j^-*^A5.ois,H-i+ VTiDi^- Cornell University Library arV11595 introduction to politicai science: mill Hill III 1 1 , 3 1924 031 323 219" olin.anx Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924031323219 INTEODUCTION TO POLITICAL SCIENCE INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL SCIENCE TWO SERIES OF LECTURES SiE J. E. SEELEY, K.C.M.G., Litt.D. EEGIOS PROFESSOR OF MODERN HISTORY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE FELLOW OF GONVILLE AND CAIUS COLLEGE ; FELLOW OF THE ROYAL HISTORICAL SOCIETY, AND HONORARY MEMBER OF THE HISTORICAL SOCIETY OF MASSACHUSETTS fLoniott MACMILLAN AND CO. AND NEW YORK 1896 T All Hghts reserved EDITOE'S PEEFACE Elementary instruction in Political Science — re- garded not merely as a subject cognate to history, for which the study of history is a preparation, but as a method of studying history itself — formed for many years an important part of the teaching given by the late Sir John Seeley as Professor of History in Cam- bridge. Usually, however, this instruction was given not in formal expository lectures, but in a weekly conversational class. His manner of conducting this class has been clearly described by one who attended it — Mr. J. E. Tanner — in the English Historical Review for July 1895 (p. 512). I quote a portion of his description : — His old pupils carry with them grateful recollections of his " Conversation Class." The subject was political science studied by way of discussion, and discussion under the reverential conditions that prevailed resolved itself into question and answer — Socrates exposing the folly of the Athenians. It was mainly an exercise in the defi- nition and scientific use of terms. What is liberty? Various definitions of the term would be elicited from the class and subjected to analysis. The authors of them VI INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL SCIENCE would be lured by a subtle cross-examination into tbem- selves exposing their inconsistencies. Then the professor would take up his parable. He would first discuss the .different senses in which the term had already been used in literature. . . . From an examioation of inconsistent accounts the professor would proceed to the business of building up by a gradual process, and with the help of the class itself, a definition of his own. ... It was not told us on authority as something to remember, but we assisted ourselves at the creation of it. Thus it became a possession to be enjoyed with a title analogous to the title of authorship. It took an hour to define liberty, but the leisurely process had the highest educational value. The discussions thus described were repeated weekly, year after year, with new sets of students ; while Seeley's expository lectures — which were also delivered usually once a week during term-time — • were for the most part on special historical subjects, and thus bore no close relation to the matters treated in the conversation class. Tvnce, however, he thought it useful to deviate from his ordinary plan, and treat political science in a course of expository lectures : first, in two series of lectures, occupying respectively the Michaelmas and Lent terms of the academic year 1885-86; and again in a course of half the length, delivered in the Michaelmas term of 1891. ^ When Lady Seeley consulted me as to the desir- ^ This second course was repeated, without much change, in the year 1893, illness having compelled him to make an exception to his principle of composing a new set of lectures every year. PKEFACE VU ability of giving to the world some part of the numerous sets of lectures which her husband had left behind completely ■written, it seemed clear to me that our first choice ought to fall on one of the two courses on Political Science ; as representing a funda- mentally important part of his work as a teacher, and expressing, more fully and systematically than any of his writings hitherto published, his general view of the true aims and method of historical study. The difficulty was to choose between the two courses above mentioned. Had they been of equal length, I should, as a matter of course, have chosen the later. But, after carefully comparing the two courses, I found, on the one hand, that the general views expressed in both were in the main the same ; while, on the other hand, the compression of the subject into a single term's lectures had neces- sitated the omission, or a comparatively meagre treat- ment, in the later course, of many topics of interest which were fully discussed in the earlier course. On the whole, therefore, it seemed to me best to pub- lish the earlier and longer course ; but, at the same time, to incorporate in it as far as possible such portions of the later lectures as appeared to indicate any change of view either as to the matters discussed or as to the manner in which they should be treated. This incorporation has been effected in two different ways : some passages from the later course have been viii INTBODUCTION TO POLITICAL SCIENCE added in the form of notes or appendices ; in other cases I thought it best to substitute the later passages for the earlier, in order to avoid wearisome repeti- tions. The method of substitution is used almost solely in Lectures VI. and VII. of the first series in this volume; the latter of which, as here printed, is in fact mainly composed of Lecture VI. in the 1891 course. This extensive transfer appeared to me necessary, in order to represent the later views of the author ; since I found that — in spite of the severe limitations of space under which he worked in composing the later course — he had treated the topics discussed in the lecture in ques- tion much more fully than in the longer course of 1885-86. I therefore inferred that in 1891 he would A fortiori have regarded the earlier treatment as too scanty for the longer course. A further change was rendered necessary by this substitution ; for there remained a fragment of the older Lecture VII., which had to be retained, because it commenced a discussion continued in Lecture VIII. As this fragment could not well stand alone, I thought it best to combine it with the original Lecture VIII. This combination led to the excision of certain pas- sages, — chiefly repetitions which had been caused by the division of the subject between two lectures; and it also rendered it necessary for me to compose a couple of opening sentences for the new Lecture PREFACE IX VIII., as the connection of thought had been broken by the large transfer of matter from the 1891 course in Lecture VII. Further, I have not hesitated to make one or two minor consequential changes of phrase which appeared to be rendered necessary by the insertions that I have just described, in order to prevent slight inconsistencies between the earlier and later expressions of the writer's views. I have also here and there omitted repetitions more suitable to an oral lecture than to a book, and once or twice altered the position of sentences; and, generally speaking, have made such corrections as I thought it probable that the author would have made before publishing the lectures. In the books prepared by himself for publication, Seeley was, as I know, un- sparing of pains in rewriting such portions as did not come up to his ideal. I have felt, therefore, that it would be unjust to his memory to let this posthumous book go forth without such correction of inadvertencies as I was able to make. No reader can feel more strongly than I do how inadequate a substitute this is for his own revision. In reading these lectures it is important to bear in mind that, being written for oral delivery, they were composed on a plan materially different from that which would be appropriate in a manual of political science designed to be read. Their aim was not to impart a complete system, but to communicate X INTEODUCTION TO POLITICAL SCIENCE a method, and to excite the hearers to an independent exercise of thought in applying it. It is from this point of view that the lecturer's incisive and un- sparing criticism of current notions and accepted generalisations should be judged : since even those who may think it occasionally somewhat one-sided can hardly refuse to admit the stimulating quality of this criticism. I do not mean to suggest that Seeley ever artificially forced his ideas into a para- doxical form ; such a procedure would have been incompatible with his habitual sincerity and his ideal of academic duty. But the conversations, always deeply interesting, which I from time to time had with him on different subjects at which he was work- ing, led me to think that truth was apt to come to him in the garb of paradox — using the word in its strict sense; that the new ideas which his original and penetrating intellect developed had a natural tendency to assume, quite spontaneously, a form strongly opposed to the popular drift of thought on the subject; and that it required a subsequent de- liberate effort to qualify and reduce this opposition. As regards the general view that these lectures enforce and illustrate — the two-sided doctrine (1) that the right method of studying political science is an essentially historical method, and (2) that the right method of studying political history is to study it as material for political science — I think it may be said PEEFACB XI that this was one of his deepest and most permanent convictions. He announced it in the inaugural lecture which he delivered on his accession to the Chair of History in Cambridge ; and it grew stronger and clearer as years went on, and assiduous study en- larged his knowledge and deepened his insight into the development of historic polity. Indeed, he once said to me that he valued the wide popularity of his Expansion of England, not only for the effects that might be hoped from it in furthering practical aims that he had at heart, but also not less because the book seemed to have proved itself a persuasive ex- ample of his method : because it had brought home to Englishmen throughout the Empire, that, in order to know what England ought to be and do now, they must study what she has been and done in the past. In conclusion, I must express my gratitude for the help ungrudgingly afforded me in preparing this book for the press by Mr. B. E. Hammond, Fellow of Trinity College, and Mr. J. E. Tanner, Fellow of St. John's College, whom I have consulted throughout on all points of importance, and whose advice and suggestions have been of much value to me. I have also to thank Lady Seeley for the kindness with which she has rendered my task as easy as it was possible to render it, and for her aid in revising the proofs. H. SIDGWICK. Cambridge, Jammry 1896. EIEST SEEIES (Michaelmas Term 1885) LECTURE I It has been my practice ever since I was appointed to this chair — now sixteen years ago — to give in- struction in two subjects which are commonly held to be altogether distinct, — in history proper and in that which hitherto in the scheme of our Tripos has been called Political Philosophy, and which it is now proposed to call Political Science. But I have not usually adopted the same method of teaching in the two subjects. History proper I have expounded in formal, public lectures ; Political Philosophy I have taught by means of a Conversation Class. This plan of conversation I was led to adopt in consequence of the want of a satisfactory text-book to which I could refer students. I hold, indeed, that the conversational method is always useful in teaching a subject which requires exact thinking and a precise use of terms. But it is not only useful ; it seems to ^ B iS INTRODUCTION TO lbot. me indispensable where the subject is of this kind, and yet has never been mapped out, arranged, and put before the student in a methodical text-book. Political science, as I conceived it, was in this pre- dicament. Such books as Aristotle's Politics did not seem to me adapted to the needs of the present generation of students, while the manuals that have recently appeared either did not seem to me satisfactory or were for one reason or another not accessible to the Cambridge student. But the conversational method is only appropriate to a small class, and there are some reasons why it is desirable occasionally to expound the subject also in formal lectures. I have done so in former years, though not very recently. I propose to do so again in this year. But this time I shall try the experiment of treating the same subject at the same time, both by the conversational method in a conversation class, and formally in this lecture-room, so that during this year my conversation class will bear the same relation to this class as the individual teaching by examination papers and conversation bears to their public lectures in the work of my colleagues. Perhaps on this announcement a thought may occur to some of you which, if j'ou put it into words, would take this form. " What ! you are a Professor of History ; and yet you tell us that during this year you are not going to lecture on history at all, but on I POLITICAL SCIENCE 3 a different subject, — Political Science or Political Philosophy ! " Now, if I heard this objection from you I should not admit it to be well-founded. I should answer. Certainly I am going to lecture on Political Science, but when did I say that I was not going to lecture on history? True it is that I do not intend this year to select a period and investigate or narrate the occurrences which took place within it. That no doubt would be lecturing on history, but there is another way of doing so. And in my opinion, to lecture on political science is to lecture on history. Here is the paradox — I use the word in its original sense of a proposition which is really true, though it sounds false — which I have tried for many years to commend to the consideration of students commencing the study of history in this University. Even when my subject did not allow me to dwell long upon it, I have taken pains to state it fully at least once in an opening lecture. But in this course, which is devoted to political science, I shall not content myself with a mere statement. It is my point of departure; it is the first aphorism in the system of political science which I am about to expound to you, that this science is not a thing distinct from history but inseparable from it. To call it a part of history might do some violence to the usage of language, but I may venture to say that 4: INTRODUCTION TO leot. history without political science is a study incomplete, truncated, as on the other hand political science without history is hollow and baseless — or in one word: History without political science has no fruit ; Political science without history has no root. To establish the truth of this aphorism will be the object of the present lecture. I need not make any long introduction to show that if true it is important. History has usually been taken to be concerned simply with facts. Evidently it would be entirely transformed if we came to consider the facts estab- lished by history as mere raw material out of which a science was to be constructed. Such a view would on the one side impart a new interest of a very vivid kind to historical research ; on the other hand, perhaps you may think it would deprive history in a great degree of the peculiar charm which it has hitherto possessed. Hitherto there has hung about historical study a delightful atmosphere of leisure and enjoyment J it has had a dainty flavour of romance, curiosity, poesy, which we may regret to see replaced by the potent, pungent, acrid taste of science. Whether the los? would be more than counterbalanced by the gain is a further question; in any case, the revolution which would take place in the study could not but be momentous, and for you who are on the threshold of the study it is all I POLITICAL SCIENCE 5 important to decide in what spirit you will apply yourselves to it. Now you have always, I am sure, heard history spoken of as a serious study. " How delightful it is," may be a reflection more frequently made because it is not quite so obvious; that a knowledge of the great events which have happened in the world must needs be in the highest degree useful and instructive is perhaps seldom expressly stated because it is scarcely ever denied or doubted. It appears, then, that we do not quite literally investigate historical facts for their own sake : a knowledge of them, we hold, is useful ; that is, it is a means to an end. But in what way is it useful? "In a hundred ways," we shall be told ; but when we press for a more precise answer we shall find that the conviction that history must be useful is based more or less immediately upon the principle that what has occurred may occur again. There is regularity in human affairs; the same causes will in the main produce always the same efi'ects ; evidently, therefore, he who wishes to be wise, since wisdom consists in understanding the relation of causes and effects, cannot do better than inquire into the past experience of mankind, or, in other words, cannot do better than study history. Now this argument is obvious enough, but what I wish you to observe is that the application of it is not in any way confined to what -^e now call speci- 6 INTRODUCTION TO leot. ally history. It is the fundamental argument which applies equally to all knowledge, which makes know- ledge a useful and indispensable thing, and justifies the ancient saying of the wise man, " Wisdom is the principal thing ; therefore get wisdom : and with all thy getting get understanding." We live in a universe which proceeds according to regular laws ; the same causes produce the same effects ; therefore if we would guide ourselves aright we must register what we observe, then we must compare our observations and generalise upon them ; so we shall obtain general laws, and thus the knowledge of the past will lead us to a knowledge of the future. I need not here enter into the old controversies about innate ideas, truths of the reason, truths given in consciousness and the like. It is enough that the vast mass of our knowledge is inductive or founded on the observation of facts. If, then, we take history to mean the record of what has happened, we may say that the vast mass of our knowledge is founded upon history. It does not matter what inductive science you select, its conclusions will be found to be based upon history. Our astronomic knowledge is based upon facts which at a given time and place were observed by this or that astronomer to take place in the heavens ; our knowledge of the laws of hfe, though it may now take a general form, rests ultimately upon facts in the history of this or that plant or animal 1 POLITICAL SCIENCE 7 which were registered by some naturalist, that is, some historian of nature. The practice has gradually been formed of appro- priating the word history to the record of a particular sort of facts. But it is worth while to remember that the word need not be, and originally was not, thus appropriated, and that in the main facts of all kinds are recorded in the same way and for the same pur- pose. Plato says Natural History where we should say Natural Science ; Pliny's great collection of wonderful and curious natural facts is called " Historia Naturalis,'' and till quite recently it was usual to call zoology by the name of Natural History. It has now become the custom to exclude from books called historical a vast number of facts, in themselves memorable and curious, on the ground that they are more fitly recorded in books of science. We do not look in a history of England for a record of the in- teresting meteorological or biological phenomena that may have occurred in England. We have come to think that facts of this kind do not belong to history. And yet if history registers events in order to discover laws, and so to guide the life of man, it ought certainly to register these, for precisely such observations have led to the great discoveries in natural science. And in the infancy of history such facts filled a large space. In the earlier books of Livy, where he draws from the most ancient sources accessible to 8 INTEODUCTION TO LBOT. him, there frequently occur paragraphs in which he sums up the curious natural occurrences that had been noted in a particular year, how at Privernum a bull had been heard to speak, how at Corioli blood had fallen for rain. Now assuredly we have not become less, but infinitely more curious in the observation of nature than those primitive chroniclers ; we may smile at their credulity, but we respect them most sincerely for registering what natural occurrences they fancied themselves to have witnessed. Why, then, do modern historians omit to register occurrences of this kind ? The answer is obvious. Such occurrences are now sifted and registered with a care which in those remote periods was unknown, but they are not registered by historians. The phenomena that occur in the world have been divided into classes, and to each class a special body of investigators and narrators is assigned. Of occurrences such as I just now instanced, one would fall to the meteorologist, another to the physi- ologist. And there follows upon this change of prac- tice a peculiar alteration in the case of the words " history " and " historical." These occurrences, which originally were regarded as historical or belonging to history, do not, properly speaking, in any way cease to be so because they are recorded under a particular heading by a particular class of specialists. And yet we cease to speak of them as historical. We give I POLITICAL SCIENCE 9 them henceforth the name of the science which deals with them. They are supposed > to be taken away from history and appropriated by science. We speak of them now as meteorological or biological facts, not as historical facts belonging to meteorology or biology. History, then, as the word is now used, is the name of a residuum which has been left when one group of facts after another has been taken possession of by some science. We are accustomed to think that his- tory records the facts which concern human beings, and this is roughly true, but it is only true because what we call natural science was earlier successful and established itself earlier on an inductive basis than the sciences that concern man. Even now there are a vast number of facts concerning man which we do not consider to fall within the province of the historian, — physiological and pathological facts for in- stance. We do not expect from the historian infor- mation about cases of disease, however important they may be, except where an epidemic has appeared on so large a scale as to produce social and political effects. This is because the sciences of physiology and pathology have successfully taken possession of some classes of facts relating to man. Other sciences are already grappling with other human phenomena. Now suppose these sciences to be successful, in the end, I ask you, what will become of history ? — that is of general history, history proper, or history pure and 10 INTRODUCTION TO LECT. simple.^ When each new human science has carved out a province for itself, will not the residuwm at last entirely disappear ? Political economy is dealing with the facts of industry, the science of jurisprudence is dealing with the facts of law. Already the historian feels that on economical questions, for example, he can afford to be sketchy and summary, because he may refer the reader for fuller information to economical authorities. Now it is only reasonable to suppose that all these sciences will make rapid pro^ gress. Will not the day then soon come when on almost every subject the historian will be able to refer to some scientific authority who has spared him the trouble of minute exposition, who, in fact, has told his story better than he could tell it himself ? And will not this day be the eve of another day when the historian will feel himself to be superfluous altogether, when we shall cease to speak of human history as we have already almost ceased to speak of natural history ? Darm wird einst anisgesungen Das alte ewige Lied. The ^ "A distinction must be drawn between two different kinds of history, of which the one may be called special and the other general. There is scarcely any department of human activity which may not be made the subject of history in the special sense. We have histories of art, of science, of invention and discovery. We might well have a history of history. To this special kind of history there is no end, nor can any one say that it is not legiti- mate, or that it may not produce most important results. Yet uo one calls this sort of history by the simple name of history. His- tory proper is understood to be general history ; you know very well that I could not in my character as Professor announce a course of lectures on the history of the Tuscan schools of painting." — (Prom the First Lecture of the 1891 Course.) 1 POLITICAL SCIENCE 11 old, endless tale will then be told, and history will be swallowed up in science. When I picture this sort of disappearance of his- tory, you will understand that I only mean history considered as a grave serious pursuit, a study for grown men. Some writers have lately protested — one of them, Mr. Birrell, did me the honour to select me personally as the object of his attack — that history has no relation whatever to any kind of science, and cannot therefore be affected by any conceivable advance of science, that Clio is a Muse, that in other words men have a natural joy in great actions and great events, and that history is only the natural literary expression of this joy. According to this view, the historian is only an eloquent, sympathetic narrator, and will always have his function so long as men feel and enjoy; history, like poetry, will exist as long as human beings exist. I do not care to question this, and far be it from me to undervalue literature and poetry. As a matter of course men will always enjoy lively narratives of famous events, but considered as a mere branch of literature I do not think that history can even rank high. The great ancient historians have been ad- mired partly no doubt for their eloquence, but mainly for their truth and depth. That is, they have been on one side, as it were, literary men, and on the other side men of science. The development I have 12 INTRODUCTION TO LBCT. described would deprive them of the latter character and leave them only the former. If all the more serious part of their work — investigation and gene- ralisation — were taken out of their hands by specialists and no function left to them but that of eloquent narration, their importance would sink very much. Their works would contain no solid information that could not be found more fully and precisely given in the works of the specialists, and as mere literary artists they would be at a great disadvantage com- pared to the poets and romancers. For they would not be allowed to invent or embellish ; they would be in strict bondage to fact ; and that is not a pre- dicament in which artistic genius can display itself. They would be mere popularisers, and their narra- tives would be in request chiefly among young people. Certainly history, so understood, could have no place in a university. However, I fully concede to Mr. Birrell that history of the old kind will pro- bably always subsist as a somewhat insignificant branch of literature. It is history, the great teacher of wisdom, the great instructress of statesmen, that I am thinking of, and it does seem to me that the residuum which now exists must go the way of the rest, and that the time is not very distant when a science will take pgssession of the facts which are still the undisputed property of the historian. But I also think that the change I POLITICAL SCIENCE 13 will not be so great as might be supposed, for this reason, that the group of facts still remaining will not dwindle gradually or be distributed among a number of sciences, but will become altogether the property of a single science. What science 1 Political Science. You see, then, what I meant when I said that to lecture on Political Science is to lecture on History. In my view a science has for a very long time past been insensibly growing up by the side of history, and every one has perceived that it has some connection with history, and must draw a great part of materials from history ; this is political science. On the other side, within the department of history itself, it has been more and more felt that the accumulation of facts suggested the possibility of a science ; what was to be done with them if no generalisations were possible which might reduce them to order ? But all this time it has been over- looked that the science which lay so near to history was itself the very science which historians were calling out for. And now I must tell you more distinctly what I mean by political science. We start of course from the fact that man is a social or gregarious animal, but we deal, not with the sociability of man simply, but with one peculiar phenomenon connected with it. For the sociability of 14 INTRODUCTION TO lbot. man has many aspects, and brings into existence several sciences ; for example, the science of language and economic science. The phenomenon in question is this. As a matter of course human beings, like other animals, are united together in families, and we might be prepared to find the family tie stronger and the family organisation somewhat more developed in them than in inferior animals. But we observe something more, something which, when we think philosophically,- — that is, when we contemplate it as if we had not been familiar with it all our lives, — is very surprising and unexpected. We find that men have another bond of union beyond that of the family, and another higher organisation. In nature there is seldom breach of continuity, and so this higher organisation is seldom quite dis- tinct from the family, and sometimes might be explained away as if it were not distinct at all. Usually, however, it is tolerably distinct. Almost in any place, in any circumstances where a human being might be found, if you questioned him you would find that he considered himself to belong to some large corporation which imposed duties and conferred rights upon him. Each man has a name which belongs to himself alone, and another name which he has in common with all other members of his family ; but if you would describe him and class him sufficiently you must learn a further fact about I POLITICAL SCIENCE 15 him, you must know to what state he belongs. State 1 But what is state 1 When I say "I am an Englishman," what do I mean? Does it refer to my parentage or family? Well ! I cannot absolutely say that it does not. I regard myself as being in some sort of kin to other Englishmen, as though we were all alike descended from some primitive Anglus. I feel this very strongly in the presence of foreigners, for I find that they speak a different language and seem both mentally and bodily of a somewhat different type. But whether it really is so is after all of no practical importance. I am an Englishman, and should be so just as much if my ances- tors were Frenchmen. And yet that I am an English- man and not a Frenchman is all-important to me. Mankind fall into classes in different ways accord- ing to the observer's point of view. The anthropol- ogist divides the species according to some bodily difference ; e.g. Blumenbach according to colour, Eetzius according to the shape of the skull, recent anthropologists according to the character of the hair. The ethnologist introduces new distinctions founded upon language, and these are distinctions unknown to the anthropologist. He talks of Indo-Germanic and Semitic races ; but the anthropologist protests that he knows of no such distinction, and that to him all the races called Indo-Germanic and all the races called Semitic appear to belong to one variety. 16 INTEODUCTION TO lbot. Now in political science the groups are different again. Language, bodily conformation, decide nothing here. We and the Channel Islanders speak diiFerent lan- guages, we and the Anglo-Americans speak the same; but in political science we and the Channel Islanders are in the same class, we and the Anglo-Americans in different classes, because here, men are grouped according to states. The division of mankind into states is of vast importance, first, because of its universality; secondly, because of its intensity and the momentous conse- quences it has had. When I speak of its universality I admit that I stretch considerably the meaning commonly given to the word state. In the Greek or Eoman, or in the European sense of the word, the state has been and is by no means universal ; on the contrary, it is somewhat rare among mankind. But we want some one word to denote the large corpora- tion, larger than the family yet usually connected with the family, whatever form it may assume, and the word state is the only word which can be made to serve this purpose. Sometimes it would be better called a tribe or clan, sometimes a church or religion, but whatever we call it the phenomenon is very universal. Almost everywhere men conceive them- selves as belonging to some large corporation. They conceive themselves too as belonging to it for life and death ; they conceive that in case of need I POLITICAL SCIENCE 17 this corporation may make unlimited demands upon them ; they conceive that they are bound, if called upon, to die for it. Hence most interesting and memorable results follow from the existence of these great corporations. In the first place, the growth and development of the corporations themselves, the various forms they assume, the various phases they pass through ; then the interaction of these corporations upon each other, the wars they wage, the treaties they con- clude, all the phenomena of conquest and federation ; then again the infinite effects produced upon the individual by belonging to such a corporation, those infinite effects which we sum up in the single expres- sive word civilisation ; here, you see, is a field of speculation almost boundless, for it includes almost all that is memorable in the history of mankind, and yet it is all directly produced by the fact that human beings almost everywhere belong to states. This peculiar human phenomenon then, the state in the largest acceptation of the word, distinct from the family though not unconnected with it, distinct also from the nation though sometimes roughly coincid- ing with it, is the subject of political science. Or since the distinctive characteristic of the state, wherever it appears, is that it makes use of the arrangement or contrivance called government, we may say that this science deals with government as c 18 INTEODUCTION TO lect. political economy deals with wealth, as biology deals with life, as algebra deals with numbers, as geometry deals with space and magnitude. Such is the subject of the science. The problems it presents will evidently arrange themselves under two heads. First will come those presented by the internal structure and development of the state itself, the manner in which government enters into it, and the machinery through which government works; then will follow the problems of the interaction of one state upon another, or the external action of the state. And now what shall be our method in dealing with these problems'! You know how much depends on method in scientific investigation. Especially you know what a peculiar difficulty rises when we investi- gate human phenomena. For here we are under an almost irresistible temptation to mix up what ought to be with what is. As we know it to be all-important that we should go right in political action, we are tempted to think that political science, if it is to be worth anything, must show us what is right, and under this strong prepossession we are apt to enter on the inquiry with no other category in our minds but the category of right and wrong. If we set out in this way we shall make it our object to find the perfect or ideal state. Our first step will be to ask for what purpose a state exists, and having determined I POLITICAL SCIENCE 19 this to our satisfaction, we shall proceed to inquire what institutions, laws, and practices are best adapted for the attainment of this object. This is the ancient method of treating political science of which Plato and Aristotle have left us examples. We may adopt quite a different method and treat states just as if they were natural growths, just as if they were trees or animals. We may look at them, as it were, from outside and register impartially what we see as if we had no personal concern in it. The naturalist does not proceed at all in the method I just now described. He does not, in considering plants, begin by asking what is the object for which a plant exists, and proceed to deduce what must be the characteristics of the perfect plant. He hardly professes to know whether plants have an object at all ; certainly he does not profess to decide that one plant is better than another. He has nothing to do with the category of right and wrong, but contents himself with (1) classifying the plants he observes ; (2) with analysing the structure of the plant, and dis- tinguishing the functions of the several organs ; (3) with tracing its growth and development, and noting the morbid affections to which it may be liable ; (4) with speculating on the origin of the different species and on the nature of vegetable life in general. Now I think you will see at once that it is possible to study states in just the same way. These, too, can 20 INTRODUCTION TO LECT. be classified, the diiferent organs of the state can be described and their functions noted; phases of de- velopment and morbid conditions present themselves in states, and the theory of evolution can be applied to states. But, you will say, to proceed thus is very strange and unnatural. After all, a state is not a mere natural production, but the result of human will, invention, and ingenuity. After all, states do fall under the category of right and wrong ; some insti- tutions, some laws are good and others bad ; if it were not so, how vain would be all the trouble we take, all the excitement we undergo, about politics ; and if it is so, the all-important thing is to distinguish the right from the wrong, and in comparison with this all classification and analysis are irrelevant and unimportant. Now it is quite true that states are to a certain extent products of conscious contrivance, or, in one word, machines. But it is equally true that they are not mere machines. It has become a political axiom that states are not made but grow. They have their roots in the instinctive unconscious part of human nature, and for this reason, though they ought not to be treated solely as natural productions, yet they ought to be treated as such. Moreover, experience has taught us in almost every department of thought the danger of too much haste, I POLITICAL SCIENCE 21 of attacking too directly and too eagerly the problems which it is practically urgent to solve. Thus the first theorists in medicine wanted a universal panacea, the first chemists wanted to turn everything into gold. When we look back upon the first modern essays in political science, the theories of an original contract, and the patriarchal theory, we see illustrations quite as striking of the same mistake. However this may be, it is sufficient for my immediate purpose that states can be treated in the same way as plants or as animals. Let us now inquire what aspect our science would wear if it pursued this method. Inductively pur- sued, political science would live and move among historical facts. It would begin by collecting these facts with great industry and verifying them with most scrupulous care, for it would be keenly alive to the danger of confounding mere rumour or legend or party-statement with such facts as science can recog- nise. Next, it would not attempt to bolster up with the facts so obtained some preconceived theory ; all such theories it would put on one side, and honestly wait to see what theories arose naturally out of the facts. For this purpose it would begin by grouping and classifying the facts, placing together, for example, such facts as bear on the internal growth of states, and in another group such as relate to their external action or to the interaction of states upon each other. It would not be wonderful, considering the intricacy 22 INTRODUCTION TO LEOT. of the subject, if this work of classiiication proved to be very difficult and ponderous, as in some other sciences, especially botany and zoology. But further, we know that the inductive sciences obtain their facts in two different ways. In some cases it is by experiment, that is, the observer creates artificially the facts he wishes to observe. But in other cases, owing to the peculiar nature of those facts, this is impossible. For example, in chemistry experiment is possible ; if we want to know what affinity there is between two kinds of matter we bring them together and observe the result. But in astronomy experiment is impossible ; the sun and the moon are not at our beck and call ; we must wait on them, they will not wait on us. Now in this latter class of sciences observation, being the only resource, requires to be pursued with the utmost industry and care. Everything here depends upon a large supply of — what shall I say ? I was going to say "historical" — facts carefully observed and exactly registered. Having established, then, that our political science is to be inductive, we proceed to inquire whether it can work by experiment or is reduced to depend on observation. And it will be evident at once that in this respect it resembles astronomy rather than chemistry. If we want to discover, for example, what would be the effect of suddenly introducing I POLITICAL SCIENCE 23 democratic institutions into a country, we cannot take a state, pass the necessary Reform Bill in it, and then stand by watching the result. No, all we can do is to study the states that are before us, or those that have left record of themselves from past times. Thus only can we obtain the facts which are essential for our science. Political science, like astronomy, will need an immense supply of trustworthy registered observations. But a state is not, like the sun or moon, a mere physical, but rather a moral, entity. It is not visible to the eye or through a telescope. What is done by it is only done constructively; literally, it is done not by the state but by some individual. Much again is done secretly, and sometimes false accounts of what is done are intentionally laid before the public. Hence the authentication of the facts with which political science deals is far more laborious than in other sciences. Many other causes concur to produce this result. Especially this, that we have before us a vast mass of observations, recorded by various observers at very various periods, which are only partially trustworthy, sometimes because the observers were not scientific, or because they were prejudiced, or because they made their observations rather for amusement than with any serious object, or because they lived when the art of writing was either un- known or little used. We cannot aflford to put all 24 INTEODUCTION TO leot. this mass of observations aside, and yet we cannot use it without subjecting it to tests which in other sciences are not needed, and which have to be invented for the occasion. You will see that this mass of observations of which I speak is neither more nor less than what we call history. All that perplexity about the object of their labours which besets historians, all that perplexity about their method which hampers those who would form a political science, disappear together if we regard history as the mass of facts, brought together by observers who were but half conscious of what they were doing, out of which an inductive science of states is to be constructed. I say these observers have been but half conscious; altogether unconscious they have not been. If you examine history as it is and as it has long been, you will see both by what it records and by what it omits that it is instinctively aware that it is concerned with the state. I have spoken of those large classes of facts which it once recorded but now deliberately omits. There are classes of facts which not deliber- ately but, as it were, instinctively it either omits or passes over slightly. These are sometimes facts of immense importance. The historian of James I.'s reign scarcely mentions Shakspeare's plays ; he says a great deal about the rise and fall of Robert Carr ; the historian of William III. says little about I POLITICAL SCIENCE 25 Newton's discoveries, but a great deal about Fen- wick's plot. Which was more important, Shakspeare or Can-, Newton or Fenwick 1 But the influence of Carr affected, and the plot of Fenwick endangered, the state ; whereas Shakspeare and Newton worked in another region. Historians are instinctively aware that it is not their region. They pass over phenomena of this kind or relegate them to a sup- plementary chapter, though sometimes they under- stand their own correct instinct so little as to ex- press regret that they are obliged to speak of the pomp of kings or the crimes of ambitious warriors, while they pass over greatness more genuine and peaceful triumphs more glorious. There is really nothing to regret in this. The question is not of glory or greatness, but of accurately knowing the laws which govern the organism called the state. Now, government and legislation, and wars and alliances, concern the state, but scientific discoveries or artistic masterpieces do not. When, twenty years ago, Mr. Buckle succeeded in flashing upon the English mind the notion of a science of history, he threatened us with a revolution in historical writing. We were to read henceforth comparatively little about governments and parlia- ments and wars ; history was to resolve itself into a discussion of the physical environment of a people, the climate, the geography, the food. The view I 26 INTEODUCTION TO leCt. present, you see, is diiferent, and it is not at all revolutionary. I do not dispute the importance of those physical inquiries, and the results of them must be used by the historian ; but his own province, according to me, is distinct. He is not an anthro- pologist or an ethnologist, but if I may coin a word, he is a politicise The political group or organism — the state — is his study. On this principle it will appear that historians hitherto, instead of being wrong in the main, have been right in the main. Their researches into legislation and the growth of institutions have laid a firm basis for the first part of political science, which is concerned with the classification and analysis of states. Their investiga- tion of wars, conquests, alliances, federations, have laid a basis for the second part, that which is con- cerned with the action of states upon each other. All that is needed is that they should pursue with clearer purpose the path they already tread. They have been right in the main, but hesitating, and therefore somewhat desultory. They have been haunted with the notion that they were bound to record everything of importance that had hap^ned in a given country ; in short, that their subject was the country, whereas in truth their subject was the state. They have been haunted with the notion that they were literary men, not men of science, that their function was similar to that of the poet, I POLITICAL SCIENCE 27 who works upon the feelings by narrating heroic deeds. It is not wrong that great deeds should be related in noble style. But the notion that this function is inseparably associated with that of the investigator of states, so that the handler of docu- ments, the weigher of evidence, the expert in poli- tical phenomena, the discerner of historical sequence and causation, should be bound to be in his own person also the eloquent narrator, the epic poet or ballad-writer in prose, this notion forgets that we do not live in the days of Herodotus, or Thucydides, or Livy, but in a time of specialised study. There was in those ancient historians a popular element and a scientific element ; these have since been separated and differentiated. We have now the eloquent narrator who at times, as in Carlyle's French Bevolu- tion, may almost rise to the dignity of the epic poet. We have also, but seldom in the same person, the hi^orical scientist. He is a student of the state, but he studies it inductively, that is, by the aid of history. This is what I endeavour to do, and would lead you to do. If we would succeed we must carry on two processes at once. We must think, reason, generalise, define, and distinguish. We must also collect, authenticate, and investigate facts. If we neglect the first process, we shall accumulate facts to little purpose, because we shall have no test by 28 INTKODUCTION TO lect. which to distinguish facts which are important from those which are unimportant ; and of course if we neglect the second process, our reasonings will be baseless, and we shall but weave scholastic cobwebs. But in this course of lectures I lead you through the first process. I speak of the state in general, not of any particular state. And I think you understand by this time why I consider that it belongs to my function, as a Professor of History, to do this. [The following passage, which forms the conclu- sion of the first lecture of the 1891 Course, may be fitly placed here as an Appendix to the present lecture. — Ed. J When on former occasions I have laid this general view of history before my pupils, the objection has some- times occurred to my own mind that if it were really possible, as I suggest, to make the facts of history an in- ductive material out of which to construct a political science, this would have been accomplished long since. There were political speculators in the eighteenth century, such as Montesquieu ; and in the seventeenth there were Locke and Hobbes. While other sciences were established on a solid foundation, why was this one, so important, still kept waiting ? But an answer to this objection also occurred to me. It was this. The inductive basis was wanting. A Montesciuieu or a Locke did not and could not know the history of the world. I mean this more literally than you may suppose. It is surprising how I POLITICAL SCIENCE 29 little sound knowledge of mere Wstorical fact was possessed a hundred or a hundred and fifty years ago. This may be partly estimated from the occasional historical illustra- tions which the writers I have mentioned produce. They are commonly worthless, and betray clearly the infancy of historical criticism, the uncertainty in the handling of authorities, and the newness and rawness of the whole subject. In fact, almost all that we now call history has grown up since that time. If this be so, if history itself he a growth so modern, it is not surprising that the elaboration of a science out of history should be still in a great degree reserved for the future. What was called history in the middle of the eighteenth century was too unsound to form a basis for anything. The case is different now. The present generation has a vast treasure of historical knowledge which is trustworthy and available for the purposes of LECTUEE II I MADE sufficiently clear in my last lecture what is the phenomenon which is to be investigated. Human beings, as we see them around us, are found to be enrolled or regimented in certain large groups which are organised in a peculiar way, held together by the contrivance known as government, and called states. So it is now in the nineteenth century and here in Europe. But when we consult the mass of observa- tions we find that it was so not less many centuries since. Nay, when we bring before us by means of the dead languages the life which was led by human beings two thousand years ago, though we observe many differences, yet in this respect we find that men were the same then that they are now. Ancient men, too, lived in states and submitted to govern- ment. And if we go to countries remote from Europe, to China, which has always been unaffected by western civilisation, or to India, which has usually been so, we still find governments and states. It is true that these ancient or remote states differ very much from those with which we are familiar. LEOT. II INTEODUCTION TO POLITICAL SCIENCE 31 They differ, indeed, more than we readily under- stand. Observers and students, instead of being surprised at the resemblances, have been too much disposed to assume them and exaggerate them. They have taken for granted that men, wherever found, must have kings and nobles and governments like those of Europe. And perhaps some error has crept into history from this cause ; as, for instance, it has recently been maintained that the Spanish accounts of ancient Mexican institutions are too much coloured by Spanish prepossessions. But when all due allowance has been made for this cause of error, we do find states, even if states of a different kind, just as Vre find languages everywhere, though the unlikeness of the Bantu or the Chinese language to Greek or German may be greater than we could at first have conceived possible. In large regions of the globe, however, especially where the soil is ex- ceptionally unfruitful, as in the deserts of Arabia or Central Asia, and in certain mountain districts, we find less of this kind of organisation than elsewhere. Here it is customary to say that states are not found, for it would seem improper to apply that title to the Arabian tribes or to the clans of the Scottish Highlands. It is important on the threshold of the subject to decide whether in our investigation we ought to con- form to this custom. Ought we to say, "Political 32 INTRODUCTION TO LEOT. science concerns itself of course only with civilised states; it cannot be expected to take notice of the wild and confused associations in which savage, or at least barbarous, men may be pleased to live ? " This, indeed, has usually been the position taken in books of political science. All the classification with which we are so familiar, all that is said about monarchies and republics, aristocracies and democracies, does not apply to primitive tribes, or barbarous communities with strange fanatical ways of life. Nay, if you examine the book which has furnished the model to most political speculators, Aristotle's Politics, you will see that he almost excludes from his investiga- tion all states but that very peculiar kind of state which flourished in his own country. Not only is he almost silent about barbarous communities, but even about all states that are not also cities ; and perhaps, indeed, we ought to think that he attached a more restricted meaning than we do to the word Politics, so that it ought not to be translated Science of States, but Science of Cities. But it seems to me that this exclusive way of handling the subject, this intolerant way of pushing on one side the institutions which we disapprove or which excite our disgust, does not suit the inductive method which we have elected to adopt. It is natural and appropriate to those who are inquiring for the perfect state, since it is evident that the most II POLITICAL SCIENCE 33 civilised states fall short of what such investigators want, and that therefore to cast even a look at uncivil- ised states must be a mere waste of time. But we have resolved, for the present at least, to give up the quest of the perfect state. Nor do we even propose at this early stage to pass judgment at all upon the states we study. We content ourselves with distinguishing and arranging the various kinds in the same purely observant spirit which a Liuneeus brought to plants or a Cuvier to animals. Having once elected to take this course, we can no longer think of excluding any state because we do not like it, any more than a naturalist would have a right to exclude plants under the contemptuous name of weeds, or animals under the name of vermin. Accordingly we must throw open our classification to political organisms the most unlike our own and the most unlike those which we approve. The analogy of plants and animals will suggest to us that there are lower as well as higher organisms. Look at the classification of the animal kingdom. When we use the word " animal " we have commonly in mind one of the higher animals — a dog, or a horse, or a lion — though we may be vaguely aware that there are lower organisms which also in strict- ness are animal. But when the classification is made on the true comprehensive principle we find all the, animals with which we are familiar, all which seem fully to deserve the name of animals, confined to D 34 INTKODTJCTION TO lect. one out of the four sub-kingdoms. Actually three parts out of four are assigned to strange outlying organisms in which the vital principle is either but slightly developed or developed in such a manner that the organism bears little external resemblance to what is popularly called an animal, — strange in- sects or flower -like molluscs and sponges. Let us imagine political organisms handled in the same manner ; — it would not be surprising if all the states described by Aristotle, and all the states of modern Europe into the bargain, should yield but a small proportion of the whole number of varieties, while those states less familiar to us, and which our manuals are apt to pass over in silence as barbarous, yielded a far larger number. But this inductive method, though less intolerant, ought to be just as rigorous as the other. It wiU not reject a specimen as bad or as contemptible, but it will reject the most plausible specimen which does not really belong to the class of phenomena under investigation. The zoologist admits all animals, but he excludes that which is not properly animal. On this principle the most barbarous tribe or sept in the most primitive population will have an equal right with ancient Kome or modern England to our atten- tion provided only that it is really of the same kind. But perhaps we may for a moment doubt whether those rude aggregations of men have really anything n POLITICAL SCIENCE 35 in common witli the civilised state. Nobody thinks of applying the word "state" to them; perhaps the simple reason of this is that they are not in any sense states, and have nothing in common with the state. Let us consider this question for a moment. The fundamental fact to which I pointed in my last lecture, which seems so surprising and so pro- foundly deserving of study, is that men should con- ceive themselves as belonging, and belonging in such an intimate and momentous union, to a corporation which is not simply their family. Look at the modern Englishman. He may chance to have no drop of English blood in his veins, and yet we hold that there is actually no sacrifice which England might not, in case of need, demand of him. At the same time, though the tie is not simply, and in a particular case may not be at all, that of kindred, yet it is not wholly distinct from kindred, and in general Englishmen do regard themselves as of kin to each other. The English state may be held together in some degree by a common interest, still it is not a mere company composed of voluntary shareholders, but a union which has its root in the family, and which has grown, and not merely been arranged, to be what it is. Now, it is surely impossible not to admit that this phenomenon, vast and highly de- veloped as it now appears, is in its large features similar to the most primitive and barbarous tribe. 36 INTRODUCTION TO lect. That, too, is a groat association, to which its members are attached for life and death. For that, too, its members fight ; about its interests they debate. In the tribe, too, we can often discover that individuals may have no attachment by kindred to the whole ; they may have come in as slaves and received emancipation, or as foreigners by adoption. And yet in the main and on the whole the tribe is an extension of the family, a family on the large scale. In short, compare the most advanced state with the most primitive tribe, and you will see the same features, though the proportions are different. In the state there is more of mind, in the tribe more of nature. Free-will and intelligent contrivance have more play in the former ; blood and kinship rule in the latter. Still the state has not ceased to a tribe ; kinship still counts for much in it, as the nationality-movement of the present century has strikingly proved. On the other hand, the tribe, wherever we can get information about it, is found to be also in some degree a state. The rigid family organisation always shows itself insufficient, needing to be supplemented by more artificial institutions. Thus, apart from kinship, there is a common characteristic which brings to- gether the most primitive and the most advanced of these associations — I mean the principle of government. Here, again, the proportion may be different — this is what gives rise to varieties — II POLITICAL SCIENCE 37 but the .common characteristic is there on which depends unity of kind. The apparatus of command and obedience has become by familiarity so trivial in our eyes that we may omit to give it the atten- tion it deserves. Yet upon this simple arrange- ment, by which the will of an individual determines the actions, not of himself only, but of a multitude, depends almost everything important in human history : and, as I said before, political science may be called the science which investigates the phenomenon, government. Here, then, is the first peculiarity of a system of political science which is frankly inductive. It begins by putting aside as irrelevant the distinction of barbarous and civilised, and by admitting to an impartial consideration all political aggregates, all societies held together by the principle of government. This is seldom done consistently and uniformly by historical speculators who take the widest view. Most of them abandon only partially the old dogmatic method. They may be less exclusive than the eighteenth-century school, may be prepared to see the good side of medievalism, to appreciate or even over- appreciate some forms of political life which used to be treated with contempt. But the system I put before you goes much further, for it does not ask at all that the phenomena it studies shall be good or noble. It simply wishes to find out as much as 38 INTRODUCTION TO lbct. possible by observation and induction about tbe nature of states and the laws of their development. For this purpose all facts are welcome, and if corrupt or morbid phenomena appear these will have, not indeed the same interest as the phenomena of health, but another interest peculiar to themselves. The only facts which will be unimportant are those which present nothing new, but only confirm in a superfluous manner what was well known already. When we have once got rid of the notion that the tribes and claijs of barbarism are contemptible and unworthy of attention, we obtain a somewhat different view of the state. Before we naturally regarded states, since they were peculiar to civilised people, as being more or less of the nature of inventions, like the art of writing; but now we see that they are more like language itself, that is, that though they may differ infinitely in the intelligence they display, yet they are found uniformly and universally, or nearly so, wherever human beings are found. Everywhere the human being belongs to something which may be called a polity, and is subject to something which may be called a government. How then shall we deal with this universal phenomenon, how shall we set about investigating it? Shall we begin by laying down some grand proposition with respect to the object for which the state exists? This was long usual. The state exists to put down violence and n POLITICAL SCIENCE 39 protect the weak against the strong. It exists to do justice between man and man and to compose differ- ences. It exists to defend the country against foreign invasion. It exists, in fact, to attain any end which we anywhere find the state aiming at. One school urged particularly that a high and noble view should be taken of its functions. It should consider itself to exist for the sake of virtue or of man's highest well- being in whatever way that may be conceived. Another school took a more modest view: holding that the state ought to rest content with keeping order and protecting property, and that the pro- motion of virtue ought to be left to other agencies. This is an example among many how the discussion of high and important subjects falls into a groove in which it moves on interminably, blending with party politics and imparting to these a dignity they sadly want, but settling nothing because it proposes no definite question. Do we want to know what the state should aim at or what it does aim at 1 The first question is quite legitimate, and it is all-important, but it is wholly distinct from the other, and we may add that a general answer to such a question, an answer deduced directly from the abstract idea of the state, is scarcely to be expected. What the state should aim at now is likely to be quite different from what it either did or could aim at in ancient Rome, or Sparta, or Persia, or India. 40 INTRODUCTION TO lbot. I suggest that we should abandon for the present the enterprise of deciding what the state ought to be and to aim at, and consider by way of pure observa- tion what it has actually been. When we do this, and especially when we take note of the more primi- tive forms of the state, we may surely doubt whether we ought to speak so glibly of the object of the state. We do not speak of the object of a tree or an animal. Now certainly the state 'is not so purely a natural product as a tree or an animal ; still it is in part a natural product, and to the extent that it is a natural product it must be said to be in the strict sense without an object. Nay, further, long after its development has begun to be influenced by human will, conscious intelligence continues to be wanting ; the will that acts in it is mere instinct. So that only states that are far advanced and that are composed of modern men can be treated in the abstract method, can be referred to and judged by a theoretic standard. But if this method is not satisfactory, what other method shall we adopt 1 In what way shall we bring the mass of facts which history and observation present to us into some system ? In those subjects which we are able to contemplate calmly, because they do not immediately affect our interests or excite our feelings, the first step which science takes is to arrange the phenomena in classes. Some little classification has to be done at the com- II POLITICAL SCIENCE 41 mencement of every science. Euclid begins by arranging the simple phenomena with which he has to deal, lines, plain figures three-sided and four-sided, etc., curved figures. The astronomer distinguishes the small number of classes of heavenly bodies, fixed stars and planets, satellites, comets, etc. Now it is evident that political science also will have a task of classification to undertake. Some of the technical terms of political classification are very famous. The names monarchy, aristocracy, democracy, etc., con- stitute almost all the political science most of us know. But there are some sciences in which the prelimin- ary work of classification is not so easily dispatched as in astronomy or geometry. In dealing with i^lants and animals, it has been found so difficult and so large a work as almost to require a separate science to itself. Thus by the side of vegetable physiology, which analyses the plant and deals with the laws of life in its vegetable form, we have botany, a science wholly occupied with the description and classification of plants ; and it was found in the eighteenth century, when the Linnsean system grew up, had its day of acceptance, and then gave way to the natural system introduced by Jussieu and others, that in mere classification difficulties may arise, mistakes may be made, and the higher faculties of the mind may be called into play, scarcely less than in the discovery 42 INTRODUCTION TO LBOi. of laws. Zoology stands in a relation precisely similar to animal physiology. But this has taken place only in certain sciences. The question there- fore suggests itself whether in a science of states we may expect that classification will be soon and easily dispatched, or are to prepare ourselves to overcome serious difficulties. Look at those two sciences of classification ; you will see at once that they deal with phenomena of the same sort, viz. with living organisms. This suggests to us that it must be specially difficult to classify living organisms. And as soon as the suggestion is made we see that it is true. For wherever life is at work it displays itself in vast numbers of organisms which show striking resemblances, but at the same time infinite, almost indescribable differences. "No two men are alike,'' we say. True, but on the other hand no two men are very different. And what is true of men is true of other animals and also of plants. This infinite blending of resemblances with differences is peculiar to living organisms. Nothing similar presents itself in the substances dealt with by inorganic chemistry, still less in the abstractions dealt with by mathematics. And therefore those sciences have no equally difficult problem of classification. For it is precisely where an infinite number of complex individuals exhibit a small number of types and innumerable differences that classification becomes n POLITICAL SCIENCE 43 difficult. We may expect, then, that a science which has to do with living organisms will present a serious problem of classification. Now, are not states living organisms 1 Let us consider what is meant by organism. It is derived from a Greek word meaning a tool, and may be said to mean etymologically much the same thing as a machine, that is, a composite tool. But in English both organ and organism are usually applied, not to mechanical but to living tools. Thus a pair of pincers is a tool or machine for holding ; the hand, which performs the same function but is alive, may be called an organ for holding. Now it is a characteristic of life which has been made very prominent in recent science, that substances informed by it receive what is called organisation, that is, the different parts acquire different capacities and adapt themselves to perform different functions. Each part becomes more or less a living tool or organ. Take something inorganic, e.ff. a stone. One part of it is like another, or if accidentally it differs in shape does not differ in its capacities. But an organic substance, e.g. an animal, is a complex, not merely of parts, but of organs, that is, of tools specially adapted to do work necessary or conducive to the well-being of the whole, — eyes for seeing, feet for walking, and so on. But this is precisely what characterises a state. a INTRODUCTION TO lect. A state is a number of human beings not merely crowded or massed together but organised. This is so strikingly true that all the technical terms applied to physical and political organisation are interchangeable, and the word organisation itself is applied in both departments alike without metaphor. We say a man is a member of a state. What does the word member mean 1 It means " limb." We say the eye or the ear performs a function. What does function mean? It is a political term meaning the discharge of a public office. These examples show how early and how instinctively the analogy between that differentiation which in the physical body creates organs, and that selection which in the state assigns special functions to special men or to special classes, was perceived. The same thing is illustrated by the ancient fable of the Belly and the Members, which you may read either in Livy or in Shakespeare, and by passages well known to all of you in Plato's Republic and in St. Paul's Epistles. There should be no schism in the body, says St. Paul, and Plato says, as we do not say, "A finger has pain," but, "A man has a pain in his finger,'' so in the state we ought not to say, "Some one suffers,'' but "The state suffers in some one." The analogy of course must not be overstrained. There are points of difference as well as points of resemblance between physical and political organisa- 11 POLITICAL SCIENCE 45 tion. Nevertheless, it is no mere fanciful or rhetorical, but a really important analogy. In any case the resemblance is sufficiently close to justify us in anticipating the same difficulty of classification in political that we find in physiological science. The states tha,t we see scattered over the globe at present, or over the wide field of past history, are just as be- wildering in their differences and correspondences as the plants and animals which exercised the classi- fying talent of Linnaeus and of Cuvier. Here as there certain great types strike the eye, but at the same time each state is so complex, the organs are so many and afford room for such infinite small differences, that we find ourselves compelled to make subdivision after subdivision, and often uncertain under what heading some individual ought to be placed. I must confess that I cannot find that very obvious classification which comes down to us from Aristotle, and which is still assumed and accepted almost on all hands, at all satisfactory. Let us consider it. States diflfer, it tells us, according to the number of persons which compose the government. This may consist either of one person, or of a few, or of many. Hence we get three classes, now commonly called Monarchy, Aristocracy, and Democracy. Aristotle, you know, introduced a further distinction, and after admitting these three classes as legitimate under the names 46 INTEODXJCTION TO lect. of Monarchy, Aristocracy, Polity, placed by the side of each a perverted variety of it. The perverted Monarchy he calls Tyranny, the perverted Aristocracy Oligarchy, the perverted Polity he calls Democracy. It seems to me strange that though everything in politics has altered since Aristotle's time, though the states we deal with are marvellously unlike the city communities he had in view, we should still think such a classification as this sufficient. And yet it seems to me that in all our political discussion we still use, and even confine ourselves to, these simple categories. Parties still dispute on Monarchy and Non- Monarchy, which they call Eepublic, on Aristocracy and Democracy : adhering to Aristotle, except in this that whereas he, almost as a matter of course, held Aristocracy to be the best form and classed Democracy among perversions, we have come to speak of Democracy as a sort of ultimate ideal, while the word Aristocracy, in the Aristotelian sense, has gone out of fashion. This classification presented itself almost inevit- ably to Aristotle, who saw on one side Persia and Macedonia exhibiting in a commanding form the Monarchy which he also read of in Homer, while in Greece itself he had before him the sharp contrast between contemporary democracy and contemporary oligarchy. In modern Europe the types are much less simple and distinct. When we take a modern II POLITICAL SCIENCE 47 state and inquire whether it is governed by one, or by few, or by many, we find it usually' impossible to obtain a satisfactory or plain answer. For what are we to think if we find that the functions of govern- ment are divided between a king and one or several assemblies ? Aristotle does not seem to contemplate such a case. In Persia the great king, in Macedonia Philip or Alexander, did not seriously share their power with any assembly ; in Athens no individual and no small assembly could enter into competition with the vast democratic Ecclesia. The contrary is the case almost everywhere in the modern world, as indeed it used to be a boast of English constitution- alists that the English constitution was a beautiful compound of the three forms of government, and had the advantages, with none of the drawbacks, at once of Monarchy, Aristocracy, and Democracy. Since popular institutions were introduced during the present century into almost every continental country, France and Germany and Italy and Spain may, if they choose, make the same boast. . Everywhere, and even in the United States, we find government divided between the one, the few, and the many. England is called a Monarchy, but beside the Monarch it has a House of Lords and a House of Commons. So has Italy, so Prussia, so Belgium, Holland, Spain and Portugal. France and America profess to be democratic Republics, but both beside a popular 4» INTEODUCTION TO lect. assembly have a smaller Senate and also a supreme President. The American Senate has decidedly greater power than our House of Lords, and the American President decidedly greater power than our Monarch. Under which heading then are we to class these states ? It is usual to say England is a Monarchy, America is a democratic Republic. This ought to mean at the very least that in England the One, if not ruling alone, yet has greater power than the Few or the Many, and also greater power than any One in the American Republic. The contrary is the case. The One here has far less power than the Many, and decidedly less power than the One, the President, in America. The accepted classification then tells us, I do not say nothing, but the contrary of the truth.^ The truth is, that though we continue to use the ancient words we do not use them in the ancient sense, but in a sort of metaphorical manner which is not admissible in any discussion which professes to be exact. It is no doubt possible to lay it down that in a given state, whatever the formal institutions may be, the predominant influence is in the hands perhaps ' 111 the corresponding lecture of the 1891 course, after pointing out tlie predominance of the assembly, representing the many, in the so-called English " Monarchy," the author adds — with reference to the principle of Aristotle's double classification — " If we are re- quired to say whether this assembly governs honestly for the good of the whole or pervertedly for its own good, I do not know what answer we could make but the unsatisfactory one, — partly for the one, partly for the other." n POLITICAL SCIENCE 49 of the people, or of a class, or of some influential individual. We may express this popularly and shortly by calling such a state democratic, or aristo- cratic, or monarchic, but we must not dream that by using the words in this metaphorical way we are adhering to the old classification. That classification was intended to be taken literally, and it referred to the recognised institutions of the state, not to some hidden influences which we may be able to detect by looking below the surface. If we go in search of such influences and choose to treat them as deter- mining the character of the state, we adopt a wholly new and very strange principle of classification, even though we may abide by the old technical terms. But if we take those terms, as we ought to do, always in their literal sense, then I think we shall seldom find the old classification serviceable. The case of Rome, for instance, appears almost as com- plex as England. The comitia tribuia, a democratic assembly, sometimes seems quite supreme, but more usually the senate, which is aristocratic. The senate, however, at no time possesses undivided power, for the many, represented by the comitia, and the one, repre* sented by the consuls, have always large competence. And when we travel beyond the ancient city states, and go to the medieval or modern states, an instance of government in the hands either of one, or of a few, or of many, is seldom to be found. In one or two 50 INTRODUCTION TO lect. cases all power has been thrown by exceptional causes into the hands of an individual, and in some small and poor communities, lost to view among barren mountains, what little government is needed has been done by the many. Otherwise government has been a complex thing, and has been distributed among a number of individuals and assemblies. Some func- tions are almost everywhere assigned to the one, others almost everywhere to the many ; almost every- where, too, there has been found occasion for select councils representing valuable qualifications possessed only by the few. ''* But even if this old classification were valuable, who can for a moment regard it as sufficient ? Do states differ only or chiefly in the number of their rulers 1 In the old histories of Greece or Eome the writers seem so much preoccupied by thoughts of republican liberty that they quite overlook a peculiarity of those ancient states which might seem even more interesting and obvious. They seem scarcely to notice that those states are cities and not countries. What an enormous, what a pregnant difference ! Ought not this to enter into our classification 1 Ought we not to say, There are not only aristocracies and democracies; there are also city-states and country- states. To the former class belong the famous states of antiquity, the states which Aristotle studied ; to the latter almost all the states of modern Europe. II POLITICAL SCIENCE 51 This is now one of the great fundamental distinctions of political science, but it was almost overlooked in the speculations of the eighteenth century, except where it was exaggerated by Kousseau. Again, take a government like that temporal state of the Pope which was taken from him in 1870. A serviceable classification would seize the dominant peculiarity of this and bring it into the same list with other governments which are really of the same kind. But how can a classification which only inquires after the number of rulers do this 1 It can only discover that the government in question is a monarchy, and therefore to be classed along with the government of Louis XIV. or that of Queen Victoria. Surely this arrangement will not help us much. It is evident that the peculiarity of this govern- ment is that it is priestly. Do we find elsewhere in history governments of the same kind? Yes, the government of the Jews after their return from captivity, when the High Priest assumed the position of a prince, was similar. Somewhat similar was the authority of the earliest Mohammedan caliphs, an Omar and an Ali. And everywhere history testifies that priestly authority has a tendency to convert itself into political authority, and will do so when circumstances favour it. But if so, ought not this kind of government to have a place in our classi- fication ? The truth is that in the records of history 52 INTKODUCTION TO POLITICAL SCIENCE lect. ii theocracy is a phenomenon almost as prominent as aristocracy or democracy. Yet it is almost over- looked by Aristotle, and has been but slightly referred to by most modern writers on political science. The result, then, is that in political science classi- fication may be expected to be most important and difficult, and also that the accepted classification suggested originally by the very partial and peculiar experience of the Greek philosophers is scarcely applicable to the states with which we have chiefly to deal, and is also insufficient. LECTUEE III In my last lecture I brought together the civilised state and the rude primitive community to which we usually deny the name of state, and I asserted that they belonged together as much as the insect or mollusc belongs together with the bird and beast. I asserted that political science ought to find a place for the rude communities and not to pass them by on the ground that they are uncivilised, while it confines its investigations to states which it dignifies with the name of civilised. Still civilisation is a great thing, and a thing, if we may trust its etymology, par- ticularly important in political science, for it seems to be a way of living or thinking peculiarly adapted to the civiias or state. When I maintain that the rude community should not be overlooked, I do not maintain that it should be put in the same class with the civilised state, any more than in zoology the mollusc is put in the same class with the vertebrate. And as we propose to busy ourselves with the classi- fication of states, and must therefore go in quest of large differences, we can scarcely find a. larger or 54 INTRODUCTION TO LEOT. more striking difference than this to begin with. The question why it is that some communities are so different from others that we are inclined altogether to refuse them the name of states, will probably, if we can find an answer to it, yield us the most funda- mental and the broadest of the distinctions we want. ' I indicated slightly in the last lecture the most prominent point of difference between the primitive and the civilised state. The primitive man may, no doubt, differ from the civilised man in a hundred different ways, but the primitive state — that is, the political organisation of the primitive man when com- pared with that of the civilised — always, I think, differs from it in the same way, viz. that it is far more closely connected with the family. Take any highly civilised state, whether from ancient or from modern history, you scarcely perceive any relation or affinity between its organisation and that of the families composing it. In modern England or France, in the Greece or Rome of Demosthenes and Cicero, the family has ceased to have any political importance. So much is this the case that those who, in the seventeenth century, speculated upon the origin of states often show themselves unaware even that in their origin and first beginning states were connected with families. The very tradition of the connection has been lost. It is supposed that a condition of lawless violence, in which the weak were at the mercy of the strong, Til POLITICAL SCIENCE 55 originally prevailed, and that this was brought to an end by the invention of government, that is, by an agreement to surrender to a single strong man a part of the liberty which each man originally possessed, in return for protection. This theory seems to conceive the primitive community as a mere unorganised crowd of individuals.^ But the beginning of political organisation is given by nature in the family relation. The authority of the paterfamilias may, or may not, be primeval and universal ; but certainly in those cases where we are able to trace the history of states furthest back, the starting-point seems not to be a condition of universal confusion, but a powerful and rigid family organisation. The weak were not at the mercy of the strong, because each weak man was a member of the family, and the family protected him with an energy of which modern society can form no conception. In these cases, too, we are able to trace that the state was not suddenly introduced as a kind of heroic remedy for an intolerable confusion, but that the germ of organisation given by nature was developed artificially ; that the family grew into something more than a mere family ; that it developed itself gradually so much, and acquired so much additional organisation, as to disengage itself from the literal family, which now reappeared in an inde- 1 The MS. has here a pencil note : " This is more true of Hobbes than Loclce." 56 INTRODUCTION TO LECT. pendent form within it ; and that at last the conven- tional or fictitious family acquired a character of its own, until it first forgot and then at last denied and repudiated its connection with the natural family. Observe, I do not mean to assert that the state has in all cases grown up in this way ; only that in the most conspicuous instances, where its growth can be traced most certainly, it has gone through these stages. For an example I will take one of the states best known to you — ancient Eome ; I might equally well take ancient Athens. In the time of Cicero the state had a char- acter as advanced and independent as it has in England or France ; and those who speculated upon its origin often forgot as completely to connect it with the family as in modern times did Hobbes and Locke. They said that Eomulus had opened an asylum to which robbers had flocked, and that this robber community had afterwards stolen wives and transformed itself into a state. But certain institu- tions still existed in Rome, which were of immemorial antiquity, and which to Cicero and his contemporaries had become quite unintelligible, but which, atten- tively considered and compared with the traditionary history by modern scholars, have betrayed the secret of the development of the Roman state out of the family. Particularly, there was the institution of the Ill POLITICAL SCIENCE 57 gens. The second name of every Roman, ending always in ius, Fabius, Julius, TuUius, showed to what gens he belonged, and yet Cicero almost confesses that the nature and meaning of the gens are quite obscure to him. But Athens had just the same institution, and the analogy of other primitive communities shows us that we have here the clan, that is, the conventional family — a family enlarged and strengthened by means of various legal fictions. What puzzles Cicero is that in the condition of the gens in which he saw it the fictions were too transparent, so that he cannot think of it seriously as a family. But we know that there is an earlier stage in the development of law when legal fictions are taken quite seriously. We can therefore easily conceive that five hundred years before Cicero these institutions, the gentes, may have been thoroughly intelligible and full of vitality. And now, when we take up the early books of Livy and read the account of that strange primitive party- struggle between the patricians and plebeians, we are able to discern the primitive nucleus of the Roman community in the original clans, the patri- cian gentes. For we find references to an ancient maxim that no plebeian belongs to a gens ; now as in later times this had ceased to be true, we see that the struggle had been not merely for ofiice but also for status, social as well as political ; in short, that it was the effort of expansion by which the old family 58 INTRODUCTION TO LEOT. mould was broken and the state proper disengaged itself from the clan. Again, the history of the city of Rome shows us that the nucleus of it was composed of a number of primitive clans living each in its separate settlement, but side by side, for the oldest districts of the city have the names of the ancient patrician gentes. In short a number of indications concur to show that Rome — though in the time of Cicero the fact had been quite forgotten — ^first took shape as a league of cognate but distinct clans, each clan being a conven- tional family into which admission could only be pro- cured through the fiction of adoption. The same fact is almost as evident in the history of Athens. And in almost every state the develop- ment of which has been at all recorded it is possible to recognise that the family is infinitely more promi- nent in the earlier stages than in the later, so that the further you ascend the stream the more you see the state taking the form of a tribe or clan, or league of tribes and clans. So far, then, we have arrived at a grand distinction which roughly corresponds to the distinction between civilised and uncivilised states. For the most part we find that the uncivilised state is only a tribe that is a more or less conventional family. But is this all ? No ; when I compare in my mind the so-called civilised with the more primitive states Ill POLITICAL SCIENCE 59 I am struck with another diflference equally pregnant. I am struck with the immense political importance of religion in the primitive state. I use the word religion here in its most literal popular sense, the worship and apparatus of worship of special deities in literal temples. In the higher sense I should maintain that religion rather gains than loses by the advance of civilisation in a state, and I do not myself believe that the state can disengage itself from religion taken in this higher sense. But as the state gradually disengages itself from the family, so it is a historic law that the state as it develops tends to disengage itself from the particular form of religion with which in its primitive period it had been connected, and in its earlier stage the state is very frequently found thus intimately connected with some such special form of religion. This has been somewhat concealed from the readers of history, owing to the fact that many of the most famous histories have been written in a time of scepticism with respect to the religious system with which they have to deal. Thucydides, Polybius, Livy, Tacitus, are not believers in the ancient national religions of Greece and Eome respectively. The same is true also of Aristotle. Accordingly all these historians and speculators rationalise somewhat, and in their accounts of early history the religious colour is in a great degree 60 INTRODUCTION TO lect. washed out. Still, in the early books of Livy it is clearly recognisable that a strong religious feeling entered into the struggle of patricians and plebeians, and that the former regarded themselves as defending the ancient religious institutions, the "sanctities of old." And in general we may perceive that both in Greece and Eome the later generations when they looked back perceived that religion had formerly been much more prominent in public life than it was in their own time, as we ourselves feel when we compare modern politics with the politics of Charles I.'s time. " Majores nostri, religiosissimi mortales,'' says Cato, and Sophocles tells of Athens that it boasted itself to be " most religious " (Oeoaefiea-TaTai), as indeed it appears in the ideal picture of it given both by that poet aod by Aeschylus. The legends of Numa Pompilius and of Epimenides; the ancient priest- hoods, more ancient commonly thaii purely secular institutions; many survivals, such as the Amphictyonic Confederation and the Oomitia Curiata, — all these indications in Greek and Eoman history, and others quite similar in the histories of other states, lead us to conclude that of states it may be said, as the poet has said of individuals, " Heaven lies about them in their infancy.'' These examples have been drawn from heathen religions, but the history of the last two centuries has shown that in Christian states, too, a time comes when the State tries to disengage itself Ill POLITICAL SCIENCE Gl from the particular institution of Christian religion with which in earlier times it has been connected. Down to about the time of Queen Anne the English state was also in some sense the English Church, but since that time it has been in a manner secularised, and so visibly that the very complexion of its history has been altered. About the same time the same change passed over the leading Catholic states, so that an ever-growing hostility to the spiritual power is throughout a characteristic of continental history in the eighteenth century. Looking upon states in general from our own point of view, which is that of a somewhat secularised state, we perceive a great difference between states like our own and others in which politics are closely connected with religion. Like our own are the states of modern Europe, and also the classical states of antiquity in their later periods; to the other class belong the medieval states, most of the Oriental communities, and most communities anywhere that are in a primitive stage. This particular influence of religion, its influence upon politics, tends to become exhausted after a certain time, just as the influence of the family does, because after a time the state becomes independent, and able, as it were, to stand without props. Hence we see that political theory forgets the influence of religion as it forgets that of the family, because political theory commonly 62 INTEODUCTION TO lect. belongs to an advanced period of the stiite when it has become independent. Aristotle in the Politics is almost entirely silent on the subject of religion. Not only does he not recognise that one most important and common form of government, the theocracy, is absolutely founded on religion, but he does not seem to recognise that even in primitive periods religion is a leading cause of the develop- ment of states out of tribes. We shall find it quite impossible to follow him in this respect when we found a political science upon induction and history. Historically, religion is a ruling influence in most states during their period of growth ; in some conspicuous cases it seems almost to create the state ; and many centuries commonly elapse before it becomes possible to distinguish the two ideas of state and church, much more to think of dividing the two institutions. Accordingly we have here another leading difference between the states called civilised and those which are more primitive ; in the primitive state not only the family but also religion is far more prominent, and has a substantial political importance. How does this influence work ? As to the family, we saw how, by a gradual extension and sophistica- tion of the simple idea of the family, the state may gradually come into existence. But historically we see states at times springing into existence in quite another way, through religion. Look at the great Ill POLITICAL SCIENCE 63 states of Islam. A religious doctrine was preached in the seventh century among the Arab tribes, and forthwith those populations, till then feeble and disunited, took the form of a mighty state, and in the course of a century had founded cities, over- thrown empires, and established a great federation of states, covering a considerable section of the globe, and united among themselves by the bond of a common religion. This is the largest phenomenon of the kind ; but we have all read in our Bibles how two thousand years earlier another prophet had given a law in the same neighbourhood, which law had in like manner created a state. These are extreme and striking examples of the state-building power of religion, because they seem to show us religion creating states, as it were, out of nothing. But as a concurrent factor religion is seen wherever the formation of a state can be traced. In the Semitic or Hamitic East, wherever a barbarous tribe has raised itself at all above the level of barbarism and taken any development, it has done so usually through conversion to Islam. In Europe it was by alliance with the Church that the Germanic nationality first achieved durable political creations ; thus did Clovis create and Pepin restore the Prankish Empire. In England, too, it was religion that first brought the tribes together and laid the foundation of an English state. G4 INTRODUCTION TO LBCT. The reason why the family is capable of developing into the state is that it creates a strong link between individuals. The son belongs in the most intimate sense to the father ; the members of a family belong together. Once given such a solid bond, human con- trivance and invention may by degrees add suitable organisation; but the bond is indispensable. Now perhaps the only other influence which creates such a bond is religion. It forms churches which, so long as the religious influence continues genuine, unite their members for life and for death as the family does. These unions may be barbarous; the deity worshipped, the rites practised, may appear to the outside world repulsive, as in other cases they may appear noble and admirable; but whether good or bad, the bond created by religion is of that strong, natural, elementary, instinctive kind, that it lasts for centuries, and allows infinite modifications and de- velopments in the body which it holds together to take place without dissolution of the body. We see then two ways in which the state may come into existence. It may have its root in the family, it may have its root in the Church. But are these roots really distinct 1 Do churches spring up quite independently of clans or tribes'! We do not intend here to speculate; we wish to follow the indications of fact and of history. Whatever may be possible in the abstract, in historic experience they are Ill POLITICAL SCIENCE 65 generally found together. The family influence and the religious influence operate side by side. Mohammed did not bring together individuals that had been isolated, but tribes that had been distinct, and, more- over, in spite of their distinctness, cognate. Moses made a church or rather a church-nation, but he made it out of tribes, and behind the Mosaic we see the patriarchal, Abrahamic community. Take other examples. The early history of Eome shows us a religious legislator, Numa Pompilius, endowing the community, while it was yet in political infancy, with an elaborate organisation of worship. We cannot lay any stress upon the personality of Numa, but it is clear that early Eome passed through a phase of intense religious feeling, for all evidence shows that the religious institutions in Eome were more ancient than the political, that Eome had many priesthoods, many temples, at a time when she had scarcely any magistrates. The nucleus of the world- state was a group of sacred shrines, the Ara Maxima by the Tiber, the shrine of Faunus on the Palatine, and then the great temple of Jupiter on the Capitoline. Shall we say then that Eome developed itself out of a primitive church 1 I think we may say so. But it is equally clear, as I said before, that Eome grew out of a league of tribes or clans. The tribal character is just as manifest as the theocratic character in that primitive community, not less so than in the earliest F 66 INTRODUCTION TO LBCT. phase of the Hebrew community. It appears, then, that the ecclesiastical form is not diverse from the tribal form, but may be superimposed upon it — nay, possibly springs out of it by normal development. However this may be, it is certain that in some communities the theocratic stamp is most marked, in others the tribal ; while again both these classes of state appear to us primitive and old-fashioned, because we are accustomed to a third class in which both the influence of religion and that of the family have ceased greatly to influence the state, which now assumes to be independent of either. This is a large generalisation, but it is not at all recondite. It merely collects together some facts which, if they are often overlooked, are overlooked only on account of their largeness and obviousness. The word stale and the conception state seem wanting in some communities, which in other respects also appear to be imperfectly developed. Accordingly such communities have been passed over by political speculators who were in search of states, since they do not even profess to be states. But as my object is to bring together all the political phenomena which are really of the same kind, and as these communities appear to be of the same kind as the recognised state, though they do not adopt the same name, I desire to include them. I find two l^ge varieties of them. That which strikes me first because it is most POLITICAL SCIENCE 67 barbarous, most unlike the civilised state, is the which I find chiefly in the great desert regions of the world, in North Africa, Arabia, and Central Asia. But I find another variety which cannot be called the tribe, for it has quite other characteristics. The Turkish Empire is the great example of it. It is often of great extent, and often has much organisation. It reminds us of what we ourselves, the nations of Europe, were in the Middle Ages, and we think of it rather as medieval than as barbarous. The prominent feature of it is not the family but religion. In the Turkish Empire no question is raised of a man's nationality, but only of his religion. True believers are all equal, and men differ only as they are true believers or infidels. We have then three great varieties of state. There is the state proper, there is the tribe, and there is this ecclesiastical community, which I have just described, — we may call it perhaps the theocracy. They are all states in this sense, that they are all alike corporations to which men belong for life and death, but corporations distinct from, and larger than, the mere natural family. In what do they differ? In the motive which attaches men to them ; in the conception which the members have of the corporation to which they are thus closely attached. Ask a tribesman what binds him to his tribe, what he means when he says he 68 INTKODUCTION TO LEOT. belongs to it : he will answer that " blood is thicker than water," that he belongs by kinship to his tribe, that he is a Macgregor or a Gordon, and must go with the Macgregors or the Gordons ; ask the same question of a Jew or a Mussulman — they will speak of the God in whom they believe and of their circum- cision ; ask an Englishman or a Frenchman — they will give again a different answer, one not so easy to express in a few words, to the effect that it is of infinite advantage to them to belong to a great England or a great France. Thus one speaks of community of race, another of community of religion, another of community of interest. But all alike are agreed that the tie, whatever it is, is infinitely strong ; and that if the corporation to which they are attached should be endangered they would be morally bound to make all sacrifices in its behalf. States, then, may be classified according to the motive which holds them together, and this is perhaps the most comprehensive principle — that is, the principle which is independent of all differences in form of government, and which includes the least developed organisms that can pretend to be political. It is useful in the same way as all principles of classification that are founded upon real and important differences — that is, it brings together and makes available for use a large number of scattered facts. But at this stage we know only that the political in POLITICAL SCIENCE 69 community appears in these three shapes ; we must not for a moment assume that we have here three different species, as the word species is understood in physiology — that is, varieties so rigidly separated that they can either not at all, or only in very long periods of time, pass into each other. On the contrary, all appearances show that we have here only three different stages in the development of the same state. For it is important to remark that the three motives are not generally found operating separately. One of the three is commonly predominant, but the other two are generally observable either in germ or in decay. This cannot be better illustrated than by considering our own state and the way in which we ourselves regard it. Among us the state has gained independence; we are in an advanced stage of development. We belong to it mainly because we hold it useful, beneficial ; the bond that holds us all together is community of interest. But does this mean that the other older motives have quite ceased to act, that the older ties have quite fallen away ? Not at all ; we are still Englishmen. When we speak of the colonies and rejoice to think that they will not lightly separate themselves from us, 'we still use the old phrase and say that blood is thicker than water. Nor has the religious tie by any means ceased to hold not only individuals but also the state together. In the presence of Mohammedans or idolaters -we 70 INTEODUCTION TO LBCT. feel in the most vivid manner that we are Christians, and when we travel in Italy or Spain we mostly feel in the same manner that we are Protestants. Thus in the advanced communities all the three motives act at once. They are states proper, held together by interest ; this is their predominant character. But they have by no means entirely ceased to have the nature of theocracies, held together by religion, nor have they ceased to have the nature of tribes held together by kinship. I have already remarked in like manner that in the theocratic state, though the theocratic motive predominates, the tribal motive is commonly also operative ; the theocracy is a tribe or league of tribes at the same time. Conversely, it is not to be supposed that the tribal motive has in it no germ of theocracy. What I have called shortly the sense of kinship is in those primitive minds in which it is most influential by no means the simple rational thing it is in our- selves. There it is closely blended with religion ; it is a worship of ancestors, and as the ancestors are regarded as gods, so the gods are regarded as ancestors, so that no line can be traced where family feeling ends and religion begins. Once more, both in the tribe and the theocracy there are observable very distinct germs of the state proper. The notion of a common interest has not indeed detached itself, and we can observe that when Ill POLITICAL SCIENCE 71 it begins to do so those who have been accustomed to the older motives receive a shock, cry out on utilitarianism, and predict the downfall of the nation. But implicitly the notion must always have been at work, and however little avowed must have worked powerfully. For such primitive communities are under an intense pressure from danger and from suffering. The enemy is often at their gates, the men are exposed to massacre, the women and children to slavery. In such circumstances the community of interest is much more palpable, more undeniable, than in the vast nation-states and empires of a more civilised time ; and if it is not so much mentioned this is only because the older notions are still vigorous enough by themselves to hold the society together and satisfy the minds of the citizens. Thus, when we make the experiment of bringing together the rude and civilised communities, we dis- cover that the difference is not so much one of kind as of degree of development, and this is what the common expression, progress of civilisation, would lead us to expect. In the main it appears that the barbarous states, or those we call Oriental, of the present day, are not essentially different from our own, but only less developed — that they are now what we were once. I have distinguished three different state-motives and three different forms of state corresponding to 72 INTRODUCTION TO LEOT. them. But can we find no fourth motive and no fourth kind of state 1 I daresay your first impression will be that it is easy to find states which do not fall under any of these three heads. You will cite for instance the Eoman Empire, which was composed of various races and various religions. And you will ask, What common interest held together the conquering Eomans and the provincials who were plundered by Roman proconsuls and propraetors ? And similar to the Roman Empire are all states founded on con- quest, where a ruling race lives in the midst of dependent races ; such states occur in history as frequently as those which we have hitherto contem- plated. Evidently, then, there is a fourth state- motive, simpler and no less effective than the three we have examined, viz. force. Sheer superiority of force on the part of the ruling class, inspiring first terror, and after a certain time inert passive resignation, — this is the explanation of, perhaps, half the states in the world. This brings us to another distinction which is very fundamental. We began by laying it down that the state is an organism, and that the processes by which it is developed are analogous to those by which animal or vegetable organisms receive their peculiar form and organisation. But these are natural pro- cesses, the result of the power which life has of Ill POLITICAL SCIENCE 73 adapting itself to its environment. We see something analogous to this when a group of men, held together by some living bond and pressed by some difficulty or danger from without, takes a shape and puts forth organs that may enable it to withstand the pressure. We see here the natural genesis of the state. But among the mass of states which history presents we find a whole class which have not arisen in this way at all. They ought, no doubt, to form a fourth class by the side of the three which we have distinguished, if it did not seem more just to refuse them the name of state altogether. For these so- called states are not natural organisms. They are inorganic. The natural states exist side by side, and are often crowded together in a narrow room. Hence wars arise between them, and for the most part not such wars as we see now among European states, which are closed by a treaty and an indemnity, but wars in which either state aims at the destruction of the other. * This destruction is often accomplished. Government is swept away, organisation is dissolved, the victorious state enters the territory and has the conquered population, now reduced to a mere crowd, at its mercy. What does it do? Sometimes it annexes the territory to its own. In this case it will set up a new government, which will be in the hands of alien officials. From this time there will be 74 INTRODUCTION TO LECT. nominally one large state where before there had been two smaller states. Now, as most actual states have often engaged in war, this process has occurred very frequently indeed, and most states now include some territory and some population which was origin- ally incorporated in this way. But for our purpose it is essential to draw a sharp distinction between the natural organic union out of which. the living state grows and this sort of violent incorporation. Not because we may disapprove of such violence, for, as I have said, our moral approval or disapproval is wholly irrelevant to the question of classification ; but because the difference between the society held together by force and the natural society is so great that they ought not to be described by the same word. At least, if we must in conformity with usage call the former " state," let us add the epithet "inorganic." Properly speaking, such a society is a double thing. The conquering class or horde, taken by itself, is a real state, a vigorous organism. Thus I quoted the Turkish Empire as a typical example of the theocracy. It is so if we think of the ruling Mussulman population, but outside this in the same territory there are the subject Christian populations, who form properly no state at all, either by them- selves or in conjunction with their rulers, but an inorganic crowd. in POLITICAL SCIENCE 75 Nevertheless the inorganic quasi-state imitates the organic state, and has one characteristic of the true state in a high degree. For we said that the state is characterised by government, which means command enforced by punishment; this, then, the inorganic quasi-state has, and indeed depends exclusively upon it. It is time to sum up the results of this lecture. History and observation show us that human popu- lations are often united by an organic process analo- gous to that which combines natural substances into a living organism. The family, in withstanding external pressure, extends and modifies itself by means of legal fictions till it becomes the clan, and several clans unite themselves by means of a federal league. Again, the worshippers of a deity engage in religious war against the worshippers of some other deity, and the pressure of war gives rise to organisa- tion. Hence we have two types of organic governed society; but these two types are commonly found blended together. After a certain time the society thus founded on kindred or common religion or both, becomes aware that its union is a thing valuable for its own sake, that government and organisation and co-operative life are useful in themselves to the indi- viduals who possess them. Hence there springs up ^ the conception of a common good, a common weal, which is independent of such considerations as kin- 76 INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL SCIENCE LEOT. Ill dred or religion ; by degrees the society disengages itself from these props, and begins to rest by prefer- ence upon utility, the word being understood not necessarily in any sordid sense. Hence the organic state appears in three different forms : clannish, or theocratic, or properly political ; but these forms are, to all appearance, only different stages of a single normal development. By the side of these organic forms history shows us another sort of political society which, if the state is an organism, can only be called a quasi-state. It is not organic — that is, it is not developed from within. It is the result of conquest, but has a similar appear- ance to the organic state, because it adopts and imitates the organisation of it. In history, however, since conquest has been very frequent, this quasi- state occurs at least as often as the organic state. If we speak seldom of it in these lectures the reason will be, not that it does not deserve study, but that it ought to be carefully distinguished and studied separately, and that our present undertaking concerns rather the organic state. LECTURE IV The practical use of the classification I laid before you in the last lecture is that it helps us in under- standing the history of primitive and uncivilised states, and enables us to conceive that, however different in appearance, they are substantially pheno- mena of the same kind as the modern civilised state. For these purposes it is, in my opinion, of very great use. Everywhere in history the ordinary student suffers lamentably from the want of general ideas. Some compass we must have in the sea of facts. In modern and recent times we are not quite without this compass, for we understand in general that constitutional freedom is the object iimed at, and despotism the evil struggled with. But in primitive times all is different. Here we want other categories, other generalisations, yet we are scarcely aware of this, and hence we try to make the familiar categories serve again. But it is not really true to say that the struggle of the plebeians against the patricians was a struggle for liberty, and it is of little use to apply modern principles to that long stretch of primitive 78 INTRODUCTION TO LEOT. history which is so familiar to us in the Old Testa- ment. In all these parts of history we should dismiss the notions of liherty, constitutionalism, checks on royal power, writs of habeas corpus and petitions of right. Wholly different notions are required here, and the clue is given when you understand that the clan is struggling with the theocracy, and the theocracy with the state proper. Some Numa or Mohammed or Moses breaks the hard tribal organisa- tion by some grand religious proclamation. Augustine breaks in upon the rude heptarchy, Clovis holds out a hand to Catholicism. The community assumes a theocratic form. Then at a later period the theo- cracy too is put upon the defensive. Political ideas are now gaining head; a royal house establishes itself ; the theocracy, as represented by the prophet Samuel, is indignant that the people should ask for a king ; or the royal house itself has been allied with the theocracy, or it may be an aristocratic government has endowed itself with priesthoods ; in this case the rising movement will attack aristocracy or monarchy, the precinct of religious privilege will be invaded, and the plebeians will break into the priesthoods and pontificates. Such are the party struggles of the primitive age, but the primitive age is nearer to us than we are apt to suppose. The rationalistic mode of writing history effaces, as I said, the religious colour of ly POLITICAL SCIENCE 79 national life. We have a trick of dividing ecclesias- tical history from civil and relegating it into special treatises ; but it is in this ecclesiastical history that the primitive ideas under which the state was first formed are preserved. Thus, in our struggle with the Stuarts there is evidently a very large ecclesiasti- cal element, but we do not allow to it all the weight we ought, because of the prejudice which leads us to think that this does not belong to history proper, but only to ecclesiastical history. If we allowed ourselves to contemplate that struggle as a whole, we should see that it was not a mere struggle with, monarchy for freedom, that it was at the same time the effort by which the state made itself independent and passed out of its theocratic stage. We may pass now to another of the large distinc- tions by which states are divided into classes. I take intentionally such as are most obvious, because I want to take note of the largest differences first. Those who in our modern period study the history of Greece and Eome are not perhaps at first struck by the fundamental difference between the classical states and those of modern Europe. Compared with the primitive state, or even with the medieval state, Greece and Eome have quite a modern appearance. The school of Voltaire used to couple the age of Louis XIV. with the great age of Greece and Eome as being of the same kind, and to treat all that came 80 INTRODUCTION TO lbct. between as deserving only to be forgotten. Since Voltaire's time the modern state has grown still more like the classical one, for it has acquired liberties and popular assemblies. And yet what a difference ! A difference that must take by surprise those who think that states differ almost exclusively in the number of their rulers ! It flashes on us after a time that by a state the ancients mean a city, and that we mean a country ! When I say the ancients I mean of course the Greeks and Eomans. Outside the classical world we see traces of a similar arrangement in antiquity, for Carthage seems to be a sovereign city like Eome or Athens. But antiquity, too, has large country states, the Macedonian Monarchy, the Persian Empire, the primeval Egyptian state. Substantially we have to deal with the fact that in two countries, Greece and Italy, the political vital principle seized small groups of population and turned them into highly developed organisms, whereas in modern Europe (and now also in America) and in Asia, the political organism is very large and tends also to become larger. In modern times the substance of the organism is commonly a population speaking the same language. Sometimes, however, it is a population with two or three languages, but one of them generally pre- ponderating. So Switzerland has three languages, IV POLITICAL SCIENCE 81 but German gi'eatly preponderates; Austria has several languages, and much difficulty is caused by the fact that no one now preponderates quite decidedly. In ancient Greece and Italy language had no political effect. The polity embraced only a small number of those who spoke the same language. So it was in Greece, where the language was spread over no great space, and yet within that space there were dozens of independent states. So, too, in Italy, where languages closely cognate were spread over a large section of the country, and yet we find Rome and Veii and the cities of the Latin league con- tending together in much the same way as Athens, Megara, and Corinth. In the modern world something similar has been seen again in Italy, and also in Switzerland. In both countries in the fourteenth century, owing to the failure of the power of the Emperor, cities be- came for practical purposes again sovereign, and in the cases of Florence and Venice highly developed. In Germany, too, from the same cause, a number of free cities, such as Niirnberg and Frankfurt, became practically almost independent republics. These have been momentary glimpses, in the case of Italy some- thing more than a glimpse, of the ancient classical world, but in the end the modern tendency has set more and more decidedly against the small state, G 82 INTEODUCTION TO LBOT. and seems likely now to replace its large states by states larger still, states of 20,000,000 by states of 80,000,000, If you will reflect you will see that a difference so great as this must necessarily involve innumerable other differences of organisation. The government of a town council cannot possibly follow the same rules as the government of a great country. This simple fact shows us how hollow must have been the political theories of the last century, which aimed at the imitation of the classical states, and yet for the most part forgot such a fundamental difference. I mention it here for the sake of founding upon it a classification, but, as a matter of fact, a great part of history is occupied not so much with the proceedings of states of these two kinds as with the struggles and confused endeavours of human society to form states of these two kinds. In particular, the gradual growth of the large nation-state in the bosom of the dissolving Roman Empire occupies many centuries full of history on the largest scale. Though I have not space to treat of this, I may find room here for a suggestion as to the causes which may have led the poHtical vital principle to embody itself in different countries in these two diflFerent ways. We might perhaps imagine that that rational way of setting up a state which charms philosophers so much may really have given birth to the old city- iv POLITICAL SCIENCE 83 states, though not to