■ * CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY _ Cornell University Library B 395S55 U5 Unify of Plato's fhoughf ,. 3 1924 032 292 108 °''" Overs DATE DUE I ^W^ M)^ittJK«> .jjsm^^w- I^^^ •"mSiWSKKKim MMid^iH . 4 ^it f CAVLORD PRINTtDINU.S.A. The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924032292108 THE UNITY OF PLATO'S THOUGHT THE UNITY OF PLATO'S THOUGHT PAUL SHOREY THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS The University of Chicago Press, Chicago }7 The University of Toronto Press, Toronto 5, Canada Copyright 1903 by The University of Chicago New Impression 1960 Printed in the United States of America THE UNITY OF PLATO'S THOUGHT Paul Shobet PART I INTKODUCTION DuEiNG the past twenty years Platonic Forschung has come to mean the investi- gation of the relative dates of the dialogues by the statistical study of vocabulary and idiom. The general trend of modern philology and the reaction against mystical and metaphysical Platonism favored this tendency, and the work would perhaps not have been done at all if the workmen had not cherished illusions as to its value. To combat these illusions or to test in detail the logic of Sprachstatistik is not the purpose of this paper. A merely negative attitude toward any harmless form of human endeavor is unfruitful. But granted, since life is short, all that is claimed by the enumerators of KaOdirep and tC fi^v, the essential quality of Plato's thought remains for some Platonists^ a more interesting topic of discussion than the conjectural chronology of his writings. It has become the fashion to assert that the one depends upon the other, that we cannot interpret Plato's philosophy until we have determined the historic sequence of the dialogues, and with it the true order of development of his thought. But we have always known that the Laws and Timceus are late, that the Republic belongs to Plato's full maturity, and that the minor Socratic dialogues are as a whole presumably early. To affirm that more is necessary is to beg the question; it is to assume the very point in controversy that the philosophy set forth in the dialogues did develop in the sense required by the argument. The question is partly verbal. Every man's thought is developed out of nothing somewhere between infancy and maturity. Any author whose literary activity, like that of Plato, extends over half a century undergoes many minor changes of opinion, and reflects many varying moods of himself and his contemporaries. But it is not true of all, or of a majority, of the world's great thinkers that their first tentative gropings toward a philosophy and a criticism of life are depicted as in a votive tablet in their earliest published writings, or that the works of their riper years present a succession of shifting and dissolving views. Yet something like this is the assumption made by the increasing number of investigators who, in emulation of the triumphs of the statistical method, are endeav- oring to confirm, refute, or correct its results by a study of alleged inconsistencies, contradictions, or developments in Platonic doctrine. Abstractly the followers of this method would probably repudiate the principle here attributed to them. In their practice the desire for striking arguments and definite results leads them to assume that Plato was capable of producing a masterpiece like the Protagoras before his most characteristic philosophical and ethical conceptions had taken shape in his mind, and 1 Notably for Bonitz ; see the judicious observations in Platonische Studien, 3d ed., pp. 270 B. and passim. The Unity of Plato's Thought that throughout the period of his maturest writings his leading ideas were in a state of Heraclitean flux, or were being casually developed from year to year. This method misleads scholars of great acumen and erudition to make false points, to labor fantastic analogies, and to cite irrelevant parallels. It betrays them into misplaced emphasis, disregard of the context, and positive mistranslation. In short, it necessitates the systematic violation of all the canons of the simple, sane, and natural interpretation of literature." Plato avoided rather than sought a rigid technical terminology, and prodigally varied the language and imagery in which he clothed hia most familiar thoughts. Every variation of phrase and imagery is pressed to yield significant contradictions or developments. The most far-reaching conclusions are drawn from the different shades of meaning attached to such words as "opinion," "dialectic," "philosophy," "sensation," "reminiscence," "participation," "presence," "com- munion," freely and untechnically employed by Plato to suit the theme and context.' The absence in any work of explicit insistence on a thought is supposed to prove the absence of the thought from Plato's mind at the time, and as a consequence, we are expected to believe in the most incredible combinations of maturity and naivete within the same writing. Or we are taught that Plato's development, like some Sophoclean sentences, proceeds in the order aba, and consisted in the acceptance, the rejection, and the re-acceptance of the same idea. The most reckless assertions are made that certain elementary thoughts appear for the first time in certain dialogues. The emphatic introduction of a term or idea is, according to the exigencies of the theory, now taken as proof that it is a novelty, and now explained away as a mere dramatic artifice. The rapid outline of an argument is alternately regarded, according to the requirements of the "chronology," as an anticipatory germ or a later r6sum6 of the fuller treatment found elsewhere. Fantastic conceits or bare possibilities as to Plato's literary motives and polemical intentions are treated as absolute psychological and historical certainties and made the basis of serious arguments.* May there not be some Trpwrov i/reuSos involved in a conception that thus betrays its advocates? It is of course a priori conceivable that Plato's thought did unfold itself in this tentative and fumbling fashion. Examples of such mutations and nuta- tions can be found among the Pichtes and Schellings of modern philosophy. They are still more frequent, as Professor Gildersleeve has wittily shown, in the history of modern philology, and, as I may add, in the in;terpretation of Plato. But it is at least equally probable that Plato's philosophy and his conception of life had taken shape at the age of thirty or thirty -five, and that his extant works, though not of course a pre- determined systematic exposition, are the naturally varied reflection of a homogene- ous body of opinion, and of a consistent attitude in the interpretation and criticism of 2 Examples throughout the paper. alized statements and criticisms o£ tendencies in the ,., jT„„. ,,/-.■■ J ^ tu ^ thought of the time, and especially the hypothesis that he s Infra, and Lutoslatvski, Origin and Growth of .. • j ^ ■ ^ \^ . ,• . , _ . . satirized contemporaries under the names or earlier ' Sophists. Such hypotheses will be wholly disregarded in * To this category belong nearly all conjectures as to the following study, as a mere hindrance to the apprehen- the particular philosophers referred to in Plato's gener- sion of Plato's own meanings. Paul Shoeey contemporary life. And if this were the fact, it would be a far more important fact for the interpretation of his writings than the determination of the relative dates of the Phcedo and Symposium or even than the demonstration that the Sophist, Statesman and Philebus follow rather than precede the Republic. I am not arguing against such a dating of the dialectical dialogues. I do not deny the value of the more vivid conception that we gain of Plato's later mood and manner by combining and compar- ing the traits of these dialogues with those of the Laws and Timceus. This is no a/37os \o'7o? directed against all sober critical investigation of the difficult problem of Plato's chronology. But the attempt to base such a chronology on the variations and developments of Plato's doctrine has led to an exaggeration of Plato's inconstancy that violates all sound principles of literary interpretation and is fatal to all genuine intelli- gence of his meaning. The implicit canon of this method is that variation in literary machinery and expression must be assumed to imply divergence or contradiction in thought. To this I wish to oppose an interpretation based on the opposite canon: that we are to assume contradiction or serious alteration in Plato's thought only in default of a rational literary or psychological explanation of the variation in the form of its expression. As Professor Maguire says in his forgotten but very acute essays on the Platonic ethics : " If we are anxious to find out inconsistencies in appearance, we shall find them in abundance. But the student of Plato will perhaps discover that it is more fruitful, because more philosophical to commence with the points of agree- ment." The ultimate test of the two methods must lie in the appeal to specific texts and contexts, and there will be no lack of this in the following pages. But by way of preparation it is first advisable to enumerate some of the general features of Plato's writings that make the sane and simple literary interpretation of his meaning so diffi- cult and so rare. 1. Plato is not only a thinker, but also a dramatic artist and an impassioned moral and religious teacher. Although, as Schopenhauer says, he is really the most severe and consistent of logicians, and holds the threads of his design in an iron hand, his dramatis personae affect to follow whither the argument blows,* and he often seems more concerned to edify or entertain than to demonstrate and conclude. Wherever his aesthetic or moral preferences are involved he cavils on terminology and breaks into seemingly irrelevant eloquent digressions in a Ruskinian fashion sorely puzzling to those not in sympathy with his mood. If forced to accept the substance of a repug- nant theory, he translates it into language more consonant with his feelings. This peculiar mixture of rhetoric and logic, of edification and science, misleads both the sentimentalist and the scientific puritan. The one often mistakes the ornament for the substance, the other distrusts perfectly sound reasoning because of his distaste for its emotional accompaniment. Again, Plato stimulates our own speculation in so many ways that we are apt to mis- take the drift of his meanings not because it is not clearly defined, but because we abandon s Not only in the earlier dialogues, but in Bep., 394 D ; Thecetet., 172 D ; Laws, 667 A. 6 The Unity op Plato's Thought it to pursue our own. The clever essayist tells us what he himself thought db propos of this or that brilliant suggestion. The investigator too often begins by selecting a few detached notions and formulas as adequately representative of each dialogue, and then proceeds to juggle with ingenious combinations of these and .the interpretations put upon them by his predecessors. Neither interprets Plato's real thoughts as they lie open to any competent reader who will patiently study him to the end and report the things on which he lays most stress." 2. In the second place, Plato's dramatic quality affects not only the artistic setting and the personages, but the ideas which he brings upon the stage. Plato's serious meaning detaches itself with perfect distinctness for the faithful student. But the hasty reader is more likely than not to receive as Platonic ideas that have a purely dramatic significance ; or that are falsified by isolation from their context.' And the investigator in pursuit of a thesis too often attributes specifically to Protagoras, Antisthenes, EucKd, or Isocrates ideas that Plato has generalized and decked out beyond all recognition, as representatives of the spirit of the age. Again, arguing for victory, the maintenance of a thesis in jest to test an oppo- nent's metal or display one's own ingenuity was a common practice in the world which Plato depicts, and is frequently illustrated in his writings. The Platonic Socrates, under cover of an ironical profession of ignorance, employs a similar method to expose showy pretenders to universal knowledge, to produce a salutary conviction of ignorance, or to stimulate youthful thought, and prepare the way for a more serious analysis by an exposition of the antinomies latent in conventional opinions. It fol- lows that the ostensible failure to conclude an argument, the avowal of bewilderment and perplexity, the admission even of positive fallacies of logic in any given dialogue prove nothing as to the stage of development of Plato's own thought at the time. The hypothesis that the fallacy was intentional, and that the airopCa was affected for a purpose, has at least an equal claim to be tested by all the probabilities in each case. 3. Expositors of Plato seem strangely oblivious of the limits thus far set to all systems of philosophy. They treat as peculiar defects of Plato the inconsistencies which they detect in his ultimate metaphysics after they have elaborated it into a rigid system which he with sound instinct evaded by poetry and myth. They habitually write as if they themselves and their intelligent readers were in possession of a final philosophy which reconciles all conflicting claims of metaphysical analysis and common sense, and from the heights of which they may study merely as a his- torical phenomenon Plato's primitive fumbling with such problems as the nature of 6 Such a reader is Bonitz for the most part in his ad- were intended seriously, and not a few continue to quote mirable analyses. The,j,., « . , r /Ac^ot ffxeSoj' aya^ol ■yt-yfoi'Tai. 26 Cf. my note in A. J. p.. Vol. X, p. 77. 10 The Unity of Plato's Thought infinite foreknowledge of God, and the absolute continuity of physical causation. It is, then, unprofitable to inquire whether Plato taught free-will or determinism."' But it should be distinctly noted that in the Laws he employs precisely the logic of modern determinism to prove that the involuntary character of wrongdoing is com- patible with the distinction for legal purposes of voluntary and involuntary acts.^' Virtue is knowledge because it must be assumed to be a good, and the only certain good, the only sure guide to the good use of what the world calls good, is knowledge.^" Opinion and habit may often suffice to regulate action, but persistent right opinion presupposes knowledge in its teachers, and the highest rule of conduct must be deduced from and referred to a rational apprehension of ultimate good.'" Virtue is one because each of the virtues is a form of knowledge,'" or because each, when taken in the highest sense, involves all the others.'^ Virtue is teachable in the senses in which knowledge and right opinion may be taught. The capacity for knowledge, the divine faculty, is innate, but teaching and guidance may direct it toward the good.'" The ordinary virtues of habit and opinion may fairly be said to be taught when they are systematically inculcated by superior wisdom enlisting all the forces of society ^n its service."* This is not the case at Athens,'^ and therefore the Platonic Socrates alternately affirms and denies the possibility of teaching "virtue,""* and at the close of the Meno declares that under present conditions it comes by a grace divine which is equivalent to chance."' Plato uses, but is not himself confused by, the Socratic analogy between the virtues and the arts and sciences."" That comparison, though it ignores the distinctively ethical element, contains a certain measure of truth. In a sense, each of us is good in that which he knows. "^ Knowledge as ordinarily understood is not virtue, but it 27ZELLEE, p. 853; JowETT, Vol. Ill, PP. 408, 425. to knowledge, opinion is imparted iy rH iraiSeU, 429C, i. c, 28 861-864 C. The meaning of the passage, though often '^ virtually taught, misunderstood, is perfectly clear, and Plato warns us, 34j;ep., 500D, 429CD; Poirt.,'309 D ; Laws, passim. 864B, not to catil about the terminology. 35jJep., 492E; Tim., 87B; Meno, 93Bffl.; Protag., 320; 2«Ev.thydem., 281, 289; Merw, 88C. Cf. from another ^«i'- 520B -Euthyphro, 2CD; Gorg., 521D; Apol, 24,25; point of view Fhoedo, 69 AB ; Protag., 356, 357, with Fhileb., Laches, 179 C D. 41E. ^Protag.; Meno; Buthyd.,2&2G {274E). sojlfeno, 97B; Meno, 100 A, olos koI aK\ov n-oi^crai, eti-. Cf. 37 For this interpretation of «ecV (loip^i see Magciee, p. Euthyd., 292D; infra, p. 16: Laws, 951 B. 63, andZELLEE's full refutation of other views, p. 594, n. 4, T^ pp . Rep., 492, 493. At present good men spring up avTo^arot nLaches; Protag.; Phmdo, 69AB. Meno, 71 D ff., is (jj^^ _ gjOB; cf. Protag., 320A; Euthyd., 282C); even in logical rather than ethical. The unity of aper, is postu- ^j^j^^^ gj^jg^^ ^^^^^ gj^ ^ ^^^ ^^.^. ^^^^^ „. ^„^^^, lated, like that of any other abstract idea, as a precondi- ^„^^„„, ^^jj^ ^sj.\ov iv ^iv^i^ovixivai, ^6K^„,v ij «ai ^r,. tion of a definition. „„mi » -r^. . . , . ^. 38 The lesser Htppias (certainly by Plato) presents the 31 Gorg., 507 A; Laws, 696 C. There is a suggestion of fallacy inits most paradoxical form (the voluntary lie better this also in the (of course intentional, BoNlTZ, Platonic ji^an the involuntary) and by its obvious irony (372 DE, Sttidies, p. 265) faUacies of Protag., 330, 331. 376 C) shows that Plato " already " in the Socratic period 33 iJep., 518B, 519A. This apparently contradicts the does not take it seriously, but merely uses it for dramatic statement of the Meno, 99A, and.Protojr., 361B, that ini- or propadeutio purposes. Zelleb, p. 597, takes this as '' • ■ • • "^P" i-vip^iiiv - 7re*u«eVai, (196 E) . In the Be- V ■ are included public (430 B), Plato chooses to deny the term bravery '""""' ■ to mere animal courage. In the iajos, 963 E, he attributes ^5 402 0, €A£v9.pidT>)!, neyaAoirpe>r«i,a536A. ^ ^j^^^j ^^ courage to children and animals. But oy^oim 56 Cf. also Protag., 331 A. Trtijiuicei/ai pointedly ignores the distinction of tempera- oi If it were desirable to produce a Platonic definition ment. Paul Shoeet 13 us happy, the distinction between the virtues vanishes;*" or in the tautology that the knowledge that is good is knowledge of the good.*' It is often assumed (1) that Plato was serious in these attempts to express by a phrase or a substituted synonym the essence of a virtue and the various and contradic- tory meanings of its conventional name ; (2) that the failure and pretended perplexity of Socrates at the close mark the point reached by Plato's own thought at the time. This is a priori conceivable. But the following considerations make it highly improbable : a) Plato, in this unlike Xenophon,*^ always proceeds as if he were aware of the true theory and use of the definition and of the multiple meanings of ethical terms. All attempts in his writings to work out abselute and isolated definitions fail.*' His own definitions, when not mere illustrations,** are always working hypotheses*' or epigrammatic formulas, subordinate to and interpreted by the argument of which they form a part, and recognized as imperfect, but sufficient for the purpose in hand.** The definitions of the virtues in Rep., 429 ff. cannot be understood apart from their context, and are never used again. They are declared to be a mere sketch — vTToypa^ijv, 504 D.*' How shall we explain this on the supposition that he was under any illusion as to the value of absolute and isolated definitions? b) Plato repeatedly refers in a superior way to eristic, voluntary and involuntary,** and more particularly to the confusion, tautology, and logomachy into which the vulgar fall when they attempt to discuss abstract and ethical problems.*' Some of these allusions touch on the very perplexities and fallacies exemplified in the minor dialogues.'* They do not imply that Plato himself had ever been so confused." Why should we assume that he deceives us in order to disguise his changes of opinion, or 60 Laches, 199 E. dialogues cures. Cf. Meno, 84 A B. So Soph., 232 A B, gives 61 CTiarm., 174 B; c/. Kep., 505BC — a connection gener- the raison d'etre of passages (.Gorgicn, Protag., Jon) in ally missed. which a pretender to universal knowledge is pressed for a 62 The Xenophontic Socrates perceives no difficulties, specific definition of his function which he naturally is is never in doubt, and propounds dogmatically such defini- unable to give. tioas as y6^ilJ.oy = SiKaLov, Mem., iy,i, 12. ■'oPolit., 306 ff., especially 306 A, rh yap apcrJ,, ^epos 63 Except the not quite serious definitions reached by »""?' "«" S;«*opoj- eW r.^a Tpd^ro.. To«jrepi Adyot, a^*.<.p,- dichotomy in the Sophist and PolUicus. Cf. Charmide,, :\"'^ «? ""^ '"/-"S^tov ^po, ra, ™. woKXu,. Jof«. Cf. Laws, Laches, Lysis, Meno, Theoetetus, Euthyphro, Hippias Major. «" »• '"^^''''"''r'" " ' ; " Z""" '■""'' '"' Z 6*Taxo,, Laches, 192B; ..x^a, Meno, 75, 76; .,Ad,. Be^b., 3iS^, .^xo^..' a. re X.y..y .ara ra .o^.(.^^^^ / ^ - -i • J ono T^ With reference to the arguments of Gor-ff., 474 C ff. Cf.Laws, Theoetet., 147 C ; .,Ato!, ibtd., 208 D. g^, ^^ ^.^j^ reference to the problem of the Lysis ; Laws, 65PAoedr.,237D, 6MoAoyi?«e>ievoiopor. C/. 263DE. gg^ g^ gg^^ ggg^ ggg 3_ where the paradox of Gorg., 467, is 66S.flr.,pT|ToputT)=iroAiT«^5)iopi'oiieISioXoi/, Gorg.,463D,but reaffirmed, ei iJ.iv poiiXeo-Oe (is Trai^av, el S' 0)5 airovSa^ioy; in Phcedr., 261 A, vfiuxaY^Y'a "i «iA Adyioi-. Cf. the defini- iJepMbJJc, 505 B, with Cfcarm., 173 £-174 B; Pep., 505 C, with tions of (TM^poffvn), Phcedr., 237 E. Gorg., 499 B, where Callicles is forced to admit that some ■ 67 The Laws repeats the substance of the definition of pleasures are bad. Zellee(p. 604) thinks that Sep., 505 C, justice, 863E: Ti)v yi-ii rofl »vnoO .... ital eiri9i/(iii>' ev ipvxji refers to the Philetms. But the advocates of a late date TvpavviSa .... irapTws aSixiav npoaayopevot. Cf. 689 A B, rh fQj. tjjg philebus rightly deny any specific parallel, yop Kvirovittvov kox TiUp.tmv avrit (sc. T^i if^x^') ""^'P ^W" 71 Even after the Republic and Politicus, Plato in Imws, re icai irA^os TrdAeiit ianv. Cf. Pep., 442 A, o «)) nkilarov t^i 963 ff., approaches the problem of the "political art" and ^X^«» 6*-^. the unity of virtue precisely in the manner of the tentative 68Uep., 454 A; Phileb., 14 C, e«oO*po ' a- does not preclude Plato from arguing that his ideal of the moraland social life is better than that of average Athenian 442 E, 443 A. opinion, and that the definitions which embody it are right 86 Grote, followed by many others, denies this. But as against formulas that express some aspect of the tradi- that is because he persists in attributing to Plato the tional belief. doctrine that ethical abstractions ("mixed modes") have 87 ijep., 427E, oVat i,^:^ tV toAcv reA.o,, ivaOV one meaning only which can be expressed in an absolute ,j„„.. s^^ov ir, St. /-, tn notice of the different meanings and sub-species covered , '°P"^-' 504 B C D, 505 A, r, toC iyaSoO iSea ,; SUaia by one generic term (Pfiwdr., 161, 162; Euthydem., 277, 278; ""' '' '^'"' '/""XPIo-i/ieva x/'W^H-t «" ia.a iavrv mm., 29 E) and a God see Idea of Good, pp. 188, 189. j^^^ constraction of (92 B) eUi.^ toO rorjTov (sc. (>fov not SeoO, 93 Fantastic because due (1) to the wish to depress c/. 38CD). ilSovn to the fifth place; (2) to the neo-Platouic device of 95 jfeno, 87 D ; iocAes, 192 C, 193 D ; Protoff.,349E; Bipp. extending the intelligible hierarchy by the interpolation of j^i^j., 284 D ; Bep., 332, 333. new members between the highest and the lowest. It 96 See Idea o/ Good, pp. 200-204. belongstorhetoricorreligiousemotion,then,nottoPlatos ,,^„j^^^^ 282E, 290, 291C; Charm., 170B; Protag.. scieutilio ethics. ^^g^. Gorff., 501AB, 503D; PoUt, 289C, 293D,309C; Bep., 94 .E. g., one hundred and fifty pages separate Zellee's ^^ jj treatment of the idea of good (P- 101) /'o^ ^JltTrrer »»Cy. Meno, 80E, Euthydem., 286D., The<^tet., 191 B of the ethical good (p. 867). In elucidation of the former J , , n he quotes little or nothing from the ethical dialogues and i*^- , t .,-t^x, r ™» cites neither PAi. •» i. /.j -ri - t* -_» « - * ' however, refers partly to the lower education as well. ■•-^-j.' 101 Cf. Lysis, 218 A, with Symp., 203 E. Paul Shoeey 19 become the commonplaces of the philosophy and poetry of modern Europe: the strange antinomy between the love of like for like and the attraction of dissimilars in man and nature; the exaltation of character and mood in passionate love and friend- ship; the transfiguration of the passion in the love of aesthetic, moral, and intellectual beauty;"^ the overloading of the instinct to achieve the ends of nature — the immor- tality of the species."* The student of the Lysis, Phcedrus, Symposium, Republic, and Laws will find it impossible to fix a date at which these ideas first presented themselves to Plato's mind."" The mood, the treatment, the emphasis varies. Some of the thoughts are omitted in each dialogue, none are treated in all, and contradic- tions and developments may be "proved" by uncritically pressing the language and the imagery. But the differences between the Symposium and Phcedrus, both pre- sumably works of the middle period, are as noticeable as those found in any other works that touch on the theme. The Symposium mentions one idea, the Phcedrus several; the former ignores immortality and avdfivTj- 13^; Par- losCf. Rep., 402, 403, with Symp., 2100; Bep., 490ABi ,„,^ ^^ ^^.^ ^.^^.^ *ao„o«er, etc , Symp., 203 E, which Laws, 688B, *pov,.r« ko. vov, ko. 6oJa ^er _.p»T05 T. LOTosLAwaKI (p. 239) thinks an important new point, in ..( i^^Ov^ias; Sep., 499C, with I,a«,s, -IID, ora. ep<«5 O.cot ^^^^^^^ ^^^^ „f j^^ Cra*j,I««, is " already" in iym, 218 A. Ti- ^u,^p6vmv re «al ^«t in the Symposium and RepublicT or Euthydem., 295 B C, and the fallacy by which it is illus- "o 263 C, 265 E. 20 The Unity of Plato's Thought •KepiKa^ov iraaav airopiav koI cradTov airepyd^eTai. How familiar the two etBrj were to Plato appears from the almost technical use of the phrase 5t' ofioioTrjTa ensable initia- 12E, and in language suggesting the protest against eristic tory stimulus to philosophy. But the Symp., 210 C, xiv ia Sophist, 259D, points out that (generic) resemblance is trjiiKpbi' ai/So! Ixn. and the Bep., 402 D, emphasize the unim- compatible with difference and even contrariety (cf, also portance of the beauty of the body as compared with that Meno, 74 D). He does not explain himself fully, however, of the mind. And in the same vein Socrates says, /coAbs yap and Socrates, ignoring the point, proceeds to trip him up el Si ©eainiTe .... 6 yifi KnAu; Xe'-yoii' xiiAds, etc., 186 E. The by a fallacious use of the principle that one thing can have Platonic Socrates is still the epoiTiitdt as he was in the Lysis, only one opposite. Whatever the date of the Euthydemus, nor can we suppose that he would ever have found the its author was aware that a word used in two senses may beautiful Meno as helpful an "initiatory stimulus to phUos- have two opposites, quite as early as he was capable of ophy" as the snub-nosed Theeetetus. writing the Protagoras. The passage is merely a dramatic 113 Bep., 363 B C D, 367 E, 612 B C. The Oorgias does not illustration of Socrates's superiority in the same of ques- difier herein from the Bepublic, as Eitohie {p. 156) seems to tio° ^^^ answer. Again in 350 B-351 A, when it is argued think. The argument is complete without the myth, and the "i^* bravery ia knowledge because knowledge imparts con- phrases at the end about living justly in order to prepare Mence, Protagoras points out that we cannot convert the for the judgment of Minos prove no more than the iva of universal afarmative proposition, "all bravery is confi- Bep. 621 C. dence," and distinguishes as bravery the confidence that arises from nature and training. Though not a match for lUKaKov, Bep., 457 B. Socrates, Protagoras is a far better reasoner than Laches ii'Eep., 440E, 571C, 605B. or Nicias, and again Socrates refutes him only by taking Paul Shobey 21 theses incompatible with the positions from which they started."* But the full expla- nation lies deeper. In the Republic Plato undertakes to demonstrate the intrinsic desirability of virtue against two forms of disbelief — the explicit skepticism of the cynic, who affirms that natural justice is the advantage of the stronger and human justice an artificial convention, and the unfaith of the ordinary man, who virtually admits this theory by commending justice solely on external and prudential grounds."' The CalLicles of the Gorgias represents the former view, Gorgias himself and (less obviously) Protagoras the latter. Like other Sophists, he is the embodiment of average public opinion which his teaching reproduces."" He himself says that all men teach virtue. He modestly claims at the most only to teach it a little more effectively and persuasively than the layman.™ Plato would .admit both assertions, with the reserva- tion that the virtue so- taught hardly deserves the name, and that the teaching is neither systematic nor philosophical. The molding power of public opinion, operating through countless social and educative agencies, is admirably depicted in the myth attributed to Protagoras, the main thought of which is repeated in the Bepublic.^'' There, however, the philosophic rulers are to employ this irresistible force for the inculcation, not of average Greek opinion, but of Platonic virtue. The Protagoras dramatically illustrates the dialectic incapacity and philosophic" superficiality of the great popular teacher. His ethical teaching is spiritually and logically on a level with the precepts of the worthy sires and guardians satirized by Adeimantus."^ However unlike in temper and practical effect, it is philosophically akin to the individual hedonism of Callicles and Thrasy- machus who reject all morality as an unreal convention. Protagoras is naturally unaware of this. Like the populace, he recoils from the naked exposition of the principles implied in his preaching and practice. He accepts the terminology of indi- vidual hedonism only under compulsion of Socrates's superior dialectic. But Socrates's explicit challenge to him and the assembled Sophists to name any other final good than '^BovT) is a proof that one of Plato's objects was to identify the Sophistic ethics with hedonism.'^* But neither this nor the demonstration of Protagoras's inability to cope with Socrates in dialectic exhausts the significance of the dialogue. Plato, however reluctantly, always recognized a certain measure of truth in the Benthamite analysis here attributed to Socrates. He knew that " act we must in pursuance of that which (we think) will give us most pleasure " Even the Gorgias contains phrases of utilitarian, if not hedonistic, implication.'^^ The Eudsemonism of np a new line of argument— the identity of pleasure and ^^^Bep., 362 E S. Of. Zelleb, p. 603, n. 1. good, and the consequent unity of the virtues in the 120 ijep., 492 ff. 121 Prof as., 328 B. "measuringart." Platoof conrsewasawarehere,andinthe „ , , ,° , u ii. I ■ „■„„! „»! , 12JE1TOHIE (p. 156) says: "The argument of the Sophist SMtAt/pAro (12), and everywhere, that a universal amrma- • ^ „ ^ j v m i n ^ ji«.c./ti,>//wv I o;, o J , „ .J. „. tu. Protagoras .... is now fully accepted by Plato," etc., as tive cannot be directly converted. But it is a part of the ., „, f , ,, . , i iv ^ * , " ,. , iv i -D i. „ , ,1. 1.1 „„!,.>„„„„ if Plato was not the author of the Pr-otofforas. scheme of the dialogue that Protagoras should make some good points, though defeated in the end. And Socrates is 123 Rep., 362 E. 12< 354 D, 358 A. baffled in or fails to complete other proofs of the unity of 125 499 D. Ritchie (p. 155) strangely says that in the virtue, and so is driven to rely on the proof from hedonism, Eepublic Plato recognizes, in marked advance upon the which is the chief feature of the dialogue. position of the Gorgias, that there are good pleasures as 1 18 Protag. , 361 . well as bad ! 22 The Unity of Plato's Thought the Republic has often been pointed out,'^° and in the Laws Plato explicitly declares, in language recalling that of the Protagoras, that it is not in human nature to pursue any course of action that does not promise a favorable balance of pleasure.'" But the inference which he draws is not that it is safe or desirable to proclaim that pleasure is the good, but that it is necessary to demonstrate that the good — the virtuous life — is the most pleasurable. To a Benthamite this will seem a purely verbal or rhetorical distinction. And Aristotle himself hints that Plato's aversion to the name of pleasure cast a suspicion of unreality over his ethical teaching."' But Plato is not alone in his aversion to the word. Matthew Arnold acknowledges a similar feeling. And Jowett, in his admirable introduction to the Philebus, has once for all set forth the considerations by which many clear-headed modern thinkers, who perfectly understand the utilitarian logic and accept whatever is true in its psychology, are nevertheless moved to reject its language. The Greek word '^Sovq is much more closely associated with a low view of happiness than the English word "pleasure;" and Plato had, or thought that he had, much stronger reasons than the moderns have, for identifying hedonism with the negation of all moral principle. The Gorgias and Philebus nowhere explicitly contradict the thesis of the Pro- tagoras that a preponderance of pleasure, rightly estimated and abstracted from all evil consequences, is good.'^' The doctrine which they combat is the unqualified iden- tification of pleasure and good, coupled with the affirmation that true happiness is to be sought by developing and gratifying the appetite for the pleasures of sense and ambition.'** Plato represents Callicles and Philebus as unable or unwilling to limit these propositions even by the qualifications of the Protagoras. ^^^ It is he, not they, who introduces the distinction of pure and impure,"^ true and illusive,"' wholesome and unwholesome,'" necessary and unnecessary pleasures.'^* The modern critic may object that Plato was not justified in attributing to any contemporaries either this dialectical incapacity or this cynical effrontery. Plato thought otherwise. It is a question of historical evidence. But it is not legitimate to attribute to the Callicles and the Philebus of the dialogues the utilitarianism of Grote or John Stuart Mill, or even that of the Protagoras, and so convict Plato of self-contradiction.'^° With these remarks we may dismiss so much of the Gorgias and Philebus as is merely dialectical, dramatic, or rhetorical, directed against the crudest form of hedonism which Plato chooses to bring upon the stage before grappling with the problem in 126 357 B, riSovai otrat a^XajSet? goods per se,* 457 B, 458 E, and the explanation that some painful goods are medicliial 581 B (with Laws, 732 E), nij ort irpbt to iciXAiov itaX alo-xioi' ?i)i» (354 A = Sep., 351 C), and is checked by the calculus of all iu.i)5e TO x^^pov (cat afj-cLvov, ctAAa jrph^ auTo TO ^Stoi' KaX a^vTTOT- consequences, -all of which is ignored by Callicles and tpov. Philebus. 127 Laws, 733, 734 ; cf. 663 A. 128 Mh. nic, X, 1. 132 pMleb., 51, 52. 133 IMd., 36 C ff. l29PAiJe6., 60AB, is verbally a direct contradiction of mibid., 41A; Gorg., 499DE. 135 iJep., 558 D. ^^■' ' 136 Plato, as Jowett says, is "playing both sides of the 130 Gmg., 495 A, 492 D E ; Phileb., 12 A, 12 D, 27 E. game .... but it is not necessary in order to understand 131 The verbal identification of ^Sovt) and ayiL&hv in 355 him that we should discuss the fairness of his modes of has been preceded by such phrases as ita9' h ijiia iariv, 351 C, proceeding." Paul Shorey 23 earnest."' The real arguments which he employs, not so much to refute the thesis of the Protagoras as to limit its practicable application and justify his repudiation of its terminology, may be summed up as follows: The distinction between good and bad pleasures once admitted, the statement that pleasure as such is the good, becomes an unreal abstraction."' The reality is specific kinds of pleasure and the principle of distinction, whether intelligence, measure, or the will to obey the "opinion of the best," "' becomes more important than the bare name of pleasure, and more nearly allied to the good."" The "measuring art" postulated in the Protagoras is impracti- cable. Pleasure and pain are, like confidence and fear, foolish counselors;'" either deprives the mind of the sanity required for a just estimate.'" No scale of human judgment can be trusted to weigh the present against the future, and make allowance for all the illusions of memory, hope, and contrast."' The most intense pleasures and pains are associated with a diseased condition of mind and body.'** And the habit of pursuing pleasure, of thinking and speaking of it as the good, tends to make the world of sense seem more real than that of thought and spirit.'*^ The contrary is the truth. The world of sense is a pale reflex of the world of ideas,'*' and the pleasures of sense are inherently unreal, illusory, and deceptive, and may in sound logic be termed false, as fairly as the erroneous opinions that accompany them.'*' They are false becaiise composed of hopes and imaginations not destined to be fulfilled;'** false, because exaggerated by the illusions of distance in time or contrast;'*' false, because i37pftiJe6., 55AB, and Gforp., 495 C, 499 B, show that the arguments of Gorrg.., 495 C-499 B, are, in the main, a con- scious dialectical sport. I recur to this point so often be- cause the Gorgias and the first book of the Republic are the chief source of the opinion, widely spread by Qrote, Mill, and Sidgwick, that Plato is a magnificent preacher, but often a weak reasoner. Cf. Mill, Diss, and Discuss,, IV, 291 : " This great dialogue, full of just thoughts and fine observations on human nature, is, in mere argument, one of the weakest of Plato's works." Cf. Idea of Good, pp. 213-15. iisPhileb., 12 DE. In answer to the question, Trii yap rjSoviq ye ijSovg fj-Tj ovx, ofioioTarov av elij ; Socrates shows that generic (verbal) identity is compatible with specific diflfer- ence or even opposition, a logical principle "already" glanced at in the Protag., 331 D, with the same illustration of (icAav and Ktvicov. LuTOSLAWSEI, p. 467, misunderstands 13 A, TovT^ Tw \6yta firi miTTeue, T<5 iravra Ta efaxTiiiraTa ev irotovvTi — "we need not attempt a reconciliation of all con- tradictions I " 139 PAcedr., 237 D, ifk^vros .... iiriOviiia. ^fioi'ui' .... eiriKTijTos ho^ay e0ie/xef 7) toO apiffTOv. Cf, Laws, 644 D, 645 A. Phcedo, 99 A, un-b 5o^t)5 t^epoixeva ToG ^eATiVTOV. ^^Phileb., 64C, Ti . , . . iiaXiar* atnor elvcu fiofeiej/ av rili.tv ToO irafft yeyovevai irpocr^iA^ T»)»' TotavTijc Biaffeaw • with the context. 1*1 Cf. Tim., 69 D, with Laws, 644 C. UiB^., 402E; Phileb., 63D; Phcedo, 66B. "3Cy. Phileb., 41Eff., with Protag., 356, 357; Gorgias, 500 A, 3p' oiv ffavTos avSpoi eariv efcAef avdai, etc. Laws, 663 B, iTKorofiii'iai' Se to iroppiaOev opiafievov na^apr,r^|i/ t^s xe'P'X'ot Mtv iov aiaBrjacciv tii Iv Koyi.aii.ii ^vraipoujuei-oi/. and inventive minds to let in light on a dark subject." toCto ii ianv ai-ajiinjcris, etc. Cratyl., 399 C, fidi'oi' ruv Bripiav They belong to the " theories which have arisen in in- opSois 6 avOptairiK avdpuTro^ uvop.dtrSij, dvadpSn' 4 oirwirei'. genious minds from an imperfect conception of the pro- phmdo, 75 B, on vivra. ra ei- Taii aifffl^Veaii' eneiVov re hpiytrai, cesses of abstraction and generalization." But it is not ^5 o Io-tii/ Xirov, etc. really thinkable that the author of the Sophist, Politicus, and Phoedrus (249 B) did not "understand" the common- i»' Parmen., 132, ydw«« oUiH,; St-to! f, ov/c o^tos; sense explanation of the universal through abstraction and • ■ • ''™ o*" ''«« •""'" """ " -"ovM^-o^ Iv elvai, ie. oy to generalization. He rejected it, on the contrary, precisely «"" «"•' '''«'"'; Lutoslawski, p. 403, misquotes and mis- beoause he foresaw that, if consistently carried out and interprets this passage. Peofessoe Ritchie, Plato, pp. accepted as the final account of the matter, it leads 91. "2, 113, recognizes that it is conclusive against con- straight to Mill's ultimate phUosophy, which he would not ceptualism. Cf. Zblleb, p. 668. The further objection have on any terms. ^^^^ '^ ^^^ ideas are thoughts and things partake of them, .„' , , , . , , . .,, things must think, is generally treated as a verbal equivo- ^^Protag., 330 C,, S«acoav., ^pay^. rj «rn. , ovS,v ^^y^^_ Euthydem., 287DE. But, for the underlying ^pay^a; PAosdo, 65D, «a;... n eira. ««ato. avTo , ovj..; 76E, metaphysical problem, see my discussion of Aristotle de 77 A, j.,n,-u:\n,A .. 41, , . .. iu J.- n J. , I,- if 4.i,» „«■• t of the doctrine of Po!t*ic««, 291 B and 303 E-304 A, as to the but if any athetizer will stake his reputation on the point, ,._ ,, , ,. .^. . , . ,, . . . t- • .1 ... ,, , difficulty of distinguishing the statesman from his imita- tors and the true relation of piTopeia to 6«a . o, • joot, - ->, • . , . o N .,v. i . . tt * 201 But cf. 474 D, an-oSAeTTwi' ; 488 D, ra riav itoKaihv fo/xiua, elfios .... er ... . irept CKOiTTo Ta iroAAa) — auTO to eI6o5 w, ... _ . «t. . - . , .. . . l ^ /r... _, .nr.-r. ~ , ' ..r nn rf " Tr With 2?ep., 479 D, Ttt T(OV ITOAAwi' ITOAAa VO^l/ia, OtC. ; GOTg., etc. (Pftoedo, lOOD, TitaAii);-JfejM>, 72C, ei/ye Ti tWo! . . . . , , . ,,, . fit' &), airop\eiTbiv .... TrapafieiyjLtaTt, 497 E, irapovtria . . , , oU av /caAAoc irapy. 199 301 A. It is not the word irapeaTi that proves this, a- ' 7 i ■> but the entire context cTcpa avToO ye ToO KoAoi), etc. Ltjtos- LAW8KI (p. 212) affirms that Plato "would have said later 203 On this passage as the chief Platonic source of the iripeo-Ti TO xaAAo; (avTb ica9' oiiTd)." He never did say, nor Aristotelian doctrine of matter and form see my remarks could he have said, anything of the kind. HapeaTi .... in A. J. P., Vol. XXII, No. 2, p. 158. Campbell, overlooking airb icafl' auTo he would have felt as a contradiction in this passage, finds in Polit., 288 D, the earliest approach to terms. (On the correct and incorrect use of avra wafl' ai/ra., the distinction of matter and form. 32 The Unity of Plato's Thought into the plastic stuff of human nature the forms or ideas of justice and temperance which he contemplates as existing in the transcendental world (e'«et), and so becomes an artisan of political and popular virtue.^"* Expressed in slightly different imagery, this is the function of the statesman in the Politicus, 309 C (c/. 308 D). He is to implant in those rightly prepared by education, fixed, true opinions concerning the honorable, the just, and the good.'"'^ The thought and the imagery belong to Plato's permanent stock. We find them in the Gorgias, 503 E-504 D.^°° Here, too, Plato conceives the true teacher, artist, or statesman as contemplating ideas or forms, which he strives to embody in the material with which he works, even as the Demiurgus of the Timceus stamps the ideas upon the matter of generation. The origin, first suggestion, exposition, or proof of the theory of ideas is variously sought by different critics in the Meno, the Cratylus, the Thecetetus, or even in the Phcedrus, Parmenides, and Symposium. Obviously Plato could at any time argue indirectly in support of the ideas as necessary postulates of ontology and epistemology. Our chief concern is with the hypothesis that the exposition of some particular dia- logue marks a date in the development of his own thought. The doctrine of remin- iscence is introduced in the Meno to meet an eristic use of a puzzle allied to the psychological problem of " recognition." ^^ How, if we do not already know, shall we recognize a truth or a definition when we have found it?™' Socrates replies that the soul has seen all things in its voyagings through eternity, and that all our learning here is but recollection.^"' This theory is confirmed in the case of mathematical ideas by Socrates's success in eliciting by prudent questions a demonstration of the Pythag- orean proposition from Meno's ignorant slave."" The Phcedo distinctly refers to this argument as a proof of the reality of ideas,^" and the myth in the Phcedrus describes the ante-natal vision of the pure, colorless, formless, essences of true being. '^'^ It fol- lows that, though the ideas are not there explicitly mentioned, the reminiscence spoken of in the Meno must refer to them."' But it is extremely improbable that this repre- sents Plato's first apprehension of the doctrine. Psychologically and historically the origin of the theory is to be looked for in the hypostatization of the Socratic concept and the reaction against Heracliteanism."* Its association with Pythagoreanism and 204 a elect opif /leAeT^irai ct9 avBptoiriav rj&rj .... TLdei'ai 207 ji/e/io^ 80 D ff . Cf. my dissertation i)e Platonis ideOr . , . , iritLLovpyov .... ti>potrvyj}v t« koX SiKaLotrvvTii, Cf. rum doctrina, pp. 15 ff. 501 B, TTVKva ay eKarepwcre aTTOjSAeTrotej' .... koX Trpby €Ktlvo a5 onn - ^ - - • - - v ' . « j ti ■ ".'.,„, , - ^., T, 7-i onnt^ - • - zlWouTe iriTtiv ouTc anopciv avev rrpoAi)i/(fco5, Sext. Empir. h ev Toiff arOpwn-ois e/Airotoicr, Cf. FoUt.y aJd 1>, touto auTO Mnth 1 ^7 e/iiroiEic, 205 This does not refer exclusively to the higher ednca- '"' " I^'^i^'s pent dire comme le Dieu do Pascal : ' Tu tinn as Zeller affirms °® ™® chercherais pas, si tu ne m'avaisdfij^ trouvfi.'" — ' ; ....... FouiLLfiE. C/. PoZtt., 278 D; Tim., 41 E,Ti,^To07raiT65*vViK 206 aT^o^AET^(l>f Trpos Tt .... ottws av elfios ri aurw trxrt toOto tfietf e. Cf. infra p 43 o epya^eTOLi. This is applied first to the body, then to the soul. The Tafis and icd;' the Thecetetus. It appears explicitly again only not quite sure of them. His real object is to eliminate the *" *•>« Parmenides, and not in the " late " PhiUbv^ and self-existent idea altogether. Tinuzus. It is not included in the ten kinds of motion in „^ J 1 ■ I » J • non ■ the Laws, 893, 894, and L. finds it only by implication in 217 Cf. supra, p. 31. The doctrine of CratyL, 389, is ^^ .^, .^^_ .^^ ^.^^ ^. ^j, ^^^.^^^ .^^^^^ iKKoui^T,, which furthermore identical with that of Bepub., 596 A fl. .^ ^^ ^^^^ ^^pjj^.j ^.j^^^ ^^^ Cratylus or Bepublic. 218 386, 439, 440. On the ini ov and i/(evS^5 Sofa fallacy, 429 a., cf. infra, p. 53. On the p^^c, cf. 411 B C with "''W. J. Aleiandeb in Stvdies Dedicated to Gilder- Phcedo, 90C;PAiie6.,43A. Lutoslawski affirms (pp. 366, sJeewe, p. 179, thinks its teaching to be : knowledge is of the 367) that the subdivision of «..n,Tti into *opa and aWo;«.a« ideas, error arises from imperfect i,'i^vr,a,,. is a new and important discovery of the Thecetetus, 181, C. ^"Supra, u. 185. He fails to note that the argument of Cratylus, 339, 340, dis- 34 The Unity of Plato's Thought herself,^^' and whose essence is apprehended through their relation of opposition/^'' are mentioned, after ova-ia, the ofioiov and avofioiov, the ravrov and the erepov of the Sophist. But also, as in the Parmenides, the ethical ideas, kuXov, aiaxpov, ayaOov, and KaKov ;^^' and lastly, as in the Republic, the qualities of sense, aKXrjpov and pLoXaicov!^^'' The actual sensation of these opposites comes of course through sense. But the oixrla and the 6 ti ia-rov, as in the Republic, is apprehended by the mind as an idea. There is no argument for holding these ideas to be mere concepts that would not prove the same for the Republic, which of course is impossible. '^^^ This point established, we may concede that the Thecetetus may be, not an introduction to the ideas, but an indirect argument in support of the familiar doctrine. The polemic against Heraclitus is always that.^^* And, though Plato himself may not be aware of it, the statement that the syllable is not the sum of its elements, but fiia Ihea a/j.epia-TO';, embodies the prin- ciple and justification of a realistic logic. ^' The conceptual whole is not the sum of its parts, but a new entity and unity .^^* What has been said of the Thecetetus applies to Zeller's theory ^^' that the second part of the Parmenides is an indirect argument for the ideas. That this is not the main purpose of the Parmenides will appear in the sequel. And Zeller was mistaken in stating that only relative contradictions followed from the being of the one, while absolute contradictions resulted from its not being. But the Platonic idea is always suggested by the antithesis of the one and the many. And in the eighth hypothesis, 164 B ff., the "one" and "others" are no longer treated with dialectical impartiality, but there is a hint that the one may be regarded as the symbol of the idea. Symme- try leads us to expect the argument that, if the one is not (relative /u.^ 6v), other things both are and are not all contradictory predicates. Instead of "are" we find " appear" or " seem." Other things are indefinite bulks that break up under inspection and only seem to partake of unity and other predicates that derive from unity. These 07/cot certainly suggest the world of matter uninformed by ideas, the " being" of the materialists which the friends of ideas in the Sophist call " becofning" and break up into little bits.^^" And the statement that, as they cannot be other than the (non- existent) one, they are the other of one another, reminds us of aX\i]\oK .... aw- 221 avrri ^ i^ux^l86B. C/. 187A; Phmdo, 65 C; Bep,, 524 paradox, but passes on to show how mathematics leads B C, 526 B. the mind to the apprehension of abstract and ideal unity. 222 tV ivavTionrroL irpbt iW^Kio. Of. Sep., 524 D, « liiv eii Fhilebus, 14 D £E., is concerned with logical method ; Bep., Tijv ala-eriiTi.i' i)t.a Tols ivavrioit iavrolt i^mmei. Mr. Henry ^23-6, with psychology and education. But the thought of Jackson and others confound this special use of Trpbt aXX.)At « -Ic >-<"«»'. „,.,,,,_ ,. , J iu u c See also J^. J. P., Vol. XXII, No. 2, p. 158. in Phileb. ,UT3, are Sc6rifj.tvii.eya are made the bases of a ' i "• i f ""• dialectical course in Bep., 523-6. This is a misapprehen- 229Set forth in his Platonic Studies and the earlier edi- sion. The Bepublic mentions (525 A) that the same object ''""s of his History, but now virtually withdrawn. is perceived as one and many. It does not sport with the 230Spp7i., 246 B.C. Paul Shobet 35 SeSeffdai in the theory of pure relativity in Thecetetus, 160 B. Similar hints occur in the fourth hypothesis, 157 B, which deals with aWa on the supposition that the one is.™ The main conclusion that aXXa, then, admit all contradictory predicates is indi- cated very briefly (159 A). What is emphasized is the fact that aXKa per se are ifKridr] . . . . iv oh to ev ovk evi, that they are airetpa (cf. Phileb.) ; that it is the one which introduces Tre/jo? Trpo? aXXrjXa ; and that, having parts, these parts must relate to iud<; Tcvbi lBea i Bxpresslon of their relatloH. 250 130 D. See Zeller, 700, 701, for lists of ideas. But, as we have seen, to admit that there is any conceptual "' See my note iaA.J.P., Vol. X, No. 1, p. 66. Zblleb, unity not referable to an idea is to make the theory a mere Sitzunasber. d. Berl. Akad., 1887, No. 13. play of fancy, and deprive it of all psychological and onto- 251 51, 52. logical meaning. 255 51 C, rb Se oiSiv ap' V t^'I" ^"Yos. For the impossi- 2ii 51 C. Cf. supra, n. 188. bility of taking Advos as " Socratic concept " see my note in 252 The TpiTos ii-SpcoTTos is repeated in 132 DE. Other -4. J. P., Vol. X, p. 65. difficulties follow, and the final summing up, 135 A, is 256 Me. Abcheb-Hikd's attempt (Jour, of Phil,, Vol. couched in the most general terminology : ei eitriv atrai at XXXV, pp. 49 ff.) to "circumvent" this passage is based on a ifieai rS>v ofTuf Kai bpietrai Tts avTo Tt eKeurrov eiSo^, There is misinterpretation of 39 E. Since an idea of fire is not men- no suggestion that a. new form or terminology makes any tioned in the exhaustive enumeration there given of the difference. The much misunderstood passage, 133 C D, is ideas contained in the supreme idea, an idea of fire he merely a special application of the general difficulty to argues, cannot be meant seriously here. But 39 E does not relative terms. Ideal slavery is related only to ideal speak of the " supreme idea," which is a figment of modern ownership, the slavery in us only to the ownership in us. Flatonists. The ivov is simply the universal of animal or There is no discrimination here of a class of aira. i • 1 v i ■ !•!.•„. *„..,„ ment of it in other dialogues and for this purpose presses formal fallacy). Plainly, whatever implications we force , j . m- cot. *•«-«- Til i , J . - . • i. i. i.^ 11 ..„ avTTVov Avcrtc, Tim., 52 B. upon Plato s words, his purpose here is not to attribute ^ ' ' soul to the ideas, but to remove from the path of logic the 268 to Kara ravTa koI uo-avTus ex^uv, etc. 40 The Unity of Plato's Thought 250 B, offa dWa Tifiia yfrvxal's), have no copies in the world of sense, and must be appre- hended by reason. This is precisely the doctrine of Phcedrus, 250 BCD and 263 A B, and ought to end controversy.'''^' We have already seen that the Philebus bids us assume ideas and disregard the difficulties of the Parmenides."'' There is no hint that they are only concepts."' We may assume, then, that the language of 58 A, 59 0, and 61 E implies the ideas. "^ III. PSYCHOLOGY Supposed variations in Plato's psychology have been used to determine the evolu- tion of his thought and the relative dates of the dialogues. The chief topics are: (1) the immortality of the soul; (2) the unity of the soul, or its subdivision into faculties; (3) the general argument that the psychology of the "later" dialogues is richer and more precise than that of the earlier. 1. The immortality of the individual soul is for Plato a pious hope,"' and an ethical postulate,"* rather than a demonstrable certainty."" He essays various demonstrations, but nearly always in connection with a myth, and of all the proofs attempted but one is repeated. In the Apology Socrates, addressing his judges, affects to leave the question open."° But we cannot infer from this that the Apology antedates Plato's belief in immortality. For, to say nothing of Pythagorean sources of inspiration, he had pre- sumably read Pindar's second Olympian with approval; and Socrates's language in Criio, 54 B, is precisely in the tone of the Gorgias and the Phcedo.'^^^ The Meno™ assumes the immortality and the prior existence of the soul to account for a priori knowledge. The Phcedo presents a complicated proof or series of proofs. The Sympo- sium seems to recognize only the subjective immortality of fame, and the racial immor- tality of offspring."' The "early" Phcedrus and the late Laws alone agree in a proof based on the conception of the soul as the self -moving."*" It is easy to foresee the hypotheses which an ingenious philology will construct from these facts. Krohn, Pflei- derer, and Eohde gravely argue that Book I of the Republic must be very early because the aged Cephalus neglects the opportunity to supplement his citation from Pindar with a scientific proof of immortality. Horn tells us that the Phcedrus represents the first 269Fora;'a)i>'iI(7ismthePoiiKcMsc/. m/ro, p. 44. Phmdo, 115 DE; and with the idea, 959 B, that the only 2™ See A. J. P., Vol. IX, p. 279. Po^Seia at the bar of Hades is a just life in this world, cf. 271 Ldtoslawski, p. 467, mistranslates, or, if he prefers, Gorg., 522 C D, 526 E ; Onto, 54 B. misinterprets, 15 D : " the nature of thought requires the 275 Phcedo, 85 C, to iikv o-ai^e; tlSiuai 4v tu vvv fiia ^ iSvua. union of notions into higher units, and this constitutes an toi' elmt ^ irayx'''^'™'' ". Cf. 107 A B ; Tim., 72 D ; Memo, eternal necessity of the human mind. " Cf. supra, p. 36. 86 A B ; Phcedr., 265 C. 272 TTji' yap TT€pl TO or kol to orTW? icai to Kara ravTov aei 276 4Q Q, Cf. also Pkcedo 91 B. , , '. , , , . . . ^^^Cratylus, 403 DE, implies the doctrine of Phcedo, ra a-VTcL ilcravTcos afliKToTnTa exovTa.— i) «e eiri Ta j«)Te yi,yvoit.eva. (57 oa w>7Te aTToAAu'iLLera, «aTo ravTa 6e «ai wcraUToj? ovTa aei. Cf. 62 A, ' ' {t7fl S"! r^ aiiTrjs irepi 6c«aio divided into TO iv ij/xii' and TO ei- TJ) ^vaei. This seems to Kill Y^y «ai ie'pa TrpuTu ^yeiaflai Tilv irai-Tior eti-tti. Cf. Phileb., yield three things: the ideapcrse, the idea in the particular, 30A; TheoBtet., 155 E, 184 D; Sophist, 246Aj Tim., 51 C, and the particular as affected by the idea. (C/.SMpra,n. 252.) r, TauTa, oirep «ai ^AeTrojiei- .... i^ova iml ToidvTtiv IxovTa bqj there are really only two things: the idea, and the aA^Seiav. particular affected by the " presence " of or " participa- 28i J. €., the argument ex rStv ivavrCtav Ta ivavria, 70 E ff., tion " in the idea. How the idea can be at once in itself proves merely that the state of the soul after death is the and in the particular may be, as we have seen, a mystery, same as that before birth. The argument from irajinjo-w. But it does not justify the duplication of the idea, which is 73 ff., supplements this by the proof that before birth the a device employed here only, and presumably with full soul possessed intelligence. The final argument meets all consciousness, for the purpose of the argument. For by its 42 The Unity of Plato's Thought the immortality of soul, not of the individual. This Plato presumably knew, but we cannot expect him to say so by the death-bed of Socrates or in the ethical myths, which obviously assume individual immortality.'''* But neither this unavoidable funda- mental ambiguity nor the fanciful variations of the eschatological myths convict Plato of serious inconsistency, or supply any evidence for the dating of the dialogues. 2. In the Republic Plato bases the definitions of the virtues and the three classes of the population on a tripartite division of the soul, which he warns us is not demon- strated absolutely, but sufficiently for the purpose in hand.^'° A poetical passage of the tenth book hints that in its true nature the soul is one and simple, but that we cannot perceive this so long as, like the sea-god Glaucus, it is disguised by the accre- tions of its earthly life.^" The tripartite division is embodied in the myth of the PhcBdrus, which, if we pedantically press the poetical imagery ,'*' implies the pre- existence even of the appetites.^'' In the Timceus the immortal soul is created by the Demiurgus, the mortal, which falls into two parts, spirit and appetite, by his minis- ters.^" Here the tripartite division is subordinated to a bipartite, as Aristotle would have it.^"' But we are explicitly warned that the revelation of a god would be required to affirm the absolute scientific truth of this division, and to distinguish precisely the mortal from the immortal part.^''* In the Laws the question whether the dv/j.o'; is an affection or a distinct part of the soul is left open.'"" As Aristotle says, it makes no difference for ethical and political theory.^* The Phcedo, attempting to prove immor- tality, naturally dwells rather upon the unity of the soul, as does the tenth book of the Republic. But it distinguishes, quite in the manner of the Republic, the three types of character, the t' -. .0 n • . , . . - , ... does not admit death (while Ufe is present), (2) that which ^. l^.'^^' ^'"'^ ^' ^^' ^' °'°'' " '""' "''"l""' '"'^'" '^'""' " '' does not admit death at all. ^ * 38! Gorff., 524 ff.;iJep., 614 ff. Of. Laws, mBC; Tim., 292 72Di c/. PAvcr€i wepX to, toiv ttcivtodv crrot^^eta ireiTovdvla does not refer mainly or solely to our liability to error, as might be sup- posed from Campbell's "is naturally liable to the same infirmity," or from Jowett's "has the same uncertainty." It refers to the whole preceding comparison of which the starting-point is that the soul knows all things in a sense, even as the children know all their letters imperfectly. That this is the meaning of (jivaeu .... ireirovOvla appears further by comparison with Phcedrus, 249 E, "jraa-a fiev avOpayirov y^vxri (j>va-ei, redearat ra ovra. The doctrine of avdfivrjai<;, then, repeated in the Politicus, is not abandoned in the Philebus. This conclusion might have been affirmed a priori. For " recollec- tion," once indissolubly associated with the ideas and the pre-existence of the soul, would not be given up while they were retained. But pre-existence is assumed in the Laws,^' and the ideas, as we have seen, occur in the Politicus^^" and are reaffirmed in the TimcBus, which also implies the soul's prior knowledge of all things, in language recalling the Phcedrus and Politicus.'^^ h) The general problem of the relation of mind and body is involved in that of immortality and the parts of the soul. As we have seen, the Timceus, though it assigns separate seats to the mortal and immortal soul, declines to dogmatize without the assur- 305 277 D, Kivfivfeuet yap 7}fiwv CKOtrTos olov ovap ct£fa>9 airafTa 306 Meno^ 85 C, Sarirep ovap apri KeKLVTiVToi. al Bo^ai a^rat. a.i ira\i.v i>(T7rep vTrap ayvoeZv. RITCHIE, p. 143, misapprehends 307iJep«6., 402AB; cf Soph., 253A; Phileb., ISC; Thece- this passage when he associates it with the " lie of approxi- f^f 201 B* Tim. 48 B etc. mation.'^ We must nse examples, not because in difficult matters it is permissible to fall back upon "picture- thinking and symbolism," but because only by beginning with easy examples can we learn how to convert our dream- ^"*i ^*®' like knowledge into real knowledge. The yap introduces siogupra, p. 39. the whole parallel, of which the dreamlike knowledge of 311 41 E, t>|v toO iravTb? (Juffii- eStife all things is only the first point. 308 278 E, rexvjl yvj.ir.,v ivay.aiop.ivov, ivapyC, 816 Thecetet., 184 D. itttdirTeaBat, Ttiiv ovriav. The whole passage is in seeming con- „ „ „ „ tradictionwiththethonght of PAoedo.lOOA, andJJep.,473A, 3" TAecetet., 184 C ; Phcedo, 65 D, 79 C ; Tim., 67 B. ^^^^^ ^^^^^ (thought) come nearer to truth than deeds. See ns Phcedo, 65 C (cf. Theostet., 187 A), 66 A, eikiKpivel rg also Jfeno, 87B. SMvoCa; 67 C, t6 x^P'^e''' o " liiKurra iiro roB aii/iaTot rhv 825(Jrote, Jowett, Mr. Henry Jackson, and others. 'h'xvv. HOBN, who rejects the Philebus, says (p. 380) that it assigns 319 Thecetet., 179 C, to iraphv «a., 55 B, explicitly affirms that pleas- 442 A; Tim,, 64 A; Phileb., 41 C, to trUiia ^v to jrapexo/iei'oi'; ure is in the soul only: wit ovk aAoyo;' inTi. /j.riSei' iyaOhv elfoi. Rep,, 584 A, to ye ^5v ev ^XV yi-yyofievov; 442 A. .... it\i}v er i/'i'xn "at evTav9a ijSovtjv ij.6vov, 331 47 E-50D, 46C, 47 C D. 3^^Q&C,KaX yap iroKenov^ Koi araaets KaX ^a;^a; ovSel/ oAAo 332 46BC, 50 D. So Prodicus in ProtOff., 337 C. The irapexei i to o-ijia ical oi tovtou eiriSufiial. statement, Phileb,, 31 B, that pleasure and pain originate ^^^Phcedo, 94B ft.; Pep., 441 B, 390 D. Paul Shorey 47 Gorgias and "later" Philebus. One might as well argue that the tenth book of the Republic antedates or abandons the tripartite soul because the doctrine is ignored in the proof of immortality attempted there. c) Lastly it is sometimes affirmed that the later dialogues show an increased preci- sion in the use of psychological terminology. In fact, however, Plato's psychological vocabulary is nowhere technical. He is content to make his meaning plain by the context. Nor can we find in Spinoza or Kant or in any modern text-book the consist- ent precision that is sometimes demanded of Plato. There is no modern terminology which sharply discriminates mental states that are or are not supposed to involve the element of judgment and belief. There is none that shows independently of the context the precise line intended to be drawn between sensation and perception, or distinguishes revived and compounded "images" from "images" regarded as immediate impressions. We cannot, then, expect Plato to emphasize distinctions not needed for his immediate purpose, but if we bear this in mind, we shall find no serious inconsistencies or significant variations in his use of such terms as a'iaOqaL'i ho^a and M(Tdr](Tt.,UK; Charm., SMPhileb., 38E, koX Xoyos Si, yiyovtv oCtu! 'o totc Sdlai- 159 A. eicoAoCfie^. ,„„„ ,, , 3il Phileb., 38 D; Thecetet, 189 E, 190 A. Soph., 263 E, 33' Rep., 523 B, (is iitai-cos viro ttjs aiaOriireai Kpivonera. ■' '"">"•' "" . _ . ' , , Phileb., 38 C, 7roAAa«« Mpr. .... ^ovl^^eac Kpiv..v «v Jiwoi)- imKTiros S6(a. Tim., 11 B. In Thecetet., l&l A, So(aieiv is fl^^at ^dvoi- iyx"?"- almost the pure thought of Phcedo, 65 C. 3»5 533 D, ou irepi m6p.aTot i)i^il^oZ, Kal ni^i toI, tolovto,,. Soph.,26iA,iTav m Kae' airnv iv^ TO elSoiXov avToO, eto. "'^^ *'' '"''*^''«"' ""^ri rm TO ToiovTo.- ail 7ri»o! ; i. e. it is here not a memory image, but a percept accompanied by belief. 3^^ Phileb.^ 39 C, irept .... rSiv fteWovTutv; 40 A B, and the fantastic account of the functions of the Uyer, Tim., , , ^' ^"P^- ^^- ^enoe here 263 D, 4,avTa,rU, and Phileb., 71 A B. Grote, expecting the modern atomistic order : sen- ^ ^' *'""-»<"*«™ (= imagmations or imaged expectations) sation, image, idea, judgment, is surprised that in PhiUb., ^"^^ ^^^^ *° ^'i™i' *'^"*^ ^""i falsehood. Modern atomistic 39, memory and sensation first write \6yo, in the soul, and Psy^olosy sometimes conceiTes " images" as mere pictures that, secondly, a painter supervenes who paints images of i-^™!""? no affirmation or belief. Aristotle seems to ex- these Wyo. and the corresponding 6dfac. But it is charac- P^«^^ ^^^^ ™w ™ ^« Anima, 432a, 10, eVri «• i, ^.a^ra^U teristic of Plato to put the image after the idea, the word, ^"1""' *""■"' "»' «'""(>«<'""5- Bit in 428o, 12, thinking of and the judgment everywhere. Moreover, the images here P^"ebm, 40 A B, he says, ai «€ ■j.avraaia.K yCvovrai ai n\Uavt are not the primary images of perception, which are in- '''"' "'■ eluded in Plato's aIo-9rjavTa(7iav in Sophist, 260 E, as distinct faculties implies an advance on the Thecetetus. But the Thecetetus does not identify the words by using them once or twice as virtual synonyms. The Sophist, 264 A, temporarily distinguishes (jiavraaia as a judgment present to the mind, St' ato-^Tjff-em?,**' while Bo^a is a judgment, iv ^^vyri Kara Bidvoiau .... fier^ aiyri<;. But to press this would prove too much by distinguishing the Sophist from the late Philebus also. Lastly, Lutoslawski argues °*^ that the Phcedrus and Thecetetus are later than the Eepuhlic, because they familiarly employ BvvaiM<; in a sense first explained in Republic, 477 C. He overlooks Protag., 330 A, and the five occurrences of the word in Char- mides, 168, in a passage fully as metaphysical and abstract as that cited from the Republic. Indeed, the case cited from the Phcedrus, 246 D, irTepov Bvvani<;, is a mere periphrasis like ^ re toO vrepov va-i,i\oa-0(f>ia p,e0oBo<;, r) tSiv Xoycov Te^vrj, etc."' PAKT II The dialogues were composed in some order, and a study of their parallels, coinci- dences, or variations in thought will often seem to indicate the plausible, possibly the real, historic sequence. That is not the purpose of this paper. I wish to show (1) that our conception of Plato's philosophy is not appreciably affected by placing the dialectical dialogues — the Sophist, Politicus, Philebus, and possibly the Parmenides and Thecetetus — after, rather than before, the Republic; (2) that the evidence is at present insufficient to date the dialogues of the "earlier" and "middle" Platonism, and that, again, from the point of view of the interpretation of the content, it does not greatly matter. The chief value of such negative results is that the way to them lies through a further positive interpretation of Plato's true meanings. There are certain perennial puzzles of language or thought that present them- 360 Gors., 451 DE. " In earlier works Plato used the term soul as free from 361C/. Themtet.,mC; s«pm, p. 48, u. 350. every ambiguity. Here we see already a trace of doubts about the existence of the soul. He might as well say 362 Pp. 331, 396. that the existence of the soul is called in question by Crito, 363 Cf. the statement, p. 373, d, propos of the innocent 48 A, Uklvo 5 Tt ttot' co-tI, etc., or by Symp,, 218 A, riji' KapSiav phrase, Thecetet, 184 C, «t€ »^uxV "« o ti Bel Ka\eiv that: ij \l/vxhv yap ri 6 ti Ul bvofj-Mai. 50 The Unity op Plato's Thought selves to Plato in three forms: as mere eristic sophisms; as hindrances to a sound logical method; as serious problems of epistemology and metaphysics. They may be roughly enumerated as the problem of Being and not-Being, or the true nature of predication and negation; the antithesis in thought and things of the one and the many, the whole and the part, permanency and change, rest and motion ; the nature and possibility of real knowledge, and the meaning of consciousness of self. They are all directly or indirectly involved in the theory of ideas, but we may also study them in the group of dialogues in which they are most prominent. The Euthydemus presents a broad burlesque of all the chief sophisms of eristic. The Parmenides systematically exposes all the antinomies concerning the one and the many, the whole and the part, rest and motion, that can be deduced from the abuse of the ambiguity of the copula. The Thecetetus covers with persiflage the forms of eristic associated with one-sided theories of knowledge, especially materialism and extreme Heracliteanism, and makes a serious effort to solve the epistemological prob- lem. Here perhaps, and here only, does the Socratic avowal of perplexity express Plato's own state of mind. The Sophist makes explicit the lessons implied in the Parmenides and Thecetetus, and finally disposes of fourth-century eristic so far as it affects the presuppositions of practical logic and sound method. The Politicus applies the method of the Sophist to the definition of the true statesman, reaffirming from a different point of view, and perhaps with less confidence in the ideal, the chief doc- trines of the Republic. The Philebus restates the true logical method that emerges from eristic or metaphysical debate and applies it to the ethical problem of the summum bonum. We will begin with the Sophist, which contains the fullest exposition of method and the most explicit analysis of the fundamental eristic sophism. For our purpose there are three topics ; (1) the method of definition by dichotomy ; (2) the problem of Being and not-Being; (3) the logical and grammatical analysis of the sentence. 1. The formal dichotomies of the Sophist and Politicus lend these dialogues a very un-Platonic aspect. They may be said to be characteristic of Plato's "later" style, so far as this can be true of a feature that is less prominent in the Laws than it is in the Gorgias or Phcedrus. Their significance for Plato's later thought is very slight. To understand this we must distinguish the elaboration of a definition by successive dichotomies from the more general logical use of distinction, division, and classification. Aristotle is at great pains to prove that the method of dichotomy assumes and does not establish the definition.^ His criticism may have been needed against literal -minded pupils of the Academy. Plato obviously is amusing himself by playing with the method.'** He clearly recognizes that formally correct dichoto- mies may lead to half-a-dozen definitions of the same object.^" All depends upon the tact with which the original "one," the concept to be divided, is chosen,**' and the suj_nal.Pr.,31; Anal, Post., II, 5; Part. An., 1,2 B. 3&7 md., 232 B, aWi' axoAi/Sco/iev tv irpuroi' tUv irepi rot •'65 See BONITZ, pp. 180 ff. croi/mrTTjr €ipi]fi€viav. ev ydf> Tt jiioi /laAio-Ta KaT€av€Z TiVL KtiTai. with PoZif., 285 B, Sitw^opas .... inroaainep ef eiSecrt KcifTat; 580 D, SL^pi)Tat, Kara rpio elST], oi/Tto (eat ypvx^ .... Tpixs* 376 244 E, 253 C, 210 B, 271 D. 377 It is often affirmed (Jowett, Natorp, Jackson, Bury, etc.) that the method of the Philebus, Politicus, and Sophist is more advanced than that of the PhcedrtLS, in which " the complementary methods of generalization and division are applied merely to the discovery of Socratic definitions with a view to consistency in the use of debatable terms." Well, the. subject of the Phcedrus being the necessity of basing rhetoric upon definitions and dialectic, that point is naturally emphasized there (265 D, 'iv iKatnov opiCop-evot SrjtiOV iroijj, irepl 00 av del SlSatrKftv edf^j)). But all theories of a sharp distinction between the method of the Phcedrus and that of the "later" dialogues will only injure the scholarship of their propounders. The Phcedrus requires Tijv op.oiOTi)Ta Ttav ovTtav SiiiSivai (262 A; c/. Soph., 231 A, SeZ TTaVTUiV paKiaTa irepi Tas OfiOiOTtjTai iroieZadau Tljf i^vXaKiqv; Phileb., 13AB). To do this we must know o Jo-tiv tKoxnov tUv ovTioi/ (262 B). The method is twice described (265, 266, and 270 D). We must first reduce to unity Ta iroAAaxn Sieo^- 7ia.pp.iva. (265 D; cf. Phileb., 16 D, aei piav iUav irepl irafToi endffTOTe flejiei-ovt itfTeZv; cf. 26 D). This Unity we are to divide icaT ap9pa n TivKt (265 E; cf. Po!i«., 262, and with xaTay^vVai cf. Polit, 287 C, 265 D, icaTaflpaueii') and subdivide (266 A, TtpLvaiv oiiK eirafij/te), distinguishing and following up separately the right- and left-hand paths (266 A, Sejii .... dpUTTcpa; cf. Soph., 264 E, TTopeiieirSai icaTa Toiirl Se|la del (lepos TOU T)jr|W>'TO!), till the object of our search and of our praise 52 The Unity of Plato's Thought what seems to us the purely logical treatment of the ideas as conceptual genera and species, the Phcedrus pictures the prenatal vision of them; the Republic announces the most naive realism with regard to any and every universal; and the Timceus sol- emnly reaffirms their objectivity.'" In the face of these facts, it is impossible to maintain that the dichotomies of the Sophist are evidence of a later doctrine in which the transcendental or naively realistic idea is discarded for the genera and species of conceptual logic. The emphasis and center of interest may shift from dialogue to dialogue — the doctrine remains the same. But the opposition between the two points of view cannot be denied or disguised. The noumenal idea is one. But not only as reflected in things, butjsjubdiyidedJby- logic, it is many. By a natural and inevitable metaphor both Plato and Aristotle speak of particulars and lower species as parts of the higher conceptual whole to which they are subordinated. By the theory of ideas, as we have said, each of these parts, every subordinate concept, is an idea, not only the summum genus and the lowest species, as animal and dog, but the intermediate groups, mammal and quadruped, etc. The Aristotelian objection that the one dog will thus embody a whole series of ideas we have dismissed with the metaphysics of the subject. The relation of the particular to the idea is a mystery. And once we have accepted the metaphors "presence," "participation," "pattern," a number of ideas can be reflected by or present in one thing as easily as can one idea. But the elaboration of logical and scientific classification brings up the difficulty in a new and more specific form less easily evaded. For the theory of ideas any and every subordinate group apprehended as a conceptual unit by the mind is an idea."' For sound logical and scientific classification only true genera and species are ideas — not necessarily "true species" in the sense of the mod'fern naturalist, but in the sense of the Platonic logic; that is, classes and groups based on significant and relevant distinctions. From the one point of view we expect every part to be an idea ; from the other, Plato explicitly warns us against mistaking for true ideas what are mere frag- ments or parts. ^^ His embarrassment shows that he felt the difficulty. Sound and blame is found (266A; cf. Soph., 235C, iwdKoXovOelv etc.; PoUt., 285A, etc.; Laws, 894AA, 963D, 965C. Each aiiTtZ SuLLftovvTa? , . . . emairep av At)(^0^). He who can thus dialogue brings out some aspect of it less emphasized in look 615 If Kol ewl iToXXa. is a dialectician {266 B C ; cf. Par- the others. We cannot expect Plato to repeat himself men., 132 A, Mta Tiff laiot SoKeZlSea elvai eirl iravra iSovTLf Soph., verbatim. But these variations have little or no signifi- 235 C, TTjv Ttiiv ovTai 8vvafj.dviav ixerUvat, Koff iKoxna. Te Kal ejrt cance for the evolution of his thought. iravTa ^e'^oSoy) . Again, looking at it from the point of view 375 ^y^^y^^ p 35 u 238 * d S7 u 256 of science rather than of rhetoric and dialectic (270), the object of investigation is either simple or manifold. If ^'">Bep., 596 A., 479 D; Soph., 225 C, ravra iiriov ^iv elSo?, it has many cISt), we must enumerate them (270 D, raCra ipi9- «"•«'»•«/> aurb SUyvmntv is irepov iv 6 Advos, irap eirai^v^ia? liTimJ-ifcvi; Cf. Phileb., 16 D, V" «" tis tov ipLBftov avroi o"" viv v^' ii^liv -nixtlv ofior. PAtJeft., 18 C D, the Stir^ds of Trai-Ta Kartfj) tov ij.tTa(v toO ijreipov re «al tov enjs), and treat association in our minds makes a unity, and hence an idea each subordinate ev (cf. Phileb., 16 D, Kat rStv iv iiteivtav sKa- ^^ ypa-fifiariKj]. tmv iraXii/ ilo-avToij) as we do the original unity — i. e., study 380 PoUt., 287 C, implied " already " in Phoedr., 265 E ; its potentialities (5uVa/xi9, active or passive; cf. Soph., c/. Polii., 262 B.aAAa to /Ac'pos ajuta elSos exeroj. We are more 247 DE) in relation to other things. Rhetoric is a special likely to "meet with ideas" if we bisect the universal psychological application of this general scientific method. (fiKroTojieiK) and proceed by successive dichotomies, than if It is one method which is described in Phxzdr., 265, 266, we attempt to separate the ultimate species at once. Cf. 270D; Phileb.,Vo-l%; Cratyl.,i2AC; Soph., 226C, 2350,253, the insistence on ra >i.eo-a in PMJeh., 17 A. Paul Shoeet 53 method required him to emphasize the distinction. But he was quite unable to define its nature.^' The nominalistic logic of the modern "flowing philosophy" of evolution would meet the problem by making both "true species," and the tentative species of imperfect or erroneous generalization alike relative to the purposes of man — working hypotheses, instruments of greater or less precision and range, employed by thought in the effort to shape in its own image or check for its own ends the ever-flowing stream of change. Plato would have preferred mystery and self-contradiction to this as an ultimate philosophy. But his logical practice approaches nearer to it than does any interme- diate compromise of common-sense from Aristotle to the nineteenth century. Psycho- logically and ontologically all universals, as opposed to sensations and images, are equally noumenal ideas, whether language provides a name for them or not.'*^ In logical and scientific practice the only ideas worth recognizing, whether named or not, are those that embody significant distinctions relevant to the purpose in hand.^^ The recognition that words are mere counters'** and do not always stand for (relevant) ideas ''^ is an apparent, but not real, contradiction of the abbreviated formula of the Republic that we assume an idea for every word.*'* Similarly, as we have already seen, the occasional and inevitable use of conceptual language is no derogation from Plato's philosophic realism.'*' Practical logic and psychology must treat ideas as con- cepts, whatever else or more they may be. 2. The puzzle that false speech and erring opinion are impossible because we cannot say or opine that which is not, is nothing, must be translated into Greek to win even a semblance of seriousness. To appreciate Plato's achievement in disposing of it forever we must have studied it in the poem of Parmenides and in the eristic of the fourth century.''* Our problem here is the seeming contradiction between the Republic and the Sophist. The Republic distinctly avers that it is impossible even to opine that which is not — thus apparently yielding to the fallacy."' The admirable analysis of the Parmenides and the Sophist explains it by pointing out that is, in its double function of copula and substantive verb, is ambiguous,"" and that this ambiguity extends to the convenient Greek idiomatical use of the parti- 381 Polit.t 263 A B, to distinguish genus (or species) and 386 59$ A. The common name of n-oAAa does imply a con- part would require a long discussion. He can only say ceptual ev, which implies an idea, though it may not be that, while every species is a part, every part is not a relevant or worth while (afioi- eiru>'U|ni'a!) for the classifica- species (elfios). tion or purpose in hand. 382 Supra, p. 37, n. 250. 387 E. g., Phcedr., 263 D E, iivayKairev ^jiSs inoXafic'iv .... 383J2ep., 445 0,544 AD, 17 riva aAXijv ex«« iSiav iroXiTeitts, gy yt jSiv ovTutv, etc.; Folit.^ 258 C, 5vo cIStj BiavorjQ^vai 7r}V ^Tts Kal €V eiSei Stai^avet Ttvl KEiral; Tim.t 83 C, €ts n-o\Aa /itt- tpyx^iv ijtiSiV jroi^o-at; Phileb,^ 18 C D, 23 E, vo^ffat, n-fl jroTe ^v KoX avoiioia pAejrctv, opal' 6« €v avToU ev yeVoff kvhv a^iov CTTiuru- aVTtov fv Kal iroXXi eKarepov, See SUpra^ p. 39, n. 264. ,.;«; Soph., 229 D, y.vajxo" a.a.>e^.v a^«. e^..vv^i«; 223 A, ^^j g^^ ^ j ^^j Xjj ^^ g ^^^ ^^, ^^ 225 C, 267 D, names for ideas often fail because the ancients „ „ were neglectful of t^s tS>v yevuv Kar elSij 5iatpe(rccu9. Polit,, ZeOE, aviiwiiov . . . . ivoita irepov airroi! TTapoiX'^priirai'Tti ee(reai. 389 478 B. Cf. Parmen., 132 B C, 142 A, 164 A, 166 A; Tiya; 261 E, to /iij airovSaiciv ejrl Toil oi/d/iao-i, 263 C. Thecetet., 167 A, 188 D. 384 "Already," Charm., 163D; Polit,, 261E; Thecetet,, 390 pormen., 142 C, "vf ie ovk aiirri iij''e0a iv rots Xo'7oi9.*"° And when he yields, Socrates commends him on the ground that this is not the place to argue the question.*"' There is a further anticipation of the Sophist in the suggestion that those who insist on the quibble are oyjniMaOei'}.*^ 391 It is tme that Plato nowhere states the ambignity most effective analysis of the fallacy in the form in which of the copula with the explicituess of Aristotle and John Greek usage presented it. Plato is, for the rest, aware of Stuart Mill. But the passages cited in the preceding note the distinction between contradictory and contrary op- prove that he understood it perfectly. Grote, in his criti- position (Symp.^ 201 E; Farmen.^ 160BC; Soph., 25TB, ovk cism of the Sophist, objects (1) that Plato fails to distin- dp', evavriav orai' dlrdt^atrts Ae'yijrat tnjftalvetv trvyxupijirofieBa), guish €' is not to be pressed here, religious or ontological associations which half playfully, half seriously, he was resolved to preserve for tlvai. to tirj 393 Euthyd., 283, 285 A. iv, besides its ontological meaning, can be naturally used ^^ 286 C, where, as in the Themtet, it is attributed to in Greek idiom as a mere category embracing all particular Protagoras with a malicious aUusion to iA^Seia. cases of (o) negative predication, (b) misstatement. Any 395 429 B ; c/. Hipp, ma/or, 284 E; J/jtios, 314 D ff. particular /i-ij ov is something other than the corresponding 396 429 D. ov ; and, generalizing, Plato may say that ni ov is the other „, , . . , ^ „ , „„ „ ' , . .^, ^. , . i, ... • it 11. . I, 1 1 397,oni((oTe))Oi (levo Aoyos 1, itaT e(ie, etc.: C/. SopA., 239B. of the ov without implying that it IS the other of absolute aogioiP v^., v.uviy«., ioox.. Being. For the same reason, in explaining the nature of error and misstatement, he is justified in substituting for '" *30 D, eirl Se Tolt i^ojiao-i Trpbs riZ op6r,v Kal iAi,9^. the general category jii) ov a concrete (affirmative) mis- *™ 430 D. 401 431 a. statement, " Theaetetus flies." It all sounds crude enough, *oa 433 A, fidf ai/iev avT^ rjj aAijdei^ ovtw n-ws ikuKv^ivat, oi/iiot- if we think it only through English idiom. But it was the Tepoi' toC Scoi-toi. Cf. Soph., 251 B, 259 D. Paul Shoeey 55 It is obvious (1) that the fallacy is none to Plato ; (2) that he feels himself able to carry the analysis farther; (3) that he does not do so because he wishes to write the Cratylus, not the Sophist. In the Theoetetus the matter is somewhat more complicated. As we shall show more fully below, the object of the Thecetetus is not to refute or analyze the logical fallacy that false opinion is impossible, but to explain the psychological nature of error, and with it of cognition: ti ttot' earl tovto to ird6o<; Trap' ^fiiv ical riva rpoTrov iyyiyv6fievov.*°^ For this the /Mr) 6v quibble would have been wholly unfruitful. But it could not be altogether ignored. Hence it is perfunctorily dismissed in a page with the admission that the method of elvat and iirj etvai offers no explanation of error, since 6 Bo^d^mv ev ti 8of afet, and o firjSev So^d^cov to irapdirav oi/Se fio^a^et.™ We are thus left free to pursue the psychological analysis kuto, to elSevai koX p^r). But it is absurd to suppose that Socrates is really baffled in the Thecetetus by a fallacy at which he laughs in the Euthydemus and Cratylus. And his real opinion of it is sufficiently indicated by his attribution of it to Protagoras in this very dialogue."^ The final analysis of the fallacy in the Sophist is introduced and accompanied by persiflage in the manner of the Euthydemus and Cratylus, and by hints that it is a mere eristic puzzle.*" The final common-sense formula that true speech and opinion represent to, ovtu oj? e^ei or w? eVrt is not new.*"' It evades the psychological prob- lems of the Thecetetus, and it is reached by arguments purely logical and practical. If we do not admit that prj 6v normally means otherness rather than non-existence, we shall make all rational speech and thought impossible.*™ The absolute 6v (and pr} 6v) of the Parmenides to which no intelligible predicates attach is reserved for ontology and mysticism.*"' But iv rot? irap fjplv X6yoi<} (251 D) we must accept a doctrine of mixed and relative Being and not-Being.*'" The result of the inquiry is that, if Plato in the Republic falls into this fallacy, the Republic must be earlier and less mature, not only than the Sophist, but than the Euthydemus and the Cratylus. But Plato does not yield to the fallacy in the Repub- lic. He merely varies his terminology to suit his theme. He needs the transcendental absolute Being for the world of ideas as opposed to the world of sense, for the sym- bolism of the idea of Good, the image of the sun, the cave, and the conversion from the shadows to the realities. It would have been singularly tactless to preface these passages with an explanation that ov, like pf) 6v, is a relative term, and that all ovtw with which human logic can deal are likewise p-q ovtu. There is no occasion for the ovra and p^ oma of practical logic here. Absolute not-Being is consigned to total ^^ 187 D. ^* 188, 189 A. 407 263 B, Aeyei fie a.VTu>v o fikv aAi)di}s tol ovra ws eo-Tt irepl trov. *05 In Socrates 's ironical defense of uUra-Protagorean- Qf.Cratyl.,dS5'B,osavTa.6vTa\€yT[ibi^e| ' eAeyJas r, mW' "'P i^i . . . . iroAai KoX Ta vvv rimu^ivov av tvpoi irepl rhv To5 /<,), -^ iSui-aTB, KtKTiav ual ««V(j. icaOairep iifjiclt, etc., 260 A. Si-TO! eAeyxoi', etc.; c/. 242A, 243AB, 252C. Note also the laovanv t to close parallelism of this part of the Sophitt with the inten- 258 E ; c/. snpra, p. 39. tional fallacies of the Ponncntdes, infra, pp. 58, 59. 4io 251 A, 254 C D, 259 A B. 56 The Unity of Plato's Thought ignorance as it is in the Sophist.*" Pure Being is reserved for the ideas, as it is in the Timceus, which was written at a time when the results of the Sophist were cer- tainly familiar to Plato. Its antithesis, the world of phenomena, is described as tum- bling about between Being and not-Being — as a mixture of the two; the things of sense are always changing — they are and are not.*" It is not necessary to dash the spirit of mystic contemplation and enthusiasm by the reminder that the ideas them- selves, when drawn down into the process of human thought, move to and fro and partake of both Being and not-Being."' We are concerned here only with the broad contrast between the two worlds. To say that the objects of sense and the notions of the vulgar tumble about between Being and not-Being, is merely another way of saying that they belong to the domain of the mixed or relative Being and not-Being described in the Sophist."* Only a deplorably matter-of-fact criticism can find in this adapta- tion of the terminology to the immediate literary purpose a concession to a fallacy ridiculed throughout the dialogues. And the arguments that would prove the results of the Sophist unknown to the author of the Republic would apply almost equally to the Timceus; for there, too, Plato calmly reinstates the absolute ov which the Sophist banishes from human speech as no less contradictory than the absolute /xi) ov, and treats as an inaccuracy the expression to /xtj- ov jxt) ov ehai, the practical necessity of which the Sophist demonstrates."^ Yet the treatment of the "same" and the "other" in the ■^^vyp'^ovia (35) proves that the analysis of the Sophist was familiar to the author of the Timceus. 3. The explicit discrimination of ovo/Mara as names of agents and of pij/iara as names of actions is peculiar to Sophist, 262. So the special definition of Btdvoia is confined to the Republic,*^'' and nearly every dialogue employs some definition or distinction which Plato does not happen to need again. Even if we concede that this greater explicitness of grammatical and logical analysis marks the Sophist as late, its significance for the development of Plato's thought is slight. It is not repeated in the Politicus or Laws,*" and it is virtually anticipated in the Cratylus, where it is twice said that Xoyo'; is composed of prifiaTa and ovofiaTa.*^^ It is barely possible, but not necessary, to take prifiara here in the sense of "expression" or "phrase." Even then it must include the verb. For ovo/jia is plainly used in the sense of "name" or "noun." Lutoslawski's argument"' that "it would be unjustifiable to apply to the Cratylus a definition given only in the Sophist," obviously begs the question. The expression (425 A), Kal cruWo/Sa? av crvvTi0evTe •■ - ■ • /o\ J.^ The5 oioiMevot Ta iiei' taTavat, Ta >-« .,... .-* , . „ - . ,. T.1 i , 1 • • * ii. Ml? o**, orav tmn tv ci /atj effTt, Kai iiTU€y o Aevet (cf. Soph., Sj (cii-eiffSai Tioi' ovTii)!', show Plato's real opinion of these oi.-,t>\ ■«.n-c t - 7- • •- ■ T, \ j.'^^±--., absolute antinomies; c/.SppA., 249 CD. For the negation „.' .,,' ^~ ' ^ ... '^ . . ■ ■ • • i^ \ . ,, . ^ IT -Li J- i ^ 1JO A ici -D n 1. «jo ^ iroAAbtv oufiei' KWAvet. From this OVffiaff ucrevetl' and then of all intelligible predicates cf. 142A, 164B Soph., 248C; , , . j j j t ,n^ ,00,-. ^. t- . - „, " _. ,_„v, T I ii D J Tts eii'ou MOV are deduced; confro (7) 163 C, Ti>i«/ii)«(7Tii/ ... . Tfterefef., 157 B. In general the Parmenides exemplmes , , .,, ..... , , / . ,, . ,,,«,- ..i mew ' c ox *P* ^^ T' ^^o cnj^ati-et jj ovo-iac aTrovo'iai'; (cf. Ae., Met, what the Sop/wet terms, 245 E, T0U5 .... «i Tav akkav, etc. f„. (y_ Soph., 245, 256 D E, 258 D E. Cf. Euthyd., 284 A, iv fL^v KaKelvo y eo-Ti Tii- Sxtmi-, 6 Wy" HI 144 E, oO liovov ipa. TO if ev iroXAa effTiK aWa Kal aiiTo to xVs f"" i^^". TftecBte*., 205 C, SioTi avro itaS' auTo «a(7Tov .^ ^^.^ ^^. .^^^^ Siavey€pir,pii>'ov; cf. USA. Republic, 525E, e'lT) iavvBerov, Kal ovSi to eli/a. irepi auTov 6p»i! ex"' irpoo-^epowa however, points out that thought must restore the abstract €itrely. Another form of this fallacy, irSi/ iirb iravriK x<»p'fe'^, unjty ^g f^gt as analysis divides it : iM' iav av KepnaTiiiji appears in the Protagorean doctrine: Cratyl., 385E, iSi? ^^^.^^ Utlmi iro^XairXoffioSaiy, eiXa^ovjievoi p.-f, irort ifavf to iv auTii- ii oidia elvai Uaarif, Thecetet., 166 C, Uiai oiir9i)v yiyvovrai. Absolutism, whether sensational or ^^^ Parmenides, cf. Soph., 258 D. verbal and ideal, destroys rational thought, and is refuted ^^^ ^^ ^^ ,^^ .^^^^^ ^,_^^^ Tb ^), 5^ . . . . «al lap.tv o Xeyei. by pushing it to the extreme where this is apparent. ^^ ^^^ ^^ ^^ ^^ ^^^^ 255 A B. 440 137 C - 142 A. Similar results follow for tIAXo from ^ jgj A, Ser ipa airh SeapLov ixtiy to5 p.ri elvai Tb elxai p.r, iv. taking tv \v ep/irpoa-dev ae\ pr)6evra>v irXdvrjv. In view of these facts, it is idle to attempt to date the Parmenides and the Sophist by their philosophical content. The substantial identity of doctrine does not, of course, exclude many minor differences in the literary form and the secondary pur- poses of the two dialogues. One object of the Parmenides, for example, is to illus- trate exhaustively the " both and neither " of the eristic caricatured in the Euthydemus. The absolute hypotheses issue in blank negation. In order to make the " both and neither" plausible, some reasoning from the absolute point of view is introduced into the relative hypotheses. *'' Again, it is not easy to say how much importance Plato attached to the third division of the argument in which the contradictions of the first two hypotheses, and, by implication, of all the others, are resolved. Contradictory predi- cates (the "both") can be true simultaneously — they belong to different times. The "neither" belongs to the instantaneous moment of transition, the "sudden" which is outside of time altogether."^ It would be possible to read a plausible psychological meaning into this ingenious solution of the Zenonian problem of change.*" But it cannot easily be translated into the terminology of the theory of ideas. Pure Being admits of neither of the contradictory predicates, and the ideas as noumena are out- side of space and time. But the "one" which is here spoken of as out of time, and without predicates at the moment of transition, is apparently not the idea, but any one thing which may participate in the ideas. This consideration, and the fact that the i^aLvrj'; is never mentioned again, seem to indicate that it was only a passing fancy. Lastly, though the main object of the dialogue is the illustration of the ambi- guity of the copula, and the fallacy of isolating the ideas, the one is in some passages a representative of the Platonic idea, and in others of the absolute Being which ontology and mysticism recognize even after its banishment from logic. This explains and partly justifies the interpretations of the neo-Platonists and that of Zeller already considered; but does not necessitate any serious qualification of that here proposed.*** THE POLITICUS The Politicus quotes the Sophist,*^^ and is closely related to the Timceus and the Laws. Its style and its tone of "mixed pathos and satire""' in the reluctant aban- donment of impracticable ideals*^' mark it as probably late. But there is nothing in the thought to necessitate or strongly confirm this view.*'' It cannot be shown that Zeller, Grote, or, more recently, Pohlman**' are led into error in the interpretation of the thought by their assumption that it precedes the Bepublic, and the attempts of «i B. ff., in 149 E-150 the denial of communion between *54 Supra, p'. 34. *55 257 A, 266 D, 284 B, 286 B. the ideas : oiSi rt eo-rot tr/iiitpbi' itAtji' avT^j n)5 aun) i^uffi! aroiros Tts eyKa97)Tai 158 For the theory of ideas and iva/xvijo^is, cf. supra, fitra^v T^S KtvrjtTeia^ Kal trTatrtwq, ec xp6v, 287 C, 281 CE, etc., and in the Timceits, 46 C, and nowhere 471284D, it apa iiyryriov ijioi'iot, etc. Phoedo, 77 A, tit ri else, proves nothing. A periphrasis is used tor the idea in o/wius elvai, etc. Tim., 51 D. 62 The Unity of Plato's Thought been misunderstood.*" It is implied in the doctrine of ideas,*" in Plato's polemic against mere relativity,"* and even in the remark attributed to Prodicus in Phcedrus, 267 B, avTo<; . . . . &v Bei Xdyav re')(vqv' helv Bk ovre ixaKpmv oire ^paxecav, aWd fjuerplmv. The fact that it is explicitly stated "for the first time" in the Politicus proves no more than does the fact that it is never stated again. Plato happened to formulate it only once, but it is clearly involved in Republic, 531 A, aWijXot? avafierpovvTei, etc. The myth may be profitably compared with the Timoeus, Philebus, and Laws, but cannot be pressed to yield developments or contradictions of doctrine. Its service to the argument is merely to distinguish the mythical ideal of a shepherd of the people, who plays providence to his flock, from the modem ruler who leaves other specialists to feed, clothe, and house them, and confines himself to his specific task of govern- ment.*" In other words, it emphasizes the demand often repeated in Plato for a precise definition of the specific function and service of the royal or kingly art ; and, as Zeller says, rejects with a touch of irony ideals drawn from a supposed state of nature. This ruler is further discriminated, as in the Euihydemus and Gorgias,"' from the pretenders or subordinate ministers who usurp his name, the rhetorician,*" the general,*'* the dicast.*" Lastly, his special task is defined. As implied in the Meno and Euthydemus, and stated in the Republic, he is to teach virtue and incul- cate right opinion.**" And that his teaching may be effective and the seed fall in good ground, he is, like the rulers of the Republic and the Laws, to control marriages and the propagation of the race — especially with a view to harmonizing and blending the oppositions of the energetic and sedate temperaments.**' The accompanying classification and criticism of forms of government imply no change of opinion unless we assume that Plato was bound to repeat himself verbatim. The classification of the Republic is first the ideal state governed by philosophic wis- dom, whether ^aa-iKeia or apiaTOKparia,^'^ and then in progressive decadence timarchy, oligarchy, democracy, tyranny. The Politicus apparently recognizes seven states : one, the right state (302 C), the only Polity deserving the name (293 C), in which the rulers are e-maTrjp.ove';. Six others are obtained by distinguishing the good and bad forms of the three types recognized in ordinary Greek usage. *** We thus get monarchy or royalty, and tyranny, aristocracy, and oligarchy, and democracy, lawful and law- less.*** The differences are due mainly to the necessity of presenting a continuous i'ii E.g., by Siebeok, Untersuchungen nur Phil, d. *'9 305B. Griechen, pp. 92 ff., who over-emphasizes the analogies with 450 309 D the ircpo! of the Philebus. ' ,„_^ , . „„, . T. X ft ,. , *" 309, 310. The ieeiwWic recognizes the control of mar- 473The ^«Tpco„ Y..e,r.5 284ABto which every artist ^age, 460, and the importance and difflcnlty ot recon- looks, is virtually the idea which he tries to realize, <,iii„g tj^^t^o temperaments. 503 C. It does not happen Gorg., 503 E. t^ ^^.j^g jj^^ ^^^^ j^^^^ together. The Laws, 773 A B, does. "*Cf'rphj iAA,Aa four times in 283, 284 with The,Btet., 482445 D. It cannot be a democracy, because *>Wo*o. 160B,182B,Porme».,164C. _ _ ^^-^^^ iSvWror tlva. = Polit., 292 E, m»i' oiv iowl 475 274, 275. *76 Gorg., 517 B, 521 T}, wA^Ods ye ev iroAet TavTriP ry]v iirtar^fxriv Swarhv elvai KTntraff&tu, «'304D, £««Aj/dem., 289DE. Cy. Gorp., 464-6, 502 E. 433 iJep., 338 D. Pindar., Pj/i oi', the crepoi' of the Sopftiat, the matter or space of comparative degree, rh ii.a\K6v re ital !ittov, Phileb,, 24 ; and the Timcetis, the principle of necessity or evil, and the many minor examples, Polit., 279, 280, 289. ne'ya /cni (xiicpdi/. More precisely (p. 89), the oVeipoi' is the 601 ScHNELDEE, p. 133, and Siebeck, p. 73, make it a mediating link between the Oirepov of the Sophist and the mediating principle between the idea and phenomena. x^P" of the Timceus. Now these terms undoubtedly have But Platonever speaks of the "idea," but only of the ideas this in common, that they are variously opposed to the or the idea of something, nipas is itself an idea and is the ideas, but Plato employs them in different connections and cause of limit, in any given case, precisely as the idea of we cannot equate them. Siebeck argues (pp. 58 ff.) that whiteness is the cause of white, or the idea of dog the the absolute (i>i ov abandoned in the Sophist (258 E) must cause of a dog. mean something. He finds it in the absolute hypothesis of Paul Shoeet 65 physical and chemical "process," as opposed to ideally or mathematically defined "states." ^ (4) The insatiate, limitless character of undisciplined desire and appetite — a conception which we have met in the Gorgias.^ The fUKTov is the mixture or union of 7repai'.,i^u,m\j. jj 261.) 610 In SOD the /StwriXi/tijK 'fnixn", etc., = the soul of the SrEBECK then proceeds to associate the logical i-nupav world, and the airias Sivay.iv = the Demiurgus. and the Bartpor with space and to attribute to Plato an "' Cf. Idea of Good, pp. 188, 189, n. 2. " intelligible " as well as a phenomenal space by pressing E12 Schkeideb identifies God not with the Idea of Good, all passages in which the logical relations of concepts are but with the ideas. The ideas, he argues, must be real and expressed in spatial terms (p. 90). As the human mind they must be thoughts. They are, therefore, thoughts of naturally thinks logical determinations in spatial im- God. We have already considered this theory, sMpra, p. 38. agery, he has no difficulty in finding such passages. But It is for the modem systematic philosopher the most plainly the method is vicious. We cannot infer an Intel- plausible escape from the difficulty of positing two dis- ligible " space " or the identity of Sartpov and space tinct noumena, God and the Ideas. Perhaps Plato would because the ideas are spoken of as '^living apart," or have accepted it, if it had been presented to him. Unlike " included" in a larger idea, or because the method of the majority of its advocates, Schneideb does not misin- dichotomy proceeds to the right and leaves on the left the terpret particular passages in order to support it. He other of the particular idea pursued. Still less c£in we merely combines and equates lines of thought which Plato infer it from the vtntrot ro-nat, or from the fact that move- left unfinished and distinct. 66 The Unity of Plato's Thought Philebus, and seen that neither contradicts or appreciably modifies the doctrine of the earlier dialogues."' There remains only the question whether the demonstration of the unreality of pleasure presupposes, or, as Zeller still maintains, is presupposed by, the shorter proof of the Republic. Believing that the Philebus is probably late, I am logically committed to the first branch of the alternative. But this opinion is entirely compatible with the view that the difiPerences between the two treatments of the theme are not in themselves sufficient to show which must be the earlier. It is impossible to determine a priori whether the slighter treatment is an anticipation or a r6sum6 of the fuller discussion. The main doctrine was always a part of Plato's thought, as appears from the Gorgias, the Phcedo, and the Phcedrus."* The differences between the Bepublic and the Philebus have been much exaggerated. The abbreviation of the argument in the Republic is sufficiently explained by the subordinate place which it occupies in the scheme of the entire work. It affords no proof of the date, and no presumption even of a change of doctrine."^ THE THE^TETUS The date of the Thecetetus has been much debated on external grounds.'" Its wealth of thought and dramatic vivacity of style make it one of the most difficult dialogues to classify. In psychological depth and dialectical acuteness it ranks with the Sophist, Philebus, and Parmenides, many of the thoughts of which it anticipates or suggests.'" But it has nothing of their dogmatic finality of manner. Socrates is still the midwife delivering ingenuous youth of opinions which fail to stand the test of the elenchus. And the conclusion is an avowal of Socratic ignorance. ''* Before losing ourselves in details we must recall why this is so. There are two reasons: (1) The formal quest for an absolute definition always fails in Plato."' (2) It is not possible to define knowledge or explain error. We can only describe and classify different stages of cognition and various forms of error. All seemingly intel- ligible explanation rests on material images, like Plato's figure of the wax tablets and the aviary. But these analogies either commit us to sheer materialism and the flowing philosophy, or they explain nothing. No spatial image can represent the synthetic 513 Supra, pp. 24, 43, 45 ff. that the Bepublic is not yet acquainted with the thought ^^^ Supra, p. 24. that the neutral state implies not absolute quiet in the ■ina ^nr.nn Kjo rri, f I, iv, 1 body, but slight motions which do not cross the threshold »i» See Zellee, p. 548. The question whether pleasure , . Tii^vit ti-- i-j.„ ^^ . . • ... J ,„ cnj!T>\ A I. %. o or consciousness. But the thought is implied in ifec. Of. or pofri) ox quibble, 167 A. Qf. problem of ifrevSiit Sofa and the psychological analysis that "v^-''^ j e, »i j oocri prooioiiiuir " .,,. -I, .1 „ „.„„n„„ ,.c„it supra, n. 405, and j;«{fti/dem., 286 C. it provokes. It is a "digression" and a negative result j- 1 • only for those who naively assume that Plato himself ei- 629 See Natoep's acute Forschungen zur Geschichte des pected to reach a positive definition. Erkenntnissproblems im AUerthum, and his "Protagoras 622184CD 200AB. und sein Doppelgftnger," Philologus, Vol. L, pp. 262 S. 623Sitpra,'p.34,n.283. Cf. Theaitet.,\HG S. UptolSSC Natoep's analyses. retain their value, even if we doubt the identity of iiT^iT-i,y.-r, and atcrSijo-it is refuted only so far the possibUity of reconstructing»Protagoras. For Antis- as it depends on extreme Protagorean relativity or Hera- thenes and the TheiBtetus see the phantastic conjectures of cliteanism, which makes all thought and speech impossible. Joel, Der echte urui der xenophontische Sokratet, Vol. II, Kara y€ TJjy tov Ttavra Ktxclo-Oat ttido^ov. PP- °^ "• 68 The Unity of Plato's Thought practical tendency of the age repugnant to Plato's taste and feeling; This seems to be overlooked in the controversy between Natorp (Philologus, 50) and Gomperz, as to the meaning of the formula. Plato, as Natorp shows, explicitly affirms the thought to be: things are to (each and every) man as they appear to him. If sugar tastes bitter to the sick man, it is bitter to him — there is no other test. But there is no evidence and no probability that Protagoras had systematically drawn out the consequences of generalizing this proposition in its application to ethical and logical truths. He did not need to ask himself whether he meant by dvdpanro^ this, that and the other man, or human cognitive faculties in general. He took ovra, as he found it in Greek idiom, without distinguishing things, qualities, and truths — though his simplest examples would naturally be qualities. By o>? he presumably meant "that," but "that" and "how" are closely associated in Greek idiom and are often confounded in popular not to say in Platonic usage. If he used ^aiverai and {ftavraa-ia he probably did not distinguish the "it seems to me" of actual. sensation from the "it seems to me" of any opinion,^*' and Plato avails himself of the ambiguity for the half serious •jrepiTpoiri] that since Protagoras's "truth" does not seem true to the majority, it is admitted by Protagoras himself to be oftener false than true.'^' ndvra pel Plato himself accepts for the phenomenal world."' As a metaphysical dogma it is tantamount to materialism in that all materialists are more or less con- sciously Heracliteans, though all Heracliteans need not be materialists.''' As a neo- Heraclitean paradox it is the negation of the ideas, of the universal, of rational logic and speech.^'* As a rhetorical formula it is the symbol of the restless spirit of innova- tion which Plato detested.''" Before generalizing and restating for serious refutation what he conceives to be the common psychological presuppositions of these catchwords, Plato covers them with persiflage and assails them with arguments which he admits to be rhetorical and eristic. There is no probability that the representatives of these doctrines could have explained their meaning or defended themselves as well as Plato has done it for them. So far as we know, he is the first thinker who was capable of distinguishing, dividing, classifying, and generalizing ideas, of noting the affinities and differences of philosophic doctrines, and of translating them freely into different terminologies. All other early thinkers, like the majority of thinkers always, are the prisoners of their formulas and can only aboimd in their own sense. Plato, as Emerson says, "needs no barbaris war paint, for he can define and divide," and he delights to prick with the keen point of his dialectic the bubbles of imagery, rhetoric, and antithesis blown by his predecessors. Heraclitus means well when he says that the one is united by disimion,"° or that the hands at once draw and repel the bow."' But the epigram vanishes under logical analysis. The pre-Socratics discourse, in a 630 Cf. supra, p. 48. 63* Cratyl., 439, 440 ; Thecetet, 179, 180 ; Soph., 249 D. 531 no, 171. Cf. Euthyd., 288 C, taX tov's re a AAou! avinpinoiv 635 Pateb, Plato and Platonism, pp. 16-20. 632Cra<2/Z., 439 D; Si/mp., 207 D; KTmiBiw, possim. „, „ .„„ _, . . „ ,. 637iJep 439B. The saying is Heraclitean in tone. 533r7iecEte«., 155E,156A. Paul Shobey 69 fine imaged style, about Being, but a plain man can not be sure of their meaning. ''* Absolute formulas, like irdvra pel, irav ev, Travrmv fierpov avBpcoTro^, have an imposing sound, but if we press for their interpretation, prove to be either truisms or paradoxes, destructive of intelligible speech. °^' It is an ingenious sport to construct for Protagoras some subtle and nicely guarded modem system of phenomenalism. But we must then pass over the purely dramatic parts of Plato's discussion, and limit ourselves to his final and seriously meant arguments against the psychology of materialism and the logic of relativism. There are two such arguments which neither Plato nor his critics are careful to distinguish sharply: (1) The first is that the senses are organs of mind and that sense perception itself implies the "soul" or some central "synthetic unity.""" This, if fully under- stood, is conclusive against the sensationist materialism of Condillac's statue. But Plato's chief interest is in the second argument derived from this. (2) The objects of each sense we can perceive only through the specific organ of that sense.^' But the general common categories of Being, not-Being, number, likeness, difference, the same, and the other,"' as also ethical universals, and the abstr-act definitions of sensuous qualities °" are apprehended without subsidiary organs solely through the action of the mind, and its reflections on the contradictions of sense. Availing himself of the double meaning of ovaia (1) logical essence, (2) reality, truth, Plato argues, as in the Phcedo,''^ that truth and reality are attained only by the "pure" thought of the soul acting independently of the body. A modem Theaetetus, of course, might deny that abstract thought has no bodily organ, or that its objects are more "real" than the perceptions of sense. But the absolute identification of ato-^jjo-t? and ewiarrifiri is sufficiently refuted, and the suggest- iveness of this definition having been exhausted, a fresh start is made with the definition "knowledge is true opinion." But this implies that we understand erroneous opinion, and error proves to be inexplicable. The attempt to explain it calls forth many interesting analogies and distinctions. '** One large class of errors is accounted for as arising from the wrong reference of present sensations to stored up memory images.'^ The distinction between latent or potential and actual knowledge postpones the final difficulty."' But in the end it must be faced: error as a matter of fact occurs in "pure" thought. How can pure thought misapprehend its object? A bodiless intelligence either touches or does not touch the object of thought. We can understand 638 Soph., 242, 243. nerves, but Empedocles " already " remarked of the senses, 6390ra{jl., 439,440; Thewtet., 183AB, n9DE; Soph., oi Svvatreai n HA^Kav Kpivciy, Theophr. sens.,!, Dox. 500. 249CD. 542185CD. 6« 186 A B. C/. supra, nn. 221 and 222. 6*0 184 D, «"r6v yip ^ov, S, ir«i, « iroWiii tc«5 iv ji^lv, S,a^,p ^^^ y^^^j^j^ jg, ^ . pj^,^^^ gS C. iv SoupEiow t;riro«, atffS^ireit eyicaftiji'Tot, aXAa (tij «i! /iiov riva iSiav, .Ire ^xX" "Te 5 « &,l Kol^lv, nivra TaSra {v-ret-et, etc. '" Of- '"i*^"' V.55;u. 520 with text. 6"185AC. LUTOSLAWSKI, pp. 276, 372, fancies that this . 6««193,194. The memory image is treated as knowledge, ei5i lEi'al. is an anticipation of the modern " law of specific energies of the senses," " already " glanced at in Bep., S52E, but showing progress in the formulation here. The modern law could not be anticipated without knowledge of the »iii eiSiviu. of the senses," " already " glanced at in Sep., S52E, but 5*7197. This is the distinction invoked in JJutAyd., 277, showing progress in the formulation here. The modern 278, to meet the eristic fallacy of the alternative liJfVat % 70 The Unity op Plato's Thought the confusion of one object with another, the misplacement of cognitions, only in terms of spatial imagery which, if accepted literally, is materialism again, and if taken as a symbol implies the synthetic unity of mind behind it, and so renews the puzzle in infinite regress."* Modern metaphysicians evade the difficulty by assuming aa infinite thought of which our erring thought is a part. Their task then is to preserve the iudividuality of a consciousness that is part of another mind. This problem disappears in a mist of theistic language enveloping pantheistic doctrine. Plato does not soar to these heights, but having carried the psychological analysis to the limit, he disposes of the equation, eTna-Trjtirj =^ \6yo. appears, e. p., from the reservation ill ve ev iroAireio, 309 E, In the Meno, 98A, right opinions became knowledge when which is precisely equivalent to ttoAituc^i' -/<: in Sep., 4S0E. bound oirias Aoywrj^y. InSymp., 202A, opOaSofa^eti- — avcvroO 5525itpya, p. 17; n. 91 with text. BSSfif-jipj-a, n. 549. Paul Shoret 71 tion/" Socrates has heard a theory that the first elements of things are simple and not objects of knowledge. — Eqt know ledge imp lies giving and taking an account, and no account can be given of elements beyond naming them. They^wHTnot admit any other predicate."^ In this paragraph we may discover allusions to Antisthenes's paradox about predication and definition, to current philosophies of materialism, and to mechanical interpretations of Plato's own formula Sovvai re koX Be^aaOai Xoyov. But whatever Plato's secondary literary intentions, his main purpose is to present a serious psychological and metaphysical problem. Is the whole the sum of its parts except in mathematics? Can the world be explained as a mechanical summation of elements? The problem presents itself to us in psychology and cosmogony. *'° Plato treats it in dialectical abstraction, taking the syllable and its letters ("elements," a-Toi)(^e2a) as representatives of elements and compounds. He decides (1) that the syllable is not the mere equivalent of its elements, but a new emergent form and dis- tinct idea ; (2) that, whether this be so or not, the elements and the syllable are equally knowable and unknowable. For if the syllable is the sum of the elements it cannot be known if they are not. And if it is a new unity it is as elemental as they and can- not be explained by resolution into its parts. The second conclusion disposes of the proposed definition. The first, as we have already seen, is a suggestion of the doctrine of ideas as against philosophies of mechanical materialism.*" But we are not therefore justified in making this episode the chief purpose of the dialogue. Two other possible meanings of XSyo's are shown to yield no result, and the dialogue closes with the Socratic moral that we are at least wiser for knowing that we do not know. THE PHiEDEUS The Phcedrus, with its profusion of ideas, its rich technical and poetical vocabu- lary, and its singular coincidences with the Laws"'^ and Timceus,^^^ makes the impres- sion of a mature work. This impression is confirmed by Sprach-Statistik, and by the fact that it directly parodies a sentence of Isocrates's Panegyricus published in SSO."*" It is possible to say that the thoughts are merely sketched in a "program" of future work ; that the dithyrambic vocabulary is due to the theme ; and that the phrase of Isocrates is taken from an older, common source.^' Anything may be said in debate. B5*.LtiT03LAW8Ki (p. 371) argues that the Thecetetue re- 5" 202. jecting Ao-yot, etc., contradicts the opinion "provisionally" ^^^E.g., Wcndt's psychology differs from that of the received in JfejM), 98A, Sj/mp., 202A, and PA(E-«- ■<»•«-• ■^""- °. /^ t sijie guo rwwi of knowledge (202 C), but only m connection - , .- - ,. with the rejected theory of elements, and its fuU dialecti- "'"'"" «"'^»"''- «»<:• cal significance is not developed. '" Gompebz, Ueber neuere Plato-Forschung. 72 The Unity of Plato's Thought But there is an end to all use of Isocratean parallels if we cannot infer that the Phcedrus is later than a work which it explicitly parodies. If we assume Lysias, who died in 378, to be still living, the date may be still more precisely determined to about the year 379. The strongest confirmation of this date is the weakness of the arguments for an earlier date, which it is hard to take seriously. The politician who recently called Lysias a Xoyoypd(j)0'i need not have been Archinos, and, if he was, Plato's use of evayyp'i may be merely dramatic.^*" The patronizing commendation of Socrates at the end°°^ is not incompatible with a sly parody of his Gorgian style, nor even with the sharp rap on the knuckles administered to him (if it is Isocrates) at the close of the Euthydemus. Still less can we say that Plato and Isocrates could never have been friends after the declaration at the close of the tract against the Sophists that virtue cannot be taught, or, for that matter, after any other polemical innuendo in their works. Huxley, Matthew Arnold, Frederick Harrison, Herbert Spencer, and other knights of nineteenth -century polemics, com- bined much sharper thrusts than these with the interchange of courteous or slightly ironical compliments. Our chief concern, however, is with arguments drawn from the thought. We have already seen that the dialectical method of the Phcedrus is not appreciably less mature than that of the Philebus or the Sophist,^^ and that, on the other hand, there is nothing in the psychology or ethics of the Phcedrus that necessarily fixes its rela- tion to the Republic, the Phcedo, or the Symposium.^ What can be said, then, of the attempts of distinguished scholars to show that the thought of the Phcedrus dates it circa 392, or even ten years earlier ? The only one that calls for serious consideration is Natorp's argument™ that the immaturity of the Phcedrus is proved by the absence of the notion of a supreme science, or of ultimate categories found in the Symposium, Republic, Sophist, and even in the Euthydemus. The answer is that such a notion never appears in Plato except in some special form adapted to a particular argument. Natorp includes very different things under this rubric. The supreme science of the Symposium is merely the knowledge of the idea — of the idea of beauty as distin- guished from particular beauties. That of the Republic is knowledge of the idea — of the idea of good as the o-kotto'; or aim of true statesmanship. That of the Euthyde- mus is in one place by implication dialectic (290 C), in another the "political art" (291 C). In other passages the unity of science is merely the unity of the concept or idea, eVtcrT^/iT;.^" The ontological categories of the Thecetetus, Sophist, and Parmeni- des belong to a different line of thought and have a mainly logical significance. They are connected with the notion of a universal science only in so far as they are appre- hended and discriminated by dialectic. Now the subject of the Phcedrus did not call for the explicit assumption either of supreme categories or a universal science. The chief point in the myth, ignored by Natorp and the majority of commentators, is that 662 257 C . 564 Supra, u. 377. 565 Supra, pp. 19, 43 ; n. 152. 663 279 A, Tout Adyows oil fiy p6vrjaii (Rep., 505 B), and the enthusiastic declaration that if wisdom (^poVijo-t?) could be seen by mortal eyes (as beauty in some measure can) it would enkindle Seivov,.t„«,sr. ,, , * u i - i.1. u- -i; * *-k« 575 pTtoedr., 250 D, seems destined to misinterpretation, voupyiCT embraces all forms of rhetoric, the higgling of the ^ «u,u., ., wv i|> =«. „n.„„r*i.o, ..,,1 „„IJ *,,„ T.„„i..,-. „t „f fl,« r>»r»=itB. and t,hB whole LCTOSLAWSKI, p. 339, misses the meaning altogether, and market, the Lucianic art of the parasite, and the whole HOEN, pp. 212, 213, actually takes Seii-ovs Ipwraj (understand- teaching and eristic of the Sophists. .^^ ^^'JJ^-^ ^ ^ ^^^ ^^^^ ^^ p^^^^,^ _.^^^^^ ^^^ ^^ ^^^^ ^^ 571 263 D E. 672 265, 266 A. 673 16 C D B. ^^jj images of other ideas than beauty, and objects that 574 The division of all things into ire'pas, airnpoi', ^i.kt6v, the passionate love of justice would be a good, since it and aWia is given in a different connection, and has nothing would not be exposed to sensual excess I 74 The Unity op Plato's Thought a prelude is a mere commonplace of rhetoric, as in Phcedo, 108 C ; Meno, 239 C ; Polit, 269 C. The argument that dialectic is first introduced as a new term in 266 will not bear scrutiny. In Philebus, 53 E, eveKci tov is introduced still more circumstantially. The ideas are a dream in Cratyl., 439 C ; dialectic is dramatically led up to in Cratyl., 390; and in Sophisi, 265, 266, an elaborate explanation has to be given of what is taken for granted in the phrase (pavrdcrfiaTa Oeia, Rep., 532C."° Natorp says "der Begriff Dialektik ist im Gorgias noch nicht gepragt, sondern erst im Phcedrus." But StaXeyeaOai is contrasted with prjTopiKrj in the Gorgias, 448 D, and the term StaXe/crt- ic6<;-i], if I may trust my memory and Ast, does not happen to occur in the Symposium, Thecetetus, TimcBus, Parmenides, Phcedo, Philebus, or Laws. It is begging the question, then, to assume that Bia\ejea-6at in the Gorgias does not connote true Pla- tonic BcaXeKTiK'^, but only Socratic conversation. There is not a word about "damo- nischen BiaXcKTO'i" in Symp., 202 E, 203 A, and the notion of philosophy as the seeking rather than the attainment of knowledge occurs not only in Symp., 203 D- 204 B, "after" the Phcedrus, but in Lysis, 218 A. As for Xoywv rexvr), it is any "art of words," whether actual or ideal rhetoric, dialectic, or even eristic.^" It is uncritical to press the various meanings which different contexts lend to such a general expression. Rhetoric is called the Xdyav rexvrj in 260 D, but Socrates immediately adds that there is no true Xeyeiv Te^yr) avev tov aX'qOeCa^ rj6ai; i. e., without dialectic. There is, then, no inconsistency between this and the use of rrj? irepl toxk \6yov<; Te^^wys in Phcedo, 90 B ; nor can it be said that the \6y(ov iJ,edoBo<: of Sophist, 227 A, differs appreciably from the fiedoSo:; of Phcedr., 270 D."' Lastly, Natorp's argument (pp. 408-10) that the method of avvaywyrj and Biaipea-K described in the Phcedrus does not go far beyond the suggestions of the Gorgias and Meno is, of course, merely a further con- firmation of our main thesis. But when he adds that IBea is used vaguely in 237 D, 288 A, 246 A, 253 B, etc., and not, as in the " later" iJepM&Kc and Phcedo, in the strict sense of Platonic idea, the reply must be that this vague, untechnical use of elSo? and ISea is always possible in Plato."" Omitting Thecetetus, 184 D, since Natorp thinks that also "early," we find it in Rep., 507 E; Philebus, 64 E, and Cratylus, 418 E, where ayaOov IBe'a does not mean "idea of good." Since the transcendental idea is established for the Phcedrus, of what possible significance is the occasional use of the word IBea in a less technical sense ? These illustrations might be multiplied indefinitely. They do not establish a universal negative, but they certainly create a presumption against all arguments of the type which careful scrutiny always shows to be fallacious. And the experience of the untrustworthiness of many such arguments creates in the minds of sober philolo- gians a more justifiable "misology" than that which Plato deprecates in the Phcedo. 5™ See Adam, ad loc. "s cf. supra, u. 377. 'I'T Euthyd., 288 A, iiMtTdpat rexriJI .... oiT(aal 9aviiim)t H'SSee JoWETT AND Cahpbell, Vol. II, pp. 294 fl. outTTjs ets aKpipeiav Adywc. Paul Shoeet 75 THE CRATYLUS In vivacity and comic verve the Cratylus is "early," ^"' in maturity and subtlety of thought "late." Its most obvious feature, the playful allegorical use of etymol- ogizing, is anticipated or recalled in many other dialogues/*' Admirable is the art with which etymologies recognized to be little better than puns are made the vehicle of a true philosophy of language, and a profound discussion of the relations of lan- guage and thought. With this we are not concerned. We have already seen that the attempt to assign the dialogue an early place in the development of Plato's own thought breaks down.^ Plato is "already" in full possession of the theory of ideas and of the essen- tial arguments of his polemic against the flowing philosophers.™' His repudiation of eristic fallacies is as distinct and as clearly, if not as fully, expressed as it is in the Euthydemus and Sophist.^"* It remains merely to enumerate, as a part of our cumulative argument, some of the minor resemblances that link the Cratylus to its predecessors or successors, and make it a sort of abbreviated repertory of Platonic thoughts and classifications. In 386 D there is a reference to the doctrine of Euthydemus: irda-i irdvra onoCoa'i elvai ana ical aei. In 386 D, Tr/aafets are an elSo? rmv ovtcov; cf. Thecetet., 155 E. In 387 B \eyei,v is TrpaTreiv, cf. Euthyd., 284 0. In 388 C ovofia dpa hihaaKaXiKov n icrriv opjavov Kal SiuKpiTiKov Trj<} ouCTwis, coupled with the statement, 390 B 0, that only the dialec- tician can use this tool, implies the imagery and doctrine of Sophist, 226-31 B, where the KadapcTK of dialectic and Sophistic is a branch of SiaKpcTiKrjov yeve'a0ai, cf. Symp., 184 C; 284 B, \eryeiv is irpaTreiv, cf Cratyl, 387 B; 287 A, if there is no error, TtVo? BiBdaKoXoi rjKere, cf. Thecetet., 161 E, 178 E; 287 D, irorepov ovv yjrvxvv exovra voel to, voovvra. The quibble suggests the metaphysical problem of Parmen., 132 D, cf. A. J. P., Vol. XXII, p. 161; 289 C, the art of the user and the art of the maker, cf Bep., 601D, Cratyl, 390 B, 290 A, cf Gorg., 454; 290CD, cf Polit, 305 A, and supra, p. 62; 290 C, the mathematician subordinated to the dialectician, cf. Bep., 528 B; 291 B, Sxnrep ra iraiBCa to, tov^ KopvBow BimKovTU, etc., is the germ of the image of the aviary in the Thecetetus; 291 C, cf. Polit., 259 D ; 292 D, cf Charm., 167 0, Meno, 100 A, Protag., 312 D; 301 A, cf supra, n. 199; 301 B, cf. supra, n. 426. 585 Sitpra, pp. 54, 58. verbreitet ist. Man sollte doch in Erw5gen Ziehen, ob B86 Of Idea of Good, p. 204 ; supra, a. 97. ^e^^ j^^e Euh6 und Sicherheit der Discussion einer Frage 687 292; cf.mpra, n. 71. Bonitz, p. 125, protests against als Frage far jemand mOglich ist, Mr den sie eben nur the assumption that Plato is really baffled in 292 E, and ^'X'^ Problem ist und eine MOglichkeit der LOsung sich sensibly adds : " Ich erwahue dies nur, weil diese Art der "^'cht dargoboten hat." Folgerung und der Erklaning Platonischer Dialoge weit ^^^ Supra, nn. 547, 548. Paul Shobey 77 The significance of the closing conversation with Crito is often missed."" Nothing, of course, can be inferred from the casual admission (307 A) that xpjj/toTto-TtK^ and jyqropiKr} are ayaSov; or from the "contradiction" of the Hepublic in the statement that philosophy and iroKmKr) trpa^ii are both ayadov, but -n-pm aWo sKarepa. Socrates is speaking to his worthy friend the business man Crito from the point of view of common- sense. We have also seen that the allusion to Isocrates (?) does not determine the date.'*" Plato is defending himself and Socrates against the criticism that such trivial eristic is unworthy of the attention of a man of sense. The dignified rhetorician to whom the criticism is attributed, like Isocrates, confounds eristic with philosophy and proclaims the futility of both.'" Plato replies (1) that in philosophy as in other pursuits the majority are bad; (2) even eristic may be a useful logical discipline. The second thought is implied rather than expressed. It is implied by the interven- tion of the Saifioviov (272 E) and by the statement that the gentlemen who in Prodicus's phrase °°^ hold the borderland of philosophy and politics, and who think the philosophers their only rivals for the first place, are badly mauled in private conversa- tion when they fall into the hands of eristics like Euthydemus.°'' Socrates, on the other hand, though ironically admitting defeat, has shown himself throughout able to do what is postulated of the true dialectician in the Sophist, 259 C: rots Xeyofievoi 72 ^°^ "*" ^lyt^'i^S be inferred from coincidence in common- ^ ' places or in ideas that can be found in Euripides and Ml 305 A, ital oStoi (Dionysodoms and Enthydemus) iv Thucydides. It would be easy to "prove" by these methods Toit KpaTioToi! eicri rav vvv. jjjjj^i jjjg Busiria follows the Bepublic and precedes the B92See Joel, Der echte und der xenophontische Sohra- Sj/mposmm which contradicts it (c/. Busiria, I, -wittSymp., tea Vol. n, p. 634. 198 D) . Strangely enough, the very critics who force a , , . . ... ~. reference to the Helena upon Bepublic, 586C, are apt to 593305D, .V Se To« cSto« X.iyo« W ..roWSo,^... Cf .^ ^^^ ^^^^^^^ ^j ^^^.^ chronology, the two almost Theiztet., m B or. ay .«., X070.Se, Sov... re «a. 6.fa^^ Supra, nn. 244, 375, pp. 34, 36, 42, 46, 55, 62. comic poet at the end of the Symposium is an apology for 606 See Zelleb (pp. 551 ff.) , who dates it in 375. The the comic touches in that dialogue and an announcement coincidences between the Bepublic and the Ecclesiazousae Paul Shoeey 79 The relations already indicated between the Republic and other dialogues force extreme partisans of "development" to break it up into distinct sections which they assign to different periods.™' Such hypotheses are beyond the scope of serious criti- cism, which in the total absence of evidence can neither affirm nor deny them. It can only point out the fallacy of the reasoning by which they are supported. The "argu- ments" of Krohn, Pfleiderer, and their followers have been refuted in more than suffi- cient detail by Hirmer, Campbell,*' Grimmelt, and other defenders of the unity of the Bepublic. They may be reduced, broadly speaking, to a petitio principii and a few typical fallacies. The petitio principii is the assumption that the numerous connect- ing links and cross-references that bind together the "parts" of the Republic were inserted by Plato as an afterthought. The chief and fundamental fallacy is the appli- cation to a great and complex literary masterpiece of canons of consistency and unity drawn from the inner consciousness of professional philologians. The architectural unity of the Republic is superior to that of the Laws, the Philebus, the Phcedrus, or to that of the parts into which the disintegrators resolve it, many of which plainly could not exist by themselves. Secondary intentions, a prelude, digressions, and a peroration, postlude, afterpiece, or appendix may be expected in so long a work. As Jowett sensibly says:*"' "We may as well speak of many designs as one; nor need any- thing be excluded from the plan of a great work to which the mind is naturally led by the association of ideas and which does not interfere with the general purpose." It is uncritical, then, to assume a central argument and prune off everything that is not indispensable to its development. The argument might conceivably have started from the restatement of the problem by Glaucon and Adeimantus at the beginning of the second book. Plato might have drawn up a sketch of a reformed state, omitting all mention of the higher education, the rule of the philosophers, and the degenerate forms of government. He might have closed the work abruptly with the demonstra- tion of the main thesis at the end of the ninth book. Or, if he wished to add the myth, he might have omitted or found another place for the digression in which the banishment of the poets is justified on deeper grounds. But these bare possibilities do not raise the slightest presumption that the Republic was, in fact, pieced together out of detached and disjointed essays. The different topics were closely associated in Plato's thought. And if they were all present to his mind from the beginning, it of AristophaneB yield at the most a terminus post quern. the picture of the tyrant (577) "must" fall after the first Of HiBMEB "Entstehung nnd Komp. d. Plat. Eep.," Jaftr- Sicilian journey and before the second when Plato was on bUcherfar Phil Snppl., N.F., Vol. XXIU, p. 655; Adam, friendly terms with Dionysins the younger; (3) because The Bepublic of Plato, Vol. I, pp. 345-55. Hibmee (pp. 660 £E.) Cheist has " proved " that the eleventh epistle (circa 364) disposes of the attempt to date the Bepublic by the allu- is genuine, and the eleventh epistle implies the completion sion to Ismenias (336 A), and to Polydamas (338C), by the of the Bepublic and the beginning of the Ttmcetts. supposed allusion to Eudoxus (530) , and by Rbinhaedt's cot Pfleideeee, Zur Ldsung d. plat. Frage, p. 79 : " Das reference of 410 BC to Isocrates's Antidosis, 181, and of Znsammenwerfen ganz verschiedener Phasenin der Bep.. 498DE to the Areopagiticus. He himself, with as little ^jg j^jj behaupte, musste nothwendig far Jeden, der sonst proof, thinks that 498 DE alludes to the Euagoras. He gerne Phasen und Perioden gesehen hatte, die geahnten dates the completion of the Bepublic circa 370 : (1) because, Greuzlinien wieder verwischen." after Christ, he believes that the protest against interne- ^^^ n^pMic, Vol. 11, essay III. cine war between Greeks (471 A-C) "must" refer to the J^i- ' .. ' destruction of Plattea by the Thebans in 374; (2) because ««' Vol. HI, p. vu. so The Unity of Plato's Thought would not be easy to suggest a more natural and effective order of presentation than that in which we now read them. To prove, then, that, as a matter of fact, the "parts" of the Republic were com- posed at different times recourse is had to two other fallacies : (1) it is assumed that what is not explicitly mentioned in any part is not known to the author at the time ; and (2) slight variations in phrasing are taken to imply serious differences of doctrine. The application of this method to the theory of ideas and to Plato's psychology has already been considered."" A few words may be added here on the second point. Rohde"' says that the immortality of the soul is ignored in the earliest part, II- V, 471 C ; first appears as a paradox in X, 608 D ; and is assumed in its sublimest form in VI, VII. But his arguments will not bear scrutiny. "Was nach dem Tode kom- men moge, soUen die t, 7„.,- 620 p/tcedo, 95A, ovts yap av , , , , OuTjptd Petto TrOfnTn praises Homer without irony, and earlier than P/KEdrns , ^.Q »3^ttf Ttdc irotTjTuc — in both passages seriously, as the con- thepoet. But Natokp, thinking of other passages of the ! i. -i, Phcedrus, is positive that such a dialogue could not have 'ext shows. been written after the rejection of poetry in the Republic ; '" 23 C ; cf. the Ion. and Mem, 99 E. while DOmmleb (Vol. I, p. 269) places the Symposium after 622 394 D, lirm Si «at n^^eto. e-rt rourtui/. 82 The Unity op Plato's Thought in emphasizing the distinction between dramatic and narrative poetry Plato carelessly speaks as if the former alone were imitative, proves nothing.'^' A far more important new point made in the tenth book is already distinctly implied in the Protagoras — the antithesis between the principle of measure in the soul and rj tov (f)aivofievov Svm/it?,"" to which poetry makes its appeal.'^^ The mood of the Symposium differs from that of the Gorgias and the Republic. But this does not prove either that the Symposium is earlier, or that Plato had been mellowed by success. A banquet at which Agathon was host and Aristophanes a guest was obviously not the place for a polemic against dramatic poetry. But even here the ironical superiority of the dialec- tician is maintained, and the inability of the poets to interpret or defend their art is revealed. °^° CONCLUSION. IDEAS AND NUMBERS. THE LAWS The value of Plato's life-work would be very slightly affected even if it were true that in the weakness of extreme old age the noble light of his philosophy did " go out in a fog of mystical Pythagoreanism." It is not in the least true, however, and the prevalence of the notion is due mainly (1) to the uncritical acceptance of the tradition concerning Plato's "latest" doctrine of ideas and numbers; and (2) to the disparaging estimate of the Laws expressed by those who care only for dramatic charm of style, or by radicals like Grote, who are offended by the " bigotry" of a few passages. A word must be said on each of these points. 1. Aristotle's account of Plato's later identification of ideas and numbers has been generally accepted since Trendelenburg's dissertation on the subject.'^" Zeller rightly points out that the doctrine is not found in the extant writings, but adds that for Plato numbers are entities intermediate between ideas and things of sense. In my discussion of the subject ^'^ I tried to establish two points : first, that we need not accept the testimony of Aristotle, who often misunderstood Plato, and was himself not clear as to the relation of mathematical and other ideas; second, that the doctrine of numbers as intermediate entities is not to be found in Plato, but that the passages which misled Zeller may well have been the chief source of the whole tradition about ideas and numbers. The first point is a matter of opinion. I did not deny the testi- mony of Aristotle, and no one who chooses to accept it can be refuted. The relation of ideas to numbers was doubtless much debated by the scholastics of the Academy. Aristotle's reports of the intolerable logomachy do not make it clear just how much of this nonsense he attributed to Plato. But I do not intend to enter upon the inter- pretation of the eleventh and twelfth books of the Metaphysics. No reader would 623 393 C, 394 D. 62*Pro«aff., 356D. man is "inspired" by the tragic muse, another by the 625 Rep., 602, 603. comic. If poetry were a matter of science, the poet could 626 201 B, KH-Svi/evio, S> Sai/(pare9, oiSiv eiSivat mv Tore eiiroi-. '^^e both forms, even as the scientific interpreter of poetry Kai fiT|v KaAis ye elTTes, avai., S> "Ayieui/. Cf. also 223 D, where would not, like the " inspired " Ion, be limited to Homer. Socrates compels Agathon and Aristophanes to admit toC This we may plausibly conjecture to be the meaning. But avTOv avSpo^ elvai, KtafitoSiav Kai TpaytoSiav iiriirrairOai, iroicl*'. *t IS only conjecture. This is thought to contradict Bepub.^ 395 A, but the contra- ^^"^ Plat, de id. et numeris doctritia, 1828. diction is removed by pressing rix<'ri in what follows. One 628 Oe Plat, id, doctrina, pp. 31 H. Paul Shoeey 83 follow me, and no results could be won. If Aristotle's testimony be accepted, there is an end of controversy. Plato taught in his lectures the doctrine of ideas and numbers. But the second point is not so elusive. It is possible to test the argument that the extant writings do not recognize an intermediate class of mathematical numbers, and yet might easily suggest the notion to mechanical-minded students. Now Zeller in his fourth edition confounds the two questions. He gives the impression that he is answering me by a Quellenbelege from Aristotle and Philoponos. He wholly ignores my interpretation of a number of specific Platonic passages, which he appar- ently takes for the mere misunderstandings and blunders of a beginner.'^^ I have no hope of convincing Zeller, nor do I wish to force myself into a polemic with the honored master of all who study Greek philosophy. But, as Mr. J. Adam, a scholar whose scrupulous candor makes it a pleasure to argue with him, has expressed surprise in his edition of the Republic that I still adhere to my opinion in spite of the mass of evidence, I will endeavor tb state my meaning more plainly. The theory of ideas, the hypostatisiation of all concepts, once granted, numbers do not differ from other ideas. The phrase, irepl airrSiv rmv apiOfJ^wp (Rep., 525 D), denotes ideal numbers or the ideas of numbers, and opara fj aina aw/jLara exovrai apidfiov<} are numbered things, things of sense participant in number.**' That is all there is of it, and there is no extant Platonic passage that this interpretation will not fit. For educational purposes it is true that mathematical science holds an inter- mediate place between dialectic and the perceptions of sense. Mathematical abstractions [r/ irepl to ev iid6rj / 71- V 1 My objection was that both grammar and Aristotelian °''™'' '"'■<' "CXI!- usage showed that otra rdv oltrB-riTiov, etc., are also abstralc- ^^^ Fhileb., 56 BE. te Begriffe (in the German or English sense of the words). 84 The Unity of Plato's Thought maticians (Rep., 5 26 A), Trept iroloov apiOfimv SiaXe^eade; and the answer is, irepl tovtcov wv BiavorjOfjvai fiovov iyx^P^h coupled with an exposition that recalls the Parmenides of the pure idea of unity .''^ Simple as all this appears, it might easily be misunder- stood by the pupils of the Academy. Mathematics was intermediate from an educational point of view. In cosmogony numbers and geometrical forms are the mediators between chaos and the general idea of harmony and measure."^* The expression, numbers (arithmetic), of the vulgar and numbers of the philosopher would lead a perverse ingenuity to ask of the mathematicians, in the words of the Republic, Trepl iromv apiOfiSiv SiaXejecrOe ; Plato's use of "dyad" and "triad" as convenient synomyms for the pure idea of two and three would be mistakenly supposed to imply a distinction."^^ The innocent question {Rep., 524 C), rt ovv ttot' eVrt ro fii'ya av koI to (TfiiKpov,^^ would suggest that it was a terminus technicus for some mysterious ultimate philosophical principle, and set students upon hunting it and its supposed synomyms through the dialogues, and, inasmuch as /leya -f- a/jLCKpov indubitably = 2, it might well be identified with the indeterminate dyad and its supposed equivalents, or any other "principle" posited in antithesis to the one."" The folly once set a-going, there are no limits to its plausible developments. All the unanswerable questions as to the relation of ideas to things may assume special forms for special classes of ideas. Plato himself shows this for ideas of relative terms in a much misunderstood passage of the Parmenides.^" The problem of the relations of numbered things, of the supposed mathematical numbers, and of ideal numbers, offered a rich feast for the quibblers and the oyfrifiadeh of the Academy. "Before and after" is essential to number, but there is no "before and after" in the ideas. Multiplicity is inherent in number, but the "idea" even of a million must be one. Other ideas may be imperfectly copied by things, but is not the number five entirely present in five things ? Echoes of this pitiful scholasticism are preserved for us in the metaphysics of Aristotle. But what possible reason can there be for attributing it to Plato? Adam himself (Vol. II, p. 160) repeats the disconsolate question: irepl ttoicov apiOyiSiv ^ia\e<; tov? Se St' akri6ov, j t, ,-^- r, > i.i ^ recent Sopftist, Phtlebus,a.ua Pohticus. Zelles's attempt 650 632 C. The parallelism with the Republic is obvious. t^ distinguish between ((.pdi/i),r« and the voSt of the Republic There, too {412 A, 497 C D) , there is a similar anticipation of jg ^ false point. <^i>ovr,aK is used in PAcedo, 69 B. the need of guardians who know as distinguished from the g^j ^^ „ assistants. In Laws, 818 A, there is another anticipation of the higher education. Mathematics only is mentioned «»2Proto0., 311 B; Gorff., 447, 448, 449 E ; Sitaj/d., 291 C ; because Plato is explaining that it is not needful for the Bep., 333. multitude to study it profoundly. There is no occasion for 653961,962. Paul Shorey 87 No state can prosper or be saved unless such knowledge resides in some part of it as a v\aKTripiov.^ The beginning of such knowledge is to fir] -rrXavaaOai tt/so? TroWa a-Toxa^ofievov aW ek ev ^ejrovra, etc/°^ Now to, t&v iroXeav vo/xifia aim at many things — wealth, power, and tov ikevdepop S^ ^lov!'^ Our aim is virtue. But virtue is both four and one. The intelligent physician can define his one aim. Must not the intelligent ruler be able to define his? It is easy to show how the four virtues are many. To exhibit their unity is harder.^" A man who amounts to anything must know, not only the names, but the \6''jo Xo^w ivSeiKvvaOai.^^ The thing being so clearly indicated, it would be pitiful quibbling to object that the word BiaXeKTiKr) does not happen to occur here. Its omission is possibly due to the fact that the Athenian throughout the Laws talks down to the level of his unsophisticated Spartan and Cretan interlocutors. Mathematics and astronomy, then, are not substituted for dialectic, but are added for a special reason among the airovSaia which the guardians must understand with real knowledge. The multitude may follow tradition. The guardians must be able to demonstrate the truths of natural religion, as we have done.*" Astronomy, the study of the ordered movements of the heavens, is a great aid to this. With astronomy is involved the necessary mathematics, which also in their relation to music and the arts are of use to him who is to shape the characters and laws of men.**^ He who cannot learn these things can never be a ruler, though he may be an assistant. In the last two pages of the Laws Plato evades giving a detailed account of the curriculum of the higher education thus indicated — perhaps he was weary, perhaps he did not care to repeat the Republic.'^ In any case, there is no justification for the statement that the Laws ignore the higher education of the rulers or substitute in it mathematics and astronomy for dialectic. On the contrary, the unity of Plato's 654 962 C J cf. Bep., 424 C. **■ Cf, PTiwdr., 265 D ; and with rauTTj! ouk iari. na^tirripa 655962D. (»e9oSo!, cf. Phileb., 16B; Phoedr., 266 B. 656C/. ilep., 563A, ivaSij iXevflepo! B. 662965 D. Meno, 74 A, r'riv Si ilUv, i Sii izivTuii' TOVTiav 65' Of. Phileb., 18 E, nm eo-Tix Ix ical TToAAi airHv tKirepov. iariv, oil ivvilt-aOa. avtvptlv. 658 964 C ; cf. Rep., 366 E, rj avrov Svvi.iJ.ii if rf toC cxoi-tos 663 966 B. ifmxB ei-oi/. *** In Book X. 659 964 E ; c/. Tim. , 69, 70. «65 967 E. •60965A. 666968D. 88 The Unity of Plato's Thought thought is strikingly illustrated by his return in the pages just analyzed to some of the favorite ideas of the Republic and earlier dialogues. °" It is not necessary to prolong this study. The Timceus, so far as it affects our argument, has already been considered.""' The TimcBUS as a whole I have studied elsewhere.''^" The object of this discussion and the expression "unity of Plato's thought" may easily be misunderstood. I may therefore be permitted, in conclusion, to repeat that I have not meant to sophisticate away the obvious and inevitable variations in Plato's moods, and minor beliefs from youth to old age. Nor in the study of such develop- ment would I reject the aid of a sober and critical method of style statistics."" My thesis is simply that Plato on the whole belongs rather to the type of thinkers whose philosophy is fixed in early maturity (Schopenhauer, Herbert Spencer), rather than to the class of those who receive a new revelation every decade (Schelling). And I have tried to show that the method which proceeds on the contrary assumption leads to mis- interpretation of his writings. The illustrations given are merely typical. There has been no attempt to catalogue exhaustively the opinions of contemporary Platonists. The polemic is, I trust, not discourteous, and is, I am sure, not intentionally disloyal. In any case, it turns generally on the meaning or relevancy of specific passages and can easily be tested. Some excuse for its prominence may be found in Mill's statement that "there are few, if any, ancient authors concerning whose mind and purpose so many demonstrably false opinions are current, as concerning Plato." 667GOMPERZ supports his view of the anti-dialectical tendency of Plato's mind in the Laws by the hostility of the Sophist to every kind of antilogy. But surely eristic is one thing and dialectic another. The true Socratic elen- chus is described and the diificulty of distinguishing it from eristic indicated in a locus classicus in the Sophist (230BfE.); and hoih the Sophist and the PoUticus employ the keenest dialectic in order to meet and defeat eristic on its own ground iSoph., 259 CD). In the Philebus, which Goraperz thinks late, dialectic is still the highest science of truth {Phileb., 58). But Plato had other interests than dialectic, and it is unreasonable to expect him to fill the Laws and Timceus with repetitions of what had been said once for all in the Sophist, PoUticus, and Philebus, 668 Supra, p. 37. 669 a. J. P., Vol. IX, pp. 395 £f 6'OAs, e. g., that of Eittee, "Die Sprachstatistik in Anwendung auf Platon und Goethe," N&ue Jahrbiicher etc., 1903. INDEX AfilivriiTK, 32, 43, 44, 19, n. 109. AvdptajTOq fL€Tpov, 67. Cardinal virtues, 12. Charmides, 15. Copula, ambiguity of, 54. Courage, 11, 15, n. 43. Cratylus, 75 £E., 54, 56. Definition, 13, 16, 66, n. 86; by dichotomy, 50 S. Dialectic, 74, 86 ffi : negative goes too far, 17 S. Dichotomy, 50 S. Eristic, 13, 14, 19 n. 108, 50, 77, n.667. Ethics, 9 ff. Euthydemus, 76 ff., 54. Euthyphro, 12, 31. Fallacies of Plato, inten- tional, 4, 6, 20, 23 n. 137, 54, 57 n. 426, n. 32, n. 42, n. 70, n. 106, n. 528, n. 548. Freedom of the will, 9. Generalizations, n. 500. Good, idea of, 16 ff., 74. Gorgias, 22, 31, 32, 25 n. 167, 77. Government, forms of, 62. Happiness and virtue, 25 ff. Hedonism, 20. Hedonistic calculus, 23. Heraclitus, 28, 68. Hippias Minor, 10 n. 38. Ideas, theory of, 27 ff. ; diffi- culties of, 36, 52, 84; not concepts merely, 29, 30, 38, 39; not thoughts of God, 30, 38, 65j n. 512 ; origin of, 32; in late" dialogues, 37 ff. ; and numbers, 83 ff. Isocrates, 71, 72, 77. Laches, 15, n. 603. Laws, 85 ff. Lie, voluntary and involun- tary. 10 n. 38. Love (epu/?), 19 ff. Lysis, 18, 19. Materialism, 68, 69, n. 283. Matter or space, not firi 6v, 38, n. 502, n. 503. Merw, 32, 33, 77. Mi) Of, fallacy of, 53 ff. Method (icaT eifiij, etc.) 51. Minor dialogues, dramatic, 13, 15. Negative dialectic, goes too far, 17 ff. 'OvofJ-ara and p^/xara, 56. Parmenides, 57 ff., 34, 36, 37. ndvTO. pel, 68. Phcedo, 35, 41, 77. Phoedrus, 71 ff., 19. Philebus, 17 n. 93, 22, 23, 43, 46, 63 ff. Pleasure, 22; negativity of, 23, 24 ; in mind, not body, 45,46. Poetry, Plato's attitude- toward, 81 ff. Political art, 17, 62. PoUticus, 60 ff., 44. Protagoras, 12 n. 48, 20, 21, 77. Psychology, 40 ff., 66 ff. (Thecetetus) . Psychological terminology, 47 ff. Republic, 78 ff., 14, 26, 35 n. 238, 41, 42, 55, 51, n. 375. Socratic ignorance, 6; in minor dialogues drama- tic, 15. Socratic paradoxes, 9. Soul, immortality of, 40 ff., 80. Soul, tripartite, 42. Sophist, 50 ff. Sprach-Statistik, 1, 5, 7 n. 10,88. SufaiTioi/, n. 461. 2u0po(riivTj, 15. Symposium, 19, 77. Temperaments, the two, 12 n. 59, 13 n. 70, 62 n. 481. Thecetetus, 66 ff., 33, 55. Timceus^ 37, 88. Utilitarianism, 20 ff. Vice, involuntary, 9. Virtue, is knowledge, 10; unity of, 10; coincides with happiness, *25 ff.