...t\ . , .tf?;-ftlf,f
aXXijXois.
CAMBEIDGE:
DEIGHTON, BELL, AND CO.
LONDON: BELL AND DALDT.
1862.
UNIVERSITYi
LIBRARY
A
VI PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION.
give an accottnt in a compendious form of some of his
speculations in Jurisprudence; inasmuch as on this
subject his writings are voluminous, and their leading
features may not be readily seized by the general
reader.
I have pointed out freely both Mr Bentham's
merits and his defects in this department : for in-
stance, in the Classification of Offenses I have pointed
out that his method produces cross divisions of the
subject, ciunbrous and shapeless appendages to the re-
gular members of his classification, and the absence
of obvious places for some of the most common
offenses, as Fraud, Breach of Contract, Debt. I do
not know that any of Bentham's admirers have at-
tempted to show that his system does not labour
under these defects : indeed he himself allows it. I
have attempted also to show how these defects may be
avoided.
The Dissertations of Dugald Stewart and of Mack-
intosh on the history of Moral Philosophy go over
much of the same ground as my Lectures : but stUl
I hope that the reflexions which the perusal of our
English moralists has suggested to me, may have some
interest for those who trace the progress of moral
opinions and principles among men.
Of the kind of interest which such a view of the
subject may excite, a curious example has recently
appeared in a volume which has drawn much notice
entitled Essays and Reviews. Mr Pattison the
author of one of those ' Essays,' entitled ' Tendencies
of Religious Thought in England, 1688 — 1750,' has
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION. Vll
to speak of several of the same -writers of wtom I
have spoken in the following Lectures. The con-
nexion of 'Keligious Thought' -with moral specula-
tion naturally brings him into the same field on which
I have ofiered my remarks. And Mr Pattison agrees
with what I have said in the beginning of Lecture VI.
as to the profligate and sensual tone of speaking and
writing which prevailed at the beginning of the last
century, and which I have exemplified especially in
Mandeville. He goes on to say (p. 323): "Though
there is entire unanimity as to the fact of the pre-
vailing corruption, there is the greatest diversity of
opinion as to its cause." He then proceeds to enu-
merate various causes of this state of things, assigned
by various parties; and this he does in a manner
which makes his list amusing, but, I think, somewhat
sarcastic towards the persons enumerated in it. The
Nonjurors and High Churchmen, he says, attribute
it to the Toleration Act and the Latitudinarianism
allowed in high places : for instance, to the favour
shown to Bishop Hoadley's celebrated Sermon. The
Latitudinarian Clergy divide the blame between the
Freethinkers and the Nonjurors. The Freethinkers
point to the hypocrisy of the Clergy, who, they say,
lost all credit with the people by having preached pas-
sive obedience up to 1688, and then suddenly finding
out that it was not a scriptural truth. The Noncon-
formists lay it to the enforcement of conformity and
the unscriptural terms of communion; whUe the
Catholics rejoice to see in it the 'Protestant Reforma-
tion at last bearing its natural fruit. And Warbur-
Vm PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION.
ton attributes it to the bestowal of 'preferment' by
the Walpole Administration.
I certainly should not have expected that I should
figure in such a list as this: nor does it seem very
reasonable that a speculator on the Tendencies of
Eeli^ous Thought, at the period here spoken of,
should group a speculation on the Tendencies of Moral
Thought, written one hundred and fifty years later,
with such writers as are here quoted : these being
obviously put forward as persons blinded by passion
and party prejudice. Indeed Mr Pattison seems to
feel that it is only by force of very comprehensive
grouping that he can include such a writer in his
picture; and with generous condescension, as he seems
to mean it, he gives me the benefit of his most com-
prehensive mood.
"Lastly," he says, "that every one mo/y have his
say, a professor of moral philosophy in our day is
found attributing the same facts to the prevalence of
that low view of morality which rests its rules upon
consequences merely." And he then quotes the picture
which I have given of this inroad of corrupt doctrines.
Having thus made an opening for me in his view of
'Tendencies,' he proceeds to discuss the question
whether the low moral principles then prevalent were
the cause of the immoral habits which also prevailed.
He thinks not. He says, "The actual sequence of
cause and effect seems, if it be not presumptuous to
say so, to be as nearly as possible inverted in this
eloquent statement." I do not wish to revive here
the discussion of this point. When licentiousness of
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, IX
talk and manners prevail at the same time as low
moral doctrines, it must needs be very difficult to say-
in what degree each is cause and is effect. But there
is one argument used by Mr Pattison which I may
notice, in order to explain further the view which
I intended to take. " If," he says, " as Dr Whewell
assumes, and the whole doctrinaire school with him,
the speculative belief of an age determines its moral
character, that should be the purest epoch when the
morality of consequences is placed in the strongest
light — when it is most convincingly set before men
that their present and future welfare depends on how
they act : that ' all that we enjoy and great part of
what we suffer is placed in our own hands.' "
If Mr Pattison had done me the honour to attend
to the Lectures which he has quoted, he would hardly
have expected that this argument would appear to me
of any force. Throughout those Lectures I have put
in opposition to each other the morality of principles
and the morality of consequences. The latter I have
everywhere spoken of as a low and imperfect scheme
of morality: and because it is low and imperfect in
theory, it appears to me likely to be conjoined with a
low and lax morality in practice. It cannot make
men 'pure.' I do not at all know who the doctrinaire
school are, who, Mr Pattison says, agree with me in
holding this ; but I think we have with us the com-
mon voice of mankind. It seems to be a general
opinion that Epicurean principles of morality are
likely to be accompanied by licentious talk and licen-
tious action. The morality which reasons from the
X PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION.
consequences of action does not break this connexion.
However ' convincingly ' it proves to men that licen-
tious conduct is a mistake, they are not convinced for
purposes of practice. The voluptuary says, ' Accord-
ing to your own account I am right in seeking plea-
sure; and I shall seek it in my own way, not in
yours.' And so it is nothing wonderful to us — ^to me
and the doctrinaires who think with the common
people, — that the doctrine of moral consequences, ap-
plied, as Mr Pattison says it was, ' as the most likely
remedy of the prevailing Kcentiousness,' did not suc-
ceed.
I do not well understand whether Mr Pattison
thinks that opinions have any influence on practice.
In his view of the Tendencies of Religious Thought,
he seems to connect the licentiousness of which we
have been speaking with the Religious thought of the
time. Does he hold that religious views affect prac-
tice, though moral views do not ? It may be so ; but
one might have wished to see some further illustration
of so curious an aphorism.
Mr Pattison also thinks that I am in error in
saying that Butler shuns the use of technical terms,
and is thus driven to indirect modes of expression,
(p. 295.) The matter is not of much consequence, but
what I said was not lightly said, and I stiU believe
that a careful examination of Butler's writings will
prove its truth.
The fourteen Additional Lectures now first pub-
lished were written, like the former Lectures, for
delivery by me as Professor, and were most of them so
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION. XI
delivered. Some of them refer to ethical -writers and
ethical doctrines which have not commonly been in-
cluded in the history of moral philosophy : but they
will I think interest those who wish to view the whole
progress of human speculations on such subjects.
Trinity Lodge,
April II, 1862.
LECTUEES ON THE HISTOEY OF MOEAL
PHILOSOPHY IN ENGLAND.
INTEODTJCTOEY LECTURE.
PAGB
The Poini or View , i
LECTURE I.
Febeins. Ames. Hall. Sakdebsok. Taylob. Db
KHIGHTBBIOGB , l8
LECTURE 11.
EoBEEs I • : 40
LECTURE III.
Henet Mobb. Whiohootb. Wobihington. Wilkins 60
LECTURE IV.
CnMBEBLAinj. CnDWQBIH 75
Lecture v.
Loose. Glabee 91
LECTURE VI.
MANDEVILLB. ■WAEBDRTOir . . , . . 100
LECTURE VIL
PUMBBBLANB. SHAFIBSBrBT. HUTOHEBOIT. BaLGTJT.
Sooth ' . io7
XIV CONTENTS.
LECTURE VIII.
PAGB
Bdtlbe. Shambsbdrt. Waebubton. Beekbley.
TiNDAL. BaL&UT 126
LEGTUBE IX.
Waebubton. Law. Jacksoit. Uutheefokth. Wa-
TEELAMD ^4'^
LECTURE X.
Gat. Tuokbb. Palet '54
LECTURE XI.
Palet. Gisbobnb 178
LECTURE XII.
61BBOENE. Peabson. Pbicb. Robbet HaiiL . . 190
LECTURE XIII.
Bentham. His Biography. TTia Style of Discussion . 203
LECTURE XIV. •
Bektham. His Principles of Morals and Le^lation . 216
LECTURE XV.
Bbkthau. Objections to his System . . . . 228
LECTURE- XVI.
Bbnihau. Classification of Offenses .... 243
LECTURE XVIL
Bbnihau. Classification of Offenses continued . . 255
, LECTURE XVm.
Bentham. Defect of his System 268
Appendix. Recent Arrangements for the Horal Studies
at Cambridge 277
ADDITIONAL LECTUEES ON THE HISTOEY
OF MOEAL PHILOSOPHY.
LECTURE I.
PAQB
PlATO I
LECTURE II.
Abistotlb's Pstohologt and Lisi or Vietues , 6
LECTUEE IIL
Objections to Abistotlb's List op Vibtueb . . i8
LECTURE IV.
Abistotle on Justice and Equity . . . . 24
LECTURE V.
Abistotle and Plato — On the Rule op Lipe . 30
LECTUEE VI.
Abistotle on Rights — Plato's Politt ... 40
LECTURE VIL
Stoics and Epiocebaits— Cicbbo .... 50
LECTUEE VIIL
Jus 63
XVI CONTENTS.
LECTURE IX.
PAGB
Roman Law 7°
LECTURE X.
Cheistian Mobalitt. — St Augustine on Lying . '78
LECTURE XI.
Scholastic Mobalitt. — Pbtek Lombakd ... 94
LECTURE XII.
The Schoolmen. — Thomas Aquinas .... 98
LECTURE Xin.
Recapitulation. — Db S. Clabkb
loS
LECTURE XIV.
Reason and Undebstandinq. — S. T. Colekidge . 119
THE
HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
INTEODUCTOEY LECTIJEE.
The Point of View.
THE folio-wing Lectures contain criticisms on the
views and doctrines of a series of ethical writers;
they attempt to point out how far each was right, and
in what way he contributed to the progress of moral
speculation in this country. It is plain that such
judgments must be affected by the views and doctrines
of the critic himself. Nor is this a disadvantage in
such criticism, if the critic's point of view be defi-
nite and evident. In my "Elements of Morality"
I have given that view of the grounds and relations of
moral truths to "which the best parts of all previous
moral speculations appear to me to converge; but it
may still be of use to explain here, more briefly and
poiatedly, the System of Morality there presented.
Schemes of Morality, that is, modes of deducing
the Eules of Human Action, are of two kinds : —
those which assert it to be the law of human action
to aim at some external object, (external, that is, to
the mind which aims,) as for example, those which in
ancient or modern times have asserted Pleasure, or
Utility, or the Greatest Happiness of the Greatest
Number, to be the true end of human action ; and
those which would regulate human action by an in-
1
2 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
temal principle or relation, as Conscience, or a Moral
Faculty, or Duty, or Rectitude, or the Superiority of
Eeason to Desire. These two kinds of schemes may
be described respectively as Dependent and Indepen-
dent Morality. 'Sow it is here held that Independent
Morality is the true scheme. "We maintain, with
Plato, that Reason has a natural and rightful autho-
rity over Desire and Affection; with Butler, that
there is a difference of kind in our principles of
action; with the general voice of mankind, that we
must do what is right at whatever cost of pain and
loss. "We deny the doctrine of the ancient Epicureans,
that pleasure is the supreme good; of Hobbes, that
moral rules are only the work of men's mutual fear;
of Paley, that what is expedient is right, and that
there is no difference among pleasures except their
intensity and duration; and of Bentham, that the
rules of human actions are to be obtained by casting
up the pleasures which actions produce. But though,
we thus take our stand upon the ground of Independ-
ent Morality, as held by previous writers, we hope
that we are (by their aid mainly) able to present it in
a more systematic and connected form than has yet
been done.
Let us begin with the doctrine of Plato just refer-
red to ; that Reason has a natural and rightful autho-
rity over Desire and Affection, which doctrine Butler
has further illustrated. In making this principle the
groundwork of morality, we seem to be guilty of an
oversight; for the word rightful already involves a
moral notion: thai is rightful authority, and th^t
only, which it is immoral to disobey. lu order to
make our scheme complete, we must define rightful,
and prove that the authority of Reason over Desire is
rightful.
The Definition of rigliifid, or of the adjective right,
is, I conceive, contained in the maxim which I have
already quoted as proceeding from the general voice
of mankind: namely this, that we must do what is
right at whatever cost. That an action is right, is a
reason for doing it, which is paramount to all other
INTRODUCTORY LECTURE, 3
reasons, and overweighs them all when they are on
the contrary side. It is painful : but it is right ;
therefore we must do it. It is a loss : but it is right;
therefore we must do it. It is unkind : but it is
right; therefore we must do it. These are self-evi-
dent propositions. That a thing is right, is a supreme
reason for doing it. Right implies this supreme,
unconquerable reason; and does this especially, and
exclusively. No other word does imply such an
irresistible cogency in its effect, except in so far as
it involves the same notion. What we ought to do,
what we should do, that we must do, though it bring
paiu and loss; but why? Because it is right. The
expressions all run together in their meaning.
And this supreme rule, that we must do what is
right, is also the moral rule of human action. Hav-
ing got this notion of what is right ; what we ought
to do ; what we should do ; we are already in the
region of morality. What is right ; what it is that
we ought to do ; we must have some means of deter-
mining, in order to complete our moral scheme ; but
whatever we so determine, we are involved in a moral
system, as soon as we begin to use such words as right
aad ought.
Thus then we see that the supreme reason of
human actions and the moral nature of them cannot
be separated. The two come into our thoughts toge-
ther, and are in otir conceptions identical. And
this identity is the foundation, in a peculiar and cha-
racteristic manner, of the System of Morality to which
we have been led.
In thus speaking of the reasons of human actions,
it is plain that I am using the term reason, not for
the Faculty by which we judge, but for the grounds
of our judgment ; not for the Power of mental seeing,
but for something which we see. Reasons and the
Reason thus differ nearly as thoughts and Thought.
The Reason sees the reasons for human actions: and
among these, it sees the supreme reason, which is,
that they are right : and because the Reason is the
Faculty which sees this, while Desire and Affection
1—2
4 HISTOET OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
tend blindly to their objects, not seeing reasons, but
feeling impnlses, or at least, seeing reasons only as
subordinate things j — therefore it is that we say that
the Reason has a natural and rightful authority over
Desire and Affection. It is right that Reason should
control and direct Desire and Affection, because Rea-
son alone can see what is right; alone can understand
that there is such a character as rightness.
But though the general statement of the ground
of Morality may thus be found at a very early
period of ethical speculation, several additional steps
are requisite in order to deduce from this principle a
systematic scheme ; and some of these steps, it seems
to me, have not been previously made in a satisfactory
manner. The Reason, we have said, must control and
direct the Desires and Affections; — must so control
and direct them, that they may act rightly. But
how are we to carry this Rule into detail 1 What are
the conditions of acting rightly, in the case of the
Desires and Affections 1 How is the Supreme Rule
of Human Action, Rightness, brought into contact
with these Impulses, these Springs of Human Action,
as we may call them ?
In order to answer this question, we classify the
Springs of Human Action, as they commonly exist
among men, namely, the Desires and Affections ; and
we look for conditions of Rightness, corresponding to
this classification of the Desires and Affections. We
shall JGLnd such.
The task of classifying the Springs of Human
Action, the Desires, Affections, and the like, has been
attempted by various moralists in modem times, es-
pecially by Reid and Dugald Stewart. Their classi-
fications supply useful suggestions, but appear to me
to be both defective and redundant. I have had
therefore in a great degree to make my own classifica-
tion. It may be said, I think, that the leading
Desires of man, . in their largest form, in which they
are expressed by means of general terms, and in which
they include the Affections, are. The Desire of Per-
sonal Safety, the Desire of Having, the Desire of
INTRODUCTORY LECTURE. 5
Family Society, (whicli includes tlie Family Affec-
tions,) and the Desi/re of Civil Society, (-wHch. includes
tlie more general Social Affections) . There are other
Desires which are not of this primary character, as
the Desire of Knowledge, and the like. These primary
Desires in their various operation regulate the whole
scheme of human life. Men's personal safety, their
possessions, their families, and the concerns of the
community in which they live, are, in their eyes,
the greatest objects which exist. No actions can be
conformable to Rule, if the actions which refer to
these objects are not conformable to Rule. If these
objects are not ordered, secured, respected, reverenced,
there can be no order, no security, no respect, no
reverence anywhere. However other Desires and
Affections be controlled and directed, if these be not,
there can be no real control and direction. If these
great primary forces are not in equilibrium, or at least
in moderated movement, there can be no valid effect
produced by adjusting the smaller and slighter im-
pulses which operate upon man.
But the Desires which regard these great primary
objects, Personal Safety, Possessions, Family, Civil
Society, — how are they to be regulated so that they
may conform to the condition which we have assigned;
to the Supreme Rule of Human Action; in short,
that they may be right ? That is the question which
we have now to answer.
We do not at present want a complete answer, but
a starting point from which we may proceed towards
a complete answer. How the Desires and Affections
are to be regulated, so that they may be right in the
highest sense, is an inquiry which requires a long
train of careful thought: but is there no condition
which is obviously reqtiisite, as a general rule, in
order that those Desires and Affections may be right ?
There plainly is such a condition generally esta-
blished among men. In order that the Desires and
Affections with regard to the Personal Safety, Posses-
sions, Family, CivU Condition of other men may be
right, they must conform to this primary and univer-
6 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
sal Condition, that they do not violate the Rights of
others. This condition may not be sufficient, but it is
necessary. Thou shalt do no violence ; thou shalt not
steal ; thou shalt not commit adultery ; thou shalt not
oppress ; — these are rules which all men acknowledge
as the very foundations of Morality. However far
we may go, we must begin here.
And here we find, as we said we should find, con-
ditions of rightness corresponding to the primary
springs of human action : for we find a classification
of Rights corresponding to the classification of primary
Desires, to which we were led. As the primary De-
sires of men are the Desire of Personal Safety, of
Possessions, of Family, and of Civil Society ; so the
primary kinds of Rights among men are everywhere
the Eights of the Person, the Rights of Property, the
Rights of the Family, and Political Rights, which
depend upon the constitution of the community to
which they belong, and the place of each man in it.
But these large classes of Rights thus correspond-
ing to the leading Desires and Affections of men, do
not quite exhaust the kinds of Rights commonly
recognized among men. We cannot make a good and
complete arrangement of Rights, withotit putting, as
one large class. Rights of Contract; — Rights arising
from agreement among men : for though these may
often be about Property, and may thus seem to enter
into the class of Rights of Property, they may also be
about other things as well, and do really depend upon
a different principle.
As the other classes of Rights correspond, each to
each, to leading Desires of men, we may ask to what
Desire do the Rights of Contract correspond; and to
this the answer must be, that such Rights do not
depend exactly upon a Desire, but upon what may be
called more fitly a Need; one of the most universal
and dominant Needs of man in his social condition ;
the Need of a mutual understanding among men, so
that one man may regulate his intentions and actions
by those of another : a Need of which the satis-
faction is possible through the existence of Language.
INTR0DTTCT0R7 LECTURE. 7
So tten we have five acting principles, — Springs
of Action, and Sources of Rights among men ; — ^the
Desire and Love of Personal Safety ; of Property ; of
Family ; and of Civil Society ) and along -with these.
Language, or the Desire of a mutual understanding
which Language enables them to gratify. And we
have in like manner, five classes of Eights ; — those of
Person, Property, Family, State, and Contract.
This symmetrical division of the Springs of Human
Action and Rights existing in Human Society is the
starting point- of our system of Morality ; being, as
we have said, the point where the Springs of Human
Action come in contact with the supreme Rule of
Rightness on which Morality depends. For though
the adjective right in a moral sense, and the substan-
tive Right in a legal sense, are words of very different
extent, the one is necessarily comprehended within the
sphere of the other; Nothing can be a man's Right
but that which it is right he should have, though he
may not have a Right to eveiything which it would
te right for others to give him. And thus when we
have once arrived at the existence of Rights, we have
reached a point from which we may go on to Right-
ness of a higher kind, and may thus construct the
whole edifice of a system of Morality.
In what manner, it may be asked, do we rise
from mere legal Rights to moral Rightness ? I reply,
that we do so in virtue of this principle : — that the
Supreme Rule of man's actions must be a rule which
has authority over the whole of man ; over his inten-
tions as well as his actions ; over his Affections, his
Desires, his Habits, his Thoughts, his Wishes. The
man's being cannot be right, except all these be right.
If he abstain from outward violations of the Rights of
others, he may satisfy Law, but he does not satisfy
Morality. It is not enough that he do not steal ; it
is also necessary that he do not covet ; and not only
so, but that he do not nourish a love of wealth which
leads to covetousness ; — ^that his affections be fixed, his
thoughts employed on other things, not on mere
worldly goods. And thus we rise from legale Obliga;-
8 HISTORY OF MOEAL PHILOSOPHT.
tion to moral Duty; from Legality to Virtue ; from
blamelessness ia the forum of man, to innocence in
the court of conscience. Every Eight points to an
ascending series of Virtues ; and again, all the differ-
ent Virtues run and melt into each other and con-
verge to one supreme and central Idea of Goodness,
the union and the origin of them all.
To this scheme of Morality various objections may
be made, some of which I will here state, and reply to
as briefly and as distinctly as I can.
(I.) It may be said that in the system which has
thus been described. Morality is founded upon Law,
that is, upon the Laws which actually exist among
men; and that such a Morality must necessarily be
narrow, low, and formal ; being bounded by the nature
and extent of its foundation.
To this we reply, that our Morality, though it
derives a portion of its form from our classification of
Eights, and so far, of Laws, is not at aU bounded by
the nature and extent of Law, but on the contrary is
necessarily immeasurably more comprehensive, deep
and high than Law is, in virtue of the principle just
stated as the leading principle of our Morality; —
that Morality claims empire over the whole man, in-
cluding internal purpose, affection, and thought;
whereas Law is concerned only with outward actions.
We may add to this reply, that Law, or Rights,
are in our system, not the foundation, but only the
starting point, of Morality. Though we begin from
them, we do not build upon them. Indeed with us,
Eights, and the Laws which establish them, instead of
being the foundation of Morality, are only the foun-
dation of the mode in which Morality regards exter-
nal things, such as property, fe.mily ties, and the Uke :
and the way in which Morality regards such things
must, in all systems, be greatly regulated by existing
laws ; — ^nor is this the case in ours more than in other
systems.
(II.) But again it may be objected that our
Morality, being derived from existing Law, must ne-
cessarily be controlled by existing Law; so that
INTEODTJCTORT LECTURE. 9
however absurd, unjust, or oppressive be tlie Laws, the
precepts of our Morality must be conformed to them.
To this we reply, our Morality is not derived from
the special commands of existing Laws, but from the
fact that Laws exist, and from our classification of
their subjects. Personal Safety, Property, Contracts,
Family and Civil Relations, are everywhere the sub-
jects of Law, and are everywhere protected by Law ;
therefore we judge that these things must be the sub-
jects of Morality, and must be reverently regarded by
Morality. But we are not thus bound to approve of
all the special appointments with regard to these sub-
jects, which may exist at a given time in the Laws of
a given country. On the contrary, we may condemn
the Laws as being contrary to Morality. We cannot
frame a Morality without recognizing Property, and
Property exists through Law; but yet the Law of
Property, in a particular country, may be at variance
with that moral purpose for which, in our eyes, Laws
exist. Law is the foundation and necessary condition
of Justice ; but yet Laws may be unjust, and when
unjust, ought to be changed. The cases in which
Morality and Law come into conflict, are difficult
problems in all systems of Morality. We have no
greater difficulty in propounding and in solving such
problems than any other Moralists.
(III.) It may be objected that by deriving Moral-
ity from existing Laws we make it depend upon some-
thing accidental, partial, variable in different countries
and times ; whereas we require that Morality should
be something necessary, universal, uniform in all
places and times.
And to this we reply, as before, that we do not
derive Morality from Law in such a way as to make
it share the accidental, partial, variable character of
Law. We derive it from the fact that Law every-
where establishes, or endeavours to establish. Personal
Security, Property, Contracts, Families and States;
which objects of Law are, we conceive, universal, con-
stant, and the necessary conditions of man's moral
existence. So that Morality, however it may begin by
lO HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
borrcwing a suggestion from Law, may still be said
to be in its nature necessary, universal and eternal. ^
(IV.) Again, it may be said that the necessity
of which we here speak, when we say that the funda-
mental kinds of Eights exist necessarily, is the neces-
sity arising from mutual fear. Property, for example,
is established by Law, as a kind of term of truce
to the endless quarrels concerning the objects of
human desire which would otherwise take place among
men.
But that mutual fear alone could not establish
property and the other kinds of Rights, is evident
from this : that such Rights do not exist among brute
animals, in spite of their mutual fears and conflictiQg
desires. Rights do not arise from mutual fear, but
from the whole nature of man ; and especially from
his nature as being capable of living under rules
of action, and incapable of living otherwise. He
cannot live except under rules of external action,
directing and controlling him ; hence men have Rights.
He cannot live except with the recognition of rules of
internal action, giving a character to his intentions
and purposes, as wrong or right; and thus he must
have Morality.
(V.) The same answer might be made if it were
urged that by making our Morality begin from Rights,
we really do found it upon Expediency, notwithstand-
ing our condemnation of systems so founded. For,
it may be said. Rights, such as property, exist only
because they are expedient. We reply, as before, that
Rights are founded- on the whole nature of man, in
such a way that he cannot have a human existence
without them. He is a moral being, and must have
Rights, because Morality cannot exist where Rights
are not. Rights are expedient for man, just as it is
expedient for man that his blood should circulate. If
it do not, he soon ceases to be man.
Thus it will be seen that according to our view.
Morality is founded upon the whole nature of man, as
containing Desires and Affections, and as subject to a
Rule which must govern his whole being. The Rea-
INTRODUCTORY LECTURE. II
son is employed both, in giving to the objects of the
Desires and Affections a more general and ideal cha-
racter, and in discerning the manner in which they
may be controlled and directed so as to conform to
Eule, and to the Supreme Eule which all other Eules
necessarily imply. We thus assent to those who say
that it is the office of Reason to govern the Desires
and Affections ; and we add that Reason, by its nature,
must tend to govern them so that they may be right.
We assent to those who say that Virtue consists in
acting conformably to man's Nature; meaning that
his nature is a moral nature, and necessarily implies
a Rule of Tightness. We assent to Butler when he
speaks of man as having a determinate mental consti-
tution; meaning thereby a constitution in which the
Desires and Affections must be controlled by Rules,
and therefore governed by Reason. We assent to
those who speak of man as having a Moral Faculty,
meaning that he has the Faculty of seeing the necessity
of such Rules and of referring actions to them. We
do not speak of man as having a Moral Sense ; because
the discovery of the conformity of actions to a Moral
Rule is a process entirely different from the operation
of any sense. We speak with reverence of Conscience,
meaning by Conscience the judgment which we form
of our actions as being right or wrong : and we are
willing to assert the authority of Conscience, meaning
thereby that our judgment of our actions as right or
wrong, is a ground of action superior to any other
view of them ; but we do not speak of the authority
of Conscience as swprerm, meaning that what we judge
to be right is necessarily right, and what we judge to
be wrong necessarily wrong. For our judgment on
these points may be erroneous. We may have wrongly
conceived or wrongly applied the Supreme Rule of
human action; and thus our erroneous Conscience
may require to be enlightened and instructed by a
better use of our rational Faculty.
We do not rest our Rules of action upon the ten-
dency of actions to produce the Happiness of others,
or of mankind in general ; because we cannot solve a
12 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
problem so difficult as to determine which, of two
courses of action -will produce the greatest amount of
human happiness : and "we see a simpler and far more
satisfactory mode of deducing such Rules; namely, by.
considering that there must be such Rules ; that they
must be Rules for man; for man living amwng men;
and for the whole of man's being. Siace we are thus
led directly to moral Rules, by the consideration of
the internal conditions of man's being, we cannot think
it wise to turn away from this method, and to try to
determine such Rules by reference to an obscure and
unmanageable external condition, the Amount of Hap-
piness produced. But we do not doubt of the truth
of the doctrine. That right action does produce the
greatest amount of human happiness ; and we conceive
that happiness must be so apprehended and so under-
stood as to be consistent with this general truth.
"We do not deduce our Rules of action directly
from the tendency of actions to produce our own hap-
piness, in the way of reward; because we do not suf-
ficiently know, on independent grounds, the Laws
according to which our Judge will administer his
rewards. We believe that He will reward what is
right and punish what is wrong : but we believe that
He intends us to use our rational and moral Acuities
in discovering what is right and what is wrong. He
has given us other helps in the task, but He has not
superseded these. We cannot be content to make our
Morality depend, as Paley does, on these two steps; —
that God wishes the happiness of mankind, and that
therefore he will reward what we do for the promotion
of that happiness; for we conceive that to determine
in what sense Tmjumam. happiness is to be understood,
when we say that God wishes it and wishes us to
promote ii^ is far more difficult, than it is to determine
God's will by seeking for it in the Supreme Rule of
human action : besides which, even if we could deter-
miae what this happiness is, we might still be unable
to discern the best means of promoting it. But we do
not doubt that the Supreme Rule of human action,
the rule which requires action to be right, is identical
INTRODUCTORT LECTURE. I 3
with the "Will of God; and that His Will is the high-
est and strongest sanction by -which any Eide can be
enforced.
Though, as yre have already said, our Morality
does not depend upon actually existing human Laws,
nor even upon the necessary existence of Law; yet
will Morality, and the Laws which necessarily exist
in human society, rest upon the same foundation, the
moral nature of man. And iu tracing this funda-
mental basis of Law and of Morality into a system of
each, there may be, and naturally will be, a corre-
spondence between certain general provinces and divi-
sions of the one and of the other, of Law and of
Morality. And thus as we have five leading kinds of
Rights, we have also five leading kinds of Duty and
of Virtue. These five are Benevolence, Justice, Truth,
Pwrity, and Wisdom; which last, reckoned by Aris-
totle and others as an intellectual virtue, (in distinction
to the others, which are termed moral virtues,) may
be called Order; siuce it manifests itself both in the
discovery of right Rules and of means for upholding
them. Without pressing too much upon the parallel-
ism between these five kinds of Yirtue and the five
kinds of Rights respectively, we may venture to say
that these five Virtues may be regarded as a convenient
division of Virtue, so far as virtue is divisible : and
these may deserve to be termed the Cardinal Vvrtmes,
far better than that ancient quaternion, which moralists
have so often assumed, of Justice, Temperance, Forti-
tude and Prudence. And as this is a division of
Virtues, which are habits of action, so is it a division
of Duties, which are occasions of such actions; and
we have Duties of Benevolence, of Justice, of Truth,
of Purity and of Order.
Duty is a term which especially belongs to Mora-
lity, not to Law. The term Obligation is used in both
subjects : we speak of the legal Obligation of paying
our debts, and the moral Obligation of relieving the
distressed: It would produce some convenience if the
term were confined to the former meaning; but at any
rate the two senses ought not to be confounded. We
14 HISTOET OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
ought not to speak, as Paley does, of obliged and ougJU
as synonymous terms ; seeing that men are often obliged
to do what they ought not to do.
Nor again, ought the habit of such phraseology to
lead us to suppose that because legal obligations are
always obligations to some person, therefore moral ob-
ligations are also always due to some person. Duties
to others, as they are sometimes termed, are much
better spoken of as Duties simply : for they are to be
performed not only out of regard to others, as what
thei/ ought to have, but far more, from regard to our-
selves and what we ought to be.
To every (Legal) Obligation which we contract
or have, corresponds a Eight which another person
requires or has : but to our Duties correspond no
Rights of others. If however we wish for a correlative
term to Duties, we may use the phrase Moral Claim ;
we may say that a poor man in distress has a Moral
Claim on his rich neighbour, even if the law do not
give him a legal Eight.
And many of our Duties which regard our special
relations to particular persons, and which we may
therefore term Relative Duties, may be conveniently
arranged and treated of according to those Eelations.
Having these views of the most convenient way of
using the term Obligation, we should avoid using such
terms as perfect and imperfect Obligation, which have
been common among Moralists. Such phrases have
the inconvenience of implying that no Obligations are
perfect but those which the law imposes, and that all
our Duties are of the nature of Debts, only less perfect
in degree.
It may be asked how we can apply these general
heads of our System to particular actions and to special
moral questions, such as Moralists are expected to
decide : and it may be urged that some reference to
the results of actions and to some external object of
action is requisite for such purposes. But it will be
found that this is not so, and that a consideration of
the ideas of Benevolence, Justice, Truth, Purity and
Order, determined in the way in which we have de-
INTRODUCTORY LECTURE. 1 5
termined them, combined with a regard to the various
relations in which men stand to each other, will enable
us to draw out a complete scheme of human duties.
And we conceive that this is not only a possible mode
of proceeding, but that it is the way in which men do
naturally and spontaneously endeavour to decide for
themselves such moral questions as come before them.
If the doubt be what course of action Justice, or Truth,
requires, and if they reason morally on the question,
they do not generally so much consider what will come
of each course, — what they will gain or lose by it, —
as what it is that Justice, or that Truth means, and
how the meaning is applicable in the particular case.
That in this manner a detailed scheme of human duties,
and a solution of ordinary moral . questions may be
obtained, is, we conceive, shown in the Elements of
Morality which have been published with this view.
Although we begin the arrangement of our Morality
by taking account of the kinds of Eights established
among men by actual Law, this, as we have already
said, does not prevent omx passing judgment upon ex-
isting Laws as moral or immoral, just or unjust. But
though some existing Laws may be unjust, we must
in our System of Morals, and in all systems of morals
which can be recognized by human society, look upon
existing Laws in general with great respect, as highly
important elements in all moral questions. In general,
what is Property, what is a Contract, what is a Mar-
riage, in any Society, must be determined by the Laws
of that Society; and as our Duties, as well as our legal
Obligations, are concerned about Property, Contract,
Marriage, and the like, our Morality must involve a,
regard to existing Laws. The existing Laws of each
state belong to its history; — have grown out of its
history or with its history, and change with its histo-
rical changes. Hence our Morality, besides involving
the ideal elements of which we have spoken, the ideas
of Justice, Truth, and the like, must include an histo-
rical element, belonging to each separate community.
Along with the Idea of Morality we must include the
Fact of Law. And the bearings of Law and Morality, —
1 6 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
the dependence of ■vrhat oughi to he on what is, —
the conversion of what is into what ought to be in
each community, — forms a large and important pro-
vince of speculation which we can by no means leave
out of our consideration. To this province belong all
general questions of Political Morality; questions con-
cerning the Eights and Duties of Governments as well
as of individuals. We may add, as also coming within
the sphere of our reasonings, questions of Justice con-
cerning property, contracts, and the Uke, as determined
by supposing the most general forms of actual Law,
which province we may term General Jiurisprudence.
The radical part of the term Jurisprudence, namely
Jus, (the special study of Jurists,) denotes a branch of
speculation which may be distinguished from Morality
proper by saying that Jus is the doctrine of Bights
and Obligations, Morality the doctrine of Virtues and
Duties; the term Obligations being here used in the
strict sense above spoken of.
Besides these, we conceive it proper to include in
our Morality questions as to what is just and ri<;ht in
the dealings of Nations with one another. This is
commonly termed International Law; but since there
is no supreme authority among nations by which Laws
affecting them can be enforced, these questions can-
only be discussed by assuming a common understand-
ing respecting the Rights and Obligations of nations;
and hence the subject may rather be termed Inter-
national Jus.
The subject of Religion is intimately connected
with Morality ; or indeed Religion may rather be said
to include the subject of Morality, regarding it ac-
cording to her own special view of man's nature, con-
dition, and prospects. But there result important
advantages from treating separately Morality accord-
ing to Reason, and Morality according to Religion:
and this therefore we do.
The explanation which has thus been given of the
relation of our System of Morality to the Systems
published by other writers, will have shown in a great
degree the objections to the schemes of our predecessors
INTRODUCTORY LECTURE. I 7
■which, prevent our resting satisfied with their labours.
With regard to Palsy's Frincvples of Moral Philosophy
in particular, the book which is recognized by the
University of Cambridge as an especial subject of ethi-
cal study, I have repeatedly pointed out what appear
to me to be defects and errors'. But I have thought
that it might be convenient to my readers to find here
some remarks on a writer who has erected his system
of Morality and Jurisprudence on the same basis as
Palej', but with more of systematic method and logical
consistency : I mean Jeremy Bentham. I have there-
fore given some account of his principal works on
these subjects, and have ventured to point out what
appear to me their grave defects in principle, reason-
ing, method, and spirit. With regard to the objec-
tions to the principles, they are, of course, much the
same as the objections to Paley's fundamental doc-
trines, modified according to Mr Bentham's mode of
stating them. As a specimen of Mr Bentham's me-
thod, I have taken his classification of Offenses, as it
appears in his Frindples of Morals and Legislation.
I have attempted to show that this Classification is
very defective, mainly in consequence of his introduc-
iag the Head of Offenses against Condition, and not
taking as one of his Heads, Contract, a province of the
subject so abundant in rules and subdivisions among
the best preceding Jurists. It appears to me to result
from this examination that the division of Rights into
five kinds. Rights of the Person, of Property, of Con-
tract, of Marriage, and Political Rights, with corre-
sponding Offenses or Wrongs, arising from the viola-
tion of these Rights, is both more philosophical and
more practical. I have also ventured to point out in
a particular case (as an example) the impossibility of
making a scheme of Law without recognizing in Law a
moral purpose.
1 See the Preface to Bntler'a Three Sermons; also the Ekmcnts of Moral-
til, Art. 454, &c
LEOTUEE I.
MoEAL Philosophy. Casuistry.
Perkins— Ames— Hall — Sanderson — ^Taylor —
Dr Knightbridgb.
I NOW appear before tte TJnivei-sity for the first time
in the attempt to discharge my public functions as
Professor of Casuistry, or Moral Philosophy ; to which
chair I was elected in June last, 1838. The office of
Professor, in this as in other Universities, is generally
understood to imply the duty of delivering Public
Lectures upon the subject which the Professorship de-
signates ; and in the case of the Professorship which I
have the honour to hold, this duty is expressly enjoin-
ed by the Founder, and directions are given in the
deed of Foundation with a view of securing its effec-
tual performance. As, however, notwithstanding these
reasons for the delivery of Public Lectures by the
holder of this Professorship, circumstances had in fact
led to a discontinuance of them, I did not find myself
by this appointment placed in a situation in which I
had to continue and carrj' on an existing system of
teaching, on the subject thus committed to my care.
I am well aware that it may easily happen to a Pro-
fessor, from the nature of his subject, or from other
circumstances, that he may better hope to promote the
study of his science, and the interests of the academic
body to which he belongs, in other ways, — ^by his ad-
vice, his writings, or his judgments on what is done
by others, — than by the delivery of Lectures to the
general body. With particular subjects, and under
particular circi;inietences, this may very readily be con-
CASUISTBT. 19
ceived to be so : but in almost all cases it would seem to
be desirable, that a person, who has conferred upon Mm
such a distinction as is among us implied in a Profes-
sorship of any branch of science or learning, should come
forwai-ds in some manner which may show to the Uni-
versity that he has made, or is making, a study of that
which he professes ; — that his attention is employed in
examining its principles and tracing its progress; —
that he is at his post, prepared with his proper share
of the learning and knowledge of past times; and
ready, when any new doctrines claim his attention,
to resist error, and to welcome truth. It is by possess-
ing a body of persons who hold their respective places
in our Universities in such a spirit, whether they bear
the name of Professor or Tutor, or any other, that these
bodies will be, as such bodies ought to be, the deposi-
taries and diffusers of sound learning — the asylums of
solid and substantial truth — ^the golden links which
connect The Permanent with The Progressive. When
therefore I was elected into this office, I thought that
it became incumbent upon me to show, in some public
manner, that I was giving my best attention to the
subject with which I was thus charged. And among
other steps to which I felt myself thus directed, it
appeared to me that a course of Public Lectures, such
as the foundation of the Professorship enjoins, might
be both of use and of interest to a portion of the Uni-
versity. Such a course, therefore, although in the pre-
sent year, for reasons which I may hereafter refer to,
it must be a brief and very incomplete one, I now
propose to commence.
The subject which I consider as committed to my
charge by my professorship is Moral Philosophy, ac-
cording to that view of the position and limits of the
science to which the best modern authors have been
led. Even if by taking this subject so defined and
bounded, it should appear that it does not employ itself
upon precisely the same class of questions which the
Founder had in his view when he endowed the office,
I should still not fear that the University would look
upon such a modification of the Professor's task as not
2—2
20 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
only allowable, but, Tinder proper conditions, laudable.
For, in order to teach or to speculate with advantage,
we must recognize those relations of the different sci-
ences — those unions and those separations of the vari-
ous fields of knowledge — ^those cardinal questions and
fundamental alternatives, to which the best researches
of later as well as earlier times have led. And if,
a century and a half ago, the traditionary partition of
the various branches of religion and morals was unphi-
losophical and confused; or if the questions then con-
sidered most important, have now become frivolous
or superfluous; it would be unwise for us to allow
ourselves to be bound down to technicalities and errors,
prevalent in those days,* but now detected or obsolete.
Such conduct would be a perverse obedience to the
letter of our benefactor's instructions, which might
almost look like irony; since by such obedience we
should certainly and knowingly thwart his real inten-
tion. It will be a far more cordial and generous inter-
pretation of his injunctions, and of the purpose of the
University in accepting his bequest, if we direct our
attention to the branch of knowledge which- now
stands in the place of that which he recommended;
which preserves all that was most valuable in the
older body of learning, while it brings before us ques-
tions and principles such as are now, at this day, of
the deepest interest, and of the most grave concern to
the prospects and convictions of men. I may add,
that such a substitution of a newer form of science
full of life, hope, interest, and solid truth, for the older
and more imperfect speculations upon related subjects,
is what you, the University, have accepted with satis-
faction and applause from many, or I may say from
all, of the rest of your professors.
I shall therefore reckon upon the implied sanction
of this University, in considering myself as Professor
of Moral Philosophy; a branch of study of which a
professorship exists, I believe, in every university but
our own : a branch of study, too, as I trust to be able
to show, which cannot be excluded without leaving the
general body of knowledge, such as we should here
CASUISTRY. 2 1
present it to our students, in an intolerable degree
maimed and imperfect.
You are probably aware that the person holding
this professorship is designated in the Foundation
Deed, as Professor of Moral Tlieology or Casuistical
Divinity; and has usually been termed Professor of
Casuistry. Although, for the reasons I have just
stated, I altogether disclaim the notion that my pro-
fessorial province is to be defined or limited by an an-
tiquarian investigation as to what Casuistry was at
first, or at any period ; and although, as I have said,
another phrase appears to me to be at present far
more fitted to express my office, it may iiiterest you,
in parting with this subject its an acknowledged sci-
ence among us, to cast back a glance, very briefly,
upon its nature and course.
I need not remind any one here that the term in-
dicates that portion of Christian Morals which treats
oi Gases of Conscience ; and that Cases of Conscience
are questions of human conduct in which conflicting
duties, or obscurity in the application of moral rules,
seem at first to perplex and disturb the faculty which
judges of right and wrong; and make it necessary to
trace, in an exact and methodical manner, and with a
careful exclusion of everything hut moral considera-
tions, the consequences of the fundamental rules of
morality, in order that thus we may escape the doubt
and confusion with which we are threatened. The
Gases of Conscience of Jeremy Taylor, as one of his
works is often termed, and similar writings of many
others of our best divines, will at once recur to your
recollection.
Nor, again, need I remark, (although the circum-
stance is full of instruction,) that since, in cases where
obvious duties appear to be in conflict, we cannot
decide either way without transgressing, or seeming to
transgress, some plain rule of morality, the common
mind is never fully satisfied with such a conclusion :
and even when the decision is made on the most purely
moral grounds, and when the reasons assigned for it
are, to a person capable of following such reasoning,
22 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
perfectly convincing and demonstrative, still the care-
less hearer attends to nothing but the fact that reasons
are given for omitting a duty.
Hence it has come to pass, that when, in any cases,
reasons are stated tending to evade some generally
acknowledged rule of conduct, although the reasons
have only the most shallow and transparent pretence
of morality, still the popular mind will not take the
trouble of distinguishing between such sophistry and
the indispensable distinctions contemplated' by the ge-
nuine moralist. And thus such evasive perversion of
reason is also called Casuistry; and hence the word, in
more modern times, and in certain classes of writers,
is used in a somewhat* obnoxious sense. Pope will
supply us with examples of both shades of significa-
tion: as, first, in the sense of decisions on the best
authority : —
Who shall decide when doctors disagree,
And soundest casuists doubt, Jike you and me?
and again, in the unfavourable sense : —
Morality by her false guardians drawn.
Chicane in furs, and Casuistry in lawn.
Technical law and technical morality are both often,
as here, the objects of sarcasm and blame. Yet it
must be obvious to every considerate person, that laws,
to be consistent in practice, must be technical; and a
very little attention to the subject will show us that
morality also, in order to become a portion of exact
truth, must assume, as all sciences must, a technical
form. Such a form is one which the popular mind
cannot and will not comprehend, and on which it will-
ingly avenges itself by ridicule and dislike.
We know however that, notwithstanding the pre-
valence of such feelings, it is ov/r business, in this, no
less than other subjects, to aim at truth of the most
rigorous and exact form, as weU as of the most soHd
certainty. Nor wiU it ever be possible to treat of
morality, in any complete and sufficient manner, with-
out taking into our account the question of conflicting
duties, and other questions such as have been termed
CASUISTRY.
23
Cases of Conscience. And though such cases are nei-
ther the main part of our subject (Moral Philosophy),
nor that from which it can with propriety derive its
name, it may, as I have said, "be worth our while to ex-
amine how an appellation so derived has been, in past
times, applied and understood; and it will, I trust,
be found that in this manner some light will be thrown
on the more recent progress of moral philosophy.
The works which contained collections of cases of
conscience, and of which the title commonly was Sv/m-
ma Casuum Cdnscientice, or something resembling this,
were compiled at first for the use of confessors and
ecclesiastical persons, who had to give their advice
and decisions to those who made confession to them.
It was requisite for them to know, for instance, in
what cases penance of a heavier or lighter kind was to
be imposed ; and what offenses must, for the time, ex-
clude the offender from the Communion.
As early as the 13th century Rajrmond of Penna-
forti had published his Casuistical Summa, which came
into very general use, and was referred to by the
greater part of the succeeding casuists.
In the 14th and 15th century the number of such
books increased very greatly. These Sum/mce were in
common speech known by certain abbreviated names,
borrowed from the designation of the author, or other
circumstances. Thus there was the Astesana, which
derived its name from its author Astesanus, a Mino-
rite of Asti in Piedmont; the Angelica, compiled by
Angelus de Clavasio, a Genoese Minorite ; the Pisama
or Pisanella, which was also termed Bartholina or
Magistrucda; the Padjica; the Rosella; the Sylves-
trina. In these works the subjects were usually ar-
ranged alphabetically, and the decisions were given in
the^form of Eesponses to Questions proposed'; the
1 I will give, as an example of tlie
Sv/nvmts, one of the questions imder
the word Mrietas in the
Angelica,
P. 61. "Mridas est privatio in-
tellectus facta ad aliquod tempus ex
immoderato potu vini vel cnjusoun-
que rei potabilis.
24
HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
opinions being often quoted from, or supported hj, the
authority of the Scripture, or the Fathers, or Schoolmen.
Thus, Astesanus says in his preface, that, conscious of
his own poverty, he had," like Kuth, gone to glean in
the grounds of the wealthy, the books of great doctors ;
and that he had put in his book " ilia tantum quae
pertinebant ad consilium in foro conscientise tribuen-
dum." There was not in these books any attempt to
lay down general principles which might show that the
decisions were right, or which might enable the in-
"Q. Utrum ebrietas sit peccatum
mortale. Bespondetur ut colligo ex
Alexan. Secninda Secimdce, et Glo.
xxF. Dist. sect, alias ea demum. Et
docetur ibidem quod aut raro con-
tigit aut assiduS. Si raro: sic dis-
tingue, quod aut inebrians se cog-
noscit vini poteutiam, et suam com-
plexionem dispositamadebrietatem,
et tunc magis vult ebrietatem incur-
rere quam a viao abstinere, ei sic
est peccatum morbale; aut inebrians
se nescit viui potentiajn et ignorat
quod ex tali potu potest inebriari
vel non advertit; et sic est nullum
peccatum vel veniale secundum ex-
cessmn in potu, et negligentiam la
advertendo. Siveroassiduasitebrie-
tas: sic est mortale peccatum, non
propter Iterationem. actus, quss mul-
tiplicatio actuum venialium non au-
getininfinifcum; sed quod non potest
esse quod homo assidud inebrietur
quin sciens et volens ebrietatem in-
currat: aut saltern omittat diligen-
tiam quam debet adhibere de neces-
sitate ne inebrietur cum habeat tem-
pus deliberationis reprimendi motus
veuiales ne procedant in regnum
peccati."
I will also give the part of the
article which refers to Addict, aicqSCa,
Indifference, and Dejection with re-
gard to doing good, which the school-
men had made a special sin. By
Aquinas it is ranked among the vices
opposite to the Christian virtue of
Hope.
P. 3. "Addia, secundum Bicar-
dum de Sancto Victore, est torpor
mentis bona inchoari negligentis, et
secundum Damascenum est tristitia
aggravans mentem ut nihil bona ei
agere libeat. Q. Utrum acidia sit
contra aliquod praeceptum Becalogi.
Eespondet Alexander, Trac. de Aci-
dia, quod est specialiter et explicite
contra illud. EccL xxxviiL 20. [Taike
no heaviness to heart: drive it away,
and remember the last end. Forget
it not, for there is no turning again :
thou shalt not do hini good, but hurt
thyselt] Implicite vero est contra
illud Exod. XX. [Remember that
thou keep holy the sabbath-day.]
In acidia est tristitia de spirituali
bono cum amore quietis camalis.
In illo vero precepto est amor sanctse
quietis quae cum gaudio est in bono
spirituali, licet sit laboriosum."
P. 68. "Ervhescentia de 6ojm) Test
peccatum, et est filia acidiae."
CASUISTRY. 25
quirer to determine for himself tlie matter by which
his conscience was disturbed. The lay disciple was
supposed to be in entire dependence upon his spi-
ritual teachers for the guidance of his conscience;
or rather, for the determination of the penance and
mortification by which his sins were to be oblite-
rated. Moreover, a very large proportion of the
offenses which were pointed out in such works were
transgressions of the observances required by the
Church of those days, and referred to matters of which
the conscience could not take cognizance, without a
very considerable amount of artificial training. Ques-
tions of rites and ceremonies were put upon an equal
footing with the gravest questions of morals. The
Church had given her decision respecting both; and
the neglect or violation of her precepts, and of the
interpretations of her doctors, could never, it was held,
be other than sinful. Thus the body of Casuistry, of
which I have been speaking, was intimately connected
with the authority and practices of the Church of
Rome. When, therefore, the domination of that Church
was, by the blessing of Providence, overthrown in this
and other countries, the office of such Casuistry was
at an end. The decision of moral questions was left
to each man's own conscience ; and his responsibility
as to his own moral and spiritual condition could no
longer be transferred to others. For himself he must
stand or fall. He might, indeed, aid himself by the
best lights which the Church could supply — by the
counsel of wiser and holier servants of God; and he was
earnestly enjoined to seek counsel of God himself by
hearty and humble prayer. But he could no longer
lean the whole weight of his doubts and his sins upon
his father confessor and his mother church. He must
ascertain for himself what is the true and perfect law
of God. He could no longer derive hope or satisfac-
tion from the collections of cases, in which the answers
rested on the mere authority of men fallible and sinful
like himself.
Thus the casuistical works of the Eomanists lost
aU weight, and almost all value, in the eyes of the
26 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
Reformed Churches. Indeed, they were looked upon,
and in many respects justly, as among the glaring evi-
dences of the perversions and human inventions by
•which the truth of God had been disfigured; so that
a great Eeformation became necessary ; and from this
period, beyond doubt, we may trace the origin of the
disrepute under which, up to the present time, the
name of Casuistry has laboured.
The writers of the Reformed Churches did not at
first attempt to substitute anything in the place of the
casuistical works of the Romish Church. Besides an
averseness to the subject itself, which, as I have said,
they naturally felt, they were, for a considerable
period after the Reformation, fully employed upon
more urgent objects. If this had not been so, they
could not have failed soon to perceive that, in reality,
most persons do require some guidance for their con-
sciences ; and that rules and precepts by which men
may strengthen themselves against the temptations
which cloud the judgment when it is brought into
contact with special cases, are of great value to every
body of moral and Christian men. But the circum-
stances of the times compelled them to give their
energies mainly to controversies with their Romish
and other adversaries, and to leave to each man's own
thoughts the regulation of his conduct and feelings.
They had to man the walls and carry on a war against
an external enemy for their very existence ; and hence
they could the less bestow their labour in building the
halls of justice, the houses of charity, and the temples of
God, within their city. Or, to use an image of one of
the first of our writers' who attempted to remedy this
defect : " For any public provision of books of casuist-
ical theology, we were almost wholly unprovided; and,
like the children of Israel in the days of Saul and
Jonathan, we were forced to: go down to the forges of
the Philistines to sharpen every man his share and his
coulter, his axe and his mattock. We had swords and
spears of our own, enough for defence, and more than
> Jeremy Taylor.
CASUISTRY. 27
enough for disputation : but in this more necessary-
part of the conduct of consciences, we did receive our
answers from abroad, till we found that our old needs
were very ill supplied, and new necessities did every-
day arise."
In the use of this image, Taylor followed, perhaps
imitated, a still earlier English writer on the same
subject — ^William Ames. He, in the preface to his
" Conscience, with the power and Cases thereof,"
(English Ed. 1643), says, "This part of prophecy
hath hitherto been less practised in the schools of the
prophets, because our captains were necessarily en-
forced to fight always in front againt the enemies to
defend the faith, and to purge the floor of the Church ;
so that they could not plant and water the fields and
vineyards as they desired, as it useth to fall out in
time of hot wars. They thought -with themselves in
the meanwhile (as one of some note writeth), if we
have that single and clear eye of the gospel, if in the
house of our heart the candle of pure faith be set
upon a candlestick, these small matters might easily
be discussed. But experience hath taught at length,
that through neglect of this husbandry, a famine of
true godliness hath followed in many places, and out
of the famine a grievous spiritual plague j insomuch
that the counsel of Ifehemiah had need be practised,
namely, that every one should labour in this work
with one hand holding the plough, and in the other a
spear or a dart, whereby he may repel the violence of
the enemies."
Among the earliest and most considerable of
the moral writers of the English Church, imme-
diately after the Reformation, I may notice William
Perkins, a learned divine who lived in this place in
the reign of Queen Elizabeth. He was educated at
Christ's College, of which' he became Fellow in 1582 ;
and being much admired as a preacher, was chosen
minister of St Andrew's Church ; in which church he
was also buried in 1602' He was esteemed the first
* I haTe not, however, been able to discover his tomb in this church.
28 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHT.
.preacher of his time, and one of the most laborious
theological students ; as indeed his works show him to
have been. The work which it particularly concerns
us to notice at present is entitled, The whole Treatise
of Cases of Conscience, distinguished into^ three books,
taught and delivered hy Mr W. Perkins, in his Holy-
day Lectv/res. In this work we akeady see the differ-
ent spirit of the Casuistry of the Reformed and the
Eomish Church. The editor of Perkins's work (for
it was a posthumous one) says, " We have just cause
to challenge the Popish Church, who in their case-
writings have erred, both in the substance and circum-
stances of their doctrine : —
" First, because the duty of relieving the conscience
is by them commended to the sacrificing priest....
" Secondly, they teach that their priests, appointed
to be comforters and relievers of the distressed, are
made by Christ hhaseli judges of the conscience, having
in their hands a jvdicia/ry power and authority truly
and properly to bind or loose, to remit or to retain sin,
to open or to shut the kingdom of heaven —
" Thirdly, that a man may huild himsdf on the
faith of his teachers, and for his salvation rest con-
tented with an implicit and unexpressed faith." . ..To
which other objections are added.
Instead of this transferred responsibility, this sub-
mission of the conscience to an earthly tribunal, this
reliance on a human foundation, the Reformation taught
individual responsibility to a heavenly Master, and re-
moved aU other foundation than his word and will.
The conscience was subject to no subordinate autho-
rity : it might be instructed by man, or enlightened by
God ; but it had a supremacy of its own for each man.
It was, as Perkins declared (p. 1 1), "in regard of autho-
rity and power, placed in the middle between man and
God, so as it is under God, and yet above man."
In consequence of this change in the authority and
force previously ascribed to the decisions of moral
writers concerning Cases of Conscience, which was
thus brought about by means of the Reformation, the
mode of treating the subject was also changed. Since
PERKINS. AMES. 29
the assertions of the teacher had no inherent autho-
rity, he was obliged to give his proofs as well as his
results. Since the conclusions in each case de-
rived ■ their weight from the principle which they
involved, it became necessary to state the principle
and to show its application. Since the examples were
thus of value, not in themselves, but as they illus-
trated the moral or religious truths which dictated the
decisions, it was no longer useful to accumulate so
vast a mass of instances, or to attempt to exhaust all
possible cases. The teacher's business now became,
not to prescribe the outward conduct, but to direct the
inward thought ; not to decide cases, but to instruct
the conscience. In the title of his work {Gases ofCon-
sdence), the attention had hitherto been bestowed
mainly on the former word; it was now transferred to
the latter. The determination of Cases was replaced
by the discipline of the Gonscience. Casuistry was no
longer needed, except so far as it became identical
with Morality.
Accordingly, we find that the collections of cases
of conscience by writers of our Church are, in fact,
treatises of Moral Philosophy. This is the case even
with the earliest of them, that of Perkins, which I
have mentioned ; as is noticed by foreign writers upon
this subject, among whom his reputation has generally
been greater than it has been in his own country.
Thus Staiidlin' says of him, " He wrote a treatise on
Casuistick, yet did not prescribe any definite limits to
his subject; but solved questions which cannot be
called questions of Conscience, and produced well nigh
a Christian Ethick."
We may perhaps discern one reason why Perkins
produced no great direct effect upon the studies of
English divines, if we turn our attention to his pupil,
also an eminent writer on this subject, whom we
have already mentioned, William Ames. Ames was,
like his master, of Christ College in this university.
"I gladly call to mind the time," thus he begins
1 Gmh. der Christ. Moral, p. 423.
30 HISTOKT OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
his address to his reader, " when being young, I heard
worthy Master Perkins so preach in a great assem-
bly of students that he instructed them soundly
in the truth, stirred them up effectually to seek after
godliness, made them fit for the kingdom of God, and
by his own example showed them what things they
should chiefly intend, that they might promote true re-
ligion in the power of it, unto Grod's glory and others'
salvation." Ames goes on to say of Perkins, that " he
left many behind him affected by that study (the study
of Cases of Conscience) who by their godly sermons
(through God's assistance) made it to run, increase, and
be glorified throughout England." But probably many
of these, like Ames himself, belonged to the party of the
Puritans, and had their influence in England crippled
by their unhappy dissensions with the Established
Church. In the pulpit of St Mary's, Ames expressed
a vehement disapprobation of the festivities by which
the season of Christmas was then celebrated at some
of the colleges in this University ; — relicte, as he de-
clared them to be, of paganism. And cards, which
at that festival are tolerated by some of our ancient
statutes, he pronounced to be an invention of the
devil. With so severe and hostile, a view of practices
which seemed to the majority of his countrymen at
that time innocent recreations, he might naturally be
not unwilling to migrate to a country where the reign-
ing opinions were more in accordance with his own.
He accepted an invitation sent by the States of East
Friesland to become Professor of Divinity in their
imiversity of Franeker ; and from that place he be-
came known to the Uterary world, tmder the name of
Amesius, by his treatise I>e Gonscientia, ejus Jure et
Casilms, published in 1630.
Although Ames's book is an important one in the
history of the science, I shall not dwell upon it; but
proceed to subjects more closely connected with En-
glish literature.
Another eminent English writer, who shortly after
this time wrote upon Cases of Conscience, was Joseph
Hall, Bishop of Norwich in the time of Charles the
HALL. SANDERSON. 3 1
First. He was educated at Emmamiel College, of
■which he also became a fellow. His book, entitled,
Besolutions and Decisions of divers Practical Gases of
Conscience in continual use am,ong men, was published
in 1649, while he resided at Heigham, near Norwich ;
his bishopric having been sequestrated by the Parlia-
mentary Commissioners. This work is, mainly, the
resolution of forty separate Questions, many of them
relating to the common conduct of life, and affecting
individual consciences; as, "Whether the seller is
bound to make known to the buyer the faults of that
which he is about to sell," — "Whether, and how far,
a man may take up arms in the public quarrel of a
war." But others of these questions are really dis-
cussions, not so much concerning the application of
moral rules, as concerning the validity both of moral
rules and of civil laws: — ^as, "Whether tithes be a
lawful maintenance for ministers under the Gospel," —
"Whether marriages once made may be annulled."
Thus, though this book on Cases of Conscience is not,
like others which our Church has produced, a treatise
of Morals in general, it still is, for the most part, a
series of moral disquisitions, in which questions are
decided, not by authority or arbitrary selection, but
by reason and Scrij)ture; and in which the individual
is supposed to make himself acquainted with the
foundations as well as the result of the reasoning.
Bishop Sanderson's Cases of Conscience are in a
great measure of the same nature as Bishop Hall's;
except that they bear still more strongly upon their
face the impress of the times in which the work was
written; reminding us of the peculiar conjunctures
and relations to which the civil and religious dissen-
sions of the time gave rise. Among the cases which
he discusses are, — the case of marrying with a recu-
sant ; the case of a military life ; of a bond taken in
the king's name; of the engagement by which fidelity
to the Commonwealth was promised; of the Sabbath;
and of the Liturgy. These were questions in which
the minds of a large proportion of Englishmen were
intensely and practically interested. Even these, how-
32
HISTOKT OF MOKAL PHILOSOPHY.
ever, are in some respects general questions of morality,
rather than special cases of conscience. But besides
these, Sanderson wrote upon morals in a more general
form. His treatises De Ohligatione Consdentice, and
De Juramenti Ohligatione, were of great repute in
their time, and exhibit well the foundations of the
morality of conscience. In the former Treatise, at
the outset, he examines the opinions of those who
hold that Conscience is an Act, a Power, and a Habit ;
and decides that it cannot be considered any of these,
with so much propriety as a Faculty, partly innate
and partly acquired.
Sanderson was intimately acquainted with the ca-
suists and other moral writers who had preceded him;
and we find in his wiitings something of the subtlety
and technicality of the scholastic writers; but this is
very far from preventing their exhibiting great moral
acuteness and much sound reasoning '.
The tendency of the Casuistry of the Reformed
Churches to become systematic Morality, was apparent
in other countries, as well as in our own; and the
questione thus brought into discussion being treated
with a predominant reference to scriptural authority
and religious doctrines, the subject was naturally
termed Moral Theology. Treatises with this title
became very common in Germany towards the end of
the seventeenth century; but, for reasons already
mentioned, I shall not now dwell upon this portion
of ethical literature. Confining ourselves to the works
of English moralists, the most conspicuous is one with
which many persons here are, doubtless, familiar — the
Rule of Conscience, of Jeremy Taylor, published in
1660: and this celebrated book, like the preceding
labours of English divines on similar subjects, is a
treatise on the leading doctrines of morality ; the au-
thority and attributes of conscience being made the
basis of the system. As, by the effect of the Refor-
1 I have recently published
an edition of Sanderson's work
De Obli^atitme ConscienUie, with
Notes in which I have endeavour-
ed to point out his characteristic
merits.
JEEEMY TAYLOR. 33
mation, Casuistry became Moral Theology, so in agree-
ment with the unbroken tradition of Christian specu-
lation, Moral Theology was established on Conscience
as one of its foundation stones.
The study of the authority of Conscience formed
an important part of Moral Theology. Abelard in
the twelfth century had already laid down the leading
principles of this subject, by teaching that the funda-
mental principle of morality is the will of God revealed
to us by means of our Conscience, as well as by means
of the Holy Scriptures. Jeremy Taylor's view is
nearly the same with this. Many of you may recol-
lect the manner in which the noble work of which I
have spoken, the Rule of Conscience, or Ductor Dubi-
tantium, opens : — " God governs the world by several
attributes and emanations from himself. The nature
of things is supported by his power, the events of
things are ordered by his providence, and the actions
of reasonable creatures are governed by laws; and
these laws are put into a man's soul or mind as into a
treasure or repository : some in his very nature, some
in after actions, by education and positive sanction,
by learning and custom," And having thus stated
his general view, Taylor proceeds to illustrate it with
his usual copiousness of learning and fancy'- "So that
it was well said of St Bernard, Gonscientia candor est
lucis ceternce, et speculum sine macula Dei Majestafis,
et imago bonitatis illius : ' Conscience is the brightness
and splendour of the eternal light, a spotless mirror of
the Divine Majesty, and the image of the goodness of
God.' It is higher which Tatianus said of conscience,
Mwov elvai (rvveiBrjcnv ®e6v — ' Conscience is God unto
us : ' which saying he had from Menander :
'BpoTols airan ffwdStiais Geis.
And it had in it this truth, that God, who is every-
1 In the Notes to the De Obi.
Come Prselect. 11. Sect, i, I have re-
marked that Taylor has, in this
passage, borrowed from Sanderson.
The expression that Conscience is
under God and above man, has been
already (page 28) quoted from Per-
kins.
8
34 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
where in several manners, hath the appellative of his
own attributes and effects in the several manners of
his presence.
'Jupiter est quodounque vides, quoeunque moveris.'"
"That Providence," he adds, "which governs all
the world, is nothing else but God present by his
providence: and God is in our hearts by his laws; he
rules us by his substitute, our conscience." He then
proceeds to illustrate this in his own way : " God sits
there, and gives us laws; and, as God said to Moses,
I have made thee a God to Pharaoh, that is, to give
him. laws, and to minister in the execution of these
laws, and to inflict angry sentences upon him; so hath
Gtod done to us, to give us laws, and to exact obedience
to those laws; to punish them that prevaricate, and
to reward the obedient. And therefore conscience is
called otKetos l> ZXL/, /' O ^
I have the more willingly dwelt a little upon the
Cambridge Moralists of this period, because I conceive
that there has always been in this place an important
school of moralists ; and it is interesting not only to us,
but to all who regard the history of Moral Philosophy,
to trace the changes through which the course of spe-
culation here has passed.
I now turn back to speak of the effect produced on
the public by these opponents of Hobbes. More's re-
ligious writings were extremely admired in their day.
The Mystery of Godliness, and the Mystery of Iniquity,
were extraordinarily popular; as also his Divine Dia-
logues concerning the Attributes and Providenoe of God.
These works found a peculiar public who delighted in
his pure and tranquil tone of thought, and his trains of
religious contemplation, by which they found them-
selves elevated and soothed. But this mystical and
enthusiastic spirit was altogether out of sympathy with
the general temper of the most active-minded men of
the times, and with the tendency of their speculations.
The inquirers of the age demanded something far more
definite and material than the Platonic Mrst Good;
and looked for something exhibiting more of the air of
novelty. Hence we shall not be surprised that More's
doctrines made few converts among the newer school :
and that his writings did not produce any very general
effect ia resisting the spread of the Hobbian tenets;
which, more or less modified, made their way very ex-
tensively. The doctrine of a complete distinction of
virtuous and sensual enjoyments, when considered only
as enjoyments, was not easy to impress upon the
popular mind. And gradually, as the difficulty of
maintaining the war at this point was more and more
felt, the higher school of moralists sought for aid in
another element of the subject; — namely, the will and
government of the Divine Lawgiver.
Undoubtedly this aspect of moral duty had never
74 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHT.
been lost sight of by Christian Moralists ; but still there
■was, philosophically speaking, a difference in the modes
in ■which the Diidne sanctions of Morality were intro-,
duced by different -writers ; which difference it is, for
pur purpose, necessary to state broadly and distinctly.
Some theologians taught that God rewarded actions
and dispositions because they were good, while others
maintained that actions were only therefore morally
good because they were commanded by God. The
former doctrine ■was held by Cudworth, and other as-
serfcors of an independent morality; and these ■were, in,
fact, the genuine antagonists of the Hobbian school.
But in the first burst of the assault on the old ethical
■FiewSj Morality had been driven to a lower ground;
and this, as the contest continued, they found it neces-
sary to entrench more carefully than they had at first
expected. And after the war had for some time gone
on in this direction, it ended, as we shall hereafter se^
in a hollow compromise ; which, as I think it is impos'
sible to doubt, has been very injurious to moraUty,
This, however, is a subject for future discussion.
LECTUEE IV.
CUMBEBLAITD. CxjD WORTH.
I HAVE already said that there were, among those
of the English moralists, who rejected the doc-
trines of Hobbes, two schools: those who held that
goodness was an absolute and inherent quality of
actions, of whom was Cudworthj aod those who did
not venture to say so much, but derived morality from
the nature of man and the will of God jointly; and so
doing, introduced more special and complex views.
Eichard Cumberland, Fellow of Magdalene College,
Cambridge (about 1655), afterwards Bishop of Peter-
borough, was the opponent of Hobbes who took the
principal step towards the latter result which I have
mentioned. His BisquisUio Be Legibus Nativrce, pub-
lished in 1672, is the first extensive attempt to con-
struct a system of morals, which, being founded on
the consideration of the consequences of actions,
should still satisfy those moral feelings and judgments
of man in his usual social condition, which had been
revolted by many of Hobbes's doctrines and modes of
reasoning. That the work was intended to contain a
refutation of the Hobbian doctrines, is stated on the
title-page; and is evident, not only in the controversial
parts of the work, which constitute a large portion of
it, but also in the selection of the main principles of
the doctrine. Hobbes had maintained that the state
of the nature of man is a universal war of each against
all; and that there is no such thing as natural right
and justice; these notions being only creations of
civil society, and deriving their sanction entirely from
the civil ruler. Cumberland's fundamental proposi-
tion is, that the la.w of nature with regard to man's
76 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
actions is a universal benevolence of each towards all.
It will easily be conceived that when this proposition
is once established, most of the common rules of
morality may be deduced from it. But a question
which also belongs ,to our present purpose is, how far
the author's proof of the principle is effective. Two
of the steps which his reasoning involves, enable him
easUy to place a wide interval between himself and
the Hobbian school: namely these: — First, that the
laws of human action must be universal; valid for all,
and consistent with themselves; for the Law of
Nature, as far as morals is concerned, cannot prescribe
to Titius to do that which it enjoins Sempronius to
prevent: and, second, that the Law of Nature, still
speaking with reference to morals, prescribes internal
dispositions as well as external actions, and contem-
plates the effect of actions upon the dispositions and
satisfactions of the mind, as well as upon the comforts
and pleasures of our body and outward state. These
two principles do certainly enable the moralist of con-
sequences to keep the mere sensualist at bay; and
have for a long period assisted many intelligent and
good men to frame systems of morals in which they
have been able tp rest tolerably well satisfied.
Whether such principles do not in fact assume dif-
'ferences which they do not expressly state, and
whether they do not give up the univei-sality, or at
least the independence, of the fundamental principle
of the system (the pursuit of mere happiness, special
or general), I shall not here examine. From the
time of Hobbes to our own, the degree of importance
practically given to these two considerations, has been
a leading feature of distinction among different schools
of moral writers ; and has determined, in a great mea-
sure, the general complexion of their system, as it did
in the case of Cumberland.
But Cumberland further, as I have said, calls to
his aid another great principle, which also was used
still more prominently by his successors. The proof
which he gives, that universal benevolence is a law of
our nature, is principally this: that the general pre-
CUMBERLAND. CTTDWOBTH. "Jf
valence of such a rule of action, and of such dis-
positions, tends in the highest degree to the happiness
and well-being of all. But he is not content with
looking upon this tendency as a mere result of some
blind necessity, as an idtimate law of nature, by which
we must govern ourselves, looking no higher. The
tendency of all things is evidence of the purpose of
the Creator of all. The Law which nature thus
teaches us, is the law of a Divine Lawgiver. That
benevolence is thus the effective condition of the well-
being of his creatures, is a proof that he wishes us to
be benevolent: and thus universal love is his com-
mand, and those duties which flow from such a source,
are duties which he enjoins and sanctions.
We appear now to have advanced very far towards
the systems of morals prevalent in our own time ; yet
a slight attention to the differences which still remain
will show ns that there are several wide steps to make
before we pass from the moral system of Cumberland
to that of recent authors. In the first place, it is
very remarkable that though he thus introduces and
repeatedly insists on this aspect of the Laws of Nature
as the commands of a Divine Legislator, he nowhere
distinctly fortifies his system by a reference to a
future retribution; still less does he aid himself by an
appeal to the revealed will and promises of God.
This may appear very strange to those who are ac-
quainted only with the more recent aspect of this
subject; and I will therefore quote the passages which
specially refer to this part of the argument. After
explaining^ how benevolence to all rational beings is
necessarily connected with our own most perfect
mental state, he proceeds to show that other good and
bad consequences also are connected with, actions con-
formable to and at variance with this law of action ;
and that these consequences, whether resulting from
the course of nature or the institutions of men, may
be looked upon as the sanctions of a Divine Law.
He then adds^ not as a separate consideration, but
1 Cap. V. Sect. i5. = Cap. v. Sect, ss-
78 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
in a paragraph at the end of a long section, " Further,
if God teaches men to judge, that it is necessary both
to the common good and the private good of particular
persons, that all violations of the peace should be
restrained by punishments, when men come to know
of what evil consequence they are; — we may clearly
gather by parity of reason, not only that He himself
so judges, and wills that men shoiUd do so too ; but
also that He makes the same judgment on actions
equally hurtful, which men either do not know or
cannot punish.... This reasoning is obvious to all;
whence they cannot but think with themselves that
God has appointed punishments to their secret crimes;
and that He will avenge their insults upon the weak;
for there is no reason to doubt but that He will
pursue this end, the common good, in which both His
own honour and the happiness of rational beings is
contained. For a greater end there cannot be : and a
less end cannot be taken for the greatest by Him who
judges truly." Here we might expect, from the order of
the thought, to find a reference to a future state, in
which those sins are punished which escape with im-
punity in this life. But we do not find this. On the
contrary, the authqr merely says, "Thus the pangs
and obligations of conscience take their origin from the
government of God." And having thus, as he would
seem to imagine, provided sufficiently for the punish-
ment of secret crimes, he proceeds to another section,
beginning thus : "But let us return to the punish-
ments inflicted by men." He does, indeed, a little
afterwards, say', "Among the rewards [of virtue] is
that happy immortality which natural reason promises
to attend the minds of good men, when separated from
the body:" and, he adds, as applying to this future
state no less than to the present life, "that the happi-
ness of good men is inseparable from the remembrance
and exercise of virtue." "But," he proceeds, "it is
sufficient for me briefly to have hinted this, which has
by others been handled more at large."
I Cap. T. end of Sect. 42.
CUMBERLAND. CUDWORTH. 79
Perhaps it is not difficult to see why this most
■weighty and solemn consideration of a future state, is
introduced in so subordinate a manner, and so soon
dismissed again, by a writer of unquestioned and
earnest piety, Hobbes had made his attack upon the
established theory of morals, as it was commonly
entertained among men ; and it was the object of the
moral writers of his time to repulse this robust and
audacious assailant. According to the opinions cur^
rent up to the period of this controversy. Virtue might
claim respect and obedience on all grounds^ She was
an eternal and independent power, not a creation of
co^mmand supported by external force. She had d.
natural and indisputable authority, not needing the
assistance of threat and promise. She was her own
reward, even if she had no other. She had the pro-
mise of this life, as well as of that which is to come.
She was beautiful in herself, as well as rich in her
dowry. These were the pretensions which Hobbes so
rudely assailed. These opinions therefore the oppo-
nents of Hobbes could not at once abandon. If they
had immediately called in a future life, as the only
mode of defending the cause of viriiue, they would
have seemed to give up the very point which was
assaulted. Could they instantly relinquish to the
sensualist the empire Of this world? Could they grant
to him, that, so far as the present life is concerned, his
doctrines are a wise rule of action ? Could they forth-
with abandon all mention of the dignity, the beauty,
the authority, the peace and joy, which belong to
Virtue? To do this at once, would have been too
shocking. If they had thought of it, the very heathen
would have put them to utter shame. 'For in
the ancient world they had before their eyes a glo-
rious phalanx of writers — Plato and Cicero, Epictetus
and Seneca, Academics and Stoics, who had never
shrunk from the defence of Virtue for her own sake.
These writers had found themselves able to frame a
system of independent morality which had elevated
and purified men's minds, and in some measure guided
their conduct; which had filled them with admiration,
80 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
and ■won tlieir sympathy, even before the Christian
religion came into the world to teach how man's
moral condition might be still further improved. Not
only so, but these ancient moralists had resisted, and
successfully, this very warfare, the fierce and bold
assault of the sensual school, before which the modern
moralists now wavered, and thought to change their
ground. It was impossible for these moralists, at
once, in the sight of the enemy, and after the first
modern attack, to abandon positions so dear to all
lovers of virtue, so nobly defended hitherto ; position^
so strong in their ancient majesty, that even the
traditionary respect which hung around them would
secure them from a pudden revolution and ruin.
Tet, on the other hand, it is tolerably evident
that, in truth, some of the most important doctrines
of the Christian religion had a large share in making
moralists become more willing than they had hitherto
been, to give up the independent authority of V^irtue.
The views of man's nature, and of his relation to his
heavenly Master, which prevailed among our divines,
co-operating with the inherent defects of the ancient
system of moral's, — defects never supplied, nor capable
of being supplied, — made men not unwilling to try
what could be done to satisfy the cravings of his
speculative nature by combining moral with religious
views. The deficiencies of the moral system which
spoke of the inherent beauty and iudependent author-
ity of virtue were indeed evident enough: for alas!
with all its charms and its rights, how little can it
efi"ect among men ! how blind are they to its beauty !
how rebellious to its authority! Even if we can, by
the light of nature, discover a rule of action, how little
can we discover motives which are fitted to urge men,
such as in general they exist, to conform to the rule!
That we here need some extraneous power which may
enforce our law, is too obvious. That the Divine
Government of the world which religion discloses to
us, is a motive needed by man and suited to his needs,
all moralists will gladly allow. Here, therefore^ we at
once see great advantages which result from calling in
CUMBEELAND. CUDWOETH. 8 1
Religion to assist the ■weakness of independent moral-
ity. The law which had hitherto been feeble and
almost ineffective, thus became a living rule of con-
duct, realized by the prospect of the highest rewards
and most awful punishments. Man could thenceforth
no longer, as of old, separate with impunity knowing
from doing; — no longer see and approve the better
and follow the worse. But moreover this disposition
to give up the independent authority of moral good
was favoured by other theological views then prevalent
among our Divines : — by the desii-e to put, in the most
prominent and impressive forms, the supreme author-
ity of God, and the coiTuption of man's nature. The
former of these tenets was, or at least appeared to be,
strengthened by declaring God to be not merely the
assertor but the author of moral distinctions. The lat-
ter tenet, the corruption of man, was put in a strong
point of view, when it was held that he was so per-
verted as not only not to be able to do, but not able
even to hnow what was good.
I shall not here discuss these views at length.
I will only observe, in order to obviate any mistakes
which the statement of these opinions without any
corrective might occasion, that if we make Holiness,
Justice, and Purity, the mere result of God's com-
mands, we can no longer find any force in the declara-
tion that God is Holy, Just, and Pure; since the
assertion then becomes merely an empty identical
proposition. And with regard to the other point, if
man cannot, by the best exertion of his natural facul-
ties, attain to any knowledge of the distinction be-
tween right and wrong, he cannot, without a revela-
tion of God's will to him, be capable of vice or sin,
since these are the violations of moral rules and
Divine Laws concerning right and wrong actions.
It is with reluctance that I have introduced these
subjects, even in the most transient manner: but it
seemed to me that if I were not to do so, the state of
the question, which I am now treating historically,
could not be understood : and I trust to the indtilgence
of all my readers, to interpret in the most favourable
6
82 HISTORY or MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
manner, these scanty hints thus occasionally thrown
out, on subjects of the deepest importance.
But to return to the author of the Treatise Be
Legibus Naiwrce, of whose place in this discussion
I was speaking. I observe that the considerations
to which I have referred, and which withheld the
moralists of his time, even when they made conse-
quences their only guide, from at once reducing Virtue
to the mere pursuit of enjoyment, have very strongly
affected his work; and have left it full of expressions
and tenets which his successors in this path gradually
abandoned. For instance, he attaches great impor-
tance to what he calls Right Reason, and thus often
approximates to the school of Independent Morality;
as when he speaks of the obligation of the Laws of
Nature as immutable' : and again, at other times he
uses language like that of Henry More, as when he
speaks with enthusiasm of the pleasure of benevolent
dispositions^; "that joy which arises in our minds
from the prosperity of others, and which brings our-
selves home a plentiful harvest."
I will only further observe, as one of the causes
which contributed to the influence of this book upon
the succeeding course of English Moral Philosophy,
that it is constructed with a laborious imitation of
mathematical forms of demonstration; which, from
the reputation of the writings of Descartes, and the
progress of mathematical physics, were now beginning
to be looked upon as the genuine forms of true know-
ledge. In the same spirit, there is a frequent refer-
ence to mathematical examples to illustrate the nature
of necessary truths and demonstrative reasonings :
and the recent physiological discoveries are called in
to confirm the other indications which tend to show
that universal benevolence is the law of nature. Thus
he quotes from WiUis, the physician, an account of
the Plexus Nervosus of the intercostal nerve, and
even inserts a copper-plate, in order stiU further to
explain this structure; because, as he says, this part
1 Cap. v. Sect 23. a Sect 16.
CUMBERLAND, CUDWORTH. 83
of the nervous system is one of tte things which
better enable man to rule his affections. His quota-
tion from "Willis is curious : " That the thoughts
relating to acts of the ■will or understanding (in "which
the powers of prudence and the virtues are conspi-
cuous) may be duly formed, it is necessary that the
torrent of blood in the breast be kept within bounds,
and the inordinate motions of the heart be restrained
by the nerves, as by reins, and be reduced to regu-
larity." Which purpose the intercostal nerve, he con-
ceives, answers; for "by these branches it supplies the
place of an extraordinary courier, communicating, to
and fro, the mutual sensations of the heart and brain."
The indications of purpose in man's structure and
constitution are most rightly taken into account, by
the moralist as well as by the physiologist; but I do
not conceive that this part of Cumberland's reasoning
was very happily developed by him. Indeed the
whole work, notwithstanding its mathematical form,
is wanting in method, and is constantly made tedious
and confused by the insertion of criticisms of Hobbes
in every part. It was however, as I have said, the
basis of much of our succeeding moral philosophy.
It was translated, or rather abridged, in English by
James Tyrrel, in 1692; and in I'jz'j a translation
was published by the Eev. John Maxwell. In the
remarks made by the translator in this edition, we
see that the author had not succeeded in conveying
clear systematic notions to his readers, at least of that
day. For these notes often complain of the author's
obscurity, and sometimes give an explanation which
is at variance with the system. This is not surprising ;
for in the mean time several other speculations had
come forth which altered the state of public thought,
and made it different from that which prevailed when
Cumberland's work was written.
These occurrences I must afterwards notice, but
I must first attend to the other division of the oppo-
nents of Hobbes. I have spoken of those who treated
virtue as a means to some other end : I must now
speak of those who considered it as an end in itself.
. 6—2
84
HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
I have described the reasonings of those who consi-
dered Virtue as commendable, because she leads to
man's happiness and -weU-being : but I must now give
an account of those who ascribe to her an independent
value. The former, as we have seen, approximated
by degrees towards a view of morality such as now
prevails; the tendency of the doctrines of the latter
will appear as we proceed.
Of these assertorsof independent morality,Cudworth
is the principal. Ralph Cudworth, Fellow of Emma-
nuel College about 1637, Master of Clare Hall in 1644,
and of Clmst's College iu 1651, was, as I have already
said, the most genuine antagonist of Hobbes, since
he descended to no compromise, but steadily main-
tained the immutable and independent authority of
moral right. In doing this, he took the old high
Platonic ground on which the battle had in ancient
times been fought, although he both modified and
fortified the position by a judicious attention to the
recent progress of philosophy. Familiar with the
writings of the ancient moralists, he at once perceived
that all the bold and paradoxical dogmas of Hobbes,
strange and monstrous as they sounded in modem
ears, were but the repetition of the sophistries of
former times. His Treatise concerning Eternal and
Immutable Morality, begins by showing that there
have been some ia aU ages who have maintained that
Good and Evil, Just and Unjust, were not naturally
and immutably so, but only by human laws and
appointments. This assertion, which had been made
by Protagoras' and many others, was connected by
* Though the commentators on
Plato often speak as if Protagoras
were the prominent example of i^
moralist who reduced Eight and
Wrong to mere Pleasure and Pain,
Gain and Loss, yet in truth, there
seems to be no reason to put bim in
this position. In the Platonic Dia-
lOsHe which bears his same, and in
which he is the principal figure, he
repudiates this doctrine. The doc-
trine that Might is Eight is asserted,
not by him, but by other Interlo-
cutors in the Platonic Dialogues; as
CaJlicles and Folus in the GSorgias,
and Thrasymachus in the first Book
of the Bepnblic.
CUMBERLAND. CUDWOETH. 85
them with, the doctrine that we derive our knowledge
from our senses, which cannot give us information
of any thing certain and permanent ; and that in the
ever-flowing stream of the universe nothing can be
immutable and eternal. Plato himself had made it
one of his most serious tasks to reason against this
school. Two tenets of the Protagorean philosophy,
that the universe is constituted of atoms, and that
all our knowledge is only relative and phantastic, were
both rejected by Plato, as alike leading to skepticism.
Cudworth, taught by the recent progress and prospects
of physical philosophy, takes care not to make the
cause of the eternal fixity of truth depend upon the
rejection of the mechanical theory of the universe. On
the contrary, he turns the battery of the Atomic Theory
upon his adversaries : and maintains that the genuine
result of that Theory is, That Sense alone is not the
Judge of what does really and absolutely exist, but
that there is another Principle in us superior to Sense.
He further asserts that knowledge is an Inward active
Energy of the mind, not arising from things acting
from without : that some Ideas of the mind proceed
not from sensible objects, but arise from the inward
activity of the mind itself: that the intelligible notions
of things, though existing only in the mind, are not
figments of the miad, but have an immutable nature;
and hence he concludes, in an assertion of Origen,
that Science and Knowledge is the only firm thing in
the world.
This view of the nature of knowledge is proved, as
I have already said, upon the principles which are
unfolded so skilfully and agreeably in Plato's Dia-
logues ; the exposition being however materially modi-
fied with reference to the state of modem philosophy.
But the application of this doctrine of the eternal
and immutable nature of truth in general to the
particular case of moral truth, is less fully and clearly
developed \ After he has proved that "wisdom,
knowledge, mind, and intelligence, are no thin shadows
' Cap. VI. p. 292,
86 HISTORY or MORAL PHILOlsOPHT.
or images of corporeal and sensible things, but have an
independent and self-subsistent being, whicb in order
of nature is before body;" be contents himself with
saying, "Now from hence it naturally follows, that
those things which belong to Mind, and Intellect, such
as are Morality, Ethics, Politic?, and Laws, which
Plato calls the offspring of the mind, are no less to be
accounted natural things, or real and substantial, than
those things which belong to stupid and senseless
matter."
It must, I think, be allowed that the treatise of
Immutable Morality produced very little effect on the
Hobbian controversy : and though always mentioned
as one of our standard works on Morals, even now
produces little impression on most of those who view
it as an ethical work\ Nor is it diflB.cult to assign
reasons for this want of effectiveness in the book. In
the first place, this result is almost sufficiently account-
ed for by what I have stated : namely, the principles
of the work are not manifestly brought to bear on the
question. It may be well proved, we may suppose,
that all truth is independent and immutable; but we
want a great deal more than this general principle to
satisfy us that moral distinctions are independent and
immutable. We require a detailed application of the
general reasonings to the particular case. If it be so,
we would know how it is so :— what form the demon-
stration assumes when we use the terms of the propo-
sition we would establish : how the difficulties and
obscurities which seem to hang about it are affected by
this demonstration. Men will not be satisfied that
there is an adamantine chain, except we can show them
the links of which it consists. They will not believe
that moral ideas are determined lay eternal laws,
except we show them what these laws are ; just as
they would not believe that the motions of the planets
are governed by fixed laws, tiU these laws were
1 Mr Hallam, Iiii5(?ur'5wei2ea507i only. He
included the Intuitm Reason, which
his predecessors had held to be tlie
ground of moral judgments. I have
attempted to rectify the misstatement
in a supplementary Lecture printed
among the Additional Leclmres which
I follow these.
7
9 8 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
degree in this University, he was actively engaged in
introducing into the academic course of study, first,
I the philosophy of Descartes in its best form, and next,
the philosophy of Newton immediately after its first
'publication. He was naturally led, therefore, both by
his familiarity with recent metaphysical distinctions,
and by his love of demonstration, to ascribe a great
weight to intellectual relations, and to overlook as
parts of the subject those in which the intellect had
not a direct or sole jurisdiction. If this had not been
the case, he could hardly have failed to see how in-
sufficient an account of moral distinctions it was, to
say that the denial of them implies an absurdity and
a contradiction. When Cudworth and the ancient
philosophers talked of wickedness being contrary to
Right Reason, the Reason was looked upon as the
governing faculty of all provinces of man's nature. It
was the fountain and treasure-house of all fundamental
general principles, by which we judge of truth of all
kinds ; and it was also the authority which applied
these principles to their practical uses. So viewed,
therefore, the Reason was qualified to pronounce moral
judgments; to extricate out of her own nature the
speculative truths which are involved iu her recog-
nized functions. But now the case was altered. The
office of Reason had been greatly narrowed and bound-
ed; and this had been done, I will suppose, for the
sake of argument, with great advantage to the clear-
ness and distinctness of metaphysical doctrines ; stDl
this change made it less safe than before to say, that
eternal distinctions of moral good and evil were objects
of the Reason. The Reason had now had her business
reduced to the employments of collecting ideas and
general principles from experience, and of combining
these according to the processes of discursive reasoning.
How could any one find, in this series of operations,
the road to eternal and immutable truths, concerning
good and bad, right and duty ?
Thus the doctrine of Clarke, Kke the opinion of
Locke which I before mentioned, that Morality is
capable of demonstration, may be considered as rem-
lOCKE. CLAEKE. 99
nants retained by them of a philosophy then past j —
propositions already antiquated when they were pub-
lished ; — traditionary assertions repeated, because they
■who asserted them did not perceive ho"w great a revo-
lution the import of their terms had undergone. If
Morality is still to be capable of demonstration, — ^if
her distinctions are really steadfast and unchangeable,
— we must seek some new source of just principles for
our reasoning, some new basis of fixity and perma-
nency. The discursive Eeason, generalizing and com-
bining the measures of good and ill which she obtains
from the senses, can never soar back again into the
higher region of absolute good ; though she may retain
some dim remembrance of it, which may still influence
her wanderings in this lower world.
V— a
LECTUEE VI.
Mandeville. Warbtjeton'.
I HAVE endeavoured to explain in my previous
lectures that the tendency towards the lower view
of morality, which rests its rules upon consequences
merely, had acquired an extensive and powei-ftd pre-
valence in the beginning of the last century. This
view had been connected by Locke and his followers
with their metaphysical doctrines ; and these again,
besides their other recommendations, had been con-
nected, how rightly or necessarily it may hereafter be
our business to consider, but in men's minds they had
been connected with the general progress of science
and knowledge, and of new opinions, which that period
witnessed. And so striking and wonderful was that
progress, that we cannot at all marvel if men were
carried too rapidly onwards by the current, and were
led to think that the new metaphy.-ical doctrines which
had thus formed an alliance with an admirable body
of new truths, must be far sounder and better than the
old modes of speculation, which had been pursued for
so many ages with so little visible positive result.
The two sides of the great alternative of the Theory
of Morals, the Morality of Principles, and the Morality
of Consequences, had been combined respectively with
the old and the new metaphysical systems. Or rather,
while the Morality of Principles, as a system, remained
still involved in great perplexity and obscurity, the
Morality of Consequences was perpetually worked out
into clearer and clearer forms, and exjiressed in a more
MANDEVILLB. WARBUHTON. lOt
pointed and precise manner. Hence, both Clarke;' who
asserted the doctrines of the higher moral school in.
terms no longer •well fitted to express them, and Butler,
■who, maintaining them steadfastly, strove to avoid the
responsibility of expressing them in any fixed and
constant terms, produced little permanent effect upon
the general habits of thought of their contempora-
ries. The Morality of Consequences, the doctrine that
actions are good or evil as they produce pleasure or
pain, was pushed further and fiirther. A principle so
simple and tangible, all, it seemed, could apply. AU,
or at least a great number of men, ill fitted for the
office of moral teachers, did actually take courage and
apply it. The reverence which, handed down by the
tradition of ages of moral and religious teaching, had
hitherto protected the accustomed forms of moral good,
was gradually removed. Vice, and Crime, and Sin,
ceased to be words that terrified the popular speculator.
Virtue, and Goodness, and Purity, were no longer
things which he looked up to with mute respect. He
ventured to lay a sacrilegious hand even upon these
hallowed shapes. He saw that when this had been
dared by audacious theorists, those objects, so long
venerated, seemed to have no power of punishing the
bold intruder. There was a scene like that which
occurred when the barbarians of old broke into the
Eternal City. At first, and for a time, in spite of
themselves, they were awed by the divine aspect of the
ancient rulers and magistrates : but when once their
leader had smitten one of these venerable figures with
impunity, the coarse and violent mob rushed onwards,
and exultingly mingled all in one common destruction.
The general diffusion of the estimate of moral good
and ill by the pleasure and pain to which it leads, pro-
duced a profligate and sensual tone of moral discussion ;
and this extended with a rapidity not imaptly repre-
sented by the above image. As a promin'ent example
of this spirit, we may take the well-known Fable of
the Bees. This was a short apologue in verse, published
in F5ei4, by a physician of the name of Mandeyille,
the professed object of which was to shew that Private
102 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHT.
Vices are Public Benefits ; that the vices, as they are
usually held, of Selfishness, Luxury, and Lust, -within
certain limits, are the elements upon which the pros-
perity of a state depends, and, " that all the moral
virtues are no better than the political offipring which
flattery begot upon pride." The work possesses little
or no literary merit; and is only remarkable for
the notice it excited, and for the mode in which the
author, when put upon his defence, supported his
tenets : namely, as I have intimated, by professing
to trace to their consequences the courses which he
palliated. The main impression which the book is
calculated to convey is, the old licentious doctrine,
that virtue and vice are only conventions for keeping
society in order ; that virtue has nothing really lovely,
and vice nothing absolutely mischievous ; but that
on the contrary, our supposed virtues arise from the
coarsest springs, and our vices often produce the most
beneficial consequences ; (see for example, pp. 83, 4) ;
and especially that vice is an essential constituent of
riches and greatness in a moral state.
The book was presented as a nuisance, on account
of its profligacy, by the grand jury of the county of
Middlesex in 1723. And although this cii-cumstance
may be alleged, I hope justly, as proving that the
poison of the principles promulgattd. by this author
had not yet entirely pervaded English society, we may,
observe on the other hand, that the Presentment states
that many books and pamphlets are published almost
every week against religion and morals ; and it assigns
this general viciousness of literature as the reason for
singling out this book, and another which is mention-
ed, for condemnation.
Similar complaints, most emphatically expressed,
are made by almost all the Divines and Moralists of
the time. Attacks on religion and on morals, (for
these were, as may be supposed, very generally com-
bined,) were so common and so licentious, that many
pious and good men appear to have looked upon the
progress of thought and feeling with despondency and
despair.
MANDEVILLB. WARBURTON'. I03
In such, a state of things it manifestly beeam e the
duty of the lovers and guardians of morality to collect
their forces and put themselves in a condition suited
for defence. They had been fighting loosely and care-
lessly, and disunited; so confident of their inherent
strength, so relying upon general respect, that they
had hardly believed the combat was in earnest. They
had looked upon it rather as a mere academic disputa-
tion than as a trial in which their preservation or ruin
was involved : rather as an encounter of wits for
superiority, than as a struggle of moral principles for
life. That the battles of speculators concerning Moralsp
Politics, and Religion were an affair of real practical
import, heavy with the most solemn consequences, the
history of the remainder of this eighteenth century
showed too clearly ; but it was only about the time of
which I speak, that this conviction began to force
itself upon the minds of the friends of the principles
then established. It was however now plain, that the
emergency was a weighty one, and that it behoved
the teachers of morals and religion to provide for
the safety of the host which looked up to them for
guidance.
A bold and vigorous champion stept forth, and
proceeded to order the mode of defence which the
defenders of morality were to adopt. Learned in
ancient and accomplished in modem literature, acute
in the conduct of arguments, ingenious in the inven-
tion of theories, self-confident almost to haughtiness,
sarcastic, lively, he was beyond doubt the ablest con-
troversialist of his day. I speak of Warburton ; who
did, in fact, give to the theory of morals the form in
which it has been received among us almost up to the
present time. He, I say, at the time now under con-
sideration, set himself to arrange the principles of
morality in such a form that they might be systema-
tically and successfully defended. He did not hesitate
at once to collect and unite forces of variotis kinds, so
far as they could be made subservient to a common
purpose. It was no longer now a time, he conceived,
when it was wise or fit to insulate the various bodies
104 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY,
of gemiine moralists ; — to separate those who founded
morality oa the relations of things, and those who
derived it from the will of God. The history of the
subject had shown the evil of this. The old Platonic
moralists, such as Cudworth and More, had been
abandoned by their brethren j and their little host,
insulated from the rest, seemed to have crumbled
away. The independent moralists who stiU remained,
as Clarke and Butler, could be upheld only, "War-
burton thought, by surrounding them by a line of
more robust combatants. And along with these, he
was willing to accept as allies that other class of
moralists who had lately assumed a distinct shape,
and who ascribed to man what they called a Moral
Sense; the school, as we shall see, of Shaftesbury.
Warburton considered Shaftesbury as one of the
adversaries whom he had to oppose, since his writings
were directed against the Christian religion : but this
did not prevent him from adopting the Moral Sense,
in the most distinct and positive manner, as one of his
principles. The first books of the Divine Legation of
Moses, in which this was done, appeared in 1738.
Warburton's basis of the defence of morality, is a com-
bination, or as such a system is sometimes termed by
writers on the History of Philosophy, a syncretism, of
all the principles on which immoral writers and mere
sensual moralists had been pi'eviously opposed : namely
the Moral Sense, — the Eternal Differences of Actions,
— and the WiU of God (p. 136). He shows great
skill in asserting and maintaining the co-existence and
relative offices of these three principles. " God," he
says, "graciously respecting the imbecility of man's
nature, the slowness of his reason, and the violence of
his passions, hath been pleased to afford three different
excitements to the practice of virtue ; — something
that would hit men's palate, satisfy their reason, or
subdue their vnlV He complains that "this admir-
able provision for the support of virtue hath been in
great measure defeated by its pretended advocates,
who, in their eternal squabbles about the true founda^-
tion of morality and the obligation of its practice, have
MANDEVILLE. WARBURTON. 105
sacrilegiously untwisted this Threefold Cord; and each
running atray with the part he esteemed the strongest,
hath affixed that to the throne of God, as the golden
chain that is to unite and draw all unto it." He then
proceeds, with great dexterity, to play off these three
sects against each other. The advocates of the Moral
Sense, he says, (pointing at Shaftesbury) hold the
essential differences in human actions " to be nothing
but words, notions, visions, the empty regions and
shadows of philosophy : the possessors of them are
moon-blind wits; and Locke himself is treated as a
schoolman. And to talk of reward and punishment
consequent on the will of a superior, is to make the
practice of virtue mercenary and servile." He then
speaks of those who adopt the Essential Differences
of things as the ground of morality : and according to
these, he says, " God and his Will have nothing to do
in the matter." And the third, he says, "who pro-
poses to place morality on the will op a superior,
which is its true bottom, acts yet on the same exter-
minating model. He takes the other two principles
to be merely visionary : the moral sense is nothing but
the impression of education ; the love of the species,
romantic, and invented by crafty knaves to dupe the
young, the vain, and the ambitious." He proceeds
with still more ingenuity, to find a recognition of this
threefold aspect of virtue in St Paul : " Finally, bre-
thren, whateoever things are true, whatsoever things
are honest, whatsoever things are just : To Xoiirw aS€X-
o\ ocra IotIv dXrjOrj, ocra (TEjixva, ocra SiKaia; akrjOyj
evidently relating to the essential difference of things,
o-E/ivoi, (implying something of worth, splendour, dignity)
to the moral sense which men have of this difference ;
and SiKata, just, is relative to will or law." In the
same manner he distributes "pure, lovely, of good
report," into the three pigeon-holes of his theory, "ayva,
pure, referring to abstract truth ; irpoa-i^ikrj, lovely,
amiable, to innate or instinctive honesty : and evi^yjixa,
of good report, reputable, to the observation of will or
law." He again makes a similar attempt on the con-
cluding words of the passage, although they do not
I06 HISTOET OP MOKAL PHILOSOPHY.
form a triad It is easy to see that if they had been
these, " if there be any virtue, if there he atiy wisdom,
if there be any praise," he ■vrould have been most
triumphant : that is, he -would have said, — if I may
venture to complete what he has said, — " if the moral
sense can make the practice of morality a virtue ; if
the essential differences of things" [can render it con-
formable to reason;] if obedience to a superior will can
make it matter of praise ; think of these things. But
though we cannot &il to admire the ingenuity with
which Warburton thus constructed and illustrated his
system, it is difficult for the genuine moral philosopher
to maintain it in precisely that form which he assigned
to it. In his desire to engage in his service all the
strongest supports of morals which he could discover,
he has hardly sufficiently attended to the nature of
each, and to their mutual relations. If these three
elements are to be united in order to obtain a basis for
our system of morals, this must be done, not by arbi-
trarily and forcibly twisting them together, but by
combining them in their proper relations, so as to form
an organic and living whole. That Warburton has not
done so, it is not difficult to show. But before I show
this, I must consider more in detail the history of the
elements which he here attempts to combine. This I
shall proceed to do in the next Lecture.
LECTURE VII.
Cumberland. Shaftesbury. Huxcheson. Balgut.
South.
IN my last lecture, I stated that when the general
prevalence of licentious speculative opinions re-
specting morality had become very alarming, of which
state of things the publication of the Fable of the Bees
and similar -works was an indication, Warburton tried
to put the cause of sound morals in a better condition
for defence, by combining all the principles which had
been employed by his predecessors against the doc-
trines of the sensual school. The principles which he
thus associated were, I stated, these : Bight Reason,
the Moral Sense, and the Divine Command. Of the
first of these doctrines and its features, I have already
given an account in several Lectures. I must now
trace the rise and progress of the other two forms of
opinion; and first the Moral Sense.
In a former Lecture, I endeavoured to explain
how the controversy between the school of indepen-'
dent morality, and the school of the morality of con-
sequences, was afiected by the new metaphysical
opinions to which Locke's essay gave currency and
authority. It appeared that those who had, till then,
maintained that moral rectitude consists in eternal
and injmutable relations recognizable by the reason of
man, had their arguments weakened and perplexed by
the analysis of the human mind which was now gene-
rally admitted, and by the limits within which the
province of the reason was now circumscribed. Such
doctrines as those of Cudworth and Clarke, though
I08 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
still asserted by some, began now to be considered as
remnants of a past philosophy; — propositions anti-
quated before they were published; — traditionary as-
sertions, repeated only because those who uttered
them did not perceive how great a revolution the
import of their terms had undergone, or how much
the views of philosophers had changed, concerning the
region in which truth resided, and the road by which
her votaries were to travel to her. A few short
phrases of weariness and contempt were considered by
the world as answer enough to the most acute and
laborious works which breathed the old Platonic strain.
Yet in this, as in other cases, when a great contro-
versy is thrown into confusion by a change in the
speculative opinions which its terms imply, after a
season of vacillation and misunderstanding, the an-
tagonist parties again form themselves, and stand, as
before, with opposite fronts, though, it may be, with
new watchwords, on each side. From the time' of
Locke, the morality of consequences appeared to pre-
vail over the morality of a priori principles ; but still
the spirit of independent morality was alive, and soon
found a garb in which it could claim the respect of
men.
Though moralists no longer found the common voice
of mankind respond to them, when they declared that
virtue and vice were founded upon eternal and im-
mutable distinctions, apprehended by the reason, there
were still many who could not be content with such a
representation of man's nature, as that which assigns
to him no higher motives than the love of pleasure
and the aversion to pain. And these persons sought
in various quarters, and under various forms, the prin-
ciples of genuine morality, and the faculties by which
we apprehend those principles. One such principle,
thus ascribed to human nature, was a general. Bene-
volence and Sociality, — a love of his kind, — which man
possesses, it was held, in addition to his regard for his
individual pleasure and interest. This doctrine was
at this time very commonly maintained by moralists
and jurists throughout Europe, having been made by
eUMBERLAKD, SHAFTESBURY, &C. IO9
iGrotius and Puffendorf the basis of their systems.
Cumberland aSerEed~in'a very decided manner that
such was the proper ground of human action, clearly
dividing this principle of benevolence from the regard
to -our own good. Thus he says (Chap. v. Sect. 22);
"His own happiness is an extremely small part of that
end which a truly rational man pursues; and bears
only that proportion to the whole end (the common
good with which it is interwoven by God the author
of nature) which one man bears to the collective body
of all rational beings, which is less than that of the
smallest grain of sand to the whole mass of matter."
And although he sometimes speaks of our acting so as
is necessary to complete our own happiness (Sect. 27),
he immediately adds that "this happiness necessarily
depends upon the pursuit of the common good of all
rational agents; as the soundness of a member depends
upon the soundness and life of the whole animated
body; or as the strength of our hands cannot effect
tually be preserved without first preserving that life
and streagth which is diflfused through our whole
body." Thus the well being of the whole community
is assumed as necessary, not only to the attaining, but
to the conceiving the well being of the individual;
and I note this the more especially, because this fea-
ture and the images by which it is illustrated, may
sometimes enable us to distinguish to which of the
two antagonist schools moralists belong, when they
seem to approach near to the boundary line. Com-
parisons, such as are here employed, (the human body
and the human species,) belong almost exclusively to
those who maintain that morality is an end in itself.
They are employed by Plato in his Dialogues, the first
clear argumentation on that side of the subject which
was given to the speculative world ; and we shall see
that they stUl continue to be used by those who may
be looked upon as the assertors of the same side of the
question, at a period later than that of which we are
now speaking.
Of the moralists of this school, in the period im-
mediately, succeeding the publication of Locke's Essay,
no HISTORY OF MOIIAL PHILOSOPHY.
Lord Shaftesbury may be considered as one of the
bast representatives. His grandfather, the celebrated
Achitophel of Dryden, had Locke for his intimate
friend; and the grandson was bred up in a habit of
deference to the philosophica;! reformer. But this did
not prevent him from discerning the real tendency of
the morality which was involved in the new system;
nor from declaring himself the opponent of the doc-
trines thus promulgated. In his "Letter to a Student
in the University," after observing that "all those
called free writers now-a-days have espoused those
principles which Mr Hobbes set a^foot in the last age,"
he adds, "Mr Locke, as much as I honour him, on
account of other writings (on government, policy,
trade, coin, education, toleration, &c., and as well as I
know him, and can answer for his sincerity, as a
most zealous Christian and believer,) did however go in
the selfsame tract, and is followed by the Tindals and
all the other ingenious free authors of our time."
"'Twas Mr Locke," he adds, "that struck the
home blow, for Mr Hobbes's character and base slavish
principles of government, took off the poison of his
philosophy. 'Twas Mr Locke that struck at all fun-
damentals, threw all order and virtue out of the world,
and made the very ideas of these (which ai-e the same
as those of God) unnatural and without foundation in
our minds."
In opposition to these dangerous and degrading
opinions, Shaftesbury maintained the independent and
original nature of moral distinction. He calls himself
a Moral BeaUst, as opposed to others who he says
(Characteristics, ii. 257) are mere Nominal Moralists,
making virtue nothing in itself a creature of WiU
only, or a mere name of Fashion. His view of the
ground of morality is nearly the same as that which
we have already seen in Cumberland. Virtue requires
an attention in each individual to the good of the
whole; and the loss of this disposition is a disorder
which includes the unhappiness of the individual
among its evil consequences. [Inquiry concerning
Virtue; Characteristics, u. 82), "When there is an
SHAFTESBURY, HUTCHESON, &C, III
absolute degeneracy, a total apostasy from all candour,
equity, trust, sociableness, friendship, there are few
who do not see and acknowledge the misery which is
consequent. Seldom is the case misconstrued when
at worst. The misfortune is, we do not look on this
depravity, nor consider how it stands, in less degrees.
The Calamity, we think, does not of necessity hold
proportion with the Injustice or Iniquity. As if to
be absolutely im>moral and inhuman were indeed the
greatest misfortune and misery; but that to be so in a
little degree should be no misery nor harm at all."
And then follows one of the characteristic illustrations
of this school, "Which to allow is just as reasonable
as to own that it is the greatest ill of a body to be
in the utmost manner distorted or maimed : but that
to lose the use only of one limb, or to be impaired
in some one single organ or member is no inconveni-
ence or ill worthy the least notice."
It is not difficult to see here and in similar expla-
nations of the school of moral realists, that although
calamity, misery, unha/ppimess, and the like terms, are
used to describe those attributes of vice which make it
a thing to be shunned and hated, the real fundamental
notion of this evil is the violation of man's nature, as
a system in which the parts have certain essential rela-
tions to each other, and to the whole. Accordingly
the author adds, immediately after the passage I have
quoted, "The parts and proportions of the mind, their
mutual relation and dependency, the connection and
frame of those passions which constitute the soul or
temper, may easUy be understood by any one who
thinks it worth his while to study this inward anatomy.
'Tis certain that the order or symmetry of this inward
part is in itself no less real and exact than that of the
body" — and to the same train of thought belongs what
he elsewhere says (ii. 121), "that to want conscience
or natural sense of the odiousness of Crime and Injus-
tice, is to be most of all miserable in life."
Shaftesbury possesses great merits as a writer, and
was much admired by a great number of his con-
temporaries. And beyond doubt his influence contrir
112 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
bated to preserve his countrymen in some measure
from that very low scheme of morals which results
from resolving virtue into a mere pursuit of pleasure.
But while he did this, he found, or fancied, that there
was a school of divines, as well as a school of philo-
sophers, whose tenets were at variance with his ; and
the harshness, and I may say petulance, with which
he condemns and ridicules these adverse theological
doctrines, together with his want of reverence for
revealed religion, produced an enmity between him
and Christian writers, to whom, on some points, he
might otherwise have been a valuable ally. The main
point of oflFence with him is the practice, which he
lays to the charge of divines, of making virtue a mere
matter of self-love, by resting her obligation entirely
on the hopes and fears of a future life (ii. 59). If any
divines had done this in such a way as to lose sight of
the goodness and justice of the great Judge, and of the
love of goodness which he demands even more than
outward acts, they would be justly liable to the ac-
cusation of perverting religion, no less than morality.
I am not aware of the existence, at this time, of books
of any degree of general currency which put forth such
mistaken views; and I think we may rather ascribe
this noble writer's ebuUitions of ill humour on such
subjects to a dislike towards the clergy and their
peculiar views ; which we may trace very generally in
the men of the world of the period now under con-
sideration.
Without here attempting to analyse the origin of
this feeling, I may observe that so fer as our subject
is concerned, it manifested itself in two ways. The
philosophical revolution brought about by Hobbes and
Locke had divided the speculative world between two
opinions, the old and the new. If the clergy adopted
the new doctrine, that seK-love is the only spring of
human action, they were iipbraided as lowering the
dignity and purity of virtue; — ^if on the contrary, they
kept their ancient ground, and held that virtue is a good,
to be sought for its own sake, they were sneered at as
the obstinate assertors of visionary and obsolete notions.
SHAFTESBTTRY, HUTOHESON, &C. II3
Shaftesbury is to be condemiied so far as he op-
posed morality to religion ; but the objections to him
would have been unphilosophical if they had merely
depended upon his distinguishing morality and reli-
gion. We must not refuse to accept Shaftesbury as
the origin of a new school of real moralists, if he be
indeed so. And there was an opening for such a
school.
The ancient school of Cudworth and Clarke was
now nearly extinct : yet a divine of some note who
answered Shaftesbury, still upheld the credit of this
school. This was John Balguy , vicar of Northallerton,
and prebendary of Salisbury (!B.A. in 1705). In 1 ^26
and 1728 he wrote replies to Shaftesbury's Inquiry
Ooncerning Virtue, and also to the work of Hutcheson,
which we shall soon have to mention. In these pub-
lications he speaks of " that excellent, that inestimable
book, Dr Clarke's BoylSs Lectures" and expresses his
surprize that a person of the discernment and pene-
tration which he ascribes to his adversary, rose dis-
satisfied from that work with regard to the points before
us, namely, the foundations of morals {Tracts, p. 66).
Balguy {Tracts, p. 66) did not hesitate still to
declare his assent to the ancient formularies of the
Cambridge school — that the morality of actions consists
in conformity to Reason, and difformity from it — ^that
virtue is acting according to the absolute fitness of
things, or agreeably to the Nature and Relations of
things — ^that there are eternal and immutable Dififer-
ences of things absolutely and antecedently; that there
are also eternal and unalterable Relations in the nature
of the things themselves; from which arise agreements
and disagreements, congruities and incongruities, fit-
'ness and unfitness of the application of circumstances
to the qualifications of persons. To these Clarkian
and Oudwoi-thian phrases Balguy adds others, as "that
virtue consists in the conformity of our wUls to our
understandings," and these ways of speaking he endea- -
vours to explain and defend.
But these were now becoming antique and unusual
sounds. In general the moral realists were aware that
8
114 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
they gave their adversaries an advantage, when they
ascribed the discernment of moral relations to the
Reason, narrowed as the domain of that faculty had in
later times been. They now found it more convenient
to assert that moral distinctions were perceived by a
peculiar and separate Faculty. To this faculty some
did not venture to give a name, but described it only
by its operations and results, while others applied to it
a term. The Moral Sense, which introduced a new set
of analogies and connections. Each of these courses
had its inconveniences for the assertors of the faculty,
as we shall see. And first of the latter course.
It has been customary of late among those who
have written concerning the History of Ethics in
England, to speak of Hutcheson as the writer who
introduced this term the Moral Sense. The phrase,
however, is repeatedly used by Shaffcesbuiy, whose
follower Hutcheson was. In the Inquvry concerning
Virtue we are told (p. 44), " Sense of right and wrong
being as natural to us as natural affection itself, and
being a first principle in our constitution and make,
there is no speculative opinion, persuasion, or belief,
which is capable immediately or directly to exclude or
desti-oy it." And this sense of right and wrong is
constantly, in the margin nt l e ast, termed, " The Moral
Sense."
As this phrase, and the faculty to which it is ap-
plied, have in more recent times become so celebrated,
perhaps it will be allowed me to lay before you
more particularly the manner in which the faculty
was described, when it was first, in its modem form,
brought into a prominent position in Ethics. Shaftes-
bury likens the natural sense of the right, to the
natural sense of the beautiful, which he assumes as
incontestable. "The mind," he remarks {Inquiry,
p. 39), "observes not only things, but actions and
affections. The mind which is thus spectator and
auditor of other minds cannot be without its eye and
ear; so as to discern proportion, distinguish sound,
and scan each sentiment or thought which comes before
it." He goes on to say that thus observing, it must
SHAFTESBURY, HUTCHESON, &C. II5
admire or condemn — "It finds a foul and a fair, a
harmonious and a dissonant, as really and truly here
as in musical numbers or visible forms. It cannot
■withhold its admiration and ecstasies, its aversion and
scorn. To deny the common and natural sense of a
sublime and beautiful, is," the noble ■writer pronounces,
"mere affectation. And as this is true of the natural,
so is it of the moral world. The heart at such a spec-
tacle cannot possibly remain neutral ; however false and
comapt it be, it judges other hearts. It mnst approve
in some measure ■what is natural and honest, and
disapprove ■what is dishonest and corrupt."
I shall not stop to show how this assumption of
such a Sense is employed by Shaftesbury in establish-
ing that ■which is the general Thesis of his Inquiry: —
that it is according to the private interest and good of
every one to work towards the general good; ■which
if a creature ceases to promote, he is actually so far
■wanting to himself, and ceases to promote his o^wn
happiness and ■welfare. I proceed to his foUo^wer,
Hutcheson'.
Francis Hutcheson -was the son of a djag^ting
minister in Ireland, and was educated at the Univer-
sity of Glasgow. His Inquiry into the Ideas of Bea/uty
and Virtue was much admired on its first appearance
(about 1727). In this work the author notes that
fundamental antithesis of moral systems which we
have all along kept in view. There are, he says, two
opinions entirely opposite, both intelligible, each con-
sistent ■with itself (pp. 207-211). The first of these
opinions is, that all actions flow from the prospect of
private happiness; the other which he opposes to this
is, that we have not only self-love, but benevolent
affections, and a moral sense. The moral sense he
iLord Shaftesbury, 16139, Iitmrnm amcemmg Virtm.
Dr F. Hutcheson, 1727, IngvAry mto the Ideas of Beauty and Virtue.
Dr Balguy, 1728, The FoundaMon of Moral Goodness.
Dr Butler, 1726, Sermons.
Wollaston, 1726, Meli^ion of Nature.
■Warburton, 1738, Dwime Legation.
Il6 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
describes as that -which determines us to approve the
actions which flow from the love of others.
It is evident that the Moral Sense here comes for-
ward as the main element on the side of independent
morality, and thus takes the place of the fitness, truth,
light reason, and other former strong-holds of that
school. But though the Moral S^se is thus substi-
tuted for the ancient EecSiuaePSEe things are very
far from being equivalent; and by this substitution,
the character of the controversy was very materially
altered.
It will perhaps best serve to show the nature of
this transition if we enquire how the new view was
looked upon by the remaining adherents of the old
realist school — those who maintained, with Clarke and
Cudworth, that the morality of actions consisted in
their conformity to Reason.
I have already noticed Balgiiy as a combatant in
the ranks of this now scanty host. He very soon pub-
lished a Eeply to Hutcheson's Inquiry, which he enti-
tled The Foundation of Moral Goodness, or A Fwrth&r
Inquiry into the original of our Idea of Vi/rPue (1728).
His objections to Hutcheson's system are mainly
these : — (i) That Virtue, according to the new doctrine,
depending entirely upon two Instincts, Benevolent
Aifection and the Moral Sense, becomes arbitrary and
insecure : (2) That brutes, since they have kind in-
stincts or affections, have, on these grounds, some
degree of Virtue : (3) That if these afiections constitute
Virtue, the Virtue must be the greater in proportion
as the affections are stronger; and that thus we contra-
dict the notion of Virtue which represents it as con-
troUiog the affections : (4) That Virtue is degraded by
being made a mere result of Instincts : (5) To these
are added some more peculiarly realist arguments ; as
(6) (p. 49) that, according to this view, we can attach
no meaning to the assertion that the Laws delivered
by God are holy, just, and good, since the standard of
goodness, which the theory sets up for man, cannot
apply to Him : and (7) that, according to the theory,
if God had not given us this benevolent instinct, we
SHAFTESBURY, HDTCHESON, &C. II7
should have been incapable of Virtue; and tliat on
that supposition, notwithstanding Intelligence, Reason,
and Liberty, it would have been impossible for us to
perform one action really good — a conclusion which
the adherent of the ClarHan school holds to be absurd.
The main force of these arguments as they apply
against the assertion of a Moral Sense, — and it is ia
fact a very weighty consideration, — resides in this :
that the doctrine of the Moral Sense, as delivered by
Hutcheson, represents that Sense as a mere Instiaot,
and thus takes Virtue out of the domain of the Reason.]
This, as was to be supposed, the disciple of Clarke
conceives to be a monstrous and degrading proceediug,
(p. 63). "To make the Rectitude of Moral Actions
dependent upon Instinct, and in proportion to the
warmth and strength of the Moral Sense, rise and fall
like spirits ia a thermometer, is depreciating the most
sacred thing in the world, and almost exposing it to
ridicule." Again (p. 58), "If virtue and the approbation
of virtue be merely instinctive, we must certainly think
less highly and less honourably of it than we should do
if we supposed it to be rational : for I suppose," he adds,
"it will be readily allowed that Reason is the nobler
principle." No, he ciies in another place (p. 46), "Let
virtue by all means be natural; but let it also be
necessary — Let it reign without a rival, but let its
throne be erected in the highest part of our nature."
It cannot be denied, as I have already intimated,
that there is great force and signification in this re-
monstrance. Beyond all doubt we do not rise to a
just idea of virtue except we represent it to ourselves
as a rational activity, not an instinctive impulse of our
nature. Instinct is blind, but Virtue must see her
object and be conscious of her purpose. She partakes
of the nature of Reason in the highest sense of the
term. Whatever be the source of the truth which
Virtue contemplates, it is a part of her office to con-
template truth; even to discover it when hidden; — ^to
bring it forth when obscure ;-^to combine principles ; —
to look to consequences ; — to conduct trains of demon-
stration;— to detect fallacies;— to expose sophistry.
Il8 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
If virtue be not a mere modification of the Reason, at
least she must be both reasooable and rational; con-
formable to right reason, capable of just reasoning.
It is true, as I have already remarked, the identi-
fication of Yixtue with Right Reason which had long
found favour in the eyes of moraKsts, was now dissolved
by the circumscription which the province of Reason
had undergone in modern times. Reason was now no
longer, at least no longer commonly, used to designate
aU the higher faculties of our nature. It no longer
included all by which the rational are superior to the
irrational creatures. Virtue was perhaps thus shut
out of the narrowed limits of mere Reason. Granted,
that this might be so ; but she was not by this driven
into the immeasurably inferior jurisdiction of Instinct.
If Virtue was not Right Reason, at least she was not
irrational. If she was not a mere system of clear
views, at least she was not a mere collection of blind
impulses.
Thus the moralists of Right Reason, the old Cud-
worthian school, had arguments of no small weight to
urge against the new assertors of the Moral Sense.
These latter moralists, actuated, unconsciously perhaps,
by a perception of the difficulties which the Realist
school had of late sufiered, in maintaining its old high
ground, had moved downwards, but had been by no
means cautious in the exact selection of their new
position ; and had not taken pains to adopt the most
unexceptionable phraseology to express their views.
The term Instinct, which exposed the system to such
glaring objections, had not been shunned by Hutcheson.
He says (Vol. i. p. 155) : "The true spring of virtue
is some determination of our nature to study the good
of others, or some instinct which influences us to the
love of others, as the moral sense determines us to
approve" certain actions. Even the term which was
employed as the most usual designation of the principle
thus spoken of, and which has now almost acquired an
established place as a technical term, the moral Sense,
was very far from being unexceptionable. In its wider
signification, no doubt, this term might be employed
SHAFTESBURY, HUTCHESON, &C. II9
to designate any mode of apprehending things and the
relations of things. Shaftesbury, the leader of this
school, had illustrated his Sense of right and -wrong,
by comparing it with the apprehension of beauty and
deformity j and thus had shown plainly enough that
he did not intend to suggest the analogy of the bodily
senses. But the Sense of Beauty was almost as much
a matter of controversy as the Sense of moral Bight; —
divided analysers and theorizers as much; — ^was the
subject of opinions as opposite, concerning its ultimate
foundation and genuine elements. In this, as in the
other subject, there were realists and nominalists, a
rational and a sensual school. Some maintained an
Independent Beauty, as some maintained an Inde-
pendent Morality ; but others held that the ideas of
Beauty were mere modifications of some agreeable im-
pressions or other, made originally upon the bodily
senses. This perception of Beauty, then, could be no
secure guide to a true understanding of the perception
of Eight and Wrong : the Beautiful was not a stable
and solid enough foundation to allow philosophers to
erect upon it the important structure of the Good. If
the Moral Sense could not be made clearer than this
analogy made, it, the theory of such a sense was vague
indeed ; and its form Ul fitted to bear the shock of
controversy.
To avoid this vagueness, the defenders of the exist-
ence of the Moral Sense inclined to giye more definite-
ness to the term by accepting the analogy which it
ofiered with the bodily senses. This course at first
seemed to offer some advantages. For instance, it
enabled them, when pressed for a definition of moral
right and good, to avail themselves of the Lockian
maxim that "Simple Ideas are incapable of defini-
tion ;" — ^that right and good were as undefinable as
whiteness and warmth; and were, notwithstanding,
like these others, real and clear ideas. But though
this answer might serve for the moment, it could
hardly render much service to the party who could
find none better. For who could steadily and calmly
maintain the existence of a sense which tells us
120 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
whether any given action is good and right, of the
same nature as the senses which tell us that snow
is white and cold? When the Theory of a Moral
Sense is presented to men in this form, it veiy natu-
rally calls forth their loudest opposition ; and indeed
is generally received with ridicule, if not with anger
and indignation, as implying a claim on the part of
its propounders to the possession of a Sense which
their neighbours have not : and this too precisely such
a Sense as apprehends superiority and inferiority of
the very highest kind.
Thus the assei-tors of the Moral Sense found it
very difficult to make good the intermediate position
between the higher and the lower schools of moralists,
into which they had thrown themselves, as the fortress
whence they were prepared to defend the cause of
genuine morality. The old champions of immutable
morality directed their antique artillery of Eight Rea-
sons and Eternal Relations upon the Moral Sense, as
too low, too blind, too arbitrary, too variable, too limit-
ed, to be the main element of vii-tue : while the sensual
school angrily assailed the fort on the other side, as
■ built upon their own foundaitions, and presuming to
tower above them with most arrogant and absurd pre-
tensions. The new moralists tried to occupy a posi-
tion between Reason and Sense, and upon this, the
advocates both of Sense and of Reason turned upon
them as foes. Their natural aUiance was doubtless
with the latter : for if Yirtue must belong either to
Reason or to bodily Sense, it is plain that her place
is in the domain of the former. Even if we take the
LocMan division of aU Ideas into those of Sensation
and those of Reflection, it cannot be doubted that the
Idea of Right and of Moral Good must derive its
existence -from Reflection, not from Sensation.
If all our conceptions and notions belong either
to Sense or to Reason, Virtue must be ranged either
in one division or the other. If, on the other hand,
Yirtue be neither a part of Sense nor of Reason, this
cannot be a complete division of the human feculties.
And this appears plainly to be the case, from the
SHAFTESBURY, HUTCHESON, &C. 121
course of the controversy which I have described. In
any rigorous sense of the terms, it was found impos-
sible to maintain either that Virtue was merely a result
of Reason, or a result of a Sense. And the two terms
had in modern times had a rigorous meaning given to
them. This had been the effect of the general pro-
gress of philosophy. Reason had been limited, Sense
had been definitely studied. Nor was it fitting to
undo what had thus been done, in order to get rid of
the difficulty about the Moral Sense. If metaphysics
have really become more precise, we must not attempt
again to throw the subject into confusion, for the pur-
pose of providing a temporary refuge for Morality. If
Sense and Reason have taken up fixed positions, and
Virtue cannot find a place with either of them, we
must seek one which is appropriate to her. If philo-
sophers have analysed man's intellectual being, and
ascertained that moral good does not derive its origin
from thence, we must analyse the remainder of his
being, and try if we can discover what the true source
of moral relations is.
We must do this, that is, if we can, and as soon as
we can. It is easy to say, "we must discover," but
this declaration of necessity does not necessarily lead
to discovery. It is easy to say, "we must analyse,"
but it is hard to analyse aright. If it be trae that in
recent times the Senses and the Intellect have been
more thoroughly studied, more completely dissected,
their structure and processes better determined than
had before been done; how much labour, how much
time, how much ability, how long a succession of per-
severing enquirers, each profiting by the labours of his
predecessors, has this progress required ! How little
can one man, one generation, perform in such a task !
If, after all the attempts to discover the true nature
and grounds of moral rectitude, we have the labour
to recommence, we can hardly hope that we shall be
permitted to see it completed.
But this is not so. It is far from being, true, in
the progress of knowledge, that after every failure we
must recommence from the beginning. Every faUure
122 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
is a step to success. Every detection of what is false
directs us towards what is true : every trial exhausts
some tempting form of error. Not only so; but
scarcely any attempt is entirely a failure; scarcely
any theory, the result of steady thought, is altogether
false; no tempting form of Error is without some
latent charm derived from Truth.
If we have learnt that the foundation of Morality
is not to be sought either in the Sense or in the In-
tellect, there is already something learnt. If the per-
ception of this foundation, though wrongly designated
as a Sense, be still a peculiar operation of our inward
being, we may perhaps apply to it a more suitable
designation. If we cannot teU what this perception
is, we may still perhaps be able to say what it does.
If we cannot assign to it an exact place in the human
constitution, we may stiU mark out, in some wider
manner, the region of human nature in which its
operations are carried on ; and may thus prepare the
way for a closer approximation at some future time.
We have seen some of the inconveniences which
the defenders of independent morality incurred by
designating by a special name, and attempting to de-
scribe with some exactness, the faculty which discerns
moral distinctions. But, as I have already mentioned,
there was another class of writers, who, aware perhaps
of the danger of entangling themselves in the defence
of a theory technically enunciated, contented them-
selves with asserting their docti-ines in general and
variable phraseology, so as to show that they did not
consider the truth of their system wrapt up in any one
or two special forms of expression. Of these writers
I must now speak.
Those who have asserted Independent Morality
without introducing any technical name, like the
Moral Sense, of the eighteenth century, or the Boni-
form . Faculty of the seventeenth, have always been
a numerous party among divines and moralists. With
them the word Gonscience has always been a favourite
term to describe this power and its operations. But
how far they were, by the use of such a term, from
SHAFTESBURY, HUTCHESON, &C. 1 23
propounding any precise theory concerning its nature,
and from pretending to decide concerning its character,
as innate or acquired, original or derived, simple or
complex, is easily seen by looking at the controversies
which took place on these subjects. Thus the school-
men disputed whether conscience be an A ct, a Habit,
or a Power. Sanderson, in his treatise de Conscientice
Ohligatione, examines in a very acute and satisfactory
manner the arguments on the various sides of this
question, and decides that Conscience is something
intermediate between an acquired habit and a true
power; and hence he prefers to call it a Faculty, which
appears to him to be a term in some measure appli-
cable in common to habits and powers. It will easily
be understood that such discussions as this, though
they may not terminate in any intellectual theory so
precise as those of modem times, still proceed upon
some view then current of the constitution and parts
of man's nature ; and perhaps we may be allowed to
say, that the portions into which the human mind was
resolved by the philosophy of that and of preceding
times, were in many respects as well made out and as
clearly established as the elements which are presented
to us by modem systems. The mind of man contained
the Understanding, the Passions, and the Will ; and
the Understanding was considered as the Speculative
and the Practical Understanding. This division, then,
being admitted, the Conscience was defined by Sander-
son to be (p. 13) "a Paculty or Habit of the Practical
Understanding, by which the mind, through discourse
of reason, applies the light which is in it to its own
particular acts." And this view was accepted so widely
among divines that we may consider it as prevailing,
except when it was interfered with by bolder theories,
up to the time of Butler, whom I am of course led to
take as the representative of the Unsystematic Moral-
ists, at the time when the system-makers propounded
tHe theory of the Moral Sense.
I will only illustrate what I have said by a single
example, which may serve to show in a striking man-
ner the functions and character ascribed to Conscience
124 HISTORY OF MOKAL PHILOSOPHY.
during the prevalence of these views. In a Sermon of
South's on the Image of God, he makes it his business
to describe man with the glorious attributes which he
possessed before his PaU from his original brightness.
The description of the faculties and powers of man in
that primary condition is, of course, a representation
of all that was conceived most consummate and com-
plete, both in the faculties and in their relation to
each other. The preacher passes in review the various
parts of the mind such aa I have just stated them;
he says on the siibject now before us, such things as
these :
" The Image of God was no less resplendent in that
which we call Man's Practical Understanding, namely
that storehouse of the Soul in which are treasured up
the Eules of Action and the Seeds of Morality :" and
after speaking of the notions which reside in this pro-
vince of the soul, he adds, " It was the privilege of
Adam innocent, to have these notions also firm and
untainted, to carry his monitor in his bosom, his law
in his heart, and to have such a conscience as might
be its own casuist. Reason was his tutor, and First
Principles his Magna Moralia — the Decalogue of
Moses was but a transcript, not an original — all the
laws of nations or wise decrees of states, the Statutes
of Solon and the Twelve Tables, were but a paraphrase
upon this standing rectitude of nature ; Justice," that
is, as it appears by his context, the internal principle
of Justice, "was not subject to be imposed upon by
a deluded fency, nor yet to be bribed by a globing
appetite, for an Utile or Jucuridium, to turn the balance
to a false or dishonest sentence. In all its directions
to the inferior faculties it conveyed its suggestions
with deamess and enjoined them with power ; it had
the passions in perfect subjection; and though its com-
mand over them was biit suasive and political, yet it
had the force of coactive and despotical. It was not
then as it is now, when the conscience has only power
to disapprove, and to protest against the exorbitances
of the passions, and rather to wish than make them
otherwise. The yoice of conscience now is low and
SHAFTESBURr, HUTCHESON, &C. 1 25
weak, cHastising the passions as old Eli did his lustful
domineering sons : IT^ot so, m/y sons, not so : but the
voice of conscience then was not, this should, or this
ought to he done; but this mMst, this shall be done.
It spoke like a legislator; the thing spoken was a law:
and the manner of speaking it a new obligation. In
short, there was as great a disparity between the prac-
tical dictates of the understanding then and now, as
between empire and advice, counsel and command,
between a companion and a govei-nor."
It would be easy to select other passages containing
similar representations of the functions and authority
of conscience, in writers of the period of which I now
speak (the early part of the eighteenth century); al-
though they become more rare as the systematic repre-
sentations of morality as founded on pleasure and pain
on the one side, and on a peculiar moral sense on the
other, encroach upon the old more natural and fami-
liar modes of representing man's moral nature. It
would be easy, also to adduce other forms of expression
employed by unsystematic writers to designate the
powers, habits, faculties, and acts of man's nature by
which he judges of his own deeds and affections. But
enough has probably been said to show that the old
opinions concerning the fiinctions, duties, and autho-
rity of that part of man's nature in which his moral
principles reside, the opinions which we noted as ap-
pearing in the earliest writers whom we had to quote,
still existed and continued to animate a considerable
portion of our literatui'e, till the time of Butler, or
at least till within a very short interval of that time.
Butler then I look upon as the successor of the
unsystematic writers on morals. He took the phraseo-
logy of the subject as he found it in use among those
who wrote on morals for practical purposes, and he
abstained, studiously as it might appear, from giving
an exclusive or constant preference to any one of them.
In this way he obtained some advantages, but also
incurred some inconveniences; and these must now
be considered by us.
LECTURE VIII.
Butler. Shaptesbukt. Waebtteton. Berkeley.
TmDAL. Balgut.
THE view wliicli I have given of the progress ht
ethical speculation in England has brought us to
Butler. I have already attempted in some measure
to point out the place which he occupies in reference
to the different schools of morahsts. The controversy
which had divided philosophers from the time of Plato,
between the higher and the lower moralists, had as-
sumed various aspects. At first it was the opposition
of Ideas and Sense ; — of Ideas, the principles of eternal
tiniths, not derived from the material world ; and of
Sense, which supplied to man manifest undeniable
material good. The reign of a purer rehgion had for
fifteen hundred years suppressed the sensual doctrine ;
but at the end of that time. Sense began vigorously
to reassert its claims, as the source at least of lich
stores of natural knowledge j and the reverence for
Ideas began to waver. When this struggle was car-
ried into Ethics, at first the supporters of Ideas put
them forth in their ancient form, as the foundations
of Eternal and Immutable Eelations : but it appeared
that in this shape, they were no longer well suited
to resist the new philosophy of Sense, flushed as it
was with triumphs obtained in the natural world.
Many moralists, no longer confiding in Ideas, in the
necessary relations and fitnesses of things, sought to
balance the morality founded upon mere bodily Sense,
by a morality founded upon a principle, nominally
indeed a Sense, but really an element opposed to sense
— a Sense of the moral beauty and goodness of actions
UNSYSTEMATIC MORALISTS. 1 27
as a peculiar quality. These asserfcors of the Moral
Sense became the systematic oppcments of the sensual
school ; or, using a term less obnoxious, of those who
derived all morality of actions from the consideration
of resulting pleasure and pain. But the common feel-
ings of mankind, which have in all ages recognized
right and wrong, good and evil, as something different
from agreeable and disagreeable, from gain and loss,
caused the adherents of independent morality to be a
much larger body than the school who thus undertook
their defence in this technical manner. Many persons
admired the beauty of virtue, and felt the obligation
of duty, who did not know, or could not be persuaded,
that they did this by means of a peculiar Moral Sense.
There were many who thought that their moral con-
stitution was more truly represented by the ancient
and familiar phrases, than by this new theory of a
Moral Sense. These I have termed the Unsystematic
Moralists. They asserted, or assumed without assert-
ing, the existence of a power of moral judgment ; but
they did not pretend to separate this from other powers
in any exact manner. Some separation of the human
powers, indeed, is involved in the very language which
describes them. Such differences as those of the Head
and the Heart, the Understanding and the Reason,
the Passions and the WUl, are familiar to all men ;
and among such terms, the Conscience implied a prin-
ciple as real and distinguishable as any other. And
phrases even implying more of positive classification
had found very general acceptance, as when the moral
actions of man were ascribed to the Rational Principle,
or to the Practical Understanding. By the progress
of thought, — by the increased liabits of mental analysis
fostered by the general circumstances of human know-
ledge, and infused into the minds of all men by the
contagion of society and the very use of language, — ■
even unsystematic thinkers were compelled to take a
more systematic view than they had hitherto done, of
the constitution and provinces of the human mind;
and hence those who were convinced that they could
perceive moral distinctions as something peculiar and
128 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHT.
of their ovsm nature, must also believe that they pos-
sessed a faculty, hcwever it was to be described, how-
ever to be derived, by which they apprehended such
distinctions.
To assert the existence of a Moral Faculty more
clearly and positively than had yet been done, without
incumbering himself with too systematic a description
or definition of its nature, was the merit of Butler, at
the period when Hutoheson was publishing his as-
sertion of the Moral Sense. All truths are seen dimly
before they are seen clearly ; — arfe conveyed in a vague
and confused shape before they are expressed in a
definite and lucid form. The analysis of bodies into
their elements employed many generations, and was
for centuries most obscurely and imperfectly appre-
hended ; and yet, during these centuries, philosophers
were travelling towards the truth, and were at every
point obtainiag positive truths of great importance.
The analysis of the mind, like the analysis of matter,
may be imperfect, and yet valuable. It is no proof
of an absence of worth and importance in the doctrine
of a Moral Faculty, that at first, the boundaries of
such a Faculty seem vague, and even its indepen-
dence questionable. It is of far more importance to
prove the reality of its office, and to show that its
existence gives a consistent and satisfactory account
of those moral rules and convictions which the doc-
trine of consequences cannot explain.
In order to do this without making any super-
fluous assumption, Butler appears purposely to have
shunned any appearance of technical names for the
elements of our moral constitution on which he specu-
lated ; and to have studiously varied his phrases. Thus
he speaks of mamls hdng a law to Mnhself; of a dif-
ference in hind among maris principles of action, as
well as a difference of strength; of an internal con-
stitution in which conscience has a natural and right-
ful supremacy; along with other forms of expression.
But the course thus taken by Butler had incon-
veniences as well as advantages. Clarke adopted the
received and metaphysical phraseology of Ms times, ..
BUTLEK. 129
•which, so far as moral philosophy was concerned, -was
not ■well adapted for tracing out his doctrines in a
forcible an.d clear manner. Butler avoided this error ;
but was, in this manner, constantly driven to peri-
phrastic and indirect modes of expression which blunt
the point and obscure the aim of his reasonings. Hence,
though he lays down his arguments in a clear and or-
derly manner, in good plain language, and with suf-
ficient detail of steps and circumstances, he has always
been found, by common readers, a difficult and obscure
writer. And this was the opinion entertained of him
in his own time by men of the world. " The bishop
of Durham," says Horace Walpole, " had been wafted
to that see in a cloud of metaphysics, and remained
absorbed in it."
Joseph Butler, of whom I speak, was educated for
the ministry of the dissenters, but was brought over
to the episcopal church by his conviction of its valid
claims. When yet young, and unknown, the interest
which he took in speculations such as those of Clarke,
had led him to enter into a correspondence with that
divine, in which he displayed great acuteness and
ability. This correspondence is published at the end
of the later editions of the Discourse on the Beimg and
Attributes o/Gfod. Butler soon after became Preacher
at the RoUs Chapel (in 17 18), and his sermons preached
there were published a few years later. It is in these
sermons particularly that his moral doctrines are to
be found.
So much has been said in recent times of Butler's
place among the English writers on moral philosophy,
that it is the less necessary at present to dwell upon
that subject ; the more especially, as my object in the
present course of lectures is, not to discuss and decide
questions such as that of the Moral Faculty, but to
give an historical sketch of the steps of the great con-
troversy carried on in England concerning the arbi-
trary or necessary nature of moral truth.
I will only make two or three remarks. In the
first place, I observe that Butler does really and effect-
ively assert the principles which are the foundation of
9
I30 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
Independent Morality, more decidedly than he may at
first reading be thought to do ; his assertions being,
as I have said, somewhat blunted, and apparently
mitigated, by the generality of the language which he
uses, and by his avoidance of technical terms. That
he really does rest his moral system upon ideas, al-
together distinct from consequences, will appear when
we recollect how sedulously he insists upon the pro-
positions, that among our principles of action there is
a difierence of Tdnd as well as a difference of degree ; —
that to certain of our faculties belongs, by their nature,
an authority and supremacy above others, and that
this appears by a mere contemplation of the ideas
of those faculties. Thus, when he puts the question
(Serm. II.) " Which is to be obeyed, appetite or re-
flection ?" he replies (p. 4 1), " "Would not the question
be intelligibly and fully answered by saying that the
principle of reflection or conscience, being compared
with the various appetites, passions, and affections in
man, the former is manifestly superior and chief, with-
out regard to strength, and how often soever the latter
happen to prevail it is mere usurpation ? The former
remains in nature superior, and every instance of such
prevalence of the latter is an instance of breaking in
upon and violation of the constitution of man."
These notions so steadily adhered to, — of a differ-
ence of kind \ a peculiar constitution of man in which
each faculty and motive principle has its place ; a
nature which determines what ought to be as well as
what is ; relations which are seen and apprehended
as manifest by contemplation of the conceptions which
they involve, — are the proper characters of the school
of Independent Morality, and show how justly Butler,
notwithsta^iding some vagueness, and perhaps some
vacillation of expression, is taken as one of the prin-
cipal ||fiIosophers who have upheld that side of the
great antithesis of opinion on the foundations of morals.
There is another principle repeatedly employed by
Butler, and which is, I think, worthy of more notice
than has been given to it in general. In his view of
the constitution of man, he considers the various
BUTLER, 131
affections and passions which belong to this constitu-
tion, not only as actual parts of our nature, which we
must govern and control as virtue directs, but also
as elements inserted by our Creator with peculiar
purposes, and for definite moral ends; and he conceives
that we may discover what is the true regulation of such
affections by tracing the moral purpose which they are
fitted to answer. Thus he says (p. 35), "Since' then
our inward feelings, and the perceptions we receive
from our external senses, are equally real ; to argue
from the former to human life and conduct is as little
liable to exception, as to argue from the latter to
absolute speculative truth. A man can as little doubt
that his eyes were given him to see with, as he can
doubt the truth of the science of Optics, deduced from
ocular experiments. And allowing the inward feeling,
shame, a man can as little doubt whether it was given
him to prevent his doing shameful actions as he can
doubt whether his eyes were given him to guide his
steps'."
Butler pursued this view of the irascible part of
our nature somewhat further. He distinguished
Eesentment, the name by which he describes this
element, into sudden Eesentment, which is given us as
a Protector which acts with energy before Reflection
has time to rouse herself into action, and whose office
is to repel harm, without regard to its being wrong
as well as harm; — and settled Resentment, which is
naturally directed against vice and wickedness. "The
one stands in our nature for self-defence, the other for
the administration of justice." It is by considerations
such as these that the Idea, which at first appears so
wide and barren, of a certain undefined Constitution of
man, is traced by Butler into special moral duties. The
proper office of each of the principles of our nature
1 We may recollect that the same
train of thought has already come
before us in previous writers on this
side; as in the case of Henry More,
whom we have seen adopting the
Platonic notion that appetite pro-
vides for the needs of man's nature
and anger for its defence, both in
subservience to the governing power
of reason.
9—2
132 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
assists Tis also to determine their limits, and to
lay down rules for their direction, control, or re-
straint.
I have already observed that while, among the
defenders of Independent Morality, Clarke, in stating
his moral opinions, entangled himself by adopting the
terms of the prevalent metaphysical system, Butler
too often perplexed his readers by trying to avoid all
systematic metaphysics. But this mode of treating
the subject does not answer the needs of those who
pursue it as a speculative study. For short technical
expressions, when they are familiar to us, enable us to
avoid much labour of the intellect which we must
otherwise incur ; and to fix our attention at once upon
the critical part of each proposition and argument.
If there shall be found to be introduced afterwards a
technical classification of the faculties and operations
of the human mind, which shall be consistent with
the truths asserted by Butler, the business of under-
standing his arguments will be much simplified. We
may conceive that, in his enquiries, he was doing that
which, in fact, discoverers always have to do. They
search at the same time for true propositions and for
precise definitions. Each of these elements depends
upon the other ; they are found at the same time, and
approximated to by the same degrees. Men go on
towards moral as they go on towards physical truth.
The proposition that the planets are directed by a
central force, became more and more certain, as the
conception of a central force became more and more
clear. We have already compared Cudworth to Kep-
ler, who was confident there was such a force, yet
most vague and loose in his description of it : perhaps
not even Butler can be compared with Newton, who
laid down the law of this force with complete evidence,
and traced it to its remotest effects. He rather
resembles BoreUi or Wren or Huyghens, who referred
this force to its true center, and saw with entire con-
viction the certainty of its operation, but wavered
from one form of expression to another in their de-
scription o'f its nature; and though they asserted its
BUTLER.
133
existence, did not lay down its law in words, nor
draw out a system of its consequences.
Of the three principles of morality included in the
Syncretism of 'Ny^arburton, Eight Keason — the Moral
Sense — and Divine Command, we may now consider the
third ; which brings us nearer to the domain of Theology.
I have hitherto considered Butler and his con-
temporaries (for, as I have said, Hutcheson's Inquiry
and Butler's Sermons were published about the same
time') merely as moralists; as employed in determiaing
the fouudatiomi of natural morals ; — ^the principles of
human conduct according to mere philosophy. But
we shall not be able to understand the true bearing of
the speculations of this time, and the causes which
affected the fortunes of the subject in its next shape,
without taking a survey of these speculations from
another point of view ; without considering what bear-
ing Morality, according to the systems which were in
currency at the time of which I speak, had upon
E«ligion ; — how men's views of their duties in this
life were connected with their eternal hopes.
The system of Clarke, according to which Morality
is derived by rigorous deduction from right reason,
and the doctrine of the Shaftesbury school, that virtue
is the object of a peculiar Sense or Taste, each gave to
virtue a kind of independence, which seemed to make
extraneous support superfluous. And hence the ene-
mies of revealed religion saw with pleasure, and its
friends with pain, the probability of an attack upon it
from this side ; which accordingly took place. I have
already said that Shaftesbury had been looked upon,
and we must regret to say, with incontestable justice,
as an enemy of Christianity ^ Not only did his view
of the differences of actions, as founded upon inhe-
i-ent qualities, and perceived by a peculiar sense, make
his Morality independent of Divine Command in its
1 Butler's Sermons, 1726; Hutche-
son's Inquiry, tMrd edition, 1729 ;
the Dedication, to.the second edition,
is dated 1725.
2 This is regretted by his ad-
•mirer Hutcheson. Predace to Inr
qwvry.
134 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHT.
foundations, but he seemed unwillingly to admit a
Divine Judgment into his scheme. It is true, that
he often spoke of the Supreme Being and his govern-
ment in a manner far from unseemly, Thus he says,
(Inquiry, p. 56), " If there be a belief or conception of
a Deity, who is consider'd as worthy and good, and
admir'd and reverenc'd as such ; being understood to
have, besides mere power and Imowledge, the highest
excellence of Nature, such as renders him justly
amiable to all ; and if in the manner this Sovereign
and mighty Being is represented, or, as he is histo-
rically described, there appears in him a high and
eminent regard to what is good and excellent, a con-
cern for the good of all, and an affection of Benevolence
and Love towards the whole ; such an example must
undoubtedly serve (as above explain'd) to raise and
increase the affection towards Virtue, and help to
submit and subdue all other affections to that alone."
And to the influence of the Honour and Love which
we must bear to such a Being, he adds the influence of
a persuasion of his constant Presence. And again,
" When the Theistical belief (his technical expression
for the belief in a God) is intire and perfect (p. 57),
there must be steady opinion of the superintendenoy
of a Supreme Being, a witness and spectator of human
life, and conscious of whatsoever is felt or acted in the
universe : so that in the perfectest recess, or deepest
solitude, there must be One still presum'd remaining
with us; whose presence singly must be of more
moment than that of the most august assembly on
earth. In such a presence, 'tis evident, that as the
shame of guilty actions must be the greatest of any;
so must the honour be of well-doing, even under the
unjust censure of a world. And in this case, 'tis very
apparent how conducing a perfect Theism must be to
virtue, and how great deficiency there is in Atheism."
And he allows that a belief in a future state of re-
ward and punishment may support and preserve a man
wavering between right and wrong ; may even restore
and repair the moral constitution when by evil practice
it has been debauched and perverted (p. 61) ; and may
BUTLER. 135
make virtue, wliicli was at first pursued for its conse-
quences, to be loved for its o-wn sake (p. 62). " In the
same manner, wkere instead of regard or love, there is
rather an aversion to what is good and virtuous, (as,
for instance, where lenity and forgiveness are despis'd,
and revenge highly thought of and beloVd) if there be
this consideration added, 'That lenity is, by its rewards,
made the cause of a greater self-good and enjoyment
than what is found in revenge ; ' that very affection
of lenity and mildness may come to be industriously
nourish'd, and the contrary passion depress'd. And
thus Temperance, Modesty, Candour, Benignity, and
other good affections, however despised at first, may
come at last to be valu'd for their own sakes, the con-
trary species rejected, and the good and proper object
belov'd and prosecuted, when the reward orjpunishment
is not so much as thought of"
But this was so grudgingly allowed, so limited with
conditions, and balanced with attendant dangers, that
it was hardly to be wondered at that those who had
trained their minds to think it man's duty to do all with
reference to his great Master and Judge, were dissatis-
fied, and found that the language of the Characteristics
was harsh and dissonant to their feelings. Of this we
may take as an example the expressions of Bishop
Berkeley, a man allowed by all his contemporaries of
all parties to be one of the most amiable of men. In
his Vindication of his Theory of Vision, p. 5, he says,
" What availeth it in the cause of Virtue and Natural
Eeligion, to acknowledge the strongest traces of wisdom
and power, throughout the structure of the universe,
if this wisdom is not employed to observe, nor this
power to recompense our actions; if we neither believe
ourselves accountable, nor God our Judge ?
"All that is said of a vital principle of Order,
Harmony, and Proportion; all that is said of the
natural decorum and fitness of things ; all that is said of
taste and enthusiasm, may well consist and be supposed,
without a graia even of Natural Religion, without any
notion of Law or Duty, any belief of a Lord or Judge,
" any religious sense of a God ; the contemplation of
136 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
the miad upon the ideas of Beauty, and Virtue, and
Order, and Fitness, being one thing, and a sense of
Religion another. So long as we admit no principle
of good actions but Natural Affection, no reward but
Natural Consequences ; so long as we apprehend no
judgment, harbour no fears, and cherish no hopes of a
future state, but laugh at all these things, with the
author of the Cha/racterisiics, and those whom he
esteems the Uberal and polished part of mankind, how
can we be said to be religious in any sense ? Or what
is here that an Atheist may not find his account in, as
well as a Theist ? To what moral purpose might not
Fate or Nature serve as well as a Deity, on such a
scheme ? And is not this, at bottom, the amount of
aU those fair pretences' ?"
Sir James Mackintosh in speaking of this passage
(History of Ethics, p. 158) says, that here "this most
excellent man sinks for a moment to the level of a
railing polemic." But this expression is, I think it
must be allowed, far too strong. How adverse the
influence of Shaftesbury had been to the real belief
in religion, was well and generally known. And no
thoughtful Christian could be ignorant how baseless
and hollow is a scheme of rules for human conduct
which has no sanction beyond the beauty of virtue,
and the existence of a moral sense. However much
such a sense may aid us in discovering the rules of our
duty, and even our relation to the Supreme Legislator
and Judge, it is only when its indications are pursued
in that upward direction, that we obtain such pro-
spects as are requisite to support and animate us in
our progi-ess. We may have such faculties, such a
sense if you will, as is sufficient to enable us to find
our way through the wilderness; but except this is
accompanied with a firm belief ia the beauty of the
promised land, our wanderings may stiU be devious,
perverse and interminable. It was natural that Chris-
tian divines should grieve to see the internal light
1 Berkeley, Theory of Vision, p. z. (1733).
SHAFTESBUKT. TINDAL, 1 37
whicli exists in. the mind of man employed to bewilder
instead of direct him ; — spoken of as if it were the
end not the gidde of this path ; — as if he had to walk
to it not hy it.
But the Clarkian school, sincere and earnest Chris-
tians themselves, had no less, as I have already in-
timated, opened the way to a similar attack. It is
true, that there was a broad difference between them
and the school of Moral Instinct. For the Eternal
Reasons which made things right and wrong in the
eyes of all reasonable creatures when they were guided
by their reason, could be no other than the Eea-
sons which determined the Divine Will ; and therefore
regulated the Divine Commands. And thus, there
was, in this scheme, a necessary coincidence between
the Morality of Reason and the Commands of God.
And thus, the judgment of right and wrong were
not, in their scheme, the results of an instinct, taste,
or sense, which contained no indication of a deeper
ground, and higher sanction.
But then, this very identification of Reason and
Command was urged by others as rendering one of the
two superfluous. The opportunity of pressing the at-
tack on this ground was taken by Dr Matthew Tindal,
a Fellow of AU Souls' College, Oxford, who had all his
life been known as a writer against the Church of
England and her Clergy, but who in 1730, at an ad-
vanced age, published a work in which all revelation
was aimed at. The title of the book was Christianity
as old as the Creation. Tindal's two principal works
against the Church and against Morals are referred to
by Pope :
But art thou one, whom new opinions sway,
One who believes as Tindal leads the way,
Who Virtue and a Church alike disowns.
Thinks that but words, and this but bricks and stones?
Fly then, on aU the wings of wild Desire,
Admire whate'er the maddest can admire.
His professed object was to show that Christianity,
being the external revelation of the will of God, must
138 HISTORY OF MOEAL PHILOSOPHY.
agree with natural religion, which, is the internal reve-
lation of the same will ; and the inference which was
insinuated was, that Christianity is needless and use-
less; the original law and religion of nature being so
perfect that nothing can he added to it by any sub-
sequent external revelation.
I have said that this attack was in some measure
occasioned by the doctrines which Dr Clarke had re-
cently published. Accordingly an argument founded
upon these was urged in the work, and was by some
supposed to have a formidable aspect. Balguy, whom
I have already mentioned as a supporter of Clarke's
views, wrote an answer to Tindal, entitled A Second
Letter to a Deist (iloB first letter to a Deist was the
answer to Shaftesbury) concerning a late hook entitled
' Christianity as old as the Creation,' more pa/rticularly
that chapter which relates to Dr Clarke. In this letter,
it appears that Balguy's correspondent had proposed
to him divers questions on the subject of Tindal'a
book: one of which was, "Has not the author, in his
last chajiter, plainly proved Dr Clarke inconsistent
with himself : and that one part of his Lectures clashes
with another?" The contradiction is, that the Law
of Nature is asserted to be complete, and again as-
serted to be insufficient; and to this the author an-
swers very triumphantly : " In setting forth the obli-
gations of morality, Dr Clarke everywhere speaks of
the Law of Nature in the highest and most advan-
tageous terms. He considers it as arising necessarily
and invariably from the true natures, reasons, and
relations of things. He represents it as a system of
eternal, universal, and unchangeable truths ; as a per-
fect Eule of Action; as a Law independent of, and
antecedent to, all other laws and obligations whatever.
He declares, that all rational creatures are obliged
to govern themselves, in all their actions, by the
eternal Rule of Reason; and that it is not only a law
to creatures, but to God himself, who is pleased to
make it the unalterable rule of his actions in the go-
vernment of the world. These, and many other decla-
rations of the like nature, are made by Dr Clarke;
TINDAL. BALGUT. 1 39
and some of them are quoted at large by your author
in the fore-mentioned chapter.
"Has then Dr Clarke advanced anything after-
wards in contradiction hereto t Has he anjrwhere
denied the truth or perfection of this sacred rule 1
Has he, in any part of his book, expressed himself
in derogation from it, or diminution of it ? Not one
syllable can I find to any such purpose. What then
has he done 1 "Why, he has brought a charge against
mankind, of ignorance, negligence, perverseness, stu-
pidity. He has a£5rmed, that they are such weak,
frail, corrupt creatures, that sometimes they cannot,
and, very often, will not understand, of themselves,
what belongs to their duty. He has represented men,
even the wisest of them, as in^dncibly ignorant, with-
out Revelation, of some points of the utmost conse-
quence. And as to the generality, he has shown, that
they stand in need, upon many accounts, of more light,
and better instruction, than either their own reason,
or that of the ablest philosophers, could ever afford
them. Whether these be facts, or mistakes, I desire
to know where lies the inconsistency ? On the one
hand, we find excellent truths; a complete rule; a
most Divine law: on the other hand, men corrupt;
faculties neglected; understandings depraved. I have
brought these doctrines close together, to give you.
Sir, a fairer opportunity of discovering that opposition
which your author pretends to find between them.
But who can find it besides himself? Will any man
say, that the reality, or perfection of a rule, depends
upon the skill or disposition of the agent? Can the
eternal truth and reason of things be disannulled, or
any way altered,- by the ignorance or frowardness of
mankind ? Why then so much pains taken to bring
in Dr Clarke as an evidence against himself? Why
so many passages produced, in order to prove that he
had often ^aid, what, indeed, he always said, and never
once denied'?"
1 £algU7, p. Sg6.
140 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
Balgiiy adds (p. 277) another illustration to retort
the edge of the argument, that the law of nature is
perfect, that all men are capable of discovering it,
and that therefore the Gospel is not needed. "Let it
be granted," he says, " that temperance and exercise
constitute a complete rule of health, and that aU men
are capable of discovering this. Does it then foUow
that physic and physicians are useless ?" And thus it
is that the completeness of the moral rule, even if it
be complete, only proves more entirely how much our
human nature requires something more than a rule.
The end of our Ethics conducts us to the beginning
of our Gospel The place which the rules of morality
hold in aU sound systems of the philosophy of man,
is that which St Paul assigns to them. The wrath
of God is revealed against all unrighteousness and un-
godliness of men; but stiU these men hold this truth,
this revelation of conscience, in unrighteousness; and
thus it becomes necessary that the Gospel Revelation
should supply the needs which the revelation of Con-
science only discovers. The Gentiles have a law in
their hearts, as the Jews have on the tables of stone;
but what is the place which this great doctrine holds
in the high argument into which the apostle intro-
duces it ? Neither more nor less than this, to prove,
of Jews and of Gentiles alike, that they are all under
sin.
Thus the systems of ethics which found morality
upon original and independent principles, not deducing
our rules of action from commands and consequences
merely, but assigning to them an inherent and es-
sential value, do not in any way really trench upon
the domains of religion, or interfere with the teaching
of Christianity. Tet the pain and controversy occa-
sioned by such attacks as that of which I have spoken,
even when successfully resisted and repelled, seem to
have been among the motives which induced divines
first to combine the other principle of morality with
this one of the divine command, which, as I have al-
ready stated, was done by Warburton in 1738, and a
little later, to resign, or at least to cease to put for-
TINDAL. BALGUT. I4I
■ward, as any essential part of their principles of mo-
rality, the Clarkian tenets of eternal relations, and the
like. The form of Morals which thus became preva-
lent in this country must now be the subject of our
consideration.
LECTUEE IX.
"Wabburton. Law. Jackson. Etjtheefokth.
■WATEKLAin).
WARBURTON, as I have said, attempted to
combine, in his view of the true foiindations of
morality, the three principles of Right Reason, the
Moral Sense, and the Divine Command. But in doing
this, he did not avoid the objections which lie against
each, as I must briefly show.
1. By speaking of the Moral Sense as an Instinct
(following Hutcheson, as we have seen), he has put the
assertion of such a sense in the most obnoxious and
objectionable form. When asserted in this shape, it
is difficult or impossible to find any unquestionable
proofs of its existence. It is difficult to discover any
instincts which are moral, or which cannot be resolved
into such as are not moral; — which cannot be traced
into such instincts as are subservient to self-preserva-
tion; or such as those by which families are formed
and held together. "When the moral sense is asserted
in this form, separate from all reflex operation of the
mind, or rational insight into the connexions and mo-
tives of actions, the usual arguments so often brought
against its existence assume a very formidable front,
and can hardly be opposed by any satisfactory replies,
without, in some measure, changing the ground of the
controversy.
2. The doctrine of essential difierences in things,
apprehended by the Reason alone, does not establish
a genuine moral character of actions, as I have already
observed in speaking of Clarke's view of morality.
WARBPBTON. I 43
Whatever of fitness or unfitness for certain ends, of
agreement or disagreement with certain ideas, there
be in this or that course of willing or acting, the dis-
covery of these relations does not give an aspect of
moral good or evil to actions, except it be conjoined
with a sentiment of approval or disapproval, which it
is not one of the functions of the Reason, strictly un-
derstood, to give. By adopting, as one element of his
system, this doctrine of difierences apprehended by
the Reason, when the term reason was understood of
the intellect only, Warburton made a disadvantageous
a,Uiance. No succeeding writers on morals have been
able to develope the assertion of such difierences into
any thing of real value and strength.
3. Warburton thus made the assertion of the
moral sense too coarsely definite, and that of eternal
difierences too barely rational. This arose from his
separating too violently, from these elements, that
idea which gives them their moral character : and this
idea, thus injuriously insulated, he perverted. This
was the idea of Obligation. This idea is really in-
volved in the very conception of all moral rule and
moral relation. That is right which we ought to do.
If our moral faculty approves of a deed, we are under
an obligation to perform it. The obligation may be
evaded or disobeyed, but we cannot help recognizing
it, by the very mental act by which we recognize the
action as good. When our conscience tells us that we
do wrong, we can have no doubt that we have violated
an obligation.
This appears plain enough, but with this Warbur-
ton was not content. He laid it down as an axiom
{Dvv. Leg. B. i. Sect. iv. p. 141) that "Obligation ne-
cessarily implies an Obliger;" — that the will can only
be bound by an external Lawgiver. That the sanctions
of a Divine Government are necessary to induce cor-
rupted man to discharge the duties of Morality, we
shall all agree. But that, in metaphysical analysis,
there is no other basis of Obligation, appears to be
quite inconsistent with the best ideas we can apply
to the subject. We cannot but estimate actions as
144 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
right or -wrong; as what we ought and what we ought
not to do; as duties and crimes : and in this very esti-
mate, is involved an obligation to do and to abstain.
Who doubts that we are bound to tell the truth, to
observe compacts, without bringing into the Court of
Conscience an external power to punish intentional
falsehood and bad faith ? Does not the theory which
resolves Social Duties into a Social Compact ackuow-
ledge an original obligation in a Compact 1 That this
obligation is too weak for practical purposes, is not the
question: — at least not the question which concerns
us here, though it must be allowed that this considera-
tion had a material bearing upon the argument of
Warburton's book. But that the obligation did not
compel man's will, by no means showed that it was
not an obligation. The question concerning the nature
and foundation of moral rules must be treated on its
own ground : both for the sake of truth, and because,
without this, we lose that sublime testimony to the
Divine Government of the Universe which the Mo-
ral World, far more than the Natural, is capable of
bearing.
4. This notion of Obligation, however, was not
taken up gratuitously by Warburton, but for the pur-
poses of his argument, or at least in harmony with
those purposes. He had formed the project of placing
the Alliance between Morality and Eeligion on a new
basis. In the old form of the argument, it had been
urged in favour of Religion, that she distinctly teaches
that future retribution which Morality anticipates and
requires. But he inverted the argument, and stated
it thus ; — ^that Morality does indeed require a state of
Divine Government, and that therefore, if, while all
other Religions assume this as futwre, one does not,
such a Edigion must have been able to poiut to this
Divine Grovemment as present: and this he applied
to the ancient history of the Jewish Religion. And
having taken this course, not content with the con-
clusion at which mere human moralists had previously
arrived, that Morality requires and anticipates, and
renders probable, a future state of rewards and punish-
WAEBURTON. J45
nients; he ■would make the connexion still more rigor-
ous, so that all Moral Obligation should imply a Divine
Obligor, -who must be perceived as presiding at present,
if he were not taught as one who was to administer
justice in future.
5. It is due to Warburton, and to the subject, to
state, that however little we may be disposed to assent
to his argument in favour of the Divine Character of
the Jewish dispensation (as in fact I believe that cur-
gtiment has not been very generally assented to), his
representation of the relation between Natural and
Revealed Morality is really very instructive and valu-
able. He remarks (Book m. Sect. v. p. 536), that
previous writers had either tried to prove the reason-
ableness of Christianity, by showing that the best
pagan philosophers had arrived at moral rules and a
doctrine of future retribution approaching to those
which Christianity teaches: or else they have denied
to the pagans a knowledge of such doctrines, in order
to prove the necessiPy of revelation : — But that either
way the argument was capable of being reversed; the
infidel who ascribed these doctrines to the pagans,
inferring revelation to be unnecessary; and he who
could find no such truths in the conclusions of the
natural understanding, declaring Christianity to be
unreasonable. To both these views Warburton op-
poses his own. " The only view of antiquity which
gives a solid advantage to the Christian cause, is such
a one as shows natural reason to be clear enough to
perceive truth, and the necessity of its deductions when
proposed, but not generally strong enough to discover
it, or to draw right deductions from it." "Having
of late seen," he afterwards says, "several excellent
treatises of morals, delivered on the principles of natu-
ral religion, which disclaim, or at least do not own,
the aid of Revelation, we are apt to think them, in
good earnest, the discoveries of natural reason; and
so to regard the extent of its powers as an objection to
the necessity of further light. The objection," he adds,
"is plausible; but sure there must be some mistake at
bottom; and the great difference in point of excellence!,
10
146 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
between these supposed productions of mere reason,
and those real ones of the moat learned ancients, will
increase our suspicion. The truth is (he continues),
these modem system-maters had aids, which, as they
do not acknowledge, so, I will believe they did not
perceive; and these aids were, the true principles of
religion, delivered by revelation: principles so early
imbibed, and so clearly and evidently deduced, thafe
they are now miistaken to be amongst our first and
most natural ideas: but those who have studied an-
tiquity, know the matter to be far otherwise."
He adds an illustration, drawn from the history of
science, which appears to be of a perfectly justifiable,
and very instructive nature, making some allowances.
"I cannot," he says, "better illustrate the state and
condition of the human view before revelation than
by the following instance. A summary of the Atomic
Philosophy is delivered in the Thesetetus of Plato : yet
being given without its principles, when Plato's writ-
ings at the revival of learning came to be studied and
commented upon, this summary remained absolutely
unintelligible; for there had been an interruption in
the successiou of that school for many ages ; and nei-
ther MarsiUus Ficinus nor Serranus could give any
reasonable account of the matter. But as soon," he
says, "as Descartes had revived that philosophy by
excogitating its principles anew, the mist removed,
and every one saw clearly (though Cudworth, I think,
was the first who took notice of it) that Plato had
given us a curious and exact account of that excellent
physiology. And Descartes was thought by some to
have borrowed his original ideas from thence; though
but for the revival of the atomic philosophy, that pas-
sage had still remained in obscurity. Just so," he
continues, " it was with respect to the powers of the
human mind. Had not revelation discovered the true
principles of religion, they had without doubt con-
tinued altogether unknown. Yet on their discovery,
they appeared so consonant to human reason, that
men were apt to mistake them for the production of
it."
■WARBURTON. 1 47
In our assent to this comparison, we must, as I
have said, make some allowances : — wo must recollect
the disposition which prevails, to believe that great
physical truths, even of the most recent discovery,
may be found anticipated in ancient authors of re-
nown; — we must recollect also the triumphant position
then occupied by the atomic theory, which at that
period had met with no check from men of science ;
and we must bear in mind the current admiration
for Descartes which even then had not faded away.
It is true in morals, not only as much, but very far
more than in physics, that the greatest truths, when
once promulgated, are profoundly persuasive and con-
vincing by their own evidence. It is true in morals,
as well as in physics, that truths which multitudes of
the most sagacious of men had laboured for ages with-
out discovering, when discovered, are held to be ob-
vious and self-evident. It is true, even in physics, that
we cannot analyse or explain the process by which
great discoveries suddenly dart their light over the
earth, truth taking the place of error, and knowledge,
once shed abroad, operating upon and modifying men's
thoughts without their being aware whence their new
and clear insight proceeds. So far we may perhaps,
with no irreverent feeling, assent to Warburton's com-
parison. But the burning up of the torch of science
from time to time is a most imperfect image of the
sunrise of the Gospel. The revolution of thought pro-
duced by the greatest discoveries is a very inadequate
representation, even so far as the rules and grounds of
morals only are considered, (which are all that we here
consider,) of the immeasurable improvement in man's
views of truth which the Christian revelation pro-
duced. Religion says, with regard to moral philoso-
phy, as well as with regard to man's relation to his
Master and Judge, "that which ye ignorantly believe
or blindly seek, that declare I unto you." But still
Religion recognizes the moral law, as a schoolmaster
whose previous training is a most valuable prepara-
tion and assistance to her own lessons. It is with
this training that my business liesj and it is of vast
10—2
T48 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
importance tliat the principles taught in this stage of
man's progress should be pure and true. I have at-
tempted to show how far this was the case at that
point of the history of the subject at which we have
now arrived. And I have endeavoured to make it
appear that, by separating the idea of Obligation from
Natural Morality, and by transferring it entirely to
the Divine commands and promises, natural morality
was deprived of its peculiar instruction, and incapaci-
tated from bearing the testimony which it so readily
and emphatically renders, when it is allowed to speak
freely to the perfections of God's character and the
holiness of his law.
I now purposely turn away, as the course of my
subject requires me to do, from the consideration of
revealed morality, to resume the history of the dis-
cussions concerning the natural foundations of our
duties.
Warburton's system naturally exercised a great
influence upon the theologians and moralists of this
country. His peremptory analysis of the idea of ob-
ligation into the commands of a superior, appeared to
simplify the subject, and was very generally accepted.
For it resolved that element of a moral law which,
though essential to it, requires a peculiar effort of
abstract thought, into an external condition, easily un-
derstood, and, as at first appeared, easily applied. This
therefore soon became the common foundation of mo-
rality among a large class of English moralists, and
particularly divines. It appears especially to have
found favour in this University.
Among the persons who inclined to such views
was Edmund Law, afterwards bishop of Carlisle, who
held the Professorship in virtue of which I am now
addressing you, from 1760 to 1769. He was previ-
ously a Fellow of Christ's College, in this University j
a college, as we have already seen, most fertile in mo-
ralists. His Notes on Archbishop King's Origin of
Evil were published (with his translation of the work)
in 1732, and therefore before the Divine Legation.
And accordingly he does not in these Notes go to the
LAW. JACKSON. 1 49
lengths of Warburton. He says that he does not place
the obligation of virtue in the mere will of God', "as
if his will were separated from his other attributes,"
which of itself, he owns, " would be no ground of ob-
ligation at all; since upon such a blind principle we
could never be secure of happiness from any being
how faithfully soever we resemble him in perfection :"
that is, I presume, except we should believe what is
demanded of us to be good, as well as com/manded, we
could not pursue it with any confidence or satisfaction.
But still he approached sufficiently near the notion
of a morality founded upon mere extraneous will, to
incur remonstrance on that ground. At the time of
which I speak, Clarke's work On the Being and At-
tributes of God had excited considerable controversy,
as among men of a metaphysical turn of mind it was
natural it should do: and Law had declared himself
against the validity of the argument there urged.
Those who defended the cogency of Clarke's reasoning,
were very naturally also disposed to adhere to his
views of morality as founded upon the essential re-
lations of things; and these they maintained, at least
so far as this, that they conceived that these relations,
perceived by the Divine Mind, determined the com-
mands which he had given to man. Among the per-
sons who on this ground opposed Law, was John
Jackson, Rector of Ropington in Yorkshire, and
Master of "Wigston's Hospital in Leicester. He pub-
lished, in 1734, 4 Vindication of Dr Clarke's Demon-
stration; and in 1735, A ftm-ther Vindication, in an-
swer to a Book by Law entitled. An Enquvry into the
Ideas of Space, Time, ImTnensity amd Eternity, as also
the Self-existence, Necessofry Existence, and Unity of
the Divine NaMure. I do not here meddle with this
celebrated argument, except so far as it bears on the
ground and obligation of Morality, which is the subject
of a Postscript to Jackson's First Vindication. He
there says, " The author of the Notes desires to know
1 Vol. n. p. 313.
150 HISTOET OF MOKAL PHILOSOFHT.
the precise meaning of the words Rectitude and Per-
fection of the Divine Nature, which I make to be the
ground of the Divine Acts. In answer, the author
of the thoughts may please to take my thoughts as
follows : The rectitude and perfection of the Divine
Nature which I make to be the ground of the DiTine
Acts, is the natural, essential, and perfect Intelligence
or Keason of the Divine Mind, that on which is founded
the unalterable disposition of God always to act ac-
cording to what he cannot but know is fit and right
in itself, or will naturally tend to the communication
of happiness to rational and moral agents." We here
see that the irremediable vagueness and emptiness of
the Clarkian notion of Fit and Eight, as apprehended
by reason alone, was driving his followers to lean upon
an object to which this fitness was subservient, namely,
the happiness of rational agents. This notion was no
doubt far more easily intelligible than a mere absolute
Eightness; but if followed out, and liberated from all
that was incongruous with it, it leads to a view con-
siderably different from that which it was brought to
support. For fitness to the moral nature of man, and
not mere subservience to his enjoyTnents, had been the
principle on which duties had been rested by the former
defenders of independent morality; but this principle
their successors were gradually allowing to sJip away
from their grasp.
As the Cambridge men in general thus rejected
the fitness of things, they were also indisposed to
admit the Moral Sense. Though Warburton, as we
have seen, was willing to accept the Moral Sense as
a part of the forces belonging to the cause of virtue,
the Cambridge moralists looked upon this new ally
with suspicion, as incapable of being entirely recon-
ciled to their philosophy. This feelmg appears from
a work in which the doctrine of the Moral Sense was
noticed, and which shows that the opposite system
was becoming a part of the habitual teaching of this
place. I speak of an Essay on the Nature and Obliga-
tions of Virtue, published in 1744, by "Dr Eutherforth,
Fellow ajid Tutor of St John's College. It is dedi-
KDTHERFORTH. 151
cated to one of his former pupils, Anthony Thomas
Abdy, Esq., of Lincoln's Inn; to whom he says,
"There is little in the following sheets which you
have not heard me explain, upon different occasions,
while you were under my care at the University." In
this work he argues strenuously against Hutcheson's
opinions. "The common and ordinary feelings of
mankind, the senses and perceptions which are upper-
most in the human constitution and are most attended
to, plainly direct to private good, and instruct each
individual to provide for himself in the best manner
he can. But some of the later moralists," he says,
"think they have discovered another sense in man,
as natural to him as these are, though less observed —
an appetite for doing good ; a sense which has virtue
for its object, and gives a disinterested approbation
of all her dictates; an affection which though it may
perhaps be overlooked by the careless, or lie unculti-
vated in the minds of the dissolute, will yet sometimes
break out, and force even the most inattentive to take
notice of the charms of virtue, and the most aban-
doned to admire them." Hutcheson is referred to in
the margin ; and Kutherforth proceeds to disprove the
existence of this peculiar sense. And he afterwards
goes on to lay down his moral principles on much the
same basis as that with which we have since been so
familiar : — that " Every man's happiness is the ulti-
mate end which reason teaches him to pursue : and
that the constant and uniform practice of virtue to-
wards all mankind becomes our duty when revelation
has informed us that God will make us finally happy
in a life after this :" if we practise it.
This is teaching which undoubtedly is true as far
as it goes; and which would perhaps do little harm
in practice, so long as it was employed on the side
of good morals. But its inherent defectiveness cannot
be concealed; for how does our obedience to God on
this view differ from our obedience to an arbitraiy
tyrant invested with superior power, or from the ser-
vice which the idolater renders to an impure and cruel
deity 1 Undoubtedly no one can charge such writers
152 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
as I have noticed ■with making any sach monstrous
confiision. But what I wish to remark is, that they
do not give the distinction its due place in the foun-
dation of their system, where it ought to appear.
It is evident that the consideration which makes
the difference between the cases is, that we have a
moral esteem for the character and the law of the true
God, as well as an obedience governed by his pro-
mises. We believe our Divine Kuler to be supremely
holy, just, and good; and therefore we obey him with
joy and love, as weU. as hope. But this distinction
necessarily implies that we can form an idea of moral
goodness, justice, holiness, quite other than obedience
tathe will of a superior; siuce it is only by combining
these two elements that we obtain a true view of
Christian virtue. And thus, when these two elements
of virtue have been separated, as for purposes of ana-
lysis they should be, if, instead of reuniting them in
one common service, we reject and despise one of them,
we obtain a mutilated and deformed system, which
has no real stability or completeness. This view is
very clearly expressed by Dr Waterland, who was
Master of Magdalene College in this University, and
was one of the ablest opponents of Clarke. " It may
be asked," he says', "whether, if God had commanded
raen to be unjust and ungrateful, it would have been
morally good to be unjust and nngratefuL To which.
I answer, that it is putting an absurd, self-contra-
dictory supposition : for it is supposing a Grod that is
not necessarily wise and good, a God and no God."
In this view all parties may unite: — but I confess,
I do not think a genidne moralist, or even a person
of genuine moral feeling, could really assent to what
Waterland subjoins. "Abstract from the considera-
tion of the Divine Law, and then consider what justice
and gratitude would amount to. To be just or grate-
ful so far as it is consistent or coincident with our
temporal interest or convenience, and no farther, has
1 M'urlis, V. p. 50S.
"WATERLAND. 1 53
no more moral good in it than paying a debt for our
present ease in order to be trusted again; and the
being further just and grateful without future pro-
spects, has as much of moral virtue in it as folly pr
indiscretion has : so that the Deity once set aside, it
is a demonstration there could be no morality at all."
I cannot but think this a very harsh and repulsive
mode of stating that side of the question. Every
person of generous mind must be revolted when he
is told that to be just and grateful withovi futv/re pro-
spects has no more of good in it than any other folly
and indiscretion has. If men will propound their
opinions in such a form, we are obliged to answer
them also in a way that may seem somewhat severe.
If they hold, as Waterland here does, that an action
of justice or gratitude proposed for the sake of a small
future advantage has no moral character, they are
surely quite inconsistent in maintaining that the same
action derives its moral character from being performed
with a view to an immeasurably great reward. If to
aim at enjoyment in a future state on earth do not
promote, but rather destroys the morality of our acts,
how can they acquire a moral aspect from being di-
rected towards the happiness of a future state, even
in heaven ? It will be replied, I believe, that this
is so, because the happiness of heaven is inseparably
connected with goodness : and thus we come round to
the same point again; and thus too we see, as appears
to me, how arbitrarily those speculators proceed who
wish to separate these two considerations, which, as
soon as they are called upon to justify themselves,
they are compelled to reunite in order to make their
doctrine tolerable.
LECTUEE X.
Gay. Tcckeb. Paley.
EDMUND Law's reasonings mther refeiTed to tte
previous thaai to the succeedrag aspect of moral
speculation. He was rather of importance as con-
futing opinions tiU then prevalent, than as antici-
pating doctrines afterwards generally accepted. But
there was prefixed to his translation of King's Origin
of Evil a dissertation which has a more manifest af-
finity with the succeeding course of Cambridge mo-
rality. This was a Dissertation coneeming the Funda-
jmntal Principle of Virtue or Morality, anonymous,
but written by Mr Gay, of Sidney CoUege. This piece
has been referred to by Mackintosh and others as en-
tertaining an anticipation of the opinions afterwards
put forwards by Hartley, respecting the results of the
principle of the Association of Ideas; and in that point
of view, it has an important place in the history of
the speculations upon that subject, to which Hartley's
doctrines led, in Scotland and elsewhere : but I here
consider Gray with reference to his place in the history
of Cambridge moralists rather than metaphysicians.
Law, in his notes on The Origin of EvU, rejected the
Clarkian doctrine of absolute relations, as the founda^
tions of Eight and Wrong, and made a considerable
advance towards the morality founded merely upon
the plea.sure and pain resulting from actions. LaVs
speculations however were of the nature of the work
on which he commented, mixed up with discussions
concerning the h priori arguments respecting the being
of God, and the most abstract considerations which
the human mind can attaia to, respecting space and
GAY. TUCKER. PALET. 1 55
time, cause and effect, good and evil: but Gay must
be regarded as the predecessor of Paley.
The course which I have pursued has led me to
the writers by whom the scheme of morality which
has been taught in this University for the last century
was framed, and I shall at present go on to describe
the further steps of the development and fixation
of this system. I may afterwards, if the time allow,
resume the consideration of the progress of moral
speculation among other classes of English writers
from the time of Warburton, downwards. The views
of Hutcheson, Hume, Smith, and Hartley, were pur-
sued into many interesting and instructive specula-
tions by Reid, Stewart, and Brown, and Mackintosh
himself. But our Cambiidge moralists employed them-
selves rather in constracting a system of morals on the
seMsh principle, than in metaphysical analysis. For
the latter task, an indifference or distaste seems to
have grown up in England about the time of which
I speak. There was no wish to move onwards. The
Scotch school of metaphysicians engaged with great
assiduity in the analysis of man's faculties and prin-
ciples, and endeavoured to advance further and further
in this wide speculation. But the English moralists
shunned rather than sought such enquiries. Cam-
bridge men had taken their stand upon Locke in
metaphysics, as they had taken their stand upon New-
ton in mathematics. They were weary of constantly
changing their ground, and seeking new modes of
defence against the enemies of morality.
I have already compared the attack of Hobbes and
his foUowei's upon the old defences of morality, to the
assault of Rome by the Gauls. The readers of Livy
wUl recollect that after that calamity the Romans
deliberated whether they should migrate in a body
to Veii; and that while they still doubted, a centurion
who had marched his company into the forum gave
the word, " Signifer, statue signum, hie manebimus
optime'." The Senate forthwith exclaimed, " that they
' Livy, V. 55.
156 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
accepted tte omen." In the same manner this Uni-
versity seemed to have accepted the omen of the Lock-
ian system, and to have resolved to rest at the point
which had been indicated by -words caught from the
lips of those eminent men -whose names I have just
uttered; and she long rejected as superfluous or per-
verse all attempts to lead her to move to any other
position; to add to or alter the system -which they
had thus adopted. As, ho-wever, the metaphysical
system of Locke did really require, to say the least,
important corrections, and as the moral system -which
-was deduced from his principles, at least as here in-
terpreted, involved most serious defects, -we may easily
conceive that the resolation not to change, prevented
us from sharing in the advances -which these sciences
made elsewhere; as a rigorous adherence to and ex-
clusive admiration of Ne-wton long prevented our
sharing in the progress of mathematics which took
place on the continent. I am far from thinking that
the teaching of a university ought to be readily sus-
ceptible of change, and eager in the adoption of novel-
ties. Such institutions have for their object, as I have
already said, to combine permanence -with progress.
But perhaps this caution was not enough attended
to in admUting the systems of Locke and his followers,
and therefore ought not to be held of paramount
weight as a reason for retaining them. If they were
too hastily accepted and established here, they ought
to be at least gradually removed and replaced, if not
suddenly discarded.
The morality of general consequences, in the naked
and harsh form in which it has prevailed here, would,
I do not doubt, have been modified and purified, as
was done in other places, if it had not been for its
singular felicity in finding an expounder, who at the
same time systematized it, and set it forth in language
of the most admirable clearness and poignancy. It
-will be imderstood that I speak of Paley; and having
elsewhere in what I have said, sufficiently perhaps,
stated my -views of the defects of his principles, I have
no desire to dwell upon the subject : but I shall make
GAT. TirCKEE. PALEY. 1 57
a few remarks tending to show that his •work, like
most others which hare acquired a settled establish-
ment and permanent authority, was rather a clear and
systematic expression of opinions already current, than
an original Tiew, or even a set of original reasonings.
Gray, of whom I have already spoken as the author
of the Dissertation prefixed to the translation of Abp.
King, was, I believe, John Gay who took the degree
of B.A. at Sidney College in 1721, and was afterwards
Fellow of the College. I will quote one or two pas-
sages of Gay, that you may see how near he comes
to Paley in his leading views. He says : " Now it
is evident from the Nature of God, viz. his being
infinitely happy in himself from all eternity, and from
his goodness manifested in his works, that he could
have no other design in creating mankind than their
happiness; and therefore he wills their happiness;
therefore, the means of their happiness : therefore, that
my behaviour, as far as it may be a means of the hap-
piness of mankind, should be such. Here then we are
got one step further, or to a new criterion: not to a
new criterion of Yirtue immediately, but to a crite-
rion of the Will of God. For it is an answer to the
enquiry. How shall I know what the Will of God in
this particular is ? Thus the Will of God is the im-
mediate criterion of Virtue, and the happiness of man-
kind the criterion of the Will of God ; and therefore
the happiness of mankind may be said to be the cri-
terion of Virtue, but once removed."
You may recollect Paley's expression, " there are
many ends besides the far end." So Gay, " As there-
fore happiness is the general end of all acuions, so each
particular action may be said to have its proper and
peculiar end. Thus the end of a beau is to please
by his dress; the end of study, knowledge. But nei-
ther pleasing by dress, nor knowledge, are ultimate
ends; they still tend, or ought to tend, to something
farther, as is evident from hence, viz. that a man may
ask and expect a reason why either of them are pur-
sued. Now to ask the reason of any action or pursuit,
is only to enquire into the end of it : but to expect
158 HISTOBT OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
a reason, i. e. an end, to be assigned for an ultimate
end, is absurd. To ask why I pursue happiness, will
admit of no other answer than an explanation of the
terms."
Gay's definition of Virtue is wider than Palsy's :
"Yirtue is the conformity to a rule of life, directing
the actions of all rational creatures with respect to
each other's happiaess ; to which conformity every one
in aU cases is obliged: and every one that does so
conform, is, or ought to be approved of, esteemed, and
loved for so doing."
The interval from 1731 and 1756, the date of the
publications I have mentioned by Gay, Law, and
Rutherforth, to the publication of Paley's Principles
of Morality and Politics in 1785, is considerable; but
I am not aware of any events belonging to the in-
termediate time, and holding very important position
in the history of moral studies in this place. In 1765
PaJey had obtained one of the Bachelors' Essay Prizes,
for a comparison between the Stoic and Epicurean
philosophy. He had, as was natural with his habits
of mind, taken the Epicurean side. This was not an
effusion hastily and thoughtlessly flung from his pen,
for it was accompanied with elaborate notes in English,
and is still recollected for a genuine vivacity of thought
and expression which gave a promise of his future
style; as, for instance, when he called the Stoics
"those Pharisees in philosophy;" which however he
probably had from Taylor's Ciml Law, where the com-
parison of the Stoics with the Pharisees is quoted from
Josephus and from St Jerome (p. 67). During a por-
tion of the subsequent period (from 177 1) Paley him-
self lectured as Tutor of Christ's College', of which
he was a Fellow : and the subjects of his lectures were
Locke's Essay, Clarke On the Attributes, and Butler's
Analogy. He also lectured on Moral Philosophy, and
1 Law, the son of the Edmond
IJaw, Professor of Casuistry, Master
of Peterhouse, and afterwaids Bi-
shop of Carlisle, whom I have al-
ready mentioned, was his coadjutor
in the tuition.
GAT. TUCKER. rALEX. 159
his views on this svibject were, I presume, mainly
ooiacident with those explained by Bishop Law in the
notes to his translation of King's Origin of Evil, and
with the opinions contained in the Preliminary Dis-
sertation to that work, which was, as I have said, by
Gay of Sidney.
We also find Paley mentioning with great praise
another work, The Light ofNaiurejpwsued, hy Edwa/rd
Search, Esq., really however written by Abraham
Tucker, of Betchworth Castle, near Dorking. The
first three volumes of his work were published in
1768; the last four after his death, which took place
in 1774.
This work, cannot, I think, be looked upon as
occupying any very important place ia the progress
of Moral Philosophy; but there is in it an original
unsystematic freedom of thinking, and a temperate
good sense and virtuous moral feeling, which are
peculiarly English. There is, moreover, and this is
the quality which has most struck the notice of its
admirers, a fertility and brilliance of illustration which
are almost unrivalled, and which make it a mine of
thought for its speculative readers. This merit has
so often been noticed, that it may, I think, be in-
teresting to give an example of it. I take for this
purpose his modification of an image of Plato's, which
is, as Mackintosh says', "of characteristic and tran-
scendent excellence." He is speaking of the relation
between Reason and Passion.
" The metaphor employed by Plato was that of
a charioteer driving his pair of horses, by which latter
he allegorized the concupiscible and irascible passions :
but as we have nowadays left off driving our own
chariots, but keep a coachman to do it for us, I think
the mind may be more commodiously compared to a
traveller riding a single horse, wherein reason is re-
presented by the rider, and imagination with all its
train of opinions, appetites and habits, by the beast.
1 Bus. p. 271, note.
l6o HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHX.
Everybody sees the horse does all the work; the
strength and speed requisite for performing it are his
own; he carries his master along every step of the
journey, directs the motion of his own legs in walking,
trotting, galloping, or stepping over a rut, makes many
by-motions, as whisking the flies with his tail or play-
ing with his bit, all by his own instinct; and if the
road lie plain and open, without bugbears to affright
him or rich pasture on either hand to entice him, he
will jog on although the reins were laid upon his
neck, or in a well-acquainted road take the right
turnings of his own accord. Perhaps sometimes he
may move startish or restive, turning out of the way
or running into a pond to drink, maugre all endea-
vours to prevent him; but this depends greatly upon
the discipline he has been used to. The office of the
rider lies in putting his horse into the proper road
and the pace most convenient for the present purpose,
guiding and conducting him as he goes along, check-
ing him when too forward or spurring him w^hen too
tardy, being attentive to his motions, never dropping
the whip nor losing the reins, but ready to interpose
instantly whenever needful, keeping firm in his seat
if the beast behaves unruly, observing what passes
in the way, the condition of the ground ajid bearings
of the country, in order to take directions therefrom
for his proceeding. But this is not all he has to do,
for there are many things previous to the journey;
he must get his tackling into good order, bridle, spurs
and other accoutrements; he must learn to sit well
in the saddle, to understand the ways and temper of
the beast, get acquainted with the roads, and ensure
himself by practice to bear long journeys without
fatigue or galling; he must provide provender for his
horse and deal it out in proper quantities, for if weak
and jadish, or pampered and gamesome, he wiU not
perform the journey well; he must have him. weU
broke, taught all his paces, cured of starting, stum-
bling, runniug away, and all skittish or sluggish tricks,
trained to answer the bit and be obedient to the word
of command. If he can teach biTn to canter whenever
GAT. TUCKER. PALEY. i6l
there is a smooth and level turf, and stop when the
ground lies rugged of his own accord, it will contri-
bute to make riding easy and pleasant; he may then
enjoy the prospects around or think of any business
without interruption to his progress. As to the choice
of a horse our rider has no concern with that, but
must content himself with such as nature and edu-
cation have put into his hands: but since the spirit
of the beast depends much upon the usage given him,
every prudent man will endeavour to proportion that
spirit to his own strength and skill in horsemanship;
and according as he finds himself a good or bad rider'
will wish to have his horse sober or mettlesome. For
strong passions work wonders where there is a stronger
force of reason to curb them : but where this is weak
the appetites must be feeble too, or they will lie under
no coutroul'."
I cannot refrain from adding some of his remarks
on selfishness: "Persons deficient in this quality
[benevolence] endeavour to run it down, and justify
their own narrow views by alleging that it is only
selfishness in a particular form : for if the benevolent
man does a good-natured thing for his own satisfac-
tion that he finds in it, there is self at bottom ; for he
acts to please himself Where then, say they, is his
merit ? What is he better than us ? He follows con-
stantly what he likes, and so do we : the only differ-
ence between us is, that we have a different taste
of pleasure from him. To take these objections in
order, let us consider that form in many cases is all
in all, the essence of things depending thei-eupon.
Fruit when come to its maturity, or during its state
of sap in the tree, or of earthly particles in the ground,
is the same substance all along : beef, whether raw or
roasted or putrefied, is still the same beef varying
only in form : but whoever shall overlook this dif-
ference of form will bring grievous disorders upon
his stomach : so then there is no absurdity in sup-
posing selfishness may be foul and noisome under one
i Light ofNabuTBj Vol. n. p. 176,
11
1 62 BISTORT OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
form, but amiable and recommendable under another.
But we have no need to make this supposition, as
we shall not admit that acts of kindness, howmuch-
soever we may follow our own inclination therein,
carry any spice of selfishness. But men are led into
this mistake by laying too much stress upon ety-
mology, for selfishness being derived from self, they
learnedly infer that whatever is done to please one's
own inclination must fall under that appellation, not
considering that derivatives do not always retain the
fall latitude of their roots. Wearing woollen cloaths
«r eating mutton does not make a man sheepish, nor
does employing himself now and then in reading render
him bookish: so neither is eveiything selfish that re-
lates to oneself. If somebody should tell you that
such a'bna was a very selfish person, and for proof
of it give a long account of his being once catched
on horseback by a shower, that he took shelter under
a tree, that he alighted, put on his great coat, and
was wholly busied in muffling himself up, without
having a single thought all the while of his wife or
children, his friends or his country : would not you
take it for a banter ? or would you think the person
or his behaviour could be called selfish in any pro-
priety of speech 1 What if a man agreeable and
obliging in company should happen to desire another
lump of sugar in his tea to please his own palate,
would they p-onounce him a whit the more selfish
upon tbat accouat 1 So that selfishness is not having
a regard for oneself, but having no regard for any-
thing else. Therefore the moralist may exhort men
to a prudent concern for their own interests and at
the same time dissuade them from selfishness, without
inconsistency'."
Mackintosh has considered Tucker principally as
to his views of that analysis of our moral judgments,
which was the leading point of speculation of the
Scotch school. But as connected with the main sub-
ject of the present course of Lectures, we have to look
VoL n. pp. 313-^15.
GAY. TUCKEK, PALEY. 163
prmcipally at his views of the foundations of morality.
In reference to this question, he obviously belongs
to the school who rest the obligation of duties upon
the consequences, in the way of pleasure and pain,
to which they lead. He states this view in many
parts of his work. For example, he has a chapter
entitled " Ultimate Good;" he informs his reader that
he intends this phrase as a translation of the swinmwm
bonum of the ancient schools of moralists. Nor can
it be questioned that this translation far more truly
brings before us the import of those ancient contro-
versies than any of the more usual ways of rendering
the phrase, as the "chief good." "For," he says,
" the enquiry was not to ascertain the degree of good-
ness in objects, to determine what possessed it in
the highest pitch beyond all others: but since the
goodness of things depends upon their serviceableness
towards procuring us something we want, to discover
what was that one thing intrinsically good which
contented the mind of itself, and rendered all others
desirable in proportion as they tended directly or
remotely to produce it'." Then, referring the reader
to his own account of motives, he says, "Whoever
shall happen to think they contain a just representa-
tion of human nature, need not be long in seeking
for this summum bonum; for he will perceive it to
be none other than pleasure, or satis&ction, which
is pleasure taken in the largest sense as comprising
every complacence of mind, together with the avoid-
ance of pain or uneasiness." "Perhaps," he adds,
" I shall be charged with reviving the old exploded
doctrine of Epicurus upon this article, but I am not
ashamed of joining with any man of whatever cha-
racter, in those parts where I think he has truth
on his side." In accordance with this profession, he
treats other parts of his subject. Thus when he comes
to speak of Rectitude and Right: "Right," he says
(p. 200), " belongs originally to lines, being the same
as straight in opposition to curve and crooked. . . .
1 VoL n. p. 182.
11—2
164 HISTORY or MORAL PHILOSOPHT.
From hence it has been applied by way of metaphor
to rules and actions, which lying in the line of our
progress to any purpose we aim at, if they be wrong,
they will carry us aside, and we shaU either wholly
miss of our intent, or must begin again and take a
longer compass than necessary to arrive at it : but if
they conduct effectually and directly by the nearest
way, we pronounce them right. Therefore the very
expression of right in Usdf is absurd, because things
are rendered right by their tendency to some end,
so that you must take something exterior into the
account in order to evince their rectitude." It is
curious that his own illustration here did not cause
at least some scruple in his mindj for in truth, we
do not take anything exterior into account to deter-
mine whether a line be straight or crooked. Its re-
ference to some given point, or other condition, may
determine whether it is in the right direction; but
it is a straight line in virtue of necessary relations
of space, and not of its leading to the given point.
If the difference between moral right and wrong can
be made to depend upon principles as pure from
external regards as the difference between straight
and crooked, the doctrine of morality sepai-ate from
the pursuit of pleasure will be as clearly established
as the doctrine of geometry separate from the mea-
surements of material objects. Again : " Everybody,"
he say.s, "knows a right line is the shortest distance
between two points, so as to touch them both, and
the nearest approach from any. one to any other given
point is along such right Une. From hence," he adds,
"it has been applied by way of metaphor, to rules
and actions." But according to his own showing, and
that of all the assertors of dependent morality, the
analogy here fails altogether; for justice and virtuous
self-denial, which are the right roads to enjoyment, ac-
cording to their doctiine, are certainly not the shortest :
on the contrary, they are therefore right, because they
reach the end better, by a very circuitous process ; .
and the short cut to pleasure, which appetite and pas-
sion offer, is without hesitation pronounced wrong.
GAY. TUCKER. PALET. 165
The same embarrassment in the management of
his principle of mere satisfaction, or utility, occurs
to him, as ' it must occur to all virtuous moralists,
when he comes to the best defined cases of moral
duties. Thus he says in pursuance of his general
principle, that justice is to be measured by utility,
and that an extreme case of inconvenience arising
from a common precept of justice, nullifies the rule
for that case. But yet he adds (p. 305), that "if
a righteous man be asked vhy he fulfils his engage-
ments though to his own manifest detriment, he will
answer, Because it would have been unjust to have
failed in them; for he wants no other motive to in-
duce him : and if the querist be righteous too, he
will want no other reason to satisfy him." And after
supposing the enquiry to be still prosecuted, he adds,
"But could it be made appear that injustice in some
single instance was to the general" [observe the gene-
rat] " advantage, he would not think himself warranted
to practise it, because the mischief of setting a bad
example and weakening the authority of a beneficial
rule would be greater than any present advantage
which might accrue from the breach of it." Here
the example is taken into the account; and it is
supposed that the evil which it occasions cannot be
remedied, by the fact that those who see the rule
violated, may see also the reasons of its violation.
But he goes further. " Even supposing his injustice
could be concealed from all the world, so that it could
do no hurt by example, still he would not believe
it allowable, for fear it should have a bad influence
upon his own mind." Thus we come to this result :
that the way to understand the true nature and
demands of justice, and the conditions under which
her rules admit of resemblance, is to look at the con-
sequences; but agaru, the way to avoid being misled
is not to look at the consequences, but to follow the
rules as rising above the region of exceptions. This
is the kind of dilemma which shows how insufficient
the contemplation of the consequences of actions alone
is, to lead to a system of morality which will satisfy
1 66 HISTORT OF MORAL PHILOSOFHT.
the common judgments ■which practical life generates
in the breasts of virtuous men.
It is not my purpose to give a general analysis of
Tucker's Tirork, which, indeed, from its prolix, devious,
and unsystematic character, would be no easy task;
and which its place in the history of philosophy does
not render necessary. But I may remark, that the
author extends his speculations to the philosophy of
religion as well as of morality, treats of the connexion
of the two subjects, and supplies the deficiencies of
the one by the other. Thus in the former part of his
work, on Morality, he refers to the case of Regulus,
the ancient stock example of the schools for the state-
ment of the question between virtue and pleasure.
He decides that upon his principles, so far as he has
then pursued them, Regulus "acted imprudently'."
This in a chapter entitled LimHiatian of Virtue : but
further on in the work' there appears a chapter writ-
ten with express reference to this preceding one, and
entitled Re-erdargement of Virtue. And here taking
into account, though but vaguely and dimly, the pro-
spect of a future retribution, he reverses this decision.
I wiU give the whole passage.
" Therefore now we may do ample justice to Ee-
gnlus, whom we left under a sentence of folly for
throwing away life with all its enjoyments for a
phantom of honour. For he may allege that he had
not a fair trial before, his principal evidence being
out of the way, which having since collected in the
course of this second Book, he moves for a rehearing.
For he will now plead that it was not a fantastic
joy in the transports of rectitude, nor the Stoical
rhodomontade of a day spent in virtue containing
more enjoyment than an age of bodily delights, nor
his inability to bear a life of general odium and con-
tempt, had his duty so required, which fixed him in
his resolution: but the prudence of the thing upon
a full and calm deliberation. Because he considered
> VoL II. p. 373 sq. > VoL ill. p. 502, § 5.
GAT. TUCKER. PALEY. 167
himself as a citizen of the universe, whose interests
ai-e promoted and maintained by the particular mem-
bers contributing their endeavours towards increasing
the quantity of happiness, wherever possible, among
others with whom they have connexion and inter-
course.
"He saw that his business lay with his fellow-
creatures of the same species, among whom a strict
attachment to faith and honour was the principal
bulwark of order and happiness, that a shameful con-
duct in his present conflict would tend to make a
general weakening of this attachment, which might
introduce disorders, rapines, violences and injuries
among multitudes, to far greater amount than his
temporary tortures; that if he behaved manfully, he
should set a glorious example, which might occasion
prosperities to be gained to his country and all be-
longing to her, overbalancing the weight of his suf-
ferings, especially when alleviated by the balmy con-
sciousness of acting right. He was persuaded likewise
that all the good a man does, stands placed to his
account, to be repaid him in full value when it will
be most useful to him : so that whoever works for
another, woi'ks for himself; and by working for num-
bers, earns more than he could possibly do by working
for himself alone. Therefore he acted like a thrifty
merchant, who scruples not to advance considerable
sums, and even to exhaust his coifers, for gaining
a large profit to the common stock in partnership.
Upon these allegations, supported by the testimony
of far-sighted philosophy, and confirmed in the ma-
terial parts by heaven-born religion, I doubt not the
jury will acquit him with flying colours, and the judge
grant him a copy of the record, to make his proper
use of, whenever he might be impeached or slandered
hereafter."
I have with the less unwillingness given these long
extracts from Tucker, since we have few English
writers of any merit to occupy this interval, and the
vivacity of his style makes it an ungrateful task to
reduce him to mere abstract assertions. Moreover,
1 68 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPUY.
hia influence upon the subsequent progress of the sub-
ject was far from trifling; for as I have said, he was
the favourite author of Paley. This latter moralist,
so important from the place he has long held among
us, I have already begun to speak of, and I now
proceed with the further notice of the reception and
effect of his system.
Paley's ethical work is mainly employed in de-
ducing arguments for our duties, and rules for de-
ciding critical cases, from the principle of general
utility. If this undertaking had been kept in its
due place, moralists of all shades of opinion might
have received such a work with pleasure; for all agiee
that sound morality is invariably the road to the
greatest general good; and to trace the mode in which
the principles produce the result, is satisfactory and
instructive, even to those who do not think that such
a deduction discloses the full force and significance
of our duties. Moreover, in Paley's mode of executing
this task, he displayed a moderation, a shrewdness,
and a poignant felicity of idiomatic expression, which
it was impossible not to admire. If the work had
been entitled MoralUy as derived from the Frindple
of General Utility, and if the Principle had been
assumed as evident or undisputed (instead of being
rested on the proofs which Paley gives), the work
might have been received by the world with uumingled
gratitude; and the excellent sense and temper, which,
for the most part, it shows in the application of rules,
might have produced their beneficial effect without
any drawback.
But Paley chose to give proofs of his principles ;
and in doing this, he both fell into false philosophy,
and assumed a tone and temper unsuited to the occa-
sion. The doctrine of ultimate utility as the measure
and ground of moral rules had been so long current,
almost uncontradicted, among English writers, that
those who were formed in this school could not con-
ceive the possibility of its being rationally opposed,
and could not avoid treating with contempt and ridi-
cule those who rested on any other principle. Hence
GAT. TUCKER. PALET. 1 69
•we find that Paley cannot speak of the opinion which
represents the soul to be superior to the body, the
rational to the animal part of our constitution, without
calling such views "much usual declamation." In
like manner, his account of the Law of Honour is
rather like the language of a poignant satirist, than a
moralist gravely and calmly stating an extensive prin-
ciple of hujnan action. " The Law of Honour is a
system of rules constructed by people of fashion, and
calculated to facilitate their intercourse with one an-
other, and for no other purpose... Profanen ess, neglect
of public worship or private devotion, cruelty to ser-
vants, rigorous treatment of tenants or other depend-
ants, want of charity to the poor, injuries done to
tradesmen by insolvency or delay of payment, with
numberless examples of the same kind, are accounted
no breaches of the Law of Honour... It allows of for-
nication, adultery, drunkenness, prodigality, duelling,
and of revenge, in the extreme." And it is to be
recollected that while he says this, he recognizes no
other ordinary rules of life than these, the Scriptures,
the Law of the Land, and this Law of Honour.
The fact is that Paley had no taste, and therefore
we may be allowed to say that he had little aptitude,
for metaphysical disquisitions. In this there would
have been no blame, if he had not entered into specu-
lations, which, if they were not metaphysically right,
must be altogether wrong. We often hear persons
declare that they have no esteem for metaphysics, and
intend to shun all metaphysical reasonings ; and this
is usually the prelude to some specimen of very had
metaphysics : for I know no better term by which to
designate the process of misunderstanding and con-
founding those elements of truth which are supplied
by the relations of our own ideas. That Paley had
no turn or talent for the reasoning which depends on
such relations, is plain enough. His examination of
the question of the Moral Sense throughout proves
this. For example, he states as an argument against
the doctrine of a moral sense, this consideration : If
such a principle of action were implanted in man, it
170 HISTORY or MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
could not subsist except there were implanted also
the ideas which it includes j and thus we are led to
innate ideas. The argument is well worthy notice;
so also is the reply : " The argument," it is replied,
" bears against all instincts, and against their exist-
ence in brutes as well as in men, but these certainly
do exist; hence the argument cannot be conclusive."
We have here a dilemma which must be solved in
some way before we can have any right to pronounce
upon the question at issue. Now what is Paley's
conduct in this case ? He simply states the argument
and the defence; and adds that as there is such a de-
fence, the argument will hardly, he supposes, produce
conviction, though it may be difficult to find an an-
swer to it.
We may remark, however, in justice to Paley on
this subject, that the habit of speaking of the Moral
Faculty as an Instinct, and of calling it the Moral
Sense, which practices were common in preceding
writers, naturally led a person whose mind like his,
had altogether a practical and not a metaphysical
turn, to embody this supposed Instinct or Sense in a
particular hypothetical instance, as he does in the
story of Caius Toranius. And thus this mode of
putting the question of the Moral Faculty, which has
justly been blamed as unphUosophical and irrelevant,
is not entirely to be charged upon Paley only.
In like manner a logical objection may be made
to his definition of Virtue', that it is inconsistent
with his own scheme, for it formally excludes duties
to God and to ourselves : besides the inherent vice of
his doctrine which it involves, in making no actions
virtuous which are not done from the prospect of a
future reward. This part of the subject has been so
often discussed that I shall not now dwell upon it.
It is a still more remarkable example of this want
of metaphysical turn in Paley, that he takes the no-
1 " Virtue is the doing good to I of God, and for the sake of ever-
vumklnd, in obedience to the will | liisHng happiness."
GAT. TUCKER. PALET. 171
tibn of Obligation, which Warburton, and, after him,
the Cambridge moralists, had already degraded from
an internal element of a duty to an external and
material constraint; and degrades and materialises it
still further. He tries to aid himself by the idea of
a case in which he is obliged to give his vote to the
disposal of a powerful benefactor. It does not appear
to have occurred to him that he might be thus obliged
to vote for A, though he ought to vote for B. His
talent lay in adducing and estimating practical cases,
and he tried to apply this process, even in metaphy-
sical inquiries; although it is obviously the way to
complicate, not to elucidate, the ultimate analysis of
ideas. In no other way could any one have been led
to assert moral obligation to be the state of a man
who is " urged by a violent motive resulting from the
will of another." If it had been asserted that a man
so circumstanced is not an example of moral obliga-
tion, the statement would have been much more
nearly true. It is plain that a man committing some
great wickedness contrary to his own wish, under the
influence of the threats of a powerful tyrant, is the
strongest example we can conceive of a person im-
pelled by this kmd of moral obligation. . Or we may
put the objection in another form. When a large
class of English moralists had made obedience to the
will of God a necessary part of .the idea of virtue,
there was a principle involved in their views which
made them not only tolerable to genuine moralists,
but made this way of speaking appear to many good
and pious men, far more reverent, and more suited to
man's real condition, than any independent idea of
rectitude. "What was this principle which thus re-
commended the combination of external command
with. the other elements of virtue? It was, as we
have seen, that this external will was not any one's
will, but the will of God: that the external command
was not arbitrary command, but the laws of the Being
in whom we conceive all goodness and holiness neces-
sarily to reside. The most sensitive virtue was not
offended at being impelled by his promises; the most
Jja HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
snow-white purity was not soiled by contact with hi
behest, which was itself purity. Hence, as we hav<
seen, those who asserted that God's command made
actions virtuous, stUl allowed that he could not com-
mand injustice or ingratitude; and those who asserted
that actions were in themselves right, allowed at once
that all such actions were commanded by God. And
thus the obligation which resided in the nature of
virtue itself, and the obligation which resulted from
the Divine Command, were never really separated.
They were like the circumference and center of a
circle which must coexist. But this necessary con-
nexion was a speculation of a kind for which Paley
had no relish, and from which he wished to free the
subject. Accordingly he at once tears the notion of
obligation loose from the idea of duty. We are
obliged when we are impelled by the will of another :
not, as hitherto, when we are commanded by him
whose commands we know to be right; — but by the
will of another — any other — for example, any candi-
date who canvasses us for a vote. Such was the con-
sequence of Paley's disposition to represent every
thing in a practical form. And thus obligation ceases
to have any connexion with what we ought to do;
and indeed to have any moral aspect whatever. In
previous ways of treating the subject, the circle of
our duties and obligations, or any part of it, was not
deformed, because it was referred to its natural center,
the central idea of God. But the center of the line
which represents Paley's obligation is arbitrary and
variable; and thus would tend to disfigure and con-
found the form of duty, if it were not corrected by
other considerations.
Leaving then this part of Paley's work, which
deals with the analysis of ideas, and the establish-
ment of the foundations of morality, as by no means
deserving of confidence or admiration ; I turn for an
instant to the superstructure, in order to make a
single remark. I have already said that his general
])rinciple being assumed, his application of it is often
very instructive and happy. It may be asked how
GAT. TUCKER. PALET. 173
the original vice of his system, his referring to the
resulting pleasure and utility as the test of moral
right, can ever be got over. Granting, it may be
said, that we believe that moral rectitude does best
promote human happiness, when we take in the whole
train of consequences, yet who can trace all the con-
sequences of any one single action 1 Who can prove
that if I tell an apparently harmless or agreeable lie,
it will in the long run, and taking all the history of
the world together, produce more pain than if I had
told a truth? If we throw a stone into a lake, we
can trace but a little way the waves which it pro-
duces; in like manner if we attend to the conse-
quences of any human action, we can trace them a
little space, but they soon ramify and spread and are
modified in a thousand ways, so that we are obliged
to call back our thoughts from the vain pursuit.
How then can we deduce from the contemplated con-
sequences of human actions, a system of morality
which shall determine all .imaginable cases? And
how can it be that Paley, having constructed his
Ethical system by such a consideration of conse-
quences, has nevertheless in most or in all cases, de-
termined right on doubtful questions, and obtained
sound and good rules of moral action?
To this I reply, that in systems so constructed the
unmanageable nature of one fundamental assumption
is remedied by another assumption. The moralist
assumes that human conduct is to be determined by
the consideration of the total consequent pleasure.
But this consideration is incapable of being developed
in finite terms; — (if I may be here allowed a mathe-
matical expression). The moralist then assumes an-
other principle : — that the consideration of conse-
quences is to be applied by means of general rules : —
that all like actions are to be forbidden :^that to
violate a general rule is itself an evil : — that this evil
is so great as to do more than balance the apparent >
good results of any action.
I speak of this as an asswmption: for the supreme
principle of the system cannot supply a rigorous proof
174 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHT.
of the assmnption. The supreme principle of the sys-
tem of which I speak is, the happiness resulting from
each action. General rules therefore are good, only
because, and so far as, they are subservient to happi-
ness. We have no light, on such principles, to demand
for them any greater generality, any greater rigour,
than we can establish by showing such a subsei-vience.
But in constructing such system of morality we do
demand more. We demand so much more, that we
make their very generality a ground for rejecting
perceived consequences. We do not limit the gene-
rality by the utility, by its tendency to produce bene-
fits of known kindsj we declare the generality to be
a new kind of utility'.
This assumption does in fact, if acted upon, bring
the two systems of morality, the dependent and the
independent, into very close proximity as to their re-
sults. Por as soon as it is held that rules must be
universal, we can have little doubt what the rules are
to be. It cannot, on any principles of morals, be
generally indifierent whether we tell the truth or tell
a lie : and we must have a rule of universal validity :
— therefore " Tell the truth," which must be the gene-
ral rxde, must be the universal rule. And thus the
system of dependent morality, from this point, may be
made to assume a form as firm and solid as if it had
for its base the essential distinctions of things.
I may observe that this is very much like what
has taken place in other biunches of science. In
many branches of science there have been controversies
whether the principles of the science are necessarily
true, or are known by experiment only; just as in
morals, the question constantly imder our notice has
been, whether the rules of ethics can be necessarily
deduced from the idea of moral rightness, or must be
learnt by tracing actions to their consequences^ Now
those who have maintained the empirical foundation
of such sciences, of mechanics for example, have still
1 See Paley, Book ii. a 7 and 8.
GAT. TUCKER. PALEY. 1 75
held the propositions wHch the science contains to
be universally true. Take the case of any machine in
•which the machinist would calculate the effect. Sup-
pose that a projector brings forward some mechanical
contrivance, which possesses, as he maintains, powers
far greater than any hitherto known : however com-
plex, however novel the construction, the mechanical
philosopher proceeds unhesitatingly upon the principle,
that in the working of the machine what is gained in
power is lost in velocity. But how does he know
that the principle is true in this new case? He may
have proved its truth experimentally in other in-
stances; but here, the projector maintains that an
entirely novel construction is employed: — the old
maxims, he asserts, are no longer valid. The me-
chanist heeds him not: he does not waver as to the
truth of his mechanical principle. It must be true
in this case, though hitherto tested only in others.
Whence is this •confidence? How is it that experi-
mental mechanical truths thus assume the character
of necessity ? The answer is important : they must be
universal by their nature : and hence, proved in one
case, they hold for all others. Thus in the case just
referred to. Action and reaction must be equal :
action and reaction must depend upon the masses and
upon their velocities: — action and reaction are ^rojoor-
tional to the masses and velocities jointly; or else
they are not thus proportional : but in either case the
proposition is general. Action and reaction cannot be
one thing in one material combination, and another
thing in a different combination. Therefore the mea-
sure of action and reaction, the joint proportion of
the masses and velocities, is either universally true or
universally false. But we know that it is true in
many simple cases : — hence it is true in all cases,
however varied, however complex, however novel.
Thus this assumption of the necessary generality
of our propositions makes the procedure nearly alike,
after a certain point, of those who cultivate the sci-
ence asserting it to rest upon independent foundations
in the nature of our ideas, and of those who refer it
176 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHT.
entirely to empirical grounds. And this is the case
in morals as it is in mathematics.
A moral projector might come to the casuist, as-
serting that he was in possession of a falsehood which
it would be of the greatest service to mankind to
promulgate as a truth. What would the casuist say?
" It never can be right to promulgate falsehood." If
he were a moralist of expedience, if the question had
bejen proposed to Paley, he would have said: "It
must in the long run do more harm than good to put
about your lie." But the projector pleads that he has
calculated the good and the harm, and that the good
immensely predominates. The moralist has not calcu-
lated ; how can he know ?-JfcJ)oes the moralist hesitate
at this ? Not an ins^nt. He says, " You violate a
general rule. No other good can compensate for the
mischief of this." And thus he nobly leaps over his
barrier of calculated consequences, and places himself
at one bound, in defiance of his theory, upon the solid
basis of rules by their nature universal. And thus it
is that there is no inevitable divergence in the results
of the different, or even opposite schools of moralists,
as to rules of conduct : and in those of them who
accept the light of religion, even as a collateral aid,
there is the most remarkable coincidence, notwithstand-
ing the different courses they at first seem to pursue.
Yet it is still true, that the different spirit of
these different schools continues to pervade them,
even in their practical conclusions. Thus Paley,
though he avails himself of the consideration of the
necessary generality of rules, in order to gain a solid
footing for sound morality, still appears to have a
misgiving respecting this assumption, and shrinks
back again from the general rule to the special con-
sequences. " Not to violate a general nfle for the
sake of any particular good consequences we may
expect is for the most part" he -says, " a salutary
caution, the advantage seldom compensating for the
violation of the rule." Hence we see he introduces
words which infringe the integrity of the rule, and
indeed may easily be used to destroy it altogether.
GAY. TUCKER. PALET. 1 77
In the same way, althougli general rules, if they
are of supreme importance in morals, must be allowed
also to be of great value in government, the considera-
tion of these appears to be laid aside when it ought to
be recollected most. Thna Paley says : " This prin-
ciple [of expediency] being admitted, the justice of
every particular case of resistance [in political con-
troversies] is reduced to a computation of the quantity
of the danger and grievance on the one side, and the
probability and expense of redressing it on the other."
Hence he appears to have left out of the account the
immense mischief of violating that long-tried and ap-
proved system of rules which we call the Constitution,
of which he might easily say, with as much truth
as of any system of moral rules, that not to violate
it is a salutary caution, the advantage so gained rarely
compensating the violation of the rule.
It is not my intention to discuss at present Paley's
views with regard to special duties. I shall have a
few remarks to make on the reception which his prin-
ciples met with in this University and this country;
and with these I shall conclude the historical sketch
■which I have thus attempted.
12
LECTURE XL
Paley. Gisboene.
IN order to make more complete our account of the
reception of Pale/s work in general, and especially
in this place, let us go back a few years. The works
of Eutherforth I conceive we may take as representing
the teaching common at Cambridge in the middle
of the last century. Besides the Essay which T have
mentioned, he published in 1754 and 1756, as I have
said, his Institutes of Nativral Law, being the substance
of a Course of Lectures on Grotius de Jure Belli et
Fads, read in St John's College, Cambridge. The
work consists of two volumes; the first being on the
Rights and Obligations of Mankind, considered as In-
dividuals; the second, on the Rights and Obligations
of Mankind, considered as Members of Civil Societies.
His work was, I believe, in common use in the Uni-
versity, tUl that of Paley was introduced. Although
it professes to be a Course of Lectures on Grotius,
neither the basis of the system, nor its arrangement,
have any close resemblance with those of Grotius.
The work of Grotius holds a very important place in
the history of Moral Philosophy ; but in order to ad-
here to my plan of pursuing at present the history of
this Philosophy in England only, I do not attempt to
speak of it now. I will only remark (as I believe I
have already done), that the fundamental doctrines of
Grotius are very nearly the same as those of Cumber-
land ; a general principle of sociality, or regard to the
good of human kind, being the main basis of their
morality.
This principle in Cumberland, as we then said, was
emphatically declared to be something far higher and
PALEY. 179
•wider than a regard to private good. But the leading
English moralists, having now taken private good for
their foundation principle, it is proper to consider in
what manner they applied this principle in particular
cases. Supposing the controversy with their opponents
to be terminated, what did they teach their disciples!
Having demolished the ancient palace of Moral Rec-
titude, how did they proceed to give solidity to' the
commodious modern mansion which they undertook
to erect on its ruins?
We find, in the works of Eutherforth, examples
of the modes of procedure which, from this time, were
commonly pursued by our moralists for this purpose ;
these are, for the most part, attempts to deduce special
duties in detail, by tracing the special evils which arise
from the neglect of them. Thus, in his Essay, inso-
briety and other sensual indulgences are vices, because
they prevent our doing all the good we might, by dis-
turbing our health, occupying our time, distracting
our attention. We cannot help seeing how low and
lax is the morality to which we should thus be led.
It is true that purer precepts, borrowed from holier
sources, are constantly operating among Christian mo-
ralists, to correct and elevate the perverse and debased
conclusions which low and poor principles entailed
upon them; but then, in proportion as their moral
systems were made in this way practically harmless,
they were made theoretically worthless. The bright
and firm precepts of Christianity, like new pieces on
an old garment, shone here and there the more con-
spicuously for the sordid and flimsy ground on which
they were placed; but though, for the moment, they
might serve to conceal the nakedness of the wearers,
they tended rather to tear the theorist's robe into
tatters, than to render it a lasting and suitable ves-
ture.
From the time of which I speak, up to that of
Paley, I am not aware that any material alteration
took place in the nature of the Ethical Philosophy
generally received here.
I come now to the further consideration of Paley's
12—2
1 86 HISTORY OF MORAL' PHILOSOPHY.
ethical work, and of the reception which it met "with,
and especially its reception in this University. In-
deed, it is much more my purpose at present to con-
sider the manner in which the book was received, and
the place which it holds in the progress of moral
speculation in England, than further to discuss the
solidity or the weakness of the principles on which it
rests. Some indication of the arguments beaiing upon
this latter question will be requisite for my purpose :
for the place of a work in the histoiy of philosophy
cannot be exhibited without showing, in some measure,
how far it tended to promote truth, and how far to
propagate error. And among the criticisms delivered
by objectors to such a work, those only will demand
our notice, which contain or illustrate some of the
principles intimately involved in the establishment of
sound moral doctrines. So far, therefore, as the se-
lection of such criticisms goes, I cannot avoid at pre-
sent delivering some -judgment with respect to Paley's
moral system. But any direct and complete examina-
tion of the work, beyond that which an historical view
thus requires, I must reserve for future occasions.
You will recollect that Paley's work was but the
summing up of a system of teaching which had long
been current in the University, not a newly- introduced
subject or system. Moral Philosophy had never ceased
to be habitually taught in Cambridge; and the current
discussions upon that subject always excited a strong
interest among the speculators who were nourished
here. The great controversy respecting the d, priori
evidence of the fundamental principle of Theologv and
Morality had been zealously carried on in this Uni-
versity at the beginning of the seventeenth century,
John Balguy being the main combatant on the ct priori
side. In 1732, the translation of King's Origin of
Evil, with Gay's Dissertation and Law's Notes, showed
that the subject was by no means asleep ; and these
Notes of Law's were the matter of some controversies,
which I omit. In 1744, Rutherforth dedicated his
Essay on Virtue to his pupil, containing, he told him,
nothing which he had not heard him explain upon
PALEY. l8l
different occasions -wMle he was under his care at the
University. In 1754 and 5, Rutherforth published
his Institutes of Natural Law, the substance of a
Course of Lectures read in St John's College. In
1755, too, Taylor published his Elements 0/ Civil Law,
which he had drawn up with a view to the education
of young men committed to his care. Gradually we
find ourselves in another generation of academics.
Thomas Balguy, the son of the John just mentioned,
and Powell, afterwards Master of the College, are
teachers at St John's. " I have ever thought my warm-
est gratitude due," says one of their pupils ', " to that
Being through whose kind providence the care of my
education was entrusted to Drs Powell and Balguy."
A little later (177 1), we find Law, son of the Bishop
of Carlisle, himself afterwards Bishop of Elphin, en-
gaged in the tuition at Christ's College, along with
Paley; the subjects of their Lectures being Locke's
Essay^ Clarke On the Attributes, and Butler's Analogy.
The heads of Balguy's Lectures were comprised in a
Syllabus, which was handed about to various persons
in the University; and from this Syllabus also Dr
Hey, the late Norrisian Professor, delivered Lectures
at Sidney College ^ Similar Lectures formed part of
the usual course of instruction in other colleges ; and
the value of the subject, as an element of education,
was invariably acknowledged. A large portion of these
Lectures were, doubtless, thoroughly Lockian in their
principles, although, from time to time, the natural
influence of higher principles would break through,
and produce a remedial inconsistency. Butler and
Clarke, as we have seen, were bound together in the
same bundle with Locke. But the general tendency
was to the morality of mere pleasure and pain, as
we have seen in Giay, the elder Law, Rutherforth,
and, as I might have shown, in others. Still the
doctrine of a higher ground of morality had its de-
fenders even here. The elder Balguy does not pecu-
I T. Ludlam's Logical Tracts.
s Pearson, JReinarke: Theor. p. 212, and p. ill.
1 82 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
liarly belong to the academic line of writers. But
there were othera who, more or less, mitigated the
rigour of the Lockian morality. Thus Pearson, whom
I have to notice as one of the answerers of Paley,
speaks of "that school which boasts of the names of
Butler, Powell, Balguy, William Ludlam, and Hey;"
to which he adds Thomas Ludlam (p. vi). I shall,
however, now turn to the consideration of Paley's
Works, and their acceptance here.
The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy,
or, as it was originally entitled, The Principles of
Morals and Politics, was first published in 1785. It
was very favourably received by the public, and was
almost immediately adopted into the course of teach-
ing in this "University. Mr Jones, then senior tutor
of Trinity College, who discharged the duty of Mode-
rator in 1786 and 1787, introduced it as a standard
book in the disputations which were then held in the
schools upon a moral question, along with the mathe-
matical disputations: and also in the subsequent ex-
amination for the degree of Bachelor of Arts. In
fact, as we have already seen, the principle upon
which Paley's book is based, the doctrine that actions
are good in as far as they tend to pleasure, and obli-
gatory in as far as they are commanded by a powerful
master, had already long been tanght in this Uni-
versity, and had undoubtedly taken a strong hold of
the minds of men. They had accustomed themselves
to look upon it as the only rational and tenable doc-
trine ; and one which was as superior in these respects
to the vague and empty doctrines, of loftier sound,
which had preceded the time of Locke, as the philo-
sophy of Newton was to that of Aristotle. Hence it
seemed to them quite natural and fitting, that a sys-
tem founded upon this principle should be produced,
displaying all the exactness, precision, and simplicity,
of a mathematical treatise. When, therefore, the
work t)f Paley appeared, in which the commonly-
received rules of morality are all professedly deduced
from this principle; in which there is a clearness of
statement and expression which produces the effect,
PALET. GISBORNE. 183
for a moment, of demonstrative reasoning; and in
which the want of sound morality in the fundamental
principle, is tempered by good sense and good feeling
in almost all the instances, they at once saw, in this
work, the standard book which they had long wanted,
as a means of conveying these doctrines to their
pupils in the definite and connected form which ele-
mentary instruction requires. Perhaps we may add,
that they were not unwilling to join with Paley in
rejecting all the more profound investigations into the
foundations of moral principles, as useless metaphy-
sical subtleties or empty declamation ; and thus to
assume an air of superiority over those who took
any other road than theirs. We may add, too, that
though there were some points of morality on which
Paley's conclusions have been charged with being lax,
as well as his principles unsound, many of his con-
temporaries were, it is understood, willing to accept
such a decision as he gave on these very points; and
thus, were not repelled from the work by the appear-
ance, which some saw in it, of tampering with im-
portant moral precepts. So that the work had many
recommendations, internal and external, to publid
favour.
But though Paley's system was received with favour
by a large part of the public, and especially by those
who, in this place, had long held the opinions which
he had systematised with so much clearness and good
sense, there were not wanting, from the first, persons
who protested against its doctrines as false and im-
moral.
Such objections to Paley's doctrines were uged not
only by strangers, but by persons belonging to his
own university. Mr Gisborne, since appointed a pre-
bendary of Durham, favourably known to the public
as the author of several works on subjects connected
with Morals, remonstrated against the adoption of
Paley's principles by this University, in an Examina-
tion of tliem which he published in 1790'. "Thd
> This is the date of the Second Edition.
184 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
subsequent Treatise," he says in the Preface to this
■work, "was occasioned by an appointment -which I
understand to have taken place in the University of
Cambridge, that candidates for the degree of Bachelor
of Arts shall be examined in the Elements of Moral
and Political Philosophy." He proceeds to say that,
rejoicing that the study of Morality is thus made a
portion of academical instruction, he is still persuaded
that Paley's fundamental principle is exposed to most
grave objections. In the sequel, he states the objec-
tions to which he thus refers. His iirst argument is
from the impossibility of really and rigorously apply-
ing the criterion by -which Paley professes to decide
questions of morals. He takes in succession the steps
of Paley's reasoning: To the first, "that God -wills
and -wishes the happiness of his creatures," he assents;
as also to the second, that " those actions -which pro-
mote that happiness must be agreeable to him, and
the contrary." He then comes to the inference dra-wn
from these positions, "that the method of coming at
the will of Grod concerning any action, by the light of
nature, is to inquire into the tendency of that action
to promote or diminish the general happiness." Here
he stops, and refuses his assent. How does it appear,
he asks, that we can wield with good effect a principle
so vast and complex as this one of universal tendency ?
"Were the power of the human intellect unlimited,
and capable of deriving knowledge from any specified
source, of drawing it forth from every secret repository
in which it is stored, Mr Paley's conclusion would be
just. In that case, in order to indicate the method of
obtaining knowledge of any kind, nothing more could
be requisite than that the storehouse in which it is
hidden should be specified. But human faculties being
imperfect and circumscribed, no one can be justly held
to have pointed out the method of acquiring a know-
ledge either of the will of God or of any other subject,
unless, besides pointing out the source, he proves also
that man has faculties enabling him to derive it from
that source." But this Paley does not do. He con-
tents himself -with directing us to inquire, when he
PALET. GISBORNE. 185
should have proved us able to discover. This defect
utterly destroys the validity of his argument, and
leaves, as an assertion unsupported by proof, the con-
elusion that the consideration of general expediency is
the method of learning the will of God. Mr Gisbome
then proceeds to illustrate this remark by comparison
■with the case of a workman executing the plan of an
architect. This image appears to me by no means
happily chosen for his purpose; and has been retorted
by writers on the other side. But as the argument
against the doctrine of general expediency, drawn from
the impossibility of fitly applying it with our limited
views and faculties, is one of great importance, I will
take the liberty of offering an illustration of a differ-
ent kind, which, in this University at least, may,
I trust, be considered as allowable, and which seems
well fitted to throw light on the subject. I have on
former occasions endeavoured to point out an analogy
between the progress of the science of Morals and
other sciences ; and such a comparison is, I believe,
very far from being merely fanciful. I conceive we
may especially derive instruction regarding the pro-
gress of all branches of human knowledge, by con-
templating the history of a science of which the
successive steps and advances can all be distinctly
traced, and which has risen from gross en-ors, and
rudiments of mere practical knowledge, through vari-
ous gradations of partial truths, up to truths of the
most general kind, which, now that they are thus
established, appear to be self-evident. I speak of the
science of Mechanics.
Now it is well known to those who have attended
to the history of this science, that in the course of the
last century a principle termed the Frinciple of Least
Action, was propounded as a mode of determining the
course which a body would follow moving from point
to point under the influence of external agents. The
import of the principle was, that the body would
select such a path, and move in such a manner, that
the total action which took place in consequence
of the body's motion would be smaller than if the
1 86 HISTORY OV MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
body had moved in any other line or in any other
manner. .
Maupertuis, the philosopher who first asserted this
principle, conceived that he could establish it as a
universal truth by reasonings drawn from the natiire
of the Deity and the rules of His operation. And if
true, it undoubtedly embraced all cases of motion
under all circumstances, and promised to give the
solution of all mechanical problems whatever.
The truth and the meaning of this principle were
the subject of a long and angry controversy; and, as
is usual in such controvei-sies, the meaning of the
principle was so modified as to ensure its truth. For
what is quantity of action? Many dififerent meanings
might be given to such a word : but it was found that
one very simple meaning might be assigned to it,
which would make the Principle include many me-
chanical truths. And in the sequel, it was proved by
Lagrange, that, with the definition which had been
adopted, the principle was a universal and necessary
truth in all possible combinations of bodies and mo-
tions.
Thus then the Principle of Least Action was
allowed and proved to be true. But how far was it
adopted as a means of solving special problems? Did
it supersede other methods of dealing with mechanical
questions? Did men apply it to the simf)le cases of
mechanical action which they had to consider ? Was
it desirable that they should do so? Could they have
done so if they had tried?
If a mathematician of Maupertuis' time had set
about solving a simple problem, or almost any pro-
blem, by means of the principle of Least Action, as
the best way of obtaining the solution, he would have
been very unwise. The principle then was precarious;
for every mechanical principle is precaiious so long as
it rests upon metaphysical reasonings alone, though
these may, perhaps, convert known truths into neces-
sary truths : — the principle was of doubtful meaning if
true, for its real meaning was only established when
its universal truth was proved. But, dismissing these
PALEY, GISBORNE. 187
.objections, the method -was a bad method of solution,
as being superfluously and extravagantly general and
complex; — introducing the consideration of very many
indetinite and entangled elements, in a case which
really required but few and simple considerations.
And this is not th^ less the case, now that the princi-
ple is demonstrably confirmed. If any mechanical
calculator were to attempt to trace the path of a
projectile or a planet by Maupertuis' principle of
Least Action, he would be looked upon with a smile of
pity by all good mathematicians. He might perhaps
excite admiration in some novice, enthusiastic in his
love of generalities; but the probability is, that he
would fail in his attempt, arid be lost in the labyrinth
of symbols into which he had so unadvisedly and
unnecessarily rushed.
What the Principle of Least Action is in Mor
chanics, the Principle of Greatest resulting Good is in
Morals. No one questions its truth : every investigation
has more and more firmly established its reality. But
then, how hard to fix its precise meaning! What is
Good 1 Our judgments of the nature of Good change,
as our views of the tendency of all things to good
expand. Is Pleasure the Good? So says the system
of which we are speaking: but what pleasure? The
Pleasure of a calm mind, a pure conscience, a benevo-
lent heart : the Pleasure of a state of future happiness
when all sensual delights shall have passed away ? But
when we have given our principle this meaning, how
shall we apply it ? Who can foresee how far men's
actions tend to increase such good as this ? Who can
calculate all the efi^ect which his actions produce by
their consequences immediate and remote; by their
operation on his own character and habits; by their
influence in the way of example and reputation; by
their fitting him for another state of existence ? Can it
really be true that we cannot estimate the good or
evil of any of our doings, without summing the in-
finite series of such terms as these, which is appended
to each ? and each of these terms, too, depending upon
actions and thoughts of other men as its elements : — >
1 88 HISTORY OF KORAL PHILOSOPHY.
all these series, each in itself involving so much that
is indefinite, so much that is incalculable, all mixed
and entangled, and inter-dependent in modes innu-
merable. If we cannot call our actions good or evil
till we have performed this summation, till we have
balanced against each other the positive and the
negative quantities of such a calculation, we are
surely thrown upon a task for which our faculties are
quite unfit : we have the tangled course of life to run,
and are blindfolded by the band which is to assign
the prize.
But it will perhaps be said that we have no better
means of solving the moral problem of our being; it
will be demanded what other rule can be proposed for
determining the good or evil of our actions than the
consideration of their consequences. If such a ques-
tion were asked, we should have to reply, in the first
place, that this is not the matter under consideration.
Our business at present is to weigh the value of the
theory of morals which is based upon general expe-
diency. If this theory can be shown to be incapable
of being rightly employed, the arguments which prove
this are not turned aside by demanding some better
theory : nor would they lose their force if we were
driven to acknowledge that no general theory of
morals is attainable. And even if we are able to
construct a sounder and better system, this must be
a distinct task; and is not to he confounded with
the criticism which we apply to a system which is
held, by the objectors now under our review, to be
altogether unsatisfactory and false. It would merely
produce confusion and needless repetition, to quit this
ground, and to mix together the discussion of several
systems at once. Yet before quitting the illustration
which I have just employed, drawn from the science
of Mechanics, I may notice, in the slightest possible
manner, the instruction which it siiggests with regard
to the formation of any other sciences.
The science of Mechanics was not deduced, nor
could have been deduced, as we have seen, from the
general Principle of Least Action, though that Prin-
PALEY. GISBORNE. 189
ciple is indisputably true. How then was this pro-
vince of human knowledge so demonstrably -proved,
and made into so solid and extensive a system of
truths, general and particular 1 The answer is plain.
It was by the consideration, in the first place, of
special problems, reasoned upon by means of princi-
ples which, in those narrower applications at least,
were self-evident; and — in pi-oportion as these limited
principles were clearly seen and steadily possessed —
by passing from these to others which were true be-
cause they included the partial truths at first dis-
covered ; and which were applicable to more com-
preheusive and complex cases : — universal principles
which include all possible cases, being arrived at only
through these intermediate ones: — and these very
general truths being dimly and vaguely apprehended
at first ; and never becoming, not even at last, the
best mode of obtaining practical results.
Now so far as this general description goes, I do
not think it at aU extravagant to . expect that the
history of the Science of Mechanics may be a type of
the genuine course of real progress in other sciences,
even in those which deal with the internal world of
thought and feeling, as well as in those that regard
only the external world of matter and motion. But
the further prosecution and development of this view,
if it is permitted to me to trace it to its consequences,
must be the work of future years, a;nd of a maturer
study of the subject. At present I have ventured to
refer to it, only because I would not seem to criticize
existing systems, without any steady belief that a
better may be found; or to declare a mode of pro-
ceeding to be wrong, without knowing which way to
look for the right. I shall now return to the recep-
tion of Paley's system among English readers.
LECTURE XII.
GisBOBNE. Pearson. Price. Robert Hall.
BESIDES the argument against the doctrine of ex-
pediency, derived from the impossibility of ap-
pl3ring it, Mr Gisbome stated other objections to
Paley's ethical system. He urged that since actions
are asserted to be blameable only so fe.r as their con-
sequences are injurious, and since, of the probable
consequences, each man is for himself the judge; it
foUows that, if a man be persuaded that any action,
of those which are by the world called crimes, would
produce au overweight of good over bad consequences,
it ceases to be in him a crime, and becomes a duty:
and thus rapine, hypocrisy, peijnry, murder, may be
entitled to the highest rewards of virtue.
With regard to this argument, it goes to prove the
untenable character of PaJey's pretended analysis of
moral obligation, and has already been considered in
substance when I spoke of that subject. I may ob-
serve, however, that in stating this argument, Mr
Gisborne has anticipated the answer sometimes made
to it ; — that all moral rules must be applied in virtue
of the conviction of the agent, and by means of his
judgment; and that therefore the difficulty arising
from this circumstance, whatever it amount to, Ls no
argument against Paley's principles more than against
other systems of morals. Mr Gisborne repli^, that
the system of general utility is not upon an equal
footing with other systems in this respect. The
teachers of positive independent morality obtain
general definite rules; as, not to take what belongs to
another — to perform what we promise — and the like.
GISBORNE, PEARSON, PRICE, ROBERT HALL. I9I
There is no confusion or vagueness in applying such
rules. Utility, on the contrary, leads us to no abso-
lute roiles; for she has never exhausted the stock of
possible consequences. She confirms such precepts as
the above ; but still, confirms them as liable to excep-
tion, and valid only upon the supposition that nothing
unforeseen alters the usual result. I think that we
cannot deny that the consideration of general conse-
quences, thus directly employed to establish moral
precepts, does, by its nature, leave them charged with
a large amount of insecurity and vagueness; and
indeed makes them in a great degree precarious. All
peremptory and rigorous moral rules become, on this
system, as I have already said, rather assumptions
made to suit the needs of practical morality, than fair
deductions from the principle, supported by just and
adequate demonstrations.
Mr Gisborne further urged, that Paley's rule is
irreconcileable with the Scriptures, which enjoin us
not to do evil that good may come: and he con-
demned, with a very natural severity, a passage to
which I have already referred, in which Paley dilutes
and almost nullifies this serious command, by terming
it a caution, salutary for the most part, the advantage
seldom compensating for the violation of the rule.
Mr Gisborne was not the only assailant of the
Paleian system on its introduction into this Univer-
sity. Dr Pearson, afterwards the Master of Sidney
College, also published two pamphlets (in 1800 and
1 801), one directed against the theoretical, and the
other against the practical part of Paley's ethical
work. Some of Dr Pearson's principal objections
were aimed at some of the defects of the work in
system and reasoning, which its most ardent admirers
could hardly deny ; as in the case of the confusion
(already noticed) which is to be found in Paley's defi-
nition of virtue. Dr Pearson's own definition of
Virtue is. Voluntary obedience to the will of God.
But he contends that the will of God may be ascer-
tained in various ways ; by the eternal fitness of
things, conformity to truth, the moral sense, and, if
192 HISTORY OP MOKAL PHILOSOPHT.
really applicable, general utility : any of tliese prin-
ciples may, lie asserts, be employed in discovering the
path of our duties. As a practical rule, this commix-
ture of views fundamentally different, may be ad-
mitted; but it may be observed that we should never
in this way obtain a sound theory, or a coherent sys-
tem of ethics. It may be, that each of these prin-
ciples is true, and that each has its place in a true
system: but then, that place must be definite, and
must be assigned by the most profoimd and compre-
hensive philosophy which belongs to the subject.
Such philosophy can never countenance a tumultuary
assemblage of all the principles which have ever been
propounded, brought together on the supposition that
they have all equal and independent rights.
In 1797 a defence of Paley's Moral Philosophy
against its assailants was attempted by Dr Croft, of
Birmingham, formerly of University College, Oxford.
But this work was not of a nature to throw much
new light upon the subject : and at that period
Paley's boot was too firmly established as a standard
work on morals to need such a defender. It had be-
come a constant and prominent part of the teaching
and the examinations carried on in this University,
and both by the hold it thus obtained upon the minds
of many young men of good ability and good condi-
tion, by its own merits of style and execution, and by
its congruity with the principles and feelings of a
large portion of English society, its views and reason-
ings had pervaded the whole mass of English thought.
Every attempt at general abstract reasoning on moral
subjects was made after the manner of the reasonings
in Paley's works, and generally, upon the same fun-
damental principles ; and thus, besides the direct ope-
ration of the work, there was an indirect influence
exerted which, in time, tinged the habits of thinking,
reasoning 'and expression in this country, to at least
as great an extent as any previous moral doctriue had
ever done.
Besides those who thus objected to Paley's doc-
trine, and those who defended it, there was another
GISBOENB, PEARSON, PEICE, EOBERT HALL. 1 93
class -wto gladly accepted the principle of morality
founded upon consequences, and of right and wrong
regulated by the bearing of actions upon general uti-
lity : and who accepted it only to carry it very much
farther than Paley or any of his predecessors had done,
and to strip it of all the cautions and limitations by
which he had endeavoured to render it salutary.
This body of speculators did not immediately show
itself upon the appearance of Paley's book, nor even
directly after its general reception and establishment
here. But when, by being constantly employed in
this University as the basis of our moral teaching,
the principles of which I speak had become firmly
fixed in men's minds, and recognized by a great part
of the nation as the true grounds of human conduct
and judgment, it was natural that persons with very
difierent views from Paley should try whether their
system might not be built on his foundations. His
system embodied in itself the Christian belief, recom-
mended the usually-acknowledged virtues, and was,
for the most part, opposed to changes in the state of
society and government. But persons who wished for
a system without such ingredients, found that they
could easily employ the doctrine of general utility so
as to obtain their own most cherished conclusions.
For this end, they held that the principle of the
greatest happiness required to be followed out more
rigidly, more resolutely, more purely, than Paley had
done it: and there were not wanting persons who
performed this task with joy and exultation, and then
very naturally called upon their countrymen, and
especially those of Paley's school, to admire what they
had done, and to give it its practical efiect.
I am not now going to discuss any further the
speculations to which I thus refer : for they belong to
our own time, and are hardly yet a subject for mere
history. I will only observe that, whatevef any one
may think obnoxious or dangerous in the conclusiona
to which such speculations have led, is by no means
to be cast as a matter of blame upon Paley. Even
if such conclusions were deducible in the most logical
13
194 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
and demonstrative manner from principles which
Paley lays down, stUl, as he himself does not acknow-
ledge, but on the contrary, disclaims and condemns
such opinions as those to which I refer, he is not
chargeable with them; for it has been generally
allowed that man, whose duties are practical, not
theoretical, is not to be made responsible for conse-
quences widch he does not intend or foresee, even if
they follow inevitably from what he does or says. He
is not morally bound always to reason in a perfect
manner. He is bound to reason as well as he
can, but not bound to rea.son better. He must use
his best endeavour to apply such faculties as God
has given him to the discovery of the truth; and if,
doing this, he faUs, his error is not necessarily his
sin. If, therefore, Paley did not see the necessity of
the offensive consequences which have been deduced
from his doctrine, or seeing them, conceived they
might be averted by the considerations which he
offered, he is not to bear the whole blame of the opi-
nions which others have thus promulgated. He may
be a bad philosopher, an unsound theorist; but he
may still continue a blameless writer, a virtuous man.
And if this be so, even assuming Paley's principles to
be identical with those which lead to dangerous and
immoral tenets, how much less is he answerable for
the conclusions of those who copy his mode of specu-
lation, but who leave out of theii' system that which
is the main and guiding element in his, the rewards
and punishments of another life ! The study of Paley's
Moral Philosophy in this place may have produced
evU, which may perhaps now have accumulated so as
to overbalance the good. But I hope it will always be
understood that I acquit Paley himself of blame ; —
consider him as an admirable and instructive writer
who has edified and directed practically aright an
immense body of readers; — and look up to him with
gratitude for many most valuable services to the cause
of religion and virtue.
Having thus considered the Moral and Political
Philosophy of Paley, and its reception, I have a very
GISBOENE, PEARSON J PRICE, ROBERT HALL. 1 95
fe'w -words to add. The doctrine of Paley -was accept-
ed, as we have seen, in this University, and among
the moralists of the English Church in general. It
might seem that there is something congenial to the
mental habits of Englishmen in a philosophy of this
kind, which, assuming peremptorily an ultimate point
of analysis, receives with some impatience and some
contempt all endeavours to analyse further. " Obli-
gation is the command of a Master who can reward
and punish." This was a maxim which was all the
more easy to assent to, because it spared men the
effort of really understanding what Obligation means.
" Actions are right which tend to increase human hap-
piness." Here, again, was a principle which supplied
the means of stating arguments in favour of all com-
monly-received duties; and though from the same
principle, arguments might be adduced against many
of these duties; and though the principle supplied no
means of weighing one side against the other, the
Paleians rested in security on the repugnance and dis-
favour with which they knew that their hearers in
general would receive the reckoning of the pleasure
produced by vice, when put forwards as a moral ele-
ment. The usual mode of argumentation was simple.
When men spoke of right and wrong as independent
qualities, the English moralist demanded definitions,
or shrugged his shoulders, and declared that he could
not understand the phrases : — when men doubted whe-
ther vice might not sometimes produce an overplus of
pleasure, the English moralist again declared (and no
doubt in general with great truth) that it was disgust-
ful to him to have to balance such an account.
The Englishman who turned his thoughts towards
morals was willing to take the dignity and compla-
cency, but not the labour and risk, of philosophizing ;
— willing to reason, but not willing to confine himself
to precise ideas, so that his reasonings should be con-
clusive; — ^willing to reason in favour of virtue, but not
williag to weigh the reasons of her adversaries. Through
all his pretences at theorizing, he was, in fact, guided
by his practical understanding. He handled for a little
13—2
196 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
■while the ancient Gordian knots of metaphysical con-
troversy, and then cut them across with the hard sharp
weapons which he Tised in daily life. If he were taxed ""
with this inconsistency, he would perhaps reply that
to tie and untie what was so weak a bond in practice,
could he little gain. Yet he might be reminded that
this process brings as its reward all the gain that
man's speculative nature looks for; — the preservation
of a coherent and continuous thread of thought and
reason, through aU the windings of human life and
action. When the strong man's sword alone divides
this complicated line, it presents to us nothing but
detached fiagments and unconnected ends, in which
the rational principle sees only contradiction and ab-
sui-dity ; and by, which the heart, so far as its views
are enlightened by the reason, is disturbed and discon-
tented.
But though in England men dealt so impatiently
with the great moral controversies and systems, these
controversies still went on, and these systems were
still matters of interest, in other parts of the empire.
I wiU give an instance or two of this before quitting
the subject.
It was assumed in this place, as proved, that men
have not a peculiar Moral Faculty; but elsewhere this
Moral Faculty and its analysis were the main subject
of discussion. I have already shown how the school
of Cudworth and Clarke, who ascribed the discern-
ment of moral differences to the Reason, were in a
great measure superseded by the school of Shaftesbury,
who ascribed this perception to a Moral Sense. "We
have seen how ably Hutcheson tore in pieces the old
Clarkian formula. David Hume reasoned with no less
acuteness on the same side. He thus argues against
the opinion that right and wrong consist in relations
of actions'.
" But it [crime] consists in certain moral relations,
discovered by reason, in the same manner as we dis-
cover, by reason, the truths of Geometry or Algebra.
r, VoL II. p. 322.
GISBORNE, PEARSON, PRICE, ROBERT HALL. I97
But what are the relations, I ask, of which you here
talk? In the case stated above, I see first, good will
and good offices in one person; then Ul will and ill
offices in the other. Between these, there is the rela-
tion of contrariety. Does the crime consist in that
relation? But suppose a person bore me ill will, or
did me ill offices; and I, in return, were indifferent
towards him, or did him good offices. Here is the
same relation of contrariety; and yet my conduct is
often highly laudable. Twist and turn this matter as
much as you will, you can never rest the morality on
relation; but must have recourse to the decisions of
sentiment.
"When it is afGrmed that two and three are
equal to the half of ten; this relation of equality I un-
derstand perfectly. I conceive that if ten be divided
into two parts, of which one has as many units as the
other; and if any of these parts be compared to
two added to three, it wiU contain as many units as
that compound number. But when you draw thence
a .comparison to moral relations, I own that I am
altogether at a loss to understand you. A moral ac-
tion, a crime, such as ingratitude, is a complicated
object. Does the morality consist in the relation of
its parts to each other? How? After what manner ?
Specify the relation. Be more particular and explicit
in your propositions, and you will easily see their
falsehood. No, say you, the morality consists in the
relation of actions to the rule of right ? In what does
it consist? How is it determined? By reason, you
say, which examines the moral relations of actions.
So that moral relations are determined by the com-
parison of actions to a rule. And that rule is deter-
mined by considering the moral relations of objects.
Is not this fine reasoning?"
Hutcheson the Irishman, and Hume the Scotch-
man, thus seemed to trample on the very ruins of the
old fortress of immutable morality, which English mo-
ralists had abandoned. But a champion, and a very
able one, soon issued from Wales, and did no little to
restore the fortunes of the fight. I speak of Dr Price,
1 98 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
the son of a dissenting minister in Grlamorganshire,
himself also an eminent dissenting minister. He pub-
lished, in 1757, a volume of Essays, (republished in
1787), in which the foundations of morals are dis-
cussed ; and in this work there are, perhaps, the germs
of a greater change in the prevalent philosophy of the
subject than has yet taken place. He undertook the
then unpopular cause of Immutable and Eternal Mo-
rality. And in him we find that which gives a new
aspect to the controversy; the apprehension of the
imperfection of Locke's philosophy, as being the ground
of the moral fallacy. Price saw that the dogma, that
all our ideas are derived from Sensation and Reflection,
was not readily reconcileable with our apprehension
of Moral Good and Evil; which, it had appeared by
the course of speculation in this century, cannot be
traced to either of these sources. But then, he turns
round and asks, are these the only Ideas which we
cannot refer to these asserted fountains of all Ideas?
Far from it. All our knowledge of all universal truths
involves Ideas which, as much as these, are irreducible
to sensation and reflection. Whence, he asks, is the
idea of impenetrability? of inertia? of substance? of
duration? of space? of cause? These are not ideas of
sensation borrowed from the external world : nor are
they obtained simply by reflection on the world within.
No, — ^he says, — the Lockian account is incomplete.
The understanding itself is a source of new Ideas. Try
the very act of understanding what we contemplate,
we have convictions concerning it which are the source
of truth; and among such convictions, are our con-
^'ictions of moral good and evil. Actions and active
principles have a nature and essence like anything
else; and when we contemplate them, the understand-
ing judges of these as of other objects. A rational
agent can see a difierence of fitness and unfitness in
actions- And if we have given to reason such a sense
that we cannot ascribe this judgment to that faculty;
we must at least ascribe it to that faculty, however we
analyse it, by which we understand, and not to any
sense which we do not understand, but only feeL
GISBORNE, PEARSON, PRICE, ROBERT HALL. 1 99
I shall not pursue this subject further at present.
I ■will only observe that these views of Price seem to
me to be capable of being developed into a very valu-
able corrective of the errors of his contemporaries.
You will not be surprised to find that he expressed a
strong disapprobation of the .doctrine of Paley. In
1787 he published a new edition of his work, and in
this he inserted a Note upon Paley's work. After
giving his statement of some of Paley's principles
(p. 485), he says, " Never have I met with a theory of
morals which has appeared to me more exceptionable."
He then makes objections to some of Paley's special
conclusions, and adds, "I am very sensible of the
merit of many parts of this work. But these parts of
it (those to which he had referred) I have read with
surprise, and also with a concern, the pain of which
has been much increased by the reflection that they
contain principles which have been inculcated many
years at Cambridge, and which therefore have proba-
bly been imbibed by many young persons when under
preparation for public life."
Under present circumstances, it does not appear to
me that I could with advantage to you, my audience,
pursue the history of Moral Philosophy among suc-
ceeding writers. I have not shunned to declare my
conviction that the system of morals which is now
taught among us is unworthy of our descent and
office; and it will be my endeavour in future years, ■
as far as my powers and opportunities allow, further
to point out, and, if possible, to remedy the defects
which I lament. That they are lamented by others
also, by a great body of the well-wishers to our com-
mon country, I do not doubt ; and I shall not hesitate
to conclude by a passage expressive of this feeling,
written by a great preacher of our own time, though
not of our own Church'. "Here I cannot forbear
remarking a great change which has taken place iu
the whole manner of reasoning on the topics of
1 Robert Hall's Sermm, on tlie Sentiments proper to the present Crisis
1803), p. 42.
20O HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
morality and religion, from what prevailed in the last
century, and, as far as my information extends, in
any preceding age. This, which is an age of revolu-
tions, has also produced a strange revolution in the
.method of viewing these subjects, the most important
by far that can engage the attention of man. The
simplicity of our ancestors, noui-ished by the sincere
milk of the word, rather than by the tenets of a dis-
putatious philosophy, was content to let morality
remain on the firm basis of the dictates of conscience
and the will of God. They considered virtue as some-
thing ultimate, as bounding the mental prospect.
They never supposed for a moment there was any-
thing to which it stood merely in the relation of a
means, or that within the narrow confines of this
momentary state anything great enough could be
found to be its end or object. It never occurred to
their imagination that that religion which professes
to render us superior to the world is in reality
nothing more than an instrument to procure the
temporal, the physical good of individuals, or of
society. In their view it had a nobler destination;
it looked forward to eternity : and if ever they appear
to have assigned it any end or object beyond itself, it
was an union with its Author, in the perpetual fi^uition
of God.
"They arranged these things in the following
order : — Religion, comprehending the love, fear, and
service of the Author of our being, they placed first ;
social morality, founded on its dictates, confirmed by
its sanctions, next; and the mere physical good of
society they contemplated as subordinate to both.
Eveiything is now reversed. ' The pyramid is in-
verted : the first is last, and the last first. Religion
is degraded from its pre-eminence, into the mere
handmaid of social morality ; social morality into an
instrument of advancing the welfare of society ; and
the world is all in all. Nor have we deviated less
from the example of antiquity than from that of our
pious forefathers. The philosophers of antiquity, in
the absence of superior light, consulted with reverence
GISBORNE, PEARSON, PRICE, ROBERT HALL. 201
the permanent principles of nature, the dictates of
conscience, and the best feelings of the heart, which
they employed all the powers of reason and eloquence
to unfold, to adorn, to enforce ; and thereby formed a
luminous commentary on the law written on the
heart. The virtue which they inculcated grew out of
the stock of human nature ; it was a warm and living
virtue. It was the moral man, possessing in every
limb and feature, in all its figure and movements, the
harmony, dignity, and variety which belong to the
human form ; an effort of unassisted nature to restore
that image of God which sin had mutilated and de-
faced. Imperfect, as might be expected, their morality
was often erroneous ; but in its great outlines it had
all the stability of the human constitution, and its
fundamental principles wei* coeval and coexistent
with human nature. There could be nothing fluctu-
ating and arbitrary in its more weighty decisions,
since it appealed every moment to the man within the
breast ; it pretended to nothing more than to give
voice and articulation to the inward sentiments of the
heart, and conscience echoed to its oracles. This,
wrought into different systems, and under various
modes of illustration, was the general form which
morality exhibited from the creation of the world till
our time. In this state revelation found it; and,
correcting what was erroneous, supplying what was
defective, and confirming what was right by its pecu-
liar sanctions, superadded a number of supernatural
truths and holy mysteries.
" How is it, that on a subject on which men have
thought deeply from the moment they began to think
and where consequently, whatever is entirely and fun-
damentally new, must be fundamentally false, how is
it, that in contempt of the experience of past ages, and
of all precedents human and divine, we have ventured
into a perilous path which no eye has explored, no foot
has trod ; and have undertaken, after the lapse of six
thousand years, to manufacture a morality of our own,
to decide by a cold calculation of interest, by a ledger-
book of profit and of loss, the preference of truth to
202 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
falsehood, of piety to blasphemy, and of humanity and
justice to treachery and blood?
" In the science of morals we are taught by this
system to consider nothing as yet done ; we are invited
to erect a fresh fabric on a fresh foundation. All the
elements and sentiments which entered into the es-
sence of virtue before are melted down and cast into a
new mould. Instead of appealing to any internal
principle, every thing is left to calculation, and de-
termined by expediency. In executing this plan, the
jurisdiction of conscience is abolished, her decisions
are classed with those of a superannuated judge, and
the determination of moral causes is adjourned from
the interior tribunal to the noisy forum of speculative
debate.
" Everything, without exception, is made an affair
of calculation, under which are comprehended not
merely the duties we owe to our fellow-creatures, but
even the love and adoration which the Supreme Being
claims at our hands. His claims are set aside, or
suffered to lie in abeyance, until it can be determined
how far they can be admitted on the principles of ex-
pediency, and in what respect they may interfere with
the acquisition of temporal advantages. Even here,
nothing is yielded to the suggestions of conscience,
nothing to the movements of the heart : all is dealt
out with a sparing hand, under the stint and measure
of calculation. Instead of being allowed to love God
with all our heart, and all our strength, the first and
great commandment, the portion of love assigned him
is weighed out with the utmost scrupulosity, and the
supposed excess more severely censured than the real
deficiency."
To this I can only say,
Pudet hseo opprobria nobis
Et dici potuisee, et non potuisse refelli.
On us the shame
That we must bear and not refute the blame.
LECTUEE XIII.'
Bentham— His Biography — His Style or Dis-
cussion.
IN order to complete our view of the progress of
Moral Philosophy in England in recent times, I
■will give some account of Jeremy Bentham and his
speculations on the subjects with which we are here
concerned : for no moralist has been placed so high by
his admirers, or has been more resolute and compre-
hensive in applying his principles to practical policy
and legislation. The school of Bentham, for a time,
afforded as near a resemblance as modem times can
show, of the ancient schools of philosophy, which were
formed and held together by an almost unbounded
veneration for their master, and in which the disciples
were content to place their glory in understanding and
extending the master's principles. And though, to the
general public, the Benthamite doctrines had an ex-
ceedingly harsh and repulsive aspect, and were made
formidable by the sweeping purposes of reform with
which they were connected; yet Bentham 's real acute-
ness in discussion, his laborious perseverance, his ex-
hibitions of complete and exhaustive systems of analysis
and reasoning on many of the largest political ques-
tions; gave him great weight with many statesmen
both at home and abroad. Perhaps few moral and
political writers have exercised a greater influence
upon their generation than he has done; and to us
he is especially interesting as manifesting in a more
complete and consistent form the results of that scheme
of morality, which, in a less resolute manner, was put
forwards by Paley.
1 This and the following Lectures were not delivered in the first course.
204 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
Bentham lived in our own time, (lie died in 1832 ;)
and by the ardent zeal of his disciples and admirers,
and by his publications continued to the time of his
death, and the references of other writers to them,
was kept in a peculiar manner present to our minds
as a contemporary. Yet by the earlier period of his
life he belonged rather to the literature of the last
century. He belonged to a club where he met John-
son'; he was not much younger than Burke; he
attended Blackstone's Vinerian lectures, and after-
wards criticised the Gommenta/ries as a contemporary
work; he was anticipated unexpectedly by Paley in
publishing a theory of morals founded upon TJtility.
But he was, through his long period of literary ac-
tivity, eminently consistent. He adopted very early
the views and doctrines which he employed his life in
inculcating ; and he also showed very early that pe-
culiar onesidedness in his mode of asserting and urg-
ing his opinions which made him think all moderation
with regard to his opponents superfluous and absurd.
Here we are not concerned directly with the main
field of his exertions. Jurisprudence, and the Politics
of the time; but Morality, in his view and in our
view, is clearly connected with the former of these,
Jurisprudence; and his doctrines on Morality have
excited perhaps quite as much notice as on the other
subjects.
It may be worth our while to notice some circum-
stances connected with the earlier period of Bentham's
literary and personal history. He was bom in London
in 1748. His father was a prosperous attorney, ex-
tremely desirous of the worldly prosperity of his son,
whose precocious talents promised to gratify the pa-
ternal wish. He was sent to Queen's College, Oxford,
at the unusually early age of twelve; and took his
degree, not only of B.A. but of M. A. before he was of
full man's age. Many of his school and college ex-
ercises have been published by the affectionate zeal of
1 Johnson, b. 1709, 4 1784; Bnrke, b. 1730, d. 17157; Bentham, b. 1748,
d. 1832.
BENTHAM — HIS BIOGRAPHY. 205
Ms biographer, (Dr Bowring,) and show an average
acquaintance witli the Latin language ; which is no-
ticeable, because at a later period Bentham, probably
having lost his acquaintance with the ancient writers,
in consequence of a contempt for them which he care-,
fully nourished and inculcated, scarcely ever made any
reference to Greek or Latin without showing some ex-
traordinary ignorance.
He appears to have been unhappy at Oxford, and
to have learnt little there: but in later life, he was
accustomed to refer to this period his adoption of his
favourite universal principle of Morals and Polities'.
Dr Priestley published his Essay on Government in
ij68. He there introduced in italics, as the only rea-
sonable and proper object of government, the greatest
happiness of the greatest Tvumber. Mr Bentham feU in
with this book at " a little circulating library belong-
ing to a little coffee-house " close to Queen's College.
By this expression of Priestley, Bentham conceived
that his own principles on the subject of Morality,
public and private, were determined. For us, who
have traced the progress of opinions on this subject
and of doctrines of this kind in other writers, it is
evident that there was in the general current of lite-
rature and thought at that time a set towards such
doctrines and such expressions ; and indeed Bentham
himself pointed out other previous writers iu whom
expressions and thoughts very similar occur. This
being the case, it is extraordinary that he should so
constantly have talked of himself, and have been
talked of by his admirers, as the discoverer of the
principle; the more so, as it was soon after, by Paley,
put forth in a systematic manner, and unfolded into a
treatise on Morality. But Bentham appears to have
been one of those persons to whom every thing which
passes throiigh their own thoughts assumes quite a
different character and value from that which the
same thing had when it passed through the thoughts
of other persons.
1 Deontol. i. 298.
206 HISTOKT OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
Bentham, from this time, was engaged ia follow-
LQg out his principle; but how far it assumed addi-
tional value in his hands we may afterwards have to
examine. He also then or soon afterwards assumed
the office, which he repeatedly exercised at subsequent
periods, of a severe and pungent critic of current doc-
trines and their authors. The disposition to such cri-
ticism gave rise to his first considerable publication,
A Fragment on Government. This subject was pro-
bably suggested to him in an .especial manner by his
residence at Oxford; for the work was a critique of
certain portions of the Commentaries of Blackstone,
whom, as I have said, he had himself heard lecturing.
The Commentaries on the Laws of Eriglamd, then re-
cently published, had been received with great general
favour, and acquired at once the reputation they stUl,
I believe, retain. Yet probably there are few persons
who, looking at the work carefully, will hold that it
is composed in a very philosophical spirit, or that the
general reasonings which are introduced, and those on
Government in particular, are rigorous and blameless.
Probably most of the admirers of the work, looking to
it for merit of quite other kinds — a clear and connect-
ed exposition of the existing law of England — ^would
not think the goodness or badness of logic and philo-
sophy of the author's general preliminary reflections, a
matter of much consequence. Not such was the tem-
per of Bentham. A fallacy, a sophism, or what he
thought such, was to him an inevitable provocation to
a vehement attack; and on this as on other occasions,
he rushed upon such things as his prey, with some-
thing of the instinctive keenness with which a cat
springs upon a mouse. I think we may allow that
many of his objections to Blackstone's loose general
talk are reasonable, though we may doubt whether it
was worth while to write a book about them; and still
more, whether it was worth while to publish in impe-
tuous haste, that Fragment of a book which referred
to these generalities, while the part which referred to
the main body of the work, "the Comment on the
Commentaries," which he also meditated, remained
BENTHAM — HIS STYLE OF DISCUSSION. 207
behind unexecuted. But it ■was ngt unnatural that
■with his vehement con^victions and with his lively
mind he should be eager to find some opportunity of
appearing before the public.
In this work he introduced Utility as the funda-
mental principle of political morality; — as the test, for
instance, ■when resistance to government is allowable.
Thus Ch. IV. Art. xx. " It is the principle of utility
accurately apprehended and steadily applied, that affords
the only clew to guide a man through these straights."
And Art. xxi. " It is then, we may say, and not till
then, allowable to, if not incumbent on, every man, as
well on the score of duty as of interest, to enter into
measures of resistance, when, according to the best
calculation he is able to make, the probable mischiefs
of resistance (speaking with respect to the community
in general) appear less to him than the probable mds-
chiefs of submission^ ." You will recollect how very
closely this approaches to the doctrine delivered by
Paley a few years later, (this was ui'iyye), and to the
manner of delivering it. It was a point to which the
doctrines of Locke and his successors had gradually
led; but which, when stated in this fearless and point-
ed manner, naturally excited some notice; startling
some, while to others it sounded like a new-discovered
axiom.
It does not appear that at this time Bentham had
learnt to consider the term utility as a far more im-
perfect expression of his favourite principle, than the
greatest ffood of the greatest number, which he after-
wards much preferred. We may remark in this Frag-
ment some specimens of a candour which' he seems
ever afterwards to have thought too weak to be re-
peated; for he speaks ■with considerable approbation
(in the Preface to the Fragment) of Blackstone's style,
and his exposition of the Law. So with regard to the
doctrine of the Original Compact, which Bentham con-
demns as a Fiction, and a Fiction which his admirers
1 So Ch. I, xlTiii. "Now this other { trhat other can it be than the prvn-
piinciple that still recurs upon us, | dpfeo/UTniTT?"
208 HISTOET OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
consider him as having utterly demolished; — not, I
think, quite supported in this view by the subsequent
history of political discussion; — but with regard to
Fictions in general, on the occasion of this, he speaks
with a moderation which he afterwards altogether dis-
carded. (Ch. 1. Art. xxxvii.) "With regard to this
and other fictions, there was once a time, perhaps,
when they had their use. With instnunents of this
temper, I wiU not deny but that some political work
may have been done, and that, useful work which
under the then circumstances of things could hardly
have been done with any other." In the Preface to
the second edition, published at a long subsequent
period (1828), he no longer used such moderate lan-
guage. On the contrary he says (p. 243), " A fiction
of law may be defined a wilful falsehood, having for
its object the stealing legislative power by or for
hands which could not, or durst, not, openly claim it,
— and but for the delusion thus exercised could not
exercise it. Thus it was that, by means of mendacity,
usurpation was got up, exercised, and established."
And he then goes on to illustrate this '.'power-stealing
system," as he calls it, remarking that mendacity is a
name too soft for falsehood thus applied; — says that it
is practised to procure profit to the judge or judges;
— ^that they are called the court for the sake of letting
in the servants to a share of the worship paid to the
master, and so on.
This pass^e, in the second edition, is a specimen
of the impossibility, under which Bentham soon began
to labour, of seeing anything but felsehood, fraud, and
self-seeking greediness, in the character of those whose
doctrines he attacked. His constant habit is to assume
himself to be in the right, and to treat his adversaries
with ridicule and contempt: and among other forms
of contempt, with that of ascribing to them arguments
and expressions utterly different from those they ever
used : as if it was not worth while reading their books,
or. attending to what they say; and as if they were
not sufficiently his equals to make it possible that
they should be treated with injustice. He was in the
BENTHAM — HIS STYLE OF DISCUSSION. 209
habit of declaiming against them whenever he had
occasion to mention them, undoubtedly with great
vivacity and fertility of language, but without the
smallest fairness; and very often he declaimed against
them, for their declamation, in a manner hardly less
comic than Sir Anthony Absolute's anger at his ne-
phew's anger. Thus he says (p. 8i), that "the all-
comprehensive, all-directing, greatest happiness-prin-
ciple, is in some shape or other, in some point or other
brought forward" in every attempt at reform. "But
of this fountain of all political as well as moral good,
the water is an- object of horror to all who are en-
gaged in the war of politics: the sound or the sight
of it is to them that which the touch of the salted
holy water is to the unclean spirits; to the unclean
spirits on both sides; and at the bottom no less than
at the top of the world of politics all spirits that move
in it are unclean. From this field of universal de-
pravity arises at all times a loud and indefatigable
cry of excellence," and so on (p. 81). The passage
ends with some phrases of religious reverence used in
ironical mockery, which is also, I am sorry to say,
not at all unusual in Bentham's writings. I shall,
however, have more to say of Bentham's mode of
arguing when we come to deal with his doctrines
themselves: for the present, I wish to point out in
some measure the manner in which they came before
the world.
The reception of the Fragment on Government was
not altogether unprosperous ; but probably far less
favourable than the author, in the glow of reforming
zeal and triumphant conviction, had expected. " No
sooner," he afterwards said, "had my farthing candle
been taken out of the bushel, thaji I looked for the
descent of torches to it from the highest regions : my
imagination presented to my view torches descending
in crowds to borrow its fire." Anything which could
be described precisely thus, did not happen. But the
work, published without the author's name, was as-
cribed to many of the greatest men of the day: to
Lord Mansfield, Lord Camden, Lord Ashburton. It
U
2IO HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
was the means of introducing Bentham to Lord Shel-
bume, and thus of making him a frequent visitor at
Bowood. And these visits formed the happiest part
of his life, and veiy much influenced his future career.
He had turned aside from the practice of the law,
in which his &ther had tried to involve him ; he now
ga,ve himseE entirely to his political and moral specu-
lations, and was soon looked upon by his friends as
an acute and powerftil thiaker, and a great master
of political and jurisprudential pjiilosophy; — of course
of the most liberal cast. He was employed upon a
work On the Principles of Morals ami Legislation,
which was already printed in 1781, though not pub-
lished tUl 1789. In his Prefe«e to the second edition,
— ^a most amusing piece of autobiography, — he nar-
rates, (Art. XII.) that Lord Shelbume got into his
hand^ the unpublished treasure of wisdom, and could
not be withheld from reading it to the ladies at the
breakfiist-table; and that, iuasmuch as all the great
springs of human action were distinctly referred to,
this occasioned some embarrassment.
But this Pre&ce is most curious as illustrating
what I have already said, that Bentham could not
conceive that those who dissented from him in any de-
gree, were not actuated by some selfish view and some
fraudulent purpose. He could not understand how
his Fragment had not drawn more public notice, and
led to greater results. He knew that it had been
seen by several eminent persons; as Wedderbum,
afterwards Lord Loughborough, Lord Mansfield, Lord
Camden, Mr Dunning, CoL Barr6: and the mode in
which he accounts for their slight notice of the work
is very curious and amusing. Wedderbum had said
that it was a dangerous book ; and Bentham declares
that at the time it was inconceivable to him. how
utility could be dangerous; but afberwards he came
to see clearly that Wedderbum meant that it would
be dangerous to the mass of power, wealth, and fac-
titious dignity which such persons as he enjoyed at
other people's expense. Lord Mansfield, when it was
read to him, had said at parts, "now he seems to be
BENTHAM — HIS STYLE OP DISCUSSION. 211
slumbering;" and at other parts, "now he is awake
again." Bentham afterwards discovered that there
was a heart-burning between Lord Mansfield and
Blackstone, and at a later period he saw that the
wakeful pai-ts to Lord Mansfield were those in which
was seen the tormentor of Ms tormentor; the sleepy
plDrfcions, those in which there was a liberalism and
a logic threatening his despotism and rhetoric. Lord
Camden, who was a guest along with him at Bowood,
told him that he played too loud in accompanying
Miss Pratt on the violin, and that he ate too much;
besides never speaking to him of his book. Dunning
too was a guest there, and merely scowled at him.
Col. Barr6, another guest thpre, was to him stately
and distant; and when Bentham gave him an Essay
of his on Deodands to read. Col. Barr6 said, " Mr Ben-
tham, you have got yourself into a scrape;" which
Bentham afterwards discovered to mean that he had
written what was against the interest of the ruling
few. And Bentham is quite clear in his conviction
that it could not be anything in his own manners
that drew on him this repulsive behaviour : for Miss
Pratt did not share her father's rage at the loud
playing, nor did Mrs Dunning, whose music his violin
also accompanied. It was the fear of danger to their
own interests which made all those men neglect Ben-
tham's writings, treat him with coldness, and enter
into a confederacy to keep him back, which for a time
succeeded. Even Lord Shelbume's kindness to him
was stimulated, he thinks, by that nobleman's quarrel
with Blackstone; and when one day he said, " Mr Ben-
tham, what is it you can do for me V he wanted help
to his party which Bentham would not undertake to
give. Some years afterwards he surprised Lord Shel-
bume much by asking him for a seat in Parliament
somewhat vehemently (in a letter of sixty-one pages),
but took very good humouredly the refusal which was
involved in the reply.
But Bentham had already, as I have said, gone on
from the Fragment, to the composition and printing
of his Principles of Morals and Legislation. His
14—2
212 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
friends already called him "the Newton of legisla-
tion," and imdoubtedly he expected that the pubKca-
tion of his ■work wonld make the world regard him in
that light. Why he delayed so long the publication
of the work already printed, I do not know : but a
little later he was induced by various causes to travel
into Bussia (1784). During the time that he was
there, Paley's Principles of Moral and Political Phi-
losophy was published, in 1785 ; and Bentham's friends
could not fail to see in how great a degree this antici-
pated his system. His correspondent, George Wilson,
gives him this account. "There is a Mr Paley, a
parson and archdeacon of Carlisle, who has written a
book called Principles of Moral and Political Philo-
sophy, in quarto, and it has gone through two editions
with prodigious applause. It is founded entirely on
utility, or, as he chooses to call it, the will of God as
declared by expediency, to which he adds, as a supple-
ment, the revealed will of Grod. But notwithstanding
this, and some weak places, particularly as to oaths
and subscriptions, where he is hampered by his pro-
fession and his past conduct, it is a capital book, and
by much the best that has been written on the subject
in this country. Almost everything he says about
morals, government, and our own constitution, is
sound, practical, and free from commonplace. He has
got many of your notions about punishment, which
I always thought the most important of your disco-
veries; and I could almost suspect, if it were possible,
that he had read your Introduction; and I do very
much fear that, if you ever do publish on those stib-
jects, you may be charged with stealing from him
what you have honestly invented with the sweat of
your own brow. But for all that, I wish you would
come and try; for I am stiU persuaded, my dear
Bentham, that you have for some years been throwing
away your time ; and that the way in which you would
be most likely to benefit the world and yourself is, by
establishing, in the first place, a great literary reputa-
tion in your own language, and in this country which
you despise." He goes on to notice as an example of
BENTHAM — HIS STYLE OF DISCUSSION, 213
Paley's merits, his inquiry into the guilt of a drunken
man who kills another, and the quantum of punish-
ment which ought to be applied to him ; " which is,"
he says, " as correct and exhaustive as if you had done
it yourself"
In reply to this, Bentham writes in a strain of
grotesque pleasantry : " I had ordered horses for Eng-
land to take triumphant possession of the throne of
legislation, but finding it full of Mr Paley, I ordered
them back into the stable. Since then I have been
torturing myself to no purpose, to find any blind alley
in the career of fame, which Mr Paley's magnanimity
may have disdained." And again, in the same letter,
"To speak seriously of Parson Paley, I should not
have expected so much from him, &c. People were
surprised to see how green my eyes were for some
time after I received your letter, but their natural
jetty lustre is now pretty well returned." It would
seem that some of his friends having their attention
fixed on Bentham alone, and not attending to the
course of thought in the rest of the world, could not
get rid of the absurd notion of Paley having had some
intimation of Bentham's doctrines. Wilson again re-
turns to it two years later: "I have often been
tempted to think that Paley had either seen your
Introduction or had conversed with some one who
was intimate with you." And the biographer who
publishes these letters gravely refers from the one
passage to the other, as if they confirmed each other.
But when driven, as any sober thought must drive
them, from this empty conjecture, they have recourse
to the most extravagant assertions of the difierence
between Paley's and Bentham's doctrines. Thus in
Bentham's Deontology we are told by the same bio-
grapher (Dr Bowring), that Paley " mentions the prin-
ciple of utility, but seems to have no notion of its
bearing on happiness." The person who writes thus
can hardly, it would seem, have seen Paley's book.
But he appears, like Bentham himself, to have thought
that he had means of knowing what Paley's doctrines
miist be, which made it superfluous to examine what
214 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY,
they -were. " And if," adds this disciple of Bentham,
" Paley had any such idea" as that of the bearing of
utility on happiness, "he was the last man to give
expression to it." Observe the reason "why. "The
work was for the youth of Cambridge," of one of the
Colleges of which he was tutor. Now Paley had left
the Pniversity ten years before, and his book was not
adopted by the University till some time afterwards.
But let us hear the writer's account of Cambridge.
" In that meridian eyes were not strong enough, nor
did he desire they should be strong enough, to endure
the light from the orb of utilitarian felicity." But
how does the writer know what Paley desii-ed? By
deducing from a rumoured pleasantry of Paley, an
account of his character and habits utterly at variance
with known truth. " Insincere himself, and the bold,
often declared, advocate of insincerity, over his bottle
those who knew him, knew that he was the self-
avowed lover and champion of comiption, rich enough
to keep an equipage, but not (as he himself declared)
rich enough to keep a conscience." In general " con-
science" is not spoken of by the Benthamites with
much reverence; but let us not quarrel with their
inconsistency in this respect. Let us, however, look
once more at the state of their knowledge respecting
the English Universities. " For the remaining twenty
years of his (Paley's) life, his book was the text-book
of the Universities." For the ten preceding years
and all the remaining years of his life, Paley had no
share in the conduct of his University : the book was
gradually introduced into use by the taste of indi-
vidual examiners, but for a very long time not re-
cognized formally by the University of Cambridge;
and at Oxford it has never, I think, been at all coun-
tenanced. So far, however, as at any place it has
been received, it has been received as the exposition
of a system which founds morality upon the promotion
of human happiness; and it is a curious example of
jealousy for the master's honour overcoming regard
for the doctrine, when this admiring Benthamite goes
on to say that Paley "left the utilitarian controversy
BENTHAM — HIS STYLE OF DISCUSSION, 215
as lie found it, not even honouring the all-beneficent
principle with one additional passing notice."
It may seem superfluous to notice misstatements
so gross and partiality so blind: but without at all
wishing to deny great merit to some of Bentham's
labours, (as I shall soon have to show), I am obliged
to say that such misrepresentations and such unfair-
ness are the usual style of controversy of him and his
disciples; and it is fit that we, in entering upon the
consideration of their writings, should be aware of
this. I conceive it was more to Paley's credit to
"leave the utilitarian controversy where he found it,"
than to carry it forwards by such ways of managing it
as these : — although, in truth, it is difficult to see how
a writer could do more for the doctrine of utility than
Paley did, by deducing from it a system which, as
George Wilson, Bentham's great admirer, said, was
sound, practical, and free from commonplace. But
we shall now return to Bentham • and this I shall do
in the next Lecture.
LECTURE XIY.
Bentham — His Pkinciples of Mokals and
LEGISIiATION.
BEFORE I notice any of Bentham's more peculiar
merits, I must again illustrate the extravagant
unfairness to adversaries which was habitual in him.
The Inlroduclvm, to the Principles of Morals wad
Legislation appeared before the public in 1789. The
first chapter of this work is "On the Principle of
Utility;" the second, "On Principles adverse to that
of Utility." These adverse principles are stated to
be two : The Prraciple of Asceticism, and the Prin-
ciple of Sympathy. The Principle of Asceticism is
that principle which approves of actions in proportion
as they tend to diminish human happiness, and con-
versely, disapproves of them as they tend to augment
it. (ch. II. § in.) The Principle of Sympathy (§ xii.)
is that which approves or disapproves of certain ac-
tions, "merely because a man finds himself disposed
to approve or disapprove of them, holding up that
approbation or disapprobation as a sufficient reason
for itself, and disclaiming the necessity of looking out
for any extrinsic ground." And these two Principles
are, it seems, according to Bentham's view, the only
Principles which are, or which can be, opposed to the
Principle of Utility !
Now it is plain that these are not only not fair
representations of any principles ever held by moral-
ists, or by any persoiis speaking gravely and deli-
berately, but that they are too extravagant and fan-
tastical to be accepted even as caricatures of any such
BENTHAM — HIS MORALS AND LEGISLATION. 217
principles. Tor who ever approved of actions because
they tend to make mankind miserable? or who ever
said anything which could, even in an intelligible
way of exaggeration, be so represented? Is it possible
to guess at whom a writer is pointing who allows him-
self such Kcense as this? To me, I confess, it appears
quite impossible. From, these phrases, I should have
had no conception what class of moralists were thus
held up to ridicule. For of course every one feels
that this description of them is given in order to
make them ridiculous, even while the expression is
grave and tranquil ; and Bentham's humour runs
into extremes which remove even the assumption of
gravity.
But who then are the ascetic school who are thus
ridiculed? We could not, I think, guess from the
general description thus given; but from a note, it
appears, that he had the Stoical Philosophers and the
Keligious Ascetics in his mind. With regard to the
Stoics, it would of course be waste of time and thought
to defend them from such coarse buflFoonery as this,
which does not touch their defects, whatever those
may be. With regard to the Religious Ascetics, I
may notice a further trait in Bentham's account of
them, in order to show how strongly the spirit of
satire grew upon him. He says that the principle of
following certain courses of action, because they make
men miserable, has been extensively pursued by men
in their treatment of themselves, but only rarely in
their treatment of others, and particularly in matters
of government; — that saints have often "voluntarily
yielded themselves a prey to vermin ; but though many
persons of this class have wielded the reins of empire,
we read of none who have set themselves to work and
made laws on purpose with a view of stocking the
body politic with the breed of highwaymen, house-
breakers, and incendiaries. If at any time they have
sufi'ered the nation to be preyed upon by swarms of
idle pensioners, or useless placemen, it has rather been
from negligence and imbecility than from any settled
plan of oppressing and plundering of the people."
2l8 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
This might appear, one would think, severe and sar-
castic enough. But this moderation of his earlier
time, -when the habit of condemning had not been
enflamed by the deference of a school, did not satisfy
his later and more imperious mood. In a subsequent
edition he appends to this passage a note, " So thought
anno 1780 and 1789, not so anno 1814, J. Bentham."
To acquit the governors of nations of a settled plan of
oppressing and plundering the people out of a desire
for their misery, and of nourishing for this purpose
the vermiu of the body poUtic, was only possible for
Bentham in the guileless innocence and blind con-
fidence of his youth.
And so much for the ascetic principle according
to Bentham; for you will recoUect that at present,
I am not discussing his doctrines, but pointing out
his habits of thought and expression ; — a task which
will not be without its value in enabling us to esti-
mate his doctrines and his arguments.
Perhaps, however, in order to show the effect pro-
duced by this mode of arguing, if arguing it is to be
called, I may quote one of Mr Bentham's disciples, who
at a later period (in 1832) published the Deontology
of his master, and added some remarks of his own.
" The ascetic principle," he says, " received a mortal
wound from Mr Bentham, by his exposure of it in
the Introdiiction to Morals and Legislation. No man
is, perhaps, now to be found who would contend that
the pursuit of pain ought to be the great object of
existence." It is marvellous to find a man who had
so entirely confined his attention to Bentham's writ-
ings, as to suppose that there ever were such people,
merely because Bentham had said so, in what I must
be allowed to call his buffoonery.
But this is not a solitary instance of the kind
of worship with which Bentham was treated. Every
farcical representation which he gave of his opponents
was considered as a clear victory, because nobody
could be found to own it, as indeed it fitted nobody.
He had his world all to himself; for he described Ms
adversaries as he chose, and neither he nor his fol-
BENTHAM — HIS MORALS AND LEGISLATION. 219
lowers generally took any pains to compare Us de-
scriptions of these adversaries with their own account
of their own opinions.
This may be seen in the case of the other Prin-
ciple, adverse to that of Utility, which Bentham men-
tions — the Principle of Sympathy. For who ever
asserted that he approved or disapproved of actions
merely because he found himself disposed to do so,
and that this was reason sufficient in itself for his
moral judgments? Or what advantage can be gained
to moral philosophy by such misrepresentations as
this, whatever it be which is thus misrepresented?
which is a point, here, as in the other case, quite
obscure, in consequence of the reckless extravagance
of the misrepresentation. In a note however, again,
we learn that the philosophers who are all included
in this account are Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Hume,
Beattie, Price, Clarke, WoUaston, and many others.
And as a further example of Bentham's mode of deal-
ing with such matters, I may notice what he says of
one class of these. "One man says he has a thing
made on purpose to tell him what is right and what
is wrong : and that it is called a moral sense, and then
he goes to work at his ease, and says, such a thing is
right, and such a thing is wrong. Why? 'Because
my moral sense tells me so.'" And after treating
various other classes of moralists with the like fair-
ness, he has suitably led the way to the last class
which he mentions. " The fairest and openest of all
is the sort of man who speaks out and says, I am of
the number of the Elect: now God himself takes
care to inform the Elect what is right : &c. &c. If
therefore a man wants to know what is right and
what is wrong, he has nothing to do but to come
to me."
Extravagant as this ridicule is — for I should try
in vain to conceal my opinion that it is nothing better
than extravagant ridicule — it has been accepted in per-
fectly good faith and humble admiration by Mr Ben-
tham's followers. The editor of the Deontology says
with the greatest gravity (i. 321), "The antagonist to
2 20 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
the felicity -maximising principle is the ipse-dixit prin-
ciple." And he considers this as so settled a matter
that he proposes to use the derivatives of this term,
and to speak of ipse-dixitists and ipse-dixitism. Cer-
tainly, if there have ever been, in modern times, per-
sons who have quoted the words of their master with
a deference equal to that which in ancient times gave
rise to the phrase ipse dixit, the disciples of Mr Ben-
tham are peculiarly and eminently ipse-dixitists.
But wild as this mode of dealing with adverse
moralists is, (and we have seen that it is used towards
all the most eminent moralists of the preceding cen-
tury,) Bentham appears to have soon come to think
that it was too good for them. The Principle of Sym-
pathy and Antipathy, was, he began to think, too
tolerant a designation for the doctrine of those who
had recognized any other basis of morality than
Utility. In 1789, he added to his work a note in
which he said that the Principle ought rather to be
styled the Principle of Caprice. It is evident that
such an expression could only mean that the person
using it could not, or wovdd not, understand the
reasons given by those whom he thus called capricious.
And so fer, no doubt, it had a meaning. It is easy
for two opposite parties, who do not and will not
understand each other's views and opinions, to call
each other capricious, as it is to call each other by
any other condemnatory term; but it is plain this
shows nothing but the incapacity for arguing, in
those who use such terms. When men have written
long and careful and acute trains of reasoning and
speculations, as the moralists have whom Bentham
condemns, a man must have an almost fatuous con-
fidence in his own opinions, and in the deference of
his readers, who fancies he can dispose of the whole
of this by saying it merely expresses the Principle of
Caprice.
The same note contains another very curious ex-
ample of the incredible confidence in himself, and
carelessness of what was urged by others, with which
Bentham disposed of doctrines which he rejected. He
BENTHAM — HIS MORALS AND LEGISLATION. 221
says that many maxims of law have derived their
authority merely from the love of jingle — which he
further illustrates by some laborious pleasantry about
Orpheus and Themis: and he gives, as his examples,
Delegatus non ^potest delega/re, and Servitus Servitutis
non datur.
I may notice, too, as examples of the boldness for
which we must be prepared in dealing with his doc-
trines, the imperious manner in which he rejects and
alters the significations of words. Thus, in illustrating
the Principle of Antipathy (§ xiv. note), he says that
it is on this principle that certain acts are repro-
bated, as being unnatural — for instance the practice
of exposing children. No, he says, this language is
not to be allowed. Unnatural, when it means any-
thing, means unfrequent ; and here it is not the un-
frequency, but the frequency of the act of which you
complain. It is curious that he should have thought
he could prevent men from calling, as they used to do,
acts unnatural, which are contrary to those natural
and universal feelings which aU men recognize as the
proper guides of life. But that was precisely the ground
of his displeasure with the word. It recognized, in
parental afiection, a natural and acknowledged guide
of human action: and this recognition was to be con-
tradicted. This however leads us to the doctrines
themselves, which we are not here discussing.
At a later period Bentham became quite wanton
and reckless in his innovations in language ; but even
at the period which we are now considering, that of
the publication of the Introduction, he altered the sig-
nification of many words in a very arbitrary manner;
a manner for which we ought to be prepared in read-
ing him. Thus, in estimating pleasures, he speaks of
their pv/rity as one element of their value : but by this
he does^ not mean their freedom from grossness — for
he aeknowledges no value in this kind of pv/rity, and
no evU in grossness : his purity is the freedom of plea-
sure from the mixture of pain.
Again he says, (c. v. i.) " Pains and pleasures may
be called by one word, interesting perceptions :" which
222 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
tHey may, only if we disregard the ordinary meaning
of the word.
I might ppint out, as examples of Bentham's sslf-
oomplacent boldness, his extraordinary misstatements
with regard to the classical languages and their lite-
rature; for instance, his ascribing the doctrine of the
four cardinal virtues to Aristotle; and the equally
extraordinary confusion which prevails in his attempt
to arrange the sciences, a confusion which necessarily
resulted from his complete ignorance of the subject.
But it is our more special business to regard him as a
moralist.
In considering Bentham's system of Morality, I
by no means wish to make it my sole business to
point out the errors and defects of it. On the con-
trary, it will be very important to my purpose to show
what amount of truth there resides in it; since by so
doing, I shall both account for the extensive accept-
ance which it has found, and shall be advancing to-
wards that system which contains all that is true in
all preceding systems : and that is plainly the system
at which we of this day ought to aim.
Of Bentham's system, indeed, we have in a great
measure spoken, in speaking of Paley's : for as I have
said, the two systems are in principle the same; and
the assertions of Bentham's followers as to the great
difference of the two systems, vanish on examination.
The basis of Paley's scheme is Utility: — Utility for
the promotion of Human Happiness. Human Hap-
piness is composed of Pleasures : — Pleasures are to be
estimated by their intensity and Duration. All this
Paley has. Has Bentham anything more? He has
nothing more which is essential in the scheme of Mo-
rality, so far as this groundwork goes. For though in
enumerating the elements in the estimate of pleasures,
Bentham adds to Intensity and Duration, others, as
Certainty, Propinquity, Fecundity, Purity (in- the
sense which I have spoken of); these do not much
alter the broad features of the scheme. But undoubt-
edly Bentham attempts to build upon this groundwork
more systematically than Paley does. If there is to
BENTHAM — BIS MORALS AND LEGISLATION. 223
be a Morality erected on sucli a basis as that just
described, the pleasures (and the pains as well) which
are the guides and governors of human action must be
enumerated^ classed, weighed and measured. It is by
determioing the value of a lot of pleasure (the phrase
is Bentham's) resulting from an act, that the moral
value of an act is known, in this system. We must
therefore haye all the pleasures which man can feel,
passed in review; and all the ways in which these
pleasures can increase or diminish by human actions.
This done, we shall be prepared to pass judgment on
human actions, and to assign to each its rank and
value in 'the moral scale; its title to reward or punish-
ment on these principles.
Can this be done? Has Bentham done this? If
he has, is it not really a valuable task performed?
These questions naturally occur.
In reply, I may say that the task would undoubt-
edly be a valuable one, if it were possible; but that,
so fer as the moral value of actions is concerned, it is
not possible, for reasons which I will shortly state;
that even for the appropriation of punishment in the
construction of laws, — the purpose for which the author
mainly intended it, — it is far from completely exe-
cuted, or perhaps capable of being completely executed;
but that the attempt to execute it in a complete and
systematic manner, over the whole field of human
action, led to many useful and important remarks on
schemes of law and of punishment; and that these,
along with the air of system, which has always a
great effect upon men, not unnaturally won for Ben-
tham great attention, and even gave a sort of ascend-
ancy to the rough and distorting pleasantry which he
exercised towards opponents. I may afterwards speak
of his merits as a jural and political philosopher, but I
must first explain why, as I conceive, his mode of
estimating *the moral value of actions cannot suffice
for the purposes of Morality.
Let it be taken for granted, as a proposition which
is true, if the terms which it involves be duly under-
stood, that actions are right and virtuous in propor-
2 24 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
tion as they promote the happiness of mankind ; the
actions being considered upon the whole, and with
regard to all their consequences. Still, I say, "we can-
not make this truth the basis of morality, for two
reasons : first, we cannot calculate all the consequences
of any action, ^nd thus cannot estimate the degree in
which it promotes human happiness ; — second, happi-
ness is derived from moral elements, and therefore we
cannot properly derive morality from happiness. The
calculable happiness resulting from actions cannot
determine their virtue ; first, because the resulting
happiness is not calculable ; and secondly, because the
virtue is one of the things which determines' the re-
sulting happiness.
These asisertions are, I think, tolerably evident of
themselves; but we may dwell upon them a little
longer. First, I say the amount of happiness result-
ing from any action is not calculable. If we ask
whether a given action will increase or diminish the
total amount of human happiness, it is impossible to
answer with any degree of certainty. Take ordinary
cases. I am tempted to utter a flattering falsehood:
to gratify some sensual desire contrary to ordinary
moral rules. How shall I determine, on the greatest
happiness-principle, whether the act is virtuous or the
contrary? In the first place, the direct efiect of each
act is to give pleasure, to another by flattery, to
myself by sensual gratification: and pleasure is the
material of happiness, in the scheme we are now con-
sidering. But by the flattering lie, I promote false-
hood, which is destructive of confidence, and so, of
human comfort. Granted that I do this, in some
degree,— although I may easily say, that I shall never
allow myself to speak falsely, except when it will give
pleasure, and thus, I may maintain that I shall not
shake confidence in any case in which it is of any
value; but granted that I do in some degree shake the
general fabric of mutual human confidence, by my
flattering lie,— still the question remains, how much I
do this; whether in such a degree as to overbalance
the pleasure, which is the primary and direct conse-
BENTHAM — HIS MORALS AND LEGISLATION. 225
quence of the act. How small must be the effect of
my solitary act upon the whole scheme of human
action and habit ! how clear and decided is the direct
effect of increasiag the happiness of my hearer ! And
in the same way we may reason concerning the sen-
sual gratification. The pleasure is evident and cer-
tain; the effect on other men's habits obscure and
uncertain. Who will know it? Who will be influ-
enced by it of those who do know it? What appre-
ciable amount of pain will it produce in its conse-
quences, to balance the palpable pleasure, which,
according to our teachers, is the only real good? It
appears to me that it is impossible to answer these
questions in any way which will prove, on these
principles, mendacious flattery, and illegitimate sen-
suality, to be vicious and immoral. They may pos-
sibly produce, take in all their effects, a balance of
evil ; but if they do, it is by some process which we
cannot trace with any clearness, and the result is one
which we cannot calculate with any certainty or even
probability; and therefore, on this account, because
the resulting evil of such falsehood and sensuality is
not calculable or appreciable, we cannot, by calcula-
tion of resulting evil, show falsehood and sensuality
to be vices ; and the like is true of other vices ;
and on this ground the construction of a scheme
of Morality on Mr Bentham's plan is plainly im-
possible'.
But the disciples of Bentham will perhaps urge
1 The impossibility of really ap-
plying the principle that we are to
estimate the virtue of actions by
calculating the amount of pleasure
which they wUl produce, appears
further, by looking at the rude and
loose manner in which Bentham
makes such calculations. Among the
consequences of acts of robbery, for
instance, which make them vicious,
he reckons the alarm which such an
act produces ia other persons, and
the danger in which it places them.
And this alarm and danger are care-
fully explained, as to their existence
(ch. xir. § via.). But the probability
of each is not at all estimated. This
however is rather where he is looking
at the grounds of judicial punish-
ment than of moral condemnation^
15
226 BISTORT OF MORAL PHILOSOl'HT.
that falsehood is -wrong, even if it produce immediate
pleasure, because the violation of a general rule is
an evil which no single pleasurable consequence can
counterbalance; and because, by acts of falsehood, we
weaken and destroy our own habit of truth. And
the like might be said in the other case. Now when
men speak in this manner, they are undoubtedly ap-
proaching to a sound and tenable morality. I say
approaching to it; for they are still at a considerable
distance from a really moral view, as I shall have to
show. But though when men speak in this manner,
they are approaching to sound morality, they are re-
ceding from the fundamental principle of Bentham.
Eor on that principle, how does it appear that the
evil, that is the pain, arising from violating a general
rule once, is too great to be overbalanced by the
pleasurable consequences of that single violation ? The
actor says, I acknowledge the general rule? I do not
deny its value; but I do not intend that this one act
should be drawn into consequence. I assert my right
to look at the special case, as well as at the general
rule. I have weighed one against the other : I see
that the falsehood gives a clear balance of pleasure:
therefore on our Master's principles, it is right and
virtuous. What does the Master say to this? If he
say, " you must be wrong in violating the general rule
of truth — of veracity : no advantage can compensate
for that evil;" — if he say this, he speaks like a moral-
ist; but not like a Benthamite. He interposes, with
an imperative dogma drawn from the opposite school,
to put down the manifest consequences of his own
principles. If, on the other hand, he allow the plea;
— if he say, Be sure that your lie brings more plea-
sure than pain, and then lie, and know that you are
doing a virtuous act; — ^then indeed he talks like a
genuine assertor of Mr Bentham's principles, but he
ceases to be a moralist in any ordinary sense of the
term.
But let us look at the other reason against an act
of falsehood, that by such acts we weaken and destroy
our habit of truth. To this, the person concerned
BENTHAM — HIS MORALS AND LEGISLATION, 227
might reply, that a habit of truth,, absolute and un-
conditional, is, on Bentham's principles, of no value ;
that if there be cases in ■which the pleasure arising
from falsehood is greater than the pleasure arising
from truth, then, in these cases, falsehood is virtuous
and veracity is vicious ; that, on these principles, the
habit to be cultiv&.ted is not a habit of telling truth
al/ways, but a habit of telling truth when it produces
pleasure more than pain. To this I do not know
what our Benthamite could reply, except that a habit
of telling truth so limited, is not a habit of veracity
at all; that the only way to form a habit of veracity
is, to tell truth always, and without limiting condi-
tions; that is, to tell truth if we tell anything; not to
tell falsehood. This again is teaching quite consistent
in the mouth of a moralist : but not consistent in the
mouth of a Benthamite. It makes the regulation of
our own habits, our own desires, paramount over any-
thing which can be gained, pleasure or profit, by the
violation and transgression of such regulation. Vera-
city comes first; pleasure and gain are subordinate.
And this is our morality. But the Benthamist doc-
trine is, pleasure first of all things : veracity, good it
may be; but good only because, and only so far as, it
is an instrument of pleasure.
The other branch of the argument will be pursued
in the next Lecture.
15—2
LECTURE XV.
Bentham — Objections to his system.
IN" the last Lecture, I stated that the Benthamite
scheme of determining the m.orality of actions by
the amount of happiness which they produce, is inca-
pable of being executed for two reasons; first, that we
cannot calculate all the pleasure or pain resulting from
any one action; and next, that the happiness produced
by actions depends on their morality. I have attempt-
ed to illustrate the former argument. I now proceed
to the latter.
In the last lecture I tried to show that the Ben-
thamite doctrine, that acts are virtuous in proportion
as they calculably produce happiness, — ^that Ls, again,
according to the Benthamite analysis, pleasure, — can-
not be made the basis of morality, because we cannot
for such purposes calculate the amount of pleasure
which acts produce: and if we attempt to remedy
the obvious defects of calculations on such subjects,
by taking into account rules and habits, we run
away from the declared fundamental principle alto-
gether.
To show further how impossible it is to found
morality on the Benthamite basis, I now proceed to
observe that we cannot derive the moral value of
actions from the happiness which they produce, be-
cause the happiness depends upon the morality. Why
should a man be truthful and just? Because acts of
veracity and justice, even if they do not produce
immediate gratification to him and his friends in
other ways, (and it may easily be that they do not,)
BENTHAM — OBJECTIONS TO HIS SYSTEM. 229
at least produce pleasure in tins way; — that they
procure him his own approval and that of all good
men. To us, this language is intelligible and signi-
ficant; but the Benthamite must analyse it further.
What does it mean according to him? A man's own
approval of his act, means that he thinks it virtuous.
And therefore, the matter stands thus. He (being a
Benthamite) thinks it virtuous, because it gives him
pleasure : and it gives him pleasure because he thinks
it virtuous. This is a vicious circle, quite as palpable
as any of those in which Mr Bentham is so fond of
representing his adversaries as revolving. And in
like manner, with regard to the approval of others.
The action is virtuous, says the Benthamite, because
it produces pleasure ; namely the pleasure arising from
the approval of neighbours ; — ^they approve it, and
think it virtuous, he also says, because it gives plea-
sure. The virtue' depends upon the pleasure, the
pleasure depends upon the virtue. Here again is a
circle from which there is no legitimate egress. We
may grant that, taking into account all the elements
of happiuess, — the pleasures of self-approval, — of peace
of mind and harmony within us, and of the approval
of others, — of the known sympathy of all good men ; —
we may grant that including these elements, virtue
always does produce an overbalance of happiness ; but
then we cannot make this moral truth the basis of
morality, because we cannot extricate the happiness
and the virtue, the one from the other, so as to make
the first, the happiness, the foundation of the second,
the virtue.
This consideration of virtue itself as one of the
sources of pleasure, — one of the elements of happi-
ness, — is a point at which, as appears to me, the
Benthamite doctrine loses all the clearness which, in
its early steps, it so ostentatiously puts forward. Con-
sidering the pretensions of the system to rigorous
analysis, I cannot but think there is something ro-
bustly rude in the mode in which these matters of
self-approval and approval from others are disposed of.
That self-approval, and the approbation of neighbours,
230 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
are pleasures, cannot be denied. Accordingly, they
are reckoned by Bentham in his list of pleasures.
But these sentiments involve morality — the very
thing we are analysing into its elements : how are we
to give an account of this ingredient of pleasure?
How does Bentham make these into elementary plea-
sures ? or if not elementary, whence does he take the
moral element of these pleasures, having already pro-
fessed to resolve morality into pleasures? As I have
said, I think the answer to these questions is one
which deprives Bentham's analysis of Morality of aU
coherence and completeness. In order to make an
, opening, by which Morality may find its way into the
mind of the actor and of the spectators, he throws the
theatre open to an unbounded and undefined range of
external influences. He has recourse to the dimness
of childhood and to the confusion of the crowd, to
conceal his defect of logic. Whence does man get
his grounds of self-approval and self-condemnation?
"From Education." Where reside the rules by which
his neighbours applaud or condemn ? "In Public
Opinion." And thus these two wide and loose ab-
stractions. Education and Fublic Opinion, become the
real soui'ces of Morality. They are really the ele-
ments into which all Morality is analysed by Ben-
tham: — those, which themselves need analysis far
more than the subjects which he began to analyse,
Virtues and Vices. For is not Education (moral
Education) the process by which we learn what are
Virtues and what are Vices ? Is not Public Opinion
the Opinion which decides what acts are virtuous and
what are vicious ? What an analysis then is this !
Virtue is what gives pleasure. Among the principal
pleasures so produced are self-approval and public ap-
proval. Self-approval is governed by what we have
been taught to think virtuous : Public approval, by
what the Public thinks virtuous. Surely we are here
again in a palpable circle j as indeed we must be, if we
want to have a Morality which does not depend on a
moral basis.
That Bentham really does recur to Public Opinion,
BENTHAM — OBJECTIONS TO HIS SYSTEM. 23 1
however loose and insecure a foundation that may be,
for the basis of Morality, is indeed abundantly evident
from the general course of his discussion of the sub-
ject. Among the Sanctions by which the laws of
human conduct are toforced, he puts in a prominent
place, and constantly and emphatically refers to, what
he calls tha Popular or Moral Sanction; that is his
often-repeated phrase, — ^the Popular or Moral Sanc-
tion, — as an enforcing power, which stands side by
side with legal punishment, physical pain, and the
like. Popula/r and Moral with him, then, are, in this
application at least, synonymous, or coincident. He
cannot tell us what is moral, except he first know
what is popular. Popular Opinion is, with him, an
ultimate fact, upon which Morality depends. He
cannot correct Popular Opinion in any authoritative
manner, for it supplies one of his ruling principles ;
namely, one of the pleasures by which he determines
what is right and what is wrong. If murder, sensu-
ality, falsehood, oppression, be in any cases popular,
this popularity tends to make them virtues, for it
gives them the reward of virtue; and his virtue looks
only to reward, and to such reward among others.
True, — -"he may, in certain cases, say that the pain
produced by such acts overweighs the pleasure, even
including the pleasure of popular applause. But then,
if the applause bestowed by popular opinion be strong
enough, if the pleasure which it gives becomes still
greater, the opposite pain may thus be overbalanced,
and those acts are still virtues. That murder, sensu-
ality, falsehood, oppression, may, by many men, be
practised as virtues, on account of such applause, is,
no doubt, true ; but it cannot but sound strange to us,
to hear that doctrine called Morality, which approves
of them on this account. All mankind include in
their notion of moral rules this condition ; — that such
rules, when delivered by a person who, being a moral-
ist, cannot allow himself to assent to popular errors
and vices, shall correct and rebuke such errors and
such vices. But this he cannot do if he depend upon
Popular Opinion for one of the Sanctions of his
232 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHT.
Morality; and not only for one of these sanctions, but
for the only one which is specially called nwral.
Bentham does indeed attempt to make some stand
against popular judgment, at one period of his pro-
gress : for he "warns his disciples against the general
tendency to decide the character of actions and springs
of action, by giving to them names implying approval
and disapproval ; — ^what he calls eulogistic and dyslo-
gistic names. But these eulogistic and dyslogistic
names are part of the expression of public opinion ;
— ^part of the machinery by -vfhich the " popidar or
moral sanction" works. Men are deterred from ac-
tions that have a bad name; — led to actions that have
a good name. It is surely, on his grounds, fit that
they should be so. If they were not, where would be
the effect of this popular sanction ? If men were not
eulogistic and dyslogistic in their way of speaking of
actions, how should they express that moral judgment
which is an essential part of Bentham's system —
which is the broadest foundation stone of his edifice
of Morality?
Of course, we too know that such names have
their influence, and that, a very powerful one. We
know that the popular voice on subjects of morality
produces a mighty effect upon men. We rejoice in
this influence, when it is on the side of true morality.
We rejoice, too, to think that in general it is so; —
that truth, kindness, justice, purity, orderliness, are
generally approved by men ; and that, in general, the
popular voice enforces the moralist's precepts. But
we do not take from the popular voice our judgment
as to what actions are truthful, kind, just, pure,
orderly. Bentham might perhaps reply, but neither
does he thus form his judgments of actions ; — ^that he
too has grounds on which he can correct the popular
prejudices respecting actions. But still, he cannot but
allow that, according to him, the popular prejudice
does much to make l;hose actions virtuous which it
approves,^-those actions vicious which it condemns ;
since it can award to the one class, honour, to the
other, infamy: and ■where are there pleasures and
BENTHAM — OBJECTIONS TO HIS SYSTEM. 233
pains greater than honour, and than infamy? Now
by the greatness of the pleasures, and the pains, re-
sulting from actions, their virtuous or vicious cha-
racter according to him is determined. So that, as
we have said, virtue and vice depending upon plea-
sures and pain, and pleasures and pain again depend-
ing upon the popular opinion of right and wrong, we
cannot here find any independent basis for virtue and
vice, and right and wrong.
But it may be asked, does not the popular judg-
ment of certain classes of actions as right, and certain
others as wrong, depend upon an apprehension, how-
ever obscure and confused, that the former class are
advantageous to the community, the latter disadvan-
tageous 1 To this I reply, that if by advantage be
meant external tangible advantage, independent of
mental pleasures, I conceive that they do not so
depend : and if we take in mental pleasures, we are
brought back to that independent moral element
which the utilitarians wish to ^iclude. But if it be
alleged that this (namely, general advantage) is the
ground of the public opinion of the rightness and
wrongness of actions, let it be shown that it is so.
Let the Benthamite begin by analysing public opinion
into such elements; and let him use, in his system,
those elements, and not the unanalysed opinion in
that compound concrete form in which he calls it
"the popular or moral sanction." If Morality de-
pend upon external advantage, both directly, and
through the popular apprehension of it, let this ad-
vantage be made, once for all, the basis of the system,
and not brought in both directly in its manifest form,
and indirectly, disguised as popidar or moral opinion.
But I think that Bentham has not so analysed public
opinion ; and has been unable to do so. And that he
despaired of so doing, I judge from the impatience
with which he speaks of the eulogistic and dyslogistic
phraseology by which such opinion is conveyed. If
he could have said, "the eulogistic terms imply a
supposed tendency to the increase of human pleasure,
and I will show you how far they are right;" these
234 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHT,
terms would have been useful steps to tie exposition
of his doctrine : instead of which, he everywhere
speaks of them as impediments in the way of the
truths which he wishes to disclose; — as disguises
which tend to conceal the true bearing of actions
upon the promotion of happiness. I conceive there-
fore that Bentham saw that public opinion concerning
%irtues and vices included some other element than
that which he wished alone to recogoize ; and that he
therefore accepted public opinion as implying some-
thing in addition to the elementary pleasures and
pains which he expressly enumerates.
But again : It may be said that the public opinion
of men, and of communities, as to what is right and
wrong, is a fact in man's nature ; and an important
fact, of which all moralists must recognize the in-
fluence : and it may be asked whether Bentham as-
cribes to it more influence than justly belongs to it.
And to this I reply, that the public opinion as to
what is right and wrong is undoubtedly a very im-
portant fact in man's nature; and that the most im-
portant lesson to be learnt from it appears to be this :
— that man cannot help judging of actions, as being
right or wrong; and that men universally reckon this
as the supreme difference of actions; — the most im-
portant character which they can have. I add, that
this characteristic of human nature marks man as a
moral being; as a being endowed with a faculty or
faculties by which he does thus judge; that is, by
which he considers that right and wrong are the
supreme and paramount distinctions of actions. That
this is an important point we grant, or rather we pro-
claim, as the beginning of all Morality : and we say
that if Bentham accepts the fact in this way, he gives
it no more than its just importance. We do not
require that this Faculty or those Faculties by which
man thus judges of right and wrong should be any-
thing peculiar and ultimate, but only that the distinc-
tion should be a peculiar and ultimate one. And if
Bentham, finding that men do so judge of actions, and
perceiving that he could not, consistently with the
BENTHAM — OBJECTIONS TO HIS SYSTEM. 235
state of their minds, analyse this their judgment into
any perception of advantage and disadvantage, was
■willing to leave it as he found it, and to make the
fact of such a judgment one of the bases of his system ;
so far he was right, and did not ascribe too much
importance to this judgment, — to this public opinion.
But then, if taking the moral ju.dgments of mankind
in this aspect, Bentham puts side by side with this
element, the other advantages, say bodily pleasure or
wealth, which certain actions may produce, we say
that he makes an incongruous scheme, which cannot
pass for Morality. If he say, for instance, ''public
opinion declares lying to be wrong, and I have no-
thing to say against that; for I cannot analyse this
opinion of a thing being wrong into any thing else.
But recollect, that though it be what they call wrong,
it may be very pleasant and profitable, and therefore
you may still have good reasons for lying; and you
wm have such, if the pleasure and profit which your
lie produces, to you and other persons, outweighs that
disagreeable thing, infamy, which public opinion in-
flicts upon the liar;" — if he were to say this, he would
hardly win any one to look upon him as a moralist.
Yet this, as appears to me, is a rigorous deduction
from the Benthamite doctrine, that the proper and
ultimate ground for our acting is the amount of plea-
sure and advantage which the action will produce,
including popular approval as one among other ad-
vantages.
As I have said, the real importance of the great
fact of the universal and perpetual judgments of man-
kind concerning actions, as being right and wrong, is,
that such judgments .are thus seen to be a universal
property of human nature : — a constant and universal
act, which man performs as being man. And it is
because man does thus perpetually and universally
form such judgments, that he is a moral creature, and
that his actions are the subjects of morality; not
because he is susceptible of pleasure and pain. And
this is the reason why animals are not the subjects of
morality; — they have no idea of right and wrong; —
236 HISTORY OF MOKAL PHILOSOPHY.
their acts are neither moral nor immoral. Animals
may be indeed the objects of morality. We may treat
them with kindness or with unkindness ; and cruelty
to animals is a vice, as well as cruelty to men. But
cruelty to animals and cruelty to men stand upon a
very different footing in morality. The pleasures of
animals are elements of a very different order from
the pleasures of men. We are bound to endeavour to
augment the pleasures of men, not only because they
are pleasures, but because they are huma/n pleasures.
We are bound to men by the universal tie of human-
ity, of human brotherhood. We have no such tie to
animals. We are to be humane to them, because we
are human, not because we and they alike feel animal
pleasures. The Morality which depends upon the in-
crease of pleasure alone would make it our duty to
increase the pleasures of pigs or of geese rather than
those of men, if we were sure that the pleasure we
could give them were greater than the pleasures of
men.
Such is the result of the doctrine which founds
Morality upon the increase of pleasure. Such is a fair
deduction from Bentham's principles. Do you think
this an exaggerated statement ? — an argument carried
too far ?— Not so. He has himself accepted this con-
sequence of his system. Thus he says (Oh. xix. § iv.)
" TJnder the Gentoo and Mahometan religion the in-
terests of the rest of the animal kingdom seem to have
met with some attention. Why have they not, univer-
sally, with as much as those of human creatures, allow-
ance made for the difference in point of sensibility ?
Because the laws that are, have been the work of
mutual fear; a sentiment which the less rational ani-
mals have not had the same means as man has of
turning ito accoimt. Why ow^Ai they not? No reason
can be given.... The day may come when the rest of
the animal creation may acquire those rights which
never could have been withholden from them but by
the hand of tyranny It may come one day to be re-
cognized that the number of the' legs, the viUosity of
the skin, or the termination of the oa sacrum, are
BENTHAM^ — OBJECTIONS TO HIS SYSTEM.' 237
reasons insufi&cient for abandoning a sensitive being
to the caprice of a tormentor. What else is it that
should trace the insuperable line? Is it the faculty of
reason, or perhaps the faculty of discourse? But a
full-grown horse or dog is beyond compaxiaon a more
rational, as well as a more conversable animal, than
an infant of a day, a week, or even a mouth old. But
suppose the case were otherwise, what would it avail ?
The question is not, can they reason? nor, can they
speahl but, can they suffer i"
This appears to me a very remarkable passage, for
the light which it throws upon Bentham's doctrine, as
he foimd himself bound by the nature of his principle
to accept it, when logically unfolded. When he had
not only made pleasure his guide, but rejected all that
especially made it human pleasure, allowing no differ-
ences but those of intensity and duration ; he had, and
could have, no reason for stopping at the pleasures of
man. And thus his principle became, not the greatest
amount of human happiness, — as he had arbitrarily
stated it, with a baseless limitation, which he here re-
jects; — ^but the greatest amount of animal gratifica-
tion, including man among animals, with, it may be,
peculiar forms of pleasure, but those forms having no
peculiar value on account of their kind. But when
the principle is thus stated, we are surely entitled to
ask, why it is to be made our guide ? — why utility for
such an end is to be made the measure of the value of
our actions? For certainly, that we are to regulate
our actions so as to give the greatest pleasure to the '
whole animal creation, is not a self-evident principle.
It is not only not our obvious, but to most persons not
a tolerable doctrine, that we may sacrifice the hap-
piness of men, provided we can in that way produce
an overplus of pleasure to cats, dogs and hogs, not to
say lice and fleas. Even those who, in the regions of
Oriental superstition, have felt and enjoined the great-
est tenderness towards animals, have done so, it would
seem, in all cases, not because they considered that
the pleasures of mere brutes were obviously as sacred
.as that of men, but because they imagined some mys-
238 HISTOBT OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
terious comnmnity of nature between man and the
animals which they wished to save from pain. That
we are to increase human happiness where we can,
may be asserted, with some truth, to be universally
allowed, and in some measure self-evident: but that
we are to make it an object equally important in kind,
to increase the pleasures of animals, is not generally
accepted as a rule of human conduct; stiU less as a
basis of all rules. If we are asked to take this as the
ground of our morality, we must at least require some
reason why we should adopt such a foundation prin-
ciple. No such, answer is given : and thus, the whole
Benthamite doctrine rests, it seems, on no visible
foundation at all. It is, as we hold, false to make
even human pleasure the source of all virtue. We
think that we have other things to look at as our guides,
not overlooking this. But in order to estimate the
value of this standard, we have begun by allowing it
to be true ; and by denying only that it is either ap-
plicable or independent. But when we are required
to take the pleasures of all creatures, brute and hu-
man, into our account, and forbidden to take account
of anything else, we cannot submit. Such a standard
appears to us not only false, but false without any
show of truth. We can see no reason for it, and Mr
Bentham himself does not venture to offer us any.
Why, then, are we to take his standard at all? He
himself shows us what its true nature is; and so do-
ing, shows, as I conceive, that it is absurd, as well as
inapplicable and self-assuming.
I say nothing further of Mr Bentham's assumption
in the above passage, that because a child cannot yet
take care of itself, and cannot converse with us, its
pleasures are therefore of no more import to the mo-
ralist than those of a kitten or a puppy. We hold
that there is a tie which binds together all human
beings, quite different from that which binds them
to cats and dogs; — and that a man, at any stage of
his being, is to be treated according to his human
capacity, not according to his mere animal condition.
It "would be easy to show what strange results would
BENTHAM — OBJECTIONS TO HIS SYSTEM. 239
follow from estimating the value of oliildren in men's
eyes by Mr Bentham's standard as here stated; but
I shall not pursue the subject.
There is another remark which I wish to make
on Mr Bentham's mode of proceeding, which is ex-
emplified in this passage,, among many other places.
Mr Bentham finding in the common judgments and
common language of men a recognition of a supreme
distinction of right and wrong, which does not yield
to his analysis, is exceedingly disposed to quarrel with
the terms which imply this distinction; while at the
same time he cannot really exclude this distinction
from his own reasonings; (as no man can;) nor avoid
using the terms which imply it, and which he so
vehemently condemns in others. The term ought is
one of these. In the Deontology, he says', " The talis-
man of arrogance, indolence and ignorance is to be
found in a single word, an authoritative imposture,
which in these pages it will be frequently necessary
to unveil. It is the word 'ought' — 'ought or ought
not,' as the case may be. In deciding ' you ought to
do this' — ' you ought not to do it' — is not every
question of morals set at rest?" "If," he goes on,
" the use of the word be admissible at all, it ought
to be banished from the vocabulary of morals." Yet
he finds it quite impossible to banish it from his own
vocabulary; and not only uses it, but uses it in the
way in which it is so commonly used by others, as
representing a final and supreme rule, opposed, it may
be, to the existing actual habits of action. Thus, in
the passage on the treatment of animals just quoted :
'!They are not treated as well as men. True as to
the fact. But oiu,ght they not!" And he puts the
word in italics to show how much he rests upon it.
So in giving a description of an altercation betwe'en
an ancient and a modem — ^he makes the former, with
whom he obviously sympathizes — say, " Our business
was to inquire not what people thvnk, but what they
' I. 3l-
240 HISTORY OF MOEAL PHILOSOPHY.
oibght to ihinhi" again italicizing the word. Numerous,
almost innumerable, other examples might be pro-
duced'.
Perhaps it may be worth while considering for
a moment what may appear to be the reason for the
extraordinary manner in which Bentham and the
Benthamites have been in the habit of treating their
opponents; for their perpetual assertions that the oppo-
nents' principles are unmeaning — are mere assump-
tions — ^perpetual beggings of the question — ipse dixits
— ^vicious rounds of baseless reasons : — for this is their
usual mode of speaking of opponents. They rarely
quote them; and appear to conceive that men so ex-
tremely in error could not have injustice done them ;
— ^that any assertion might be made about them, for
their absurdity was so broad that the most random
shot must hit it. This appears to be the mood ia
which Bentham speaks of all opposing moralists. Now
you may ask, whether any probable reason can be
given why he should allow himself such liberties; —
why he should be so incapable of seeing any sense
or reason in any previous scheme of ethics. I do not
pretend to explain the matter: but I think we may
go as far as this : — That his mind was so completely
possessed by his own system of thought, that he could
not see any sense or reason in any differing system :
and that it was this want of any sense or reason
' So, PriTiciples, Ch. xviii. Art. i
Classes of Offenses, Art. i. "It is
necessary at the outset to make a
distinction between snch acts as are
or maij be, and such as ov^ghX to be
offenses."
So, same Chap. Art. xxr, note, he
would call the person benefitted by
a trust, the benefidend^ry, " to pat
it more effectually ont of doubt that
the party meant was the party who
oujQhi to receive the benefit, whe-
ther he actually receives it or no."
So, same Chap. Art xivii. text
and note: "The trust is either of
the number of those which ought by
law-to subsist ... or is not" " What
articles ought to be created [pro-
perty], &a" The whole page and
note swarms with ovijhis.
So same Chap. Par. ilii. "Whe-
ther any and what modes of servi-
tude ought to be established and
kept on foot »" Again, Par. xivi, ixt
BENTHAM — OBJECTIONS TO HIS SYSTEM. 24 1
apparent to him ia the opinions of others -w^hich raised
him into his strange mood of arrogance, his intoxi-
cation of self-complacent contempt for adverse systems
and arguments, which his admiring disciples held to
be so overwhelming to all opponents. I think we
may go further. We may see a little nearer why it
was that he found no meaning in opposite systems.
It appears to me to have been thus. He had set
himself to discover and lay down a general principle
of human action by which all rules of action must
be determined. His principle was, that we must aim
at a certain external end : — at happiness, as it is fii-st
stated: — but happiness is plainly not altogether ex-
ternal; happiness depends upon the mind itself. Di-
vest, then, the object of this condition; make it wholly
external to the mind : it then becomes pleasure. Plea-
sure, then, must be the sole object of human action;
and Pleasure variously transformed must give rise to
all the virtues. If you are not. satisfied with this, he
cries, show me any other external object which men
either do care for or can care for. Swimrvu/m Bormm,
Sonestum, Kakav, why should they care for these if
they give them no pleasure ? And if they do, say so
boldly, and have done with it. Of course the answer
is, that we are so made that we do care for things
on other grounds than are expressed, in any common
and simple way, by saying they give us pleasure.
Men's care for justice, honesty, truth, and female
purity, is not expressed in any appropriate or intel-
ligible or adequate way, by saying that these give
them pleasure. Men are so constituted as to care for
these things. But this idea of a constitution in man,
an internal condition of morality, was quite out of
Bentham's field of view. No, he said : I want you
to point out the thing which men get, and try to get,
by virtuous action. If you will not do this, I cannot
understand you. If you do this, you must come to
my standard. And this habit of mind was, I conceive,
in him, not afiected, but real : and after a whUe, broke
out, as I have said, in the most boisterous ridicule of
all who difiered from him.
16
242 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
In quitting these general considerations, and turn-
ing to detail, it -wrould be unjust to Benthani not to
allow that in that portion of Ethics ia which his prin-
ciple is really applicable, there is a great deal of
felicity, and even of impressiveness, in the manner in
which he foUows out his doctrine. I speak of the
virtues and duties which depend directly upon Bene-
Tolence. He enjoins kindness, gentleness, patience,
meekness, good humour, in a manner which makes
him conspicuous among the kindlier moralists. He
has for instance such precepts as this : " Never do
evil for mere iU desert'," with many other like pre-
cepts (209), &c. At the same time, it must be said
that a great many of the precepts which he thus gives
are rather rules of good manners than rules of mo-
rality. And though he extends his injunctions to the
subjects of discourse and action in a wider view, he
appears to be most at home in pointing out what
Civility, or, as he cails it, negative efficient Bene-
volence, requires us to do, and to refrain from, in
the very rudest provinces of good manners ; and this
he traces with a gravity and a technical physiological
detail which are truly astounding^
> Demtol a. 193. 2 ibid. 237, Sk.
LECTURE XVI.
Bbuth AM— Classification of Offenses.
I HAVE found myself obliged to speak with so
much dispraise of Bentham's arrogance and un-
fairness, and of the narrow and erroneous basis of his
moral philosophy, that you may perhaps not expect
me to find in him anything which is valuable. This
however is far from being the case. He laboured
assiduously to reduce jurisprudence to a system ; and
such an attempt, if carried through with any degree
of consistency, could hardly fail to lead to vahiable
results. In a body of knowledge so wide and various,
all system-mating must bring into view real con-
nexions and relations of parts ; and even if the basis
of the system be wrong, the connexions and relations
which it points out will, admit of being translated into
the terms of a truer philosophy. As Bacon says,
truth emerges from error, sooner than from confusion.
But Bentham's principle, of general advantage as the
standard of good in actions, is really applicable to a
very great extent in legislation; and covers almost the
whole of the field with which the legislature is con-
cerned. Almost, I say, not quite the whole : and even
this almost applies only to the material and external
limitation of advantage, to which Bentham professes
and endeavours to confine himself. If we make such
advantage the absolute and uncorrected standard of
law, we shall find that we cannot advance to the
highest point of good legislation. But still the consi-
deration of general utility, as the object of laws,
extends so far, that an arrangement of the whole field
of law, formed on this principle, will not fail to ba
16—2
244 HISTOET OF MORAL PHILOSOPHT.
interesting and instructive in a very high degree.
Accordingly, the parts of Bentham's writings -where
he employs himself on this task, appear to me to be
both the one and the other. In his mode of per-
forming the task, as in the -whole of his -writings,
there are great merits and great drawbacks. The
merits are, system, followed out with great acuteness,
illustrated with great liveliness, and expressed in a
neat, precise, luminous style; for at the period of
which I speak he was content to construct English
sentences, and to use English words ; limitations which
he afterwards discarded. The drawbacks are, the arro-
gance and self-conceit of which I have spoken, which
breaks out from time to time, even in the most tran-
quil portions of his discussion. Moreover, though
affecting much systematic rigour, he is really unable
to carry out his system consistently into every part
of his subject. Professing to classify offenses, for
instance, by what he calls an exhaustive method,
namely a method which exhausts all the kinds of dif-
ference among the things classified, and is therefore
necessarily complete, he is really obliged frequently to
desert his exhaustive process, and to take the classes
which are suggested by the common habits of thought
and language on such subjects. Thus he says of one
such group (ch. xviii. p. 54) : " It would be to little
purpose to attempt tracing them out a priori by any
exhaustive process : all that can be done is to pick up
and hang together some of the principal articles in
each catalogue by way of specimen." And he has
several times to say things of this kind, in excuse of
his de-viations from his professed method'.
I will now give some account of that Chapter of
Bentham's Principles of Morals and Legislation which
1 SoChap.XTin.Partx,Bote,Ben-
tliam laments : "But such is the fate
of science, and more particularly of
the moral branch ; the distribution
of things must in a great measure be
dependent on their names : arrange-
ment, the worlt of mature reflection
must be ruled by nomenclature, the
work of popular caprice."
BENTHAM — CLASSIFICATION OF OFFENSES. 245
is entitled Division of Offenses. I shall consider it in
some measure with reference to the classification of
Rights which I have myself given, as one of the steps
of Morality, and the enumeration of Wrongs accord-
ing to the English and Roman Law, which I have
given as exemplifying the historical form which this
subject necessarily assumes'. Bentham, on the con-
trary, professes to classify Offenses or Wrongs in a
manner independent of history, and equally applicable
to the Laws of all Nations; — a bold, and, as I have
said, an instructive attempt : but one which, I think,
we have good reason for deeming incapable of full
realization. His scheme, however, may very well
serve to suggest corrections and completions, of which
any other may stand in need; and I shall use it for
this among other purposes. I shall not attempt to
give the exhaustive process by which Bentham obtains
his results, but shall briefly consider some of the re-
sults themselves.
His first division of Offenses is into five Classes,
which are,
1. Private Offenses, detrimental to assignable in-
dividuals.
2. Semi-PvMic Offenses, detrimental to a class or
circle of persons, but not to assignable individuals.
3. Self-rega/rding Offenses, against a man's sel£
4. Pyilic Offenses, against the whole community.
5. Multiform Offenses, (i) Offenses by Falsehood,
(2) Offenses against Trust.
We already see the incongruity of the character of
the fifth Class, as compared with the other four; we
see that the difficulty of a homogeneous and symme-
trical classification has not been overcome by Ben-
tham; and this he fairly acknowledges. And not-
withstanding this defect, we may allow that the clas-
sification is so &r, good, simple, and convenient.
I EUmenis of Morality, induding Polity, Book it. (znd edition.)
246 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
Bentham subdivides these classes according to the
interests which are aflfectedj and .thus he finds as
Divisions of Class i,
Offenses against, i, Person; 2, Property; 3, Be-
piUation; 4, Condition; 5, Person emd Beputation;
6, Person and Property.
You wiU recollect that our Divisions of Rights
were those of, i. Person; 2, Property; 3, Contract;
4, Family; and 5, Government.
And to see how far these are parallel with the clas-
sification of Bentham, we may observe that Offenses
against the rights of Contract are relegated by Ben-
tham into another general class, that of Multiform
Offenses, by an anungement which he allows to be ano-
malous ; while both the kinds of Rights in our scheme,
those of Family and those of Government, are violated
by Offenses against Condition : the term Condition
being used by Bentham in a very wide sense, to in-
clude the Rights of Master and Servant, Guardian
and Ward, Parent and Child, Husband and Wife. On
this we may remark, that some of these conditions are
rather expressed by Bights o/Contract than, by anything
requiring a separate class. Thus the Rights of Master
and Servant are, in this country at least. Rights of
that kind of Contract called Siring and Service ; whUe
the principal conditions, as Parent and Child, Hus-
band and Wife, are evidently expressed by Bights of
Family : and though it may perhaps be true that other
conditions, as Guardian and Ward, are not strictly
included in the Bights of Family, still they may be
classed with those of Family, as consequences, exten-
sions, and analogous conditions. Other conditions again,
as those of Patron and Client, may be more properly
arranged with the Bights of GovermwMt. And it is
plaiQ, in fact, that the transition from the relations of
Family to those of Government, that is, constitutiorud
relations, must be gradual in most societies, and va-
rious in all, according to their history.
Proceeding further with the subdivision of the sys-
tem, we come to what Mr Bentham calls the Gen&ra
of Class 1. And these we may in the first place, look
BENTHAM — CLASSIFICATION OP OFFENSES. ^47
at, in the result at whicli lie arrives. I will insert
them in a note '.
1 Genbba of Pbivate Ofpekses.
Offenses against Person.
I Simple corporal injuries.
■2 Irreparable corporal injuries,
3 Simple injurious restrainment fyit^<™' confinement,
4 £f£»i^fe injurious compulsion j^Xtirr '^'
5 "Wrongful confinement.
6 Wrongful banishment..
7 Wrongful homicide.-
8 Wrongful menacement.
9 Simple mental injuries.
Offenses against Beputation.
1 Defamation.
2 Vilification.
Offenses against Property.
1 Wrongful non-investment of Property.
2 Wrongful interception of Property.
3 Wrongful divestment of Property.
4 Usurpation of Property.
5 Wrongful investment of Property.
6 Wrongful withholding of Services.
7 Wrongful destruction or endamagement.
8 Insolvency.
9 Wrongful obtainment of Services.
10 Wrongful imposition of Expence.
ri Wrongful imposition of Services.
12 Wrongful occupation,
13 Wrongful detention.
14 Wrongful' disturbance of proprietary Bights.
15 Theft.
16 Embezzlement.
17 Defraudment.
iS Extortion.
Offenses against Person poCKoriiiLa.. Love of Honour.
UX-flBaa. Truth.
The Social Virtues.^ e&rpairefda. Good-Humour.
( ipiKla. friendliness.
Now in Michelet's explanation I see no account
of several of the virtues of Aristotle's scheme, as
irpoonys, trc/AvoTT/s, oiScis, ve/ieo-is. But without dwelling
upon this, it is evident that if Michelet's account of
the spring of human action be complete, all virtues,
in any enumeration, however confused, must find their
place somewhere or other in his system, but that this
does not in the smallest degree show that a given enu-
m.] OBJECTIONS TO ARISTOTLE. 21
meration is systematic. If Michelet have rightly clas-
sified the springs of hiimaii action, all the virtues,
(since they have reference to these springs of action,)
and Aristotle's virtues among the number, must have
places provided for them in Michelet's system j but this
does not show any identity, or even correspondence,
between the scheme of Aristotle and of Michelet.
If Michelet's or if Hegel's system of the springs of
action and the consequent distribution of virtues, or if
any other, be complete, it must include all previous and
imperfect systems, but cannot, by including, merely,
justify any one of them. After all that has been
said, I think we cannot hold the Aristotelian system
of virtues to be any other than arbitrary and formless.
What has been hitherto said applies to the ethical
virtues, as Michelet remarks. This refers to a distinc-
tion in the Aristotelian classification of virtues which
I have already mentioned ; and which is one of the
most noted parts of it, and is by no means without its
value. I mean, the distinction of ethioal and intel-
lectual virtues. Thus in the Eudemian Ethics (ii. 2),
there are two kinds of virtue, ethical and intellectual ;
()/ [tXv ■qOi.K-q, 1) 8e SiavoijTtKi; ;) " for we praise not only
the just but also the intelligent and the wise:" it
being thus assumed that we may give the name of
Virtue to all those qualities which we praise, upon
which principle also Aristotle reasons in other pas-
sages. But these intellectual virtues belong to the
reason, and not to the ■760s, the disposition. When
we describe of what kind a person is as to his dispo-
sition (jToio's Tts TO ^6os), we do not say he is wise or
clever, but that he is courageous or meek. And the
intellectual virtues are enumerated and discussed both
in the fifth Book of the Eudemian Ethics, and at the
end of the first Book (i. 35) of the Great Ethics.
But the most full and complete account of the In-
tellectual Virtues is that contained in the Sixth
Book of the Nicomachean Ethics (vi. 3), a part of the
work much praised by the admirers of Aristotle. The
Intellectual Virtues are five— five faculties by which
the truth is discerned — namely, Art, Science, Pru-
22 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [lECT.
dence, Wisdom, Intuition. I give this last term,
Intuition, as the representative of Aristotle's term
Novs, and I think a little consideration wiU show that
this nearly expresses its meaning. " Science," Aristotle
says (vi. 6) "is an apprehension of universal and
necessary truths. Now all demonstration and all
science proceeds from principles. But the first prin-
ciples of science cannot be the subject of Science, nor
of Art, nor of Prudence : for the matter of Science is
demonstrative — ^but Art and Prudence are concerned
about contingent things which might be otherwise.
Nor is Wisdom the ground of our knowledge of these
principles of demonstration; for the wise man himself
may require demonstration in some cases. And thus
this knowledge of first principles of demonstration,
since it cannot be the business of Prudence, Science, or
Wisdom, must belong to another faculty, namely, In-
tuition." Whatever name we give to the Facvdty by
which we perceive first principles (for instance the
Axioms of Geometry, and of any other subject), it is
plain that that Faculty is here intended. The term
Reason is undoubtedly so employed by some philoso-
phical writers as to describe this Faculty ; but the term
Heason extends so much more widely than this
meaning, that it appears better to take a term of a
more definite application.
It is however to be observed, that these Intel-
lectual Virtues of Aristotle are not, properly speaking.
Virtues at all. They are Virtues in that wider sense
of the term, Excellences, or matters of praise, which,
as I have already said, Aristotle assumes. But they
are not Virtues in the special sense in which Morality
requires the term to be used. They are not Duties.
We cannot say that we transgress a moral Duty, if we
are not wise. The progression from merely practical
to purely speculative knowledge which we have in the
five terms. Art, Science, Prudence, Wisdom, Intuition
— is remarkable enough; but it is no part of morality
— not even of the philosophy of morality, but rather
of general psychology and metaphysics, as I have
already said.
III.] OBJECTIONS TO ARISTOTLE, 23
Still yre are not to fall into the error of supposing
that there are no intellectual Virtues and intellectual
Duties. It is plain that Imprudence in moral matters is
a violation of Duty, and therefore Prudence is a Virtue.
And Aristotle has very properly dwelt at some length
upon Prudence ((^povijo-ts). He arranges under it other
subordinate habits of the same kind — evjSovXia, a-ivea-K,
yviafiri — Deliberation, Intelligence, Justness of thought.
The remarks which he makes on each of these subjects
are acute and lively, but they do not easily fall into a
systematic form, and have not, I think, much affected
subsequent systems.
LECTUEE IV.
Aeistotle on Justice aitd Equitt.
THEEE is another part of the Ethics of -which the
language and the divisions have been extensively
adopted in later times. I mean the fifth Book, on
Justice. Aristotle's division of Justice into distri-
butive and corrective or commutative Justice — Justice
in Distribution and Justice in Contracts (t. 3, 4, •n-epl
rov ev Suivojuais SikoCov and ircpl tov hf rois (rwaX-
\ay ftxunv huadao). These distinctions have been retained
in later times, and various attempts have been made to
divide Justice into two parts in some way analogous to
the meaning of these terms, though not, I think, -with
any great clearness or success. Aristotle explains his
division by a geometrical illustration. Distributive Jus-
tice makes A's share to B's share (of wealth or honour,
or the like) as A's claim to B's claim: and is thus a
geometrical proportion. Corrective Justice, on the
other hand, takes from B to give to A, so that their
shares, which have not the equality required by the
contract, may be made equal j and thus establishes an
arithmetical mean between them. It is not difGlcult to
see that these two kinds of proportion would coincide if
applied in similar cases : for if A and B have, by con-
tract, claims which are as 2 and i, this division is at
the' same time the proportion which distributive jus-
tice requires and the equaUiy which corrective justice
directs. But according to Aristotle's explanation of
his own terms, Distributive Justice is rather concerned
in establishing the distribution of property, and Cor-
rective Justice in restoring it when disturbed by wrong-
LECT. IV.] ARISTOTLE ON EQUITY. 2$
doing. He very properly distinguishes Injustice in a
large sense in which, it includes in its meaning all
violation of law, from Injustice as one of a class of
vices co-ordinate with those which we have already
spoken of. In this sense, Injustice is wrong done for
the sake of gain, when our misconduct arises from
the desire of promoting our own profit or honour, or
gain in any other form.
This Fifth Book is also noted for a chapter on the
origin and nature of Money, in which Aristotle's ad-
mirers find the basis of some of the most important
speculations of the economists of modem times. These
subjects however do not now concern us.
But I will briefly notice a quality which Aristotle
places as an appendix to Justice; and the more so, in-
asmuch as a similar appendix to Justice has been com-
monly introduced not only into Morality, but into Law.
I speak of the virtue which Aristotle calls iTrieiKeia, and
which is commonly translated Equity: a translation
which though not, I think, expressing the sense of the
Greek word, does very exactly indicate the relation to
Justice in the modem system which was intended in
the ancient ones. Indeed so close and familiar was
this identity, in moral aspect, of hntiKeua. and Equity,
that some later writers, in ages when the knowledge
of Greek was not very general, appear to have been
unable to persuade themselves that there was not an
etymological connection between the two. Thomas
Aquinas, in his enumeration of virtues, in a part of
his celebrated Secwnda Secvndce, in which he is
evidently following Aristotle — whether directly or
through derivative influence — mentions among his
virtues Upicheia, — adding, dicitur ab epi quod est
supra et caion quod est justwm,^. As you know,
hndnvjo. in its common use means fairness, in oppo-
sition to strict justice; or means even a yieldingness
which gives up beyond what reasonable equity as well
> I need not explain the entire ignorance of Greek which this derivation
implies.
26 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [LECT.
as strict justice could require. But in Aristotle's
explanation the term is plainly Reasonable Equity ia
opposition to strict verbaJ. Law; and the distinction
as drawn by liim is really sagacious and valuable. It
is, he says, the same as justice, but it is a better kind
of justice. " It is not legal right, it is a rectification
of legal right. And the reason is, that the law is
expressed in wniversal terms; but there are things
which it is impossible to express rightly in universal
terms. In these cases, the law takes the general con-
dition, not being ignorant that it is inaccurate; — and
it does rightly, for the inaccuracy is not in the law,
nor in the lawgiver, but in the nature of the case.
Such is the matter of which practice consists. And
thus when the law has expressed its command uni-
versally, and something happens which is out of the
circuit of the universal expression, it is right that the
defect should be supplied; — for this is what the law-
giver himself would have done, if he could be con-
sulted. And this is the nature of hnaK\xxn.Kdv, to Se
vo/ufjiov). That is natural which has everywhere the
same force, and does not depend upon convention;
that is legal (posUive law, in modem phrase) which
is at first indifferent, and may be one way or another :
as, that a mina only shall be required for the ransom
c£ a prisoner; and particular laws, as that Brasidas
shall be honoured with heroic worship; and all that
comes in the shape of decrees or resolutions. But
some think that all rights are of this kind ;" namely,
mere matters of positive institution. This is precisely
the point of difficulty. "For, they urge, what is
natural is immutable, and has everywhere the same
force: thus fire bums here and in Persia alike: but
LECT. VI.] ARISTOTLE ON RIGHTS. 41
rights, they say, are various and changeable. But
this is not so," he says. " Things which are natu-
ral may yet be susceptible of change — at least in
this our world — (for I will not deny that among the
Gods in heaven what is natural is unalterable) — and
' yet some things are natural and some are not. We
can see plainly what things, which are susceptible of
change, are natural, and what are not natural but
matters of institution and compact. The same dis-
tinction is observable in other things. The right hand
is naturally stronger, yet all men might have been
ambidexter."
" With regard to mattei-s of convention,'' he goes
on to say, " they are regulated by man's interests, like
the measures of wine and corn in different places.
And thus the rights which are not natural, but of
human institution merely, are not the same every-
where; for the political constitutions are different.
But there is one natural constitution which is the
best." .
I confess I do not see in this passage any solution
of the difficulty which so obviously presents itself :
^^iow can we assert that there are universal natural
rights, when rights are different in every different
community? — If we look at the Greater Ethics for
the corresponding passage, we find the argument a
little more fully given (i. 34). After his illustration
about the right hand, he says : " Even if we were all to
practise our left hands so that we could use them like
the right, still the right is better than the left. That
the thing has undergone a change does not make it
cease to be natural. If for the most part and at most
times the left is the left hand and the right the right,
it is naturally so. And so with regard to natural
rights, it does not follow because they can be changed
by our practice that therefore they are not natural
rights. That which is a right for the most pa/rt is
plainly a natural right."
Now this is, as appears to me, quite intelligibley
and is an attempt to solve the difficulty which has.
been, in substance, often repeated in subsequent times.
42 HISTORY OF MOBAL PHILOSOPHY. [lECT.
It is an appeal to the general consent of nations in
favour of the natural character of certain rights. Those
rights which are found to obtain in all nations, or in
all with few exceptions, are held to be natural. But
it does not appear to me that this is a solution of the
difficulty, or even a remark of any value. If natural
rights are to be recognized by their prevailing in most
nations, we shall find it impossible to sanction any
distinction between natural and conventional rights;
for what amount of prevalence are we to require for
the first class? According to this account of the
matter, there is a gradation from the one class to the
other so entirely unbroken, that it is impossible to
draw any line or to preserve any distinction. What
kind of right has not been rejected in great bodies of
nations. Is a man's right to his own person, his own
limbs, his own labour, a natural right ? Surely if any
right be natural this must be so. And yet this right
has been denied, and unhappily is still denied, over
wide portions of the earth'^ surface, that is, wherever
slavery is established; — in almost all the old world in
old times ; in. a large portion of the new world even in
our own days. And if we cannot tell whether personal
freedom is a natural or a conventional right, how can
we say, with Aristotle, that it is easy to decide what
rights are natural and what are conventional? And
the same may be said of all other rights. Is private
property a natural right ? This again is so, if there be
any natural rights, and Aristotle himself has done
much to prove it so, in another place and on other
grounds. Yet how far is the right of private property
from universal prevalence! It was contrary to the
law at Sparta. It was excluded in Plato's Republic.
It is limited so that it may be reduced to nothing by
the power of the Sovereign in a Despotism, by taxes
and the fear of the people in Democracies. Is marriage
a natural right? Polygamy, a most wide-spread insti-
tution, divests women, in a great measure, of the
civil and social position which belongs to marriage as
a condition invested with rights; and the variations
which obtain in the conjugal relation in different
VI.] ARISTOTLE ON RIGHTS. 43
countries leave us hardly any room to reason upon in
their agreement. Or at least, it is not the mere Fact
of actual agreement of institutions in. different countries
which must be the basis of our reasoning on this matter,
but their agreement in that which we, from our know-
ledge of human nature, its springs of action and their
operation, see to be a thing in which they must agree.
If indeed there be rights which are not only universal
among men, anomalies excepted, but also necessary
conditions of human being where its faculties are
unfolded, these may be considered as natural rights.
And the way in which I think we may conveniently
express this, is that the Conception of each of the
rights of which this is true belongs to the Idea of
Humanity, while the Definition of this Conception
is a matter belonging to the domain of things, not
of Ideas, — of practice, not of speculation; — is given by
the historical career and institutions of each country,
and consequently may be different in each.
But in another place, Aristotle has proved pri-
vate property to be a natural right, so far as is done
by proving it to be a necessary condition of man's
social existence. I speak of his refutation of that
part of Plato's institutions in his ideal Eepublic in
which the philosopher prohibits private property and
establishes a community of goods. Aristotle [Polit.
II. 3) argues against this arrangement with great force.
It would, he says, destroy the pleasure which we have
in thinking anything our own. It would destroy the
pleasure of bestowing anything upon our friends, or our
companions, or on deserving persons. There could be
no such virtue as liberality. Socrates was deceived.
He took for granted that the union of his citizens
could not be too intimate; whereas in reality this
union carried beyond certain limits .would prove the
destruction of the commonwealth. "Symphony is
good," he adds, illustrating the subject by a reference
to music, an art so familiar to his countrymen, " and
metre is good ; not symphony when it becomes iden-
tity of note; nor metre when it is the mere repetition
of the same beat (/Satrts)."
44 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [lECT.
The necessity of the Eight of Private Property has
been put in a somewhat more general and demonT
strative form in modern writers, but Aristotle's argu-
ment, expanded and pursued, is involved in such de-
monstrations. The proof has been thus stated. Man,
in order to act at aU, must have something to act
upon and to act with. His actions take place in a
world of things, and affect those things, and he must
have some fixed relation, some connection, with a por-
tion of these things, in order that his actions may be
referred to him. He must have something which he
can take, which he can give, which he can use, which
he can destroy, which he can preserve, increase, move,
in order that he may perform such actions as taking,
giving, using, destroying and the Hke, at all. If no-
thing is his, he is nothing; at least no independent
thing, however much he may be a member of a large
organized body. And thus, he is no moral agent on
this supposition. But though the argument in this
form is more general and abstract, it is more intel-
ligible and convincing to a common reader in the form
in which Aristotle puts it; and at any rate, to have
the aa-gumeut put in the popular and practical shape
in which it stands in The Politics, was a valuable step
towards the proof of the doctrine that the Eight of
Private Property is a necessary element of man's
moral condition.
Of course there may be urged arguments of the
same kind to show the necessity of Marriage, as those
which show the necessity of Property : and Aristotle
argues against the community of wives and of children
in the Platonic Eepublic as he does against the com-
munity of goods. The arguments are obvious and are
forcible. I shall not dwell upon them. Man without
property, without family, withoiit freedom to act and
to choose his line of action, is not man, the moral
agent, with which our morality, or any intelligible
morality, is concerned. Man in such a condition — what
has he to care for? to aim at? to do? He has to pro-
mote the hypothetical good of a State with which he
is not concerned by any ordinary human ties. Why
vi.] Plato's polity. '45
should he do it? Aristotle very properly urges this
consideration. " Even the governors of the Socratic
commonwealth," he asija, (Folit. ii. 3), "subjected to
so many privations and bound to so many hard duties,
would not deserve to be called happy : and if happi-
ness does not belong to them, can we expect to find it
among the peasants and artisans? Socrates indeed
says that it is the business of a legislator to consult,
not the good of any particular class of men, but of the
whole State: he forgets that the whole cannot be
happy if the greater part, or all the parts, or at least
some, are not happy. Happiness is not like number,
where the whole may be even though the parts are
odd."
It will be observed that Aristotle in this criticism
regards Plato's Dialogues on the Republic as a pro-
posal for a Political Constitution in a State, and not
merely as an Analogical Image by which the consti-
tution of the Human Soul is to be illustrated; which
latter is the view we formerly took of it. And, in-
deed, taking into account Plato's own expressions, and
the manner in which in the Greek Idea, political and
moral life were inseparably connected, it cannot be
doubted, I conceive, that the political theory, as well
as the moral proof, belonged to Plato's intention. It
is true, that the Dialogues on the Laws are more
distinctly and expressly a proposal for a political con-
stitution; and in this the community of wives and of
possessions is rejected, and marriage is reckoned one
of the fundamental points of the State; although ever
here the liberty of individual action is much restrained.
But we may consider, as an explanation of the relation
between the two Polities — that of the Republic and
that of the Laws, — some passages in the latter work,
I refer especially to a passage in the fifth Book of the
Laws (v. 9, 10), where, after having delivered the general
Proem to the Code which his legislator is to promul-
gate (a Proem which is a summary of his moral sys-
tem and an exhortation to virtuous act and thought)
he says, before proceeding" to legislate concerning
property and the like — "Our legislation may now
46 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [LECT.
perhaps seem strange, but it is to be recollected that
it is the constitution of a second best state — (^oveiTai
OEvreptds av irdXts olKeitrOai irpos ro /SekTurrov." He
adds, " The best way is to describe the best form of
Polity, and the second best, and the third, and to
leave the master of the colony to choose among them.
The first and best polity — the best laws — are when
there prevails in every part of the constitution the
old maxim, Koiva ra ^tXtoi/, all things are common
among friends. If then this be any where the case,
or ever shall any where be, that all things are in com-
mon in a city — ^the wives, the children, the goods,
and if aU private possession (to keyofievov iSlov) is in
every way removed out of life — if contrivances are used
so that even those things which by nature belong to
individuals are, in a way, common — as eyes and ears
and hands — when men see in common, and hear and
act, and praise and blame, and joy and grieve, and
the laws make the city as much as possible one — ^then
will the nearest approach be made to perfect virtue.
This would be a city of the gods and the children of
the gods. This is the true paradigm of a Polity
which we ought first of aU to aim at : that which we
now describe wUl be next to that immortal type, and
second only to it." And accordingly, Aristotle, in
speaking of the Polity described in the Laws of Plato,
often calls it Plato's Second Polity.
It may be observed, that neither Aristotle nor any
succeeding writer has exposed more completely than
Plato himself has done, in the passage I have just
quoted, the utterly unnatural character of the Polity
which he describes in the Republic. His own expres-
sions show how repugnant the institutions which he ad-
vocates are to the attributes of humanity. A collection
of creatures who hear and see and feel, and continue
their kind, and joy and grieve, not as individuals, but
in common, is not a body of men. It is more like
one of the zoophyte coralline animals, in which a
number of mouths, belonging to one body, have each
a dim and obscure kind of individual action; but the
life of the united mass, which runs through the whole.
VI.] • Plato's polity. 47
is more truly life than that of any member. Plato
has endowed the separate mouths of his zoophyte
•with some human faculties and with human con-
sciousness, while he retains that closeness of moral,
and even bodily connection, which makes his image
too much of a zoophyte to have any real resemblance
to a body of men. Hobbes's Leviathcm was an image
of society which represented it as a mere crowd, in
which the weaker are kept in awe by the stronger.
Plato's image, introduced for the same purpose, is a
compound polyp; and is hardly a better image than
a tree would be; for his individuals have hardly
more of individual human life than the buds of a
plant. However inadequately Hobbes's image may
express the real nature and organization of human
society, of a civil community, the relation of the in-
dividual is at least an intelligible human relation.
But in Plato's Eepublic men are supposed to be kept
together, not by hope or fear, — for the subjects of hope
and fear are excluded, — but by some necessity which
does not belong to human life, and must be conceived
as merely physiological or zoological.
I shall not pursue Aristotle's criticism of Plato's
second Polity — that proposed in the Laws : nor shall
I now attempt to lead you into Aristotle's own poli-
tical speculations, and his scheme of the best form of
Polity. I wUl not leave the subject however without
saying that this work of Aristotle — his Politics — is
in the highest degree instructive, interesting and able.
In this work it is, I think, that the author appears
to most advantage. His habit of taking a practical
view of his subject makes every sentence contain
something worthy of notice, and something which
throws light upon the subject: and the want of
solidity which seems to me to hang about his moral
doctrines does not manifest itself when he passes be-
yond the first and most general principles which
belong to the theoretical foundation of the subject.
Then his vast acquaintance with the political con-
dition of the world in his time, and of the previous
political writers, with his clear and calm statement
48 HISTOET OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [LECT.
of what he has collected, make his work a treasure-
house of knowledge of political experiments. And it
is not too much to say that many of the political
doctrines which have been received with applause
when delivered by subsequent writei-s, may be found
in him, plainly asserted.
I will only, as a specimen of his speculations of
this kind, give his enumeration of the necessary parts
of a state. This enumeration occurs in that which
is commonly printed as the Seventh Book ; but which
those who in modern times have translated the work,
into English and into French, have independently
seen undeniable reasons for placing immediately after
the Third Book (Gillies, and J. Barth€16my St ffilaire),
thus making it the Fourth. The Book contains Ari-
stotle's Idea of the best Polity; and is the 7th Chapter
of this Book (ed. Gbttling, vii. 7).
" We must consider what these parts are without
which the state cannot be. They are, first food ; then
arts ; for life requires many arts ; then arms ; for those
who are to live together must have arms to. keep the
disobedient under, and to resist external aggressions;
then a certain supply of money, both for their own
needs, and for war; and fifth and Jirst, the service of
the gods, the priesthood; and sixth and most neces-
sary of all, judgments concerning the interest of the
whole and the mutual rights of each.
" These parts a State must have, for a State is not
a casual crowd, but a collection of men provided with
all which human life requires. And if any of the
above parts be wanting, the community has not that
which life requires. And thus the City must contain
these classes: Agricultural Labourers, who provide
food; Artisans, Soldiers, Rich Men (to eun-opov),
Priests, and Judges of the public necessity and uti-
lity."
I may notice also his reference to his own Ethics
(Folit. VII. 1 2). " We have said in the Ethics {Nic.
I. 13) (if there be any utility in that work), that hap-
piness is a perfect activity and use of virtue, not
limited hypotheticaJly, but simply exerted. By hy-
VI.] ARISTOTLE ON EIGHTS. 49
pothetical, I mean virtue applied in acts necessary by
a hypothesis : by simply, that which is ideally good.
Thus, punishment for offences and penal inflictions
are effects of virtue, but necessary, and good because
necessary : but it would be better if neither the state
nor individuals needed punishment. But what tends
to honour and wealth is simply good. The former
kind of acts are a choice of evils ; these are not : they
are simply productions and acquisitions of good."
M. P. n.
LECTUEE VII,
Stoics and Epicukeans — Cicero.
THE great antithesis of moral systems, though, it
plainly shows itself in the school of Socrates, did
not produce a steady distinction and opposition tUl a
later period. The general and coherent tendency of the
Platonic dialogues is to oppose what is uierelj pleasant
to what is good in a higher sense, and to represent the
latter, the Good, as the proper object of human desire,
not the former, the Pleasant : — yet these two notions,
the good and the pleasant, are not there steadily and
resolutely kept asunder and opposed, as they were
when they had become the watch-words of rival sects.
Sometimes Plato appears as if he wished to try what
aspect his moral philosophy would take by compound-
ing these notions, and allowing them to be reducible to
identity, as in the latter part of the Protagoras. And
Aristotle still more obviously abstains from rejecting
pleasure altogether, as an end of human action. In
the end of the Second Book of the Nicomachean Ethics,
he tells us that we miist avoid by all means the in-
fluence of Pleasure, and urge her removal from our
state, as the Trojan old men wanted to have Helen's
pernicious beauty removed from among themj (refer-
ring to Homer, II. in. 156),
They cried. No wonder such celestial channs
For nine long years have set the world in arms.
Yet hence, Heav'n, convey that fatal face,
And from destruction save the Trojan race.
Yet in the last Book of the Ethics (x. i) he warns us
against too largely depreciating pleasure as the end of
LECT.VII.J STOICS AND EPICUREANS — CICERO. 5 1
action. He says (p. 503, Gillies' Aristotle), "Severe
moralists, therefore, think that they cannot too much
stigmatise Pleasure, that those whom they wish to
benefit by their discourses may be deterred from ex-
cess, and confined within the bounds of propriety.
They should take care, however, lest this proceeding
be not attended with effects contrary to their expecta-
tion ; for in practical matters, men pay less attention
to what is said than to what is done ; and when opi-
nions, just and reasonable within certain limits, are
carried to a length manifestly inconsistent with expe-
rience, they are rejected disdainfully and completely;
even the truth which they contain being overwhelmed
and lost in the suiTOunding falsehood. Thus, those de-
tractors of pleasure, when they are observed on any
occasion to pursue it with much eagerness, appear to
the bulk of mankind no better than hypocritical volup-
tuaries; for the people at large are not capable of
making distinctions ; they consider things in the gross,
and therefore continually confound them. The truth,
therefore, best serves not only to enlighten our under-
standings, but to improve our morals. For when our
doctrines are true, our lives will more naturally be
conformable to them ; and our precepts being con-
firmed by examples, will produce conviction, and ex-
cite emulation of our virtues, in those with whom
we live." But the distinction between pleasure and
moral good, considered each as the supreme or sole
end of human action, became more apparent when
two sects were formed, one maintaining the one, and
the other the other of these two extreme opinions.
The Epicureans and the Stoics, who respectively held
these two opinions, may be looked upon as being de-
velopments of the tendencies of thought which we
have seen in Polemarohus and Thrasynoachus on the
one side, and in Socrates on the other, in the Eepvhlic.
And although we may assent to the prudence of Ari-
stotle's caution against expressing these oppositions in
a too vehement and partial manner, yet we shall find
that there is a real opposition in these trains of thought,
and that the views which are arrayed against each
4—2
52 HISTORY OF MOBAL PHILOSOPHY. [lECT.
other in the moral dialogues of Plato do natui-ally
unfold themselves into antagonist systems, such as
those of the Epicureans and the Stoics.
In order to bring before the reader the opposition
of these t-wo sects, 1 shall refer to Eoman rather than
to Greek writers — ^to Cicero, rather than to the accounts
■which we have of the teaching of Epicurus and of
Zeno. For these contrasted schools had assumed more
of reality among the Romans than the disputations of
Greek schools alone could have given them. And
there is this further charm in the dialogues of Cicero :
they are invested with costume and circumstance,
which, though entirely different from those of the Pla^
tonic dialogues, have the same national and local truth.
Eor the leading men of Rome in the time of Cicero, —
those who like him employed themselves in thoughtful
and literary occupations,— did really attach themselves
to one or other of the rival sects to which Greek
masters had given birth; and a comparison and balanc-
ing of the doctrines and arguments of these sects was
a favourite employment of their moments of leisure.
Cato loved to speak as well as to act Stoically; and in
his sphere of utterance and of action, in the senate and
the campaign, in the extreme positions of eminence
and peril in which public business and civil commo-
tions placed man, and that man a Roman, he was a far
more splendid and normal example of a Stoic than
Greek ingenuity without the aid of Roman history,
could have produced. It is to Cato that the office is
given of expounding the Stoical doctrines in the work
of Cicero to which I mainly refer at present ; the Dia-
logue De Finibus Bonorwm et Malonim,, Of the Ends of
action. That this is the meaning which he intends to
convey by the title of the work we see in the Eirst
Book of the Dialogue (c. 12, ad fin.), where he says : " Id
est vel . "Clarke and Leibnitz Papers. Appendix on Collins, p. 9. And Reply
to 2nd Cambridge Letter, p. 409."
2 Prospective Hemew, Not. 1852, p. 563.
XIII.] DR S. CLARKE. 109
Clarke's views on the subject under question are
given in- his Discourse concerning the Unchangeable
Obligations of Natural Religion, preached as the Boyle's
Lectures in 17,05. His Discou/rse on the Being and
Attrihut%s of God was in like manner composed of the
Sermons preached in the year 1704. The two Dis-
courses being commonly printed in the same volume,
the latter, the ethical one, has perhaps come to be less
noticed than the former, the theological dissertation.
The argument for the being of God founded on the
idea of self-existence, which occupies the principal place
in the Theological Treatise, is perhaps too abstruse and
metaphysical for most persons in these days to feel its
force: but the arguments against Hobbes's view of
human nature and human morality, which occur in the
later Discourse, are worthy of our attention, and may
still be accepted, as weighty and substantial, if we take
care not to be misled by the author's illustrations.
To the assertion of Hobbes, that there is not
by nature any such thing as justice and injustice, —
right and wrong, the answer is, that such an assertion
is contrary to the natural and universal conviction of
the human mind; — that we do constantly and necessa-
rily recognize such distinctions as right and wrong,
such qualities as justice and equity; and perceive in
these distinctions, and these qualities, an obligation to
follow one course of action and to shun another. This is
an answer to the Hobbian, — the antimoral doctrine, —
which, in one foi-m or other, all persons of ordinary
moral habits of thought are ready to make.
But in order to make this answer definite and precise
enough for the purposes of philosophical argumentation,
ethical writers have naturally attempted to explain, by
definition and comparison, the nature of this conviction.
We have an irresistible and inevitable conviction, as
we have said, that there are such relations as right
and wrong, just and unjust, and that rightness and
justice involve obligation on us. But in what Faculty
does the source of this conviction reside? Of irre-
sistible and inevitable convictions have we any other
examples by which we may illustrate these funda-
no HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [lECT.
mental moral convictions? To the latter inquiry, the
answer was obvious, that we have irresistible and in-
evitable convictions, necessary and universal truths,
concerning various external matters — concerning space,
time, and number, for instance; we have th^ axioms
of geometry, the ftindamental principles of arithmetic ;
— these are truths which we must hold and assent to
if we think on such subjects at all. These are truths
which are necessary and universal ; and the relations
on which they depend may be called eternal, for we
cannot conceive any world in which they do not exist,
and do not give rise to such truths; we cannot con-
ceive any mind which perceives the relations and does
not perceive the resulting truths. If the fundamental
moral convictions of which we have spoken be as firm
and sure as these, they belong to the most stable part
of our nature ; and the relations on which these con-
victions depend may also be called eternal. If this be
so, the denial of the existence of Tightness and justice,
in the cases ia which the relations exist from which
Tightness and justice result, is a contradiction of our
nature of the same kind as the denial of an evident
geometrical or arithmetical truth.
And Clarke, holding that this is the case, was led
to speak of antimoral doctrines in the same language
which we apply to geometrical falsities. The fitness
and unfitness of certain courses of action was held to
be as manifest as the congruities or incongruities of dif-
ferent mathematical figures (p. 177), "For a man endued
with Reason to deny the tmth of these things is as if
a man that understands Geometry or Arithmetic (p. 1 7 9)
should deny the most obvious and known proportions
of lines or numbers, and perversely contend that the
whole is not equal to all its parts, or that a square is
not double a triangle of equal base and height." And the
denial of such moral proportions can only arise " from
the extremest stupidity of mind, corruption of manners,
or perverseness of spirit." "Any man of ordinary ca-
pacity and unbiassed judgment, plainness, and simpli-
city; who had never read and never been told that
there were men and philosophers who had in earnest
XIII.] DR S. CLARKE. Ill
asserted and attempted to prove that there is no natu-
ral and unalterable difference between good and evil ;
■would at the first hearing, be as hardly persuaded to
believe that it could enter into the heart of any intel-
ligent man to deny all natural difference between right
and wrong, as he would be to believe that there could
be any geometer who would seriously and in good
earnest lay it down as a first principle, that a crooked
line is as straight as a straight one." " There are in
morals as in geometry certain eternal and unalterable
relations, aspects, and proportions of things, with they:
consequent agreements and disagreements (p. i86).
And what these absolutely and necessarily are in them-
selves, that also they appear to be to the understand-
ings of aU Intelligent Beings : except those only who
understand things to be what they are not, that is,
whose understandings are either very imperfect or
very much deformed. And by this understanding or
knowledge of the natural and necessary relations, fit-
nesses and proportions of things, the wills likewise of
all intelligent beings are constantly directed; except-
ing those only who wiU things to be what they are
not and cannot be; that is, whose Wills are corrupted
by particular Interests or Affections, or swayed by
some unreasonable and prevailing passion."
And this is put again and again. Thus p. 1 88 : " He
that refuses to deal with all men equitably, and as he
desires they should deal with him, is guilty of the very
same unreasonableness and contradiction in one case,
as he that in another case should affirm one number or
quantity to be equal to another, and yet that other at
the same time, not to be equal to the first." And if
rational creatures do not regulate their will by right
Keason and the necessary difference of good and evil ;
"these (p. 189), setting up their own unreasonable self-
will in opposition to the nature and reason of things,
endeavour (as much as in them lies) to make things be
what they are not and cannot be : which is the highest
presumption and greatest insolence, as well as the
greatest absurdity imaginable. 'Tis acting contrary
to that understanding, reason and judgment which
1 12 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [lECT.
God has implanted in their nature on purpose to enable
them to discern the difference between good and evil.
'Tis attempting to destroy that order by which the
universe subsists. 'Tis offering the greatest affi-ont
imaginable to the Creator of all things, who made
things to be what they are, and governs everything
according to the Laws of their several natures. In a
word, all wilful wickedness and perversion of Right is
the very same incoherence and absurdity in moral mat-
ters, as it would be in natural things for a man to pre-
^nd to alter the certain proportions of numbers, to
take away the demonstrable relations and properties of
mathematical figures, to make darkness light and light
darkness; to call sweet bitter and bitter sweet."
In this language we have the attempt to claim
for our moral convictions the same degree of evidence
which belongs to our mathematical convictions; but
the attempt is inainly supported by these repeated
assertions that the evidence in one case is not only as
complete as in the other, but also that it is so far of
the same kind, that it may be illustrated by the other.
To cheat in a bargain, is compared to the act of con-
founding straight and curved. The former is as ab-
surd as the latter. The same phrases are applied to
the violation of moral rectitude, as of geometrical
tmth.
Now that the conviction in morals is as clear as in
geometry, maybe: but even if it be so, it is not of the
same kind; and the subject can only be confused by
an attempt to assimilate the expressions of moral con-
viction to those of mathematical certainty. The fact
is, that each of these classes of convictions has its
appropriate language. What we accept into our con-
viction in geometry, we accept as true; what we accept
in morality, we accept as right. In the one case, we
assent, in the other,' we approve. What we object in
mathematics, we deny, as false ; what we reject in
ethics, we condemn, as wrong. There is a fundamental
difference between these two classes of tmths. It does
not express our convictions, to say it is absurd to
cheat, to lie, to murder : absurd or not, it is wrong, it
XIII.] DR S. CLARKE. II3
is wicked. It does not express our convictions to say
that it is insolent, •presumpiMous, to pretend to alter
the truths of geometry : it is simply absiM-d to talk of
it, for we cannot set about it. It does not express
our convictions to say that by violating moral rules -we
endeavour to make things what they are not; and that*
this is absurd, insolent, presumptuous, and therefore
to be avoided. To act as if we had not made a pro-
mise when we have done so, is fraudulent; but the
condemnation which we bestow on the act is not con-
veyed by calling it absurd, presumptuous and inso-
lent. When we refuse to pay our creditor, we treat
him as if he were not a creditor, and thus violate, it is
said, the nature of things : Be it so. But we treat
him as a person whose money is useful to us, which
may be quite agreeable to the nature of things. It
must be that especial natv/re of things which belongs
to morality, which is violated, and not merely some
wider nature of things which includes geometry, in
order that we may have moral convictions on the case.
All the progression of terms, from false and ahswd
at one extreme, to vmreasonahle, preswmptuous, inso-
lent — destructive of order — affrort to the Creator — at
the other extreme, are intended to make a transition
from eosistence to obligation — from being to duty — from
mathematical to moral truth — ^from the pure indicative
to the implied imperative — a transition which cannot
thus be made. And so far, Dr Clarke's scheme, or at
least his illustrations, are not satisfactory.
But if we suppose this defect remedied — ^if we
suppose the illustrations to express merely the degree
of conviction, and not the kind of truth: — will
Dr Clarke's views then deserve to be adopted ? Will
his arguments then have a good claim on our assent ? In
a great degree I conceive that they will. For we really
have a settled and unchajigeable conviction that there
is a difference of right and wrong, and that rightness
implies obligation on us to act. That an action is right,
is a reason for doing it, supreme above all other
reasons, and against which any other reason has no
force. To form the conviction of such Rightness in
M, P. II. 8
1 14 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHT. [lECT.
actions is a fundamental and universal habit of the
human mind.
Bat may this conviction be properly said to be a
perception of a fitness arising from the eternal relations
of persons and actions, in the same sense in -which
• the conviction of the axioms of geometry arises from
a perception of the eternal relations of space? It
•would, I think, be somewhat bold, and a boldness by
which nothing is gained for ethical philosophy, to
use such language. Even in geometry, it is difficult
to see what we gain by calling the truths of the
science, or the relations on which they depend, eternaZ.
But however this be, it is plain that moral truths
depend upon the relations of human nature as it is ;
and though it may be impossible for us to conceive
a moral being other than such as we know man to be,
yet such as he is, we know him only by knowing
what other men are, and what we ourselves are: —
by observation, experience, consciousness. To call the
relations of persons, dispositions, actions, with which
morality has to do, eternal relations, is language neither
necessary for the dignity of moral truth, nor autho-
lized by an examiuation of the case. The fundamental
truths of morality may be as solid as we need, and as
comprehensive as their nature admits o^ though they
be limited to the time, place, manner, and conditions
of man's existence. But though there is nothing
gained by calling them etekn^al truths, it is of the
greatest value to us to know them to be truths. And
the conviction that they are so, which Clarke's ex-
pressions imply, belongs to that part of human nature
by which we (men in general) reject and disown such
antimoral doctrines as those of Hobbes.
The part of human nature in which these convic-
tions reside, Dr Clarke calls, as we have seen, the
Reason, the Under stamding, and the Uke. Is there
any ground for rejecting or condemning this phraseo-
logy- — If it he accepted according to the usage of
preceding English philosophical writers, I conceive that
there is not. The Reason was with them the faculty
by which we apprehend the truth oi first principles of
Xm.] DR S. CLARKE. I15
reasoning, as -well as the faculty by wliich we reason
from first principles to consequent truths. And this
■was understood so as to include the principles of moral
truths as well as of mathematical. And the Under-
standing differed from the Reason, when it was made
to differ at all, only as it accepted the results of the
Reason in an implicit and ultimate form, instead of
regarding explicitly the steps by which they were
obtained. So far therefore there was no obstacle to
Clarke's saying that by the use of Right Reason, we
discern the moral relations of persons and actions, the
difference of right and wrong, the superiority of justice
over injustice.
But though this was conformable to the usage of
preceding philosophical writers, and might then, and
may still, be properly said, Clarke himself had la-
boured much, in this very book, to make it appear that
the truths which Reason contemplates, and which she
can derive from first principles, are all of the nature
of mathematical truths. He had done this, as I have
said, by constantly comparing false moral propositions
with false mathematical propositions; and by applying
to the moral doctrines which he rejects, the expres-
sions which imply the grounds of rejection of mathe-
matical doctrines ;— -that they are absurd, — contrary to
the eternal relations of things, — and. the like.
I conceive, therefore, that it may truly be said of
Clarke (nearly as I have said of him p. 98), that he
ascribed great weight to intellectual relations, and
spohe as i/ he overlooked those relations in which the
intellect had not a direct or sole jurisdiction: and
that in this way, his language on the subject of moral
distinctions as perceived by the Reason, was not so
consistent and satisfactory as that of Cudworth and
the ancient philosophers. By him, in his illustrations
at least, the office of Reason had been narrowed and
bounded: and on this account it was less safe (or at
least less appropriate) to say that the distinctions of
moral good and evil were objects of the Reason, than
it had been before. But in saying, as I have said,
that this separation of Reason from the other facul-
8—2
Il6 HISTORY OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [LECT.^
ties was made in virtue of the teaching of Descartes,
Locke and others, I have spoken erroneously. It
was the work of Clarke himself; who thus, in at-
tempting to make his doctrine precise, and to illus-
trate it luminously, really made it untenable; at least,
except we enlarge his view of the Keason as it is
exhibited in his illustrations. Moral distinctions and
consequent truths may be said to be perceived by
the Reason; but in order to avoid misapprehension we
may say that they are perceived by the Moral Reason,
as mathematical distinctions and consequent truths
are perceived by the Pure Intellect.
But when we say that moral distinctions and
moral truths are perceived by the Moral Reason,
we may be asked how we are to determine what truths
are thus perceived. Is the Moral Reason a Moral
Sense, which discerns truths directly without reasoning,
as any other sense discerns the qualities of its objects?
No: this is a doctrine which the use of the term
Beason excludes. Reason, as we have said, discerns
truths deduced from first principles of reasoning, and
discerns also such first principles themselves. In the
former sense it has been tei-med the Discursive Rea-
son ; in the latter, the Intuitive Reason.
But we may then be asked, what are the first
principles of morality which the Reason thus discerns?
Where are they to be found ? how many are they ?
how limited? how recognized? has Dr Clarke given
a list of them, or shown how such a list may be
constructed? Many such questions may naturally be
asked : and the answers, as contaiued in Dr Clarke's
books, are, I conceive, very imperfect. They are im-
perfect, among other reasons, for the reason already
stated: that he clothes his moral principles as much
as possible in language which implies a parallelism
with mathematical principles, and which is consistent
with the declaration that they are derived from the
eternal relations and difierences of things. Whereas, as
we have said, the differences and relations on which
moral truths depend, are the qualities of Human Na-
ture as we find it : 3,nd the firpt principles of morality
XIII.] DR S. CLAEKE. II7
must depend on the Springs of Action by which men
are impelled, and the relations of human society which
the play of those springs requires. It is by taking
into account these springs of action, and these rela-
tions, that the Moral Eeason gives substance and dis-
tinctness to the first principles of which it perceives
the truth. We perceive, by the moral use of our
E.eason, a difference of Justice and of Injustice, and
the obligation of Justice upon our course of action.
But what is Justice? In order to be able to answer,
in general, we must assume the existence of Property,
a fact of Human Society, not properly described as an
eternal truth. The Eight of Property being estab-
lished, the Idea of Justice has something to operate
upon; without some such subject to deal with, the
Idea of Justice can scarcely take an intelligible form.
Thus Clarke's language prevented his following
into detail, at least in a complete and systematic
manner, his doctrine of fundamental moral truths
apprehended by the Eeason. We hold, as he held, that
there are certain moral truths of which all men are
convinced, and which are the basis of all real morality;
but we hold also that these truths are suggested, and
the application of them governed, by the kinds of
Eights which exist among men : and these kinds of
Eights are determined, as we have said, by the pre-
dominant Springs of human Action, and the Eolations
of society necessary for the orderly and permanent
operation of those springs of action. Such a determi-
nation of the various kinds of Eightness or Virtue,
by taking the various kinds of Eights as their fixed
points, and material centers, is, we conceive, needed
to complete the doctrine of the necessary perception of
moral truths by the Eeason of man.
I have dwelt the longer on Clarke's speculations,
because I conceive that, with the correction which
I have mentioned, the rejection of the attempt to
force the nature of moral truth to agree with that of
mathematical truth, his views would probably have
been accepted by Locke. I have been blamed for
injustice to Locke, as well as to Clarke : and I believe,
Il8 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [lEOT.XIII.
as I have said, that Locke would have rejected with
disgust the antimoral doctrines of Hobbes, and of his
followers. But it is not the less true that those doc-
trines were the natural consequence of the doctrines
of Locke himself. (See Lect. p. 96). Yet the expres-
sions which he uses (see Lect. p. 95) are such as would
very well faU in with Clarke's views. And I am willing
to allow that in what I have said in p. 92, I have
pressed too far what Locke has said; of good and evil
being nothing but pleasure and pain'.
1 On this subject see also Defena of Clarke, by Balguy, Lectnre, p. 13P.
See also p. 113.
Hunie's Objections to Clarke's doctrine that moral qualities are appre-
hended by the Beason 1 have stated in p. 196.
LECTUEE XIV.
Reason and UNDEKSTANDUfa — S. T. Coleeidge.
IT has appeared in the last Lecture and elsewhere,
that the term Reason is sometimes used in a higher
sense, to denote a faculty -which discerns certain
truths by intuition, and sometimes in a lower sense, to
denote a faculty which deals with derivative truths.
Mr Coleridge and his admirers have attempted to mark
this difference, by calling the former faculty the Bea-
son, the latter the UnderstcmcKng. Coleridge's influ-
ence on the philosophy of England in our days has
been so great, and in many respects so beneficial, that
a distinction which was propounded by him as a
cardinal one deserves a careful consideration j and I
shall now examine what he has said on this subject.
The passages to which I refer are contained in the
book published under the title of Aids to RefleoUon.
In this book are given certain Aphorisms on Spiritiml
Religion; of which a portion consists of sentences
extracted from Archbishop Leighton, with a Comment
by Mr Coleridge. To the Comment on Aphorism viii.
is appended a Dissertation On the Difference in Kind
of the Reason a/nd Understa/nding . In this disserta-
tion are found the assertions of Mr Coleridge which
I have now to notice.
According to him, the Understanding is the faculty
which judges according to Sense, and obtains truth by
generalizing from experience; while Reason sees
Truth by Intuition. Thus, by the Understanding
we see that all the triangles which we observe have,
each of them, two sides together gres^ter than the
third. But by the Reason we know, without expe-
I20 HISTORY or MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [lECT.
rience, that every triangle must have two sides
greater than the third. He draws up coliunns of
antitheses between the two, which run thus : Under-
stcmding is discursive, Eeason is fixed: Understanding
is the faculty of reflexion: Reason, of contemplation;
and so on. He, further, teaches that Understanding
is so far dilfferent from Eeason, that it is of the same
nature with the Instinct of brutes.
Now all this I conceive to be quite at variance
both with the universal use of our language, and with
any just analysis of our mental faculties. All good
writers agree in describing the Eeason, not the Under-
standing, as the faculty which is discursive, as well as
intuitive ; that is, which not only perceives first truths
by intuition, but also obtains second and third truths
by running backwards and forwards among these first
truths, in short, by reasoning. The very term Dis-
course is only an abbreviated expression for Discourse
of Reason, Discwrsus Rationis; so essentially is the
Eeason discursive^.
The distinction between the Eeason and the Under-
standing as substantives, is not so evident as the dis-
tinction between the verbs to reason and to under-
stand. These are often put in opposition. We may
say, for example, that we understand a thing at once,
without reasoning about itj — ^that we understand the
sense of a language, without reasoning about the ety-
mology or syntax. And I think the sense in which
the verb to umderstamd is thus taken is, as I have
stated^, that we understand anything when Ve mentally
apprehend it according to certain assumed ideas and
rules; whereas when we reason about the same thing,
1 We may remark that Milton makes the Intuitive Keason predominate
in natures superior to human^ while the Discursive Keason belongs more
properly to man. The Angel tells Adam that the productions of the material
world (P. L. Book v. 483I,
Man's nourishmentj by gradual scale sublimed.
To vital spirits asjjiie, t« animal.
To intellectual: give both life and sense.
Fancy and understanding: whence the soul
Beason receives, and reason is her being
Discursive or iittuiUve; discourse
Is oftest yourSt the latter most is ours^
BifFering but in degree, of kind the same.
' Elementa of Morality, Art 11.
XIV.] REASON AND UNDERSTANDING. 121
•we do not assume otir rules, but prove them from
preceding truths. And thus, exactly contrary to what
Mr Coleridge says, Understanding is fixed (by assimip-
tion or previous proof), and Beason is discursive (in
ratiocination).
And this is the vie-w taken by old writers, and
by them confirmed by a reference to the supposed
origin of the two words. Thus Sir John Davies, in
his Poem on the Immortality of the Soul, says of the
Mind,
"When she rates things, and moves from ground to ground,
The name of Reason she obtains irom this ; (ratio)
But when by reason she the truth hath found.
And standeth firm, she Understanding is.
That is, the mind is called Reason, Batio, when it
rates and compares things, regarding them from dif-
ferent points of view: it is called Understanding,
when having acquired a fixed view, she remains steady
in that. We make our conviction to stajid under the
visible or sensible appearance, so as to give meaning
to it. This account of the origin of the word under-
stand may "be fanciful, and is etymologioally doubtful ;
but it is consistent with our view, and may serve to
fix that view in our minds.
Mr Coleridge, when he says that the Keason is
fixed and contemplative, while the Understanding is
discursive and reflective, does so, with a view of
placing the discursive fiiculty below the contemplative.
And no doubt the verb to reason is not generally re-
garded with so much respect as the substantive Rear-
son. The Reason has higher senses than Reasoning.
In the Femmes Sgavantes the master of the hpuse
complains that there is in his family so much Rea-
soning that there is no Reason j
Raison est I'emploi de toute ma maison,
Et le raisonnement en chasse la Raison.
The verb to reason is always employed to desig-
nate the discursive or ratiocinative operations of the
mind; and as the verb to understand implies a fixed
122 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHT. [lBCT.
contemplation, if we were to adopt Mr Coleridge's
account of the distinction of the substantives, we
should have to assert that by the Understcmdinff we
reason, and by the Reason we vnderstand. But, as I
have ventured to say elsewhere, this is neither good
English nor good philosophy.
Nor do we find any better support for Mr Cole-
ridge's view if we turn to the author to whom he him-
self refers. He ascribes to Archbishop Leighton the
definition of Understanding, that it is the Faculty
judging according to Sense : but Leighton's words are,
as "Eeason corrects the errors of sense,, so super-
natural Faith corrects the errors of Reason" (not Un-
derstanding,) "judging according to sense."
Mr Coleridge lays great stress upon this definition
of Understanding, that it is the Faculty judging ac-
cording to sense; and makes it the basis of a distinc-
tion of the Reason and the Understanding, at the
foot of which he writes Q. E. D. He also further ex-
alts the Reason, by ascribing to it the Newtonian
theory of the universe, while the Understanding,
judging according to sense, gave rise to the Ptolemaic
hypothesis. But this distinction and contrast is alto-
gether false and baseless. The Ptolemaic and the
Newtonian system do not proceed from different
faculties of the mind, but from the same power, exer-
cised more and more completely. By the Ptolemaic
theory we understand mttch of the motions of the
planets, as their cycles of movement and the like:
by the Newtonian theory we understand stOl more,
their elliptical paths, and the forces which guide them
therein. The Ptolemaic system introduces its own
constitutive Ideas and laws supplied by the Reason,
quite as much as the Newtonian system does : — indeed
more; for instance, the Idea and Law of uniform cir-
cular motion as universal : — a law not supplied by the
senses, and in fact, when carefully examined, contrary
to the phenomena. The Newtonian system intro-
duces its Ideas and Laws, of which the value and the
proof is that they are "according to sense," that is,
consistent with the phenomena. In both cases, by
XIV.] REASON AND UNDERSTANDING. J 23
reasoning from the pienomena, and by applying our
Reason to them, we are in the end, able to wnderstamd
them. The work of the Reason is then completely
done when we Understand : so far is the understand-
ing (if the substantive have any connexion with the
verb,) from being a lower faculty than the Eeason, as
Mr Coleridge teaches.
Mr Coleridge says that the Ptolemaist was misled
by sense, in supposing the .earth to stand still. He
was so; and why? Because he did not understand
the effect of relative motion to produce apparent rest
in the spectator, and apparent motion in the station-
aiy center. It was not because he used his under-
standing only, but because he did not use it enough,
that he stopped short of the Copernican theory. The
Copemican, the Newtonian, employed no new organ,
no new faculty, neglected by the Ptolemaist. Each
of these in his turn used the same organ, his Reason,
so as to wnderstand the phenomena better.
In short, science gives no countenance to such a
distinction and subordination of faculties. There is
in science no faculty which judges according to sense
without doing something more; and no creative or
suggestive faculty which must not submit to have its
creations and suggestions tested by the phenomena.
False science is known precisely by its not bearing
this test. But true and false science proceed from the
same faculties, well or ill employed; and any attempt
to establish a ready criterion of truth and error, by
ascribing some theories and doctrines to Reason and
some to Understanding, is purely arbitrary; and can
only lead to ignorant dogmatism : — to groundless de-
l)reciation of the opinions thus rejected, and equally
groundless confidence in those adopted.
But the disposition to disparage the Understand-
ing appears in Mr Coleridge in another form, of
which it may be proper to say a few words, because
he urges it as very important; though I do not think
that really it bears much upon our moral or religious
systems. He asserts the Understanding of man to be
tibe same faculty in kind with the faculty by which
124 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [LECT.
brutes act, and wliicli we commonly call Instinct. I
suppose that the antithesis between Reason and 7w-
stinct which is commonly current, while yet there are
many acts of animals which we can with difficulty,
or not at all, distinguish from rational actions, ap-
peared to him to receive a kind of solution by the
assumption of a lower faculty in man, of the same
kind with the faculties of animals : and by introducing
the Understanding as such an intermediate fecully,
the Ereason of man was, as it were, hedged off from
the lower faculties which brutes possess, and its dig-
nity preserved intact. But I do not think that tMs
mode of meeting the difficulty is justified either by
the use of language or by the facts of the case. If
we commonly say that animals are destitute of Rea-
son, we sny no less usually that they have no .Under-
standing. £e ye not like to horse and mule, which have
no wnder standing. In the language of Scripture, in-
deed. Understanding is used for the highest form of
mind : " Who hath stretched out the heavens by His
Understanding," Jer. li 15; and so, in many other
places.
In reality, the word understand is not nearly
so appb'cable to brutes as the word reascm. Instinct
is often called a blind, or unconscious, or undeveloped
Eeason; but it is never called a blind Understanding.
And this must needs be so; for Instinct leads to ac-
tion, and therefore may be the result of a Uind faculty ;
but to understand, involves seeing. A blind impulse,
producing effects like that of reason, shows itself in
instinctive actions; but it is only when the reason
acquires its power of sight, that it makes its possessor
understa/nd what he does.
We may illustrate this by a story of instinct told
by Sir W. Jardine, and diffeiing a little from the
stories which Mr Coleridge quotes from Kirby and
Spence. A cat lived near a mill, and notwithstanding
the adage, caught fish in the water. When the mUI
was stopped, the dam was closed, the water below
became shallow, and the cat could carry on her fishing
with success. After some time she became so well
XIV.] REASON AND UNDEESTANDING. 125
acquainted with the order of events that whenever
she heard the mill-hoppei- stop, she ran to the water
and began the chase of her prey. Was this Reason 1
Was it Understanding? Perhaps many persons will
think that the process is sufficiently accounted for by
being ascribed to the Association of Ideas; or as in
this case, at least, we may better describe it, the
Association of Impressions. The silence of the mill
was by habit associated with the shallowness of the
water. And a human being, a man, as well as a cat,
might have done the same thing and on the same
ground; might have noticed that the silence of the
mill was constantly accompanied by the shallowness
of the water, and have acted on this observation.
But if the man knew nothing of the structure of the
mUl, he would say, I find that this is so, but I cannot
vmderdand why it is : and when be came to perceive
the mode of working of the stream, the sluice-gate
and the mill, he might say, Now I understand: that
is, precisely when he obtains the view which distin-
guishes the man from the brute, he wnderstamds.
Understanding is the peculiai'ly human faculty,
Nor does the assumption of an intermediate faculty
at all help to solve the real difficulty of the question
concerning the relation of Reason and Instinct. The
difficulty is suggested by the very phrase which I have
used; that Instinct is a blind Reason : for it being the
essence of Reason to see, how can she exist blind? or,
stating the matter otherwise, how can animals act as
if they had a knowledge of the relations of space, force,
and the like, when they have no such knowledge? If
their instinctive acts proved their knowledge, they
must have more knowledge than man has. How can
the effects of a profound Reason be produced in crea-
tures which are not rational?
And it is well known that this difficulty has ap-
peared to some persons so great that they have solved
it by saying, Beus est anima brutorum, God is the
soul of brutes. Without pretending fully to solve
this problem, we may remark that man has Instincts,
as well as other animals; but that in man these In-
126 HISTORY or MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [lECT.
stincts are gradually superseded by Reason. Instinct
blindly assumes relations, -whicli Reason sees; but
Reason may come to see these relations, and then
the actions cease to be blindly instinctive. Instinct
is stimulated to act by the impressions of sense;
but these impressions also awake the Reason, by
which feculty we contemplate the relations of things.
Instinct and Reason in man are not two separate
spheres. They have a common center, the impres*
sions of the individual. But in man, the boundaries
of the sphere of Instinct are more and more oblite-
rated, as its elements are absorbed into the wider
sphere of Reason : and the sphere of Reason has no
discoverable boundary, but expands wider and wider,
and endeavours to extend its contemplations to the
whole universe. Instinct assumes the- relations of
things to be what they are : Reason aspires to know
what they are, and has a consciousness that the task
is hers. " The same views which lead men to say
that Gcod is the soul of brut-es, lead them also to
say that the Reason of man is derived from and has
something in common with the Universal Reason
which made the relations of things to be what they
are.
This doctrine is I think, really, the important part
of Mr Coleridge's speculations on this subject: and
this doctrine does not depend upon his distinction of
the Reason and the Understanding. The Reason, in
some of its aspects, may be regarded as the image or
participation of a Universal Reason. Reason is con-
sidered as the same in all men. It leads to truth, not
in virtue of individual personal impressions, but in
virtue of its own nature. To Reason, so understood,
Mr Coleridge has ground for applying the scriptural
expression, that It is the Light thai lighteth every one
thai Cometh into the world; though we must own that
the attempt to weave scriptural expressions into a
scheme of metaphysics is not without its inconveni-
ences and dangers. Reason so considered is not too
highly spoken of, when we describe it as .^n image of
the Divine mind; for truths which we conceive as
XIV.] REASON AND UNDERSTANDING. 127
necessary aad universal, we must conceive to be con-
templated as truths by the Mind which framed the
universe and created other minds. In this sense, the
Reason of man implies a participation iu an Eternal
and Universal Reason.
But if this be so, we ai-e naturally led to ask,
What subjects come within the sphere of Reason so
considered? We plainly cannot content ourselves with
including in it merely the relations which sense per-
ceives, as space, mechanical action, and the like.
Reason, to make it answer such an account as we
have given, must include the things and actions which
belong to man's moral and spiritual nature : for these
also belong to the scheme which the Eternal and
Universal Mind has brought into being, and which
connect us with that mind. They do this, at least as
much as do the relations which can be apprehended by
our external sense. Have we then, with regard to
moral and spiritual things, as with regard to things of
sense, a Reason which is the source of universal and
necessary truths, such as sense could never assure us
of? Mr Coleridge maintains that we have. Even if
we follow him in this, we must, I think, allow that he
makes the transition from Reason in its application
to the sensible world, to Reason in its application to
the moral and spiritual world, somewhat abruptly and
unsatisfactorily. For after giving his proof (from the
example of geometrical truths) that Reason extends
the truths of sense farther than sense could prove
them, he asserts that Reason affirms truths which no
sense could perceive, nor experiment verify, nor expe-
rience confirm; assertions which his geometrical ex-
ample does not support. Not only so : but he goes on
to add fiirther, as a test and sign of such truth, that
it is inconceivable, and rrmst come out of the mould of
the Understanding in the disguise of two contradictory
propositions; which certainly is not the case with
geometrical truths.
The object of this startling saltus appears to be,
to claim the authority of Reason, thus exalted, for
some mysterious doctrines of religion, natural or
128 HISTORY OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY. [lECT.
. revealed : namely, That God is a circle the center of
which is everywhere and the circumference nowhere :
That the soul is all in every part : and the declaration
implying the eternal nature of God, Before Abraham
was, I a/m. But it can hardly be considered ■wise
to rush, so suddenly and abruptly at least, through
an inference from the principles of geometry to the
highest truths of religion : and I think that the con-
nexion of the two kinds of truth is not much illus-
trated by what Mr Coleridge says in these passages.
In the present work, I am priucipally concerned
with the bearing of such views on Moral Philosophy.
If there be a faculty such as Reason is thus described
to be, a source of truths of the highest order, which
truths are not capable of being derived, at least in
their folness, from experience, we naturally ask what
truths of this kind can be pointed out in the region of
Morality. Mr Coleridge has indicated that his philo-
sophy contains such truths, and has coupled, (as many
writers have done before him,) Right Reason and
Conscience. But such a conjunction requires some
explanation. There is, at first sight at least, a great
difference between a man's Conscience in its practical
personal operation; and Conscience in that larger
sense in which it is associated with Right Reason, and
almost, it would seem from Mr Coleridge's language,
made identical with that faculty. He does not give
any examples of truths discovered by the Conscience,
as he gives examples of truths discovered by the Reason ;
except perhaps in that part of his disquisition which
refers to Original Sin, where I shall not attempt to
follow him.
We may, however, I think, find examples of
truths derived from the Universal Conscience or eter-
nal Reason of man, and necessarily entering into our
view of morality. Such a truth I conceive is this:
That in order that a man may be really moral, not
only his external actions, but his internal springs of
action, must conform to the Moral Law. Tliis truth
is, I conceive, accepted with clear and iadestructible
conviction by every one who thinks steadily and con-
XIV.] REASON AND UNDERSTANDING, 1 29
sistently on moral subjects, and yet cannot be proved
in its full extent in any other way. It is therefore, I
conceive, a dictate of the Universal Conscience 'or
Moral Reason of mankind.
The -work of Coleridge appears to be valued in
America for this reason especially, that it is supposed
to assert free-will in opposition to necessary connec-
tion; and to maintain the existence of a spiritual as
well as a natural world. See J. Marsh's Preface to
the American edition of the work.
In the preceding remarks, I have said that Reason
in its highest sense may be fitly described as an Image
of the Bivine Mind. This is an expression which has
often been used by the philosophers who have assigned
the most important office to Reason in the appre-
hension of moral, religious and spiritual truth. But I
am not aware that such philosophers have undertaken
to describe the relation of the Image to the Original
Reality otherwise than in the broadest and most gene-
ral terms. In the speculations which I have had to
pursue respecting the progress of scientific discovery,
I have found myself led to attempt to give a more
precise and definite account of this relation; and
though all attempts at definiteness on such a subject,
must be vastly imperfect and scanty, it still appeared
to me that we might justifiably proceed somewhat
beyond the more general and abstract expressions in
which the truth has hitherto been conveyed. In the
work which I have published On the PhUosopky of
Discovery, there is a Chapter (Chapter xxx.) entitled
The Theological Bearing of the Philosophy of JDiscovery,
which contains the views which result from the history
of human thought. And by comparing the aspect of
man as a moral and as a speculative creature, I am
led (Chapter xxxii.) to the aphorisms, that
Mam's Intellectual Progress consists in the Idealiza-
tion of Facts, and that man's Moral Progress consists
in the BealizaMon of Ideas : and further, that
M. P. II. , 9
130 HISTORY 01" MORAL PHILOSOPHY, [lECT. XIV.
All the progress made hy man, ho(h in the Idealiza-
tion of Facts and in the Realization of Ideas, is, and
always will he, exceedingly scanty and incomplete.
And thus though by both these kinds of pro-
gress, man is constantly led and drawn towards the
Divine Nature, he must always remain at an im-
measurable distance below the Divine Eeality. The
Human Reason, however truly it may be termed an
Image of the Divine Mind, must always be an Image
immeasurably imperfect, dim and limited, when com-
pared with the Divine Light and Fulness : this we
can see even by the light of Reason itself. This
is true of the scientific Reason, the Mind of man,
which deals with speculative relations, some of which
we are capable of seeing with intuitive clearness. Still
more is this true of that moral Reason which we
ascribe to the Soul of man. These aspects of the
Reason, the Light that lighteth every man that cometh
into the world, are emanations and beams of the Di-
vine Light : they can lead us but a little way towards
the Divine Light; and in the chasm of darkness which
intervenes between these emanations and their source,
we have abundant need and abundant room for any
helps which may be presented to the mind and soul
in such a way that Reason may i-ather take the name
of Faith.
THE END.
CAMBRIDGE : PRINTED AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS.
WORKS BY WILLIAM WHEWELL, D.D.
The Platonic Dialogues for English Readers,
Vol. I. Containing Dialogues of the Socratio School and
those referring to the Trial and Death of Socrates. Second
Edition. Foolscap Octavo. Cloth, 7«. 6d.
Vol. II. Containing Antisophist Dialogues, Foolscap
Octavo. Cloth, 6s. 6d.
Vol. III. Containing the Eepublic and the Timseua. Fools-
cap Octavo, Cloth, 6s, 6d,
History of the Inductive Sciences. Third Edition.
Three Volumes, Small Octavo, 24s.
History of Scientific Ideas, being the First Part of a
Third Edition of the " Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences."
Two Volumes, Small Octavo, 14s,
Novum Organon Eenovatum ; being the Second Part
of a Third Edition of the "Philosophy of the Inductive
Sciences," With Additions. Small Octavo. 7s.
On the Philosophy of Discovery, Chapters Historical
and Critical ; including the completion of a Third Edition of
the "Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences." Small Octavo, ps.
Indications of the Creator ; Theological Extracts from
the "History and Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences."
Second Edition, Post Octavo. 5s, 6d.
iilements of Morality, including Polity. Third Edi-
tion, with a Supplement, Two Volumes, Small Octavo, igs.
Lectures on Systematic Morality. Octavo, ys, 6d.
On a Liberal Education in General, and with Particu-
lar reference to the Studies of the University of Cambridge,
Parts I. and II, in One Volume. 7«. 6d, Part HI, 2S,
Wofrks hy Dr Whewell contimied.
On the Principles of English University Education.
Second Edition. 5s.
College Chapel Sermons. 10s. 6d.
Notes on German Churches. Third Edition. 1 2s.
Mechanical Euclid, containing the Elements of Me-
chanics and Hydrostatics. Fifth Edition. 5s.
Mechanics of Engineering, gs.
Doctrine of Limits, with its Applications, gs.
Conic Sections. 2S. 6d.
Butler's Sermons on Human Nature. With Preface
and Syllabus by W. Whewell, D.D. 3s. 6d.
Butler's Sermons on Moral subjects. With Preface
and Syllabus, by W. Whewell, D.D. Third Edition. ^sM.
Newton's Principia : Book I. Sections I. II. III.
In Latin. With Notes and Keferenoes, by W. Whewell, D.D.
■2S. 6d,
PUBLISHED BY
DEIGHTON, BELL AND CO.,
AGENTS TO THE UNIVERSITY.
Messiah as Foretold and Expected : A Course of
Sermons on the Prophecies of the Messiah, as Interpreted
by the Jews before the Coming of Christ. Preached before
the University of Cambridge, in the months of February
and March, 1862. By E. Habold Bbownb, B.D., Nor-
rlsian Professor of Divinity, and Canon Residentiary of
Exeter Cathedral. Octavo. Price 4s. [Meady.
Jerusalem Explored : being a Description of the
Ancient and Modem City, with upwards of 100 Illustra-
tions, consisting of Views, Ground-plans, and Sections, by
Ebmbtb Pieeotti, Doctor of Mathematics, Captain of the
Corps of Engineers in the Army of Sardinia, Architect-
Engineer to His Excellency Soorraya Pasha of Jerusalem,
and Architect of the Holy Land. Imperial Quarto.
The Greek Testament : with a Critically revised Text ;
a Digest of various Readings; Marginal References to
Verbal and Idiomatic Usage ; Prolegomena ; and a Critical
and Exegetioal Commentary. For the use of Theological
Students and Ministers. By Henby Alfoed, D.D., Dean
of Canterbury. Octavo.
Vol. I. FonEiH Editimt, containing the Four Gospels.
£1. 8s.
Vol. II. FoiJBTH Edition, containing the Acts of the
Apostles, the Epistles to the Romans and Corinthians.
£1. 4S.
Vol. III. Thied Edition, containing the Epistles to the
Galatiana, Ephesians, Fhilippians, Colosaians, Thessa-
lonians, — to Timotheus, Titus and Philemon. i8s.
Vol. IV. Part I. Second Edition. The Epistle to the
Hebrews: The Catholic Epistles of St James and St
Peter. i8s.
Vol. IV. Part II. Second Edition. The Epistles of St
John and St Jude, and the Revelation. 14s,
Works Published hy Deighton, Bell and Co.
Codex Bezse Cantabrigiensis. Edited, with Prolego-
mena, Notes and Fac-similes, by F. H. Sobivenbb, M.A.
\In die Press.
Observations on the attempted Application of Pan-
theistic Principles to the Theory and Historic Criticism of
the Gospels. By W. H. Mill, D.D. late Eegius Professor
of Hebrew in the University of Cambridge. Second Edition,
■with the Author's latest Notes and Additions, Edited by
B. Webb, M.A. Octavo. 14s.
" It is the one book which we shovJd urge our Divinity
students thoroughly to master, if they would be armed
against the hydraheaded scepticism of our days." — Literary
Churchman, December 2, 1861,
Bentleii Critica Sacra. Notes on the Greek and
Latin Text of the New Testament, extracted from the
Bentley MSS. in Trinity College Library. With the Abb^
Eulotta's Collation of the Vatican MS., a specimen of
Bentley's intended Edition, and an account of all his Col-
lations. Edited, with the permission of the Master and
Seniors, by the Eev. A. A. Ellis, M.A., late Fellow and
Junior Dean of Trinity College, Cambridge. Octavo.
8s. 6d. [Ready.
A Plain Introduction to the Criticism of the New-
Testament. With numerous Fac-similes. For the use of
Bibhoal Students. By F. H. Sceivbnbe, M.A. Octavo. 15*.
" Though well aware, from Mr Scrivener's invaluable
contributions, of his peculiar ability for the task he has
undertaken, we must say that it was not without some
feelings of wonder that we examined the volume before us —
so minute and accurate is the detailed information it con-
veys, and so comprehensive and enlarged is the view which
it takes of the extensive field of Biblical criticism," — English
Churchman,
Novum Testamentnm Grsecum, Textus Stephanici,
1550. Accedunt varise lectiones editionum Bezse, Elzeviri,
Lachmanni, Tischendorfii, et Tregellesii. Curante F. H.
SOBIVENBE, A.M. 4!. 6d.
An Edition on Writing Paper, for Notes. Quarto. Half-
bound. I2S.
" One of the latest additions to the admirably printed
pocket series of Cambridge Greek and Latin Texts
Those portions of the text of which various readings are
given at the foot of each page are printed in a thicker
character of type, so as to be readily perceived." — English
Chwchrmm,
Works Published ly DeigJiton, Bell and Co.
A Companion to the Ne-w Testament. Designed for
the use of Theological Students and the Upper Forms in
Sohoola. By A. C. Babkbtt, M.A. Fop. Octavo, ss.
''A list of the passages of the New Testament explained
or illustrated in its pages, concludes this valuable little
volume, which will not only prove a great acquisition to
Theological Students, but may, in the absence of larger
works, be profitably consulted as a book of reference by
aU engaged in Biblical Studies." — lAterwry Churchmcm,
Sept. 1 6, 1 86 1.
A General Introduction to the Apostolic Epistles,
with a Table of St Paul's Travels, and an Essay on the State
after Death. Second Edition, enlarged. To which are
added a Few Words on the Athanasian Creed, on Justifi-
cation by Faith, and on the Ninth and Seventeenth Articles
of the Church of England. By- a Bishop's Chaplain.
Octavo. 8s. 6d.
The Example of Christ and the Service of Christ, con-
sidered in Three Sermons preached before the University of
Cambridge, in February, i86i. To which are appended a
Few Remarks upon the present State of Religious Feeling.
By Feanois France, B.D., Archdeacon of Ely, and Fellow
of St John's College. Crown Octavo. 2s. 6d.
A. History of the Articles of Religion. To -which is
added a series of Documents from A.D. 1536 to A.D. 1615.
Together with Illustrations from Contemporary Sources.
By Charles Hardwick, B.D., late Archdeacon of Ely.
Second Edition, corrected and enlarged. Octavo. 1 2S.
A considerable amount of fresh matter has been incorpo-
rated, especially in the two chapters which relate to the
consliniction and revision of our present code of Articles.
Psalter (The), or Psalms of David in English Verse.
With Preface and Notes. By a Member of the University
of Cambridge. Dedicated by permission to the Lord Bishop
of Ely, and the Reverend the Professors of Divinity in that
University. 5«.
An Historical and Explanatory Treatise on the Book
of Common Prayer. By W. G. Hitmphbt, B.D., late
Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge. Second Edition,
enlarged and revised. Post Octavo. 7s. 6d.
Works Published hy Deighton, Bell and Co.
The Seven Words Spoken against the Lord Jesus : or,
an Investigation of the Motives which led His Contempo-
raries to reject Him. Being the Hulseau Lectures for the
Year i860. By John Lamb, M.A., Senior Fellow of
Gonville and Caius College, and Minister of S. Edward's,
Cambridge. Octavo. 5s. 6d.
BY THE VERY REV. H. GOODWIN, D.D.
DEAN OP ELT.
On the Imitation of Christ. A New Translation.
i8mo. 3s. 6d.
A Commentary on the Gospel of S. Matthew. Crown
Octavo, lis.
A Commentary on the Gospel of S. Mark. Crown
Octavo. 7«. 6s.
Intended for the English Keader, and adapted for either
domestic or private use.
Parish Sermons. Krst Series. Third Edition. 1 2mo.
6s.
Parish Sermons. Second Series. Third Edition. 1 2mo.
6s.
Parish Sermons. Third Series. Second Edition. 1 2mo.
^s.
Parish Sermons. Eonrth Series. i2mo. 7s.
Parish Sermons. Eifth Series. In the Press.
A Guide to the Parish Church. Second Edition.
iSmo. 3s. 6d.
A Cheaper Edition for distribution. Price is. sewed,
IS. 6d. cloth.