Mtia |?orfe ^tatc College of ^Qtimltme ^t Cornell Winibetsitp Htbrarj* Cornell University Library BF 133.W96 1896a Outlines of Psy*^'^'''"^)?,',,,,,,!!!! 3 1924 014 474 534 Cornell University Library The original of tiiis book is in tine Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924014474534 OUTLINES OF PSYCHOL O GY BY WILHELM WUNDT TKANSLATBD WITH THE COOPERATION OF THE AUTHOR BY OHAELES HDBBAED JODD, Ph. D. INSTEUCTOE IN WESLETAN UNIVlEESIXr LEIPZIG PUBLISHED BY WILHELM ENGELMANN LONDON I NEW YOKK WILLIAMS & HOEGATE | GTJSTAV E. STECHEET 1897. Br d- C2l (^x^ y^ TMNSLATOE'S PEEFACE. 1 HIS translation has been made with the cooperation of the author, who has not only contributed many valuable criticisms and suggestions in regard to terminology, but has read all the proof-sheets as they were being prepared for the press. A few verbal changes have been introduced into the text with a view to making the discussion somewhat clearer. The difficulties that arise in choosing English equivalents for many German words, are too familiar to require detailed discussion. The translator has derived assistance in this respect from a comparison of other standard translations, especially the English versions of Falckenberg's '-History of Modern Philosophy", Wundt's "Lectures on Human and Animal Psychology", and Kiilpe's "Outlines of Psychology"'. The terminology here employed differs, however, at many points from that used in the works mentioned. A glossary of the principal terms has been added for the benefit of those familiar with the German. The translation of the word "Perception" is unusual. If it were translated 'perception' it would be easily confused, especially in its verbal forms, with the only possible equivalent of "Wahrnehmtmg", '■^ivah.r- nehmen", and '•'■ Ansdiauung" . Since the process referred to IV Iranslaior's Preface. by '■'■Perception^'' is so entirely different from that indicated by the English word perception, it seemed best to employ a word whose signification is not so fixed. Apprehension was, accordingly, nsed, and the danger of confusing it with the translation of "Auffassung" was for the most part avoided by using other equivalents for the latter. The thanks of the translator are due to the author for his courtesy throughout the progress of the work. Mr. G. H. Stempel has kindly aided in the task of preparing the proof- sheets for the press. Middletown, September, 1896. C> H. J. AUTHOE'S PEEFACE. 1 HIS book has been written primarily for the purpose of furnishing my students with a brief manual to supplement the lectures on Psychology. At the same time it aims to give the wider circle of scientific scholars who are interested in psychology, either for its own sake or for the sake of its applications, a systematic survey of the fundamentally im- portant results and doctrines of modern psychology. In view of this double purpose, I have limited myself in detailing facts to that which is most important, or to the examples that serve most directly the ends of illustration, and have omitted entirely those aids to demonstration and experiment which are properly made use of in the lecture-room. The fact that I have based this treatise on the doctrines that I have come to hold as valid after long years of labor in this field, needs no special justification. Still, I have not neglected to point out both in a general characterization (Introduction § 2), and with references in detail, the chief theories that differ from the one here presented. ^ The relation in which this book stands to my earlier psychological works will be apparent after what has been said. The " Cfrundxiige der physiologisefien Psychologie" aims to bring the means employed by the natural sciences, VI Author's Preface. especially by physiology, into the service of psychology, and to give a critical presentation of the experimental methods of psychology, which have developed in the last few decades, together with their chief results. This special problem ren- dered necessary a relative subordination of the general psy- chological points of view. The second, revised edition of the "Vorlesungen uber die Menscheiv- und Thierseele" ') (the first edition has long been out of date) seeks to give a more popular account of the character and purpose of experimental psj'chology, and to discuss from the position thus defined those psychological questions which are also of more general philosophical importance. While the treatment in the "Grund- xilge" is, accordingly, determined, in the main, by the relations of psychology to physiology, and the treatment in the " Vm-- lesungen"' by philosophical interests-, this Outlines aims to present psychology in its own proper coherency, and in the systematic order that the nature of the subject-matter seems to me to require. In doing this, however, it takes up only what is most important and essential. It is my hope that this book will not be an entirely unwelcome addition even for those readers who are familiar with my earlier works as well as with the discussion of the "Logik der Psychologie''' in my "Logik der Geisteswisseoischaften" (Logik, 2. Aufl. II, 2. Abth.). I have not thought it necessary to repeat here the refer- ences to psychological works, in view of the fact that I have given such references very fully under the various heads in my " Grundxiige''\ The reader who wishes to make a more 1) Translated by Prof. J. E. Creighton and Prof. E. B. Titchener: "Lectures on Human and Animal Psychology'^ Swan Sonnenschein"& Co., 1894. Author's Prefcu:4}. VII thorough study of any particular question will turn in any case to the more elaborate work. For the literature that has appeared in this department since the fourth edition of the " Gi-undzilge^'' (1893), the reader has but to refer to the last volumes of the various periodicals devoted to psychology: to the "Philosophische Studieii", the ^^Zeitschrift fur Psyehologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane" , the "American Journal of Psychohgy", and the "Psychological Revieiv". The last three contain also reviews of the current literature in psy- chology. As a recent addition to these the "Psychologischen Arbeiten" edited by E. Kraepelin and devoted especially to individual characterology and practical psychology, may be mentioned. Leipzig, January, 1896. W. Wundt. CONTENTS. INTEODUCTION. page § K Problem of Psychology 1 1. Older definitions. 2. Psychology as the science of immediate experience. 3. Relation to the mental and to the natural sciences. § 2. General Theories of Psychology 6 1. Metaphysical psychology: spiritualistic and material- istic, dualistio and monistic systems. 2. Empirical psy- chology: two principles for the classification of its varieties. 3. Psychology of the inner sense. 4. Psychology as the science of immediate experience. 5. Descriptive psychology: faculty-psychology. 6. Explanatory psychology: intellec- tualistic and voluntaristic psychology. 7. Intellectualistic trends : logical theory and association-psychology. 8. Er- roneous attribution of the nature of things to ideas, in intellectualistic psychology. 9. Voluntaristic psychology. 10. Governing principles of the following treatise. § 3. Methods of Psychology 18 ]. Relation of experiment and observation in general. 2. Application to psychology: particular significance of ex- perimental methods for psychology. 3. Pure observation m psychology. Analysis of mental products: social psy- chology. § 4. General Survey of the Subject 24 1. Analytic and synthetic problem of psychology. Psy- chical elements. 2. The various synthetic problems in order: psychical compounds, interconnections, and developments. 3. Laws of psychical phenomena and their causality. X Contents. I. PSYCHICAL ELEMENTS. page § 5. Chief Forms and General Attributes of Psy- chical Elements 28 1. Discovery of psyolaioal elements through abstraction. 2. Two kinds of psychical elements: sensations and simple feelings. 3. Elementary nature and specific character of psychical processes not identical. 4. Common attributes of psychical elements : quality and intensity. 5. Homogeneous and complex, one-dimensional, two-dimensional, and many- dimensional systems of quality. 6. Distinguishing charac- teristics of sensational and aflfective elements. 6a. Remarks on the history of the concepts sensation and feeling. § 6. Pure Sensations - 38 1. The concept pure sensation. 2. Rise of sensations. Sense-stimuli. 3. Physiological substrata of the sensational systems. Mechanical and chemical senses. 4. The so-called law of specific energy of nerves. 5. The law of parallelism of changes in sensation and in physiological stimulation. A. Sensations of the general sense 45 6. Definition of the general sense. Sensational systems of this sense. 7. Attributes and differences of the various parts of the organ of the general sense. 8. The fobr systems of the general sense in detail. B. Sensations of sound 48 9. Simple noise-sensations. 10. Tone-sensations. 11. The system of tonal sensations. C. Sensations of smell and taste 52 12. Sensations of smell. 12a. Classes of olfactory qualities. Reciprocal neutralization of odors. 13. Sensa- tions of taste. The four primary qualities. 13 a. Mixture and neutralization of gustatory stimuli. D. Sensations of light 54 14. Sensations of achromatic light. 15. Sensation of chromatic light. 16. Saturation of colors. 17. Brightness of colors. 18. Relations between sensations of achromatic and sensations of chromatic brightness. 19. Three-dimensional system of light-sensations. 20. The four principal sensations. 21. Relations between sensation and stimulus for the visual sense. 22. Complementary colors and color-mixtures. 23. The Contents. XI \ three fundamental colors. 24. Inference of tlie photochemical character of retinal stimulation. 25. Persistence of the stimu- lation. 26. Light-contrasts and color-contrasts. 26 a. Phy- siological theories. § 7. Simple Feelings 74 1. General characterization of the simple feelings. 2. Sense-feelings (affective tones of sensations). 3. Relations between changes in sensations and feelings. 4. Influence of qualitative sensational changes on the affective state. 5. Influence of sensational intensity on the feelings. 6.' Great variety of the simple feelings. 7. The three chief directions of feelings. 8. Examples of the various forms. 9. Inter- connection of the three affective directions with the course of psychical processes. 10. Physiological concomitants of feelings. 11. Special relation to the pulse. 11a. Physiological scheme of the activity of the pulse. II. PSYCHICAL COMPOUNDS. § 8. Definition and Classification of Psychical Com- pounds 90 1. Definition of the concept psychical compound. 2. Com- position of the psychical compounds. 3. Classification of the same. § 9. Intensive Ideas 93 1. General attributes of intensive ideas. Fusion. 2. Survey of the intensive fusions in the various sensational spheres. 3. Intensive auditory ideas : the single clang. 4. Conditions for the rise of complete clang-fusion. 5. Compound clangs. 6. Difference-tones. 7. Noise. 7 a. Theories of clang-analysis and tonal fusion. § 10. Spacial Ideas 102 1. General concept of extensive ideas. Special charac- teristics of spacial ideas. 2. Psychological problem of anal- ■ ysis of spacial ideas. 3. Kinds of spacial ideas. A. Spacial touch-ideas 104 4. Localization of touch-stimuli. Qualitative local signs. 5. Else of spacial touch-ideas in normal cases with vision. 0. The tactual sense of the blind. 7. Theory of spacial ideas of the blind. 8. General character of the space-fusions of XII Contents. page touch. 9. Fusions with memory-elements. 10. Ideas of one's own movements when vision is present. 11. Ideas of one's own movements in the case of congenital blindness. 12. Ideas of the position and movement of the whole body. 12a. Theo- ries of the rise of spacial ideas of touch. B. Spacial sight-ideas 115 13. General character of visual ideas. 14. General factors of such ideas. a. The location of the elements of a visual idea in relation to one another 116 15. Localization in the field of vision. 16. Keenness of localization in different regions of the field of vision. Direct and indirect vision. 17. Ocular movements. 18. Relation of ocular movements to localization. 19. Constant optical illusions of direction and magnitude due to the laws of ocular movements. 20. Variable illusions in direction and magnitude due to the universal attributes of voluntary movements. 21. Distances in the field of vision not dependent on the proximity of retinal elements to one another. 22. Two elements of spacial vision. Necessity of assuming retinal local signs and empirical demonstration of the same. 23. General theory of spacial vision. b. The location of visual ideas in relation to the ideating subject . 130 24. Point of orientation in binocular vision. Direction of the line of orientation. 25. Idea of the length of the line of orientation. 26. Discrimination of far and near. 27. Per- ception of points at different distances. 28. Theory of binocular ideas of three dimensions. 29. Varying conditions for ideas of depth. Influence of lines of fixation. 30. Bi- nocular double images and localization in depth. c. Relations between the location of the elemtents in regard to one another and their location in regard to the subject .... 136 31. Erect vision. 32. Surface of the field of vision. 32 a. The complex local signs of depth and binocular paral- lax. 33. The stereoscope. 34. Monocular ideas of depth. Influence of accommodation. 35. The elements of perspec- tive. 35 a. Survey of the theories. § 11. Temporal Ideas 142 1. General conditions for temporal ideas. 2. Charac- teristics of temporal as distinguished from spacial order. 2 a. The forms of temporal ideas and their names. Contents. XIII page A. Temporal toiiclt-ideas 144 3. Relation of the mechanical attributes of the limbs to the temporal ideas. 4. The rhythmical tactual move- ments. 5. The tactual ideas of beats. B. Temporal auditory ideas 148 6. Favoring attributes of the auditory sense. Continuous and discontinuous rhythms. 7. Analysis of simple ideas of beats. 8. Changes in the rhythmical perception through various objective conditions. 9. Subjective conditions of rhythmical time-ideas. C. General conditions for temporal ideas 153 10. Specific character of temporal ideas. 11. The inner fixation-point. 12. The continuous S.ovr and one-dimensional character of time. 13. General theory of temporal ideas. The temporal signs. 13 a. Geometrical representation of time. Nativistic and genetic theories. § 12. Composite Feelings 158 1. Affective processes in general. 2. Character of inten- sive affective combinations. 3. Component feelings: and resul- tant partial feelings and total feelings. Interlacing of the affective elements. 3 a. Exemplification with musical com- pound clangs. 4. Common feelings. 4a. Deficiency of the physiological theories of common feelings. 5. Pleasurable and unpleasurable feelings. 6. Contrast-feelings. 7. Elementary aesthetic feelings. Agreeableness and disagreeableness. 8. Intensive and extensive feelings. 9. Intensive feelings: color-combinations and clang-combinations. 10. Extensive feelings: feelings from form and those from rhythm. 11. Psy- chological theory of composite feelings. 12. Principle of the unity of the affective state. § 13. Emotions 169 1. Definition of emotions. 2. Names of emotions. 3. General course of emotions. 4. Physical concomitants: expressive movements. 5, Classification of the expressive move- ments. 5 a. Symptomatica! significance of these movements. 6. Changes in the pulse and respiration. Quiet, sthenic and asthenic, rapid and sluggish emotions. 7. Connection of changes in innervation with the formal attributes of emotions. 8. Intensification of the emotions through the physical concomitants. 9. Psychological classification of the page emotions. 10. Emotional forms of the aflfective qualities. Pleasurable and unpleasurable, exciting and depressing, straining and relaxing emotions. 11. Names of emotions. 12. Emotional forms of affeotiye intensities: weak and strong emotions. 13. Forms of occurrence: sudden, gradu- ally rising, interihittent emotions. 13a. Predominating significance of the affective qualities for the discrimination of emotions. § 14. Volitional Pkooesses 183 1. Relation to the eniotions. 2. External volitional acts. 3. Relation to the feelings. 4. Motives of volition. 5. Devel- opment of volition. Impulsive acts. 6. Voluntary and selec- tive acts. 7. Resolution and decision. The feeling of activity. 8. Weakening of emotions through intellectual processes. 9. Development of internal volitional acts. 10. Retrogra- dation. Volitional processes become mechanical. Purposive character of reflex movements. 10 a. Critique of theories of -will. 1]. Temporal course of volitions. Reaction-experi^ ments. Sensorial and muscular reactions. 12. Compound reactions. 13. Reactions become automatic. 13 a. General significance of reaction-experiments. Chronometric ap- paratus. ni. INTERCONNECTION OP PSYCHICAL COMPOUNDS. §15. Consciousness and Attention 201 1. The concept consciousness. 2. Physiological con- ditions. 2a. Localization of psychical functions in the brain. 3. Simultaneous and successive interconnections of con- scious processes. Grade of consciousness. The sinking of psychical processes into the state of unconsciousness. 4. Apperception and attention. 5, Degree of clearness of contents of consciousness. 6. Scope of attention and of consciousness. 6 a. Methods for the investigation of momen- tary states of consciousness. 7. Affective influence of con- scious contents which are merely apprehended. 8. Feeling of apperception. Passive and active apperception. 8 a. Ex- perimental methods. 9. Interconnection of processes of attention and of volition. 10. The concepts subject and object. 11. Self-consciousness. 12. Further development of the discrimination between subject and object. 12a. Critique Coiiienfs. XV page of the dualistic hypotheses. 13, Transition to the various psychical processes of combination. § 16. Associations 224 1. History of the concept of association. 2. The ordinarily so-called associations complex products of elementary as- sociative processes. 3. Chief forms of elementary associa- tive processes. A. Simultaneous associations 227 4. Chief forms: assimilation and complication. a. Assimilations . . 228 5. General character of assimilations. 6. Auditory as- similations. 7. Assimilations in the sphere of intensive affective processes. 8. Spacial assimilations of touch. 9. As- similations in the case of visual ideas. 10. Psychological analysis of assimilative processes. 11. Differences among these processes. Illusion. b. Camplications 231 12. Attributes and chief forms of complications. B. Successive associations 235 13. Interconnection with the assimilations. 14. General character of successive associations. 14 a. Serial association. a. Sensible recognition and cognition .. .. 237 15. Attributes and differences of these processes. 15a. Ex- perimental investigation of the influence of complications. 16. Passage from simultaneous to successive processes. 17. Differences between processes of recognition and those of cognition. b. Memory-processes 241 IS. Rise out of processes of recognition. 18a. Inter- connection and general significance of memory-processes. 19. Stages of a memory-process: mixed forms between recognition and remembering. 19a. The so-called "mediate association" 20. Memory-processes based on repeated re- cognitions and cognitions. 21. Elements of memory- processes. 22. Character of memory-ideas. 23. The concept memory. § 17. Appeeceptive Combinations 248 1. Subjective attributes of apperceptive combinations. 2. Relation to associations. 3. General classification of apperceptive combinations. XVI Contents. page A. Simple apperceptive functions (relating and comparing) 250 4. The relating process. 5. The comparing process. 6. Discovery of agreements and differences, "i- Measure- ments of psychical elements and compounds. 8. Difference between psychical and physical measurement. 9. Methods of psychical measurement. 10. Stimulus -threshold and difference-threshold. Weber's law. 10 a. Weber's law in detail and the methods for its demonstration. 11. Psy- chological contrast-phenomena. Interconnnection with the physiological contrasts in vision. 1 3. Contrast between im- pression and expectation. B. Complex apperceptive functions (synthesis and analysis) . 260 14. Aggregate ideas. 15. Psychological analysis of the activity of "imagination". 16. Psychological character of the activity of "understanding". 17. Psychological character of concepts. 18. Imagination and understanding as indi- vidual traits. Talent. § 18. Psychical States 267 1. General conditions of abnormal states. 2. Changes in elements. 3. Changes in ideational compounds: hallu- cinations and illusions. 4. Abnormities .in affective and volitional processes: states of depression and exaltation. 5. Abnormities of consciousness. 6. Changes in association and in apperception. 7. Dreams. 8. Hypnosis. 9. Relations between sleep and hypnosis. 9 a. Physiological theories of sleep, dreams, and hypnosis. IV. PSYCHICAL DEVELOPMENTS. 19. Psychical Attributes of Animals 276 1. General remarks on the pryohical development of animals. 2. Bate of animal development and one-sidedness of their functions. 3. Animal instincts. 4. Development of the instincts. 5. Genetic relation of animals to man in regard to mental development. 5 a. Deficiency of deter- mination of the line of division in regard to psychological attributes. Theories of instincts. Contents. XVII page § 20. Psychical Development of the Child .... 283 1. Development of sense-functions. 2. Psychical ele- ments in the individual development. 3. Rise of spacial ideas. 4. Development of temporal ideas. 5. Associations and apperceptive combinations. 6. Development of self- consciousness. 7. Development of will, 8. Development of speech. 9. Activity of the child's imagination. Play-im- pulse. 10. Functions of the understanding. 10 a. Mistakes in child-psychology. _ § 21. Development of mental Communities 296 I. Differences betv^een human and animal communities. 2. Products of human communities. A. Speech 298 4. Gesture-language. 4. General development of articu- late language. 5. Changes in sound and meaning. 6. Psy- chological significance of the order of words. B. Myths ' 303 7. Personifying apperception. 8. General conditions for its development. 9. Animism and fetishism. 10. The nature- myth. C. Oustoms 306 II. Relations to Myths. 12. Changes in the meaning of customs. 13. Differentiation into customs, laws, and morality. 14. Collective consciousness and collective will. 14 a. Critical remarks. V. PSYCHICAL CAUSALITY AND ITS LAWS. 22. Concept of Mind 310 1. The general principle of causality. 2. The concepts matter, force, and energy, 3. Mind as the supplementary concept of psychology. 4. The concept of a mind-substance. 5. Materialistic and spiritualistic concepts of mind. 0. The mind as an actuality. 7. Scientific development of the con- cept of actuality. 8. The problem of the relation between body and mind. 9. The principle of psycho -physical parallelism. 10. Necessity of an independent psychical causality. XVni Contents. page § 23. Psychological Laws of Relation 321 1. The three general laws of relation. 2. The law of psychical resultants. 3. The principle of creative synthesis. 4. Increase of psychical, and constancy of physical, energy. 5. The law of psychical relations. 6. The law of psychical contrasts. 7. Relation of the law of contrasts to the first two laws. § 24. Psychological Laws of Development 325 1 . The three general laws of development. 2. The law of mental growth. 3. The law of heterogony of ends. 4. The law of development towards opposites. Glossary 329 Index 336 INTRODUCTIOK § 1. PROBLEM OF PSYCHOLOGY. 1. Two definitions of psychology have been the most prominent in the history of this science. According to one, psychology is the "science of mind" : psychical processes are regarded as phenomena from which it is possible to infer the nature of an underlying metaphysical mind-sub- stance. According to the other, psychology is the "science of inner experience": psychical processes are here looked upon as belonging to a specific form of experience, which is readily distinguished by the fact that its contents are known through "introspection", or the "inner sense" as it has been called to distinguish it from sense-perception through the outer senses. Neither of these definitions, however, is satisfactory to the psychology of to-day. The first, or metaphysical, defini- tion belongs to a period of development that lasted longer in this science than in others. But it is here too forever left behind, since psychology has developed into an empirical discipline, operating with methods of its own; and since the "mental sciences" have gained recognition as a great de- partment of scientific investigation, distinct from the sphere of the natural sciences, and requiring as a general ground- work an independent psychology, free from all metaphysical theories. WnxDT, Psychology. 1 2 Introduction. The second, or empirical, definition, which sees in psychol- ogy a ''science of inner experience", is inadequate because it may give rise to the misunderstanding that psychology has to do with objects totally different from those of the so- called "outer experience". It is, indeed, true that there are contents of experience which belong in the spTiere of psycho- logical investigation, but are not to be found among the objects and processes studied by natural science: such are our feehngs, emotions, and decisions. On the other hand, there is not a single natural phenomenon that may not, from a different point of view, become an object of psychol- ogy. A stone, a plant, a tone, a ray of light, are, as nat- ural phenomena, objects of mineralogy, botany, physics, etc.; I but in so far as they arouse in us ideas, they are at the same time objects of psychology. For psychology seeks to account for the genesis of these ideas, and for their rela- tions both to other ideas and to those psychical processes not referred to external objects, such as feeHngs, volitions, etc. There is, then, no such thing as an "inner sense" which can be regarded as an organ of introspection, and thus dis- tinct from the outer senses, or organs of objective perception. Ideas, whose attributes psychology seeks to investigate, arise through the outer senses no less than do the sense-percep- tions on which natural science is based ; while the subjective activities of feeling, emotion, and volition, which are neglected in natural science, are not known through special organs, but are directly and inseparably connected with the ideas referred to external objects. 2. It follows, then, that the expressions outer and inner experience do not indicate different objects, but different points of view from which we start in the consideration and scientific treatment of a unitary experience. We are natur- ally led to these points of view, because every concrete ex- § 1. Problem of Psychohgy. 3 perience immediately divides into two factms: into a content presented to us, and our apprehension of this content. We call the first of these factors objects of experience, the second experiencing subject. This division points out two directions for the treatment of experience. One is that of the natural sciences, which concern themselves with the objects of ex- perience, thought of as independent of the subject. The other is that of psychology, which investigates the whole content of experience in its relations to the subject and in its attri- butes derived directly from the subject. The standpoint of natural science may, accordingly, be designated as that of mediate experience, since it is possible only after abstracting from the subjective factor present in all actual experience; the standpoint of psychology, on the other hand, may be designated as that of immediate experience, since it purposely does away with this abstraction and all its consequences. 3. The assignment of this problem to psychology, maldng it an empirical science coordinate with natural science and supplementary to it, is justified by the method of all the merited sciences, for which psychology furnishes the basis. All ; of these sciences, philology, history, and political and social j science, have for their subject-matter immediate experience as determined by the interaction of objects with the knowing and acting subject. None of the mental sciences employs the abstractions and hypothetical supplementary concepts of natural science ; quite otherwise, they all accept ideas and the accompanying subjective activities as immediate reality. The effort is then made to explain the single components of this reality through their mutual interconnections. This method of psychological interpretation employed in the mental sciences, must also be the mode of procedure in psychology itself, being the method required by the subject-matter of psychol- ogy, the immediate reality of experience. 1* 4 Introduction. 3 a. Since natural science investigates the content of ex- perience after abstracting from tte experiencing subject, its problem is usually stated as the acquirement of "knowledge of the outer world". By the expression outer world is meant the sum total of all the objects presented in experience. The problem of psychology has sometimes been correspondingly defined as "self-knowledge of the subject". This definition is, however, inadequate because the interaction of the subject with the outer world and with other similar subjects is just as much a prob- lem of psychology as are the attributes of the single subject. Furthermore, the expression can easily be interpreted to mean that outer world and subject are separate components of ex- perience or that they can at least be distinguished as inde- pendent contents of experience, whereas, in truth, outer ex- perience is always connected with the apprehending and knowing functions of the subject, and inner experience always contains ideas from the outer world as indispensable components. This interconnection is the necessary result of the fact that in reality experience is not a mere juxtaposition of different ele- ments, but a single organized whole which requires in each of its components the subject that apprehends the content, and the objects that are presented as content. For this reason natural science can not abstract from the knowing subject entirely, but only from those attributes of the subject which either disappear entirely when we remove the subject in thought, as, the feel- ings, or from those which, on the ground of physical researches, must be regarded as belonging to the subject, as, the quali- ties of sensations. Psychology, on the contrary, has as its sub- ject of treatment the total content of experience in its imme- diate character. / The only ground, then, for the division between natural science on the one hand, and psychology and the mental sciences I on the other, is to be found in the fact that all experience contains as its factors a content objectively presented, and an ex- periencing subject. Still, it is by no means necessary that logical definitions of these two factors should precede the sep- aration of the sciences from one another, for it is obvious that such definitions are possible only after they have a basis in the investigations of natural science and of psychology. All that it is § 1. Problem of Psychology. 5 necessary to presuppose from the first, is the consciousness which accompanies all experience, that in this experience objects are being presented to a subject. There can be no assumption of a knowledge of the conditions upon which the distinction is based, or of the definite characteristics by which one factor can be distinguished from the other. Even the use of the terms object and subject in this connection must be regarded as the application to the first stage of experience, of distinctions which are reached only by developed logical reflection. The forms of interpretation in natural science and psychol- ogy are supplementary not only in the sense that the first considers objects after abstracting, as far as possible, from the subject, while the second has to do with the part the subject plays in the rise of experience; but they are also supplementary in ihe sense that each takes a different point of view in cosr sidering the single contents of experience. Natural science seeks to discover the nature of objects without reference to the sub- ject. The knowledge that it produces is therefore mediate or conceptual. In place of the immediate objects of experience, it sets concepts gained from these objects by abstracting from the subjective components of our ideas. This abstraction makes it necessary, continually to supplement reality with hypothetical elements. Scientific analysis shows that many components of experience — as, for example, sensations — are subjective effects of objective processes. These objective processes in their ob- jective character, independent of the subject, can therefore never be a part of experience. Science makes up for this lack by forming supplementary hypothetical concepts of the objective properties of matter. Psychology, on the other hand, investigates the contents of experience in their complete and actual form, both the ideas that are referred to objects, and all the sub- jective processes that cluster about them. Its knowledge is, therefore, immediate and perceptual: perceptual in the broad sense of the term in which not only sense-perceptions, but all concrete reality is distinguished from all that is abstract and concep tual in thought. Psychology can exhibit the interconnection of the contents of experience as actually presented to the subject, only by avoiding entirely the abstractions and supplementary concepts of natural science. Thus, while natural science and psychology are 6 Introduction. both empirical sciences in the sense that they aim to explain the contents of experience, though from different points of view, still it is obvious that, in consequence of the character of its problem, psychology is the more strictly empirical. § 2. GENERAL THEORIES OF PSYCHOLOGY. 1. The view that psychology is an empirical science which deals, not with specific contents of experience, but with the immediate contents of all experience, is of recent origin. It still encounters in the science of to-day oppositional views, which are to be looked upon, in general, as the remnants of earlier stages of development, and which are in turn arrayed against one another according to their attitudes on the question of the relation of psychology to philosophy and to the other sciences. On the basis of the two definitions mentioned above (§1, I) as being the most widely accepted, two chief theories of psychology may be distinguished: metor- physical and empirical psychology. Each is further divided into a number of special tendencies. Metaphysical psychology generally values very little the empirical analysis and causal synthesis of psychical processes. Regarding psychology as a part of philosophical meta- physics, its chief effort is directed toward the discovery of a definition of the "nature of mind" that shall be in accord with the whole theory of the metaphysical system to which the particular psychology belongs. After a metaphysical con- cept of mind has thus been established, the attempt is made to deduce from it the actual content of psychical experi- ence. The characteristic that distinguishes metaphysical from empirical psychology is, then, its attempt to deduce psychical . processes, not from other psychical processes, but from some § 2. General Theories of Psychology. ^ substratum entirely unlike themselves: either from the mani- festations of a special mind-substance, or from the attributes and processes of matter. At this point metaphysical psy- chology branches off in two directions. Spiritualistic psychol- ogy considers psychical processes as the manifestations of a sped fie mind-substance, which is regarded either as essen- tially different from matter (dualism), or as related in nature to matter (monism or monadology). The fundamental meta- physical doctrine of spiritualistic psychology is the assumption of the sup&'sensible nature of mind and, in connection with this, the assumption of its immortality. Sometimes the further notion of preexistence is also added. Materialistic psychology, on the other hand, refers psychical processes to the same material substratum which natural science employs for the explanation of natural phenomena. According to this view, psychical processes, like physical vital processes, are connected with certain organizations of material particles which are formed during the life of the individual and broken up at the end of that life. The metaphysical character of this trend of psychology is determined by its denial of the supersensible nature of mind as asserted by spiritualistic psychology. Both theories have this in common, that they seek, not to interpret psychical experience from experience itself, but to derive it from presuppositions about hypothetical processes in a metaphysical substratum. 2. From the strife that followed these attempts at meta- physical explanation, empirical psychology arose; Wherever it is consistently carried out, it strives either to arrange psychical processes under general concepts derived directly from the interconnection of these processes themselves, or to start with certain, as a rule simpler processes, and then ex- plain the more complicated as the result of the interaction of those with which it started. There may be various fun- 8 Introduction. damental principles for such an empirical interpretation, and thus it becomes possible to distinguish several varieties of empirical psychology. In general, these may be classified according to two principles of division. The first has refer- ence to the relation of inner and outer experience, and the attitude that the two empirical sciences, natural science and psychology, take toward each other. The second has reference to the facts or concepts derived from these facts, which are used for the interpretation of psychical processes. Every system of empirical psychology has its place under both of these principles of classification. 3. On the general question as to the nature of psychical experience, the two views already mentioned (§1) on account of their decisive significance in determining the problem of psychology, stand over against each other: psychology of the inner sense, and psychology as the science of immediate ex- perience. The first treats psychical processes as contents of a special sphere of experience coordinate with the experience which, derived through the outer senses, is assigned as the province of the natural sciences, but though coordinate, totally different from it. The second recognizes no real difference between inner and outer experience, but finds the distinction only in the different points of view from which unitary experience is considered in the two cases. The first of these two varieties of empirical psychology is the older. It arose primarily from the effort to establish the independence of psychical observation, in opposition to the encroachments of natural philosophy. In thus coordinating natural science and psychology, it sees the justification for the equal recognition of both spheres in their entirely differ- ent objects and modes of perceiving these objects. This view has influenced empirical psychology in two ways. First, it favored the opinion that psychology should employ empirical §2. Qeneral Theories of Psychology, 9 methods, but that these methods, like psychological experience, should be fundamentally different from those of natural science. Secondly, it gave rise to the necessity of showing some con- nection or other between these two kinds of experience, which were supposed to be different. In regard to the first demand, it was chiefly the psychology of the inner sense that deyeloped the method of 'pure introspection (§ 3 , 2). In at- tempting to solve the second question, this psychology was necessarily driven back to a metaphysical basis, because of its assumption of a difference between the physical and the psychical contents of experience. For, from the very nature of the case, it is impossible to account for the relations of inner to outer experience, or for the so-called "interaction between body and mind", from the position here taken, except through metaphysical presuppositions. These presuppo- sitions must then, in turn, effect the psychological investigation itself in such a way as to result in the importation of meta- physical hypotheses into it. 4. Essentially distinct from the psychology of the inner sense is the trend that defines psychology as the "science of im-_ mediate experience". Eegarding, as it does, outer and inner experience, not as different parts of experience, but as different ways of looking at one and the same experience, it can not admit any fundamental difference between the methods of psychology and those of natural science. It has, therefore, sought most of all to cultivate experimental methods which shall lead to just such an exact analysis of psychical processes as that which the explanatory natural sciences undertake in the case of natural phenomena, the only differences being those which arise from the diverse points of view. It holds also that the special mental sciences which have to do with concrete mental processes , and creations , stand on this same basis of a scientific consideration of the immediate contents of 10 Introduction. experience and of their relations to acting subjects. It follows, then, that psychological analysis of the most general mental products, such as language, mythological ideas, and laws of custom, is to be regarded as an aid to the understanding of all the more comphcated psychical processes. In its methods, then, this trend of psychology stands in close relation to other sciences: as experimental psychology, to the natural sciences; as social psychology, to the special mental sciences. Finally, from this point of view, the question of the rela- tion between psychical and physical objects disappears en- tirely. They are not different objects at all, but one and the same content of experience, looked at in one case — in that of the natural sciences — after abstracting from the subject, in the other — in that of psychology — in their immediate character and complete relations to the subject. All meta- physical hypotheses as to the relation of psychical and phy- sical objects are, when viewed from this position, attempts to solve a problem that never would have existed if the case had been correctly stated. Though psychology must dispense with metaphysical supplementary hypotheses in regard to the interconnection of psychical processes, because these processes are the immediate contents of experience , still another meth- od of procedure is open from the very fact that inner and outer experience are supplementary points of view. Wherever breaks appear in the interconnection of psychical processes, it is allowable to carry on the investigation according to the physical methods of considering these same processes, in order to discover whether the lacking coherency can be thus supplied. The same holds for the reverse method of filling up the breaks in the continuity of our physiological knowledge, by means of elements derived from psychological investigation. Only on the basis of such a view, which sets the two forms of knowledge in their true relation, is it possible for psychol- §2. Oeneral Theories of Psychology. \\ ogy to become in the fullest sense an empirical science. Only in this way, too, can physiology become the true supple- mentary science of psychology, and psychology, on the other hand, the auxiliary of physiology. 5. Under the second principle of classification mentioned above (2), that is, according to the facts or concepts with which the investigation of psychical processes starts, there are two varieties of empirical psychology to be distinguished. They are, at the same time, successive stages in the development of psychological interpretation. The first corresponds to a descriptive, the second to an explanatory stage. The attempt to present a discriminating description of the different psychical processes, gave rise to the need of an appropriate classi- fication. Class-concepts were formed, under which the various processes were grouped; and the attempt was made to satisfy the need of an interpretation in each particular case, by sub- suming the components of a given compound process under their proper class-concepts. Such concepts are, for example, sensation, knowledge, attention, memory, imagination, under- standing, and will. They correspond to the general concepts of physics which are derived from the immediate apprehension of natural phenomena, such as weight, heat, sound, and hght. Like those concepts of physics, these derived psychical con- cepts may serve for a first grouping of the facts, but they contribute nothing whatever to the explanation of these facts. Still, empirical psychology has often been guilty of confound- ing this description with explanation. Thus, the faculty- psychology considered these class-concepts as psychical forces or faculties, and referred psychical processes to their alter- nating or united activity. 6. Opposed to this method of treatment found in the descriptive faculty-psychology, is that of explanatory psychol- ogy. When consistently empirical, the latter must base its inter- 1 2 Introduction. pretations on certain facts which? themselves belong to psychical experience. These facts may, however, be taken from differ- ent spheres of psychical processes, and so it comes that explanatory treatment may be further divided into two va- rieties, which correspond to the two factors, objects and sub- ject, that go to make up immediate experience. When the chief emphasis is laid on the objects of immediate experience, intellectualistic psychology results. This attempts to derive all psychical processes, especially the subjective feelings, impulses, and volitions, from ideas, or intellectual processes as they may be called on acount of their importance for objective knowledge. If, on the contrary, the chief emphasis is laid on the way in which immediate experience arises in the sub- ject, a variety of explanatory psychology results which attri- butes to those subjective activities not referred to external objects , a position as independent as that assigned to ideas. This variety has been called voluntai'isUe psychology, because of the importance that must be conceded to volitional pro- cesses in comparison with other subjective processes. Of the two varieties of psychology that result from the general attitudes on the question of the nature of inner experience (3), psychology of the inner sense commonly tends towards intellectualism. This is due to the fact that, when the inner sense is coordinated with the outer senses, the con- tents of psychical experience that first attract consideration are those presented as objects to this inner sense, in a manner analogous to the presentation of natural objects to the outer senses. It is assumed that the character of objects can be attributed to ideas alone of all the contents of psychical experience, because they are regarded as images of the ex- ternal objects presented to the outer senses. Ideas are, accordingly, looked upon as the only real objects of the inner sense, while all processes not referred to external objects, as, §2. Oeneral Theories of Psychology, 13 for example, the feelings, are interpreted as obscure ideas, or ideas related to one's own body, or, finally, as effects aris- ing from combinations of the ideas. The psychology of immediate experience (4), on the other hand, tends toward voluntarism. It is obyious that here, where the chief problem of psychology is held to be the investigation of the subjective rise of all experience, special attention will be devoted to those factors from which natural science abstracts. 7. Intellectualistic psychology has in the course of its development separated into two trends. In one, the logical processes of judgment and reasoning are regarded as the typical forms of all psychoses; in the other, certain combi- nations of successive memory-ideas distinguished by their frequency, the so-called associations of ideas, are accepted as such. The logical theory is most closely related to the popular method of psychological interpretation and is, therefore, the older. It still finds some acceptance, however, even in modem times. The associatiorir-theory arose from the philo- sophical empiricism of the last century. The two theories stand to a certain extent in antithesis, since the first attempts to reduce the totality of psychical processes to higher, while the latter seeks to reduce it to lower and, as it is assumed, simpler forms of intellectual activity. Both are one-sided, and not only fail to explain affective and vohtional processes on the basis of the assumption with which they start, but are not able to give a complete interpretation even of the intellectual processes. 8. The union of psychology of the inner sense with the intellectualistic view has led to a peculiar assumption that has been in many cases fatal to "psychological theory. "We may define this assumption briefly as the erroneous attribution of the nature of things to ideas. Not only was an analogy 1 4 Introduetion. assumed between the objects of the so-called inner sense and those of the outer senses, but the former were regarded as the images of the latter; and so it came that the attributes which natural science ascribes to external objects, were transferred to the immediate objects of the "inner sense", the ideas. The assumption was then made that ideas are themselves things, just as much as the external objects to which we refer them; that they disappear from consciousness and come back into it; that they may, indeed, be more or less intensely and clearly perceived , according as the inner sense is stimu- lated through the outer senses or not, and according to the degree of attention concentrated upon them, but that on the whole they remain unchanged in qualitative character. 9. In all these respects voluntaristie psychology is opposed to intellectuaHsm. While the latter assumes an inner sense and specific objects of inner experience, voluntarism is closely related to the view that inner experience is identical with immediate experience. According to this doctrine, the content of psychological experience does not consist of a sum of objects, but of all that which makes up the process of experience in general, that is, of all the experiences of the subject in their immediate character, unmodified by abstraction or reflection. It follows of necessity that the contents of psychological expe- rience should be regarded as an interconnection of processes. This concept of process excludes the attribution of an objective and more or less permanent character to the con- tents of psychical experience. Psychical facts are occurrences, not objects; they take place, like all occurrences, in time and are never the same at a given point in time as they were the preceding moment. In this sense volitions are typical for all psychical processes. Voluntaristie psychology does not by any means assert that volition is the only real form of psychosis, but merely that, with its closely related §2, Oeneral Theories of Psychology. 15 feelings and emotions, it is just as essential a component of psychological experience as sensations and ideas. It holds, further, that all other psychical processes are to be thought of after the analogy of volitions , they too being a series of continuous changes in time, not a sum of permanent objects, as intellectualism generally assumes in consequence of its erroneous attribution to ideas of those properties which we attribute to external objects. The recognition of the immediate reahty of psychological experience excludes the possibility of the attempt to derive any particular components of psychical phenomena from others specifically different. The analogous attempts of metaphysical psychology to reduce all psychological experience to the heterogeneous, imaginary processes of a hypothetical substratum, are for the same reason inconsistent with the real problem of psychology. While it concerns itself, however, with immediate experience , psychology assumes from the first that all psychical contents contain objective as well as subjective factors. These are to be distinguished only through deUberate abstraction, and can never appear as really separate processes. In fact, immediate experience shows that there are no ideas which do not arouse in us feehngs and impulses of different intensities, and, on the other hand, that a feeling or volition is impossible which does not refer to some ideated object. 1 0. The governing principles of the psychological position maintained in the following chapters may be summed up in three general statements. 1) Inner, or psychological, experience is not a special sphere of experience apart from others , but is immediate experience in its totality. 2) This immediate experience is not made up of unchang- ing contents, but of an interconnection of processes; not of objects, but of occurrences, of universal human experiences and their relations in accordance with certain laws. ] Q Introduetion. 3) Each of these processes contains an objective content and a subjective process, thus including the general con- ditions both of all knowledge and of all practical human activity. Corresponding to these three general principles, we have a threefold attitude of psychology to the other sciences. 1) As the science of immediate experience, it is supple^ mentary to the natural sciences, which, in consequence of their abstraction from the subject, have to do only with the objective, mediate contents of experience. Any particular fact can, strictly speaking, be understood in its full sig- nificance only after is has been subjected to the analyses of both natural science and psychology. In this sense, then, physics and physiology are auxiliary to psychology, and the latter is, in turn, supplementary to the natural sciences. 2) As the science of the universal forms of immediate human experience and their combination in accordance with certain laws, it is the foundation of the mental sciences. The subject-matter of these sciences is in all cases the activities preceding from immediate human experiences, and their effects. ^ince psych ology has for its problenLjUie_mvestigatioa_of_the iorms a nd laws o| these activities^- it is at once - the most ^neral_menta.l science,^ a,nd the foundation^for all the others, such as philology, history, political economy, juris- prudence, etc. 3) Since psychology pays equal attention to both the subjective and objective conditions which underlie not' only theoretical knowledge, but practical activity as well, and since it seeks to determine their interrelation, it is the empirical dis- cipline whose results are most immediately useful in the in- vestigation of the general prol()lems of the them-y of know- ledge and ethics, the two foundations of philosophy. Thus, psychology is in relation to natural science the supplementary, §2. Oemral Theories of Psychology. \'J in relation to the mental sciences the fundamental, and in relation to philosophy the propaedeutic empirical science. 10a. The view that it is not a difference in the objects of experience, but in the way of treating experience, that distinguishes psychology from natural science, has come to be recognized more and more in modern psychology. Still, a clear comprehension of the essential character of this position in regard to the scientific problems of psychology, is prevented by the persistence of older tendencies derived from metaphysics and natural philosophy. Instead of starting from the fact that the natural sciences are possible only after abstracting from the subjective factors of experience, the more general problem of treating the contents of all experience in the most general way, is sometimes assigned to natural science. In such a case psychology is, of course, no longer coordinate with the natural sciences, but subordinate to them. Its problem is no longer to remove the abstraction employed by the natural sciences, and in this way to gain with them a complete view of experience, but it has to use the concept "subject" furnished by the natural sciences, and to give an account of the influence of this subject on the con- tents of experience. Instead of recognizing that an adequate definition of "subject" is possible only as a result of psycho- logical investigations (§ 1,3 a), a finished concept formed exclusively by the natural sciences is here foisted upon psychology. Now, for the natural sciences the subject is identical with the body. Psychol- ogy is accordingly defined as the science which has to determine the dependence of immediate experience on the body. This posi- tion, which may be designated as "psycho-physical materialism", is epistemologically untenable and psychologically unproductive. Natural science, which purposely abstracts from the subjective component of all experience, is least of all in a position to give a final definition of the subject. A psychology that starts with such a purely physiological definition depends, therefore, not on experience, but, just Hke the older materialistic psychology, on a metaphysical presupposition. The position is psychologically un- productive because, from the very first, it turns over the causal interpretation of psychical processes to physiology. But physiol- ogy has not yet furnished such an interpretation, and never Wdsdt, Psychologj'. 2 18 Introduction. will be able to do so, because of the difference between the manner of regarding phenomena in natural science and in psy- chology. It is obvious, too, that such a form of psychology, which has been turned into hypothetical brain -mechanics, can never be of any service as a basis for the mental sciences. The strictly empirical trend of psychology, defined in the principles formulated above, is opposed to these attempts to renew metaphysical doctrines. In calling it "voluntaristic", we are not to overlook the fact that, in itself, this psychological voluntarism has absolutely no connection with any metaphysical doctrine of will. Indeed, it stands in opposition to Schopen- hauer's one-sided metaphysical voluntarism, which derived all being from a transcendental original will, and to the metaphysical systems of a Spinoza or a Herbart, which arose from intellectu- alism. In its relation to metaphysics, the characteristic of psy- chological voluntarism in the sense above defined, is its exclusion of all metaphysics from psychology. In its relations to other forms of psychology, it refuses to accept any of the attempts to reduce volitions to mere ideas, and at the same time empha- sizes the typical character of volition for all psychological ex- perience. Volitional acts are universally recognized as occurren- ces, made up of a series of continual changes in quality and intensity. They are typical in the sense that this characteristic of being occurrences is held to be true for all the contents of psychical experience. § 3. METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY. 1. Since psychology has for its object, not specific con- ) tents of experience, but general experience in its immediate character, it can make use of no methods except such as the empirical sciences in general employ for the determination, analysis , - and causal synthesis of facts. The circumstance, that natural science abstracts from the subject, while psychol- ogy does not, can be no ground for modifications in the essential character of the methods employed in the two fields, though it does modify the way in which these methods are applied. § 3. Methods of Psychology. 19 The natural sciences, which may serve as an example for psychology in this respect, since they were developed earher, make use of hvo chief methods: experiment and observation. Experiment is observation connected with an intentional interference on the part of the observer, in the rise and course of the phenomena observed. Observation, in its proper sense, is the investigation of phenomena without such inter- ference, just as they are naturally presented to the observer in the continuity of experience. Wherever experiment is possible, it is always used in the natural sciences ; for under all circumstances, even when the phenomena in themselves present the conditions for sufficiently exact observation, it is an advantage to be able to control at will their rise and progress, or to isolate the various components of a composite phenomenon. Still, even in the natural sciences the two methods have been distinguished according ta their spheres of application. It is held that the experimental methods are indispensable for certain problems, while in others the desired end may not infrequently be reached through mere obser- vation. If we neglect a few exceptional cases due to special relations, these two classes of problems correspond to the general division of natural phenomena into processes and objects. Experimental interference is required in the exact deter- mination of the course, and in the analysis of the components, of any natural process, such as, for example, light-waves or sound-waves, an electric discharge, the formation or disinte- gration of a chemical compound, and stimulation and metaboUsm in plants and animals. As a rule, such interference is desirable because exact observation is possible only when the observer can determine the moment at which the process shall commence. It is also indispensable in separating the various components of a complex phenomenon from one another. As a rule, this 2* 20 Introduction. is possible only through the addition or subtraction of certain conditions, or a quantitative variation of them. The case is different with objects of nature. They are relatively constant; they do not have to be produced at a particular moment, but are always at the observer's disposal and ready for examination. Here, then, experimental in- vestigation is generally necessary only when the production and modification of the objects are to be inquired into. In such a case, they are regarded either as products or com- ponents of natural processes and come under the head of processes rather than objects. When, on the contrary, the only question is the actual nature of these objects, without reference to their origin or modification, mere observation is generally enough. Thus, mineralogy, botany, zoology, ana- tomy, and geography, are pure sciences of observation so long as they are kept free from the physical, chemical, and phys- iological problems that are, indeed, frequently brought into them, but have to do with processes of nature, not with the objects in themselves. 2. If we apply these considerations to psychology, it is obvious at once, from the very nature of its subject-matter, that exact observation is here possible only in the form of experimental observation, and that psychology can never be a pure science of observation. The contents of this science are exclusively processes, not permanent objects. In order to investigate with exactness the rise and progress of these processes, their composition out of various components, and the interrelations of these components, we must be able first of all to bring about their beginning at will, and purposely to vary the conditions of the same. This is possible here, as in all cases, only through experiment, not through pure introspection. Besides this general reason there is another, pecuHar to psychology, that does not apply at all to natural § 3. Methods of Psychology. 21 phenomena. In the latter case we purposely abstract from the perceiving subject, and under circumstances, especially when favored by the regularity of the phenomena, as in astronomy, mere observation may succeed in determining with adequate certainty the objective contents of the pro- cesses. Psychology, on the contrary, is debarred from this abstraction by its fundamental principles , and the conditions for chance observation can be suitable only when the same objective components of immediate experience are frequently repeated in connection with the same subjective states. It is hardly to be expected, in view of the great complexity of psychical processes, that this will ever be the case. The coin- cidence is especially improbable since the very intention to observe, which is a necessary condition of all observation, modifies essentially the rise and progress of psychical pro- cesses. Observation of nature is not disturbed by this in- tention on the part of the observer, because here we pur- posely abstract from the state of the subject. The chief problem of psychology, however, is the exact observation of the rise and progress of subjective processes, and it can be readily seen that under such circumstances the intention to observe either essentially modifies the facts to be observed, or completely suppresses them. On the other hand, psychol- ogy, by the very way in which psychical processes originate, is led, just as physics and physiology are, to employ the ex- perimental mode of procedure. A sensation arises in us under the most favorable conditions for observation when it is caused by an external sense-stimulus, as, for example, a tone-sensation from an external tone-vibration, or a hght- sensation from an external hght-impression. The idea of an object is always caused originally by the more or less com- plicated cooperation of external sense-stimuli. If we wish to study the way in which an idea is formed, we can choose 22 IntrodiCelion. no other method than that of imitating this natural process. In doing this, we have at the same time the great advantage of being able to modify the idea itself by changing at will the combination of the impressions that cooperate to form it, and of thus learning what influence each single condition exercises on the product. Memory-images, it is true, can not be dii-ectly aroused through external sense impressions, but follow them after a longer or shorter interval. Still, it is obvious that their attributes, and especially their relation to the primary ideas aroused through direct impressions, can be most accurately learned, riot by waiting for their chance arrival, but by using such memory-ideas as may be aroused, in a systematic, experimental way, through immediately pre- ceding impressions. The same is true of feelings and voli- tions; they will be presented in the form best adapted to exact investigation when those impressions are purposely produced which experience has shown to be regularly con- nected with affective and volitional reactions. There is, then, no fundamental psychical process to which experimental methods can not be applied, and therefore none in whose investigation they are not logically required. 3. Pure observation, such as is possible in many depart- ments of natural science, is, from the very character of psy- chical phenomena, impossible in individual psychology. Such a possibiUty would be conceivable only under the condition that there existed permanent psychical objects, independent of our attention, similar to the relatively permanent objects of nature, which remain unchanged by our observation of them. There are, indeed, certain facts at the disposal of psychology, which, although they are not real objects, stUl have the character of psychical objects inasmuch as they possess these attributes of relative permanence, and indepen- dence of the observer. Connected with these characteristics § 3. Methods of Psychology. 23 is the further fact that they are unapprochable by means of experiment in the common acceptance of the term. These facts are the mental products that have been developed in the course of history, such as language, mythological ideas, and customs. The origin and development of these pro- ducts depend in every case on general psychical conditions which may be inferred from their objective attributes. Psy- chological analysis can, consequently, explain the psychical processes operative in their formation and development. All such mental products of a general character presuppose as a condition the existence of a mental community com- posed of many individuals, though, of course, their deepest sources are the psychical attributes of the individual. Because of this dependence oil the community, in par- ticular the social community, this whole department of psy- chological investigation is designated as social psychology, and distinguished from individual, or as it may be called because of its predominating method, experimental psychology. In the present stage of the science these two branches of psychology are generally taken up in different treatises ; still, they are not so much different departments as different meth- ods. So-called social psychology corresponds to the method of pure observation, the objects of observation in this case being the mental products. The necessary connection of these products with social communities, which has given to social psychology its name, is due to the fact that the mental products of the individual are of too variable a character to be the subjects of objective observation. The phenomena gain the necessary degree of constancy only when they become collective. Thus psychology has, like natural science, two exact methods : the experimental method, serving for the analysis of simpler psychical processes, and the observation of general '2'i IntrodueUon. mental products, serving for the investigation of the higher psychical processes and developments. 3a. Tlie introduction of the experimental method into psychol- ogy was originally due to the modes of procedure in physiology, especially in the physiology of the sense-organs and the nervous system. For this reason experimental psychology is also com- monly called "physiological psychology"; and works treating it under this title regularly contain those supplementary facts from the physiology of the nervous system and the sense-organs, which require special discussion with a view to the interests of psy- chology, though in themselves they belong to physiology alone. "Physiological psychology" is, accordingly, an intermediate dis- cipline which is, however, as the name indicates, primarily psychology, and is, apart from the supplementary physiological facts that it presents, just the same as "experimental psychology" in the sense above defined. The attempt sometimes made , to distinguish psychology proper from physiological psychology, by assigning to the first the psychological interpretation of inner experience, and to the second the derivation of this experience from physiological processes, is to be rejected as inadmissible. There is only one kind of causal explanation in psychology, and that is the derivation of more complex psychical processes from simpler ones. In this method of interpretation physiological elements can be used only as supplementary aids, because of the relation between natural science and psychology as above defined (§ 2, 4). Materialistic psychology denies the existence of psychical causality, and substitutes for this problem the other, of explain- ing psychical processes by brain-physiology. This tendency, which has been shown (§ 2, 10 a) to be epistemologically and psycho- logically untenable, appears among the representatives of both "pure" and "physiological" psychology. § 4. GENERAL SUEVEY OF THE SUBJECT. ; 1. The immediate contents of experience which constitute the subject-matter of psychology, are under all circumstances processes of a composite character. Sense-perceptions of ex- § 4. General Survey of (he Subject. 25 ternal objects, memories of such sense-perceptions, feelings, emotions, and volitional acts, are not only continually united in the most various ways, but each of these processes is itself a more or less composite whole. The idea of an ex- ternal body, for example, is made up of partial ideas of its parts. A tone may be ever so simple , but we localize it in some direction, thus bringing it into connection with the idea of external space, which is highly composite. A feeling or volition is referred to some sensation that aroused the feeling or to an object willed. In dealing with a complex fact of this kind, scientific investigation has three problems to be solved in succession. The first is the analysis of composite processes; the second is ^e demonstration of the combinations into which the elements discovered by analysis enter; the third is the investigation of the laws that are operative in the formation of such combinations. 2. The second, or synthetic, problem is made up of several partial problems. In the first place, the psychical elements unite to form composite psychical compounds which are separate and relatively independent of one another in the con- tinual flow of psychical processes. Such compounds are, for example, ideas, whether referred directly to external impressions or objects, or interpreted by us as memories of impressions and objects perceived before. Other examples are composite feelings, emotions, or volitions. Then again, these psychical compounds stand in the most various interconnections with one another. Thus, ideas unite to from larger simultaneous ideational complexes or regular successions, while affective and volitional processes form a variety of combinations with one another and with ideational processes. In this way we have the interconnection of psychical compounds as a class of syn- thetical processes of the second degree, consisting of a union between the simpler combinations, or those of elements into 26 Introduction. psychical compounds. The separate psychical interconnections, in turn, unite to form still more comprehensive combinations, which also show a certain regularity in the arrangement of their components. In this way, combinations of a third degree arise, which we designate by the general name psychical developments. They may be divided into developments of different scope. Developments of a more limited sort are such as relate to a single mental trend, for example, the development of the intellectual functions, of the will, or of the feelings, or of merely one special branch of these functions, such as the aesthetic or moral feelings. From a number of such partial series arises the total development of a psychical personality. Finally, since animals and in a still higher degree human individuals are in continual interrelation with like beings, there arise above these individual forms the gen^ eral psychical developments. These various branches of the study of psychical development are in part the psychological foundations of other sciences, such as the theory of knowledge, pedagogy, aesthetics, and ethics, and are, accordingly, treated more appropriately in connection with these. In part they have become special psychological sciences, such as child- psychology, animal and social psychology. We shall, there- fore, in this treatise discuss only those results from the three last mentioned departments which are of the most importance for general psychology. 3. The solution of the last and most general psychological problem, the ascertainment of the laws of psychical phenom- ena, depends apon the investigation of all the combi- nations of different degrees, the combination of elements into compounds, of compounds into interconnections, and of interconnections into developments. And as this in- vestigation is the only thing that can teach us the actual composition of psychical processes, so we can discover the § 4. General Survey of the Subject. 27 attributes of psychical causality, which iinds its expression in these processes, only from the laws followed by the con- tents of experience and their components in their various combinations. We have, accordingly, to consider in the following chapters : 1) Psychical Elements, 2) Psychical Compounds, 3) Interconnection of Psychical Compounds, 4) Psychical Developments, 5) Psychical Causality and its Laws. I. PSYCHICAL ELEMENTS. § 5. CHIEF FORMS A^D GENERAL ATTRIBUTES OF PSYOHIOAL ELEMENTS. l.^^AlLJ lie conten ts of psychical experience are of a com- posite chara ctei:. It follows, therefore, that psychical elements, or the absolutely simple and irreducible components of psy- chical phenomena, can not be found by analysis alone, but only with the aid of abstraction. This abstraction is rendered possible by the fact that the elements are in reahty united in different ways. If the element a is connected in one case with the elements b, e, d . . ., in another with b', c', d' . . ., it is possible to abstract it from all the other elements, be- cause none of them is always united with it. If, for example, we hear a simple tone of a certaia pitch and intensity, it may be located now in this direction, now in that, and may be heard alternately with various other tones. But since the direction is not constant, or the accompanying tone the same, it is possible to abstract from these variable elements, and we have the single tone as a psychical element. 2. As products of psychical analysis, we have psychical elements of two kinds, corresponding to the two factors con- tained in immediate experience (§ 1, 2), the objective contents and the experiencing subject. The elements of the objective contents we call sensational elements, or simply sensations: such are a tone, or a particular sensation of hot, cold, or light, when we neglect for the moment all the connections § 5. Chief Forms and General Attributes of Psychical Elements. 29 of these sensations with others, and all their spacial and temporal relations. The subjective elements, on the other hand, are designated as affective elements, or simple feelings. We may mention as examples the feelings accompanying sen- sations of hght, sound, taste, smell, hot, cold, or pain, the feel- ings aroused by the sight of an agreeable or disagreeable object, and the feelings arising in a state of attention or at the moment of a voHtional act. Such simple feehngs are in a double sense products of abstraction: each is connected with an ideational element, and is furthermore a component of a psychical process which occurs ia time, and diu'ing which the feeHng itself is continually changing. 3. The actual contents of psychical experience always i consist of various combinations of sensational and affective I elements, so that the specific character of the simple psychi-; cal processes depends for the most part not on the nature' of these elements so much as on their union into composite psychical compounds. Thus, /the idea of an extended body or of a temporal series of sensations, an emotion, and a vo- lition, are all specific forms of psychical experience. But their character as such is as little present in their sensational and affective elements as the chemical properties of a com- pound body can be defined by recounting the properties of its chemical elements. Specific character — siaA—ehmeiiia/r-y nature of j)sychical processes are, accardingly-j two -entirely different concepts. Every psychical element is a specific content of experience, but not every specific content of imme- diate experience is at the same time a psychical elenient^ Thus, especially spacial and temporal ideas, emotions, and volitional acts, are specific but not elementary processes. Many elements are present only in psychical compounds of a particular kind, but since these compounds regularly con- tain other elements as well, their special characteristics are 30 I- Psyehioal Elements. to be attributed to the mode of union, rather than to the abstract attributes, of their elements. Thus, we always refer a momentary sound-sensation to a definite point in time. This localization in time, however, is possible only by relat- ing the given sensation to others preceding and following it, so that the special character of the time-idea can not arise from the single sound-sensation thought of as isolated, but only from its union with others. Again, an emotion of anger or a voHtion contains certain simple feelings that are never present in other psychical compounds, still each of these processes is composite, for it has duration, in the course of which particular feelings follow one another with a certain regularity, and the process itself is not complete without the whole train of these feelings. 4. Sensations and simple feelings exhibit certain common attributes and also certain characteristic differences. They have in common two determinants, which we call quality and intensity. Every simple sensation and every simple feeling has a definite qualitative character that marks it off from all other sensations and feelings; and this quality must al- ways have some degree of intensity. Accordingly, we distin- guish the different psychical elements from one another by their qualities, but regard the intensity as the quantitative value which in any concrete case belongs to the given ele- ment. Our designations of psychical elements are based entirely upon their quahties; thus, we distinguish such sen- sations as blue, grey, yellow, hot, and cold, or such feelings as grave, cheerful, sad, gloomy, and sorrowful. On the other hand, we always express the differences in the intensity of psychical elements by the same quantitative designations, as weak, strong, medium strong, and very strong. These expres- sions are in both cases class-concepts which serve for a first superficial arrangement of the elements, and each embraces § 5. Chief Forms and General Attributes of Psychical Elements. 31 an unlimitedly large number of concrete elements. Language has developed a relatively complete stock of names for the qualities of simple sensations, especially for colors and tones. Names for the qualities of feelings and for degrees of intensity are far behind. Clearness and obscurity, as also distinctness and indistinctness, are sometimes classed with quality and intensity. But^^ince these attributes, as will appear later (§ 15, 4), always jrisfi-irom-Jhe,, interconnection of psychical compounds, they can not be regarded as determinants -of psychical elements. 5. Made up, at it is, of two determinants, quality and intensity, every psychical element must have a certain degree of intensity from which it is possible to pass, by continual gradations, to every other degree of intensity in the same quahty. Such gradations can be made in only two directions : one we call ino'ease in intensity, the other decrease. The degrees of intensity of every qualitative element, form in this way a single dimension, in which, from a given point, we may move in two opposite directions, just as from any point in a straight Hne. This may be expressed in the general statement: The various intensities of every psychical element form a continuity of one dimension. The extremities of this continuity we call the minimal and maximal sensation or feeling, as the case may be. In contrast with this uniformity in intensities, the qualities have more variable attributes. Every quality may, indeed, be so arranged in a definite continuity that it is possible to pass uninterruptedly from a given point to any other points in the same quality. But the various continuities of different qual- ities , which we may call systems of quality, exhibit differences both in the variety of possible gradations, and in the number of directions of gradation. In these two respects, we may distinguish, on the one hand, homogeneous and complex, on 32 I- Psychical Elements. the other, one-dimensional, two-dimensional, aiid many-dimsn^ sional systems of quality. "Within a homogeneous system, only such small differences are possible that generally there has never arisen any practical need of distinguishing them by different names. Thus, we distinguish only one quality of pressure, hot, cold, or pain, only one feeling of attention or of activity, although, in intensity, each of these qualities may have many different grades. It is not to be inferred from this fact that in each of these systems there is really only one quality. The truth is that in these cases the number of different qualities is merely very limited;,, if we were to represent it geometrically, it would probably never reduce entirely to a single point. Thus, for example, sensations of pressure from different regions of the sldn show, beyond question, small qualitative differences which are great enough to let us distinguish clearly any point of the skin from another at some distance from it. Such differences, however, as arise from contact with a sharp or dull, a rough or smooth body, are not to be reckoned as different qualities. They always depend on a large number of simultaneous sensations, and without the various combinations of these sensations into composite psychical compounds, the impressions mentioned would be impossible. Complex systems of quality differ from those we have been discussing, in that they embrace a large number of clearly distinguishable elements between which all possible inter- mediate forms exist. Li this class we must include the tonal system and color-system, the systems of smells and tastes, and among the affective systems those which form the subjective complements of these sensational systems, such as the systems of tonal feelings, color-feelings, etc. It is probable also that many systems of feelings belong here, which are objectively connected with composite impressions, but as § 5. Chief Forms and Oeneral Attributes of Psychical Elements. 33 feelings are simple in character; such are the various feelings of harmony or discord that correspond to the different com- binations of tones. The differences in the number of dimensions have heen determined with certainty only in the case of certain sensa- tional systems. Thus, the tonal system is one -dimensional. The ordinary color-system, which includes the colors and their transitional qualities to white, is two-dimensional; while the complete system of Hght-sensations, which includes also the dark color-tones and the transitional quahties to black, is three - dimensional. 6. In the relations discussed thus far, sensational and affective elements in .general agree. They differ, on the other hand, in certain essential attributes which are connected with the immediate relations of sensations to objects and of feelings to the subject. 1) When varied in a single dimension, sensational elements exhibit ^wre qualitative differences, which are always in the same direction until they reach the possible limits of variation, where they become maximal differences. Thus, in the color-system, red and green, blue and yellow, or in the tonal system, the lowest and highest audible tones, are the maximal, and at the same time purely qualitative, differences. Every affective ele- ment, on the contrary, when continuously varied in the suitable direction of quality, passes gradually into a feeling of opposite quality. This is most obvious in the case of the affective elements regularly connected with certain sensational elements, as, for example, tonal feelings or color-feeHngs. As sensations a high and a low tone are differences that approach more or less the maximal differences of tonal sensation; the corresponding tonal feelings are opposites. In general, then, sensational qualities are limited by maximal differences, affec- tive qualities by maximal opposites. Between these opposites WoNDT, Psychology. 3 34 /• Psychical Elements. is a middle zone, where the feeling is not noticeable at all. It is, however, frequently impossible to demonstrate this in- difference-zone, because, while certain simple feelings disappear, other affective qualities remain, or new ones even may arise. The latter case appears especially when the transition of the feeling into the indifference-zone depends on a change in sen- sations. Thus, in the middle of the musical scale, those feelings disappear which correspond to the high and low tones, but the middle tones have still other, independent affective qualities which do not disappear with these opposites. This is to be explained hy the fact that a feehng which corresponds to a certain sensational quality is, as a rule, a component of a complex affective system, in which it belongs at the same time to various dimensions. Thus, the affective quaUty of a tone of given pitch belongs not only to the dimension of pitch-feelings, but also to that of feehngs of intensity, and finally to the different dimensions in which the clang-qual- ities of tones may be arranged. A tone of middle pitch and intensity may, in this way, lie in the indifference-zone so far as feelings of pitch and intensity are concerned, and yet have a very marked clang-feeling. The passage of affec- tive elements through the indifference-zone can be directly observed only when care is taken to abstract from other accompanying affective elements. The cases most favorable for this observation are those in which the accompanying elements disappear entirely or almost entirely. Wherever such an in- difference-zone appears without complication with other affective elements, we speak of the state as free from feelings, and of the sensations and ideas present in such a state, as indifferent. 2) Peelings of specific, and at the same time simple and irreducible, quality appear not only as the subjective com- plements of simple sensations, but also as the characteristic attendants of composite ideas or even complex ideational § 5. Chief Forms and General Attributes of Psychical Elements. 35 processes. Thus, there is a simple tonal feeling which varies with the pitch and intensity of tones, and also a feeling of harmony which, regarded as a feeling, is just as irreducible, but varies with the character of compound clangs. Still other feelings, which may in turn be of the most various kinds, arise from melodious series of clangs. Here, again, each single feehng taken by itself at a given moment, appears as an irreducible unit. Simple feelings are, then, much more various and numerous than simple sensations. 3) The various pure sensations may be arranged in a number of separate systems, between whose elements there is no qualitative relation whatever. Sensations belonging to different systems are called disparate. Thus, a tone and a color, a sensation of hot and one of pressure, or, in general, any two sensations between which there are no intermediate qualities, are disparate. According to this criterion, each of the four special senses (smell, taste, hearing, and sight) has a closed, complex sensational system, disparate from the other senses; while the general sense (touch) contains four homo- geneous sensational systems (sensations of pressure, hot, cold, and pain). All simple feelings, on the contrary, form a single interconnected manifold, for there is no feeling from which it is not possible to pass to any other through inter- mediate forms or through indifference -zones. But here too we may distinguish certain systems whose elements are more closely related, as, for example, feelings from colors, tones, harmonies, and rhythms. StUl, they are not absolutely closed systems, but there are everywhere relations either of likeness or of opposition to other systems. Thus, such feelings as those from sensations of moderate warmth, from tonal hamorny, and from satisfied expectation, however great their qualitative differences may be, are all related in that they belong to the general class of "pleasurable feelings". Still closer relations 3* 36 I. Psychical Elements. exist between certain single affective systems, as, for example, between tonal feelings and color-feelings, where deep tones seem to be related to dark colors, and bright colors to high tones. When in such cases a certain relationship is ascribed to the sensations themselves, it is probably due entirely to a confusion of the accompanying feelings with the sensations. This third distinguishing characteristic shows conclu- sively that the origin of the feelings is more unitary than that of the sensations, which depend on a number of differ- ent and in part distinguishable conditions. It is the same distinction that we find in the characterization of the sub- ject, which stands in immediate relation to the feelings, as a unit, in contrast with the plurality of the objects, to which the sensations are related. 6 a. It is only in modem psychology that the terms "sen- sation" and "feeling" have gained the meanings assigned to them in the definitions above given. In older psychological literature they were sometimes used indiscriminatingly, sometimes inter- changed. Even yet sensations of touch and those from the internal organs are called feelings by physiologists, and the sense of touch itself is known as the "sense of feeUng". This corre- sponds, it is true, to the original significance of the word, where feeling is the same as touching, still, after the very useful difierentiation has once been made, a confusion of the two terms should be avoided. Then again, the word "sensation" is used even by psychologists to mean not only simple, but also com- posite qualities, such as compound clangs and spacial and tem- poral ideas. But since we have the entirely adequate word "idea" for such compounds, it is more advantageous to limit the word sensation to psychologically simple sense-qualities. Finally, the term "sensation" has sometimes been restricted so as to mean only those stimulations which come directly from external sense- stimuli. For the psychological attributes of a sensation, however, this circumstance is entirely irrelevant, and therefore such a definition of the term is unjustifiable. § 5. Chief Forms and Qeneral Attributes of Psychical Mements, 37 The discrimination between sensational and affective elemenl.s in any concrete case is very much facilitated by the existence of indifference-zones in the feelings. Then again, from the fact that feelings range between opposites rather than mere differ- ences, it follows that they are much the more variable elements of our immediate experience. This changeable character, which renders it almost impossible to hold an affective state constant in quality and intensity, is the cause of the great difficulties that stand in the way of the exact investigation of feelings. Sensations are present in all immediate experiences, but feelings may disappear in certain special cases, because of their oscillation through an indifference-zone. Obviously, then, we can, in the case of sensations, abstract from the accompanying feel- ings, but never vice versa. In this way two false views may easily arise, either that sensations are the causes of feelings, or that feelings are a particular species of sensations. The first of these opinions is false because affective elements can never be derived from sensations as such, but only from the attitude of the subject, so that under different subjective conditions the same sensation may be accompanied by different feelings. The second is untenable because the two classes of elements are distinguished , on the one hand by the immediate relation of sensations to objects and of feelings to the subject, and on the other by the fact that the former range between maximal differ- ences, the latter between maximal opposites. Because of the objective and subjective factors belonging to all psychical ex- perience, sensations and feelings are to be looked upon as real and equally essential, though everywhere interrelated, elements of psychical phenomena. In this interrelation the sensational elements appear as the more constant; they alone can be isolated through abstraction, by referring them to external objects. It follows, therefore, of necessity that in investigating the attributes of both, we must start with the sensations. Simple sensations, in the consideration of which we abstract from the accompanying affective elements, are called ^wre sensations. Obviously, we can never speak of "pure feelings" in a similar sense, since simple feelings can never be thought of apart from the accompanying sensations and combinations of sensations. This fact is directly connected with the second distinguishing characteristic mentioned above (p. 34 sq). 38 I. Psychical Elements. § 6. PURE SENSATIONS. 1. The concept "pure sensation" as shown in § 5 is the product of a twofold abstraction: 1) from the ideas in which the sensation appears, and 2) from the simple feelings with which it is united. We find that pure sensations, defined in this way, form a number of disparate systems of quality ; each of these systems, such as that of sensations of pressure, of tone, or of hght, is either a homogeneous or a complex con- tinuity (§5, 5) from which no transition to any other system can be found. 2. The rise of sensations, as physiology teaches us, is re- gularly dependent on certain physical processes that have their origin partly in the external world surrounding us, partly in certain bodily organs. We designate these pro- cesses with a name borrowed from physiology as sense-stiTn- uli or sensation- stimuli. If the stimulus is a process in the outer world we call it physical; if it is a process in our own body we call it physiological. Physiological stimuK may be divided, in turn, into penpheral and central, according as they are processes in the various bodily organs outside of the brain, or processes in the brain itself. In many cases a sensation is attended by all three forms of stimuli. Thus, to illustrate, an external impression of hght acts as a physical stimulus on the eye; in the eye and optic nerve there arises a peripheral physiological stimulation; finally a central phys- iological stimulation takes place in the corpora quadrigemina and in the occipital regions of the cerebral cortex, where the optic nerve terminates. In many cases the physical stimulus may be wanting, while both forms of physiological stimuli are present; as, when we perceive a flash of light in consequence of a violent ocular movement. In still other cases the central stimulus alone is present; as, when we recall a hght- § 6. Pure Sensations. 39 impression previously experienced. The central stimulus is, accordingly, the only one that always accompanies sensation. When a peripheral stimulus causes a sensation, it must be connected with a central stimulus, and a physical must be connected with both a peripheral and a central stimulus. 3. "The physiological study of development renders it probable that the differentiation of the various sensational systems has been effected in part in the course of general development. The original organ of sense is the outer skin with the sensitive inner organs adjoining it. The organs of taste, smell, hearing, and sight, on the other hand, are later differentiations of it. It may, therefore, be surmised that the sensational systems corresponding to these special sense- organs, have also gradually arisen through differentiation from the sensational systems of the general sense, from sensations of pressure, hot, and cold. It is possible, too, that in lower animals some of the systems now so widely differentiated are even yet more alike. From a physiological standpoint the primordeal character of the general sense is also apparent in the fact, that it has for the .transfer of sense-stimuli to the nerves either very simple organs or none at all. Pressure, temperatiu-e, and pain-stimuli can produce sensations at points in the skin where, in spite of the most careful investigation, no special end-organs can be found. There are, indeed, special receiving organs in the regions most sensitive to pressure (touch-cor- puscles, end-bulbs, and corpuscles of Vater), but their struc- ture renders it probable that they merely favor the mechanical transfer of the stimulus to the nerve-endings. Special end-organs for hot, cold, and pain-stimuU have not been found at all. In the later developed special sense-organs, on the other hand, we find everywhere structures which not only effect the suitable transfer of the stimuli to the sensory nerves, but generally bring about a physiological transformation of the 40 I- Psyehical Elements. stimulation which is indispensable for the rise of the peculiar sensational qualities. But even among the special senses there are differences in this respect. The receiving organ in the ear, in particular, appears to be of a character different from that of the organs of smell, taste, and sight. In its most primitive forms it consists of a vesicle filled with one or more solid particles (otoliths), and sup- plied with nerve-bundles distributed in its walls. The particles are set in motion through sound-vibrations, and must cause a rapid succession of weak pressure-stimulations in the fibres of the nerve-bundles. The auditory organ of the higher animals shows an extraordinary complexity, still, in its essential struc- ture it recalls this primitive type. In the cochlea of man and the higher animals the auditory nerve passes at first through the axis, which is pierced by a large number of fine canals, and then emerges through the pores which open into the cavity of the cochlea. Here the branches are distributed on a tightly stretched membrane, which extends through the spiral windings of the cochlea and is weighted with special rigid arches (arches of Corti). This membrane — the basilar membrane, as it is called — must, according to the laws of acoustics, be thrown into sympathetic vibrations whenever sound-waves strike the ear. It seems, therefore, to play the same part here as the otohths do in the lower forms of the auditory organ. At the same time one other change has taken place which accounts for the enormous differentiation of the sensational system. The basilar membrane has a differ- ent breadth in its different parts, for it grows continually wider from the base to the apex of the cochlea. In this way it acts like a system of stretched chords of different lengths. And just as in such a system, other conditions re- maining the same, the longer chords are tuned to lower and the shorter to higher tones, so we may assume the same to ^' 6. Pure Sensations. 41 be true for the different parts of the basilar membrane. We may surmise that the simplest auditory organs with their otoliths have a homogeneous sensational system, analogous perhaps to our systems of sensations of pressure. The special development of the organ as seen in the cochlea of higher animals explains the evolution of an extraordinarily complex sensational system from this originally homogeneous system. Still, the structure remains similar in this respect, that it seems adapted, in the latter case as in the former, to the best possible transfer of the physical stimulus to the sensory nerve rather than to any transformation of the stim- ulus. This view agrees with the observed fact that, just as sensations of pressure may be perceived on regions of the skin not supplied with special receiving organs, so, in the case of certain animals, such as birds, where the conditions are specially favorable for their transmission, sound-vibrations are transferred to the auditory nerve and sensed even after the removal of the whole auditory organ vnth its special re- ceiving structure. With smell, taste, and sight the case is essentially differ- ent. Organs are present which render direct action of the stimuli on the sensory nerves impossible. The external stim- uli are here received through special organs and modified before they excite the nerves. These organs are specially metamorphosed epithelial cells with one end exposed to the stimulus and the other passing into a nerve-fibre. Everything goes to show that the receiving organs here are not merely for the transfer of the stimuH, but rather for their trans- formation. In the three cases under discussion it is probable that the transformation is a chemical process. In smell and taste we have external chemical agencies, ia sight we have light as the causes of chemical disintegrations in the sensory cells; these processes in the cells then serve as the real stimuli. 42 I- Psychical Elements. These three senses may, as chemical senses, be distinguished from the mechanical senses of pressure and sound. It is impossible to say with any degree of certainty, to which of these two classes sensations of cold and hot belong. One indication of the direct relation between stimuU and seiisation in mechanical senses, as contrasted with the indirect relation in chemical senses, is that in the first case the sensation lasts only a very little longer than the external stimulus, while in the latter case it persists very much longer. Thus, in a quick succession of pressures and more especially of sounds, it is possible to distinguish clearly the single stimuH from one another; lights, tastes, and smellSj on the other hand, run together at a very moderate rate of succession. 4. Since peripheral and central stimuli are regular physical concomitants of elementary sensational processes, the attempt to determine the relation between stimuH and sensations is very natural. In attempting to solve this problem, physiol- ogy generally considers sensations as the result of physio- logical stimuli, but assumes at the same time that in this case any proper explanation of the effect from its cause is impossible, and that all that can be undertaken is to deter- mine the constancy of the relations between particular stimuli and the resulting sensations. Now, it is found in many cases that different stimuh acting on the same end-organ produce the same sensations ; thus, for example, mechanical and elec- trical stimulations of the eye produce light sensations. This result was generalized in the principle, that every receiving element of a sense-organ and every simple sensory nerve-fibre together with its central terminus, is capable of only a single sensation of fixed quality; that the various quaUties of sen- sation are, therefore, due to the various physiological elements with different specific energies. This principle, generally called the "law of specific energy § 6. Pure Sensations. 43 of nerves", is untenable for three reasons, even if we neglect for the moment the fact that it simply refers the causes of the various differences in sensations to a qualitas occulta of sensory and nervous elements. 1) It is contradictory to the physiological doctrine of the development of the senses. If, as we must assume according to this doctrine, the complex sensational systems are derived from systems originally simpler and more homogeneous, the physiological sensory elements must have undergone a change also. This, however, is possible only under the condition that organs may be modified by the stimuli which act upon them. That is to say, the sensory elements determine the qualities of sensations only secondarily, as a result of the prop- erties which they acquire through the processes of stimulation aroused in them. If, then, these sensory elements have under- gone, in the course of time, radical changes due to the nature of the stimuU acting upon them, such changes could have been possible only under the condition that the physiological stimu- lations in the sensory elements varied to some extent with the quality of the stimulus. 2) The principle of specific energy is contradictory to the fact that in many senses the number of different sensory elements does not correspond at all to that of different sen- sational quahties. Thus, from a single point in the retina we can receive all possible sensations of brightness and color; in the organs of smell and taste we find no clearly dis- tinguishable forms of the sensory elements, while even a limited area of their sensory surfaces can receive a variety of sensations, which, especially in the case of the olfactory organ,- is very large. Where we have every reason to assume that qualitatively diferent sensations actually do arise in differ- ent sensory elements, as in the case of the auditory organ, the structure of the organ goes to show that this difference 44 !• Psyehical Elements. is not due to any attribute of the nerve -fibres or of other sensory elements, but that it comes originally from the way in which they are arranged. Different fibres of the auditory nerve will, of course, be stimulated by different tone-vibrations, because the different parts of the basilar membrane are tuned to different tones; but this is not due to some original and inexplicable attribute of the single auditory nerve-fibres, but to the way in which they are connected with the end-organ. 3) Finally, the sensory nerves and central elements can have no original specific energy, because the peripheral sense- organ must be exposed to the adequate stimuli for a suf- ficient interval, or must at least have been so exposed at some previous period^ before the corresponding sensations can arise through their stimulation. Persons congenitally bhnd and deaf do not have any sensations of light or tone whatever, so far as we know, even when the sensory nerves and centres were originally present. Everything goes to show that the differences in the qual- ities of sensations are conditioned by the differences in the processes of stimulation that arise in the sense-organs. These processes are dependent primarily on the character of the physical stimuH, and only secondarily on the peculiarities of the receiving organ, which are due to its adaptation to ihese stimuli. As a result of this adaptation, however, it may happen that even when some stimulus other than that which has effected the original adaptation of the sensory elements, that is, when an inadequate stimulus acts, the sensation corresponding to the adequate stimulus may arise. Still, this does not hold for all stimuh or for all sensory elements. Thus, hot land cold stimulations can not cause cutaneous sensations of pressure or sensations in the special sense-organs; chemical and electrical stimuli produce sensations of Hght only when they act upon the retina, not when they act on § 6. Pure Sensations. 45 the optic nerve; and, finally, these general stimuli can not arouse sensations of smell or taste. When an electric current causes chemical disintegration, it may, indeed, arouse such sensations, but it is through the adequate chemical stimuli produced. 5. From the very nature of the case, it is impossible to explain the character of sensations from the character of phy- sical and physiological stimuli. StimuU and sensations can not be compared with one another at all; the first belong to the mediate experience of the natural sciences, the second to the immediate experience of psychology. An interrelation between sensations and physiological stimuh must necessarily exist, however, in the sense that different kinds of stim- ulation always correspond to different sensations. This principle of the paraUelism of changes in sensation and in physiological stimulation is an important supplementary prin- ciple in both the psychological and physiological doctrines of sensation. In the first case it is used in producing defi- nite changes in the sensation, by means of intentional varia- tion of the stimulus ; in the second it is used in inferring the identity or non-identity of physiological stimulations from the identity or non-identity of the sensations. Furthermore, the same principle is the basis of our practical life and of our theoretical knowledge of the external world. A. SENSATIONS OF THE GENERAL SENSE. 6. The definition of the "general sense" includes two factors. In point of time, the general sense is that which precedes all others and therefore belongs to all beings endowed with mind. In its spacial attributes, the general sense is distinguished from the particular senses in having the most extensive sensory surface exposed to stimuli. It includes not only the whole external skin and the adjoining areas of 46 I- Psychical Elements. the mucous membrane, but a large number of internal or- gans supplied with sensory nerves, such as joints, muscles, tendons, and bones, which are accessible to stimuli either always, or at certain times, under special conditions, as is the case with bones. The general sense includes four specific, distinct sensa- tional systems: sensations of pressure, hot, cold, and pain. Not infrequently a single stimulus arouses more than one of these sensations. The sensation is then immediately recognized as made up of a raixture of components from the different systems; for example, from sensations of pressure and pain, or from sensations of hot and pain. In a similar manner, as a result of the extension of the sense-organ, we may often have mixtures of the various qualities of one and the same system, for example, quahtatively different sensations of pres- sure, when an extended region of the skin is touched. The four systems of the general sense are all homogeneous systems (§ 5, 5). This shows that the sense is genetically earlier than the others , whose systems are all complex. The sensations of pressure from the external skin, and those due to the tensions and movements of the muscles, joints, and tendons, are generally grouped together under the name touch- sensations, and distinguished from the common sensations, which include sensations of hot, cold, and pain, and those sen- sations of pressure that sometimes arise in the other internal organs. This distinction, however, has its source in the re- lation of the sensations to ideas and concomitant feelings, and has nothing to do with the qualities of the sensations in themselves. 7. The ability of the different parts of the general sense- organ to receive stimulations and give rise to sensations, can be tested with adequate exactness only on the external skin. The only facts that can be determined in regard to § 6. Pure Sensations. 47 the internal parts, are that the joints are in a high degree sensitive to pressures, while the muscles and tendons are much less so, and that sensations of hot, cold, and pain in the internal organs are exceptional, and noticeable only under abnormal conditions. On the other hand, there is no point of the external skin and of the immediately ad- joining parts of the mucous membrane, which is not sen- sitive at once to stimulations of pressure, hot, cold, and pain. The degree of sensitivity may, indeed, vary at different points, in such a way that the points most sensitive to pressure, to hot, and to cold, do not, in generally, coincide. Sensitivity to pain is everywhere about the same, varying at most in such a way that in some places the pain-stimulus acts on the sur- face, and in others not until it has penetrated deeper. On the other hand, certain approximately punctiform cutaneous regions appear to be most favorable for stimulations of pressure, hot, and cold. These points are called respectively, pressure-spots, hot-spots, and cold-spots. They are distributed in different parts of the sldn in varying numbers. Spots of dif- ferent modality never coincide ; still, temperature-spots always receive sensations of pressure and pain as weU ; and a pointed hot stimulus applied to a cold spot always causes a sen- sation of hot, while hot-spots do not seem to be stimulated by pointed cold stimuli. Furthermore, hot-spots and cold- spots react with their adequate sensations to properly applied mechanical and electrical stimuli. 8. Of the four quaHties mentioned sensations of pressure and pain form closed systems which show no relations either to each other or to the two systems of temperature-sensations. These last two, on the other hand, stand in the relation of opposites; we apprehend hot and cold not merely as different, but as contrasted sensations. It is, however, very probable that this is not due to the original nature of the sensations, 48 I- Psychical Elements. but partly to the conditions of their rise, and partly to the accompanying feelings. For, while the other qualities may be united without Limitation to form mixed sensations — as, for example, pressure and hot, pressure and pain, cold and pain — hot and cold exclude each other because, under the conditions of their rise, the only possibilities for a given cu- taneous region are a sensation of hot or one of cold, or else an absence of both. "When one of these sensations passes continuously into the other, the change regularly takes place in such a way that either the sensation of hot gradually dis- appears and a continually increasing sensation of cold arises, or vice versa the sensation of cold disappears and that of hot gradually arises. Then, too, elementary feelings of opposite character are connected with hot and cold, the point where both sensations are absent corresponding to their indifference- zone. In still another respect the two systems of temperature- sensations are peculiar. They are to a great extent depen- dent on the varying conditions under which the stimuli act upon the sense-organ. A considerable increase above the temperature of the skin is perceived as hot, while a con- siderable decrease below the same is perceived as cold, but the temperature of the skin itself, which is the indifference- zone between the two, can adapt itself rapidly to the existing external temperature within fairly wide Umits. The fact that in this respect too, both systems are aUke, favors the view that they are interconnected and also antagonistic. B. SENSATIONS OF SOUND. 9. We possess two independent systems of simple auditory sensations, which are generally, however, connected as a result of the mixture of the two kinds of impressions. They are § 6. Pure Sensations. 49 the homogeneous system of simple noise-sensations and the complex system of simple tone-sensations. Simple noise-sensations can be produced only under con- ditions that exclude the simultaneous rise of tonal sensations, as when air-vibrations are produced whose rate is either too rapid or too slow for tone-sensations to arise, or when the sound-waves act upon the ear for too short a period. Simple sensations of noise, thus produced, may vary in intensity and duration, but apart from these differences they are quahta- tively alike. It is possible that small quaUtative differences also exist among them, due to the conditions of their rise, but such differences are too small to be marked by distin- guishing names. The noises commonly so called are com- pound ideas made up of such simple noise-sensations and of a great many irregular tonal sensations (cf. § 9, 7). The homogeneous system of simple noise-sensations is probably the first to develop. The auditory vesicles of the lower animals, with their simple otoliths, could hardly produce any- thing but these. In the case of man and the higher animals it may be surmised that the structures found in the vestibule of the labyrinth receive only homogeneous stimulations, corre- sponding to simple sensations of noise. Finally, experiments with animals deprived of their labyrinths, make it probable that even direct stimulations of the auditory nerve can produce such sensations (p. 41). In the embryonic development of the higher animals, the cochlea develops from an original vestibular vesicle, which corresponds exactly to a primitive auditory organ. We are, therefore, justified in supposing that the complex system of tonal sensations is a product of the' differentiation of the homogeneous system of simple noise- sensations, but that in evefy case where this development' has taken place, the simple system has remained along with the higher. Wdndt, Psychology. • 4 50 !• Psychical Elements, 10. The system of simple tone-sensaUons is a continuity of one dimension. We call the quality of the single simple tones pitch. The one -dimensional character of the system finds expression in the fact that, starting with a given pitch, we can vary the quality only in two opposite directions: one we call raising the pitch, the other lowering it. In actual experience simple sensations of tone are never pre- sented alone, but always united with othei^tonal sensations and with accompanying simple sensations of noise. But since, according to the scheme given above (§5, 1), these concomitant elements can be varied indefinitely, and since in many cases they are relatively weak in comparison with one of the tones, the abstraction of simple tones was early reached through the practical use of tonal sensations in the art of music. The names c, c**, d**, and d stand for simple tones, though the clangs of musical instruments or of the human voice by means of which we produce these different pitches, are always accompanied by other, weaker tones and often, too, by noises. But since the conditions for the rise of such concomitant tones can be so varied that they become very weak, it has been possible to produce really simple tones of nearly perfect purity. The simplest means of doing this is by using a tuning-fork, and a resonator tuned to its fundamental tone. Since the resonator increases the intensity of the fundamental only, the other, accom- panying tones are so weak when the fork sounds, that the sensation is generally apprehended as simple and irre- ducible. If the sound -vibrations corresponding to such a tonal sensation are examined, they will be found to corre- spond to the simplest possible form of vibration, the pendulum- oscillation, so called because the vibrations of the atmospheric particles follow the same laws as a pendulum oscillating in § 6. Pure Sensations. 5| a very small amplitude'). That these relatively simple sound- vihrations correspond to sensations of simple tones, and that we can even distinguish the separate tones in compounds, can be explained, on the basis of the physical laws of sympathetic vibrations, from the structure of the organs in the cochlea. The basilar membrane in the cochlea is in its different parts tuned to tones of different pitch, so that when a simple oscillatory sound-vibration strikes the ear, only the part tuned to that particular pitch will vibrate in sympathy. If the same rate of oscillation comes in a compound sound-vibration, again only the part tuned to it will be affected by it, while the other components of the wave will set in vibration other sections of the membrane, which correspond in the same way to their pitch. 11. The system of tonal sensations shows its character as a conUrvuous series in the fact that it is always possible to pass from a given pitch to any other through continuous changes in sensation. Music has selected at option from this continuity single sensations separated by considerable inter- vals, thus substituting a to'nal scale for the tonal line. This selection, however, is based on the relations of tonal sensations themselves. We shall return to the discussion of these relations later, in taking up the ideational compounds arising from these sensations (§ 9). The natural tonal line has two extremities, which are conditioned by the physiological capacity of the ear for receiving sounds. These extremities are the lowest and highest tones; the former corresponds to 8 — 3 double vibrations per second, the latter to 40,000 — 50,000. 1) Pendulum-oscillations may be represented by a sine-curve, be- cause the distance from the position of rest is always proportional to the sine of the time required to swing to the point in question. 4* 52 I. Psyehiecd Elements. C, SENSATIONS OF SMELL AND TASTE. 12. Sensations of smell form a complex system whose arrangement is still unknown. AU we know is that there is a very great number of olfactory qualities, between which there are all possible transitional forms. There can, then, be no doubt that the system is a continuity of many dimensions. 12 a. Olfactory qualities may be grouped in certain classes, each of which contains those sensations which are more or less related. This fact may be regarded as an indication of how these sensations may perhaps be reduced to a small number of prin- cipal qualities. Such classes are, for examples, sensations like . those from ether, balsam, musk, benzine, those known as aromatic, etc. It has been observed in a few cases that certain olfactory sensations which come from definite substances, can also be pro- duced by mixing others. But these observations are still in- sufficient to reduce the great number of simple qualities con- tained in each of the classes mentioned, to a limited number of primary qualities and their mixtures. Finally, it has been observed that many odors neutralize ' each other, so far as the sensation is concerned, when they are mixed in the proper intensi- ties. This is true not only of substances that neutralize each other chemically , as acetic acid and ammonia , but also of others, such as caoutchouc and wax or tolu-balsam, which do not act on each other chemically outside of the olfactory cells. Since this neutralization takes place when the two stimuli act on entirely different olfactory surfaces, one on the right and the other on the left mucous membrane of the nose, it is probable that we are dealing, not with phenomena analogous to those ex-, hibited by complementary colors (22) , but with a reciprocal central inhibition of sensations. Another observed fact tells against the notion that they are complementary. One and the same olfactory quality can neutralize several entirely different qualities, sometimes even those which in turn neutralize one another, while among colors it is always only two fixed qualities that are complementary. § 6. Pure Sensations. 53 13. Sensations of taste have been somewhat more thoroughly- investigated, and we can here distinguish four Aistinct primary qualities. Between these there are all possible transitional tastes, which are to be regarded as mixed sensations. The primary qualities are sour, sweet, bitter, and saline. Besides these, alkaline and metalHc are sometimes regarded as inde- pendent qualities. But alkaline quaUties show an unmis- takable relationship with sahne, and metalhc with sour, so that both are probably mixed sensations (alkaline made up perhaps of saUne and sweet, metalhc of sour and saUne). Sweet and saline are opposite qualities. When these two sensations are united in proper intensities, the result is a neutral mixed sensation (commonly known as "insipid"), even though the stimuh that here reciprocally neutralize each other do not enter into a chemical combination. The system of taste- sensations is, accordingly, in all probabiKty to be regarded as a two-dimensional continuity, which may be geometrically represented by a circular surface on whose circumference the four primary, and their intermediate, qualities are arranged, while the neutral mixed sensation is in the middle, and the other transitional taste-qualities on the surface , between this middle point and the saturated qualities on the circumference. 13 a. In these attributes of taste-qualities we seem to liave the fundamental type of a chemical sense. In this respect taste is perhaps the antecedent of sight. The obvious interconnection with the chemical nature of the stimulation, makes it probable even here that the reciprocal neutralization of certain sensations, with which the two-dimensional character of the sensational system is perhaps connected, depends, not on the sensations in themselves, but on the relations between the physiological stimu- lations, just as in the case of sensations of hot and cold (p. 48). It is well known that very commonly the chemical effect of certain substances can be neutralized through the action of cer- tain other substances. Now. we do not know what the chemical 54 /■ Psychical Elements. changes are that are produced by the gustatory stimuli in the taste-cells. But from the neutralization of sensations of sweet and saline we may conclude, in accordance with the principle of the parallelism of changes in sensation and in stimuli (p. 45), that the chemical reactions which sweet and saline substances produce in the sensory cells, also counteract each other. The same would hold for other sensations for which similar relations could be demonstrated. In regard to the physiological conditions for gustatory stimulations, we can draw only this one conclusion from the facts mentioned, namely, that the chemical processes of stimulation corresponding to the sensations which neutralize each other in this way, probably take place in the same cells. Of course, the possibility is not excluded that several different processes liable to neutralization through opposite reactions, could arise in the same cells. The known anatomical facts and the experiments of physiology in stimulating single papillae separately, giye no certain conclusions in this matter. Whether we are here dealing with phenomena that are really analogous to those exhibited by complementary colors (v. iaf. 22) is still a question. D. SENSATIONS OF LIGHT. 14. The system of light-sensations is made up of two partial systems: that of sensations of achromatic light and that of se?isations of chromatic light. Between the quaUties in these two, all possible transitional forms exist. Sensations of achromatic light, when considered alone, form a complex system of 07ie dimension, which extends, like the tonal line, between two limiting quahties. The sensations in the neighborhood of one of these limits we call black, in the neighborhood of the other white, while between the two we insert grey in its different shades (dark grey, grey, and light grey). This one -dimensional system of achromatic sensations differs from that of tones in being at once a system of quality and of intensity; for every qualitative change in the direction from black to white is seen at the § 6. Pure Sensations. 55 same time as an increase in intensity, and every qualitative change in the direction from white to black is seen as a decrease in intensity. Each point in the series, which thus has a def- inite quality and intensity, is called a degree of brightness of the achromatic sensations. The whole system may, accord- ingly , he designated as that of sensations of pure brightness. The use of the word "pure" indicates the absence of all sen- sations of color. The system of pure brightness is absolutely one-dimensional for, both the variations in quality and those in intensity belong to one and the same dimension. It differs essentially, in this respect, from the tonal Hne, in which each point is merely a degree of quaUty, and has also a whole series of gradations in intensity. Simple tone -sensations thus form a two-dimensional continuity so soon as we take into account both determinants, quality and intensity, while the system of pure brightness is always one-dimensional, even when we attend to both determinants. The whole system may, therefore, be regarded as a continuous series of grades of brightness, in which the lower grades are designated black so far as quality is concerned, and weak in point of inten- sity, while the higher grades are called white and strong. 15. Sensations of color also form a orie-dimensional system when their qualities alone are taken into account. Unhke the system of sensations of pure brightness, this system returns upon itself from whatever point we start, for at first, after leaving a given quality, we pass gradually to a quality that shows the greatest difference, and going still further we find that the qualitative differences become smaller again, until finally we reach the starting point once more. The color- spectrum obtained by refracting sunlight through a prism, or that seen in the rainbow, shows this characteristic, though not completely. If in these cases we start from the red end of the spectrum, we come first to orange, then to yellow, yellow- 56 I. Psyehieal Elements, green, green-blue, blue, indigo-blue, and finally to violet, which is more like red than any of the other colors except orange, which lies next to red. The line of colors in the spectrum does not return quite to its starting-point, because it does not contain all of the colors that we have in sen- sation. Purple-red shades , which can be obtained by the ob- jective mixture of red and violet rays, are wanting in the spectrum. Only when we fill out the spectral series with them, is the system of actual color- sensations complete, and then the system is a closed circle. This characteristic is not to be attributed to the circumstance that the spectrum actually presents for our observation a series returning nearly to its beginning. The same order of sensations can be found by arranging according to their subjective relationship , colored objects presented in any irregular order. Even children who have never observed attentively a solar spectrum or a rain- bow, and can, therefore, begin the series with any other color just as well as with red, always arrange them in the same order. The system of pure colors is, then, to be defined as one- dimensional. It does not extend in a straight , line, however, but returns upon itself. Its simplest geometrical represen- tation would be a circle. From a given point in this system we pass, when the sensation is gradually varied, first to similar sensations, then to those most markedly different, and finally to others similar to the first quahty, but in the opposite direction. Every color must, accordingly, be related to one other particular color as a maximum of difference in sen- sation. This color may be called the opposite color, and in the representation of the color-system by a circle, two oppo- site colors are to be placed at the two extremities of the same diameter. Thus, for example, purple-red and green, yellow and blue, light green and violet, are opposite colors, that is,, colors which exhibit the greatest qualitative differences. § 6. Pure Sensations. 57 The quality determined by the position of a sensation in the color-system, in distinction to other quahtative deter- minations, is called color-tone, a figurative name borrowed from tonal sensations. In this sense the simple names of colors, such as red, orange, yellow, etc., denote merely color- tones. The color-circle is a representation of the system of color-tones abstracted from all the other attributes belonging to the sensations. In reality, every color-sensation has two other attributes, one we call its saturation, the other its brightness. Saturation is peculiar to chromatic sensations, while brightness belongs to achromatic sensations as well. 16. By saturation we mean the attribute of color-sensa- tions by virtue of which they appear in all possible stages of transition to sensations of pure brightness, so that a con- tinuous passage is possible from every color to any point in the series of whites, greys, and blacks. The term "satura- tion" is borrowed from the common method of producing these transitional colors objectively, that is, by the more or less intense saturation of some colorless soluble with color- pigment. A color may be ever so saturated, yet it is possible to think of a still greater saturation of the same color-tone, and, on the other hand, pure brightness always denotes the end of the series of diminishing grades of saturation for any color whatever. A degree of saturation may, therefore, be thought of as an attribute of all color-sensations, and, at the same time, as the attribute by which the system of color-sensations is directly united with that of sensations of pure brightness. If, now, we represent some particular sen- sation of white, grey, or black by the central point of the color-circle, aU the grades of saturation that can arise as transitional stages from any particular color to this particular sensation of pure brightness, wiU obviously be represented by that radius of the circle which connects the centre with 58 !■ Psychical Elements. the color in question. If the grades of saturation correspond- ing to the continuous transitional stages from all the colors to a particular sensation of pure brightness, are thus geo- metrically represented, we have the system of saturation-grades as a circular surface whose circumference is the system of simple color-tones, and whose centre is the sensation of pure brightness, corresponding to the absence of all saturation. For the formation of such a system of saturation-grades any point whatever in the series of sensations of pure bright^ ness may be taken, so long as the condition is fulfilled that the white is not too bright or the black too dark, for in such cases differences in both saturation and color disappear. Systems of saturation which are arranged about different points in the series of pure brightness, always have different grades of brightness. A pure system of saturation, accord- ingly , can be made for only one particular grade of bright- ness at a time, that is, for only one point in the series of sensations of pure brightness. "When such systems are made for all possible points, the system of saturation will be sup- plemented by that of grades of brightness. 17. Brightness is just as necessary an attribute of a color-sensation as it is of achromatic sensations, and is in this case, too, at once a quality and degree of intensity. Starting from a given grade, if the brightness increases, every color approaches white in quality, while at the same time the intensity increases; if the brightness decreases, the colors approach black in quahty, and the intensity diminishes. The grades of brightness for any single color thus form a system of intensive qualities, analogous to that of pure brightnesses, only in place of the achromatic gradations between white and black, we have the corresponding grades of saturation. From the point of greatest saturation there are two opposite directions for variation in saturation: one positive, towards § 6, Pure Sensations. 59 white, accompanied by an increase in the intensity of the sensation, and the other negative, towards black, with a corresponding decrease in intensity. As limits for these two directions we have, on the one hand, the pure sensation white, on the other, the pure sensation black; the first is at the same time the maximum, the second the minimum of inten- sity. White and black are in this way opposite extremities of the system of sensations of pure brightness, and also of the system of color-sensations arranged according to grades of brightness. It foUows obviously that there is a certain .medium brightness for every color, at which its saturation is greatest. From this point, the saturation diminishes in the positive direction when the brightness increases, and in the negative direction when the brightness decreases. The grade of brightness most favorable for the saturation is not the same for all colors, but varies from red to blue, in such a way that it is most intense for red and least intense for blue. This accounts for the familiar phenomenon that in twilight, when the degree of brightness is small, the blue color-tones — of paintings, for example — are still clearly visible, while the red color-tones appear black. 18. If we neglect the somewhat different position of the maximal saturation of the various colors in the line of brightness, the relation that exists between sensations of chromatic brightness and those of pure, or achromatic, brightness, by virtue of the gradual transition of colors into white on the one hand, and into black on the other, may be represented in the simplest manner as follows. First, we may represent the system of pure color-tones, that is, of the colors at their maximal saturation, by a circle, as above. Then we may draw through the centre of this circle, perpendicular to its plaiie, the straight line of pure brightness, in such a way that where it cuts the plane of the circular surface, 60 !■ Psychical Elements. it represents the sensation of pure brightness corresponding to the minimum of saturation for the colors with which we started. In hke manner, the other color-circles for increasing and decreasing grades of brightness, may be arranged per- pendicularly along this line, above and below the circle of greatest saturation. But the decreasing saturation of the colors in these latter circles must be expressed in the short- ening of their radii; just as in the first circle, the shorter the distance from the centre, the less the saturation. These radii grow continually shorter, until finally, at the two extrem- ities of the Mne, the circles disappear entirely. This corre- sponds to the fact that for every color the maximum of brightness corresponds to the sensation white, while its mini- mum corresponds to black'). 19. The whole system of sensations of chromatic bright- ness may, accordingly, be most simply represented by a spher- ical surface whose equator represents the system of pure color-tones, or colors of greatest saturation, while the two poles correspond to white and black, the extremities of the sensations of chromatic brightness. Of course, any other geo- metrical figure with similar attributes, as, for example, two cones with a common base and apexes pointing in different directions, would serve the same purpose. The only thing essential for the representation, is the gradual transition to white and black, and the corresponding decrease in the variety of the color-tones, which finds its expression in the continual decrease in the length of the radii of the color-circles. Now, as above shown, the system of saturations corresponding to 1) It must be observed, however, that the actual coincidence of these sensations can be empirically proved only for the minimum of brightness. Grades of brightness which approach the maximum are so injurious to the eye that the general demonstration of the approach to white must be accepted as sufficient. § 6. Pure Sensations. gj a particular sensation of pure brightness, may be represented by a circular surface which contains all the sensations of light belonging to one grade of brightness. When we unite grades of saturation and brightness to a single system, the toted system of all light s&nsaUons may be represented by a solid sphere. The equator is the system of pure color- tones; the polar axis is the system of pure brightnesses ; the surface represents the system of chromatic brightnesses, and, finally, every circular plane perpendicular to the polar axis, corre- sponds to a system of saturations of equal brightness. This representation by means of a sphere is indeed arbitrary, in the sense that any other sohd figure with analogous attri- butes may be chosen in its place; still, it presents to view the psychological fact that the total system of light-sensations is a closed continuity of three dimensions. The three-dimen- sional character of the system arises from the fact that every concrete sensation of light has three determinants : color-tone, saturation, and brightness. Pure, or achromatic, brightness and pure, or saturated, colors are to be regarded as the two extreme cases in the series of saturations. The closed form of the system comes from the circular character of the color-line, on the one hand, and, on the other, from the termination of the system of chromatic brightness in the ex- tremes of pure brightness. A special characteristic of the system is that only the changes in the ttvo dimensions, or those of color-tones and saturations, are pure variations in quality, while every movement in the third dimension, or that of brightness, is at once a modification of both quality and intensity. As a consequence of this circumstance, the whole three-dimensional system is required to represent fully the qualities of Hghl^sensations, but it includes also the in- tensities of these sensations. 20. Certain principal sensations are prominent in this 62 !■ Psychical Elements. system, because we use them as points of reference for the arrangement of all the others. These are white and block, in the achromatic series, and the four principal colors, red, yellow, green, and bltie, in the chromatic. Only these six sensations have clearly distinguished names in the early de- velopment of language. All other sensations are then named either with reference to these or even with modifications of the names themselves. Thus, we regard grey as a stage in the achromatic series lying hetween white and black. We designate the different grades of saturation according to their brightness, as whitish or blackish, Kght or dark color-tones; and we generally choose compound names for the colors be- tween the four principal ones, as, for example, purple -red, orange-yellow, yellow-green, etc. These all show their relatively late origin by their very composition. 20 a. From the early origin of the names for the six qualities mentioned, the conclusion has been drawn that they are funda- mental qualities of vision, and that the others are compounded from them. Grey is declared to be a mixture of black and white, violet and purple-red to be mixtures of blue and red, etc. Psychologically there is no justification for calling any light- sensations compound in comparison with others. Grey is a simple sensation just as much as white or black; such colors as orange and purple-red are just as much simple colors as red and yellow ; and any grade of saturation which we have placed in the system between a pure color and white, is by no means, for that reason, a compound sensation. The closed, continuous character of the system makes it necessary for language to pick out certain especially marked differences in reference to which all other sensations are then arranged, for the simple reason that it is impossible to have an unlimited number of names. It is most natural that white and black should be chosen as such points of reference for the achromatic series, since they designate the greatest differences. When once these two are given, however, all other achromatic sensations will be considered as transitional § 6. Pure Sensations. 63 sensations between them, since the extreme differences are connected by a series of all possible grades of brightness. The case of color-sensations is similar; only here, on account of the circular form of the color-line, it is impossible to choose directly two absolutely greatest differences. Other motives besides the necessary qualitative difference, are decisive in the choice of the principal colors. We may regard as such motives, the frequency and affective intensity of certain light- impressions due to the natural conditions of human existence. The red color of blood, the green of vegetation, the blue of the sky, and the yellow of the heavenly bodies in contrast with the blue of the sky, may well have furnished the earliest occasions for the choice of cer- tain colors as those to receive names. Language generally names the sensation from the object that produced it, not the object from the sensation. In this case too, when certain principal qualities were once determined, all others must, on account of the continuity of the series of sensations, seem to be intermediate color-tones. The difference between principal colors and tran- sitional colors is, therefore, very probably due entirely to external conditions. If these conditions had been other, red might have been regarded as a transitional color between purple and orange, just as orange is now placed between red and yellow^). 21. The attributes of the system of light-sensations above described, are so peculiar as to lead us to expect a priori that the relation between these psychological attributes and the objective processes of stimulation, is essentially different from that in the cases of the sensational systems discussed before, especially those of the general and auditory senses. Most 1) The same false reasoning from the names of sensations, has even led some scholars to assume that the sensation blue developed later than other color-sensations, because, for example, even in Homer the word for blue is the same as that for "dark". Tests of the color- sensations of uncivilized peoples whose languages are much more deficient in names for colors than that of the Greeks at the time of Homer, have given us a superabundance of evidence that this as- sumption is utterly without ground. 64 !■ Psychical Elements. striking, in this respect, is the difference between the system in question and that of tones. In the latter case, the prin- ciple of parallelism between sensation and stimulus (p. 45), holds not only for the physiological processes of stimulation, but to a great extent for the physical processes as well. A simple sensation corresponds to a simple form of sound- yibration, and a plurahty of simple sensations to a compound form. Furthermore, the intensity of the sensation varies in proportion to the amplitude of the vibrations, and its quality with their form, so that in both directions the subjective difference between sensations increases with the growing differ- ence between the objective physical stimuli. The relation in the case of light -sensations is entirely different. Like objective sound, objective light also consists of vibrations in some medium. To be sure, the actual form of these vibrations is still a question, but from physical experiments on the phenomena of. interference we know that they consist of very short and rapid waves. Those seen as light vary in wave-length from 688 to 393 milhonths of a millimetre, and in rate from 450 to 790 billion vibrations per second. In this case, too, simple sensations correspond to simple vibrations, that is, vibrations of like wave-length; and the quality of the sensation varies continuously with the rate: red corresponds to the longest and slowest waves, and violet to the shortest and most rapid, while the other color-tones form a continuous series between these, varying with the changes in wave-length. Even here, however, an essential difference appears, for the colors red and violet, which are the most different in wave-length, are more similar in sensation than those which lie between'). 1) Many physicists, to be sure, believe that an analogous relation' is to be found between tones of different pitch, in the fact that every tone has in its octave a similar tone. But this similarity, as we § 6. Pure Sensations. 65 There are also other differences. 1) Every change in the amplitude of the physical vibrations corresponds to a sub- jective change in both intensity and quality, as we noted above in the discussion of sensations of brightness. 2) All light, even though it be made up of all the different kinds of vibration, is simple in sensation, just as much as objectively simple light, which is made up of only one kind of waves, as is immediately apparent if we make a subjective comparison of sensations of chromatic light with those of achromatic hght. From the first of these facts it follows that light which is physically simple may produce not only chromatic, but also achromatic sensations, for it approaches white when the am- pHtude of its vibrations increases, and black when the ampli- tude decreases. The quality of an achromatic sensation does not, therefore, determine unequivocally its source; it may be produced either through a change in the amplitude of objective light-vibrations or through a mixture of simple vibrations of different wave-lengths. In the first case, however, there is always connected with the change in amplitude a change in the grade of brightness, which does not necessarily take place when a mixture is made. 22. Even when the grade of brightness remains constant, this achromatic sensation may have one of several sources. A sensation of pure brightness of a given intensity may re- sult not only from a mixture of all the rates of vibration contained in solar light, as, for example, in ordinary day- light, but it may also result when only two kinds of ligh1> waves, namely those which correspond to sensations sub- shall see (§ 9), does not exist between simple tones, but depends on the actual sympathetic vibration of the octave in all compound clangs. Attempts to support this supposed analogy by finding in the color-line intervals corresponding to the various tonal intervals, third, fourth, fifth, etc., have all been entirely futile. WoNDT, Psychology. 5 QQ I. Psyohioal Elements. jectively the most different, that is, to opposite colors, are mixed in proper proportions. Since opposite colors, when mixed objectively, produce white, they are called complementary colors. As examples of such opposite or complementary col- ors we may mention spectral red and green-blue, orange and sky-blue, yellow and indigo-blue. Like achromatic sensations, each of the color-sensations may also, though to a more limited extent, have one of several sources. When two objective colors which lie nearer each other in the color-circle than opposites, are mixed, the mixture 'appears, not white, but of a color which in the series of objectively simple quahties lies between the two with which we started. The saturation of the resulting color is, indeed, very much diminished when the components of the mixture approach opposite colors ; but when they are near each other, the diminution is no longer perceptible, and the mixture and the corresponding simple color are generally subjectively ahke. Thus, the orange of the spectrum is absolutely indistinguish- able from a mixture of red and yellow rays. In this way, all the colors in the color-circle between red and green can be obtained by mixing red and green, all between green and violet by mixing green and violet, and, finally, purple, which is not in the solar spectrum, can be produced by mixing red and violet. The whole series of color-tones possible in sen- sation can, accordingly, be obtained from three objective col- ors. By means of the same three colors we can also pro- duce white with its intermediate stages. The mixture of red and violet gives purple, and this is the complementary color of green; and the white secured by mixing these complemen- tary colors, when mixed in different proportions with the various colors, gives the different grades of saturation. 23. The three objective colors that may be used in this way to produce the whole system of light -sensations, are § 6. Pure Sensatio7is. 57 called fundamental colms. In order to indicate their signif- icance, a triangular surface is chosen to represent the system of satiu'ations , rather than the circular surface which is de- rived from the psychological relations alone. The special signif- icance of the fundamental colors is then expressed by placing them at the angles of the triangle. Along the sides are arranged the color-tones in their maximal saturation, just as on the circumference of the color- circle, while the other grades of saturation in their transitions to white, which hes in the centre, are on the triangular surface. Theoretically, any set of three colors could be chosen as fundamental col- ors, provided they were suitably distant from one another. Practically, those mentioned, red, green, and violet, are preferable for two reasons. First, by using them we avoid haviug as one of the three, purple, which can not be produced by objectively simple light. Secondly, at the two ends of the spectrum sensations vary most slowly in proportion to the period of vibration, so that when the extreme colors of the spectrum are used as fundamental colors, the result ob- tained by mixing two neighboring ones is most hke the intermediate, objectively simple color'). 24. These phenomena show that in the system of light- sensations a simple relation does not exist between the physical stimuh and the sensations. This can be understood from what has been said above (3) as to the character of the physiological stimulation. The visual sense is to be 1) In the neighborhood of green this advantage does not exist, and the mixtures always appear less saturated than the intermediate simple colors. This is a clear proof that the choice of the three fundamental colors mentioned is indeed the most practical, but nevertheless arbitrary, and at bottom due to the familiar geometrical principle that a triangle is the simplest figure that can enclose a finite number of points in the same plane. 5* 68 I- Psychical Elements, reckoned among the chemical senses, and we can expect a simple relation only between the photochemical processes in the retina and the sensations. Now, we know from experience that different kinds of physical light produce like chemical disintegrations, and this explains in general the possibility mentioned above, of having the same sensation from many different kinds of objective light. According to the principle of parallelism between changes in sensation and in the physio- logical stimulation (p. 45), it may be assumed that the various physical stimuli which cause the same sensation all produce the same photochemical stimulation in the retina, arfd that altogether there are just as many kinds and varieties of the photochemical processes as kinds and varieties of distinguishable sensations. In fact, all that we know, up to the present time, about the physiological substratum of light-sensations is based upon this assumption. The investigation of the physiological processes of stimulation through light, has not yet given any further result than that the stimulation is in all probability a chemical process. 25. The relatively long persistence of the sensation after the stimulation that originated it, is exphcable on the assumption that the Hght-stimulations are due to chemical processes in the retina (3, p. 42). This persistence is called, with reference to the object used as stimulus, the after-image of the im- pression. At first this after-image appears in the same brightness and color as the object: white when the object is white, black when it is black, and if it is colored, in the same color. These are the positive and like-colored after-images. After a short time it passes, in the case of achromatic impres- sions, into the opposite grade of brightness, white into black, or black into white; in the case of colors, it passes into the opposite or complementary color. These are the negative and complementary after-images. If hght-stimuli of short duration § 6. Pure Sensations. 69 £lct upon the eye in darkness, this transition may be repeated several times. A second positive after-image follows the negative, and so on, so that an oscillation between the two phases takes place. The positive after-image may be readily explained by the fact that the photochemical disintegration caused by any kind of light, lasts a short time after the action of the light. The negative and complementary after-images can be explained by the fact that disintegration in a given direction causes a partial consumption of the photochemical substance most directly concerned, and this results in a corresponding modification of the photochemical processes when the stimulation of the retina continues. 26. The origin of a part of the phenomena included under the name light-contrasts and color-contrasts is very probably the same as that of the negative and complemeiitary after- images. These phenomena consist in the appearance of simul- taneous sensations of opposite brightness and color in the neighborhood of any light-impression. Thus, a white surface appears to be surrounded by a dark margin, a black surface by a bright margin, and a colored surface by a margin of the complementary color. These phenomena, which are called "marginal contrasts" when they are limited to the immediate neighborhood of the object, are in part at least nothing but negative or complementary after-images that are simultaneously visible in the immediate neighborhood of the impression as a result of continual weak ocular movements. Whether there is also an irradiation of the stimulation is a question; its existence still wants certain proof. The fact that these con- trasts increase as the light becomes more intense, just as after-images do, speaks for their interconnection with the latter. In this respect, this physiological contrast differs essen- tially from ceriSim psychological contrast-phenomena, with which it is generally confused. The latter are closely connected in 70 I- Psychical Elements. their rise with numerous other forms of psychological contrast, so that we will not discuss them until later, when we enter into the general treatment (§ 17, 9) of such phenomena. 26 a. If we take the principle of parallelism between sensation and physiological stimulation as the basis of our suppositions in regard to the processes that occur in the retina, we may conclude that an analogous independence in the photochemical processes corresponds to the relative independence which appears between achromatic and chromatic sensations. Two facts, one belonging to the subjective sensational system, the other to the objective phenomena of color-mixing, can be most naturally ex-' .plained oh this basis. The first is the tendency that every color- sensation shows, of passing into one of pure brightness when the grade of its brightness decreases or increases. This tendency is most simply interpreted on the assumption that every color- stimulation is made up of two physiological components, one corresponding to the chromatic, the other to the achromatic stimulation. To this assumption we may easily add the further condition, that for certain medium intensities of the stimuli the ■chromatic components are the strongest, while for greater and smaller intensities the achromatic components come more and more to the front. The second fact is that any two opposite colors are complementary ; that is, when mixed in suitable proportions, they produce an achromatic sensation. This phenomenon is most easily understood when we assume that opposite colors, which are subjec- tively the greatest possible differences, represent objective photo- chemical processes that neutralize each other. The fact that as a result of this neutralization an achromatic stimulation arises, is very readily explained by the presupposition that such a stimulation accompanies every chromatic stimulation from the first, and is therefore all that is left when antagonistic chromatic stimulations counteract each other. This assumption of a relative independence between the chromatic and achromatic photochemical processes, is supported in a very striking way by the existence of an ab- normity of vision', sometimes congenital , sometimes acquired through pathological changes in the retina, namely total color- blindness. In such cases all stimulations are, either on the whole § 6. Pure Sensations. 7 1 retina or on certain parts of it, seen as pure brightness, without any admixture of color. This is an incontrovertible proof that the chromatic and achromatic stimulations are separable physiological processes. If we apply the principle of parallelism to the chromatic stimulation, two facts present themselves. The first is that two colors separated by a limited, short distance, when mixed give a color that is like the intermediate simple color. This indicates that color-stimulation is a process that varies with the physical stimulus, not continuously, as the tonal stimulation, but in short stages, and in such a way that the stages in red and violet are longer than in green, where the mixture of colors fairly near each other, shows the effects of complementary action. Such a non-continuous variation of the process corresponds entirely with its chemical nature, for chemical disintegration and synthesis must always have to do with groups of atoms or molecules. The Second fact is that certain definite colors, which correspond to rather large differences in the stimuli, are subjectively opposite colors, that is, are maximal differences, and the same colors are objectively complementary, that is, mutually neutralizing, processes. Chemical processes, however, can neutralize each other only when they are in some way opposite in character. Any two com- plementary color-stimulations must, therefore, stand in a relation to each other similar to that which exists between the neutraliz- ing processes operative in the case of antagonistic achromatic stimulations. Still, there are two very essential differences here. First, this opposition in the character of color- stimulations is not limited to one case, but appears for every color distinguishable in sensation, so that we must conclude, according to our pre- supposition, that for every stage of the photochemical process of chromatic stimulation which is to be assumed on the ground of the results obtained by mixing neighboring colors, there is a certain complementary process. Secondly, the difference between two opposite colors, which is subjectively the greatest possible difference, is mediated by transitional forms, not merely in one direction from each color, as in the case of black and white, but in two opposite directions. In a similar way, the objective complementary action of two colors gradually diminishes as, start- ing from opposite colors, they approach each other in either of 72 !■ Psychical Elements. these two directions. We may, then, infer from this twofold elimination of complementary action that the return of the color-line to its starting point, corresponds to a repetition of related photo- chemical processes, on the same grounds that led us to infer the opposite character of the processes corresponding to opposite colors, from the fact that they are complementary. The whole process of chromatic stimulation, beginning with red and passing beyond violet through purple mixtures to its starting point, running parallel, as it does , with continuous changes in the wave-length of objective light, is to be regarded as an indefinitely long succession of photo- chemical processes. All these processes together, form a closed drck in which, for every stage, there is a neutralizing opposite and a possible transition to this opposite in two different directions. We know nothing about the total number of photochemical stages in this circle of processes. The numerous attempts made to reduce aU color-sensations to the smallest possible number of such stages, lack adequate foundation. Sometimes they indis- criminatingly translate the results of physical color-mixing into physiological processes, as in the assumption of three fundamental colors, red, green, and violet, from the different mixtures of which all sensations of light, even the achromatic, are to be derived (Young-Helmholtz hypothesis). Sometimes they start with the psychologically untenable assumption that the naming of colors is not due to the influence of certain external objects, but to the real significance of the corresponding sensations (v. sup. p. 63), and assume accordingly four fundamental colors as the sources of all color-sensations. The four fundamental colors here assumed are the two pairs red and green, yellow and blue, to which are added the similar pair of sensations of pure brightness, black and white. All other light -sensations such as grey, orange, violet, etc., are regarded as subjectively and objectively mixed colors (Her- ing's hypothesis). The evidence in support of the first as of the second of these hypotheses has been derived for the most part from the not infrequent cases oi partial color-blindness. Those who accept three fundamental colors, assert that all these cases are to be explained as a lack of the red or green sensa- tions, or else as a lack of both. Those who accept four, hold that partial color-blindness always includes two fundamental colors that belong together as opposites, and is, therefore, either § 6, Pure Sensations. 73 red-green-blindness or yellow-blue-blindness. An unprejudiced examination of color-blindness does not justify either of these assertions. The three-color theory can not explain total color- blindness, and the four-color theory is in contradiction to cases of pure red-blindness and pure green-blindness. Finally, both theories are overthrown by the cases that unquestionably occur, in which such parts of the spectrum as do not correspond to any of the three or four fundamental colors, appear colorless. The only thing that our present knowledge justifies us in saying, is that every simple sensation of light is conditioned physiologically by a combination of two photochemical processes, a mcmochromatic and a chromatic. The first is made up, in turn, of a process mainly of disintegration, when the light is more intense, and a process of restitution, when the light is weaker. The chromatic process varies by stages in such a way that the whole series of photochemical color-disintegrations forms a circle of processes in which the products of the disintegration for any two relatively most distant stages, neutralize each other'). Various changes as a result of the action of light have been ob- served in the living retina, all of which go to support the assump- tion of a photochemical process. Such are the gradual change into a colorless state, of a substance which in the retina not exposed to light is red (bleaching of the visual purple); microscopical movements of the pigmented protoplasm between the sensitive elements, or rods and cones; and, finally, changes in the form of the rods and cones themselves. Attempts to use these phenomena in any way for a physiological theory of light- stimulation, are certainly premature. The most probable con- clusion which we can now draw is that the difference in the 1) The further assumption is made by the defenders of the four fundamental colors, that two opposite colors are related just as bright and dark achromatic stimulations, that is, that one of these colors is due to a photochemical disintegration (dissimilation), the other to a restitution (assimilation). This is an analogy that contradicts the actual facts. The result obtained by mixing complementary colors is on its subjective side a sttppression of the color-sensation , 'while the mixture of white and black, on the other hand, produces an intermetUaie sensation. 74 !• Psychical Elements. forms of tte rods and cones is connected with a difference in function. The centre of the retina, which is the region of direct vision in the human eye, has only cones, while in the eccentric parts the rods are more numerous; furthermore, in the centre (which also wants the visual purple) the discrimination of colors is much better than in the eccentric regions , while the latter are much more sensitive to brightness. The natural conclusion from these facts is that the differences in sensitivity are connected with the photochemical properties of the rods and cones. Still, we lack here too any particular evidence. § 7. SIMPLE FEELINGS. 1 . Simple feelings may originate in very many more ways than simple sensations, as was noted in § 5. Even sucli feelings as we never observe except in connection with more or less complex ideational processes, have a simple character (p. 34 sq.). Thus, for example, the feeling of tonal harmony is just as simple as the feeling connected with a single tone. Several tonal sensations together are required to produce a harmony, so that it is a compound so far as its sensational contents are concerned, but the affective quality of certain harmonious compound clangs is so different from that of the feelings connected with the single tones, that both classes of feehngs are, subjectively, equally irreducible. The only essential difference between the two is that the feehngs which correspond to simple sensations can be easily isolated from the inter- connections of which they form a part in our experience, by the same method of abstraction which we employed in dis- covering the simple sensations (p. 38). Those, on the other hand, that are connected with some composite ideational compound, can never be separated from the feehngs which enter into the compound as subjective complements of the § 7. Simple Feelings. 75 sensations. Thus, for example, it is impossible to separate the feeling of harmony connected with the chord c e g from the simple feelings connected with each of the single tones c, e, and g. The latter may, indeed, be pushed into the background, for as we shall see later (§ 9, 3a), they always unite with the feeling of harmony to form a unitary total feelmg, but they can never be eliminated. 2. The feeling connected with a simple sensation is com- monly known as a sense- feeling, or the affective tone of a sen- satimi. These two expressions are capable of misinterpretation in two opposite senses. There is a tendency to think that by "sense-feeling" we mean not merely a component of imme- diate experience that may be isolated through abstraction, but one that really exists by itself. "Affective tone", on the other hand, may be regarded as an affective quality that must inevitably belong to a sensation, just as "color-tone" is a ne- cessary determinant of a color-sensation. In reahty, however, a sense-feeling without a sensation can no more exist than can a feeling of tonal harmony without tonal sensations. When, as is sometimes the case, the feelings accompanying sensations of pain, of pressure, of hot, and of cold, and muscle-sensa- tions, are called independent sense-feelings, it is due to the confusion of the concepts sensation and feeling (p. 36) which is still prevalent, especially in physiology. As a result of this confusion certain sensations, such as those of touch, are called "feelings", and in the case of some sensations accom- panied by strong feelings, as sensations of pain, the dis- crimination of the two elements is neglected. In the second place, it would be just as inadmissable to ascribe to a given sensation a definite feeling fixed in quahty and intensity. The real truth is that in every case the sensation is only one of the many factors that determine the feeling present at a given moment; besides the sensation, the processes that have 76 /. Psychical Elements. gone before and the permanent dispositions — conditions that we can only partially account for in special cases — play an essential part. The concept "sense-feeHng" or "affective tone" is, accordingly, in a double sense the product of anal- ysis and abstraction: first, we must think of the simple feeling as separated from the concomitant pure sensation, and secondly, we must pick out from among all the various changiag affective elements which are^ connected with a given sensation under different conditions, the one that is most constant and is connected with the sensation after the removal, so far as possible, of all the influences that could disturb or complicate the simple effect of the sensation. The first of these conditions is comparatively easy to meet, if we keep in mind the psychological meaning of the concepts sensation and feehng. The second is very difficult, and, especially in the case of the most highly developed sen- sational systems, the auditory and visual, it is never really possible to remove entirely such indirect influences. "We can infer what the pure affective tone of a sensation is, only by means of the same method that has already been used for the abstraction of pure sensations (§ 5, p. 28). Here, too, we may assume that only that affective tone which remains constant when all other conditions change, belongs to the sensation itself. The rule is easily applied to sensation, but only with great difficulty to feelings, because the secondary influences referred to are generally as closely connected with the sensation as is the primary occasion of the affective tone. Thus, for example, the sensation green arouses almost unavoidably the idea of green vegetation , and since there are connected with this idea composite feelings whose character may be entirely independent of the affective tone of the color itself, it is impossible to determine directly whether the feeling observed when a green impression is presented, is a §7. Simple Feelings. 77 pure affective tone, a feeling aroused by the attending idea, or a combination of both. 2 a. This difficulty has led many psychologists to argue against the existence of any pure aifective tone whatever. They assert that every sensation arouses some accompanying ideas and that the affective action of the sensation is due ia every case to these ideas. But the results of experimental variation of the conditions for light-sensations, tell against this view. If the attendant ideas were the only sources of the feeling, it would necessarily be strongest when the sensational contents of the im- pression were most like those of the ideas. This is by no means the case. The affective tone of a color is greatest when its grade of saturation reaches a maximum. The pure spectral colors observed in surrounding darkness have the strongest affective tone. These colors are, however, generally very different from those of the natural objects to which accompanying feelings might refer. There is just as little justification for the attempts to derive tonal feelings from such ideas exclusively. It can not be doubted that familiar musical ideas may be aroused through a single tone ; still, on the other hand, the constancy with which certain tonal qualities are chosen to express particular feelings, as, for example, deep tones to express grave and sad feelings, can be understood only under the condition that the correspond- ing affective quality belongs to the simple tonal sensation. The circle in which the argument moves is still more obvious when the affective tones of sensations of taste, smell, and the general sense are derived from the accompanying ideas. When, for example, the agreeable or disagreeable tone of a taste-sensation is increased by the recollection of the same impression as expe- rienced before, this can be possible only under the condition that the earlier impression was itself agreeable or disagreeable. 3. The varieties of simple sense-feelings are exceedingly numerous. The feelings corresponding to a particular sen- sational system also form a system, since, in general, a change in the quality or intensity of the affective tone runs parallel to every change in the quality or intensity of the sensations. 78 I- Psyehioal Elements. At the same time these changes in the affective systems are essentially different from the corresponding changes in the sensational systems, so that it is impossible to regard the affective tone as a third determinant of sensations, analogous to quality and intensity. If the intensity of a sensation is varied, the affective tone may change not only in intensity, hut also in quality; and if the quality of the sensation is varied, the affective tone usually changes in quality and inten- sity both. For example, increase the sensation sweet in intensity and it changes gradually from agreeable to dis- agreeable. Or, gradually substitute for a sweet sensation one of sour or bitter, keeping the intensity constant, it will be observed that, for equal intensities, sour and, more especially, bitter produce a much stronger feeling than sweet. In gen- eral, then, every change in sensation is usually accompanied by a twofold change in feeling. The way in which changes in the quality and intensity of affective tones are related to each other follows the principle already stated (p. 33) that every series of affective changes in one dimension ranges between opposites, not, as is the case with the corresponding sensational changes, between greatest differences. 4. In accordance with this principle, the greatest quah- tative differences in sensations correspond to the greatest opposites in affective quality, and to maxima of affective in- tensity which are either equal or at least approximately equal, according to the special pecularities of the qualitative opposites. The middle point between these two opposites corresponds to an absence of all intensity, so far as only the single dimension to which the opposites belong is concerned. This absence of intensity can be observed only when the corresponding sen- sational system is absolutely one-dimensional. In all other cases, a point which is a neutral middle for one particular series of sensational differences, belongs at the same time to another § 7. Simple Feelings. 79 sensational dimension or even to a number of such dimensions, in each of which it has a definite affective value. Thus, for example, spectral yellow and blue are opposite colors which have corresponding opposite affective tones. In passing grad- ually along the color-line from one of these to the other, green would be the neutral middle between them. But green itself stands in affective contrast with its opposite color, purple; and, furthermore, it is, like every saturated color, one extremity of a series made up of the transitional stages of a single color-tone to white. Again, the system of simple tonal sensations forms a continuity of only one dimension, but in this case more than in others it is impossible to iso- late the corresponding affective tones through abstraction, as we did the pure sensations, because in actual experience we always have, not only intermediate stages between tones of different pitch, but also transitions between absolutely simple tones and noises made up of a profusion of simple tones. The result of these conditions is that every many-dimensional sensational system has a corresponding complex system of affective tones, in which every point generally belongs at once to several dimensions, so that the feeling corresponding to a given sensation is a resultant of the affective elements due to its position in various dimensions of the sensational system. It follows that discrimination between simple and composite feehngs in the sphere of affective qualities, can not be carried out. The feeling that corresponds to a particular sensation, is as a rule, for the reasons given, a product of the fusion of several simple feelings, though it is still as irreducible as a feeling of originally simple nature (cf. § 12, 3). A further consequence is that the neutral naiddle between opposite affective quaUties, can be actually found in experi- ence only in the special cases where the affective tone of a particular sensation corresponds to the neutral middle of all go I. Psychical Elements. the dimensions to which it belongs. This special condition is obviously fulfilled for the many-dimensional sensational systems, especially those of sight and hearing, in just the cases in which it is of special practical value for the undis- turbed occurrence of affective processes. In the one case, sensations of medium brightness and those of the low grades of chromatic saturation approximating them, in the other, the auditory impressions of our ordinary environment, which are between a tone and noise in character (as, for example, the human voice), form the neutral indifference-zones of affective quality. On both sides of these zones arise the more intense affective tones of the more marked sensational qualities. The existence of such indifference-zones makes it possible for the complex feelings which correspond to the various combi- nations of these sensational qualities, to develop almost in- dependently, without regard to the accompanying sense-f eeKngs. 5. The variations in affective quality and intensity that run parallel to the grades of sensational intensity, are much simpler. They can be most clearly seen in the homogeneous sensational systems of the general sense. Each of these systems is of a uniform quaUty throughout, and can be fairly well represented geometrically by a single point, so that the only possible sensational changes are those of intensity, and these can be attended only by a one-dimensional series of affective changes between opposites. The neutral indifference- zone is, accordingly, always easy to observe in these cases. It corresponds to the medium sensations of pressure, hot, and cold, that are connected with the normal, medium in- tensity of ordinary sense-stimuli. The simple feehngs on both sides of this zone exhibit decidedly opposite characters, and can, in general, be reckoned, on the one side, to pleas- urable feelings, on the other, to unpleasurable (v. inf. 6). The unpleasurable feehngs are the only ones that can be § 7. Simple Feelings. §1 produced with certainty, by increasing the intensity of the sensation. Through habituation to moderate stimuli, such an expansion of the indifference-zone has taken place in these systems of the general sense, that when the stimuli are weak, as a rule only a succession of sensations very different in intensity or quality, can produce noticeable feehngs. In such cases, feelings of pleasure always correspond to sen- sations of medium intensity. The regular relation between sensational intensity and affective tone, can be better observed without this influence of contrast, in the case of certain sensations of smell and taste. At first a pleasurable feeling arises with weak sen- sations and increases with the increasing intensity of the sen- sations to a maximum, then it sinks to zero with a certain medium sensational intensity, and finally, when this intensity increases still more, the feeling becomes unpleasurable and increases until the sensational maximum is reached. 6. The variety of simple affective qualities is exceedingly great, much greater than that of sensations. This is due to two facts. First, every sensation of the many- dimensional systems belongs at once to several series of feelings. Secondly, and this is the chief reason, the different compounds arising from the various combinations of sensations, such as inten- sive, spacial, and temporal ideas, and also certain stages in the course of emotions and volitions, have corresponding feelings, which are, as above remarked (p. 76), irreducible, and must therefore be classed among the simple feelings. It is greatly to be regretted that our names for simple feelings are so much more hazy than those for sensations. The proper nomenclature of feeling is limited entirely to the expression of certain general antitheses, as pleasurable and un- pleasurSible, agreeable and disagreeable, grave and gay, excited and quiet, etc. These designations are usually based on the Whsdi, Psychology. 6 82 / Psychical Elements. emotions into which the feelings enter as elements, and are so general that each includes a large number of single simple feelings of Yery different character. In other cases, complex ideas whose affective character is similar, are used in describing the feelings connected with certain simple im- pressions, as, for example, by Goethe in his description of the affective tone of colors, and by many musical writers in describing the feelings accompanying clangs. This poverty of language in special names for the feehngs, is a psycho- logical consequence of the subjective nature of the feehngs. All the motives of practical life which give rise to the names of objects and their attributes, are here wanting. To con- clude, for this reason, that there is a corresponding poverty of simple affective qualities themselves, is a gross psycho- logical mistake, which is furthermore fatal since it makes an adequate investigation of the composite affective processes impossible from the first. 7. In consequence of the difficulties indicated, a complete list of simple affective qualities is out of the question, even more than is such a Hst in the case of simple sensations. Then, too, there are still other reasons why it would be im- possible. The feelings, by virtue of the attributes described above, do not form closed systems, as do the sensations of tone, of light, or of taste, but are united in a single manifold, interconnected in all its parts (p. 35). Furthermore, the union of certain feelings gives rise to feehngs which are not only unitary, but even simple in character (p. 75). In this manifold of feelings, made up, as it is, of a great variety of most delicately shaded quahties, it is nevertheless possible to distinguish certain different chief directions, including certain affective opposites of predominant character. Such directions may always be designated by the two names that indicate their opposite extremes. Each name is, however, to be looked § 7, Simple Feelings. § 3 upon as a collective name including an endless number of feelings differing from one another. Three such chief directions may be distinguished; we will call them the direction of pleasurable and unpleasurable feelings, that of arousing and subduing (exciting and depress- ing) feelings , and finally that of feelings of strain and re- laxation. Any concrete feeling may belong to all of these directions or only two or even only one of them. The last mentioned possibihty is all that makes it possible to distin- guish the different directions. The combination of different affective directions which ordinarily takes place, and the above mentioned (p. 79) influences which are due to the overlapping of feelings arising from various causes, all go to explain why we are perhaps never in a state entirely free from feeling, although the general nature of the feelings demands an in- difference-zone. 8. Feelings connected with sensations of the general sense and with impressions of smell and taste, may be regarded as good examples of pure pleasurable and unpleasurable forms. A sensation of pain, for example, is regularly accom- panied by an unpleasurable feeling without any admixture of other affective forms. Li connection with pure sensations, arousing and subduing feelings may be observed best in the case of color-impressions and clang-impressions. Thus, red is arousing, blue subduing. Feelings of strain and relaxation are always connected with the temporal course of processes. Thus, in expecting a sense-impression, we note a feeling of strain, and on the arrival of the expected event, a feeling of relaxation. Both the expectation and satisfaction may be accompanied at the same time by a feeling of excitement or, under special conditions, by pleasurable or unpleasurable feelings. Still, these other feelings may be entirely absent, and then those of strain and relaxation are recognized as 84 I- Psychical Elements. specific forms whicli can not be reduced to others, just as the two directions mentioned before. The presence of more than one direction may be discovered in the case of very many feelings which are, nevertheless, simple in quaUty, just as much as the feelings mentioned. Thus, the feeUngs of seriousness and gaiety connected with the sensible impres- sions of low and high tones or dark and bright colors, are to he regarded as characteristic qualities which are outside the indifference -zone in both the pleasurable and unpleasurable direction and the exciting and depressing direction. We are never to forget here that pleasurable and unpleasurable, ex- citing and depressing, are not names of single affective qual- ities, but of directions, within which an indefinitely large number of simple qualities appear, so that the unpleasurable quality of seriousness is not only to be distinguished from that of a painful touch, of a dissonance, etc., but even the different cases of seriousness itself may vary in their quahty. Again, the direction of pleasurable and unpleasurable feelings, is united with that of feelings of strain and relaxation, in the case of the affective tones of rhythms. The regular succession of strain and relaxation in these cases is attended by pleasure, the disturbance of this regularity by the opposite feeling, as when we are disappointed or surprised. Then, too, under certain circumstances the feeling may, in both cases, be of an exciting or a subduing character. 9. These examples lead very naturally to the assumption that the three chief directions of simple feelings depend on the relations in which each single feehng stands to the whole succession of psychical processes. In this succession every feeling has in general a threefold significance. 1) It repre- sents a particular modification of the state of the present moment; this modification belongs to the pleasurable and impleasurable direction. 2) It exercises a certain definite § 7. Simple Feelings. 85 influence on the succeeding state; this influence can be distin- guished in its opposite forms as excitation and inhibition. 3) It is determined in its essential character by the preced- ing state ; this determining influence shows itself in the given feeling in the forms of strain and relaxation. These conditions also render it improbable that other chief directions of feeling exist. 9 a. Of the three aifective directions mentioned, only that of pleasurable and unpleasurable feelings has generally been recog- nized; the others are reckoned as emotions. But the emotions, as we shall see in § 13, come from combinations of feelings; it is obvious, therefore, that the fundamental forms of emotions must have their antecedents in the affective elements. Some psychologists have regarded pleasurable and unpleasurable feel- ings, not as collective terms including a great variety of simple feehngs, but as entirely uniform, concrete states , so that, for example, the unpleasurableness of a toothache, of an intellectual failure, and of a tragical experience are all regarded as identical ia their affective contents. Still others seek to identify the feelings with special sensations, especially with cutaneous sensations and muscle-sensations. Such entirely untenable assertions require no criticism. They indicate , however, the uncertain state of the doctrine of feelings, even at the present time. 1 0. The question has been raised whether or not particular physiological processes correspond to the simple feehngs, as is the case for the sensations. Older psychology was inclined to answer this question in the negative, and to contrast the feehngs as inner, purely psychological, states with sensations as processes aroused from without. In modern times, on the contrary, the affirmative answer has generally been given, but for the most part without the support of adequate em- pirical proof. Obviously, our assumptions in regard to the physiological phenomena accompanying the feelings must be based on 86 /• Psychical Elements. actually demonstrable physiological processes, just as our assumptions in regard to the physiological conditions of sen- sations were deduced from the structure and functions of the sense-organs. In looldng for such processes, it follows from the subjective nature of the feelings, that we should not expect to find them among the processes produced in the organism directly by external agents, as the sensations are, but rather in reactions which arise indirectly from these first processes. The observation of compounds made up of affective elements, that is, of emotions and volitions, whose easily perceptible concomitants are always external move- ments or changes in the state of the organs of movement, also points in the same direction. The analysis of sensations, and of the psychical compounds derived from them, makes direct use of the impression- method; while the investigation of simple feelings, and of the processes resulting from their combinations, can employ this method only indirectly. On the other hand, the expressitm- method, that is, the investigation of the physiological reactions of psychical processes, is especially adapted to the examination of feelings and processes made up of them, because as shown by experience, such reactions are regular symptoms of affective processes. All the phenomena in which the inner state of the organism is outwardly expressed, may be utiUzed as aids for the expression-method. Such are, besides the movements of the external muscles, especially the respiratory and cardiac movements, the contraction and dilation of the blood-vessels in particular organs, the dilation and contraction of the pupil of the eye, etc. The most dehcate of these is the beating of the heart, which can be examined as exactly reproduced in the pulse of some peripheral artery. All other phenomena are generally wanting in the case of a simple feeling. It is only for high intensities, where the feelings always pass into § 7. Simple Feelings. ,87 emotions, that we have other, added symptoms, especially changes in respiration, and mimetic expressive movements. 11. Of the chief directions of feeling mentioned above, especially that of pleasurable and impleasurable feelings can be shown to stand in regular relation to the pulse. When the feeling is pleasurable, the pulse is retarded and intensified, when unpleasurable, the pulse is accelerated and weakened. For the other directions, the accompanying changes can only be inferred with some degree of probability, from the effects of the corresponding emotions (§ 1 3, 5). Thus, exciting feelings seem to betray their presence only through stronger pulse- beats, and subduing through weaker, without a change of rate in either case. For feehngs of strain, we have retarded and weakened pulse, for those of relaxation, accelerated and in- tensified pulse. Single feelings belong for the most part to several of these directions at the same time; as a result, the action of the pulse is in many cases so complex that the most that can be concluded is the predominance of one or the other direction. The conclusion is, however, uncertain so long as it is not confirmed by direct observation of the feehng. 11a. The relations that seem probable from experiments on the symptoms of feelings and emotions as found in pulse- activity, may be presented in. the following scheme. retarded pleasurable feeling Pulse strong accelerated retarded I weak accelerated exciting feeling of feeling of subduing unpleasura- feeling relaxation strain feeling ble feeling. I Exciting and subduing feelings, then, show themselves by simple changes in the pulse, the others by double changes. But 88 I. Psychical Elements. this scheme, which is derived for the most part from the effects of complex emotions, needs confirmation from experiments in which attention is paid to the isolation of these various affective directions. Changes in respiration , muscle-tension , etc., also need further investigation. It is obvious from the equivocal character of each symptom, that when a particular feeling is given in psychical experience, we can infer particular resulting inner- vations from the symptoms which appear, but that we can never infer the presence of particular feelings from the physiological symptoms. It follows that the expression-method can not be as highly valued from a psychological point of view as the impression- method. From the very nature of the case, the impression- method is the only one that can be used in arousing and varying psychical processes at will. The expression-method gives results that explain only the physiological phenomena which accompany feelings, not the psychological nature of the feelings themselves. The variations observed in the pulse must be regarded as the results of a changed innervation of the heart, coming from the cardiac centre in the brain. Physiology shows that the heart is connected with the central organs by two kinds of nerves: eaxitatory nerves, which run through the sympathetic system and originate indirectly in the medulla, and inhibitory nerves, which belong to the tenth cranial nerve (vagus) and also have their source in the medulla. The normal regularity of the pulse depends on a certain equilibrium between excitatory and inhibitory influences. Such influences come not only from the brain, but from the centres in the ganglia of the heart itself Thus, every increase and every decrease of the heart's energy may be inter- preted in two different ways. The first may be due to an increase of excitatory, or to a decrease of inhibitory innervation, and the second may be due to a decrease in excitatory or to an increase in inhibitory innervation, or in both cases the two influences may be united. We have no universally applicable means of investigating these possibil- ities, still, the circumstance that the stimulation of the inhibitory nerves has a quicker effect than the stimulation of the excitatory, gives us good ground in many cases for conjecturing the presence of the one or the other. Now, the changes in the pulse always follow very quickly the sensations that cause them. It is, therefore, probable that in the case of feelings and emotions, we have § 7. Simple Feelings. 89 chiefly changes in inhibitory innervation, originating in the brain and conducted along the vagus. It may veell be assumed that the affective tone of a sensation on its physiological side, corre- sponds to a spreading of the stimulation from the sensory centre to other central regions which are connected with the sources of the inhibitory nerves of the heart. Which central regions are thus affected, we do not know. But the circumstance that the physiological substrata for all the elements of our psychological experience, are in all probability to be found in the cerebral cortex, leads very naturally to the assumption that the same" is true for the centre of these inhibitory innervations. Further- more, the essential differences between the attributes of feelings and those of sensations, make it probable that this centre is not identical with the sensory centres. If a special cortical region is assumed as the medium for these effects, there is no reason for supposing a special one for each sensory centre, but the complete uniformity in the physiological symptoms goes more to show that there is only one such region, which must then at the same time serve as a kind of central organ for the con- nection of the various sensory centres. (For the further significance of such a central region, and its probable anatomical position, compare § 15, 2 a.) 11. PSYCHICAL COMPOUNDS. . § 8. DEPENITION AND CLASSIFICATION OF PSYCHICAL COMPOUNDS. ]. By "psychical compound" we mean any composite component of our immediate experience which is marked off from the other contents of this experience by particular characteristics, in such a way that it is apprehended as a relatively independent unity and is, when practical necessity demands it, designated by a special name. In developing these names, language has followed the general rule that only classes and the most important species into which phe- nomena may be grouped, shall have special designations, while the discrimination of concrete compounds is left to immediate perception. Thus, such expressions as ideas, emotions, voli- tional acts, etc., designate general classes of psychical com- pounds, such expressions as visual ideas, joy, anger, hope, etc., special species included in these classes. So far as these designations, which have arisen from practical experience, are based upon actual distinguishing characteristics, they may be retained by science. But science must give an account of the nature of these characteristics and also of the pecul- iar contents of each of the chief- forms of psychical com- pounds, in order to give every single term an exact meaning. In doing this, we must avoid from the first two presuppo- sitions to which the existence of these names might easily naislead us. The first is the view that a psychical compound § 8. Definition and Classification of Psychical Cojnpounds. 91 is an absolutely independent content of immediate expe- rience. The second is the opinion that certain compounds, as, for example, ideas, have the nature of things. The truth is that compounds are only relatively independent units. Just as they are made up of various elements, so they themselves unite to form a complete interconnection, in which relatively simple compounds may continually combine to form more composite ones. Then, again, compounds, like the psychical elements contained in them, are never things, but processes which change from moment to moment, so that it is only through deliberate abstraction, which is, indeed, in- dispensable for the investigation in many cases, that they can be thought of as constant at any moment (§ 2, p. 13 sq.). 2. All psychical compounds may be resolved into psychi- cal elements, that is, into pure sensations and simple feelings. The two kinds of elements behave, however, in an essentially different manner, in accordance with the peculiar properties of simple feelings as described in § 7. The sensational ele- ments found by such a resolution, always belong to one of the sensational systems already considered. The affective elements, on the other hand, include not only those which correspond to the pure sensations contained in the compounds, but also those due to the interconnection of the elements into a compound. The systems of sensational qualities, accordingly, always remain the same, no matter how great a variety of compounds arises, while the systems of simple affective qual- ities continually increase. Connected with this increase is another attribute which is thoroughly characteristic for the actual nature of psychical processes. The attributes of psychical compounds are never limited to those of the ele- ments that enter into them, but new attributes, peculiar to the compounds themselves, always arise as a result of the com- bination of these elements. Thus, a visual idea has not only 92 n. Psychical Compounds. the attributes of the light-sensations and of the sensations of ocular position and movements contained in it, but also that of the spacial {irrangement of the sensations, which these elements in themselves do not have. Again, a volition is not only made up of the ideas and feelings into which its single acts may be resolved, but there result from the combi- nation of these acts, new affective elements which are specif- ically characteristic of the complex vohtion. Here, again, the combinations of sensational and affective elements are different. In the first case, on account of the constancy of the sensational systems, no new sensations can arise, but only peculiar forms of their arrangement. These forms are the extensive spacial and temporal manifolds. When, on the other hand, affective elements combine, new simple feelings arise, which unite with those originally present to make «w- tensive affective units of composite character. 3. The classification of psychical compounds is naturally based upon the character of the elements that make them up. Those composed entirely or chiefly of sensations are called ideas, those consisting mainly of affective elements, affective processes. The same limitations hold here as in the case of the corresponding elements. Although com- pounds are more the products of immediate discrimination among actual psychical processes than the elements are, still, there is at bottom no pure ideational process and no pure affective process, but in both cases we can only abstract to a certain extent from one or the other - component. As in the case of the two kinds of elements, so here we can neglect the accompanying subjective states when dealing with ideas, but must always presuppose some idea for the affective pro- cesses. Still, these ideas may be of very different kinds for the single species and varieties of affective processes. We distinguish, accordingly, three chief forms of ideas: § 9. Intensicc Ideas. 93 1) intensive ideas, 2) spacial ideas, 3) temporal ideas; and three forms of affective processes: 1) intensive afEective com- binations, 2) emotions, 3) volitions. Temporal ideas constitute a sort of link between the two kinds of processes , for cer- tain feelings play an important part in their formation. § 9. INTENSIVE IDEAS. 1. A combination of sensations in which every element is connected with any second element in exactly the same way as with any other, is called an intensive idea. Thus, for example, a compound clang made up of the tones d f a is such an intensive idea. For the immediate apprehension, each of the partial combinations into which this compound clang can be resolved, as df, da, fd, fa, ad, nf, are all entirely equivalent, in whatever order they are thought of. This is obvious at once if we compare the compound clang with any succession of the same tones, where df, da, fd, fa, etc., are essentially different ideas. We may define intensive ideas, accordingly, as combinations of sensational elements, in ivhicJi the order of flie eletnents may be indefinitely varied. It follows from their nature, that intensive ideas do not have, arising from the way in which their elements are united any characteristics, by means of which they can be resolved into separate parts. Such a resolution is possible only through the differences in the constituent elements themselves. Thus, we discriminate the elements of the compound clang d f a, only because we hear in it the qualitatively different tones d, f, and a. Still, the separate components in such a unitary idea are less clearly distinguishable than in their isolated state. This fact, that the elements are pushed into the background by the impression of the whole, is of great im- 94 11, Psyehieal Compounds. portance for all forms of ideational combination. "We call it the fusion of sensations, and in -particular, for intensive ideas, intensive fusion. If the connection of one element with others is so close that it can be perceived as a part of the whole only through unusual concentration of the attention aided by experimental variation of the conditions, we call the fusion compute. If, on the other hand, the elements are im- mediately recognized in their proper qualities, and merely recede somewhat into the background in comparison with the impression of the whole, we call the fusion incomplete. If certain particular elements are more prominent in their characteristic qualities than others, we call them the pre- dominating eleme^its. The concept of fusion as here defined is a psychological concept. It presupposes that the fused elements of the idea are really subjectively distinguishable. It must not be confounded with the entirely different and purely physiological concept of the fusion of external im- pressions into a single resultant stimulation. For example, when complementary colors unite and give white, the fusion is, of course, not psychological. In reality, every intensive idea always enters into certain spacial and temporal combinations. Thus, for example, a compound clang is always a process having a cei'tain duration, and is at the same time localized by us in some direction or other, though often only very indefinitely. But since these temporal and spacial attributes can be indefinitely varied, while the intensive character of the ideas remain the same, we may abstract from the former in investigating the inten- sive attributes. 2. Among ideas of the general sense we have intensive fusions in the form of combinations of sensations of pressure with those of hot or cold, or combinations of pain-sensations with those of temperature or pressure. All these fusions ^ 9. Intensive Ideas. 95 are incomplete, and very often there is no decidedly pre- dominating element. The combination of certain sensations of smell and taste are more intimate. This is obviously favored on the physiological side by the proximity of the sense-organs, on the physical side by the regular connection between certain stimulations of the two senses. In such cases the more intense sensations are generally the predominating elements, and when these are the sensation of taste, the composite impression is usually regarded as a taste-quahty only. Thus, most of the impressions known in ordinary life as "tastes", are in reality combinations of tastes and smells. The greatest variety of intensive ideas, in all possible grada- tions of complexity, are presented by the sense of hearing. The relatively most simple of these ideas and those which are most closely related to simple tones , are the single clangs. As more complex forms, we have compound clangs. Comple.r, noises may arise from the latter when they are united with sensa- tions of simple noises, and under certain other circumstances. 3. A sijigle clang is an intensive idea which is made up of a series of tonal sensations regularly graded in quality. These elements, the partial tones of the clang, form a complete fusion, in which the sensation of the lowest partial tone be- comes the predominating element. The pitch of the tone is determined by this principal tone. The other elements are higher and are, accordingly, called overtones. The overtones are all grouped together under the name clang-color as a second determinant of the clang, added to the predominating tone. All the partial tones that go to determine the clang- color are placed along the tonal line at certain regular inter- vals from the principal tone. The complete series of possible overtones in a clang consists of the first octave of the prin- cipal tone, the fifth of this octave, the second octave of the principal tone, and the major third and the fifth of this 9g //. Psychical Compotmds. second octave, etc. This series corresponds to the following proportions between the number of objective tonal waves: 1 (principal tone), 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, ... . (overtones). When the pitch of the principal tone remains constant, only the second determinant of the tonal quality, the clang-color, can vary according to the number, position, and relative in- tensity of the overtones. In this way we can explain the great variety of clang-colors in musical instruments, as well as the fact that for every instrument the clang-color changes somewhat with the pitch; for in the case of low tones the overtones are generally relatively strong, in that of high relatively weak, while they disappear entirely when they are too high to be audible. Even the slight differences in clang-color in single instruments of the same kind, are to be explained in the same way. From a psychological point of view the chief condition for the rise of a single clang, is the complete, or approxima- tely complete, fusion of several tonal sensations with only one predominating element. As a rule, it is impossible to distinguish with the unaided ear the overtones in a clang. They can be made perceptible by the use of resonators (re- sonator-tubes tuned to the overtones sought), and after they have been isolated in this experimental way, the stronger ones can be successively heard in the clang, even without the aid of the resonators, if the attention is directed to them. 4. There are three conditions necessary if there is to be only one predominating element in a tonal fusion. First, one tone must be relatively more intense. Secondly, in its quah- tative relations to the other partial tones, the principal tone must be the fundamental of a series whose members are all harmonious. Thirdly, all the partial tones must be uniformly coincident. This , coincidence is objectively guaranteed by deriving the clang from a unitary source, (that is, producing § 9. Intensive Ideas. 97 the clang through the vibrations of one string, 07ie reed-pipe, etc.) The result is that the objective vibrations of the partial tones always stand in the same relation to one another — a result which can not be secured when clangs from several sources are united. The first two of these conditions relate to the elements, the third to the form of their combinations. The first is the least essential to the idea of a single clang. If the second is not fulfilled, the combination becomes a compound clang when the predominating fundamental is wanting, or a noise when the series of tones is not harmonious, or a mixed form between a clang and a noise when both parts of the condition are un- fulfilled. If the third condition, of constancy in the phases of the partial tones, is not met, the clang becomes compound even when the first two conditions are compKed with. A series of simple clangs from a member of tuning-forks which should unite to a single clang so far as intensity and quality are concerned, always produces in reality the idea of a com- pound clang 1). 5. A compound clang is an intensive combination of single clangs. It is in general an incomplete fusion with sevetal predominating elements. There are, as a rule, all possible 1) The case is different when the fundamental itself contains overtoaes of noticeable intensity, which are also repeated as inde- pendent clangs in the compound tone. The single clangs of such a series arrange themselves in the same phases as these overtones, and the compound clang has the character of a single clang, with very strong overtones. Helmholtz concluded from experiments in which he combined in various ways simple clangs from tuning-forks, that differences in phase have no influence on the clang-color. But as the idea of a single clang can not be produced in this way, it is probable that an entirely constant relation of the phases of different tonal vibrations from independent sources can never be brought about with this method. Experiments by R. Koenig tell for the in- fluence on the clang-color, of the form of the clang as determined by the relation of the vibration-phasee. Wdndt, Psychology. 7 98 II- Psyehiml Compdunds. grades of fusion in a compound clang, especially when it is made up of single clangs of composite quality. In such a case, not only does every single clang form a complete fusion in itself, but these single clangs fuse the more completely with one another the more their fundamentals approach the relation of elements of a single clang. So it comes that in a compound clang made up of single clangs rich in overtones, those components whose fundamentals correspond to the overtones of some other single clang in the compound, fuse more completely with this related clang than with others. The other clangs, in turn, fuse the more completely the more their relation approaches that of the first members of a series of overtones. Thus, in the compound clang c e g e' the clangs c and c' form a nearly complete fusion, while the fusions of the clangs c and g, c and e, are incomplete. Still less complete is the fusion between c and e^. A measure for the degree of fusion may be obtained in all these cases by allowing an observer to hear the compound clang for a very brief interval, after which he is to decide whether he perceived only one clang or several. This experiment is repeated many times, and the relative number of judgments in favor of the unity of the clang is a measure for the degree of fusion. 6. Besides the elements contained in the single clangs of a compound, there are always, arising from the combination of vibrations in the auditory organ, additional elements which cause new tonal sensations, characteristic for the different kinds of compound clangs. These may also fuse more or less completely with the original clang. They are sensations of difference-tones; they correspond, as their name indicates, to the difference between the number of vibrations in two pri- mary tones. They may have a twofold origin, either from the interference of the vibrations in the outer ear, especially in the tympanum or chain of ossicles (Helmholtz's combi- § 9. Intensive Ideas. 99 nation-tones), or from the interference of the vibrations in the auditory nerve-fibres (Koenig's beat-tones). The first are, from the very character of their origin, weak tones; espe- cially in comparison with the original tones, they are always relatively very weak. The second class, on the other hand, are generally stronger and may even surpass the original tones in intensity. It is probable that the first appear only in the case of harmonious compound clangs, while the second appear also in dissonant compound clangs. The fusion of difference-tones with the chief tones of the compound is the more complete the less intense the former are, and the more they tend to form a simple harmonious tonal series with the original components of the clang. As a result of these attri- butes, the difference-tones are to compound clangs what the overtones are to single clangs. They are, however, almost entirely independent of the clang-color of the components of the compound, but vary greatly with the relation in which the principal tones of these components stand to one another. This explains the relative uniformity in the character of a given compound clang even when the clang-colors of its com- ponents vary. 7. A compound clang may pass through all possible inter- mediate stages into a third form of intensive auditory ideas, that of noises. "When two tones are no longer included within a series of harmonious tones and when at the same time the difference between the number of their vibrations does not exceed certain limits, for higher tones about sixty vibrations and for lower thirty or even fewer, there arise disturbances in the compound clang, which correspond in number to the difference between the number of vibrations in the primary tones, and are due to the alternating coinci- dence of like and opposite phases of vibration. These dis- turbances are either interruptions of the clang-sensation, IQQ II. Psyehical Compounds. beats, or, especially in the case of deep tones, intermittent sensations of a difference-tone, tonal beats. If the differences in the number of vibrations exceed the numbers mentioned, the tones at first sound continuous, for the interruptions disappear, but they are harsh. Later the harshness dis- appears and we have pure dissonance. Ordinary dissonance is made up of a mixture of beats or harshness and pure dissonance. The first two are due to perceptible or just , disappearing interruptions of the sensation, the latter to the entire absence of the unity of the clang, that is, of the con- sonance that would have arisen if a complete or partial fusion had taken place. This lack of accord in tones, due to the relation of their pure qualities, may be designsited bisonance. If through the simultaneous sounding of a great number of non-accordant tones the various conditions for an ordinary dissonance, beats, tonal beats, harshness, and "bisonance, are all added together, a noise is the result. Qn the psychological side this means that the predominating tonal elements disappear entirely or become mere modifying elements in the total idea. For our apprehension of noises, in the case of those which last a short interval only, the general pitch of the most in- tense elements is determinative, in the .case of those which last longer, the form of the disturbance resulting from the rapidity of the beats, from the accompanying tonal beats, etc., also has an influence. Human articulations are characteristic examples of different forms of noise. The vowels are intermediate between clangs and noises with predominantly clang character; the resonants are noises of long duration, and the proper consonants' noises of short duration. In whispers the vowels become simply "lioises. The circumstance that the differences in vowels are perfectly distinct in whispers, goes to prove that the character of vowel§ depends essentially on their noise-elements. It is § 9. Intensive Ideas. 101 probable that simple sensations of noise (p. 49) enter into all noises together with the numerous tonal elements that go to make them up. The ii-regular air-vibrations arising from the disturbances in the tonal waves, excite both the nervous elements in the vestibule of the labyrinth, which are sensitive to such stimulations, and the auditory nerve- fibres themselves. 7 a. Helmholtz's resonance hypothesis has aided us materially in understanding the physiological substratum of intensive auditory ideas, especially those of clangs (p. 51). It is assumed that certain parts of the auditory organ are so tuned that tonal waves of a given rate always set in sympathetic vibration only the part correspondingly tuned. This explains in a general way the analyzing ability of the auditory sense, as a result of which we can distinguish the elements not only in. a compound clang, but to some extent even in a single clang. The resonance hypothesis, however, accounts physiologically for only one side of tonal fusion, the persistence of the single sensation in the total intensive idea, not for the other side, the more or less intimate combination of the elements. The assumption of an imaginary "organ of fusion" in the brain for this purpose, is one of those fictions that are more harmful than helpful, in which the attempt is made to satisfy a demand for explanation with an empty word. The tonal elements that produce an intensive clang-idea persist as real sensations and still give up their independence more or less in the total idea. Tonal fusion is, then, a psychical process and requires a psychological explanation. But since this fusion is very different under different objective conditions, as, for example, when the impressions are due to the combined vibrations from a single source or to vibrations from several distinct sources; these differences must have some physiological and physical grounds for their explanation. The most natural way to attempt such an explanation is properly to supplement the resonance hypothesis. If we assume that besides the analyzing parts of the auditory organ, the resonant membrane, still others exist which are effected by the total, unresolved clang, we have a sufficient physiological substratum for the different effects of the various conditions. The 102 !!• Psychical Compounds. observations (p. 41) on birds deprived of their labyrinths make it possible to infer that the auditory nerve-fibres in the canals of the labyrinth may be such organs. Then, too, the existence of beat-tones (p. 99), which sometimes surpass the primary tones in intensity, and the observation that the interruptions of a single tone may unite to form a second sensation when sufficiently rapid, both seem to require a similar supplementation of the resonance hypothesis. § 10. SPAOIAL IDEAS. 1. Spacial and temporal ideas are immediately distinguished from intensive ideas by the fact that their parts are united, not in an arbitrarily variable, but in a definitely fixed order, so that when the order is thought of as changed the idea itself changes. Ideas with such a fixed arrangement are called in general extensive ideas. Of the possible forms of extensive ideas, spacial ideas are distinguished by the fact that the fixed arrangement of the parts of a spacial compound holds only for the re- lation of the parts to one another, not for their relation to the ideating subject. This latter relation may be thought of as indefinitely varied. The objective independence of spacial compounds from the ideating subject is called the movability and torsibility of spatial compounds. The number of directions in which such movement and torsion may take place, is limited. They may all be reduced to three dimensions, in each of which it is possible to advance in two opposite directions. The number of directions in which the parts of a single compound may be arranged as well as the number in which various compounds may be arranged with reference to one another, is the same as the maximal number of directions in which movement and torsion are possible. This is what we call the three-dimensional character of space. A §10. Spacial Ideas. 103 single spacial idea may, accordingly, be defined as a three- dimensional compound whose parts are fixed in their location ivith regard to one another, hut capable of indefinite variation in their location with regard to the ideating subject. This definition neglects, of course, the frequent changes in the arrangement of the parts, which occur in reality. When these changes take place, they are to be regarded as transitions from one idea to another. This three-dimensional arrangement of spacial ideas must of necessity include one-dimensional and two-dimensional arrangements as special cases. In such cases, however, the wanting dimensions must always be added in thought as soon as the relation of the idea to the ideating subject is taken into account. 2. This relation to the ideating subject, which is really present in all spacial ideas, renders it from the first psycho- logically impossible that the arrangement of the elements in such an idea should be an original attribute of the elements themselves, analagous to the intensity or quaUty of sensations ; it requires rather that this arrangement should result from the bringing together of these elements, and should arise from some new psychical conditions that come with this coexistence. If this is not admitted, it becomes necessary not only to at- tribute a spacial quality to every single sensation, but also to postulate for every sensation, however limited, a simultaneous idea of the whole of three-dimensional space in its location with regard to the ideating subject. This would lead to the acceptance of an a priori space-perception prior to all concrete sensations, which is not only contradictory to all our ex- periences as to the conditions for the rise and development of psychical compounds in general, but also contradictory to all our experiences as to the influences that affect spacial ideas in particular. 3. All spaoial ideas are arrangements either of tactual 104 II- Psychical Compounds. or of visual sensations. Indirectly, through of connection of other sensations with either tactual or visual ideas, the spa- cial relation may be carried over to other sensations. In the cases of touch and sight, it is obvious that the extended sur- face of the peripheral sense-organs, and their equipment with organs of movement, which render possible a varying location of the impressions in regard to the ideating subject, are both favorable conditions for an extensive, spacial arrangement of the- sensations. The tactual sense is the earlier of the two here in question, for it appears earlier in the development of organisms and shows the structural relations in much coarser, but for that reason in many respects much plainer, form than the more delicately organized visual organ does.. Still, it is to be noted that where vision is present, the spacial ideas from touch are greatly influenced by those from sight. A. SPACIAL TOUCH-IDEAS. 4. The simplest possible touch-idea is a single, approxi- mately punctiform impression on the skin. If such an impres- sion is presented even when the eyes are turned away, there arises a definite idea of the place touched. Introspection shows that this idea, which is called the localization of the stimulus, under the normal condition where vision is present is not im- mediate, as we we should expect it to be if the spacial quality were an original attribute of sensations, but that it depends upon a secondary, generally very obscure, visual idea of the region touched. Localization is, therefore, more exact near bounding Unes of the touch- organs than on the uniform intervening surfaces, since these bounding lines are more prominent in the visual images. The arousal of a visual idea through the tactual impression, even when the eyes are turned away, is possible because every point of the organ of touch §10. Spacial Ideas. 105 gives to the touch-sensation a pecuHar qualitative coloring, which is independent of the quality of the external impres- sion and is probably due to the character of the structure of the skin, which varies from point to point and is never exactly the same in two separate regions. This local coloring is called the local sign of the sensation. It varies in different regions of the skin at very different rates : rapidly on the tip of the tongue, on the ends of the fingers, and on the lips; slowly on the broader surfaces of the limbs and trunk. A measure for the rate of this variation may be ob- tained by applying two impressions near each other to any region of the skin. So long as the distance of the impressions is less than that of distinguishable local signs they are perceived as a single one, but so soon as they pass this Umit they are perceived as spacially separate. The smallest, just noticeable distance be- tween two impressions is called the spaee~fhreshold for touch. It varies from one or two millimetres (tips of tongue and fingers) to sixty-eight millimetres (back, upper arm, and leg). On the pressure-spots (p. 47), when the stimuli are favorably applied, still shorter distances can be perceived. Then, too, the threshold is dependent on the condition of the tactual organ and on practice. As a result of the first, for example, the threshold is smaller for children than for adults, since the differences in structure that condition the local signs, are obviously more crowded together. As a result of practice, the threshold is smaller in the case of the bHnd than of those who have vision, especially at the ends of the fingers, which are most used for touching. 5. The influence of visual ideas of the regions touched, where vision is present, as just described, teaches that the localization of tactual impressions and the spacial arrange- ment of a number of such impressions is not due to an original spacial quality of cutaneous points or to any 106 II- Psychical Compcmnds. primary space-forming function of the tactual organ. On the contrary, it presupposes spacial ideas of sight, which can be made use of, however, only because the various parts of the tactual organ have certain qualitative attributes, local signs, which arouse the visual image of the part touched. There is no reason for attributing an immediate spacial relation to the local signs themselves; it is obviously enough that they act as qualitative signals to arouse the appropriate visual images. This connection with vision depends upon the frequent union of the two. The keenness of localization will, there- fore, be aided by all the influences that increase either the clearness of the visual images or the quaHtative differences in local signs. We may describe the formation of spacial ideas in this case as the arrangement of tactual' stimuli in visual images already present. The whole process is a consequence of the consta.nt connection of these images with the qualitative local signs of the stimuli. The union of the local signs and the visual images of the corresponding region may, then, be regarded as an incomplete, but very constant, fusion. The fusion is incomplete because both visual image and tactual impression retain their independent character; but it is so constant that, when the state of the tactual organ remains the same, it seems invariable. This last fact explains the relative certainty of localization. The predominating elements of this fusion are the tactual sensations. For many persons the visual images are pushed so far into the backgroimd that they can not be perceived with any certainty, even with the greatest attention. The apprehension of space, in such cases, is perhaps an immediate function of tactual and motor sen- sations, as for the blind (v. inf. 6). As a rule, however, more careful observation shows that it is possible to recognize the position and distance of the impressions only by attempting §10. Spacial Ideas. 107 to make the indefinite visual image of the region touched more distinct. 6. The conditions that hold when vision is present, are essentially different from those found in cases of blindness, especially congenital or early acquired blindness. Blind per- sons retain for a long time memory images of familiar visual objects, so that the spacial ideas of touch always remain, to some extent, products of a fusion between tactual sensations and visual images. But these visual images can not be con- tinally renewed, so that the persons in question come more and more to make use of movements. The sensations of movement that arise from the joints and muscles in passing from one tactual impression to another (p. 46), serve as a measure for the movement executed and, at the same time, as a measure for the distance between the two impressions. These sensations of movement, which in acquired bhndness are additions to the gradually fading visual images and in part substitutes for them, are, in congenital blindness, the only means present from the first for the formation of an idea of the relative position and distance of the single impressions. We observe in the latter case contin- ual movements of the touch -organs, especially the fingers, over the object. Added to these movements are a more concentrated attention to tactual sensations and a greater practice in their discrimination. Still, the low grade of devel- opment of this sense, in comparison with sight, always shows itself in the fact that the apprehension of continuous Hnes ^nd surfaces is much less perfect than that of approximately punctiform impressions arranged in various ways. The neces- sity of making a blind-alphabet of arbitrary figures formed by various combinations of raised points, is a striking proof of this. Thus, for example, in the ordinary alphabet (Braille's) one point represents A, two points in a horizontal line B, J 08 H- Psychical Oamponrnds. two points in a vertical line C, etc. With six points at most all the letters can be formed, but the points must be far enough apart to be perceived as separate with the end of the index finger. The way in which this alphabet is read is characteristic for the development of the space-ideas of the blind. As a rule the index fingers of both hands are used for this purpose. The right finger precedes and appre- hends a group of points simultaneously (synthetic touch), the left finger follows somewhat more slowly and apprehends the single points successively (analytic touch). Both the syn- thetic and analytic impressions are united and referred to the same object. This method of procedure shows clearly that the spacial discrimdnation of tactual impressions is no more immediately given in this case than in the case where vision was present, but that here the movements by means of which the finger that is used for analytic touch passes from point to point, play the same part as the accompanying visual ideas did in the normal cases with vision. An idea of the extent and direction of these movements can arise only under the condition that every movement is accompanied by an inner tactual sensation (p. 46, 6). The assumption that these inner tactual sensations are immedi- ately connected with an idea of the space passed through in the movement, would be highly improbable, for it would not only presuppose the existence of a connate perception of surrounding space and of the position of the subject in respect to the same (p. 103), but it would include another particular assumption. This is the assumption that inner and outer touch-sensations, although they are otherwise alike in quahty and physiological substrata, still differ in that inner sen- sations give, along with the sensation, an image of the po- sition of the subject and of the spacial arrangement of the immediate environment. This would really necessitate a return §10. Spaeial Ideas. 109 to the Platonic doctrine of the memory of innate ideas, for the sensations of movements arising from touch are here thought of as the mere external occasional causes for the revival of innate transcendental ideas of space. 7. Apart from its psychological improhabihty, such an hypothesis as that just mentioned can not be reconciled with the influence exercised by practice on the discrimination of local signs and of differences in movements. There is no other way except to attribute the rise of spaeial ideas here, as in normal cases with vision (p. 106), to the combinations of the sensations themselves as presented in experience. These combinations consist in the fact that in passing from one outer tactual impression to another, any two sensations, a and b, with a certain difference in local signs, always have a corresponding inner touch-sensation, a, accompanpng the movement; while two sensations, a and c, with a greater dif- ference in local signs, have a more intense sensation of move- ment, y. For the bhnd there is always such a regular com- bination of inner arid outer touch-sensations. From the strictly empirical point of view it can not be affirmed that either of these sensational systems, in itself, brings the idea of spaeial arrangement; we can only say that this arrange- ment results regularly from the combination of the two. On this basis the spaeial ideas of the bhnd, arising, as they do, from external impressions, may be defined as a product of the fusion of external tactual sensations and their qualita- tively graded local signs, with internal tactuM sensation graded according to intensity. The external sensations with their attributes as determined by the external stimulus, are the predominating elements in this fusion. These push the local signs with their quahtative peculiarities, and the sen- sations of movement with their intensive attributes, so far into the background, that, like the overtones of a clang, they no II. Psyehieal Compounds. can be perceived only when the attention is especially con- centrated upon them. Spacial ideas from touch are, accord- ingly, due to a complete fusion. Their characteristic peculi- arity, in contrast, for example, with intensive tonal fusions, is that the subordinate and supplementary elements are dif- ferent in character, and at the same time related to one another according to definite laws. They are different, for the local signs form a pure qualitative system, while the iimer touch-sensations which accompany the movements of the tac- tual organs, form a series of intensities. They are related, for the motor energy used in passing through an interval between two points, increases with the extent of the interval, so that, in proportion to the qualitative difference between the local signs, there must also be an increase in the intensity of the sensations of movement. 8. The spacial arrangement of tactual impressions is thus the product of a twofold fusion. First, the subordinate ele- ments fuse, in that the various qualities of the local sign system, which is spread out in two dimensions, are related to one another according to the grades of intensity of the sensations of movement. Secondly, the tactual impressions as determined by the external stimuli, fuse with the product of the first union. Of course, the two processes do not take place successively, but in one and the same act, for the local signs and movements must both be aroused by the external stimuli. Still, the external sensations vary with the nature of the objective stimulus, while the local signs and internal tactual sensations are subjective elements, whose mutual rela- tions always remain the same even when the external im- pressions vary. This is the psychological condition for the constancy of attributes whiclv,we ascribe to space itself, in contrast wich the great changeableness of the quaHtative attri- butes of objects in space. § 10. Spaeial Ideas. m 9. After the fusion between local signs and internal tac- tual sensations has once been effected, either one of these elements by itself, though perhaps in a limited degree, is able to bring about a localization of the sensations, and even to arouse complex spaeial ideas. In this way not only normal individuals with vision, but also the blind, even the congen- itally blind, have an idea of the place touched, and can per- ceive as spacially separate two impressions that are far enough apart, even when the touch-organs remain perfectly quiet. Of course, the congenitally blind can have no visual image of the region touched, but they have instead of this an idea of a movement of the part touched and, where several im- pressions are received, the idea of a movement from one to the other. The same fusion takes place injdeas thus formed as in the ordinary ones, where movements are really present, only here the one factor, the inner tactual sensation is merely a memory-image. 10. In the same way, we may have the reverse process. The real contents of experience may be a sum of inner tac- tual sensations which arise from the movement of some part of the body, while no noticeable external tactual sensations whatever are given, and yet these internal sensations which accompany the movement may still be the basis of a spaeial idea. This is regularly the case when we have pure ideas of our own movements. If, for example, we shut our eyes and then raise our arm, we have at every moment an idea of the position of the arm. To be sure, external tactual sensations that arise from the torsion and folding of the skin, play some part here too, but they are relatively unimportant in comparison with the internal sensations from the joints, tendons, and muscles. It can be easily observed that where vision is present, this idea of position comes from an obscure visual image of the 112 II- Psychical Compounds. limb with its surroundings, which is aroused even when the eyes are closed or turned away. This connection is so close that it may arise between the mere memory-image of the inner tactual sensation and the corresponding visual idea, as is observed in the case of paralytics, where sometimes the mere will to execute a certain movement arouses the idea of a movement really executed. Evidently, the ideas of one's own movements depend, when vision is present, on incomplete fusions, just as the external spacial ideas of touch do, only here the internal sensations play the part that the outer sensations play in the former case. This leads to the assump- tion that the inner tactual sensations also have local signs, that is, the sensations in the various joints, tendons, and mus- cles show certain series of local differences. Introspection seems to confirm this view. If we move alternately the knee-joint, hip-joint, and shoulder- joint, or even the correspond- ing joints on the right and left sides, the quality of the sensation seems each time a little different^ even if we neglect the connection with a visual image of the limb, which can never be entirely suppressed. Then, too, it is impossible to see how accompanying visual images could arise at all with- out such differences. That would require not only a connate idea of space in the mind, but also a connate knowledge of the position and movements of the Hmbs in space for every moment. 11. Froni the relations that exist in the normal cases with vision, we can understand the way in which the ideas of their own movements arise in the case of the congenitally bhnd. Here, instead of a fusion with a visual image, there must be a fusion of sensations of movement mth the local signs. Outer tactual sensations also act as aids in this case. In fact, they are much more important here than when vision is present. The ideas of the blind as to their own move- §10. Spaeial Ideas. 113 ments are exceedingly uncertain so long as they are unaided by contact with external objects. When, however, they touch such objects, they have the advantage of greater practice with the external tactual sense and a keener attention for the same. The so-called "distance-sense of the blind" is a proof of this. It consists in the ability to perceive from some distance, without direct contact, a resisting object, as, for example, a neighboring wall. Now, it can be experi- mentally demonstrated that this distance -sense is made up of two factors: a very weak tactual stimulation of the fore- head by the atmospheric resistance, and a change in the sound of the step. The latter acts as a signal to concentrate the attention enough so that the weak tactual stimulations can be perceived. The "distance- sense" disappears, accord- ingly, when the tactual stimulations are prevented by binding a cloth around the forehead or when the steps are rendered inaudible. 12. Besides our ideas of the position and movements of the various parts of our body, we have also an idea of the position and movement of our whole body. The former can never have anything but a relative significance; it is only when considered in connection with the latter that they become absolute. The organ of orientation for this general idea is the head. We always have a definite idea of the position of the head; the other organs are localized in our ideas, generally, indeed, very indefinitely, with reference to it, according to the particular complexes of inner and outer tactual sensations in each case. The specific organ of orientation in the head is the system of semicircular canals, to which are added as secondary aids the inner and outer tactual sensations resulting from the action of the muscles of the head. The function of these canals as an organ of orientation can be most easily understood by assuming that Wdkbt, Paycliology. 8 114 II- Psychical Compounds. inner tactual sensations with especially marked differences in local signs, arise in them through the influence of the chang- ing pressure of the fluid medium, which fills them. It is highly probahle that dizziness, which comes from rapid rotation of the head, is due to the sensations caused by the violent movements of this fluid. This is in accord with the observations that partial derangements of the canals bring about constant illusions in localization, and complete de- rangement of the same is followed by an almost total sus- pension of the ability to localize. 12 a. The antagonistic theories in regard to the psycHcal formation of spacial ideas, are generally called nativism and empirism. The nativistic theory seeks to derive localization in space from connate properties of the sense-organs and sense- centres, while the empiristic theory seeks to derive it from the influences of experience. This discrimination does not give proper expression to the actual opposition that exists, for the assumption of connate spacial ideas may be attacked without affirming that these ideas arise through experience. This is the case when, as above, space-perceptions are regarded as products of psychical fusions due both to the physiological properties of the organs of sense and of movement, and to the general laws for the rise of psychical compounds. Such processes of fusion and the arrange- ments of sense-impressions based upon them, are everywhere the substrata of our experience, but for this very reason it is inadmissible to call them "experience" itself. It is much more proper to poiat out the opposition that really exists, as that of nativistic and genetic theories. It is to be noted that the wide- spread nativistic theories contain empirical elements, while, on the other hand, empirical theories contain nativistic elements, so that the difference is sometimes very small. Supporters of the nativ- istic view assume that the arrangement of impressions in space corresponds directly to the arrangement of sensitive points in the skin and retina. The special way in which the projection out- ward is effected, especially the ideas of the distance and magnir tude of objects, and the reference of a plurality of spacially § 10. Spacial Ideas. 115 separated impressions to a single object, are all regarded as dependent upon "attention", "will", or even "experience". Sup- porters of the empirical theory, on the other hand, generally presuppose space as given in some way or other, and then in- terpret each single idea as a localization in this space due to some empirical motive. In the theory of spacial ideas from sight, tactual space is generally regarded as this origiaally given space; in the theory of tactual ideas, original spacial qualities have sometimes been attributed to motor sensations. Thus, in the actual concrete theories empirism and nativism are very ill defined concepts. They agree in the use of the complex con- cepts of popular psychology, such as "attention", "will", and "experience", without any examination or analysis. In this respect they are different from the genetic theory, which seeks to show the elementary processes from which the ideas rise, by means of a psychological analysis of the ideas. In spite of their weak- nesses, the nativistic and empiristic theories have served to set the psychological problem that exists here, clearly before us, and to bring to light a great number of facts for its solution. B. SPACIAL SIGHT -IDEAS. 13. The general properties of the touch-sense are repeated in the visual sense, but in a more highly organized form. Corresponding to the sensory surface of the outer skin, we have here the retina with its rods and cones arranged in rows and forming an extraordinarily fine mosaic of sensitive points. Corresponding to the movements of the tactual organs, we have the movements of both eyes in fixating objects and following their bounding lines. Still, while tactual impressions are perceived only through immediate contact with the objects, the refractive media in front of the retina throw inverted, reduced images upon it. These images are so small that space is allowed for a large number of simultaneous im- pressions, and the ability of light to traverse space makes it possible for both neighboring and distant objects to yield 116 II. Bsyehical Cdmpoimds. impressions. Vision thus becomes a distance-sense in a much higher degree than hearing. Light can be perceived from incomparably greater distances than sound. Furthermore, only visual ideas are directly localized at different distances from the subject; for auditory ideas this locaKzation is al- ways indirect, through the aid of visual ideas of space. 14. With regard to its spacial attributes, every visual idea may be resolved into two factors: 1) the location of the single elements in relation to one another, and 2) their loca- tion in relation to the ideating subject. Even the idea of one single point of Mght, contains both these factors, for we must always represent a point in some spacial environment, and also in some direction and at some distance from our- selves. These factors can be separated only through dehb- erate abstraction, never in reality, for the relation of any point in space to its environment, regularly determines its relation to the ideating subject. As a result of this depend- ence, the analysis of visual ideas may better start with the location of the elements in relation to one another, and then take up later the location of the compound in regard to the subject. a. Tfie Location of the Elements of a Visual Idea in Relation to One Another. 15. In the apprehension of the reciprocal relations between elements of a visual idea, the attributes of the tactual sense are all repeated, only in a much more highly organized form,, and with a few modifications significant for the visual ideas. Here, too, we immediately connect with the simplest possible, approximately punctiform, impression the idea of its place in space; that is, we give it a certain defi- rdte position in relation to the parts of space about it. This localization is not effected, however, as in touch, by the § 10. Spaeial Ideas. 1 1 7 direct reference of the impression to the corresponding point of the sense-organ itself, but we project it into a field of vision, which lies at some distance outside of the ideating subject. Here too we have a measure, as in the case of touch, for the accuracy of localization, in the distance at which two approximately punctiform impressions can be just distinguished as spacially different. The distance is not given in this case as a directly measurable linear extension on the sensory surface itself, but as the shortest perceptible interval between two points in the field of vision. The field of vision may be thought of as placed at any distance whatever from the subject, so that it is best to use as a measure for the fineness of localization, not a linear exten- sion, but an angle, the angle formed by the intersection of the lines passing through the nodal point of the eye, from the points in the field of vision to the corresponding retinal points. This angle of vision remains constant so long as the size of the retinal image is unchanged, while the distance between the points in the field of vision increases in pro- portion to their distance from the subject. If an equivalent linear distance is sought in place of the angle of vision, it can be found in the diameter of the retinal image. This may be reckoned directly from the angle and the distance of the retina from the nodal point of the eye. 16. The measurements of the keenness of localization with the eye, made according to this principle, show that there is a great difference for different parts of the field of vision, just as was found for different regions of the tactual organs (p. 105). StUl, the distances that measure the smallest per- ceptible intervals here are all very much smaller. Then, again, there are many regions of finer discrimination scattered over the tactual organ, but only one region of finest discrim- ination in the field of vision. This is the middle, which 118 //. Psychical Compounds. corresponds to the centre of the retina. From this region towards the periphery the fineness of localization diminishes very rapidly. The whole field of vision or the whole retinal surface, is, accordingly, analogous to a single tactual region, as, for example, that of the index finger, except that it very much surpasses the latter in fineness of localization, especially at the centre, where two impressions at a distance corre- sponding to 60" — 90" in the angle of vision, are just distin- guishable, while two degrees and a half toward the periphery, the smallest perceptible extension is 3' 30", and at eight degrees it increases to 1°. In normal vision we turn the eye towards objects of which we wish to gain more accurate spacial ideas, in such a way that they lie in the middle of the field of vision, their images falhng, accordingly, on the centre of the retina. "We speak of such objects as seen directly, of all others, which he in the eccentric parts of the field of vision, as seen indireetly. The centre of the region of direct vision is called the point of regard, or the ficcation-point. The line that unites the centre of the retina with that of the field of vision is known as the line of regard. If we reckon the distance on the retina that corresponds to the smallest angle of vision at which two points in the centre of the field of vision may be perceived as separate, it will be found to be .004 to .006 mm. This distance is equal to the diameter of a retinal cone, and since the cones are so close together in the centre of the retina that they are in direct contact, it may be concluded with probability that two impressions must fall upon at least two different retinal elements if they are to be perceived as sep- arate in space. This view is supported by the fact that in the peripheral regions of the retina the rods and cones, which are the two forms of elements sensitive to Hght, are § 10. Spaeial Ideas. 1 ] 9 really separated by greater intervals. It may, then, be assumed that the keenness of vision, or the ability to distin- guish two distinct points in the field of vision, is directly de- pendent on the proximity of the retinal elements to one another, for two impressions can be distinguished as spacially different only when they act upon different elements. 16 a. Because of this interrelation between the keenness of vision and the arrangement of retinal elements, it has often been concluded that every such element has from the first the property of localizing any stimulus that acts upon it, in that position in space which corresponds to its own projection in the field of vision. In this way the attempt has been made to reduce the property of the visual sense by virtue of which it represents its objects in an external field of vision at some distance from the subject, • to a connate energy of the retinal elements or of their central connections in the visual centre in the brain. There are certain pathological disturbances of vision that seem at first sight to confirm this assumption. When some region of the retina is pushed out of place as a result of inflammation under- neath, certain distortions in the images, the so-caUed metamor- phopsia, arise. The extent and direction of these distortions can be fully explained when it is assumed that the displaced retinal elements continue to localize their impressions as they did when in their normal positions. But it is obvious that these distor- tions of the images when, as in most cases, they appear as con- tinually changing phenomena during the gradual formation and disappearance of the excretion, furnish us with no more evidence for a connate energy of localization in the retina than does the readily observed fact that distorted images of objects are seen when one looks through prismatic glasses. If, on the other hand, . a stationary condition is gradually reached, the metamorphopsia disappear, and that, too, not only in cases where it may be as- sumed that the retinal elements return to their original position, but even in those cases where such a return is entirely iniprob- able on account of the extent of the affection. In cases like the latter, the development of a new connection between the single retinal elements and their corresponding points in the .field 120 11- Psychical Compounds. of vision, must be . assumed >). This conclusion is supported' by- observations made with normal eyes on the gradual adaptation to distorted images which are produced by external optica,l appli- ances. If a pair of prismatic glasses are worn before the eyes, marked and disturbing distortions of the images are the regular results'. The straight bounding lines appear bent and the forms of the objects are thus distorted. These disturbances gradually disappear entirely if the glasses are worn some time. When the glasses are removed the distortions may appear in the opposite direction. All these phenomena can be understood if we pre- suppose that the spaoial localizations of vision are not original, but acquired. 17. Besides the fetinal sensations there are other psychical elements that always take part in the reciprocal spacial arrangement of light-impressions. The physiological proj)er- ties of the eye point a priori to the sensations that accom- pany ocular movements, as such elements. These movements obviously play the same part in the estimation of distances in the field of vision as the tactual movements do in the estimation of tactual impressions. The grosser conditions of touch are, however, here reproduced in a much more delicate and hightly developed form. The eye can be turned in all directions about its centre of rotation, which is fixed in its relation to the head, by means of a most admirably arranged system of six muscles. It is thus well suited to following continuously the bounding lines of objects or to passing each 1) A process analogous to this elimination of the metamopTiopsia is sometimes observed in "binoeula/r vision when the disturbances arising from sqidnting are gradually oirercome. When the ' squiiiting begins,' the two lines of regard no longer meet in the field of vision, so that double images of Objects arise. These may gradually dis- appear, however, if the condition of the eyes remains perfectly stationary; a new set of relations is developed for the retinal ele- ments of the squinting eye. §10. Spacialldeas. 121 time in the shortest line from a given fixation-point to another. The movements in the directions wliich correspond to the position of the objects most frequently and closely observed, namely, downward and inward movements, are favored above the others by the arrangement of the muscles. Furthermore, the movements of the two eyes are so adapted to one another through the synergy of their innervation, that normally the two lines of regard are always turned upon the same fixation- point. In this way a cooperation of the two eyes is made possible which not only permit a more perfect apprehension of the position of objects in relation to one another, but, more especially, furnishes the most essential means for the deter- mination of the spacial relation of objects to the subject (24 seq). 18. The phenomena of vision teach that the idea of the relative distance of two points from each other is depend- ent on the motor energy of the eye employed in passing through this distance, just as the discrimination of two dis- tinct points in the field of vision depends on the arrangement of the retinal elements. The motor energy becomes a com- ponent of the idea through its connection with a sensation wliich can be perceived, especially in extensive movements and by comparing ocular movements in various directions. Thus, for example, the upward movement of the eyes is clearly accompanied by more intense sensations than the downward movements; and the same is true of outward movements of one eye as compared with its inward move- ments. The influence of sensations of movement on the locali- zation are most apparent in the cases of disturbance arising from partial paralysis of single ocular muscles. These disturb- ances correspond exactly to the changes in the amount of energy required to move the eye. The general principle 122 II' PsyeMeal Compotmds. of such disorders is that the distance between two points seems greater when they lie in the direction of the more difficult movement. The more difficult movement has a correspondingly more intense motor sensation, which under normal conditions accompanies a more extensive movement. As a result, the distance passed through appears greater. Furthermore, the same illusion may appear for distances that lie in the same direction, but have not been actually passed through, for the standard found during a movement deter- mines the motor impulse in the eye even when it is not moved. 19. Similar differences in the estimation of distances can be demonstrated for the normal eye. Although the ocular muscles are so arranged that their movements in various directions require about the same amount of exertion, still, this is not exactly so. The reasons are apparently closely connected with the adaptation of the eye to its functions. The neighboring objects of our immediate environment, on which the hnes of regard must be converged, are the ones most often looked at. For this reason, the muscles of the eye have so adapted themselves that the movements for the convergence of the lines of regard are the easiest, particu- larly those directed downwards as compared with other pos- sible movements of convergence. This general facilitation of convergence has been acquired by the addition of special auxiliary and compensatory muscles (superior and inferior obHque) to the muscles that move the eye upwards and downwards (superior and inferior recti). As a result of the greater complexity of muscular activity thus necessary for the upward and downward movements of the eyes, the exer- tion is greater in these directions than towards the two sides, where only the internal and external recti act. The relative ease of downward movements of convergence shows itself partly in the differences in the intensity of sensations accom- §10. SpacialMeas. 123 panying the movements, as already remarked (p. 121), and partly in the fact that downward convergence is involuntarily too great and upward too small. There are certain constant optical ilkmons depending on the direction of the object in the field of vision, which cor- respond to these differences in the motor mechanism. They are of two kinds: illusions of direction, and those of mag- nitude. Both eyes are subject to an illusion as to the direction of vertical lines in the field of vision. Such a line whose upper end is incUned 1° — 3° outward, appears vertical, and one really vertical, seems inclined inward. Since the illusion is in opposite directions for the two eyes, it disappears in binoc- ular vision. It can obviously be explained by the fact just noted, that the downward movements of the eyes are con- nected with an involuntary increase, and the upward move- ments with a decrease, in the convergence. This deflection of the movement from the vertical is not noticed, but we refer it to the object as a deflection in the opposite direction. An equally regular illusion in magnitude appears when we compare distances extending in different directions in the field of vision. This, too, is very probably to be referred to the asymmetry in the arrangement of the muscles which arises from the adaptation of the eye to the ordinary posi- tion of objects in space. A vertical straight line is judged on the average Ye too long as compared with an equal hori- zontal hne. ^ square, accordingly, appears as a rectangle whose base is shorter than its sides, and a square drawn by the eye is always too low. This illusion is explained when we remember that, as a result of the highly developed tendency to convergence, the muscular activity for upward and downward movements is much more complex than for inward ] 24 !!• Psychical Compounds. and outward movements. The consequence is the same as in the case of partially paralyzed eyes, distances in the direcfiion of the more difficult movement appear greater. 19 a. Besides this difference between vertical and horizontal distances, which is most noticeable because it is so large, there are less marked differences between upward and downward, as well as between outward and inward distances. The upper half of a vertical line is overestimated on the average by '/i 6 of i^ length, and the outer half of a horizontal line by Y40. The first may be due to a slight asymmetry in the arrangement of the upper and lower muscles, or it may be due to the involuntary convergence of the lines of regard in downward movement, or, finally, to a combination of both influences. The effect of con- vergence is due to the fact that it corresponds to an approach of the object, so that we are generally inclined to see the lower half of the line nearer. In accordance with certain conditions of association to be described later (§ 16, 9), when the angle of vision remains constant, whatever is judged as nearer is judged to be smaller, so that the lower half of a line seems shorter than the upper. This explanation by the perspective can not be applied to the greater illusion in the overestimation of vertical as com- pared with horizontal ilines, for if it were applicable, the illusion would at most be about equal to that found in the comparison of the two halves of a vertical line, while in reality it is approx- imately three times as great. The fact that this greater illusion appears only when straight distances are compared, not in the case of objects bounded by curved lines, is also a proof against the explanation by perspective. A circle, for example, does not appear as an ellipse with a longer vertical axis, but as a real circle. The slight overestimation of the outer half of a hori- zontal line is also due most probably to the asymmetrical activ- ity of the muscles, which arises from the relative ease of con- vergence-movements. 20. Added to these two illusions, which arise from the special structure of ocular muscles in their adaptation to the purposes of vision, there are certain other variable optical § 10. Spaeial Ideas. ] 25 illusions tliat are due to certain attributes of all voluntary movements and have their analoga in the movements of the tactual organs. These illusions may also be divided into those of direction, and those of magnitude. The former follow the rule that acute angles are overestimated, obtuse under- estimated, and that the dii'ection of the intersecting lines varies correspondingly. For the illusions of magnitude we have the rule, forced or interrupted movements require more exertion than free and continuous ones. Any straight line that neces- sitates fixation is, accordingly, overestimated in comparison with an open distance marked off by two points, and a straight line interrupted by several dividing lines is over- estimated in comparison with an uninterrupted line. The tactual analogon of the illusion in angles is the ten- dency to overestimate small articular movements and to underestimate large ones. This comes under the general principle that a relatively greater expenditure of energy is required for a short movement than for a more extensive one, because it is more difficult to begin a movement than to continue it after it is already started. The tactual phe- nomenon analogous to the overestimation of interrupted lines, is that a distance estimated by a movement of one of the limbs always seems shorter when it is passed through in a single continuous movement than it does when the movement is several times interrupted. Here, too, the sensation corre- sponds to the expenditure of energy, which is, of course, greater for an interrupted than for a continuous movement. The overestimation of interrupted lines by the eye, takes place, as we can easily understand, only so long as no motives arise from the way in which the division is made, to hinder the movement of the eye over the interrupted line. Such a hindrance is present, for example, when the line is inter- rupted only once. This one point of division makes fixation ;^26 ^^- Psychical Compotmds. necessary. If we compare such a line with a continuous one, we tend to estimate the first without any movement, with the point of division as a fixation-centre, while the sec- ond is apprehended by a movement of the eye. As a result the continuous line seems longer than the interrupted line. 21. All these phenomena point to the immediate depend- ence of the apprehension of spacial directions and magnitudes on ocular movements. As further evidence pointing in the same direction, we have the negative fact that the arrangement of the retinal elements, especially their proximity to one another, normally has no influence on the ideas of direction and magnitude. This is most strikingly evident in the fact that the distance between two points appears the same whether observed in direct or indirect vision. Two points that are clearly distinguished in direct vision, may become one in the eccentric parts of the field of vision, but so soon as they are distinguished at all, they will appear just as far apart in one region as in the other. This independence of the prox- imity of the retinal elements, in our perception of magnitude, holds even for a part of the retina that is not sensitive to light at all — for the blind spot, where the optic nerve comes into the eye. Objects whose images fall on the bHnd spot are not seen. The size of this spot is about 6°, and it is located 15° inward from the point of fixation. Images of considerable size, as, for example, that of a human face at a distance of six feet, may disappear entirely on it. Still, when points appear at the right and left or below and above this region, we locaUze them just as far from each other as we should in any other, uninterrupted part of the field of vision. The same fact is observed when some part of the retina becomes blind through pathological conditions. The resulting break in the field of vision shows itself only in the fact that images falling on it are not seen, never §10. Spaoial Ideas. 127 through, any changes in the locaHzation of objects lying on opposite sides of the blind region.') 22. All these phenomena teach that the keenness of vision and the apprehension of directions and distances in the field of tision, are two different functions, which depend upon different conditions : the first depends on the prommity of the retinal ele- ments to one another, the second on ocular movements. It follows directly that spacial ideas from sight can not be regarded as original and given immediately in the action of impressions of light with their spacial arrangement, any more than can the spacial ideas of touch. The spacial order is, here too, developed from the combination of certain sensational com- ponents which, taken separately, have no spacial attributes whatever. Other conditions also indicate that the sensational elements are related here in the same way as in the case of touch, and that the development of visual space under normal conditions runs entirely parallel to the development of space in congenital blindness, the only condition under which touch attains a similar independence. Retinal impressions corre- spond to impressions of contact, and ocular movements to touch-movements. Tactual impressions can gain spacial qualities only through the local coloring of the sensations connected with them — the local signs — and in like man- ner, we must presuppose the same for retinal impressions. 22 a. To be sure, a qualitative gradation of local signs on 1) In this connection, we have the fact that the blind spot does not appear as a break in the field of vision, without sensational con- tents, but as a continuation of the general brightness and color of the whole field; for example, as white when we are looking at a white surface, as black when we look at a black one. This filling out of the blind spot is possible only through reproduced sensations, and is to be considered as one of the phenomena of association to be discussed later (§ 16). 128 H. Psychical Gompounds. the retina can not be demonstrated with the same evidentness as for the skin. Still, by the use of colors it can be established in general that for greater distances from the retinal centre the sensa- tional quality gradually changes. The colors are not so saturated in indirect vision, and the color-tone also changes; for example, yellow appears orange. There is, indeed, in these properties of the retina no strict proof for the existence of pure local differ- ences ia the sensations, at least not in the fine gradations that must be assumed in the retinal centre, for example. Still, they show that local differences in sensations do exist, and this seems to justify the assumption of such even beyond the limits of dem- onstration. This is all the more justifiable because here, where the gradations are much finer, the tendency to translate sen- sational dififerences directly into local differences, which has already been noticed in the case of touch, will be much more apt to destroy their specifically qualitative character. As a confirmation of this view we have the fact that the clearly demonstrable sen- sational differences at greater distances from the retinal centre, can be observed only under the favorable conditions of limited impressions, and disappears entirely when surfaces of uniform color are looked at. This disappearance of qualitative differences which are in themselves considerable, must be attributed in part at least to their relation to local differences. When, however, such relatively great differences disappear as a result of this relation, so that special methods are required for their demon-' stration, it can not be expected that very small differences will be demonstrable at all. 23. "We assume, accordingly, qualitative local signs, which, judging from the data derived from the keenness of" vision, are graded in the finest stages at the retinal centre and more slowly in the eccentric parts. The formation of visual space may then be described as a combination of this system of local signs arranged in two dimensions, with a system of intensive sensations of movement. For any two local signs a and b there will be a corresponding sensation of movement a arising from the movement through the distance a b and § 10. Spacial Ideas. 129 serving as a measure of the same. A longer distance a c will have a more intense sensation of movement, y. Just as the point of finest discrimination on the finger is the centre of reference, so in the same way the retinal centre is such a point of reference for the eye. In fact, this is from the laws of ocular movements more obvious for the eye than it is for the tactual organ. Any luminous point in the field of vision is a stimulus for the centre of ocular innervation, and tends to turn the line of regard reflexly upon itself. This reflex relation of eccentric stimuli to the retinal centre is probably an essential condition for the development of the synergy of ocular movements mentioned above, and is, at the same time, an explanation of the great difficulty of observ- ing objects in iadirect vision. This difficulty is evidently due to the greater reflex impulse toward a point in indirect vision when the attention is concentrated upon it, than toward less favored points. As a result of the preeminent impor- tance which the retinal centre has for ocular movements, the point of fixation necessarily becomes the centre of reference in the field of vision, and all distances in this field are brought under a unitary standard by being determined with reference to the fixation-point. The excitation of local signs is due to the action of external impressions, and both to- gether cause the movement towards the retinal centre. The whole process of visual space-arrangement is thus due to the fusion of three different sensational elements: first, the sen- sational quahties depending upon the character of the exter- nal stimulus, second the qualitative local signs depending on the places where the stimuh act, and third, the inten- sive motor sensations determined by the relation of the stimulated points to the centre of the retina. The latter elements may either accompany actual movements — this is the original case — or, when the eye remains at rest, are W0NDT, Psycliology. 9 130 JI- Psychical Compounds. mere motor impulses of a particular intensity. Because of the regular connection between qualitative local signs and intensive sensations of movement, they may both together be regarded as a single system of complex heal signs. The spacial localization of a simple visual impression, is a pro- duct of a complete fusion of the sensation caused by the external stimulus with the two interconnected elements be- longing to this system of complex local signs. The arrange- ment of a number of simple impressions in space consists in the combination of a great number of such fusions, which are graded in quality and intensity according to the elements of the system of local signs. The predominating elements in these fusions are the sensations due to the external stimu- lation. In comparison with these, the elements of the system of local signs are so obscure, even in their original qual- ity and intensity, that for the immediate apprehension of objects they are entirely lost except as spacial quahties. Connected with this complex process of fusion, which determines the order of the elements in the field of vision, is still another. This latter process, which takes place in the formation of every spacial idea, arises from the relation of the object seen to the subject. We pass now to the consideration of this second process. b. The Location of Visual Ideas in Relation to the Ideating Subject. 24. The simplest case of a relation between an impres- sion and the subject, that can appear in a visual idea, is evidently that in which the impression is reduced to a single point. If a single point of hght is presented in the field of vision, both lines of regard are turned upon it as a i-esult of the reflex impulse exerted by the stimulus (p. 129), in such §10. Spacial Ideas. 131 a way that in both eyes the images fall upon the retinal centres. At the same time the organs of accommodation are adapted to the distance of the point. The point thus repre- sented on the centres of both retinas is seen as single and as situated in a certain particular direction and at a certain particular distance from the ideating subject. The subject is represented, as a rule, by a point that may be defined as the middle point of the straight line connecting the centres of rotation of the two eyes. "We will call this the point of wientation for the field of vision, and the straight line drawn from it to the intersection of the two lines of regard, that is to the extemaL fixation-point, the line of orientation. When a point in space is fixated, there is always a fairly exact idea of the direction of the hne of orientation. This idea is produced by the inner tactual sen- sations connected with the position of the two eyes. Such sensations are very noticeable because of their intensity, when the eyes are rotated much out of the central position. They are just as perceptible for a single eye, so that locali- zation in direction is as perfect in monocular as in binocular vision. In the former case, however, the line of orientation generally coincides with the line of regard i). 25. The idea of the distance of the objects from the subject, or of the absolute length of the Hne of orientation, is much more indefinite than that of its direction. "We are always inclined to ideate this distance shorter than it really is, as may be shown by comparing it with a standard 1) The habit of seeing -with two eyes results in exceptions to this rule. Often when one eye is closed, the line of orientation re- mains the same as in binocular vision and does not coincide with the line of regard. In such cases the closed eye usually makes the cor- responding movements of convergence upon a common fixation-point with the open eye. 9* 132 II- Psychical Compounds. placed somewhere in the field of vision perpendicular to the line of orientation. In this way we find that the distance on the standard judged to be equal to the line of orientation, is always much shorter than the real length of this line. The difference between the two increases the further away the point of fixation moves, that is, the longer the hne of orientation becomes. The only sensational components that can produce this idea of distance, are those inner tactual sensations con- nected with the position of the two eyes, that arise partic- ularly from the convergence of the Hues of regard and give somewhat of a measure for the absolute extent of this con- vergence. In fact, it is possible to observe sensations when the convergence is changed; mainly from the inner angle of the eye when the degree of convergence is increased, from the outer, when it is decreased. The sum of all the sen- sations corresponding to a given position of convergence distinguishes it completely from aU other positions. 26. It follows that an idea of a definite, absolute length of the Hne of orientation can be developed only through the influences of experience, where in addition to the sen- sational elements a great many associations also have a part. This explains why these ideas always remain indefinite and why they are sometimes aided, sometimes interfered with by other components of visual ideas, especially by the size of the retinal images of famihar objects. On the other hand, we have a relatively fine measure in the sensations of convergence for differences in the distances of objects seen, that is, for the relative changes which the length of the line of orien- tation undergoes when the fixation-point approaches or recedes. For positions in which the lines of regard are nearly parallel, changes in convergence may be perceived . that correspond to an angle of vision of 60" or 70". "When the convergence increases, this least perceptible change in convergence also §10. Spacial Ideas. 133 increases considerably, but, in spite of that, the corresponding differences in the length of the hne of orientation become smaller and smaller. Thus the purely intensive sensations which accompany movements of convergence, are translated directly into ideas of changes in the distance between the fixation-point and the point of orientation of the subject. This translation of a certain particular sensational com- plex into an idea of distance, is not due to any connate energy, but to a particular psychical development, as is shown by a great number of experiences which point to such a development. Among these is the fact that the apprehen- sion both of absolute distances and of differences in distance, is greatly improved by practice. Children are generally inclined to localize very distant objects in the immediate neighborhood: they grasp at the moon, at the slater on the tower, etc. In the same way, it has been observed that the congenitally bUnd are, immediately after an operation, entirely unable to distinguish near and far. 27. It is of importance for the development of this dis- crimination between far and near, that under the natural conditions of vision not mere isolated points are presented, but extended three-dimensional objects, or at least a number of points at different depths, to which we assign relatively different distances along their respective lines of orientation. Let us consider first the simplest case, where two points a and b are presented, lying at different depths and connected by a straight line. A change in the fixation from a to 6 is always accompanied by a change in convergence, and brings about, first, the passage through a continuous series of retinal local signs corresponding to the line ab, and, secondly, a sensation of movement, a, corresponding to the difference in convergence between these two points. This gives us here, too, the elements of a spacial fusion. The J 34 II- Psychical Compounds. product of this fusion is, however, peculiar in kind ; it differs in both its components, in the successive series of local signs and in the -concomitant sensations of movement, from the fusions that arise when a line in the field of vision is passed over (p. 128). In the latter case the changes in local signs and sensations of movement are alike for both eyes, while in changing the point of fixation from far to near or the reverse they are opposite in the two eyes. For when the convergence gives the right eye a rotation towards the left, it will produce a rotation towards the right in the left eye, and vice versa. The same must also hold for the movement of the retinal images: when the image of the point as it leaves the point of fixation, moves towards the right in the right eye, it moves towards the left in the left eye, and vice versa. The first takes place when the eyes turn from a nearer to a more distant point, the latter, when they move in the opposite direction. Such fusions arising from movements of convergence have, so far as their qualitative and intensive components are concerned, a composition analagous to that on which the arrangement of the elements in the field of vision with regard to one another depends; but the special way in which these elements are united is entirely different in the two cases. 28. Thus, the fusions between local signs and sensations of convergence form a system of complex heal signs which is analogous to that deduced above (p. 130), but still pecuhar in its composition. This system, differing in composition from the system of local signs in the field of vision, is supple- mentary to the latter in that it adds to the reciprocal rela- tion between the objective elements a relation between the ideating subject and these elements. The relation to the subject divides into two ideational elements, characterized by peculiar sensational elements : the idea of direction and § 10. Spacial Ideas. 135 that of distance. Both refer primarily to the point of orien- tation in the head of the ideating subject, and are then secondarily applied to the relations of external ohjects in regard to one another. Thus, we come to assign to two points which lie at different distances along the hne of orientation a direction and distance in relation to each other. All such ideas of spacial distance referring to various positions along the hne of orientation, when taken together, are called ideas of depth, or when they are also ideas of particular single objects ideas of three dimensions. 29. An idea of depth arising in the way described varies according to objective and subjective conditions. The deter- mination of the absolute distance of an isolated point in the field of vision, is always very uncertain. Even the deter- mination of the relative distance between two points a and b lying at different depths is generally certain only under the condition assiuned above, that they are connected by a line along which the points of fixation for the two eyes can move in changing the convergence from a to b. We may call such lines which connect different points in space with one another lines of fixation. The principle may then be for- mulated: points in space are apprehended in their true rela- tions only when they are connected by hues of fixation, along which the point of fixation may move. This principle is ex- plicable on the ground that the condition of a regularly connected change in the local signs of the retina and in the accompanying sensations of convergence, that is, the condition for the rise of ideas of depth as we found before (p. 133), is obviously fulfilled only when impressions are pre- sented which can arouse the appropriate local signs. 30. When the condition mentioned is not fulfilled, there arises either an imperfect and indefinite idea of the different relative distances of the two points from the subject, or else 136 ^I- Psyohical Compounds. the two points seem to the equally distant -^ a phenomenon which can appear only when one of the points is rigidly fixated. Under the latter condition still another change al- ways arises in the idea; only the fixated point is seen as single, the other is double. The same thing happens in looking at extended objects when they are not connected with the binocular fixation-point by means of lines of fixa- tion. Double images that arise in this way are uncrossed — i. e., the right belongs to the right eye, the left to the left eye — • when the fixated point is nearer than the observed object, and crossed when the point is beyond the object. Binocular localization in depth and binocular double images are, accordingly, phenomena directly interrelated; where the former is indefinite and imperfect, we have double images, and. where, on the other hand, the latter are absent, the localization in depth is definite and exact. The two phenomena stand in such a relation to the line of fixation that, when it is present, localization is aided and double images removed. Still, this rule is not without exception, for when a point is rigidly fixated with both eyes, double images arise easily in spite of any lines of fixation that may be present. This is explained by the general necessary con- ditions for ideas of depth as mentioned above (p. 133). Just as the absence of Hnes of fixation results in the lack of the required succession of the local signs, so in a similar man- ner the sensations of convergence connected with movement, are absent in rigid fixation. c. Relations between the Location of the Elements in Regard to one another and their Location in Regard to the Subject. 31. When the field of vision is thought of as merely a location of visual impressions in relation to one another, we represent it to ourselves as a surface, and call the single ob- § 10. Spaeial Ideas. 137 jects lying in this surface ideas of two dimensions, in con- trast to the ideas of depth. But even an idea of two dimensions must always be related to the seeing subject in two ways. First, every point in the field of vision is seen in a particular direction on the subjective line of orien- tation mentioned above (p. 131). Secondly, the whole field of vision is locahzed at some distance or other from the subject, though this distance may be very indefinite. The location in a particular direction results in an eu'ect ideational object corresponding to an inverted retinal image. This relation between the objective localization in direction and the retinal image is as necessary a result of ocular movements as the inversion of the image itself is a result of the op- tical properties of the eye. Our line of orientation in space is the external line of regard or, for binocular vision, the middle line resulting from the combined effects of movements of fixation. A direction upward on this fine of orientation in external space corresponds to a direction downward in the space where the retinal image lies, behind the centre of ocular rotation, and vice versa. It follows that the retinal image must be inverted if we are to see the object erect. 32. The location at some distance or other, which is also never absent, brings about the result that all the points of the field of vision seem to be arranged on the surface of a ccmcave hemisphere whose centre is the point of orientation, or, in monocular vision, the point of the eye's rotation. Now, small areas of a large curved surface appear plane, so that the two-dimensional idea,s of single objects are as a rule plane; thus, for example, figures drawn upon a plane, as those of plane geometry. But as soon as some parts of the general field of vision separate from it in such a way that they are localized before or behind, that is in different planes, the idea of two dimensions gives place to one of tln-ee. 138 ^- Psychical Compounds. 32 a. The fusions formecl between qualitative local signs and sensations of convergence when we change from the fixation of a more distant point to a nearer, or the reverse, may be called complex local signs of depth. Such local signs form for every series of points lying before or behind the fixation-point, or for an extended body which is nothing but a series of such points, a regularly arranged system in which a stereometric form located at a particular distance is always unequivocally represented by a particular fusion. When one of two points lying at different distances is fixated, the other is characterized by the different position of its images in the two eyes, and by the correspondingly different direction of the complex local signs in the two cases. The same is true for connected series of points or extended bodies. When we look at a solid object, it throws images in the two eyes that are difi'erent from each other on account of the different relative position of the object with regard to the two eyes. We may designate the difference between the positions of a certain point in the image in the two eyes as the binocular parallax. This parallax is zero for the point fixated and for those points which are equally distant on the line of orientation; for all other points it has some real positive or negative value ac- cording as they are more or less distant than the fixation-point. If we fixate solid objects with both eyes, only the point fixated, together with those points which are equidistant and in. its neigh- borhood in the field of vision, will give rise to images corresponding in position in the two eyes. All points of the object located at different distances, give images varying in position and size. These differences in the images are just what produce the idea of the solidity of the object when the proper Unes of fixation are present. For in the way above described, the angle of binoc- ular parallax for the image of any point lying before or behind the point of fixation and connected with the same by a line of fixation, furnishes, according to its direction and magnitude, a measure for the relative distance of. this point in depth through the complex local signs connected with the angle of parallax. This angle of parallax for a given objective depth, decreases proportionally to the distance of the solid object, so that the im- pression of solidity diminishes, the further off the objects are, and when the distance is so great that all angles of parallax § 10. Spacial Ideas. I39 disappear, the body will appear flat, unless the associations to be discussed later (§ 16, 9) produce an idea of depth. 33. The influence of binocular vision on the idea of depth may be investigated experimentally by means of a stereos- cope. This instrument consists of two prisms with their angles of refraction turned toward each other in such a way that it renders possible a binocular combination of two plain drawings which correspond to the retinal images from a three- dimensional object. The influence of the various conditions that underlie the formation of ideas of depths, may, in this way, be studied much better than by looking at actual three- dimensional objects, for here we may vary the conditions at will. To give a concrete illustration, it is observed that complex stereoscopic pictures generally requirg several movements of convergence back and forth before a clear plastic idea arises. Furthermore, the effect of the parallax appears in looking at stereoscopic pictures whose parts are movable in respect to each other. Such movements are accompanied by changes ia the relief which answer exactly to the corresponding changes in binocular parallax. This parallax is dependent on the distance of the two eyes from each other, so that ideas of depth can be produced even in the case of objects too distant in reality to give a plastic effect, by combining in the stereoscope pictures taken from positions much fur- ther apart than the two eyes are. This is done, for example, in making stereoscopic photographs of landscapes. The result is that these photographs when combined do not look like real landscapes, but like plastic models regarded from a short distance. 34. In monocular vision all the conditions are absent which are connected with movements of convergence, and with binocular differences in the retinal images, and which may be 140 ^^- Psychical Compounds. artificially reproduced with the stereoscope. Still, not all the influences are wanting eren here to produce a localization in the third dimension, although this localization is more imperfect. The direct influence of movements of accommodation have in comparison with other conditions a relatively small, per- haps entirely insignificant influence. Still, like movements of convergence, .they too are accompanied by sensations which can he clearly perceived in the case of greater changes of accommodation from distant to neighboring points. For smaller changes in depth these sensations are very uncertain. As a result the movement of a point in the direction of the hue of regard, when it is looked at with only one eye, is generally not clearly observed until a change in the size of the retinal image appears. 35. For the development of monocular ideas of depth the influences which the components of the so-called per- spective exercise, are of the greatest importance. These are the relative magnitude of the angle of vision, the trend of limiting liaes, the direction of shadows, the change in colors due to atmospheric absorption, etc. All these influences, which act in exactly the same way in monocular and biaoc- ular vision, depend on associations of ideas, and will, there- fore, be treated in a later chapter (§ 16). 35 a. "We have in general the same opposing theories for the explanation of visual ideas as for tactual ideas (p. 114). The empirical theory has sometimes committed the fallacy of limiting itself to optics and turning the real problem of space perception over to touch. In such cases it has tried to explain only how a localization of visual ideas can take place with the aid of ex- perience, on the basis of already existing spacial ideas from touch. Such an interpretation is, however, not only self-contradictory, but it also conflicts with experience, which shows that in normal per- sons with vision, visual space-perception determines tactual, not the reverse (p. 104). The fact of general development, that touch §10. Spacial Ideas. 141 is the more primitive sense, can not be applied to tlie develop- ment of the individual. The chief evidences in support of nativ- istic theories are, first, the metamorphopsia after dislocation of retinal elements (p. 1 1 9) and, secondly, the position of the line of orientation (p. 1 H 1 ), which indicates united functioning of the two eyes from the first. It has been noted already (p. 120) that the metamorphopsia and other related phenomena prove the exact opposite as soon as the changes to which they are due become stationary. Furthermore, the fact that in long continued use of only one eye the line of orientation comes to coincide with the line of regard (p. 131), proves that the position of this line is not given from the first, but that it has arisen under the influ- ence of the conditions of vision. Still another fact against the nativistic and in favor of the genetic theory is the development in the child of the synergy of ocular movements under the influ- ence of external stimuli and the organization of space-perceptions which apparently accompanies it. Here as in many other respects the development of most animals is diiferent. In the latter cases the reflex connections of retinal impressions with movements of the eyes and head function perfectly immediately after birth, (v. inf. § 19, 2). The genetic theory has gained the ascendency over older nativistic and empirical views primarily through the more thorough investigation of the phenomena of binocular vision. Nativism has difficulty with the question why we generally see objects single although they produce images in each of the two eyes. The effort is made to avoid the difficulty by assuming that two identical retinal points are connected with the same optic fibre which divides in the chiasma, and that in this way they repre- sent in the sensorium only a single point. This doctrine of the "identity of the two retinas" was, however, untenable as soon as the actual conditions of binocular vision in three dimensions be- gan to be investigated. Especially the invention of the stereo- scope thus brought with it a new era for the genetic theory of vision. J 42 //. Psychical Compounds. § 11. TEMPOEAL IDEAS. 1. All our ideas are at once spacial and temporal. Just as the conditions for the spacial arrangement of impressions belong originally only to the tactual and visual senses, and just as spacial relations are only secondarily carried over from these to all other sensations, so there are oiily two kinds of sensations, namely, the inner tactual sensations from movements and the auditory sensations, vfhich are the primary sources of temporal ideas. Still, there is a characteristic difference between spacial and temporal ideas in the fact that in the first the two senses mentioned are the only ones which can develop an independent spacial order, while in the sec- ond the two most important kinds of sensation are merely those in which the conditions are most favorable for the rise of temporal ideas. These conditions are not entirely wanting, however, for any sensations. This indicates that the psychological bases of temporal ideas are more general, and that they are not determined by the special structures of particular sense-organs. It follows from this fact that even when we abstract from the ideas that enter into any series of psychical processes, and take account only of the subjective phenomena accompanying the ideas, such as feel- ings and emotions, we still ascribe to the affective processes thus isolated through abstraction exactly the same temporal attributes as to the ideas. In philosophy the conclusion has generally been drawn from this fact that time is a "universal form of perception", that is, there is absolutely no psychical content that does not have a position in time, though such content may exist without spacial attributes. This conclusion that time-perception is more universal, arising, as it does, from the greater universality of the conditions of such perception, is erroneous and is not confirmed by psychological observation. § 11. Temporal Ideas. 143 In the same way that we carry over spacial attributes from the two senses that give us space-perception to other kinds of sensations, we also give them secondarily to feehngs and affective processes through the sensations and ideas insepa- rably connected with them. It may with equal right be doubted whether affective processes in themselves, without their related ideas, would have temporal attributes, for among the conditions of a temporal order are certain attributes of the sensational elements of ideas. The real facts in the case are that our ideas and, therefore, since ideas enter into every psychical experience, all psychical contents are at once spacial and temporal. The spacial order arises from certain particular sensational elements : in normal cases where vision is present from visual, in blindness, from tactual impressions ; while time-ideas can arise from all possible sensations. 2. Temporal compounds like spacial and in contrast to iatensive ideas, are characterized by the definite, unchange- able order of their component elements. If this order is changed, the given compound becomes another, even though the quality of its components remains the same. In spacial compounds, however, this unchangeableness of the order refers only to the relation of the elements to one another, not to the relation of the elements to the ideating subject. In temporal compounds, on the other hand, when the relation of one element is changed with regard to other elements, it is at the same time changed with regard to the ideating sub- ject. There is no change of position in time analogous to that possible in the case of space-compounds. 2 a. This property of the absolute, strictly speaking unchange- able, relation of every temporal compound and every time-ele- ment, however short, to the ideating subject, is what we call the flow of time. Every moment in time filled by any con- tent whatever has, on account of this flow, such a relation to 144 n. Psychical Compoimds. the ideating subject that no other moment can be substituted for it. With space the case is just reversed: the very possibil- ity of substituting any spacial element in its relation to the subject for any other element whatever, is what gives rise to the idea of Constance^ or absolute duration, as we express it, by applying a time-idea to a space-idea. The idea of absolute dura- tion, that is of time in which no change takes place, is strictly speaking impossible in time-perception itself. The relation to the subject must change continually. We speak of an impres- sion as lasting, when its single periods in time are exactly alike so far as their sensational contents are concerned, so that they differ only in their relation to the subject. The concept of dura- tion when applied to time is, therefore, a merely relative con- cept. One time-idea may be more lasting than another, but no time-idea can have absolute duration, for without the double relation of different sensations to one another and to the ideat- ing subject, no such ideas at all could arise. Even an unusually long unchanging sensation can not be retained. We interrupt it continually with other sensational contents. We may, however, separate the two temporal relations always united in actual experience, that of the elements to one another and to the ideating subject, since each is connected with certain particular attributes of time-ideas. In fact, this separation of the two relations found its expression in particular words for certain forms of occurrence in time even prior to an exact psycho- logical analysis of time-ideas. If the relation of the elements to one another is alone attended to, without regard to their relar tion to the subject, temporal modes come to be discriminated, such, for example, as brief, long, regularly repeating, irregularly changing, etc. If, on the contrary, the relation of the subject is attended to and the objective forms of occurrence abstracted from, we have as the chief forms of this relation the temporal stages past, present, and future. A. TEMPORAL TOUCH-IDEAS. 3. The orginal development of temporal ideas belongs to touch. Tactual sensations, accordingly, furnish the general substratum for the rise of both the spacial and temporal §11. Temporal Ideas. 145 arrangements of ideational elements (p. 104, 3). The spacial functions of touch, however, come from the outer tactual sensations, while the inner sensations which accompany move- ments are the primary contents of the earliest temporal ideas. The mechanical properties of the limbs are important physiological bases for the rise of these ideas. The arms and legs can be moved in the shoulder-joints and hip-joints by their muscles, and are at the same time subject to the action of gravitation drawing them downward. As a result there are two kinds of movements possible for them. First, we have those which are continually regulated by voluntary ac- tivity of the muscles and may, therefore, be indefinitely va^ ried and accommodated at every moment to the existing needs — we will caU. these the arhythmical movements. Secondly, we have those in which the voluntary energy of the muscles is operative only so far as it is required to set the limbs oscillating in their joints and to maintain this movement — rhythmical movements. We may neglect for our present consideration the arhythmical movements exhibited in the various uses of the limbs. Their temporal attributes are in aU probability derived from the rhythmical movements, and only a very indefinite comparison of the duration of irregular movements is possible. 4. With rhythmical movements the case is different. Their significance for the psychological development of time-ideas is due to the same principle which gives them their importance as physiological organs, namely, the principle of the isochron- ism of osciUations of like amplitude. In walking, the regu- lar oscillations of our legs in the hip-joints not only make the muscular energy expended less, but reduce to a minimum the continual voluntary control of the movements. Further- more, in natural walking the arms are supplementary aids. WosDT, Psychology. 10 146 II- Psychical Compounds. Their oscillation is not interrupted at every step like that of the legs by the placing of the foot on the ground, so that they furnish because of their continuity a means for the more uniform regulation of the movements. Every single period of oscillation in such a movement is made up of a continuous succession of sensations that are repeated in the following period in exactly the same order. The two limits of the period are marked by a complex of outer tactual sensations: the beginning by the impression accompanying the removal of the foot from the ground, the end by that accompanying its return to the ground. Be- tween these there is a continuous series of weak inner tactual sensations from the joints and muscles. The beginning and end of this series of inner sensations coincide with the outer sensations and are more intense than those between them. They arise from the impulse of movement coming to the muscles and joints and from the sudden inhibition of the same, and serve also to mark off the periods. Connected with this regular succession of sensations is a regular and exactly parallel series of feelings. If we con- sider a single period in a series of rhythmical movements, there is always at its beginning and end a feeling of fulfilled expectation. Between the two limits of the period, beginning with the first movement, is a gradually growing feeling of strained expectation, which suddenly sinks at the last moment from its maximum to zero, to make place for the rapidly rising and sinking feeling of fulfillment. From this point on the same series is again repeated. Thus, the whole process of a rhythmical touch-movement consists, on its affective side, of two qualitatively antagonistic feehngs. In their general character these feelings belong to the direction of straining and relaxing feelings (p. 83). One is a momentary feeling, that is, one that rises very rapidly to its maximum and then § 11. Temporal Ideas. 147 sinks with equal rapidity; the other is a feeling of long duration which gradually reaches a maximum and then suddenly dis- appears. As a result, the most intense affective processes are crowded together at the extremities of the periods, and are made all the more intense through the contrast between the feeling of satisfaction and the preceding feeling of ex- pectation. Just in the same way that this sharply marked hmit between the single periods has its sensational substratum in the strong outer and inner tactual impressions that arise at this instant, as above mentioned, so we have a complete correspondence between the gradual rise of the feehng of expectation and the continuous series of weaker inner tactual sensations accompanying the oscillatory movements of the hmbs. 5. The simplest temporal ideas of touch are made up of the rhythmically arranged sensations that follow one another with perfect uniformity in the manner described, when like oscillatory movements are repeatedly carried out. But even in ordinary walking a slight tendency toward a somewhat greater complication arises ; the beginning of the first of tico successive periods is emphasized, both in the sensation and in the accompanying feeling, more than the beginning of the second. In this case the rhythm of movement begins to be metrical. In fact, such a regular succession of accented and unaccent- ed ideas corresponds to the simplest measure, ^/s-time. It arises easily in ordinary walking because of the physiological superiority of the right side, and appears very regularly when several persons are walking together — in marching. In the latter case even more than two periods may be united into one rhythmical unit. The same is true of the complicated rhythmical movements of the dance. But in such composite tactual rhythms the auditory temporal ideas have a decided influence. 10* 148 -^' Psychical Compounds. B. TEMPORAL AUDITORY IDEAS. 6. The attribute of tlie auditory sense which most of all adapts it to the more accurate apprehension of the temporal relations in external processes, is the exceedingly short per- sistence of its sensations after the external stimulation; so that any temporal succession of sounds is reproduced with almost perfect fidehty in the corresponding succession of sensations. In close connection with this we have certain psychological properties of temporal auditory ideas. In the first place, they differ from temporal ideas of touch in that often only the extremities of the single intervals that go to make up the total idea, are marked by sensations. In such a case the relations of such iatervals to one another are estimated essentially by the apparently empty or heteroge- neously filled intervals that lie between the limiting sen- sations. This is especially noticeable in the case of rhythmical auditory ideas. There are in general two possible forms of such ideas: continuotis or only rarely interrupted successions of relatively lasting sensations, and discontinuous successions of strokes, in which only the extremities of the rhythmical periods are marked by external sounds. For a discontinuous succession of entirely uniform sounds the temporal attributes of the ideas are in general more apparent than for lasting impressions, since in the former case the influences of the tonal qualities are entirely wanting. We may confine our consideration to discontinuous series, because the principles that apply here hold for continuous successions also. In fact, the rhythmical division in the latter case, as may he easily observed, is made by means of certain single accents which are either given in the external impression or abitra- rily applied to it. § 11. Temporal Ideas. 149 7. A series of regular strokes made in this way as the sim- plest form of temporal auditory ideas, is distinguished from the simplest form of temporal touch-ideas, described above (p. 147), mainly by the absence of all objective sensational content in the intervals. The external impressions here do nothing but divide the separate intervals from one another. Still, the intervals of such a series are not entirely empty, but are filled by subjective affective and sensational contents which correspond fully to those observed in tactual ideas. Most emphatic of all are the affective contents of the inter- vals. These feelings in their successive periods of gradually rising and suddenly satisfied expectation, are the same as in the course of a rhythmical tactual movement. Even the sensational substratum for these feehng is not entirely ab- sent ; it is merely more variable. Sometimes it is nothing but the sensations of tension of the tympanum in their various intensities. Then again it is the accompanying sensations of tension from other. organs, or finally other sensations of move- ment in cases where an involuntary rhythmical movement is connected with the auditory series. But on account of the changeable character and generally small intensity of these motor sensations, the affective processes in auditory ideas are very much more clearly perceptible. It follows from the conditions described that the influence of the subjective elements on the character of time-ideas is the easiest to demonstrate. First of all, this shows itself in the effect which different rates of the sensations have on the formation of temporal ideas. It is found that there is a certain medium rate of about 0.2 sec. which is most favor- able for the union of a number of successive auditory im- pressions. Now, it is easy to observe that this is the rate at which the above mentioned subjective sensations and feel- ings are most emphatic in their alternation. If the rate is 150 II' Psyehieal Compov/nds. made much slower, the strain of expectation is too great and passes into an unpleasurable feeling which becomes more and more unendurable. If, on the contrary, the rate is acceler- ated, the rapid alternation of feehngs becomes fatiguing. Thus, in both directions Hmits are approached where the synthesis of the impressions into a rhythmical time-idea is no longer possible. The upper limit is about one second, the lower about 0.1 sec. 8. Then again, this influence of the course of our sen- sations and feelings upon our apprehension of temporal inter- vals, shows itself just as clearly in the changes that our idea of such an interval undergoes when the conditions of its apprehension are varied without changing its objective length. Thus, it has been observed that in general a period divided into intervals is estimated as longer than one not so divided. "We have here a phenomenon analogous to that observed in the illusion with interrupted lines (p. 125). The overestimation is generally much greater for temporal intervals. This is ob- viously due to the fact that the oft repeated alternation in sensations and feelings in an interval of time have a much greater influence than the interruption of the movement through points of division in the case of the similar space- iUusion. Furthermore, if in a long series of regular beats single impressions are emphasized by their greater intensity or by some quaMtative peculiarity, the uniform result is the overestimation of the intervals preceding and following the emphasized impression, in comparison with the other inter- vals of the same series. If, however, a certain rhythm is produced successively with weak and then with strong beats, the rate appears slower in the first case than in the second. These phenomena are also explicable from the influ- ence of the sensational and affective changes. An impres- sion distinguished from the rest, demands a change in the §11. Temporal Ideas. 151 course of the sensations, and especially of the feelings, preceding its apprehension, for there must be a more intense strain of expectation and a correspondingly stronger feeling of rehef or satisfaction. The feeling of expectation lengthens the interval preceding the impression, the feeling of relief that following. The case is different when the whole series is made up at one time of weak impressions, and at another of strong ones. In order to perceive a weak impression we must concentrate our attention upon it more. The sensations of tension and the accompanying feelings are, accordingly, more intense, as may be easily observed, for weaker beats than for stronger ones. Here too, then, the different intensities of the subjective elements that give rise to them are reflected in the differences between temporal ideas. The effect is, therefore, not only lost, but even reversed, when we compare not weak with strong but strong with still stronger beats. 9. The tendency found in the case of rhythmical touch- ideas for at least two Hke periods to unite and form a re- gular metrical unit shows itself in auditory ideas also, only in a much more marked degree. In tactual movements, where the sensations that limit the single periods are under the influence of the will, this tendency to form a rhythmical series shows itself in the actual alternation of weaker and stronger impressions. With auditory sensations, on the other hand, where the single impressions can be dependent only on external conditions, and are, therefore, objectively exactly alike, this tendency may lead to the following characteristic illusion. In a series of beats which are exactly alike in in- tensity and are separated by equal periods of time, certain single beats, occurring at regular intervals, are always heard as stronger than the others. The time that most frequently arises when there is nothing to determine it, is the 2/s-t™^, that is, the regular alternation of arses and theses. A slight 152 II- Psychical Compounds. modification of this, the 3/8-t™ie, where two unaccented fol- low one accented heat, is also very common. This tendency to mark time can be overcome only by an effort of the will, and then only for very fast or very slow rates, where, from the very nature of the series, the limits of rhythmical per- ception are nearly reached. For medium rates, which are especially favorable to the rise of rhythmical ideas, a sup- pression of this tendency for any length of time is hardly possible. If the effort is made to unite as many impressions as possible in a unitary time-idea, the phenomena become more complicated. "We have accents of different degrees which alternate in regular succession with unaccented members of the series and thus, through the resulting divisions of the whole into groups, the number of impressions that may be comprehended in a single idea is considerably increased. The presence of two different grades of accent gives 74-tinie and -Yg-thne, the presence of three grades gives Y4-time and 74-time, and as forms with three feet we have ^/s-time and ^"^l^-iime. More than three grades of accentuation or, when the unaccented note is counted, more than four grades of intensity, are not to be found in either musical or poetical rhythms, nor can we produce more by voluntarily formation of rhythmical ideas. Obviously, these three grades of accentua- tion mark the limits of the possible complexity of temporal ideas, in a way analogous to that in which the maximal num- ber of included beats (§ 15, 6) marks the limits of their length. The phenomenon of subjective accentuation and its in- fluence on the sensation of rhythms, shows clearly that temporal ideas, like spacial ideas, are not derived from objective impressions alone, but that there are connected with these, subjective elements, whose character determines the appre- hension of the objective impressions. The primary cause §11. Temporal Ideas. I53 of the accentuation of a particular beat is always to be found in the increased intensity of the preceding and concomitant feelings and sensations of movement. This increase in the in- tensity of the subjective elements is then carried over to the objective impression, and makes the latter also seem more intense. The strengthening of the subjective elements may be voluntary, through the increase of the muscular strain which produces sensations of movement, and in this way, finally results in a corresponding increase in the feelings of expectation; or this strengthening may take place with- out volition, when the effort to perceive a nxmiber of im- pressions together brings about an immediate articulation of the temporal idea through the corresponding subjective sen- sational and affective variations. C. GENERAL CONDITIONS FOR TEMPORAL IDEAS. 10. If we seek to account for the rise of temporal ideas on the basis of the phenomena just discussed, and of the regular combination of subjective sensational and affective ele- ments with objective impressions, as it is there apparent ; we must start with the fact that a sensation thought of by itself, can no more have temporal than it could have spacial attri- butes. Position in time can be possible only when single psychical elements enter into certain characteristic relations with other such elements. This condition of the union of a number of psychical elements holds for temporal ideas just as much as for those of space, but the kind of union is characteristic, and essentially different from that in space- ideas. The members of a temporal series a b c d e f, can all be immediately presented as a single whole, when the series has reached /, just as well as if they were a series of points in space. In the latter case, however, they would, on ac- 154 ^- Psychical Compounds. count of original ocular reflexes, be arranged in relation to the point of fixation, and this fixation-point could, at different times, be any one of the impressions a to f. In time-ideas, on the other hand, it is alwa-ys the impression of the present moment in relation to which all the rest are arranged in time. When a new impression becomes, in a similar manner, the present impression, even though its sensational contents are exactly the same as that of the earlier, still, it will be ap- prehended as subjectively different, for though the affective state accompanying a sensation may, indeed, be related to the feelings of another moment, the two can never be iden- tical. Suppose, for example, that following the series a h c d e /", there is a second series of impressions, a' V d d' e' f, in which a = a, b' = b, c' = c, etc., so far as their sen- sational elements are concerned. Let us represent the ac- companying feelings 'bj a jS y 6 s cp and «' /?' y' 8' s'