BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME FROM THE SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND THE GIFT OF 1891 '^ ^ Cornell University Library B398.E8 C77 Metaphysical basis of Plato's, ejhics, olin 3 1924 028 994 965 Cornell University Library The original of this book is in the Cornell University Library. There are no known copyright restrictions in the United States on the use of the text. http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924028994965 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS OF PLATO'S ETHICS THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS OF PLATO'S ETHICS BY ARTHUR BERNARD COOK M.A. FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE CAMBRIDGE "Quis ille primus, cuius ex imagine Natura solars finxit humanum genus, Aeternus, incorruptus, aequaevus polo, Unusque et universus, exemplar Dei?" — , MILTON Cambri&ge DEIGHTON BELL & CO. London GEORGE BELL & SONS 189s CAMBRIDGE PRINTED BY JONATHAN PALMER ALEXANDRA STREET CONTENTS PAGE Preface ix Part I. The Platonic Theory of Mind . . . i § I. The Parmenides i § 2. The Sophist 17 § 3. Aristotle's Psychology 23 Part II. Higher and Lower Mentality . . . 54 § I. Purpose and Necessity 55 § 2. Identity and Difference 68 § 3. Theology 85 Part III. Metaphysical Descent and Moral Ascent. 113 Index Locorum 153 PREFACE Tt oZv fi/ieii ipovft.iv eirl ToiToirois Kal roioirois i^TiyiiTais rov Uhdraii/os! Kal tI ■npoaBiiaoiiiv 4k rris ruierepas eirrtas ; Proklos in Parm. ed. Cousin vi. 30. The following essay is neither a systematic account of Plato's metaphysics, nor an adequate exposition of Plato's ethics. Its scope is a narrower one. It aims at clearing up the connection between the two. And, if the attempt has led me to reinterpret the metaphysical scheme that underlay the ethics of matured Platonism, my purpose throughout has been to show how intimately— and indeed vitally — the latter was connected with the former. Thus far at least I find myself in accordance with the general tendency of modern Platonic criticism. For the sup- posed independence, not to say antagonism, of the several parts of Plato's philosophy, which still mars the work of certain exponents, is nowadays falling into disrepute. We are beginning to look askance on all constructions involving the philosopher in incon- gruous positions. And this is due partly, I think, to PREFACE. a growing appreciation of the artistic side of his thought, partly to special efforts that have been made to determine from theoretical content or linguistic style the true order of the Platonic writings. The former movement postulates that here, if anywhere, a speculative system must mean a harmonious whole ; the latter has shown that sundry seeming inconsis- tencies are but tide-marks of a progressive develop- ment. But, whatever be the precise causes which have of recent times tended to discredit the patch- work Platonism of the past, it will fairly be demanded of any fresh endeavour to articulate the Idealist doctrine that it represent that doctrine as an organic unity. This being admitted, the only safe course is to regard the Platonic philosophy from the standpoint of some opo'i 6pi,cr6eh /li'ya'i for which Plato is himself responsible. Now of all such Spot that which is most constantly affirmed and most jealously guarded is the reality of the Ideal world. The late Dr. Maguire has somewhere said that "the objectivity of the Idea is the corner-stone of Platonism." I should prefer to substitute the term "reality" as a translation of oiicrta, because the cardinal dogma of the Timaeiis asserts that the nature of ovaia is to be at once raiiTov and PREFACE. XI Qdrepov, i.e. not only objective but also subjective. And here it may conduce to clearness if, by way of preamble, I sketch the main drift of my essay, in- dicating in the briefest possible manner how this theory of objective and subjective ovcria furnished a satisfactory foundation for the superstructure of morality. Plato conceived the universe to be a vo-qrov ^aiov containing within itself a series of vorjTa ^aa. Every such ^a>ov, whether supreme or subordinate, — if it is to make good its claim to real being — must (he says) pass from the objective phase of self-identity into the subjective phase of self-differentiation. The former state consists in the intuitional exercise of pure thought ; the latter comprises the emotive presenta- tions of knowledge, opinion, sensation. But the passage from the one to the other is a necessary feature of each and every votjtov ^wov. As regards nomenclature, — the supreme K,5)ov in its higher con- dition is the sovereign Mind ; in its lower condition it- is the 6eol 6eS>v. The subordinate iJSa in their higher condition are the Ideas ; in their lower con- dition they are particular specimens of the natural kinds. And since the higher mentality must be deemed superhuman, Plato calls the sovereign Mind xu PREFACE. 6e6v and the Ideas aiSt'ot deoi, in contradistinction to particulars which are at best only Saifiovedvai, e^ei Xoyov. Again, it is noteworthy that in Parmenides' first retort the same postulate was ouaia Kol vovs ayiniros Koi \6yos &ppriTos), and not always then {e.^. [Alex.] in Arist. Met. ed. Hayduck p. 670, 27 t^i/ yhp voijt^v koI Beiav iroWdi fiii flvai hi/o^Tics iLiti^vavTo). In view of these objections I have followed n. simpler syntax, and given to Aj/iJijtos a meaning that Stephanus calls " frequentissimum et passim obvium" {e.g. Plat. Tim. 30 B, where, as in Gorg. 514 c, ia/6iiTos is opposed to vovv exiiv). THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS tacitly made by the'words — Ov'x^ evo? tm/ov, o eTrl iraaiv €Kelvo TO vorjfjia ivbv voel, fiiav rtva oZaav IBeav ; In short, both the language of the first retort and the fact that the second is couched in the form of a dilemma lead us to suppose that the Platonic Sokrates and his critic were alike prepared to main- tain that everj/ vorjfia must be a voovv. Whether this assumption is an axiom or a paradox will depend upon the exact significance that we attri- bute to vorjfia. As with our own word " thought," so in the case of vorifia it is possible to distinguish a variety of allied meanings. Proklos in Parm. ed. Cousin v. 147 observes Xiyerai yap vorjfia koi to vorirbv avrb to vorjdh) ical to ivepyr/fia xal to yvaaTiKov rov voovvto^, i.e. the term vdrnia is applied (i) to the actual object of thought, the thing thought of ; (2) to the process of thinking, or more strictly to that process as exem- plified on any definite occasion ; (3) to the cognitive faculty of the thinker. If in the passage with which we are concerned vorifia bears this third sense, then the statement vorjtia voel is self-evident, and further enquiry is futile. But the usage of vo-qixa to denote the "cognitive faculty" is poetical, as may be seen from the lexica^; and at this juncture, where much may hinge on the right selection of a single word, a a e.g. Horn. Od. 215, Hes. Op. 129, Theog. 656, Empedocl. ed. Karsten w. 313, 316, 317. OF PLATO'S ETHICS. poet's licence would be utterly out of place. Had Plato meant " the thinker " or " the thinking faculty," he would assuredly have used to voovv or 6 vovi. Can it be then that v6r)fia here bears its second meaning, and denotes "a process of thinking".'' Two objec- tions at once suggest themselves. In the first place, \i A thinks B, it is fair to describe A or A's mind as thinking ; it may also be fair to presume that B or ^'s mind has a similar faculty for thought; but is it fair to say that A 's thinking thinks .' Has the express- ion vortixa voei thus interpreted any intelligible mean- ing ? And in the second place, if we grant that by a laxity of phraseology such a statement might be made^ it must be admitted that v6r]fj.a thus becomes the equivalent of vorjcri':. But it is difficult to believe that for a common and straightforward term Plato would have substituted a comparatively rare and ambiguous one.* A glance at Ast's Lexicon will ' The elasticity of the English language tolerates the following sen- tence : " If the passing thought be the directly verifiable existent, which no school has hitherto doubted it to be, then that thought is itself the thinker, and psychology need not look beyond " (W. James, The Principles of Psychology, i. 401, cp. 369). The nearest approach to this that I know of in Greek is a clause quoted by Stephanus s.v. voep6s : " Mire cum yiiina conjungit Niceph. Callist. H. E. vol. i. p. 8 B, V 5 ffoi fiey Koi d vovs . . . a66\wTOS, fipiuv voeph. Koi Beta yoijiiaTa" But Byzantine bombast is foreign to the Parmenides. * It might be argued, on the strength of Arist. Psych. A, 3. 13. 4070 7 ^ Se v&i\ais Tck Ko^/tara, that nfinara is used as the plural of t>6riiTis. But (i) in that passage "thought is thoughts" means that the THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS show that, as compared with vortaif, v6r)ij,a occurs but seldom in the -Platonic writings. Discounting Meno 95 E, Soph. 22,7 A, 2S8d, as quotations and Symp. 197 E, an avowedly poetical passage in Agathon's speech, we meet with it again only in Politicus 260 D, where heralds as a class are said to issue commands aWoTjOta vorjfiaTa irapaBe'Xp/j^vov. The word is appos- ite there just because it has not a subjective but an objective value — the king entrusts his v6r)fj,a to the herald, as the manufacturer hands over his wares to the retail dealer. It appears to me certain, therefore, that in the present passage also vorj/xa is used in the ^rst of the three senses enumerated by Proklos. It denotes "the actual object of thought, the thing thought of" We may still, however, raise the ques- tion whether vorifia means (a) the object thought of, as it is independently of the thinking subject, or (ii) the object thought of, as represented by the thinking subject to his own mind. The former, to speak with all accuracy, is to votjtov or to voovfievov, "that which can be" or "that which actually is appre- mental activity of the thinking subject consists in representations of objects thought, not merely in repeated exhibitions of itself : where the process of thinking is entirely self-contained, iariv ri rdTjo-ij voiicreus v6ii(ris, not yo^^uoToj or votiiiirav v6ritrts ; (2) the plural yoiitreis was available. To Arist. J°reil. IH. ^. 917 a 39 (quoted by L. & S.) and Plut. Mor. 691 C, 1120 A (quoted by Stephanus) add Porphyr. Op. ed. Holsten p. 66 eis 5e iiun^v iXaiovaa irphs rhv vovv iv toij voitafai •yiyverai (sc, ji ifiux^) • • ■ «"' "«' i> r$ 3 iariv %v Svtus iwiffTii/iriv oiffav Kol T&K\a ixraiTies Tcl ivTa Avras Secura/ievri k.t.K, Mutatis mutandis this passage is applicable to the Idea as it is portrayed in the Parmenides. 10 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS this mental activity being exclusively restricted to the domain of Ideal truth : Parm. 134 A Ovkovv koI iirurrrjiir], v iirio'TrjiJ.mv ^ etrnv, eKatnov tmv ovtcov, o ecTTiv, eir) av eTncTTijfiy i] ov ; Pi at. Let us here pause to enquire from what sources these fundamental doctrines derive. The conviction that every vorjua must be a voovv might prima facie be ranged under the general belief that " like is known by like,'' appeal being made to Plato's earlier utter- ance : — Phaedo 80 A, B. raSe Jjfiti/ ^va^aivei, t&J /j,ev Geitp Koi adavdrcj) kol vor)T

v yevvrjffevTeov. As they are voovvra, so It is a vow : Phikb. 30 C ea-riv, a TroWa/cts elpi^Ka/iev, aveipov re ev rm TTavrl iroXv Kal nripwi iKavbv xai Tts eV avToi'; alria ov La jcal vow? \0yofievr] BiKaioTar' av. Laws 897 C 17 ^vfiiraaa ovpavov 080? afia Kal ifiopa Kal r&v €V avTm ovrcov arrdvrmv vov Kivrjaei Kal TTepi^opd Kal Twyia-fioK ofioiav ^vaiv ej(et. , This conception of a vor]rov dvev v\riv voriT&v otov rov votjtov deov Kal tov vov Kal, eiirep eltrlv ISiai, Kal t&v ISe&v, irapiaTai Tai^Ttt? TrpaTa<; ovaUi UapfieviBr], . . . av fiev v given in Sopk. 247 E, 248c was regarded as provisional and not final. "Whatever possesses 20 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS Applying this all-important result to the issues of last section, we note that the argument from the Parmenides dealt with only one side of the truth. It regarded ovaLa as the subject and object of vorjaK, without taking into account any lower intellectual faculty, such as that of yvaffii or XoyKTfw's. The Sophist warns us against persisting in such neglect. It bids us to observe that the supreme vov^ of the Philebus is not only a voS?, but also a vonyrov ^u>ov — Cp. Tim. 39 E iva toS' co? Ofwiorarov y rm reXeat KOi vorjTw 5»?' "fpof TTiv Ti}? Suntoviav fllfl7]a-lV Phileb. 30 D OvKovv iv . . . ry tov Aio<: epet? (fivaet ^aaiXiKrjv (J-ev '^^v^^v, ^curiXtKov Be vow 677171'- eaOab SiA ttjv t^s atrial Bvvafiiv — and that the ideal voijuara of the Parmenides are not only vorifiara, but also vorfrb, tjua — Cp. Tim. 30 c TO, yhp Sij vo-qra ^Sia Travra eKelvo iv eavrm irepiXa^bv exei. Ibid. 31 A TO 7ap 7repUj(ov iravra, mrbva vorjra fwa. — inasmuch as every vovs, whether supreme or sub- the power of doing or suffering " would indeed aptly characterise oliiria qu& subject and object of yvSaais. But qui subject and object of viriaa this same ohala. was admitted to be i.tta9-i\s. Consequently, unless Sivafus can be taken to denote the power of passing from the first or static into the second or kinetic condition, we must substitute the amended definition implied in 249 d. _ a -o eg or PLATO'S ETHICS. 23 ordinate, is forced by the necessary nature of its own ovaui to pass out of its tranquil atrddeia into the wonj/jiara and ircBrifjuaTa of animation.'^ Thus by emphasising the fact that, wkerever^^ pure thought is found, there will its shadow the lower mental phase be found also, it enables us to extend our previous scheme as in the diagram. § III. Aristotle's Psychology. Having learnt in the preceding section that all oiaia deserving of the name must necessarily pass from higher to lower phase, we have yet to enquire '^ For Plato's conviction that vovs must be attached to i^uxi see the following passages : Phiieb. 30 c ao^ia /liiy koI koOs &yev 'f'vxvs ouk Hr iroTe ytvoiaSriv, Parm. 132 B /iJ) tuv tiSav %KaaTov ^ roirwv v6iiiia, Kal oiSa/ioO alir^ irpoff^Kj) eyyiyveirBiu i,\\o9i t) iv ifivxt'S, SopA. 249 A dwA toBto fiiv a/KJidrtpa (yoBi and fai^) iviin' airf Ktyojiev, oh fjAtP ii/ ^vxv ye tfytitro/iei' ainh ^X"" ""tA; koI rlv' ttv eVcpoK ?x<" TpcJirov; Tim. 30 B vovy 5* aS x^P^s ij/vxvs hZivmov vapayeveirBai rtp, IHd. 46 D Tutv yh.p &VTUV § vouv iiivip KTuffSat TpoaiiKei, KeKreov rjivx'/iv. Compare Arist. Psych, r. 4. 4. 429a 27 Ka2 cS S^ 01 Xiyovrts t\v ^vy^v eJvai Tiitov eiSwi/, ■n\'t{v 8tj oStc 8\7) 4\\' t\ votfriK'i], oSre 4vT(\exfl^ iWti, Svpifiei rii eWri, Met. A. 3. 10700 26 T] ^vxh . . . fiii iraaa oAX' i vovs, Archytas in frag. phil. Gr. ed. MuUach i, 565 olfcrflao-is jAv iv aduart ylyerai, vAos S' iv i/'ux?. " See Soph. 249 B ^vnPalvei S' odv, Si BettlrriTf, aKivhrav re 6vtuv voVv firiSfvl Iff pi /iTiSevhs ftvai /i7)Sajuov, the counterpart of 249 c Ti S' ; &vev ro{iT(ev {sc. tov Karh rayrd k.t.K.) vovv xaBop^s 6vTa ^ yev6^evov tiv Kal dvovovv; "HKiiTTa. 24 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS how this passage may be effected, transporting us as it does from the realm of serene intelligence — Tim. 52 A TO Kara ravTO. elSo<; e^ov, dyevrjTov Kai avmkedpov, ovre eh eavro elffSejfpfievov aXKo aWo0ev 0VT6 avTo 6t? aWo iroi lov, doparov Be Koi aWa)' ev — ,rhv S\ ToS 4itiireSov ipi9iihy Stilav, atadiiaiv SJ rhv rov areptov- 01 piiv yiip iptSiiol ra etSri aliTo. Kal ipXi'l 4\4yovTO — e'url S' 4k ray arotxfiuv — jKplyerai Sc tA vpiyyiara ra likv y^, t4 S' ^jTiiTT^/iij, Tck Si S6^ri, to S' aiirei)v aroix^uov. This conclusion, says Aristotle, is to be found in the Timaeus. And we can hardly doubt that he refers on the one hand to Tim. 35 A, where the cosmic soul is composed of tuvtov and ddrepov, which coalesce to produce ovcria ; and on the other hand to Tim. 41 D, where the subordinate souls are compounded of the same ingredients, though in a less pure condition. It seems certain, therefore, that by ra iTToixeia Aristotle here denotes the principles of Identity and of Differ- ence, which are represented in the Timaeus by the symbols ravTov and ddrepov. Again, the force of the argument depends on the identification of these aroi'xeia with ai dp^aL It has, indeed, been suggested that tcl aroi'xela are rainov, ddrepov and ovaia considered as the elements of the -* Cp. Simplic. in Arts/. Psych, ed. Hayduck p. 29, 11 hirtynv Toivvv fis rhs ifx^^ '"'^ '"' 7>'« jiyoSvTiu apx^" ical irroiXE'a. 28 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS And if the substitution of t&v dpx&v for t&v alritov r&v eKaaroi^ avaToi'xmv. Themistius, who (66 B, ed. Spengel p. zoseqq) simi- larly finds in the words 6/ioico<; Be kuI . . . ofioioTpoTTtoi a description of the cosmos as object thought, and in the succeeding clause an account of the soul as sub- ject thinking, is liable to the same objections, vis. (a) that in the words 6fioia<; Be xal . . . ofioiorpoirwi we expect to discover a comparison between ^vwariKov and yvcoa-Tov, not between different kinds of 'yvaard, and (d) that the phrase to, S' dWa o/wioTpoTrux; is an over-statement^^ of the case. Nor does Philoponus (C. fol. 2 A) improve upon this by understanding ra d\\a of such ill-assorted elements as rh vorjTo,, tA v ISe&v ttXij- pcofia' TO avroiv, f] ainoh)dop K.T.X. ibid. M, 9. 1085 a 26 iroTepov to ^&ov avTo iv TO) ^atw 57 erepov avTov ^a>ov,/rag. 184. 1510* 14 ^ fiev Kal i,5)6v icfTi, fiere-xpi &v Kal avTov tov ^mov. Plato himself employs the plural of the same' term to describe the Ideas of animals generally : ^^ That is, the supreme Nous in its passage into cosmic existence, as opposed to that cosmic existence which originates from the evolution of the supreme NoSy. OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 35 Rep. 532 A TT/Do? avra ^Stj to, foJa eTrt^etpeti/ airo- PXeireiv Kal Trpos avra aarpa k.t.X. I conclude, therefore, that to restrict the phrase to "the universal Subject" is a limitation unwarranted by either Aristotelian or Platonic usage. Mr. Wallace, who interprets amo to %mov as " the subject knowing" i.e. the microcosm, and to. aWa as " the objects known " i.e. the macrocosm, escapes the first of these objections — because the particular ^S)ov (the microcosm) is of course the given Idea (^ tov ev6^ ISea) as it appears in three-dimensional space. But he too traverses the terminology of Aristotle, who by avTo TO tpiov elsewhere denotes not a particular^* but an Idea. Another suggestion takes both avTo to ^S)ov and TO, oKKa as " subjects " — the contrast between subject and object being not expressed but only implied in the sentence. The former will then mean the supreme fwoK ; the latter the subordinate t,Ssa. This view, apart from its liability to the objections which I have brought against Dr. Jackson's version, seems to me to destroy the balance of Aristotle's triple argument. We should have him adducing three clauses for the express pur- pose of pointing out the similarity between subject '^ Plato, according to Mr. Archer-Hind's rendering, uses out^ t^ ^uov of the individual animal in Tim. 89 B : but the passage, as we shall see, may be taken differently. 36 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS and object, and then omitting to make any mention of that object in the central clause of the three.^^ It is, I think, possible to rectify all these flaws by understanding avro to ^&ov as " ike absolute animal" that is any given voriTov ^&ov — (whether it be the -n-avTeXk ^wov of Tim. 3 1 B, or one of the iv fiepov; eihei ^ma of Tim. 30 C),— and ra aXKa as "the remaining absolute animals." This somewhat obvious rendering of the words ra aX\a is suggested by Philo- ponus (C. 2 TO, S' aXKa ofioioTpoircoi;, ra aWa, rjTOi, . . . ^ TO, dXKa irapahetr/iMara, olov to avroKaXov, to avTodv- 6poyjroov as percipient and the remain- ing ^ma as percepts are constructed ofiocoTpoTreo^, since in every case an absolute animal if subjected to logical analysis will be found to consist of that form of TO ev which is appropriate to itself (hence the article Trj<; tov evo? iSea?) and the successive dimen- sions through which it is evolved. This interpretation escapes the two objections urged on p. 34 by admitting the claim of any and every intelligible animal to the title airo to ^&ov, instead of confining the term to the supreme ^&ov.^ It preserves too the symmetry of the argument ; and that, not only by emphasising Aristotle's main con- tention — the similarity between percipient and percept — but also by identifying the subject of the present with that of the preceding sentence : for in the first clause we saw that any given efiyjrvxov — whether it be the whole cosmic ^wov or one of the partial Ideal §wa — is formed out of the same elements as the other efiyfru'^a which constitute the objects of its cognition ; and now in the second clause we see that any given avTo ^Ssov — whether it be the whole cosmic animal or '* As a matter of fact — excluding Tim. 89 B, at present subjtidice — the supreme fSoc is not elsewhere, either in Plato or Aristotle, called ouri ri (iaov. It is however spoken of as out!) faoi/ in Tim. 37 c, D iis Se KiiiriSiV avrl} KaX fSc iv6riiTe . . • KaSdwcp oiv ourb Tvyx^vti (aov alSiov iv K.r.K., which is perhaps the passage referred to by Proklos on Tim. 40^ voririi irivrav aWia xal irapaSeiyiiaTiKii rav uiri toD Sifiuovp- yov iroiovfievwu, %v Koi auTo^wov Sti touto KaKeTv A YlKdruv ii^ltoffef. 38 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS one of the partial Ideal animals — is developed through the same four stages as the other fwa which consti- tute the objects of its cognition. The argument, I conceive, is exactly parallel in the first two clauses, and raises a presumption that it will be so in the third also. But before passing to the last consideration we must enquire further concerning the nature of the four stages that have hitherto been mentioned without comment. Aristotle alludes to them again in Met. M. 2. 1077(2 24 eVi al <^evkdvr] fj.eraffoXij'i re KoX Kivi]aea)<; atrdarfi alrla dtraaiv ; — Ovk, dXKa iKavcoTaTa SeSeiKrat >frvxv f&v irdvriov irpeG- jSvTaTi;, v irpw^iidTav must balance the statement that the percipient has four modes of cognition symbolically denoted by the same numbers (1.2.3.4.); '^^^ since a quasi-spacial account of those modes has been given already (in the words iiria-Trj/irjv Be ra Suo* nova-)(^S}'s yap e^' ev Tov Be Tov iirnreSov apidfiov Bo^av, aLo-Otjcriv Be tov Tov arepeov), it is probable that these e'iBr] t&v Trpayfidrcov are things in general grouped according to the four stages'^ through which, as we learnt from the second clause, percept Ideas pass into the region oi aladr}(Ti,<;: certainly the broad meaning thus assigned to the word etSo? = " class " or "group" is supported by the fact that the article, prefixed to the same word when used above in its technical sense (ra elBrf avra), is here absent. The argument, I take it, may be set out as follows : — Again, the one is vow, the two is eirLffTrifir), the no. of the plane {i.e. three) is 56^, the no. of the solid {i.e. four) is a'ia-dtja-t,^. Now, on the one hand {fiep) the Numbers were called the fundamental Ideas of the Platonic system — though, to speak with all precision, they are con- "' Simplic. in Arist. Psych, ed. Hayduck p. 29, 12 Si^povv Si rd re SvTtt oil KOTcfc ir\dTos, i.\K^ Kwri. 0deos, els t« ret i/07)t& koI iniaTiiTct Kai So^airrlt Kal aiareriTi, koI dfioias rets yviiireis fis vovv Kal iiriirTlinriv Kol Si!|ai' Koi aterjyov Se els rhs eiSijTiKeks ipx^^ ""^ Tcks ifivxiicas 48 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS separate entities, are but the Ideal animal Man re- garding itself on the plane of acadrjan: : what we see is therefore a plurality of men moving in three- dimensional space. When we entertain opinions about things, we rise to a higher level and portray them to ourselves by a kind of mental delineation : they still shape themselves as pluralities, but pluralities moving in two dimensions, a flat and it may be delusive picture of surrounding life. As individuals we are capable of a yet higher method of cognition, namely that of eVto-TjjjUTj : when a man knows a thing, he so to speak goes " straight to the point " (fiovaxw yap e^' ev) in his intellectual presentation ; and though irda'as yi'^trets, rijv juei/ voepkv &s Ka6* eva&iv afieptffTov ffvvatpov^GV7]v tls r^v juoj/c£8a, t^v Se 4TriffT7jfioi'iK^v us &.ve\L(rffQfi4vrjv Ka\ uis dirh eripov Tov airiov eis rh aiTiarhv irpoayofieyTjVj us Sc Kol SiSt rh airKavfs Koi ael Sict Tuv avTuv Hfvov els T^v dvd^a, t^v 5e i6^av eis t^i/ rpiiiSa Si^ rh rijp Svvafiiv aitTTJs fiij 4vl r'^ aiirh ael, aA\& Torh fieu 4vl rh &\ij0cs TOrk Se iirl rh \fievSos xKiveiv, tis Si t^ji' TetpiSa t^v i£laBi)inP 810 rh au(i.6.Tu\i fivai ami\i\TrTtK'l]v. Themist. in Arist. Psych, ed. Spengel p. 21, 17 Tiv juir vovv ex^'" ^^ ^^s toS kvhs iSeas oiT^x [sc. T^Ji' tfii/x^x) Siupi^ovro, riiv Se iiriirTiifaiv iK rrjs wpdrris SvdSos- aip' ivhs "yip iip' %v xaX ri ^iriiTT^/ir)" 4irb yap tuv trporicreuv M xb iiaTOS iSe'o" vepX yiip rh ToiavTov ffa/ia r\ aXaBiiins. Sophonias in Arist. Psych, ed. Hayduck p. r3, 37 hvhs yap tA itriffTTj fioviKSi rh vod^v tttj upitrfievus ^x*"'''"' rptits fie ff S6^a' rpiTTck yiip Kal t^ Bo^affrh Sih rh afj/pippeves* &.irh 3i ttjs rerpdSos riiv aXattiiriv, in irepX rh irw/ia, 5 rerpiSi avvreSftrai. OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 49 Aristotle^ scofifs at those who are content to regard the soul's knowledge as a series of lines, yet the modern science of psychophysics has certainly tended to confirm Plato's acute conjecture. To rise above iiria-r^fjirj is impossible for us — Laws 8q7 D fit] roiwv e'f ivavria^ olov el" TeAoy, rhv (rvK\oyi c9 b s3i (3 o -^ 1: b - o ■g Ui O U 1 & ■« tfl s- b- u e ^1 2§ o OF PLATO'S ETHICS. S3 ditions, viz. (a) the immutable being of jj tov Ij/o? Ihia, and (j3) the mutable becoming of the same in space of one, two, and three dimensions. Its objects of cogni- tion are again the remaining and similarly developed animals. (3) Each Idea in its perceptive evolution acquires four planes of consciousness : — As endowed with wO? it voel ; As passing into einarrifjL'q it inioTaTai, As passing into Bo^a it So^ofet, As passing into aitrdTjaii it aladdvereu. Moreover, the object of its perception throughout these four stages is any other Idea, perceived — by vou? as an apidfioi ; by iTnajriiit} as a fj.fJKO';, by Bo^a as an etriiTeBov, by aicrffijcri'} as a arepeov. Thus the passage as a whole enables us to fill up and complete the outlines of the Platonic scheme. PART II. HIGHER AND LOWER MENTALITY. At the outset of the present enquiry I proposed to analyse certain incidental passages of pregnant meaning in order to obtain some simple and yet adequate formula for the interrelations of Plato's Idealism. This analysis has established the main fact that Mind is operant in two different ways within the limits of Platonic ontology. For, in the first place, Mind is a Unity self-pluralised into a conclave of Minds, which are objective — i.e. really existent — Ideas. And in the second place, on pain of forfeiting its claim to real existence. Mind passes everywhere out of its own condition of permanent and immutable thought into the transitory and mutable phases of knowledge, opinion, sensation, thereby producing subjective — i.e. phenomenally exist- ent — particulars. In the words of Proklos : traaa i\ T&v yjrvyf&v rd^K eh Bvo Tavrai dv^pTijrai •7rr)yd<;, rijv re SrjfiiovfyyiKTjv Kal ttjv ^moyoviKi]V.^^ So far the outlines of the theory. It remains to ^ Proklos /« Tim. 3 19 A. OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 55 indicate the ethical colouring of the whole. But before attempting this further task, it will be well to secure due perspective by emphasising afresh the salient points of view. I shall, therefore, in the present chapter endeavour to illustrate from the Platonic dialogues the contrast thus formulated between the objective and subjective aspects of Mind, in the hope that each successive illustration, while exhibiting Plato's technical consistency in the use of non-technical terms, may bring into clearer light the moral significance of his design. § I. Purpose and Necessity. Timaeus 47 E discriminates (a) to, Bm vov BeSrj- fiiovfyyqfieva from (b) to. Si dvaf/K-rj^ jiyvofieva, and declares that the universe is the combined product of both : fie/itr/fievij yap ovv rj rovBe rov Kocr/iov yeveaK i^ avdr/Kri^ re Kal vov <7UO"Tacr6aj? iyevvrjBr). Now {a) the creations of vov<;, as we learnt from the Parmenides, comprise a series of subordinate Minds called the Ideas, which are unified in a single supreme Mind conceived as their basis and ground- work. Again, {b) ra Bi dvdyKrji ytyvofji^va are the results brought about by the necessary passage of the said Minds from the higher mode of " being " into the lower mode of " becoming " ; and this lapse, this S6 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS deviation, is as such^' referred in the Timaeus to r) irXavtatievr) ahia. It is clear, therefore, that Plato, when he contrasts ra 8io vov BeStjutovpyrj/Meva with to, Si dpdyK7]'i yiyvofieva, is describing just those two aspects of Mind which I have termed "objective" and "subjective." And we are confronted by the question : on what principle of distinction is the latter and not the former assigned to dvayKt] ? The reason of the change is not, I think, far to seek. It is uvdyK-rj that the supreme Mind should pass from the ravT6Tr)<; of I'ou? into the erepori;? of itnarriiiri, So^a, aiadr^aif. It is dvdyKt), too, that the subordinate Ideal Minds should similarly pass from perfect to imperfect thought. But it is not dvdyKt) that the supreme Mind should multiply itself into the Ideas. That process of objective pluralisation is never in Plato described as dvar/Koiov. It is on the contrary directly referred to 0ov\r]ai^, the very opposite^^ of dvdyK-q. In proof of this contention I may cite first Tim. ^ Mr. Archer-Hind seems to me ill-advised in stating (ed. Tim. p. 167 n.) that "Plato calls avdyKij the irAavoi/iEVr) alrla, because, though working strictly in obedience to a certain law, it is for the most part as inscrutable to us as if it acted from arbitrary caprice." The term iT\ava>nevi) surely denotes nothing more than deviation, and is the equivalent of Bdrepov as opposed to rv-hriv. ^^ For jSotSATjffis ) ( h.v&yKi] cp. Crat. 420 D where rb Karh. rifir Poi\r\(riv ytyvd/xevov is opposed to rh i,vayKa!ov koX ivrirvTov, irapet OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 57 29 E — premising that the supreme vov, to the latter as irepa^ irapixovra to arreipa. These conditions being granted, knowledge becomes a possibility {Farm. 155 D). We may well follow Dr. Jackson when in this class of intermediates he recognises the Ideas of Plato's own ontology." It appears, then, that both in the Philebus and in the Parmenides the Ideas are regarded as a bond between the single objective Mind and the indefinity «' The Journal of Philology, yi\,y%. 62 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS of subjective phenomena, their prerogative being to introduce the Trepai of the former into the direipia of the latter. The words of Aetios*^ are strictly- accurate : IBea icrrlv ovaia daciofjbaTOi;, ai/ria t&v oia iaTiv airf/ teal irapdSeiy/jLa tt)? rS)v Kara vaiv e')^6vrmv ala-OrjT&v VTro(nd ddppoQ)fjLoicofj,evov €Tepov roiovTov (Soph. 240 A). Now if all that lapses not from the identity of ■oWw? ovala be fitly termed tuvtov, the domain of TavTOTi}'; will comprise on the one hand (a) the supreme Mind ; for the ordering of the chaotic universe could not impair the moveless calm of intelligence : Tim. 42 E 6 fiev hri [de6<;, i.e. vow) diravTa ravra Biard^ai; ep,ev€V ev tc3 eavTOv Kara rpoirov rjdef p,ivovTO<; Se voriaavTeiJ,dXov ^vo-ews. (That avKTorrif here=:^ Oarepov ^vfn avTw /iTfhe e(TTdvai, fit) Ioto? Se Kiveladai ; OvTtov. Again {0) tuvtov connotes £ood, ffdrepov evil. " These passages probably refer to Plato notwithstanding Philop. in Arist. Phys. ed. Vitelli p. 352, 20 tXeyav Sc 01 Tlvia-^/ifeiai t'i\v Klin\aiv fJvtti «t«(kJtj)To koI imtrSTiiTa Kal rh tiij in. ^' Arist. Psych. P. 10. 8. 433 b 24 is parallel only in appearance. 74 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS For this we have Aristotle's express testimony — Met. A. 6. 988 a 14 ert Se Trfv tov eZ Koi rod KaKwvaei, voWovt elvat -rraXiv tov Kal tw (lopl^ . . . Outo)?. Ovkovv ere pa Svra rov evbq fiedi^et ra /jieri'xpvra avrov ; II5>^ 8' ov ; That is to say that to okov [=ro rrav- T6\6S i/Ssov of Tim. 3 1 B) as well as ra p.6pta (= ra ev /iipovi e'lSei §Sa of Tim. 30 c) passes into the sphere of Odrepov. • Agreeably to this Phikb. 30 D represents the Creator as having not only vovaii^v Tjplv d'jroBeSely(6ai, — repeats the assurance of Phaedo 62 D — THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS eiiXoyaf e^ei to deov tc eivai tov iiri/ieXovfievoifi" 7)/jb&v Kal ■^fidf eKeivov KT'^fiara etvai. The moral bearings of this question call for further consideration : for the present I proceed, noting merely that if the supreme ^&ov can pay separate attention to the individual souls of men, it must — unless the argumentation of Parmenides be entirely groundless — pass from the rauTOTijs of pure thought into the crepoTj?? of knowledge, opinion, and even sensation. To challenge that passage is indeed to obscure the connection between Plato's ethical speculations and their ontological basis. (6) Mr. Archer-Hind commenting on Tim. 86 E writes : — " Absolute being, absolute thought, and absolute goodness are one and the same. Therefore from the absolute or universal sout can come no evil." Had he in lieu of "soul " repeated the word " thought," no exception could have been taken to the dictum. As it stands, the second clause seems to me a specific denial of the evil world-soul described in the tenth book of the Laws. The description there given cannot be ignored ; — •ifvyj) . • • vovv /lev irpoakapovtra ael 6eov debos. OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 85 and it forces upon us the conclusion that the cosmic soul qud. cosmic functions not only in the mode of tamov as perfect thought, but also in the mode of ddrepov as imperfect thought. These are the main arguments which tend to show that ike erepoTi;? 0/ the One must not be confused either with the ravTOTrj^ or with the eTepoTTj^ of the Many. Its more precise determination will be attempted in the succeeding section. § III. Theology. In discussing the evolution of vow we have more than once had occasion to use the words ^eo? and fieto?. We are not, however, entitled to adapt theo- logical terms to the purposes of philosophy unless we can return an afiSrmative answer to the vexed ques- tion — Did Plato, or did he not, bring his religious convictions into any intimate connection with his metaphysical views.' Dr. Zeller, who here as else- where represents modern orthodoxy at its best, holds that theology does not rank with Dialectics, Physics, and Ethics, as a definite part of the Platonic doctrine ; that it cannot even be classified under any of these sciences" ; that, in short, " the particular notions which bring Plato in contact with positive religion are «- Plato and The Older Academy, p. 494. 86 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS for the most part mere outworks of his system, or else an inconsistent relapse into the language of ordinary opinion." ^^ And yet there are certain a priori con- siderations which militate strongly against the ortho- dox position. It is difficult to believe that a speculator so thorough-going and fearless as Plato would have shrunk from the attempt to base his own religion on a sound intellectual foundation. And that foundation lay ready to hand. For it must be observed that, if by a personal being is meant one conscious of uniting in itself a diversity of its own states, then the supreme Mind and the Ideal Minds have substantial claims to personality; and further, that in the said Minds is vested the directorate of the universe. We shall not then be sinning against antecedent likelihood, if we enquire how far Plato provides material for the expression of the Idealist creed in terms of divinity. (A) Broadly speaking we may say that, in the Platonic scheme, the objective realm of ravrbv is characterised as divine, and its denizens as deities : Polit. 269 D TO KaTk Tama. KoiX mo-owTO)? e)(e.LV ae^ Koi, TavTov elvai rot? irdmmv deioTaTOi^ irpo- ff'^Kei /lovoii}. In fact, v67]ai9 8e KivTjOev avro koI ^&v ivorjae rSsv aiBiav 6eSiv lyer/ovov of/aXfia 6 •yevv^aav iraTijp, rjiycurdr), — '' Stob. Eel. I. X. 16 a ed. Wachsmuth i. p. 127, 20. Eel. I. i. 29* (Aetios) ibid. p. 37, 4 nXcErwv Se rh ev, rh fioi/otpves, rh fiovaStK6V) rh &VTUS $v, ThyaB6v, Tl&VTa 8£ Tck TotavTa twv ovofjiArtov els Thv vovv awtiSei. NoCs oiv i 8e6s. Cp. Eel. I. vi. la (Menander) iiiil. p. 83, 20, I. i. 24, Hid. p. 31, 5 ri tot' iirrl Beisi vovs. THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS where they are termed 6eol as being the first plural- isation®* of ^eo?, and atSiot 6eo\ as being the first pluralisation of that which is an aiSiov ^Stov (Tim. 37^). Mr. Archer-Hind well urges®* that Plato "used this strange phrase with some deliberate purpose in view." I cannot however agree with him that " the signific- ance of so calling them is very hard to see." It appears to me a direct indication that the Ideas are the partial Minds into which the universal Mind multiplies itself The Politicus perhaps allegorizes the same Unity and Plurality of gods, when it states (271 D seq^ that in the golden age the universe as a whole was managed by a 6eo- Xijijseaav Saifiovei;, avrdptcrji eh irdvra exaaTo^ eKoarov; wv ol? avro? eve/iev. (271 D) (B) But ravrov must of necessity pass into Odrepov. There is need, therefore, to examine the subjective manifestation of these objective deities. And since '* irpara SiaKeKpiftdva tt/s aiiepiiTTOv ivdiircus, as Simplicius in Arist, Psych, ed. Hayduck p. 28, 22 calls them. " Ed. Ttmamsp. 118 «. " Cp. Polif. 272 E at KUTii roils Tifirouj mydpxoiTei r^ ^eyiory iaiiiovt Bfol. OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 89 we have distinguished the erepoieaaK of the cosmic 0609 from that of the partial ffeoi, our enquiry sub- divides itself into two questions : (a) What is the minor mode of the supreme 6e6iuvi/ifvos, t)v Si oi. Soph. 237 D hiiyicfi t6» t« Xiyovra iv yi tj \fyeiv. 90 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS I take it that 6 &v del Seo? is contrasted with 6 irore €(r6fi€vos, (&ov ix (^ui> Kal Behs in Stay, Zehs Sh Kal , xaBh vovs lupf oS irpotpspertu vdvra, 0Tt Stj/jnovpyei rots voijficurw. OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 93 When, therefore, we meet the phrase Oeol detov we are tempted to find in it the plural (representing the subjective indefinity) of him who is the 0e6v. So far as the phrase itself is concerned, this would be a perfectly simple and straightforward solution. But it remains to be seen whether the nature and functions of the 6eol 6e&v, as described in the Timaeus, tally with those of the supreme vmyrhv ^wov conceived as the percept of particular percipients. And first as to their nature. Tim. 34 B segg. nar- rates how the original blend of ■^frvx'j was compounded of the three primal elements. It was used for the cosmic soul, being divided into the circles of the Same and the Other. Tim. 41 B tells how the second blend oiy^vxv was compounded of the same elements, though in a less pure condition. It went to form the subord- inate souls, each of which possessed a similar pair of circles. Now in between these two brews we have the planets described as Sea-yiioi? e/ii/ruj^ots awfjuara Se06vra %&a (38 e), and the fixed stars called ^maOela Kol diSca (40 B). Whence — it may be asked — came the animation of these ^aa? It could not be fur- nished by the second mixture of '^v^ri, since that had not yet been compounded. Moreover, the first mixture had been entirely used up (36 b) in the making of the cosmic soul. It is obvious, therefore, that the starry fwa are the externalisation of the cosmic soul as distinguished from the subordinate souls. 94 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS It was natural that their bodies should be placed not only in the circle of the Other to perform the planetary functions, but also in the circle of the Same to be a veritable K6cr/j,o<;. For they are the exponents of the Godhead in the sight of men ; and by setting forth the twofold aspect of " their great original " act as an everlasting witness to an eternal truth. It was no mere access of astronomical ardour which led Plato to write : T(bv vvv Xoyav irepl rov Traj/ro? Xeyo/ievtov ovSeh av TTOTe ipp'^drj fiTJre dcrrpa fjurfie rjKmv fi/qre ovpavov ISovTtov (Tim. 47 a). There can, then, be little doubt that the 6eoi deSyp, whom Tim. 41 A identifies with these stars, are simply a subjective pluralisation of the supreme Mind. Were we capable of pure viyqai,^, we should apprehend them as a single deov. The same lesson may be learnt from the Laws along with sundry practical corollaries. For it is more than probable that the gods, whose care over men is there vindicated by the Athenian, are identical with the 6eo\ 6e&v of the Timaeus. This becomes evident, otoi/ TeKfitjpia \epiaifiev to? elai 6eoi, ravra aiiret irpo^povrei}, ^\i6v re km creK'^vijv xal aarpa koI v KoX iraamv mp&v irept Tiva aXKov \6yov ipovfiev fj tov ainov tovtov, v there is a constant oscillation between the use of the singular and the plural number. Thus we have deot (44 D) . . . Oeov (44 E) . . . deal (45 A) . . . ^eds (46 C) ...0e6s (47A)...^e6i/ (47B)...06oi) {/^y C) . . .de&v (47c). The alternation may be seen on an extended scale from Tim. 69 C to almost the end of the dialogue. In 92 A the grammatical change is not even marked, the subject of ^evvT/aav viz. deal being supplied from the previous 0eov jSao-ei? inroTidevToa are multiples of the supreme fwoj/, whose '" This doctrine was a refinement upon the teaching of the earlier dialogues, e.g: Phaedrus 245 E irSv yaf aapta ^ fiiv ^uOev rh KivtiaBai, Ihjiuxov, $ !4 tvioBfV o4t^ i^ aarov, lfi\fivxov, as Tairr)! oUffiis ibiaeus rfnjx^s- ^^ Cp. TYfft, 69 C rwv /lev Beiuv ainhs ylyvfrai SrifjLiovpySi, I02 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS subjectivity therefore takes logical precedence of theirs. Plato in fact goes more to the root of the matter by assigning the causation of the dvrjrbv 'yevo? eotxe, im hi (144 D — e) Kai firjv TO, ye iravra fiepr) ret avrov rb ev ia-Ti, Kal ovTe Ti Trkeov ovre eKarrov ^ iravra. (14S C) From these passages I gather that what Aristotle ^ calls TO, TToWa T&v vjis a'iro8av6i'Tos ixdiTTOv. The former passage conceives the individual mind confronting that which is oAt6 KaB" airh linff airov /iovoiiSh i,e\ iv, the latter represents the disembodied soul of the particular man after death. Both depict a juxtaposition of the properties of oitrla and yivtais, which except in a moment of transition is impossible. OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 105 mode of rairov, and the term elimv to denote the cognitions of ifrvxv functioning in the mode of Odrepov, then I conceive that the position assigned by Plato to the ^601 6emv may be fairly represented by the follow- ing diagram : irapa^eiyfta elxcov deo9 0eol 6eu)v {b) Lastly, we approach the question, What of the subjective aspect of the Ideal gods ? There is but one fitting term for a minor order of ot'Stot Oeoi, namely SaifioveTa av Tavavrla tovtok aTrepyd^erai. Theaet. 176 E irapaZeir/fidrav, & ^!Xe, ev r(p ovn earancov, tov fiev delov eiSainoveardTov, rov Se ddeov dBXitoTarov — or in that of the subordinate minds, — Tim. 86b voaov fiev Sf) ■^f^^s avoiav ^vyx^mprjTiov. Rep. 589 E el Be to eavTov QeioraTov inrb toJ ddeo)- rdrtp re Kal fiiapcoTaTm Sov\ovrat...ovK apa a6\i6itpi,Ti)s.. oix iare\iri(ei Kal h- rots &K6yoti fiiJoii (quoted by Zeller op. cit. p. 592«.). OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 109 Plato's opposition between the power that makes for good and the power that makes for evil reappears perhaps in Xenokrates' broad contrast ®^ between Zevvaei e^ei ri delov. But a modified system of metaphysics caused certain changes in his theological vocabulary. The conception of a creative vovTav (frnvepav Phys. JB. 4. 1960: 33, ta Oela adofjLara Met. A. 8. 1074a 30, de caelo B. 12. 292 iJ 32, and the more definite expressions of [Alex.] in Met. ed. Hayduck p. 709, 28 fif. Q eo\ . . , roaovToi oaai al a^alpai, i^prrjfiivoi, tjj? deioTdTr}<; koX dpia-TT)'; ova-Ladv possesses four faculties, namely vow, eiri(TTii/ji,r], So^a, a'ia-OrjaK, — the three last being moments in the sub- jective evolution of the first, and opposed to it as yiveaK to ovtw? ovaui. Particulars which, as such, belong to the region of yiyvofneva are consequently debarred from vorjaif. they are, however, endowed with . eTTiaTijfjiij, So^a, and aia6rja-K *^ though in the lower forms of life even these are to a greater or less extent in abeyance. This catalogue of the cognitive powers accords well with the usage of the more advanced Platonic writings. In the earlier dialogues pure thought is not unfrequently ascribed to individual thinkers (e.g. Rep: S 1 1 C, D, 5 24 c, Ptiaed. 83 B. alib.}. The Philebus adopts a half-way position ; for it expressly distinguishes the human i/oO? of 21 D, 22 c, 58 D, from the aKt]6iiVo ""'''' ^X""' (^9 B)= "sensible, reasonable," and the compounds ivvoiiv (87 d), Karavoeiv (90 D) etc. But to avoid them would have been mere pedantry. Il8 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS ZiavmffiaTav jj Ik rov vov ^epofiivr} SvvafiK ^* (7 1 ^)- '^^ females and the lower animals it alludes in 91 D — 92 B, arranging them in a descending scale according as they approximate to or recede from that higher mentality — vov koI avoiat airo^oXy koX KTtja-ei (92 B) ; while 77 B brings even vegetable life into the same register, — «5 So^rji; /lev Kal Xoyianov { = eiriarr;ii7)' Ji/iav tUvi vooi/uva ii6yov, the position of the pronoun is instructive. "" Simplicius {in Arist. Psych, ed. Hayduck p. 317, 11) states that plants %x^"' V-^v Tiva cHatriiriv, ItjuiSforcpav Si ^ Kurii rck KWais ^wi^a, Kal &s c^t) XlKirwv oTov KafledSovtrai' aXaB7iaTeov, vov Se deov<;, avdpmirwv fie yivo €K deSiv ipplv del Xeyofievmv elvai,, iripav 8e Kal diretplav iv avTOK ^vfi<}>vTov ij(6vTtov. The last phrase of this passage aptly expresses just that scheme which one particular man could not by his unaided reason have descried ; it gives us the appended diagram, in which h denotes the supreme Mind, and iroWa the Ideal series. (2) But if any one turns a deaf ear to this theory of inspiration, or quotes by way of retort Re/>. 381 E — firjS av inro rourmv dvaveidofievai al firjTepei; rii iraidia eKSeifiaTovvTcov, Xeyovcrat tou? jxvOow KUKW, w dpa 6eol rivei •rrepiep'XpvTai vvKTtop TToX^OK ^ivof! Kal iravToSaTroii! IvSaWo/Mevoi, "va lii) dfia fiev eli Oeovf ffKatrtfyijii&a-iv, dfia Be rov; TratSas wTrepyd^vrai, BetKoTepotK — Plato can fall back on a less pregnable position. He holds that the souls of individuals have before their incarnation stood face to face with the Creator, 124 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS and learnt from his lips rrjv tov ttoi/to? 4>^a-tv {Tim. 41 e). This they were enabled to do, because the souls of men conceived as not yet associated with their bodies do not differ from the Idea of Man, under whose intuition all noetic existence would naturally fall.^"^ The doctrine of Anamnesis is in fact the safe- guard of Idealism. It may be denied : but it can hardly be disproved, and — as has before been hinted — it presupposes some such relation of the ideas to Mind as was elicited from the assumptions of the Parmenides. The confinement of pure thought to the world of Ideas cannot, then, invalidate the foundations of the Idealist system, because the individual philosopher not only builds upon the experience of previous thinkers but also possesses an innate criterion of his own structure : Phaedrus 249 B, C Sel.yap-dp9p(07rov-^iH€vai Kar^ 6(So; Xeyo/ievov, ex TroWav lov aladrjaetov et? ev Xoyta/jiw ^vvaipovfievov. tovto Si ii\oa-6(f>ov Sidvota • irpb^ fyap eKeivoitK6vyr) Be o/mioxtk 6e& Kara to SvvaTov. 126 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS Tim. 29 E irdvra 6 ti fiaXiara r^evevOai i^avKridit irapairK^aia eavT&. Laws 716 c Tov oZv T& roiovTfp [sc. 6e&) vpoi\i} yevriaofievov eldvKvia . . . jjSu Kal 7rpoa-VKev dr/a'7rr)TW diroBiSov, Hearing. — I3id. 80 B ■fjBovijv fiev tok d(f>pocnv, ev Ioutwj;,^" logically distinct types. In this substrate the transient shapes of particulars, the elaiopja Koi i^iovra of Tim. 50 C, are momentarily expressed. They are declared to be T&v ovreov ael fiifiij/iara ; for bodily shape is — as already stated — the individual soul as viewed by our imperfect faculties, and the individual soul is but the Idea as it passes into the triple phase of genetic thought. This holds good, whether percipient and percept belong to different species or to the same, or again coincide in a single personality. So far as method is concerned it matters not whether Sokrates beholds a star, or a friend, or himself In any case a voryrov ^wov is cognised by a votjtov ^S>ov on the plane of sensation, and the result must be a localisation of the former by the latter in the inroSoxv- Now it is clear enough that the material content of this localisation is a fractional part of the whole cosmic ffvaraa-K. What is not at once clear is the determination of specific contour and its connection with the shape of the universe. Why, for example, '" Tim. 51 B. 132 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS is Sokrates' body unlike that of a star, and by no means hard to distinguish from that of his friend ? And how are all three related to the mundane sphere ? The answer to these questions, though implicit rather than explicit in Plato's writings, seems in- evitable. If a particular shape is a particular soul as it appears to particular cognition, it follows that difference of embodiment presupposes difference of soul. In fact we formulate the law : As is the imita- tion of the active ■v/ry^Tj, so will be the imitation of the passive a&fia. Individual souls were grouped under certain definite types, vis. the votjto, ^wa, according to their degree of approximation to the cosmic soul. Therefore individual bodies will be similarly grouped under certain fixed forms, vis. the natural kinds, according to their degree of approximation to the cosmic body. A being endowed with superhuman — say, stellar — thought will be apprehended not as a man but as a star. Again, within the limits of each several species differences of personal shape will be referred to differences of personal attainment, allowance being made for certain retarding tendencies soon to be noticed. That in Plato's view physical was thus dependent upon psychical development may be gathered from Aristotle's criticism in Psych. A. 3. 22-23, 4°/^ iS-24: awcmtovai 7A/3 km TiBeacriv ehs amfia ttjv '^uj^jJi'j ovdep trpoa^iopiaavTei; Sici riv' alriav ical ttw? OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 133 ej(pvTov Tov atn&v arfiiBa ry t^s •^i;;^^? i\o^jr6<})03V, XvaK koX ytapiap.o'i '^vxV'i o.iro aa>fiaTO6pe9 ov eh fiev • alria Be dviaorrji; o5 t^? dvmiJidXov ^wcreft)?, where — as I showed from Aristotle — awo-oTijs is equivalent to 17 Bwrepov Svva/j.i epKe'i ireTrTjjWTaj | i(rTiTioy Kviiaaovras ivtlpvirtv. 142 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS body eh ttiv sk t'^? Koi\La<; eirl ra? ov attains that degree of excellence which is the external manifestation of the next higher ^ebov, or sinks to that degree which marks the next lower ^mov, the particular shape under which the said activity was seen must of necessity undergo a corresponding change. To take an example. The Ideal being Man on the plane of sensation perceives himself as a diverse multiplicity of men. One member of this multiplicity — say, Orpheus — is apprehended as possessing poetic genius. When his particular form perishes, a com- pensating form is bound to appear somewhere within "8 Ed. Tim. p. 344 k. OF PLATO'S ETHICS. 147 the limits of the cosmic ^wov. And since transmigra- tion is ever towards to ofji,oiov — Laws 904 E KaKio) fj,ev ryiyvofievov Trpo? ra? KaKiovi •^v^d's, dfjieivas Se Tr/ao? ras afieivovi iropevo- fievov ^^^ — the new form will appear in the presentations of that Idea which is the paradeigm of the acquired qualities, — say, the Idea of Swan. What has happened is this. The Idea of Man has not become the Idea of Swan ; for every Idea is an eternal being ovre et? iavrb elaSex- Ofievov aXXo dWodev ovre aino et? aXKo iroi lov {Tim. 52 a). But one e^iov of Man has vanished and one eltribv of Swan appeared in virtue of the fact that the Ideal series is the unitary Mind existent as a plurality. But, it will be asked, if the body is such an infallible index of the soul, why do not acquired characteristics gradually display themselves in form and features .' How comes it that Horace's fancy is not a commonplace fact } — " lam iam residunt cruribus asperae pelles, et album mutor in alitem superne, nascunturque leves per digitos humerosque plumae." "' Stobaeus Ed. I. xlix. 60 (Porphurios) ed. Wachsmuth i. p. 445, 23 observes that, according to Plato, the soul iv rah Xeyo/isvais .\v ifwv t4 Bv/iThv aiou lyivero, \ rh S' iBivarov i^i\pe wphs rhv aepa. | toi/t' IS2 METAPHYSICAL BASIS OF PLATO'S ETHICS. ouSef aWo ep^ov rm irerTevry XetTrerat irKqv lieraTiOevai to /lev aiieivov yvyvofievov ^0ov ef dvwyier)'; •rradriixdrcov. Thus in the last resort we come back to the 6eo<; de&v, and have warrant for describing Plato's ethical theory as the moral synthesis of a metaphysical analysis, the return of Unity towards itself, — a process that is discrete rather than continuous, inasmuch as the aireipa journey towards the ^v through the several stages of the TToWa. INDEX LOCORUM Alex, de anim. ed. Bruns p. Arist. Met. A. 6. 9880 14 74 85,20 7» — — 9-990*7 78 in Anst. Met. ed. Hay- — — 9- 990* 13 7| duck p. 92, 19, 22 7« — — 9. 991 a 2 o^* — p. 670, 27 3» — — 9. 991 b 26 iS« — p. 700, 27 4S — B. 4. looi b 23 72 — p. 709, 28ff no — E. I. 1026a 18 no — P- 709. 33 no — Z. 14. 1039* 9—16 34 — P- 721. 31 no — — 15. 1040025 91 — p. 731. 16 39 » — — 16. 1040* 12 73 Alexis Olympiad, frag. com. — — 16. 1040* 29 78 ed. Meineke iii. 455 151 n — A'. 9. 1066 fl 10 73 Archilochus 3. 4 105 « — yl- 3. 1070a 26 23 « Archytas in frag. phU. Gr. — — 7. 1072* 18—30 109 ed. Mullach i. 565 23 « — — 7. 1072 b 20 14 Arist. de an. gen. B. 3. 736 — — 7. 1073 a n 19 » *27 no — — 8. 1073 a 16 4S de caelo B. 12. 292 b 32 no ' — — 8. 1073020 44 de mundo 2. 391 * 14 — 1 9 no — — 8. 1074 a 30 no depart, an. A. i. 642 a — — 8. 10744 8 — 14 no 32 62 n — — 8. 1074 b 16 no S. 645a 4 no — - 9- 1074*33 80 — A. 10. 686 a 28 no — — 9- io74*35ff ii7« Eth. Eud. H. 12. 124S* — — 9- 107503 14 16 109 — — 10. 1075034 74 14. 1248a 27 III — M. 2. 1077024 38 Eth. Nic. Z. 7. 1 141 a 34 no — — 2. 1077 29 49 » — H. 14. 1153*32 109 « — — 4. 1079 a 2 78 — K. 7. 11770 16 in — — 4. 107909 78 frag. 46. 1483027 109 — — 4. 1079325 78 — 184. isioa 4 i8» — — 4- 1079032 78 — 184. iSioa 14 34 — — 6. 1080* 12 126 — 187. 1511043 in — — 7. 1081*31 28 — apud Philoponum 46 — — 7. 1081* 35ff 79 « Met. A. 6. 987 b 10 78 — — 7. 1082 * 32 133 6. 987 b 10 78 — — 8. 1083 9 iSffi 6. 987* 10 103 « — — 8. 10840 12 44 6. 9880 2 78 — — 8. 10840 29 45 154 INDEX LOCORUM. PAGE PAGE Arist. Met. M. 8. 1084 a 34 74 Arist. /ltyi:-4./'. 4. 12. 43002 14 9. 1085 a 26 34 5. I. 430a 17 19 « 9. 1086 a 26 27 6. 430a 28 zn — N. I. 1087^ 4 ff 72 8. 3. 4320 12 7 I. 1087^ 12 27 10. 3. 433 b 24 73 « — — I. 1087 ^ 14 41 Topka B. 6. 112 a yi 108 « I. 1088 a 15 72 — E. 6. 136*7 109 I. 1088 15 10 45 / — Z. 10. 148 a 15 96 » I. io88^ II 46 10. 148 a 20 18 » 2. 1088*32 72 Chalcidius8« Plat. Tim. ed. 2. 1089* 6 ff 72 Wrobel p. 200 97 « 4. 1091 6 3 27 — p. 202 ii9« 4. 1091 15 19 27 — p. 203 68 « 4. 1091 (5 25 — — p. 204 68 » 1092 a 5 74 Ciceto de fin. ii. 12. 40 III 4. 10920 6 27 — denat. dear. i. 13. 34 91 « S. 1092 a 29 72 Clemens Strom. V. xiii. 87 108 « Phys. A. 9. 192 a 14 74 xiv. 116 109 « — B. 4. 196 a 33 no — VI. vi. 53 III — r. 2. 201 b 19 72 Diog. La.ert. iii. 12, 13 18 « 6. 206 b 32 45 - 38, 63 124 « — A. 2. 209(5 33 "5 — 42, 78 128 » 2. 209 * 35 78 — iv. 2. I 78 » . Pol. B. s. 1264* 12 98 « Dionys. Areop. de div. »om. — r. 16. 1287328 109 C. I 2« Probl. IH. 7. 917 a 39 6« Empedocl. ed. Karsten vv. — Ar. 7. 962 a 22 III 313, 316, 317 4» 9. 962035 III Eur. Alk. 965 63 « Psych. A. 2. 6. 404 b 8 24 — Frag, Trag. adesp. 421 N 63 « 2. 7. 404 i 16 25 « Hes. Op. 129 4« 2. 7. 404* 17 42 — Theog. 656 4« 2. 7. 404 b 24 40 « Hippolyt. Ref. vii. 29 67 2. 7. 404* 25 42 Horn. Od. 215 4« 2. 17.405032 no — hymn, Merc. 80 2« 2. 20. 4051} 15 26 Horace Odes 11. xx. 9 ff 147 3. 8. 406 * 12 73 Niceph. Callist. H.E. vol. i. 3. II. 406* 25 — p. 8 b. s« 23. 407 b 26 135 Oppian Hal. iii. 341 — 370 141 » 3. i3-407«7 s« Parmenides ed. R. & P. vv. 3- IS- 407 a 29 49 K 39-40 10 3. 22—23. 407 >> — V. 73 2« 15—24 132 — vv. 94 — 96 II 4. 14. 408 b 29 19 « Philoponus in Arist. Phys. 4. 14. 408 b 29 no ed. Vitelli p. 352, 20 73 « 4- 17- 409«5 49 « in Arist. Psych. A. 2. — ^. 8. 10. 420* 19 f 62 « 7. 404* 19 32 — r. 4. 4. 429027 23 » — 2. 7. 404* 19 46 INDEX LOCORUM. I5S Philoponus in Arist. Psych. A. 2. 7. 40415 19 — 2. 7. 40415 21 — 2. 7. 404* 21 Plato Cratylus 397 c — 398 B — 403c — 420 D — 439 E Def. citirBnirts, v6ri 138 — 44D 139 — 44E 95 — 4SA 95 — 46 c 95 — 46 D 23 « — 46 D 117 — 46 E 68 — 47 A 94 — 47 A 95 — 47B 83 — 47B 95 — 47 c 95 — 47 c 95 _ 47E ^5 _ 47E 65 — 48 A 63 — 48E 71 — 49A 71 — 50 c 131 — 50D 97 — 5IB 131 « — 5ID ii8» — 51 E 120 INDEX LOCORUM. IS9 PAGE PAGE Plato Tim. 74 A 139 Plato Tim. 90 D 83 — 7SA 66 — 90 D ii7» — 75E 96 — 90 D 127 — 75D 139 — 90 E 36 — 76 E 148 « — 91 A f 145 — 77A 66 — 91B 146 — 77B 118 — 91 c 145 -78a 141 — 91 D — 92 B 118 — 78 a— 79 E 140 — 91 D — 92 B 134 -78c 141 - 9IE 83 — 78E 142 — 9IE 139 » — 79B 66 — 92 A 95 — 80 B 130 — 92 B 118 — 80D 142 — 92c . 90 — 81 A 139 — 92 c 96 » — 81B 149 Tim. Locr. 94 B 120 — Sic 149 — — lOI D 140 — 81C 149 Plotinus Enn. n. ix. 8 II2» — 81C ISO — V. i. T 79 » — 81D ISO — V. i. ■ III n — 81 D — E 130 — V. i. 2 II2» -83A 130 — V. i. 2, 4 II2» — 84B 150 « — V. i. 4 49 « -85A 83 — V. i. 4 II2» — 86b 107 — V. i. 4 II2» — 86c iSo» — V. i. 7 II2» — 86e 84 — V. i. 8 12 » — 87 A 83 — V. i. 10 49 « — 87A 134 — V. V. I 49 « — 87 c 144 — V. ix. 8 79 « — 87D ii7« — VI. viii. 18 64 » — 87D 126 Plut. deplacit. phil. i . 10 IS — 87D I3S — iv. II 7 — 88 b 83 Mor. 691 c 6» — 88b 106 — 1007 F 109 « — 88b 137 — 1 120 A 6k — 88c 140 Porpli. in Categ. ed. Busse — 88d 140 p. 91. 14 14 — 89B 35 « Op. ed. Holsten p. — 89B 37 » 66 6» — 89B 66 VU. Plot. 10 II2« — 89B ii7« Proklos in Farm. ed. Cousin — 89B 152 V. 140 7 — 90A loS — V. 147 4 — 90 c los — V. 148 „ ',5 — 90c 128 — vi. 30 Pref. — 90 c 129 The. Plat. ii. II .p. no 92 i6o INDEX LOCORUM. Proklos in Tim. 4 c PAGE 37 » — 94c II2« — 319A 54 « Sextus MatA. viii. 286 Ii8» Simplicius in Phys. A, ed. Dielsp. 87, 17 I2« — p. 143, 18 ff I2« — p. 143, 26 ff 79 » — p. 147. 21 ff 79 » — p. 197, 10 67 in Psych, ed. Hayduck P- 10, 33 50 n — p. 28, II 13s — p. 28, 22 88 « — p. 28, 22 ff 31 — p. 29. 2 47 » — p. 29, II 26 » — p. 29, 12 43 » — P- 317. II ii8» Sophonias de anim. paraph. ed. Hayduck p. 13, 6 32 — in Arist. Psych, ed. Hayduck p. 13, 37 48 » Stob. Eel. I. Pro. 10 (Plu- tarch) ed. W. i. p. 22, s 47 « — I. i. 24 (Philos. Incert.) ed. W. i. p- 31. S 87 » — I. i. 25 (Porphyry) ed. W. i. p. 31, 8 92 » — I. i. 29A(Aetios)ed. W. i. p. 37, 2 108 « PAGE Stob. Eel. 1. i. 29 b (Aetios) ed. W i. p. 37, 4 87 « — I. vi. I a (Menander) ed. W. i. p. 83, 20 87 n — I. X. 160 (Aetios) ed. W. i. p. 127, 19 IS — I. X. i6a(Aetios)ed. W. i. p. 127, 20 87 « — I. X. 16* (Aetios) ed. W. i. p. 128, 14 27 « — I. xii. I a (Aetios) ed. W. i. p. 134, 9 97 — I. xii. I a (Aetios) ed. W. i. p. 134, 9 ff 62 » — I. xii. 2 a (Arius Didymus) ed. W. i. p. 136, 10 82 « — I. xii. I (Hermes) ed. W. i. p. 277 15 68 n — I. xlix. 6 (Hermes) ed. W. i. p. 324, S 148 « — I. xlix. 60 (Porphy- ry) ed. W. i. p. 445, 23 147 » — I. Ixi. I (Hermes) ed. W. i. p. 27s, 16 117 « — I. Ixi. I (Hermes) ed. W. i. p. 27s, 17 19 » Themistius j» Arist. Psych. ed. Spengel p. 20 36 — p. 20 ff 32 — p. 21 32 « — p. 21, 17 48 « 1