordance with the conception of certain laws. And such a faculty can be found only in rational beings. Now that which serves the will as the objective ground of its self-determination is the end^ and if this is as signed by reason al one, it must hold for all rational beings. On the other hand, that which merely contains the ground of possibility of the action of which the effect is the end, this is called the means. The subjective ground of the desire is the spring, the objective ground of the volition is the motive ; hence the distinction between subjective ends wHiclr rest on springs, and objective ends which depend on motives valid for every rational being. Practical principles are formal when they abstract from all subjective ends, they are material when they assume these, and therefore ^particular springs of action. The ends which a rational being proposes to himself at pleasure as effects of his actions (material ends) are all only relative, for it is only their relation to the particular desires of the 'subject that gives them their worth, which therefore cannot furnish_£rinciples universal and necessary for all rational beings and for every volition, that is to say practicar Taws. Hence all these relative ends can give rise only to hypothetical imperatives. £56] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 55 Supposing, however, that there were something whose existence has in itself an absolute worth, something which, being an end in itself , could be a source of dgfinite laws, theri'in this and this alone would lie the source of a possible categorical imperative, i.e. a prac- Now I say: man and generally any rational being ■£^SiLS-!LS^,.^F^ in himself, not merely as a means to be arbitrarilyusedTytKiTof that will, but in all his actions, whether they concern himself or other rational beings, must be always regarded at the same time as an end. All objects of the inclinations have only a conditional worth, for if the inclinations and the wants founded on them did not exist, then their object would be without!' value. But the inclinations themselves being sources of want, are so far from having an absolute worth for which they should be desired, that on the contrary it must be the universal wish of every rational being to be wholly free from them. Thus the worth of any object- which is to he acquired by our action is always condi- tional. Beings whose existence depends not on our will bi?t on nature's, have nevertheless, if they are irra- tional beings, only a relative value as means, and are^ therefore called things ; rational beings, on the contrary, are called persons, because their very nature points them out as, endsin-tljemselves, that is as something which must not be used merely as means, and so far therefore restricts freedom of action (and is an object of respect). These, therefore, are not merely subjective ends whose existence has a worth for us as an effect of our action, but objective ends, that is things whose existence is an end in itself: an end moreover for which no other can be substituted, which they should subserve merely as means, for otherwise nothing whatever would possess S6 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [57] absolute worth ; but if all worth were conditioned and therefore contingent, then there would be no supreme practical principle of reason whatever. If then there is a supreme practical principle or, in respect of the human will, a categorical imperative, it must be one which (57), being drawn from the concep- tion of that which is necessarily an end for every one because it is an end in itself, constitutes an objective principle of will, and can therefore serve as a universal practical law. The foundation of this principle is : ra- tional nature exists as an end in itself. Man necessarily ; conceives his own existence as being so : so far then this 'is a subjective principle of human actions. But every other rational being regards its existence similarly, just ;Qn the same rational principle that holds for me ■} so that Ht is at the same time an objective principle, from which as a supreme practical law all laws of the will must be .-eapable^oT being deduced. Accordingly the practical imperative will be as follows : So act ai to treat humanity, , whether^ in thine own person or in that of any qther^ in . every case as an end withal, never as means only. We will now inquire whether this can be practically carried out. To abide by the previous examples : Firstly, under the head of necessary duty to oneself: He who contemplates suicide should ask himself whether his action can be consistent with the idea of humanity as an end in itself. If he destroys himself in order to escape from painful circumstances, he uses a person merely as a mean to maintain a tolerable con- dition up to the end of life. But a man is not a thing, that is to say, something which can be used merely as ' This proposition is here stated as a postulate. The grounds of it will be found in the concluding section. [S8] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 57 means, but must in all his actions be always considered as an end in himself. I cannot, therefore, dispose in any way of a man in my own person so as to mutilate him, to damage or kill him (58). (It belongs to ethics proper to define this principle more precisely so as to avoid all misunderstanding, e. g. as to the ampu- tation of the limbs in order to preserve myself ; as to exposing my life to danger with a view to preserve it, &c. This question is therefore omitted here.) Secondly, as regards necessary duties, or those of strict obligation, towards others ; he who is thinking of making a lying promise to others will see at once that he would be using another man merely as a mean, without the latter containing at the same time the end in himself. For he whom I propose by such a promise to use for my own purposes cannot possibly assent to my mode of acting towards him, and therefore cannot himself contain the end of this action. This violation of the principle of humanity in other men is more obvious if we take in examples of attacks on the freedom and property of others. For then it is clear that he who trangresses the rights of men, intends to use the person of others merely as means, without considering that as rational beings they ought always to be esteemed also as ends, that is, as beings who must be capable of containing in themselves the end of the very same action.^ Thirdly, as regards contingent (meritorious) duties to oneself; is not enough that the action does not violate 1 Let it not be thought that the common : quod tibi non vis fieri, &"€., could serve' here as the rule or principle. For it is only a deduction from the former, though with several limitations ; it cannot be a universal law, for it does not contain the principle of duties to oneself, nor of the duties of benevolence to others (for 58 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [59] humanity in our own person as an end in itself, it must also harmonize wzVA itXS9)- Now there are in humanity capacities of "greater perfection, which belong to the end that nature has in view in regard to humanity in ourselves as the subject : to neglect these might per- haps be consistent with the maintenance of humanity as an end in itself, but not with the advancement of this end. Fourthly, as regards meritorious duties towards others : the natural end which all men have is their own happi- ness. Now humanity might indeed subsist, although no one should contribute anything to the happiness of others, provided he did not intentionally withdraw any- thing from it ; but after all this would only harmonise negatively not positively with humanity as an end in itself, if every one does not also endeavour, as far as in him lies, to forward the ends of others. For the ends of any subject which is an end in himself, ought as far as possible to be my ends also, if that conception is to have lis full effect with me. This principle, that humanity and generally every rational nature is an end in itself {yihich. is the supreme limiting condition of every man's freedom of action), is not borrowed from experience, firstly, because it is universal, applying as it does to all rational beings whatever, and experience is not capable of determining anything about them; secondly, because it does not present humanity as an end to men (subjectively), that is as an object which men do of themselves actually many a one would gladly consent that others should not benefit him, provided only that he might be excused from showing benevolence to them), norsfinaUy that of duties of strict obligation to one another, for on this prmciple the criminal might' argue against the judge . who punishes him, and so on. [6o] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. S9 adopt as an end ; but as an objective end, which must as a law constitute the supreme limiting condition of all our subjective ends, let themlje what we will ; itjnusjf _therefore spring^ from ^ure reaso n. In fact the objec- tive pniiicTple of all practical legislation lies (according to the first principle) in the rule and its form of univer- sality which makes it capable of being a law (say e. g., a law of nature) ; but the subjective principle is in the end; now by the second principle the subject of all ends is each rational being (60), inasmuch as it is an end in itself. Hence follows the third practical principle of the will, which is the ultimate condition of its harmony with the universal practical reason, viz. : the idea of the will of every rational being as a^ univer- sally legislative will._. y~ On this principle all maxims are rejected which are inconsistent with the will b eing itself universal legis latoj . Thus the will is riot subject simply to the law but so subject that it must be regarded as itself giving the law, and on this ground only, subject tomelaw~('a - whichlt can regard itself as the author). In the previous imperatives, namely, that based on the conception of the conformity of actions to general laws, as in ^. physical system of nature, and that based on * the universal prerogative of rational beings as ends in themselves- ^these imperatives just because they were conceived as categmkal,.excluded from,.ajQ.y„aiiare .in their ajith,Qrity_all admixture of any interest as a spring of action ; they were however only assumed to be cate- gorical, because such an assumption was necessary to explain the conception of duty. But we could not prove independently that there are practical proposi- tions which command categorically, nor can it be proved in this section; one thing howevsr could be 6o FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [6i] done, namely, to indicate in the imperative itself by some determinate expression, that in the case of volition from duty all interest is renounced, which is~ the specific criterion of categorical as distinguished from hypothetical imperatives. This is done in the present (third) formula of the principle, namely, in the idea of the will of every rational being as a uitiver- .salty legislating will'. (6i) For although a will which is subject to laws may be attached to this law by means of an interest, yet a will which is itself a supreme lawgiver so far as it is such cannot possibly depend on any interest, since a will so dependent would itself still need another law restricting the interest of its self-love by the condition that it should be valid as universal law. Thus the principle that every human will is a wilt which in all its maxims gives universal laws,''- provided it be otherwise justified, would be very well adapted to be the categorical imperative, in this respect, namely, that just because of the idea of universal legislation it is not based on any interest, and therefore it alone among all possible imperatives can be unconditional. Or still better, converting the proposition, if there is a cate- gorical imperative (?'. e., a law for the will of every rational being), it can only command that everything be done from maxims of one's will regarded as a will which could at the same time will that it should itself give universal laws, for in that case only the practical principle and the imperative which it obeys are uncon- ditional, since they cannot be based on any interest. ' I may be excused from adducing examples to elucidate this principle, as those which have already been used to elucidate the categorical imperative and its formula would all serve for the like purpose here. [62] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 6i Looking back now on all previous attempts to discover the principle of morality, we need not wonder why they all failed. It was seen that man was bound to laws by duty, but it was not observed that the laws to which he is subject are only those of his own giving, though at the same time they are universal (6z), and that he is only bound to act in conformity with his own will ; a will, however, which is designed by nature to give universal laws. For when one has conceived man only as subject to a law (no matter what), then this law required some interest, either by way of attraction or constraint, since it did not originate as a law from his own will, but this will was according to a law obliged by something else to act in a certain manner. Now by this necessary conse- quence all the labour spent in finding a supreme prin- ciple oiduty was irrevocably lost. For men never elicited duty, but only a necessity of acting from a certain interest. Whether this interest was private or otherwise, in any case the imperative must be conditional, and could not by any means be capable of being a moral command. I will therefore call this the principle of Autonomy of the will, in contrast with every other which I accordingly reckon as Heteronomy> The conception of every rational being as one which must consider itself as giving in all the maxims of its will universal laws, so as to judge itself and its actions from this point of view — this conception leads to another which depends on it and is very fruitful, namely, tljat of a kingdom of ends. " P^«Jih- - ^-^^ ^^---A J '-^• By a kingdom- I understand the union of different rational beings in a system by common laws. Now since it is by laws that ends are determined as regards their ^ [Cp. Critical Exa?nination of Practical Reason, p. 184.] 62 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [63] universal validity, hence, if we abstract from the perso- nal differences of rational beings, and likewise from all the content of their p;:ivate ends, we shall be able to conceive all ends combined in a systematic whole (including both rational beings as ends in themselves, and also the special ends which each may propose to himself), that is to say, we can conceive a kingdom of ends, which on the preceding principles is possible. (63) For all rational beings come under the law that each of them must treat itself and all others never merely as means, but in every case at the same time as ends in themselves. Hence results a systematic union of rational beings by common objective laws, i.e., a kingdom which may be called a kingdom of ends, since what these laws have in view is just the relation of these beings to one another as ends and means. It is certainly only an ideal. A rational being belongs as a member to the kingdom of ends when, although giving universal laws in it, he is also himself subject to these laws. He belongs to it as sovereign when, while giving laws, he is not subject to the will of any other. A rational being must always regard himself as giving laws either as member or as sovereign in a king- dom of ends which is rendered possible by the freedom of will. He cannot, however, maintain the latter position merely by the maxims of his will, but only in case he is a completely independent being without wants and with unrestricted power adequate to -his will. Morality consists then in the reference of all action to the legislation which alone can render a kingdom of ends possible. This legislation must be capable of existing in every rational being, and of emanating from his will, so that the principle of this will is, never to act [64] METAPHYSIC OF ll^ALS. 63 j'on any maxim which could not without contradiction be I also a universal law, and accordingly always so to act that the will could at the same time regard itself as giving in its maxims universal laws. If now the maxims of rational beings are not by their own nature coincident with this objective principle, then the necessity of acting on it is called practical necessitation (64), i.e., duty. Duty does not apply to the sovereign in the kingdom of ends, but it does to every member of it and to all in the same degree. ,_The practical necessity of acting on this principle, i.e., duty, does not rest at all on feelings, impulses, or incli- nations, but solely on the rejation of rational beings, ta one another, a relation in which the will of a rational being must always be regarded as legislative, since other- wise it could not be conceived as an end in itself. Reason then refers every maxim of the will, regarding it as legislating universally, to every other will and alsa to every action towards oneself ; and this not on account of any other practical motive or any future advantage, but from the idea of the dignity of a rational being, obey- ing no law but that which he himself also gives. In the kingdom of ends everything has either Value or Dignity... Whatever has a value can be replaced by something else which is^iguivalent; whatever, on the other hand, is above all value, and therefore admits of no equivalent, has,a .dignity. Whatever has reference to the general inclinations and wants of mankind has a. market value; whatever, without presupposing a want, corresponds to a certain taste, that is to a satisfaction in the mere puvposebss play of our faculties, has a. fancy value; but tfiat'whicn- constitutes the condition under which alone anytEng caii'be an end in TtselfV this has not merely a relative 64 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [65] worth, t. e., value, but an intrinsic worth, th at is Now morality is the condition under which alone a rational being can be an end in himself, since by this alone is it possible that he should be a legislating member in the kingdom of ends. 'j^Thus morality, and humanity as capable of it, is that which alone has dignity (65). Skill and diligence in labour have a markef'value ; wit, lively imagination, and humour, have fancy value ; on the other hand, fidelity_Jo promises, benevolence from principle (not from_ in- stinct), have an intrinsic worth. Neither nature nor art contains anything which in default of these it could put in their place, for their worth consists not in the effects which spring from them, not in the use and advantage which they secure, but in thet .disposition o f mind, Jjiat. is, thejnaxims of the will, which are ready to manifest themselves in such actions, even though they should not have the desired effect. These actions also need no recommendation from any subjective taste or sentiment, that they may be looked on with imme- diate favour and satisfaction : they need no immediate ■ propension or feeling for them ; they exhibit the will that performs them as an object of an immediate respect, and nothing but reason is required to impose them on the will ; not to flatter it into them, which, in the case of duties, would be a contradiction. This estimation therefore shows that the worth of such a disposition is dignity, and places it infinitely above all value, with which it cannot for a moment be brought into comparison or competition without as it were violating its sanctity. What then is it which justifies virtue or the morally good disposition, in making such lofty claims ? It is [66] JIETAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 65 nothing less than the privilege it secures to the rational being of participating in the giving of universal laws, by which it qualifies him to be a member of a possible kingdom of ends, a privilege to which he was already destined by his own nature as being an end in himself, ■and on that account legislating in the kingdom of ends; free as regards all laws of physical nature, and_obe£ing. those only_whicli he himself_gives, and by which his ^maxims can belong~f6~a' system of universal law, to which at the same time he submits himself. For nothing has any worth except (66) what the law assigns it. Now the legislation itself which assigns the worth of everything, must for that very reason possess dignity, that is an unconditional incomparable worth, and the word respect alone supplies a becoming expression for the esteem which a rational being must have for it. Au/a namv- then is the basis of the .dignity of human and of every rational nature. The three modes of presenting the principle of morality that have been adduced are at bottom only so many formulae of the verj- same law, and each of itself involves the other two. There is, however, a difference in them, but it is rather subjectively than objectively practical, intended namely to bring an idea of the reason nearer to intuition (by means of a certain analogy), and thereby nearer to feeling. All maxims, in fact, have — 1 . A form, consisting in universality ; and in this view the formula of the moral imperative is expressed thus, that the maxims must be so chosen as if they were to serve as universal laws of nature. 2. A matter^ namely, an end, and here the formula 1 [The reading ' Maxime,' which is that both of Rosenkranz and Hartenstein, is obviously an error for ' Materie.'] F 66 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [67] says that the rational being, as it is an end by its own nature and therefore an end in itself, must in every maxim serve as the condition limiting all merely relative and arbitrary ends. 3. A complete characterisation of all maxims by means of that formula, namely, that all maxims ought by their own legislation to harmonise with a possible kingdom of ends as with a kingdom of nature' (67). There is a progress here in the order of the categories of unity of the form of the will (its universality), plurality of the matter (the objects, i.e., the ends), and totality of the system of these. In forming our moral judgment of actions it is better to proceed always on the strict method, and start from the general formula of the cate- gorical imperative : Act according to a maxim which can at the same time make itself a universal law. If, however, we wish to gain an entrance for the moral law, it is very useful to bring one and the same action under the three specified conceptions, and thereby as far as possible to bring it nearer to intuition. We can now end where we started at the beginning, namely, with the conception of a will unconditionally good. That will is absolutely good which cannot be evil, in other words, whose maxim, if made a universal law, xould_never contradict itself. This principle then is its supreme lawT~SS always on such a maxim as thou canst at the same time will to be a universal law ; this is the sole condition under which a will can never contradict itself; and such an imperative is categorical. Since ' Teleology considers nature as a kingdom of ends; Ethics regards a possible kingdom of ends as a kingdom of nature. In the first case, the kingdom of ends is a theoretical idea, adopted to explain what actually is. In the latter it is a practical idea, adopted to bring about that which is not yet, but which can be realised by our conduct, namely, if it conforms to this idea. [68] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 67 the validity of the will as a universal law for possible actions is analogous to the universal connexion of the existence of things by general laws, which is the formal notion of nature in general, the categorical imperative can also be expressed thus : Act on maxims which can at the same time have for their object themselves as universal laws of nature. Such then is the formula of an absolutely good will. Rational nature is distinguished from the^estpl nature by^this, that jLa£ts_befor e itself an end. This end would be the matter of every good will (SK). BuTsiilCie-i-n the idea of a will that is absolutely' good without being limited by any condition (of attaining this or that end) we must abstract wholly froiij' every end to be effected (since this would make every will only relatively good), it follows that in this case the end must be conceived, not as an end to be effected, but as an independently existing end. Consequently it is conceived only nega- tively, i.e., as that which we must never act against, and ~which, therefore, must never be regarded merely as means, but must in every volition be esteemed as an end likewise. Now this end can be nothing but the sub- ject of all possible ends, since this is also the subject of a possible absolutely good will ; for such a will can- not without contradiction be postponed to any other object. The principle : So act in regard to every ra- tional being (thyself and others), that he may always have place in thy maxim as an end in himself, is accord- ingly essentially identical with this other : Act upon a maxim which, at the same time, involves its own universal validity for every rational being. For that in using means for every end I should limit my maxim by the condition of its holding good as a law for every subject, this comes to the same thing as that the fundamental F 2 68 FXJNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [69] principle of all maxims of action must be that the subject of all ends, i.e., the rational being himself, be never employed merely as means, but as the supreme condition restricting the use of all means, that is in every case as an end likewise. It follows incontestably that, to whatever laws any rational being may be subject, he being an end in himself must be able to regard himself as also legislat- ing universally in respect of these same laws, §ince^it is jugLlJaJ^-fitMss oif^h^jiiax^^ universal legislation that distinguishes him as a n end in himseliT; also it follows that this implies his dignity (prerogative) above all mere physical beings, that he must always take his (6g) maxims from the point of view which regards him- self, and likewise every other rational being, as law- giving beings (on which account they are called persons). In this way a world of rational beings {mundus intelK- gibilis) is possible as a kingdom of ends, and this by virtue of the legislation proper to all persons as mem- bers. Therefore every rational being must so act as if he were by his maxims in every case a legislating mem- ber in the universal kingdom of ends. The formal principle of these maxims is : So act as if thy maxim were to serve likewise as the universal law (of all rational beings). A kingdom of ends is thus only possible on the analogy of a kingdom of nature, the former how- ever only by maxims, that is self-imposed rules, the latter only by the laws of efScient causes acting under necessitation from without. Nevertheless, although the system of nature is looked upon as a machine, yet so far as it has reference to rational beings as its ends, it is given on this account the name of a kingdom of nature. Now such a kingdom of ends would be actually realised by means of maxims conforming to [7o] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 69 the canon which the categorical imperative prescribes to all rational beings, if they were universally followed. But although a rational being, even if he punctually follows this maxim himself, cannot reckon upon all others being therefore true to the same, nor expect that the kingdom of nature and its orderly arrangements shall be in harmony with him as a fitting member, so as to form a kingdom of ends to which he himself contributes, that is to say, that it shall favour his expec- tation of happiness, still that law : Act according to the smaxims of a member of a merely possible kingdom of ends legislating in it universally, remains in its full . force, inasmuch as it commands categorically. And it is just in this that the paradox lies ; that the mere dignity of man as a rational creature (70), without any other end or advantage to be attained thereby, in other words, respect for a mere idea, should yet serve as an inflexible precept of the will, and that it is precisely in this inde- pendence of the maxim on all such springs of action that its sublimity consists ; and it is this that makes every rational subject worthy to be a legislative member in the kingdom of ends : for otherwise he would have to be conceived only as subject to the physical law of his wants. And although we should suppose the kingdom of nature and the kingdom of ends to be united under one sovereign, so that the latter kingdom thereby ceased to be a mere idea and acquired true reality, then it would no doubt gain the accession of a strong spring, but by no means any increase of its intrinsic worth. For this sole absolute lawgiver must, notwithstanding this, be always conceived as estimating the worth of rational beings only by their disinterested ..behaviour, ^ag-prefTcTibed to"themselves .from J;hat idea [the dignity of man]'alone. The essence of things is not altered by 70 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [71] their external relations, and that which abstracting from these, alone constitutes the absolute worth of man, is also that by which he must be judged, whoever the judge may be, and even by the Supreme Being. Mor- ality then is the relation of actions to the autonomy of the will, that is, to the potential universal legislation by its maxims. An action that is consistent with the autonomy of the will is permitted ; one that does not agree therewith is forhidden. A will whose maxims} necessarily coincide with the laws of autonomy is a holy I will, good absolutely. The dependence of a will not ' absolutely good on the principle of autonomy (moral necessitation) is obligation. This then cannot be ap- plied to a holy being. The objective necessity of actions from obligation is called.^^^. (71) From what has just been said, it is easy to see how it happens that although the conception of duty implies subjection to the law, we yet ascribe a certain dignity and sublimity to the person who fulfils all his duties. There is not, indeed^_any sublimity in him, so far as ^he, is subject io the moral law; but inasmuch as in regard to that very law he is likewise a legislator, and oh that account alone subject to it, he has sublimity. We have also shown above that neither fear nor incli- nation, but simply respect for the law, is the spring which can give actions a moral worth. Our own will, so far as we suppose it to act only under the condition that its maxims are potentially universal laws, this ideal will which is possible to us is the proper object of respect, and the dignity of humanity consists just in this capacity of being universally legislative, though with the condition that it is itself subject to this same legislation. [72] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 71 The Autonomy of the Will as the Supreme Principle of Morality. AjitQQpm^jj of the will is that property of it by which J±_js a law to itself, (independently on any property of the objects of volition). The principle of autonomyi then is : Always so to choose that the same volition shall comprehend the maxims of our choice as a uni- versal law. We cannot prove thiat this practical rule is an imperative, i.e., that the will of every rational being is necessarily bound to it as a condition, by a mere analysis of the conceptions which occur in it, since it is a synthetical proposition (72) ; we must advance beyond tie cognition of the objects to a critical exami- nation of the subject, that is of the pure practical reason, for this synthetic proposition which commands apodictically must be capable of being cognised wholly A priori. This matter, however, does not belong to the present section. But that the principle of auto- nomy in question is the sole principle of morals can be readily shown by mere analysis of the conceptions of morality. For by this analysis we find that its principle must be a categorical imperative, and that what this commands is neither more nor less than this very autonomy. Heteronomy of the Will as the Source of all spurious Prin- ciples of Morality. If the will seeks the law which is to determine it anywhere else than in the fitness of its maxims to be universal laws of its own dictation, consequently if it goes out of itself and seeks this law in the character of a'iiy~of 'its" objects, there always results heteronomy. TKe"wi]T''rirtTtiat case does not give itself the law, buf 72 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [73] it is given by the object through its relation to the will. This relation whether it rests on inclination or on conceptions of reason only admits of hypothetical imperatives: I ought to do something because I wish for something else. On the contrary, the moral, and there- fore categorical, imperative says : I ought to do so and so, even though I should not wish for anything else. Ex. gr., the former says : I ought not to lie if I would retain my reputation ; the latter says : I ought not to lie although it should not bring me the least discredit. The latter therefore must so far abstract from all objects that they shall have no influence on the will, in ■order that practical reason (will) may not be restricted* to administering an interest not belonging to it (73), but may simply show its own commanding authority as the supreme legislation. Thus, ex. gr., I ought to endeavour to promote the happiness of others, not as if its realization involved any concern of mine (whether by immediate inclination or by any satisfaction indi- rectly gained through reason), but simply because a maxim which excludes it cannot be comprehended as a universal law' in one and the same volition. CLASSIFICATION Of all Principles of Morality which can be founded on the Conception of Heteronomy. Here as' elsewhere human reason in its pure use, so long as it was not critically examined, has first tried all possible wrong ways before it succeeded in finding the one true way. All principles which can be taken from this point of view are either empirical or rational. The former, drawn ' [I read allgemeines instead of allgemeinem.'] [74] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 73 from the principle of happiness, are built on physical or moral feelings ; the latter, drawn from the principle of perfection, are built either on the rational conception of perfection as a possible effect, or on that of an inde- pendent perfection (the will of God) as the determining cause of our will. Empirical principks are wholly incapable of serving as a foundation for moral laws. For the^uniYargality.- with which these should hold for all rational beings without distinction, the unconditional practical neces- sity which is thereby imposed on the m is los.t whenlheir, foundation is Jaken hom the particular constitution of human- nature^ or~the accidental (74) circumstances in wBtcTi'iris placed. The principle of private happiness, however, is the most objectionable, not merely because it is false, and experience contradicts the supposition that prosperity is always proportioned to good conduct, nor yet merely because it contributes nothing to the establishment of morality — since it is quite a different v thing to make a prosperous man and a good man, or to ' make one prudent and sharp-sighted for his own interests, and to make him virtuous — but because the springs it provides for morality are such as rather I undermine it and destroy its sublimity, since they put jthe motives to virtue and to vice in the same class, and only teach us to make a better calculation, the specific |- diflference between virtue and vice being entirely extin- guished. On the other hand, as to moral feeling, this | supposed special sense,' the appeal to it is indeed > 1 I class the principle of moral feeling under that of happiness, because every empirical interest promises to contribute to our well- being by the agreeableness that a thing aflFords, whether it be immediately and without a view to profit, or whether profit be regarded. We must likewise, with Hutcheson, class the principle of sympathy with the happiness of others under his assiimed moral sense. 74 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [75] superficial when those who cannot thinh believe that feeling will help them out, even in what concerns "general laws : and besides, feelings whi ch nrjUira lly differ infinitely i" rlpgrpp nnnnt furnish a uniform standa rd of Rood and evil, nor h as any one a right to I form^ judgments^ for others by his own feel injfs : never- jtheless this moral feeling is nearer to morality and its dignity in this respect, that it pays virtue the honour of ascribing to her immediately the satisfaction and esteem we have for her, and does not, as it were, tell her to her face that we are not attached to her by her beauty but by profit. (7s) Amongst the ra/zb«a/ principles of morality, the ontological conception ol perfection, notwithstanding its defects, is better than the theological conception which derives morality from a Divine absolutely perfect will. The former is, no doubt, empty and indefinite, and consequently useless for finding in the boundless field of possible reality the greatest amount suitable for us ; moreover, in attempting to distinguish specifically the reality of which we are now speaking from every other, it inevitably tends to turn in a circle, and cannot avoid tacitly presupposing the morality which it is to explain; it is nevertheless preferable to the theological view, first, because we have no intuition of the Divine perfec- tion, and can only deduce it from our own conceptions, the most important of which is that of morality, and our explanation would thus be involved in a gross circle ; and, in the next place, if we avoid this, the only notion of the Divine will remaining to us is a conception made up of the attributes of desire of glory and dominion, combined with the awful conceptions of might and vengeance, and any system of morals erected on this foundation would be directly opposed to morality. [76] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 75 However, if I had to choose between the notion of the moral sense and that of perfection in general (two systems which at least do not weaken morality, al- though they are totally incapable of serving as its foundation), then I should decide for the latter, because it at least withdraws the decision of the question from the sensibility and brings it to the court of pure reason; and although even here it decides nothing, it at all events preserves the indefinite idea (of a will good in itself) free from corruption," until Tt shall be more precisely defined. For the rest I think I may be excused here from a detailed refutation of all these doctrines ; that would only be superfluous labour, since it is so easy, and is probably so well seen even by those whose office requires them to decide for one of these theories (because their hearers would not tolerate suspension of judgment) (76). But what interests us more here is to know that the prime foundation of morality laid down by all these principles is nothing but heteronomy of the { will, and for this reason they must necessarily miss their aiw- --— -^ • In weryx'^e^wnere an object of the will has to be supposed, in order that the rule may be prescribed which is to determine the will, there the rule is simply heteronomy; the imperative is conditional, namely, t'/ or because one wishes for this object, one should act so and so : hence it can never command morally, that is categorically. Whether the object determines the will by means of inclination, as in the principle of private happiness, or by means of reason directed to objects of our possible volition generally, as in the principle of perfection, in either case the will never determines itself immediately by the conception of the action, but 76 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [77] only by the influence which the foreseen effect of the action has on the will ; / ought to do something, on this account, because I wish for something else; and here there must be yet another law assumed in me as its subject, by which I necessarily will this other thing, and this law again requires an imperative to restrict this maxim. For the influence which the conception of an object within the reach of our faculties can exercise on the will of the subject in consequence of its natural properties, depends on the nature of the subject, either the sensibility (inclination and taste), or the understanding and reason, the employment of which is by the peculiar constitution of their nature attended with satisfaction. It follows that the law would be, properly speaking, given by nature, and as such, it must be known and proved by experience, and would consequently be contigent, and therefore incapable of being an a.podictic prac tical rule, such as the moral rule must be. Not only so, but it is inevitably only heteronomy (77); the will does nol _gay£-its£l£_thejaw, but it is given by a foreign impulse by means of a particular natural constitution of the subject adapted to receive it. An absolutely good will then, the prin-^ ciple of which must be a categorical imperative, will be indeterminate as regards all objects, and will contain, merely the form of volition generally, and that as auto- nomy, that is to say, the capability of the maxims of every good will to make themselves a universal law, is itself the only law which the will of every rational being imposes on itself, without needing to assume any spring or interest as a foundation. How-Such _a..synthetical practical h. priori proposition is possible and why it is iiecessary, is a problem whose so- lution does not lie within the bounds of the metaphysic [77] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 77 of morals ; and we have not here affirmed its truth, much less professed to have a proof of it in our power. We simply showed by the development of the univer- sally received notion of morality that an autonomy of the will is inevitably connected with it, or rather is its foundation. Whoever then holds morality to be any- thing real, and not a chimerical idea without any truth, must likewise admit the principle of it that is here assigned. This section then, like the first, was merely analytical, ^few t^_Br ove that mo rality is no_creation of the brain, which it cannot be It th'e~categorical imperative and with it the autonomy of the will is true, andasana priori principle absolutely necessary, this sup poses \!\l1& possihility''of'a'syni7retic'use of pure practical reason, which however we cannot venture on without first giving a critical examination of this faculty of reason. In the concluding section we shall give the principal outlines of this critical examination as far as is sufficient for our purpose. 78 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [78] [78] THIRD SECTIW- TRANSITION FROM THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS TO THE CRITIQUE OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The Concept of Freedom is the Key that explains the Auto- nomy of the Will. The will is a kind of causality belonging to living beings in so far as they are rational, and freedom would be this property of such causality that it can be efiR- cient, independentlj;_afa„fsi£lgB-£a]iSP.s determining it ; just as physical necessity is the property' that the cau- sality of all irrational beings has of being determined to activity by the influence of foreign causes. The preceding definition of freedom is negative, -and therefore unfruitful for the discovery of its essence; but it leads to a positive conception which is so much the more full and fruitful. Since the conception of causality involves that of laws, according to which, by something that we call cause, something else, namely, the effect, must be produced [laid down];' hence, although freedom is not a property of the will depend- ing on physical laws, yet it is not for that reason law- less ; on the contrary it must be a causality acting 1 \Gesetzt. — There is in the original a play' on the etymology of GeseU, wliich does not admit of reproduction in English. It must be confessed that without it the statement is not self-evident.] [79] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 79 according to immutable laws, but of a peculiar kind ; otherwise a free will would be an absurdity. Physical necessity (79) is a heteronomy of the efficient causes, for every effect is possible only according to this law, that something else determines the efficient cause to exert its causality. What else then can freedom of thd will be but autonomy, that is the property of the will tq be a law to itself ? But the proposition : The will is irn every action a la w to jtself, only expresses the_principle, to act on no other maxim than that which can alsc have as an .object itself as a universal law. N ow this ii precisely the formula of th e categorical imperative anc is the princi£le_cif morality, so that afreewill_aiid.J£L_ will subject jto^rnoral Ja^s_a^LQneLand-_the--saiBie. On' the hypothesis then of freedom of the will, ■ morality together with its principle follows from it by mere' analysis of the conception. However the latter is still a. synthetic proposit ion ; vi z., an ^abaoJutely -good will is that -whose niax im can alwa ys include itself regarded as j^ universal law ; for this property of its rnaxim"cair never be discovered by analysing the conception of an absolutely good will. Now such synthetic propositions are only possible in this way : that the two cognitions are connected together by their union with a third in which they are both to be found. The positive concept of freedom furnishes this third cognation, which cannot, as with physical causes, be the nature of the sensible world (in the concept of which we find conjoined the concept of something in relation as cause- to something else as effect). We cannot now at once show what this third is to which freedom points us, and of which we have an idea a priori, nor can we make intelligible how the concept of freedom is shown to be legitimate from principles of pure practical reason. 8o FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [8i] and with it the possibility of a categorical imperative ; but some further preparation is required. [80] FREEDOM Must he presupposed as a Property of the Will of all Rational Beings. It is not enough to predicate freedom of our own will, from whatever reason, if we have not sufficient grounds for predicating the same of all rational beings. For as morality serves as a law for us only because we are rational beings, it must also hold for all rational beings ; and as it must be deduced simply from the property of freedom, it must be shown that freedom also is a property of all rational beings. It is not enough then to prove it from certain supposed experi- ences of human nature (which indeed is quite im- possible, and it can only be shown a priori'), but we must show that it belongs to the activity of all rational beings endowed with a will. Now I say every being that cannot act except under the idea of freedom '\% just for that reasbii in a practical point of view really free, that is to say, all laws which are inseparably connected with freedom have the same force for him as if his will had been shown to be free in itself by a proof theoretically conclusive. • Now I affirm that we must attribute to every rational being (81) which has a will that it has 1 I adopt this method of assuming freedom merely as an idea which rational beings suppose in their actions, in order to avoid the necessity of proving it in its theoretical aspect also. - The former is sufficient for my purpose ; for even though the speculative ptoof should not be made out, yet a being that cannot act except with the idea of freedom is bound by the same laws that would oblige a being who was actually free. Thus we can escape here from the onus which presses on the theory. [Compare Butler's treatment of the question of liberty in his Analog^^ part I., cli. vi.] [82] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 81 also the idea of freedom and acts entirely under this idea. For in such a being we conceive a reason that is practical, that is, has causality in reference to its objects. Now we cannot possibly conceive a reason consciously receiving a bias from any other quarter with respect to its judgments, for then the subject would ascribe th€' determination of its judgment not to its own reason, but to an impulse. It must regard itself as the author of its principles independent on foreign influences. Consequently as practical reason or as the will of a rational being it must regard itself as free, that is to say, the will of such a being cannot be a will of its own except under the idea of freedom. This idea must therefore in a practical point of view be ascribed to every rational being. Of the Interest attaching to the Ideas of Morality. We have finally reduced the definite conception of n^orality to the idea of freedom. This latter, however, we could not prove to be actually a property of ourselves or of human nature ; only we saw that it must be pre- supposed if we would conceive a being as rational and conscious of its causality in respect of its actions, i.e., as endowed with a will ; and so we find that on just the same grounds we must ascribe to every being endowed with reason and will this attribute of determining itself I to action under the idea of its freedom. Now it resulted also from the presupposition of this idea that we became aware of a law that the subjective prin c iples o f action,_ z".g., maxim s, must always be so assumed that they can also hold as objective (82), that is, universal principles, and so serve as universal laws of our own dictation. But why then should I subject myself to this principle and that simply as a rational G 82 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [83] being, thus also subjecting to it all other beings en- dowed with reason ? I will allow that no interest urges me to this, for that would not give a categorical impera- tive, but I must take an interest in it and discern how this comes to pass ; for this ' I ought ' is properly an ' I would,' valid for every rational being, provided only that reason determined his actions without any hindrance. But for beings that are in addition affected as we are by springs of a different kind, namely, sensi- bility, and in whose case that is not always done which reason alone would do, for these that necessity is ex- pressed only as an ' ought,' and the subjective necessity is diiferent from the objective. It seems then as if the moral law, that is, the principle of autonomy of the will, were properly speaking only presupposed in the idea of freedom, and as if we could not prove its reality and objective necessity indepen- dently. In that case we should still have gained some- thing considerable by at lea^ determining the true principle more exactly than had previously been done ; but as regards its vaUdity and the practical necessity of subjecting oneself tout, we should not have advanced a step. For if we werdi asked why the universal validity of our maxim as a lawanust be the condition restricting our actions, and on what we ground the worth which we assign to this manniier of acting — a worth so great that there cannot be any higher interest ; and if we were asked further how it happens that it is by this alone a man believes he f^els his own personal worth, in comparison with which that of an agreeable or disagreeable condition is to 'be regarded as nothing, to these questions we could give no satisfactory answer. (83) We iind indeed sometimes that we can take an «M ^.i' ^'"^- [.83] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 83 interest^ in a persorifll quality which does not involve any interest of exteri^al condition, provided this quality makes us capable of participating in the condition in case reason were to effect the allotment ; that is to say, the mere being worthy of happiness can interest of itself even without tlje motive of participating in this happiness. This judgment, however, is in fact only the effect of the importance of the moral law which we before presupposed (when by the idea of freedom we detach ourselves from every empirical interest) ; but that we ought to detach ourselves from these interests, i.e., to consider ourselves as free in action and yet as subject to certain laws, so as to find a worth simply in our own person which can compensate us for the loss of everything that gives worth to our condition ; this we are not yet able to discern in this way, nor do we see how it is possible so to act — in other words, whence the moral law derives its obligation. It must be freely admitted that there is a sort of circle here from which it seems impossible to escape. In the order of efficient causes we assume ourselves free, in order that in the order of ends we may conceive our- selves as subject to moral laws : and we afterwards conceive ourselves as subject to these laws, because we have attributed to ourselves freedom of will ^— for freedora-aniself-legislation of will are both autonomy, and therefore a,re reciprocal conceptioas-, aii3~for'this _yery j:eas.on one must not be used to explain the other or_give— tbe_reason .o£ it,. but. -at. mo5t..i3Jily. for logical purposes to reduce apparently different .jn^otions_of_thfi. .aame_QbJ£ct_tQ-£in£L.singi£^finjcept-4as we reduce diffe- rent fractions of the same value to the lowest terms). / ' [' Interest ' means a spring of the will, in so far as this spring is presented by Reason. See note, pp. 96, 97]. G2 84 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [84] One resource remains to us, namely, to inquire whether we do not occupy different points of view I when by means of freedom (84) we think ourselves as causes efficient a priort'lsladl'^'^sn we form our concep- tion of ourselves from our actions as effects which we see before our eye^^. It is a remark which needs no subtle reflection to make, but which we may assume that even the commonest understanding can make, although it be after its fashion by an obscure discernment of judg- ment which it calls feeling, that all the ' ideas ' ' that come to us involuntarily (as those of the senses) do not enable us to know objects otherwise than as they affect us ; so that what they may be in themselves remains unknown to us, and consequently that as regards 'ideas' of this kind even with the closest attention and clear- ness that the understanding can apply to them, we can by them only attain to the knowledge of appearances, never to that of things in themselves. As soon as this distinction has once been made (perhaps merely in consequence of the difference observed between the ideas given us from without, and in which we are passive, and those that we produce simply from our- selves, and in which we show our own activity), then it follows of itself that we must admit and assume be- hind the apppearance something else that is not an appearance, namely, the things in themselves ; although we must admit that as they can never be known to us except as they affect us, we can come no nearer to them, nor can we, ever know what they are in them- selves. This must furnish a distinction, however crude. 1 [The common understanding being here spoken of, I use the word ' idea ' in its popular sense.] [8s] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 85 between a world of sense and the world of, understanding, of which the former may be different according to the difference of the sensuous impressions in various ob- servers, while the second which is its basis always remains the same. Even as to himself^a-man cannot pretend to know what he is in himself from the know- ledgejie hjs by internal sensation (85). For as he does not as it were create himself, and does not come by the conception of himself a priori but empirically, it naturally follows that he can obtain his knowledge even of himself only by the inner sense, and consequently only through the appearances of his nature and the way in which his consciousness is affected. At the same time beyond these characteristics of his own subject, made up of mere appearances, he must necessarily suppose something else as their basis, namely, hisj|», whatever its characteristics in itself may be. Thus in respect to mere perception and receptivity of sensations he must reckon himself as belonging to the world of sense, but in respect of whatever there may be of purej activity in him (that which reaches consciousness im-l mediately and not through affecting the senses) he must reckon himself as belonging to the intellectual world, of which however he has no further knowledge. To such a conclusion the reflecting man must come with respect to all the things which can be presented to him : it is probably to be met with even in persons of the com- monest understanding, who, as is well known, are very much inclined to suppose behind the objects of the senses something else invisible and acting of itself. They spoil it however by presently sensualizing this ^ invisible again ; that is to say, wanting to make it an ' object of intuition, so that they do not become a whit the wiser. 86 FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [86] Now man really finds in himself a faculty by which he distinguishes himself from everything else, even from himself as aifected by objects,, and that is Reason. This being pure spontaneity is even elevated above the understanding. For although the latter is a spontaneity and does not, like sense, merely contain intuitions that arise when we are affected by things (and are therefore passive), yet it cannot produce from its activity any other conceptions than those which merely serve to bring the intuitions of sense under rules (86), and thereby to unite them in one consciousness, and without this use of the sensibility it could not think at all ; whereas, on the contrary. Reason, shows so pure a spontaneity in the case of what I call Ideas [Ideal Conceptions"] that it thereby far transcends eVferything that the sensibility can give it, and exhibits its most important function in dijUBgrnshJag-the-wotld—aL sease-ixoia. that-iaf-aode-t- _staiiding, anjL thereby grescribing..JJia.-Iimitsk.o£ the- ■ understandin^itself.. : ForThis reason a rational being must regard himself qua intelligence (not from the side of his lower faculties) as belonging not to the world of sense, but to that of understanding ; hence he has two points of view from which he can regard himself, and recognise laws of the exercise of his faculties, and consequently of all his actions : first, so far as he belongs to the world of sense, he iinds himself subject to laws of nature (heteronomy) ; secondly, as belonging to the intelligible world, under laws which being independent on nature have their foundation not in experience but in reason alone. I As a rational being, and consequently belonging to the intelligible world, man can never conceive the causality of his own will otherwise than on [87] METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 87 condition of the idea of freedom, forjndependense _on__Uie _d^ermining_caiiises_^^ sensjble^wQrld (an independence which Reason must always ascribe to itself) is freedom. Now the idea of freedom is insepar- ably connected with the conception of autonomy, and this again with the universal principle of morality which is ideally the foundation of all actions of rational beings, just as the law of nature is of all phenomena. Now the suspicion is removed which we raised above, that there was a latent circle involved in our reasoning from freedom to autonomy, and from this to the moral law, viz. : that we lay down the idea of freedom because of the moral law only that we might afterwards in turn infer the latter from freedom (87), and that consequently we could assign no reason at all for this law, but could only [present]^ it as a.petttio principii vihich well disposed minds would gladly concede to us, but which we could never put forward as a provable proposition. For now we see that when we conceive ourselves as free we transfer ourselves into the world of understanding as members of it, and recognise the autonomy of the will with its consequence, morality ; whereas, if we conceive _ ourselves as under obligation we consider .ourselves as belonging to the world of sense, and at the same time to the world of understanding. How is a Categorical Imperative Possible ? Every rational being reckons himself qua intelligence as belonging to the world of understanding, and it is simply as an efficient cause belonging to that world that he calls his causality a will. On the other side he is also conscious of himself as a part of the world of 1 [The verb is wanting in the original.] < ^s p- FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE [88] J >