CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHILQgOPHY^ NO. II. \ -f^ Lfroh thb sbmihar m logic] ^^'"*«C~^B' •' THE NECESSARY AND THE CONTINGENT IN THE ARISTOTELIAN SYSTEM BY WILLIAM ARTHUR HEIDEL, Ph.D., (dOCBKT IH PHILOSOmV IN THB OIHVBIISITr OP CHICAGO) CHICAGO 1L\t lanibfcstts of i.\o(70(t>av. IN THE ARISTOTELIAN SYSTEM 5 phases to be understood as the construction of selecting mind under the direction of interest, — and to apply to each certain definite tests, according to the end which for the time we have in view. When we have finished our survey of the fact thus analyzed and have defi- nitely noted it as answering to such and such particular ends, we hasten to recompound it in the completer definition. To each of these phases or aspects, thus abstracted from the concrete whole for practical purposes in the definition of fact in terms of means and end, we apply a name ; and after we have practically restored the unity in our enriched experience of fact, our functionally erected abstractions remain, as fossilized in the words, to haunt us as so many "things" or as "qualities" which merely "inhere" in them. The mind's economy is such that when it has once found an "open sesame" with which to unlock one of life's multitudinous doors, it tends to hold it fast and to use it on all occasions rather than trust to finding it again on occasion. But we must insist that this multiplication of words and so of "things" is purely a practical device for practical — not theoretical — ends, and is, therefore, justified only of its children ; justified, that is, only in the service it actually performs in the enrichment of experience. Yet this practical enrichment results in theoretical embarrassment, if it merely erects new facts instead of reconstructing the one fact.^ From this point of view we may judge the folly of that inane prac- tice which endeavors to cashier every new experience by merely naming it. My sophisticated friend, for example, who dashed my youthful rapture at the sight of an extraordinary meteorological phenomenon by calmly labeling it "sun-dogs" rendered me thereby, if possible, somewhat less a philosopher without making me a better scientist. If he could have shown me how those four seeming suns were one, and how the presence of ice-crystals in the atmosphere was just the meaning of that gorgeous pageantry of rival parhelia and broken solar halos, he might have accompJished something more worthy of his vaunted knowledge. ' Something like to this is indicated in Royce's The Spirit of Modern Philosophy. See particularly the example drawn from the experience of St. Paul on Malta, ibid., p. 402. The case well admits of further analysis. If Paul's companions had solved the question suggested by the natives calling him & god, they would have stated fully the relation of man to God in the universe and thus have solved the problem of religion by realizing it. 6 THE NECESSARY AND THE CONTINGENT If, then, surprise is thus the beginning of philosophy, its goal must be the elimination of surprise : for this feeling, as we have seen, indicates the need of reconstructing the fact. And this is probably just what Aristotle intended by saying that this state must revert into its opposite in such wise that wonder would be excited «/such were not the fact, that is, if a further reconstruction were required.' He states this problem in terms of possibility : if this hypotenuse were commensurable with the sides of the triangle, if a common unit could be found for them in terms of which it could be directly measured. Even here then the implication is that we have attained a necessary truth, which could not be otherwise^ It is, how- ever, sufficiently clear at the outset that nothing is gained by denominating it a necessary truth over and above what is meant by stating it to be the truth. When we have attained the complete definition of the truth, it is clear that everything inconsistent with it is false : and then we say with perfect assurance that nothing else can be truth, since this is precisely the truth. Every stage short of this of completed description reveals its functional value in the elasticity or ambiguity of its reference; it characterizes itself as opinion relatively well or ill founded. When knowledge is achieved, when the fact is fully made out in all its details, it merely is the truth ; before its attainment this or that definition or statement regarding it may or may not be true : as certainty grows upon our minds, wh'ile as yet we have not quite adjusted all the elements which go to make up the whole, we say it must be so. Hence "contingent" and "necessary" truths relate not to objective fact at all, but merely register the degrees of adjustment in our judgments of fact previous to their settling down into a simple categorical assertion. To say, therefore, that opinion or empirical experience attains the "that," while scientific knowledge gives the "why," is to utter a partial truth as viewed from the subjective side, but is 'Aristotle, Afifto/ji., 9830 12 ff., esp. 17: hii^'eh Toivavrlav ... dToreXeuT?- xi) as it was set forth in the cosmogonies. IN THE ARISTOTELIAN SYSTEM 9 equally to the working out of the predicate and to the derivation from it of the subject. But as they ^llow only for quantitativeL change they cannot account fully for things as they appear in per- ception, and consequently they are driven to denounce sense as fallacious. Thus they come in the end to agree with the Eleatics ; the inductive movement is assured, but the deductive lags. Heraclitus, however, holds a place apart ; for in his system the - copula, the cosmic process, has absorbed all that is real. Subject and predicate, taken as permanent entities, both completely dis- appear, and m their room stands the eternal law of change. This,_ his only reality, he calls dfiapitxvri, Fate, or Logos.' Amid all the endless fiux of things there runs an adamantine thread of rationality, and when he calls this Fate, it is sufficiently clear that necessity stands with him only for the insistent "Is" which defies the vanity of nothingness. And when the Atomists assert that the tumultuous motion of the atoms in the void is regulated by dvayKr/, this expres- sion means precisely what has been said above : it marks the growing assurance of definiteness with a residue of the unexplained. This residuum is indeed taken account of in the same breath, in the confession of something "tumultuous" or "irregular" in their motion. Anaxagoras is doubtless to be regarded as the originator _ of conscious teleology' in Greek thought, and to him we must look as the source of that most fruitful conception which met with great favor on the part of the dramatic poets, chiefly of Euripides, and through Socrates passed over into the systems of Plato and Aristotle only to become the plaything of the Stoics. The Sophists then appeared, "men of no system but surveying all," only to find a multitude of ineffectual predicates applied to the world. By the rivalry between the schools and the publication of hand-books of dialectics like those of Zeno and Melissus, the weak- nesses of the several philosophies became known to the general educated public, and the appearance of the rixvai pr/TopiKai, which form a complete parallel to this dialectic, disseminated still more the art of logic-chopping which served only practical purposes and defeated theoretical ends. Then came the application of the ' See Heinze, Die Lehre vom Logos, pp. 1-57. ' Diimmler in his Akademika has treated of this subject, but his work is unfortunatel)' not trustworthy. 10 THE NECESSARY AND THE CONTINGENT Heraclitic doctrine to the subject after the predicate had been sum- marily dismissed. Protagoras, indeed, still regarded some feelings ' as valid, but he proceeded quite evidently on the supposition that a . state must exist; that is, he accorded to these data of experience, as he thought, an absolute reality, but still he could not vindicate it for them except as they were accepted as means toward an end. And herein he laid bare the only satisfactory criterion of truth and reality. But his successors disclaimed this or any end as valid, and so reduced vd/xoi and ^vV«t, particular and universal, to one, namely, the unmeaning brute impulse of the moment. Thus there is neither predicate nor copula: only a would-be subject remains to which is denied all valid ulterior reference, and so in a true sense not even a subject is left. It was just here that Socrates took his stand. For he accepted the challenge of the Sophists to fight the battle on their own ground, conscious that in order even to defend their position they must have a real subject and eo ipso a real predicate. In other words, Socrates had seized upon the logic of Protagoras' demand for the validity of certain data of consci ousness, and, being an intensely practical man as well as a philosopher, he saw that in orde^ to right action kno wledge is necessary, and a real predicate in order to knowledge. "Granted," we may conceive him saying, "granted that we have only the subject, the percept, our problem is then to find the predicate, the concept." Socrates, that is to say, represents purely and simply the attitude of the mind in surveying the means at its disposal with a view to finding the end.' This is precisely the ' These, according to Plato's Protagoras, 320 C ff., were aldiis and Ski;. = All of the characteristic expressions and aims of Socrates fall definitely into line with this position. His self-examination {airiv i^erdj^ctv), his intellectual mid- wifery (^uoicuTiK^), his irony, his confession of ignorance, clearly indicate his being occupied with the subject. So, too, his favorite injunction yvw9i iravriv and its correlate aapoirivii characterize the need of keeping close to the means in order to find out just what they are or stand for. We readily see why it was that Socrates did not hypostatize the concept, as Aristotle tells us ; for he had not fairly attained it : he was just seeking it. Even his definitions were only tentative, like those in the minor Platonic dialogues. Socrates' conviction that virtue is knowledge likewise represents just this stage in the development of judgment. Intellection is not coextensive with right action, but is only a moment in it. It comes in at the point when the self is defining itself as means to ascertain its legitimate end and defining the means, in turn, in terms of the end. It can, therefore, be made synonymous IN THE ARISTOTELIAN SYSTEM I I % meaning of his search for definitions, and Aristotle was certainly- right in singling out induction and djfinition as the specific con- tribution of Socrates to the history of thought. Necessary and helpful as Socrates' procedure was, it was undeniably fraught with serious consequences for all subsequent thought. In order to prove that certain conceptions were valid, he , thought it necessary to discover them in the minds of all : but this inevitably led to seeking out these notions by eliminating as non- essential every mark which was not everywhere present.' The result was the abstract and relatively contentless concept." This view completely dominated ancient thought, and even now it is not wholly a thing of the past. Socrates, however, did not hypostatize the concepts, but this, as we have said, was chiefly due to his not having fairly attained them. In like manner, he regarded the Good as purely functional and relative, giving it no precise defini- • tion;^ for his position, as we have seen, was on the side of the means, or subject. But his followers did hypostatize both the Good and the Ideas, the Megarians calling Virtue or the Good the only real. Hence it is clear that the standpoint of his successors was for the most part on the outcome of his search, on the predicate, and their problem will be seen to be just the reverse of his. Aristip- pus and Antisthenes are the only real exceptions, and Aristotle fitly classed the former as a Sophist. It is quite common to suppose that there was a period in Plato's philosophizing when he had not reached the standpoint of his with right action, which it assures, only if the concrete act is broken up and this one phase is set off as the whole. This appears to me the truth that underlies the rather complicated criticism of Socrates' views of the dicoi50apTtv, and yet knowledge, which deals in universals, has to do only with t4 iiSia; and one really sees "man in general," just as we find him asserting that the entire minor premise — a judg- ment—is given in perception, particularly in the practical syllogism. Cf. Zeller, p. 238, n. 2, and p. 584 for examples. With such wholesale acquisition of highly complex elements by perception and an equal immediateness in the intuition of the highest concepts, a special need for fertility in the intellectual process is satisfac- torily set aside. = It is perhaps worth noting here in evidence of Plato's movement toward the concrete that most of his followers, not Aristotle alone, displayed a great interest in scientific research. IN THE ARISTOTELIAN SYSTEM 1 5 movement away from, but within, by a movement toward, the con- crete. The concept, in other words, is to be gained by defining the particular. But just here we discover the bad influence of the Socratic induction, proceeding as it did by the elimination of the non-essential, without being fully conscious of the meaning of this exclusion. For Socrates, indeed, because he had yet to find his concept, the particular still possessed a positive value. It was the nature of the particular, in fact, which constituted the concept. But Plato was, as it were, a traveler going over the ground for a second time. The concrete things of sense had for him only a negative worth, as affording the occasion or the suggestion for remembrance of the end attained or enjoyed before.' Aristotle's induction also is of this essentially negative and barren character, so far as he is conscious of it in theory ; for by means of it he reaches only the foregone conclusion of his highest intuitive principles. And it is clear that this result was due not to his logical position, but to his psychological bias or preconceptions. Given a psychology that considers the concrete object as presented intact by sense-perception and the highest genera as merely envisaged or intuited by the rea- son, instead of recognizing both as mental constructs, and the con- clusions of the Aristotelian system, incongruous as they are, follow by a logical necessity. Viewed from a practical standpoint the exclusion of the non- essential from the concept is not only justified, but it even indicates a truth which ought to lead to the destruction of the theoretical category of "things" and so of the "given." When we are engaged in realizing an end which we have set up after a preliminary review or examination of our means, we find in our experience as presented in memory certain clusters of qualities which we commonly denote as things. These clusters are the net results, so to speak, of innumerable previous experiences, in which these "things" did service as ends in themselves or as means toward further ends. We cannot too gratefully acknowledge the serviceableness of this our minds' economy, by which our experience and, therefore, our whole fund of materials or means for future action is definitely organized so as to obviate the fatality of depending on more or less chance • This I take to be the logical significance of Plato's doctrine of ivdnvriffis and ffvrayuy^. 1 6 THE NECESSARY AND THE CONtlNGENT suggestions. The essential point, on the theoretical side, is to recognize that what "man makes he breaks," or that he may and in fact does readjust these clusters of qualities, according as this or that content is peculiarly desirable for a particular end, though he need not, and, if wise, will not, utterly destroy the whole outcome of his former experience for the sake of an immediate purpose. It is precisely this regrouping of qualities by discarding those that are for the nonce indifferent or "non-essential," which is effected in the subordination of a particular to a universal through the intervention of an intermediate act. Spun out and cast into the form of judg- ments this process is what we call syllogistic reasoning, in which a particular conclusion is deduced from the major premise through the mediation' of the minor. When our immediate end is accom- plished we look back over our work and put the materials at our disposal in readiness for future action. Then we reconstitute our world of "things" much as it was before, except that it has become enriched by the added mark of being good for such and such pur- poses ; and forthwith we are confronted by a problem wholly of our own making. The previously discarded qualities, now again seen in the "things," are classed as "accidents" as opposed to the "essence." This once done, the arena is prepared for all the fruit- less battles that have been fought over substance and attribute and inherence. When we say that something is "given" we mean only that it is at our service ; but to infer that because it is here it has always been what it is and must always remain such, is not only to forget the way by which we came, but also to cut off all hope of advance in the future." Now this, I take it, is precisely what Aristotle has done. The concept, as we have seen, was received as a legacy of mere fact from 'It is interesting to note what an importance Aristotle attaches to the ii.4iTov in research. See, e. g.. Anal. Post., 90 a 5 ff.: avfi^alvei &pa iv airiaan rais ftjT^rreiri ^riTeiv i) el iiTTL liiaov ij tI icrri t6 iiA(Tov. rb fiiv yap ainov ri ijA(rov, iv ScrrtuTi. Si toCto fTjTen-ai. See also iiiii., 94 a, 20 ff. This mediation on the practical side is precisely, as Aristotle half suggests, the getting of the essential, z. e., indispensable means not already in our control ; and when the fact is analyzed after the attain- ment of the result this means is denominated the "cause," while the other less important means take rank as "conditions." The "conditions" are the "acci- dental" or "non-essential." ■I shall hope to show later on that this psychological fallacy is at the base of the distinction between the necessary and the contingent. IN THE ARISTOTELIAN SYSTEM l^ the Socratic movement, and the percept became fixed in like man- ner by the Platonic. Aristotle then assumes both these limits of the intellectual process as finally set uj3^and immovable, leaving as: a sphere of alleged free movement only the interval between them. But it must be evident at first glance that a process which is supposed to be vitally connected with, and bound to, these stable points can accomplish a progress that is such in name only. And this status is seen to present itself in manifold forms in every sphere of Aristotle's system, and marks, as it were, in one word, the hope- less dualism into which he had fallen. Induction and deduction, as functional aspects of real intellectual advancement, cannot be harmonized on this basis, and hence it was left for modern episte- mology, after centuries of fruitless toil within the old barriers, to prepare a way in a truer psychology for their ultimate reconciliation. Let us stay for a moment to enquire just what this juxtaposition of two fixed limits, — the concept and the percept, — stands for in the practical activity of life, of which logic is only an abstract cross- section. An illustration may best serve our purposes. I have agreed to prepare this paper for the press by a given date. Sup- pose then that I intend to complete it within the specified time. This purpose is seen at once to fix one of the limits of my activity; but it really determines both. For, immediately the question arises, What date is this, and just how much have I already accomplished? Everything will depend on that. In other words, my present end and the means at my disposal for its attainment, are just what they are, neither more nor less ; and, if I persist in my present intention, but only if I persist, they must be thus determined or specified. Both the "if" and the "must" are relative to the deliberately defined activity. But the end I set up is merely my conception of the meaning of what I am now doing, and my momentary status, when abstracted from the whole continuous process, appears as the means available towards its accomplishment. In psychological terms, therefore, the immediate situation is then said to be "given" in perception, although the percept is clearly a mental construct formed under the influence of discriminative (abstracting) attention ; and the meaning which the mind attaches to the percept is predicated of it as a concept, which seems in turn to be "given," though it too is determined only by the same movement of interest that selected l8 THE NECESSARY AND THE CONTINGENT this particular phase of the general situation from which to organize the percept. If, then, a single act of mind, the purposive direction of discriminative attention, produces both the percept and the con- cept, which, though not distinct, may be regarded from two paints of view, namely as existence or as meaning; then the problem of pre- dication should present no insuperable difficulties. But if the "exis- tence" of the presentation is divorced from its meaning or quality, pot only is the validity of synthetic judgments thereby called in question, but "substance" and "inherence" forthwith stare one in the face. It is well known that the relation of the particular and the general was one of Aristotle's most trying problems. All knowl- edge is of the general, and all reality is in the particular. To be sure Aristotle cannot consistently maintain such a doubtful posi- tion.' It is his opinion that the universal exists, but only poten- tially (8wa/u.et) in the concrete. There is surely no need to point out that potentiality can convey no meaning unless it is understood as a capacity of the mind to produce the concept, but if understood in this sense it must be extended also to the power to construct percepts, anql so this ultimate difference between the two breaks down.'' The fixing of the two limits of the process, to which we have just referred leads to a number of false positions in Aristotle's logic. In the first place he claims to have found, in the concrete, that which is always subject and never predicate. Again, since neither of these can really pass over into the other, there must be separate faculties by which they are apprehended, sense and reason, fully as unreconcilable as their objects, and they must achieve their content by a wholly unmediated act of intuition.' It is really un- 'According as Aristotle is following the one or the other of the two opposite movements by which his system is rent in sunder, he calls now the concept, now the percept, a vptlrrri oiaia. Naturally, as continuing the deductive movement initiated by Plato, the general is less often so called than the particular. ' Interpreted by a more advanced psychology Aristotle's own statement would answer : De Anima, III, 8 : ti ^vxh t4 6vTa riis iari. irivra. fi yhp alaSitri ri. trra. tl vo-qri, iari 8' ^ hrLCTiio) p^v rck ^irio-rijrd ttwi, i^ S' aXae-i]opav.). For it is the life of those that possess it from which spring the desires for any object.'" How easy it would have been for Aristotle to translate the whole of his system into one of spiritual monism may be seen by consid- ering some of his usual forms of statement. Throughout the entire concrete sphere he aims to recognize only relative distinctions between the potential and the actual, distinctions which are relative in the end to human purpose. To be sure his language is not con- sistent, for he also speaks of individual ivreXix^uu, as, e. g., a man; but it is plain that in his system man gua individual is not fully realized. He is essentially a ^Zov ttoXitikov, and as such finds his truest meaning in the state. And so it might perhaps, with perfect justice to Aristotle, be said that the significance of these lower entelechies is only that "things" at a certain stage of individuation have acquired sufficient intrinsic value to be able to stand alone. Such a standpoint is indeed quite legitimate, but when these things are objectified, and are taken to be fixed entities, it marks, if any- thing, our inability to show as yet precisely how God is the meaning of all the world." Again, something may perhaps be gained by consid- ering Aristotle's "four causes," if we remember that they stand for explanation, and are not equivalent to physical causation as vulgarly understood. The reason, it would seem, why he could place God so entirely beyond the concrete process of the world, was that he had virtually found its real meaning within it; for it proceeded on its way with only the shadow of influence from without. This con- sciousness of the all-sufficiency of the concrete system of develop- ment was in all probability the strongest motive for the Stoic pan- theism. The symbolical significance of Aristotle's fourfold principle of explanation would therefore seem to be just this: the process of ■In Wimmer's Theophraslus, III, 152. •Aristotle himself seems at times to realize this: See, e. g., Phys., 194 b 13 £f: dvOpmros ykp &v8pairov yevvf Kal tjXms. ttus S' cx" ''^ X"/"""''^'' "^"i rl iari, lai TTJs Trpiirijs Sioplrai, ipyov, and cf. Met., 1076 a 13 ff. In fact, the two last books of the Metaphysics deal largely with this problem. 24 THE NECESSARY AND THE CONTINGENT development, as material cause, is j-x^ ^^ <">' toiJtuj' ri yeyovlna, Sii xal ijrl tSu yivoiUvwv daairwi' 6,vb 8 roO Tpdrepov o6k %'' if the end exists or will exist, so does or will the antecedent also ; if not, as before [in the case from mathematics] if the consequent is not true the premise also is not, so likewise here of the end and the purpose ; for this also is a starting point, not indeed of an action but of infer- ence regarding it. (In the case of mathematics the end or the con- cept is the starting point of inference,' for it is a theoretical, not a practical art.) Hence, if a house is to exist, then these particular ante- cedents must happen or exist, or more broadly, the means towards a result ; as, e. g., the bricks and stones, if there is to be a house ; yet not for the sake of these things, save as materials. None the less, but for them there will be neither house nor saw — neither the tinctions between means and ends as objectively opposed to the self. At some stage in the process every means is desired and is in so far forth an end ; but the only true end is the experience, or more definitely still, the self experiencing it. ' From this point onward it will be necessary to render the rather obscure pas- sage somewhat freely. Scholars will observe that I have felt obliged to deviate from Prantl's interpretation here and there. 'I believe that ivitriCKiv here is a corruption. The "reservation" regarding the parallelism between mathematics and natural (or artistic) products I conceive to refer merely to the fact that, on Aristotle's view, necessity in the former proceeds from the definition or the realized end, while in the latter it inheres in matter or the means. Hence in mathematics you cannot reason from a consequent back to the prmciple, which is more inclusive ; and in physics, since there is free purposive action, you cannot infer a result from the existence of an antecedent. The fallacy of both views is apparent : given all the antecedents and the result is assured ; given all the consequences, and the principle is established. In either case the " all " is the concept or fact. 3 See Gen. Anim., 742 b 33 ff. 30 THE NECESSARY AND THE CONTINGENT house without the stones, nor the saw without the steel. Nor yet, in the mathematical instance, will the premises be true, unless the sum of the angles be equal to two right ones. It is evident, then, that the necessity in natural products is that of matter and its motions. Consequently the physical philosopher has to speak both of the free or final cause and of the necessary or material cause, but chiefly of the former; for it is the explanation of matter, and not matter of the end. The end is the purpose and his starting point is the defin- ition or conception, just as in matters of art : since the house is such and such, this and that means towards its construction are necessary, and since health is peculiarly constituted, that and the other must needs take place before it can be realized Doubtless there is necessity also in the conception. The function of sawing is defined as a particular kind of cutting. This will not be realized, however, unless the saw have teeth of a definite structure, and this in turn will not be such unless the saw be made of steel ; for certain parts [or marks\ enter into the concept as its matter."' It is sufficiently clear that Aristotle recognizes only a conditional or hypothetical necessity in nature in so far as it proceeds purely in accord- ance with purpose. This necessity is merely the reflex of the stress in the adjustment of means to ends, and since the means constitute the end they are the object of free teleological desire as o-vvatria' quite as much as the end itself, and hence are not in any true sense forced upon the process from without. Aristotle came to recognize, moreover, at the close of the above selection, that it is the end which conditions the necessity of the means, although he had before main- tained, and generally was quite consistent in asserting, that the necessity lay in matter as such. It is obvious that this view alone comports with his conception of purpose, and is in reality the true one. This thought of Aristotle's that nevertheless matter is the cause of necessity is curiously set off by his equally firm conviction that it is also the source of all chance occurrence. In fact it is only the reverse side of the same false position. Matter, even on his own principles, cannot strictly be a cause at all.^ It is merely an abstrac- ' This is only the logical recognition of the fact pointed out above, p. 28, u. 3. = Zeller (p. 331, n. i) has gathered many passages which serve to illustrate this aspect of necessity. 'See Be Gen. el Corrupt., 324* 18 : 7 S' vKi) J iiXij iraeiiTiKtii. IN THE ARISTOTELIAN SYSTEM 3 1 tion, as we have seen, from the concrete whole of experience, purely relative to the teleological process of means and ends, and serves to designate certain qualities as not singly*or merely in themselves desired, but still available' for recomposition into a concrete end; and only as it becomes hypostatized as an objective entity unrelated to any definite pursuit, can it be said to be the basis of all that is non-purposive. But this is precisely what we have remarked of Aris- totle's position from the beginning, as being the ground of all his self-contradictions. All this appears most strikingly in the second form of necessity which he distinguishes as "restraint," "hindrance," or "resistance."' This amounts, in modern psychological terms, only to "inhibition," and represents the purely negative aspect of a partial definition of fact. If, in defining a thing or an act, we take account of certain qualities as present but not particularly desirable and essential, they fall, so to speak, just outside the field of distinct vision and appear later as accidents. But it is also possible to ignore a factor completely in the organization of the means to a certain end, and therefore in the process of its realization a hitch will occur. Just because the actual result was not, in anticipation, foreshadowed ^completely in the steps proposed for its attainment, an element wholly unexpected and alien to the purpose appears in it, which may be of sufficient importance to frustrate the expected enjoyment. It is what the Germans so expressively call "ein Strich durch die Rech- nung." Democritus was right when he said, " Men have invented the image of Fortune to palliate their own imprudence." Aristotle distinctly recognizes the relativity of this inhibition to action according to ends.^ It would have no meaning whatever were it not as the sheer negation of purposiveness. Yet he accords it a very important place in his system, since without it he could ■This is what I take to be the aspect of truth from which Aristotle's Simius was abstracted and hypostatized. "This form of necessity is variously denominated by Aristotle; among the expressions most frequently occurring are these : ri plaiov, §la, rb kuKvov, t4 iitito- Sl^ov, and rd Ka\vriKbv. ^Met., lOlS a 26 ff.: irirb piaiov Kal i; pta {sc. dvayKatop X^vcrai)' tovto S' iarl t6 irapb, Tijv bpii^v Kal ri/v rpoaipeaiv i^iToSl^ov xal kw\vtik6v. See also Phys., 215 a, I: TrpSiTOP piv obv, irt Trdffa Klvriiiyos, namely, that the principle would lead to sloth, since action and prudence would be unavailing. Aristotle himself adduces this consideration,* for he is supremely interested in deliberate conduct. Accordingly, the fact of deliberation, the weighing of means, occupies a great share of his ' This fact is shown not only by the frequency with which mention is made of the law of Excl. Middle in all of the rather voluminous writings of the ancients on the subjects of Fate, Divine Foreknowledge, Divination, Astrology, etc., but also by the importance attached to Aristotle's dictum by all of his commentators. Thus Ammonius : toOto iUv toi rh BedpiiiM rb vvv iv' 'ApiffToriXovs Kivoiixevov, SokcT /jiv elvai \oyiK6vj Kard. &\-^6eiav di wpbs wdvra fi6pia r^$ tf>L\offotf>las iffrlv dvayKotov jvard re yhp t^v '^dtKijv ipiXoffoipiav iraffav ivdyKij Trpotrkafi^dvetv^ us oO irdvra iffri re KoX ylverai i^ dyiy/njj, 4XX' iari rivh. Kal i4>' ^pXv. Another commentator praises Aristotle for not confining himself to purely logical consideration in this logical treatise and giving scope to the largest and most important considerations of philosophy. Simplicius in his Comment, on the Categories, 103 B, expressly states that the Stoics (presumably first) applied the law also to futures. In my Disserta- tion Pseudo-Platonica, p. 26, 1 have collected some of the references to this con- troversy. I could now add many others if it seemed desirable. ' See Cicero, De Nat. Deorum, I, XXV, 69 f ., with Mayor's note, esp. 70 : " Idem facit (Epicurus) contra dialecticos ; a quibus cum traditum sit in omnibus disjunctionibus in quibus ' aut etiam aut non ' poneretur, alterum utrum esse verum, pertimuit, ne, si concessum esset hujus modi aliquid, ' Aut vivet eras aut non vivet Epicurus,' alterutrum fieret necessarium, etc." There is a slight inaccuracy here which Cicero himself corrects De Fato. c. 37. Indirectly Epicurus' attitude serves to confirm the age if not the genuineness of the tract De Interpretatione. 3 Schmekel's Philosophic der mittleren Stoa, 1892, pp. 155-184, has done good service in tracing back later arguments against Fate, like Cicero's, etc., to the school of Carneades. There is, however, still much to do in this direction. * De Interpret., 18^31: Siarc oSre pov\e6e