M2 Cornell University Library JC327 .A93 The Austinian theory of law olin 3 1924 030 439 602 The original of tliis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924030439602 THE AUSTINIAN THEORY OF LAW First Edition • . • . June,jlQp6.' Rifrintcd .... Octobtr, igia Reprinted Nmember, igio THE AUSTINIAN THEORY OF LAW BEING AN EDITION OF LECTURES I, V, AND VI OF AUSTIN'S "JURISPRUDENCE," AND OF AUSTIN'S "ESSAY ON THE USES OF THE STUDY OF JURISPRUDENCE" WITH CRITICAL' NOTES "AND EXCURSUS BY W. JETHRO BROWN LL.D. (Camb.), LiTT.D. (Dubl.) OF THE MIDDLE TEKPLE, BAHBISTEB-AT^LAW ; SOMETIME MACMATIOM srruDENT OF ST. John's college, Cambridge ; pkofessob of COMPARATIVE LAW IN THE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF WALES AUTHOR OF "THE NEW DIMOCHACT," ETC. \ LONDON JOHN MURRAY, ALBEMARLE STREET, W. 1920 i\-S^b^\'^ :v T By W. JETHRO BROWN, LL.D., Litt.D. THE PREVENTION AND CONTROL OF MONOPOLIES THE UNDERLYING PRINCIPLES OF MODERN LEGISLATION Third Edition, Revised and Enlarged. By JOHN AUSTIN LECTURES ON JURISPRUDENCE Or, The Philosophy of Positive Law Edited by Robert Campbell. Two volumes. STUDENT'S EDITION OF AUSTIN'S JURISPRUDENCE. Compiled from the above work by Robert Campbell. ANALYSIS OF AUSTIN'S JURISPRU- DENCE. By Gordon Campbell. LONDON: JOHN MURRAY "John Austiu ^tait un dee hommes les plus distingu^s, ub des eBprita les plus rares, et un des coeurs les plus nobles que j'ai connus." QoizOT. " Though the merit and work of Austin's writings as a contribution to the philosophy of Jurisprudence are conspicuous, their educational value as a training school for the higher class of intellects will be found, we think, to be still greater. Considered in that aspect there is not extant any other book which can do for the thinker exactly what this does. ... As a mere organon for certain faculties of the intellect, a practical logic for some of the higher departments . of thought, these volumes have a claim to a place in the education of statesmen, publicists, and students of the human mind." John Stuart Mill. " To Bentham, and even in a higher degree to Austin, the world is indebted for the only existing attempt to construct a system of juris- prudence by strict scientific process, and to found it, not on a 'priori assumption, but on the observation, comparison, and analysis of the various legal conceptions. There is not the smallest necessity for accepting all the conclusions of these great writers with implicit deference, but there is the strongest necessity for knowing what those conclusions are. They are indispensable, if for no other object, for the purpose of clearing the head." — Sir Henry Maink. " I seem still to see his (Austin's) erect figure, his white hair, and his large dark eyes, as, in his musical, rich voice, he told me it was most important to think distinctly, and to speak my thoughts with meaning." — Janet Ross. PREFACE T WISH to acknowledge my indebtedness to the Editors of the " Law Quarterly Eeview," the "Columbia Law Review," and the "Juridical Re- view " for permission to make use of certain articles which have previously appeared in one or other of the Reviews mentioned. I have also to acknow- ledge my great indebtedness to Dr. J. M. Gover for consenting, at a time of stress, to undertake the work of revising the proofs. W. J. B. CONTENTS PART II EXCUESUS A / The Statb . . ^ ... 254 PAQB EXCURSUS B Sovereignty . . . ... 271 EXCUESUS C The English Judge as Law-makbe . . . 288 EXCUESUS D J CusTOMABT Law in Modern England . , . 303 EXCUESUS E A CONSIDKEATION OP SOME OBJECTIONS TO THE CONCEPTION OF Positive Law as State Command . . .331 EXCUESUS F The Sciences of State Law . ... 355 Index . , ... 379 INTRODUCTION THE chief object of the present work is to present, for the use of students of legal science, a statement and a critical interpretation of the theory of sovereignty and law which has been traditionally associated with the name of John Austin. In several respects I endeavour to defend that theory against the attacks of more recent writers ] where I feel impelled to differ from Austin, I venture to suggest the lines along which a reconstruction of his doctrine appears to me possible. THE STATEMENT OF AUSTINIAN DOCTRINE The statement of the Austinian doctrine is taken from the text of the fifth edition of Austin's " J urisp rudence," which was edited by Mr. Eobert Campbell in 1^5. But I have made use of no more than a small fragment of this original ; and with the text of that fragment I have taken many liberties. My action in both respects calls for a word of explanation and apology. The number of students who wish to cover the whole ground of Austin's work, even in the abbreviated edition known as " The Student's Austin," has naturally diminished with the publication of more recent manuals. Yet, so stimulating is Austin as an author, so rare is his power of analysis, and so far-reaching has been his influence upon later thought, that no student of legal science in the Anglo- Saxon world, who is in earnest about his subject, can afford to remain wholly unacquainted with the Austinian text. xii INTRODUCTION The present work includes just so much of that text as appears to me indispensable. The task of selection has not been difficult. The most characteristic and valuable part of Austin's work is undoubtedly to be found in the earlier lectures which were published in his lifetime under the title of "The Province of Jurisprudence Determined." Lectures I, V, and VI of that part, in an abbreviated form, almost constitute the present text. "We feel certain," wrote John Stuart Mill, in speaking of Lectures V and VI, ' that any competent student of the subject who reads thoes, lectures once will read them repeatedly, and that each read- ing will raise higher his estimate of their substance." The liberties taken with Austin's text will be excused by all who have any acquaintance with the original. Although Austin's style has been subjected at times to an exaggerated censure, no one can doubt that he repeated him- self beyond all reasonable limits, or that his employment of the superlative of invective at times bordered on the truculent. In preparing this edition, I have not hesitated to delete a word, a phrase, or even a paragraph, where no real sacrifice of meaning was involved. The text has been thereby reduced by at least one-third. In the great majority of the occasions on which Austin employed italics, I have ventured to substitute ordinary type. Substantially, such changes are no more than a necessary consequence of the endeavour to adapt oral lectures for publication in book, form. It is greatly to be regretted that Austin, or a courageous secretary under his direction, did not make them in the course of preparing the first edition. AN INTEEPEETATION AND A CRITICISM The need for an interpretation of Austin may be disputed by those students who, imagining censure to be criticism, are more eager to abuse Austin than to understand him. But INTKODUCTION xiii the need will be admitted without hesitation by all who, as teachers or examiners in Jurisprudence at our Universities, have been in a position to realize with what facility the student may swallow both Austinian dogma and later criti- cism without understanding either. With the object of helping the student to a more profitable employment of his time, I have added to Austin's text a series of Questions and Notes. The inclusion of Questions may raise, in the minds of some, false hopes of a vade mecum for examination purposes. My real aims have been very different, and find their justification in the belief that our receptive faculties to-day grow at the expense of the original or initiative. The bulk and accessibility of modern literature threaten to become a snare to the unwary student, who is led away from the practice of thinking for himself. To have his thinking done for him by another is so easy and so inviting, and the temptation waylays him at every turn. Books there are of all kinds, and at all prices, wherein he may find knowledge codified, and little left for him to do but passively accept the conclusions which others have won. Surrounded by temptation, pressed too by the prospective struggle for livelihood, the student is very apt to yield himself to a soul-destroying despotism. He becomes a mere receptacle for the views of others. Such a fate were a calamity for any student, but must seem peculiarly abhorrent when it be- falls one who has undergone the discipline of an Academy. In truth, it is relatively unimportant how much a student knows when he leaves the University. It is of incalculable importance that he should have schooled himself in right methods of thinking, that he should have learnt to give a reason for the faith that is in him, that he should have won his way to freedom of thought. "Students," as a great thinker has warned us, " should be told as little as possible. xiv INTRODUCTION J and induced to discover as much as possible." The Questions in the present work are designed to assist the student in the work of achieving for himself an independent interpretation and criticism of Austin, They assume that the student has read so much of Austin's text as is included in the present volume ; and that he is endeavouring on a second reading of that text to deal with it in a more reflective and critical manner. He will, of course, give his own answer before seeking for hints in the Notes. Some of the Questions he will find very elementary. Others may seem difficult. If he can answer all of them to his satisfaction, he is more fortunate than the present author. Tor I have never re- frained from asking a Question because I have thought it might be unsatisfactorily answered, if in point of fact it seemed calculated to set the student a-thinking. If the Questions achieve the objects just suggested, the student may find my Notes superfluous. Though I shall be well contend if this prove to be the case, I do not allow my- ( self to entertain extravagant hopes in this direction. In the presence of the prevailing fetichism of mere information, , weighable out for examination purposes by the pound avoir- , dupois, the student is too prone to act upon the assumption that hie who stops to think is lost. But even if the student can rise above the temptation to sacrifice the discipline and spirit of true culture to quantitative conceptions of knowledge, he may not always have the imagination to see the real difficulties in a text, or to appreciate those difficulties when formally stated in the interrogative form. Austin's work, particularly, calls for some guidance in these respects. It is apt to create in the student's mind a quite illusory sense of comprehension and mastery. The first object of the Notes has been to draw attention to'the meaning and difficulties of the text; the second, to make some suggestions towards a serviceable criticism of it. I venture to hope that a student rNTRaDHCTICTN XV of the present work, in addition to understanding Austin ^ better, will have made some not insignificant progress in that ; art of reading in which our time is sadly deficient. i The programme just sketched may tell for intellectual unrest. But intellectual unrest is preferable to unreasoning acquiescence. Moreover, I do not for a moment design this work as a substitute for tuition. On the contrary, I rather hope that the student will gain a clearer perception of the high purposes which tuition may serve. A RECONSTRUCTION ^ What is the most serious criticism that can be urged against Austin's .theory of^ siffifiifiigpty and law ? Not, I think, its positive errors ; but its inadequacy. Austin possessed extraordinary powers of analysis, but his analysis was apt to stop short at a point where the requirements of logical definition seemed to be satisfied. He clearly dis- tinguished between Positive Law and Morality, yet his definition of the former omits elements which must be deemed essential. So in distinguishing the sovereign from the subject he made no attempt to view these as parts of that larger whole without which they cannot be adequately, understood. In so far as such deficiencies prejudiced Aus- tin's discussion of particular problems, I have endeavoured to. deal with them in the Notes. In the Excursus, I have given a more complete and formal exposition of certain topics which seemed to call for fuller discussion. Two of the Excursus, I ought to add, deal with Judiciary and Customary Law, and are essentially an endeavour to justify conclu- sions which Austin adopted, but later critics have called in question. , PART I CHAPTER I THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 1. The matter of jurisprudence is positive ja^: law, simply The and strictly so called : or law set by political superiors to ™*' ^'^ ° •' . junspru- political inferiors. But positive law (or law, simply and dence. strictly so called) is often confounded with objects to which it is related by resemblance, and with objects to which it is related in the way of analogy : with objects which are also signified, properly and improperly, by the large and vague expression law. 2. A law, in the most general and comprehensive accepta- Law : in tion in which the term, in its literal meaning, is employed, ™°?* '"'.™" may be said to be a rule laid down for the guidance of literal an intelligent being by an intelligent being having power *^°'*- over him. In this the largest meaning which it has, without extension by metaphor or analogy, the term law embraces the following objects: — Laws set by ^tgd to his human • creatures, and laws set by men to men. 3. The whole or a portion of the laws set by God to men L»w of is frequently styled the law of nature, or natural law: being, ° " in truth, the only natural law of which it is possible to speak without a metaphor, or without a blending of objects which ought to be distinguished. But, rejecting the appellation 2 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW Law of Nature as ambiguous and misleading, I name those laws or rules, as considered collectively or in a mass, the Divine law, or the law of God. Human 4 j^g^^g ggt \)j men to men are of two leading or principal T^o classes. Some are established by political superiors, sover- tlasses. eign and subject: by persons exercising supreme and I^L^sVet subordinate government, in independent nations, or inde- ! bjpoiaicai pendent political societies, the aggregate of the rules 1 gupenors. ^^^ established, or some aggregate forming a portion of that aggregate, is the appropriate matter of juris- prudence, general or particular. To the aggregate of the rules thus established, or to some aggregate forming a portion of that aggregate, the term law, as used simply and strictly, is exclusively applied. But, as contradistinguished to natural law, or to the law of nature (meaning, by those expressions, the law of God), the aggregate of the rules, established by political superiors, is frequently styled positive law, or law existing 6y position. As contradistin- guished to the rules which I style positive morality, and on which I shall touch immiediately, the aggregate of the rules, established by political superiors, may also be marked com- modiously with the name of positive law. For the sake, then, of getting a name brief and distinctive at once, and agreeably to frequent usage, I style that aggregate of rules, or any portion of that aggregate, £ositiveJ.aw : though rules, which ^ are not established by political superiors, are also positive, or exist by position, if they be rules or laws, in the proper signification of the tetm. 2nd class. 5. Though some of the laws or rules, which are set by Laws set •. 1 • , i I by men not ^^^ ''° ^^^' ^^^ established by political superiors, others are political not established by political superiors, or are not established superiors. ^^ political Superiors in that capacity or character. Objectsim. g. Closely analogous to human laws of this second class, properly £ i.* are a set of objects frequently but improperly termed laws, THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 3 being rules set and enforced by mere qjainion, that is, by the but by opinions or sentiments held or felt by an indeterminate "'"'" ""^ body of men in regard to human conduct. Instances of such termed a use of the term law are the expressions — ' The law of ^"'* honour ' ; ' The law set by fashion ' ; and rules of this species constitute much of what is usually termed ' Inter- national law.' 7. The aggregate of human laws properly so called Tbe two l&sti 'd1&C6q belonging to the second of the classes above mentioned, ino^eolass with the aggregate of objects improperly but by close under the analogy termed laws, I place together in a common class, ^^^^^^^ and denote them by the term positi ve morality . The name ity. morality severs them from positive law, while the epithet positive disjoins them from the law of God. And to the end of obviating confusion, it is necessary or expedient that they should be disjoined from the latter by that distinguishing epithet. For the name morality (or morals), when standing unqualified or alone, denotes indifferently either -e|;- the following objects: namely, positive morality as it is, or without regard to its merits; and positive morality, as it would he, if it conformed to the law of God, and werei therefore, deserving of approbation. 8. Besides the various sorts of rules which are included Objects in the literal acceptation of the term law, and those which ™***P ^°^ are by a close and striking analogy, though, improperly, termed termed laws, there are numerous applications of the term ''''''• law, which rest upon a slender analogy and are merely metaphorical or_figurative. Such is the case when we talk of laws observed by the lower animals ; of laws regu- lating the growth or decay of vegetables ; of laws de- termining the movements of inanimate bodies or masses. For where intelligence is not, or where it is too bounded to take the name of reason, and, therefore, is too bounded to conceive the purpose of a law, there is not the will 4 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW which law can work on, or which duty can incite or restrain.* 9. Having suggested the purpose of my attempt to deter- mine the province of jurisprudence ; to distinguish positive law, the appropriate matter of jurisprudence, from the various objects to which it is related by resemblance, and to which it is related, nearly or remotely, by a strong or slender analogy : I shall now state the essentials of a law or rule (taken with the largest signification which can be given to the term ■properly). Laws or 10- Every law or rule (taken with the largest signification rules ;)ro- which can be given to the term properly) is a command. S'fd^°are 0^> rather, laws or rules, properly so called, are a species a^ecies of commands.* J " 11. Now, since the term command comprises the term law, the first is the simpler as well as the larger of the two. But, simple as it is, it admits of explanation. And, since it is the key to the sciences of jurisprudence and morals, its meaning should be analysed with precision. 12. Accordingly, I shall endeavour, in the first instance, to analyse the meaning of ' command ' : an analysis which, I fear, will task the patience of my hearers, but which they 8. The classification suggested in the text may be arranged in tabular form : Laws propsrly so called Laws improperly so called I 1 I— -' 1 Laws of God Human Laws Laws by analogy Laws by metaphon .. r ' 1 Po£ittve Laws or Laws set by men, not as Laws strictly political superiors (nor in so called.: pursuance of legal right.\ Positive Morality Q. In what senses of the term law may it be applied to the rules which are imposed on lunatics living within the walls of aa asylum 1 10. Q. Austin makes this statement as if it were a self-evident truth. Has he good reason for doing so ? If not self-evident, is it true ? Cf . Hobbes : Leviathan, xxv.-vi. THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 5 will bear with cheerfulness, or, at least, with resignation, if they consider the difficulty of performing it. The elements of a science are precisely the parts of it which are explained least easily. Terms that are the largest, and, therefore, the simplest of a series, are without equivalent expressions into which we can resolve them concisely. And when we endeavour to define them, or to translate them into terms which we suppose are better understood, we are forced upon tedious circumlocutions. 13. If you express or intimate a wish that I shall do The meao- or forbear from some act, and if you will visit me with '"£°^ * * ' •' term com- an evil in case I comply not with your wish, the espres- mand. sion or intimation of your wish is a command. A com- mand is distinguished from other significations of desire, not by the style in which the desire is signified, but by the ,power and the purpose of the party commanding to inflict an evil or pain in case the desire be disregarded. If you cannot or will not harm me in case I comply not with your wish, the expression of your wish is not a command, although you utter your wish in imperative phrase. If you are able and willing to harm me in case I comply not with ' your wish, the expression of your wish amounts to a com- mand, although you are prompted by a spirit of courtesy to utter it. in the shape of a request. ' Preces erant, sed quibus contradici non posset.' Such is the language of Tacitus, when speaking of a petition by the soldiery to a son and lieutenant of Vespasian. 14. A command, then, is a signification of desire. But a command is distinguished from other significations of desire by this peculiarity: that the party to whom it is directed is liable to evil from the other, in case he comply not with the desire, 15. Being liable to evil from you if I comply not with aThemeai*- wish which you signify, I am louTid or obliged by your ^^^ °^^ command, or I lie under a^tt^ to obey it. If, in spite of 6 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW that evil in prospect, I comply not with the wish which you signify, I am said to disobey your command, or to violate the duty which it imposes. The terms 16. Command and duty are, therefore, correlative terms: mMmtU jj^g meaning denoted by each being implied or supposed by and duty " •' • n i j i. are corre- the other. Or (changing the expression) wherever a duty ladve. jjgg^ ^ command has been signified; and whenever a com- mand is signified, a duty is imposed. The mean- 17. The evil which will probably be incurred in case a ingofthe command be disobeyed or (to use an equivalent expression) tion. in case a duty be broken, is frequently called a sanction, or an enforcement of obedience. Or (varying the phrase) the command or the duty is said to be sanctioned or enforced by the chance of incurring the evil. 18. Considered as thus abstracted from the command and the duty which it enforces, the evil to be incurred by dis- obedience is frequently styled a punishment. But, as punishments, strictly so called, are only a class of sfinctions, the term is too narrow to express the meaning adequately. To the ex- 19. I observe that Dr. Paley, in his analysis of the term iatenoeofa oUiqation, lays much stress upon the violence of the motive command, aduty.and to Compliance. In so far as I can gather a meaning fromhis • sanction, loose and inconsistent statement, his meaning appears to be motive to this: that unless the motive to compliance be violent or compli- intense, the expression or intimation of a wish is not a com- reciuisite. ™aiid, nor does the party to whom it is directed lie under a duty to regard it. 20. The truth is, that the magnitude of the eventual evil, and the magnitude of the chance of incurring it, are foreign to the matter in question. The greater the eventual evil, and the greater the chance of incurring it, the greater is the efficacy of the command, and the greater is the strength of the obligation. But where there is the smallest chance of incurring the smallest evil, the expression of a wish amounts a THE DEFINITION OP A LAW 7 to a command, and, therefore, imposes a duty. The sanction, if 70U will, is feeble or insufficient; but still there is a sanction, and, therefore, a duty and a command.* 21. By some celebrated writers (by Locke, Bentham, and, Kewarda I think, Paley), the term sanction is applied to conditional j(„^^„^ good as well as to conditional evil: to reward as well as to punishment. But, with all my habitual veneration for the names of Locke and Bentham, I think that this extension of the term is pregnant with confusion and per- plexity. 22. Bewards are, indisputably, motives to comply with the wishes of others. But to talk of commands and duties as sanctioned or enforced by rewards, or to talk of rewards as obliging or constraining to obedience, is surely a wide de- parture from the established meaning of the terms. 23. If you expressed a desire that I should reader a sorvice, and if you proffered a reward as the motive or inducement to render it, you would scarcely be said to 20. Q. (1) Austin's statement is open to objection on the ground that the phiase, "the smallest chance of incurring the smallest evil," reduces the definition of command to an absurdity. It would be more consistent with Austin's general analysis to require a real chance of a real evU. But assuming this to be the case, who is to decide whether such a chance exists t The person who is commanded ? The person who commands ? Or a third party t Give reasons in either case. S2) Is a command issued to B in the following cases 1 a) B dreads A's displeasure. A,^who is ignorant of the fact, asks B to lend him £5, adding, " If you deny me this kindness, I shall think you very mean." (b) B is ordered by G* his medical adviser, to take a tour round the world. C adds, " If you do not go, I will not answer for the consequences." (c) B is requested by D to marry D's daughter. D threatens B, in case of non-compliance, with a punishment which he doea not expect to be able to inflict, but intends to inflict if he can. (d) B is ordered by E to do something under threat of a thrashing. E has not the slightest intention to carry out the threat. 8 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW command the service, nor should I, in ordinary language, be obliged to render it. In ordinary language, you would promise me a reward, on condition of my rendering the service, whilst I might be incited or persuaded to render it by the hope of obtaining the reward. 24. Again : If a law hold out a reward as an inducement to do some act, an eventual right is conferred, and not an obligation imposed, upon those who shall act accordingly: The imperative part of the law being addressed or directed to the party whom it requires to render the reward. 25. In short, I am inclined to comply with the wish of another, by the fear of disadvantage or evil. I am also inclined to comply with the wish of another, by. the hope of advantage or good. \But it is only by the chance of in- curring evU, that I am boun d or obliged to complianca It is only by conditional evil, that duties are sanctioned or en- forced. It is the power and the purpose of inflicting eventual evil, and not the power ^and the purpose of impart- ing eventual good, which gives to the expression of a wish the name of a command. 26. If we put reward into the import of the term sanction, we must engage in a toilsome struggle with the current of ordinary speech; and shall often slide uncon- sciously, notwithstanding our efforts to the contrary, into the narrower and customary meaning.* 26. Q. (1) A says to B, " Do this and I •will give you the £5 I owe you. If you do not do it, I will certainly give you nothing." Does A command B ? (2) What have been the reasons ■which have determined the State to rely upon penalties rather than rewards ? Note. — The consideration of such questions as those suggested may lead the student to doubt the propriety of Austin's refusal to admit the possibihty of a sanction of reward. TJlpian declared the purpose of law to consist in securing good conduct, " not only by the fear of punishment, but also by the hope of reward."* ' Digest I. i. 1. THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 9 27. It appears, then, from what has been premised, that The the ideas or notions comprehended by the term command are "°*'°"' As Ihering has remarked, although the public recompense has a purely social expression in modern society, it had at Home a legal expression. The general of the army had a right to the triumph, a soldier a right to one or other of the Boman military orders, and in either case the right was one of which the tribunals would take cognizance.^ The modem titles of nobility, on the other hand, whoUy depend upon the grace of the sovereign. It would be possible to go further than Locke, and claim that a command may be sanctioned by the reverence for an authority as well as the fear of punishment or the hope of recompense. Thus some chivalrously-minded people might say that the invitation of the King or the request of a fair lady is per se a command. The matter is not purely one of courtesy. " He alone lives by the Divine Law," said Spinoza, " who lovesC God not from fear of punishment, or from love of any other { object, such as sensual pleasure, fame, or the like ; but solely ' because he has knowledge of God or is convinced that the know- ' ledge and love of God is the highest good." Divine law so regarded is a command, not through fear of punishment, but for love and reverence of the Divine Being. Such differences of opinion with respect to the definition of sanction and the essence of command are referred to, not to confute Austin, but to bring out the meaning and significance of his position It is not until we have dealt with objections to a position that we understand what that position really is. I have discussed the general question in Excursus E. If , as I have there argued, positive law is something more than command, it is at least command, and is sanctioned typically by penalties. In this connection a very practical question may be asked : Does the Austinian conception of sanction cover the cases described as sanctions of nullity? The question is illustrated by the case of Cowan v. Milhoum.^ In that case the defendant agreed to let rooms to the plaintiff, but after discovering that the rooms were intended to be used for the purpose of delivering lectures of a blasphemous character, he refused to stand by the agreement. It was held by the court that, since the object of the contract was illegal, the contract could not be enforced at law. Baron Bramwell, in his judgment, said : "It is strange there should be so much difficulty in making it understood that a thing might be unlawful, in the sense that the law will not aid it, and yet that 1 " L'Evolution du Droit," pp. 324-6. « L. R. 2 Exch. 230. , 10 THE DEFINITION OF A LATV- oompre- the foUowing. 1. A wish or desire conceived hj a rational hended by ^^^j^g^ ^Yi&t another rational being shall do or forbear. 2. An Mml™ . evU to proceed from the former, and to be incurred by the latter, in case the latter comply not with the wish. 3. An expression or intimation of the wish by words or other signs. Theinse- 28. It also appears from what has been premised, that P*™''^*. command, duty, and sanction are inseparably connected orth*e ""^ terms : that each embraces the same ideas as the others, **"* though each denotes those ideas in a peculiar order or terms, eommand, series. duty, and 29. ' A wish conceived by one, and expressed or intimated tanclion. the law will not immediately punish it. If that only were un- lawful to which a penalty is attached the consequence would be that, inasmuijh as no penalty is provided by the law for prostitution, a contract having prostitution for its object would be valid in a court of law." The command of the State implied in the judgment of Baron Bramwell may be expressed as a prohibition of the making of certain kinds of contract — prohibition sanctioned, not by a positive penalty, but by a mere refusal to enforce the contract. Can we regard this negative punishment as included within the Austinian conception of sanction 1 "I agree," wrote Sidgwick, "with critics of Austin in thinking that the conception of ' command ' — ^implying announcement of wish, together with power and purpose of punishing its violation — can only be applied in an indirect way, and by a process of inference sometimes rather complicated, to many of the rules that make up' the aggregate of civil law. Still I think that Austin's conception is always applicable, if it is interpreted as rueaning only that the expectation of some penalty, to result from the action or inaction of government or its subordinates, constitutes a motive for conforming to the rules we call 'laws,' and supplies a broadly distinctive characteristic of such rules ; though the penalty (1) may consist only in the enforced payment of damages to a private individual injured by the violation of the rule, or (2) may be merely negative, and consist in the withdrawal from the law- breaker of some governmental protection of his interests to which he would otherwise have been entitled." ^ ' "Elements of Politics," p. 22 n.; cf. Heam, "Legal Duties and Rights," pp. 83-8. ner of thi connec- - THE DEFINITIOlT OF A LAW 11 to another, with an evil to be inflicted and incurred in case the wish be disregarded,' are signified directly and indirectly by each of the three expressions. Each is the name of the same complex notion. 30. But when I am talking directly of the .expression or The mm intimation of the wish, I employ the term command: The expression or intimation of the wish being presented promi- tion. nently to my hearer ; whilst the evil to be incurred, with the • chance of incurring it, are kept (if I may so express myself) 3 '■' ' in the background of my picture. 31. When I am tol king direc tly of the chance of incur ring -^ the eyij^ or (changing the expression) of the liability or obnoxiousness to the evil, I employ the term duty, or the term obligation: The liability or obnoxiousness to the evil being put foremost, and the rest of the complex notion being signified implicitly. 32. When I am talking immediately of the evil itself, I employ the term sanction, or a term of the like import : The evil to be incurred being signified directly; whilst the obnoxiousness to that evil, with the expression or intimation of the wish, are indicated indirectly or obliquely. 33. To those who are familiar with the language of logicians (lai^age unrivalled for brevity, distinctness, and precision), I can express my meaning accurately in a breath. — ^Each of the three terms signifies the same notion; but each denotes a different part of that notion, and connotes the residue. ^ 34. Commands are of two species. Some are laws or Laws or rules. The others have not acquired an appropriate name, '7*'" •'"" nor does language afford an expression which will mark f^J^ ^^^ them briefly and precisely. I mtist, therefore, note them as mands well as I can by the ambiguous and inexpressive name of J '"• "^ 'occasional or particular comma.nds.' or particu^ 35. The term laws or rules being not unfrequently applied 12 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW to occasional or particular commands, it is hardly possible to describe a line of separation which shall consist in every respect with established forms of speech. But the distinction between laws and particular commands may, I think, be stated in the following manner. 36. By eYerY ^ommand , the party to whom it is directed is obliged to do or to forbear. 37. Now where it obliges geiierally to acts or forbearances of a class, a command is akw or,rjile. But where it obliges to a specific act or forbearance, or to acts or forbearances which it determines specifically or individually, a command is occasional or particular. In other words, a class or de- scription of acts is determined by a law or rule, and acts of that class or description are enjoined or forbidden generally. But where a command is occasional or particular, the act or acts, which the command enjoins or forbids, are assigned or determined by their specific or individual natures as well as by the class or description to which they belong. 38. The statement which I have given in abstract expres- sions I will now endeavour to illustrate by apt examples. 39. If you command your servant to go on a given errand, or not to leave your house on a given evening, or to rise at such an hour on such a morning, or to rise at that hour during the next week or month, the command is occasional or particular. For the act or acts enjoined or forbidden are specially determined or assigned. 40. But if you command him simply to rise at that hour, or to rise at that hour always, or to rise at that hour till further orders, it may be said, with propriety, that you lay down a rule for the guidance of your servant's conduct. For no specific act is assigned by the command, but the command obliges him generally to acts of a determined class. 41. If a regiment be ordered to attack or defend a post, or to quell a riot, or to march from their present quarters, THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 13 the command is occasional or particular. But an order to exercise daily till further orders shall be given would be called a general order, and might be called a rule. 42. If Parliament prohibited simply the exportation of corn, either for a given period or indefinitely, it would establish a law or rule : a kind or sort of acts being deter- mined by the command, and acts of that kind or sort being generally forbidden. But an order issued by Parliament to meet an impending scarcity, and stopping the exportation of corn then shipped and in port, would not be a law or rule, though issued by the sovereign legislature. The order re- garding exclusively a specified quantity of corn, the negative acts or forbearances, enjoined by the command, would be determined specifically or individually by the determinate nature of their subject. 43. As issued by a sovereign legislature, and as wearing the form of a law, the order which I have now imagined would probably be called ^ law ;. And hence the difficulty of drawing a distinct boundary between laws and occasional command^ 44. Again: An act which is not an offence, according to the existing law, moves the sovereign to displeasure: and, though the authors of the act are legally innocent or un- offending, the sovereign commands that they shall be pun- ished. As enjoining a specific punishment in that specific case, and as not enjoining generally acts or forbearances of a class, the order uttered by the sovereign is not a law or rule. 45. Whether such an order would be called a law, seems to depend upon circumstances which are purely immaterial : immaterial, that is, with reference to the present purpose, though material with reference to others. If made by a sovereign assembly deliberately, and with the forms of legis- lation, it would probably be called a law. If uttered by an absolute monarch, without deliberation or ceremony, it would 14 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW scarcely be confounded with acts of legislation, and would be styled an arbitrary command. Yet, on either of these suppositions, its nature would be the same. It would not be a law or rule, but an occasional or particular command of the sovereign One or Number. 46. To conclude with an example which best illustrates the distinction, and which shows the importance of the dis- tinction most conspicuously, judicial commands are com- monly occasional or particular, although the commands which they are calculated to enforce are commonly laws or rules. 47. For instance, the lawgiver commands that thieves shall be hanged. A specific theft and a specified thief being given, the judge commands that the thief shall be hanged, agreeably to the command of the lawgiver. 48. Now the lawgiver determines a class or description of acts ; prohibits acts of the class generally and indefinitely ; and commands, with the like generality, that punishment shall follow transgression. The command of the lawgiver is, therefore, a law or rule. But the command of the judge is occasional or particular. For he orders a specific punish- ment, as the consequence of a specific offence. 49. According to the line of separation which I have now attempted to describe, a law and a particular command are ' distinguished thus. — Acts or forbearances of a class are en- ^ joined generally by the former. Acts determined specifically, are enjoined or forbidden by the latter. Black- 50. A different line of separation has been drawn by stone's ae- Blackstone and others. According to Blackstone and others, thedis- a law and a particular command are distinguished in the tinetion. following manner.— A law obliges generally the members of the given community, or a law obliges generally persons of a given class. A particular command obliges a single person, or persons whom it determines individually. THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 15 51. That laws and particular commands are not to be distinguished thus, will appear on a moment's reflection. 52. For, first, commands which oblige generally the members of the given community, or commands which oblige generally persons of given classes, are not always laws or rules. 53. Thus, in the case already supposed ; that in which the sovereign commands that all corn actually shipped for exportation be stopped and detained; the command is obligatory upon the whole community, but as it obliges them only to a set of acts individually assigned, it is not a law. Again, suppose the sovereign to issue an order, enforced by penalties, for a general mourning, on occasion of a public calamity. Now, though it is addressed to the community at large, the order is scarcely a rule, in the usual acceptation of the term. For, though it obliges generally the members of the entire community, it obliges to acts which it assigns specifically, instead of obliging generally to acts or forbearances of a class. If the sover- eign commanded his subjects to wear black, his command would amount to a law. But if he commanded them to wear black on a specified occasion, his command would be merely particular. 54. And, secondly, a command which obliges exclusively persons individually determined, may amount, notwith- standing, to a law or a rule. 55. For example, a father may set a rule to his child or children : a guardian, to his ward : a master, to his slave or servant. And certain of God's laws were as binding on the first man, as they are binding at this hour on the millions who have sprung from his loins. 56. Most, indeed, of the laws which are established by Privjlegi* political superiors, or most of the laws which are simply and strictly so called, oblige generally the members of the 16 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW political community, or oblige generally persons of a class. To frame a system of duties for every individual of the community, were simply impossible ; and if it were possible, it were utterly useless. Most of the laws established by political superiors are, therefore, general in a twofold manner : as enjoining or forbidding generally acts of kinds or sorts: and as binding the whole community, or, at least, whole classes of its members. Laws established by political superiors, and exclusively binding specified or determinate persons, are styled in the language of the Eoman jurists, privilegia. Though that, indeed, is a name which will hardly denote them distinctly: for, like most of the leading terms in actual systems of law, it is not the name of a definite class of objects, but of a heap of heterogeneous objects. Tit may be noted that where a privilegium merely imposes a duty, it exclusively obliges a determinate person or persons. But where a privilegium confers a right, and the right conferred avails against the world at large, the law is primlegiy,m, as viewed from a certain aspect, but is also a general law as viewed from another aspect. In respect of the right conferred, the law exclusively regards a determinate person, and, therefore, is privilegium. In respect of the duty imposed, and corre- sponding to the right conferred, the law regards generally the members of the entire community. Thedefi- 57. It appears from what has been premised, that a nitionofajaw, properly so called, may be defined in the following properly 'manner. Jf so called./ 58. A law is a command which obliges a person or persons. ' "=; > ^^ ^ ' """" ^ b9rEul, as contradistinguished or opposed to an occa- sional or particular command, a law is a command which obliges a person or persons, and obliges generally to acts or forbearances of a class. THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 17 60. In language more popular but less distinct and pre- cise, a law is a command which obliges a person or persons to a course of conduct.' 60. Q. (1) Most laws have a general application, but it is one thing to say generality is a normal element of law, and quite another to say that it is an essential element. What reasons can be assigned for insisting on generality as an essential element ? 2. Apply Austin's test of generality of command to the foUow- ng cases : — (a) A prohibition from fishing for salmon in a particular stream during a particular season. (b) The orders of an officer to a particular sentinel (a) to shoot all trespassers, (b) in no case to leave his post until so directed. (c) A special proclamation by the sovereign calling upon all subjects to refrain from molesting an ambassador then passing through the country. (d) An Act of Parliament, passed in the first instance for ten years only, but periodically re-enacted, requiring all who wish to sell alcoholic drinks to take out a license annually. - Note. — The student who has dealt conscientiously with the above questions will perhaps pardon a few suggestions with respect to the following topics : (1) the meaning of the Austinian test of generality; (2) the tests proposed by other writers; (3) the grounds for excluding particular commands from the province of jurisprudence; (4) the general argument of the present chapter. (T) The meaning of the Austinian test of general commands. Austin's attempt to establish a test is not free from ambiguity. This is particularly apparent with regard to forbearances. B orders A to call him at eight each morning for the next three weeks. Clearly a particular command. The case would not be so simple if the order had been " not to leave the house this or any other evening for the next three weeks." Such a command might involve an indefinite number of forbearances if the temptation to leave the house were constantly present to B's mind. I take Austin's general idea to be that a law aims at determining a course of conduct. The test which he proposes for determining in a given case whether or not a course of conduct is prescribed, implies the consideration of questions which might be expressed as follows : What is the reasonable construction to be put upon the mental attitude of the person who commands ? Does he, or does he not, contemplate a definitely limited number of acts or forbearances on the part of the person commanded 1 In dealing with such ques- tions all the circumstances of the case must be taken into con- 18 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW The mean- 61. Laws and other commands are said to proceed from "8°"!''' mperiors, and to bind or oblige inferiors. I will, therefore, tennsjM- analyse the meaning of those correlative expressions; and perier and inferior, sideration, and among such circumstances a time limit would be of some, though not conclusive value. If on January 1, a master issues an order to his servant which is to be carried out once each morning for the whole year, it would be surely pedantry to describe the command as particular. Logically, three hundred and sixty-five acts are enjoined; practically, the attitude of the person commanding may be more justly expressed by saying that he wishes to enjoin a rule of conduct, the limitation of the command to a certain period of time being in. all probability an irrelevant detail. (2) Some tests proposed by other toriters. The Eoman jurist Ateius Capito opposed Lex, "generale jussum popnli aut plebis, rogante magistratu," to Privilegia, "jussa de singulis concepta."' Similarly Ulpian : " Jura non in singulas personas, sed generaUter 1 constituunter."^ Austin's account of Blackstone's conception of generality is criticized by Professor Clark, who contends that Blackstone really meant a standing order as distinguished from an occasional one.* Some writers have combined both tests of generality, requiring that the command must apply to an indefinite number of persons as well as enjoin an indefinite number of acts. Sheldon Amos, on the other hand, repudiated both tests as value- less and misleading. "The most apparently isolated decree, if imperative and peremptory, is addressed to all the members of the Executive needed to carry it into effect,* and to all persons in the "community capable of interfering with its being carried into effect." M. Esmein proposes the test of perpetuity. If an Act of the sovereign legislature is to be regarded as a law, it must be passed for an indefinite period.^ " On reconnalt," writes M. Duguit, "qu'une disposition est une regie g^ndrale et abstraite, quand elle ne s'dpuise pas par son application dans un cas prdvu et d^termin^ d'avance, quand elle survit k cette application, alors meme qu'en fait elle ne s'appUque qu'k un seul cas, ou mime qu'k un seul individu."^ (3) The real grounds for insisting upon generality as an essential element in law. A prima facie case is made out for insisting upon generality from the mere fact that so many jurists, though perhaps 1 Willems, "Le Droit Public romain," p. 178. ' Digest 1, 3, 8. ^ ^. « Practical Jurisprudence," p. 112. * " Science of Jurisprudence," p. 74. ' " Elements de Droit constitutionnel," 1899, p. 9. * "Le Droit objectif et la Loi positive," 1901, p. 503. THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 19 will try to strip them of a certain mystery, by which that simple meaning appears to be obscured. differing as to the precise test of generality, agree in demanding tome test. The Roman tradition on this point is sufficiently indicated by the quotations already cited. Bacon affirms in his collection of juristic aphorisms, " Law is nothing else than a com- manding nde."^ Boueseau, though less influenced by scientific considerations, elaborates the position that Law considers subjects in a body and actions as abstract, never a man as an individual nor an action as singular.* "The French doctrine of to-day," writes M. Duguit, " holds almost unanimously that generality is an essential element of law (la loi)."* The author gives a very practical significance to the question by contending that the Act of 1886, which exiled from French territory the heads of families which had reigned in France, together with their direct heirs, was arbitrary and illegal. A very brief reflection is sufficient to convince us that juristic opinion in this matter rests upon the firm foundation of the very nature of society. Aristotle, in discussing the question whether it is better to be subject to the best man or to the best laws, refers to the argument that laws are general in their terms and therefore cannot meet particular cases. " Even in Egypt, a doctoi can alter the prescribed course of treatment after three days." Hence he concludes that a polity which rests upon writtrai formulae or laws is not the best. On the other hand, he is careful to point out that officers of State should proceed according to general principles. He concludes in favour of having a code of laws, while at the same time allowing officers of State to act independently wherever the needs of the particular case may demand it.* Although throughout the argument he assumes that laws mtist be general, his statement discloses some of the reasons why generality is desirable. The reasons have also been stated by Sir Henry Maine, who points out that the distance of the sovereign from the bulk of the subjects compels him to.deal with great classes of acts and with great classes of persons, rather than with isolated acts and with particular individuals.^ This has not always been the case, and the author jnst quoted remarks that, in the small family groups of early society, laws as commands would have been less associated with invariable order than with inscrut- 1 "De Augmentis," Lib. VIII. 2 "Le Contrat Social," II, chap.vi. 3 " Le Droit objectif et la Loi positive," 1901, p. 509. 4 " Politics," Book III, chap. xv. s " Early History of Institutions," p. 393. 20 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 62. Swperiority is often .synonymous with precedence or excellence. We talk of superiors in rank ; of superiors in wealth ; of superiors in virtue : comparing certain persons with certain other persons; and meaning that the former precede or excel the latter in rank, in wealth, or in virtue. 63. But, taken with the meaning wherein I here under- stand it, the term sv feriority signifies migh t: the power of affecting others with evil or pain, and of forcing them, through fear of that evil, to fashion their conduct to one's wishes. able caprice. In the modern state, however, the State neces- sarily governs by the general way. True, cases may arise for ])artictilar action, but such action, even though it may assume the form of law, must be carefully distinguished from that law which is the subject-matter of legal science. For the purposes of such a science, the particular commands of a sovereign are des quantites nigligeables. (4) Review of Austin's general argument. The steps in Austin's general argument may be expressed as follows '. Law is a command' (§ 10). It therefore involves the elements of duty and sanction (§17). It also involves the elements of superiority (§ 70) and of generality (^ 34-60). In a word, Law implies not merely Power controlling human action, but also Power con- trolling courses of human action. There seems no adequate reason for failing to insist upon generality of persons as well as of acts. , The grounds which apply in one case apply also in the other. Austin'i^ failure in this respect may be attributed perhaps to an oversight of the fact that a command, apparently to an individual, is often really addressed to a class. An Act of Parliament applying to the Lord Chancellor, applies to him not as a particular person, but as holder for the time being of a certain office.^ On the other hand, an Act of Parliament which applies to a particular individual or enjoins a definitely limited number of acts is to be described as an act of administration rather than of legislation. It assumes the form, though not the nature, of law. The distinction between legislative and adminis- trative functions, however, has difficulties of its own, to which I shall return in the note on § 289. 1 Cf. also Pollock, "Jurisprudence," p. 34 ; Markby, "Elements of Law," p. 2 ; Clark, "Practical Jurisprudence," pp. 112-13. THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 21 64. For example, God is emphatically the superior of Man. For his power of affecting us with pain, and of forcing us to comply with his will is unbounded and resistless. 65. To a limited extent, the sovereign One or Number ia the superior of the subject or citizen: the master, of the slave or servant : the father, of the child. 66. In short, whoever can oblige another to comply with his wishes, is the superior of that other, so far as the ability reaches : the party who is obnoxious to the impending evil, being, to that same extent, the inferior. 67. The might or superiority of God, is simple or absolute. , But in all or most cases of human superiority, the relation of superior and inferior, and the relation of inferior and superior, are reciprocal. Or (changing the expression) the party who is the superior as viewed from one aspect, is the inferior as viewed from another. 68. For example, to an indefinite, though limited extent, the monarch is the superior of the governed: his power being commonly sufficient to enforce compliance with his wilL But the governed, collectively or in mass, are also the superior of the monarch : who is checked in the abuse of his might by his fear of exciting their anger; and of rousing to active resistance the might which slumbers in the multitude. 69. A member of a sovereign assembly is the superior of the judge : the judge being bound by the law which proceeds from that sovereign body. But, in his character of citizen or subject, he is the inferior of the judge : the judge being the minister of the law, and armed with the power of en- forcing it. 70. It appears, then, that the term superiority (like the terms duty and sa7ud;ion) is implied by the term com/mand. For superiority is the power of enforcing compliance with a wish: and the expression or intimation of a wish, with the 22 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW power and the purpose of enforcing it, are the constituent elements of a command. 71. 'That laws emanate from superiors' is, therefore, an / identical proposition. For the meaning which it affects to impart is contained in its subject. 72. If I mark the peculiar source of a given law, or if I mark the peculiar source of laws of a given class, it is possible that I am saying something which may instruct the hearer. But to affirm of laws universally 'that they flow from superiors,' or to affirm of laws universally 'that in- feriors are bound to obey them,' is the merest tautology. Laws (m- 73. Like most of the leading terms in the sciences of ^^'r'^'° jurisprudence and morals, the term laws is extremely ambig- which are uous. Taken with the largest signification which can be not com- given to the term properly, laws are a species of commands. xnands, and yet are But the term is improperly applied to various objects which within the have nothing of the imperative character : to objects which of°juri3- ^^^ °°* commands ; and which, therefore, are not laws, pro- prudence^ perly so called. 74. Accordingly, the proposition 'that laws are com- mands' must be taken with limitations. Or, rather, we must distinguish the various meanings of the term laws; and must restrict the proposition to that class of objects which is embraced by the largest signification that can be given to the term properlyy- 75. I have already indicated, and shall hereafter more fully describe, the objects improperly termed laws, which are not within the province of jurisprudence (being either rules enforced by opinion and closely analogous to laws properly so called, or being laws so called by a metaphorical application of the term merely). There are other objects improperly termed laws (not being commands) which yet may properly be included within the province of jurispru- dence. These I shall endeavour to particularize : THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 23 76. (1) Acts on the part of legislatures to explain positive i. Acts to law, can scarcely be called laws, in the proper signification ^^v}^ of the term. Working no change in the actual duties of the Uwa. governed, hut simply declaring what those duties are, they properly are acts of interpretation by legislative authority. Or, to borrow an e:cpression from the writers on the Boman Law, they are acts of authentic interpretation. 77. But, this notwithstanding, they are frequently styled laws ; declaratory laws, or declaratory statutes. They must, therefore, be noted as forming an exception to the proposi- tion ' that laws are a species of commands.' 78. It often, indeed, happens (as I shall show in the proper place), that laws declaratory in name are imperative in effect : Legislative, like judicial interpretation, being fre- quently deceptive ; and establishing new law, under guise of expounding the old.* 79. (2) Laws to repeal laws, and to release from existing 2. Laws duties, must also be excepted from the proposition 'that*°"P^ laws. laws are a species of commands.' In io far as they release from duties imposed by existing laws, they are not com- mands, but revocations of commands. They authorize or permit the parties to whom the repeal extends, to do or to forbear from acts which they were commanded to forbear from or to do. And, considered with regard to this, their immediate or direct purpose, they are often named permis- sive laws, or, more briefly and more properly, permissions. 78. In Great Britain the operation of Declaratory Acts is not retrospective to the extent of depriving a party of a vested right unless such effect is explicitly demanded by the language of the Act. But if such explicit demand is made, the courts are bound by it. In the United States, however, such an attempt on the part of the legislature would be held invalid by the courts as an unlawful assumption of judicial power.* V. Black, " Interpretation of Laws,* p. 371. 24 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 80. Eemotely and indirectly, indeed, permissive laws are often or always imperative. For the parties released from duties are restored to liberties or rights : and duties answer- ing those rights are, therefore, created or revived. 81. But this is a matter which I shall examine with exactness, when I analyse the expressions 'legal right,' ' permission by the sovereign or state,' and ' civil or political liberty.' 8. Laws of 82. (3) Imperfect laws, or laws of imperfect obligation, imperfect ^^^gj. ^-^^ ^le excepted from the proposition ' that laws are obligation. ^ a species of commands.' 83. An imperfect law (with the sense wherein the term is used by the Eoman jurists) is a law which wants a sanction, ancf which, therefore, is not binding. A law declaring that certain acts are crimes, but annexing no punishment to the commission of acts of the class, is the simplest and most obvious example. 84. Though the author of an imperfect law signifies a desire, he manifests no purpose of enforcing compliance with the desire. But where Ihere is not a purpose of enforcing compliance with the desire, the expression of a desire is not a command. Consequently, an imperfect law is not so much a law, as counsel, or exhortation, addressed by a superior to inferiors. 85. Examples of imperfect laws are cited by the Boman jurists. But with us in England, lawe professedly impera- tive are always (I believe) perfect or obligatory. Where the EngHsh legislature affects to command, the English tribunals not unreasonably presume that the legislature exacts obedi- ence. And, if no specific sanction be annexed to a given law, a sanction is supplied by the courts of justice, agreeably to a general maxim which obtains in cases of the kind. 86. The imperfect laws, of which I am now speaking, are laws which are imperfect, in the sense of the Boman jurists • THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 25 that is to say, laws which speak the desires of political superiors, but which their authors (by oversight or design) have not provided with sanctions. Many of the writers on morals, and on the so-called law of nature, have annexed a different meaning to the term imperfect. Speaking of im- perfect obligations, they commonly mean duties which are not legal: duties imposed by commands of God, or duties imposed by positive morality, as contradistinguished to duties imposed by positive law.* 86. "Lex aut perfecta est, aut imperfecta, aut minus quam perfecta" (Ulpian). The full passage, as restored by Cujas and Schilling, is translated in Abdy and Walker's "Gaius and Ul- pian," p. 371. " A law is either perfect, or imperfect, or short of perfect. " A perfect law is one which forbids something to be done, and rescinds it if it be done, of which kind is the Lex Aelia Sentia. An imperfect law is one which forbids something to be done, and yet, if it be done, neither rescinds it nor imposes a penalty on him who has acted contrary to the law : of which character is the Lex Gincia, prohibiting donations beyond a specified amount, except those to certain persons, relations for instance ; and yet not revoking a gift in excess. A law short of perfect is one which forbids something to be done, and if it be done does not rescind it, but imposes a penalty on him who has acted contrary to the law ; of which character is the Lex Furia Testamentaria, prohibiting all persons, save those specially exempted, froui taking more than a thousand asses as a legacy or gift in prospect of death, and appointing a fourfold penalty against anyone who has taken a larger sum." Ashby V. White ^ is the leading authority in English law for the maxim uhijvs ibi remedium. The judgment of Lord Holt in that case declared that an injury imports a damage, and sustains an action, even if no pecuniary damage is shown. The franchise, it was asserted, is a right for the vindication of which there must be a legal remedy; if a man were to have no remedy, it would be equivalent to denying the existence of the right. Q. (1) Might a royal proclamation prescribing a period of national mourning be regarded as a lex imperfecta i • (2) Has a judge, who delivers a judgment which is c(jntrary to law, violated a lex imp^feeta f » Lord Eaymond, 938 ; Smith, L. C, 10th ed., 231. 26 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW Laws (pro- 87. I believe that I have now reviewed all the classes P^rhjo of objects to which the term laws is improperly applied, whichmay The laws (improperly so called) which I have here lastly semnot enumerated, are (I think) the only laws which are not tive!" commands, and which yet may be properly included within the province of jurisprudence. But though these, with the so-called laws set by opinion and the objects metaphorically termed laws, are the only laws which really are not com- mands, there are certain laws (properly so ca:lled) which may seem, not imperative. Accordingly, I will subjoin a few remarks upon laws of this dubious character. Twhioh 88. (1) There are laws, it may be said, which merely merely create rights. And, seeing that every command imposes rights. a duty, laws of this nature are not imperative. 89. But, as I have intimated already, and shall show completely hereafter, there are no laws merely creating rights. There are laws, it is true, which merely create duties: duties not correlating with correlating rights, and which, therefore, may be styled absolute. But every law, really conferring a right, imposes expressly or tacitly a relative duty, or a duty correlating with the right. If it specify the remedy to be given, in case the right shall be infringed, it imposes the relative duty expressly. If the remedy to be given be not specified, it refers tacitly to pre- existing law, and clothes the right which it purports to create with a remedy provided by that law. Every law, really conferring a right, is, therefore, imperative : as impera- tive, as if its only purpose were the creation of a duty, or as if the relative duty, which it inevitably imposes, were merely absolute.* 89. To the difficult cases discussed by Austin Mr. Frederic Harrison adds others, e.g. the rules relating to judicial procedure.* » " Fortnightly Review," No. 143 (n.a.), p. 684. THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 27 -^ 90. (2) According to an opinion which I must notice 2. Cnstom- incidentally here, though the subject to which it relates "^ ^^'' will be treated directly hereafter, customary laws must be i excepted from the proposition 'that laws are a species of/ commands.' ' 91. By many of the admirers of customary laws (and, especially, of their German admirers), they are thought to oblige legally (independently of the sovereign or state), because the citizens or subjects have observed or kept them. Agreeably to this opinion, they are not the creatures of the sovereign or state, although the sovereign or state may With regard to such cases, three attitudes are possible : (1) "We may accept the Austinian analysis as it stands. (2) We may accept Austin's description of law as a command, and contend that the examples are really not inconsistent wifch the definition. This position is forcibly stated and defended in the article on " Law " in the " EncyclopaBdia Britannica." "If we avoid the error of treating each separate proposition enunciated by the lawgiver as a law, the cases in question^need give us no trouble. Bead the declaratory and repealing statutes along with the principal laws which they affect, and the result is perfectly consistent with the proposition that all law is to be resolved into a species of command. . . . Rules of procedure again have been alleged to constitute another exception. They cannot, it is said, be regarded as commands involving punishment if they be disobeyed. Nor is anything gained by considering them as commands addressed to the judge and other ministers of the law. There may be, no doubt, in the law of procedure a great deal which is resolvable into law in this sense, but the great bulk of it is to be regarded, like the rules of interpretation, as entering into the substantive commands which are laws. They are descriptions of the sanction and its mode of working."^ (3) We may modify or vary Austin's definition of law. This is the course adopted by Professor Holland : " Such cases will cease to be anomalous if we recognize that every law is a proposition announcing the will of the State, and implying, if not expressing, that the State wiU give effect only to acts which are in accordance with its will, so announced, ' while it will punish, or at least visit with nullity, any acts of a contrary character." ^ 1 XrV, p. 358; cf. Markby, "Elements of Law," § 6, and infra, Excursus E. * " Jurisprudence," 9th ed., pp. 82-4. 28 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW abolish them at pleasure. Agreeably to this opinion, they are positive law (or law, strictly so called), inasmjich as they are enforced by the courts of justice : But, that notwith- standing, they exist as positive law by the spontaneous adop- tion of the governed, and not by position or establishment on the part of political superiors. Consequently, customary laws, considered as positive law, are not commands. And, consequently, customary laws, considered as positive law are not laws or rules properly so called. 92. An opinion less mysterious, but somewhat allied to this, is not uncommonly held by the adverse party : by the party which is strongly opposed to customary law ; and to all law made judicially, or in the way of judicial legislation. According to the latter opinion, all judge-made law, or all judge-made law established by subject judges, is purely the creature of the judges by whom it is established immedi- ately. To impute it to the sovereign legislature, or to sup- pose that it speaks the will of the sovereign legislature, is one of the foolish or knavish fictions with which lawyers, in every age and nation, have perplexed and darkened the simplest and clearest truths. 93. I think it will appear, on a moment's reflection, that each of these opinions is groundless : that customary law is imperative, in the proper signification of the term ; and that all judge-made law is the creature of the sovereign or state. 94. At its origin, a custom is a rule of conduct which the governed observe spontaneously, or not in pursuance of a law set by a political superior. The custom is transmuted into positive law, when it is adopted as such by the courtst)f justice, and when the judicial decisions fashioned upon it are enforced by the power of the state. But before it is adopted by the courts, and clothed with the legal sanction, it is merely a rule of p ositive morality : a rule generally observed by the citizens or subjects ; but deriving the only THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 29 force, which it can be said to possess, from the gftnaral d^g- ^ , approbation falling on those who transgress it. 95. Now when judges transmute a custom into a legal rule (or make a legal rule not suggested by a custom), the legal rule which they establish is established by the sovereign legislature. Asubordinate or subject judge is merely a minister. The portion of the sovereign power which lies at his disposi- tion is merely delegated. The rules which he makes derive their legal force from authority given by the state : an auth- ority which the state may confer expressly, but which it com- monly imparts in the way of acquiescence. For, since the state may reverse the rules which he makes, and yet permits him to enforce them by the power of the political community, its sovereign will ' that his rules shall obtain as law ' is clearly evinced by its conduc t, though not by its express declaration. 96. The admirers of customary law love to trick out their idol with mysterious and imposing attributes. But to those who can see the difference between positive law and morality, there is nothing of mystery about it. Considered as rules of positive morality, customary laws arise from the consent of the governed, and not from the position or establishment of political superiors. But, considered as moral rules turned into positive laws, customary laws are established by the ^7 state : established by the state directly, when the customs are promulged in its statutes ; established by the state jcizr .cuitously, when the customs are adopted by its tribunals. 97. The opinion of the party which abhors judge-made laws, springs from their inadequate conception of the nature of commands. 98. Like other significations of desire, a command is express or tacit. If the desire be signified by words (written or spoken), the command is express. If the desire be signi- fied by conduct (or by any signs of desire which are not words), the command is tacit. y 30 THE DEFINITION OF A LAW 99. Now when customs are turned into legal rules by decisions of subject judges, the legal rules which emerge from the customs are tacit command s of the sovereign legis- lature. The state, which is able to abolish, permits its ministers to enforce them : and it, therefore, signifies its pleasure, by that its voluntary acquiescence, ' that they shall serve as a law to the governed.' I 100. My present purpose is merejly this : to prove that the positive law styled customary (and all positive law made judicially) is established by the state directly or circuitously, and, therefore, is imperatwe. I am far from disputing, that law made judicially (or in the way of improper legislation) and law made by statute (or in the properly legislative manner) are distinguished by weighty differences. I shall inquire, in future lectures, what those differences are; and why subject judges, who are properly ministers of the law, have commonly shared with the sovereign in the business of making it. Laws 101. I assume, then, that the only laws which are not not oom-^ imperative, and which belong to the subject-matter of juris- mands, prudence, are the following: — 1. Declaratory laws, or laws explaining the import of existing positive law. 2. Laws abrogating or repealing existing positive law. 3. Imperfect laws, or laws of imperfect obligation (with the sense wherein the expression is used by the Eoman jurists). 102. But the space occupied in the science by these im- proper laws is comparatively narrow and insignificant. Ac- cordingly, although I shall take them into account so often as I refer to them directly, I shall throw them out of account on other occasions. Or (changing the expression) I shall limit the term law to laws which are imperative, unless I extend it expressly to laws which are not.* j. * The subject of Customary Law is discussed mfra Excursus D. enumer- ated. CHAPTER II THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 103. The term law, or the term laws, is applied to the Laws pro- following objects : — to laws proper or properly so called, and ^^J?^'" to laws improper or improperly so called : to objects which laws im- have all the essentials of an imperative law or rule, and P'^°P^'^^y so called, to objects which are wanting in some of those essentials, but to which the term is unduly extended either by reason of analogy or in the way of metaphor. 104. Strictly speaking, all improper laws are analogous to laws proper : and the term law, as applied to any of them, is' a metaphorical or figurative expression. For every meta- phor springs from an analogy : and every analogical extension given to a term is a metaphor or figure of speech. The term is extended from the objects which it properly signifies to objects of another nature; to objects not of the class wherein the former are contained, although they are allied to the former by that more distant resemblance which is usually styled analogy. 105. But, taking the expressions with the meanings which Analogy custom or usage has established, there is a difference between *" ™***' ° pnor as an employment of a term analogically and a metaphor, used in By a metaphorical or figurative application, we usually ooni™°" mean one in which the analogy is faint, the alliance between defined, the primitive and the derivative signification remote. When the analogy is clear, strong, and close; when the subjects to which the term is deflected lie on the confines of the class properly denoted by it, and have many of the properties 3X 32 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS common to the class, we hardly say that the name is employed figuratively or metaphorically. The difference between metaphor and analogy is hence a difference of degree, and not to be settled precisely by drawing a strict line between them. Lawsim- 106. Now a broad distinction obtains between laws im- proper are properly so called. Some are closely, others are remotely kinds— analogous to laws proper. The term law is extended td 1. Laws by some by a decision of the reason or understanding. The 2°Lawsb ^^'^"^ ^"''"' ^^ extended to others by a turn or caprice of the metaphor, fancy. 107. In order that I may mark this distinction briefly and commodiously, I avail myself of the difference, es- tablished by custom or usage, between the meanings of the expressions analogical and figurative. — ^I style laws of the first kind laws closely analogous to laws proper. I say that they are called laws by an analogical extension of the term. I style laws of the second kind laws metaphorical or figur- ative. I say that they are called laws by a metaphor or figure of speech. Diviaionof 108. Now laws proper, with such improper laws as are laws pro- closely analogous to the proper, are divisible thiis :*— laws by 109- Of laws properly so called, some are set by God to analogy, ijjg human creatures, others are set by men to men. 110. Of the laws properly so called which are set by men to men, some are set by men as political superiors, or by men, as private persons, in pursuance of legal rights. Others may be described in the foUowmg negative manner. They are not set by men as political superiors, nor are they set by men, as private persons, in pursuance of legal rights. Laws by 111. The laws improperly so called which are closely ana "gy- analogous to the proper, are merely opinions or sentiments held or felt by men in regard to human conduct. As I shall show hereafter, these opinions and sentiments are THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 33 styled laws, because they are analogous to laws properly 80 called : because they resemble laws properly so called in some of their properties or some of their effects or con- sequences. 112. Accordingly, I distribute laws proper, with such Diatribu- improper laws as are closely analogous to the proper, under !^™ °^ three capital classes. per, and 113. The first comprises the laws (properly so called) ^^''^ ^^ uialogYi which are set by God to his human creatures. under 114. The second comprises the laws (properly so called) tl»ree which are set by men as political superiors, or by men, as daases. private persons, in pursuance of legal rights. 115. The third comprises laws of the two following species : 1. The laws (properly so called) which are set by men to men but not by men as political superiors, nor by men, as private persons, in pursuance of legal rights : 2. The laws, which are closely analogous to laws proper, but are merely opinions or sentiments held or felt by men in regard to human conduct. — I put laws of these species into a common class, and I mark them with the common name of positiv^e morality or positive moral rules. 116. My reasons for using the twa expressions 'positive The ex- law' and 'posiiiw morality,' are the following: — ' presaion* posUiw 117. There are two capital classes of human laws. The ?ato and first comprises the laws (properly so called) which are set^"**'*'* , ,., . ... , . . , morality. by men as political superiors, or by men, as private persons, in pursuance of legal rights. The second comprises ^he laws (proper and improper) which belong to the two species above mentioned. 118. As' merely distinguished from the second, the, first of those capital classes might be named simply^ law. As merely distinguished from the first, the seconc}. of those capital classes mi|;ht be named simply morality. But both must be distinguished from the law of God: and, for the 34 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS purpose of distinguishing both from the law of God, we must qualify the names law and morality. Accjordingly, I style the first of those capital classes ' positive law : ' and I style the second of those capital classes ' positive morality.' By the common epithet positive, I denote that both classes flow from human sources. By the distinctive names law and morality, I denote the difference between the human sources from which the two classes respectively emanate. 119. Strictly speaking, every law properly so called is a positive law. For it is put or setby its individual or collec- tive author, or it exists by the position or institution of its individual or collective author. 120. But, as opposed to the law of nature (meaning the law of God), human law of the first of those capital classes is styled by writers on jurisprudence 'positive law.' This application of the expression ' positive law ' was manifestly made for the purpose of obviating confusion ; confusion of human law of the first of those capital classes with that Divine law which is the measure or test of human. - 121. And, in order to obviate similar confusiorl, I apply the expression 'positive morality' to human law of the second capital class. For the name morality, when standing unqualified or alone, may signify the law set by God, or human law of that second capital class. If you say that an act or omission violates morality, you speak ambiguously. You may mean that it violates the law which I style 'posi- tive morality,' or that it violates the Divine law which is the measure or test of the former.* 121. Professor Claik, in discussing Austin's use of the three expressions, proper, positive, and strictly so called, writes, "Proper signifies that the law emanates from a determinate author; positive that such author is human; strictly so called, that the human author is sovereign."^ The statement is scarcely justified 1 " Practical Jurisprudence," p. 136. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 35 122. From the expression positive law and the expression ExpUna- positive morality, I pass to certain expressions with which fj^^j^g they are closely connected. ~^ - — . - - expiea- 123. The science of jurisprudence (or, simply and briefly, *'°°s="^> jurisprudefice) is concernfed with positive laws, or with laws jurispru- strictly so called, as cofisidered without regard to their good- "^'""^ '""^ seienee of ness or badness. positive 124. Positive morality, as considered without regard to '""'"'»'*!'»■ its goodness or badness, might be the subject of a science ^^}^^|^ ^^ closely analogous to jurisprudence. I say ' migM be : ' since deontologt/, it is only in one of its branches (namely, the law of nations J^!^^^, or international law) that positive morality, as considered and jciejie* without regard to its goodness or badness, has been treated "/""^"^ by writers in a scientific or systematic manner. — For the science of positive morality, as considered without regard to its goodness or badness, current or established language will hardly afiford us a name. The name morals, or science of morals, would denote it ambiguously : the name morals, or science of morals, being commonly applied (as I shall show immediately) to a department of ethics or deontology. But, since the science of jurisprudence is not unfrequently styled ' the science of positive law,' the science in question might be styled analogically 'the science of positive morality.* The department of the science in question which relates to international law, has actually been styled by Yon Martens, a recent writer of celebrity, 'positives oder prac- tisches Volkerrecht : ' that is to say, ' positive international law,' or 'practical international law.' Had he named that department of the science 'positive international moral- by Austin's language. Proper undoubtedly indicates that the law has a determinate author. Positive, on the other hand, although it always means human, carries the further implication of political ■when used with law simply. Positive Law and Law strictly so called are identical expressions. 36 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS ity' the name would have hit its import with perfect precision.* 125. The science of ethics (or, in the language of Mr, Bentham, the science of deontology) may be defined in the following manner. — It affects to determine the test of posi- tive law and morality. In other words, it affects to expound them as they should be ; as they would be if they were good or worthy of praise ; or as they would be if they conformed to an assumed measure. 126. The science of ethics (or, simply and briefly, ethics) consists of two departments : one relating specially to posi- tive law, the other relating specially to positive morality. The department which relates specially to positive law is commonly styled the science of legislation, or, briefly, legislation. The department which relates specially to positive morality, is commonly styled the science of morals, or, briefly, morals. Metning 127. The foregoing attempt to define the science of ethics ft *t^ T ^^*^^*% l®^TnTna n(lR express or tac it, and therefore emanate from laws pro- a certain source. Positive laws, or laws strictly so called, ^^}yj° <~-^ — .^ ' •' ' called. are established directly or immediately by authors of three kinds : — by monarchs, or sovereign^ bodies, as supreme politi- cal superiors : by men in a state of subjection, as gubprdinate political superiors: by subjects, as private- persons, in pur- suance of legal rights. But every positive law, or every law strictly so called, is a direct or circuitous command of a monarch or sovereign number in the character of political superior: that is to say, a direct or circuitous command of a monarch or sovereign number to a person or persons in a state of subjection to its author. And being a command (and therefore flowing from a determinate source), every positive law is a law proper or a law properly so called. 139. Besides the human laws which I style positive law, The gen- there are human laws which I style positive morality, rules ""* "''"* of positive morality, or positive moral rules. The generic positire character of laws of the class may be stated briefly in the ™°''*^ following negative manner. No law belonging to the class is a direct or circuitous command of a monarch or sovereign number in the character of political superior. 140. But of positive moral rules, some are lawp proper, or Of positive laws properly so called : others are laws improper, or laws ™°"^ improperly so called. some'are 141. The positive moral rules which are laws properly so ^'■^^ P"- called, are distinguished from other laws by the union of 0^5,3°^^, two marks. — 1. They are imperative laws or rules set by laws im- men to men. 2. They are not set by men as political P™P*'- superiors, nor are they set by men as private persons, in y^' ^^n\ pursuance of lega,l rights. Inasmuch as they bear the latter rules of these two marks, they are not commands of sovereigns J^^°^ "• in the character of political superiors. Consequently, they perly so are not positive laws : they are not clothed with legal °^^^^> -,,,.,„., , sue com- sanctions, nor do they oblige legally the persons to whom mand$. 42 THE DIFFERENT, KINDS OF LAWS they are set. But being^Mmgian^ (and therefore being established by determinate individuals or bodi^), they are laws properly so called - they are armed with sanctions, and impose duties, in the proper acceptation of the terms. 142. Of positive moral rules which are laws properly so called, some are established by men who are not subjects, or are not in a state of subjection to a monarch or sovereign number. Of these some are established by men living in the negative state which is styled a state of Jiature or a state of anarchy : that is to say, by men who are 7wt members, sovereign or subject, of any political society: others are established by sovereign individuals or bodies, but not in the character of political superiors. 143. Of laws properly so called which are set by subjects, some are set by subjects as subordinate political superiors ; others are set by subjects as private persons : Meaning by 'private persons,' subjects not in the class of subordinate political superiors, or subordinate political superiors not considered as such.— 4liaws set by subjects as subordinate political superiors, are positive laws : they are clothed with legal sanctions, and impose legal duties.^ They are set by sovereigns or states in the character of political superiors, although they are set by sovereigns circuitously or remotely. Although they are made directly by subject or subordinate authors, they are made through legal rights granted by sovereigns or states, and held by those subject authors as mere trustees for the granters. Of laws set by subjects as private persons, some are not established by sovereign or supreme authority. And these are rules of positive morality : they are not clothed with legal sanctions, nor do they oblige legally the parties to whom they are set.— But of laws set by subjects as private persons, others are set or established" in pursuance of legal rights residing in the subject authors. And these are positive laws or laws strictly so called. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 43 Although they are made directly by subject authors, they are made in pursuance of rights granted or conferred by sovereigns^ in the character of political superiors : they legally oblige the parties to whom they are set, or are clothed with legal sanctions. They are commands of sovereigns as political superiors, although they are set by sovereigns cir- cuitously or remotely. 144. A law set by a subject as a private person, but in pur- Laws set suance of a legal right residing in the subject author, is either ^.™^' ** a positive law purely or simply, or it is a positive law as persons, in viewed from one aspect, and a rule of positive morality as P^"u»nce viewed from another. The person who makes the law in rights, pursuance of the legal right, is either legally bound to make the law, or he is not. In the first case, the law is a positive law purely or simply. In the second case, the law is com- pounded of a positive law and a positive moral rule. 145. For example, A guardian may have a right over his pupil or ward, which he is legally bound to exercise, for the benefit of the pupil or ward, in a given or specified manner. Now if, in pursuance of his right, and agreealjly to his duty or trust, he sets a law or rule to the pupil or ward, the law is a positive law purely or simply. It is properly a law which the state sets to the ward through its minister or instrument the guardian. It is not made by the guardian of his own spontaneous movement, or is made in pursuance of a duty which the state has imposed upon him. The position of the guardian is closely analogous to the position of subordinate political superiors ; who hold their delegated powers of direct or judicial legislation as mere trustees for the sovereign granters. 146. Again : the master has legal rights, over or against his slave, which are conferred by the state upon the master for his own benefit. And, since they are conferred upon him for his own benefit, he is not legally bound to exercise or use 44 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS them. Now if, in pursuance of these rights, he sets a law to his slave, the law is compounded of a positive law and a positive moral rule. Being made by sovereign authority, and clothed by the sovereign with sanctions, the law made by the master is properly a positive law. But, since it is made by the master of his own spontaneous movement, or is not made by the master ia pursuance of a legal duty, it is properly a rule of positive morality, as well as a positive law. I'hough the law set by the master is set circuitously by the sovereign, it is set or established by the sovereign at the pleasure of the subject author. The master is not the instrument of the sovereign or state, but the sovereign or state is rather the instrument of the master. 147. Laws which are positive law as viewed from one aspect, but which are positive morality as viewed from another, I place simply or absolutely in the first of those capital classes. If, affecting exquisite precision, I placed them in each of those classes, I could hardly indicate the boundary by which those classes are severed without resort- ing to expressions of repulsive complexity and length, caaasifioa-, 148. It appears from the foregoing distinctions, that tion of I positive moral rules which are laws properly so called are positive I , . moral / of three kinds. — 1. Those which are set by men living in a rules I state of nature. 2. Those which are set by sovereigns, but which are . , . - . . , . ^^ , j^^g ] not by sovereigns as political superiors. 3. Those which are proper. I set by Subjects as private persons, and are not set by the subject authors in pursuance of legal rights. Examples. 149. To cite an example of rules of the first kind were superfluous labour. A man living in a state of natui'e may impose an imperative law : though, since the man *s in a state of nature, he cannot impose the law in the character of sovereign, and cannot impose the law in pursuance of a legal right. And the law being imperative (and therefore proceed- ing from a determinate source) is a law properly so called: THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 45 though, for want of a sovereign author proximate or remote, it is not a positive law but a rule of positive morality. 150. An imperative law set by a sovereign to a sovereign, or by one supreme government to another supreme govern- ment, is an example of rules of the second kind. Since no supreme government is in a state of subjection to another, an imperative law set by a sovereign to a sovereign is not set by its author in the character of political superior. Nor is it set by its author in pursuance of a legal right : for every legal right is conferred by a supreme government, and is conferred on a person or persons in a state of subjection to the granter. Consequently, an imperative law set by a sovereign to a sovereign is not a positive law or a law strictly so called. But being imperative (and therefore pro- ceeding from a determinate source), it amounts to a law in the proper signification of the term, although it is purely or simply a rule of positive morality. 151. If they be set by subjects as private persons, and not in pursuance of legal rights, the laws following are examples of rules of the third kind: namely, imperative laws set by parents to children ; imperative laws set by masters to servants; imperative laws set by lenders to borrowers; imperative laws set by patrons to parasites. Being im- perative (and therefore proceeding from determinate sources), the laws foregoing are laws properly so called : though, if [ihey be set by subjects as private persons, and be not set by eir authors in pursuance of legal rights, they are not posi- ^e laws but rules of positive morality. •152. Again: a club or society of men, signifying its collective pleasure by a vote of its assembled members, passes or makes a law to be kept by its members severally under pain of exclusion from its meetings. Now if it be made by subjects as private persons, and be not made by its authors in pursuance of a legal right, the law voted 46 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS and passed by the assembled members of the club is a further example of rules of the third kind.* 152. Q. (I) Austin divides commands set by subjects into foui classes : — (a) Those set by subjects as political subordinates. (b) Those set by subjects as private persons in pursuance of legal rights, but not as subject to a legal duty ; (c) Those set by subjects as private persons in pursuance of legal rights, and also as subject to a duty. (d) Those set by subjects as private persons and ■ not in pursuance of legal right. Suggest concrete examples of these different classes. (2) Which of the above-mentioned classes are positive laws? (3) Into which of the classes should the following be placed : (i) The order of a guardian to his ward (a) to marry X, (b) not to marry Y, (c) to abstain from smoking, (d) to take lessons in music, (ii) The command of a husband to his wife not to contract debts in his name. (iii) A resolution of a boating club increasing (a) the entrance fee (6) the annual subscription^ Note. — Autonomic Laws. — In the complete edition of his Lectures, Austin says: "Another species of law not made by the supreme legislature are laws (if such they can be called) which are established by private persons, and to which the supreme legislature lends its sanction. These (in truth) are nothing but obligations imposed by virtue of rights which the legislator has conferred. For example, by my will, I may impose certain conditions on my devisees or legatees. By virtue of a contract, the contracting parties impose upon one another certain obligations." i This language should be carefully compared with sections 144-7, which appear as a note in the complete edition and raise several difficulties. Private persons are said to impose rules in pursuance of legal rights. These rules are said to be positive laws. But no adequate guidance is suggested for de- termining the precise conditions under which a rule may be said to be set in pursuance of a legal right. Had this diffi- culty been duly considered by Austin, he would not have failed to recognize that a legal right to set rules of conduct must be carefuUy distinguished from a legal right to set positive laws. ' II, 524. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 47' — t 153. The positive moral rules which are laws improperly The posi- Iso called, are laws set or imposed Jyy general opinion : that is f ^® "*"* Many general commands of subjects to subjects, though set in ^^^ ^^_ pursuance of a legal right and directly or indirectly enforced properly by the State, establish no new law, but only bring into oper- go called, ation some existing law. Austin appears to be conscious of the fact in the second volume of his work, but to have overlooked it in his first volume. X enters into a contract with Y, and subsequently gives to T an order within a reasonable interpreta- tion of the original contract. A rule of conduct is imposed on Y; if Y refuses to observe this rule he may be sued for a breach of contract. In such a case there is of course no new law ; the real law applicable to the case is the very important one that agree- ments which fulfil certain conditions shall bind the parties. Again, Austin speaks of the commands of a guardian to his ward as positive laws, but it is not easy to find examples which justify this statement. In the case of Hall v. Hall, an application was made to compel a boy of fifteen to return to Eton, where he had been placed by his guardian. Lord Chancellor Hardwicke said that the guardian was the proper judge of the school to which the youth was to be sent, that the school was of very great reputation, and that if he refused to go he would be compelled. The Lord Chancellor quoted an instance in Lord Macclesfield's time of an undergraduate who, on the application of his guardian, was sent back to Cambridge in the custody of Lord Macclesfield's tipstafi^.^ This is very far from saying that a general command of a guardian, in fulfilment of his responsibilities as guardian, is a posi- tive law. Where the State enforces a command of the guardian, it does so merely in fulfilment of the general law that a ward shall render reasonable obedience. On the other hand, if B, for his own amusement, touches the alarm signal of a railway train when half-way between two stations, he breaks a by-law of the railway company and becomes liable to a fine of £5. It is clear that a positive law has been set to individuals by an authority which legislates in virtue of a delegation from the sovereign power. A very obvious differ- ence exists between this case and that of a guardian ordering his ward to rise each morning at a certain hour. In the case of the railway by-law, a power of imposing rules and of attaching to them a definite sanction is expressly granted by the State. The State will enforce the sanction through the courts ; whereas, in the case of the guardian and ward, the State will upliold generally the authority of the guardian without necessarily taking > 3 Atk. 721. 48 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS j to say, by the general opuiion of any class or any society of I persons. For example, some are set or imposed by the into consideration any particular sanction which the guardian may have attached to his command. The case of club rules, referred to by Austin, also deserves con- sideration, A man who joins a social club brings himself within the operation of its rules, including the rule as to payment of subscrip- tion. He may be sued for the subscription. If he violates the general rules, he may be expelled from the club. His expulsion, if carried out in a proper and formal manner, will be upheld by the courts. According to the constitution of most clubs, a member is bound by new rules which have been passed by the majority in ■ opposition to his wishes. He may be compelled to observe these new rules under penalty of expulsion. On a superficial view, the club may seem to be a number of private persons who set positive laws in pursuance of a legal right. Bules of conduct are imposed, and somewhere or other behind them is the force of the State. On a second view of the matter, however, I think it will be clear that the court does not enforce club rules as such, but only as being the terms of a contract. "The plaintiflF," said Vice-Chancellor Bacon, in a leading case on club law, "has made the law for himself, in this case, by becoming a member, and thereby sub- mitting to the rules, and he must be bound by it. . . . The case is governed by a written agreement to which the plaintiff has given his assent, and I base my decision on the clear-writtea contract between the parties." ^ Where the constitution of a club does not provide for the revision of the rules, a new rule requires the assent of all the members.^ Apart from the objection just considered, that many general commands, though enforced by the State, merely bring some existing law into operation, difficulties of another kind arise in connection with the distinction between legislative and executive functions. As Professor Gray remarks, if jurisprudence, defined as the science of the commands of the sovereign, is to be extended to include judge-made law, it ought to be extended to in- clude colonel-made and postmaster-made law. Jurisprudence, he urges, should include those commands of the sovereign, the main object of which is to define and enforce rights, as opposed to furnishing machinery for other ends, e.g. building of roads, distri- bution of letters, and the maintenance of army discipline.* The difficulty which exists with regard to such cases is discussed ^ Lyttelton v. Blackburne, 45 L. J. Ch. 223. ' DoAiMns V. Antrobus, 17 Ch. D. 620. ' " Harvard Law Review," April, 1892, p. 25. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 49 general opinion of persons who are members of a profession or calling : others, by that of persons who inhabit a town or province : others, by that of a nation or independent political society : others, by that of a larger society formed of various nations. 154. A few species of the laws which are set by general opinion have received appropriate names. — For example. There are laws or rules imposed upon gentlemen by opinions current amongst gentlemen. And these are usually styled the rules of honour, or the laws or law of honour. — There are by Mr. Etederic Harrison. As this learned ciitic lemaiks, it is necessary to distinguish, the sanctions of administrative and executive discipline from the sanctions of the law courts. " He [Austin] should have pointed out the difference between the rules enforced by the courts, which are laws, and rules enforced by executive powers, which are regulations with which the lawyer has nothing to do." i The difficulty is more easy to illustrate than surmount. Some writers appear to assume that generality is a sufficient test of the distinction between legislative and adminis- trative action. Thus Hearn remarks that the order of a general to his soldiers is not a law, because not framed "with intent to establish a rule of conduct." ^ Obviously, such an order might be designed expressly to establish a rule of conduct. By whatever precise test we distinguish such rules, the im- portant fact is that they must be distinguished. Positive Law as the subject-matter of Jurisprudence ought not to be held to include any of the following classes : — (a) The particular commands of political superiors. (6) The general commands of private individuals which merely bring some existing law into operation. (c) The general commands of executive discipline, with the enforcement of which the courts are not directly con cerned. Differences of opinion are certain to arise with respect to the precise definition of each of these classes. It is probably sufficient for the student of Jurisprudence to recognize their general character, and to remember that they do not properly come within the sphere of his science.^ * " Fortn^htly Review," pp. 24, 689. ' " Legal Duties and Rights," p. 9. s Cf. infra note on § 289. •^0 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS laws or rules imposed upon people of fashion by opinions current in the fashionable world. And these are usually ' styled the law set hy fashion. — There are laws which regardl the conduct of independent political societies in their vari-l ous relations to one another: Or, rather, there are laws which regard the conduct of sovereigns or supreme govern-, ments in their various relations to one another. And laws or rules of this species, which are imposed upon nations orl sovereigns by opinions current amongst nations, are usually | styled 'i/nfe.fl^ftnnnnl Inni!^. < A law set 155. Now a law set or imposed by general opinion is a by general jg^^ improperly so called. It is styled a law or rule by an opinion, is . merely tii n analogical extension of the ter m. When we speak of a law opinion ggt; ^y general opinion, we denote, by that expression, the terminate following fact. — Some intermediate body or uncertain aggre-.j body of gate of persons regards a kind of conduct with a sentime nt' regard to" °^ aversion or liking. In consequence of that sentiment or kind of opinion, it is likely that they or some of them will be dis- con no . pigage(j yiHii a party who shall pursue or not pursue conduct of that kind. And, in consequence of that displeasure, it is likely that some party (what party being undetermined) wHl visit the party provoking it with some evil or another. 156. The body by whose opinion the law is said to be set, does not command, expressly or tacitly, that conduct of the given kind shall be forborne or pursued. For, since it^is not a body precisely determined or certain, it cannot, as a body, express or intimate a wish. As a body, it cannot signify a wish by oral or written words, or by positive or negative deportment. The so-called law or rule which its opinion is said to impose, is merely the sentiment which it feels, or the opinion which it holds, in regard to a kind of conduct. 157. A determinate member of the body, who opines or feels with the body, may doubtless be moved or impelled, by that very opinion or sentiment, to command that conduct of I THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS the kind shall be forborne or pursued. But the command expressed or intimated by that determinate party is not a law or rule imposed by general opinion. It is a law pro- perly so called, set by a determinate author. — For example, JThe so-called law of nations consists of opinions or senti- ments current among nations generally. It therefore is nol| law properly so called. But one supreme government may doubtless command another to forbear from a kind of con- duct which the law of nations condemns. And, though it is fashioned on law which is law improperly so called, this conmiand is a law in the proper signification of the term Speaking precisely, the command is a rule of positive morality set by a determinate author. For, as no supreme government is in a state of subjection to another, the govern- ment commanding does not command in its character of political superior. /If t he government receiving the com- mand were in a state of subjection to the other, the com- mand, though fashioned on the law of nations, would amount to a positive law.* /'. 157. International Law. The propriety of clescribing Inter- national Law as morality has been severely criticized by many ■writers.^ Austin, in view of his recognition of a fundamental distinction between a definitely organized society with determinate organs for making and enforcing law, and a society which lacks such organs, naturally held Positive Law and International Law to belong to different categories. To do justice to his position we must remember that he denies neither the analogy between Inter- national and Positive Law nor the existence and practical efficiency of international penalties. Professor Westlake, on the other hand, holds that we ought not to make the classification of law depend on a verbal definition aa if it were an exact science, but should follow the practice approved Science of International Law," pp, Droit," 217-19 ; " L'Esprit du Droit remain," t.~I, § 11 ; Holland, "Jurisprudence," 9th ed., p. 125 : Willoughby, "Nature of the State," pp. 19&-200. 52 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 158. The foregoing description of a law set by general opinion imports the following consequences : — that the party who will enforce it against any future transgressor is never determinate and assignable. The party who actually en- in natural history, where the classifications are founded on likeness I to types. The leading idea which determines the use of the English word law, he contends, is enforcement through action, regular or irregular, of a society. Kules of International Law he regards as rules approvedJbY the general op inipn of an inter- national society, not as expressing conduct to he recommended without heing enforced, like telling the truth or being charitable, but as expressing conduct to be enforced bv aucli means as exist . States do not act upon the rules as freely choosing to do so in each instance, but obey them from a ggiguasion that the rules are law. This mental attitude towards theruTes is considered by the learned author a sufficient justification for calling them law.i f If one may venture to hold an opinion where the prophets differ, I should incline to agree with the conclusion, if not with all the arguments, of Professor Westlake. As a matter of fact, the term International Law is at present too generally adopted to admit of questioning its propriety. But apart from this, the I severest accusation that can be urged against the term is simply Jthat it is a trifle previou s. Just as in the history of particular so'cieties there are periods when the differentiation between law and morality is in the process of becoming rather than actually realized — periods when a something which is to become positive law is being sldwly differentiated from positive morality — so in relation to the society of nations to-day there is a body of rules in which a distinction is being established and developed between rules which must be obeyed, if nertaiTi penalties are not in h n incurred , and rules which are merely the expression of inter- national comity and goodwill. Kul«s of the former class, by virtue both of the popular conception of their obligatory character, and of the type of organisation implied in their formulation and inter- pretation, are more nearly allied to positive law than, to positive niorality,and are therefore less inaccurately described as International Law than as International Morality. They are law in becoming- law struggling for existence, struggling to make itself good in con- tradistinction from International Morality, and, Hke the customary law of undeveloped societies, entitled to be called law in virtue of 1 " International Law," I. pp. 6-7. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 53 forces it against an actual transgressor is of necessity cer- tain. But that certain party is not the executor of a command proceeding from the uncertain body. He has not been authorized by that uncertain body to enforce that so- called law which its opinion is said to establish. He is not in the position of a minister of justice appointed by the sovereign or state to execute commands which it issues. He harms the actual offender against the so-called law or (tu speak in analogical language) he applies the sanction annexed to it, of his own spontaneous movement. Consequently, though a party who actually enforces it is, of necessity, certain, the party who will enforce it against any future offender is never determinate and assignable. 159. It follows from the foregoing reasons, that a so- A brief called law set by general opinion is not a law in the proper s^^™'"* signification of the term. It also follows from the sameianalogy I reasons, that if-, ia nnh a,rmfid wi't.b a. Ra.np.hinn and does notJj'^*^*"'' » T , ■ , 1 . . ■ 1. , 1 • \l*w proper impose a duty, m the proper acceptation of the expressions.|an,i a law Por a sanction, properly an called , is an evil annexed to a set by command. And duty properly so called is an obnoxious- ^^0™^ ness to evils of the kind. But a so-called law set by general opinion is closely analogous to a law in the proper significa- tion of the term. And, by consequence, the so-called sanc- tion with which the former is armed, and the so-called duty which the former imposes, are closely analogous to a sanction and a duty in the proper acceptation of the expressions.* 160. The analogy between a law in the proper signi- their likeness to law strictly so called — the Positive Law, which is the subject-matter of Jurisprudence. The conditions under which municipal courts will enforce rules of International Law are considered in Excursus C. In the present note, I have discussed the status of International rule apart from such enforcement. 159. That obedience to laws set by opinion is encouraged by rewards as well as by penalties is a further and important difference between this class and laws strictly so called. Sidgwick, 54 THE DIFFERENT KIA'DW OF LAWS fication of the term and a so-called law set by general opinion, may be stated briefly in the following manner.— 1., In the case of a law properly so called, the determinate individual or body by whom the law is established wishes that conduct of a kind shall be forborne or pursued. In the case of a law imposed by general opinion, a wish that conduct of a kind shall be forborne or pursued is felt by the uncertain body whose general opinion imposes it. 2. If a party obliged by the law proper shall not comply with the wish of the determinate individual or body, he probably will suffer, in consequence of his not complying, the evil or inconvenience annexed to the law as a sanction. If a party obnoxious to their displeasure shall not comply with the wish of the uncertain body of persons, he probably will suffer, in consequence of his not complying, some evil or inconvenience from some party or another. 3. By the sanction annexed to the law proper, the parties obliged are inclined to act or forbear agreeably to its injunctions or prohibitions. By the evil which probably will follow the displeasure of the uncertain body, the parties obnoxious are inclined to act or forbear agreeably to the sentiment or opinion which is styled analogically a law. 4. In conse- quence of the law properly so called, the conduct of the parties obliged has a steadiness, constancy, or uniformity, which, without the existence of the law, their conduct in discussing the relations of the two classes, remarks : "Positive Law and Positive Morality may be distinguished by their respective sanctions. But they also differ importantly, regarded merely as intelligible systems ; since in the former case doubts as to what is law may be authoritatively removed by judicial interpretation, and divergences between what is and what oughi to be law may be removed by legislation. But with morality it is otherwise ; hence there is much greater conflict, vagueness, and uncertainty in the established moral code than in the established law.''^ ' Elements of Politics," Ist ed., pp. 191- THE DIFFERENT KllSUS OF LAWS 55 would probably want. In consequence of the sentiment or opinion which is styled analogically a law, the conduct of the parties obnoxious has a steadiness, constancy, or uni- formity, which, without the existence of that sentiment in the uncertain body of persons, their conduct would hardly present.* "^ 161. In the foregoing analysis of a law set by general Distinc- opinion, the meaning of the expression ' indeterminate body . "j of persons ' is indicated rather than explained. To complete terminate, my analysis of a law set by general opinion, I will here insert *"^ ^^ a concise exposition of the following pregnant distinction : namely, the distinction between a determinate and an in- determinate body of single or individual persons. 162. I will first describe the distinction in general or abstract terms, and will then exemplify and illustrate the general or abstract description. 163. If a body of persons be determinatej all the persons who compose it are determined and assignable. 164. But determinate bodies are of two kinds. Either, 1. The body is composed of persons determined specifically or individually. Or, 2. It is composed of all the persons , who belong to a given class, or who belong respectively to two or more of such classes. 165. If a body be indeterminate, all the persons who com- pose it are not determined and assignable. Or (changing the expression) every person who belongs to 'it is not de- termined, and, therefore, cannot be indicated. — For an indeterminate body consists of some of the persons who belong to another and larger aggregate. But how many of those persons are members of the indeterminate body, or 160. Q. Admitting that in the expression laws of honour, the term law is used analogically, are we also compelled to admit that in the expression rules of honour the term rule is used analogically 1 66 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS which of those persons in particular are members of the indeterminate body, is not and cannot be known completely and exactly. 166. For example, the trading firm or partnership of A B and C is a determinate body of the kind first described above. Every member of the firm is determined specifically, or by a character or description peculiar or appropriate to himself. And every member of the firm belongs to the determinate body, not by reason of his answering to any generic description, but by reason of his bearing his specific or appropriate character. It is as being that very individual person that A B or C is a limb of the partnership. 167. The British Parliament for the time being, is a de- terminate body of the second kind above "described. It comprises the only person who answers for the time being to the generic description of king. It comprises every person belonging to the class of peers who are entitled for the time being to vote in the upper house. It comprises every person belonging to the class of commoners who for the time being represent the commons in parliament. And, though every member of the British Parliament is of necessity determined by a specific or appropriate character he is not a member of the parliament by reason of his bearing that character, but by reason of his answering to the given generic description. It is not as being the individual George, but as being the individual who answers to the generic description of king, that George is king of Britain and Ireland, and a limb of the determinate body which is sovereign or supreme therein. It is not as being the individual Grey, or as being the individual Peel, that Grey is a member of the upper house, or Peel a member of the lower. Grey is a member of the upper house, as belonging to the class of peers entitled to vote therein. Peel is a member of the lower house, as answer- THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 57 ing the generic description ' representative of the commons in parliament.' 168. To exemplify the foregoing description of an inde- terminate body, I will revert to the nature of a law set by general opinion. Where a so-called law is set by general opinion, most of the persons who belong to a determinate body or class opine or feel alike in regard to a kind of conduct. But the number of that majority, or the several individuals who compose it, cannot be fixed or assigned with perfect fulness or accuracy. For example, A law set or imposed by the general opinion of a nation, by the general opinion of a legislative assembly, by the general opinion of a profession, or by the general opinion of a club, is an opinion or sentiment, relating to conduct of a kind, which is held or felt by most of those who belong to that certain body. But how many of that body, or which of that body in particular, hold or feel that given opinion or senti- ment, is not and cannot be known completely and correctly. Consequently, that majority of the certain body forms a body uncertain. Or (changing the expression) the body which is formed by that majority is an indeterminate portion of a determinate body or aggregate. -HGenerally speaking, there- fore, an indeternainate body is an indeterminate portion of a body determinate or certain.) But a body or class of persons may also be indeterminate, because it consists of persons of a vague generic character. For example. The body or class of gentlemen consists of individual persons whose generic character of gentleman cannot be described precisely. Whether a given man were a genuine gentleman or not, is a question which different men might answer in different ways. — An indeterminate body may therefore be indetermi- nate after a twofold manner, v It may consist of an uncertain portion of an uncertain body or class.] 169. (a determinate body of persons is capable of corporate 58 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS conduct)| Whether it consist of persons determined hy specific characters, or of persons determined or defined by a character or characters generic, every person who belongs to it is determined and may be indicated. In the first case, every person who belongs to it may be indicated by his specific character. In the second case, every person who belongs to it is also knowable : For every person who answers to the given generic description, or who answers to any of the given generic descriptions, is therefore a member of the body. Consequently, the entire body, or any proportion of its members, is capable, as a body, of positive or negative conduct : As, for example, of meeting at determinate times and places ; of issuing expressly or tacitly a law or other command ; of choosing and deputing representatives to per- form its intentions or wishes; of receiving obedience from others, or from any of its own members. 170. An indeterminate body is incapable of corporate con- duct, inasmuch as the several persons of whom it consists cannot be known and indicated completely and correctly. In case a portion of its members act or forbear in concert, that given portion of its members is, by that very concert, a determinate or certain body. Tor example, A law set or imposed by the general opinion of barristers condemns the sordid practice of hugging or caressing attorneys. And'as those whose opinion or sentiment sets the so-called law are an indeterminate part of the determinate body of barristers, they form a body uncertain and incapable of corporate con- duct. But in case a number or portion of that uncertain body assembled and passed a resolution to check the prac- tice of hugging, that number or portion of that uncertain body would be, by the very act, a certain body or aggre- gate. It would form a determinate body consisting of the determined individuals who assembled and passed the reso- lution. — A law imposed by general opinion may be the cause THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 59 of a law in the proper acceptation of the term. But the law properly so called, which is the consequent or effect, utterly differs from the so-called law which is the ante- cedent or cause. The one is an opinion or sentiment of an uncertain body of persons ; of a body essentially incapable of joint or corporate conduct. The other is set or established by the positive or negative deportment of a certain indi- vidual or aggregate. 171. For the purpose of rendering my exposition as little intricate as possible, I have supposed(that a body of persons, forming a body determinate, either consists of persons deter- mined by specific characters, or of persons determined or defined by a generic description or descriptions j— But a body of persons, forming a body determinate, may consist of persons determined by specific or appropriate characters, and also of persons determined by a character or characters generic. Let us suppose, for example, that the individual Oliver Cromwell was sovereign or supreme in England : or that the individual Cromwell, and the individuals Ireton and Fleetwood, formed a triumvirate which was sovereign in that country. Let us suppose, moreover, that Cromwell or the triumvirs convened a. House of Commons elected in the ancient manner : and that Cromwell, or the triumvirs yielded a part in the sovereignty to this representative body. Now the sovereign or supreme body formed by Cromwell and the house, or the sovereign and supreme body formed by the triumvirs and the house, would have con- sisted of a person or persons determined or defined specifi- cally, and of persons determined or defined by a generic character or description. A body of persons, forming a body determinate, may also consist of persons determined or defined specifically,^hd determined or defined moreover by a character or characters generic. / A select committee of a body representing a people or nation, consists of individual 60 THE DIFFEBENT KINDS OF LAWS persons named or appointed specifically to sit on that given ' committee. But those specific individuals could not be members of the committee, unless they answered the generic description ' representative of the people or nation.' 172. It follows from the exposition immediately preced- "ing'that the one or the number which is sovereign in an independent political society is a determinate individual person or a determinate body of persons^ If the sovereign one or number were not determinate or certain, it could not command expressly or tacitly, and could not be an object of obedience to the subject members of the community.- 173. As closely connected with the matter of the exposi- tion immediately preceding, the following remark concern- ing supreme government may be put coihmodiously in the present place.— ^In order that a supreme government may possess much stability, and that the society wherein it is supreme may enjoy much tranquillity, the persons who take the sovereignty in the way of succession, must take or acquire by a given generic mode, or by given generic modesi Or (changing the expression) they must take by reason of their answering to a given generic description, or by reason of their respectively answering to given generic descrip- tions. — For example, the Eoman Emperors or Princes did not succeed to the sovereignty of the Eoman Empire or World by a given generic title: by a mode of acquisition given or preordained, and susceptible of generic description. It was neither as lineal descendant of Julius Caesar or Augustus, nor by the testament or other disposition of the last possessor of the throne, nor by the appointment or nomination of the Eoman people or senate, nor by the elec- tion of a determinate body formed of the military class, nor by any mode of acquisition generic and preordained, that every successive Emperor, or every successive Prince, ac- quired the virtual sovereignty of the Eoman Empire or THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 61 World Every successive Emperor acquired by a mode of acquisition which was purely anomalous or accidental : which nad not been predetermined by any law or custom, or by any positive law or rule of positive morality. Every actual Occupant of the Imperial office or dignity (whatever may have been the manner wherein he had gotten possession) was obeyed, for the time, by the bulk of the military class ; was acknowledged, of course, by the impotent and trembling senate ; and received submission, of course, from the inert and helpless mass which inhabited the city and provinces. By reason of this irregularity in the succession to the virtual sovereignty, the demise of an Emperor was not uncommonly followed by a shorter or longer dissolution of the general supreme government. Since no one could claim to succeed by a given generic title, or as answering for the time being to a given generic description, a contest for the prostrate sovereignty almost inevitably arose between the more influ- ential of the actual military chiefs^ 173. Q. Discuss the propriety of the expression, imperative, and therefore proceeding from a determinate source. Examine the following criticism : " To Austin the statement that a body uncertain as to number cannot act as a body, and cannot, there- fore, issue commands, seems so self-evident as to need no further argument. To one surrounded with institutions of a ' popular ' character, and accustomed, almost every day, to see goyernment affected and controlled by various agencies of clamour, mass meet- ing, petition, and newspaper writing, this inability of a body numerically uncertain to express itself, as a body, in ways having the force of command, will, I think, seem less axiomatic." ^ Note. — The author from whom the criticism in the above question is quoted, while objecting to Austin's theory of sover- eignty as inhering in a specific number of individuals, admits that Austin is quite right in laying emphasis upon the idea of determinateness, since the idea suggests the existence of definite organs. "Except as sovereignty secures for itself definite and ' Professor Dewey, "Political Science Quarterly," March, 1894, pp. 37-8. 62 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS Laws set l74. Before I close my analysis of those laws improperly hj general ^^ galled which are closely analogous to laws in the proper opinion, . . . the only acceptation of the term, I must advert to a seeming caprice opinions ^f current language. A law set or imposed by general or senti- ' a o ^ j ■ j , mentsthat opinion, is an opmion or sentiment,\ regarding conduct of a have got- kind, which is held or felt by an indeterminate body : that ie name of ^^ ^^7' ^^ indeterminate portion of a certain or uncertain laws. aggregate. Now a like opinion or sentiment held or felt by an individual, or held or felt universally by the members of a body determinate, may be as closdy analogous to a law proper as a so-called law set by general opinion. It may bear an analogy to a law in the proper acceptation of the term, exactly or nearly resembling the analogy to a law proper which is borne by an opinion or sentiment of an indeterminMe body. An opinion, for example, of a patron, in regard to conduct of a kind, may be a law or rule to his own dependant or dependants, just as a like opinion of an in- determinate body is a law or rule to all who might sufifer by provoking its displeasure. And whether a like opinion be held by an uncertain aggregate, or be held by every member of a precisely determined body, its analogy to a law proper is exactly or nearly the same. 175. Deferring to this seeming caprice of current or es- tablished language, I have forborne from ranking sentiments of precisely determined parties with the laws improperly so definable modes of expiession, sovereignty is unrealized and I inchoate." 1 The remark rer.alla Thp^inp's definition of the Rtata ag I the re gulated and assured exercise of social compulsio n. It , I suggests, moreover, the possibility of distinguishing beiween legal and moral rules by reference to a difference in the ^£giee_af organization which may exist for the purposes of their expression, interpretation, and enforcement. The whole question is involved with certain theories of sovereignty which I discuss in Ex- cursus A and B. ' Ibid., pp. 51-2. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 63 called which are closely analogous to the proper. Yet with a few slight and obvious changes, my analysis of a law set by general opinion will serve as an analysis of a law set by any opinion. For between the opinion or sentiment of the v_^ indeterminate body, and the opinion or sentiment of the / precisely determined party, there is merely the following | difference. — The precisely determined party is capable of issuing a command in pursuance of the opinion or sentiment. But the uncertain body is' not. For, being essentially in- capable of joint or corporate conduct, it cannot, as a body, signify a wish or desire, and cannot, as a body, hold an intention or purpose.* 176. It appears from the expositions in the preceding The fore- portion of my discourse, that laws properly so called, with f^'^^^.*^ such improper laws as are closely analogous to the proper, of laws are of three capital classes. — 1. The law of God. 2. Positive ^^^7 law. 3. Positive morality. lated. 177. It also appears from the same expositions, that posi- tive mOTal rules are of two species. — 1. Those positive moral rules which are express or tacit commands, and which are therefore laws in the proper acceptation of the term. 2. Those laws improperly so called (but closely analogous to laws in the proper acceptation of the term) which are set by general opinion, or are set by opinion: which are set by opinions of uncertain bodies; or by opinions of uncertain bodies, and opinions of determinate parties. 175. Q. (1) What is the precise character of the relation between " the opinions of precisely determined parties " and " the implied commands of a determinate superior " f (2) Apply Austin's test of the distinction between determinate and indeterminate bodies to the following : — (a) The colliers of Wales. (b) The lunatics of the United Kingdom. (c) Nonconformists. (d) Non-Freemasons. 64 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS The 178. The sanctions annexed to the laws of God, may be oorreB- styled religious. — The sanctions annexed to positive laws, sanctions, may be styled, emphatically, legal: for the laws to which duties and ^.j^gy. ^j,g annexed, are styled, simply and emphatically, laws or Idw. Or, as every positive law supposes a TroXty or civitas, or supposes a society political and independent, the epithet political may be applied to the sanctions by which such laws are enforced. — Of the sanctions which enforce compliance with positive moral rules, some are sanctions properly so called, and others are styled sanctions by an analogical ex- tension of the term: that is to say, some are annexed to rules which are laws imperative and proper, and others en- force the rule which are laws set by opinion. Since rules of either species may be styled positive morality, the sanctions which enforce compliance with rules of either species may be styled moral sanctions. Or (changing the expression) we may say of rules of either species, that they are sanctioned or enforced morally. 179. The duties imposed by the laws of God may be styled religious. — The duties imposed by positive laws, may be styled, emphatically, legal. — Of the duties imposed by positive moral rules, some are duties properly so called, and others are styled duties by an analogical extension of the term : that is to say, some are creatures of rules which are laws imperative and proper, and others are creatures of the rules which are laws set by opinion. Like the sanctions proper and improper by which they are respectively en- forced, these duties proper and improper may be styled TnoraV 180. Every right supposes a duty incumbent on a party or parties other thah the party entitled. Through the im- 179. Q. X has committed a theft. Is he under a legal duty (a) to surrender to justice ? {h) to submit to the punishment which the judge imposes 1 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 65 position of that corresponding duty, the right was conferred. Through the continuance of that correspondii^ duty, the right continues to exist. If that corresponding duty be the creature of a law imperative, the right is a right properly so called. If that corresponding duty be the creature of a law improper, the right is styled a right by an analogical ex- » tension of the term. Eights conferred by the law of God, or rights existing through duties imposed by the law of God, may be styled IHvine. — Eights conferred by positive law, or rights existing through duties imposed by positive law, may be styled, emphatically, legal. Or it may be said of r^hts conferred by positive law, that they are sanctioned or pro- tected legally. — The rights proper and improper which are conferred by positive morality, may be styled moral. Or it may be said of rights conferred by positive morality, that they are sanctioned or protected morally.' 181. The body of laws which may be styled the law of The coin- God, the body of laws which may be styled positive law, ""^^"^ and the body of laws which may be styled positive morality, flict of sometimes coincide, sometimes do not coincide, and some- ^*''*- times conflict. 182. One of these bodies of laws coincides with another, when acts, which are enjoined or forbidden by the former, are also enjoined, or are also forbidden by the latter. For example. The killing which is styled murder is forbidden by the positive law of every political society; it is also forbidden \(j a so-called law which the general opinion of the society has set or imposed ; it is also forbidden by the law of God as known through the principle of utility. 183. One of these bodies of laws does rwt coincide with 180. Austin defines a legal right as follows: "A party has a right, when another or others are bound or obliged by the law, to do or to forbear towards or in regard of him." * "Jurisprudence," I, p. 393. 66 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS another, when acts, which are enjoined or forbidden by the former, are not enjoined, or are not forbidden by the latter. For example, Though smuggling is forbidden by positive law, and (speaking generally) is not less pernicious than theft, it is not forbidden by the opinions or sentiments of the ignorant or unreflecting. Where the impost or tai is itself of pernicious tendency, smuggling is hardly forbidden by the opinions or sentiments of any : And it is therefore practised by any without the slightest shame, or without the slightest fear of incurring general censure. Such, for instance, is the case where the impost or tax is laid upon the foreign commodity, not for the useful purpose of raising a public revenue, but for the absurd and mischievous purpose of protecting a domestic manufacture. Offences against the game laws are also in point : for they are not offences against positive morality, although they are forbidden by positive law. A gentleman is not dishonoured, or generally shunned by gentlemen, though he shoots without a qualifi- cation. A peasant who wires hares escapes the censure of peasants, though the squires, as doing justiceship, send him to the prison and the tread-mill. 184. One of these bodies of laws conflicts vnth another, when acts, which are enjoined or forbidden by the former, are forbidden or enjoined by the latter. For example. In most of the nations of modern Europe, the practice ol duelling is forbidden by positive law. It is also at variance with the law which is received in most of those nations as having been set by the Deity in the way of express revelation. But in spite of positive law, and in spite of his religious convictions, a man of the class of gentlemen may be forced by the law of honour to give or to take a challenge. If he forbore from giving, or if he declined a challenge, he might incur the general contempt of gentlemen or men of honour, and might meet with slights and insults sufficient j THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 67 to embitter his existence. The negative legal duty which certainly is inciunbent upon him, and the negative religious duty to which he believes himself subject, are therefore mastered and controlled by that positive moral duty which arises from the so-called law set by the opinion of his class. 185. The simple and obvious considerations to which I have now adverted, are often overlooked by legislators. If they fancy a practice pernicious, or hate it they know not why, they proceed, without further thought, to forbid it by positive law. They forget that positive law may be superfluous or impotent, and therefore may lead to nothing but purely gra- tuitous vexation. They forget that the moral or the religious sentiments of the community may already suppress the prac tice as completely as it can be suppressed; or that, if the practice is favoured by those moral or religious sentiments, the strongest possible fear which legal pains can inspire may be mastered by a stronger fear of other and conflicting sanctions.* 185. Q. Is the phrase "frequent coincidence of positive law and positive morality " consistent with Austin's definition of law-i by analogy as rules set and enforced by mere opinion f ^ Note. — CotTicidenee and conflict of laws. — Austin's account of the coincidence and conflict of laws suggests the following diagram of three circles representing respectively the Law of God, Positive law, and Positive MoraUty : — \PosHive Law Law of God /Positive Vorality Rules which come under classes a, c, and g are readily » Cf. §§ 6, 111, 163, 182, 187. 68 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 186. In consequence of the frequent coincidence of positive Jaw and morality, and of positive law and the law of God, the true nature and fountain of positive law is often absurdly mistaken by writers upon jurisprudence. Where positive suggested. Thus " Be ye perfect " illustrates class a. It is a Law of God which is neither a Positive Law nor a rule of Positive Morahty. An Act of Parliament popularly regarded as immoral would illustrate class c. The rule that a man must avenge an insult may be quoted as an example of g. When, however, we attempt to give examples of rules coming under the re- maining classes, we are confronted by a difficulty of which the existence is suggested in the question preceding the present note. If a law by analogy be defined as a law set and enforced by mere opinion, then a rule of conduct which, in addition to being enforced by popular sentiment, is also enforced by the State, might seem to be taken ipso facto out of the sphere of Positive Morality. This however is not Austin's meaning. Eeflection upon the fact serves to emphasize his general point of view of laws as rules set by superiors to inferiors. Homicide, in so far as it is prohibited by popular sentiment, is prohibited by a rule set by mere opinion and accordingly by a rule of positive morality. The rule is quite distinct from the corresponding Positive Law, if not as to scope, at least as to source and sanction. Strictly speaking, the phrase coincidence of Positive Morality and Law is not a happy one, since the coincidence is less one of rules than of the acts and for- bearances which rules are designed to regulate. If, however, we regard the above diagram as referring to acts or forbearances, we have to face another difficulty. The act of killing a man from trifling motives may be quoted as illus- trating class e, since it is an ait condemned by all three systems. But let us suppose that Parliament passes a Bill imposing a tax on bachelors, which is to be paid annually. Would a refusal to pay this tax be at once a violation of the Law of God and of Positive Lawl If we answer this question in the negative we seem to overlook the fact that divine law ordains loyalty to the State and to the law of the State in all things " lawful" If we answer in the affirmative we make nearly all disobedience to Positive Law disobedience to divine law. Popular usage limits the conception of an act in conflict with the Law of God to acts which immediately contravene, either a special divine precept, or one of the fundamental rules of morality. A similar reflection is suggested in considering the relation of Positive Law to Positive Morality. We speak of an act as being in contravention of Positive Morality when it directly and immediately contravenes THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 69 law has been fashioned on positive morality, or where positive law has been fashioned on the law of God, they forget that the copy is the creature of the sovereign, and impute it to the author of the model. 187. For example: Customary laws are positive laws fashioned by judicial legislation upon pre-existing customs. Now, till they become the grounds of judicial decisions upon cases, and are clothed with legal sanctions by the sovereign one or number, the customs are merely rules set by opinions of the governed, and sanctioned or enforced morally : Though, when they become the reasons of judicial decisions upon cases, and are clothed with legal sanctions by the sovereign one or number, the customs are rules of positive law as well as of positive morality. But, because the customs were observed by. the governed before they were clothed with sanctions by the sovereign one or number, it is fancied that customary laws exist as positive laws by the institution of the private persons with whom the customs originated. some popularly accepted principle of conduct. If, in the case just suggested, a bachelor refuses to pay his tax, we do not think of his act as being contrary to Positive Morality, save in so far as we con- sciously refer to the generally accepted rule that a citizen should abide by the laws, and so regard the act as a sort of rebellion. The above considerations must be borne in mind if we are to make any use of the suggested diagram. If we regard the several circles as referring to rules, not to acts, we must remember that rule in such a case is considered in detachment from the source from which it draws its authority, and the sanction by which it is enforced. "Thou shalt not steal," from this point of view, may be regarded as at once a Law of God, a Positive Law, and a rule of Positive MoraUty. If, on the other hand, we regard the circles as referring to acts, not to rules, we must remember that an act is not in contravention of a system of rules unless it is directly and immediately prohibited by that system. Q. Illustrate each of the classes in the above diagram, regard- ing the circles as referring (a) to rules, (b) to acts and forbearances. 70 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 188. Again: The portion of positive law which is parcel of the law of nature (or, in the language of the classical jurists, which is parcel of the jus gentium) is often supposed to emanate, even as positive law, from a Divine or Natural source. But (admitting the distinction of positive law into law natural and law positive) it is manifest that law natural, considered as a portion of positive, is the creature of human sovereigns, and not of the Divine monarch. To say that it emanates, as positive law, from a Divine or Natural source, is to confound positive law with law whereon it is fashioned, or with law whereunto it conforms.* 188. The Law of Nature. — The term Law of Nature is used in several distinct senses, of which the following are the moat important : — (1) The whole code of moiH duty as determined by Eeason as distinct from Revelation. (2) The ideal totality of the rules of conduct thought fit for political enforcement. (3) The statement of the sequences of natural or social pheno- mena. In this sense the term law could only be applied, accord- ing to Austin, by metaphor. Moreover, it is used concretely to indicate a particular instance, not a class. To indicate the class, the plural must be employed. So it has been remarked of yavigny that he substituted natural laws for Natural Law. The subject will receive further consideration in discussing laws by metaphor. Austin's remark on the relation of the Law of Nature to Positive Law may seem obvious. That it was not always so may be illustrated by the following dictum from the argument in Calvin's case : " The legeance or faith of the subject is due to the king by the law of nature, which is part of the law of England; existed before any judicial or municipal law, and is immutable." 1 "The mediaeval notion of sovereignty," writes Dr. Gierke, "always differed from that exalted notion which prevailed in after times. For one thing, there was unanimous agreement that the Sovereign Power, though raised above all Positive, is limited by Natural Law." ^ ' Broom, " Constitutional Law," p. 17. ' Gierke, " Political Theories of fixe Middle Age," p. 95. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 71 189. I may here note a prevailing tendency to confound what is with what ought to be law or morality, that is, 1st, to confound positive law with the science of legislation, and positive morality with deontology; and 2ndly, to con- found positive law with positive morality, and both with legislation and deontology.* 190. The existence of law is one thing ; its merit or 1st. Ten- demerit is another. Whether it be or be not is one inquiry ; '^*°?^ *°, ^ •' ' confound whether it be or be not conformable to an assumed standard, positive is a different inquiry. This truth, when formally announced ^*^ '?*'' the science as an abstract proposition, is so simple and glaring that it of legisla- seems idle to insist upon it. But simple and glaring as *^<"^ f"** it is, when enunciated in abstract expressions, the enumera- morality tion of the instances in which it has been forgotten would ^'t^ "• fill a volume. ° °^' 191. Sir William Blackstone, for example, says in his " Commentaries," that the laws of God are superior in obli- gation to all other laws; that no human laws should be Buffered to contradict them ; that human laws are of no validity if contrary to them ; and that all valid laws derive their force from that Divine original. 192. Now, he may mean that all human laws ought to conform to the Divine laws. If this be his meaning, I 189. §§ 189-204 were incorporated by Mr. Bobert Campbell in his edition of Austin's work, and appended at the end of the present lecture.^ They are taken from certain notes made by John Stuart Mill of Austin's lectures as originally delivered. Mr. Campbell remarks : " I think it of some value to preserve this passage, both as calculated to aid the student in applying the principles stated in the text, and also as illustrative of the author's mode, when orally amplifying in presence of his class the lecture which in substance he always had committed to writing." I have ventured to include the passages in the body of the lecture instead of at the end, as they are closely connected with the subject- matter of §§ 178-188. ' I., 214-19. 72 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS assent to it without hesitation. The evils which we are exposed to suffer from the hands of God as a consequence of disoheying His commands are the greatest evils to which we are obnoxious; the obligations which they impose are con- sequently paramount to those imposed by any other laws, and if human commands conflict with the Divine law, we ought to disobey the command which is enforced by the less powerful sanction; this is implied in the term ought: the proposition is identical, and therefore perfectly indisputable. 193. Perhaps, agaio, he means that human lawgivers are themselves obliged by the Divine laws to fashion the laws which they impose by that ultimate standard, because if they do not, God will punish them. To this also I entirely assent : for if the index to the law of God be the principle of utility, that law embraces the whole of our voluntary actions ih so far as motives applied from without are re- quired to give them a direction conformable to the general happiness. 194. But the meaning of this passage of Blackstone, if it has a meaning, seems rather to be this : that no human law which conflicts with the Divine law is obligatory or binding; in other words, that no human law which conflicts with the Divine law is a law, for a law without an obligation is a contradiction in terms. I suppose this to be his meaning, because when we say of any transaction that it is invalid or void, we mean that it is not binding : as, for example, if it be a contract, we mean that the political law will not lend its sanction to enforce the contract, 195. Now, to say that human laws which conflict with the Divine law are not binding, that is to say, are not laws, is to talk nonsense. The most pernicious laws, and there- fore those which are most opposed to the wiU of God, have been and are continually enforced as laws by judicial tribu- nals. Suppose an act innocuous, or positively beneficial, be THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 73 prohibited by the sovereign under the penalty of death ; if I commit this act, I shall be tried and condemned, and if I object to the sentence that it is contrary to the law of God, who has comnumded that human lawgivers shall not pro- hibit acts which have no evil consequences, the Court of Justice will demonstrate the inconclusiveness of my reason- ing by hanging me up, in pursuance of the law of which I have impugned the validity. An exception, demurrer, or plea, founded on the law of God, was never heard in a Court of Justice, from the creation of the world down to the present moment. 196. But this abuse of language is not merely puerile, it is mischievous. When it is said that a law ought to be dis- obeyed, what is ineant is that we are urged to disobey it by motives more cogent and compulsory than those by which it is itself sanctioned. If the laws of God are certain, the motives which they hold out to disobey any human com- mand which is at variance with them are paramount to all others. But the laws of God are not always certain. All divines, at least all reasonable divines, admit that no scheme of duties perfectly complete and unambiguous was ever imparted to us by revelation. As an index to the Divine will, utility is obviously insufficient. What appears per- nicioi^s to one person may appear beneficial to another. And as for the moral sense, innate practical principles, conscience, they are merely convenient cloaks for ignorance or sinister interest : they mean either that I hate the law to which I object and cannot tell why, or that I hate the law, and that the cause of my hatred is one which I find it incommodious to avow. If I say openly, I hate the law, ergo, it is not binding and ought to be disobeyed, no one will listen to me : but by calling my hate my conscience or my moral sense, I urge the same argument in another and a more plausible form : I seem to assign a reason for my dis- 74 V' THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS like, when in truth I have only given it a sounding and specious name. In times of ciAol discord the mischief of this abuse of language is apparent. In quiet times the dictates of utility are fortunately so obvious that the anar- chical doctrine sleeps, and men habitually admit the validity of laws which they dislike. To prove by pertinent reasons that a law is pernicious is highly useful, because such pro- cess may lead to the abrogation of the pernicious law. To incite the public to resistance by determinate views of utility may be useful, for resistance, grounded on clear and definite prospects of good, is sometimes beneficial. But to proclaim generally that all laws which are pernicious or contrary to the will of God are void and not to be tolerated, is to preach anarchy, hostile and perilous as much to wise and benign rule as to stupid and galling tyranny. Another 197. In another passage of his "Commentaries," Blackstone examp e gjj^gjg ^^^q ^^ argument to prove that a master cannot have a right to the labour of his slave. Had he contented him- self with expressing his disapprobation, a Very well-grounded one certainly, of the institution of slavery, no objection could have been made to his so expressing himself. But to dis- pute the existence or the possibility of the right is to talk absurdly. For in every age, and in almost every nation, the right has been given by positive law, whilst that per- nicious disposition of positive law has been backed by the positive morality of the free or master classes.* 198. Grotius, PuffendorfF, and the other writers on the so-called law of nations, have fallen into a similar con- interna- fusion of ideas : they have confounded positive international tional law. 197. On the general subject of this section Sommersett'a case (1771-2) and the case of Stanley v. Harvey (1762) deserve attention.^ > Broom, "Constitutional Law,'' pp. 59, 114 ; 2 Eden, p. 126. Black- Btone. Example from the ■writers on THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 75^ morality, or the rules which actually obtain among civilized nations in their mutual intercourse, with their own vague conceptions of international morality as it ought to he, with that indeterminate something which they conceived it would be, if it conformed to that indeterminate something which they call the law of nature. Professor Von Martens, of Gottingen, is actually the first of the writers on the law of nations who has seized this distinction with a firm grasp. He distinguished the rules which ought to be received in the intercourse of nations from those which are so received, endeavoured to collect from the practice of civilized com- munities what are the rules actually recognized and acted upon by them, and gave to these rules the name of positive international law. 199. I have given several instances in which law and 2nd. Ten- morality as they ought to be are confounded with the law "^^^y *" , confound and morality which actually exist. I shall next mention positive some examples in which positive law is confounded with '** with positive morality, and both with the science of legislation morality and deontology. and both 200. Those who know the writings of the Eoman lawyers ^l^^^^l only by hearsay are accustomed to admire their philosophy, deonto- Now this, in my estimation, is the only part of their writings ^^^' which deserves contempt. Their extraordinary merit is evinced not in general speculation, but as expositors of the Eoman law. They have seized its general principles with great clearness and penetration, have applied these principles with admirable logic to the explanation of details, and have thus reduced this positive system of law to a compact and coherent whole. But the philosophy which they borrowed from the Greeks, or which, after the examples of the Greeks, they themselves fashioned, is naught. Their attempts to define jurisprudence and to determine the province of the jurisconsult are pitiable. 76 THE DIFPEBENT KINDS OF LAWS 201. At the commencement of the Digest is a passage attempting to define jurisprudence. I shall first present you with this passage in a free translation, and afterwards in the original. ' Jurisprudence,' says this definition, ' is the knowledge of things divine and human ; the science which teaches men to discern the just from the unjust.' 'Juris- prudentia est divinarum atque humanarum rerum notitia, justi atque injusti scientia.' In the excerpt from Ulpian, which is placed at the beginning of the Digest, it ia attempted to define the office or province of the jurisconsult 'Law,' says the passage, 'derives its name from justice, jmtitia, and is the science or skill in the good and the equitable. Law being the creature of justice, we the juris- consults may be considered as her priests, for justice is the goddess whom we worship, and to whose service we are devoted. Justice and equity are our vocation; we teach men to know the difference between the just and the unjiist, the lawful and the unlawful ; we strive to reclaim them from vice, not only by the terrors of punishment, but also by the blandishment of rewards ; herein, unless we flatter ourselves, aspiring to sound and real philosophy, and not like some whom we could mention, contenting ourselves with vain and empty pretension.' 'Juri operam daturum prius nosse oportet, unde nomen juris descendat. Est autem a justitia appellatum; nam, ut eleganter Celsus definit, jus est ars boni et sequi. Cujus merito quis nos sacerdotes appeUet; justitiam namque colimus, et boni et sequi notitiam profite- mur, sequum ab iniquo separantes, licitum ab iUicito dis- cernentes, bonos non solum metu pcenarum verum etiam prsemiorum quoque exhortatione efficere cupientes, veram, nisi fallor, philosophiam, non simulatam affeotantes.' 202. Were I to present you with all the criticisms which these two passages suggest, I should detain you a full hour. I shall content myself with one. Jurisprudence, if it is THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 77 anjthing, is the science of law, or at most the science of law combined with the art of applying it; but what is here given as a definition of it, embraces not only law, but positive morality, and even the test to which both these are to be referred. It therefore comprises the science of legisla- tion and deontology. Further, it affirms that law is the creature of justice, which is as much as to say that it is the child of its own offspring. For when hy just we mean anything but to express our own approbation we mean some- thing which accords with some given law. True, we speak of law and justice, or of law and equity, as opposed to each other, but when we do so, we mean to express mere dislike of the law, or to intimate that it conflicts with another law, the law of God, which is its standard. According to this, every pernicious law is unjust. But, in truth, law is itself the standard of justice." What deviates from any law is unjust with reference to that law, though it may be just with reference to another law of superior authority. The veriest dolt who is placed in a jury box, the merest old woman who happens to be raised to the bench, will talk finely of equity or justice — the justice of the case, the equity of the case, the imperious demands of justice, the plain dictates of equity. He forgets that he is there to enforce the law of the land, else he does not administer that justice or that equity with which alone he is immediately concerned.* 203. This is well known to have been a strong tendency Example of Lord Mansfield — a strange obliquity in so great a man. ^''°™ ^°^^ ° ^ •' ^ Mansfield. 202. Mr. Leslie defends Ulpian's idealism. "The greatest iaiiryer — be he judge or jurist — is he who combines a firm grasp of the material realities of life with a clear vision of the ideal .beyond." ^ < • "Journal of Comparative Legislation," XI, pp. 23-4, article on Uljpian. 78 THE iJiFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS I will give an instance. By the English law, a promise to give something or to do something for the benefit of another is not binding without what is called a considera- tion, that is, a motive assigned for the promise, which motive must be of a particular kind. Lord Mansfield, however, overruled the distinct provisions of the law by ruling that moral obligation was a sufficient consideration. ISow, moral obligation is an obligation imposed by opinion, or an obliga- tion imposed by God : that is, moral obligation is anything which we choose to call so, for the precepts of positive morality are infinitely varying, and the will of God, whether indicated by utility or by a moral sense, is equally matter of dispute. This decision of Lord Mansfield, which assumes that the judge is to enforce morality, enables the judge to enforce just whatever he pleases.* Judicial 204. I must here observe that I am not objecting to Lord legisla- Mansfield for assuming the office of a legislator. I by no means disapprove of what Mr. Bentham has chosen to call by the disrespectful name of judge-made law. I cannot understand how any person who has considered the subject can suppose that society could possibly have gone on if judges had not legislated, or that there is any danger what- ever in allowing them that power which they have in fact 203. The doctrine attributed by Austin to Lord Mansfield was upheld by Sir James Mansfield in Lee v. Muggeridge.^ l£ was definitely overruled by Lord Denman in Eastwood v. Kenyon,'' the learned judge remarking that the doctrine would annihilate the necessity for any consideration at all, inasmuch as the mere fact of giving a promise creates a moral obligation to support it. The subject is discussed by Sir William Markby, who contends that an express undertaking of a liability ought to be held binding, "not upon the stupid ground that a moral 3onsideration supports a promise, b^t upon the ground that a liability was intended and ought to be enforced." * 1 Taunton, V, p. 36. " A. and E. XI, p. 446. 3 "Elements of Law," 5th ed., pp. 317-18. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 79 exercised, to make up for the negligence or the incapacity of the avowed legislator. That part oi the law of every country which was made by judges has been far better made than that part which consists of statutes enacted by the legislature. Notwithstanding my great admiration for Mr. Bentham, I cannot but think that, instead of blaming judges for having legislated, he should blame them for the timid, narrow, and piecemeal manner in which they have legislated, and for legislating under cover of vague and indeterminate phrases, such as llbrd Mansfield employed in the above example, and which would be censurable in any legislator.* 205. The foregoing distribution of laws proper, and of The fore- such improper laws as are closely analogous to the proper, S°}^S dis- tallies, in the main, with a division of laws which is given of i^^s incidentally by Locke in his Essay on Human Understanding, tallies, in And since this division of laws, or of the source of duties or ^^^^^ ^ obligations, is recommended by the great authority which division of the writer has justly acquired, I gladly append it to my own ^^e''^ division or analysis. The passage of his essay in which the division occurs, is part of an inquiry into the nature of relation, and is therefore concerned indirectly with the nature and kinds of law. With the exclusion of all that is foreign to the nature and kinds of law, with the exclusion of a few expressions which are obviously redundant, and with the 204. §§ 202 and 204 should be carefully compared. In the earlier section, the judge held up for admiration is the judge who abides by the law ; in the later section, the judge held up for admiration is the judge who adds to the law. Q. (1) How are these apparently inconsistent sections to be reconciled 1 ^ (2) Examine the statement that the subject-matter of Juris- prudence consists of " the principles on which the courts ought to decide cases." * 1 Cf. Excursus G, infra. » Professor Gray, " Harvard Law Review," April, 1892, p. 27. 80 THE DIFFEEENT KINDS OF LAWS correction of a few expressions which are somewhat obscure, the passage containing the divisions may be rendered in the words following : 'Good or evil is nothing but pleasure or pain, or that which occasions or procures pleasure or pain to us. Mard good or evil, then, is only the conformity or disagreement of our voluntary actions to some law, whereby good or evil is drawn on us by the will and power of the law-maker : which good or evil, pleasure or pain, attending our observance or breach of the law, by the decree of the law-maker, is that we call reward or punishment. 'Of these moral rules or laws, to which men generally refer, and by which they judge of the rectitude or pravity of their actions, there seem to me to be three sorts, with their three different enforcements, or rewards and punishments. For since it would be utterly in vain to suppose a rule set to the free actions of man, without annexing to it some en- forcement of good and evil to determine his will, we must, wherever we suppose a law, suppose also some reward or punishment annexed to that law. It would be in vain for one intelligent being to set a rule to the actions of another, if he had it not in his power to reward the compliance with, and punish deviation from his rule, by some good and evil that is not the natural product and consequence of the action itself : for that being a natural convenience or incon- venience,, would operate of itself without a law. This, if I mistake not, is the true nature of all law properly so called. 'The laws that men generally refer their actions to, to judge of their rectitude or obliquity, seem to me to be these three: 1. The Bivim law. 2. The civU law. 3. The law of opinion or reputation, if I may so call it. — By the relation they bear to the first of these, men judge whether their actions are sins or duties : by the second, whether they be THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 81 criminal or innocent : and by the third, whether they be virtues or vices. ' By the Divine law, I mean that law which God hath set to the actions of men, whether promulgated to them by the light of nature, or the voice of revelation. This is the only true touchstone of rhoral rectitude. ' Virtue and vice are names pretended, and supposed every- where to stand for actions in their own nature right or wrong : and as far as they really are so applied, they so far are coincident with the Divine law above mentioned. 'But yet, whatever is pretended, this is visible, that these names virtue and vice, in the particular instances of their applica- tion through the several nations and societies of men in the world, are constantly attributed to such actions only as in each country and society are in reputation or discredit. Nor is it to be thought strange, that men everywhere should give the name of virtue to those actions which amongst them are judged praiseworthy, and call that vice which they account blameable; since they would condemn themselves, if they should think anything right, to which they allowed not commendation ; anything wrong, which they let pass with- out blame. ' Thus the measure of what is everywhere called and es- teemed virtue and vice, is this approbation or dislike, praise or blame, which by a secret and tacit consent establishes itself in the several societies, tribes, and clubs of men in the world whereby several actions come to find credit or dis- grace amongst them, according to the judgment, maxims, or fashions of that place. 'But though, by the different temper, education, fashion, maxims, or interest of different sorts of men, it fell out, that what was thought praiseworthy in one place, escaped not censure in another, and so in different societies virtues and vices were changed, yet, as to the main, they for the most Q 82 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS part kept the same everywhere. For since nothing can be more natural, than to encourage with esteem and reputation that wherein everyone finds his advantage, and to blame and discountenance the contrary, it is no wonder that esteem and discredit, virtue and vice, should in a great measure every- where correspond with the unchangeable rule of right and wrong which the law of God hath established : there being nothing that so directly and visibly secures and advances the general good of mankind in this world as obedience to the law He has set them, and nothing that breeds such mis- chiefs and confusion as the neglect of it. And therefore men, without renouncing all sense and reason, and their own interest, could not generally mistake in placing their com- mendation or blame on that side which really deserved it not. Nay, even those men, whose practice was otherwise, failed not to give their approbation right: few being de- praved to that degree, as not to condemn, at least in others, the faults they themselves were guilty of. Whereby, even in the corruption of manners, the law of God, which ought to be the rule of virtue and vice, was pretty well observed. ' If any. one shall imagine that I have forgotten my own notion of a law, when I make the law, whereby men judge of virtue and vice, to be nothing but the consent of private men who have not authority to make a law ; especially wanting that which is so necessary and essential to a law, a power to enforce it : I think, I may say, that he who imagines /Com- mendation and disgrace not to be strong motives on men to accommodate themselves to the opinions and rules of those with whom they converse, seems little skilled in the nature or history of mankind : The greatest part whereof he shall find to govern themselves chiefly, if not solely, by this law of fashion : and so they do that which keeps them in reputa- tion with their company, little regard the law of God or the magistrate. The penalties that attend the breach of God's THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 83 law, some, nay, perhaps, most men seldom seriously reflect on ; and amongst those that do, many, whilst they hreak the law, entertain thoughts of future reconciliation, and making their peace for such breaches. And as to the punishments due from the law of the commonwealth, they frequently flatter themselves with the hope of impunity. But no man escapes the punishment of their censure and dislike, who offends against the fashion and opinion of the company he keeps, and would recommend himself to. Nor is there one of ten thousand, who is stiff and insensible enough to bear up under the constant dislike and condemnation of his own club. He must be of a strange and unusual constitution, who can content himself to live in constant disgrace and dis- repute with his own particular society. Solitude many men have sought and been reconciled to : but nobody that has the least thought or sense of a man about him, can live in society under the constant dislike and ill opinion of his familiars, and those he converses with. This is a burthen too heavy for human sufferance : and he must be made up of irreconcileable contradictions, who can take pleasure in company, and yet be insensible of contempt and disgrace from his companions.' — Essay concerning Human Understand- ing. Book II. Chap. XXVIII. 206. The analogy borne to a law proper by a law which Laws opinion imposes, lies mainly in the following point of resem- ™®**P'"'" blance. In the case of a law set by opinion, as well as in figuratiT*. the case of a law properly so called, a rational being or —Their 1 • 1 • • -1 • 1 o 1 common beings are subject to contmgent evil, in the event of their and neg»- not complying with a known or presumed desire of another t'^* °a- being or beings of a like nature. The analogy between a law in the proper acceptation of the term, and a law im- properly so called which opinion sets or imposes, is, there- fore, strong. The defect which excludes the latter from the rank of a law proper, merely consists in this : that the wish 84 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS or desire of its authors has not been duly signified^ and that they have no formed intention of inflicting evil or pain upon those who may break or transgress it. 207. But, beside the laws improper which are set or imposed by opinion, there are laws improperly so called which are related to laws proper by remote analogies. I style these laws metaphorical, or laws merely metaphorical. The analogies by which they are suggested will hardly admit of a common and positive description ; but laws metaphori- cal have the following common and negative nature. — No property or character of any metaphorical law can be likened to a sanction or a duty. Consequently, every meta- phorical law wants that point of resemblance which mainly constitutes the analogy between a law proper and a law set by opinion. Examples. 208. The most frequent and remarkable of those meta- phorical applications is suggested by that uniformity, or that stability of conduct, which is one of the ordinary con- sequences of a law proper. We say, for instance, that the movements of lifeless bodies are determined by certain laws: though, since the bodies are lifeless and have no desires or aversions, they cannot be touched by aught which in the least resembles a sanction, and cannot be subject to aught which in the least resembles an obligaton. We mean that they move in certain uniform modes, and that they move in those uniform modes through the pleasure and appointment of God : just as parties obliged behave in a uniform manner through the pleasure and appointment of the party who imposes the law and the duty. — Again : We say that certain actions of the lower and irrational animals are determined by certain laws: though, since they cannot understand the purpose and provisions of a law, it is impos- sible that sanctions should efifectually move them to obedi- ence, or that their conduct should be guided by a regard to THE DIFPEEENT KINDS OF LAWS 85 duties or obligations. We mean that they act in certain uniform modes, either in consequence of instincts (or causes which we cannot explain), or else in consequence of hints which they catch from experience and observation : and that, since their uniformity of action is an effect of the Divine pleasure, it closely resembles the uniformity of conduct which is wrought by the authors of laws in those who are obnoxious to the sanctions. — In short, whenever we talk of laws governing the irrational world, the metaphorical appli- cation of the term law is suggested by this double analogy. 1. The successive and synchronous phsenomena composing the irrational world, happen and exist, for the most part, in uniform series: which uniformity of succession and co- existence resembles the uniformity of conduct produced by an imperative law. 2. That uniformity of succession and coexistence, like the uniformity of conduct produced by an imperative law, springs from the will and intention of an intelligent and rational author. — When an atheist speaks of laws governing the irrational world, the metaphorical appli- cation is suggested by an^ analogy still more slender and remote than that which I have now analysed. He means that the uniformity of succession and coexistence resembles the uniformity of conduct produced by an imperative rule. If, to draw the analogy closer, he ascribes those laws to an author, he personifies a verbal abstraction, and makes it play the legislator. He attributes the uniformity of succession and coexistence to laws set by nature : meaning, by nature, the world itself ; or, perhaps, that very uniformity which he imputes to nature's commands.* 208. Q. " You say the laws of mattei are inevitable ; but in what sense — potentially or actually 1 Cannot each law be interfered with at any moment by some other law, so that the first law, though it may struggle for the mastery, shall be for an indefinite time utterly defeated ! The law of gravity is immutable enough. But do all stones veritably fall to the ground? Certainly not, if I 86 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 209. Many metaphorical applications of the term law or rule are suggested by the analogy following. — An imperative choose to catch one and keep it in my hand. It remains there by laws ; and the law of gravity is there too, making it feel heavy in my hand ; but it has not fallen to the ground, and v^ill not, till I let it. So much for the inevitable action of the laws of gravity, as of others. Potentially, it is immutable ; but actually, it can be conquered by other laws." Criticize the conception of a natural law implied in this passage. Note. — Natural laws. — The fallacy into which Kingsley falls in the above-quoted passage is by no means uncommon. In many minds, a disposition exists to personify nature and to regard it as issuing orders to which matter must conform ; for example, commanding all stones to fall to the ground. According to this view, all stones do their best to get to ground, impelled thereto by the law which nature has set. In reality, natural laws are not impelling forces, but abstract formulae. 'Thus with regard to the law of gravitation we have to distinguish : (1) Gravity, i.e. the attraction which one body has for another. (2) The law of gravity, viz. that the attraction of one body for another varies directly as the mass and inversely as the square of the distance. (3) The immediate consequence in any particular case resulting from the combined action of gravity and of other forces. The conception of a natural law is applicable to society as well as to external nature. It is in the former connection that most difficulty is likely to be felt iu distinguishing the law metaphorical from other laws. "Moral principles, when they are true," affirms Mr. John Morley, " are at bottom only registered general- izations from experience. They record certain uniformities of antecedence and consequence in the region of human conduct."* While a difference of opinion may exist as to whether moral principles are not something more than this, no one will doubt that most moral principles can be expressed in the form suggested by Mr. Morley, and that when so expressed they belong to the class of laws by metaphor. "Speak the Truth" is a law by analogy, whilst the statement of Whately — "It makes all the difference in the world whether we put truth in the first or the second place" — may be described as a law by metaphor. That one implies the other may be admitted. The expression of a moral principle, however, may easily take such a form that it is open to doubt whether we are, or are not, thinking in the realm of law by metaphor. ' " On Compromise.'' THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 7i law or rule guides the conduct of the obliged, or is a norma, model, or pattern, to which their conduct conforms. A pro- posed guide of human conduct, or a model or pattern offered to human imitation, is, therefore, frequently styled a law or rule of conduct, although there be not in the case a shadow of a sanction or a duty. 210. For example : To every law properly so called there are two distinct parties : a party by whom it is established, and a party to whom it is set. But, this notwithstanding, we often speak of a law set by a man to himself : meaning that he intends to pursue some given course of conduct as exactly as he would pursue it if he were bound to pursue ib by a law. An intention of pursuing exactly some given course of conduct, is the only law or rule which a man can set to himself. The binding virtue of a law lies in the sanc- tion annexed to it. But in the case of a so-called law set by a man to himself, he is not constrained to observe it by aught that resembles a sanction. For though he may fairly purpose to inflict a pain on himself, if his conduct shall depart from the guide which he intends it shall follow, the infliction of the conditional pain depends upon his own will. — Again : When we talk of rules of art, the meta- phorical application of the term rules is suggested by the analogy in question. By a rule of art, we mean a prescrip- tion or pattern which is offered to practitioners of an art, and which they are advised to observe when performing some given process. There is not the semblance of a sanction, nor is there the shadow of a duty. But the offered prescription or pattern may guide the conduct of practitioners, as a rule imperative and proper guides the conduct of the obliged.* 210. Q. (1) Would it be any answer to Austin's argument with respect to self-imposed law to plead that legal sanctions are almost invariably conditional upon the will of the offender, since he may commit suicide ? (2) Ought not the class of laws by analogy to have been 88 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS Laws 211. The preceding disquisition on figurative laws is not metaphor- g^ superfluous as some of my hearers may deem it. Figura- ical or ^ i , • ■, n i • figurative tive laws are not unfrequently mistaken tor laws mipera- are often t^yg ^nd proper. Nay, attempts have actually been made, and con- and by writers of the highest celebrity, to explain and founded illustrate the nature of laws imperative and proper, by Operative illusions to so-called laws which are merely such through a and metaphor. For instance, in an excerpt from Ulpian placed proper. ^^ ^^^ beginning of the Pandects, and also inserted by Justinian in the second title of his Institutes, a fancied /ms naiv/rale, common to all animals, is thus distinguished from the yws naturale or gentium to which I have adverted above. Jus naturale est, quod natura omnia animalia doeuit : nam jus istud non humani generis proprium, sed omnium animalium quae in terra, quae in mari nascuntur, avium quoque commune est. Hinc descendit maris atque feminae conjunctio, quam nos matrimonium appellamus ; hinc liberorum pro- creatio, hinc educatio: videmus etenim cetera quoque animalia, feras etiam, istius juris peritia censeri. Jus gentium est, quo gentes humanse utuntur. Quod a naturali recedere, inde facile intelligere licet; quia illud omnibus animalibus, hoc solis hominibus inter se commune est.' The Jus naturale widened bo as to include self-imposed laws in preference to grouping such laws with statements of sequence 1 (3) Compare Austin's point of view with that expressed by T. H. Green in the following passage : "It is the very essence of moral duty to he imposed by a man on himself. The moral duty to obey a positive law, whether a la'w of the State or of the Church, is imposed not by the author or enforcer of the Positive Law, but by that spirit of man, which sets before him the ideal of a perfect life." ^ (4) May we not say of the rules of literary art that they represent certain opinions of educated men to which literary artists must conform under pain of censure and neglect? And that in consequence they are laws by analogy ? ' Prolegomena to Ethics," p. 402. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 89 which Ulpian here describes, and which he here distinguishes from the jus naturale or gentiv/m, is a name for the instincts of animals. More especially, it denotes that instinctive appetite which leads them to propagate their kinds, with that instinctive sympathy which inclines parent animals to nourish and educate their young. Now, the instincts of animals are related to laws by the slender or remote analogy which I have already endeavoured to explain. They incline the animals to act in certain uniform modes, and they are given to the animals for that purpose by an intelligent and rational Author. But these meta- phorical laws which govern the lower animals and which govern (though less despotically) the human species itself, should not have been blended and confounded, by a grave writer upon jurisprudence, with laws properly so called. It is true that the instincts of the animal man, like many of his affections which are not instinctive, are amongst the causes of laws in the proper acceptation of the term. More especially, the laws regarding the relation of husband and wife, and the laws regarding the relation of parent and child, are mainly caused by the instincts which Ulpian par- ticularly points at. And that, it is likely, was the reason which determined this legal oracle to class the instincts of animals with laws imperative and proper. But nothing can be more absurd than the ranking with laws themselves the causes which lead to their existence. . And. if human instincts are laws because they are causes of laws, there is scarcely a faculty or affection belonging to the human mind, and scarcely a class of objects presented by the outward world, that must not be esteemed a law and an appropriate subject of jurisprudence. — I must, however, remark, that the jus quod natv/ra omnia animalia docuit is a conceit peculiar to Ulpian : and that this most foolish conceit, though inserted in Justinian's compilations, has no perceptible influence on 90 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAT^S the detail of the Eoman law. The jvs naturaU of the classical jurists generally, and the jus naturale occurring generally in the Pandects, is equivalent to the natural law of modern writers upon jurisprudence, and is synonymous with the jus gentiv/m, or the jus naturale et gentium,. It means those positive laws and those rules of positive moral- ity, which are not peculiar or appropriate to any nation or age, but obtain, or are thought to obtain, in all nations and ages : and which, by reason of their obtaining in all nations and ages, are supposed to be formed or fashioned on the law of God or Nature as known by the moral sense. 'Omnes populi ' (says Gains),' qui legibus et moribus reguntur, partim suo proprio, partim communi omnium hominum jure utuntur. Nam quod quisque populus ipse sibi jus constituit, id ipsius proprium est, vocaturque jus civile; quasi jus proprium ipsius civitatis. Quod vero naturalis ratio inter omnes homines constituit, id aput omnes populos perseque custoditur, vocaturque jus gentium ; quasi quo jure omnes gentes utuntur.' The universal leges et mores here described by Gaius, and distinguished from the leges et mores peculiar to a particular nation, are styled indifferently, by most of the classical jurists, jus gentium, jus natu/rale, or jus naturale et gentium. And the law of nature, as thus understood, is not intrinsically absurd. For as some of the dictates of utility are always and everywhere the same, and are also so plain and glaring that they hardly admit of mistake, there are legal and moral rules which are nearly or quite universal, and the expediency of which must be seen by merely natural reason, or by reason without Jhe lights of extensive experience and observation. The distinction of law and morality into natural and positive, is a needless and futile subtilty : but still the distinction is founded on a real and manifest difference. The ju,s naturale or gentium would be liable to 'ittle objection, if it were not supposed to be the offspring of THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 91 a moral instinct or sense, or of innate practical principles. But, since it is closely allied to that misleading and per- nicious jargon, it ought to be expelled, with the natural law of the moderns, from the sciences of jurisprudence and morality.* 212. The following passage is the first sentence in Montes- quieu's Spirit of Laws: 'Les lois, dans la signification la plus ^tendue, sont les rapports nfoessaires qui d^rivent de la nature des choses : et dans ce sens tous les Stres ont leurs lois : la Divinity a ees lois ; le monde materiel a ses lois ; les intelligences superieures ^ I'homme ont leurs lois ; les bStes ont leurs lois; I'homme a ses lois.' Now objects widely different, though bearing a common name, are here blended and confounded. Of the laws which govern the conduct of intelligent and rational creatures, some are laws impera- tive and proper, and others are closely analogous to laws of that description. But the so-called laws which govern the material world, with the so-called laws which govern the 211. Savigny makes the following interesting apology for Ulpian's text : " The first thing which astonishes in this text, and by reason of which it has often been severely blamed, is the law and consciousness of law ascribed to beasts. When, however, the certainly ill-chosen expression is abandoned, the view itself admits of easy defence against that censure. Each jural relation has for its foundation matter of some kind, to which the form of law is applied and which therefore can also be conceived abstracted from this form. This material is, in most of the jural relations, so far of an arbitrary kind that a continuous existence of the human race can also be conceived without it ; thus in property and obligations. Not so with the two relations above named, which are rather universal natural relations common to men and beasts and without which the human race could have no enduring existence. In fact, therefore, it is not the law (right), but the material of the law (right), the natural relation lying at its base, which is ascribed to beasts. This view now is not merely true, but also important and worthy of notice."^ ' Savigny's " Roman Law," translated by HoUoway, pp. 338-9. 92 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS lower animals, are merely laws by a metaphor. And the so- called laws which govern or determine the Deity are clearly in the same predicament. If his actions were governed or determined by laws imperative and proper, he would be in a state of 'dependence on another and superior being. When we say that the actions of the Deity are governed or determined by laws, we mean that they conform to intentions which the Deity himself has conceived, and which he pursues or observes with inflexible steadiness or constancy. To mix these figurative laws with laws imperative and proper, is to obscure, and not to elucidate, the nature or essence of the latter. The beginning of the passage is worthy of the sequel. We are told that laws are the necessary relations which flow from the nature of things. But what, I would crave, are relations ? What, I would also crave, is the nature of things? And how do the necessary relations which flow from the nature of things differ from those relations which originate in other sources ? The terms of the definition are incomparably more obscure than the term which it affects to expound. 213. If you read the disquisition in Blackstone on the nature of laws in general, or the description of law in Hooker's Ecclesiastical Polity, you will find the same con- fusion of laws imperative and proper with laws which are merely such by a glaring perversion of the term. The cases of this confusion are, indeed, so numerous, that they would fill a considerable volume.* 213, Blackstone's definition of Positive Law runs: "A rule of civil conduct prescribed by the supreme power in a state commanding what is right and prohibiting what is wrong." ^ " Of law," declared Hooker, "there can be no lesse acknowledged, than that her seate is in the bosome of God, her voyce the harmony of the world." ^ 1 " Commentaries," I, p. 44. ^ " Ecclesiastical Polity," I, c. 18. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 93 214. From the confusion of laws metaphorical with laws Physical imperative and proper, I turn to a mistake, somewhat similar, °^ o***"^ '^ '^ '^ ' sanctions. which, 1 presume to think, has been committed by Mr. Ben- tham. Sanctions proper and improper are of three capital classes : the sanctions properly so called which are annexed to the laws of God ; the sanctions properly so called which are annexed to positive laws; the sanctions properly so called, and the sanctions closely analogous to sanctions properly so called, which respectively enforce compliance with positive moral rules. But to sanction religious, legal, and moral, this great philosopher and jurist adds a class of sanctions which he styles physical or natural. '' 215. When he styles these sanctions physical, he does not intend to intimate that they are distinguished from other sanctions by the mode wherein they operate; he does not intend to intimate that these are the only sanctions which affect the suffering parties through physical or material means. His meaning may, I believe, be rendered in the following manner. — A physical sanction is an evil brought upon the suffering party by an act or omission of his own. But, though it is brought upon the sufferer by an act or omission of his own, it is not brought upon the sufferer through any Divine law, or through any positive law, or rule of positive morality. For example: if your house be destroyed by fire through your neglecting to put out a light, you bring upon yourself, by your negligent omission, a physical or natural sanction : supposing, I mean, that your omission is not to be deemed a sin, and that the consequent destruction of your house is not to be deemed a punishment, inflicted by the hand of the Deity. 216. Such physical or natural evils are related by the following analogy to sanctions properly so called. 1. When they are actually suffered, they are suffered by rational beings through acts or omissions of their own. 2. Before 94 THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS they are actually suffered, or whilst they exist in prospect they affect the wills or desires of the parties obnoxious to them as sanctions properly so called affect the wills of the obliged. The parties are urged to the acts which may avert the evils from their heads, or the parties are deterred from the acts which may bring the evils upon them. 217. But in spite of the specious analogy at which I have now pointed, I dislike, for various reasons, the application of the term sanction to these physical or natural evils. Of those reasons I will briefly mention the following. — 1. Although these evils are suffered by intelligent rational beings through acts or omissions of their own, they are not suffered as consequences of their not complying with desires of intelligent rational beings. The analogy borne by these evils to sanctions properly so called, is nearly as remote as the analogy borne by laws metaphorical to laws imperative and proper. 2. By the term sanction, as it is now restricted, the evils enforcing compliance with laws imperative and proper, or with the closely analogous laws which opinion sets or imposes, are distinguished from other evils briefly and commodiously. If the term were commonly extended to these physical or natural evils, this advantage would be lost. The term would then comprehend every possible evil which a man may bring upon himself by his own voluntary conduct.* 217. Q. (I) Where would the following examples be placed by Austin in his classification of the different kinds of laws ? (1) The rule that in English the aspirate must be sounded. (2^ The rules as to the employment of the subjunctive. (3) The rule that a sentence should not be prolonged beyond what appears to be its natural close. (4) A decision of the French Academy establishing a new grammatical rule. (5) A statement of the conditions of success in the art of writing popular editorials. (6) "He who would avoid burning his fingers ought not to play with the fire." THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF LAWS 95 218. I close my disquisitions on figurative laws, and on In strict- ihose metaphorical sanctions which Mr. Bentham denominates ^^' claratory -physical, with the following connected remark. Declaratory laws, laws laws, and laws repealing laws, ought in strictness to be repealing . . laws, and classed with laws metaphorical or figurative : for the analogy laws of im- by which they are related to laws imperative and proper perfect is extremely slender or remote. Laws of imperfect obliga- ,j„ ^j^g tion (in the sense of the Eoman jurists) are laws set or sense of imposed by the opinions of the law-makers, and ought in :^^^^^ ' strictness to be classed with rules of positive morality. But ought to be though laws of these three species are merely analogous "^^^^ "■ to laws in the proper acceptation of the term, they are with laws closely connected with positive laws, and are appropriate metaphor- subjects of jurisprudence. Consequently I treat them as figurative, improper laws of anomalous or eccentric sorts, and exclude and rules them from the classes of laws to which in strictness they ^ojaHty. belong. (7) The directions of an art master to his pupils (a) on the subject of harmony in colour, (b) as to hours of attendance. (8) The suggestions in a work on chemistry as to the beet of several ways of conducting a certain experiment. (9) The laws of legal development. (10) "The King must assent to Acts passed by both Houses of Parliament." (11) Moral laws conceived — (a) As imposed by the conscience. (b) As conclusions concerning what conduceth to the conservation and defence of Mankind (Hobbes, "Leviathan," Cap. XV). (c) As precepts based upon practical utility. (12) "To thine ownself be true, and it must follow as the night the day, thou canst not then be false to any man." (II) X orders a suit of clothes to be made by his tailor. "When the suit arrives, X finds that the tailor has followed the fashions of the early Victorian period. What kinds of law, if any, have Oeen violated (a) by the tailor, (6) by X in wearing the «.uit? CHAPTER III . THE DEFINITION OF SOVEEEIGNTY Purpose of 219. In the present lecture I explain the\ marks or . Tto'* characters which distinguish positive laws, or laws strictly.' so called. And, in order to, an explanation of the marks which distinguish positive laws, I shall analyse the ex- pression sovereicirUy, the correlative expression subiectior^ . and • the inseparably connected expression indepen dent politica l' society. For the essential difiference of a positive law (or the . jlifiference that severs it from a law which is not a positive, law) may be stated thus; Every positive law, or every law. I simply and strictly so called, is set by a sovereign person, or; • la sovereign body of persons, to a member or members of ths' independent political society wherein that person or body is • Sovereign or supreme. Or (changing the expression) it is set by a monarch, or sovereign number, to a person or persons in ' % a state of subjection to its author. Even though it sprang,- directly from another fountain or source, it is a positive law,, or a law strictly so called, by the institution of that present ■ '■ sovereign in the character of political superior. Or (borrow-" ji^g the language of Hobbes) 'the legislator is he, not by. I whose authority the law was first made, ^at-by,, .yhose'l I authoii^i-it.£ontuiues to bea law.' ! The dis- 220. The superiority which is styled sovereignty, and th«l ing^marka independent political society which sovereignty implies, is of sover- distinguished from other superiority, apd from other society, a^mde- ^^ *^® following marks or characters.-^l^The MlHf of thei pendent given society are in a haint of obedience or submiBBionJ THE DEFINITION OF SOVEEEIGNTY 97 fto a idermina ie and cw samon superior : let that common political ! superior be a certain individual person, or a certain body '°^^^ , or aggregate of individual persons. / 2. Th at certain in- i dividual, or that certain body of individuals, is not in a i habit of obedience to a determinate human superior. Laws ' (improperly so called) which opinion sets or imposes, may permanently affect the conduct of that certain in- dividual or body. To express or tacit commands of other determinate parties, that certain individual or body may yield occasional submission. But there is no determinate person, or determinate aggregate of persons, to whose com- mands, express or tacit, that certain individual or body renders habitual obedience. 221. Or the notions of sovereignty and independent political society may be expressed concisely thus.-^If a determinate human superior, not in a habit of obedience to a like superior, receive habitual obedience from the bulk of a given society, that determinate superior is sovereign in that society, and the society (including the superior) is a society political and independent. / 222. To that determinate superior, the other members of The rela- the society are subject : or on that determinate superior, the *'"" °f other members of the society are depevderd. The position of eignty ' its other members towards that determinate superior, is »" Hall, " International Law," 2nd ed., pp. 28-9. FOKMS OF GOVERNMENT 141 national law, the sovereign government of such a society is and a styled a composite date. But it might be styled more aptly 'y^'^™ "' a supreme federal governmerU. rated states. eignty the British colonies " which possess independent legis- latures."^ The illustration is not a happy one. British colonies are not included by writers of International Law under the head of semi-sovereign states ; they are integral parts of the British Empire ; and the complete legal sovereignty of the British Par- liament is attested inter alia by the fact that an Imperial Act intended to apply to a colony will be held to apply to it not- withstanding anything to the contrary in the local law. In | the recent Constitution for the Australian Commonwealth, the/ legislative supremacy of the Imperial Parliament remains with! slight alterations, which may affect the occasions on which tha^ supremacy is displayed, but leave its existence unchallenged.^ (2) I turn from illustrating Austin's criticism to examine its value. Austin denies the possibility of an imperfectly sovereign state on the ground that in every political community unlimited ' ■ control must exist somewhere. I hold, on the contrary, that even if it be true- that such a control always exists, the epithet im- perfectly sovereign would not be applied inappropriately where_ the control is partly external to the State. If, in support of the* Austinian view, it be urged that the control is not external to the State since in such cases the State consists of the political community together with the external authority, I reply that this is to give an artificial and improper meaning to the term State. , In the case of a State like the Ionian Kepublic, it is within the' State itself that we must look for the organic element implied in the very idea of the State. The protected State is, unlike sub- ordinate political communities, no part of a larger whole. It is a real unit ; it is a person in International Law ; it enjoys an imperfect independence ; and as a consequence it is styled not inappropriately an imperfectly sovereign state. Its real position is analogous to the position assigned by positive law to the ward. We regard the ward as a person of imperfect independence ; we do not affirm the existence of a perfectly independent person by including within the conception of the personality of the ward some share of the personality of the guardian. In taking a different view, Aus tin sacri fices essentials to verbal .« precision. In reality. States are the creation, not of logic, but of history. We find them in every stage of being, becoming and > " The Student's Austin," p. 101. " Cf. Moore, " The Commonwealth of Australia," p. 167. 142 FORMS OF GOVERNMENT 296. It also frequently happens, that several political societies which are severally independent, or several political governments which are severally sovereign, are compacted by a permanent alliance. By some of the writers on positive ceasing to be. Whatever tests we may apply, we must always remeiMer that the first function of a classification is to represent facts; that if facts are infinitely varying, the dassification must not be inflexible. If we find that between the political com- munity which is an independent State, and the pohtical community which is only a part of an independent State, there are other political communities more nearly allied to the former than to the latter, I do not see why we should allow any abstract doctrine of sovereignty to prevent us from applying to such states the obvious epithet of imperfectly independent, or even imperfectly sovereign. Ajs Pradier-Fod^r^ remarked, metaphysically there ought not to be half-sovereign States, but historically there have (been, and there may be again.^ In refusing to recognize the fact Austin is unhistorical. Further, he endeavours to force upon the very diverse material with which the International lawyer it called upon to deal, a generalization suggested by a science avow- edly limited to highly developed States. The actual facts as they appear in International Law are wed summarized by Dr. Merriam : " When a State asks for admission to the circle of so vp™gTis, the International lawyer inquires first of all into the political powers j which the applicant possesses. In other words, sovereignty is i really regarded as a sum of - powers, a collection or aggregate !of governmental faculties, the possession of which will entitle the bearer to recognition in a sovereign capacity. These powers are of such a nature as that of making war and concluding peace, of negotiating treaties with other powers, of regulating the internal administration, and of independent legislation. For the purposes of International Law, sovereignty is regarded as the aggregate of these powers, rather than as an indivisible principle out of which they all emanate. Hence, being a sum or mass of rights, a part may be taken away without wholly destroying the sovereignty. The sovereignty may be less perfect, but it is still sovereignty." ^ , In venturing to differ from Austin as to the propriety of the expression imperfectly sovereign State, I may remind the reader that my criticism involves no attack upon the general question 1 " Traitd de droit international public," I, 159 ; cited Merriam, " History of the Theory of Sovereignty," p. 22. ° " History of Theory of Sovereignty," p. 213. tORMS OF GOVERNMENT 143 international law, the several societies or governments are styled a system of confederated states. But the several governments, considered as thus compacted, might be styled more aptly Ajpermanent confederacy of supreme governments. 297. I advert to the nature of a composite state, and to that of a system of confederated states, for the following purposes. In a political society styled a composite state, the sovereignty is so shared by various individuals or bodies, that the one sovereign body whereof they are the constituent members, is. not conspicuous and easily pfiiseiyed. Accord- ingly, I advert to the nature of a supreme federal govern- ment, to show that the society which it rules is ruled by one sovereign. And adverting to the nature of a composite state, I also advert to the nature of a system of confederated states. For the fallacious resemblance of those widely of the tenability of the Austinian doctrine of sovereignty for the purposes of a jurisprudence exclusively concerned with fuUy developed states.^ I ought also to add that Austin might have quoted high authorities on International Law in his favour, and that even to-day eminent writers are apparently prepared to defend his terminology from the point of view of Political Science. . The sections from Austin, at present under discussion, are quoted almost verbatim, and with apparent approval, by Professor Willoughby.^ Professor Burgess, having defined Sovereignty as original, absolute, unhmited, universal power over the individual subject and over all associations of subjects, says that Sovereignty is absolutely es- sential to the State, and is either entire or not at all.^ The position is not apparently distinguishable from Austin's so far as relates to the subject immediately under consideration. With both, the State subject to a joint-sovereignty must either not be called a State at all, or else be included within the circle of States by means of an artificial extension of its borders so as to include an external government. My own reasons for dissenting from this view will appear more fully in the discussion oa Sovereignty in Excursus B. ' Cf. Excursus A. " " Nature of the State," pp. 256-7. ' " Political Science and Constitutional Law," I, 52-5 ; II, 7. 144 FORMS OF GOVERNMENT different objects, tends to produce a confusion which I think it expedient to obviate. 298. (1) In the case of a convposite state, or a supreme federal government, the several united governments of the several united societies, together with a government common to those several societies, are jointly sovereign in each oii ' those several societies, and also in the larger society arising from the federal union. Or, since the political powers of the common or general government were relinquished and con- ferred upon it by those several united governments, the nature of a composite state may be described more accurately thus. As compacted by the common government which they have concurred in creating, and to which they have severally delegated portions of their several sovereignties, I the several governments of the several united societies are jointly sovereign in each and all. 299. It will appear on a moment's reflection, that the common or general government is not sovereign or supreme. A government supreme and federal, and a government supreme but not federal, are merely distinguished by the following difference. Where the supreme government is not federal, each of the several governments, considered in that character, is purely _suboEdiiiatfi : or none of the. several governments, considered in that character, partakes of the sovereignty. But where the supreme government is properly federal, each of the several governments, which were im- \mediate parties to the federal compact, is, in that character, j&Jixsihjoi the sovereign body. Consequently, although they are subject to the sovereign body of which they are con- stituent members, those several governments, even considered as such, are not purely in a state of subjection. — But since those several governments, even considered a^ such, are not purely in a state of subjection, the common or general government which they have concurred in creating is not sovereign or supreme. FORMS OF GOVERNMENT 146 301. Nor is any of those several governments sovereign or supreme, even in the society of which it is the immediate chief. If those several governments were severally sever- f eign, they would not he members of a composite state:} though, if they were severally sovereign, and yet were per- manently compacted, they would form (as I shall show immediately) a system of confederated states. 302. To illustrate the nature of a composite state, I will add the following remark to the foregoing general descrip- tion. — Neither the immediate tribunals of the common or general government, nor the immediate tribunals of the several united governments, are bound, or empowered, to administer or execute ev&ry command that the general government may issue. The political powers of the common or general government, are merely those portions of their several sovereignties, which the several united governments, as parties to the federal compact, have relinquished and con- ferred upon it. Consequently, its competence to make laws and to issue other commands, may and ought to be examined by its own immediate tribunals, and also by the immediate tribunals of the several united governments. And if, in making a law qrjss uing a particular comman dfit exceed the limited powers which it derives from the federal cbiii-^ pact,,fllLthose various t ribun als are empowered and bound to msobe^^iSnd since each of the united governments, as a party to the federal compact, has relinquished a portion of its sovereignty, its competence to make laws and to issue other commands, may and ought to be examined by all those tribunals. And if it enact a law or issue a particular command, as exercising the sovereign powers \sMphj.t has rglinqaialied by the compact, all those tribunals are em- powered and bound to disobey. 303. If, then, the general government were of itself sovereign, or if the united governments were severally L 146 FORMS OF GOVERNMENT sovereign, the united societies would not constitute one composite state. The united societies would constitute one independent society, with a government supreme but not federal; or a knot of societies severally independent, with governments severally supreme. Consequently, the several united governments as forming one aggregate body, or they and the general government as forming a similar body, are Vjointly„sovgrfiigp in each of the united societies, and also in the larger society arising from the union of all. 304. Now since the political powers of the common or general government are merely delegated tojt by the several united governments, it is not a constituent member of the sovereign body, but is merely its subject minister. Conse- quently, the sovereignty of each of the united societies, and also of the larger society arising from the union of all, resides in the united governments as forming one aggregate body : that is to say, as signifying their joint pleasure, or the joint pleasure of a majority of their number, agreeably to the modes or forms determined by their federal compact. By that aggregate body, the powers of the general govern- ment were conferred and determined : and by that aggregate body, its powers may be revoked, abridged, or enlarged. — To that aggregate body, the several united governments, though not merely subordinate, are truly in a state of subjection. 305. The supreme government of the United States of America, agrees (I believe) with the foregoing general de- scription of a supreme federal government. I believe that the common government, or the government consisting of the congress and the president of the United States, is merely a subject minister of the United Stat^S^overnments. I believe that none of the latter is properly sovereign or supreme, even in the state or political society of which it is the immediate chief. And, lastly, I believe that the sovereignty of each of the states, and also of the larger / FORMS OF GOVERNMENT 147 state arising from the federal union, resides in the states, governments as fortning one aggregate hody: meaning by a state's government, not its ordinary legislature, but the body of its citizens vyhich appoints its ordinary legislature, and which, the union apart, is properly sovereign therein. 306. {2)Acomposite state, and a system of confederated states, are broadly distinguished by the following essential differ- ence. In the case of a composite state, the several united societies ar e one independ ent^ society, or are severally subject to one sovereign body: which, through its minister the general government, and through its members and ministers the several united governments, is habitually and gener- ally obeyed in each of the united societies, and also in the larger society arising from the union of all. In the case of a system of confederated states, the several compacted societies are not one society, and are not subject to a common sovereign. Though the aggregate of the several governments was the framer of the federal compact, and may subsequently pass resolutions concerning the entire confederacy, neither the terms of that compact, nor such subsequent resolutions, are enforced in any of the societies by the authority of that aggregate body. To each of the i confederated governments, those terms and resolutions arc J merely articles of agreement which it spontaneously adopts : and they owe their legal effect, in its own political society, 1 to laws and other commands which it makes or fashions upon them, and which, of its own authority, it addresses to its, own subjects. In short, a system of confederated states is'""-) not essentially different from a number of independent r" governments connected by an ordinary alliance. So long^ as we abide in general expressions, we can only affirm generally and vaguely, that the compact of the former is intended to be permanent, whilst the alliance of the latter is commonly intended to be temporary : and that the ends or 148 FORMS OP GOVERNMENT purposes which are embraced by the compact, are com- monly more numerous, and are commonly more complicated, than those which the alliance contemplates. 307. I believe that the German Confederation, which has succeeded to the ancient Empire, is merely a system of con- federated states. I believe that the present Diet is merely an assembly of ambassadors from several confederated but severally independent governments: that the resolutions of the Diet are merely articles of agreement which each of the conlederated governments spontaneously adopts: and that they owe their legal effect, in each of the compacted com- munities, to laws and commands which are fashioned upon them by its own immediate chief. 308. I also believe that the Swiss Confederation was and is of the same nature. If, in the case of the German, or of the Swiss Confederation, the body of confederated govern- ments enforces its own resolutions, those confederated governments are one composite state, rather than a system of confederated states. The body of confederated govern- ments is properly sovereign: and to that aggregate and sovereign body, each of its constituent members is properly in a state of subjection.* 308. Q. (1) Distinguish the "state" which is member of » Federation from — (a) The State called imperfectly sovereign, e.g. the Ionian Eepublic. ' (b) The Colonial dependency, e.g. Canada. (c) An English borough. (2) Austin makes the distinction between the "State,'' which is a member of a Federal State, and the State, which is member of a Confederation, turn upon the possession of sovereignty. Members of a Confederation, however, may lose by insensible degrees their sovereignty, and so become a Federation ; and vice versa. Can any practical tests be suggested for deciding in such cases at what moment sovereignty by the member of the union is lost or acquired ? Note. — In view of the controversies which have raged round the PORMS OF GOVERNMENT 149 fascinating question of the location of the sovereignty in the Ameiican Constitution since Austin wrote, it is no small evidence of the acuteness of his powers of analysis that his remarks on this subject sl^ould he still quoted with approval by American authors.^ Those remarks, however, need a more detailed illustration. In some respects they even require qualification. In the present note I discuss briefly the following topics : (1) The distinction between a Federal State and a Unitary State ; (2) the distinction between a Federal State and a Confederation ; (3) the location of the sover- eignty in a Federal State. (1) The distinction between a Federal State and a Unitary State. — The fundamental characteristic of the Federal State con- sists in a ji'Plism fi^ g"Yernme ntal organization s. A close parallel to such a dualism may be seen in the medieval scheme of society. According to medieval theory, the Holy Boman Empire was an organization of Christendom on its ecclesiastical and temporal sides. The medieval subject owed allegiance to two distinct and mutually independent authorities which were yet regarded as parts of one organized whole. Civil allegiance was due to the Emperor ; spiritual allegiance, to the Pope. In a Federal State, on the other hand, both allegiances are political ; one is to the National government, and the other is to one of a number of Pro- , vincial governments. These Provincial governments are dis- tinguished from the local governments of a Unitary State in two respects — the Provincial government of a Federal State is very' highly organized in its constitution, and is, in fact, capable of exercising all the necessary legislative, executive, and judicial functions of a National government ; and as a consequence of the dualism to which reference has just "been made, the relation which a Provincial government in a Federal State bears to the National is one o f co-ordination, not of subordinatio n. Of the two marks, the latter is the more distinctive. H'ational and Provincial governments ar e mutua,Uy independent within their several spheres . In Unitary States witk a fundamental constitution wliicii cannot be altered by ordinary legislative process, the local government may chance to possess a certain degree of independence in its relation to the National government ; but such independence will be found to be very inferior in degree to that which is characteris- tic of the Provincial government in a Federal State. The essence of a Federal State, as distinct from a Unitary State, is therefore a governmental dualism at a highly developed stage of government. A Federal State is one of which the governmental powers are divided between a ^National government and several Provincial governments, which, as regards internal structure, are for practical » Cf. WiUoughby, "Nature of the State," pp. 258-9. 150 FORMS OF GOVERNMENT purposes as highly organized as the National government, and as regards authority are co-ordinalte with, not subordinate to, that government. The foregoing definition may serve to decide whether, in any particular case, a State is Unitary or Federal. In practice, the realization and successful working of the dual dispositiofl of governmental powers will be found to involve the following: — *(a) Some organization of the State distinct from, and superior to, the National and Provincial governments ; (b) a written con8tit,u- Jion in which the several spheres of the various governmental organizations are clearly defined; (c) some representation of the composite character of the union in the organization of the National government. Such a representation may take the form of rules relating to the constitution and functions of the National judicature. It may be effected by the equal representation of all the " States " in one of the legislative Chambers of the National government. It was effected in the Achsean League by the proviso according to which votes in the Central Assembly of the League were counted upon a civic basis as distinct from an individuahstic. In the constitution of the Australian Commonwealth, the federal principle invades every department of the Commonwealth govern- ment, and even appears in the clauses which constitute the authority, behind the central and local governments. An amend- ment of the constitution requires the support of an absolute majority of both, or of either, of the Houses of the Commonwealth Government, sanctioned by the direct popular approval of a majority of the electors in the Commonwealth, and also by majorities of the electors in a majority of the States. The reference to the constitution of the Australian Commoa- wealth suggests the reflection that the Commonwealth is a Federa- tion though it is not a Federal State. The dualism which is the most important mark of the Federal State is a dualism of govern- ments, not in strictness a duality of the State. Hence some publicists have objected to the expression Federal State. But the term is convenient, and has been adopted by usage. Govern- mental dualism, it may be added, may exist not only in a sub- ordinate political community, but even in a community composed of sovereign states. This is likely to happen where several states unite in a permanent alliance and a"ppoint a common government for special purposes. While, however, usage admits the expres- sion Federal government in the former case, it does not do so in the latter. A Federal government is either the government of a Federal state, or else the government of a subordinate political community modelled upon the government of a Federal State. Where the leading principle of Federal government is adopted ■•.xternally to the organization of the State the term Confederation IS employed. FORMS OF GOVERNMENT 151 Whether in a particular case a Constitution is Federal or Unitary is a question often difficult to answer. Governmental systems exist in every degree of complexity. One governmental type passes into another by insensible degrees. The difficulties are I increased by the fact that legal theory and constitutional organiza-| tions are often very imperfect representations of the real facts off social and political life. The British Empire affords an interesting illustration. In legal theory, the Colonial governments are sub- ordinate to, not co-ordinate with, the Imperial government ; in practice, those governments exercise wider powers and enjoy a greater independence than the Provincial governments in most Federations. Although the British Empire is not a Federal State, the facts of social and political life appear to suggest that it is on the way to become so, if not already entitled to be called "a Federal State in the making." (2) The Federal State and the Confederaiion. — The Federal State, as we have seen, is simply a single State with federa 1 government. The Confederation is a group of States which are in more or less' permanent alliance and possess a common central government fori certain limited purposes. The dual government, which is essential to the Federal State, may exist in the Confederation if the several States have sovereign" organizations from which the government of the Confederation, and the governments of the States, derive their authority. Obviously, cases may occur in which it is difficult to determine whether a union of political communities is a Con- federation or a Federal State, i.e., whether the several communities have, or have not, retained their sovereignty. By the Act consti- tuting the "Germanic Confederation" of 1820 — (a) A common central government or Diet was constituted composed of the plenipotentiaries of the several States and empowered (1) To receive and accredit envoys and conclude treaties on behalf of the Confederation : (2) To declare war against foreign States in case the terri- tory of the Confederation should be threatened. (b) The governments of the contracting States retained an independent jurisdiction over their own subjects. (c) The States had no formally recognized right of withdrawal from the Confederation, and could not make war on one another. The conclusion is suggested that the union formed a Federal State. That conclusion is refuted, however, by the following facts : — (a) The maintenance of the independence and inviolability of the Confederated States was an avowed object of the union. {h) Each of the States could receive and accredit envoys, make 152 FORMS OF GOVERNMENT treaties, and form any alliance of which the terms should not be prejudicial to the union. (c) If, in a case of alleged danger, the majority of the Diet refused to call out the united forces of the union, the minority was authorized to concert measures of self- defence. {d) The Diet could not constrain a recalcitrant State save by the power of other States who consented to place their military forces at his disposal. (e) No trace of over-soveieignty appears to have existed on the part of the Diet with regard to the citizens of the sever»l States. The citizen owed allegiance to his State govern- ment alone.^ Under these circumstances, no doubt can exist that the union was a Confederation. The highly important question remains, however, as to which, if any, of the characteristics (a)-(e) are essential to this conclusion. Is there any single conclusive test for deciding such cases? Probably not, though one test of considerable value may be suggested : if, having regard to aU the facts of the ' case, it is possible to regard the several members of the union as contracting parties who expressly or implicitly reserve to themselves the right of withdrawing from the union, the union is merely a Confederation. No such right was expressly reserved in the case of the Germanic Confederation, but its implication appears to be clear. A confederation, however, is apt to be a Federal State in the making. Both of the Confederations mentioned by Austin have long since become Federal States. Here as elsewhere, particular oases must be decided by relative degrees of likeness or unlikeness to type rather than by verbal definitions. (3) The location of the sovereignty in a Federal State. — Al- though this subject is a highly controversial one, it deserves a careful consideration if we desire to understand the nature either of a Federal State or of sovereign,ty. I propose to deal solely with the case of the Constitution of the United States. In this Constitution there are : (a) A National government; (b) Provincial governments, which, as regards internal structure, are for practical purposes as highly organized as the National government, and as regards authority are co-ordinate with that government ; (c) an organization of the State distinguishable from the National aiid Provincial governments and capable of re- adjusting their relations by amending the written constitution in which their several spheres are defined. This last-mentioned organization is provided by the fifth article of the Constitution, which leads as follows : — ' Hall, " International Law," p. 27. FORMS OF GOVERNMENT 153 " The Congress, whenever two-thirds of both houses shall deem it necessary, shall propose amendments to this constitution, or, on the application of the Legislatures of two-thirds of the several States, shall call a convention for proposing amendments, which, in either case, shall be valid to all intents and purposes, as part of this constitution, when ratified by the Legislatures of three- fourths of the several States, or by conventions in three-fourths thereof, as the one or the other mode of ratification may be proposed by the Congress; provided that no amendment which may be made prior to the year one thousand eight hundred and eight shall in any manner affect the first and fourth clauses in the ninth section of the first article, and that no State, without its consent, shall be deprived of its equal suffrage in the Senate." The significance of the provisos which conclude this section will be discussed in a later note on the limits of sovereign power. Apart from these provisos, the authorities to which reference is made in the section need to be distinguished according as they are initiative or sanctioning : — (0) Authorities of Initiation. These are either — (1^ Two-thirds of both Houses of Congress, or (2) Conventions summoned on the application of two-thirds of the States' legislatures. (4) Authorities of Eatification. These are either — (1) The legislatures of three-fourths of the several States, or (2) Conventions in three-fourths of the several States. Can the sovereignty be located under conditions so complex) In answer to this question I will venture to state two conclusions which are suggested by the letter of the section without reference to the history of its interpretation by American practice and American judges. (1) We are not entitled to say that the sovereign is con- stituted of the National and Provincial governments together with the organization of the Bepublic behind them. On the one hand, an amendment of the Constitution proposed by Conventions summoned on the application of two-thirds of the States legis- latures and ratified by the legislatures of ' three-fourths of the States, might limit the power of the Congress, though never assented to by that body. On the other hand, an amendment of the Constitution proposed by two-thirds of both Houses of the Congress and ratified by Conventions in three-fourths of the States, might limit the power of the State Legislatures, though never assented to by them. The ^National and Provincial govern- ments are accordingly subordinate to the sovereign. The fact that in a given case they may chance to form part of it, only involves the consequence that they are capable of appearing in another than their normal capacity. 154 FORMS OF GOVERNMENT (2) The sovereignty, then, must be looked for in the organi- zation of the Kepublic behind the National and Provincial govern- ments. That organization is varying in constitution, and difficult to arouse to action. Though when once aroused its positively declared will may be omnipotent, the complications of procedure and the exacting requirements as to majorities have the practical result of almost ensuring its eternal .slumber. In a word, al- though sovereignty exists within the State, and although there are means provided for the actualization of that sovereignty in authoritative organizations known to the law, those means can scarcely be deemed adequate to the needs of a great and rapidly developing Nationality. CHAPTER V THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN. POWER 309. From the various shapes which sovereignty may assume or from the various possible forms of supreme government, I proceed to the limits, real and imaginary, of sovereign or supreme? power. 310. Every positive law, or every law simply and strictly The easen- so called, is set, directly or circuitously, b y a sovereign !^°''" person or body , to a member or members of the independent positive political society wherein that person or body is sovereign or ^*^' *°^ supreme. It follows that the power of a monarch properly quenoe so called, or the power of a sovereign number in its col- thereof, legiate and sovereign capacity, is incapable of legal limit a- ^ tion. A monarch or sovereign number bound by a legal duty, were subject to a higher or superior sovereign : that is to say, a monarch or sovereign number bound by a legal duty, were sovereign and not sovereign, ^u preme power \ limite d bypositive la w, is a flat contra dip.f.inn in tfirr^s. I S 311. ISqt: would a political society escape from legal despotism, although the power of the sovereign were bounded by legal restraints. The power of the superior ji sovereign immediately imposing the restraints, or the power |i of some other sovereign superior to that superior, would still be absolutely free from the fetters of positive law. For | ^ unless the imagined restraints were ultimately imposed by a sovereign not in a state of subjection to a higher or superior sovereign, a series of sovereigns ascending to infinity would 155 < 156 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER govern the imagined community. Which is impossible and absurd. Attempts 312. Monarchs and sovereign bodies hav€J attempted to of sover- oblige themselves, or to oblige the successors to their sover- eigns to oblige eign powers. But m spite of such attempts the position them- that ' sovereign power is incapable of legal limitation ' will sucoea'sors, ^°^<^ JiBiKfilsany or without exception. The immediate author of a law of the kind, or any of the sovereign succes- sors to that immediate author, may abrogate the law at pleasure. And though the law be not abrogated, the sover- eign for the time being is not constrained to observe it by a legal or political sanction. For if the sovereign for the time being were legally bound to observe it, that present sover- eign would be in a state of subjection to a higher or superior sovereign. As it regards the successors to the sover- eign or supreme powers, a law of the kind amounts, at the most, to a rule of positive morality. As it regards its im- mediate author, it is merely a law by a metaphor. For if we would speak with propriety, we cannot speak of a law set by a man to himself : though a man may adopt a prin- ciple as a guide to his own conduct, and may observe it as he would observe it if he were bound to observe it by a sanction. 313. For example : The sovereign Roman people solemnly voted or resolved, that they would never pass, or even take into consideration, what X will venture to denominate a biU of pains and penalties. This solemn resolution or vote was passed with the forms of legislation, and was inserted in the twelve tables in the following imperative terms : privilegia ne irroganto. By that resolution or vote, the sovereign people adopted, and commended to their successors in the sovereignty, an ethical principle or maxim. The present and future sovereign which the resolution affected to obligei was not bound 6r estopped by it. Privileges enacted in spite THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 157 of it by the sovereign Boman people, were not illegal. The Roman tribunals might not have treated them as legally invalid acts, although they conflicted with the maxim, wear- ing the guise of a law, privilegia ne irroganto. 314. Again: By the authors of the union between Eng- land and Scotland, an attempt was made to oblige the legis- lature, which, in consequence of that union, is sovereign in both countries. It is declared in the Articles and Acts, that the preservation of the Church of England, and of the Kirk of Scotland, is a fundamental condition of the union : or, in other words, that the Parliament of Great Britain shall not abolish those churches, or make an essential change in their structures or constitutions. Now, so long as the bulk of either nation shall regard its established church with love and respect, the abolition of the church by the British Par- liament would be an immoral act ; for it would violate posi- tive morality which obtains with the bulk of the nation. Assuming that the church establishment is commended by the revealed law, the abolition would be irreligious : or, assuming that the continuance of the establishment were commended by general utility, the abolition, as generally pernicious, would also amount to a sin. But no man, talk- ing with a meaning, would call a parliamentary abolition of either or both of the churches an illegal act. Por if the parliament for the time being be sovereign in England and Scotland, itcannot be bo und legall y by that condition of the union which affects to confer immortality upon those ecclesi- astical institutions. That condition of the union is not a positive law, but is counsel or advice offered by the authors of the union to future supreme legislatures.* 314. Q. (1) That a legal sovereign cannot be subject to legal limitation follows from the very definition of the term. But may there not be a state without a legal sovereign? Examine especially the case of a Federal State with a written constitution containing no provision for its amendment. Note. — The limits of sovereign potoer. — I propose to examine 158 THE LIMITS OF SOVEEEIGN POWER The epithet imconati- tutional. 315. By the two examples which I have now adduced, I am led to consider the meanings of the epithet uncondUu- tional, as it is distinguished from the epithet illegal, and as it is applied to conduct of a monarch, or a sovereign number in the present place the more important of the limitations which are alleged to exist upon the supreme organized power in states, and to consider to what extent these limitations invalidate the Austinian doctrine. They may be classified for purposes of convenience under one or other of the following heads : , (1) Limitations in. fact, arising from — i (a) The character of the rulers. ! \h) The resistance of the governed. (c ) International relations. (d) Physical impossibilities. :" (2) Limitations in law, arisi^ig from — (a) Conflict with the prevailing doctrine of the sphere of State action. (6) Conflict with ordinary positive law. (c) Conflict with a superior law — Divine, Natural, Customary, or Constitution al. (1) Limitations in'fact. — The existence of these is fully admitted by Austin. A few illustrations will suffice, (a) The rulers are human, and therefore subject to the weaknesses, the ambitions, the desires, the limitations of other men. A great statesman is reported to have said that the average intelligence of the members of his Cabinet was probably not higher than the intelligence of the humbler tradesman. But, whether rulers be wise or not, their aims and policy are largely the product of their day and generation. They cannot do what they desire, and even what they desire is largely predetermined. "People," observes Professor Dicey, "sometimes ask the idle question why the Pope does not introduce this or that reform. The true answer is that a Revolutionist is not the kind of man who becomes a Pppe."^ (6) Rulers are certain to provoke the resistance of the governed if they do not keep within 6ertain limits. However wise and however noble they may be, they cannot force their views on a reluctant people, (c) Apart froin the humanity alike of the rulers and of the subjects, the will of the rulers is limited by the fact that a State is not aJoiie in the world. Other States exist, and have aspirations which are not always friendly. , A State possessed of a consuming desire foi moral and intellectual elevation may find itself exterminated by ■» neighbouring state which has set its heart upon the humbler ' " Law of the Constitution," 5th ed., p. 77. THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 159 in its collegiate and sovereign capacity. The epithet uncon- stitutional, as thus opposed and applied, is sometimes used with a meaning which is more general and vague, and is sometimes used with a meaning which is more special and definite. I will begin with the former. object of military efficiency, (d) Finally, many things which from some points of view might be very desirable, may be physi- cally impossible. Montesquieu admitted that even the British Parliament could not make a man a woman. The great American Bepublic cannot change the hue of the negro. (2) Limitations in law. — "We are here in more debatable terri- tory. Three cases deserve consideration, according as the alleged limitations arise from (a) conflict with the prevailing doctrine as to the State's sphere of action, (6) conflict with positive law, " (c) conflict with a law alleged to be superior to positive law. (a) lAmitations arising from conflict with the prevailing doctrine of the State's spliere of action. — The power of the Legislature, contended Locke, is to preserve and not to destroy ; it cannot possibly be absolutely arbitrary over the lives and fortunes of the people. 1 What a people could not (rightly) ordain over itself, ought not to be ordained by the Legislator over the People, declared Kaht.^ In the medieval State, the sphere of State action was limited by much narrower considerations. The Church in parti- ( cular occupied a privileged position; the clergy enjoyed manyi immunities, the inviolability of which was accepted at times asi completely as the order of nature. Under such conditions the ' Austinian doctrine was not tenable. The modern state, however, has taken a broader view of its function, and has affected to concern itself with the moral and intellectual elevation of the people. It has abolished the privileges of the clergy, and ex- ,^ tended the authority of law over all subjects. Modern theory, 1 differentiating between Politics and Law, relegates to the former the analysis and discussion of such doctrines as those suggested by Locke and Kant, and attributes to the supreme State organization a legally absolute power of defining its own sphere of action. What that organization ordains will not be questioned by the law courts on the ground of incompatibility with the State's purpose. Such questioning as may arise will be referred t6 other hmitations which have yet to be considered. (b) Limitations alleged to exist as a result of positive law. — Ihering, in his work on the Evolution of Law, affirms the existence ' Of. " Second Treatise on Government," § 142. 2 " PrincipleB of Politics," p. 58. 160 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 316. (1) In every independent political society, there are principles or maxims which the sovereign habitually ob- serves, and which the bulk of the society, or the bulk of its of three distinct phases of legal development. In the first phase, law is no more than unilaterally binding particular command ; in the second phase, it is unilaterally binding general command; in the third phase, it is bilaterally binding general command. In the second phase, the lawgiver may intend to respect the hv, but he does not wish to assure it against the fluctuations of his own caprice. In the third phase, the lawgiver holds himself "■ bound by the law so long as it exists. " Only in the third phase can the people feel that invincible confidence which is essential to the building up of character. ... If Eeligion may be defined as faith in God, Law may be defined as faith in the State. "^ The argument appears to me to be unanswerable. As I shall endeavoiit to show later on, the fact that a sovereign makes a law does not prevent him from being bound by it so long as it exists, if he elects to be bound by it, invariably respects it, and permits its enforcement even as against himself. In the modem state such conditions are taken for granted. Nevertheless, positive law must not be regarded as a limitation upon the sovereign in the sense of the term limitation which is at present under discussion. The sovereign can change a law at will, and is only bound by it, so long as he does not choose to amend or repeal it. (c) Limitations alleged to exist as a result of conflict with superior law. — These involve a more serious qualification of the Austinian doctrine. They allege that the highest organization known to law may be bound absolutely by virtue of some law declared to be superior to its will — Law Divine, Natural, Customary, or Constitutional. Divine and Natural Law are more important as limitations in medieval than in modern times. Speaking of the State and Law in the Middle Ages, Dr. Gierke writes: "Men taught that the highest power on earth was subject to the rules of Natural Law. They stood above the Pope and above the Kaiser, above the Kuler and above the Sovereign People, nay, above the whole Community of Mortals. Neither statute nor act of government, neither resolution of the People, nor custom, could break the bonds that thus were set." ^ A like doctrine has been affirmed by the courts in times comparatively modern.' The fact that it is no longer maintained is due partly to the > " L'Evolution du droit," §§ 152-69. 2 "Political Theories of the Middle Age," p. 75. s Of. Bonhams Case, 8 Rep. 118. Day and Savadge, Hob. 85-7 ant! supra §§ 191-7 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 161 influential members, regard with feelings of approbation. Not unfrequently, such maxims are expressly adopted by the sovereign or state. More commonly, they are not ex- growth of doctrines jof _aljgsl3Jtfi_Jgveigignty, and partly to an increased confidence in the rulers arising from the publicity of modem life and the growth of pohtical liberty. Customary Law, also, as a legal limitation upon the supreme power, may be regarded as belonging to a past order of things. Constitutional Law, on the other hand, cannot be dismissed so briefly. Two cases in particular have given rise to practical difficulties in apply- ing the doctrine of legislative omnipotence — the attempts of sovereigns to bind their successors, and the rules of fundamental Constitutional Law. The attempts of sovereigns to bind their successors have been generally held invalid. Legal interpretation in this case appears to have a sound basis in both utility and logic. Let us suppose that the British Parliament passes a Statute which purports to be unrepealable. At least three distinct interpretations are possible. The Courts might hold (a) that the Statute was binding until directly or indirectly repealed ; (b) that the Statute was binding until expressly repealed; (c) that the Statute was wholly unre- pealable. The course of legal interpretation in England suggests the probability of the first -mentioned solution. The Act of Union with Scotland provided that the Presbyterian Church should remain for ever established in Scotland. Within four years after the Union, an Act was passed which involved a violation of this provision. The validity of the later Act has been upheld by the House of Lords. But even if the Courts declared that a Statute purporting to be unrepealable was binding until expressly repealed, the declaration would involve no absolute limitation upon Parliament, since Parliament could at any moment effect such a repeal. It is just conceivable, however, that a Statute of the kind supposed might be held to be absolutely unrepealable. If such an interpretation were made, and acquiesced in, then it would have to be admitted that Parliament was no longer sover- eign. The interpretation would be contrary to utility. In my opinion, it would also be logically unsound, for the reason that an authority conferred upon a Statute by Parliament cannot be greater than Parliament, and ought to be held withdrawable by Parliament. Kules of fundamental constitutional law stand on a different footing. They appear at times to impose an absolute limitation upon the supreme organization. Bodin, though a strong advocate of absolutist doctrines of sovereignty, admitted the existence of kge$ imperii like the Salic Law, which no sovereign could trana- 162 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER pressly adopted, but are simply imposed by opinions preva- V lent in the community. In either case the sovereign or l^te is bound to observe them by merely moral sanctions. ' Or (changing the phrase) in case it ventured to deviate from gresB.^ In more modern times, the division between laws which the ordinary Legislature could amend and the laws which it could not, has given rise to difficulties in applying the doctrine of sovereignity. Such difficulties are now generally overcome by regarding sovereignity ois vested in the power which can amend the Constitution. But what if there be no such power? Where a limitation is imposed by a supreme organization it ought to be held removable by that organization. Where, however, it is imposed by some power superior to that organization, as by a Eevolutionary Assembly, the logical result appears to be that the limitation can only be removed by appeal to that Assembly. la all probability, however, an attempt would be made to evade such a consequence. Italian jurists, when called upon to interpret the Italian Constitution which made no provision for its amendment, held that the power of amending must be assumed to have been implicity conferred on the legislative body. It would have been more logical, perhaps, to have attributed it to the monarch. " Where the origin of the Constitution is due to a grant from the ruler, it would seem that the same competence that enables him to make such a grant would enable him to alter its provisions at will." 2 An interesting illustration of the difficulties of the kind under consideration is offered by the American Constitution. The fiftl section of that Constitution, after defining the organization beliind Federal and states' governments, proceeds to impose a limitation upon this organization by requiring that no state shall be deprived, save by its own consent, of its privilege to equal representation in the Federal Senate^ An amendment of the Constitution intro- ducing the principle of representation in the Federal Senate on « basis of population, if not accepted by all the states, would be invalid, though approved by the powers which for every other purpose answer the description of a legal sovereign. But what would happen if the powers last referred to, approved of an amendment of the fifth section which omitted' the proviso as to the conditions under which the states might be deprived of n equal representation in the Senate ? It appears to me that tll« — Courts would be compelled to hold such an amendment invalid » "DeRepublica,"!. VIII. > Willoughby, " Nature of the State," p. 215. THE LIMITS OP SOVEREIGN POWER 163 a maxim of the kind in question, it would not and could not incur a legal pain or penalty, but it probably would incur censure, and might chance to meet with resistance. until it had received the assent of all the Btates. The fifth sec- tion as it stands is evidently framed with the object of prescribing a sovereign organization which shall vary in constitution, not merely according to the will of certain parties, but also according to the nature of the proposed change. In other words, the famous proviso implies, not a limitation upon the sovereign power, but a special organization of the sovereign power for a special purpose. But whether this logical interpretation would be adopted to-day is apparently doubtful. Professor Burgess, in his chapter on the Sovereignty in the Constitution of the United States, writes : "From the standpoint of political science I regard this legal power of the legislature of a single commonwealth to resist suc- cessfully the will of the sovereign as unnatural and erroneous. It furnishes the temptation for the powers back of the Constitution to reappear in revolutionary organization and solve the question by power, which bids defiance to a solution according to law. There is a growing feeling among our jurists and publicists that, in the interpretation of the Constitution we are not to be strictly held by the intentions of the framers, especially since the whole fabric of our State has been so changed by the results of rebellion and civil war. They are beginning to feel, and rightly so, that present conditions, relations, and requirements should be the chief con- sideration, and that when the language of the Constitution will bear it, these should determine the interpretations. From this point of view all the great reasons of political science and of jurisprudence would justify the adoption of a new law of amendment by the general course of amendment now existing, without the attach- ment of the exception ; and in dealing with the great questions of public law, we must not, as Mirabeau finely expressed it, lose the grande morale in the petite morale."^ Summary. — If the foregoing observations be sound, it must be admitted that, apart from the de facto limitations whose existence Austin admits, other limitations upon a power claiming to be supreme have been recognized from time to time by legal theory. Limitations alleged to exist as a result of conflict with ordinary positive law may be placed on one side, since such law may be changed by the lawmaker, and may therefore be said to bind him, but not to limit his legislative power. Limitations alleged to exist as a result of conflict with a doctrine of the sphere of State action, or with Divine, Natural, or Customary law, belong » "Political Science and Constitutional Law," 1, 152, 153. 164 THE LIMITS OP SOVEREIGN POWER - 317. Now, if a law or other act of a monarch or sovereigi number conflict with a maxim of the kind to which I havi adverted above, the law or 6ther act may be called un constitutional (in that more general meaning which is some times given to the epithet). For example: The expodfacti statutes which are styled acts of attainder, may be callet unconstitutional, though they cannot be called illegal. Foi they conflict with a Drinciplfl . of legislation which parliamenl has habitually observed, and which is regarded with appro- bation by the bulk of the British community. 318j In short, when we style an act of a sovereign an unconstitutional act (with that more general import which is sometimes given to the epithet), we mean, I believe, this ; That the act, is inconsistent with some given principle oi maxim: that the given supreme government has expressly adopted the principle, or, at least, has habitually observed it: that the bulk of the given society, or the bulk of its influential members, regard the principle with approbation: and that, since the supreme government has habitually observed the principle, and since the bulk of the society to medieval lather than modern legal thought. Limitations al- leged to exist as a result of conflict with the declared will of a sovereign predecessor seem to me also irrelevant, since the authority conferred by a power on a law cannot be greater than the power itself, and can therefore be withdrawn by that power. Where, however, the limitations are alleged to exist as a result of conflict with fundamental constitutional law, a case of which a Federal Constitution without an authority for amending i;he Con- stitution would be a good example, the defender of the Austinisn doctrine is driven into a corner from which he cannot- easily escape. In such a case he may urge that the power of amending the Constitution must be assumed to have devolved on the Federal legislative body. But this is to beg the question at issue ; the assumption is a legal fiction which can only be justified on the plea of practical needs. In a word, the Austinian position that a (supreme legislature is incapable of legal limitation, is a position which does not rest, as Austin supposes, upon logicaL necessitieSi but upon the humbler ground of expediency. ^ I THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 166 regard it with approbation, the act in question must thwart the expectations of the latter, and must shock their opinions and sentiments. Unless we mean this, we merely mean that we deem the act in question generally pernicious : or that, without a definite reason for the disapprobation which we feel, we regard the act with dislike. 319. (2) The epithet unconstitutional as applied to con- duct of a sovereign, and as used with the meaning which is more special and definite, imports that the conduct in question conflicts with constitutional law. And by the expression constitutional law, I mean the positive morality, or the compound of positive morality and positive law, which figeguthft. -Constitution^ jr^ttufiture of the given supreme government. I mean the positive morality, or the compound of positive morality and positive law, which deterpaines the bharacter of the person, or the respective characters of the persons, in whom, for the time being, the sovereignty shall reside : and, supposing the government in question an aristocracy or government of a number, which determines moreover the mode wherein the sovereign powers shall be shared by the constituent members of the sovereign numbei- or body. 320. N"ow, against a monarch properly so called, or against a sovereign body in its collegiate and sovereign capacity, constitutional law is positive morality merely, or is enforced merely by moral sanctions: though, as I shall show hereafter, it may amount to positive law, or may be enforced by legal sanctions, against the members of the body considered severally. The sovereign for the time being, or the pre- decessors of the sovereign, may have expressly adopted, and expressly promised to observe it. But whether constitutional law has thus been expressly adopted, or simply consists of principles current in the political community, it is merely guarded, against the sovereign, by sentim pi^tiji nr fpplings 166 THE LIMITS OF SOVEBEIGN POWER ^ of the governed. Consequently, although an act of the sovereign which violates constitutional law, may be styled with propriety unconstitutional, it is not an infringement of law simply and strictly so called, and cannot be styled with propriety illegal. 321. For example : From the ministry of Cardinal Bichelieu down to the great revolution, the king for the time being was virtually sovereign in France. But, in the same country, and during the same period, a traditional maxim cherished by the courts of justice, and rooted in the affections of the bulk of the people, determined the succes- sion to the throne : It determined that the throne, on the demise of an actual occupant, should invariably be taken by the person who then might happen to be heir to it agreeably to the canon of inheritance which was named the SaUc Law. Now, in case an actual king, by a royal ordinance or law, had attempted to divert the throne to his only daughter and child, that royal ordinance or law might have been styled with perfect propriety an unconstitutional act. But.yiegal \it could not have been called : for, inasmuch as the actual Iking was virtually sovereign, he was inevitably independent I of legal obligation. Nay, if the governed had resisted the unconstitutional ordinance, their resistance would have been illegal or a breach of positive law, though consonant to the positive morality which is styled constitutional law, and perhaps to that principle of utility which is the test of positive rules. 322. Again : An act of the British parliament vesting the sovereignty in the king, or vesting the sovereignty in the king and the upper or lower house, would essentially alter the structure of our present supreme government, and might therefore be styled with propriety an unconstitutional law. In case the imagined statute were also generally pernicious, and in case it offended moreover the generality or bulk of I THE LIMITS OP SOVEREIGN POWER 167 the nation, it might be styled irreligious and immoral as well as unconstitutional. But to call it illegal were absurd : for if the parliament for the time being be sovereign in the united kingdom, it is the author, directly or oircuitously, ot all our positive law, and exclusively sets the measure of legal justice and injustice.* 322. Q. (1) Draw a list of acts illustrating the use of the expression " unconstitutional " in both of the senses indicated by Austin. (2) Would the following be unconstitutional in either of the senses indicated by Austin : (a) An Act of Parliament passed with the object of making the King liable to criminal process 1 (b) An Act of Parliament introducing Protection, (1) Before consulting the constituencies; (2) After? (3) Austin speaks of Constitutional Law as a compound of positive law and positive morality. What is the test for deter- mining to which of these two classes a rule of Constitutional law belongs ? Apply your answer to the rule regulating the succession to the throne in an absolute monarchy. / Note. — Austin discusses the epithet unconstitutional, as it is oppoted to illegal, and as it is applied to the conduct of the sovereign — meaning by the term, I take it, legal sovereign. The fact has been overlooked by some of his critics, who accuse Austin of refusing to admit that any rule of Constitutional Law can be a rule of positive law. Such a statement is sufficiently refuted by sections 324-30, which affirm the legal liabilities of the several members of a sovereign body. In sections 315-22 Austin is dis- cussing, not the question whether Constitutional Law is law or not, but the question whether any rule of Constitutional Law can impose legal limits upon the sovereign. Austin's description of Constitutional Law as a compound of positive law and positive morality recalls the distinction, which Professor Dicey has developed with so much skill, between Con- stitutional Law proper and the Convention of the Constitution — the former being a body of rules recognized by the Courts, as, for example, the rule that the King can do no wrong : the latter being a body of maxims or practices which, though they regulate tha ordinary conduct of the crown, of ministers, and of other persons under the Constitution, are not in strictness laws at all, e.g. the rule that the King must assent to any Bill which has been passed by both Houses of Parliament. Austin's statement that an Act of the Imperial Parliament 168 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER The mean- 323. It is affirmed by Hobbes, in his masterly treatises on H^if ■ go"^emmeiit, that ' no law can be unjust : ' which proposition proposi- has been deemed by many, an immoral or pernicious paradox, tion that jf ^g JqqJj a,t the scope of the treatises in which it occurs, i*n be °^ ^^^^ S't the passages by which it is immediately followed, anjnst.' we shall find that the proposition is neither pernicious nor paradoxical; but is merely a truism put in unguarded terms. His meaning is obviously this : that 'no positive law is legally unjust.' And the decried proposition, as thus imderstood, is indisputably true. For positive law is the measure or test — . of legal justice and injustice : and, consequently, if positive law might be legally unjust, positive law might be unjust as measured or tried by itself. For just or unjust, justice or injustice, is a term of relative and varying import. By the epithet just, we mean that a given object, to which we apply ■ the epithet, accords with a given law to which we refer it as I to a test. And as that which is just conforms to a deter- minate law, justice is the conformity of a given object to the vesting the sovereign power in the King or either of the Houses would be perfectly valid has been challenged by Professor Clark, who remarks : " I apprehend the conduct of the Parliament would be called, and reasonably called by all people, illegal." ^ ■ The time for defending such a view is now past. The British Parliament is a legal sovereign; and one of the great advantages of having a legal sovereign is to make a revolution under the forms of law '. possible. While supporting Austin on this point, I am not prepared to subscribe to the position that, as against the Parlia- ment, Constitntional Law is positive morality. The fact that Parliament can change law at will does not entitle it to regard that law as positive morality against itself. So long as the law exists. Parliament is capable of being bound by it. The contrary view belongs, in my opinion, to a very undeveloped or transitional order of legal ideas. Constitutional Law .is no legal Umit upon the British ParHament, not because the Parliament cannot be bound by it, but because the Parliament can repeal or amend it.' ' "PracticalJurisprudence," p. I7fcv JXt » Cf. notes to § 314 and § 357. C. a, ^j^ THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 169 same or a similar measure : for justice is the abstract term which corresponds to the epithet just. By the epithet i unjust, we mean that the given object conforms not to the 1 given law. And since the term injustice is merely the corresponding abstract, it signifies the nonconformity of the given and compared object to that determinate law which is assumed as the standard of comparison. — ^And since such is the relative nature of justice and injustice, one and the same act may be just and unjust as tried by different measures. Without doubt, the term justice or in- justice sometimes denotes emphatically, conformity or non- conformity to the ultimate measure or test : namely, the law of God. This is the meaning annexed to justice, when law and justice are opposed: when a positive human rule is styled unjust.* 324. When I affirm that the power of a sovereign is The legal incapable of legal limitation, I always mean by a ' sove- U»^>li*y "' members reign,' a monarch properly so called, or a sovereign number of ^ in its coUegate and sovereign capacity. Considered coUec- Bovereigu tively, or considered in its corporate character, a sovereign ° ^' number is sovereign and independent : but, considered sever- ally, the individuals and smaller aggregates composing that sovereign number are subject to the supreme body of which they are component parts. Consequently, though the body is inevitably independent of legal or political duty, any of the individuals or aggregates whereof the body is composed 323. Q. (1) Illustrate the Austinian point of view by dis- cussing the justice of the following : (a) A decision of the House of Lords which overrules an earlier decision of an inferior tribunal. (b) A decision of the House of Lords which establishes a new rule of law. (c) An Act of ParHament which involves an admitted departure from the spirit of our constitution. (2) Is it permissible to describe every act not forbidden by law as just ? 170 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER may be legally bound by laWs of which the body is the author. For example : A member of the house of lords or a member of/' the house of commons may be legally bound by an act of parliament, which, as one of the sovereign legis- lature, he has concurred with others in making. Nay, he may be legally bound by statutes, or by rules njiade judicially, which have immediately proceeded from subject or sub- ordinate legislatures : for a law which proceeds immediately from a subject or subordinate legislature is set by the author- ity of the supreme. 325. And hence an important difference between mon- archies or governments of one, and aristocracies or govern- ments of a number. 326. Considered severally, the members of a sovereign body, even as members of the body, may be legally bound by laws of which the body is the author, and which regard the constitution of the given supreme government. — In case it be clothed with a legal sanction, or the means of enforcing it judicially be provided by its author, a law set by the body to any of its own members is properly a positive law : It is properly a positive law, or a law strictly so called, although it be imposed upon the obliged party as a member of the/' body which sets it. — In case the law be invested with a' legal or political sanction, and regard the constitution or structure of the given supreme government, a breach of the j law, by the party to whom it is set, is not only wnconstitu- tional, but is also illegal. The breach of the law is imcon- stitutional, inasmuch as the violated law regards the consti- tution of the state. The breach of the law is also illegal, inasmuch as the violated law may be enforced by judicial procedure. 327. For example : The king, as a limb of the parliament, might be punishable by act of parliament, in the event of his transgressing the limits which the constitution has set THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 171 to his authority: in the event, for instance, of his pretend- ing to give to a proclamation of his own the legal effect of a statute emanating from the sovereign legislature. Or the members of either house might be punishable by act of parliament, if, as forming a limb of the parliament, they exceeded their constitutional powers : if, for instance, they pretended to give that legal effect to an ordinance or resolu- tion of their body. 328. Where, then, the supreme government is a monarchy or government of one, constitutional law, as against that government, is inevitably nothing more than positive moral- ity. Where the supreme government is an aristocracy or government of a number, constitutional law, as against the members of that government, may either consist of positive morality, or of a compound of positive morality and positive law. Against the sovereign body in its corporate and sover-| eign character, it is inevitably nothing more than positive} morality. But against the members considered severally, be they individuals or be they aggregates of individuals, it may be guarded by legal or political, as well as by moral sanctions. 329. In fact or practice, the members considered sever- ally, but considered as members of the body, are commonly free, wholly or partially, from legal or political restraints. For example : The king, as a limb of the parliament, is not responsible legally, or cannot commit a legal injury : and, as partaking in conduct of the assembly to which he immedi- ately belongs, a member of the house of lords, or a member of the house of commons, is not amenable to positive law. But though this freedom from legal restraints may be highly useful or expedient, it is not necessary or inevitable. Con- sidered severally, the members of a sovereign body, be they individuals or be they aggregates of individuals, may clearly be legally amenable, even as members of the body, to laws which the body imposes. 172 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 330. And here I may remark, that if a member considered severally, but considered as a member of the body, be wholly or partially free from legal or political obligation, that legally irresponsible aggregate, or that legally irresponsible individual, is restrained or debarred in two ways from an unconstitutional exercise of its legally unlimited power. 1. Like the sovereign body of which it is a member, it is obliged or restrained morally : that is to say, it is controlled by opinions and sentiments current in the given community. 2. If it affected to issue a command which it is not em- powered to issue by its constitutional share in the sover- eignty, its unconstitutional command would not be legally binding, and disobedience to that command would therefore not be illegal. Nay, although it would not be responsible legally for thus exceeding its powers, those whom it com- missioned to execute its unconstitutional command, would probably be amenable to positive law", if they tried to accom- plish their mandate. For example : If the king or either of the houses, by way of proclamation or ordinance, affected to establish a law equivalent to an act of parliament, the pre- tended statute would not be legally binding. And althougli the king or the house would not be responsible legally for this supposed violation of constitutional law or morality, those whom the king or the house might order to enforce the statute, would be liable civilly or criminally, if they at- tempted to execute the order. The 331. I have affirmed above, that, taken or considered severally, all the individuals and aggregates composing a sovereign number are subject to the supreme body of which they are component parts. By the matter contained in the last paragraph, I am led to clear the proposition to which I have now adverted, from a seeming difficulty. 332. Generally speaking, if a member of a sovereign body, taken or considered severally, be not amenable to positive limited monarch THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 173 law, it is merely as a member of the body that he is free from legal obligation. Generally speaking, he is bound, in his other characters, by legal restraints. But in some of the mixed aristocracies which are styled limited monarchies, the so-called limited monarch is exempted or absolved com- pletely from legal or political duty. For example : Accord- ing to a maxim of the English law, the king is incapable of committing wrong : that is to say, he is not responsible legally for aught that he may please to do, or for any for- bearance or omission. 333. But though he is absolved completely from legal or political duty, it cannot be thence inferred that the king is sovereign or supreme, or that he is not in a state of subjec- tion to the sovereign or supreme parliament of which he is a constituent member. Of the numerous proofs of this nega- tive conclusion, which it were easy to produce, the following will amply suffice. — 1. Although he is free in fact from the fetters of positive law, he is not incapable of legal obliga- tion. A law of the sovereign parliament, made with his own assent, might render himself and his successors legally responsible. But a monarch properly so called, or a sover- eign number in its corporate and sovereign character, can- not be rendered, by any contrivance, amenable to positive law. — 2. If he affected to transgress the limits which the constitution has set to his authority, disobedience on the part of the governed to his unconstitutional commands would not be illegal : whilst the ministers or instruments of his unconstitutional commands, would be legally amenable, for their unconstitutional obedience, to 'laws of that sover- eign body whereof he is merely a limb. But commands issued by sovereigns cannot be disobeyed by their subjects without an infringement of positive law- whilst the minis- ters or instruments of such a sovereign command, cannot be legally responsible to any portion of the community, except- 174 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER ing the author of their mandate. — 3. He habitually obeys the laws set by the sovereign body of which he is a con- stituent member. If he did not, he must speedily yield his office to a less refractory successor, or the British constitu- tion must speedily expire. If he habitually broke the laws set by the sovereign body, the other members of the body would probably devise a remedy : though » prospective and definite remedy, fitted to meet the contingency, has not been provided by positive law, or even by constitutional morahty. Consequently, he is bound by a cogent sanction to respect the laws of the body, although that cogent sanction is not predetermined and certain. A law which is set by the opinion of the upper and lower houses (besides a law which is set by the opinion of the community at large) constrains him to observe habitually the proper and positive laws which are set by the entire parliament. — But habitually obeying the laws of a determinate and sovereign body, he is not properly sovereign : for such habitual obedience consists not with that independence which is one of the essentials of sovereignty.* 333. Q. Define the expression " limited monarchy." Note. — In the note to Section 289 a brief reference was made to the view that sovereignty in the British Constitution might be regarded as divisible into Legislative and Executive. In opposi- tion to that view, I held that the King in Council is legally subordinate to the King in Parliament. In actual practice, the Executive fulfils its function subject to the general direction of Parliament. From the point of view of legal theory, an Act of Parliament remodelling the Executive or restricting its powers would be completely vaUd. The position is criticized by Professor Salmond, who remarks that the Crown "is not merely a part of the Legislature, but also a part without whose consent the Legislature cannot exercise any fragment of its own power. . . . A power over a person which cannot be exercised without that person's consent is no power over him at all." ^ With all deference to this acute writer, it seems to me that questions ' Jurisprudence," pp. 629-31. THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 175 334. But if sovereign or supreme power be incapable of Thenotnre legal limitation, or if every supreme government be legally °j. ^j^ absolute, wherein (it may be asked) doth political liberty liberty, consist, and how do the supreme governments which are commonly deemed free, differ from the supreme governments which are commonly deemed despotic ? 335. I answer, that political or civil liberty is the liberty from legal obligation, which is left or granted by a sovereign government to any of its own subjects : and that, since the power of the government is incapable of legal limitation, the government is legally free to abridge their political liberty, at its own pleasure or discretion. 336. Political or civil liberty has been erected into an idol, and extolled with extravagant praises by doting and fanatical worshippers. But political or civil liberty is not more worthy of eulogy than political or legal restraint. Political or civil liberty, like political or legal restraint, may be generally useful, or generally pernicious ; and it is not as of fact and law are here confused. If a radical change in the constitution of the Executive is approved by both Houses, whether the King assents to it or rejects it, he does so, not in his executive capacity as executing laws, but in his legislative capacity as making them. Legal theory requires us to differentiate between the King or the Crown in these two capacities. Professor Salmond appears to me to illustrate the difficulties which ari^ in the absence of such a differentiation when he adds that the British Constitution has a sovereign Judicature as well as a sovereign Legislature and sovereign Executive. If our sovereignty were really of this threefold character insoluble difficulties must arise as to whether in a particular case one of the sovereign powers had or hid not exceeded its sphere. In point of fact, differences might arise between our different governmental organs, but happily the Constitution provides an organization capable of dealing with all such differences. That organization is the King in Parliament, the final depositary of all governmental power, the living expression of the unity of the State. To assert an executive sovereignty or a judicial sovereignty involves a denial of the ideal unity of the King and Parliament — a unity as much a matter of law as the unity of the State is a matter of fact. 176 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER being liberty, but as conducing to the general good, that political or civil liberty is an object deserving applause. The final cause or purpose for which government ought to exist, is the furtherance of the common weal to the greatest ^possible extent. In so far as it attains its appropriate purpose by conferring rights upon its subject?, government attains that purpose through the medium of political liberty. But since it must impose a duty wherever it confers a right, and should also impose duties which have no corresponding rights, it is less through the medium of political liberty, than through that of legal restraint, that government must attain the purpose for which it ought to exist. To say that political liberty ought to be its principal end, or to say that its principal end ought to be legal restraint, is to talk absurdly: for each is merely a me^ to that furtherance of the common weal, which is the only ultimate object of good or beneficent sovereignty. But though both propositions are absurd, the latter of the two absurdities is the least remote from the truth. 337. Political or civil liberties rarely exist apart from corresponding legal restraints. Where persons in a state of subjection are free from legal duties, their hberties (generally speaking) would be nearly useless to themselves, unless they were protected in the enjoyment of their liberties, by legal duties on their fellows: that is to say, unless they had legal rights (importing such duties on their fellows) to those political liberties which are left them by the sovereign government. I am legally free, for example, to move from place to place, in so far as I can move from place to place consistently with my legal obligations: but this my political liberty would be but a sorry liberty unless my fellow-subjects were restrained by a political duty from assaulting and imprisoning my body. Through the ignorance or negligence of a sovereign government, some of the civil THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 177 liberties which it leaves or grants to its subjects, may not be protected against their fellows by answering legal duties: and some of those civil liberties may perhaps be protected 8u£Giciently by religious and moral obligations. But, speak- ing generally, a political or civil liberty is coupled with a legal r^ht to it: and, consequently, political liberty is fostered by that very political restraint from which the devotees of the idol liberty are so fearfully and blindly averse.' 337. Note. — The remarks of Austin as to the nature of political or civil liberty suggest three topics for consideration : the unity which underlies the different uses of the term " liberty " ; the distinc- tion between civil and political liberty ; and the relation between liberty and right. (1) The unity which underlies the different uses of the term " liberty." — This unity is found in the idea of freedom from some constraint which is external to the individual either in fact or in conception. The constraint may take one or other of several forms : — (a) The interference of one's fellow-citizens ; (6) The interference on the part of the ruling powers of the State ; (c) That interference with the development of one's true self, which happens when some momentary pleasure is pre- ferred to a permanent good. Restraint of the kind last mentioned may seem to need illustra- tion. "Love Virtue," said Milton, "she alone is free." So a dipso- maniac is said to be the slave of a depraved taste j a Don Juan the t ic*'im of the tyranny of passion. The apparent paradox involved in the differentiation of the two selves recalls the remark of Aris- totle that Nature implies complete development, and that the nature of a thing may be defined to be its condition when its growth is complete.^ The real self is thus conceived of as something different from the self actually existing at any particular moment, something which is becoming rather than in being, something which can only he reaUzed on the condition of rising above the flashes of momentary impulse, something which must have been present to the mind of Shakespeare when he wrote : " To thine own self be true." So Professor Bosanquet defines liberty as the condition of being ourselves. "There is something worthy of ' Pohtics," I, iL 178 THE LIMITS OF SOVEEEIGN POWER Govern- 338. From the nature of political or civil liberty, I turn ment free ^^ ^^^ supposed difference between free and despotic govern- despotic. ments. Dante in Kousseau's observation that the convicts in the galleys ,at Genoa had ' Liberty ' stamped on their chains. The fetters of 'the bad self are the symbols of freedom." ^ The region into which we are here transferred may seem remote ; but the nature of political and civil liberty will only be grasped by the student who has the courage to look occasionally beyond the immediate borders of his own special subject, and to examine that ideal of moral freedom which it is the purpose of civil and political liberty to promote. The truth of this statement will be apparent when we come to consider the conception of political liberty as consist- ing; in self-government. (2) The relation of civil to political liberty. — The freedom irom an external constraint which is fundamental in the concep- tion of liberty can only be assured in a society of human beings where each recognizes in others the claims which he makes for himself. The individual can only be free to do as he ought, on condition of recognizing that he is not free to do as he likes. •"-Liberty implies Law. We thus arrive at a conception of it as consisting in a certain power of self-determination residing alike in others and ourselves — a power not to do exactly as we wish but necessarily limited by reference to a like power in others — a power regulated by law. The expression "civil and political liberty" indicates the power of self-determination which is secured to individuals by the existing government and positive laws. The civil and political liberty which I enjoy is the power of self- determination which is assured to me by the State and the laws, and is protected from the arbitrary interference on the part of either my fellow-citizens or the officers of government. The expressions " civil liberty" and " political liberty," however, are not interchangeable. They are distinguished by reference to a positive element, the means,_gBiBlOTed for the assurance of the power of self-determination. Where we are thinking of that power, as secured to us by the laws, we employ the term " civil liberty." Where we are thinking of it as secured to us by such institutions as the franchise and representative government, wo employ the term " political liberty." In popular usage the positive element is more prominent in the conception of political liberty than in that of civil liberty, although it is implicit in both. In the development of the detail involved in the conceptions of civil and political libertv, continental usage is different from " Philosophical Theory of the State," p. 142 n. THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 179 339. Every supreme government is free from legal restraints; or (what is the same proposition dressed in a different phrase) every supreme government is legally demotic. The distinction, therefore, of governments into English. Thus M. Boutmy, after having defined civil liberty as the protection of person and property assured to the individual against the government, remarks that this protection must be guaranteed by political liberties such as the right of association and assembly, the freedom of the Press, and a national representation founded on a widely extended electoral franchise. The author then remarks that the right of association and assembly, and the freedom of the Press, are not regarded in England as political liberties, but as civil liberties. " They have never been raised to the dangerous dignity of constitutional prerogatives, but have been left in the position of purely private rights. They have always been regarded as corollaries contained in the fundamental postulate of personal liberty, from which they have become separated. The right of assembly proceeds directly from the right every man has to come, go, or stay where he likes. The right of association is simply a development of the right to enter into contracts. The liberty of the Press is a particular example of the liberty to think and speak." ^ Hitherto I have considered the terms civil liberty and political liberty as referring to actualities. The terms are sometimes used to designate idealities — the liberty which ought to exist as distin- guished from that which does exist. The ideal of political liberty is self-government — an ideal which can only be realized in a society where the restraints upon individuals which Uberty implies are self-imposed, not in the mere sense that they are popularly approved, but in the sense that they are formally made by the society through the direct vote of individual citizens, or through representatives whom those citizens have chosen and control. Used in a still deeper sense, political liberty as an ideal implies even more — the imposition of restraints in the interests of a common good — government of selves by selves in the interest of all. The individual is morally free where the true self triumpbs over the baser elements. The State is politically free when the restraints upon the action of its citizens are self-imposed in the interests of the well-being of all. In this connection the ideal of political liberty has a deeper meaning than is generally appreciated. It looks forward to a society wherein the wisdom and the virtue of the whole community triumph over the sinister interests of a class "The English People," p. 207. 180 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER free and despotic, can hardly mean that some of them are freer from restraints than others : or that the subjects of the governments which are denominated free, are protected against their governments by positive law. or of individuals — a condition to the realization of which a demo- cratic constitution, which is often made synonymous with political liberty, is but one of many means. (3) Austin'* use of the terms " liberty " and " right." The various dicta of Austin on this subject seem to indicate a lack of clearness and precision not usual with him. His general position, however, as it is indicated by a statement in a later lecture, appears to b& substantially accurate. "In liberty, the prominent or leading idea is the absence of restraint ; whilst the security for the enjoy- ment of that liberty is the secondary idea. Eight, on the other hand, denotes the protection and connotes the absence of re- straint."* The distthction may be illustrated by the following cases. One citizen has the liberty, or the right, to make a present to another citizen. If the paramount idea be that of the obliga- tion upon other citizens not to interfere with him in the exercise of this privilege, we may use the term "right." But if, as is more likely, the paramount idea be that the privilege to make gifts is part of that sphere of activity within which a man is free from external interference or control, we should use the term " liberty." Strictly speaking, we ought not to say that a man has a right to rise at six a.m. What we really mean is that he is at hberty to rise at that hour. We are not thinking of duties on the part of other citizens to refrain from interfering with him in his de- cision, but of the privilege which he enjoys to decide such ques- tions for himself without any direction from the laws. So we say that a man is at liberty to make a fool of himself rather than he has a legal right to do so. If X, observing his friend T in that predicament at amateur theatricals, succeeds in diverting the attention of the audience in order to save Y's reputation, Y is not legally protected from that interference, so long as X does not violate any specific rule of law, as by removing T bodily from the stage. In a society where the religious code consisted simply of prohibitions, against polytheism and smoking,^ a man may enjoy religious liberty to run away with his neighbour's wife, but not a religious right to do so, since the religious code imposes no obliga- tion on the husband to abstain from interfering with him in the exercise of this religious liberty. Such cases as these illustrate 1 "Jurisprudence," I, 356. ' Cf. Palgrave, "Journey through Central and Eastern Arabia," II, 11. THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 181 340. Nor can it mean that the governments which are denominated free, leave or grant to their subjects more of political liberty than those which are styled despotic. For the epithet fret, importing praise, and the epithet despotic importing blame, they who distinguish governments into free and despotic, suppose that the first are better than the second. But inasmuch as political liberty may be generally useful or pernicious, we cannot infer that a government is better than another government, because the sum of the liberties which the former leaves to its subjects, exceeds the sum of the liberties which are left to its subjects by the latter. The excess in the 'sum of the liberties which the former leaves to its subjects, may be purely mischievous. It may consist of freedom from restraints which are required by the common weal ; and which the government would lay upon its subjects, if it fulfilled its duties to the Deity. In consequence, for example, of that mischievous freedom, its subjects may be guarded inadequately against one another, or against attacks from external enemies. 341. They who distinguish governments into free and despotic, probably mean this : In every political society, the government, in conferring rights and imposing duties, more or less disregards the common or general weal, and looks to the fact that liberty and right are not inseparable. In developed systems, however, the tendency is in the direction of making them so. " The plaintiff," said Lord Lindley in Quinn v. Leathern, " had the ordinary rights of a British subject. He was at liberty to earn his own living in his own way, provided he did not violate some special law prohibiting him from so doing, and provided he did not infringe the rights of other people. This liberty involved liberty to deal with other persons who were willing to deal with him. This liberty is a right recognized by law; its correlative is the general duty of every one not to prevent the free exercise of this liberty, except so far as his own liberty of action may justify him in so doing." * 1901. A.C., 534. 182 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER the peculiar interests of a portion or portions of the com- munity. — Now the governments which deviate less from that ethical principle or maxim, are better than the govern- ments which deviate more. But, according to the opinion of those who make the distinction in question, the governments which deviate less from that ethical principle or maxim, are. popular governments, meaning by a popvlar government any aristocracy which consists of such a number of the given political community as bears a large proportion to the number of the whole society. For it is supposed by those who make the distinction in question, that, where the government is popular, the interests of the sovereign number, and the interests of the entire community, are nearly identical, or nearly coincide: but that, where the government is monarchical, or where the supreme powers reside in a comparatively few, the sovereign one or number has numerous interests which are not consistent with the good of the general. — According, therefore, to those who make the distinction in question the duties which a govern- ment of many lays upon its subjects, are more consonant to the general good than the duties which are laid upon its subjects by a government of one or a few. Consequently, though it leaves or grants not to its subjects, more of political liberty than is left or granted to its subjects by a government of one or a few, it leaves or grants to its subjects more of the political liberty which conduces to the common weal. But, as leaving or granting to its subjects more of that useful liberty, a government of many may be styled free: whilst, as leaving or granting to its subjects less of that useful liberty, a government of one or a f^w may be styled not free, or may be styled despotic or absolute. Conse- quently, a free government is a popular government: whilst a despotic government is either a monarchy or an oligarchy. 342. They who distinguish governments into free and THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 183 despotic, are therefore lovers of democracy. By the epithet free, as applied to governments of many, they mean that governments of many are comparatively good : and by the epithet despotic, as applied to monarchies or oligarchies, they mean that monarchies or oligarchies are comparatively bad. The epithets free and despotic are rarely, I think, employed by the lovers of monarchy or oligarchy. If the lovers of monarchy or oligarchy did employ those epithets, they would apply the epithet free to governments of one or a few, and the epithet despotic to governments of many. For they think the former comparatively good, and the latter com- paratively bad ; or that monarchical or oligarchical govern- ments are better adapted than popular, to attain the ultimate purpose for which governments ought to exist. They deny that the latter are less misled than the former, by interests which are not consistent with the common or general weal : or, granting that excellence to governments of many, they think it greatly outweighed by numerous other excellences which they ascribe to governments of one or to governments of a few. But with the respective merits or demerits of various forms of government, I have no direct concern. I have examined the current distinction between free and despotic governments, because it is expressed in terms which are extremely inappropriate and absurd, and which tend to obscure the independence of political or legal obliga- tion, that is common to sovereign governments of all forms or kinds.' 342. Seeley makes an interesting contribution to the distinction under discussion. All government, he argues, rests on force. But force implies the support of at least a considerable number of the community. Hence in every community, whether despotic or free, we have to distinguish between the government and the body which supports the government. Now the body which sup- ports the government may be said to make it, and certainly has the power to destroy it In States where that body ii organized, 184 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER Whyithas 343 That the power of a sovereign is incapable of legal j*™^ , limitation has been doubted, and even denied. But the doubted, that sever- difficulty, like thousands of others, probably arose from eign in- g^ verbal ambiguity. — ^The foremost individual member of a capable of legal so-called limited monarchy, is styled improperly monarch or limitation, sovereign. Now the power of a monarch or sovereign, thus improperly so styled, is not only capable of legal limitations, but is sometimes actually limited by positive law. But monarchs or sovereigns, thus improperly so styled, were confounded with monarchs, atid other sovereigns, in the proper acceptation of the terms. And since the power of the former is capable of legal limitations, it was thought that the power of the latter might be bounded by similar restraints. The pro- 344. Whatever may be its origin, the error is remarkable. '^°" t^ ^°^ ^^^ legal independence of monarchs in the proper byre- acceptation of the term, and of sovereign bodies in their nowned corporate and sovereign capacities, not only follows in- writers. evitably from the nature of sovereign power, but is also asserted expressly by renowned political writers of opposite parties or sects : by celebrated advocates of the governments which are decked with the epithet free, as by celebrated advocates of the governments which are branded with the epithet despotic. 345. 'If it he objected (says Sidney) that I am a de- fender of arbitrary powers, I confess I cannot comprehend how any society can be established or subsist without them. the government is free. In other States, the government is despotic. The distinction between a free and a despotic State is thus a distinction between States which have, and States which have not, an organization by means of which public opinion makes, supports, and destroys the government. Great Britain enjoys free government; Kussia is a despotism.^ ' Of. Seeley, " Political Science," Lectures v.-viii. THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 185 The difference between good and ill governments is not, that those of one sort have an arbitrary power which the others have not ; for they all have it ; but that in those which are well constituted, this power is so placed as it may be beneficial to the people,' 346. 'It appeareth plainly (says Hobbes) to my under- standing, that the soveraign power whether placed in one man, as in monarchy, or in one assembly of men, as in popular and aristocraticall commonwealths, is as great as men can be imagined to make it. And though of so unlimited a power men may fancy many evill consequences, yet the consequence of the want of it, which is warre of every man against his neighbour, is much worse. The condition of man in this life shall never be without inconveniences : but there I happeneth in no commonwealth any great inconvenience, but what proceeds from the subjects' disobedience. And whoso- ever, thinking soveraign power too great, will seek to make it lesse, must subject himselfe to a power which can limit it that is to say, to a greater.' — ' One of the opinions (says the same writer) which are repugnant to the nature of a commonwealth, is this: that he who hath the soveraign power is subject to the civill lawes. It is true that all Boveraigns are subject to the lawes of nature ; because such lawes be Divine, and cannot by any mtin, or by any commonwealth, be abrogated. But to the civill lawes, or to the lawes which the soveraign maketh, the soveraign is not subject : for if he were subject to the civill lawes, he were subject to himselfe ; which were not subjection, but freedom. The opinion now in question, because it setteth the civill lawes above the soveraign, setteth also a judge above him, and a power to punish him: which is to make a new soveraign ; and, again, for the same reason, a third to punish the second ; and so continually without end, to the confusion and dissolution of the commonwealth.' — 'The difference 186 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER (says the same writer) between the kinds or forms of commonwealth, consisteth not in a difference between their powers, but in a difference between their aptitudes to produce the peace and security of the people: which i» their end.' Asover- 347. Before I discuss the origin of political government eign not ^^^ society, I will briefly examine a topic allied to the of rights, liberty of sovereigns from political or legal restraints. 348. A sovereign government of one, or a sovereign govern- ment of a number in its collegiate and sovereign capacity, has no legal rights (in the proper acceptation of the term) against its own subjects. 349. Every legal right is the creature of a positivejaw : and it answers to a relative duty imposed by that positive law, and incumbent on a person or persons other than the person or persons in whom the right resides. To every legal right, there are three several parties : namely, a party bearing the right ; a party burthened with the relative duty ; and a sovereign government setting the law through which the right and the duty are respectively conferred and imposed. A sovereign government cannot acquire rights through laws set by itself to its own subjects. A man is no more able to confer a right on himself, than he is able to impose on himself a law or duty. Every party bearing a right (divine, legal, or moral) has necessarily acquired the right through the might or power of another : that is to say, through a law and a duty (proper or improper) laid by that other party on a further and distinct party. If a government had legal rights against its own subjects, it could not be sovereign, for those rights were the creatures of positive laws set to its own subjects by a third person or body. •Right is 350. It has often been affirmed that 'right is might,' or vag^t- that "might is right.' But this paradoxical proposition is either a truism affectedly and darkly expressed, or is false THE LBIITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 187 and absurd. If it mean that a party who possesses a right possesses the right through might or power of his own, the proposition is false and absurd. For a party who possesses a right necessarily possesses the right through the might or power of another : namely, the author of the law by which the right is conferred. If it mean that right and might are one and the same thing, the proposition in question is also false and absurd. My physical ability to move about, when my body is free from bonds, may be called might or power, but cannot be called a right : though my ability to move about without hindrance from you, may doubtless be styled a right, with perfect precision, if I owe the ability to a law imposed upon you by another. If, again, it mean that every right is a creature of might or power, the proposition is merely a truism disguised in paradoxical language. For every right (divine, legal, or moral) rests on a relative duty ; that is to say, a duty lying on a party or parties other than the party or parties in whom the right resides. And, manifestly, that relative duty would not be a duty substantially, if the law which affects to impose it were not sustained by might. 351. So far as subjects are bound by the law of God to obey their temporal sovereign, a sovereign government has rights divine against those subjects : rights which are conferred upon itself, through duties which are laid upon its subjects, by laws of a common superior. And so far as the members of its own community are severally constrained to obey it by the opinion of the community at large, it has also rnoral rights (or rights arising from positive morality) against its own subjects severally considered: rights which are conferred upon itself by the opinion of the community at large, and which answer to relative duties laid upon its several subjects by the general or prevalent opinion of the same indeterminate body. 352. Consequently, when we say that a sovereign govern- 188 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER ment, as against its own subjects, has or has not a right to do this or that, we necessarily mean by a right (supposing we speak exactly), a right Divine or moral : we necessarily mean (supposing we speak exactly) that it has or has not a r^ht derived from a law of God, or derived from a law improperly so called which the general opinion of the community sets to its members severally. 353. But when we say that a government, as against its own subjects, has or has not a right to do this or that, we not uncommonly mean that we deem the act in .question generally useful or pernicious. This application of the term right, resembles an application of the term justice to which I have adverted above. — An act which conforms to the Divine law, is styled, emphatically, just ; an act which does not, is styled, emphatically, unjust. An act which is generally use- ful, conforms to the Divine law as known through the principle of utility : an act which is generally pernicious, does not con- form to the Divine law as known to the same exponent. Con- sequently, ' an act which is just or unjust,' and ' an act which is generally useful or generally pernicious,' are nearly equiva- lent expressions. — An act which a sovereign government has a Divine right to do, it, emphatically, has a right to do : if it has not a Divine right, it, emphatically, has not a right. An act which were generally useful, the Divine law, as known through the principle of utility, has conferred on a sovereign government a right to do : an act which were generally pernicious, the Divine law, as known through the same exponent, has not conferred on the sovereign government a right to do. Consequently, an act which the government has a right to do, is an act which were generally useful : as an act which the government has not a right to do, is an act which were generally pernicious. 354. To ignorance or neglect of the palpable truths which I have expounded in the present section, we may impute a THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER 189 pernicious jargon that was current in our own country on the eve of her horrible war with her North American children. By the great and small rabble in and out of Parliament, it was said that the government sovereign in Britain was also sover- eign in the colonies ; and that, since it was sovereign in the colonies, it had a right to tax their inhabitants. It was objected by Mr. Burke to the project of taxing the inhabit- ants, that the project was inexpedient : pregnant with prob- able evil to the inhabitants of the colonies, and pregnant with probable evil to the inhabitants of the mother country. But to that most rational objection, the sticklers for the scheme of taxation returned this asinine answer. They said that the British government had a right to tax the colonists; and that it ought not to be withheld by paltry considerations of expediency, from enforcing its sovereign right against its refractory subjects. — Now, assuming that the government sovereign in Britain was properly sovereign in the colonies, it had no legal right to tax its colonial subjects ; although it was not restrained by positive law, from dealing with its colonial subjects at its own pleasure or discretion. If, then, the sticklers for the scheme of taxation had any determinate meaning, they meant that the British government was em- powered by the law of God to tax its American subjects. But it had not a Divine right to tax its American subjects, unless the project of taxing them accorded with general utility: for every Divine right springs from the Divine law ; and to the Divine law, general utility is the index. Consequently, when the sticklers for the schem^ of taxation opposed the right to expediency, they opposed the right to the only test by which it was possible to determine the reality of the right itself. 355. A sovereign government of one, or a sovereign govern- Appear- ment of a number in its collegiate and sovereign capacity, *'"'® °f ' may appear in the character of defendant, or may appear in govern- 190 THE LIMITS OF SOVEREIGN POWER ment the character of demandant, before a tribunal of its own e ore its appointment, or deriving jurisdiction from itself. But from tribunals, such an appearance of a sovereign government, we cannot infer that the government lies under legal duties, or has legal rights against its own subjects. 356. Supposing that the claim of the plaintiff against the sovereign defendant were truly founded on a positive law, it were founded on a positive law set to the sovereign defend- ant by a third person or body : or (changing the phrase) the sovereign defendant would be in a state of subjection to another and superior sovereign. Which is impossible and absurd. — And supposing that the claim of the sovereign de- mandant were truly founded on a positive law, it were founded on a positive law set by a third party to a member, or members of the society wherein the demandant is supreme: or (chang- l ing the phrase) the society subject to the sovereign demand- I ant, were subject, at the same time, to another supreme 1 government. Which is also impossible and. absurd. 357. The rights which are pursued against a sovereign government before tribunals of its own, and also the rights which it pursues before tribunals of its own, are merely — analog from the following general cause : namely, that the bulk of the natural society from which the political was formed, '■. were desirous of escaping to a state of government, from a ^tate of nature_or anarchy. If they liked specially the < government to which they submitted, their general perception of the utility of government concurred with their special inclination. If they disliked the government to which they submitted, their general perception of the utility of govern- ment controlled and mastered their repugnance. 370, According to a current expression, the permanence The poBi- and origin of every government are owing to the people's *'°° consent : that is to say, every government continues through emment the consent of the people, or the bulk of the political com- ooitinue» , through munity: and every government arises through the consent ^^^^^ of the people, or the biilk of the natural society from which people's the political is formed. According to the same opinion dressed in a different phrase, the power of the sovereign flows from the people, or the people is the fountain of sovereign power. 371. Now the permanence of every government depends on the habitual obedience which it receives from the bulk of the community. For if the bulk of the community were fully determined to destroy it, the might of the government would scarcely suffice to reduce them to subjection. But all obedience is voluntary or free, or every party who obeys con- sents to obey. In other words, every party who obeys wills the obedience which he renders, or is determined to render it by some motive or another. If a man condemned to imprison- ment were dragged to the prison by the jailors, he would not obey or submit. But if he were liable to imprisonment in the event of his refusing to walk to it, and if he were determined to walk to it by a fear of that further restraint, the man would render obedience to the sentence or command 200 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY of the judge. — Since, then, a government continues through the obedience of the people, and since the obedience of the people ia voluntary or free, every government continues through the consent of the people, or the bulk of the poHtical society. If they like the government, they are determined to obey it habitually, or to consent to its continuance, by their attachment. If they hate the government, they are determined to obey it habitually, or to consent to its con- tinuance, by their dread of a violent revolution. They consent to what they abhor, because they avoid thereby what they abhor more. — ^As correctly or truly apprehended, the position ' that every government continues through the people's consent,' merely amounts to this : That, in every society political and independent, the people are determined i by motives of some description or another, to obey their government habitually : and that, if the bulk of the com- munity ceased to obey it habitually, the government would cease to exist. 372. But the position in question, as it is often under- stood, is taken with one or another of the two following meanings. 373. Taken with the first of those meanings, the position amounts to this : That the bulk of every community approve of the established government, or prefer it to every govern- ment which could be substituted for it : and that they consent to its continuance, or pay it habitual obedience, by reason of that their approbation or by reason of that their preference. As thus understood, the position is ridiculously false : the habitual obedience of the people in most or many communi- ties, arising wholly or partly from their fear of the probable evils which they might suffer by resistance. 374. Taken with the second of those meanings, the position amounts to this : That, if the bulk of a community dislike the established government, the government ought not to OKIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 201 continue. And, if every actual society were adequately en- lightened, the position as thus understood would approach nearly to the truth. For the dislike of an enlightened people towards their established government, would beget a violent presumption that the government was faulty or imperfect. But, in every actual society, the government has neglected to instruct the people in sound political science ; or pains have been taken by the government, or the classes that influence the government, to exclude the bulk of the community from sound political science, and to perpetuate or prolong the prejudices which weaken and distort their undertakings. Every society, therefore, is inadequately instructed or en- lightened : And, in most or many societies the love or hate of the people towards their established government would scarcely beget a presumption that the government was good or bad. An ignorant people may love their established govern- ment, though, by cherishing pernicious institutions and fostering mischievous prejudices, it positively prevents the progress in useful knowledge and in happiness, which its subjects would make spontaneously if it simply were careless of their good. And as an ignorant people may love their established government, though it positively crosses the purpose for which it ought to exist, so may an ignorant people hate their established government, though it labours strenu- ously and wisely to further the general weal. The dislike of the French people to the ministry of the godlike Turgot, amply evinces the melancholy truth. They stupidly thwarted the measures of their warmest and wisest friend, and made common cause with his and their enemies : with the rabble of nobles and priests who strove to uphold misrule, and to crush the reforming ministry with a load of calumny and ridicule.* 374. Q. (1) Is it necessary, in defining law, to take into con- sideration the motives which compel obedience tn law 1 Consider 202 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY The posi- 375. That the permanence of every government is owing tion ' that j^ ^jjg people's consent, and that the origin of every govern- every goyern' ment is owing to the people s consent, are two positions so whether, having in view the emphasis that Austin. lays upon the popular appreciation of the utiHty of political society, he is con- sistent in defining law as a command. (Cf. § 13 as to definition of command.) (2) Why does Austin, in Sections 367-8, omit to refer to fear as a motive to obedience 1 Note. — The motives of obedience. — The question of the motives of obedience is one of extreme difiBculty. Motives vary with the age, with the individual, and with the nature of particular laws. A man who will obey most laws from exalted motives may obey others from the basest. Moreover, the motive of which a man is most conscious is by no means necessarily the most potent in deter- mining his conduct. Even if he can judge the motives which determine his own conduct, he may well feel diffident in affirm ing the motives which determine the conduct of other people. The student who wishes to pursue the subject should read the chapter on " Obedience " in Mr. Bryce's " Studies in History and Juris- prudence." 1 The learned author declares Political Obedience to be a form of compliance in general, the grounds or motives of which he sums up under five heads : — (1) Indolence, i.e. the disposition of a man to let some one else do for him what it would give bim trouble to do for himself. (2) Deference, i.e. some emotion drawing one person to another, disposing him to obey the will of that other. (3) Sympathy, i.e. "not merely the emotion evoked by the sight of a corresponding emotion in another, but the various forms of what may be called the associative tendency in mankind." (4) Fear, " a motive acting powerfully upon the ruder and more brutish natures." (5) Keason, " as guiding the more thoughtful and gentle natures." The author concludes : " In the sum total of obedience, the percentage due to Fear and to Eeason respectively is much less than that due to Indolence, and less also than that due to Defer- ence or to Sympathy." In comparing the classifications of Mr. Bryce and Austin, it will be obvious that indolence and deference are connected with habit, II, 1-43. ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 203 closely allied, that what I have said of the former will nearly ment apply to the latter. *^'="' ^ ^^ •' through 376. Every government has arisen through the consent of the the people, or the bulk of the natural society from which psop'e'^ consent. the political was formed. For the bulk of the natural society from which a political is formed, submit freely or voluntary to the inchoate political government. Or (changing the phrase) their submission is a consequence of motives, or they will the submission which fchey render. 377. But a special approbation of the government to which they freely submit, or a preference of that government to every other government, may not be their motive to submis- sion. Although they submit to it freely, the government perhaps is forced upon them : that is to say, they could not withhold their submission from that particular government, unless they struggled through evils which they are loath to endure. Determined by a fear of the evils which woidd follow a refusal to submit (and, probably, by a general per- ception of the utility of political government), they freely submit to a government from which they are specially averse. 378. The expression 'that every government arises through the people's consent,' is often uttered with the following meaning: That the bulk of a natural society about to become a political, or the inchoate subjects of an inchoate political government, promise, expressly or tacitly, to obey the future sovereign. The expression, however, as uttered with the meaning in question, confounds consent and pro- sympathy with prejudice, and fear and reason with the preference of government to anarchy. A second glance, however, must con- vince us that the two authors are not thinking of quite the same thing. Mr. Bryce answers the question : Why do subjects obey laws 1 Austin answers the question : Why do subjects submit to government 1 The one has in mind the offence of the law-breaker ; the other, the offence of the anarchist. Moreover, Mr. Bryce regards the individual citizen ; Austin the community in general. 204 OEIGIN OE CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY mise, and therefore is grossly incorrect. That the inchoate subjects of every inchoate government will or consent to obey it, is one proposition : that they promise, expressly or tacitly, to render it obedience, is another proposition. That the inchoate subjects of every inchoate government promise to render it obedience, is a position involved by an hypothesis which I shall examine in the next section. The hypo- 379. The duties of the subjects towards the sovereign j.j^^^° government, are partly religious, partly legal, and partly ginal cove- moral. The religious duties of the subjects to\^ards the nant. sovereign government, are creatures of the Divine law as known through the principle of utility. If the general good which probably would follow submission outweigh the general good which probably would follow resistance, the subjects are bound religiously to pay it habitual obedience although it accomplish imperfectly its proper purpose or eni — The legal duties of the subjects towards the sovereign government, are creatures of positive laws which itself has imposed upon them. — The moral duties of the subjects towards the sovereign government, are creatures of positive morality. They mainly are creatures of laws (in the im- proper acceptation of the term) which the general opinion of the community itself sets to its several members. 380. The duties of the sovereign government towards the subjects are partly religious and partly moral. If it lay under legal duties towards the subjects, it were not a supreme, but were merely a subordinate government. 381. It follows from the foregoing analysis, that the duties of the subjects towards the sovereign government, with the duties of the sovereign government towards the subjects, originate respectively in three several sources: namely, the Divine law (as indicated by the principle of utility), positive law, and positive morality. And, to my understanding, it seems that we account sufficiently for the OEIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 205 origin of those obligations, when we simply refer them to those their obvious fountains. It seems to my under- standing, that an ampler solution of their origin is not in the least requisite, and, indeed, is impossible. But there are many writers on political government and society, who are not content to account for their origin, by simply referring them to those their manifest sources. It seems to the writers in question, that we want an ampler solution of the origin of those obligations, or, at least, of the origin of such of them as are imposed by the law of God. And, to find that ampler solution which they believe requisite, those writers resort to the hypothesis of the original covenant or contract, or the fundamental civil pact.' 381. Q. (1) Consider to what extent, if at all, a science of law- is concerned with thp following topics : — (a) The State's purpose ; (6) The State's sphere of action ; (c) The State's origin. Note. — The origin and judiflcation of the State. — Austin has now passed from the question of the motives which induce sub- mission to government, to consider the nature of the duties between sovereign and subjects. These are seen to result from religion, law, or positive morality. In discussing the sections 375-80, we must distinguish between two great questions about which men have interested themselves in discussing the origin and cause of civil government :' — (1) How the State came to be ; (2) The right of the State to be; i.e. the right of the State to exercise authority over individual subjects. Of these questions the one is historical, the other is philosophical. How does Austin answer them? He hardly affects to consider the first. He says by impUcation : " I find governments to be estab- lished as a fact, to be considered useful, and to be supported by popular opinion. How these things came to be ? is a question that I, as a jurist, am not called upon to answer. If I must answer the question, I should say that the most important factor in the origin of society is a vague perception of the utUity of society (cf. § 369). Force, though it must be present, prevaila( less by its own might than by virtue of the presence of a con4 aciousness of advantages to be gained; and also by the power of' custom, and the attraction of such unreflecting preferences as 206 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 382. By the writers who resort to it, this renowned and not exploded hypothesis is imagined and rendered variously. But the purport or effect of the hypothesis, as it is imagined and rendered by most of those writers, may be stated generally thus : 383. To the formation of every society political and inde- pendent, or to the institution of every TroXty or civitas, aU its future members then in being are joint or concurring parties : for all are parties to an agreement in which it then originates, and which is also the basis whereon it afterwards rests. As being the necessary source of the independent political society, or as being a condition necessarily preceding its existence, this agreement of all is styled the original covenant : as being the necessary basis whereon the civitas afteirwards rests, it is styled pactum civile fundamentale. — loyalty to a chief" (cf. § 367). Two very serious olrjections may be urged against such an account. It gives no adequate ex- pression to the enormous power exercised by Eeligion in the formation of the State ; and it exaggerates the conscious element in early social evolution, almost ignoring the fact that the State is essentially a slow growth, a "gradual realization, in legal institu- tions, of the universal principles of human natme, and the gradual subordination of the individual side of that nature to the universal side."i The second of the questions to which reference has been made, the justification of the State's exercise of authority over iudividual subjects, is a question to which Austin's answer may be inferred from his accomit of the end of government. In Austin's opinion, the State is justified by the useful purpose which it serves in promoting human happiness. The answer may be compared with that of T. H. Green, who held that the State is justified by the purpose which it serves in maintaining those conditions of freedom which are essential to the moral life. The distinction between the two great questions of the State's origin and justification must be borne in mind. The theory of the original contract, to which Austin now proceeds, has been pro- pounded as an answer to both questions. * Burgess : " Political Science and Constitutional Law," I, 59. ORIGIN OK CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 207 In the process of making this covenant or pact, or the pro- cess of forming the society political and independent, there are three several stages which may be described in the following manner. 1. The future members of the com- munity just about to be created, jointly resolve to unite themselves into an independent political society : signifying and determining withal the paramount purpose of their union, or even more or fewer of its subordinate or instru- mental ends. And here I must briefly remark, that the paramount purpose of their union is the paramount purpose (let it be what it may) for which a society political and independent ought to be founded and perpetuated. By the writers who resort to the hypothesis, this paramount pur- pose or absolute end is conceived differently: their several conceptions of this purpose or end, dififering with the several natures of their respective ethical systems. To writers who admit the system which I style the theory of utility, this purpose or end is the advancement of human happiness. To a multitude of writers who have flourished and flourish in Germany, the following is the truly magnificent though somewhat mysterious object of political government and society : namely, the extension over the earth, or over its human inhabitants, of the empire of right or justice. It would seem that this right or justice, like Ulpian's justice, is absolute, eternal, and immutable. It would seem that this right or justice is not a creature of law : that it was anterior to every law ; exists independently of every law ; and is the measure or test of all law or morality. Consequently, it is not the right or justice which is a creature of the law of God, and to which the name of 'justice' is often applied emphatically. It rather is a something, perfectly self- existent, to which his law conforms, or to which his law should conform. I, therefore, cannot understand it, and will not affect to explain it. Merely guessing at what it 208 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY may be, I take it for general utility darkly conceived and expressed. 2. Having resolved to unite themselves into an independent political society, all the members of the inchoate community jointly determine the constitution of its sovereign political government. In other words, they jointly determine the member or members in whom the sovereignty shall reside : and, in case they will that the sovereignty shall reside in more than one, they jointly determine the mode wherein the sovereign number shall share the sovereign powers. 3. The process of forming the independent political society, or the process of forming its supreme political government, is completed by promises [given and acce pted: namely, by a promise of the inchoate sovereign to the inchoate subjects, by promises of the latter to the former, and by a promise of each of the latter to all and each of the rest. The promise made by the sovereign, and the promises made by the subjects, are made to a common object. The sovereign promises generally to govern to the paramount end of the independent political society: and, if any of its subordinate ends were signified by the resolution to form it, the sovereign moreover promises specifically to govern specifically to those subordinate ends. The subjects promise to render to the' sovereign a qualified or conditional obedience : that is to say, to render to the sovereign all the obedience which shall consist with that paramount purpose and those subordinate purposes. 384. The resolution of the members to unite themselves into an independent political society, is styled pactim unionis. Their determination of the constitution or struc- ture of the sovereign political government, is styled pactum constitutionis or pactum ordinationis. The promise of the sovereign to the subjects, with the promises of the subjects to the sovereign and to one another, are styled pactum suhjectionis : for, through the promises of the subjects, or ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 209 through the promises of the subjects coupled with the promise of the sovereign, the former are placed completely in a state of subjection to the latter, or the relation of subjection and sovereignty arises between the parties. But of the so-called pact of union, the so-called po/ct constituent, and the so-called pact of subjection, the last only is properly a convention. The so-called pact of union and the so-called pact constituent are properly resolves or determinations introductory to the pact of subjection: the pact of subjec- tion being the original covenant or the fundamental civil pact. 385. Through this original covenant, or this fundamental pact, the sovereign is bound (at least religiously) to govern as is mentioned above : and the subjects are bound (at least religiously) to render to the sovereign for the time being, the obedience above described. And the binding virtue of this fundamental pact is not confined to the founders of the independent political society, but extends to the following members of the same community. Tor the promises which the founders of the community made for themselves respec- tively, import similar promises which they make for their respective successors. 386. In every society political and independent, it is held, the duties of the sovereign towards the subjects (or the religious duties of the sovereign towards the subjects) spring from an original covenant like that which I now have delineated: And the duties of the subjects towards the sovereign (or the religious duties of the subjects towards the sovereign) arise from a similar pact. Unless we 8uppose\ that such an agreement is incumbent on the sovereign and ' subjects, we cannot account adequately for those their respective obligations. Unless the subjects were held to render it by an agreement that they shall render it, the subjects would not be obliged, or would not be obliged 210 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OP POLITICAL SOCIETY sufficiently, to render to the sovereign the obedience requisite to the accomplishment of the proper purpose or end of the society. Unless the sovereign were held by an agreement to govern as is mentioned above, the sovereign would not be obliged, or would not be obliged sufficiently, from governing despotically or arbitrarily: that is to say, governing with little or no regard to the proper purpose or end of a supreme political government. 387. Such, I believe, is the general purport of the hypothesis of the original covenant, as it is rendered by most of the writers who resort to it. 388. But, as I have remarked above, the writers who resort to the hypothesis imagine and render it variously. — According, for example, to some of those writers. The original subjects, covenanting for themselves and their followers, promise obedience to the original and following sovereigns. But the original sovereign is not a promising party to the fundamental civil pact. And by the different writers who render the hypothesis thus, the purport of the subjects' promises is imagined. For example : Some suppose that the obedience promised is qualified or conditional, whilst others suppose that it is passive or unlimited. But though the writers who resort to the hypothesis imagine and render it variously, they concur in this: That the duties of the subjects towards the sovereign (or the religious duties of the subjects towards the sovereign) are creatures of the original covenant. And the writers who fancy that the original sovereign was a promising party to the pact, also concur in this : That the duties of the sovereign towards the subjects (or the religious duties of the sovereign towards the subjects) are engendered by the same agreement. 389. A complete though concise exposition of the various forms or shapes in which various writers imagine and render the hypothesis, would fill a considerable volume. Besides, ORIGIN OR CAUSES OP POLITICAL SOCIETY 211 the ensuing strictures apply exactly, or may be fitted easily, to any original covenant that has been or can be conceived ; although they are directed more particularly to the fancied original covenant which I have delineated above. My state- ment of the purport of the hypothesis, I, therefore, conclude here. And I now will suggest shortly a few of the con- clusive objections to which the hypothesis is open, 390. (1) To account for the duties of subjects towards Oritioum their sovereign government, or for those of the sovereign °^ "J^" government towards its subjects, is the scope of every writer theory. who supposes an original covenant. — But we sufficiently <^) '^° • I.T ■ i_ account account for the origin of those respective obligations, when for duty we refer them simply to their apparent and obvious foun- of ^over- taius: namely, the law of God, positive law, and positive g^j^^^g morality. — Besides, although the formation of an indepen- the hypo- dent political society were really preceded by a fundamental j,g^"g^ civil pact, scarce any of the duties lying thereafter on the and in- subjects, or on the sovereign, would be engendered or *PP™- influenced by that foregoing convention. — The hypothesis, therefore, of an original covenant, is needless, and is worse than needless. It affects to assign the cause of certain phae- nomena: but the cause assigned is superfluous inasmuch as there are other causes which are at once obvious and adequate, and inefficient inasmuch as it could not have produced the phaenomena whereof it is the fancied source. 391. It will appear from the following analysis, that, * although the formation of an independent political society were really preceded by an original covenant, scarce any of the duties lying thereafter on the subjects, or of the duties lying thereafter on the sovereign, would be engendered or affected by that foregoing agreement. In other words, the covenant would hardly oblige {legally, religiously, or morally) the original or following subjects, or the original or following sovereigns. 212 OEIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY (o) Does • 392. Every convention which obliges legally (or every ""au"*^ Icontract properly so called) derives its legal efiBcacy from |a positive law. Speaking exactly, it is not the convention that obliges legally, or that engenders the legal duty: but the law obliges legally, or engenders the legal duty, through the convention. In other words, the positive law annexes the duty to the convention : or it determines that duties of the given class shall follow conventions of the given descrip- tion. — Consequently, if the sovereign government were bound legally by the fundamental civil pact, the legal duty lying on the government were the creature of a positive law : and the positive law annexing the duty to the pact would be set to the sovereign government by another and superior sovereign. Consequently, the sovereign government legally bound by the pact would be in a state of subjection. — ^Through a positive law set by their own sovereign, the subjects might be bound legally to keep the original cove- nant. But the legal or political duty thus incumbent on the (subjects, would properly proceed from the law set by their own sovereign, and not from the covenant itself. If they were bound legally to keep the original covenant, without a positive law set by their own sovereign, they would be bound through a positive law set by another sovereign : that is to say, they would be in a state of subjection to their own sovereign government, and also to a sovereign government conferring rights upon their own. (i) Nor re- 893. Again, if the sovereign or subjects were bound hgiously. ^giig^Qusly by the fundamental civil pact, the religious duty lying on the sovereign, or the religious duty lying on the subjects, would properly proceed from the Divine law, and not from the pact itself. 394. Now the proper absolute end of an independent political society, and the nature of the index to the law of God, are conceived differently by different men. But ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 213 whatever be the absolute end of an independent political society, and whatever be the nature of the index to the law of God, the sovereign would be bound religiously, without an original covenant, to govern to that absolute «nd : whilst the subjects would be bound religiously, vrithout an original covenant, to render to the sovereign the obedience which the accomplishment of the end might require. Conse- quently, whether it consisted or conflicted with that proper absolute end, the original covenant would not oblige re- ligiously either of the two parties. If the original covenant consisted with that absolute end, the original covenant would be superfluous, and therefore inoperative. If the original covenant conflicted with that absolute end, it would also conflict with the law which is the source of religious obligations, and would not oblige religiously the sovereign government or its subjects. 395. And though the original sovereign or the original subjects might have been bound religiously by the original covenant, why or how should it bind religiously the following - sovereigns or subjects ? Why should obligations be laid on those following parties, through or in consequence of a pact made without their authority, and even without their know- ledge ? Legal obligations often lie upon parties (as, for ex- ample, upon heirs or administrators), through or in consequence of promises made by other parties whose legal representatives they are. It is expedient, for various reasons, that positive law should impose obligations on the makers of certain promises : and for the same, or nearly the same, reasons, it is expedient that the legal duties which are laid on the makers themselves, should pass to the parties who legally represent them, and who take their faculties or means. But I am unable to perceive, why or how a promise of the original sovereign or subjects should biud religiously the following sovereigns or subjects : Though I see that cases of morally. 214 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY legal obligation to which I now have adverted, probably suggested the groundless conceit to those who advised the hypothesis of a fundamental civil pact, (c) Nor 396. If the sovereign were bound morally to keep the original covenant, the sovereign would be bound by opinions current amongst the subjects, to govern to the absolute end at which its authors had aimed : And if the subjects were bound morally to keep the original covenant, the subjects would be bound severally by opinions of the comin unity at large , to render to the sovereign the obedience which the accomplishment of the end might require. But the moral obligations thus incumbent would not be imposed by the positive morality of the community, through or in conse- quence of the pact. For the opinions obliging the sovereign to govern to that absolute end, with the opinions obliging the subjects to render that requisite obedience, would not he consequents of the pact, but would have been its antecedents; inasmuch as the pact itself would have been made by the founders of the community, because those very opinions were held by all or most of them. 397. We may, if we like, imagine that the fancied original covenant was constructed with some particularity and pre- cision: that, having determined the absolute end of their union, it specified some of the ends positive or negative, or some of the means or modes positive or negative, through which the sovereign government should rule to that absolute » needless, and is worse than needless: that we are able to account sufficiently, without resorting to the hypothesis, for the duties of subjects towards their sovereign government, with the duties of the sovereign government towards its subjects ; and that, though the formation of the independent political society had really been preceded by a fundamental civil pact, scarce any of those obligations would be engen- dered or influenced by that preceding agreement. It will appear from the follovWng strictures, that the hypothesis of the fundamental pact is auction approaching to an impossi- of a con veution, 220 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY bility : that the formation of a society political and indepen- dent, was never preceded or accompanied, and could hardly be preceded or accompanied, by an original covenant properly so called, or by aught resembling the idea of a proper original covenant. Essentials 409. The main essentials of a convention are these: First, a signification by the promising party, of his intention to do the acts, or to observe the forbearances, which he promises to do or observe : secondly, a signification by the promisee, that he expects the promising party will fulfil the proffered promise. That this signification of intention and this signification of expectation are of the very essence of a proper convention or agreement, will appear on a moment's reflection. 410. The conventions enforced by a positive law or moraUty are enforced legally or morally for various reasons. But of the various reasons for enforcing any convention, the follow- ing is always one. — Sanctions apart, a convention tends to raise in the mind of the promisee an expectation that its object will be accomplished : and to the expectation so raised, he naturally shapes his conduct. E"ow, as much of the business of human life turns or moves upon conventions, frequent disappointments of those expectations which con- ventions naturally excite, would render human society a scene of baffled hopes, and of thwarted projects and labours. To prevent disappointments of such expectations, is a main object of the legal and moral rules whose direct and appropri- ate purpose is the enforcement of pacts or agreements. But the promisee would not entertain the expectation, unless the corresponding intention were signified by the promising party: and, unless the existence of the expectation were signified by the promisee, the promising party would not be apprised of its existence, although the proffered promise had actually raised it. Without the signification of the intention, ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 221 there were no promise properly so called ; without the signi- fication of the expectation, there were no sufficient reason for enforcing the genuine promise which really may have been proffered. 411. It follows from the foregoing statement of the main Eisentials essentials of a convention that an original covenant properly °^ *.''°°" 80 called, or aught resembling the idea of a proper original not covenant, could hardly precede the formation of an indepen- present in dent political society. °"|gty° 412. According to the hypothesis of the original covenant, in 80 far as it regards the promise of the original sovereign, the sovereign promises to govern to the absolute end of the union (and, perhaps, to more or fewer of its subordinate or instrumental ends). And the promise is proffered to, and is accepted Vy, all the original subjects. According to the hypothesis of the original covenant, in so far as it regards the promise of the original subjects, they promise to render to the sovereign a passive and unlimited obedience, or they promise to render to the sovereign such a qualified obedience as shall consist with a given end or with given ends. And the promise of the subjects passes from all the subjects : from all and each of the subjects to the monarch or sover- eign body, or from each of the subjects to all and each of the rest. 413. Now it appears from the foregoing statement of the main essentials of a convention, that the promise of the sovereign to the subjects would not be a covenant properly, unless the subjects accepted it. But the subjects could hardly accept it, unless they apprehended its object. Unless they apprehended its object, it hardly could raise in their minds any determinate expectation: and unless it raised in their minds a determinate expectation, they hardly could signify virtually any determinate expectation, or could hardly accept virtually the proffered promise. The signs of accept- 222 ORIGIN OE CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY ance which might actually fall from them would be in reality unmeaniag noise or show. — Now we know that the great imajority, in any actual community, have no determinate Inotions concerning the absolute end to which their sovere%n (government ought to rule : or concerning the ends or means through which it should aim at the accomplishment of that its paramount purpose. It surely, therefore, were absurd to suppose, that all or many of the members of any inchoate community would have determinate notions (or notions approaching to determinateness) concerning the scope of their , union, or concerning the means to its attainment. Conse- quently, most or many of the original subjects would not apprehend the object of the original sovereign's promise: and, not apprehending its object, they would not accept it in effect, although they might accept it in show. 414. The remarks which I now have made on the promise of the original sovereign, will apply, with a few adaptations, to the promise of the original subjects. If really they proffered to the sovereign (or if really they proffered to one another) that promise to render obedience which the hypo- thesis supposes or feigns, they would signify expressly or tacitly an intention of fulfilling it. But such a signification of intention could not be made by all of them, or even by most or many of them : for by most or many of them, the object of the fancied promise would not be apprehended determinately, or with a distant approach to determinateness. 415. If you would suppose an original covenant which as a mere hypothesis will hold water, you must suppose that the society about to be formed is composed entirely of adult members : that all these adult members are persons of sane mind, and even of much sagacity and much judgment : and that being very sagacious and very judicious, they also are perfectly familiar, or at least are passably acquainted, with political and ethical science. On these bare possibilities. ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 223 you may build an original covenant which shall be a coherent fiction. 416. It hardly is necessary to add, that the hypothesis of The hyp6. the original covenant, in any of its forms or shapes, has no ^^ found*. foundation in actual facts. There is no historical evidence, tion in that the hypothesis has ever been realized : that the forma- • tion of any society political and independent has actually been preceded by a proper original covenant, or by aught appoaching to the idea. 417. In a few societies political and independent (as, for example, in the Anglo-American States), the sovereign political government has been determined at once, and agreeably to scheme or plan. But, even in these societies, the parties who determined the constitution (either as scheming or planning, or as simply voting or adopting it) were merely a_^;gnd£i_RQrtion of the whole of the independent community, and were virtually sovereign therein before the constitution was determined ; insomuch that the constitution was not constructed by the whole of an inchoate community, but rather was constructed by a fraction of a community already consummate or complete. 418. In most societies political and independent, the con- stitution of the supreme government has grown. By which fustian but current phrase, I intend not to intimate that it hath come of itself, or is a marvellous something fashioned without hands : but that it has not been determined at once, or agreeably to a scheme or plan ; that positive moral rules of successive generations of the community (and, perhaps, positive laws made by its successive sovereigns) have deter- mined the constitution, with more or less of exactness, slowly and unsystematically. Consequently, the supreme government was not constituted by the original members of the society : Its constitution has been the work of a long series of authors, comprising the original members and 224 ORIGIN OE CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY many generations of their followers. And the same may be said of most of the ethical maxims which the subjects con- strain the sovereign to observe. These are not coeval with the independent political society, but rather have arisen insensibly since the society was formed. 419. In some societies political and independent, oaths or promises are made by rulers on their accession to office. But such an oath or promise, and an original covenant to which the original sovereign is a promising party, have little or no resemblance. That the formation of the society political and independent preceded the conception of the oath itself, is commonly implied by the terms of the latter. The swearing party, moreover, is commonly a limited monarch, or occupies some position like that of a limited monarch : that is to say, is merely a limb or member of a sovereign body. 420. It is said, however, by the advocates of the hypothesis (for the purpose of obviating the difficulty which these negative cases present), that a tacit original covenant pre- i ceded the formation of the society, although its formation was not preceded by an express c6venant of the kind. 421. Now (as I have shown above) an actual signification of intention on the part of the promisor, with an actual acceptance of the promise on the part of the promisee, are of the very essence of a genuine convention or pact, be it express, or be it tacit. The only difference between an express, and a tacit or implied convention, lies in this : That, where the conven- tion is express, the intention and acceptance are signified by language, or by signs which custom or usage has rendered equivalent to language: but that, where the convention is tacit or implied, the intention and acceptance are not signi- fied by words, or by signs which custom or usage has madf tantamount to words.* 421. Quasi-Contract. — In a note to this paragraph, Austin traces the fallacy at present under discussion to a confusion of Implied ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 225 422. Most or many, therefore, of the members of the inchoate society, could not have been parties, as promisors or promisees, to a tacit original covenant. They could not have signified virtually the requisite intention or acceptance : for they could not have conceived the object (as I have shown above) with which, according to the hypothesis, an original covenant is concerned. 423. Besides, in many of the negative cases to which I now am adverting, the position and deportment of the original sovereign government, and of the bulk of the original subjects, exclude the supposition of a tacit original covenant. For example: Where the original government begins in a violent conquest, it scarcely promises tacitly, by its violences towards the vanquished, that it will make their weal the paramount end of its rule. And a tacit promise to render obedience to the intrusive and hated government, scarcely passes from the reluctant subjects. They presently Contract with the Quasi-Contract of Roman Law. The former was a true agreement, although implied from conduct rather than expressed in words. The latter was no agreement at all. It was a name adopted by the Bomans to cover a miscellaneous set of obligations which did not spring from agreement, express or implied. For example, if a Roman citizen voluntarily undertook to manage the business of an absentee without having been asked to do so, certain legal obligations sprang up between him and the absentee. These obligations were comparable in many respects to obligations arising from contract. They were said to arise, not ex contractu, but quasi ex contractu. As several authors have remarked, it is in this form that the theory of contract can be most easUy adapted to the purposes of poUtical discussion. The ruler, it may be urged, may not have promised to rule justly, the subjects may not have promised to obey, but the circumstances are such that no moral injustice is done in assuming such promises.* It must be obvious, however, that, the moment consent becomes fictitious, such philo- sophic merits as the Social Contract theory may have, cease to exist. ' Cf. Maine, " Ancient Law," pp. 344-7. ■ 226 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIEXr vnll to obey it, or presently consent to obey it, because they are determined to obey it, by their fear of its military sword. But the will or consent to obey it presently, to which they are thus determined, is scarcely a tacit promise to render it future obedience. They would kick with all their might against the intrusive government, if the military sword which it brandishes were not so long and fearful. 424. By the recent and present advocates of the hypothesis of the original covenant (who chiefly are German writers on political government and society), it commonly is ad- mitted that original covenants are not historical facts : that an actual original covenant never preceded the formation of any actual society political and independent. But they zealously maintain, notwithstanding this sweeping admission, that the only sufficient basis of an independent political society is a fundamental civil pact. Their doctrine, therefore, touching the original covenant amounts to this: namely, that the original fcovenant hath not preceded the formation of any society political and independent : but that though it hath not preceded the formation of any, it yet precedeth inevit- ably the formation of every. — Such is a taste or sample of the high ideal philosophy which the Germans oppose ex- ultingly to the philosophy of Bacon and Locke. (3) No 425. (3) I close my strictures on the hypothesis of the necessary original covenant, with the following remark: It would connection ■, i ■, ^ ■ , . i -l between Seem that the hypothesis was suggested to its authors, by con- one or another of these suppositions. 1. Where there is no, and duty convention, there is no duty. In other words, whoever is obliged, is obliged through a promise given and accepted. 2. Every convention is necessarily followed by a duty. In other words, wherever a promise is given and accepted, the promising party is obliged through the promise, let its object and tendency be what they may. — It is assumed, expressly or tacitly, by Hobbes, Kant, and others, that he who is ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 227 tound has necessarily given a promise, and that he who has given a promise is necessarily hound. 426. But both suppositions are grossly and obviously false. — Of religious, legal, and moral duties, some are imposed by the laws which are their respective sources, through or in consequence of conventions. But others are annexed to facts which have no resemblance to a convention, or to aught that can be deemed a promise. Consequently, a sovereign government might lie under duties to its subjects, and its subjects might lie under duties towards itself, though neither it nor its subjects were bound through a pact. — And as duties are annexed to facts which are not pacts or conven- tions, so are there pacts or conventions which are not followed by duties. Conventions are not enforced by divine or human law, without reference to their objects and tenden- cies. There are many conventions which positive morality reprobates: There are many which positive law will not sustain, and many which positive law actually annuls : There are many which conflict with the law of God, inasmuch as their tendencies are generally pernicious, Consequently, although the sovereign and subjects were parties to an original covenant, neither the sovereign nor subjects would of necessity be bound by it.* 426. The 'theory of the Social Contract. — Huxley expresses a familiar fact when he says that doctrines do not necessarily die from being killed. The Social Contract theory, triumphantly slain by many generations of writers, will not die. It reappears, sometimes openly and shamelessly, sometimes in disguises more or less apparent. Herbert Spencer, whUe declaring that the hypo- thesis of a social contract as assumed by Hobbes or Kousseau was baseless, elaborated a theory of his own which was essentially one of contract. Society, he urged, is in principle the same as an incorporated body, and " the general principle underlying the right government of every incorporated body is that its members contract with each other severally to submit to the will of the majority in all matters concerning the fulfilment of the objects for which they 228 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY Govern- 427. From the origin or causes of political government meutsde ^^^ society, I pass to the distinction of sovereign govern- ments into governments de jure and governments de facto. are incorporated, but in no others." ^ Although in the case of poHtical society there is no express deed of incorporation, such a deed is implicit. Its terms can he infeired by considering what would be the agreement into which citizens would now enter with practical unanimity.^ Whenever a social theory will thus insist upon reappearing from time to time, despite its complete logical refutation, it will be found to contain some important truths which deserve statement. Such truths underlie the despised doctrine of the Social Contract. The fact must be my chief excuse for supplementing Austin's admirable remarks by a brief reference to the following topics: — (1) The essential inadequacy of the doctrine ; (2) The historic forms in which the doctrine has been expressed ; (3) The underlying truths. (1) The essential inadequacy of the doctrine. — The doctrine purports to be an explanation both of the origin of the State and of the source of the State's authority. As an explanation of the origin of political society, the doctrine reaUy belongs to the age in which thinkers attempted to explain social origins by a pnori speculation rather than by investigation of an actual past. Having determined how man, who is largely what he is by virtue of pohtical institutions, would act if he were to be suddenly deprived of them, the inference was drawn that man must have so acted at the beginnings of social life. The fallacy is too apparent to call for refutation. As a matter of fact, the very idea of a contract as binding belongs to a comparatively advanced stage. Sfa tltS*, Bfl^' contract, is„the.b.a.sis.of .piimitiv-asQciety. How unreal and fanciful is the world to which the Social Contract theory belongs is happily satirized by Huxley. " To Hsten to Locke, one would imagine that a general meeting of men living in the state of nature, having been called to consider the ' defects ' of their condition, and somebody being voted to the tree (in the presumable absence of chairs), thi earliest example of a constituent assembly resolved to fonn a governmental company, with strictly limited habihty, for the purpose of defending liberty and property ; and that they elected a director, or body of directors, to be known as the sovereign, for the purpose of carrying on that business, and no other whatso- ever." ^ N The Social Contract theory as an explanation of the ground of ' " Man versiis the State," p. 83. ^ Ibid., p. 85. • "Method and Results," p. 407. ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 229 For the two topics are so connected, that the few brief govem- j monts de aptly at the end of my disquisition on the former. remarks which I shall make on the latter, may be placed' the State's authority, though less absurd, is equally untenable. It ■ rests on the postulate that man is endowed with an abstract right \ to a freedom with which no interference can be justified save by assent on the part of the individual himself. Man, in other words, is looked upon as having rights independently of his relations to society, although it is only as a member of society that he has rights at all. However clever may be our logic, vfb cannot reach a working conception of the State on such lines. The State is an organic unity ; the parts of which it is composed are largely what they are by virtue of their relation to the whole of which they are a part. To arbitrarily separate them from that whole is to deform them.^ (2) The historic forms of the doctrine. — The most famous forms of the doctrine are respectively associated with the names of Hobbes, Locke, and Eousseau. According to Hobbes, the inchoate subjects agree among themselves to surrender all rights to the sovereign. The sovereign is not a party to the contract, and, accordingly, no breach of covenant on the part of the sovereign is possible. " None of his subjects, by any pretence of forfeiture on his part, can be freed from subjection."^ According to Locke> though paternal control may pass by insensible degrees into sover- eign authority, the foundation of that authority rests, not in paternity, but in the consent of the governed.^ Hence it can be no greater than that possessed by individuals ia a state of nature, since nobody can transfer to another more power than he has in himself, and nobody in the state of nature can have more power over the life, liberty, and possession of another than is given him by the law of nature for the preservation of himself and the rest of mankind.* Hence the power of the sovereign is limited ; and resistance to him is justified if he exceed those limits. The judge of such ofience shah, be the people, "for who shall be judge whether his trustee or deputy acts well and according to the trust reposed in him, but he who deputes him and must, by having deputed him, have stiU a power to discard him when he fails in his trust 1"^ According to Eousseau, society begins in a contract the clauses of which, though perhaps never formally enumerated, are everywhere the same, everywhere tacitly admitted and recognized. • Of. infra Excursus A, " The State." ' " Leviathan," cap. xxviii. ' "Second Discourse on Government," pars. 76, 105, 110. * Ibid., par. 135. ' Ibid., pp. 232, 240. 230 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OT* POLITICAL SOCIETY 428. In respect of the distinction now in question governments are commonly divided into three kinds First, governments which are de jure and also de facto, secondly, governments which are de jure but not de facto; " These clauses may be reduced to one, that is, the total aUenation of each associate with aU his rights to the eiitire community. . . . Each gives in common his person and all his force under the supreme direction of the general will, and is received as an indivisible part of the whole. . . . Each is sovereign as weU as subject." 1 According to this view, a government which does not embrace the whole people cannot he a true sovereign, and its over- throw is only a change in the delegation of sovereign functions. The foregoing theories call for no discussion in detail. It may be noted, however, that the theory of Hobbes finds expression for government but not for the State, while that of Kousseau finds an expression for the State but none that is adequate for the government. The path taken by Hobbes leads on to governmental despotism; that taken by Eousseau, to the despotism of majorities. While Locke may be said to have apprehended the existence both of the State and the government, his doctrine easily lends itself to an individuahsm of which the final outcome must be anarchy.* (3) The underlying truths in the Social Contract theory. — In the first place, regarded as an explanation of social origins, the theory of the original contract expresses the highly important fact that society is something more than a spontaneous growth. It is a-gIQlwth_ddrectedLbyJthe fo^^ That the theory in question involves a grave exaggeration of the conscious element must be admitted; the fact need not blind us to its merit in insisting upon the presence of that element. In the second place, regs^rded as a philosophical account of the State's authority over the individual, the Social Contract theory affords an inadequate ex- pression for the truth that the conception of rights is only attain- able among men of whom each recognizes in others the claims that he makes for himself. "It is only through a recognition by certain men of a common interest, and through the expression of that recognition in certain regulations of their dealings with each other, that morality could originate, or any meaning be gained for such terms as 'ought' and 'right' and their equivalents."* In the preceding paragraph, reference has been made to an element of truth in the Social Contract theory, regarded as a 1 " The Social Contract," bk. I, chap. vi. > Of. Huxley, " Methods and Results," p. 419. » T. H. Green, "Principles of Political Obligation," § 116. ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 231 thirdly, governments which are de facto but not de jv/re. A government rfe jwre and also de, facto, is a government deemed lawful, rightful or just, which receives presently habitual obedience from the bulk or generality of the members of the independent political community. A government de jure but not de fado (or more briefly a government de jwe) is a government deemed lawful, right- ful or just, which, nevertheless, has been supplanted or dis- , placed. A government de facto but not de jv/re (or more briefly a government de facto) is a government deemed un- lawful, wrongful or unjust, which, nevertheless, receives presently habitual obedience from the bulk of the com- munity. A government supplanted or displaced, and not deemed lawful, is neither a government de facto nor a government de jure. 429. In respect of positive law, a sovereign political I government which is established is neither lawful nor un-| philosophical expression, of the ground of the authority of the State. In history, the theory has more often appeared as an expression of the ground of the authority of the Ruler. Ee- gaided from this point of view, the theory is capable of being formulated so as to express the important truth that the Euler sacrifices his claim to the obedience of the subjects when he fails to consult the interests of those subjects. The duties of obedience and protection are reciprocal. The admission that a theory contains some elements of truth involves no justification of that theory. History abundantly illustrates the fact that opinions and beliefs, which have acquired a dominating influence by virtue of the truths which they con- tained, may, through their imperfections, bring destruction to the very cause in the interests of which they have been formulated. Man's poverty of language not only compels him to wait long for some expression for the truth he vaguely feels, but also menaces him at every step when once that expression has been found, for the reason that it is certain to be inadequate. His only safety lies in the constant re-examination of his intellectual equip- ment. Neither a sane socialist nor a sane individualist of our own day would buUd his social theory upon the basis of a social contract. 232 ORIGIN OE CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY ^ lawful : neither rightful nor wrongful : neither just nor unjust: neither legal nor illegal. 430. In every society political and independent, the actual positive law is a creature of the actual sovereign. Although it was positive law under foregoing sovereigns, it is positive law presently through the power and author- ity of the present supreme government. For though the present government may have supplanted another, and though the supplanted government be deemed the lawful government, the supplanted government is stripped of the might which is requisite to the enforcement of the law con- sidered as positive law. Consequently, if the law were>not enforced by the present supreme government, it would want the appropriate sanctions which are essential to positve law. To borrow the language of Hobbes, ' The legislator is he (not by whose authority the law was first made, but) by whose authority it continues to be law.' 431. Consequently an established sovereign government, in respect of the positive law of its own independent com- munity, is neither lawful nor unlawful. If it were lawful or unlawful, by law of its own making, it were lawful or un- lawful by its own appointment. Which is absurd. — And if it were lawful or unlawful, in respect of the positive law of another independent community,, it were not an actual supreme, but an actual subordinate government. Which also is absurd. 432. In respect of the positive law of that independent community wherein it once was sovereign, a so-called government de jure but not de facto, is not, and cannot be, a lawful government : for the positive law of that inde- pendent community is now positive law by the authority of the government de facto. Being positive law by the authority of the government de facto, this positive law proscribes the supplanted government, and determines that attempts to ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 233 restore it are legal wrongs. The supplanted government, though deemed de jure, is unlawful, — In respect of the positive law of another independent community, a so-called government de jure but not de fmdo, is neither lawful nor unlawful. For if, in respect of this law, it were lawful or unlawful, it were lawful or unlawful by the appointment of the law-maker; that is to say, it were not an ousted supreme, but an ousted subordinate government. 433. In respect, then, of positive law, the distinction of sovereign governments into lawful and unlawful is a distinc- 1 tion without a meaning. For, as tried by this test, a so- called government de jure but not de facto cannot be lawful : And, as tried by the same test, a government de facto is neither lawful nor unlawful. 434. In respect, however, of positive morality, the distinc- tion of sovereign governments into lawful and unlawful, is not without a meaning. If the opinions of the bulk of the community favour the government de facto, the government de facto is morally lawful in respect of the positive morality of that particular society. If the opinions of the bulk of the community be adverse to the government ds facto, it is morally unlawful in respect of the same standard. The bulk, however, of the community, may regard it with in- difiference : or a large portion of the community may regard it v?ith favour, whilst another considerable portion regards it with aversion. And, in either of these cases, it is neither morally lawful, nor morally unlawful, in respect of the positive morality of that independent community wherein it is established. — And what I have said of a government dt fa^to, may also be said of a government not de facto. 435. And a government de facto, or a government not de facto, may be morally lawful, or morally unlawful, in respect of the positive morality which obtains between nations or states. Though positive international morality looks mainly at the possession, every government in possession 234 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY or every government de facto, is not acknowledged of course by other established governments. In respect, therefore, of positive international morality, a government de facto may be unlawful, whilst a government not de facto may be a government de jure. 436. A government, moreover, de fa/ito, or a government not de facto, may be lawful or unlawful in respect of the law of God. Tried by the Divine law, as known through the principle of utility, a sovereign government de facto is lawfully a sovereign government, if the general happiness or weal requires its continuance : it is not lawfully sovereign, if the general happiness or weal requires its abolition. Tried by the Divine law, as known through the principle of utility, a government not de facto is yet a government de jure, if the general happiness or weal requires its restoration,: a government not de facto is also not de jure, if the general happiness or weal requires its exclusion." 436. Oovemments de jure and de facto. — A sovereignty which exists in fact can only be said to be not de jure, if by jus we are thinking of somethiag other than the law of the State, e.g., of Positive Morality or luternational Law. But since, for the pur- poses of jurisprudence, jus = the law of the State, the distinction b not tenable. In the highly developed modern state, however, the sovereign may not be identical with the government. In a Consti- tution where this differentiation is recognized, the distinction between the government dejure and the government de facto may have a meaning. If, for example, the government of a 'State', member of a Federal State, assumes the practical exercise of goyern- mental functions which the constitution allots to the Federal government, such assumption might be described as government de facto, but not de jure. Mr. Bryce, in a recent work, identifies sovereignty de jure with the legal sovereignty, and sovereignty de fcKto with political sovereignty, or, to quote his own expression, " Practical Mastery."' The terminology appears to me to be open to objection. Legal sovereignty is as much a matter of fact as political sovereignty. Legal sovereignty is both de jure and de facto ; poUtical sovereignty is de facto only. Or, to take a concrete example, the British Parliament is as much a matter of fact as the British electorate. ' " Studies in History and Jurisprudence," II, 69, 70. ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 235 437. A positive law may be distinguished in the following General manner. Every positive law (or every law simply and ^ °'*^°." strictly so called) is set, directly or circuitously, by a tive law. sovereign individual or body, to a member or members of the independent political society wherein its author is supreme. 438. This definition of a positive law is assumed expressly The defi- or tacitly throughout the foregoing lectures. But it only °^*""' approaches to a perfectly complete and perfectly exact approxi- definition. It is open to certain correctives which I now mate- will briefly suggest. 439. Every law properly so called is set by a superior to an inferior or inferiors: It is set by a party armed with might, to a party or parties whom that might can reach. If the party to whom it is set could not be touched by the might of its author, its author would signify to the party a wish or desire, but would not impose a proper and imperative law. Now (speaking generally) a party who is obnoxious to a legal sanction, is a subject of the author of the law to which the sanction is annexed. But as none but members of the community wherein the law obtains are obnoxious to the legal sanction which enforces a positive law, the positive law is imposed exclusively on a member or members of that independent community. Although the positive law may affect to oblige strangers (or parties who are not members of thiit independent community), none but members of that independent community are virtually or truly bound by it. 440. Speaking, then, generally, we may say that a positive law is set or directed exclusively to a member or members of the community wherein its author is sovereign. But, in many cases, the positive law of a given independent com- munity imposes a duty on a stranger : on a party who is not a member of the given independent community, or is only a member to certain limited purposes. For such, in these 236 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY cases, is the position of the stranger, that the imposition of the legal duty consists with the sovereignty of the govern- ment of which he is properly a subject. Although the legal duty is laid on one of its subjects, it is not laid on the foreign government itself : nor does the author of the law,- by imposing the legal duty, exercise sovereign power in the community of the foreign government, or over one of its subjects as being one of its subjects. — For example: A party not a member of a given independent community, but Uving within its territory and within the jurisdiction of its sover- eign, is bound or obliged, to a certain limited extent, by its positive law. Living within the territory, he is obnoxious to the legal sanctions by which the law is enforced. And the legal duties imposed upon him by the law are consistent with the sovereignty of the foreign government of which he is properly a subject. For the duties are not imposed upon the foreign government itself, or upon a party within its independent community : nor are they laid upon the obhged party as being one of its subjects, but as being a member, to certain limited purposes, of the community wherein he resides. Again : If a stranger not residing within the given community be the owner of land or ipoveables lying within its territory, a convention of the stranger, with any of its members or a stranger, may be enforced against him by its positive law. For if he be sued on the agreement, and judgment be given for the plaintiff, the tribunal may execnte its judgment by resorting to the land or moveables, although the defendant's body is beyond the reach of its process. And this execution of the judgment consists with the sover- eignty of the government of which the stranger is properly a subject. For the judgment is not executed against that foreign government, or within the independent community of which it is the chief : nor is it executed against the de- fendant as being one of its subjects, but as owning land or ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 237 moveables within the jurisdiction of the tribunal. If the judgment were executed within the jurisdiction of the foreign supreme government, the execution would wound the sovereignty of the foreign supreme government, unless the judgment were executed through its permission and au- thority. And if the judgment were executed through its permission and authority, the duty enforced against the de- fendant would be imposed in effect by the law of his own community : the law of his own community adopting the law of the other, by reason of a special convention between the respective governments, or of a rule of international morality which the governments acknowledge and observe. 441. The definition, therefore, of a positive law, which is assumed expressly or tacitly throughout the foregoing lectures, is not a perfectly exact definition. In the cases noted and exemplified in the last paragraph, a positive law obliges legally a person or persons Twt of the community wherein the author of the law is sovereign or supreme. Now, since the cases in question are omitted by that definition, the definition is too narrow. To render that definition complete or adequate, a comprehensive summary of these anomalous cases (or, perhaps, a full enumeration of 'these anomalous cases) must be tacked to the definition in the way of supple- ment. Moreover, since the definition is defective or inade- quate, and is assumed expressly or tacitly throughout the foregoing lectures, the determination of the province of jurisprudence, which is attempted in those discourses, is not a perfectly complete and perfectly exact determination. 442. But a perfect determination of the province of jurisprudence is not the purpose of the foregoing lectures. Their purpose is merely to suggest the general character of the subject. That subject receives a more adequate exposi- tion in my entire Course. The anomalous cases to which I have referred belong to the departments of my Course which 238 ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY are concerned with the detail of the science. They hardly were appropriate matter for the foregoing general attempt to determine the province of jurisprudence : for the foregoing attempt to suggest the subject of the science, with as much of completeness and exactness as consist with generality and brevity. Member- 443. Defining sovcreigntyand independent political Society, * jF .° .* I have said that a given society is a society political and society, independent, if the bulk or generality of its members habitu- ally obey the commands of a determinate and independent party. — But who are the members of a given society ? By what characters, or by what distinguishing marks, are its members severed from persons who are not of its members ? By the foregoing general definition of independent poHtical society the questions which I now iiave suggested are not resolved or touched : And it may seem, therefore, that the foregoing general definition is not complete or adequate. But, for the following reasons, I believe that the foregoing definition, considered as a general definition, is, notwith- standing, complete or adequate: that a general definition of independent political society could hardly resolve the questions which I have suggested above. 444. (1) It is not through one mode, or it is not through one cause, that the members of a given society are subjects of the person or body sovereign therein. A person may be determined to a given society, by any of numerous modes, or by any of numerous causes : as, for example, by birth within the territory which it occupies; by birth without its territory, but of parents being of its members ; by simple residence within its territory ; or by naturalization. — Again :- A subject member of one society may be, at the same time, a subject member of another. A person, for example, who is natural- ized in'one independent society, may yet be a member com- pletely, or to certain limited purposes, of that independent ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 239 society which he affects to renounce: or a member of one society who simply resides in another, may be a member -completely of the former society, and, to limited purposes, a member of the latter. Nay, a person who is sovereign in one society, may be, at the same time, a subject member of another. Such, for example, would be the plight of a so- called limited monarch, if he were monarch and autocrator in a foreign independent conununity.-^Now if the foregoing definition of independent political society had affected to resolve the questions which I have suggested above, I must have discussed the topics which I have touched in the present paragraph. I must have gone from the generals into the detail of jurisprudence ; and therefore I must have wandered from the proper purpose or scope of the foregoing general attempt to determine the province of the science. 445. (2) By a general definition of independent political society (or such a definition as is applicable to every society of the kind), I could not have resolved completely the questions suggested above, although I had discussed the topics touched in the last paragraph. For the modes through which persons are members of particular societies (or the causes by which persons are determined to particular societies) differ in different communities. These modes are fixed differently in different particular societies, by their differeilt particular systems of positive law or morality. In some societies, for example, a person born of aliens within the territory of the community, is, ipso jure, or without an act of his own, a perfect member of the community within whose territory he is born ; but in other societies, he is not a perfect member (or is merely a resident alien) unless he acquire the character by fulfilling certain conditions. (See the French Code, Article 9.) It therefore is only in relation to a given particular society that the questions suggested above can be completely resolved. 240 OEIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY Restric- 446. I have assumed expressly or tacitly throughout the tion (a) on foregoing lectures that a sovereign government of one, or a position . , 1 • -J. 11 • that a sovereign government of a number m its collective and sovereign sovereign capacity, cannot be hound legally. In the sense bound ^^*^ which I have assumed it, the position will hold univer- legally. sally. But it needs a slight restriction, or rather a slight explanation, which may be placed conveniently at the close of my present discourse. 447. It is true universally, that as being the sovereign of the community wherein it is sovereign, a sovereign govern- ment cannot be bound legally. But, as beingji,,gu^eQ|^of a I foreign supreme government (either generally or to certaia I limited purposes), it may be bound by laws (simply and ! strictly so called) of that foreign supreme government. In the case which I now am supposing, the sovereign political government bound by positive laws bears two characters, or bears two persons : namely, the character or person o/ sovereign in its own independent society, and the charactei or person of subject in the foreign independent community And in order to the existence of the case which I now am supposing, its two characters or two persons must be distinct in practice, as well as in name and show. For example, before the French Revolution, the sovereign government of the Canton of Bern had money in the English funds: And if the English law empowered it to hold lands, it might be the owner of lands within the English territory, as weU as the owner of money in the English funds. Now, assuming that the government of Bern is an owner of lands in England, it also is subject to the legal duties with which property in land is saddled by the English law. But by its subjection to those duties, and its habitual observance of the law through which those duties are imposed, its sovereignty in its own , Canton is not annulled or impaired. For the duties are in- cumbent upon it (not as governing there, but) as owning ORIGIN OR CAUSES OF POLITICAL SOCIETY 241 lands here : as being, to limited purposes, a member of the British community, and obnoxious, through the lands, to the process of the English tribunals. 448. I have said in a preceding section, that a sovereign (*) On government of one, or a sovereign government of a number ^^"^ '^°° in its collective and sovereign capacity, cannot have legal sovereign rights (in the proper acceptation of the term) against its own ^*°"''* subjects. In the sense with which I have advanced it, the rights position will hold universally. But it needs a slight re- *g*"i3* ^^ . own sub- striction, or rather a slight explanation, which I now willjects. state or suggest. 449. It is true universally, that against a subject of its own, as being a subject of its own, a sovereign political government cannot have legal rights. But against a subject of its own, as being generally or partially a subject of a foreign government, a sovereign political government may have legal rights. For example : Let us suppose that a Eussian merchant is resident and domiciled in England : that he agrees with the Eussian emperor to supply the latter with naval stores : and that the laws of England, or the English tribunals, lend their sanction to the agreement. Now, according to these sup- positions, the emperor bears a right, given by the law of England, against a Eussian subject. But the emperor has not the right through a law of his own, or against a Eussian subject in that capacity or character. He bears the legal right against a subject of his own, through the positive law of a foreign independent society ; and he bears it against his subject (not as being his subject, but) as being, to limited purposes, a subject of a foreign sovereign. CHAPTEE VII ON THE USES OF THE STUDY OF JUKISPBUDENCE [In a prefatory note, Mrs. Austin relates that the matter which follows was taken chiefly from the opening lectures of the, two courses delivered hy Mr. Austin. The work of selection, arrangement and revision, was undertaken by Mrs. Austin, whose text I have adopted, save for the omission of less important sections. My own opinions upon the chief points discussed by Austin are given in the excursus on the Sciences of the Law.] Proper 450. The appropriate subject of Jurisprudence, in any of Jurispru- ^*^ different departments, is positive law : Meaning by positive deuce. law (or law emphatically so called), law established or ' positmn,' in an independent political community, by the ex- press or tacit authority of its sovereign or supreme govern- nient. 451. Considered as a whole, and as implicated or connected with one another, the positive laws and rules of a particular or specified community, are a system or body of law. And as limited to any one of such systems, or to any of its component parts, jurisprudence is particular or national. 452. Though every system of law has its specific and characteristic dififerences, there are principles, notions, and distinctions common to various systems, and forming analogies or likenesses by which such systems are allied. 453. Many of these common principles are common to all systems ; — to the scanty and crude systems of rude societies, and the ampler and maturer systems of refined communities. But the ampler and maturer systems of refined communities 242 THE STUDY OF JURISPRUDENCE 243 are allied by the numerous analogies which obtain between all systems, and also by numerous analogies which obtain ex- clusively between themselves. Accordingly, the various principles common to maturer systems (or the various analogies obtaining between them), are the subject of an extensive science: which science (as contradistinguished to national or particular jurisprudence on one side, and, on another, to the science of legislation) has been named General (or comparative) Jurisprudence, or the philosophy (or general principles) of positive law. 454. As principles abstracted from positive systems are the subject of general jurisprudence, so is the exposition of such principles its exclusive or appropriate object. With the goodness or badness of laws, as tried by the test of utility (or by any of the various tests which divide the opinions of mankind), it has no immediate concern. If, in regard to some of the principles which form its appropriate subject, it adverts to considerations of utility, it adverts to such considerations for the purpose of explaining such principles, and not for the purpose of determining their worth. And this distinguishes the science in question from the science of legislation : which affects to determine the test or standard (together with the principles subordinate or consonant to such test) by which positive law ought to be made, or to which positive law ought to be adjusted. 455. If the possibility of such a science appear doubtful, it arises from this ; that in each particular system, the principles and distinctions which it has in common with others, are com- plicated with its individual peculiarities, and are expressed in a technical language peculiar to itself. It is not meant to be affirmed that these principles and distinctions are conceived with equal exactness and adequacy in every particular system. In this respect different systems differ. But, in all, they are to be found more or less nearly conceived ; from the rude con- 244 THE STUDY OF JURISPRUDENCE ceptions of barbarians, to the exact conceptions of the Eoman lawyers or of enlightened modern jurists. 456. I mean, then, by General Jurisprudence, the science concerned with the exposition of the principles, notions, and distinctions which are common to systems of law: under- standing by systems of law, the ampler and maturer systems which, by reason of their amplitude and maturity, are pre- eminently pregnant with instruction. 457. Of the principles, notions, and distinctions which are the subjects of general jurisprudence, some may be esteemed necessary. For we cannot imagine coherently a system of law (or a system of law as evolved in a refined community), without conceiving them as constituent parts of it. 458. Of these necessary principles, notions, and distinc- tions, I will suggest briefly a few examples. 1°. The notions of Duty, Eight, Liberty, Injury, Punish- ment, Eedress ; with their various relations to one another, and to Law, Sovereignty, and Independent Political Society : 2°. The distinction between written or promulged, and unwritten or unpromulged law, in the juridical or improper senses attributed to the opposed expressions; in other words, between law proceeding immediately from a sover- eign or supreme maker, and law proceeding immediately from a subject or subordinate maker (with the authority of a sovereign or supreme) : 3°. The distinction of Eights, into rights availing against the world at large (as, for example, property or dominion), and rights availing exclusively against persons specifically determined (as, for example, rights from contracts) : 4°. The distinction of rights availing against the world at large, into property or dominion, and the variously restricted rights which are carved out of property or dominion : 5°. The distinction of Obligations (or of duties corre- THE STUDY OF JURISPRUDENCE 245 spending to rights against persons specifically determined) into obligations which arise from contracts, obligatiQns which arise from injuries, and obligations which arise from incidents that are neither contracts nor injuries, but which are styled analogically obligations ' quasi ex contractu : ' 6°. The distinction of Injuries or Delicts, into civil injuries (or private delicts) and crimes (or public delicts) ; with the distinction of civil injuries (or private delicts) into torts, or delicts (in the strict acceptation of the term), and breaches of obligations from contracts, or of obligations ' quasi ex contractu.' ■459. It will, I believe, be found, on a little examination and reflection, that every system of law (or every system of law evolved in a refined community) implies the notions and distinctions which I now have cited as examples; together with a multitude of conclusions imported by those notions and distinctions, and drawn from them, by the builders of the system, through inferences nearly inevitable. 460. Of the principles, notions, and distinctions which are the subjects of General Jurisprudence, others are not necessary (in the sense which I have given to the expres- sion). We may imagine coherently an expanded system of law, without conceiving them as constituent parts of it. But as they rest upon grounds of utility which extend through all communities, and which are palpable or obvious in all refined communities, they in fact occur very generally in matured systems of law; and therefore may be ranked properly with the general principles which are the subjects of general jurisprudence. 461. Such, for example, is the distinction of law into ' jus personarum' and 'jus rerum' : the principle of the scientific arrangement given to the Eoman Law by the authors of the elementary or institutional treatises from which Justinian's 246 THE STUDY OF JURISPKUDENOE Institutes were copied and compiled. The distinction, I believe, is an arbitrarily assumed basis for a scientific arrangement of a body of law. But being, a commodious \)asis for an arrangement of a body of law, it has been very generally adopted by those who have attempted such arrangements in the modern European nations. It has been very generally adopted by the compilers of the authori- tative Codes which obtain in some of those nations, and by private authors of expository treatises on entire bodies of law. Nay, some who have mistaken the import of it, and who have contemptuously rejected it, as denoted by the obscure antithesis of 'jus personarum et rerum,' have yet assumed it under other (and certainly more appropriate) names, as the basis of a natural arrangement. Meaning, I presume, by a natural arrangement, an arrangement so commodious, and so highly and obviously commodious, that any judicious methodiser of a body of law would naturally adopt it. tegiala- 462. The word Jurisprudence itself is not free from ambi- bon an gujty • it has been used to denote — Jnnspru- ° •' ' dence. The knowledge of Law as a science, combined with the art or practical habit or skill of applying it ; or, secondly. Legislation ; — the science of what oiight to he done towards making good laws, combined with the art of doing it. Inasmuch as the knowledge of what ought to be, supposes a knowledge of what is, legislation supposes jurisprudence, but jurisprudence does not suppose legislation. What laws have been and are, may be known without a knowledge of what they ought to be. Inevitable 463. It is impossible to consider Jurisprudence quite an aome- g^p^j,^ from Legislation ; since the inducements or considera- tentional) tions of expediency which lead to the establishment of laws, jmphca- jjj^gi; ^g adverted to in explaining their origin and mechanism. bon of iT D o Legiala- If the causes of laws and of the rights and obligations which THE STUDY OF JURISPEUDENCE 247 they create be not assigned, the laws themselves are unintel- tion witk ligible. i""'^^"^ ° dence. 464. Where the subject is the same, but the provisions of different systems with respect to that subject are different, it is necessary to assign the causes of the difference : whether they consist in a necessary diversity of circumstances, or in a ' diversity of views on the part of their respective authors with reference to the ends of Law. Thus, the rejection or limited reception of entails in one system, and their exten- sive reception in another, are partly owing to the different circumstances in which the communities are placed ; — partly to the different views of the aristocratic and democratic legislators by whom these provisions have been severally made. 465. So far as these differences are inevitable — are im- posed upon different countries — there can be no room for praise or blame. Where they are the effect of choice, there is room for praise or blame ; but I shall treat them not as subjects of either, but as causes explaining the existence of the differences. So of the admission or prohibition of divorce — Marriages within certain degrees, etc. Wherever an opinion is pronounced upon the merits and demerits of Law, an impartial statement of the conflicting opinions should be given. The teacher of Jurisprudence may have, and prob- ably has, decided opinions of his own ; but it may be ques- tioned whether earnestness be less favourable to impartiality than indifference ; and he ought not to attempt to insinuate his opinion of merit and demerit under pretence of assigning causes. 466. Attempting to expound the principles which are the subject of the science of Jurisprudence (or rather to expound as many of them as a limited Course of Lectures will embrace), he must not only try to state them in general or abstract expressions, but must also endeavour to illustrate 248 THE STUDY OF JURISPRUDENCE them by examples from particular systems: especially by examples from the law of England, and from the Eoman or Civil Law. Value of 467. Por the following sufficient reason (to which many of^Roman Others might be added), the Eoman or Civil Law is, of all Law. particular systems, other than the Law of England, the best of the sources from which such illustrations might be drawn. In most of the nations of modern continental Europe, much of the substance of the actual system, and much of the tech- nical language in which it is clothed, is derived from the Eoman Law, and without some knowledge of the Eoman Law the technical language is unintelligible; whilst; the order or arrangement commonly given to the system, imi- tates the exemplar of a scientific arrangement which Ib presented by the Institutes of Justinian. Even in our own country, a large portion of the Ecclesiastical and Equity, and some (though a smaller) portion of the Common Law, is derived immediately from the Eoman Law, or from the Eoman Law through the Canon. Nor has the influence of the Eoman Law been limited to the positive law of the modern European nations. For the technical language of this all-reaching system has deeply tinctured the language of the international law or morality which those nations affect to observe. By drawing, then, largely for examples on the Eoman or CivU Law, an expositor of General Jurispru- dence (whilst illustrating his appropriate subject) might present an idea of a system which is a key to the inter- national morality, the diplomacy, and to much of the positive law, of modern civilized communities. 468. It is much to be regretted that the study of the Eoman Law is neglected in this country, .and that the real merits of its founders and expositors are so little understood. ' Much has been talked of the philosophy of the Eoman Insti- tutional writers. Of familiarity with Grecian philosophy THE STUDY OF JURISPRUDENCE 249 there are few traces in their writings, and the little that they have borrowed from that source is foolishness: for example, their account of Jus naturale, in which they con- found law with animal instincts; law, with all those wants and necessities of mankind which are causes of its insti- tution. 469. Nor is the Eoman Law to be resorted to as a maga- zine of legislative wisdom. The great Eoman Lawyers are, in truth, expositors of a positive or technical system. Not Lord Coke himself is more purely technical. Their real merits lie in their thorough mastery of that system ; in their command of its principles ; in the readiness with which they recall, and the facility and certainty with which they apply them. 470. In support of my own opinion of these great writers I shall quote the authority of two of the most eminent Jurists of modern times. 'The permanent value of the Corpus Juris Civilis,' says Falck, ' does not lie in the Decrees of the Emperors, but in the remains of .juristical literature which have been pre- served in the Pandects. Nor is it so much the matter of these juristical writings, as the scientific method employed by the authors in explicating the notions and maxims with which they have to deal, that has rendered them models to all succeeding ages, and pre-eminently fitted them to pro- duce and to develop those qualities of the mind which are requisite to form a Jurist.' And Savigny says, ' It has been shown above, that, in our science, all results depend on the possession of leading prin- ciples; and it is exactly this possession upon which the greatness of the Eoman Jurists rests. The notions and maxims of their science do not appear to them to be the creatures of their own will; they are actual beings, with whose existence and genealogy they have become familiar 250 THE STUDY OF JURISPRUDENCE from long and intimate intercourse. Hence their whole method of proceeding has a certainty which is found nowhere else except in mathematics; and it may he said without exaggeration, that they calculate with their ideas. If they liave a case to decide, they begin by acquiring the most vivid and distinct perception of it, and we see before our eyes the rise and progress of the whole affair, and all the changes it undergoes. It is as if this particular case were the germ whence the whole science was to be developed. Hence, with them, theory and practice are not in fact dis- tinct ; their theory is so thoroughly worked out as to be iit for immediate application, and their practice is uniformly ennobled by scientific treatment. In every principle they see a case to which it may be applied ; in every case, the rule by which it is determined: and, in the facility with which they pass from the general to the particular and the particular to the general, their mastery is indisputable.' 471. In consequence of this mastery of principle's, of their perfect consistency (' elegantia '), and of the clearness of the method in which they are arranged, there is no positive system of law which it is so easy to seize as a whole. The smallness of its volume tends to the same end. The principles themselves, many of them being derived from barbarous ages, are indeed ill fitted to the ends of law ; and the conclusions at which they arrive being logical conse- quences of their imperfect principles, necessarily partake of the same defect. Uses of the 472. Having stated generally the nature of the science of Study of Jurisprudence, and also the manner in which I think it ought denoa. to be expounded, I proceed to indicate briefly a few of its possible uses, 473. I would remark, in the first place, that a well- grounded study of the principles which form the subject of the science, would be an advantageous preparative for the THE STUDY OF JURISPBUDENCE 251 study of English Law. To the student who begins the study of the English Law, without some previous knowledge of the rationale of law in general, it naturally appears an assemblage of arbitrary and unconnected rules. But if he approached it with a well-grounded knowledge of the general principles of jurisprudence, and with the map of a body of law dis- tinctly impressed upon his mind, he might obtain a clear conception of it (as a system or organic whole), with com- parative ease and rapidity. With comparative ease and rapidity, he might perceive the various relations of its various parts-; the dependence of its minuter rules on its general principles ; and the subordination of such of these principles as are less general or extensive, to such of them as are more general, and run through the whole of its structure. 474. In short, the preliminary study of the general principles of jurisprudence, and the mental habits which the study of them tends to engender, would enable him to acquire the principles of English jurisprudence, in particular, far more speedily and accurately than he possibly could have acquired them, in case he had begun the study of them with- out the preparative discipline. 475. There is (I believe) a not unprevalent opinion, that the study of the science whose uses I am endeavouring to demonstrate, might tend to disqualify the student for the practice of the law, or to inspire him with an aversion from the practice of it. That some who have studied this science have shown themselves incapable of practice, or that some who have studied this science have conceived a disgust of practice, is not improbably a fact. But in spite of this seem- ing experience in favour of the opinion in question, I deny that the study itself has the tendency which the opinion imputes to it. A well-grounded knowledge of the general principles of jurisprudence helps, as I have said, to a well- grounded knowledge of the principles of English jurispru- 252 THE STUDY OP JUEISPRUDENCE dence; and a previous well-grounded knowledge of the principles of English jurisprudence, can scarcely incapaci- tate the student for the acquisition of practical knowledge in the chambers of a conveyancer, pleader, or draftsman. Armed with that previous knowledge, he seizes the rationale of the practice which he there witnesses and partakes in, with comparative ease and rapidity ; and his acquisition of practical knowledge, and practical dexterity and readiness, is much less irksome than it would be in case it were merely empirical. Insomuch, that the study of the general principles of jurisprudence, instead of having any of the tendency which the opinion in question imputes to it, has a tendency (by ultimate consequence) to qualify for practice, and to lessen the natural repugnance with which it is re- garded by beginners. 476. And as a well-grounded knowledge of the science whose uses I am endeavouring to demonstrate, would facili- tate to the student the acquisition of the English law, so would it enable him to apprehend, with comparative ease and rapidity, almost any of the foreign systems to which he might direct his attention. So numerous, as I have said, are the principles common to systems of law, that a lawyer who has mastered the law which obtains in his own country, has mastered implicitly most of the substance of the law which obtains in any other community. So that the difficulty with which a lawyeir, versed in the law of his own country, appre- hends the law of another, is rather the result of differences between the terms of the systems, than of substantial or real differences between their maxims and rules. 477. Now the obstacle to the apprehension of foreign systems which is opposed by their technical language, might in part be obviated or lightened to the student of General Jurisprudence, if the science were expounded to him com- petently, in the method which I shall endeavour to observe THE STUDY OF JURISPRUDENCE 253 [f the exposition of the science were made agreeably to that method, it would explain incidentally the leading terms, as well as the leading principles, of the Eoman or Civil Law. And if the student were possessed of those terms, and were also grounded thoroughly in the law of his own country, he would master with little difficulty the substance of the Eoman system, and of any of the modern systems which are mainly derivatives from the Eoman. PART II EXCURSUS A THE STATE The State 501. " It is a fact which has received far too little notice from English lawyers," writes Professor Dicey, " that, when- ever men act in concert for a common purpose, they tend to create a body which, from no fiction of law, but from the very nature of things, differs from the individuals of whom it is constituted."^ To some this may seem a strange saying. Yet it contains a truth of the first importance which we must take full account of, if we are to make satisfactory pro- gress in the direction of a theory of the State which will serve the purposes of a reflective jurisprudence. For the State is but one of the many forms in which the associative tendency of mankind finds expression. Before we can form a theory about it, we must consider the nature of social groups in general. English 502. How has law regarded social groups in the past? law and Towards the great majority of them, English law has assumed group. an attitude of mere tolerance. It has not forbidden or at- tempted to crush them, as it might have done ; it has simply ignored them. But at times and places, this attitude of mere tolerance has not been possible. Some sort of recogni- tipn, of some sorts of groups, has become increasingly neces- 1 "Law and Opinion in England," p. 153. 254 THE STATE 255 sary as man has become more and more a social being. One form of such recognition has been to attribute a representa- tive capacity to certain individuals who act in behalf of the groups. The Crown has been a convenient scapegoat for national sins; the trustees of a nonconformist chapel have stood in law for the nonconformist congregation. In so far as legal recognition of groups is relevant to our present pur- poses, however, it has taken the form of a theory of corpora- tions. This theory may be summarized very briefly in four propositions. 503. (1) A corporation is something distinct from the in- Corpora- dividual persons who constitute it. The position is too *^"'" '■^^ ^ members. obvious to need proof. The whole is more than its parts. The individual members of a mining company have no im- mediate right of property in the mine or the machinery, and if any one of them should presume to act as owner, he would be liable to civil action as an ordinary trespasser. It is of more practical importance to point out, for the sake of the uninitiated, that the persons who constitute the corporation are not necessarily coincident with two other classes of per- sons who are directly associated with it, viz. : (a) Those persons through whom the corporation acts, (b) those persons in whose interests the corporation exists. The former are often called representatives, the latter beneficiaries. In a typical municipal corporation, the members are the mayor, aldermen, and burgesses of the borough; the beneficiaries are the inhabitants of the borough; and the "representa- tives " are the mayor, aldermen, and town councillors. In an ordinary mining company, the members, and also the beneficiaries, are the shareholders ; whilst, for most purposes, the " representatives " are the directors. Both members and "representatives" of corporations are living persons — I speak throughout of corporations aggregate as distinct from Eorporations sole — whilst the beneficiaries may be, as in the 256 THE STATE case of the University of Cambridge, an indeterminate body embracing present and future generations. Corpora- 504. (2) A corporation is, in the eye of the law, distinct f from the sum of its members. This fact received an inter- sum 01 members, fisting illustration in Eoman law. In that system, although the torture of a slave as a means of extorting information against his master was prohibited, the slave of a corporation might be tortured as a means of gaining information against any or all of its individual memiers. As regards English law, the following illustrations may be quoted : (a) Each of the members of a corporation may be solvent whilst the corporation itself is insolvent. (&) The very same persons who have registered themselves as one company may also register themselves as another and quite distinct company. If the corporation were identical with the sum of its members they would be one company, but the law holds them two. (c) The corporation remains the same, although its per- sonnel changes entirely. It is a totality of which the parts are constantly changing without affecting the continuity of the totality itself. (d) Finally, the corporation is no mere partnership. Thus, partners are, whilst corporators need not be, liable for the debts of the group. Partners own, whilst corporators do not own, the group property. A partnership possesses a practically unrestricted power in dealings with third parties, while a corporation is ordinarily limited by reference to the purposes for which it is incorporated. Finally, whilst partnership can be resolved into mere contract, a corpora- tion implies a new status. " Contract, that greediest of legal cdtegories," writes Professor Maifrland, " which once wanted to devour the state, resents being told that it cannot pain- lessly digest even a joint-stock company." ^ ' " Political Theories of the Middle Age," p. xxiv. THE STATE 257 505. (3) The corporation is a legal subject of right and Corpora- duties. If the law recognizes a distinction between a cor- °^. *^ , ° _ _ _ subject 0^ poration and the sum of its members, it is not as a mere rights. flight of fancy, or to indulge an inclination for metaphysics, but for the very practical and sufficient purpose of establish- ing the inherence of certain rights and duties which cannot be conveniently treated — or perhaps cannot be treated at all — as inhering in the members of the corporation. The property of a corporation follows the fate of the corporation, whatever that may be, not the fate of its members, whatever that may be. It is the corporation (not the members) which is creditor and debtor. 506. (4) The corporation is, therefore, in law a person. Corpora- The cardinal distinction of jurisprudence is between rights ""* * or duties, and the holders or subjects of rights or duties. Such subjects are persons in law. This does not mean that they are not also persons in fact, a suggestion which might occur to the layman who has a mother-in-law who, by the way, is a mother neither in fact nor in law. It will be obvious that while some human beings (e.g. slaves) are not persons, some persons are not .human beings. Wherever the law attributes rights or duties to an entity or institu- tion, it makes a person of, or recognizes a person in, that entity or institution. It becomes important, therefore, to distinguish between different kinds of persons in law. When the person in law is also a human being, it is called a natural person; when it is not a human being, it is some- times called an artificial person. We have hitherto con- sidered how the law regards that so-called artificial person which we know as the corporation. We have now to look behind legal rules to the nature of things, and to consider whether, in distinguishing between the corporaticm and the sum of its members, the law is merely employing a service- able fiction, or is building on certain real and deep analogies 258 THE STATE to natural personality which exist wholly apart from legal recognition. Unity of 507. The inquiry is one which leads us on from the t 6 social g^bjgpj Qf corporations to the wider subject of human association in general. Of this wider subject it is necessary ^ to speak for a moment. Whenever men act in common, I they inevitably tend to develop a spirit which is something different from themselves taken singly or in sum. No one who has had any experience as a member of a governing body, for example, can be ignorant of the fact that the decisions of such a body, even when they are unanimous, are often inexplicable if regarded from the point of view of the several characters of the individual members considered as so many units. When at a meeting of such a board, a speaker begins with the statement, " I speak as a member of this board, and I say ," there will be reason to antici- pate statements or proposals which represent the traditional policy of the board rather than the person who makes them. Under the inspiration of esprU de corps, the humane will give a cruel decision, the cruel a humane. In every group of men acting together for a common purpose, the common purpose inevitably begets a common spirit which is real, 'though it may be vague and indefinite to us because our vision is limited, or because the group is in the making. The group becomes, or tends to become, a unit ; and, as Bluntschli so well said, a mere sum of individuals as such can no more become a unit than a heap of sand can become a statue. So a symphony is something more than a mere concurrence of sounds, and a cathedral than stone and mortar. As regards the human group, in proportion as the psychical realities which inspire it become distinct and emphatic, so is the efficiency of the group increased, and its purpose promoted. The group 508. The unity of spirit and purpose just referred to is in action. THE STATE 259 developed by continuous action in common. It is not so obvious, though quite as true, that the same unity tends to beget a dififerent kind of action — the action of some in behalf of all. As psychical realities in the individual find means of expression in individual action, so psychial realities in the group find means of expression in cor- porate action. But the individual is a natural organism with predetermined organs for expressing the individual will. The group is not a natural organism, and number- less difficulties have to be overcome when the ^roup ^mind seeks realization in the external world. The difficulties^ will be overcome somehow, though possibly the group j may never pass beyond the stage when action of the whole is only possible by combined action of each of the 1 parts. In all highly developed groups, however, some one i person, or a number of persons, acquires a capacity to | express in action the will of the group. If we may employ an extremely useful and suggestive analogy, he or they are the organ of the group for the purpose of giving external expression to the corporate will. Inevitably, such expression lacks the directness and spontaneity which exist in the case of the individual ; but the group-purpose is promoted in proportion as such directness and spontaneity are approached. The member of a highly developed group is thus part of a new power or force. For this privilege, however, he forgoes something of his own liberty of action. In becoming a member of an organized whole, he loses apparently something of his significance as a unit. He ceases to become a member of an undisciplined mob that he may become a soldier in a disciplined army. 509. The realities of group life may be found in every Group u. degree of intensity. They take their beginning wherever 8'""'°n'- two individuals act in a common undertaking. Each in- dividual takes to every group with which he associates 260 THE STATE something of the group spirit with which inheritance and circumstance have endowed him. In every group sufficiently i organized to act as a group, there exist, thor^h at different I degrees of development, the phenomena which justify us in regarding society as an organic whole. Law is not in haste to recognize the fact; hut when the group is large and its organization complex, and more especially when it assumes the responsibility of owning property, recognition becomes more and more urgent. As a member of such a group, the individual is affected, however slightly, yet to some extent;, qualities are developed in him which cannot be explained save by reference to the union. More obviously, the group itself is something which cannot be analysed into the mere sum of its parts. The sum of the parts may survive the destruction of the group, but can no more explain the group than the material of a murdered organism explains the organism. The cor- 510. I return to the legal view of human groups, as that pora ion. y^g^ ^g presented to us in the theory of corporations. The corporation is a group recognized as such by law. The , psychic bonds to which I have referred as existing in all social groups, derive an added reality and efficiency from the mere fact of legal recognition. Differences of opiaion and aim may exist within the group, but there is at least one will which may be assumed to be general, the will to continue the collective work. The corporation, in a word, is an efficiently organized unity which the State has re- cognized. To it, as we have seen, the law ascribes a distinctive existence, a capacity for right and duty, a person- ality. This personality differs from the personalities of the natural persons composing it, but shares with them the important characteristic of being based on a pre-existing capacity for will and action. In view of this capacity, it is difficult to hold, as traditional theory in England professes to THE STATE 261 hold, that the law, in distinguishing between the corporation and the sum of its members, is merely employing a service- able fiction. The difficulty becomes each year more obvious, owing to the enormous development of associated activities. We may readily ignore what we see seldom or in incipient stages; what appears before us at every moment and at highly developed stages, refuses to be ignored. To the moderns it is becoming increasingly clear that "the some- thing more than the sum of its members '' which the State implicitly recognizes as a person, is no mere creation of the juristic imagination, but is rather a reality as indisputable as man himself. 511. The real character of corporate personality is sug- Early gested by certain facts in the early history of corporations W^t^'y in England. The chief attributes of the corporation, such porationa. as perpetual succession, the right to sue and be sued by name, to purchase lands, to have a common seal and to make by-laws, were long recognized before the conception of the corporation was thought of. Their attainment marked stages which corresponded to the developments of social life rather than of juristic thought. "All the ancient boroughs of England, or nearly all," wrote Stubbs, "must have possessed all the rights of corporations and been corporations by prescription long before the reign of Henry VI; and the acquisition of a formal charter of incorpor- .ation could only recognize, not bestow, these rights."^ So far from the corporation having been the creature of the law, we ought rather to regard it as an entity which has compelled the law to grant it official recognition. Acting as a person, it has compelled law to regard it as a person. The function of the State in the matter has been permissive and regulative rather than creative. The relation suggests the judicial • " Constitutional History of England." ill. 262 THE STATE adoption of a social usage. If -the judges have made new law, they have not made new rule. Similarly, statute or charter, in conferring upon a social group the legal status of a corporation, is not creating something new ; it is simply setting an official seal upon a pre-existing reality. The unin- 512. Those to whom the past history of corporations in OToup™ " English law is inconclusive, will do well to reflect upon the enormous range and variety of those unincorporated institu- tions which exist to-day, and of which many already present the more important characteristics of personality without having been officially and openly recognized as legal persons. When such an unincorporate group chooses to incorporate, the change, as Professor Maitland has well said, may amount to no more than a mere event in its history. "We could not even compare it to the attainment of full age. Eather it is as if a ' natural person ' bought a type- writing machine or took lessons in stenography." Corpora- 513. The untenability of the view that corporate per- tion V. sonality is a mere legal fiction is most clearly seen when we fictitious ,. . . , ,..,., compare corporate personalities with personalities which are really fictitious. Austin classifies "fictitious or legal persons " under three heads : — 1. Collections of physical persons, e.g. corporations aggre- gate. 2. Things, e.g. the praedium dominans. 3. Collections of rights and duties, e.g. the haereditas jacens?- No argument can be necessary to prove that in the second and third of these cases the attribution of personality is a mere legal fiction designed to facilitate certain practical objects. If the jurist visualizes the haereditas jacens as a person, it is merely because he finds it convenient to do so, person. ' Jurisprudence," 5th ed., I, 354. THE STATE 263 and not because of any realities in the haereditas jacens itself which bear a close analogy to natural personality. Unities of spirit and purpose, will and action, are wholly lacking. To talk of them is absurd. 514. To the discerning, then, it would seem that the view Fiction of corporate personality as a mere fiction is but a stage in ^^^°^y » the evolution of legal ideas. When, at a certain stage in tional national development, lawyers find themselves brought face ***8«- to face with the fact of corporate personality, they find a difficulty in knowing what to do with it. Existing legal categories find no place for it. No material reality, nothing apparent to the senses, is at hand. A crude realism denies / / that there can be any person except the corporators. Yet realities press with increasing urgency for legal recognition. It is seen to be necessary to recognize in the group a capacity for legal rights and duties — the test of personality. To call the group a person is theti the first stage — ^person not by reality, but by fiction of the law. There is nothing beyond the corporators, it is said, but let us suppose a person for convenience' sake. As groups multiply and ideas develop, this provisional solution of law is seen to owe more to realities and less to the juristic imagination than was at first supposed. The corporate person is stated to be a real person. The statement is true, though, as I shall proceed to show, it is liable to be misunderstood. 515. The outcome of the preceding argument may be Corpora- briefly expressed by saying that the corporation is a person, '°° ?' and that this person is not a legal fiction. That it must be person. in consequence a real person, seems to follow necessarily. Yet we must be careful to remember that, in such a con- nection, the term " real " person is not the same as physical person. Personality is a legal conception. A natural person is a legal conception, a physical reality, and a natural organism. A corporation is a legal conception, but neither 264 THE STATE a physical reality nor a natural organism. When we say I that a corporation is a person, we imply that it is a lega) I conception. When we say that this corporate person is not a legal fiction, we imply that it is a representation of .psJLchical realities which the law recognizes rather, than creates. The whole conception of group personality belongs to the world, not of material, but of psychical jealities. The differences between corporations and physical persons are so numerous and significant that it is important in the interests of clear thinking not to lose sight of them — a thing we are very apt to do if we press certain highly practical and profoundly suggestive analogies beyond legiti- mate limits. When a corporate person comes to will and to act, it is confronted by peculiar difficulties. The ordinary principle of willing by a majority is a triumph of conscious art. "The canon lawyers," it has been said, "escaped the fallacy that some natural law enables a majority of members in a duly convened meeting to express the will of the corporation." i The law assumes, it is sometimes urged, that the will of a majority represents what would be the unanimous will of the corporation if unanimity were in- sisted upon. It need hardly be said that this is pure assumption, justified by expediency and not by a 'priori necessity. Again, natural persons act without the mediation of another person. The corporate person can only act through the mediation of natural persons. The real sig- nificance of this difference is seen when we try to find a name for the natural persons who act for the group. Shall we call them agents ? representatives ? or organs ? To call them agents is clearly open to objection, since an agent is appointed by a» principal who himself wills and acts. To choose between representative and organ is more difficult > Pollock and Maitland, "History of English Law," I, 491. THE STATE 265 The term representative suggests a distinct person whose will and act are accepted as the will and act of another person. A more intimate term is needed to describe the persons whose acts are attributed to the corporation. They are members of the corporation, and their will has more claim to incarnate the corporate will than the will of the guardian, for example, to incarnate the will of the ward. That this is true is exemplified by common speech, which identifies the will of the natural persons acting for the group with the group itself, while refraining from speaking of the \Vill of the guardian as the will of the ward. We say the community sold; we do not say as much of the idiot, argues Le Mestre.^ On the whole, the term organ seems more apt to suggest the true inwardness of things than any other that can be suggested. Nevertheless, it is ^lear that between the organ of the group and the organ of the individual there are important differences. The one has an independent existence, the other has not; the one is a person, the other is not; the one is variable, the other is necessary and unchangeable. The natural person who follows a scriptural injunction as to offending members may find himself eternally bereft; the group person is more fortunate. The dangers of a too literal interpretation o£ the word organ are well illustrated by the anthropomorphism of an early time in accordance with which it was held that a corporation could not survive the loss of its head. So wrote King James of the body politic. " And for the simili- tude of the head and the body, it may well fall out that the head will be forced to garre cut off some rotten member to keep the rest of the body in integritie; but what state can the body be in if the head for any infirmitie that can fall to it be cut off, I leave it to the reader's judgment." * ' " Les Personnes morales," 212. * King James, "Works," ed. 1616. 266 THE STATE' The State. 516. If we now return to the problem with which we started, how to formulate a legal theory of the State, we have at our command a conception of group life which should prove of the utmost service — the conception of a corporate personality. I have endeavoured to prove, at a perhaps wearisome length, that this conception is no mere fiction of the law. My reason will be now apparent. If corporate personality were mere fiction, the propriety of consider- ing the State as a person would have to be determined by reference to purely formal considerations. But if, as I have endeavoured to prove, the corporate personality is no mere creation of the lawyer's imagination, but a generali- zation based on certain unities of spirit,. purposes, interests, and^orgamzation which exist in every social group, we can no longer deny the necessity for recognizing the personality of that highest and most developed social group, the State. Patrimonial theories of government, and doctrines of an absolute sovereignty of visible rulers, may blind us to this necessity. Its ultimate recognition is inevitable. Legal con- 517. In these respects, as in many others, the theory of servatism ^jjg jg^^ ]^^ lagged behind the thought of the nation. While with re- ■, ■ -i , . , ,. i • i speet to lawyers have admitted the existence of " personality which the State, ig a fiction " in the corporation, other people are loudly affirm- ing the existence of " a personality which is no fiction " in the State. The historian who sees in the State a growth, the scientist or sociologist who holds it a moral organism, the political philosopher who talks of social solidarity, the social consciousness, conscience, will, and intellect — all alike bear testimony to the power and growth of a conception which has enriched the political thought of our time. Even that much-abused individual, the man in the street, is beginning to feel that the State into which he is born and in which he lives and dies, which comes out of the past and passes on to an indefinite future, may have many "personal" qualities THE STATE 267 and an existence from many points of view superior to his own. Meanwhile, however, from the point of view of English law, if we are to believe what we are told, the State is no person, ideal or fictitious. In Great Britain, it is not the State, but the Crown, which owns property, is responsible for debts, enjoys rights and privileges, and administers justice. Truly the ways of transgressors are hard. Pro- hibited from admitting the personality of the State, either by the poverty of our ideas or by the conservatism of our temperament, we are driven to the device of attributing privileges and responsibilities to the king which no one can suppose to be really his. A sounder legal theory, however, knocks loudly at our door, and some day we shall awake to find we have been talking in our sleep. When that day has come, some legal fictions which are real fictions will make way for a legal theory which is a true theory — a theory, I may add, which is already implicit in many legal rules.^ 518. If it be the mission of legal science to look behind the The prob- professions of the lawyer, to harmonize those professions with I*™ °^ one another and with the facts of national life, we must con- denoe. elude that the jurist has a serious responsibility to undertake in the direction of giving some rational account of the State. He must take the legal conception of corporate personality, interpret that conception in the way most consistent with the facts of social life, and must here bring his deeper inter- pretation to bear on the problem of the nature of the State itself. In the process he will discover that the analogies between the State and the corporation are incomparably more important than the differences. 519. The most conspicuous differences between the State state v. and the corporation deserve consideration if only to convince ""^P"™" ' On the nature of the Crown as a Corporation, vide two articles in the "Law Quarterly Review," the first by Professor Maitland, vol. XVII, 131, the second by Professor Harrison Moore, vol. XX, 351. 268 THE STATE us of the superior claims of the State's personality to recog- Dition. In the first place, the State's will is sovereig n, and j therefore subject to no regulation from above ; its powers ( over members are numerous, indefinite, and irresistible ; and I its purposes, general rather than special, touch human life at j every point. In the second place, it has far more claims to be considered a natural growth than most corporationa Conscious art has far less to do in its origin. It is born before the individuals whose lives go to form it are quite aware of what they are doing. With self -consciousness comes a demand for philosophical justification of the state-building process, but that process has been going on in obedience to elemental instinct. "Law and institutions are only possible," writes Professor Bosanquet, " because man is already what they gradually make more and more explicit."^ Hence, in the ^ third place, the personality of the State is more highly developed than that of other collective persons. The share- holder in a joint-stock company is united to other shareholders by unities in every way inferior in degree and intensity to those which bind together the citizens of a state. Both com- pany and State are organized groups, but in the mind of the component individuals which go to form them, the social self in one case is strictly limited, whilst in the other case it is unlimited, extending in its range over the whole compass of individuality. Some 520. While the consideration of the differences between practical jj^g gtafce and the corporation only serves to intensify the ad van- ^ ,• u tagesof conviction of the reality of the States personality, when conception once this personality is definitely recognized, the student has person- ** ^^^ disposal a view of the State which has the merit of ality. .regresentiag^rea^ties^and incidentally of solving some of the most difficult problems of Public Law. In particular, the representation of the action of the State through its ' Philosophical Theory of the State," p. 122. THE STATE 269 government, as the action of a person through definite organs, commands respect as a representation which is both convenient and true. The value of the conception of State personality in regard to questions of sovereignty will receive some illustrations in the following Excursus. 521. If, then, the State be a person, and if that person The posi- has very special claims to legal recognition, to what position *'°° °f • • • a Btfitto 111 ft should we assign it xn a complete scheme of legal persons ? scheme of To answer this question, we must begin at the beginning ^^g"! and consider how law at present classifies persons. In the first place, we must exclude from the list of persons recog- nized as such by law, certain entities which hover on the bor- ders of recognition as persons without securing such recogni- tion. The class includes slaves, children en ventre sa mire, and group personalities of which the law takes no direct cognizance. As we have seen, no degree of psychological unity will serve to make a group for legal purposes a person : a family may be a psychological unity ; it is not as such a person : a large number of natural persons may pledge themselves, soul and body, to secure a political reform ; they do not as such become legal persons. In the second place, among legal persons we must distinguish those which are real from those which are fictitious. Instances of the last-mentioned abounded in later Eoman Law. A person who dedicated property for certain purposes, whether by will or by gift inter vivos, thereby created a new subject of rights and duties — ^it may be a hospital, poor-house, convent or church. In English Law we have an instance in the corporation sole. We attribute personality to the succession of the holders of a certain office. There can be no pretence to psychological unity in such cases. The attribution of personality may be serviceable, but is fictitious. In the third place, among legal persons which are real persons, we have to distinguish between those which consist of an 270 THE STATE individual and those which consist of a group of individuals. The former are generally called natural persons. The group of individuals is often called a moral person, but this term cannot be used with propriety by the jurist for the reason that it has been already appropriated by the philosopher. Just as the natural person of the lawyer has to be dis- tinguished from the physical person of the vernacular, so the group person of the lawyer must be distinguished from that much wider class, the moral person of the philosopher A more common designation of the group person is "juristic," though this latter term is open to the objection that the natural person is a juristic conception and therefore a juristic person. The term, however, is very generally adopted in practice and may be accepted on this ground Finally, juristic persons have to be divided into two classes according as the person is, or is not, a public body. The State finds its true place in the complete scheme as a concrete example of the last-mentioned class. Combining the various principles, we arrive at the following classifica- tion : — Persons in a wide sense. ! I 1 Legal persons. Not legal persons, though analogous thereto. Keal. Fictitious, e.g., I Corporation sole. I 1 1 1 Physical, Not physical, Physical, Not physical, i.e., natural, i.e., juristic. e.g., slaves. i.e., group entities, I such as a club, I ■" ■ " j a Nonconformist ■ Public, e.g., the Private, e.g., congregation. State or a muni- an incorporated » partnership, cipal corporation. company. etc. Such a classification may leave much to be desired from the point of view of logic, but it is perhaps as logical as the present condition of the law will admit. EXCURSUS B SOVEEEIGNTY 525. The student who invades that dread domain, the contro- Kterature of the doctrine of sovereignty, finds himself in a versial world where differences of opinion are numerous and funda- ^j ^.j^^ mental. One moment he learns that sovereignty is neces- subject sarily absolute, the next that it is eternally limited. Now he is told that in the nature of things sovereignty must be indivisible and inalienable; now he is confronted with definite illustrations of sovereignties which have been divided or abdicated. If he seeks to inquire what sovereignty is based on, he is told by some that it is based on force, by others on will, by others on reason. If he be so rash as to ask where sovereignty resides, he is referred to persons or bodies of all kinds — to a visible ruler, to governments, to constitution-revising assemblies, to an electorate, to the popular majority, or to the body politic. 526. He who knowingly and voluntarily enters upon a Suggested region of such bewildering contradictions, may be presumed^ explana- to be possessed of the doubtful blessings of an independent {^^^^ mind and a will to fight-his way to conclusions which shall be his own. He need also have a courage and a modesty not less rare, a courage to brave difiCculties which have over- come many a hardy adventurer who has gone before him ; a modesty to profit by the lessons which the failures of others may afibrd him. If he can but discover some intelligible explanation of the extraordinary divergences of opinion to which reference has been made, the explanation may enable 271 272 SOVEREIGNTY him to avoid at least some of the dangers that have been fata» to others. Three facts may be mentioned as a contribution towards such an explanation. (1) Sever- 527. In the first place, as man is constituted, sovereignty worth ''^ something well worth fighting about. It belongs, if not fighting to the things which men hold sacred, at least to the things * ■ which men hold dear. Power and, authm'ity^ over others ! In the great controversies which have raged from time to time round the subject, the student will find everywhere reflected the despotism of the emotions over the intellect \ Theories of sovereignty have been more often apologies for a fcause than the expression of a disinterested love for truth. Bodin, father of the modern doctrine, was supremely a defen- der of the centralized monarchy which was to supersede a decadent feudalism, and win for France the first place among the nations of the earth. Hobbes, if not the apologist of tyranny, was at least the defender of absolutism. Endowed with a nature which combined moral courage with physical cowardice, he was audacious in abstract speculation whilst actually engaged in building a political fabric wherein the individual might find a substitute for the infallibility of the Pope in the infallibility of the monarch. Eousseau, ^ro- pounder of a political theory which, in spite of defects and inconsistencies, revealed the subtlety of a philosopher and the fire of a prophet, was a passionate devotee of the Eights of Man. When the gospel which he proclaimed was adopted as the vindication of the Eevolution, when the Eeign of j Terror succeeded to 'the despotism of princes, the way was prepared for a host of reactionary theorists supremely con- cerned to defend the cause of social order against an imminent social anarchy. So, historically-minded jurists like Burke and Savigny, repelled by the excessive emphasis which the school of Eousseau had laid upon the conscious element in human development, proclaimed a doctrine of society as aa SOVEREIGNTY 273 unconscious growth ; philosophical jurists like Kant, alarmed lest the risings of the peoples should mean the recrudescence of barbarism, preached a doctrine yrhioh denied the right of popnlfir resistance and affirmed the doctrine of governmental . absolutism in terms which often exceeded the professions of the illustrious Bodin; and religious writers like De Maistre, shocked by the apparent irreligion of the Eevolu- tionaries, preached a doctrine of monarchical legitimacy which was scarcely distinguishable from the despised and rejected theory of the divine rights of kings. Still kter in the nineteenth century, in that great Republic of the New World which was officially pledged to the theory of the Eevolution and the Eights of Man, the doctrine of sover- eignty became the debating ground of acute and subtle thinkers who sought to defend, or to deny, the rights of par- ticular States in the Union. That controversy, as we all know, was settled by an appeal to the sword — an appeal which might have grand political results, but was unlikely to contribute to the scientific elucidation of juristic or political theory. 528. In the second place, sovereignty, being an attribute (2) Sorer- of human association, must be subject like human associa- *ig"*y » tion to the laws of developnjgpt. Generically deecribable ment. as some kind of power or authority in some kind of political community, sovereignty must necessarily change as com- munities grow. Any account of it which afifects to be — universalis almost certain to be misleading. Failure to recog- nize this simple fact, attempts to find universal theories when provisional theories alone can be at once possible and useful, have resulted in a fatal divorce between doctrine and reality. 529. In the third place, and the fact will be evident from (3) Sover- what has preceded, sovereignty is not a conception of which «'g"*y * , conception the meaning is wholly confined to one department of human of several 274 SOVEREIGNTY social thought. It disturbs the serenity of the courts of justice ; it sciences. gjj|;gj.g ^j^g arena of legislative debate; it is a matter of inter- national diplomacy which at any moment may bring the armies of the nations into savage conflict. One consequence is clear. The lawyer, the political philosopher, the inter- I national jurist — each of these must necessarily regard the / faet of supremacy in a State from his own point of view. A doctrine of that supremacy which will serve for the one, will be misleading or inadequate for the others. Failure to recog- nize this simple truth has added enormously to the perplexi- ties of the highly controversial literature of the subject. The lawyer appeals to the dicta of the statesman or the diplomatist, in order to defend a position which may be valid within the sphere of Politics or International Law, and yet be wholly inadmissible for the purposes of the settlement of judicial conflicts. On the other hand, revolutionists, while going beyond the law, have often striven to prove that they were keeping within it, and have affirmed a legal right of resistance where none but a moral right could be pretended. TheMoral. 530. The extraordinary dissidence of opinion, which might drive a student to the extremities of cynicism or despair, assumes a less terrible aspect when we remember that it can be largely explained by other considerations than the intrinsic difficulty of the subject. The labours of the student of Jurisprudence will be much lighter, and incomparably more fruitful,, if he will bear in mind that his purpose is scientific not polemic, that his field of investigation is the highly developed community not universal history, and that his point of view is that of the lawyer as distinct from that of the statesman, the diplomatist, or the political philoso- pher. He must not be surprised, however, if he finds it not always easy to observe the last of the limitations suggested. If, disdaining to regard as holy writ the consecrated formulae which the lawyer employs to conceal his thought, he looks SOVEREIGNTY 275 beyond such formulae to realities, he is brought at times into very close relations with the social sciences generally. Partly for this reason, and partly in order to illustrate the general position that the poiiits of view must be carefully distin- guished, I shall preface the discussion of the subject of sovereignty in Jurisprudence by a brief consideration of the allied subjects of sovereignty in International Law and in Political Science. I. Sovereignty in International Law 531. Discussions on the nature of sovereignty have occu- Sover- pied a prominent place in the literature of International *'S"*y "• Law. Such discussions approach the subject from a point of tional view which is distinguishable from that adopted by writers ^"'^ Com- on Jurisprudence, even when the Jurisprudence is based on l^^_ the comparative study of different legal systems, I'he stu- dent of International Law, like the student of Comparative Law, is concerned with existing forms and institutions rather than with the actualities of a remote past or the unrealized ideals of some philosophic system. Both are legalists who seek a doctrin e of sovereignty which will apply over a wide area. But at this point important differences become ap- parent. The student of Comparative Law is more especially concerned with the better understanding of the Constitution of his own country. He may take a wide view of political societies, but he is eclectic in his study of them. If he finds that his doctrine of sovereignty does not square with facts as they appear in communities less developed than his own, he does not necessarily modify that doctrine. The student of International Law, on the other hand, must find some place for such communities in his scheme. Again, the student of Comparative Law is primarily interested in the internal aspect of sovereignty ; the student of International Law in the external aspect. One thinks of sovereignty as supremacy 276 SOVEREIGNTY over the subjects ; the other as a relation of State to State. As a consequence, the student of International Law is inti- mately concerned with topics which are only incidentally discussed by the Comparative lawyer — e.g., the extent to which the independence of a sovereign may be affected by treaty obligations. Finally, the student of International Law, perplexed by the variety of the material with which he has to deal, is compelled to rest content with a conception of sovereignty as divisible into many parts, of which hardly any one is essential.^ II. Sovereignty in Political Science Legal V. 532. In the notes to the text of Austin, I have referred on Political several occasions to the distinction between legal and poHti- 80V6r- eignty. °^^ sovereignty. The distinction is of great importance even in the elementary form in which it is generally pre- sented. The lawyer is interested in the State in so far as the State takes form in definite organizations recognized by the law. The political philosopher, desirous of penetrating more deeply into the nature of things, looks behind such organizations to the powers or forces which find expression in them. Both think of sovereignty as supremacy, but one regards that supremacy as an attribute of some organization known to the law; the other regards that supremacy as a reality in the world of practical forces. Political 533. Political sovereignty is practical supremacy; but •over- where in a modern state like ovr own is this supremacy to Great ^® found ? If we are disposed towards the legal view of Britain, things, we may say that in Great Britain the House of Com- mons is the political sovereign ; or, if we are somewhat less legally minded, we may say that the real supremacy does not rest with the House of Commons, but with the electors * Cf. supra, sec. 295 n. SOVEREIGNTY 277 of the United Kingdom ; or again, shaking off the fetters of legalism altogether, we may say that the whole community is sovereign, meaning by the community either a simi of in- dividuals or an organic unity. Thus, without going beyond the British Constitution, we find at least four distinct types of the conception of sovereignty for the purposes of political science. These types may be expressed briefly as follows : — (1) The dominating power in the government. - (2) The electoral body. - (3) The populat majority. (4) The State as a moral organism. If we were to extend our analysis to other States, some of the above expressions must be made more general; some new types must be added. For present purposes, the list may be accepted as it stands. Each of the types to which reference is made has some claim to answer to the descrip- tion of the political sovereign which has been suggested by Professor Dicey. " That body is politically sovereign the \ will of which is ultimately obeyed by the citizens of the State."! 534. The choice between the four types mentioned must sover- depend upon conditions of time and circumstance. Thee>g"ty theory of sovereignty must keep pace with the progress of gjesaive society. The progress of society may assume at least three oonoep- distinct phases — territorial expansion, the extension of politi- cal power to new classes of the community, and the increase in the strength of the various bonds, material, intellectual and moral, which unite the citizens to one another and to the State. The end of the first phase is the large political aggregate; the end of the second, the democratic community; the end of the third, the realization of a national life. As progress in one or other of these phases absorbs the energies ' " Law of the Constitution," 5th ed., p. 69. 278 SOVEREIGNTY of the State, the seat of sovereignty is changed. Con- spicuously, progress in the form of territorial expansion is apt to involve some sacrifice of the results of progress in the form of advance towards organic unity ; as the social group merges in the larger group, the moral honds which have held men together as members of the smaller group may lose much of their force without being immediately suc- ceeded by moral bonds of equal strength between citizens as members of the larger group. In other words, the process of drilling men into larger communities is one in which force is apt to play the prominent part. When it does so, political sovereignty shifts from communities to a superior power : it ceases to be democratic and becomes monarchic or aristocratic. lUustra- 535. English medieva,l history affords a partial but in- *'°"" , structive illustration. The town of medieval England, in mfidieTal i. • i i. history, the course of its long struggle against the forces of feudalism, realized a high degree of organic unity. Throughout a long period, the practical forces which compelled the subject's obedience embraced both the King, by whose aid the borough community succeeded in attaining a relative inde- pendence, and the borough community itself. When, on the other hand, the strongly centralized State succeeded in establishing itself, the need for self-assertion on the part of the borough community grew less, and the spirit and authority of the town life declined. The poiitical centre of gravity shifted in the direction of the Monarch; and a point was reached at which it might have been said with a fair approach to accuracy that the King alone was political sovereign. And in 536. If we turn from medieval to modern history, we modern g^^j gg^^j^ q£ ^.jjg tjjree phases of political progress in full operation. Britain has become the United Kingdom : the franchise has been successively extended to new classes of SOVEREIGNTY 279 the community ; and, despite the loosening of many of the older social bonds, an advance has been made towards the realization of a highly organic national life. Each of these developments must be taken into consideration if we are to determine where political sovereignty resides. That we cannot stop short of the electorate will be apparent. Whether, having gone so far, we ought not to take a further step and regard the State itself as politically sovereign is a more debatable question which may be answered differently by ' different inquirers according to their estimate of the degree of progress which has been made in the different forms already suggested. Also, it may be added, according to the particular object in view. Professor Dicey, whose definition of political sovereignty has been already mentioned, rests content with the electorate. But his avowed object is simply to distinguish political from legal sovereignty. For the purposes of political science, I believe we need to carry our analysis further. 537. A suggestive contribution towards the solution of the The problem under discussion has been made by T. H. Green, in *"aly»is his work on " The Principles of Political Obligation." The Green, essential characteristic of society, according to Green, is a_ powQ Lwhich guarantees men's rights. This power, he urges, does not necessarily reside in the supreme coercive power known to law — -a statement illustrated by the case of States under a foreign dominion which retain a national life of their own ; and again, by Oriental despotisms where the nominal sovereign is a mere tax-gatherer who leaves the maintenance of right within the particular communities to local law and custom. At this stage, however, if we are to make use of Green's analysis for the purposes of developing a doctrine of political sovereignty, we must be guided by the spirit rather than the letter of his language. In a State like Great Britain, he admits the sovereignty of the government because 280 SOVEREIGNTY the government may claim to express the general will. But the circumstance that a government may claim to represent the general will does not make that government the political sovereign. As Green expressly states, the hahitual obedi- ence of the subject in Great Britain is really determined, not by the ruling power, but by the common will and reason of men — a will of which the ruling power is the agent even though some of its laws may be in conflict with that will* Both political subjection and morality, he contends, have a common source in the rational recognition by human beings of a common well-being which is their well-being, and which they conceive as their well-being, whether at any moment any one of them is inclined to it or not, and in the embodi- ment of that recognition in rules which restrain individual inclination and secure a corresponding freedom of action for the attainment of general well-being. Though the idea of the State as serving a common interest is only partially - realized among men, nevertheless, every citizen who is not a member of the dangerous classes, has a clear understanding of certain interests and rights which are common to himself with his neighbours. Habitually and instinctively he regards the claim which he makes for himself as conditional upon his recognizing a like claim in others. With such a regard, though he has no regard for the State under that name, he has still the needful elementary conception of a common good maintained by law. " We only count Eussia a state by a sort of courtesy on the supposition that the power of the Czar, though subject to no constitutional control, is so far exercised in accordance with a recognized tradition of what the public good requires as to be on the whole a sustainer of rights."^ The general conclusion may be inferred that, according to Green, a State worthy of the name is a moral 1 " Principles of Political ObHgation," §§ 90-4, 132-4. * Ibid., §§ 100-32. SOVEREIGNTY 281 or ffanis m ; practical supremacy within it can only be at- tributed to the general will. 538. Before passing from the subject of political sover- Analysis eignty, I may refer to the analysis of Austin. That analysis, ° "*" as we have seen, confuses political with legal sovereignty. But of whichever of these he is thinking, he invariably looks upon the sovereign as a superior person or body who imposes his will on inferiors. He is accordingly classed By most writers among those who base sovereignty on force. This traditional view of the Austinian analysis has been attacked by Professor Dewey, who alleges that the distinction between the Austinian theory and that implicitly adopted by T. H. Green is a distinction, not between force and general will, but between will as inhering in a part of society and will as existing in society as a whole} I regret not to be able to agree with this acute critic. Austin's references to the utilitarian ends of government, and to the popular apprecia- tion of those ends, are merely incidental. They do not enter into, and determine the nature of, his general theory of sovereignty. That theory, for all practical purposes, accepts the objec tive Jact of a sovereign will imposing itself upon inferiors as an ultimate fact behind which it is unnecessary to go. This detachment on Austin's part appears to me to jilstify the traditional presentation of his theory as based on force.' III. Sovereignty in Jurisprudence 539. Sovereignty for the purposes of Jurisprudence, The clii> sovereignty without qualifiying epithet, may be defined as^"'*"** supremaoyrecogiiizedby.Jaw. But the location of this Sover- supremacy, like the location of political sovereignty, has "iS"** and varied from time to time. In the early days of the develop- govem- ment. ' " Austin's Theory of Sovereignty" : " Political Science Quarterly," • IX, 1. 37. 282 SOVEREIGNTY ment of the modern doctrine, no practical need existed for distinguishing between the governments and the legally supreme or unlimited authority. When, however, the Puritan Eeformers of the Commonwealth were devising new constitutions, they decided to impose very important limitations upon their governmental assemblies. The Agree- ment of the People, after prescribing the Parliamentary Con- stitution, proceeds: "The power of this, and all future representatives of this Nation, is inferior only to theirs who chuse them, and doth extend ... to whatsoever is not expressly or implyedly reserved by the represented them- selves. Which are as foUoweth, 1. That matters of Eeligion, and the wayes of God's wor- ship, are not at all intrusted by us to any humane power," etc., etc. We have here in germ that distinction between I ordinary government and extraordinary government which has since become the basis of most modern constitutions. The distinction involves a practical dif&culty with regard to the location of sovereignty. WhePL governmen t and l egal absolutism are sepa ra±(^.rl, what, bBpnTn es of Bover eignty ? Some writers have sought to surmount the difficulty by locating sovereignty in both ordinary governments and the extra- ordinary governments or constituent assemblies, regarded as forming parts of an ideal whole. The solution is not always satisfactory, since the constituent assemblies may be absolutely superior to the ordinary governments, and en- titled to amend them at will. Where this is the case, it must be admitted that sovereignty and government are definitely separated unless we are to throw over the concep' tion of sovereignty as legal supremacy. ; Sover- 540. But at this stage a further difficulty arises. To what •ignty power ought formal supremacy to be attributed in the case of under The ^ ^ ° , . , . . , . . Agreement a State With a written and rigid constitution contaming no SOVEREIGNTY 2S3 provision for its amendment ? The scheme of organization of the prescribed by the Agreement of the People is a concrete ^'"^^'• example. In a note to the text of Austin, I remarked that the question might be resolved by assuming that a power to amend the constitution had been vested in the highest law- making body known to law. The answer surmounts the difficulty by help of a leg al fictio n. The more logical solution M. would be to attribute the ^sovereignty to the State itsel f." Such a sovereignty, though it cannot be immediately actualized in a way recognized by law, may still serve two important purposes. It may provide legal theory with a supreme source from which all law and all governmental institutions shall derive their authority; and it may be employed in some revolutionary crisis to give a legal form to the will of a revolutionary legislative assembly. 541. The possibility of the location of the sovereignty in the State- State itself is implicitly recognized in all modern theories ^?^*^" which state legal limitations upon the power which ranks Ruler- highest in the hierarchy of State institutions. The sovereign ^f'"" is the source of all law, and so cannot be limited by law ; ° where a legal limitation is held to exist upon a power claim- ing to be sovereign, we are compelled to infer that legal theory looks beyond the pretended sovereign to the State itself as true sovereign and ultimate source of law. Such an inference is a fat cry from doctrines of Euler-sovereignty, but may be founded on very practical considerations. Whilst there are obvious objections to a State being so organized as to make some things only possible by revolutionary process, a State may desire that it should be so organized. The desire, like other facts of the national life, may find expression in legal theory. If a;power which is highest in the hierarchy of State institutions passes a law, although that law is expressly a rule and implicitly a declaration that its passing is within the competence of the power which passes it, the tribunals 284 SOVEREIGNTY are not bound to apply the law if they feel impelled to regard it as exceeding limitations imposed upon the rulers by the will of the State. Austin would probably sajj that sovereignty in such a case exists in a combination of the Legislature and the Judicature. The contention might be urged with apparent justice where the Courts are capable of being regarded aa depositaries of a sort of tribuniciary veto. Where, however, the Courts simply rely upon limitations expressly stated in a written constitution, the view ceases to be maintainable. Suggested 542. The fact that under conceivable conditions sover- goalof leignty in g, state may not admit of being actualized in tha theory. ' law-making institutions, ordinary or even extraordinary, has a profound significance for the student of Jurisprudence. I have dwelt upon it at some length for a reason which I shall now proceed to state. When once the conclusion has been reached that under conceivable conditions sovereignty maj reside in the State itself, the more startling conclusion is suggested that sooner or later the location of sovereignty in the State must be accepted. as an axiom by legal theory in all highly developed communities. Even where legal absolutism can be attributed to some definite legislative institution, sooner or later the question is certain to arise whether, after all, formal supremacy can be attributed to that institution save as an organ of the State. In a multitude of ways the State, as owner of its territory, as invested with property and the dubious blessing of a National Debt, demands legal recog- nition. But if once the law recognizes the State as an entity capable of rights and duties, it is almost compelled to attribute , sovereignty to that entity, and to regard the supreme law- -making institution as merely an actualization of a formal j supremacy which in the last analysis can only be found in the ' State itself. Confirm- 543. The conclusion just suggested has beeti reached by ation from reference to formal considerations. But a similar conclusion SOVEREIGNTY 285 is also suggested by considerations which go to the roots of facta of things. As in the sphere of politics, in proportion as nations ^"^"^ have come to self-consciousness, political sovereignty or practical supremacy is seen to reside in the community regarded as an organic totality, so also in the sphere of Jurisprudence, those who seek to think things together, to bring legal formulae into some relation with the actual tendencies of social life, are impelled to look beyond the sovereignty of Court etiquette, and beyond the sovereignty of parliamentary institutions and constitution-revising as- semblies, to the. iotality, of the community which King, Parliament or Assembly but represent. But while in politics men have sought to give expression to thoughts and ideas that were clamouring for recognition in some theory of Society as a. m oral ^rpram'sTTi the tendency in Jurisprudence has been rather to make use of a conception which existed in germ in Eoman law and was suggested by the attempts of lawyers to find some expression for the phenomena of group life as exhibited in the universitas personantm — the concep- tion of a juristic person. The recognition and development of this conception represent the most important contribution to Jurisprudence which has been made in recent times. 544. The general conclusions of the present Excursus may Summary, be briefly summarized. Sovereignty is a conception whose meaning and incidents must vary with the particular depart- ment of thought with which the student is more immediately concerned. In Political Science, it may refer to the practical supremacy of (1) A^ggvernnoent ; i (2) An electoral body ; (3) A popular majority ; (4) The State as a moral organism. In Jurisprudence, the conception may refer to the formal supremacy of 286 SOVEREIGNTY (1) A government ; (2) The highest law-making body ordinary or extra- ordinary ; (3) The State as a juristic person. 545. Such a list can make no pretence to completeness, but will serve for the purposes of a practical discussion. The choice between the various types of theory thus grouped must vary according to conditions of time and circumstance So far as the Jurisprudence of our time is concerned, the sovereign may be defined as the power whose authority is re- garded by law as unlimited, and as the source both of all law and of the authority of all law-making or governmental institutions. Although the location of the sovereign varies in the different legal theories of different nationalities, it seems probable that the Jurisprudence of a near future will recognize that the State itself is the true sovereign, and that such a body as the Parliament of Great Britain should be described, not as the sovereign, but as the sovereign-organ. " Let us see, then," wrote Grotius, " in what subject sovereign power resides. The subject in which a power resides is either common or special ; as the common subject in which the sight resides is the body, but the special subject is the eye. And in like manner the common subject in which the sovereignty resides is the State. . . . The special subject is one or more persons according to the laws and customs of each nation."^ The conception of legal sovereignty as in- hering in a portion of the community needs then to be revised by reference to the fact that such portion is but an organ of the community as a whole. When we have escaped from the tyranny of mere forms, and have overcome the superstition that we must not regard things in their total- ity, when we have learnt that, on the contrary, it is only ^ Grotius, De Jure Belli ac Pads, Wiewell's translation, vol. I, p. 113. SOVEREIGNTY 287 when we so regard them we can hope to comprehend them, we shall find some place in legal theory for ideas which have already! profoundly affected less conservative branches of learning. We shall not fear to think of the State as a unity, a personality, a sovereign — a sovereign in whose presence the visible ruler can aspire to no higher title than that of sovereign-organ. The law may accept the declared will of that visible ruler as conclusive of the will of the Bovereign, but the fact need not prevent us from recog- nizing, even as lawyers, that the visible ruler is but an organ of the organized community. It has been said of a great scientist that he closed the door of his laboratory before he entered the door of his church. The attitude is suggestive of the provisional order of things, since a theo- logical theory which will not somehow square with the laboratory can afford no resting-place. Similarly a lawyer who leaves what he has learnt from history and science behind him when he opens his Law Reports is merely post- poning a difficulty. That difficulty will have to be met somehow. When it has been met, legal theory will not be thp less, but the more, worthy of his homage. EXCURSUS C THi ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKER Purpose of 552. In the present Excursus I propose to discuss the Excursus, questions whether, and if so, within what limits and by what authority, judges may add to the existing law by the indirect process of judicial decision. I. View 553. To the question whether judges may add to the . ? , existing law by their decisions, it might seem a sufficient not make answer to say that a great part of our law has been new law. developed in this way. Yet an ancient fiction to the contrary has displayed a quite extraordinary virility, and must be run to earth if we are ever to have a sound theory of the judicial office. At times the fiction is openly avowed as essential truth. It was expressed forcibly and with approval in a comparatively recent address delivered before the American Bar Association by a distinguished American lawyer.^ The precise words merit quotation. "All the knowledge which we really have of the law comes from the judge. But how does he get at the law? Does he make it? . . . Let us examine the process. The statute book is first consulted, and if that speaks to the point and clearly, all doubt vanishes. But in the great majority of cases the statute book is silent, and what is the resort? Inquiry is made by the judge concerning what his predecessors have done, and if he finds that a similar state of facts has been considered by them and the law pronounced in reference ^ J. C. Carter, " The Ideal and the Actual in Law," American Law Beview, 24, pp. 758-9. THE ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKER 289 to it, he declares the same rule law. But in many, indeed ' most, of the controversies brought before him, no record is found of a precisely similar case, and the law is to be declared for the first time. Here is the interesting and crucial test of the question how the law springs into existence. That the judge cannot make the law is accepted from the start. That there is already existing a rule by which the case must be determined is not doubted. Un- questionably the functions of making and declaring the law are here brought into close proximity ; but, nevertheless, the distinction is not for a moment lost sight of. It is agreed that the true rule must be somehow found. Judge and advocates — altogether — engage in the search. Cases more or less nearly approaching the one in controversy are adduced. Analogies are referred to. Customs and habits of men are appealed to. Principles already settled as fundamental are invoked and run out to their consequences; and finally a rule is deduced which is declared to be the one which the existing law requires to be applied to the case." 554. To discuss all of the fallacies in which this statement Criticism: abounds would be superfluous. Two, however, are peculiarly ^y>p*^°-- deserving of attention. In the first place, the statement formal and involves a confusion which has been exposed time after ™**°"*^ , sources of time, between the material and the formal sources of laws, legal mle. between the sources from which laws have taken their origin as rules and the sources from which laws have takea their title to rank as rules which the State will enforce Let us suppose for a moment that a judge always finds a rule, in preference to making! one. Wherever he has found it, his decision becomes a precedent for future cases. The rule may not be new or judge-made ; often the law is both. If the British Fleet discovers and annexes an island, the British possession is new-made, though the island be as ancient as the Universe. 290 THE ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKER (2) Implies 555. Apart from the confusion of the formal and material an ID nite gQuj.(.gg qJ jg^^^ ^jjg argument of Mr. Carter implies that the rules of law are of infinite range. If the judge does not make the law, but only declares it, it must have existed before. The practical result follows that the law of our time, though in great part unrevealed, provides for every case that can possibly arise. The view may be logically defensible where judges claim to be the oracles of a divine omniscience. To us who have the disadvantage of living in a more sceptical age^ it must seem the beginning of wisdom to recognize, frankly and unreservedly, that law never has been, and never will be, adequate to existing need. This must be so under the completest code that man could devise. The wisest legislator cannot foretell the future, or entirely comprehend the present. " The narrow compass of human wisdom," declared Bacon, "cannot take in all the cases which time may discover. ... It is preposterous to ' wrest statutes to omitted cases." ^ Under a system of Com- mon Law, as distinct from Statutory Law, the pretence to completeness is the more hollow. Much of the argument in ' defence L.R. 2 Exch. Div. 63. THE ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKER 29B qualifications, that International Law is a part of the law of England. "The proposition that International Law is part of the law of England," aflBrms a recent judgment of the Court of King's Bench, " requires a word of explanation and comment. It is quite true that whatever has received the common consent of civilized nations must have received the assent of our country ; and that to which we have assented along with other nations in general, may properly be called International Law, and as such will be acknowledged and applied by our municipal tribunals when legitimate occasion arises for those tribunals to decide questions to which doo- trines of International Law may be relevant. But any doctrine so invoked must be one really accepted as binding between nations, and the International Law sought to be appUed must, like anything else, be proved by satisfactory evidence, which must show either that the particular pro- position put forward has been recognized and acted upon by our own country, or that it is of such a nature, and has been so widely and generally accepted, that it can hardly be supposed that any civilized State would repudiate it."^ 560. The judgment in the two leading cases just cited appears to have created in some minds an impression of irreconcilable conflict.^ Such conflict, however, ceases to exist if we once recognize that a via media exists between declaring International Law as such to be positive law, and declaring that the Courts will never enforce it. If we once recognize the truth that judges are often compelled to go beyond the existing law, it is possible for us to regard International Law as a code of rules which are not absolutely law and yet may be made from time to time the basis of judicial decision. In my opinion, neither of the cases ' West Band Central Gold Mining Co. v. The King, 1° xciii. at p. 213, [1905] 2 K.B. 391. ' Cf. "Columbia Law Review," "VI, i. 48. 296 THE ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKER above cited is inconsistent with the view that rules of International Law, though not as such binding on our municipal tribunals, must nevertheless exercise in particular cases a very material influence upon the decisions of those tribunals; that, like the principles of public policy, they belong to the list of persuasive sources of the law, and as such must exercise an increasing influence upon the develop- ment of our judiciary law in general, and even upon the interpretation of the Acts of our Supreme Legislature.^ What 561. It is a relief to turn from discussing the origin i" ^*° „ and disadvantages of an ancient fiction to consider more in have really ° done. detail how, as a matter of fact, judges act in dealing with cases not governed by pre-existing rule. In the first place, they do not necessarily refuse to decide the case by refer- ence to the simple principle of holding for the defendant. In the second place, they reveal in their judgments, not merely the influence of ancient and established ideas and beliefs, but also the influence of a Time Spirit, thereby giving expression to rules which are new, both in the sense that they have not found expression in an earlier case, and in the sense that they could not have done ho. So far, however, there is no claim to make new law. The function of the judges being to decide disputes in accordance with law so far as that may be possible, but in any case somehow — ^in short, to administer justice — the mere fact that they apply a rule does not of necessity make that rule a part of the law. Comparatively early in English legal history, however, judges elected to be bound by precedents, not with the idea of magnifying the judicial office, but rather with the idea of limiting the judge. The discretion of the single judge ^ Of, however, Walker, "The Science of International Law," pp. 44-56 ; Holland, " International Law and Acts of Parliament," Law Qiuirterly Beview, IX, 136-52 ; Westlake, " Is International Law a part of the Law of England?" Lmv Quarterly Beview, XXII, 85 (January, 1906). THE ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKER 297 was qualified by the necessity of deciding in harmony with the decisions of predecessors. As a result of the adoption of this principle, legal decisions give rise to new law. So general rules, legal conceptions, and legal principles are resRjhed through a long series of decisions slowly working towards conclusions which at first were felt dimly or not at all. ThQirolder law is vivified by the infusion of elements drawn from the social life. Usage and opinion, social as- piration and economic needs, react upon the older law, adapting its texts, modifying their operation, developing their content, restraining, amplifying, and controlling in a thousand subtle and invisible ways. Even the judicial decision which seems merely to illustrate pre-existing law often adds to it. In purporting to apply a rule, the rule itself is modified. For the rule is held to be found, not in the language of the judges, but in the facts and the decision. Each time a new case is tried these facts are different. Each difierence of fact creates new possibilities of interpre- tation. As a result, the most conservative and timid of judges, however strenuously seeking to shelter himself be- hind the authority of earlier decisions, is driven by a power beyond his control to take his place in the ranks of the makers of law ! 562. The judge, then, is a law-maker. What are the IL Limi- iimits to his action in this capacity ? In the first place, ***'"" judges do not make law which is directly contrary to judicial Statute. The judicial interpretation of Statute in the past *"*''"'• may seem to throw a doubt on this statement. As Lord Hardwicke said of the historic act of legislation which became the basis of modern conveyancing, " A statute made (l) Judg« upon great consideration, introduced in a solemn and '*''°°* pompous manner, by a strict interpretation has had no other statuta. effect than to add at most three words to a conveyance." Curiously enough, this was an understatement of the defeat 298 THE ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKER of the legislative purpose. The Act not only failed to achieve its purpose, but even extended the evil which it was passed to prevent. The phenomenon, moreover, is not entirely a matter of antiquity. High authority has declared with regard to some of the rules of modern interpretation that they imply " that Parliament generally changes the law for the worse, and that the business of judges is to keep the mischief of its interferences within the narrowest possible bounds."^ Such statements might lead us to suppose that the judicial deference to Statute is on a level with their pretence to make no new law — a fiction serving useful purposes, but to be carefully distinguished from legal theory. The time for holding such a view, if it ever existed, is long since past. Where the will of the legislator is clearly expressed, the judge of to-day will enforce it, and will leave the legislator to deal with any unpleasant consequences that may follow. If the legislative purpose is ever defeated by judicial interpretation, it is not because of any legislative ambition on the part of judges, but because the legislative purpose has been illrexpressed. It is the result of an excessive deference to the letter, not of a will to control the spirit. The celebrated case which finally established the principle that the House of Lords is bound by its own precedent is no exception to the position just laid down. Although the court of final appeal will not reconsider its interpretation of a previous statute, however erroneous that interpretation may seem to be, the supreme legislature might declare the interpretation to have been erroneous; and the declaration would be accepted by all Courts as final. (2) Prece- 563. In the second place, judges cannot overrule a law dent and which their own practice has sanctioned. An isolated iractioe precedent, with the exception of a decision of the House of 1 Sir Frederick Pollock : " Essays in Jurisprudence and Ethics," p. 85. THE ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKEK 299 Lords, may be overruled as contrary to law or reason. A rule established by judicial practice cannot be so overruled. Positive proof that a particular precedent had been decided wrongly would avail nothing in the face of the fact that the precedent had become the basis of later judicial practice. Language has been employed at times which suggests that the distinction between precedent and practice has ceased to have any real value. " At the present day," writes Professor Salmond, "judicial usage is no longer reckoned as one of the sources of our law, for its operation as such has been merged in precedent."^ But apart from the liability of an isolated precedent to be overruled as already stated, legal theory requires us to distingviish between precedent and practice for at least two reasons, (a) The single precedent, as an authority, is more or less of an abstraction. As an authority it binds when the facts of future cases are identi- cal. In reality the facts never are identical. They may come within the operation of the underlying principle of the given case, but that underlying principle is normally based on, and implies, a number of previous decisions. We are not likely to apprehend it correctly unless we know the pre-existing state of the law. (6) If we inquire why precedents make law, as undoubtedly they do, we must look to that practice which has established and maintains that validity. If the question be asked, why is precedent binding in England, I think it a true and useful answer to say that it is binding, because the practice of the Courts has so decided. Although the distinction between judicial practice and precedent is but inadequately realized in our Courts, although, as our French critics teU us, we suffer from " la superstition du cos," ^ nevertheless, the distinction exists, and in proportion as the Law Reports increase in ' "Jurisprudence,'' p. 139. • Cf. Lambert, " Etudes de droit commun Mgislatif," I, 202. 300 THE ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKER volume, it is likely to receive a more complete recogaition and a more fruitful application. In proportion as this recognition and application take place, our legal develop- ment will advance in scientific process. The search for "the case on all fours" will give way to the search for a principle expressed or embodied in a series of cases. The stage seems to have been reached already in some American Courts, thanks, perhaps, to the thoroughly scientific treat- ment of case law which has distinguished American Law Schools, but thanks even more to the increasing volume of reports issuing from the many co-ordinate systems of judi- cature. (3) statute 564. The third limitation upon the power of the judges to may over- ^jiigji J ^gji jq draw attention is implied in preceding limi- rule pre- x x o cedent. tations, but deserves separate statement. No product of judicial precedent or practice is good as against a subsequent statute overruling it. It is, indeed, a part of the duty of the Legislature to watch the development of the law which takes place at the hands of the judges, and if need arise, to restrain or accelerate its movement. The duty is inade- quately realized and perfunctorily performed, but has re- ceived from time to time dramatic expression. III. Source 565. The consideration of the foregoing limitations upon ° tho^it* *^® capacity of the judge as law-maker should enable us to answer the question to which I shall now proceed. Whence does judicial practice derive its authority to turn precedent into law? Two answers to this question at once suggest themselves. We may say that the judicature acts as repre- sentative of the community, or that it acts as the delegate or agent of the organized Sovereign Power. The former answer is made by Mr. Bryce. " If we are to have a theory of the position of the magistrate or judge ... we must call him the recognized and permanent organ through which the mind of the people expresses itself in shaping that part of THE ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKER 301 the law which the State Power does not formally enact." ^ The statement expresses an important and familiar fact. The judges, as part of the governmental machinery of the country, are, to a large extent, creatures of their time and place, animated by the time-spirit, subject to the prejudices and passions, endowed with the ideas, the hopes, and fears of their day and generation. In devising rules through the means of precedent, they give effect to principles which are a part of the social atmosphere around them. In a deep sense they are servants of the community. 566. If, however, we are to formulate a theory of the The legal judicial office which will satisfy English Law, we must not ™*°''y- stop short at this point. To do so implies a confusion similar to that between legal and political sovereignty. Judicial authority has a formal as well as a material source, and the distinction is one of great importance so far as English Law is concerned. In a Federal State in which no machinery was provided for amending the constitution, a different conclusion might be possible. The authority of the Courts as interpreters of the constitution would be absolute. I conceive, however, that the matter is quite otherwise in a Federal constitution where an organization of the sovereign power is provided behind the governments. Still more is this the case under a unitary system such as that which exists in Great Britain. 567. Little doubt seems possible on this subject if we Theory regard in their totality the relevant facts of the existing J"^*^*^ British Constitution. As we have already seen, the judges can and do make law, but only in strict subordination to Parliament, which may set at naught their judgments and repeal the law which they have established. This subordina- tion is not a legal fiction, but a reality sufficiently attested by " Essays in History and Jurisprudence," p. 272. 302 THE ENGLISH JUDGE AS LAW-MAKER experience. When any decision of the judges or principle estabhshed by them is seriously distasteful to Parliament, action will be taken to reverse the decision or to annul the principle. Moreover, the judges themselves may be dismissed by Parliament, and their tenure and authority may be regu- lated by Parliament. An Act which should expressly recog- nize and sanction the limited power of law-making at present assumed by the judges could scarcely be regarded as anything more than sanctioning expressly what is already sanctioned implicitly. Finally, the rule which the judges lay down is enforced, not by might of their own, nor by the might of the unorganized community, but by the might of the sovereign power. If these circumstances be regarded in their totaHty, it seems impossible to impugn the statement of the judicial office expressed by Willis, J., " We sit here as the servants of the Queen and Legislature." ^ 568. In a previous Excursus, I have stated that legal theory in England might come to recognize the claims of the State as a personality in which in the last analysis sovereignty must! be held to reside. Even were this step taken, the British Parliament would still be the authoritative organiza- tion of that sovereignty ; the Courts would still be subordinate to that organization and derive their authority immediately from it, if mediately from the community at large. ' Lee V. Bude and Torrington RaiVwa/y Co., 1871, L.R. 6 C.P. at p. 582. Quoted Pollock, " First Book of Jurisprudence," p. 255. EXCURSUS D CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 569. The nature of customary law has been for ages one of the most controversial subjects of Jurisprudence. As in the case of sovereignty, other explanations of the fact of controversy than the intrinsic difficulty of the subject may be easily suggested. Three deserve a brief mention: the eternal mobility of fact, the despotism of ulterior purpose, and the confusion of legal theory with legal fiction. 570. The ever-changing nature of the material with which The the student in the social sciences has to deal makes all his ^'^["f.!. mobility generalization provisional Each decade adds its contribution of fact. to the raw material ; and each generation, however sensible it may be of its indebtedness to the past, lies under the eternal necessity to give its own account of things or rest a defaulter. The garment which was devised for the ancestor, however cunningly shaped, will never quite fit the heir, and may at times be indeed ludicrous. The part of custom in the social life is no exception to the rule. A theory about it which has become established, ought probably to be obsolete. The most superficial examination of its history will convince us that its importance and authority have varied indefinitely from age to age. There have been periods when it is para- mount; periods when it seems a mere fiction to conceal a judicial activity ; periods when it is reverenced and periods when it is denied. Needless to add, similar divergences exist with regard to different countries. He would be a rash student who should contend that the refusal of French 303 304 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND jurists to admit the law-creative power of ' custom in modern France, is a valid proof for jurists who have to deal with a non-codified system of law. Eesearches in Comparative Law and Comparative Legal History have accordingly a varying value according to the particular point of view. The value is only persuasive for English lawyers who are anxious for a theory which will fit precisely the facts of modern English Law. In the present inquiry, only the more modest and more practical object is pursued. The task of constructing a universal theory of customary law which shall relate to the past as well as to the present, to uncivilized and civilized, to Hindu, Celt, Teuton and Eoman, I leave to the philospher of legal history who shall have the courage to venture upon the undertaking. The 571. Accounts of customary law have been written, leas despotism Qfjgji ^q represent actualities, than to promote an ulterior purpose, purpose — to justify a political or constitutional policy, to secure the triumph of Eoman Law at the expense of local laws, to justify or deny the validity of judicial legislation, or to support some a priori theory of the nature of law in general. As a result, that which may have purported to be scientific has been polemic. It is not surprising that a theory which in its time has played so many parts should present strange metamorphoses not to be explained by any variations in the raw material. Canonists and post glossators wrangled about the nature of the mental element in the conception of custom, opinio necessitatis, more concerned to secure the sanction of classic texts than to represent the real facts of medieval life, and apt to find a solution of their difficulties in various interpretations of a tacit consent of the populace regarded atomistically in accordance with classic models.^ So too, if we turn from the mental to the material element ' Of. the historical sketch by M. Lambert, " Etudes de droit commun le'gislatif," pp. 111-73. CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 305 in custom, we find equally important divergences of opinion which are often inspired by merely a priori conceptions. The school of Savigny and Puchta, under the speU of an excessive subjectivism, was almost prepared to dispense with its existence. 572. Juristic controversies, moreover, have been darkened The by a confusion between legal theory and fiction. What is °°°''"\°" dignified as legal theory is often no better than a transparent theory fiction, or at best a blending of both, or a transition from '"*^ '*8»l fiction, one to the other. When first expressed, the theory was perhaps a true representation of the facts with which lawyers as such were concerned. Time has changed those facts, but the theory remains. The distinction under con- sideration must not be confused with that between Constitu- tional Law and Convention. With the last-mentioned subject the lawyer is not directly concerned. The distinction is that between the rational and the merely nominal version of legal facts. Two familiar instances may be quoted in illustration. It is sometimes said to be legal theory that English statutes are made by the King with the assent of the Lords and Commons. In reality, they are made by Par- liament with the assent of the King. The older theory is interesting as an explanation of the origin of certain con- stitutional forms, but it has long since ceased to answer to actualities. Again, it is often said that English judges only apply pre-existing law. In point of fact, they often intro- duce new rules which have no foundation in either pre- existing law or custom. Yet the older theory on the subject survives, and even when its fictitious character is admitted, it is apt to reassert itself in some form or other. Lest such dangers should prove imaginary, I will quote what appears to me to be an example in a recently published work of no less distinguished a scholar than Mr. Bryce. The learned author, while admitting the reality of judicial law-making, ! 306 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND proceeds to refute the view that such law-making may be regarded as effected in futherance of a sovereign delegation. "The theory of the English Law and Constitution has re- mained, in these points, substantially unchanged. That theory is that the judges of the Common Law Courts are nothing zaore and nothing less than the officers who expound and apply the Common Law, a body of usages held to be known to the people, and by which the people live."^ We cannot suppose that Mr. Bryce is ignorant of the fact that judges make law, since he expressly admits it, He denies, how- ever, that they make law as delegates of the sovereign power, and his reason for this is a legal theory which, by his own initial statement, is a fiction. It is difficult to see how one can uphold the view that judges make law, and then call in evidence the theory that they make no law but only declare custom, as a proof of the authority by which they act. Similar examples from the works of less distinguished authors might be added indefinitely. A sound legal theory should represent those realities of which so-called legal theory is frequently very deceptive evidence. Judicial v. 573, The moral of the foregoing considerations may be popular briefly stated. A sound theory of customary law must be custom. •' J J based on the. existing facts, and not upon any a priori con- ception of the nature of law in general, or upon any of the many fictions which mask as legal theories. As regards English Law, certain of these basic facts are quite clear. Before proceeding to their statement, however, we must carefully distinguish between two kinds of custom which are often confused. There is the custom of the people or a class ; there is the custom of the Courts. The distinction is fre- quently overlooked, and statements are made in regard to custom as embracing both kinds which really hold only with ' Essays in History and Jurisprudence," II, p. 270. CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 307 regard to one. Both may be ultimately embraced in a single theory. At the outset it is imperative to distinguish between them. I propose accordingly to dwell at some length on custom in the sense of popular usage. 574. The first and most obvious of the facts with regard (i) Popu- to popular custom relates to its character as an important ^ gonrce of source of legal rules in time past. A very large part of the law in tha English Common Law, from whatever power it may have ^*° ' gained its authority as law, has been developed as rule by the processes of popular observance, 575. A second fact is that custom remains, and must con- (2) still a tinue to remain, a source of legal rules. So long as a people H^'^" " is progressive, the need for new regulation will be felt by each generation. Inevitably the official agencies for meeting that need will be imperfect. So long as they are imperfect, the generations will be compelled to work out their own salvation, whether under the influence of an irresistible juridic sentiment, or in the consciousness of a purposeful adaptation to new conditions. Statutes and judicial decisions in particular cases may anticipate the process, or may give to it a formal sanction. The process goes on eternally in obedience to a law which is higher than judge or legislator, and is founded in the very nature of man. " Usage adopted by the Courts," said Cockburn, C.J., delivering a judgment of the Court, " having been thus the origin of the whole of the so-called Law Merchant as to negotiable securities, what is there to prevent our acting upon the principle acted upon by our predecessors, and followed in the precedents they have left to us ? Why is it to be said that a new usage which has sprang up under altered circumstances is to be less admissible than the usages of past times ? Why is the door to be now shut to the admission and adoption of usage in a matter altogether of cognate character, as though the law had been 308 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND finally stereotyped and settled by some positive and per- emptory enactment ? " ^ (3) may 576. That custom is often posterior to judicial decision is on iudioial ^oot^^r fact about which no difference of opinion is possible, decision. Under the pretence of declaring custom, judges frequently give rise to it. The phenomenon is ancient as well as modern. " Above all local customs," declare Pollock and Maitland, in speaking of justice under the Norman kings, "rose the custom of the King's Court. The jurisprudence of this court, if one may use so grand a phrase, was of necessity a flexible, occasional jurisprudence, dealing with an unprece- dented state of affairs, meeting new facts by new expedients, wavering as wavered the balance of power between the king and his barons, capable of receiving impressions from with- out, influenced by the growth of Canon Law, influenced perhaps by Lombard learning, modern in the midst of antique surroundings. ... It was not a jurisprudence that had been transplanted from Normandy, but it had been developed by a Court composed of Frenchmen to meet cases in which Frenchmen were concerned. . . . The future was to make the jurisprudence of the King's Court by far the most im- portant element in the law of England." ^ 577. The facts of medieval history thus suggest the evolu- tion of legal rules through judicial decisions based on equity rather than law, but tending to harden into a judicial usage, and thereby to create or to shape popular usage. In speak- ing of the age of Bracton, the learned authors just quoted remark: "Even the knights who were employed to take assizes in their shires, though they had read no law, would believe that they knew the law and custom applicable to the cases that came before them. Every man who does his duty ' Good-win v. Robarts (1875) L.R. 10 Exch. 337, 352. 2 ' History of English Law," I, 85, 86. CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 309 knows a great deal of law and custom ; the difficulty is to persuade him that he does not know everything." ^ 578. So far we have not had occasion to enter the region (4) When of controversy. At the present point, however, two very de- ™ batable questions call for consideration. When does custom become become positive law ? Whence does custom derive its author- ^'^ ' ity to rank as positive law ? I propose to discuss the first of these questions in some detail. At the outset we must dis- tinguish between several classes. There are customs which the people observe, in relation, for example, to such matters as the details of manner and costume, which are not law and in all probability never will become law. There are customs which, though they may hereafter satisfy certain tests which judges have affirmed, do not satisfy these tests at the present time. These are not now laws, though they may become so. Again, there are customs which have been definitely adopted by the judges. These are undoubtedly a part of the law of the land. "When a general usage has been judicially ascertained and established," said Lord Campbell, " it becomes a part of the Law Merchant, which courts of justice are bound to know and recognize." ^ Lastly, there are customs which, though they have not been definitely adopted by the judges, nevertheless appear to satisfy the judicial tests. The precise legal character of these is a matter about which different opinions are enter- tained by different writers. I 579. According to the more popular doctrine, customs Argu- may be laws, and not infrequently are laws, even before their ™*"^y[°of adoption by the Courts. The arguments by which thistr»di- doctrine is supported deserve careful attention. We are told *"•"*' that it corresponds with the language of the judges, and that stated and it is implied in the retrospective operation given by judges examined. > " History of English Law," I, 163. » Brandao v. Barnett (1846) 12 01. and F. at p. 805. 310 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND {a) The language of the judges. to customs of which they approve. "We are told also that customs are laws because the judges are hownd to enforce them. 580. The argument from the language of the judges is open to suspicion. What judges do, and what they profess to do, are not always the same, and the latter is only evidence of the former — often very misleading evidence. In particular, the judicial theory Of customary law seems to have been elaborated with the object of concealing facts rather than representing them. It has been, not a scientific analysis of custom, but a fiction to serve useful purposes. The judge, like the priest, has legislated; but whilst the latter has attributed his activities to a Supernatural origin, the former has been content to throw the weight of responsi- bility upon the mundane shoulders of the community at large. Sometimes enforcing custom, sometimes creating custom, judges have found the formula of immemorial usage a convenient cloak beneath which they might per- form no end of tricks to dazzle the credulous. In particular, we in this later day cannot too much admire the ingenuity with which judges in a past age have made royal justice prevail under the pretence of declaring popular usage, in reality deposing usage in the name of usage. Yet, if we would substitute rational theory for ancient and once service- able fiction, we must recognize that judges have made laws, and continue to make laws, and that in consequence the language of the judges in relation to such subjects as the true nature of custom must be regarded with considerable suspicion. Like the evidence of a discredited witness, it -may be true, but we are not entitled to assume its truth in the absence of more convincing testimony. 581. The argument which is based upon the retrospective operation of the judicial adoption of custom deserves a of the more serious attention. It is supported by no less an (») The letrospec tive nature CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 311 authority than Professor Holland. "To such customs as judicial come up to a certain standard of general reception and use- *^"P*"*" " -^ of custom. fulness the Courts give operation, not merely prospectively from the date of such recognition, hut also retrospectively ; so far implying that the custom was law before it received the stamp of judicial authentication. The contrary view, supported by Austin, is at variance with fact."^ The language suggests that the retrospective operation of the judicial adoption of a custom is a 'proof that the custom is already law. Such a view, however, would compel us to hold that rules of law which have been founded on principles of public policy and adopted in judicial decision were law before so adopted. The rules of law relating to undue in- fluence, to take a familiar illustration, have been developed by the judges and applied retrospectively. They were not laws, however, prior to such adoption. That laws should not be made to bind retrospectively is a rule of expediency, not an a priori necessity. It is a rule, moreover, which applies with greater force to the judicial applications of public policy than to the judicial adoption of popular custom, since people are more to be blamed for violating a rule with which they have been acquainted in the form of a popular usage, than for violating a rule which perhaps represents no more than the judicial perception of the expedient. In short, we have to reckon with the fact that the State is a very im- perfect institution. It cannot foresee all possible con- tingencies, or determine in advance how far general rules of law should be modified on particular occasions or in particular localities. Its chief function is the maintenance of some kind of order, and in the fulfilment of this function its organs employ devices which are at once seriously objec- tionable and imperatively necessary. 1 " Jurisprudence," 9th ed., p. 57. 312 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND JTistioe 582. It is a fact upon the importance of which too much J^^*'"*''*" emphasis cannot he laid that the justice which it is the function of the Courts to administer is wider than law. In a world where all things were ideal, the judge would have no more to do than to ascertain the facts and apply to them the rule of law. In the world in which we live, there is often no precise rule to apply to the group of facts which demand adjudication, either because the occasion has been wholly unanticipated, or else because the matter of dispute falls within the scope of some legal rule, which is so general in its character as to leave considerable latitude in its appli- cation. In either case the precise rule which the judge applies is not necessarily law before such application. It may be added that it does not necessarily become law by such application. For although judges are constantly adding to the specific rules of law, working out in concrete and definite form standards of duty implied in the judicial con- ception of reasonableness, the process is carried on with very considerable caution, and subject to the judicial con- i sciousness that in a world where possible combinations of fact are infinite, the proper elaboration of legal rules can never be carried to an extent which shall leave no discretion in the application. As Sir William Markby writes, " There are many rules made use of in English courts of justice which hover upon the borders of law, and we are hardly able to say whether they are legal rules or not. . . . There was at one time a struggle to establish a rule of law as to whether it was a breach of duty for the servants of a rail- way company to call out the name of a station before ^ train had reached the platform : for a time it seemed likely to be recognized that this was a matter of law, but it is now settled that each tribunal must determine in each case what is reasonable. ... To say that a standard is to be applied by the jury is the same thing as to say that th^ standard is CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 313 not a legal one. But the non-legal standard is also applied in courts when there is no jury, and the nature of the standard does not depend upon the person who applies it."^ 583. Finally, it is often asserted that judges are absolutely (c) Argn- btnmd to decide in accordance with custom. If the assertion ""^ " customs be true, the question is decided once and for all. The ground are laws of the assertion is the reality of the deference which judges 1^^°*"=^ have undoubtedly displayed towards some customs. But bound to this deference is quite consistent with the view that custom ^fo^o* them. is a persuasive rather than an absolutely binding source of legal rule. Among the many historical sources from which judges draw rult3 for application to particular cases, there are many differences of kind and of degree. If we are comparing two such historical sources as a statute of the realm and the Code Napoleon, the difference is one of kind. If, on the other hand, the historical sources under comparison be a modem text-book of high repute and the Digest of Justinian, the difference is one of degree. According to the English theory of precedents, the proposition necessarily involved in a decision needs to be distinguished, not merely from the obiter dicta, but even from the judicial declaration of the grounds of the decision. The theory involves the recognition of three historical sources of which one is bind- ing and two are persuasive, but of very different degrees of authority. "The practice of conveyancers amounts to a very considerable authority," declared Lord Eldon.^ The judgments of the Privy Council, sitting as a Court of Appeal from the colonies, undoubtedly exercise a strong influence upon English courts in general. When it is once clearly reahzed that a much greater judicial deference to one historical source than to another does not imply of necessity a difference of kind, when it is once seen that there are ' " Elements of Law,'' pp. 19, 20, and note. » Smith V. Earl Jersey (1825), 3 Bligh 444 314 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND sources of every degree of persuasiveness, sources which no judge dare overlook, and sources whose authority is so slight as to leave judicial discretion unfettered, we shall he better prepared to consider whether custom in modem English Law is an absolutely binding source of law or only one of the highest of the persuasive sources. Customs 584. The first of the arguments which seem to favour the as a per- yjg^ jj^g^^ custom is not law until it has been judicially source of adopted, is associated with the fact that courts never ^^- enforce custom as such, but only enforce custom as satisfying (o) Courts 'J J 6 do not certain tests which the courts themselves have imposed. If enforce ^g ^re to make of any custom a rule of law before adoption, merely as ^® must argue that the judge is as helpless to amend or grioh. reject it as he would be to act in either of these ways to- wards precedent. It becomes, then, important to examine the tests which are alleged as differentiating customary law from mere usage. Nature of 585. What, then, are the tests ? To answer the question the tests of ^g need to distinguish between three kinds of customs: (1) customs — , Different General customs, i.e. those which, though they may apply customs to particular classes of the community, are not limited to par- guished. ticular localities; (2) Particular customs, i.e. those which are so limited; (3) Customs which are deferred to, not as binding rules of conduct, but as affording an explanation or interpretation of some agreement ; e.g. to show that in the lease of a rabbit warren the word thousand meant in that particular part of the country twelve hundred. Such customs are ordinarily usages of a particular trade or district, with whose existence the contracting parties must be assumed to have been acquainted. They are not subject to ordinary rules for testing the validity of customs, and do not concern us here. With respect to the first two classes, we can scarcely do better than refer to certain learned authors who expound the more popular doctrine. CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 315 586. Sir Frederick Pollock states the general conditions statameut required for the validity of particular ctistom as follows : v ^"^' 1. The custom must be reasonable, that is, it must not be repugnant to any fundamental principle of justice or law. " A custom is void which purports to enable an officer of a corporation to give a conclusive certificate in a matter in which the corporation is interested." ^ 2. The custom must have a reasonable commencement. 3. It must be certain. 4. It must be ancient. 5. It must be continuous, and must be regarded by the persons concerned as a binding rule, not as a matter of in- dividual choice.^ 587. Professor Salmond, after observing that a custom, in Profesior order to be valid as a source of law, must conform to cer- * "" tain requirements laid down by law, proceeds to state that the chief of these are as follows : 1. The custom must be reasonable. "The authority of usage is not absolute, but conditional on a certain measure of conformity with justice and public utility." 2. The custom must be accompanied by the intellectual element, opinio necessitatis, "the conviction on the part of those who use a custom that it is obligatory, and not merely optional." 3. It must be consistent with statute law. 4. It must have existed from time immemorial. But this is applicable to particular customs only. " If he who dis- putes its validity can prove its non-existence at any time between the present day and the twelfth century, it will not receive legal recognition." 5. It must be consistent with the common law. This is applicable only to recent custom. " Modern custom possesses ' Day V. Samdge (1614) Hobart 85. * "First Book of Jurisprudence" (1896) pp. 264-6. Commen- taries. 316 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODEEN ENGLAND constitutive, but no abrogative power. . . . Immemorial custom, on the other hand, can destroy as well as create, so far as the common law is concerned." ^ Stephen's 588.' The fourteenth edition of Stephen's Commentaries (1903) contains the following account of general and par- ticular customs : I. General customs. "These form the Common Law in its stricter signification. . . . But here a very natural, and very material, question arises. How are these general customs or maxims to be known, and by whom is their validity to be determined? The answer is, by the judges of the several courts of justice. They are the depositaries of the laws; the living oracles, who in all cases of doubt must decide according to the law of the land. Their knowledge of that law is derived from experience and study, from the 'viginti annorum lucuhrationss ' which Fortescue mentions, and from being long personally accustomed to the judicial decisions of their predecessors. And indeed, these judicial decisions are the most authoritative evidence of the existence of the common law. . . . And thus much for the first ground and chief corner stone of the laws of England, which is general immemorial, custom, or common law, from time to time declared in the decisions of the courts." II. Particular customs. "The second branch of the un- written law of England consists of particular (or special) customs affecting only the inhabitants of particular districts ; and a custom of this kind it is usual to designate by the word custom simply, to distinguish it from the common law, or the general customs already spoken of. . . . The Law Merchant is not local, nor is its obligation confined to any particular district. Hence it cannot with propriety be considered as a special custom. The usages of particular 1 "Jurisprudence" (1902), pp. 140-9. CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 317 trades, where not restrained to some particular locality, must also be excluded, and for the same reason, from the technical name of customs. For, if there be any such usage of im- memorial observance, authenticated by judicial decisions, it will form, according to our definition, part of the general law of England. If there be any sanctioned by Act of Parliament, it will constitute part of statute law. But for the rest, the want of any peculiar locality determines these usages to be no customs, and they are consequently no rules of law at all. . . . The rules relating to particular customs regard rather the proof of their existence, their validity, and their usual method of allowance when proved. First, as to proof. As to gavelkind and Borough-English, the law takes particular notice of them. . . . All other special customs must be expressly pleaded, and their existence must be shown, not merely that the thing in dispute is within the custom alleged. . . . When a custom is actually proved to exist, the next inquiry is into the validity of it. To make a custom good the following are necessary." The custom must be : 1. Immemorial. 2. Continuous. 3. Undisputed. 4. Eeasonable. 5. Pertain. 6. Obligatory. 7. Consistent with other custom. " Next as to the allowance of special customs. N"o custom can of course prevail against the express provisions of an Act of Parliament. But, apart from this restriction, a custom, being in derogation of the general law, must be construed strictly. . . . But though customs must be strictly, yet they need not in every case be literally, construed."^ Stephen's Commentaries (1903), pp. 20-30. 318 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND Mr. Greer. 589. With the above accounts of custom it may be in- teresting to add the following statement from an article by Mr. F. A. Greer, on Custom in the Common Law : " It was in reference to 'particular customs' that the well-known tests of the validity of custom were laid down. It was said that the validity of a custom depended on its being (1) certain and unambiguous, (2) reasonable, (3) on its having existed from time immemorial. And it was further added that it should not ' exalt itself ' upon the prerogative of the "king: Nullum tempus occurrit Regi. . . . The first condition, certainty, is indeed applicable to all cases where custom is suggested as the basis of rights. But it is not properly a condition at all. It merely amounts to the obvious proposi- tion that a custom is a different thing from a variable prac- tice. . . . Both the second and third conditions are properly applicable only to particular or local customs. They were used by courts of law as a means of checking the indefinite growth of local customs."^ The fore- 590. A comparison of the foregoing accounts suggests stated several interesting facts. As regards general customs, for ments example, it is affirmed by Professor Salmond that they must compare . j^g reasonable, obligatory, in conformity with statute law and, unless immemorial, in conformity with common law. On the other hand, Mr. Greer repudiates such tests as reasonableness and antiquity, whilst in Stephen's Commen- taries all legal validity is denied to the custom iintil it has been " authenticated by judicial decisions." In other words, one of these authors holds some general customs to be law, another seems to be disposed to hold all general customs to be law, whilst a third will admit no general custom to be law except as judicially sanctioned. With regard to parti- cular customs, we find a nearer approach to unanimity, at 1 "Law Quarterly Review," IX, 156, 157. CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 319 least to the extent of an agreement that some particular customs are laws before being judicially adopted. But im- mediately we turn to inquire which particular customs, unanimity is at an end. One writer proposes five tests, another four, a third eight, and a fourth three. Although the divergences are in reality less serious than this merely numerical test might seem to imply, their very existence is suggestive. It impels ns to ask whether, in a more rational view of the tests of the validity of customs, we should not regard them as aids to the judges to guide them in dealing with a persuasive source of law, than as qualifica- tions which define what is already law. 591. Such a view receives some encouragement from a (i) The consideration of the traditional attitude of the iudges in ***|*"de " ° of judges relation to the tests of the validity of custom. Particular towards customs, to deal first with the more difficult instance, have ^^^ ''*''^- 1° Par- net been received into the law in time past as a matter of tiouiar course. In the first part of Coke's Institutes we find a very customs, interesting paragraph in which the question is raised as to what customs may be alleged in an upland town, and what in cities and boroughs. The note of the learned editors remarks: "The privilege of having special customs, dero- gating from the Common Law, is in general denied to inferior places, such as upland towns, not being either cities or boroughs, and hamlets ; though it is allowed to larger or more important districts, such as counties, manors, hundreds, honors, cities and boroughs. The special cases hinted at by Lord Coke as an exception to this restraint, seem to be those in which the custom tends to advance some right recognized by the Common Law."^ ^ 592. Again, the use that is made by judges of the test of E.g.,test reasonableness, as to the existence of which all authorities °-J^^°^' ' Coke on Littleton (1817) 110b, 320 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND are agreed, is very suggestive. The general disposition of Coke in regard to customs is expressed in the familiar state- ment " Consuetude is one of the maine triangles of the lawes of England: those lawes being divided into common law, statute law, and custome." When, however, the great judge is dealing with the statement that customs must not be against reason, he adds significantly, " This is not to be understood of every unlearned man's reason, but of artificiall and legal reason warranted by authority of law: Lex est summa ratio." ^ Later on, in discussing the validity of a custom, alleged to be ancient, that every tenant within a certain manor who marries his daughter without the Lord's consent shall pay a fine to the Lord, the learned author follows Littleton in repudiating the custom as contrary to reason. " Some have thought that such a custome generally within the manor should be good. But the answer is, that though it may be so in a particular case upon such a special reservation of such a fine upon a gift of land, yet to claime such a fine, by a generall custome within the manor, is against the freedome of a freeman, that is not bound there- unto by particular tenure." ^ Other 593. The element of certainty has been a further means of controlling custom. Thus in the case of Nailor, qui tarn, v. Scott, where a custom had been foimd by a jury " that every housekeeper in the parish of Wakefield having a child born there, should, at the time when the mother was churched, or at the usual time after her delivery when she should be churched, pay tenpence to the vicar," the court determined that the custom was bad tor uncertainty, since the usual time for women to be churched was not alleged.^ Of all the tests, however, perhaps the one which might be expected to have required most elucidation is that described as opinio teats. 1 Coke on Littleton, 62a. " Ibid., 139b, 140a. 3 Smith's Leading Cases, lOth ed., I, p. 532. CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 321 necessitatis. The general meaning of this test came under discussion in the interesting case of Meyer v. Dresser} In that case the attempt was made to establish judicially an alleged general custom giving to a consignee of goods, or an endorsee of a bill of lading, the right to deduct the value of missing goods from the freight. It was held by the judges that the alleged custom was merely a convenient practice for settling undisputed claims, and not applicable in case of con- tested rights, — a mode of settling accounts, not a foundation on which to rest a legal claim. So far as I am aware, how- ever, the difficulties involved in the conception of opinio •necessitatis have not received an adequate attention at the hands of English judges or English lawyers or jurists. A perusal of the controversial literature of the Continent upon the point might serve to warn us against too hastily under- estimating the difficulties which are- really involved.^ 594. As r^ards general customs, the leading modern case is 2° Gener»l Goodvnn v. Bdbarts? I shall venture to quote certain dicta from the judgment of this case, though with some hesitation, for the reason that the judges as a body have so clung to the fiction that they only apply pre-existing law, that their real attitude is more to be gathered from a consideration of the facts of many decisions than the langu&ge of the judges in any one. Curiously enough, however, in the leading modern case, the very language of the judges will be seen to favour the interpretation of judicial decision as transforming custom into law. The judgment of the Court (Cockburn, C.J., Mellor, Lush, Brett and Lindley, JJ.) contains the following statements : " The' substance of Mr. Benjamin's argument is, that because the scrip does not correspond with any of the forms of the security for money which have hitherto been ' (1864; 33 L. J. C. P. 289. " Of. Lambert. " Etudes de droit commun l^slatif," I, pp. 120 et J. » (1875) L R 10 Exch. 337. 522 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND held to be negotiable by the Law Merchant, and does not contain a direct promise to pay money, but only a promise to give security for money, it is not a security to which, by the Law Merchant, the character of the' negotiability can attach. Having given the fullest consideration to this argument, we are of opinion that it cannot prevail. It is founded on the view that the Law Merchant thus referred to is fixed and stereotyped, and incapable of being expanded and enlarged so as to meet the wants and requirements of trade in the varying circumstances of commerce. . . The Law Merchant is neither more nor less than the usages of merchants and traders in the different departments of trade, ratified by decisions of Courts of Law, which, upon such usages being proved before them, have adopted them as settled law with a view to the interests of trade and the public convenience. . . By this process, what before was usage only, unsanc- tioned by legal decision, has become engrafted upon, or incorporated into, the common law, and may thus be said to form part of it." The judgment proceeds to discuss the history of the development of the Law Merchant, and then continues : " But Holt having become Chief Justice, a some- what unseemly conflict arose between him and the merchants as to the negotiability of promissory notes, whether payable to order or to bearer, the Chief Justice taking what must now be admitted to have been a narrow-minded view of the matter, setting his face strongly against the negotiability of these instruments. The inconvenience to trade arising there- from led to the passing of the statute of 3 and 4 Anne, c. 9." The Court, after considering later judicial controversies, pro- ceeds to ask : " Why is it to be said that a new usage which has sprung up under altered circumstances, is to be less admissible than the usage of past times ? . . . The univer- sality of a usage voluntarily adopted between buyers and sellers is conclusive proof of its being in accordance with CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 323 public convenience; and there can be no doubt that by hold- ing this species of security to be incapable of being transferred by delivery . . . we should cause great public inconvenience."^ 595. In reviewing the preceding argument, I may remind Review of the reader that discussion has turned, not upon the question j"^|,° j whether judges should defer to usage, but upon the question whether they are hownd by usage. I began the consideration of this question by remarking the inconcliAsive character of the arguments commonly held to justify the traditional view. The language of the judges, for example, is open to considerable suspicion in view of the persistence of the fiction of judicial incompetence to add to the law. Until that fiction is definitely rejected, we can hope for no sound theory of the relation of the judges to the development of new rules. Again, that the judicial adoption of custom is retrospective proves nothing, for this is a characteristic of judge-made law in general, an inevitable result of the imperfection of human institutions, the sacrifice of formal justice that in the long run substantial justice may be done. The fact that judges often base their decision upon custom is paralleled by the fact that judges often base their decision upon convenience; in determining the significance of all such action, we must remember that in the unideal world wherein we live, justice is wider than law ; that much to which judges pay great deference is in no sense law and does not even of necessity become law as a result of the judicial decision. ' 596. On the other hand, there are real difficulties in the way of calling customs, as such, laws. Tests exist for deciding what customs are to determine or influence judicial action, but the writers who tell us what these tests are, differ from one another in important respects. The use, ' (1875) L. R. 10 Exch. 352. Of. also nmiihall v. Metropolitan Bank 1877) L. R. 2 Q. B. D. 194. 324 CUSTOMAEY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND moreover, which judges make of the tests, eind the important r61e which the argument from convenience plays in the judicial trials where customs have been approved, tend to confirm a suspicion of the existence of a fundamental difference between the attitude of the judges in dealing with custom, and their attitude in dealing with sources of law which are undoubtedly binding. Diffi- 597. Among the binding sources of law, however, there °" '^\ d ^^^ ^^^ classes which raise at this point some real difficulties. by the The precise conditions under which precedents are binding analogy of ^^^ nowhere clearly stated. Municipal by-laws it is said customa to "^ _ 1:1 iudioial must be in conformity with the general law of the land, intra precedents qji^gg, reasonable, just, certain, etc.* As no one would deny by-Jaw3, that precedent and by-law are binding sources of law, it might seem that the value of the preceding argument as to the tests of custom is seriously, if not fatally, prejudiced. I do not think, however, that it would be difficult to establish a real difference in modern judicial administration between the application of a precedent or a by-law and the applica- tion for the first time of a popular custom, — a difference that, as regards the test of reasonableness, for example, might be expressed by saying that precedent and by-law bind unless obviously unreasonable, whilst a custom must be proved positively to be reasonable and in accord with public convenience. Moreover, that the line between the binding and the persuasive sources of legal rule should be drawn somewhere beneath precedent and by-law and above popular custom, is made a priori probable by certain leading tenden- cies of social evolution to which I shall now proceed to draw attention, (c) Argu- 598. In the first place, the tendency of social evolution is merit trom towards conscious regulation in the place of unconscious the facta ° ^ ' Cf. Adler, "The Law of Corporations," p. 63. CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 325 regulation. The struggle for existence goes on eternally, of social but the knowledge of the fact in its practical bearings *^°^""°"" and implications is relatively modern. The knowledge brings far-sighted action of reflecting human beings in the place of the spontaneous development of rules. Law- making, whether by judges or usage, from being largely unconscious tends to become increasingly conscious. "Primitive societies and undeveloped races," writes Pro- fessor Sorley, "are more prone to be governed by external circumstances than to reflect upon their nature and tenden- cies, and hence their ideas of legal relations are for the most part the mere reflection of customs inherited from a previous generation or necessitated by outward events. . , . But in developed and civilized communities, where men have learned the lesson of reflection, the tendency is in the opposite direction ; custom has to justify itself at the bar of reason, and conduct comes to be guided by a definite concep- tion of its end, instead of by a vague belief that it is usual." ^ In the second place, social evolution has implied, not merely an increase in conscious regulation, but also the development of appropriate organs for this regulation. The relative position and importance of these organs vary from time to time. A claim on the part of one law- making organ to be something other than an organ, revives older sources of law by inevitable reaction. Patrimonial theories of the State and doctrines of an absolute sover- eignty, for example, have driven men to contend for the aboriginal rights of the unorganized community. The general tendency, "however, is towards a just appreciation of the position of law-making organs, and a corresponding hmitation of the term law to what is developed by organs specially provided by the State for that purpose. Finally, in Philosophical Criticism," pp. 109, 110. 326 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND social evolution has worked for an increasing definiteneas, substituting, as Herbert SpenCer would say, definite hetero- geneity for an indefinite homogeneity. In the sphere of law this increased definiteness has told for a differentiation of the natural and political bases of law, and a differentia- tion of the sources of law into respective hierarchies of those which are legal and those which are merely persuasive. Signifi- 599. The relation of these tendencies of the social evolu- canceof jJqjj ^q ^jjg question immediately under consideration must for present be apparent Judges and by-law-making authorities are puri)oae3. organs of the community which, in different ways, are called upon to make new law. Their work is, or tends to become, conscious and rational. The products of their law-making action are definite and knowable. In all these respects they stand on a somewhat different level from popular custom in which the spontaneous takes the place of the conscious, the unorganized of the organized, the in- definite and unknowable of the definite and knowable. It has been long felt to be a serious difficulty in the way of the traditional theory of custom, that if customs may be law before judicial adoption, a part of the law of the land is not only unknown of the judges, but is practically unknowable save by the circuitous process of proof by evidence of wit- nesses. A further practical proof of difference may be seen in the decline of custom as a matter of fact. It is not uncommon nowadays to limit the law-making power of custom to particular customs, and in regard to these an author who cannot be accused .of underestimating their importance or authority remarks, "The truth is that in modern times there is an express demand for legislation as soon as there is any decided trend of opinion. Except in matters outside the scope of positive law the formation of custom belongs to an archaic period in our history."' ' Pollock, " First Book of Jurisprudence," p. 265. CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND 327 Judicial precedent, not popular custom, is the extra-legis- lative source of law to-day. 600. The general conclusion at which I have arrived may Gen«»l be expressed in a sentence. When judges, in applying a"™^"°° custom which is not yet judicially authenticated, declare the custom to have been law previously to the decision, they are merely displaying a special form of the fiction of judicial incompetence. In the relatively developed character of modern institutions, more especially in regard to the de- velopment of the special organs for the amelioration and development of legal rules, it appears to me that the time has arrived for a clearer limitation of the contents of law, and for the development of a theory of those persuasive sources of law (including custom) to which judges may have recourse in cases where there is an imperative call either for a new rule or for the variation of an existing rule under particular circumstances of locality. 601. I pass from the discussion of the question as to the (6)Wheiica moment when we are iustified in saying of custom that it is °°f ■' JO custom law, to examine the theory that custom is law, not merely derive its before judicial adoption, but independently of such adoption, »n*°"*J- and by an inherent and ultimate authority of its own. Granted, it has been urged, that a custom comes within the judicial conception, and it is treated with all the deference due to an Act of Parliament. Judges may make precedent a binding source of legal rule ; custom is such independently of any authority either of a single judge or of a succession of judges. 602. The theory recalls the period in our legal history Theory n» when competent lawyers doubted whether a statute had any !°°^" authority to overrule usage, and regarded usage as a law- creating power co-ordinate with Parliament rather than sub- ordinate to it. In our own day it is not custom as such which is enforced, but custom as satisfying certain tests 328 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND which the judges themselves have fixed, and which they may vary if in their wisdom they think it desirable to do BO. The real source of the authority of general custom is sufficiently attested by the requirement that it must be reasonable, and by the emphasis laid by the judges upon considerations of public policy and convenience in cases where their validity comes before the courts.^ In respect of particular customs, the single circumstance that they must be immemorial in itself disposes of any claim to possess an inherent authority. To hold that they must be well estab- lished is consistent with such a claim; to hold that they must be established from time immemorial is completely fatal to it. I conceive that in this matter it would be inter- esting to imagine a country of which the courts should assume the right of picking and choosing between statutes, saying of some : Yes, these are good ; though their contents are not quite ideal, they satisfy — as a matter of fact — ^the conditions which we have laid down, and we will apply them. If such courts existed I do not think we should attribute to statute as such an intrinsic authority. We should be more inclined to hold that if the courts had picked and chosen among the statutes, and had laid down the con- ditions which must be satisfied by a statute before it would be enforced, such intrinsic authority as existed must be looked for rather in the judicial practice than in the statutes themselves. Signifi- 603. The emphasis which I have laid upon the test of cance of reasonableness may seem excessive in view of the fact that the test of reason- there was a time in our legal history when it was held that ablenesa. an Act of Parliament itself might be void as unreasonable. In the face of such a condition of things, it might be urged that the requirement -that a custom must be reasonable involves no denial of its intrinsic authority. But we need to * For example, Goodwin v. Robarts (1875) L. R. 10 Exch. 337. CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND ^ 329 consider precisely what was meant by the doctrine that an Act of Parliament might be void as unreasonable. In a leading case on this point, the judgment of the court con- tains the following significant statement : " Even an Act of Parliament made against natural equity, as to make a man judge in his own case, is void in itself. Jwra naturae, sunt immidahilia, and they are leges legum." ^ The view that an Act of Parliament might be void as unreasonable was but one way of saying that Natural Law was a part of the law of the land. The Act of Parliament in obvious conflict with Natural Law was thus held to be void as being in conflict with a higher law of the State. When it became a recog- nized principle that Natural Law as such was not a part of the law of the land, it could no longer be held that an Act of Parliament was void as unreasonable. If, on the other hand, the question be asked, by what authority to-day can a custom be rejected as unreasonable? we can make no appeal to Natural Law or to any express Act of Parliament. We can only appeal, and naturally would appeal, to the judicially established rule. 604. The general conclusion, therefore, is that custom is Some ob- law when it can be held that the judges are bound to enforce ^*"'*'°"' it Though there may be some difference of opinion possible as to the moment when this can be said to be the case, I do not think there can be any difference of opinion on the point that judges are bound, not by any inherent intrinsic autho- rity of custom, but by virtue of their own practice. To the question why custom is law no better answer can be given than that the judges treat it as such. The custom of the people is law, in so far as it is law, by virtue of the custom of the courts. Professor Dewey, in discussing the view that the judicial recognition of custom as law is due to an express or tacit law giving to such customs the effect of laws, 1 Day V. Samdge (1614) Hob. p. 87. 330 CUSTOMARY LAW IN MODERN ENGLAND remarks, "To say that customs are regarded as laws by virtue of a tacit law to that effect, is simply to heg the whole question. It is to say that custom is law in virtue of custom." ' The criticism receives some support from Dr. Willoughby.' " The law-creating power of custom," argues Professor Sal- mond, " is an ultimate legal principle. We may say, indeed, that it is recognized by precedent, and has there its legal source. But it may be said with equal truth that the autho- rity of precedent is recognized by, and has its source' in, custom. One or other of these two propositions may be true, but to accept them both is to reason in a circle."' " These two are co-ordinate legal sources, and each operates independently of the other. Custom does not rule the law through precedent, any more than precedent through custom."* The 605. The answer to objections of this kind appears to me to be that the people are not, what the judges are, an of&cial organ. It seems to me not only possible, but highly important, to distinguish between what the judges do or may do, and what unorganized and unofficial groups within the community do or may do. It appears to me a right and important step in the direction of a sound theory to hold that popular custom enters the law, if" not through prece- dent, at least through judicial practice ; that precedent also becomes law by virtue of judicial practice, and that in con- sequence the authority of both j^pular custom and isolated precedent find a common basis in the authority of judicial practice. In the view I hold of the matter, we have reached a stage in our legal history when a theory of customary law inevitably leads on to a theory of judicial practice in general Some suggestions towards the latter theory have been already made in the preceding excursus. •nswer. 1 " Political Science Quarterly," IX, 47. " " Nature of the State," p. 175. 3 "Jurisprudence," p. 110. ♦ lb., p. 165. EXCURSUS E A. CONSIDERATION OF SOME OBJECTIONS TO THE CONCEPTION OF POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COM- MAND 610. Austin defined a law as a species of command. The Modem definition was not original ; it had been expressed by greater ""^"g" men, forming indeed a venerable juristic succession, and tinian enjoying for centuries the sanctity of orthodoxy. Never d^^"'''''"' without rivals, however, the definition has been subjected in our own time to a searching and vehement criticism. The historian has declared it unhistorical, the lawyer unpractical, the philosopher superficial. Before such criticism, the defini- tion might have been expected to apologize for taking so unconscionable a time in dying. Its disappointment of such . expectations may serve to recall to the mind of hostile criticism a remark of Leslie Stephen that philosophical theories live long after their brains have been knocked out. We have here, it may be suggested, an illustration of the fatality of hereditary attachment. Just so, those who be- lieved the earth to be fiat have left such a taint of that impression in the blood of their descendants that some may still be heard to confess in half-shamed whisper, " I think something may be said for a flat earth after all ! " " What," I have heard one demand, " What if there be a Hell after aU!" 611. Although the modern believer in Austinian oi Neo- Not an Austinian doctrine who lives on this side of the Channel finds ^^-^ aiders and abettors in high life, he canpot be insensible to the 331 332 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND growing body of criticism which he is called upon to answer. Under these circumstances it may be a consolation for him to reflect that truth can only be won through controversy that only by refuting error can we hope to realize what the true may be. The present conflict as to the meaning of law should be welcomed as the student's opportunity to win his spurs. If knowledge rather than formulae be his goal, his lot is happier than that of the student who is born in a period when all are agreed as to what is true, while scarce any one realizes the nature of that as to which all are agreed. Certainly the student who carefully examines the objections to the conception of law as command, the reasons which may be urged for them, and the answers that can be suggested to them, will gain a new insight into the meaning of law. If the reader has not already approached the sub- ject from this point of view, he may find some material for consideration in the following excursus. The position under examination, however, is not identical with that adopted by Austin, who defined a law not law, and looked for the source of laws, not to the State, but to the visible ruler. With respect to the last-mentioned difference, my reasons for dis- senting from Austin have been stated in the excursus on the State and Sovereignty. My preference for discussing the defini- tion of law rather than of a law is the result of a conviction that for the purposes of legal science it is more important to arrive at a general conception of one's subject-matter as a whole than to obtain a verbally precise definition of the fragments of which it is composed. Objeotiona 612. The objections to which attention is drawn may l)« Bteted. briefly stated :— A. As to the Source of Law. (i.) Law is older than the State, (ii.) Customs are laws apart from State recognition, (iii.) Law, not the State, is supreme. POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 333 B. As to the Nature of Law. (iv.) A great part of law is not expressible as com- mand, (v.) Even where law is so expressible, command is not of its essence. . (vi.) In any case, the representation of law as com- mand is hopelessly inadequate. This list is not suggested as exhaustive, or as representing the tenets of any one school, but as convenient for the purposes of discussion. 613. (i.) Law is older than the State. — In a recent work, (i.) Law " The Native Tribes of South-east Australia," Dr. Howitt has °^'^«'" "*•■ shown that tribal laws or customs are obeyed by the Australian aboriginal, not from any fear of punishment by tribal authority, whether individual or collective, but from the dread of a supernatural .punishment in whose reality the individual has been taught to belieVe from infancy. The evidences of similar phenomena elsewhere might be multi- plied indefinitely. On the authority of such evidences, three distinct arguments may be suggested. The conception of law as State command is not applicable in the earlier stages of social life ; as a consequence it is not likely to represent the true inwardness of things to-day; and in any case a definition of law, to be scientific, should embrace its mean- ing in the different stages of human history. 614. The consideration of such arguments belongs to aitsinooa- science or philosophy of legal history rather than to a theory "l""^'- of the modern law. In this connection, two conceptions of the purpose of historical study require to be distinguished. We may study the history of the past to illumine the present ; or we ma^ study that history for its own sake. In the one case history is an accessory study ; in the other case it is an independent science. The former is the point of view which appeals to the theorist of things as they are. In constructing 334 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND a science of law as it is to-day, recourse may be had to history for suggestion, but not for final judgment. When, however, it is once clearly realized that there may be different sciences of law, each entitled to have its own definition of its subject- matter, the present objection to the conception of law as State command loses its force. The fact that the conception is only possible in a modem atmosphere, so far from being a criticism, is on the contrary a eulogy if our object is a science of the modern law. The historical-mindedness which should save us from the error of fastening a modem conception upon ancient fact, should also save us from the like error of forcing on modern fact a theory derived from, or suggested by, ancient data. Each generation, as I remarked in the preceding excursus, lies under the eternal necessity to give its own account of things or rest a defaulter. " There may have been a time in the far past when a man was not distinguished from an anthropoid ape, but that is no reason for now defining a man in such wise as to include an ape."^ So, too, in the life of our time, there is such a thing as State-enforced rule — a reality of profound importance and wholly worthy of being made the subject of a distinct science. The circumstance that the historical antecedent of this reality may have been enforced by an impersonal authority or a supernatural sanction, is interesting but inconclusive. For the jurist, who is concerned to achieve a theory of modem law, law implies a State and an organized ruling power within it. (ii.) Ous- 615. (ii.) A great part of the inodern law has been derived toraary jfrom popular customs which have been held to be laws before being adopted by the State, and independently of such adoption. The State enforces them because they are law ; they are not law because the State enforces them. In reality 616. If it were true that law could be made by unorganized masses of the population, the conception of law as State State com manded. Salmond, " Jurisprudence," p. 54. POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 335 command would be open to serious objection, since the term State stands for the organized community. That the un- organized masses of the population have no such power is a position I hope to have sufiBciently demonstrated, at any rate BO far as England is concerned, in the preceding excursus. Tn the opinion I have there upheld, the very small section of popular customs which can lay any claim to be called law, are law by the specific or general adoption of the judges. Such adoption is quite as much the work of the organized community as a general legislative adoption. It is true that the State enforces them because they are laws ; but they are laws because they are declared to be so, specifically or gener- ally, by the judicial organ. 617 (iii.) Law, not the State, is sv^preme. — "How is the (iii.) Law enforcement of the law regulated ? By the law itself. The ""* ^°^ t • • 1 • t T 1 T1 1 ■ supreme, force IS exercised, in fact, accordmg to law. Even when its exercise seems to be most arbitrary, there must be some legal method behind it. It is the law, then, and not the force which is supreme. . . . The law by which the ruler rules cannot be the outcome of his ruling."^ The force of Objection arguments of this kind is less directed against the concep- maintain- able tion of law as command of the State, than against the against conception of law as command of a visible ruler. Austin, Austiman failing to recognize that both rulers and subjects are parts of a larger unity, attributed the origin and authority of all law to the former. The position is not, in my opinion, maintain- able ; nor is it under consideration in the present excursus. 618. But even when we reject the error of identifying The ob- the State with the visible rulers, the criticism that law not J^"''"" "^ senses : the State is supreme may be urged in either of two senses, (o) that According to the first of these senses, law exists inde- 1*^ *^i*** , independ- pendently of its formulation by the State ; for example, as a ^ntiy of the State ; Watt, " Legal Philosophy," p. 18. 336 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND philosophic lex naturce, or as a body of rules deriving their being from the very nature of things.^ The criticism, though it may have a meaning for the purposes of a phib- sophy of law, is irrelevant for the purposes of that science of law of which the lawyer stands most in need. Such a science must recognize, as its raw material, the legal rules which actually exist. But the legal rules which actually exist are determined by reference to State-declared will As philosophers, we may believe in the existence of ideal codes- as lawyers, we have to reckon with the fact that the degree of mutual adjustment which is to be enforced in a society by the corporate will, must be determined by that will. Law only becomes actual as it is ofi&cially declared by the State and enforced by its authority. (6) that 619. The criticism that law not the State is supreme, may the State j^g based, however, upon the fact that the State is bound by IB limited > ■ r j by law. law. The existence of a State, as we understand the term to-day, implies not merely rule, but rule according to law But although the State may be bound by law, it can change that law at will, and hence in a very real sense is superior to it. The supremacy in developed States is even expressed in the visible organization. Most States possess some organ, or group of organs, which is supreme over law, not in the sense that it can violate law at will, but in the sense that it can change the law at will. ^The position has been challenged at times with regard to the rules of fundamental Constitutional Law. The fifth section of the Constitution of the United States, for example, defines the organization by which amend- ments of the Constitution may be effected ; the section is a. law of which the Supreme Court will take cognizance; the organization which it prescribes is sovereign; and accordingly that sovereign, when it makes new law, does so in the name, ^ Cf . Duguit, " Le droit objectif et la loi positive." POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 337 i and by the authority, of law. Nevertheless, the ultimate supremacy of the State is sufficiently demonstrated by the fact that, when once the sovereign organization is in being, it can change at will the very law to which it owes its origin and authority. Eightly regarded, the fifth section of the American Constitution is not superior to the State or sovereign ; it merely defines the sovereign organ. It is simply an expression of the will of the State, prescribing its mode of action for certain purposes. 620. (iv.) A great part of law is not expressible in the form (iv.) Some of command. — Austin admitted the non-imperative character '*^ ""' 1.1 1-- ■■• .••■ 1,1 . expresaibls of laws explaining or repealing positive law, and of laws of as com- imperfect obligation. Later criticism of Austin's general mand. position has been more especially directed to two other classes. In the first place, many rules of law affect not to impose duties, but to confer privileges. Thus a Settled Land Act empowers a tenant for life to exercise new rights of alienation ; a Companies Act allows any seven persons, who choose to go through certain formalities, to enjoy the privi- leges of incorporation ; and an Enfranchisement Act confers the suffrage upon a new class of the population. In the second place, such rules of procedure as relate to the admis- sibility of different kinds of evidence, or define the respective provinces of judge and jury, seem neither to impose duties nor to confer privileges, but simply to state the conditions under which Courts of Justice will apply legal sanctions. 621. Two answers have been made with respect to Buch PoBsibls classes. It may be said of them that they involve a real fi's^ers : •' " (a) Imper- imperative, i.e. the command to the judge.i Apart from the ative to obvious fact that the supreme lawgiver may also be the ^^^ jndge. supreme judge, and so not amenable to legal penalties, the answer is open to the objection of evading the primary ' Of. Ihering, "L'Evolution du droit," § 149. 338 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND (i) The aspect of legal rules for an aspect which is secondary. An ^""^ answer which is more entitled to respect dwells upon what narrowly is alleged to be an undue abstraction in determining what ■"*" , are legal rules. " A law, like any other command, must be expressed in words, and will require the use of the usual aids to expression. The gist of it may be expressed in a sentence which, standing by itself, is not intelligible ; other sentences locally separate from the principal one may contain the exceptions and the modifications and the interpretations to which that is subject. In no one of these taken by itself, but in the substance of them all taken together, is the true law, in Austin's sense, to be found. Thus the rule that every will must be in writing is a mere fragment — only the hmb of a law. It belongs to the rule which fixes the rights of devisees or legatees under a will. That rule, in whatever form it may be expressed, is, without any straining of language, a command of the legislator. That ' every person named by a testator in his last will and testament shall be entitled to the property thereby given to him ' is surely a command creating rights and duties. After testament add ' expressed in writing ' ; it is still a command. Add further, 'provided he be not one of the witnesses to the will ' and the command', with its product of rights and duties, is still there. Each of the additions limits the operation of the command stated imperatively in the first sentence." ^ Other illustrations in support of the same line of argument might be multiplied indefinitely. Mr. Bryce, in his criticism of the Austinian position, refers to Administrative Statutes which enable a public body to do something which it could not otherwise have done. But a Statute empowering Borough Councils to impose a new rate is also a command to the subjects to pay the rate when called upon to do so. The ' Encyclopaedia Britannica," XIV, 358. POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 339 Statute expresses a permission; it implies a command. Though nominally addressed to the County Council, it is really also addressed to the subject, as he will discover to his cost if he should dispute the payment of the rate. It may be regarded as a delegation by a sovereign body of a limited power of taxation ; it may also be regarded as the imposition of a conditional duty upon the subject. 622. Unfortunately, Austin himself was not free from the Austin on charge of undue abstraction in determining what are legal j^^^j rules. Statutes which interpret pre-existing Statutes are Repealing but detached parts of a whole along with which they must S***"***- be read if their true character is to be determined. A similar argument seems to hold with respect to repealing Statutes. One Statute prohibits gambling, and a later Statute repeals the prohibition. What are we to say in such a case ? That it is a rule of law that gambling is permissible ? If so, we imply a direct command to the subjects not to interfere with the gambler. The theory of English Law, however, would be better expressed by saying that there was, but is no longer, a rule of law with regard to gambling. If, subsequent to the repeal of the Statute prohibiting gambling, certain persons choose to gamble and others interfere with them, this interference will not be taken cognizance of by the Courts by virtue of the repealing Statute, but by virtue of the general rules of law which forbid assault, imprison- ment, etc. " I take the effect of repealing a Statute to be," said Tindall, C. J„ " to obliterate it from the records of Par- liament as completely as if it had never passed; and it must be considered as a law that never existed, except for the purpose of those actions which were commenced, prose- cuted, and concluded while it was existing law."^ By reading the repealing Statute along with the Statute repealed Ziiy V. Goodwin, 6 Bingham, 582. 340 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND we arrive at the general result, not of non-imperative law, but of the non-existence of law. («) Dia- 623. The objection that many rules of law are not expres- tanction g-jj|g ^ ^j^g ioim. of command may be therefore met, in part between ■' * law and at least, by the answer that the expression legal rules can laws. ijg construed, and ought to be construed, in a wide sense. In the present excursus, however, I have elected to consider, not the definition of legal rules, but the definition of law. Now the position that law in its totality is essentially a system of social regulation which the State will uphold by force, is not affected by the fact that some parts of the law are not imperative, if it be true that such parts derive a practical meaning and value from parts which are impera- tive. I referred, in expanding the general objection now under consideration, to two classes of legal rules — ^rules con- ferring privileges and rules of procedure. The latter are obviously accessory. They define the legal sanction or express the persons by whom, and the conditions under which, it will be applied. To regard them severally as im- perative is to miss their most obvious aspect ; it is otherwise when we regard them in conjunction with the totality of the legal system. The same holds good of laws conferring privileges. Such privileges would be meaningless, divorced from their context of State-enforced regulation. A Com- panies Act, for example, allows any seven persons to incor- porate under certain conditions and for certain purposes. The effect is merely to supply official recognition of a new class of person. Law is command to persons ; the Act in question offers a general definition of a class of person. Similarly, an enfranchising Statute defines the mode of the constitution of the legislative organ whose chief business it is to formulate new rules of law. (v.) Com- 624 (v.) Hven though law be expressible in the form of com- mand not ./n^nd, command is not of its essence. — The objection raises POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 341 directly an issue indirectly suggested by objections already the essence considered. Admit, it may be said, that we are only con- °^ ''*"■ cerned with the positive law of a modern State, admit that customs are not law save by virtue of the will of the State, admit that law is not superior to the State, admit that law in its totality can be expressed in the formula of command, we have yet to consider whether, when so expressed, it is most naturally and properly expressed, whether its real essence be not something other than command. The general object of law, it may be urged, is not to impose duties, but to confer rights ; not to make the citizen a slave, but to en- noble him as a man; not to compel him to walk in prescribed ways, but to provide him with opportunities for self-realiz- ation. Law, in a word, is primarily and emphatically a system of rights conferred in the interest of a common good. If it imposes duties, it is not for their own sake, but only for the purpose of securing rights. Therefore to define the totality as command is to mistake the secondary aspect of law for the primary aspect. " An examination of the current reports of the decisions of Courts of last resort will show that a great number of even common law cases are decided upon prin- ciples of utility. . . . What will work best ? is an impUed queption. This is not the jurisprudence of a system of com- mands ; it is the jurisprudence of a common welfare wrought out by free reasoning upon the actual facts of life."^ "Law, in its own notion," declared Locke, "is not so much the limitation as the direction of a free and intelligent agent to his proper interest, and prescribes no further than is for the general good of those under the law . . so that, however it may be mistaken, the end of the law is, not to abolish or restrain, but to preserve or enlarge freedom."^ > "American Law Review," Nov., Dec, 1893, p. » " Of Civil Government," i. 57. 342 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND General 625. With much of this criticism I am in entire accord. position of rpjjg^ jg^^ -g ^ great deal more than command is indeed a present ° exGuraua proposition which no one will care to combat. I will even stated. agree that command is not the most essential aspect of law, though it may be the most obvious. I hold, however, that rights are nothing apart from duties, that legal duties imply the command of the State, and that in the present constitu- tion of society any definition of law which does not give prominence to the element of command can afiford no ade- quate starting-point for a legal science. Unten- 626. The argument so stated would call for little support Austinian ^^^ ^°^ ^^^ ^*°*' '^^^ *^® conception of law as command has interpreta- been interpreted at times in a manner so extreme and one- f T t th ^^^^^ ^^ *'° create in many minds an unreasoning horror of source of the very term. Apart from the attempt to force every thea)m- igg^l rule into the formula of command which has been nana ; already made the subject of reference, a mistake has been made as to the ultimate source of those commands which have the authority of law, and the notion of command has been limited to injunctions which are obeyed through fear of a penalty. For the perpetuation of both these errors, Austin was largely responsible. In regarding laws as the command of the rulers to the subjects, he gave countenance to the in- ference that law is the arbitrary creation of the rulers. The position at present imder consideration, however, is that of law as command of the State, a totality embracing rulers and ruled. As a citizen, a man is not entitled to regard law as an arbitrary regulation of his life when it is the regula- tion imposed by a totality of which he himself forms a part. The truth of this statement is apt to be forgotten by subjects labouring under the sense of some legislative or executive wrong. Finding themselves in direct conflict with law on one point in a thousand, they concentrate all thought upon that point, and declare that law is none of their doing. POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 343 Some excuse for this illogical attitude will always exist as long as the organs for the expression of the general will are BO defective as to admit of much being done in the name of the State which is contrary to the will and interests of the State. But even under existing conditions, law, as a system, exists by virtue of the will of that totality of which each citizen is a part — a totality with a past and a future — a totality into which he enters and from which he departs, but of which he is here and now a visible, member — a totality which lives and learns, affirming for men's guidance from generation to generation new rules which express the conditions under which man's life may be lived. 627. Austin was also guilty of unduly limiting the notion (*) of tha of command. He regarded a command as an injunction to °^ " ° which a penalty was attached. When, however, he discussed mmi the question of the motives which account for submission to government, he attached most importance to the popular perception of the utility of government. The inconsistency is apparent ; it should have been avoided by a revision of his definition of command. Such a revision would have been justified by popular usage, in accordance with which the term as directly connotes the idea of authority as that of sanction. In such expressions as the royal comTnand, the idea of author- ity is the more obvious of the two. The spirit which breathes in the text, "Thy will, not mine, be done," is one of sub- mission to command wherein the idea of authority is supreme, whilst that of sanction is virtually absent. I see no reason why a citizen who defines law as a command should be taken to postulate a reluctance on his part to obey it, still less a reluctance only to be overcome by fear of a legal penalty. In the "English Historical Dictionary," the following is given as the leading definition of command: "To order, enjoin, bid, with authority or influence." The essence of command consists in the fact that it is imposed by. a 344 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND body which speaks with authority and can somehow or other punish disobedience, not in the fact of its being obeyed through fear of a penalty. To some citizens, law may appear as fulfilment ; to others a hindrance ; some may revere, others may hate it ; alike to saint and to sinner it speaks with the authority and sanction of the State. Whatever may be the motive of the citizen's obedience, the law is still law to him, still a command to him, although all thought of the legal sanction lies entirely in the unexplored recesses of his con- sciousness. Neo-Aus- 628. When once the conception of law as command is tinian in- gig^rly distinguished from the representation of legal rules tion of as the arbitrary creation of a visible ruler obeyed by subjects tommand. from fear of legal penalties, it is difficult to see on what ground the conception can be criticized. Whatever else law is, it is at least command. What makes a particular rule of conduct law, is not the fact that it may be useful, but that behind it is the maJQsty, the authority, and the force of the State. There are other rules of conduct which men observe under the influence of all kinds of impulse, but of the rules of conduct which are law, the distinguishing characteristic is the existence of the organized force of the community be- hind them. But what the community as an organized unit will enforce, it may be said with justice to command. Law, in its totality, is the voice of the organized community 'speaking to all persons subject to its control, and affirming a rule of life which men may accept with the consciousness of the might of the community to support them. It is the expression of the organized will of the community, backed by the organized force of the community. Particular rules of law may not be expressible in the imperative form, but such rules derive their meaning and value from their associ- ation with a system which, regarded as a whole, must be held to be commanded — if once the term command be de- POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 345 fined in the manner which popular usage and common sense require. 629. (vi.) The conception of Law as corfimand is inadequate (vi.) Law for the jm/rposes of Legal Science. — The proposition that law """^^ °|° is more than command will receive the assent of all classes of the community. But when we come to determine how far this something more is so essential to the nature of law as to call for expression in its definition, important differ- ences of opinion are certain to arise even amongst that very limited class of folk who are interested in legal science. One reason for such differences may be found in the fact that legal science may be approached from very different points of view, and may be pursued with very different objects. Austin affected a Jurisprudence which should serve the purposes of an introduction to the study of a particular legal system. It may be urged with much force that, for such purposes, Austin's definition was not seriously in- adequate. Among those who are interested in legal educa- tion to-day, however, there are some who demand a theory of law which will serve more ambitious purposes — a theory which will complete an academic course of legal study rather than serve as an introduction to it — a theory which, whether it be mainly history, science, or philosophy, shall give to the student of law a new interpretation of his subject as a whole. For such a theory of law as this, we must go much further in our definition of law than to characterize it as command. 630. I shall venture, in concluding this excursus, to ex- Law con- press my own opinion as to how much further we ought to stitnted of go. In two respects at least, there need be little fear of external evoking criticism. In the first place, law afiirms rules of "otio"- londuct. The command of the State, in the nature of things, cannot be directed to particular individuals or particular oc- casions. Accordingly, it regards persons and occasions gener- elements in law. 346 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND ally. In the second place, ^nce the law must be enforced, the command of the State must not invade a domain where enforcement is wholly impossible. One such domain is so obvious and important as to call for express mention. Law can compel men to act justly, not to think justly. In other words, law relates solely to external action. Austin included the first of these essentials in the definition of a law, biat not the second. Professor Holland includes both. " A law is a general rule of external human action enforced by a sovereign political authority."' Further 631. If we are to define law, as distinguished from rules of law, the foregoing analysis only expresses the results of what may be called a first view. In such familiar descriptions of law as the empire of the dead over the living, as the product of national life, as a spirit which lives and moves within the letter, we may recognize dimly the presentation of great truths which should be reflected in the definition of law. I will venture, accordingly, to urge for the inclusion of three further elements in the conception of law in addition to those to which reference has been made. The sum of the rules which go to make law is a unity; it is a unity which is also a. growth; it is a growth which is also something distinguishable from a mere natural product, being in fact an expression of human intelligence and design — " a growth directed ly conscious fore- sight." (1) Law a 632. (1) Law is a wnity. — Particular rules of law cannot unity. be interpreted as if they were detachable fragments of an atomic or mechanical whole. To explaiti their meaning we must regard them alongside of other rules of law which qualify or extend their scope and regulate their enforcement. In the last analysis, every rule of law takes its meaning from the totality of law, and legal science should aim at giving to > " Jurisprudence," ed. 9, p. 40. POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 347 the student such an appreciation of that totality as will enable him to realize the inner significance of particular rules. 633. (2) Law is a growth. — The truth must be interpreted (2) Law a in a sense deeper than that understood by Austin. " The ^° ' Constitution," he wrote, " has grown. ... I intend to inti- mate by the phrase that the constitution of the supreme government has not been determined at once, or agreeably to a scheme or plan: that positive moral rules of successive generations of the community (and, perhaps, positive laws made by its successive sovereigns) have determined the con- stitution, with more or less of exactness, slowly and unsystem- atically." Growth, in other words, implies no more than slow and unsystematic manufacture. To the student of to- day, the inadequacy of such a purely negative conception of growth will be apparent. We may patch a cloak, we may add to it or alter it, but we cannot make it grow; the patches, additions, alterations remain the same in essence; they enter into no vital relation with that to which they become related. Quite different is the case of change in law. Existing rules of law change in their meaning from age to age by slow, insensible processes, and additions or alterations of the law are no mere patchwork. The most despotic of legislators cannot think or act without availing himself of the spirit of his race and time. His most despotic laws reveal the influence and potency of that spirit. When they are once promulgated they have to be interpreted and administered ; in the process of interpretation and adminis- tration, the spirit of the legal system as a whole will reassert itself at every stage ; between the rule and the legal system vital relations become established ; and if we are to describe the change in the legal system we must call it a growth, not' in the mechanical sense conceived by Austin, but in the Uving sense in which we employ the term when describing 348 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND the developmental processes which are characteristic of organic nature. Import- 634. The fact that law has grown is a commonplace of ance of vehich the importance is seldom realized. Some general idea history, of this importance may be gained by reflecting for a moment upon the revolution effected in the nineteenth century, in the world of thought in general, by the discovery that what has grown needs to be studied in relation to the processes of its development. The historical spirit of inquiry achieved its supreme triumphs in natural science, but invaded many domains and assumed various forms. It reformed theology, revolutionized philology, and created sociology. When in literary criticism Sainte-Beuve laid down that each literary work was a mental result which could only be understood after a study of the character, ancestry, race, country, and intellectual, moral, and social surroundings of the individual who produced it, he was but once more illustrating the modern belief that a product cannot be fully understood apart from the factors, an effect apart from the cause, the present apart from the past. The same belief has invaded the domain of law. Here too we have learnt that the present is an out- come of compromises which the past alone can explain ; that if we are to tfhderstand law, we must study the processes of its development as well as the forms in which it expresses itself to-day. To Savigny belongs the honour of establishing the profound truth of this view by the irresistible logic of example. In his epoch-making treatise on Possession, he showed how much of the later Koman law is unintelligible without the aid which historical inquiry affords. In our own day, happily, we need not go to German texts to learn the power of the new method. In various treatises on the modern law, we are enabled to see how closely the origin and history of legal rules bears upon their meaning for the modern lawyer. In the great work of Pollock and Maitland POStTIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 349 we may experience, in the studies of our early law, the revelation of a new meaning in our whole legal system. 635. (3) Finally, the law which is at once a unity and a (S) Law't growth, is moreover a growth of a special kind, since it is P^n'os*. directed and guided by the forethought of man in view of purposes deemed to be good. If legal development is a process which must be described according to the categories of growth rather than those of manufacture, this growth is not the outcome of blind forces, but is in a large and ever increasing measure the expression of human initiative and design. The fact, though more obvious where legal develop- ment takes, place through acts of formal legislation, is easily discernible in the sphere of customary law. A usage may grow imperceptibly ; it takes its origin in the thought of men conscious of an end to be attained. The process is aptly compared by Ihering to the formation of a path through a virgin forest. The path was not created by the obscure instinct of the masses, but by the conscious will of the pioneers after whom the crowd followed.^ And the trans- formation of usage into law has demanded the reflective action of judges and lawyers, under whatever title they may be recognized in the different stages of social evolution, who have assisted in the work of selection, formulation, and de- finition. " The pretended obscure forces of nature," declares M. Lambert, " which are alleged to play with regard to the elaboration of custom the role which is played as regards statute law by human reason, are only the resultant of all the initiatives, all the efforts of reflection and invention, of the mental energies of innumerable practitioners who stimu- late and direct the development of our legal thought."^ 636. I wish to dwell for a moment upon the purposive Import- element in law, because I hold strongly that no science of recogniz- ing > " Histoire du droit." ' " Etudes du Droit commun et l^gislatif J' 350 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND puTpoBive law can be adequate which ignores the ends which law elem law. e emen in sgj.ygg_ jf ja^,/ is an imposition from above, it is also a rule of existence which the State has indicated as a means by which varying interests and opinions may be reconciled, con- flicts avoided, and the general well-being promoted. While the conception of law as a growth should save us from the common fallacy of supposing that law is the creature of an individual ruler dispassionately calculating, in a more or less detached or Machiavellian manner, the best means for pro- moting any particular ends he may have in view, the con- ception of law as realizing a purpose should guard us against the opposite fallacy of looking upon legal development as the spontaneous outcome of a national instinct which con- structs a system "as bees construct honeycomb without undergoing the degradation of knowing what they are doing." To regard the legislator as acting independently of the popular mind is one fallacy ; to regard his work as the unreflecting expression of that mind is another fallacy. The legislator may be looked upon as the organ of the national will ; but if so, then as an organ which not merely expresses the national will, but to some degree, and within certain limits, thinks for it. While one school of law has exaggerated the conscious element in legal evolution, another school has exaggerated the unconscious element. A complete theory of law must embrace both. Resulting 637. If the preceding argument is sound, a just conception conception ^f ig^^ implies the recognition of the elements of unity, of as an growth, and of growth consciously directed in view of an organism, end to be gained. If we wish our definition of law to express these elements, we may borrow from the thought of our time the conception of the organism. The concep- tion, originally suggested by biological analogies, has proved widely useful in the sciences concerned with human nature. Most students are familiar with the use which has been POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 351 made of the conception in the sphere of Political Philo- sophy, where men have turned from atomistic or mechanical theories of the State to the theory of it as a living whole.^ The conception will be found not less useful as an instru- ment of thought in the work of defining law. It resumes, sufi&ciently for the purpose of a definition, the elements upon the importance of which I have been insisting. In describing the totality of the law as an organism we imply at once that it is a unity, a growth, and a growth which must be studied from the point of view of function as well as from that of structure. We imply that the rules of which it is constituted are not related to it as a part of a machine to the whole machine, or as a single stone to a heap of stones, but as part of a living plant to the whole plant. We imply, i.e., that the relationship is intrinsic, not extrinsic, that into each rule of law the spirit of the whole law enters. We imply also that changes in the law are not comparable with the additions of coins to a heap of coins, or the modifications of a mechanism, however elaborate, but to the growth of an organic nature — a growth involving a constant adaptation of the new to the nature of the old. finally, we imply that law, like every other organism, must be regarded from the point of view of function as well as from that of structure — from the point of view of physiology as well as that of anatomy. 638, The conception of law as an organism has been already Ihering's suggested by learned authors, among others by Ihering in [^^"'^ ° his great work on Eoman Law. As that work is little read in England, I will venture to present a brief outline of Iheriog's doctrine so far as it relates to the subject immedi- ately under consideration.'' The author begins by remarking that the recognized rules of law are but the aspects which ' Of. supra, Excursus B. » Of. " Esprit du droit romain," I, 27, 50. 352 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND the observer realizes on a first view. They convey no adequate idea of the law, since even in the case of a system which has been expounded by lawyers of the greatest genius, a distinction is certain to exist between rules of law which are expressed and those which are latent. The latter may be applied by lawyers who have no consciousness of them, just as a man may observe rules of grammar which his mind has never expressly formulated. So a primitive code of law is no more than a few fragments of a vast unrealized whole. Even when men come to recognize the rule of law which they have once unconsciously applied, they experience the greatest difficulty in giving to it an adequate expression. As that expression is never quite perfect, a divorce between the real law and the formulated law is inevitable. If men would understand the nature of the real law, they must pass from the group of particular rules of law which establish the juridic form of a specific relation of life, to other related groups of legal rules, until they reach the systematic unities of which those rules are but an expression. For example, they must pass from the conception of the contract of sale to that of contract,, and again to that of obligation. Legal rules, legal relations, and legal institutions are thus but successive stages in a series of generalizations by means of which the lawyer passes from the formulated law to the real law. An infinite multiplicity of legal rules, which to the layman may seem the natural destination of a legal system, must appear to the lawyer an evidence of feeble digestive power on the part of those who are concerned in its administration. If we carry the process of analysis one step further, we discover at every epoch in the history of a legal system the existence of certain dominating influences — the time-spirit of a people. Law, far from being a mere aggregate of legal institutions, possesses a unity and an individuality related to appearances POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND 353 as the soul to the body. To reveal this psychic element in the law is the supreme triumph of legal science. It is a triumph which implies vater alia the fact that in law, as in other organisms, we need to know the function if we would comprehend the organ. Nothing exists in law, save through, and in view of, the end. How important is this truth we may appreciate when we reflect that a legal system may be perfect as a work of art and yet useless as a social force; or by reflecting that the excessive attention to the anatomic structure of law tells for legal classifications in which the inner meaning of rules is sacrificed to their form.i Or yet again, by reflecting how treatises on the history of Eoman Law, by regarding solely the history of the dogmatic content of the law without reference to the actual conditions of existence at the different periods has often ended in presenting to the student a mere carica- ture of the reality. In the opinion of Ihering, the history of Eoman Law would have made greater progress if it had received more attention from the historian by profession, "J'ai fait de bonne heure cette experience avec la courte esquisse de I'histoire du droit romain qui se trouve au chapitre XLIV. de Gibbon. J'ai ^t^ cependant quelque temps avant de me rendre compte du motif pour laquelle elle eiergait sur moi une attraction infiniment sup6rieure k celle que les travaux bien plus ^tendus, publics jusqu'alors par les jurisconsultes, avaient produite sur mon esprit. Gibbon est le premier qui ait offert k mes yeux un tout, tr^s concis il est vrai, mais concordant et plein de vie, tandis cpe je n'ai trouv4 dans tons les autres auteurs que des lambeaux et des fragments de regies, de lois, etc."^ ' I presume that a classification of English Law which would treat the right in personam of a cestui que trust as part of the law of obliga- tion rather than of property would be regarded by Ihering as an illustration of this error. ^ " Esprit du droit romain," I, 57 n. 2 A 354 POSITIVE LAW AS STATE COMMAND The deB- 639. If the general argument of the present excursus be mtion of gQmi^ a, science of law should venture a definition of law in aw. its totality. That definition should recognize the imperative element in law, and also certain other elements which found little or no expression in Austinian analysis. In accordance with this view, I hold that it is not wholly relevant to ask whether law is will or command or reason, since it is all three. It is an expression of the general will, affirming an order which will be enforced by the organized might of the State, and directed to the realization of some real or imagined good. Medieval schoolmen might argue that the essence of the Law of Nature was reason, and " that there would be a Law of Nature discoverable by human reason and absolutely binding, even if there were no God." ^ Such a dictum can- not be extended to positive law. If there were no organized State to enforce rules of conduct, there would be no such thing as positive law, though there might be a something which was on the way to become positive law, if the commu- nity in which such rules were observed might be said to be on its way to becoming a State. Law, as the term must be interpreted in legal science, is the organic totality of the rules relating to external human action, together with the associated systems of rights and duties which those rules imply, affirmed by the State through official organs, main- tained by the organized power of the State, and applied by the Courts of the State in the discharge of their judicial functions. 1 Gierke : "Political Theories of the Middle Age," p. 174. EXCURSUS F THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 640. Law has been described as an organic totality of the The rules of external human action, and of the associated system "°"""° of rights and obligations which those rules imply. This science, totality may be studied with special reference, either to par- ticular rules, rights and duties, or to underlying principles, fundamental conceptions and historical causes. In the former case, we may be interested ei|ther in a present content (legal exposition), or in the past development of that content (leg^l history). In the latter case, we enter the domain of legal science. 641. The distinction between law as a body of rules and Principle law as a body of principles cannot be drawn with absolute °'°'* "^*" precision. An author of a text-book on the Law of Con- tracts, for example, is inevitably impelled at times to deal. with fundamentals, in the mere endeavour to state adequately and clearly the rules of his subject. Nay, every law student who seeks to find the general in the particular is so fax a scientist. Every judgment of a court which directly assists him in doing so, is a contribution to legal science. This does not mean, however, that legal science has no existence apart from legal exposition or legal history. " I take my jurispru- dence," I have heard one student say, "from the Law Eeports." The , statement suggests courage rather than wisdom. The judgments of the Law Courts are delivered in the consciousness that they may become precedents for future casea As a result, they are expressed in terms which 355 356 THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW limit their significance to particular rules. The judges rarely venture into that region of the more general and the more abstract with which the student of legal science is concerned. The student; on the other hand, while he is not restrained by the terrifying fear which limits the word, if not the thought, of the judge, has perhaps other reasons for refusing to venture where the judge has feared to tread. While, throughout his course, he is largely engaged in turning the materials of the Law Keports into scientific form, he can only hope to gain a science of the whole law by this process if he be gifted with an extraordinary industry and a still more extraordinary insight. The 642. Legal science, then, is concerned with principles, sciences of conceptions, and causes. It has many branches. It may refer to the causes of legal development, to the principles underlying an existing system, to the principles underlying several systems, or to the principles of an ideal system. The term legal science should embrace all of these, although some authors, in a perhaps excusable zeal for the special science in which they are most interested, would limit the expression to that science and deny it to all others. In the present excursus I propose to distinguish between the several sciences, and to refer briefly to their value for the purposes which a student of law may be supposed to have in view. Natural 643. Legal science, as the science of the principles under- law. lying an ideal system of law, has been discussed by a great variety of authors who may be divided into two classes according to the degree in which they have displayed an in- clination for metaphysics, Lorimer may be taken as a type of the one ; Bentham of the other. The former is the more philosophic; the latter the more practical. The one pro- fessed a theory of Natural Law ; the other a theory of Legis- lation. The theorists of Natural Law attempted to construct, by a priori methods, an ideal law of which existing systems THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 357 were conceived to be very imperfect anticipations. The practical and scientific demerits of the school were closely connected, and have long been commonplaces. ^ Practically^ the school threw little light upon the nature of existing law ; and the result was largely due to a disposition to build up an ideal system in reliance upon the processes of abstract reason- ing from the data of man's social nature, without due regard to the revelation of that nature in history and in existing legal systems. Such a school might afford scope for philo- sophic genius, but must appear remote from practice. It might help to foretell a remote future ; it could not interpret the present. Partly owing to the character of Jhe English ''temperament, and partly owing to the bias which certain historical conditions imparted to early attempts at legal philosophy in England, the school has exercised a compara- tively slight influence upon English thought. It has indeed become a byword for the unreal and the fanciful. Its funda- mental merit consisted in its appreciation of the importance of the end of law as a subject of juristic inquiry ; its funda- mental demerit in its determination of that end by a priori analysis. The school serves to recall the luminous censure in the "Advancement of Learning" : "As for the philosophers, they make imaginary laws for imaginary commonwealths, and their discourses are as the stars, which give little light because they are so high." ^ 644. The methods of English jurists, even when they have The been idealists, have been more nearly a posteriori. Thus ^^^°^ "' legisla- Bentham, although nominally guided by reference to abstract tion. considerations of the greatest happiness of the greatest number, was mainly guided in his conceptions of the ends of law, and of the means for attaining those ends, by observation of concrete systems. As a consequence, his ideal civil and ' Book I, p. 266. 358 THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW penal code, while it contains much that is highly suggestive to the legislator, serves also to reveal incidentally the true purpose and meaning of existing rules. A law student who reads the famous "Principles of Legislation" will scarcely fail to gain a new insight into the meaning of the actual system which he is to interpret and apply. Historical 645. The student of legal science who openly and avowedly Jnrispru- leaves the world of the ideal for the world of the actual, may seek for the material of his science either in Itegal history or in legal exposition. In the former case, he aims at achieving a theory of legal development. His object is, not to formu- late a Natural Law, but to discover natural laws.^ His science might be called Historical Jurisprudence. I have referred, in a previous excursus, to the value of legal history. I shall endeavour to explain here what I conceive to be the distinction between that subject and Historical Jurisprudence. Legal history affects to describe the actual development of the law as it has been at the different periods of the national history. Historical Jurisprudence should state, as far as may be, the moral, social, and economic causes which account for that development. The one answers the question how? the other seeks to find some answer to the question why? The one describes legal development ; the other explains it. The one regaTds the development of the law more or less in isolation ; the other is compelled to bring that development into relation with the general progress of the national life. Finally, while both legal history and Historical Jurisprudence help to explain existing law, the light afforded by the former is pri- marily the result of showing how particular rules or institu- tions have come to be what they are, whilst the light afforded by the latter is rather the result of an added insight gained Cf. supra, § 188™, " The Law of Nature." THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 359 from a broad view of the development of the legal system as a whole. 646. T3ie value of Historical Jurisprudence to the law Ita value student will be universally admitted. Unhappily, the sub- '? j?*^ ject exists in imagination rather than in fact. So far as Anglo-Saxon Law is concerned, we even lack a complete legal history. Although invaluable contributions towards such a history have been made, and although those contribu- tions have been occasionally marked by a sense of causation, Historical Jurisprudence is still for us a dream of far-off things, a vision of a future that may be, more to be valued as an inspiration in the study of legal history, than as a source of positive information or as a special science of the law. 647. If the material of our science be legal exposition Compara- rather than legal history, if we are in search of a theory of *i^« J"™" o •" •' prudence. modem law rather than a theory of legal development, we are at once confronted by a very debatable question which may be expressed as follows : Ought a theory of modern law to be based on the analysis of one legal system, or on the analysis of several ? Austin, while he distinguishes between Particular and General or Comparative Jurisprudence, is clearly persuaded of the superiority of the latter. But the term Comparative Jurisprudence may be used in at least three distinct senses. In the first sense, the term may indicate a study of which the avowed object is to discover a law common to various nations — a body of legal rules which are alleged to exist in a number of different civilized com- munities and which, by virtue of ^his existence, are assumed to possess a permanent value. The idea is that of a Jus gentivm, as that term has been frequently interpreted. Such a system of rules suggests an obvious parallelism to the Law of Nature of a priori philosophy. There are, liowever, two important differences. A jus gentivm postu- 360 THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW lates neither immutability nor universality. It may grow with the growth of the different national systems from which it is drawn ; and for the test of universality, it sub- stitutes that of generality. In a second sense, Comparative Jurisprudence may be identified with the General Juris prudence of Austin, i.e. as the science of the notions, prin- ciples, and distinctions common to the various systems. This is also the sense of the term Jurisprudence as defined by Professor Holland: "Jurisprudence is not the material science of those portions of the law which various nations have in common, but the formal science of those relations of mankind which are generally recognized as having legal consequences."^ In a third sense. Comparative Jurispru- dence may indicate, not a science of the law in general, but any investigation of a particular legal topic which attempts to show how that topic is dealt with in two or more legal systems. The object of such an investigation may be to discover hints for the reform of law or for the interpreta- tion of law. In the latter case, the particular solutions which are offered by different systems of particular groups of facts are examined together, and their pyecise relation discussed. In the former case, the further attempt is made to consider the relative merits of the solutions suggested by different systems with the object of discovering that which is most adapted to serve the purposes of a particular milieu. Value of 648. What is the value, to the law student, of Compara- Compara- ^-^^ Jurisprudence in either of the senses suggested ? Aa a prudence: Jus Gentiwm, Comparative Jurisprudence is a subject of (1) as Jus speculative rather than practical interest. Even its possi- Geniiutn / bility might be challenged on the ground that the rules of law as formulated in different systems are solutions of particular combinatiops of fact largely determined by the ' Jurisprudence," 9th ed., p. 8. THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 361 circumstances of a particular milieu, and distorted when considered abstractly apart from that milieu. Even if this objection should be considered inconclusive, the subject is a highly controversial one. Unless the jus gentium is to be the mere result of arithmetical processes, the existence of a particular rule in several systems is only one of the circum- stances to be taken into consideration in deciding whether it shall be included in the system induced. Among the solutions of particular problems afforded by the different systems, an investigator must make allowance for considera- tions of quality as well as of quantity ; he must examine the claims of a rule less commonly adopted (as opposed to the claims of a rule more commonly adopted) on the grounds of the alleged superiority, either of the rule itself, or of the systems from which it is drawn. 649. The merits of Comparative Jurisprudence in the (2) as sense of an investigation of some legal topic as developed in ^ ™^^j two or more systems, is a subject with regard to which there of a special exists a strange divorce between modern profession and snbjeBt of modern practice. While it is eulogized by educational theorists, it receives little or no attention in existing schemes of legal education. Even those schemes which prescribe the study of a foreign law do not appear to contemplate that the study shall be genuinely comparative, either with regard to the whole or a part. In England, for example, although Eoman Law is often treated with much thoroughness, it is generally half forgotten before the study of English Law is begun. Learned authors and law teachers may employ the comparative method in the study; it is seldom heard of in the class-room, or seriously practised by the student. If we turn from the schools to the forum, scepticism is more avowed and even ventures to deny the value of the method from any point of view but that of the legislator. " A lawyer," it is urged, " does not know his own 362 _ THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW law better for wasting his time on some one else's. Possession of property in Eoman law under certain conditions confers certain rights. The fact is interesting, but not specially helpful, to the student of a system in which possession con- fers other rights under other conditions. The student must know his own law. The knowledge of other laws may be left to legislators who are in search of the ideal." Value of 650. Despite educational practice and professional plausi- 8UC s y ijiiitigg^ tlie value of a comparative study of a topic of law in tained. two or more systems can be demonstrated by arguments of a most elementary and conclusive character. In law, as else- where, an account of the resemblances and differences be- tween two objects is a useful way to bring out their true meaning. Whoever has not made the acquaintance of a foreign language, said Goethe, knows not the first word of his mother tongue. While no one would pretend to apply this dictum within the sphere of law, and declare that a law student who is ignorant of other systems knows nothing of his own, the thought within the speech of Goethe has never- theless a real meaning for the student of law, as well as for the student of language. Any one who reads the masterly analysis of Possession by Chief Justice Holmes in his work on the Common Law — an analysis in which the Eoman theory of possession is contrasted with the English — cannot fail to make a real advance in the direction of understand- ing both Eoman and English law. For it is one of those commonplaces of the truth of which a student needs to be constantly reminded, that the knowledge of a subject of law implies much more than an acquaintance with the mere rules of law which constitute it. Behind the rules which go to the making of our law of Possession, for example, is the conception of Possession itself, which is something distinct from particular rules — something which must be compre- hended before those rules can be rightly interpreted^some- THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 363 thing which it is within the power of comparative analysis to illumine. Comparative study puts new life into the legal formulae with which the student will have to deal in every- day life, and thus gives to him a power of vision which must prove of the highest value when he is called upon to deal with new combinations of facts which have not hitherto been made the subject of legislative or judicial interpreta- tion. The argument, both from this point of view and from that of educational discipline, was forcibly expressed by a late Lord Chief Justice. " I have heard many men say, and so far as my opinion is worth anything it is true, that an acquaintance with the Code Napoleon, which is to a great extent founded on Eoman law, and a different system from our own, was of great advantage to him (Mr. Benjamin) ; not only was it of great advantage to him in actual prac- tical argument, because it gave a breadth, and grace, and facility of illustration which might have been wanting otherwise, but it gave him a grasp of larger, wider, more general principles." ^ 651. How then are we to explain the divorce between Sceptism modern profession and modern practice to which allusion""*^'® 11! aiDjeot has been made ? If comparative analysis is capable of expiainei serving purposes so useful, why has so little use been made of that analysis in legal studies ? One obvious answer may be found in the lack of treatises in which this method has been employed with any degree of success. It was at one time imagined that magical results must foUow from a merely tabular arrangement of the legal rules of two or more systems in parallel columns. Hence a faith in the saving power of such works as that of Mackenzie on Eoman Law. Comparative analysis only begins to be useful, either as an intellectual discipline or as a source of information. ' Report of the Gresham University Commission, 1894, p. 1006. 364 THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW when the rules of different systems are brought into close and intimate relationship, and the precise differences in their scope and meaning stated and illustrated. How to 652. Fortunately for the student of law, the lack of ' treatises is no conclusive argument against the inclusion of Comparative Jurisprudence, in the sense immediately under consideration, within the general scheme of his law studies. Por, within modest limits, and by the aid of a little guid- ance from a more experienced hand, he may construct a treatise for himself. He has but to study some special subject, such, for example, as the Law of Sale in Eoman and English law, and then, instead of resting content with a superficial enumeration of resemblances and differences, honestly seek to discover how the two systems actually deal with particular combinations of fact. He need not take the trouble to state such combinations for himself, for he will find them already suggested in Ihering's work on "Law in Daily Life," which has been translated into EngKsh by Pro- fessor Goudy. If he will conscientiously deal with the practical problems suggested in this most admirable work, not only will the Eoman and English Law of Sale be incom- parably more real to him, but he will also have gained a priceless experience in the art of bringing concrete groups of facts and legal principles or rules into living relationship. (3) General 653. In neither of the senses just indicated, however, can jurispru- Comparative Jurisprudence claim to be a Science of Law in the con- *^^ sense in which that science is most needed by the law ception student. What, then, can be said of Comparative Juris- ™j '^ " prudence as the science of the principles, notions, and dis- tinctions common to maturer systems? Apparently not much, unless I have sadly misread some of the lessons the historical school has taught. A system of law is the re- sultant of many forces, of the particular social and economic conditions, of the character and history of a people. It is a THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 365 concrete expression of man's endeavour to realize the useful and the just under the conditions of a particular environ- ment. It varies according to circumstances of time and race. The legal rules of one country are not those of another. But the legal principles which it is the special mission of legal science to state, illumine and develop, are derived from legal rules. If those rules differ in different nationalities, it is difficult to see how the principles can be identical or common. When we have eliminated all differ- ences, the residuum is unlikely to be of much service for explaining or illuminating any of the particular systems which have been made the subject of analysis. The ethos, the spirit of each, has escaped us. "The revived study of Germanic law in Germany, which was just beginning in Austin's day," writes Professor Maitland, "seems to be showing that the scheme of Eoman jurisprudence is not the scheme into which English law will run without distortion."^ An 654. The conception of a General Jurisprudence appears ™P]'*^ ■^ 7 . eonfusion. to me to imply a confusion between a question of intellectual equipment and a quite distinct question of scientific method. Just as an author who wishes to give some intelligible account of the soul of a people will do well, before under- taking his task, to travel widely both in space and in literature, to reflect on the nature of several races before expounding the character of one, so an author who would express the essence of a particular system of law will do well to begin by availing himself of the discipline implied in the study of a foreign system. In either case, the object is to obtain a breadth of view, a sense of perspective, rather than to discover positive material on which to base the treatment of the subject. The practically minded law student cares little to know that certain principles of his > "Encyclopaedia Britannica," XXVII, 253. 366 THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW own system, or something like them, may exist elsewhere. He is interested, not in the universality of a principle, but in the reality of that principle as a representation of rules actually existing in his own system. Conversely, he is not less interested in a principle which possesses this reality, because it happens to be peculiar rather than general. Prestige of 655. Such considerations appear so obvious that one is at General ^^ j^gg ^^ explain why they should have been ignored, until dence ex- one remembers that juristic thought has been slow to plained by emancipate itself from the tyranny of a theory of Natural theory of Law. That theory could not long survive the progress of a law of historical methods of inquiry. But investigators were more ready to admit the formal supremacy of such methods than to accept all the consequences of the admission. Hence the disposition to cling to the old fiction of universality in the modified form of generality. The difficulties of this inter- mediate position are illustrated by a particular concession to the historical school which exponents of General Juris- prudence have been impelled to make. "Jurisprudence," declares Professor Holland, "is a progressive science. Its generalizations must keep pace with the movement of systems of actual law." To which Mr. Buckland has made the very natural rejoinder, "This admission is somewhat startling. A writer on the Jurisprudence of a single nation might make it readily enough. But what is likely to be the fate of a principle found in the law of, say, ten states which go on developing on different lines ? The probabilities are against its continuance as a general principle. And the notion that some other general principle will arise to take its place appears to be rather an article of faith than a proposition on which a science can be based." ^ ' Lam Qwwrterhj Beview, XXIV, 444, article on " The Difficulties of Abstract Jurisprudence." THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 367 656. Happily for the law student, existing treatises on (S) Inoon- General Jurisprudence reveal a practice which is in advance ™*®°"'"* of profession. The profession of such treatises might lead fession and us to suppose that their authors had laboriously constructed P™"*'**- a table of the legal principles existing in different legal systems, and had then selected the principles most generally recognized without any regard to their relative importance under particular conditions. There is little reason to suppose that either Austin or Professor Holland constructed their admirable works on such lines. Comparative analysis has served the purposes of illustration rather than formed the basis of their science. 657. In discussing the terms Historical Jurisprudence Oompar- and Comparative Jurisprudence, I have made no reference l^^'^i to the fact that the primary method in either of these Juris- sciences may be used as an accessory method in the other. P™*^*""'*- Comparative Jurisprudence may involve much historical investigation before we can be quite sure of the nature of the objects we compare; Historical Jurisprudence, while it might be based upon the study of materials derived ex- clusively from the history of a particular country, is more likely to have a permanent value if it takes note of parallel developments elsewhere. "EngUsh land law," writes Sir F. Pollock, "cannot be understood at all without a great deal of historical explanation ; it cannot be understood very well without learning how peculiar the English history of land tenure was from the Norman Conquest onwards — in other words, without comparing the divergent fortunes of English and Continental Feudalism."^ But the facts that a work on Comparative Jurisprudence may occaaionally employ the historical method, or that a ,work on Historical ' Journal of CoMparaUme Legislation, N.S., XI, 78, article on " The History of Comparative Jurisprudence." 368 THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW Jurisprudence may occasionally resort to comparative analysis for the purposes of illustration or correction, is no justification for confusing the two sciences. The object of Historical Jurisprudence is to trace development; that of Comparative Jurisprudence is to compare two subjects at some particular stage of their development. It would be possible, however, to combine both historical and comparative methods in such a way as to present a comparative theory of legal development. "By the help of God," declared Leibnitz, " I will some day compile a complete panorama of the law wherein shall be arranged in parallel columns the laws of all nations, of all countries, and of all ages." Such a panorama may be conceived as the material of a science which should examine the origin and development of law uader various conditions of race and clime. With respect to the possibilities of such a science, Mr. Bryce remarks, "It is a weak point in the historical method as ap- plied to the science or philosophy of law that it is more appUcable to the law of any particular country than to the theory of law in general, for the details of legal history vary so much in different countries that immense know- ledge and unusual architectonic power are needed to combine their general results for the purposes of a comprehensive theory." ^ 658. We have thus arrived at a classification of the legal sciences : 1 " Studies in History and Jurisprudence," II, 186. THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 369 /regarded aa a body of rules Law rwith reference to a present content I with reference to their past I develgpment 'to discover an ideal code to explain legal de- velopment reg»rded as the subject-matter I to compare different | of a Science \ systems as a which purpoi» | means of dis- ' covering tc investigate a par- ticular topic of the law in seyeral systems to state the fun- damental prin- ciples of a \ particular system Legal exposition Legal history. ' by a priori or \ Natural Law. mixed o priori I and a poster- f , iori process J Theory of Legislation, in one milieu Historical Jurisprudence. in several Comparative Historical Jurisprudence, a Jiis OerUium ■\ a General Jurisprudence Comparative Jurisprudence. Particular or National Jurisprudence. 659, The borderland between the sciences indicated cannot Varying be drawn with logical precision. In the nature of things, ^*.'°^ °' there must be much overlapping. The relationship between to law the sciences is one of co-operation, not of conflict. Each student, must borrow from others conceptions which it does not itself establish. All alike serve the great practical purpose of giving new life and meaning to existing rule. Man is a dull creature in whose hands the rule is apt to become inert. So, aspiring to bring life and meaning to rule, aspiring to adapt rules to an ever-changing social and economic milieu, he now summons to his aid the evidences of the past, now turns to the study of a foreign system, or concentrates his scrutinizing 2 B 370 THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW glance upon the sacred texts of his own — everywhere justified by the hope that he may succeed in seeing beneath externals to the innermost meaning of tl>3 law by which he lives. But whilst all the legal sciences in some degree contribute to this ultimate purpose, they do so with varying degrees of success. They have accordingly a varying value for the practically minded student. The science of which that student is most in need, appears to me to be Particular or National Juris- prudence. The historical and comparative investigations which have contributed to this science only concern him in- directly. The special purposes of the science, and the means by which those purposes may be served, are subjects to which I propose to devote the remainder of the present excursus. National 660. At the outset we must distinguish, more carefully Jurispru- jiian has been usually done, between the needs of two classes element- "f students — those who have yet to begin their legal studies, ary law. and those who have already made considerable progress in them. A student of the former class demands a treatise on elementary law rather than on National Jurisprudence. He needs a general description of the land he is about to explore in order that he may obtain some general impressions to which his own experience is hereafter to give a meaning and content. He needs, in short, an elementary outline of his system, with just sufiBcient in the nature of detailed illus- tration to make that outline intelligible. Nor, if be be wise, will he despise a foreword vas to ways and means of study. 'The use of law books and the appreciation of legal authori- ties," says Sir F. Pollock, " can be fully learned only by as- siduous practice ; but here, again, it has long seemed to me that something can be done to lighten the first steps of the beginner."^ A.rtistic ^^^- Naticpal Jurisprudence eiffeots more ambitious pur- purposes of poses than that of providing the student with a general National * " A First Book on Jurisprudence," p. 8. THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 371 introduction to legal studies. The nature of those purposes Juris- may be distinguished as artistic or practical. The artistic P™"^®""* purpose is to meet the demand, which must be felt more or less consciously by every student worthy of the name, to realize the unity of his subject and the harmony which per- vades it. In the study of the law, as in all great study, there is implied on the part of the student some sense of beauty, some love of truth for its own sake, some will to discover under an infinite variety, the unity which gives distinction and charm to every work of art. 662. What practical purposes are served by a National Practioal Jurisprudence ? Obviously, a student who has once realized P'"P°°"" that the rules of law are portions of an ordered system will more easily remember, and more readily apply, those rules. It is a more important if less obvious fact, that such a realiza- tion implies an added insight into the meaning of rules. In realizing the nature of law, we acquire a new power of inter- preting laws. In appreciating our subject-matter as a whole, we gain a knowledge which enables us to press down to greater depths the comprehension of the rules and principles which we have previously formulated. ■ 663. The means for realizing the artistic and practical Means for purposes of National Jurisprudence are not always the same. *''*^.'^ '"**'■ Juridic art is concerned with the form of law ; it implies an analysis of legal principle and a theory of leg£!,l classification. Practical Jurisprudence, on the other hand, concerned with meaning rather than form, implies in addition to such an analysis some account of what law stands for in the general scheme of things, and supremely a theory of the ends which law serves. " I must confess to a certain feeling,'' writes Lightfoot, " that law is meant to serve the interests of the people, and that no treatment of it can be called scientific which does not show how it contributes to this end. ... As long as we take our distinctions solely from English law and of law. 372 THE SCIENCES OP STATE LAW explain them merely by history, we do not enter upon science, for the distinctions and principles may he merely accidental, and the historical reasons may have no reference to utility. If, however, we were to show that these dis- tinctions and principles have a real basis in the wants of the people, we should then treat the law scientifically, and we should work out the Particular Jurisprudence of the country." ' The ends 664. Two ways of regarding the ends which law serves have alike a sound justification in fact. The one we may call the economic, the other the ethical. According to the economic view, the purpose of law may be expressed as the discovery of the conditions under which man adapts himself to his environment in so far as those conditions are main- tainable by the organized force of a political society ; the predominant and determining factor in the development of law must be sought in man's constant endeavour to respond to the pressure of economic facts, to discover some way of realizing his will to live ; laws, in a word, are what economic necessities have made them. According to the ethical view, the purpose of law is to realize man's idea of the just. Although what is just may be difficult for him to determine, yet to know the just, and to do it, is his mission. "Whether justice be regarded as something divinely revealed to man ; or as something absolute, immutable, superior to contingencies of fact, and determinable by some a priori process of reason- ing ; or again, as something whose meaning and nature are being revealed in the long course of social evolution and so to be determined by the analysis of human experience — in either of these cases we are confronted by the fact of an ideal of justice to which it is held to be the mission of law to conform. "Justice is," said Carlyle, "whether I can define it or not." ' "The Nature pf Positive Law," p. 11. THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 373 665. The legal doctrine of our time has been more ready Import- to acknowledge the importance of the economic than of the """f °^ ethical view of the ends which law serves. This is, however, view of a mere reaction against older doctrine which should be ^*^' avoided. To think of man as solely impelled by economic or elementary social necessities, is suggestive of the view which holds him a mere creature of his environment. Man not only adapts himself to his environment, but he also adapts environment to himself. He seeks not merely to live, but to live in accord with some ideal of justice. The conditions in which he has to live are not alien influences affecting him as the storm affects a windmill ; they are the material out of which he fashions his life in accordance with ideals Which he has come to revere. As Vico said, with profound truth, interest and necessity are no more than the occasions which awake in men that consciousness of right which is the constitutive principle of social life.^ I believe that evidence as to the truth and the importance of this view of law may be found in a study of the lives of great lawyers. Most of the lawyers who have profoundly in- fluenced the course of legal interpretation in their generation however limited in some respects their intellectual outlook may have been, have yet been distinguished by a deep reverence for Justice. It has been said- of Papinian that if he was the prince of jurists it was because he knew better than any of his contemporaries how to subordinate law to morals. " He has no equal in the precision with which he states a case, elimioating all irrelevancies of fact, yet finding relevancies of humanity that would have escaped the vision of most." * 666. Whether, therefore, we dwell more on the economic Need for » or the ethical views of law, whether we regard it as primarily ^°™?"" — theory. • Flint, " Vico," p. 140. " Muirhead, " Roman Law," p. 324. 374 THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW a result of the pressure of elementary social and economic necessities, or as primarily a realization of man's idea of the just, we need not ignore the indisputable element of truth in the other view. A true juristic theory will, in fact, combine them. This implies a wider interpretation of law than has been hitherto deemed necessary. It is, however, an interpretation towards which the best thought of our time is tending. "I look forward," writes Chief Justice Holmes, "to the time when the part played by history in the explanation of dogma shall be very small, and when, instead of ingenious research, we shall spend our energy on a study of the ends sought to be obtained, and the reason for desiring them. The present divorce between schools of political economy and law seems to me an evidence of how much progress in philosophical study still remains to be made." Further confirmation may be found in the practice of the law schools of Prance, Germany, Bussia, Switzerland, Hungary, Greece, and Japan. "Les sciences politiques," said a Professor from Japan at a recent Congress, " sont I'apanage de la faculty de droit." " Les juristes," said Michel Soboleff at the same Congress, " doivent §tre bien au courant de cette science (Political Economy), parce que les normes juridiques touchent principalement les relations feonomiques varices, I'achat et la vente, le loyer, le fermage, la propri^t^, etc. Pour appliquer les normes (Ju droit, il est n&essaire de savoir et de comprendre la nature des relations vitales qu'elles r^glent." ^ Such a ^^'^' ^^ °^*y ^® inferred from what has been said, that theory the to see law Steadily and see it whole is a somewhat toilsome N ti °^l business. Sociology, ethics, politics, legislation, and political Juriapru- economy suggest a range of studies wliich is too wide to be denoB within the possibilities of a course of legal study. The law ' "Le Premier Congres de rEnseignement des Sciences Sociales," pp. 23, 26, 85, 86, 93, 121, 129. THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 375 student will say, " All this is too wonderful for me ; I cannot attain unto it." Probably he will be right. Here, as else- where, he may find it necessary to content himself with a compromise. National Jurisprudence should endeavour to aid him in achieving this compromise. Each of the sciences to which I have referred has its own special view of law. A National Jurisprudence cannot hope to rival those sciences within their own special sphere. Yet by their aid it may succeed in presenting such a view of law and of the funda- mental principles and conceptions of law as will enable the student to realize in his subject a new life and meaning, to get nearer that spirit which saves from the despotism of the letter. 668. I have stated at some length the practical purposes Prevalent which might be served by a National Jurisprudence. The scepticiam excuse for this statement might be found, if excuse were value of needed, in a prevalent scepticism which has been inherited ^'at'onal from times when the avowedly scientific treatment of law ^ence ex- disdained to serve the wants of practice. " All who plained. have written of laws," says Bacon, "have trea,ted that subject as philosophers or as lawyers. And the philosophers propound many things beautiful in speech but remote from use." Even in times more modern, when the scientific treatment of law has ceased to be a sort of Jurisprudence in the air, it has yet recognized its practical function very inadequately. The logic of law has dominated the spirit. Hence an excessive attention to such matters as the theory of legal classification — a subject of more interest to the writers of text-books than the students of law. We shall only conquer this despotism of the logic, we shall only learn how the practical purposes of National Jurisprudence can be effected, when we have realized the full significance of the fact that law is the resultant of innumerable social and economic forces, and cannot be adequately studied in 376 THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW isolation from those forces. Those forces are present at the making of law; they are no less obviously present in its application. "Before a law attains its ends through the processes of administration and interpretation," very justly observed Sheldon Amos, "it is directly qualified by every strong wave, and by all the multitudinous weaker waves of thought and feeling by which, for the time, the community is swayed." 1 Refuted : 669. Let any student, who is disposed to regard all this as toeipw-r ^^^ theory, reflect for a moment upon some of the more •noe. important economic facts of the nineteenth century— the multitudinous inventions of modern science, the rapid de- velopment of commerce, trade and industry, the vast aggrega- tions of modern capital, the power of the modem trade union. Let him further reflect upon the great humanitarian and democratic movement of the nineteenth century, which has transformed theology, has emancipated woman, has changed history from a record of dynasties into a story of peoples, and has taught art and literature to see and .express something of the sacredness of the mean and lowly. Let any student, who reflects upon these things, ask himself whether it is conceivable that they have not a profound significance for the lawyer as well as for the legislator. The Law Reports afford abundant evidence on this matter. Law is proverbially conservative ; yet it would need to be a thou- sand times more conservative than it is, if new economic facts and new social ideals did not re-shape it, modifying the letter or breathing into that letter a new spirit. The lawyer, who wishes to forecast the judicial interpretation of any problem that is not already covered by precise rule will be the more capable of doing so if he has learned to regard law, not as something existing in complete detachment 1 " The Science of Jurisprudence," p. 18. THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW 377 from life, or as a mere heau chef d'ceuvre de logigue, but rather as something which is being constantly re-shaped by the facts of life, the thought and aspiration of men. 670. Scepticism on this point has sometimes entrenched (*) The itself behind the authority of the great lawyers of Imperial 1'^^*'^°' Eome. " Consider the lilies how they grow," it is said in Eome. effect; "they toil not, neither do they spin. Yet Solomon in all his glory was not arrayed as one of these."' Eoman lawyers certainly managed very well without the help of any special science of the law. Yet I believe that a con- sideration of the reasons for the high reputation which the Eoman lawyers have so justly gained, will tend to confirm, rather than weaken, our confidence in the modern claim for a science of law. In the first place, the Eomans were men of great intellectual power, who were capable of doing without many aids which lesser men would be unwise to uef use. In the second place, they were indefatigable students. They had a profound knowledge of their legal system in all its inter-relation of principle and detail. The student of the Digest is astounded to discover how rarely the Eoman jurists erred in their application of legal rules to the most diflBcult and detailed groups of facts. Their solutions harmonize with one another, and with the system as a whole. Their per- ception of the right rule to be applied seems so unerring that we are tempted to think of them as divinely inspired, or as gifted with some infallible and inexplicable instinct. In reality, they decided well because they had studied much. In the third place, they were distinguished by an exceptional regard for Justice. Such a regard may be assumed from the mere position of the Eoman as an Imperial Eace. A nation may conquer other nations without having more than the merely military virtues ; it cannot hold them in subjection for long centuries without being itself distinguished for an ex- ceptionally keen sense of fair play — a sense which both the 378 THE SCIENCES OF STATE LAW Eoman and the Anglo-Saxon have possessed in a rare degree. Finally, though the Eomans had no formulated recognition of the purposes of a National Jurisprudence as we under- stand the term, there are abundant evidences that they realized those purposes in indirect ways. Most of them were men of varied culture and philosophical training. Ifo jurists as a class have ever realized more fully the impera- tive call of law to serve practical ends. "The Eoman jurists," writes Mr. Bryce, " reason and write as men who have been thoroughly trained, who have been imbued with a large and liberal view of law, who have philosophy and analysis and the sense of historical development equally at their command. They are endowed, in fact, with the quali- ties which, as we have been led to think, a course of the Theory or Science of Law ought to impart. How, then, did they acquire these qualities ? First, by the study of philo- sophy. Though our data scarcely justify a general state- ment, it seems probable that many of the jurists, especially such as grew up at Eome, received instruction in Greek philosophy. It has been suggested that not a few professed the doctrines of the Porch. Anyhow, the conception of Nature as a force or body of tendencies prompting and guiding the progress of law was familiar to them, and appears to have influenced their ideas. . . . The Eomans, though saying little about the broad aspects or so-called Philosophy of Law, do, in fact, pursue it in a philosophic spirit, and to this the excellence of their system is largely due."i • ' " Studies in History and Jurisprudence," II, 200-7. INDEX AOE Acts determined specifically . 14 — to explain positive laws . 23 Analogy, meaning of . ,31 Aristocracy, classification of . 120 — every supreme Government is an 118 Aristotle, diflfereutiation between legislative and judicial func- tions 132 Austin, analysis of sovereignty 281 — classification of fictitious or legal persons . . . 262 — criticism of semi-sovereign, . 139 — definition of legal right . 65 — „ law criticized . . 331 — division of commands . . 45 — ,, governmental powers 131 — general argument, review of 20 — law of nature . . .70 — limitation of sovereign power 158 — on declaratory and repealing statutes .... 334 — on political civil liberty . 176 — on rights of sovereignty, criticism of . . . 193 — on unconstitutional law . 167 — on use of tenns "liberty" and " right *^ . . .180 — test of general commands . 17 — view of command, unten- ability of . . . .342 Autonomic laws . . .46 Bacon, "law is nothing else than a commanding rule " . .19 Bentham, definition of sover- eignty .... 163 Blaokstone, distinction between law and a particular com- mand . . . .14 PAQE Blaokstone, on human laws . 71, 72, 74, 92 — definition of positive law . 92 Bodin, leges imperii . . . 161 Bosanquet, on civil liberty . 177 Boutmy „ ,, . . 179 Bryce, de jure and de facto . 234 — on judicial authority . . 301 — on legal theory and fiction . 306 — on obedience . . . 202 Burgess on sovereignty . . 163 Capito, Ateius, test of general commands . . . .18 CivU liberty . . . 177, 179 Clark, criticism of generality . 18 — definition of positive, proper, strictly so called . . 34 Coincidence and conflict of laws 66 Command analysed . . ,45 — correlative with duty . . 6 — general meaning of Austinian test 17 — inseparably connected with duty and sanction . . 10 — is a signification of desire . 5 — may amount to a law or rule 15, 40 — not the essence of law . . 341 Gockbum, usage the origin of law merchant , . . 307 Confederation, distinction be- tween, and federal state . 151 Contract, criticism of original theory .... 211 — theory of social . . . 227 Convention, main essentials of 220 — not present in origin of society 221 — no necessary connection with duty 226 Corporation, a, subject of rights 257 379 380 INDEX Corporation, definition of 256, 260 — early history of . . . 261 — in law a person . . . 257 — V. fictitious person . 262 — V. physical person . . 263 — V. state .... 267 Cnstomarylaw is imperative . 28 — laws not a, species of com- mands . . .27, 69 Customs, a persuasive source of law 314 — general .... 321 — particular . . . 315-18 — when they became law . 309 Declaratory acts, when not retro- spective in Great Britain , 23 — laws classed with laws meta- phorical . . . .95 Delegation of sovereign powers 124 Democracy, definition of . . 120 Deontology, science of 35, 71, 75 Determinate and indeterminate 55 Dewey on custom law . . 829 Dicey, meaning of state and social group .... 254 Difierentiation of functions . 132 — of organs . . . .133 Divine law, definition of . 1, 81 Duty, meaning of , . .5 — correlative with command . 6 — inseparably connected with command and sanction . 10 — no necessary connection with convention . . . 226 Ethics, science and meaning of 35 Executive v. legislative powers 128 Falok on value of "corpus juris civilis" .... 249 Federal state and Unity state, distinction . . . 149 Federal state and the Confedera- tion 151 Generality, as an ment in law essential ele- 18 Gierke, on medieval notion of sovereignty . . .70 Good as applied to a human law 36 — as applied to the law of God 38 Government, every, arises and continues through the people's consent, considered . 199, 202 — every supreme, is a monarchy 118 — de jure and de facto . . 228 — forms of supreme . .117 — free and despotic . . . 178 — lawful and unlawful . . 233 — purpose of, not the protection of property nor the increase of wealth . . . .195 Green, analysis of sovereignty . 279 GrotiuB, definition of sovereignty 113 — on sovereign powers . . 286 Group, beginning of a . . 259 — in action .... 268 — social, the State is a . . 254 unity of the . . . 258 — the unincorporated . . 262 Hearn, on orders to soldiers . 49 Hobbes, definition of sovereignty 113 — on sovereign power . 185, 229 Holland, definition of law , 27 Honour, law or rules of . .49 Human laws, two classes of . 2 Huxley, on social contract . 228 Ihering, on legal development . 159 — theory of law . . . 361 Imperfect, different meanings of 26 Independent, sovereign portion of the society is . . .97 — political society, definition . 238 Indeterminate and determinate, distinction between . . 55 Inferior, meaning of . . 18 International law . 50, 51. 106 Judge, English, as lawmaker . 288 — cannot overrule statute . 297 Judical action, limitation upon . 297 — authority, source of . . 300 Jurisprudence, comparativa . 959 INDEX 381 PjLOE Jarupradence, definition of 76 — is the knowledge of law as a science .... 246 — is positive law ... 1 — historical .... 358 — and legislation . . . 246 — national , . . 370, 374 — science and meaning of . 35 Jus Gentium .... 360 Jus naturale . . . .90 Kant, on legislature . 159 Law, a growth .... 347 — a unity .... 346 — Austin's argument on . .20 — definition of . 1, 3, 16, 354 — and laws, distinction between 340 — different kinds of . 31 — divine . . . 1 . 81 — every, or rule is a command 4 — human, divided into two classes . . . . 2 — is a command which obliges a person ... 16 , 40 — is a commanding rule . 19 — is older than State 333 — is supreme not the State 334 — may amount to a command . 15 — more than command . 346 — .of God, definition of . 1 — of honour .... 49 — of nature . . . 1 70 — positive, existing by posi- tion, 2, 28, 38, 34, 38, 70, definition of . . . 235 — proper, analogy of, with law set by general opinion 53 — purpose of . 349 — set by fashion and general opinion .... 250 — by political superiors . 2 , 96 Laws, absolute 26 — autonomic .... 46 — as commands 337 — by analogy, by metaphor 32, 83 ,88 Laws, coincidence and conflict of 65 — customary, not a species of command . . 27, 69, 334 — declaratory . . . .95 — distinguished from commands 11 — improperly and properly so called . . . .31 — legal, what may be styled 64 — of imperfect obligation . 24 — religious . . . .64 — to repeal laws . . .23 — set by men in pursuance of legal rights . . .43 — when they are general . 16 — which merely create rights . 26 — which seem not imperative . 26 — which are not commands 22 Legal rights against sovereign government . . .190 — rights of sovereign against foreign subjects . . 192 — rights defined by Austin . 65 Legally a sovereign cannot be bound .... 240 Legal sciences, classification of . 367 — theory and fiction, confusion of 305 Leges legum , . . . 329 — imperii .... 161 Legislation, science of . .35 — definition of . . . 246 — theory of . . . .357 Legislative, difiFerentiation be- tween, executive and judicial functions . . . 128, 132 Lex M]ia, Sentia . . .25 — Furia Testamentaria . . 25 Liberty, nature of political or civil 175 Limited monarch, the . .172 Lindley on liberty of British subject .... 181 Locke o> human understanding 79 — on meaning of law . . 341 — on power of legislature , 159 — on sovereign power . , 229 382 INDEX FAOS Maine on generality . . .19 Mansfield, moral obligation and sufficient consideration . 78 Markby, as to liability . . 78 — on rules .... 312 Marshall on governmental func- tions 133 Martens, Von, definition of sovereignty . . . 115 — positive international law 36, 75 Merriam on sovereignty , .142 Metaphor, meaning of . .31 Monarchy, every supreme govern- ment is a . . . . 118 — limited, a form of aristocracy 121 Montesquieu, spirit of laws . 91 Morality, positive 3, 33, 34, 44, 49 Morals, science of . . .35 Morley on moral principles . 86 Natural law, definition of . 1 Nature, state of . . . 108 Obedience, habit of . , .98 — motives of . . . . 202 Obligation . . . .6 Oligarchy, definition of . . 120 Opinion, laws set by . . 2 Pactum oonstitutionis subjec- tionis . . . .208 Paley, analysis of obligation . 6 Permissions or permissive laws . 23 Permissive laws always impera- tive 24 Persons, classification of . . 270 Political government, causes of 195 — society, independent, defined 238 — superiors .... 2 Pollock, on use of law books . 370 Positive, definition of, by Clark 34 — law . 1, 28, 33, 34, 38, 71, 75, 92, 232, 242 Positive law, definition of . 235 — essential difference of . . 155 — something more than a com- mand .... 9 PAOK Positive moral rules, classifica- tion of . . 44, 49, 71, 75 Positive morality . 3, 33, 41, 233 Power, legislative v. executive . 128 Beasonableness, significance of test of . 328 Rewards are not sanctions . 7 Eoman law, value of . 248 Rousseau, on law . 29 — governmental functions . 133 — sovereign power . . 229 Right is might, discussed . 186 Rule, every, or law is a com- mand 4, 11, 15 Rules, positive moral . 41 — of honour, meaning of . 49 — of art „ . 87 Salmond, on judicial usage . 299 Sanction, an enforcement of obedience .... 6 — inseparably connected with duty and command . .10 Savigny, Eoman law, 91,249, 254, 266 Science of jurisprudence . . 35 — of legislation . . 35, 71 Seeley on destruction of govern- ments .... 183 Sidney on destruction of govern- ments .... 184 Sidgwick, positive law and morality . . . .54 Society, explained . . .101 — independent political . . 103 Sovereign government tried before its own tribunals . . 190 — , half, states, 134 ; position of 186 — legal rights against foreign subjects 191 — may have rights against the subject .... 193 — subject may have a right against . . . .194 — power, limits of . . 155, 157 Sovereignty, definition of , 11^15 — in international law, jurispru- dence, political science 275-81 INDEX 383 Spencer, Herbert, on society Spinoza, on divine law State, law, science of — the, definition of . . 254 Stubbs, on corporations . Superior, meaning of PAGE 227 9 355 , 266 261 18 PAGB Ulpian, the purpose of law . 8, 76 — jug naturale • . . .88 — test of general commands . 18 Unconstitutional, meaning of , . 158, 167 Westlake, as to classification of law 51 PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN BY BILLING AND SONS, LIMITED, GUILDFORD AND ESHER