V\Sb 1^ iiig Jifeig, : BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME * J -s PROM THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF Himrg W. Sage 1891 Aa.££.LZ. *JjJj.± Cornell University Library K 455.L87 1880 The institutes of law: a treatise of the 3 1924 017 570 528 ■fiu xa£ fmM .f&pzti^w < '* ' ■ % '■' '*Br!5B S£> '•» J - life 1 1 1! it "i WJ UJnrnpU IGaui i^rljnnl Stbranj Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924017570528 THE INSTITUTES OF LAW lias etrn vo/xos evpTj/xa fi.h> koI SiZpov ©ccov. — Demosthenes. "Das eine Gesetzbuch dos Reclits ist die Gottliche "Weltordnung. " — Krattse. "All human laws are, properly speaking, only declaratory.'' -^Bitktce. MoVov yap fiovL/xov to ko.t' d£iav 'itrov, ko! to %x elv T °- iwuv. — Aristotle. "The unfettered multitiide is not dearer to me than the unfettered king." — Channing. THE INSTITUTES OF LAW . ri . I tl !;/ l:f A TREATISE OF THE PEINCIPLES OF JUEISPEUDENCE AS DETERMINED BY NATURE BY JAMES LORIMEK ADVOCATE, REGIUS PROFESSOR OF PUBLIC LAW AND OF THE LAW OF NATURE AND NATIONS IN THE UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH, MEMBER OF THE INSTITUTE OF INTERNATIONAL LAW, AND CORRESPONDING MEMBER OF THE ACADEMY OF JURISPRUDENCE OF MADRID, ETC. 3 SECOND EDITION, REVISED AND ENLARGED CO o • III fit WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS EDINBURGH AND LONDON MDOCOLXXX G All Rights reserved PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION. It has often been a subject of regret to me that the specula- tive tendencies of my countrymen were not directed more definitely to the life of man in Society and in the State. Had those great thinkers who have rendered the Scottish School of Philosophy illustrious set before them the task of placing Politics and Jurisprudence on a scientific basis, Political Economy might, long ago, have ceased to be the only practical science for which the world was indebted to a Scotch professor. This task I recognized as more immediately incumbent on the occupant of the Chair which I had been called to fill ; and the desire of contributing, however humbly, to its accom- plishment, has determined the character both of my oral teaching and of this Text -book. Although the present is not a speculative age, in some respects it has, unquestionably, been favourable to the work which I had in hand. That mitigation of dogmatism which Mr Herbert Spencer has wittily described as the " theological thaw," by enabling us to distinguish between the temporary, local, and relative, and the permanent, universal, and absolute elements in religious systems, has given to the history of Vlll PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION. religious opinion a value for secular purposes which it did not formerly possess. I have, consequently, not hesitated to avail myself of the rich materials with which oriental scholarship has now furnished us, in order to bring into prominence the unvarying ethical element which underlies all variations of dogma and of ritual. This ethical element — clearer, from the first, in the higher than in the lower races of mankind — becomes clearer and more definite as the conscious life of each race evolves itself, and as its accordance with subjective and objective revelations of the scheme of the universe is perceived. As faith becomes more reasonable, reason becomes more faith- ful, and ultimately we must hope that the great problem of Scholasticism will be solved by their culmination in a joint result. It is to the rule of life thus gradually recognized, that I have given the name of Natural Law, and, in the concrete realization of which I have sought the line along which all true Positive Legislation must necessarily travel. Conformity or non-conformity with Natural Law, in this sense, is, to my mind, the only conceivable measure of the value of social activity that is either permanent or uni- versal ; and it is on this ground that I have adhered to the academical method which relied on it, in place of adopting the method of measuring actions by results, on which the modern science of Sociology depends. Before we can measure by results, the results must be . measured ; and my difficulty with reference to utility, when proposed as the ultimate measure, as I have elsewhere explained, is — quis mstodit custodem? Utility, in its turn, must be measured by some end or object which it seeks, and, till we reach a teleological PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION. IX measure that transcends individual or national tastes and sentiments, Pilate's question regarding truth will apply to it. Short of nature there is no science of ends ; and to ascribe either utility or inutility to means irrespective of ends, is mere baseless dogmatism. If the results which we declare to be useful be identified with the objects of nature's legislation, the whole aspect of the affair, of course, is changed. Our results become ends, and not only they, but all the means that contribute to their attainment may safely be labelled as useful. But, in that case, Sociology presupposes scientific jurisprudence. Utilitarianism, as anything more than a phase of the in- ductive method, scarcely crossed the Border, and never crossed the Channel at all. But so firm was the hold which it took on England in the last generation, that to many of my elderly and middle-aged readers the possibility of its "utility" being called in question has probably never presented itself. On the other hand, it is rare, I believe, even in England, to find a Benthamite pur sang who is under forty. I do not think one has turned up amongst my students for the last ten years, though many of them have been graduates of the English universities ; and before another decade elapses, the preference for the older and grander traditions which Grotius inherited from Socrates, "the great lawyer of antiquity," as Lord Mans- field called him, through the Stoics and the Koman Jurists, over. those which Bentham transmitted to Austin, will, I hope; be as universal and unequivocal as that for classical and mediseval architecture over the architecture of the Georgian era has already become. X PKEEACE TO THE SECOND EDITION. This second edition does not differ essentially from the .first ; but in many directions, I trust, it has been rendered clearer in statement and more consistent in argument, in consequence of the sincere though generous criticisms of my colleagues of the Institute of International Law, and the daily friction of the lecture - room, where, for the last seven years, the first edition has been used as a text- book by the exceptionally advanced and cultivated class of students whom it has been my privilege to address. As I have been careful to avail myself of suggestions and indica- tions of opinion from both sources, whenever they appeared ■to me to be of value, the work in its present form may be regarded as the result of a process of development, rather than of a single effort of composition. To some extent it has the character of a bill that has not only been read a second time, but has passed through committee ; and for this reason I present it to the profession and to the public with fewer misgivings than I felt in the case of its predecessor. For many valuable suggestions, and criticisms of a minuter kind, as well as for the revision of the sheets as they passed through the press — an aid which my imperfect sight has rendered more indispensable than formerly — I am indebted to my friend Mr John Kirkpatrick. As Mr Kirkpatrick is a graduate of three universities — Cambridge, Heidelberg, and Edinburgh — and has had much literary experience, both as a writer and an editor, his kind interposition on this occasion has been a boon to my readers as well as a favour to me. With all these advantages I must not hope that I have suc- ceeded in making this work even a perfect expression of what PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION. xi was, no doubt, an imperfect conception. But I have been mindful that, as all is not gold that glitters, so all is not deep that is dark ; and I can honestly say that I have left no in- tentional " secrets " for my readers to puzzle out. The English language is , capable of conveying clearly whatever we have got clearly into our heads, and the apology which Coleridge offered to those who accused him of obscurity — intelligibility haud intellectum adfero— is one which must be very sparingly used. The book is intended not for jurists only, but- for cultivated persons generally, and if it is not generally intelli- gible, the fault is mine. CONTENTS. INTRODUCTION. PAGE Preliminary Definitions and Divisions, . 1 BOOK I. OF THE SOUECES OF NATURAL LAW. Chapter I.— Op the Sources op Natural Law. I. The Primary Source, or Source of Law itself, ... 21 II. The Secondary Sources or Channels of the Revelation of Natural Law, . ....... 35 1st, Direct revelation, . .... 35 («) Miraculous revelation to man, . 35 (b) Miraculous revelation through man, ... 35 (c) Special revelation through man, . . .36 2d, Indirect revelation, . . ... 37 Chapter II. — Op the Schools op Jurisprudence. 1st, The Theological School, ...... 39 (a) Its reality, . . . . . . .39" (b) Its adequacy, ..... .40 2d, The Inductive or Observational School (Subjective and Objective), . 45 3d, The Subjective, or so-called Philosophical School, ... 46 4th, The Objective, or Sensational School, . . 48 Chapter III. — Op the Autonomy op Human Nature. 1st, Our nature asserts its existence, and vindicates its assertion, . 55 2d, Our nature guarantees the veracity of its testimony with reference to its qualities, . . . . . . .56 XIV CONTENTS. 3d, Our nature asserts that it is the result of a cause external to itself, and independent of its volition, .... 57 4th, Our nature accepts itself as a gift, voluntarily given, but necessarily received, ........ 58 5th, In accepting itself as- necessary, our nature accepts itself as right, and its fundamental qualities and radical impulses as the absolute criteria of right and wrong, .... 59 Chapter IV. — Inquiry into the History of Opinion with REFERENCE TO HUMAN AUTONOMY. {A) The canon of the limitation of the historical method, . 63 (B) The canon of the application of the historical method, . . 66 (C) The regulative canons for the application of the historical method, 66 1st, Preference must be given to the best witnesses, . . 67 2d, Even amongst the witnesses whom we admit, the principle that testimonia ponderanda sunt, non numeranda, must be applied, . 72 3d, The abstract value of two witnesses being equal, the value of a coincidence between their testimony will increase in proportion to the dissimilarity, and diminish in proportion to the similar- - ity, of the circumstances in which it is given, ... 73 (A) Of Oriental, or ante-Classical Anthropology generally, . . 74 (a) The Shemitic Paces, ... 74 (J) The Aryan or Indo-Germanie Races, . 77 1st, The original Aryan Family, . 80 2d, The Eastern, or Indian Branch, . 94 3d, The Western Asiatic Branch, .... 102 4th, Non--Aryan and Mixed Races of Asia, . . 104 5th, Buddhism, .... . 105 (c) The Turanian Races, . . . . 119 The Chinese, ... . 120 {B) Of Classical Anthropology, ...... 126 (a) Greece, .... . . 126 (6) Rome, ... . 145 1. The Roman Law, . . . 154 2. International Law, . . .157 (c) Alexandria, . . , . 159 (C) Shemitic and Christian Anthropology, .... 161 (a) The Bible, ... . . 161 (5) The Fathers, . . . . .162 (c) The Schoolmen and Ecclesiastical Jurists, . .165 (d) The Reformation, . . . , . .171 CONTENTS. , xv Chapter V. — Human Natube Reveals its own Impotence, . 175 Chapter VI. — How Man becomes Co&nizant of the Rule op Life. (a) The rule of life is prescribed by bur whole nature, . . .184 (i) Conscience is not a separate faculty, ..... 186 Chapter VII. — Of the Rights and Duties which Nature Reveals. 1. Nature reveals no rights in relation to the Creator, . . , 205 2. Nature reveals to us duties in relation to the Creator, . . . 207 3. In our relation to creation, animate and inanimate, nature reveals rights, ........ 212 («) The fact of being involves the right to be, . . . 212 (6) The right to be involves the right to continue to be, . . 213 (c) Like the right to be, the right to continue to be has ho validity against God, ....... 214 {d) The right to be, and to continue to be, implies a right to the conditions of existence, . . . . . .215 (e) The right to be implies a. right to develop our being, and to the conditions of its development, ..... 222 (/) The right to be involves the right to reproduce and multiply our being, ........ 226 (gO The right to reproduce and multiply our being involves the right of transmitting to our offspring the conditions of the existence which we confer, ...... 229 (h) The right to be involves the right to dispose of the fruits of being, inter vivos, ...... 230 (i) The right to be involves the right to dispose of the fruits of being, mortis ams&, ...... 233 (/) All our subjective rights resolve themselves into the right to liberty, ........ 235 (k) In the limitations which nature imposes on our subjective rights, we have the first revelation of the principle of order, . . 236 (Z) Nature reveals to us the possibility and the consequences of the transgression of her laws, ..... 237 (m) Nature reveals objective rights which exactly correspond to our subjective rights, . . . . . . . 238 4. Nature reveals objective duties, or dirties by others to us, which exactly correspond to our subjective duties, or duties by us to others, ........' 242 5. The existence of subjective and objective rights and duties, and of their mutual dependence, constitute the sole revelation which nature makes to us with reference to human relations, . . 242 xvi CONTENTS. Chapter VIII. — How wis become Cognizant of Law in General. 1. Natural laws are rational inferences from the facts of nature, . . 244 2. Natural laws are nocossary inferences from tlio facts of nature, . 24 5 3. Natural laws determine the ultimate objocts of positive laws, and fix the principles of jurisprudence as a whole, . . . 247 4. The natural or do facto basis on which positive law rests being known, the positive law which governs any given human relation may be discovered, ...... 250 5. Though necessarily existent and discoverable, positivo laws never have been, and probably nevor will be, perfectly discovered, 258 Chapter IX.— Of the Laws of Nature, or Principles of Jurispru- dence which Result from the Human Rights and Duties which Nature Reveals as Facts. {a) All human laws are declaratory, ..... 255 (b) Law cannot change the character, or altor the relations of persons, . 259 ('■) Law cannot constitute, extend, or circumscribe a proprietary relation, 259 {d) Law cannot change the price of any commodity, . . . 274 Chapter X.— Of the Relation between Legislation and Jurisdiction. Tho function of the judgo, as such, is limited to the interpretation and application of written or of consuetudinary law, . . . 277 Chapter XI. — Of the History of the Distinction between Perfect and Imperfect Obligations, and its Effect in giving rise to the Negative School of Jurisprudence. (a) Rights and duties being throughout reciprocal and co-extensive, thcro is no distinction, in principle — i.e., in nature — between one class of obligations and another, ..... 282 {!>) Tho attompt to distinguish between perfect and imperfect obligations was not unknown to antiquity, ..... 286 (c) It is generally ascribed to Thomasius, .... 288 Chapter XII.— Of Justice and Charity. (a) The principles of justice and charity are identical ; their separato realization is impossible ; and their common realization necessarily culminates in tho same action, ..... 314 CONTENTS. xvu (6) The doctrine of the identity of the principles of justice and charity was taught by Christ's mediatorial sacrifice, and is implied in the whole scheme of redemption, ..... 334 (c) The doctrine of the identity of justice and charity was not first pro- mulgated by Christ, and is not exceptionally Christian, . . 339 BOOK II. OF THE OBJECTS OF NATURAL LAW AND JURIS- PRUDENCE IN GENERAL. Chapter I. — Op the Relation between Jurisprudence and Ethics. (a) The ultimate object of jurisprudence is the realization of the idea in the ideal of humanity, ...... 353 (ft) The proximate object of jurisprudence, the object which it seeks as a separate science, is liberty, . . . 353 Chapter II. — Op the Relation between Order and Liberty. Order and liberty, like justice and charity, are in principle identical. ' They can be realized only in conjunction, and necessarily cul- minate together, . . . . . 368 Chapter III. — Op the History op the Doctrine that the Idea op Liberty involves the Idea op Absolute Equality. (a) As a protest against authority, . . 378 (6) By the Jesuits, . . .378 379 385 388 392 393 (c) By Hobbes, (d) Spinoza. (e) Rousseau, (/) Democrats of the Revolution, (g) Ahrens, Chapter IV. — Op the Relation of Equality to Liberty continued. In what sense is equality involved in the idea of liberty '! The idea of liberty involves the idea of equality in one sense only — that which is popularly called "equality before the law,' - . . 402 (a) Analytic justice, ....... 405 (6) Synthetic justice, ....... 406 xviii CONTENTS. Chapter V. — Of the Limits within which Aggression is a Natural Eight. (a) Aggression is a natural right, the extent of which is measured by the power which God has bestowed on the aggressor, or permitted him to develop. Up to this point, the right of conquest, individual, social, political, and ethnical, is involved in the idea of liberty, and included in the objects of jurisprudence, . . . 414 (b) An end that is just, justifies the means requisite for its attainment ; the right of aggression, consequently, justifies the application of force, and involves the right of war, when, and to the extent to which, force or war is necessary for its vindication, . . 419 BOOK III. OF THE SOURCES OF POSITIVE LAW, OE SPECIAL JURISPRUDENCE. Chapter I. — Of the Ultimate Sources of Positive Law. (a) The Law of Nature, ....... 425 (b) The conditions of existence under which that law must be realized, . 425 Chapter II. — Of the Proximate Sources of Positive Law. (a) The primary source of positive law is the real power of the whole community subject to the law, as exhibited in and measured by its rational will, . " . . . . . . 426 (6) The secondary sources of positive law are the means by which the community vindicates its real as distinguished from its merely apparent power, ....... 426 Chapter III. — Of the Primary Source of Positive Law. (a) Real positive law, as distinguished from mere enacted law, will exist in a community, and the community will be practically autonomous, to the extent to which power and reason exist and coincide in it, . 426 (6) Positive law can originate and subsist in a community only to the extent to which that community is free, and all true legislation is thus, in the last analysis, self-legislation, . . . 429 (c) Positive law can spring only from the whole autonomous community which obeys it, . . . , _ 434 CONTENTS. XIX (d) As the presence of positive law is proportioned to the existence and coincidence of power and reason, the contributions which the in- dividual members of the community are in a condition to make to it will be proportioned to the existence and coincidence of power and reason, or the existence of real power, in each of them, 436 Chapter IV. — The Doctrine of the Necessary Sovereignty of the Kational Will of the Whole Community is in accordance with the Common-sense of Mankind, . . .437 Chapter V. — -Of the Secondary Sources of Positive Law. The secondary sources of positive law are the means by which the com- munity vindicates its real as distinguished from its merely ap- parent power, ....... 447 I. The means by which the community forms its rational will, 447 1. The Church, ....... 448 (1.) It alone seeks to influence the will, not only indirectly, through the understanding, but directly, . . . 450 (2. ) It appeals to the classes that are least within the reach of other influences, and retains its hold on them during life, 453 2. The School, including the University, in so far as the latter is regarded merely as a means of instruction and discipline, and not as an organ for the advancement of science, . . 459 3. The Press, ...... 469 4. The Polling-booth, . . . . . ' . 472 II. The means by which the community develops its rational will, . 476 (a) Conscious effort on the part of individuals and classes, . . 476 (b) Social organisation, ...... 491 (c) By the selection, and setting apart, of exceptional workmen for exceptional work, ...... 494 III. The means by which the community ascertains its rational will, . 504 (a) The amount of organization requisite for the ascertainment of the rational will is in an inverse ratio to the amount of direct per- sonal contact with each other, on the part of the individuals whose rational will is to be ascertained, . . . 505 (J) For purposes of practical legislation it will, in general, be neces- sary that all citizens included in each political class or category be dealt, with as contributing an equal amount of rational will, 510 (c) The classification which exists for economical and social pur- poses, for the time being, affords the measure of that which is requisite for legislative purposes, .... 513 (d) The electoral system, . . • , . 514 XX CONTENTS. IV. The means by which the community declares its rational will, (a) Legislation, . • • • (fi) Consuetude, V. The means by which the rational will of the community is applied to the special case may be either spontaneous or by jurisdiction, VI. The means by which the community enforces its rational will, Of the Arm}', ...... The Police, . Public Prosecution of Crime, 515 515 516 516 517 518 519 520 BOOK IV. OF THE OBJECTS OE POSITIVE LAW. Chapter I. — Of the Ultimate and Proximate Objects of Posi- tive Law, . .... Chapter II. — Or the Primary and Secondary Objects of Positive Law. (a) Primary, (b) Secondary, The objects of positive law may be classified with reference either to the spheres within which they seek their realization, or to the forms ■ in which they are manifested, .... 1. The Soman division into public law and private law, (1.) Public law within the State, called in England constitutional law, (2.) Public law without the State, or the jus inter gentes, (3.) Private law within the State, or municipal law, (4.) Private law without the State, or private international law, II. The second scheme divides positive law into national and interna- tional ; and these again into public and private, . 1st, National public law ; and national private law, 2d, International public law ; and international private law, III. Classification of the various branches of positive law, from the domains which they severally embrace, Chapter III.— Conclusion. Of the reconciliation which the system of positive law, logically resulting from the principles of jurisprudence as determined by nature, tends to establish between the progressive and conservative schools of European politics, ... Index, 523 523 524 537 537 537 538 538 538 539 539 539 539 540 555 THE INSTITUTES OF LAW. INTEODUCTIOK Preliminary Definitions and Divisions. I. T\EFINITIONS and divisions are possible only after the subject of them is known. They must consequently be the goal, rather than the starting - point, of scientific in- quiry. But, on the other hand, inasmuch as the sight of the butt is necessary to the archer, we shall do well to place before us at the outset, as clearly as we can, the object at which we aim. This proceeding is the more necessary in consequence of the want, in our own system of legal instruc- tion, of any preliminary course corresponding to what, in Continental Universities, is called Encyclopaedia, in which the skeleton, so to speak, of the science upon which the student is about to enter is exhibited to him. It has been said with great truth that the philosophy of law, on the ground that it stands in a general relation to each of the special branches of the science of law, is itself an encyclopaedia, but that it is a philosophical encyclopaedia. 1 Such an encyclopaedia I hope to 1 Michelet, NaturrecM, pp. 17 and 18. A 2 INTRODUCTION. furnish in the sequel of this work; but it is a dogmatic sketch alone which I can attempt at the outset. With this limited aim, then, the branch of science with the study of which we shall be here engaged, may be de- scribed as having for its object the discovery of that law which, by the nature of all rational creatures, and independ- ently of their volition, determines their relations to each other and to surrounding existences, in so far as this law is medi- ately or immediately revealed to human reason and realizable by human will, under the conditions of human existence in time and space. The validity of the law of nature, it is true, is not, or at any rate cannot be conceived by us to be, limited to humanity, or to humanity under the conditions of time and space. Culverwell accordingly defines it as " that law which is intrinsical and essential to a rational creature ; " 1 and Hegel, regarding it as the divine conception of Kosmos in human relations, by which the limited or relative will of the creature is harmonized with the unlimited or absolute will of the Creator, speaks of it as " the reign of liberty realized." Seen from this latter point of view, we might define it as the law which determines the conditions of perfect human co-existence, or, of progress towards the realization of such co-existence. It is in this light that it specially concerns the jurist, as dis- tinguished from the metaphysician and the moral philosopher ; for it is when thus regarded that he begins to see in it the permanent element of positive law. The Kosmic character of existence, or, in other words, its absolute rectitude, as we shall see hereafter, is an assumption 1 Light of Nature, p. 57. INTRODUCTION. 3 which is psychologically inevitable. Eelative will cannot contend with absolute will, even ' in thought. In its origin, law, like existence, is thus involuntary and inexplicable. It is an objective phenomenon which consciousness presents to us, not from without but from within : a conception which is imposed on our cognitive faculties a priori: a postulate necessitated by the fact that we are. Law thus comes out of mystery, just as it goes out into mystery. The conscious- ness which brings it within the sphere of finite vision is as dark as the consciousness which carries it back into the infinite; for the one marks its passage into, and the other its passage out of, the conditions of time and space. Over its coming and its going we have no more control than over a ray of sunshine. But, even at the risk of misapprehension, I must, for the present, refrain from pursuing the subject further in this aspect; and in addressing myself to pro- fessional students, and having practical rather than theoreti- cal objects in view, I shall endeavour throughout to avoid all forms, both of thought and expression, which may not fairly be assumed to be familiar to cultivated persons generally in this country. In designating this subject the law of nature, it is obvious that, whilst the term law is employed in the general sense of Kosmical arrangement, we use the term nature in a more restricted sense than that in which it is often identified with created existence. The law of nature, in the jural sense, is not the whole scheme of the universe, but the branch of that scheme which has reference to human relations. It does not deal with the inevitable relations in which man stands 4 INTRODUCTION. to the external world, whether animate or inanimate. The laws of generation, of growth and decay, of digestion, assimila- tion, respiration, and the like, lie beyond its sphere, just as much as the laws of space and number, or the laws of thought. These are laws which wholly shut out the element of human volition. The natural laws by which human relations are governed, on the other hand — the laws of ethics, politics, and jurisprudence — are, in a limited sense, laws of freedom. They are laws the violation of which is physically possible, not only to the individual, but to the state, and even to the community of nations. Whether they can be permanently and ultimately violated even in this world, is a question which belongs to philosophy and theology rather than to juris- prudence. But for the immediate purposes of his science, the jurist must accept the task of demonstrating the inevitable character of these laws. He must show that, though natural laws, in the sense which he attaches to them, may certainly be broken, for a time at least — nay, though it be inconceiv- able that imperfect beings should ever observe them perfectly — they are essentially self-avenging. To use a happy Ger- man distinction, which I fear is hardly translatable, they are thus Soll-Gesetze, though not Muss-Gesetze 1 (' ought-laws, not must-laws '). Their consequences are as inevitable as their character is unchangeable ; it is their fulfilment or non-fulfil- ment alone that is dependent on human volition. As natural laws, it belongs to their conception that the rewards attached to their fulfilment, and the punishments which attach to their violation, depend as little on the wills of those who fulfil them 1 Krause's SecJits-Philosophie, p. 36. INTRODUCTION. 5 or violate them as the rising and the setting of the sun. It is this character, as we shall presently see, which distinguishes natural laws from mere human enactments, which may or may not be in conformity with them, and which, consequently, may or may not he permanently set at naught. As illustrating the difficulty of defining natural law in the jural sense, so as to keep it apart from theology on the one hand and physiology on the other, I may mention the modes in which law as a whole has been divided by two of the greatest minds that ever were brought to bear on its elucida- tion, — St Thomas Aquinas, and our own not less saintly Hooker. The first, which was generally followed by the theologians and schoolmen, was this : — 1. Eternal Law : that of the Divine and general govern- ment of the universe. Of this law Culverwell has finely said, that "it was in a manner incarnated in the law of nature." 1 2. Natural Law: 2 that of finite creatures endowed with reason. 3. Human Law : that which has reference to human relations. 4. Divine Law : the order of salvation specially provided for man. 3 The second (Hooker's scheme) was this : — 1. Law" which God from the beginning set for Himself. 2. Law which natural agents observe. 3. Law which the angels obey. 1 Light of Natwre, p. 50. * Lex naturalis nihil aliud est, quam participatio le^is seternfe iu rationali creatura. 3 Summa Theologiai, Prima Secundas, Qucestio xci. 6 INTRODUCTION. 4. Law -which directs man to the imitation of God. 1 Without entering on the manifest objections which might be stated to each of these schemes, many of which were obviated in the rich and varied discussions to which they gave rise, we may repeat, in a word, that our conception of natural law is — the law for the general government of the universe, only in so far as it has reference to the. relations of men, or is " incarnated " in human society. II. Natural law, when treated as a science, is often called the philosophy of law. 2 But, inasmuch as nature is a more definite conception than philosophy, the former epithet is preferable ; and for this reason, probably, recent writers seem mostly to have reverted to it. I have adopted the terms " Institutes of Law," and " Principles of Jurisprudence as determined by Nature," in order to indicate the fundamental relation in which the subject stands to all the departments of positive law. III. The science of the law of nature, or the philosophy of law, professes to furnish us with the doctrines of natural law in the abstract. The law of nature is thus the subject with which this science is conversant ; but it is no more identical with the science than the subject of any other branch of study is identical with the study itself — than, e.g., the laws of the vegetable or animal creation, with the 1 Ecclesiastical Polity, vi. p. 72. 2 See the list of works at the end of the first volume of Ahrens's Cours de Droit Naturel, p. 325. Michelet says that it was called Naturrecht by the jurists, aud Rechtsphilosophie by the later philosophers, p. 1. The names are now synony- mous, and it is taught both in the faculties of philosophy and of law, both by philosophers and jurists. INTRODUCTION. 7 sciences of botany, zoology, anatomy, or physiology. There are laws of nature which govern the growth and decay of plants and animals, whether we know and obey, or ignore and violate them. And just in the same way there is a law of nature which governs the human life of man, whether we discover it and follow it, or blindly and ignorantly set it at defiance. " It is," says Ahrens, " with moral order as with physical order. The law of attraction existed and governed the relations of natural existences before it was discovered by Newton and determined by science." In like manner Max Miiller tells us how long it was before the Greeks arrived at a complete nomenclature for the parts of speech. But there were parts of speech before they were dis- covered by the Greeks, and, strange as it may seem to us, they were known to Sanscrit literature. What is true of the laws of life and of language, is not less obviously true of the laws of thought, or of their applications. Logic may have been dis- covered by Aristotle, but it was both used and abused in the Garden of Eden. To suppose, then, that because positive laws existed before the natural laws, of which they were imperfect, local, and temporary realizations, had been scientifically evolved, or systematically enunciated, positive law therefore preceded natural law in point of time — as is done by those who identify natural law with the laws which they imagine to have existed in the imaginary state of nature — is just as great an absurdity as to suppose that because houses were built up and tumbled down before the law of attraction was discovered, they did not stand or fall in accordance with that law ; or that, because men spoke before they knew the parts of speech, they did not 8 INTRODUCTION. make use of nouns and verbs every time they gave -utterance to articulate sounds. And as the law of nature existed before i» was scientifically discovered, it existed equally before it was divinely revealed. "It was long extant," says Culverwell, " before Moses was born ; long before Aaron rung his golden bells ; before there was a prophet or a judge in Israel." l IV. The science of jurisprudence differs from the science of natural law, and from the philosophy of law, in this respect, that, in addition to the discovery of the doctrines of natural law and their general and permanent action, it in- cludes their local and temporal realization — i.e., positive law, properly so called, 2 in all its branches. Jurisprudence thus embraces legislation, whether the subjects with which it deals be political, economical, or social, national or international, 1 Ut sup. p. 68. 5 I find that the expression " positive law," in the sense in which I here use it — viz., of natural law realized in time and place — has occasioned confusion in the minds of some of my readers, which, even at this early stage of our discussions, it may be desirable to remove. The sense attached to positive law in England, I am told, is "law as it is " — that is to say, law enacted by a recognized authority, whether in conformity with, or in opposition to, natural law. Law which sets the principles of human nature and the facts of society at defiance is, in this sense, positive law just as much as law which recognizes them ; — sense and nonsense, if formally enacted, stand on a footing of perfect equality. Now the modicum of truth which this conception contains is sufficiently taken into account when we recognize the necessary imperfection of all human enactments. It is quite true that " law as it is " can never quite coincide with "law as it ought to be," or, in other words, can never quite realize natural law in time and place, and conse- quently, that if we were to adhere strictly to our definition, we could never have any positive law at all. But this does not hinder the " law which is " from being more or less positive, in proportion to the extent to which it approaches to, or recedes from, its own ideal ; nor does it prevent this ideal from determining the only sense in which positive law can be formally or scientifically understood. The true equivalent for " law as it is " is thus not " positive law," but "enacted law." which, without losing its character, may set both the laws and the facts of nature at defiance. — Infra, p. 10. INTRODUCTION. 9 civil or ecclesiastical, public or private, general or particular, as well as jurisdiction and execution ; whilst the sphere of an academical Faculty of Law extends to the study of the whole human relations, whether these relations be necessary and permanent, or accidental and transitory. V. Positive law may be regarded either as a science or as an art. The science is the result of a process of analysis — the art is that of a process of synthesis resting on the previous analysis ; and inasmuch as the existence of the synthesis without the analysis is impossible, there can be no art of positive law without a science of positive law. (A) The science of positive law has for its object the dis- covery (Erkenntnis's) of the law of nature in special circum- stances, and with reference to special relations. (2?) The art of positive law has for its objects the recogni- tion (Anerlcennung) of the law of nature by special enactments, and its vindication in special circumstances and relations. Law as an art assumes three functions : (a) Legislation, (b) Jurisdiction, (c) Execution, which in the earlier stages of its development are not sharply distinguished from each other. Apart from their realization in positive laws, the rules of natural law are merely hypothetical and contingent, depending for their concrete forms on the answers which may be given by observation and experience to questions of fact which they do not profess to solve. Natural law thus forms the major premiss of the syllogism of which the legislative enactment, or the judicial sentence, is the conclusion ; or, to use a professional illustration, it draws the issue to which positive law returns the verdict. 10 INTRODUCTION. Every sound legislative enactment thus involves the previous decision of a question of natural law ; and every sound judicial sentence involves the acceptance of that decision. The three moments of jurisprudence are thus — natural law, human enact- ment, and (in case of controversy) judicial decision. VI. In consequence of the imperfection which clings to humanity, human enactments never attain to the full character of positive laws. But they possess the character of positive laws, more or less, in proportion to the extent to which they are, or are not, interpretations and realizations of the law of natura Enactments, in so far as they fail to realize the law of nature, must be errors, and may be crimes. Even where there - is no want of good intention on the part of the legislature, laws formally enacted may fall short of the character of positive laws from three causes : — (a) Erom an erroneous conception of the law of nature to be realized. (&) From an erroneous appreciation of the special circum- stances in which the law of nature is to be realized, and, as a necessary consequence, of the provisions by which the law of nature is realizable. (c) Erom changes in the special circumstances of the com- munity, rendering inoperative those provisions by which the law of nature was formerly realized. But, inasmuch as men are liable to err, not only in inter- preting and realizing the law of nature anew, but in judging of the manner in which it has already been interpreted and realized, great caution ought to be exercised in condemning and altering enacted laws. Moreover, as all human enactments INTRODUCTION. 1 1 must embody some element of error, it does not follow that an existing law should be altered the moment that the fact of its divergence from natural law, or even the direction in which it diverges, has been discovered. In the latter case, the manner in which it must ultimately be altered, or developed, will, in a general way, be known; but the means of its amendment — i.e., the special form which the new enactment ought to assume — may still be undetermined. VII. Judicial sentences may honestly fail to realize the law of nature in the individual case, from three causes : — (a) From failure on the part of the judge to discover, or to understand, the enactment in which the law of nature has been more or less perfectly embodied in the wider sphere of legislation. (b) From failure on the part of the litigant, or his represen- tative, to present the facts of the individual case, or to present them intelligibly, to the judge. (c) From, failure on the part of the judge to apprehend the facts of the individual case when intelligibly presented to him. VIII. The law of nature may further be negatively denned by distinguishing it from the following subjects with which it has often been confounded : — (iy Suarez of Grenada, in his great work He Leqibus. 32 OF THE SOURCES OF NATURAL LAW. law to God, — much as it has been discussed both by jurists and moralists, 1 may be dismissed, not only as insoluble, otherwise than by the identification of God and Law, but as irrelevant, because the science of jurisprudence will rest with equal security on either of the two alternatives which it offers. All that is demanded for the foundation of a human science is a starting-point which transcends humanity. For similar reasons we may well content ourselves with humbly recognizing the hitherto impenetrable mystery which covers the origin of evil. As regards the nature of evil, how- ever, the case is different ; for if a belief in the absolute charac- ter of good be indispensable to the attainment of a basis for our science, this belief will scarcely be gained unless our study of nature should enable us to assign a relative character to evil. To make evil absolute, and sin, which God hates, eter- nal, is to limit His power, and to put Him very nearly on a footing of equality with the devil. If not altogether dualism, it is certainly Manicheism. On this point the lawyer's creed must be that of Plato and St Augustine, 2 — the creed which had been revealed to Job, 3 which Heraclitus had divined, 4 and which, with Bunsen, 5 I believe to be the instinctive creed of mankind. 1 Leibnitz has stated the argument for the independence of law with great force, but the solution at which Suarez arrives, lex-deus ipse, seems to me the true one. See Trendelenburg's Kleine Schriften, and Historisehe Beitrage zur Philo- sophie, where the fullest information regarding Leibnitz's incidental activity as a jurist will be found. On the respective views of Cudworth and Descartes, v. Tulloch's national Theology, vol. ii. p. 289. 2 Emile Saisset's introduction to his translation of the Civilas Dei, p. xxxi. 3 Job i- 6-12. 4 Schwegler's Hist, of PHI. p. 22. 6 Ut sup. i. 23. Bunsen has brought out the important fact that the original OF THE SOUKCES OF NATURAL LAW. 33 The necessity of this opinion, for the purposes of our science, has been strongly felt by the latest school of scientific jurists in Germany, 1 those who agree with Hegel in scarcely anything else accepting his dictum that evil must be regarded as " a negative element." 2 Without dwelling further, then, on subjects which belong to the sphere of theology, permit me, in conclusion, to indi- cate one very important practical effect which the recognition of the divine origin of jurisprudence has exercised on the organization of society. The place everywhere assigned to the lawyer lies between that of the priest and the secular layman, — in general consider- ably nearer to the former than the latter. In the East, in theocratic countries, and amongst the Shemitic races more especially, the offices of the lawyer and the priest are combined in the same individual. The laws of Moses and of Mahomet, and in a lesser degree those of Manu, and even of Confucius, are religious as well as legal systems. In those of Zoroaster the former is the prevailing character, though both are combined. Scribes, Pundits, Muftis, Ulemas, Mollahs, Kadis, all belong to the sacerdotal class. Nor do the races which trust to indirect, differ much from those which lay claim to direct inspiration in this respect. The classical nations spoke of us as " Priests of Justice." You remember the magnificent passage. from Ulpian with which the Digest opens; in which, after deriving jus from justitia, he exclaims : " Cujus merito quis Hebrew conception of Satan (Azazel) was that not of the opponent and rival, but of the servant of God — God's Retributive Justice. God in History, vol. i. p. 102. 1 Krause, pp. 216-220. Ahrens, pp. 128, H7, 170, 172, &c. 2 Phil, of History, Bohn's trans., p. 16. 34 OF THE SOURCES OF NATURAL LAW. nos sacerdotes appellet. Justitiam namque colimus : et boni et tequi notitiam profitemur : sequum ab iniquo separantes : licitum ab illieito discernentes : bonos non solum metu pcenarum, verum etiam prsemiorum quoque exhortatione efficere cupientes: veram, nisi fallor, philosophiam, non simulatam affectantes.'' In Christian times the separation between the priest and the jurist dates from the period when the universal priesthood of Christians was acknowledged, and it has been fully accepted only in those countries in which that recognition has taken place. In the middle ages the canonists, and not unfrequently the civilians, were priests ; and in Eome, so far as the papal authority extends, the same arrangement prevails at the present hour. The Lord Chancellor of England, till the eve of the ' Eeformation, was invariably an ecclesiastic, and there are instances of the Seals having been held by bishops down to so late a period as 1625. Even now many of the functions of the Chancellor are connected with the Church, and it is only yesterday that its ecclesiastical character was laid aside by an important branch of the legal profession in England. The judicial character of the House of Lords still (1880) exists with reference to Scotland, and bishops may sit in Scotch Appeals. On the Scotch Bench, as originally consti- tuted, one - half of the judges, besides the president, were Churchmen, and Churchmen sat upon it even after the Eeforma- tion. In the academical hierarchy of all European countries, the Legal ranks next to the Theological Faculty, and by some Universities it has been regarded as dealing with the same subjects. 1 As civilization advances, and social arrangements be- 1 Suarez, Be Legibus, lib. iii. OF THE SOURCES OP NATURAL LAW. 35 come more complicated, a division of labour becomes inevitable, by which the judicial is separated from the sacerdotal office ; but their original connection ought never to be forgotten by the lawyer who would duly appreciate the dignified and sacred character of the profession which it is his privilege to exercise. II. The secondary sources or channels of the Eevelation of Natural Law are of two kinds, — Direct and Indirect. 1st, Direct revelation. (a) Miraculous revelation to man. — All direct revelation partakes of a supernatural character ; but its miraculous character is most marked when it assumes the shape of an external communication from God to man — in other' words, when God, as what we, by analogy, call a Person, manifests himself to man, and makes him acquainted with His will. Of revelation, in this sense, the only instances admitted in Christian countries are those narrated in the Bible. Whether these interpositions are to be regarded as violations or suspen- sions of natural law, or as acts in accordance with higher natural laws than are known to man or traceable by his present faculties, is one of the many speculative questions which the jurist, as such, is not called upon to discuss. (b) Miraculous revelation through man. — When God makes choice of an individual man as a passive instrument for the conveyance of His will to mankind — though that will be not conveyed to him by an external communication — the revela- tion still possesses not only a supernatural but a miraculous character. The revelation of which the prophets and the apostles were the organs was of this kind, in all cases in which they do, not profess to report the very words that were spoken 36 OP THE SOURCES OF NATURAL LAW. to them by God. It is to this kind of revelation also that Mahomet, for the most part, lays claim in the Koran. (c) Special revelation through man. — This occurs when God, by the ordinary influences of His grace, makes His law known to the individual mind otherwise than through its conscious processes. We have here still, apparently, the immediate operation of the primary, -without the intervention of a secondary cause, which is said, on the high authority of St Thomas Aquinas, as quoted by Dante, to constitute the character of a miracle. 1 But it differs from the miracle, in the ordinary sense, in this : that it is not entirely independent of the will of the recipient, as manifested either in the relation in which he places him- self to God, or by direct petition. This revelation, through the reason (vm>i), assumes a plainly supernatural, and comes very close on a miraculous character, when it is granted in unusual measure, as, for example, to Socrates. Bunsen, in my opinion, spoke quite accurately when he characterised Socrates as " the Saint of Athens," 2 and I assent to the expressions which he uses in a letter to a friend, as reproduced in his life. 3 Beferring to the manner in which his friend had spoken of the religious aspirations of the great heathens, Bunsen says : " I should express myself differently as to the religious aspirations of Homer and Socrates, as not derived from exterior sources, no more than the philosophical notions of Deity in Plato, but from that inward revelation of the Spirit of God to which St Paul alludes.'' Such I believe 1 De Monorchia, lib. ii. sec. 4. 6 Preface to the Thsologia Germanica, lvii. 3 Vol. ii. p. 424. OF THE SOURCES OF NATURAL LAW. 37 to have been the character of the revelation of ethical truth to Socrates. What he said of the Aal^wv, I take to have been a mere figurative way of indicating the immediate relation in which he occasionally felt himself to stand to the Divine, and of which all sages and poets, seers and makers, are more or less distinctly conscious. Apart, however, from the loftier character of the subjects to which these revelations usually refer, there is, I think, a difficulty in establishing a distinction in kind between them and those intuitive acts of the mind by which logical processes, for more ordinary purposes, are unconsciously performed. 1 All " happy thoughts " come from God, and may, in a wide and loose sense, be called revela- tions, seeing that the mind in which they arise stands, for the time being, in an exceptionally close relation to Him. 2d, Indirect revelation. Indirect revelation is the ordinary means by which the law of nature, or, in other words, the will of God, with reference to temporal affairs, is communicated to man. It is divided into two branches — (a) Subjective, — The teaching of consciousness, or the re- velation derived from the study of the Ego. (6) Objective, — The teaching of external observation, or the revelation derived from the study of the Non-Ego, whether material or immaterial. 1 Duke of Argyll's Reign of Law, p. 318. 38 OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. CHAPTEK II. OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. The questions whether the various sources of knowledge, direct or indirect, which we have enumerated, he really channels of the revelation of the absolute law — and, if so, to what extent — can be answered only when the character and scope of their teaching has been investigated. On the assumption, however, that they are entitled to that character, it is obvious that the information which they communicate must be harmonious and coincident, even where it is not identical ; and that no one of them can be entitled to repudiate another. The methods, however, to which they give rise differ so essen- tially, and commend themselves to temperaments and races and generations of men so different, as to have originated various schools of jurisprudence, each of which, in its turn, has claimed exclusive possession of the key of knowledge. Of these the most clearly distinguishable are — 1st, The Theological School. 2d, The Inductive or Observational School (Subjective and Objective). 3d, The Subjective, or Philosophical School. 4th, The Objective, or Sensational School. A few observations on the methods on which these schools severally rely may be serviceable in enabling you to recognise the co-efficient character which, in reality, belongs to them all. OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. 39 1st, The Theological School 1 professes to discover the law of nature, not in the study of nature itself, but in the study of what God has told us of nature. The legitimacy of this method- is implied in what has already been said of direct revelation. If the law of nature be identical with the Divine Law, — i.e., with the will of God, — it certainly is possible, and not inconceivable, that He may have made this law known to man directly. No prudent or reverent man, however, I think, will venture on a very sharp definition of the word " directly," when used in this connection. The legitimacy of the theological method being admitted, the only questions with reference to it which here are logically open to us are, first, as to its reality ; and, second, as to its adequacy or exclusive sufficiency, (a) Its reality. — Though it be possible and credible that God should have revealed His will to man externally as well as internally, it by no means follows that He has done so at all, or that He has done so with reference to the matter in hand. The first of these questions it is not necessary, and would not be suitable, that we should discuss. A direct revelation, with reference to the relations in which man stands to God, is an occurrence in which all Christians and Mahometans, and most Heathens, profess to believe. We shall here assume its reality, with the remark that, inasmuch as it does not profess to have been given to all, its reality is a fact which those who have not personally received it, must always accept from those who have. It is only to the prophet himself that the prophecy is directly revealed. His followers 1 Ahrens, pp. 61, 66. 40 OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. receive it on his word. As regards the facts of consciousness, on the other hand, each man is his own prophet. 1 (6) Its adequacy. — But assuming its reality, does this revela- tion bear on the secular relations of men ? and, if so, does it alone furnish us with means adequate to the determination of these relations ? Tor this, we must bear in mind, is the thesis which the theological school, as such, professes to maintain. The leading doctrines of the moral law are, no doubt, laid down in the Holy Scriptures, and inasmuch as the law of nature with reference to the relations of man to man is neither more nor less than these doctrines traced out into their conse- quences in special directions, the law of nature may, in this sense, be said to have been directly revealed. But recent scholarship has taught us that this assertion must not be limited to the Christian or Hebrew Scriptures. Whether or not the starting-point of ethics was thus attained anywhere may well be questioned, but it is not doubtful 2 that its grand out- lines have the double sanction of direct and indirect injunction. 1 The remarkable revival which Catholicism has experienced, and the attempts which have been made to introduce the confessional into Protestant communions, alongside of, and no doubt as reactions against, materialism and irreligion in our own day, have given ■■• practical importance to the doctrines of the theological school which they did not possess half a century ago. Men knew then, indeed, that such persons as Molina and Bellarmine had asserted that, if the Pope, as the in- fallible interpreter of external revelation, should declare virtue to be vice and vice virtue, all good Catholics were bound to believe him ; but, in a speculative age, the assertion was rather welcomed as a reductio ad absurdum which rendered the system innoxious. Now, however, in the absence of philosophy, it is widely accepted as the only refuge against scepticism, which, beginning with religion, has extended to morality, and which, in our own department, threatens to deprive jurisprudence and politics of any basis that is independent of individual caprice. 2 Meander, Ch. His. i. p. 9. Donaldson's History of Christian Literature, ii. pp. 167, 183, 198, 225. Ackermann's Christian Element in Plato, pp. 19, 53. Aristot. Mctaph. x. 8. OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. 41 On the other hand, however, it is important to remark that, in the vast majority of instances, whilst the information which is conveyed to us with reference to the relations of man to God are express, that which has reference to the relations of man to man only admits of being partially gathered from incidental expressions, or from the life and conduct of Christ. What is revealed, primarily at least, " is the ways of God to man," not of man to man. The previous acquaintance of man- kind with the law of nature is, manifestly, assumed ; and in this assumption we cannot but perceive a plain recognition of, and reference to, other sources of knowledge. 1 Then, so far from preaching any separate system of positive law relating to secular affairs, one of the objects of Christ's mission was to abolish the only system of the kind that ever was directly revealed to man, and to place the Jews once more in the same position as the rest of mankind. The Koinan law, under which Christ himself lived, was expressly founded on indirect revelation interpreted by mere human reason, and, from the beginning to the end of His teaching, there is not the slightest indication of an opinion that it either ought to have rested, or could have rested, on any other. The exclusive pretensions of the theological school of juris- prudence are specially inexcusable in Christian countries, seeing that Christianity, as a learned and ingenious French- man has observed, is "the first religion which does not pretend that law is dependent on it." 2 A natural conse- 1 The 119th Psalm is a long prayer for the indirect revelation of natural law. 2 Do Coulanges, Cite Antique, p. 518. 42 OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. quence of thus attempting to derive guidance from a source •which was not intended to afford it, has been the most won- derful diversity in the results arrived at by theological in- quirers. From absolute monarchy and patriarchal and hier- archal despotism, ^ to democracy, communism, and anarchy, there is no condition of political or social existence which has not sought to justify itself by an appeal to the theological method. 1 Nor is it wonderful that such should have been the case, for it is obvious that anything may be proved by a system which relies on documents compiled for other purposes, and which, by repudiating reason, has moreover freed itself from the fetters of an independent organ of interpretation. But though the teaching even of Christ was not intended to supersede the revelation through nature, and from the identity of their source in the divine, to say nothing of the human character of Christ himself, cannot possibly have contradicted it, it does not follow that Christianity did not correct and supplement the conceptions which mankind had hitherto entertained, or would otherwise have been in a con- dition to form, of natural law. To the fact of its having done so, the vast difference between our conceptions of the rights and duties of human beings and those entertained by heathen or Mahometan nations, or even by the classical nations of antiquity, bears witness. Wherever any secular doctrine is to be found, then, in the Holy Scriptures, the presumption — inas- much as God does nothing needlessly — is, that it communi- cates knowledge beyond what was attainable, or at any rate 1 For an enumeration of writers, v. Ahrens, p. 64. OF THE SCHOOLS OF JUBISPKUDENCE. 43 had, up to that period, been attained by the ordinary means of observation and reasoning, and it is therefore to be studied by the jurist with reverent diligence and care. When com- pared with the information which he obtains through the indirect channels of our knowledge, he will often find that the greater completeness of its dicta enables him to decide be- tween conflicting opinions, and even becomes the starting- point ~of new scientific investigations. Let me give a single instance of what I mean. The school of jurisprudence which sets out with the vindication of the rights of the individual, very frequently falls into the error of teaching us to prefer ourselves to our neighbours, and ends in justifying selfishness, either in the form of unjustifi- able aggrandisement, or equally unjustifiable non-intervention. The opposite school, which proposes to itself the inculcation of the duties of the individual, tells us to prefer our neigh- bour to ourselves, and often falls into asceticism and fanaticism, and recommends institutions and enactments by which our neighbour suffers even more than ourselves. But the Bible enjoins us to love our neighbour as ourselves ; and in thus proclaiming the exact reciprocity of rights and duties, direct revelation, whilst it confirms the ethical teaching of the Socratic school, indicates the direction in which scientific jurisprudence, by supplying a measure at once of rights and duties, yields, as we shall see hereafter, its last and most pre- cious fruits. Yet how universally human such a sentiment is, appears from such a fact as that the Brahmans reproached the Bud- dhists with having stolen the precept of universal benevolence 44 OE THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. from the Veda. 1 It was consequently a sentiment which both professed to hold, and at which we can scarcely imagine that either of them arrived otherwise than by what are com- monly called human means. Englishmen generally, including Mr Herbert Spencer, 2 as the latest exponent of national peculiarities, fall into the error of representing Christianity as exclusively "altruistic," and heathenism, as exhibited in the Greek and Eoman writers, as exclusively " egoistic." Both statements possess truth enough to suit them for popular and declamatory purposes, but, in any stricter sense, are quite erroneous. As regards Christian- ity," let the example which I have given above suffice. As regards Heathenism, I shall take an example far more remote from Christianity than the Greek and Eoman writers. In the Chinese classics, the " golden rule " is everywhere to be found. In the Confucian Analects, for example (Book V. Chap. XL), it is written : " Tsze Kung said, ' What I do not wish men to do to me, I also wish not to do to men.' The master (Con- fucius) said, 'Tsze, you have not attained to that.'" In a previous passage the doctrine of the master is thus explained : " The master went out, and the other disciples asked Tsang, saying, ' What do his words mean ? ' Tsang said, ' The doctrine of our master is to be true to the principles of our nature, and the benevolent exercise of them to others, — this, and nothing more.' " 3 Again, in the ' Doctrine of the Mean,' (p. 258), we find that this view was held not less firm- ly by the followers of Confucius than by himself. " When 1 Max Muller's History of Ancient Sanscrit Literature, p. 85. 2 Sociology, p. 184. 3 Chinese Classics, vol. i. pp. 33, 34, and 41. OP THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. 45 one cultivates to the utmost the principles of his nature, and exercises them on the principles of reciprocity, he is not far from the path. What you do not like when done to yourself, do not do to others." Passages to a similar effect might be quoted to almost any extent from the religious literature of the other oriental races with which scholars have made us acquainted during the last twenty years. 2d. The inductive or observational school (subjective and ob- jective). Apart from such knowledge as is conveyed to us directly, or which we ohtain by efforts of which we are unconscious, all that we know either of the law of nature, or of anything else, must be learned by the ordinary processes of conscious obser- vation and reasoning ; and, consequently, all the actual, or indeed possible, schools of jurisprudence, except in certain aspects the theological, belong, strictly speaking, to a single class — viz., the inductive or observational. Bacon did not limit the inductive method to physical in- quiries, but declared it to be the true method of scientific inquiry universally. Since the time of Descartes, at all events, its applicability to the study of man and his relations has scarcely been disputed ; and whether we prosecute it subject- ively or objectively, or both, the science of jurisprudence is an inductive science, just as much as chemistry or psycho- logy. But the inductive or observational school of juris- prudence, though its two branches rest on a common founda- tion, is a house divided against itself, the occupants of which have been in the habit of barring their doors against each other even more determinedly than against the theologians, 46 OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. with whom some of them l have even been willing to claim kindred. The inductive school as a whole, then, may be divided into two sections, — the subjective and the objective, or that which relies for its starting-point on the observation of internal phenomena, and that which regards external phenomena as all-sufficient. By including the sources on which they respectively rest amongst the sources of our science, we have already recognized the legitimacy both of the subjective and objective methods, and entered our protest against the claim of either of them to exclude the other. In support of this protest, and in illus- tration of their necessary dependence on each other, one con- sideration alone would seem to suffice — viz., that the supreme rule of life which we seek is neither a doctrine of rights nor a doctrine of duties, but a doctrine of the relation between rights and duties. But a relation can become intelligible to us only when we know both of the parties related ; and as rights have a subjective and duties an objective origin, a knowledge of the relation in which they stand to each other necessarily implies a reference both to subjective and objective sources of knowledge. These considerations, however, obvious as they seem, have not prevented men opposed to each other by personal and national genius from attempting to create two schools, each resting solely on one avenue of knowledge, and as such mutu- ally exclusive. 3d, The subjective, or so-called 'philosophical school. — The ex- 1 Paley, for example, who occupies the singularly incongruous position of a theological utilitarian. OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. 47 elusive claims of the study of our subjective nature (the per- sonal Ego) to enlighten us with reference to the ultimate law, rest on metaphysical speculations which have lost their hold on the country in which they originated, and are so little in accordance with the habits of thought which prevail amongst ourselves that, even if I possessed a clear understanding of them myself, which is far from being the case, I should be disposed to leave them to the experimental refutation which, I trust, the use of the double method of inquiry in the sub- sequent pages will supply. 1 One advantage over all other methods the subjective method (die Ableitung aus der reinen Vernunft) unquestionably possesses— viz., that to mankind in general, it alone is or can be direct. Our faculties of self- observation may indeed deceive us, but we cannot be deceived by another. We take nothing on external testimony, and thus avoid at least one source of error. But to my mind, the objec- tion just stated — that a relation cannot be known by a know- ledge of one of its terms — seems to be fatal to the exclusive claims of the subjective method, to an extent to which it is not, theoretically at least, to the objective method. An objective induction, sufficiently wide and sufficiently accurate, would yield a law of relations which might be assumed to include the subject, and thus to possess universal validity ; but inas- much as we could have no security that the individual was not exceptional, no observation of subjective phenomena, however exhaustive, could with equal safety be assumed to cover the 1 In saying this, I am far from questioning the necessity of starting from the Ego (infra, p. 53). On the contrary, I fully subscribe to the saying of Krause, that "im Gedanken des Ich, der Gedanke der Rechts wesentlich mitenthalten iind mitaufgegeben ist," p. 87. 48 OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. field of objective existence. Neither method, as we have said, would be trustworthy, apart from the other ; but in this point of view, at least, the objective method would offer many chances to one, whereas the subjective method would offer only one chance to many. The subjective method, on the other hand, would have the advantage in its starting-point ; for how could I ever come to know anything of my neighbour's rights except by contrasting them with my own ? The exclu- sive claims of the subjective method, however, for the reason I have mentioned, need scarcely be discussed in this country. 4:th, The objective, or sensational school. — The case is very different with the claims of objective experience, which for generations has seemed to the common English mind not only to supply the sole legitimate method of inquiry into the rule of life, but, by furnishing a rule of life in itself, to supersede the necessity of the inquiry altogether. The utilitarian doctrine thus occupies two positions, from the one to the other of which it is continually shifting, but which require to be carefully distinguished, seeing that in the one it is, and in the other it is not, entitled to take rank as a legitimate method, and to claim a place in the science of jurisprudence. 1. In the first and most ambitious position which it as- sumes, the doctrine of utility claims to furnish us with a test of the quality of our actions, to constitute in itself a rule of life, and thus to supply the place of the law of nature, the reality of which it denies. Of the confusion of thought in- volved in this claim we have instantaneous proof if we reply to it by the question, " Useful for what ? " Actions are means, not ends, and their quality can be tested only by reference OP THE SCHOOLS OP JURISPRUDENCE. 49 to some final end or object (re\os) which they seek to attain, the measure of their value, being the approach which they make to its attainment. If the rule be, "follow virtue," "follow pleasure," "follow nature," the realization of what- ever we may choose to characterize as "virtue," or "pleas- ure," or " nature," is the object of the rule ; and the value of each particular action will be greater or less in pro- portion to the extent to which it accomplishes this realiza- tion. But " follow utility " is a rule which has no object — a fingerpost that points nowhere ! So far, then, from possess- ing the merit so often claimed for it, of supplying the simplest of all tests of conduct, the utilitarian system furnishes no test at all, and has consequently to accept its test from some one or other of the systems which it repudiates. It is for this reason that it is held by persons of the most opposite char- acter and opinions, who deduce from it the most opposite re- sults. In Mr Bentbam's hands, and those of the majority of his conscious followers, its object has been "happiness," so defined as to rise little above animal enjoyment, and utili- tarianism has thus been equivalent, not to eudaemonism in the Aristotelian sense, but to hedonism in the sense of the later Epicureans. Stung by the reproaches to which so ignoble an object and so degrading a system exposed their adherents, Mr Mill, in his later writings, has sublimated utilitarianism into something that might be called transcendental-eudaemonism. 1 1 In an interesting passage in his Autobiography, p. 189, he even speaks of the " highest realizable ideal of human life " as the true object of human endeavour, though how this ideal should have possessed such value in the eyes of one who regarded " the pretended perfection of the order of nature and of the universe " as a " superstition," is not explained. Neither do we learn the means of its dis- D 50 OP THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. The improvement as regards the object is great. But he has not improved the pretensions of utilitarianism to the character of a self-determining system, or its claim to any higher position than that of a method of inquiry into the objects of life and the means of attaining them, or, in other words, into the law of nature — a position which was never denied to it by any one, except perhaps a subjective idealist. Let us consider its merits, then, in this latter aspect. 2. Viewed as a method of inquiry into the law of nature, utilitarianism is merely a somewhat unphilosophical application of the method of external observation, — a method which, in the hands of scientific inquirers, has assumed two leading forms. (a) The statistical, or empirical, which is chiefly known in this country, and of which Mr Herbert Spencer is a brilliant disciple ; and — (l) The historical, of which, in its primary phase, Hugo, Savigny, 1 and the late Sir George Cornewall Lewis may be covery. If nature and the universe were imperfect it could not come from within, for human nature could have no perfect ideal to reveal. Neither could it come from without, seeing that direct revelation was repudiated as a still grosser super- stition. Disbelief in the order of nature is intelligible, if to nature we attach the lower sense in which the opponents of Stoicism have always taken it. To believe in nature in this sense, in a world in which there is so much relative sin and phenomenal misery, would involve a denial of the distinction between right and wrong. But to disbelieve in the order of the universe, or in nature in the sense in which it is identified with the order of the universe, is the ne plus ultra of scepticism. Even Strauss, in his last and wildest manifestations of unbelief, believed in the " Kosmic conception;" and to abandon Kosmos is surely to part company with reason altogether — in other words, to go mad. To talk of " reverence " after that is to use a word which can have no possible meaning. 1 A statement of the very sound position which Savigny ultimately took up, and which differs considerably from that which is still popularly ascribed to him, will be found in the introduction to Mr Guthrie's excellent translation of the OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. 51 regarded as the leading representatives, and which the specu- lative mind of Hegel developed in new directions. Theoretically, it is difficult to deny the pretensions of ex- ternal observation, when directed both to contemporaneous and past events, to the character even of an independent method, because it is possible to imagine an intelligent being, conver- sant with human life and action, and yet not human. Such a being could, of course, have no subjective revelation of human nature, or of the laws by which that nature is governed ; and yet he might, to a certain extent, become acquainted with human nature and its laws by the objective revelation of events — by external observation of actions and their results. To an omniscient mind the a posteriori method would, no doubt, yield conclusions universally valid, and we cannot speak of its application as impossible. For a human being to exclude his own nature from his consideration whilst investigating human nature in general, I believe to be impossible.. To him the subjective is the only possible starting-point. And as he is himself the mirror in which he beholds the universe, his aban- donment of the subjective point of view must always be partial, and is generally illusory. But some approximation to such a one-sided position is perhaps attainable ; and to the utilitarian who lays claim to it, all that I can object is, that his method is. needlessly imperfect. If he is a human being, he is wantonly throwing away the opportunities which the subjective study of his own human nature affords him of becoming, acquainted with human nature in general, and its laws. He is urging, moreover, treatise on Private International Law, whiuh forms the 8th vol. of the System des Heutigen RBmischen Eeehts, p. 12. 52 OP THE SCHOOLS OF JUEISPKUDENCE. on his own behalf, an exclusive claim which he certainly would not concede to his opponent, who, with equal truth, might allege that, as humanity as a whole is present in the nature of each individual, the study of the Ego is alone sufficient to reveal it. When the claims of the method of external observation are not pushed to this length, it has been eminently fruitful in results ; and those who believed that they were demonstrating the non-existence of natural law have often been amongst its best expositors. Still, several very serious practical objections apply to it, which have been stated with great force by its opponents in Germany. A. Supposing our acquaintance with recent events — the immediate effect of recent enactments, we shall say — to be accurate in point of fact, it is with difficulty that we appreciate them, or, in other words, determine their " utility " for the attainment of any given end whatever, for two reasons — (a) Because their ultimate consequences are still in the future ; and — t (b) Because we see them through the distorting medium of our own feelings and interests. B. As regards events long past, our information is seldom complete, and even then it is coloured by a triple medium — (a) That through which the narrator saw it. (&) That through which he intended that we should see it. (c) That through which our own passions, prejudices, igno- rances, and those of our own time, permit us to see it. 0. From diversity of circumstances, it is for the most part inapplicable as a rule of present conduct. D. Humanity has not yet culminated, and its absolute laws OF THE SCHOOLS OF JURISPRUDENCE. 53 cannot therefore be revealed by the study of its previous history. On the assumption that it is progressive, the experience of the present must be more instructive than that of any former period ; and, in this point of view at all events, the facts of statistics are of greater value than the facts of history. The remark of Lord Bacon is, however, to be borne in mind, that the most useful examples are those taken from times most resembling our own, and that these are not always the times that are nearest to us. 1 E. But the leading objection to external observation in all its forms, as an exclusive source of knowledge, is that we can- not begin with it. 2 In whatever light " facts " may be viewed by the historian or statistician, 3 to the jurist they are not ends but means ; and external facts are means which he cannot use till he has gained a starting-point, and acquired a standard which they cannot supply. After we know what our nature craves, and what God wills that it should aspire to, there is scarcely a fact, however insignificant, of observation or experience, which may not furnish precious suggestions for the realization of these objects. Nay, farther, even as regards these objects themselves, it is most true that " there is a light which shines on the ways of God out of a better knowledge, even of man's ways." 4 But the light which man's ways afford is lighted within him, and the reflected light which shines from without has reference far more to the concrete and variable, than to the abstract and permanent element of law. The science of jurisprudence, like charity, must " begin at home ; " 1 De Jvstitia Universale, Aphorism xxiv. 3 Krause, p. 91. As to the scientific significance of Statistic, o. Ahrens, vol. i. p. 5, note. 4 Reign of Law, p. 5. 54 OP THE AUTONOMY OP HUMAN NATURE. and the proper answer to the empiric is that which St Luke 1 tells us our Lord made to the Pharisees when they asked Him when the kingdom of God should come. " The kingdom of God cometh not with observation: neither shall they say, Lo here I or, lo there ! for, behold, the kingdom of God is within you." 2 CHAPTEE III. OF THE AUTONOMY OF HUMAN NATURE. The science of the law' of nature divides itself substantially into three inquiries — 1st, Is the nature of man autonomous ; is he a kosmic or a chaotic creature, or, in other words, is man "a law unto himself"? 2d, If so, in what manner is this law revealed to him ? 3d, What is the law which man's nature imposes on him, or binds him to impose on himself ? Each of these branches admits of being prosecuted, and has always been prosecuted in point of fact by competent investi- gators, 3 more or less systematically, both by the philosophical and the historical methods. In so far as it seems possible, we shall not fail to avail ourselves of this double avenue to truth ; but in seeking a response to the first question, we shall listen in the first place to what our nature tells us directly. 1 xvii. 20, 21. a ' ' The master said, ' The path is not far from man. When men try to pursue a course which is far from the common indications of consciousness, this course cannot be considered The Path.' "— Legge's Chinese Classics, vol. i. p. 257. * Gulielmi Grotii Enchiridion, Index, p. 3. OF THE AUTONOMY OF HUMAN NATURE. 55 The direct or subjective revelations which our nature makes to us of its legislative character, appear to be presented in the following order: — 1st, Our nature asserts its existence, and vindicates its assertion. Life being the root at once of our rights and our obligations, the knowledge that life is a fact must -of necessity be the first step in the science of jurisprudence, as of every other branch of the science of man. Till we know that we are, we can neither know how we are, nor inquire how we ought to be. But our existence is a fact, which each of us must ascertain for himself ; and the knowledge of which, by another, we can only assume. If a man tells me that he is not conscious that he lives, I can no more contradict him than if he tells me that he is not conscious that he loves. So far, the primary dictum of consciousness is on a footing of equality with all the subsequent dicta. But it differs from them in this respect, that neither its reality nor its veracity can be denied, or even doubted. If. my neighbour tells me that he is conscious that he does not love, I am bound to believe him ; but if he tells me that he is conscious that he does not live, or thinks that he does not live, or doubts, whether he lives or not, his assertion disproves itself. "The very statement of doubt," as Dr Adam Fergusson has said, " is a dogmatic assumption of personal existence and thought." x Nor does the accuracy of this assumption admit of question any more than the fact of the assumption ; for, in so far as its first dictum is concerned, the fact that consciousness truly 1 Fergusson's Principles of Moral and Political Science, vol. i. p. 79. 56 OF THE AUTONOMY OF HUMAN NATURE. testifies, is proof enough that it testifies truly. "To doubt of the reality of that of which we are conscious," says Sir W. Hamilton, " is impossible, for as we can only doubt through consciousness, to doubt of consciousness is to doubt of con- sciousness by consciousness. If, on the one hand, we affirm the reality of the doubt, we thereby explicitly affirm the reality of consciousness, and contradict our doubt ; if, on the other hand, we deny the reality of consciousness, we implicitly deny the reality of our denial itself." 1 2d, Our nature guarantees the veracity of its testimony with reference to its qualities. It is true that, without incurring the contradiction which the denial of the primary assertion of subjective being implies, we may deny the veracity of every subsequent assertion of consciousness. But such denial cannot possibly admit of proof, because the truth of the denial can never rest on higher testimony than the truth of the assertion. If the consciousness which tells me that I love be fallacious, the consciousness which tells me that I doubt or deny that I love may be fallacious too. It thus appears that if we deny the truth of any single dictum of consciousness the reality of which as a phenomenon is admitted, the whole fabric of truth is shaken. " If our immediate internal experience could possibly deceive us," said Leibnitz, "there would no longer be any truth of fact, or any truth of reason." 2 Consciousness, or subjective nature, being thus a living, 1 Sir W. Hamilton's Lect. on Metaph., vol. i. p. 276aiv i?xow» piaXKov tb A