EO Oat Cee ~ VIP ARS SE OSES, re i SLOG Gee OCU COOa GP epee eT ae ae RSET AK eS . ss Ries ee Leet tee eh eet ty rS Tete eee ms BOE ASN 2G re yy . aor ae re 5 SELECTED ESSAYS OF ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER. SELECTED ESSAYS OF ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER. WITH A BIOGRAPHICAL INTRODUCTION AND SKETCH OF HIS PHILOSOPHY. BY ERNEST BELFORT BAX, Author of ‘‘ Handbook of the History of Philosophy,” ete. LONDON: GEORGE BELL AND SONS, YORK STREET, COVENT GARDEN. 1891. CHISWICK PRESS :—C. WHITTINGHAM AND CO., TOOKS COURT, CHANCERY LANE. PREFACE. “HE following selection of pieces from the two volumes of Miscellaneous Essays, called by Schopenhauer “Parerga and Paralipomena,” have been made with a view of meeting the taste alike of him that is specially in- terested in philosophy and of the “ general reader.” Some of the essays included in this present volume have been translated before by Mr. Bailey Saunders, and published by Messrs. Swan Sonnenschein, & Co. I may state that the renderings here given have been made without any reference whatever to Mr. Saunders’s work, which I have purposely abstained from consulting. In translating the German author, my aim has been to combine as strict a literality as was possible with a retention of the flavour of the original style in equivalent English idioms. At the same time I have always leant rather toward the side of over-literality than that of mere paraphrase. The introductory memoir and sketch of Schopenhauer’s philo- sophy will, it is hoped, serve to render the meaning of some passages clearer than they would otherwise be to a reader who might take the book up without any previous knowledge of the system to which they belong, in its general aspect. CONTENTS. PREFACE . The Life and Philosophy of Schopenhauer Essays :— Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and Real . Fragments of the History of Philosophy , On Philosophy and its Method Some Reflections on the Antithesis of Thing-i in- -itself and Phenomenon . Z : , 5 ‘ . Some Words on Pantheism On Ethics On the Doctrine of the Tndlesteietibility ata our true N: tutte by Death ‘ , : On Suicide Contributions to the Doctrine of the ication and N ea: tion of the Will-to-live . ‘ j On the Metaphysics of the Beautiful and on | Aisthetios On Thinking for Oneself ‘ ‘ : On Reading and Books On Women INDEX PAGE ix 34 162 Is2 191 195 240 257 263 274 318 329 338 353 THE LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. HE great literary exponent of modern Western pessi- mism, as he is usually deemed, was born in the old Hanseatic town of Dantzic, the 22nd of February, 1788. He was of Dutch descent on both sides. His mother, Johanna Schopenhauer, subsequently became a novelist of considerable, though ephemeral, note. It was by a mere fluke that the subject of our sketch, Arthur Schopenhauer, was not born in England. His father, a Dantzic merchant of considerable means, had all the eighteenth century enthusiasm for English institutions, and the additional connection with Englishmen, which re- sidence in the commercial towns of the Baltic brought with it, especially at that time. He was accordingly anxious that his son should be born on British soil, and to this end undertook a tour with his wife, having London as its goal, in the summer of 1787. Before the time of birth arrived, however, Johanna was seized with a violent longing to re- turn home; and accordingly the future philosopher was ushered into the world, by birth as well as by parentage, a German. The only revenge the old merchant could take upon fate was in the name of his son—Arthur—which was bestowed on account of its cosmopolitan character, at least as regards the three leading nationalities of Western Europe. In 1793 the old “free town” was annexed by Prussia, a circumstance which involved the departure of the x THE LIFE AND Schopenhauers. For father Heinrich Schopenhauer was possessed with great ideas of Hanseatic independence, and the stern municipal republicanism which attached to it. They settled at Hamburg, where Heinrich set up @ new business, which he conducted for twelve years. It was here that Arthur Schopenhauer spent his lehajahre. Old Hein- rich Schopenhauer destined his son to follow his own call- ing. In pursuance of this idea young Schopenhauer was educated. In 1797 he was taken by his father to Paris, and subsequently boarded in the house of a merchant of Havre, Grégoire by name, where he remained for two years, being educated in companionship with the son of his host. At the expiration of this time he returned to Ham- burg, attending a private school for three years. Schopen- hauer junior had, however, never taken kindly to the idea of a mercantile career, and his wishes now definitely turned towards literature, his tastes in this direction bemg fostered by the literary society he met at his father’s house, and to which his mother was greatly addicted. His father, after much entreaty, gave his partial consent, and thought of purchasing a canoury for his son; but the pro- ject fell through, and he reverted once more to his original idea, obtaining the son’s reluctant acquiescence by the bribe of a lengthened sojourn in France and England, to be enjoyed first. Early in 1803, accordingly, the family took their de- parture from Hamburg for Calais and London. While in London, Schopenhauer was placed at the boarding- school of a clergyman at Wimbledon. He found the mechanical discipline extremely irksome to him, and, more than all, the religious training imparted in this establish- ment. There is a passage in one of his letters in which he indicates his disgust, in no measured language, of the atmosphere of cant and hypocrisy which at that time, and for long after, permeated every department of English life, PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xi which concludes: ‘“‘ When will the light of truth burn through these darknesses?” He recurs to the subject several times in the course of his miscellaneous writings, and always in the same strain of inexpressible loathing and contemptuous indignation. At the end of the year the family left England for Paris, touring their route, during the early part of 1804, through provincial France to Switzerland, and ultimately to Vienna. In September young Arthur found his way with his mother alone, his father having gone back to Hamburg, to his native place. Here he entered the office of a Dantzic merchant, and seriously endeavoured to fulfil his pledge to his father at the desk. After a few months, however, he changed the Dantzic office for a Hamburg one; but every month made it more and more apparent that his heart was not in the ledger, the number of moments stolen from business during business hours, in the interest of his books (other than ledgers), were such as to lead to serious remonstrance on the part of his superiors. Just at this time an event occurred, however, which broke up the Schopenhauer household. On the fifth of April, 1805, his father, who had for some little time pre- viously shown signs of aberration or failing of intellect, was found in the canal, having precipitated himself from the upper story of an overhanging building, the universal suspicion being that the case was one of suicide. This was a great blow to Arthur, who, in spite of their disagree- ment on the knotty point as to the choice of a profession, was devotedly fond of his father. Though now more or less free to follow his own inclinations, he did not do so immediately, but went back to the drudgery he abhorred, solely, as it would seem, to show his respect for the dead. For two long years he endured it. His mother after a few months—the business complications tending the realiza- tion of the effects of her late husband having been settled, xii THE LIFE AND and being in consequence possessed of a sufficient income— improved the situation by retiring to Weimar, which was then at its zenith as the literary metropolis of Germany. She here became an associate of the circle which centred in Goethe, and began her career as a novelist. Differences between the mother and son became manifest in the course of correspondence, but did not prevent the former at length giving her consent to a final renunciation of the counting- house. At the beginning of 1807, therefore, Schopenhauer began to devote himself seriously to study. In June he settled at Gotha, and, although in his twentieth year, did not disdain to take his place in the gymnasium of that town with a view to acquiring a thorough classical train- ing. A lampoon on one of the masters compelled his retirement, however, and he went to join his mother at Weimar. In the latter place he pursued his classical studies, but became more than ever estranged from his mother. It soon became impossible for them to live in the same house. Arthur’s inadaptability to the somewhat ceremonious etiquette of the Weimar salon did not tend to improve matters. The petty spite which only too often displayed itself at a later stage in his gibings at the academical philosophers of his time, at this period found vent in jealousy of the literary renown of his parent. The disgust at the frivolity which was indicated, as it seemed to him, in his mother’s conduct, and more espe- cially at the ease with which he thought the memory of his father had been forgotten, no doubt contributed to this ; but we must in the main ascribe Schopenhauer’s conduct to his constitutional failmg. On attaiming his majority, and with it the small income of some thousand thalerg (£150), Schopenhauer determined to enter the University of Géttingen. He here enrolled himself as a student of medicine, not so much with a view to practising, as for the sake of having a faculty. He attended for over a year PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xiil most of the classes in physical science. It was not till some months later that his distinctive leaning towards philosophy showed itself, when he began to attend the lectures of Schulze, the author of “ Mnesidemus,” and a great man in his day. Schulze advised him to study Plato and Kant, advice which he religiously followed for some time, to the neglect of other thinkers. In the summer of 1811 Schopenhauer went to the newly-established University of Berlin ; here he attended Schleiérmacher’s lectures on the History of Philosophy, the following year he also heard Fichte. Already at this time his hatred and jealousy of Academic Philosophy and philosophers began to show itself. Fichte especially came in for his attacks, as may be seen from his student’s note-books of the lectures. These exhibit the silly petulance which too often disfigure his later work. In 1813 came the disastrous campaign of Napoleon in Russia, and the attempt of North Germany to shake off the power of the invader. After the battle of Lutzen , Schopenhauer left Berlin, reaching Rudolstadt, a small principality adjoining Weimar. Here he wrote his first dook, “The Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient “Reason.” Its appearance occasioned the joke on the part of his mother, that the title sounded as though it would only interest apothecaries, to which Arthur made the retort, that it would be read when all her romances were forgotten, It was a thin volume, and at the time created no notice. Shortly after the publication, Schopenhauer had the rash- ness to try the experiment once again of living with his mother at Weimar. This visit proved the occasion of a final rupture with Johanna Schopenhauer, whom he never saw again. At Weimar at this time, however, he entered upon a closer acquaintance or friendship with Goethe than he had done previously. The special occasion of it was his strongly expressed sympathy for Goethe in his squabble xiv THE LIFE AND with the Newtonians on the subject of the celebrated “theory of colours” (Farben lehre). Proceeding northward to Dresden, Schopenhauer de- veloped his optical theories as well as his general philosophy in the latter town during the ensuing months. It was here that his pessimism became accentuated and formulated. Schopenhauer claimed to be the first modern who had dealt philosophically with the sexual impulse, which was one of the turning points of his philosophy, the sexual act being the typical illustration of the affirmation of the Will-to-live. But of this more anon, when we come to speak of Schopen- hauer’s philosophy in general. The belief in the inherent possibility and the practical necessity of a philosophy had already begun to lead him to plan out a coherent system. It was of a different nature from the con- temporary academical systems of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, in that, while no less than theirs purporting to be a metaphysic, it was nevertheless not like theirs founded on a logical deduction, but claimed to have grown together piece by piece as the fruit of observation and reflection on the phenomena of nature and man. Schopenhauer, in other words, took his stand on a different side of the « critical” philosophy of Kant to that of his contemporaries of the chair. Kant’s division of the first part of the “Critique of Pure Reason” into “The Transcendental Aisthetic,” and ‘“‘The Transcendental Dialectic,” was the basis of a divergence of view in German philosophy, of which the antithesis between Schopenhauer and Hegel is the most salient expression. While the philosophers of the “ chair” took their stand on the Transcendental Analytic aud Transcendental Dialectic, Schopenhauer took his on the Transcendental Aisthetic. For the former, the formal activity of thought—the category or concept—was the ultimate principle and starting-point of philosophy. With PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. XV Schopenhauer, on the contrary, this was not ultimate, but derived from the, for him, deeper, non-logical principle of Will. Art thus, in a sense, stood nearer philosophy than science with Schopenhauer. “ Art,” he writes at this time, “is not, like science, merely concerned with the reasoning powers, but with the innermost nature of man, in which each must count merely for what he is in reality. Now this will be the case with my philosophy, for it is intended to be philosophy as art.” ... “The mere faculty of dis- covering the sequence of conceptions, the combining, in short, of antecedents and consequents, though it may make a great scholar and scientist, will never make a philosopher, just as little as it will make a poet, a painter, or a musician.” Schopenhauer was at this time largely occupied with a perusal of the works of the French materialist writers of the last century, especially of Helvétius. The Upanishads in a Latin version also absorbed a good deal of his time, and contributed much material towards his own philosophy. He speaks of it as the noblest reading in the world, and as his highest consolation. By 1818 the great philosophical work was already all but finished, and Schopenhauer wrote to the publisher Brockhaus, of Leipsic, offering it to him as the exposition of a new philosophical system. Terms were arranged, and an edition of eight hundred copies agreed upon. But Schopenhauer chafed at the delay of the printers, and this finally culminated in the writing of a discourteous and quasi-libellous letter to Brockhaus, demanding a portion of the honorarium, and calling upon him to name a date for the completion of the publication “ with all the sincerity of which he was capable.” Brockhaus declined to act otherwise than in accordance with the terms of the agree- ment. He also wrote further letters to Schopenhauer, abusing him in well-set terms for what he deemed his in- sulting conduct, which letters remained unanswered by Xvi THE LIFE AND the latter. The volume saw the light towards the close of 1818, being dated for the following year, and bearing the title, “The World as Will and Presentment,” in four books, with an appendix containing a criticism on the philosophy of Kant. The work proved a failure, as the “Fourfold Root” had done; and Schopenhauer some years afterwards, on demanding an account as to the sale of his book, received a reply that a great part of the edition had been disposed of as waste paper. Before the book had issued from the press Schopenhauer was in Italy, refreshing himself with the southern sun, after his four years’ labour on what he deemed his life- work. It was a time of all others when a re-awakened interest in archeological research generally, and especially in that of the classical lands, was making itself felt—the time of Niebuhr and of Von Humboldt, of Thorwaldsen and of Bunsen. But Schopenhauer sympathized with none of these. The researches into the origins of Christianity which occupied his college friend at Gdéttingen, Bunsen, had no attractions for him. Just as little did he care for the new conceptions of history which were dawning, and which found their first expression in Niebuhr’s demolli- tion and partial reconstruction of the earlier Roman history. To Schopenhauer, for whom the valley of the Ganges was the one and only original source of the religious instinct, Christianity was unspeakably abhorrent. Historical re- search was uninteresting to him for the simple reason that he admitted no philosophy of history, no law in history, not even a tendency, but the mere fortuitous play of indi- vidual desire and caprice, substantially the same at one time as at another, and differing only in the superficial forms of its manifestation. For classical literature and art, on the other hand, he had a keen enthusiasm, an enthu- siasm which had its obverse side in the systematic deprecia- tion of medieval art, especially Gothic architecture, Italy PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xvii was, just at this time, “ the fair land of exiles” from the con- ventionalities of society in the more northern countries of Europe. Byron, Shelley, Scott, and other lesser lights of English imaginative literature, were languishing, rhapso- dizing, or sight-seeing in Venice, Florence, Rome, and else- where. Goethe had only recently been there, and there were plenty of other Germans, intoxicated with the “ romantic” movement now springing into life, with whom Schopen- hauer had the opportunity of quarrelling. He kept a diary during all this time, in which were set down sundry reflections on life and things of the partly platitudinary and partly paradoxical nature, so characteristic of all the meditations of our Neo-Buddhist on things in general. At Naples he received a letter from his only sister, who was a few years his junior, containing a report of the . , publication of his book, and also the welcome information that Goethe, in spite of his general repulsion to purely speculative literature, had dipped into it, and discovered two passages to his liking, one in the fourth part, which contained Schopenhauer’s views on art, and the other a passage in which he proclaims self-realization as the end of life. While at Milan, on his return home, a less welcome letter from his sister reached him, containing the informa- tion that the Dantzic house, in which his mother and sister had invested their means, had failed. Schopenhauer, who was himself involved to the extent of 8,000 thalers in the affair, was at first sympathetic, and prepared to stand by his relatives. But on hearing that they had precipitately agreed to accept the first offer made, of a composition of thirty per cent., he became disgusted, and not even the satisfaction he might have derived from seeing therein a confirmation of his theories as to the business incapacity of women, sufficed to prevent an enduring rupture. He himself resolutely stuck to his guns, refusing anything less than seventy per cent. down in settlement of claims. This b XViil THE LIFE AND he communicated to the firm indicated, ina letter, in which he states it to be his duty to defend his patrimony, at the same time justifying his attitude on quasi-philosophical grounds. He did not oppose the action of the other creditors, and hence the agreement with them was signed in the summer of 1821. The following month he sent in the first of his acceptances, and in less than a year all his three bills were paid up with interest. The amount gained or saved by his dexterous manipulation was partially lost afterwards, however, through an unlucky investment in Mexican Bonds. Schopenhauer next went to Heidelberg, and from thence to Dresden to arrange his affairs, the hope inspiring him all the time of obtaining a university appointment. Just now the universities were regarded by the governments uf Germany, in the full flood of the reaction represented by the Holy Alliance, as hotbeds of sedition. This made little difference to Schopenhauer, whose want of appreciation of history was only equalled by his contempt for politics and all public movements. For him the individual was all in all. The political atmosphere therefore was no hindrance to his applying, as he hoped with success, for a post of the kind. He first turned his attention to Berlin, and in writing to one of the professors there on the subject, he declares that what interests him alone are the things which concern every man at all times and in all places, and that so long as he has the means and opportunity of study, and of elaborating his ideas and communicating them to the world, he is satisfied, no matter what the outward circum- stances of his age and country may be. To Berlin accord- ingly he went, and after the usual formalities—presentation of copies of his books, a lecture delivered before the Senate, followed by an oral examination—he was admitted to the post of privat-docent or extraordinary professor. Thus empowered, in the summer semester of 1820 he began a course of lectures on philosophy. This, like his books, PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xix proved a complete and utter failure ; his audience dwindled to nothing before the end of the term, and Schopenhauer never again tried his luck in this direction. He was perhaps partly himself to blame for the so completely disastrous collapse of his scheme, inasmuch as he had tried conclusions with the great philosophical giant who was then at the height of his renown. Schopenhauer was literally crushed beneath the weight of Hegel. The former had had the temerity to choose the lecture hour of his famous colleague for his own course. From this time forward dates the bitter and malignant attitude of Schopen- hauer towards the great master of speculative thought. The silly ebullitions of spite which recur again and again, in season and out of season, marring the pages of Scho- penhauer’s Essays, and more than one specimen of which will be found in the following pages, are so puerile as to excite nothing else than pity for the man of unquestion- able power who could descend to them. It is only fair to say that Schopenhauer, possessed as he was with a morbid mania of suspicion, probably really believed his failure to have been due to the machinations of his arch-enemy, as he considered the author of the‘ Phenomenologie.” Asa matter of fact it is extremely improbable that Hegel ever once gave so much as a passing thought to the obscure privat- docent and his course, so far as jealousy was concerned. A review of his book in the “ Litterateur-zeitung” of Jena next drew Schopenhauer into a furious squabble with the editor. In the course of the year 1821 he fell into a dispute subsequently ending in an unsuccessful litigation, this time not with any academical or literary opponent, but with a friend of his landlady. He complained to the latter on one occasion of having found three strange women con- versing immediately outside the two rooms he occupied, and received the assurance that such a thing should not occur again. A few days afterwards, on returning home xx THE LIFE AND from his walk, he found the three women again in the same position. He ordered them to retire, but one of them, a seamstress, who occupied a room at the top of the stairs, refused. Schopenhauer thereupon went back into his room, and after waiting a few minutes returned to the charge, and finding her still in the same position, he seized her by the waist and violently flung her out, at the same time using an expression more energetic than parliamentary, and followmg up her ejection by flinging after her the work she was engaged on, together with the implements of her calling. The case, which came into court, and was de- fended by Schopenhauer himself, was decided in his favour after the lapse of some months. The plaintiff how- ever appealed, and Schopenhauer, who wished to get away to Switzerland and Italy, did not stop for the hearing, and was condemned undefended to a moderate fine. After being absent in Italy during the whole winter, he returned northwards, making a lengthened stay at Gastein, and in August he was back at Dresden, remaining there some eighteen months, and occupying himself the while with sundry literary projects, including a translation of Hume’s philosophical works, albeit this never got beyond the preface. In the spring of 1825 he was recalled to Berlin to square accounts with the redoubtable spinster, who had recently set up a fresh claim against him, on the ground of permanent disablement from gaining her livelihood, having been a consequence of the assault committed three years previously. She now demanded a regular yearly allowance as indemnity. The case had gone against him, and the previous October he had been condemned in costs, and ordered to pay the woman fifteen thalers a quarter (about £9 a year) towards her maintenance. His im- mediate object in going to Berlin now was to get the verdict reversed. In this he was unsuccessful, and after some months of litigious vexation the decree was made PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. Xxi final in March of the following year. The woman herself, who was over fifty years of age at the time, might have furnished Schopenhauer with the theme for a dissertation on the toughness of constitution possessed by the sex, or as he might have put it, on the strength of the manifesta- tion of ‘The Will-to-live ” enshrined in the female body. Among other illnesses, she was prostrated by the cholera when it appeared in North Germany a few years later, and while strong men around her were succumbing in some cases to what were apparently much lighter attacks, she recovered, and survived for many a long year to enjoy the receipt of the pension allotted to her by the law. But last of all this woman died also, and on receiving official informa- tion of the fact, Schopenhauer inscribed on the notice-paper the significant and appropriate words, Obit anus abit onus. Schopenhauer continued, notwithstanding his defeat in the law-courts, to reside in Berlin for some years, leading a solitary life, a favourite dog (he was devotedly attached to animals) his only companion. He dined regularly at the table d’héte of the Hotel de Russie, music and the drama forming his chief relaxations during the time. Among various other literary projects, he entertained an idea of translating Kant’s “Critique of Pure Reason,” ‘“ Prole- gomena,” and “Critique of Judgment” into English, his knowledge of which language was perfect. This too, how- ever, after the passage of sundry letters between Berlin and London, fell to the ground. In the summer of 1831 the cholera appeared in Berlin, one of its victims being, as is well known, Schopenhauer’s great rival Hegel. Schopen- chauer, who had a constitutional horror and terror of in- fection, fled precipitately from the capital on the approach of the enemy, and sought refuge in Frankfort-on-the- Maine, which he never again quitted for any length of time so long as he lived. Our thinker, who had a distinctly superstitious vein in him, which, moreover, in no way con- xxii THE LIFE AND flicted with his philosophy, believed himself warned in & dream that he should die of cholera if he remained. On his arrival in Frankfort a feeling of isolation, and consequent melancholy, owing to the sudden change from familiar scenes, induced him to renew a correspondence with his sister. Both mother and daughter had now quitted Weimar, and Adele—such was the name of the gister—had taken, like her mother, to the production of light literature. But though a desultory correspondence was resumed, he none the less remained estranged as before from his two relatives as far as personal intercourse was concerned. The next year, 1832, Schopenhauer removed for a few months to Mannheim, which for some reason he thought he should prefer to Frankfort as a place of residence. The change, however, proved not to his liking, and he returned to Frankfort. Among his re- mains were found an accurately drawn up pro and contra account respecting the two places, in which Frankfort wins because of its greater life and facility of amusement, its able dentists and “less bad physicians,” and last, but not least, its ‘more Englishmen.” This, like many other of the memoranda and notes of Schopenhauer, is written in the English language. His life-work henceforward was amplifying, commentating on, and illustrating his philo- sophy as embodied in his “chief work,” as he is fond of terming it. In his philosophy, as he repeatedly says, he found occupation, instruction, and recreation—the fullness of life—in short, his happiness, in so far as such was possible to him. For years his daily round was a perfectly regular one. He rose at half-past seven, took his bath, at that time a rare luxury in Germany, dressed, prepared and drank hig coffee, gave instructions to his housekeeper not to inter- rupt him till noon, and settled down to three or four hours’ work, which he considered enough for continuous intellectual application, whether in reading or writing. PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xXxill At twelve o’clock he knocked off, took a turn at practising on his flute, and at one o’clock dined at his hotel, which was at first the “ Englischerhof,’ and in later years the hotel “Zum Schwanen.” He seldom talked during or after dinner, except when an especially cultivated or ap- preciative guest happened to be sitting beside him. After dinner he returned to his domicile, took his coffee, and slept for an hour. He then read belles lettres till four o’clock, being widely versed in English and French novelists. At four, or a little after, Schopenhauer started for his constitutional, accompanied by his dog. There had been a succession of these dogs, mostly poodles, since his student days. The poodle used to be called by the chil- dren of the neighbourhood young Schopenhauer. Occasion- ally, though rarely, an acquaintance took part in these strolls. The philosopher walked rapidly, so rapidly that few could keep up with him, for two hours on end. When alone, he often stopped suddenly for a moment, if an idea struck him, in order to note it down. On his return at six o’clock, or thereabouts, he visited the reading-room, where he regularly perused “ The Times.” At half-past eight he took his supper, which consisted of a cold collation and half a bottle of light wine. He then lit his long German pipe, and read for an hour. Directly after he went to bed, always believing in a long night’s rest. To the obvious taunt which might have been applied to him that he did not carry out his own ascetic ideal, he would have replied that this could with no more reason be required of the philosopher than of any other man. If the philosopher by his insight could intellectually grasp the ideal of life and set it down in theory, this did not imply any greater obli- gation to realize it in his own person than in the case of anyone else. He who drives fat oxen need not himself be fat. The sculptor who produces a beautiful form may himself be a Silenus. And conversely, we do not expect an Adonis, just because he is an Adonis, to be also a Phidias. xxiv THE LIFE AND Schopenhauer published in 1836 a small volume on “Will in Nature.” This was his first literary production of any consequence since the completion of “‘ The World as Will and Presentment ” in 1818. In it he collected various recently discovered facts of physical science that he thought corroborated the central positions of his philosophy, which he always contended could be arrived at by an inductive process. The new work, like its predecessors, failed to arrest, much less to secure, public attention. He was much disgusted at being known as the son of the novelist Johanna Schopenhauer, rather than as the author of the great philosophical system which should for ever solve the riddle of life. In 1838 a learned society at Drontheim, in Norway, offered a prize for the best essay on the question, “Whether the freedom of the Will could be proved on the testimony of consciousness?” Schopenhauer at once com- peted, and early in the following year he received intimation that his essay had won the prize. His delight at having, after so many failures, at last secured a measure of success, if not with the greater public, at least with a learned body like the Swedish Academy, knew no bounds. So elated was he, that he at once set about competing for another prize for an essay on ‘The Foundations of Morality,’ which had been offered the previous year by the Royal Danish Academy of Copenhagen. The essay having been duly finished and sent in, its author confidently awaited the news of a second success, and was intensely disgusted when he was apprized of the fact that his work had been rejected on the grounds that it contained no adequate dis- cussion of the relation of metaphysics to ethics; that the alleged proofs of sympathy being the Foundation of Morality were insufficient ; and lastly, which was worst of all, that eminent philosopers had been treated without due respect. Who these philosophers referred to were may be imagined. Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel became more PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. XXV than ever the incarnation, for him, of deceit, sophistry, and low conspiracy to ignore him. The existent professors of philosophy. who had mostly drunk at these fountain heads, were carrying on, he was sure, the work of the arch-villain Hegel. Both treatises were published in one volume in 1841, at Frankfort, with the title “The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics.” Three years after this the second edition of “The World as Will and Presentment” was issued from the press, without much change, except in the appendix on the Kantian philosophy, where his views on the relative merits of the first and second editions of the “ Critique ” were for the first time set forth. The important new feature was the addition of a commentary on the whole in the form of a second volume, which actually exceeded the first in bulk. The days of 1848 brought Schopenhauer’s anti-political and anti-social side into prominence. He was desperately frightened lest he should lose his means in a general overturn. His essentially individualist impulses, and his views as to the functions of the “superior person” in the economy of human life, naturally led him to hate the populace—the sovereign canaille, as he called it. He saw from his window the erection of barricades on the bridge over the Maine, and his room was on one occasion used by a party of Austrian troops as a citadel from which to open fire on the insurgents in the street below. The disturbance in the even tenor of his life, caused by the events of the revolution, naturally intensified Schopenhauer’s bitterness towards it; for an egoist he was and remained, from first to last. We are not surprised, therefore, that he left a large part of his fortune to the surviving relatives of those who fell on the reactionary side. The general break-up, however, of the previous conditions of German life, both material and intellectual, of which the revolution of 1848 was an indication, told in favour of Schopenhauer’s literary xxvi THE LIFE AND , claims. Disciples and admirers now began gradually to drop in. First of all came the old “councillor ” of Mag- deburg, Dorguth by name, who was the earliest to call public attention to Schopenhauer in an exaggerated esti- mate of his claims, embodied in a pamphlet, the first of a series in the same style which ran on up to Dorguth’s death in 1854, More important was the acquisition of the popular writer on philosophical subjects, Julius Frauen- stadt. The latter became the most useful and enthusiastic exponent of Schopenhauer’s views, as well as for many years his adviser in practical matters relating to publish- ing, &c. In newspaper and review Frauenstidt was un- tiring in asserting his master’s claims to recognition, and in expounding and defending his philosophical positions. His chief literary work in this connection was his “ Letters on Schopenhauer’s Philosophy.’ But Schopenhauer, now advancing to old age, was more than ever difficult to get on with ; and a rupture of three years in the personal rela- tions between master and disciple occurred, which was only terminated a few months before the death of the former. Adam von Doss, a Bavarian lawyer, also entered upon a vigorous correspondence with Schopenhauer. Lintner, the assistant editor of the “ Vossische Zeitung,” was converted by a perusal of the “ Parerga,’”’ and paid especial attention to the theory of music contained in Schopenhauer’s system. He also collaborated with Frauenstidt, after Schopenhauer’s death, in a work, the main object of which was to defend the personal character of the master against aspersions which had been thrown upon it. In 1853 the well-known article of John Oxenford, the English dramatic critic, entitled “Iconoclasm in German Philosophy,” was published in the Westminster Review,” and Schopen- hauer was for the first time introduced to the British public. Other friends there were whom Schopenhauer won, the most important being Dr. David Asher, who was PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xxvii attracted by the pessimist’s musical speculations while a teacher at Leipsic, and who subsequently became con- nected with the publishing firm of his name; and last, but not least, his biographer, Dr. Gwinner. It was the “ Parerga and Paralipomena,” which was pub- lished in 1851, that first gave Schopenhauer a reputation with the general public. This, his last important work, was the first to attain any immediate success. It was neverthe- less declined at the outset by three publishers in succession, and, as it was, his only payment for the copyright con- sisted in a dozen copies of the book. The strange conglo- meration of literary odds and ends on things in general “caught on” almost at once, and led to a republication of the essay on “ Willin Nature”’; to a third edition of “The World as Will and Presentment”; and shortly before his death, in 1860, to a re-issue of ‘The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics.” Schopenhauer’s chief pleasure in his old age now became reading favourable notices of his own works. His appetite for public applause was vora- cious. Admirers were frequently attracted to the new philosophy by special points. To some it was his musical theories ; to others, those on sexual love; to others, again, his views on mesmerism and hypnotism. But the incoming throng of adherents, admirers, and interested readers was almost entirely composed of the class known as ‘“ persons of general culture.” The Universities still remained closed to him, and few of those specially trained in them took any interest in the new pessimism or its exponent. One day he received a visit from an officer stationed at Magde- burg, who informed him of the existence of a society of admirers among the military of that city. The officer stated that he himself had read nothing else but Schopen- hauer for the past three years. In fact, in the last few years of his life, Schopenhauer had become a celebrity whom the curious passing through Frankfort desired to XXVili THE LIFE AND see. In 1855 he sat for his portrait to a French painter. The next year he was painted by a German artist, a native of Frankfort, while a little later his bust was modelled by a young lady artist of Berlin. Still the evidences he ob- tained of his renown did not keep pace with his vanity. He could never read enough about himself. He repeatedly laments that so much that had been written about him must be escaping his notice. The first indication of any academic interest in him was furnished by the University of Leipsic, which in 1857 offered a prize for the best critical essay on his system. About this time Schopen- hauer saw his friend Bunsen for the last time. The short visit the latter paid to Frankfort seems to have been the occasion of a pleasant revival for both parties of old student memories. The summer of 1860 showed consider- able evidences of the results of old age. Schopenhauer’s strong constitution no longer stood him in good stead. Palpitation of the heart forced him to modify his constitu- tionals. An attack of inflammation of the lungs, from which he but slowly recovered, left him for a long time prostrate. Recurrent seizures of faintness seemed to indi- cate something radically wrong with his heart. Finally, on the morning of the 21st of September, 1860, after having riseu and partaken of his breakfast as usual, he was found lying back dead on the sofa by his medical attendant, who had come to pay what for some time now had been his regular morning visit. Schopenhauer has attracted as much interest by his per- sonality as by his writings. As is sufficiently obvious, his was a character of peculiar inadaptability to circumstances. Few people could have got on with him, and, as a matter of fact, he scarcely had an intimate friend throughout his life. The least suggestion of derogation from the most extravagant of his personal claims sufficed, especially in his later years, to inspire him with the keenest resentment. PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xxix Schopenhauer was, in short, as perfect a type as we could well have of the completely self-centred egoist. Not that he lacked genuine zeal for truth, or devotion to philosophy. But these things were inseparable with him from zeal for the applause and recognition of his own work, and devotion to his own personality as such. That Schopenhauer was not destitute of a certain sense of humour his writings show. But certainly there was something lacking in his feeling for the ridiculous, or otherwise he could never have penned the comically arrogant passages concerning him- self which he has done. It is a susceptibility to the comic side of things which alone saves the man of greater ability than the average from the expression of exaggerated estimates of his own powers. An excessive personal sensi- bility, leading at times to moroseness, an irritability of temper which exaggerated trifles, and a personal vanity of huge proportions, must, in short, be admitted as funda- mental characteristics of the founder of the neo-pessimismn. These things were associated with a timidity, a scenting of danger from afar, which, though it may have been, as it is with many, purely constitutional in its origin, yet was in his case unquestionably fostered and nourished by the excessive habit of self-concentration above alluded to. Schopenhauer was in a constant state of alarm as to his personal safety. He fled from the very name of an infec- tious disease. He was so afraid of fire that he would only live on the ground floor of the house; and his fear of reverse of fortune was so great that he was in the habit of concealing important business papers and other valuable property, lest it should be stolen, under the harmless label of “ materia medica.” Still there can be no doubt whatever as to the sincerity of Schopenhauer’s belief in his own mission, as the exponent of a new philosophy, or rather as the expounder in the definite formule of Western thought of the old semi-poetical philosophy of the East. Xxx THE LIFE AND Tur PuitosopHy or SCHOPENHAUER. As he is never tired of insisting, Schopenhauer’s philo- sophy is based upon the criticism of Kant. As already hinted, there were two distinct possibilities of speculative development contained in the Kantian metaphysic. Kant had divided his system into Transcendental Aisthetic, Transcendental Analytic, and Transcendental Dialectic. The first contained an exposition of the conditions of pure sensibility. These were for Kant the subsuming of the blind sense impression, the resultant of the unknown thing- in-itself under the forms of space and time. But to the completed phenomenon of so-called common-sense reality —to the object known as such—another element was necessary, that, namely, of the pure activity of thought, working through certain categories tabulated by Kant, and deducible from the ultimate unity of the conscious- ness. The exposition of the pure thought-conditions—as opposed to those of pure sense—are set forth and discussed in the second part of the “ Critique,” which Kant terms “The Transcendental Analytic.” These two first parts of the great work, since they deal, not with the completed reality as we find it, but with the conditions which that reality presupposes—with the elements which go to the making of that reality rather than with the reality as a whole—these two first parts of the “ Critique” are called by Kant the “Theory of Elements” (“ elementarlehre”). The remainder of the book consists in the so-called “ Tran- scendental Dialectic.’’ This no longer deals with the elements which go to the making or determination of reality in con- sciousness, but with the ideas or assumptions which the mind is compelled to super-impose on these, and which hinge on the conceptions of the soul as a simple substance, on the world as infinite in time and space, and on God as PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. XXX1 the self-containing principle of all reality and all possibility of reality. The Sensibility, therefore, the faculty of receiving impressions from without; the Understanding, the faculty of working up these impressions into a coherent world of objects; and the Reason, the faculty of carrying on the process of thought-activity beyond the given world of phenomena created by the synthesis of sensibility and understanding, constitute for Kant the tripartite division of consciousness in general, or knowledge, in the widest sense of the word. Kant designated his system, therefore, as ‘Theory of Knowledge,” inasmuch as it was an investiga- tion into the conditions under which alone all knowledge is possible. Now while Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, especially the first and third, had taken their stand in the main upon the element of direct thought-activity deducible from the syn- thetic unity of the consciousness, and had thus postulated thought or intelligenceas the ultimate principle of all reality, Schopenhauer thought he was able' to deduce the active, formative principle of the world from something still deeper, from a principle which was itself alogical, non-conscious— albeit the source of consciousness—a principle he identified with the so-called thing-in-itself, and the sense-impression which, according to Kant, was its result. This principle he further identified with Will, understanding by Will all nisus, all impulse, of whatever character. The intelligence is, therefore, a secondary principle, entirely subordinate to the thing-in-itself, or Will, which manifests itself in all Nature, being substantially the same whether in gravitation orin humandesire. Willis for Schopenhauer the matter, the intelligence, the form of Reality, but the two elements are everywhere distinguishable in consciousness. In Schopen- hauer’s first work, “The Fourfold Root,” he had endea- voured to establish the proposition that all the Kantian categories are ultimately deducible from that of Cause, and XXxii THE LIFE AND that this is itself a mode of the Will. “Adequate Cause” is divided by Schopenhauer into a principle of being, doing, acting, and knowing (essendi, fiendi,agendi, and cognoscendt). The law of Adequate Cause expresses the ordered connection between all our presentments, as determinable @ priori, by virtue of which nothing can be self-existent and indepen- dent of other things, but in order to be an object for our consciousness it must stand in connection with the totality of phenomena. But the manner of this connection differs according to the nature of the object. Every presentment which can become object for us falls under one or other of four classes. The first class of possible objects of present- ment is that of the completed empirical perception. The primary form of this perception Schopenhauer makes, fol- lowing Kant, to consist in space and time, the forms respectively of the outer and of the inner sense. In this class of objects it appears as the law of causality in the narrower sense of the word. Schopenhauer calls it the law of the adequate cause of becoming (principium rationis sufficientis fiendi). A change in any object or objects pre- supposes another, upon which it has followed, with absolute necessity. Such a sequence is what we commonly call cause and effect. The forms of causality in this sense are mechanical cause, organic irritability, and psychical motive. The first form, in which action and reaction are equal to one another, governs the inorganic world with its mechani- cal processes, the second governs the organic world with its physiological processes, and the third governs the world of thought and conscious action. The second class of possible objects for a subject are constituted by concepts or abstract presentments. This is the class coucerned with the adequate cause of knowing (principium rationis sufficientis cognoscendi), which proclaims that if a judgment is to express an intelligent proposition it must have a sufficient reason, hence it is termed true, truth consisting either in the PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. Xxxili logical and formal correctness of judgments, or in their adequacy for expressing a sensuous perception, which, in so far as it is based on experience, constitutes empirical truth. The third class of objects for the presentative faculty is constituted by the formal element of the com- pleted presentments, namely, the a priori given intuitions of the forms of the external and the internal sense, space and time. As pure perceptions they are distinguishable from the completed objects of perception. They have the charac- teristic that all their parts stand in one relation to each other, in respect of which each of them is conditioned by the other. In space, this relation is called position; in time, sequence. From the latter number is directly de- ducible. The law according to which parts of time and space are determined is termed by Schopenhauer the law of the adequate cause of being (principium rationis sufficientis essend?). The fourth and last class of possible objects for the faculty of presentment has its basis in the immediate object of the internal sense, the subject which wills, but which is at the same time object for the faculty of presentment, though an object of a unique kind, being only given to the internal sense, and, therefore, manifesting itself, not in space, but in time alone. In respect of Willing, the law of cause pre- sents itself as the law of sufficient reason of action, or as the law of motivation (principium rationis sufficientis agendi). In so far as motive is the external condition of an action it belongs to causes of the same kind as those mechanical ones considered under the first class of objects of possible presentment. In this last class, therefore, the circle is complete, since in it the first class merely evinces itself as ultimately the same thing viewed from the extern al side only. For motives are known to us not only from without like other causes, but also from within, and in them, therefore, we have the key to the mystery of the innermost meaning of all other kinds of causation. Motivation is c XXXiv THE LIFE AND simply causation seen from within. Such is, in brief out- line, the subject-matter of Schopenhauer’s first philoso- phical work. Those desirous of further information re- specting it may consult the English translation, which forms one of the volumes in Bohn’s Philosophical Library. Schopenhauer’s “‘ chief work,” “ The World as Will and Presentment,” is divided into four sections, of which the first treats of The World as Presentment, in the sense of empirical reality, the object of science; the second, of The World as Will, that is, the will-to-live; the third, of The World as Presentment, so to say in its second intention, as Platonic Idea, the object of art; the fourth, lastly, of The Will in its second intention, as purified from the lust of life, and turned as it were against itself. The volume ends with an appendix on the Kantian philosophy. “The World is my Presentment.’ This proposition, with which the first book begins, applies, says Schopenhauer, to every living and knowing being, albeit in man alone does it appear in the form of a reflective or abstract thought. The sundering of consciousness into object and subject is the only form under which any presentment, be it percep- tive or conceptive, is possible or thinkable. The world means simply the totality of objects existing in and for a subject, of perceptions for a perceiver, in short, of presentments ; the whole world and all that can possibly belong to it is subject to this condition ; it is only there for a subject, it is only a determination of a subject. The essential and universal forms of the object belong, how- ever, to the subject, as Schopenhauer with Kant insists, and may, therefore, be distinguished a priori in conscious- ness. The principle of adequate cause, as expounded by Schopenhauer in the book above noticed, and at less length here, is the general expression which embraces al] forms of the object. Materialism errs, in that it ignores the fact in question. The only valid standpoint consists in the PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. XXXV recognition of the complete relativity involved in all pre- sentment and in all thought. From this complete rela- tivity, amounting with Schopenhauer to a dualism, Schopen- hauer infers the prixs, or root-principle, to be something other than intelligence or knowledge. The separation of subject and object, and the law of cause which it implies, involves us in an antinomy or contradiction. For although metaphysically the existence of the world is dependent on its being known by living beings, yet, physically, these latter are themselves just as dependent on a chain of phy- sical events, of causes and effects. into which they enter as amere link. This antinomy finds its solution in the as- sumption that the World as Presentment, that is, as sun- dered into subject and object and subordinated to the principle of cause, is only its external side, and that its innermost being, its kernel, its root, in short, the “ thing- in-itself”’ of Kant, is what we term, with reference to its most direct and immediate manifestation, Will. The second book treats of the objectivation of the Will. The body is presented in a double manner to the subject of knowledge, first as a mediate presentment, or object among other objects, and subordinated to the law of causa- tion, and secondly as that immediately known to each. The act of the will and the movement of my body are not two different conditions standing in the relation to each other of cause and effect, but they are simply the same thing viewed from a double side. The action of the body is simply the act of will objectified. The question as to whether the remaining phenomena of the world, as known from the external side only, are acts of will or not, is really identical with the question as to whether they are reality or illusion. To answer it in the negative amounts to a solipsism. This is indeed a sceptical sophism which cannot be refuted, but, on the other hand, it is a theory which no one holds outside a mad-house. Hence we are XXxvi THE LIFE AND perfectly justified in assuming that the phenomenon. mani- fested in the being or action of our own body is a key to that of all other phenomena in nature, although they are only given in presentment from the outer side. This means, that could we strip off their character of presentments in an intelligence, of objects for a consciousness, what remained over would be identical with that which in the case of our body we term Will. The Will considered as thing-in- itself is entirely distinct from the same Will as phe- nomenalized, objectivized, or presented in consciousness, and. is not subject to the conditions of the latter, which condi- tions merely touch its objectivity. The will considered as thing-in-itself is one and indivisible, though its objective manifestations in the phenomenal world are infinite. But these infinite manifestations, in so far as they are double- sided like our own organism, and therefore real, are of a mixed nature, and hence do not express the element of objectivity or outwardness in its purity. The latter is only to be found in the pure idea, which is at the root of every class of phenomena, that is, in the system of Ideal types, which constitute the successive stages in the objecti- vation of the Will, as more or less confusedly reproduced in the particular phenomena in which they express them- selves. The most general forces of matter, such as gravity, impenetrability, &c., represent the lowest phase of the objectivation of the Will. Physical, chemical, and organic forces supervene on these, and represent succes- sively higher stages in the objectivation. Each stage contests its place in space and time with the one below it, This applies not only to the more important stages, but also to the subordinate ones; for example, every higher form of life has to battle for its place in nature with those below it. As a consequence, it only expresses so much of the idea as it has the force left in it to do after this conflict has been decided in its favour. Time PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. XXxvii and space as the principia individiationis have no immediate influence on the ideas, which as pure objects stand over and above the particulars or individuals in time and space which more or less adequately, more or less inadequately, embody them. This doctrine is the basis of Schopenhauer’s “ theory of art,” and is set forth in the third book of “The World as Will and Presentment.” As we have seen, at one pole is the Will as pure Subject; at the other is the Present- ment as pure Object. Between these two positions—these two modes of the noumenon or thing-in-itself—lies the phenomenal world, with its participation in both, under the conditions of Time, Space, and Causation in its four forms. The idea (the Platonic Idea, as Schopenhauer sometimes calls it), notwithstanding that it is not subject to the conditions of time and space, and the categories of cause, is nevertheless a form of knowledge—indeed, the most universal form of knowledge—it is Presentment in general. We can only attain through individual things to a knowledge of the ideas they represent, in so far as a change takes place in us—i.e., in the percipient or subject of knowledge itself, by which the latter, in so far as it is absorbed in the apprehension of the idea, ceases, pro hac vice, to be individual, and becomes universal. This form of knowledge belongs exclusively to the objectivation of the will in its higher stages. In the first instance, the intellect, or faculty of knowledge, is entirely there in the service of the Will. But as the faculty of apprehending the idea it is emancipated from this service, the pleasure experienced in esthetic contemplation being, Schopenhauer contends, will-less in its origin and nature. The capacity for abstracting the intellect from the service of the Will is the exclusive appanage of Man. With the animals the intellect always remains the slave of the appetites—that is, under the complete sway of the Will-to-live. Hence they XXXVili THE LIFE AND are incapable of zsthetic contemplation. For the art-con~- sciousness demands that we should regard the Object pre- sented apart from its why, its wherefore, its how, and its when. In doing so, we approach the pure Platonic idea— the ideal type of the Object considered in itself. The Sub- ject for the nonce is emancipated from its ordinary desires and impulses, apprehensions and interests, and becomes, so to speak, raised to a higher potency of consciousness. It is conscious no longer of the individual thing, but of the eternal form. The different branches of the fine arts represent the different stages in the objectivation of the Will. The lowest stage is that of architecture, which embodies the idea of gravity, and the forces deducible from it—in short, it expresses the Platonic idea of what appears in the phe- nomenal world as mechanics. As we rise in the scale, the natural forces expressed become more complex, and the idea conveys with deeper meaning and greater precision the truth of human life. For example, painting, which deals directly with individuals or particulars, treats them only as the representatives of a class. They are for the artist not individuals, but types. The highest achieve- ments of painting are to be found in medieval catholic art, which portrays the figure of the saint in whom the Will- to-live has died, and who has therefore already attained to a foretaste of Nirvana. The same with poetry: the highest manifestation of the poetic art is in tragedy. Music stands on a different footing from the other arts, inasmuch as it does not represent any one stage of the Will’s manifestation like them, but is the direct embodi- ment of the Will’s objectivity in general. Hence the peculiar effect, unlike that of the other arts, which music produces on minds susceptible to it. In music we have the purest expression of the free play of emotion and impulse, undetermined to any specific subject-matter. Schopen- PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xXxxix hguer carries this idea out with much ingenuity as regards both harmony and melody, the different registers, cadences, rhythms, &c. Joy and sorrow, pure and simple, is, in short, the burden of music. There is no material, as in the other arts, which covers this central fact up, overloading it with detail which obscures the real issue, but all is here directly and obviously reducible to the blind impulse which Schopenhauer terms “The Will-to-live.” The fourth and last book of the “‘ World as Will and Presentment ” treats of the Will-to-live as turning against itself, as recognizing its own futility and denying itself. This can only be attained by means of the insight that all life issues in sorrow and pain; that the evil of the world outbalances the good, and does so not accidentally but necessarily. All Willing, Schopenhauer is fond of pointing out, implies want, and all want implies suffering. Hence so long as the Will is affirmed so long are evil and suffering affirmed. The root of all life being Willing, and all Willing implying the want of something which is not, as soon as one want is satisfied another arising by the very necessities of the case, it follows that the Will in us must be destroyed, annihilated, before the blessed state of the extinction of all Willing, and of the consciousness, which is in the service of the Will, can be attained. A partial and tem- porary satisfaction may be acquired by the transforma- tion of the Will into pure objectivity, as in the art-con- sciousness. But this is not enduring. We cannot continue in this state for long, we are continually forced back into that world in which the intellect, the intelligence, is in the service of the Will. Hence the final solution of the problem of life is to be found, not in esthetics, but in ethics; it is to be found, in short, in asceticism. The destruction of the individual life is one thing, that of the Will-to-live is an- other. In the first it is the phenomenon only which xl THE LIFE AND perishes, leaving the noumenon, the thing-in-itself, or Will, remaining intact, and continuing to realize itself immediately in another individual. For this reason suicide is no solution of the difficulty, for the Will is affirmed in the very act by which the life is destroyed. On the other hand, once the Will is finally negated, the continuance of the mere phenomenonal life for a time is quite a secondary matter. The consequence of this, namely, self-starvation, the absention, as in the case of the Hindoo yogis, from all action on one’s own behalf tending to preserve life as being the highest expression of an ascetic morality, is obvious, and Schopenhauer does not shrink from it. The great turning-point in the negation of the Will-to-live is the triumph over the sexual impulse, the impulse which directly leads to the affirmation of the Will in new indi- viduals. The final stage is the triumph over the Will-to- live as expressed in the instinct of self-preservation, that is, in the desire for the continuance of the immediate per- sonality concerned. The Hindoo ascetics above all, and after them the Trappists, are Schopenhauer’s ideal. The end of Schopenhauer’s philosophy is the complete extinction of Will, and, as a natural consequence, of life itself, in all human beings, which is, therefore, the ultimate goal of all existence. The Will perishes, and the root of conscious- ness being cut away, it withers and dies. The blessed state of consciousless, Will-less extinction, the great Nothing to which all Nature points, is then attained. Schopen- hauer speaks of “the dark impression of that Nothing, which looms as the final goal behind all virtue and holiness, which we fear like children the darkness.” ‘Instead of seeking to evade it,” he concludes, “as even the Indians do by myths and meaningless words, or the Nirvana of the Buddhists, we recognize the fact freely that what remains after the complete abolition of the Will is for all those who are immersed in the Will assuredly nothing. But PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xli conversely, for those in whom the Will has turned against and denied itself, this our so very real world, with all its suns and galaxies, is also—nothing.” The above is a brief, and therefore necessarily extremely condensed, exposition of the leading principles of Schopen- hauer’s philosophy. Its merits and its defects are not far to seek for the philosophical student. Many, and some- times deep, are the insights which we come across in all Schopenhauer’s writings. The ingenuity with which he fits his own acute observations on men and things, on Nature and art, into his system, is sometimes quite startling. This is especially noticeable in the third book of “The World as Willand Presentment,” which contains his theory of art. It is, in fact, on the artistic side that Schopen- hauer has most directly influenced the world. His power in determining the theories of Richard Wagner, and thus indirectly in revolutionizing modern dramatic music, are well known, although it is curious to note that Schopenhauer himself did not appreciate the earlier works of Wagner, which were the only ones with which he was acquainted. The ethical side of Schopenhauer’s system has mainly served as a quasi-philosophical stalking-horse for the somewhat nebulous fin de siécle pessimism which is the characteristic note of the modern ‘‘man of culture.” It has been expanded and developed by many a litteratewr- philosopher, its most systematic latter-day exponent being Eduard Von Hartmann. Schopenhauer’s purely literary merits as a writer of German are so great, that his books have penetrated into circles where no other philosophical literature obtains access. He has remained what he was when he first began to be read, the popularizer of philosophy for the general reading public. His theory is comparatively easy of apprehension by the man of average general educa- tion, who is not altogether destitute of speculative faculty xhi THE LIFE AND or cravings, but who does not want the trouble of thearduous and sustained labour necessary to the thinking out of the metaphysical problem in all its bearings, or to the adequate comprehension of a thinker like Hegel. Schopenhauer’s boasted clearness, on the other hand, is often the mere clearness of superficiality. As it has been justly observed, a mere specious illustration often serves the purpose of an argument. It is a similar superficiality, wearing the ap- pearance of depth and knowledge of life, and taking its cue from the plausible but limited generalizations respect- ing what is known as “human nature” derived from observations of motives of men in the present day, and during the short span of time we term history, which is responsible for the cynicism so fashionable nowadays with the man of the world. To the latter any other attitude than that of cynicism and disbelief in “ human nature” is evidence of mere infatuation, enthusiasm, or some other amiable weakness. Your man of the world is just as little able to entertain the suspicion that his cynicism is merely a passing mood, having its origin in himself, and in the particular phase of society which has given him birth, as the ancients were to conceive the possibility of the anti- podes. To such an attitude of mind the pessimism of Schopenhauer is satisfactory, as supplying it with a quasi- philosophical justification. The denial of all progress and of any coherent development in human affairs, the natural consequence of the postulation of the individual as his own final telos, and the assertion in the most accentuated form of the introspective ethics, which has throughout history been the idealogical accompaniment of individualism in material things, all this is eminently con- genial to the modern “cultured” man of the world. In metaphysics Schopenhauer represents an important, and, as far as it goes, a well-grounded protest against one tendency of the contemporary philosophy of his time, and PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xiii especially of Hegel—the tendency, namely, to hypostatize the mere thought-form or category. Kant, in his deduction of the conditions under which all knowledge is possible, had started from the primitive “unity of apperception,” as he termed it, as expressed in the self-conscious act, “I think.” This, which with Kant was merely one side of a somewhat loosely connected theory, became with Fichte and with Hegel the keystone of the whole. While with Kant it had remained formal, with his successors it had become material as well—the root-principle of the Concrete or Real. In the “I think,” stress was laid with them, as with Kant, on the “think.” This is most noticeable in Hegel, where the I” is a mere determination of the Con- cept, u.e., of thinking. Now Schopenhauer caught at this one-sidedness, as it appeared to him, of the academic phi- losophy, and stoutly affirmed the principle that thought, or the logical, the “intelligible” principle in the constitution of reality, presupposed and was dependent on an alogical principle, which was identical with the thing-in-itself of Kant, which Hegel had eliminated from his system; that this was further identical with the Subject or “1” from which concepts and the consciousness they bring with them proceed—with the “I” which “thinks ”—and that this “T” itself was merely another name for what under its most generalized aspect we term Will. The above is really the special significance of Schopen- hauer’s system from a purely metaphysical standpoint, His opposition to the principle with which Hegel started, combined with the general bent of his mind, induced Schopenhauer to reject the greatest of all results of the German classical philosophy—a result to be found in germ in Kant, which was carried a step further by Fichte, and was perfected by Hegel—namely, the dia- lectical method. He was deeply impressed with the ad- vantages of induction, which he believed could be applied xliv THE LIFE AND to philosophy. This he had taken on as a part of his re- action against German thought, and of his prepossession in favour of the English empirical school. For him, there- fore, the method which traces the unfolding of reality through contradiction and its resolution, was nothing but sophistry and a juggle of words, designed with the object of throwing dust in the eyes of the German learned public. Schopenhauer’s quasi-inductive method of supporting his main thesis gave him the opportunity of bidding for popular applause by that introduction of illustration and plausible analogy, which has already been alluded to. The severe logical analysis of the academic thinkers was alto- gether repugnant to Schopenhauer’s turn of mind. When he believed he had hit upon a deep metaphysical truth, he cast about him for facts in Nature which he might use in support of it. As a consequence, to the philosophical student trained on another method, the continued reitera- tion of the one fundamental proposition, all things are Will, in a form but little varied in itself, and merely rein- forced from various sides, is somewhat wearisome, and is sometimes suggestive of Thales and his well-worn dictum, ‘all things are water.” At the same time, one cannot deny to Schopenhauer a certain genuine impartiality in the pursuit of truth. This is proved by the fact that his independent thought some- times leads unconsciously to conclusions in flagrant opposi- tion to his own sentiments and antipathies. Take for in- stance his utterances respecting the existing social system to be found in odd corners of his essays, or his arguments against ‘“ prescription” in vol. i., page 380, of “The World as Will and Presentment,” and remember the bitterly re- actionary sentiments of Schopenhauer in social and political matters generally. Mood is also a powerful factor in in- fluencing Schopenhauer’s utterances on various subjects of practical interest. He can sometimes work himself up PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xlv into a state of vehement indignation, as when referring to English pietism and American negro slavery. Notwithstanding the metaphysical truth enshrined in Schopenhauer’s rehabilitation of the alogical element in knowledge—experience, or reality—as against the panlogism of Hegel and the academical school, and notwithstanding the wonderful suggestiveness of many portions of his work, especially his theory of art, it will be soon apparent to the attentive student that the coherence of the system, as a system, is very superficial. There is a good deal of unexplained residuum in it. Schopenhauer never seems quite clear as to the distinction between abstract and con- crete, between element and whole or thing. For this reason, notwithstanding his protestations of Monism, his system really seems like a Dualism. According to his statement, the Will as thing-in-itself would seem to be not merely a basal element, but itself a concrete, a thing in the literal sense of the word. On the other hand, Presentment as Presentment seems to have likewise an independent existence. Thus, in the Platonic idea, the object of art, it exists apart art from the Will, inasmuch as the element of of Willing, as su such, disappears, which would seem to contradict the assumption that the essence of the thing- in-itself is Will. Then, again, Schopenhauer never really gets over the difficulty involved in his ethical doctrine, ac- cording to which the Will-to-live can turn against and negate itself. This implies, look at it as we may, on Schopenhauer’s principles, the destruction of a substance, The objection Schopenhauer himself was not unaware of, and in dealing with it he practically admits willing to be the mere attribute of a substratum in itself unknowable. Yet, again, the individualism of Schopenhauer’s ethics in- volves some further difficulties. The one Will which is the soul of all things is in itself indivisible; it is merely as object or phenomenon, as realizing itself in the conscious indi- xlvi THE LIFE AND vidual, under the forms of space, time, and causation, that the element of number enters into it. If this be true it cuts away the root of Schopenhauer’s introspective-indi- vidualist ethics. For it is either wholly present in each individual or not. In either case the negation of the Will- to-live within him, as conscious and deliberate act on the part of any one individual as individual, cannot possibly affect the noumenon or thing-in-itself, which is identical in all individuals. To admit that it could do so would be to admit that very solipsism, that denial of reality as ex- pressed in Willing to external things, against which Schopenhauer protests when discussing his theory of know- ledge. No act of the phenomenal, conscious individual, on the principles of Schopenhauer’s metaphysics, can in the least affect the root-principle of the Will which ez hypothesi manifests itself equally in all individuals. So long as one is left who dies unconverted, that is, without having of definite purpose renounced the Will-to-live, all things remain as they were before, since there can in this sense be no question of degree as to the affirmation or denial of the Will. Either it is all there, or it is completely and absolutely abolished. Whether it survives and is affirmed in the consciousness of one individual or of a thousand trillions of individuals, cannot make the slightest difference in the case of that for which plurality in the last resort has no meaning. The only way out of this difficulty for Schopenhauer, and that a not very successful one it must be admitted, would have been to have postulated the act of renunciation as performed once for all by the delibe- rate and unanimous consent of all conscious beings, and to have held this out as the goal of history. But to have done so would have been to surrender the individualism which covers Schopenhauer’s whole ethical theory, and to have got again into line, albeit in an opposite direction, with the notion of human evolution and historical pro- PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. xlvil gress, and for this the individualism of Schopenhauer’s temperament was too strong. As regards the whole question of Pessimism versus Optimism, it is extremely difficult for the man of to-day to realize that the problem involves an antinomy, and is therefore unanswerable, simply because it is wrongly stated. The problem is stated in terms of individual feeling as measured by quantity, while its subject-matter really transcends individual feeling, and is incommen- surable. It is asked, Does the amount of pleasure expe- rienced by the organic individual—an average individual being assumed—exceed, on the whole, the sum of pain experienced by the same individual or not? It is further asked with reference to the said individual, Does this in the natural course of things tend to become greater or less? The question then arises as to quality, ex- pressed in the well-known conundrum whether the pig happy would be preferable to Socrates miserable. In all these ways of putting the problem, it is the organic indi- vidual, the present conscious unit, (and his immediate pleasures or pains,) which is alone taken into consideration. Looked at in this way the question is answered by different persons differently, according to character, circumstance, mood, &c., and each, whichever side he takes up, can find support in plausible illustrations. An array of facts can be adduced in favour of the one side or of the other. In all this, however, the real gist of the question is more often than not missed. All the time, moreover, the assumption is made that the organic individual is the self-sufficient and final arbiter in the matter. Viewed from this point of view it cannot be denied that pessimists have the best of it as a general rule, but their assumption, like that of the consistent sceptic as to the reality of the external world— that solipsist who so often reappears in the history of phi- losophy—is given the lie to by the facts of existence, not- xviii THE LIFE AND withstanding plausible, and from one point of view unan- swerable, theoretical arguments. The average conscious being does prefer existence to non-existence. This is a fact which remains to be explained. The philosophical pessi- mist, like Schopenhauer, explains it on the theory of illusion. The illusion has first to be pierced and seen through by the intellectual insight before emancipation from the illu- sion is possible. The answer to Schopenhauer as regards such an explanation might be, that when it is seen through intellectually the illusion is clung to notwithstanding. Schopenhauer himself is a case in point, for judged of from his purely individualistic point of view it is no mere argu- mentum ad hominem to taunt him with his own character and life as a disproof of his theory. It would surely not be unfair to assume that the man who, on his own showing, had more than any other man in Western Europe, by dint of intellectual insight, seen through the delusion as to the worth of life, and recognized self-destruction through ascetic privation as its highest end, ought to have prac- tically realized his doctrine in his own person. That precisely he of all men had perhaps more than usual regard for the preservation of his own life under conditions of the greatest material comfort he could obtain, while those who have followed out the ascetic ideal to its practical conse- quences have been in many cases, perhaps in most cases, ignorant persons, actuated avowedly only by superstitious motives, certainly does not lend any colour or support to the theory on which Schopenhauer insists, to wit, that in- tellectual conviction of their futility tends to lead men to the renunciation of the pleasures of life, and ultimately life itself. May not the strength of the practical conviction that life is worth living, in defiance of all theoretical proofs that it is not, afford evidence of the inaccuracy of Schopenhauer’s assumption that pain is positive and pleasure negative, and PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER, xlix also some confirmation of the fact that the significance of the individual is not exhausted within the limits of his own personality? This latter point is brought out more particularly by a consideration of the question of quality in pleasure or happiness. From the standpoint of pure Hedonism, that is, of a theory which merely balances plea- sures and pains quantitatively, there can be no doubt whatever the choice must be in favour of being a contented swine rather than a discontented genius. Similarly a fortiori it must be quite plain that the greatest sum of animal enjoyment conceivable for the healthy man may possibly, nay, will probably, be greater in amount for the individual who experiences it than the highest amount of pleasure to be derived by the man of correspondingly vigorous intellectual powers and refined tastes from in- tellectual things. But yet we have an unshakable con- viction, the reverse of which is, in fact, taken seriously, unthinkable, that there is something preferable in the one to the other ; that the difference of quality upsets all cal- culations based on mere quantity—in other words, that the question of mere pleasure and pain, taken in the abstract and referred to the individual also regarded abstractly, simply involves us in a circle from which there is no escape, but which does not get us any further forward in the solu- tion of the problem of human life taken in the conezete. Mere pleasure or happiness, considered abstractly, may for practical purposes be regarded asa proximate end, and, in a similar way, the individual considered in himself, and apart from the social life and progress into which he enters, may also for practical purposes be regarded as a proximate end to himself. But we must never forget that so long as we regard things in this way we are dealing with abstractions which appear very differently when viewed from the standpoint of the meaning of the world and human nature considered as a real synthesis. In proportion as d 1 THE LIFE AND this proximate aim assumes the form for us of a supreme end, we are living on a lower plane, since we are un- mindful of the point of view from which the individual personality becomes a mere component or element of a larger whole. This position is most fully seen in the per- sonality which we describe as criminal, or immoral in the true sense of the word, that is, anti-social. But it is also characteristic in a lesser degree of the commonplace man of the world. The aim of the introspective morality, the morality, that is, whose sign-manual throughout history is the ideal of personal holiness, as attained through the mere negation of the individual, his impulses and desires, has been to change this per saltum by means of asceticism. But in asceticism the egoistic point of view is not really abandoned, but is merely inverted. Self-denial for self- denial’s sake belongs intrinsically just as much to the egoistic attitude as the mere self-indulgence of the liber- tine. In both cases the individual is viewed as end, that is, he is considered abstractly. The really higher point of view which transcends both these attitudes alike, is that which recognizes the personality and its immediate plea- sure and pain as indeed constituting a proximate or immediate end, that is, a necessary stage, which, though not ultimate, is none the less an essential element in any higher end to which we may aspire; and which further recognizes that the only lasting and effective manner in which what we may term the abstract egoistic instincts can be abolished is in the identification by the sheer neces- sity of circumstances of individual pleasure and pain—in short, individual interest, in the narrower sense, with the interest of the whole of human society. The lower or anti-social impulses, then, so to speak, abolish themselves. To borrow Schopenhauer’s phraseology, the affirmation of the Will-to-live in the individual becomes absorbed in, and identical with, the affirmation of the Will-to-live of PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. li humanity asa whole. The strain of antagonism between the two, which from the lower standpoint seemed absolute, disappears. This is a stage, however, at which the ethical and economical problems intersect. I merely refer to it here as indicating the fallacy of estimating pleasure and pain, happiness and unhappiness, in terms of quantity merely, and with exclusive reference to the individual. Whether the abolition by the transformation of social con- ditions of the antagonism at present existing between indi- vidual and social interest is the prelude to a cycle of evo- lution, the end of which will be the transference of the characteristics of personality from the organic individual to the social individual (as we may term it), understanding by this a given society in its collective capacity, is a ques- tion which, extravagant and even incomprehensible though it may seem to many, nevertheless forces itself irresistibly upon one in reflecting on the problem as to the meaning of human life as we know it, and which opens up a vista of unknown possibilities, before which arguments drawn from our own limited data shrink into nothing. On the question as to the tendency of progress towards an increase of happiness or the reverse, many reflections may be and have been made. The observation of the limited period passed through between the younger world and to-day, seems to indicate rather a change in the distri- bution of the relative happiness and misery of the world than any increase or diminution of either. The case seems to be expressed by such a fact as this, for example: the hardships of the medieval serf, the acute and devastating epidemics of the Middle Ages, the ever-present possibilities of fire and sword, the torture-chambers of the feudal castle and of the inquisition, the recurrent famines continually im- minent in one locality or another—all these things have been mitigated, and some have passed away altogether. But they have been replaced by the ever-present mass of li THE LIFE AND misery of the present day, as represented by the proletariat of our large towns, and by all that our modern polariza- tion of the extremes of wealth and poverty implies. Similarly, the naive exuberance of animal spirits and un- restrained enjoyment of the Middle Ages, work-days and holidays alike, has vanished, and its place has been taken by the subdued bourgeois equanimity of the suburban villa, or the vapid inanities of the London season and its drawing-rooms. Still, all this affords us no valid grounds for the induction as regards future change, the conditions of which must necessarily be entirely different. The fact is, the antithesis between what in its most com- prehensive aspect we designate by the words good and evil must continue in some form or shape, since they are elements mutually implicated in every Real. As to the in- crease or decrease of the one relatively to the other, we can only judge indirectly ; the state of the case being, that all specific, that is, realized evil, necessarily passes away—that what is permanent is merely, so to say, the abstract cate- gory, evil-in-general undetermined to any specific content. But although at first sight the same is true of the opposite, namely, of the good, yet the case is not precisely identical, for while the preponderance of the specific or concrete evil to be eliminated appears at the beginning of a cycle of progress, or of a specific dialectical movement of evolution, the pre- ponderance of “the good ” attained through its elimination, as expressed in the reality of the cycle in question, invariably appears as the endandcompletion of that cycle. Thisimplies, as will be readily seen, a “point” in the evolutionary process, as always given in favour of the “good.” It implies, that is, that the trend of progress is towards the “good,” though the approximation may be entirely of an asymptotic character. A reflection of this kind may indeed destroy extravagant optimism, and cause the youthful enthusiasm of those who are satisfied with nothing less than a perfection, which, PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOPENHAUER. hin when closely viewed, is simply meaningless, because ab- stract, and hence in its nature unrealizable, to be “ sicklied o’er with the pale cast of thought.” Yet for the more sober- minded enthusiast it is none the less a consolation the more valuable as resting on a philosophical truth which cannot be taken away from him, to feel that the end of every evolutionary cycle implies an increase of happiness as against its beginning. This good, or happiness, it is true— this victory of Ormuzd over Arhiman—is not enduring, in- asmuch as its very conditions contain the nidus of a further and distinct evil of its own, unknown before, and which sooner or later makes its presence evident. But, neverthe- less, in spite of this, the fact remains that in the moment of realization there is a positive and real increment of good or of happiness over the opposing principle. The old “evil” is destroyed, the new is as yet unrealized. To this process of the continual absorption of specific evil or misery in infinitely changing shape, by good or happiness, also in infinitely changing shape and on a progressively higher level, we can assign no end. The foregoing are considerations which Schopenhauer might have seen but did not, and which, if he had seen, would certainly have modified his philosophico-ethical conclusions. SKETCH OF A HISTORY OF THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. ESCARTES is rightly deemed the father of modern philosophy, and this in a special, as well as a general sense, inasmuch as he placed the reason on its own feet by teaching men to use their own brains, in the place of which the Bible had previously served on the one hand, and Aristotle on the other. But in a more special and a nar- rower sense he was this also; since he was the first to bring the problem upon which philosophy has mainly turned to consciousness—the problem of the Ideal and Real—i.e., the question as to what in our knowledge is objective, and what is subjective; in other words, what might be ascribed by us to other things, and what we must ascribe to ourselves. Images do not arise in our brain as it were arbitrarily from within, nor do they pro- ceed from the connection of our own thoughts—hence they must spring from an external cause. But these images are immediately known to us—they are given. Now what relation do they have to things existing completely sepa- rate from, and independent of us, and which are in some way the cause of these images? Have we any certainty at all that such things exist? or even if this be so, that the images afford us any clue to their nature? This is the problem, and in consequence the main endeavour of philosophers has been for the two past hundred years to separate by a correctly-drawn line of cleavage—the Ideal, B 2 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. i.e., that which belongs solely to our knowledge as such, from the Real, ¢.e., that which exists independently of it, and thus to determine the relation of each to the other. Certainly neither the philosophers of antiquity, nor yet the schoolmen seem to have arrived at a clear conscious- ness of this fundamental problem of philosophy, although we find a trace of it, as Idealism, and even as the doctrine of the Ideality of time, in Plotinus, in Enneas IIL, Lib. VIL., cx., where he teaches that the soul has made the world by its transition from eternity into time. He there says, for instance, ov ydp reg abrov rovTouv Tov mavTos rémoc, i) Wwyh. (Neque datur alius hujus universi locus, quam anima) also dei dé oby EhwSey ric Wuyfic AapBavery Tov xpdvoy Howep ovde TOY aidva exeEt z£w Tov ovroc. (Oportet autem nequaquam extra animam tempus accipere, quem- admodum neque aeternitatem ibi extra id, quod ens appel- latur.) Here it will be seen we have a distinct statement even of Kant’s ideality of time. And in the following chapter otroc 6 Biog Tov ypdvov yevva’ C6 Kai elonrar Gua TOdE TH TavTe yeyovévat, Ore Wuxi abroy pera TOBE TOU TaYTOC tyévynoev. (Haec vita nostra tempus gignit: quamobrem dictum est, tempus simul cum hoc universo factum esse : quia anima tempus una cum hoc universo progenuit.) Never- theless, this problem clearly recognized, became the specially characteristic subject of modern philosophy after the neces- sary reflection had been awakened in Descartes, who was impressed with the truth that we are immediately limited to our own consciousness, and that the world is given us merely as presentment (Vorstellung). With his well-known dubito, cogito, ergo sum, he sought to accentuate the sole certainty of the subjective consciousness in contradistinc- tion to the problematical nature of everything else, and to declare the great truth that the only real, and uncondi- tionally given, is self-consciousness. Strictly considered, his celebrated proposition is the equivalent of that from THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. 3 which I started, “The world is my presentment.’ The only difference is, that his proposition accentuates the im- mediateness of the subject; mine, the mediateness of the object. Both propositions express the same thing from two sides. They are the “reverses” of each other, stand- ing in much the same relation as the law of inertia and that of causality, as expounded by me in the preface to my “Ethics.” (‘The two ground-problems of ‘ Ethics,’ treated in two academical prize essays by Dr. Arthur Schopenhauer.” Frankfurt-am-Main, 1841, p. xxiv; 2nd edition, Liepzig, 1860, p. xxiv.) Certainly, since his time, Descartes’ proposition has been often enough repeated, owing to the mere feeling of its importance, and without a clear understanding of its special sense and purport. (See Descartes’ ‘“‘Meditationes,” Med. ii. p. 14.) He it was, then, who discovered the chasm which lies between the Subjec- tive or Ideal, and the Objective or Real. This insight he clothed in the form of a doubt as to the existence of the outer world ; but by his inadequate solution of this doubt —to wit, that the good God would not deceive us—he showed how deep and difficult to solve the problem was. Meantime, this scruple had been introduced into philo- sophy by him, and could not fail to continue to work dis- turbingly till its final settlement. The consciousness that without thorough knowledge and understanding of the distinction which had been discovered, no certain and sufii- cient system would be possible, has been from that time ever present, and the question could no longer be shirked. In order to solve it, Malebranche invented his system of occasional causes. He grasped the problem in its whole range more clearly, seriously, and deeply than Descartes (“Recherche de la Vérité,” Livre ITI., seconde partie). The latter had accepted the reality of the outer world on the credit of God; and it was curious enough that while the other theistic philosophers sought to demonstrate the 4 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. existence of God from the existence of the world, Descartes, on the contrary, determines the existence of the world from the existence and trustworthiness of God—it is the cosmological demonstration turned round. Even here, going a step farther, Malebranche teaches that we see all things immediately in God. This is certainly to ex- plain an unknown by a still more unknown. Moreover, according to him, we not only see all things in God, but God is the sole activity therein, so that physical causes are only apparently such—they are mere “ causes occasionnelles,” (Rech. d. 1. Vér.,” Liv. VI., seconde partie, ch. ii.) We have here, therefore, in all essentials, the Pantheism of Spinoza, who seems to have learnt more from Malebranche than he did from Descartes. Altogether, one might wonder that Pantheism did not gain a complete victory over Theism even in the seven- teenth century, seeing that the most original, the most beautiful, and the most thorough-going European presenta- tions of it (for assuredly none of them will bear com- parison with the Upanishads of the Vedas) all saw the light in that age, to wit, Bruno, Malebranche, Spinoza, and. Scotus Erigena, the last of whom, after he had remained for many centuries lost and forgotten, was recovered at Oxford, and in 1681, four years, that is, after Spinoza’s death, for the first time saw the light in print. This seems to prove that the insight of individuals cannot pro- duce its effect, so long as the spirit of the time is unripe for its acceptance, for in our days, Pantheism, although only presented in the eclectic and confused rechauffé of Schelling, has become the dominant mode of thought with scholars, and even with persons of ordinary culture. This is because Kant had preceded, and with his overthrow of theistic dogmatism, had prepared the ground, in conse- quence of which the spirit of the time was ready for it, as a ploughed field is ready for the seed. In the seventeenth THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. 5 century, on the other hand, philosophy forsook this path, and arrived accordingly on the one side, at Locke, for whom Bacon and Hobbes had prepared the way, and on the other at Christian Wolff, through Leibnitz. These two were dominant therefore in the eighteenth century, espe- cially in Germany, although latterly only in so far as they had been absorbed by syncretistic eclecticism. The profound conception of Malebranche gave the im- mediate occasion to Leibnitz’s system of harmonia praesta- bilita, the widely extended fame and high consideration of which in his time, affords a confirmation of the fact that it is the absurd which makes the easiest success in the world. Although I cannot pretend to have a clear notion of the monads of Leibnitz, which are at once mathe- matical points, corporate atoms, and souls, yet it seems to me unquestionable that such an assumption once decided upon might serve to spare us all further hypothesis for the explanation of the connection between Ideal and Real, and to settle the question in the sense that both are already fully identified in the monads (for which reason, in our days, Schelling, as originator of the system of identity, has displayed a particular relish for it). Never- theless, it did not please the eminent philosophizing mathematician, polyhistor, and politician to use it for the purpose; but he saw fit to specially formulate a pre-esta- blished harmony to this end. The latter furnishes us with two totally distinct worlds, each incapable of acting in any way on the other (“ Principia Philos,” § 84, and “ Examen du Sentiment du P. Malebranche,” p. 500, sq. of the “(Euvres de Leibnitz,” published P. Kaspe), each the en- tirely superfluous duplicate of the other, but both of which, once for all there, run exactly parallel, and keep time with each other to a hair; the originator of both having from the first established the exactest harmony between them, so that they proceed thenceforward.in the 6 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. most beautiful manner. We may observe, by the way, that the harmonia praestabilita may perhaps be best made comprehensible by a comparison with the stage, where very often the “ influcus physicus”’ is only apparently pre- sent, since cause and effect are connected simply by means of a pre-established harmony of the stage-manager ; as, for instance, when the one shoots and the other falls a tempo. Leibnitz has presented the matter in its mon- strous absurdity in the crassest manner, and in brief, §§ 62, 63 of his “ Theodicy.” And yet with the whole dogma he does not even have the merit of originality, since Spinoza had already clearly enough presented the harmonia praestabilita in the second part of his “ Ethics,” i.e.,in the 6th and /’th propositions, together with their corollaries, and again in P. V., prop. 1, after he had in the 5th proposition of P. IL, stated in his own manner the so very cognate doctrine of Malebranche, that we see all in God.* Malebranche is, therefore, alone the originator of this whole line of thought which Spinoza as well as Leibnitz, each in his own way, has utilized and modified. Leibnitz, indeed, might very well have dispensed with it alto- gether, since he has already forsaken the simple fact which constitutes the problem, 7.e., that the world is given us immediately as our presentment, in order to substitute for it the dogma of a corporeal world and a spiritual world, between which no bridge is possible; at the same time interweaving the question of the relation of our pre- sentment to the things in themselves with that of the possibility of the motion of the body by the will, and then 1 «Eth.,” P. II., prop. 7: Ordo et connexio idearum idem est, ac ordo et connexio rerum. P. V., prop. 1: Prout cogitationes rerumque ideae concatenantur in Mente, ita corporis affectiones, seu rerum imagines ad amussim ordinantur et concatenantur in Corpore. Also P. II., prop. 5. THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. 7 solving both together by means of his harmonia praesta- bilita, (“Systéme nouveau de la Nature,” in Leibnitz ; “Opp. ed. Edmann,” p. 123; Brucker, ‘‘ Hist. Ph.,” tom. iv., p. 1. 425.) The monstrous absurdity of his assumption was placed in the clearest light even by his own contem- poraries, particularly by Bayle, who showed the conse- quences which flowed from it (see also in Leibnitz’s smaller writings, translated by Huth, anno 1740, the observation on page 79, where even Leibnitz himself is obliged to expose the preposterous consequences of his own doctrine). Nevertheless, the very absurdity of the assumption to which a thinking head was driven by the problem in hand, proves the magnitude, the difficulty, the perplexity of it, and how little it can be got rid of, and the knot be cut, by its mere repudiation, such as has been ventured upon in our days. Spinoza again starts immediately from Descartes, hence, at first in his character of Cartesian he even retains the dualism of his teacher and assumes accordingly a substantia cogitans and a substantia extensa, the one as sub- ject the other as object of knowledge. But later, when he stood on his own feet, he found that both were one and the same substance viewed from different sides; on the one side conceived as a substantia extensa on the other as a substantia cogitans. This is as much as to say that the distinction of the thinking and extended, or soul and body, is an unfounded one and therefore inadmissible ; so that nothing more ought to be said about it. He nevertheless retains it, since he is untiring in repeating that both are one. To this he adds, as it were by a mere sic etiam that Modus extensionis et idea illius modi una eademque est res (‘ Eth.” P.IL., prop. 7, schol.) ; by which he means that our presentment of bodies and these bodies themselves are one and the same. The sic etiam, however, is an insufficient transition to this, since it does not by any means follow 8 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. from the fact that the distinction between mind and body or between the presenting and the presented is unfounded, that the distinction between our presentment and an objective and real, existing outside the same—the main problem, that is, that was started by Descartes—is also unfounded. The presenting and the presented may be perfectly well homogeneous, and yet still the question re- mains how I am with certainty to infer from presentments in my head as to the existence of beings in themselves that are independent of theformer. The difficulty is not that on which Leibnitz (e.g., ‘‘ Theodic,” Part I. § 59) would make it mainly turn, to wit, that between the assumed souls and the corporeal world as between two wholly heterogeneous kinds of substances no sort of reciprocal action could take place —for which reason he denied physical influence ; for this difficulty is merely a consequence of rational psychology and only requires to be discarded as a fiction, as is done by Spinoza; and besides this, there is the argumentum ad hominem against the maintainers of this doctrine, that their own dogma that God, who is a spirit, has created and continuously governs the corporeal world implies that spirit can act immediately on bodies. The abiding diffi- culty is rather the Cartesian, that the world, which is only given us immediately, is simply an ideal world, a world, that is, consisting of presentments in our brain ; while we, over and above this, undertake to judge of a real world existing independently of our presentment. Spinoza then, in so far as he abolishes the distinction between sub- stantia cogitans and substantia eatensa has not solved the problem but, at most, rendered physical influence again admissible. But this is insufficient to solve the difficulty for the law of causality is demonstratively of subjective origin. But even if it sprang from external experience it would still merely appertain to the ideally given world that is in question. Hence, in no case can it furnish a bridge be- THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. 9 tween the absolutely objective and the subjective, but it is rather, merely the band which connects phenomena with one another. (See “ Welt als Wille und Vorstellung,” vol. ii. p. 12.) And nevertheless, in order more nearly to explain the above adduced identity of extension and pre- sentment, Spinoza postulates something which is contained alike in the view of Malebranche and Leibnitz. In accor- dance with Malebranche, namely, we see all things in God: rerum singularium ideae non ipsa ideata, sive res perceptas, pro causa agnoscunt, sed ipsum Deum, quatenus est res cogitans, (‘‘ Eth.” P.II., pr. 5); and this God is also at the same time the real and active principle therein, even with Malebranche. The mere fact, however, of Spinoza affixing to the world the name Deus explains nothing, in the last resort. But at the same time there is with him, as with Leibnitz, an exact parallelism between the extended and the presented world: ordo et connexio idearum idem est ac ordo et connexio rerum (P. II. pr. 7), and other similar passages. This is the harmonia praestabilita of Leibnitz; only that here the objectively existing world and the presented world are not entirely separated as with the last mentioned, merely corresponding to one another by virtue of a harmonia regulated in advance and from outside, but they are really one and the same. We have here, therefore, in the first place, a thorough-going Realism in so far as the existence of the things exactly corresponds to their presentment in us, both being one; we cognize accordingly the things in themselves—they are in themselves extensa as they appear as cogitata ; in other words, in our presentment of them, they appear as eatensa (here, too, it may be remarked, by the ‘way, is the origin of Schelling’s identity of the Real and Ideal). All this is, properly speaking, based on mere assertion. The exposition is already rendered unclear by the ambiguity of the word Deus which is used in a wholly improper sense; hence, it loses itself in obscurity and 10 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. comes in the end to nec impraesentiarum haec clarius posswm explicare. But the want of clearness in the exposition arises always from a want of clearness in the understanding and thinking out of the philosopher. Vauvenargues said very truly, la clarté est la bonne fot des philosophes (see “ Révue des deux Mondes,” 1853, 15 Aout, p. 685). What in music is the “ pure section” is in philosophy complete clearness, which is the conditio sine qua non without the fulfilling of which everything loses its value, and we are compelled to say quodcumque ostendis mihi sic incredulus odt. Tf, in the ordinary affairs of practical life one has to carefully avoid misunderstanding by clearness, how much the less ought one to express oneself incomprehensibly in the very abstruse, difficult, and wellnigh ‘impenetrable subjects of thought, which constitute the problems of philosophy ? The obscurity complained of in the doctrine of Spinoza, is owing to his not proceeding in a straight- forward manner from the nature of things as he finds them; but from Cartesianism, and accordingly from all sorts of traditional conceptions, such as Deus, substantia, perfectio, etc., which he was concerned to bring in a round- about way into harmony with truth. He often expresses the best ideas only indirectly, continually speaking per ambages and almost allegorically, as in the 2nd part of the “ Ethics.” On the other hand, Spinoza expresses an unmistakable transcendental idealism amounting to, at least, a general recognition of the truth clearly expounded by Locke and still more by Kant, as to the real distinction between the phenomenon and the thing itself, and the recognition that only the first is knowable by us. As instances of this may be consulted, “ Eth.,” P. II. prop. 16, with the 2nd corollary ; prop. 17, schol.; prop. 18, schol.; prop. 19; prop. 23, where it is extended to self-knowledge; prop. 25, which expresses it clearly, and finally as résumé, the corollary to prop. 29, which distinctly says that we can neither know THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. It ourselves nor the things, as they are in themselves, but only as they appear. The demonstration of prop. 27, P. IIL, ex- presses the matter the clearest, at least in the beginning. Respecting the relation of the doctrines of Spinoza to those of Descartes I may recall here what I have said on the sub- ject in the World as Will and Presentment: vol. ii., p. 639 (8rd ed. p. 739). The fact of his starting from the con- ceptions of the Cartesian philosophy, has not only been the occasion of much obscurity and misunderstanding in the exposition of Spinoza, but he has thereby been led into many flagrant paradoxes, obvious fallacies, and indeed absurdities and contradictions. In this way his doctrine which contains so much that is true and excellent has acquired a highly undesirable addition of simply indigest- able matter, so that the reader is divided within himself between admiration and vexation. But, in the aspect con- sidered here, the chief fault of Spinoza is that he has drawn his line of cleavage between the Ideal and Real, or the Sub- jective and Objective world, from a false standpoint. Ez- tension, namely, is in no wise the opposite of presentment, but lies wholly within the latter. We perceive things as extended, and, in so far as they are extended, they are our presentment. But whether, inde- pendently of our presentment, anything is extended, or indeed whether anything exists at all is the question and the original problem. This was solved later by Kant, and in so far, with indisputable accuracy, in the sense that ex- tension or space lies entirely in the presentment; in other words, that it depends on the latter, inasmuch as the whole of space is its mere form; and therefore, independently of our presentment, no extended can exist, and most certainly does not exist. Spinoza’s line of cleavage is accordingly drawn wholly on the ideal side; he has taken his stand on the presented world, regarding the latter, indicated by its form of exten- 12 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. sion, as the Real, and therefore as existing independently of its possibility of presentment, i.e., in itself. He is on this ground, therefore, quite right in saying, that that which is extended and that which is presented—z.e., our presentment of bodies and these bodies themselves —are one and the same (P. IL. prop. 7, schol.). For assuredly the things are presented as extended and are only as extended, presentable—the world as presentment and the world in space is wna eademque res ; this we can fully admit. But were the extension, quality of the things-in-themselves, our perception would then be a knowledge of things-in- themselves, which is what he assumes, and in which con- sists his Realism. Since, however, he does not ground or prove this, to wit, that our perception of a spacial world involves a spacial world independent of this perception, the fundamental problem remains unsolved. This arises, how- ever, from the fact, that the line of cleavage between the Real and Ideal, the Objective and the Subjective, the Thing-in- itself and the Phenomenon, is not correctly drawn. On the contrary, as has been said, the cleavage, being in the middle of the Ideal, Subjective, Phenomenal side of the world—that is, drawn through the world as presentment— splits the latter into the extended or spacial and our pre- sentment of the same, whereupon much trouble is taken to show that both are only one, as indeed they are. Just because Spinoza holds entirely by the Ideal side of the world, inasmuch as he thought to find the Real in the extended belonging thereto, and as, in consequence, the perceivable is the only Real without us, and the knowing (cogitans) is the only Real within us, so he, from another side, casts the only true Real, the Will, into the Ideal, which he makes a mere modus cogitandi, even identifying it with the judgment. As to this consult “ Eth.” P. IL, the proofs of the props. 48 et 49, where we read: Per volun- tatem intelligo affirmandi et negandi facultatem ; and again: THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. 13 Concipiamus singularem aliquam volitionem, nempe modum cogitandi, quo mens affirmat, tres angulos trianguli equales esse duobus rectis, whereupon the corollary follows: Voluntas et intellectus unum et idem sunt. Spinoza has, generally, the great fault of purposely mis- using words for the designation of conceptions which throughout all the world bear other names, and of taking from these the meaning which they everywhere have. Thus he calls “God” what is everywhere termed “ World;” “Justice” what is everywhere termed ‘“ Power,” and “Will” what is everywhere termed “Judgment.” We are fully justified as regards this, in recalling the Hetman of the Cossacks in Kotzebue’s ‘‘ Benjowskij.” Berkeley, although certainly later, and with the know- ledge of Locke, went logically farther in this problem than the Cartesians, and was thereby the originator of the proper and true Idealism, that is, of the knowledge, that that in space which is extended and which fills it, in short, the perceivable world generally, can only have an existence as such, in our presentment ; and that it is absurd, and even contradictory, to attribute to it a further existence outside of all presentment, and independently of the knowing sub- ject, and thereby to assume a matter existing in itself.* 1 With laymen in philosophy, to whom many doctors of the same belong, one ought never to use the word “ Idealism,” because they do not know what it means, and carry on with it all sorts of nonsense. They understand by “Idealism” at times “ Spiritualism,” and at times something or other which is opposed to Philistinism, and are confirmed and strengthened in this view by ordinary men of letters. The words ‘‘Idealism” and “‘ Realism” are not anything and everything, but have their fixed philoso- phical meaning. Those who mean something else should employ another word. The opposition of ‘‘Idealism” and ‘Realism ” concerns the Known, the Object, while that between Spiritualism and Mate- rialism, concerns the Knowing, the Subject. (Modern ignorant muddlers confound Idealism and Spiritualism. ) 14 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. This is, indeed, a true and deep insight, but his whole philosophy consists in nothing else. He hit upon the Ideal and separated it completely; but he did not know where to find the Real, about which he troubled himself but little, expressing himself respecting it only occasionally, piecemeal, and inadequately. God’s Will and Omnipotence is with him the immediate cause of the phenomena of the perceivable world, i.e., of all our present- ments. Real existence only accrues to knowing and willing beings, such as we ourselves are; hence these constitute, together with God, the Real. They are spirits, that is, knowing and willing beings, for willing and knowing he regarded as inseparable. He has this also in common with his predecessors, that he regards God as better known than the present world, and deems a reduction to him an explanation. His clerical, and, indeed, episcopal position laid altogether too heavy chains on him, and limited him to a narrow circle of thought with which he could never come into conflict. Hence he could go no farther, but true and false had to learn to mutually accommodate them- selves in his head as well as they could. This remark, indeed, may be extended to the works of all these philoso- phers, with the exception of Spinoza. The Jewish Theism, undmenable to any test, dead to all research, and hence ‘appearing really as a fixed idea, planting itself in the way of truth at every step, vitiates them all; so that the evil which it produces here in the theoretical sphere, may be taken as a pendant to that which it has produced through- out a thousand years in the practical—I mean in the shape of religious wars, inquisitions, and conversions of nations by the sword. The closest affinity between Malebranche, Spinoza, and Berkeley is unmistakable. We see them all proceeding from Descartes, in so far as they retain and seek to solve the fundamental problem presented by him in the form of a doubt as to the existence of the outer THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. 15 world; concerned as they are to investigate the separation and connection of the world which is Ideal, subjective or given solely in our presentment, and the Real or objective, which is independent of it, and, therefore, existing in itself. As we have said, therefore, this problem is the axis on which the whole of modern philosophy turns. Locke dis- tinguishes himself from these philosophers in that, probably because be stands under the influence of Hobbes and Bacon, he attaches himself as closely as possible to ex- perience and the common understanding, avoiding as far as may be hyperphysical hypotheses. The Real is for him Matter, and without turning his attention to the Leibnitzean scruple as to the impossibility of a causal connection between the immaterial, thinking, and the material, ex- tended substance, he at once assumes physical influence between matter and the knowing subject. In this he pro- ceeds with rare deliberation and honesty so far as to confess that possibly knowing and thinking substance itself might also be matter (“On the Human Understanding,” L. IV., ¢. 8, § 6). This it was, which procured for him later the repeated praise of the great Voltaire, and in his own time, on the other hand, the malicious attacks of a cunning Anglican priest, the Bishop of Worcester." With him the 1 There is no church which dreads the light more than the English, because no other has such great pecuniary interests at stake, its incomes representing £5,000,000 sterling, which is more by £40,000 than those of the whole of the remaining Christian elergy in both hemispheres taken together. On the other hand, there is no nation which it is so painful to see thus methodistically stupefied by this most degrading superstition than the English, who outstrip all the rest in intelligence. The root of the evil is that in England there is no ministry of public instruction, for which reason the latter has remained hitherto in the hands of parsondom, which has taken care that two-thirds of the nation shall not be able to read and write ; and which even from time to time ventures with the most ludicrous impudence to yelp at natural science. It is, therefore, a human duty to infuse into 16 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. Real, i.e, Matter, generates in the knowing subject by “Impulse,” that is, contact, presentments, or the Ideal (Ibid. L. IL, ¢ 8, § 11). -We have here, therefore, a thoroughly massive Realism, calling forth contradiction by its very exorbitance, and giving occasion to the Berkeleyan Idealism, whose special origination is, perhaps, to be found when Locke at the end of § 2 of the 31st chapter of the 2nd book with such a surprising absence of reflection, says, among other things: Solidity, Eatension, Figure, Motion and Rest, would be really in the world, as they are, whether there were any sensible being to perceive them or not. For as soon as one considers the matter one must recognize the above as false, in which case the Berkeleyan Idealism stands there and is undeniable. In the meantime Locke does not overlook the chasm between the presentments in us and the things existing inde- pendently of us,in short, the distinction of Ideal and Real ; in the end, however, he disposes of it by arguments of sound but rough common sense, and by appealing to the sufficiency of our knowledge of things for practical purposes (Ibid., L. IV., ¢. 4 et 9), which obviously has nothing to do with the question, and only shows how very inadequate to the problem Empiricism remains. But even his Realism England light, rationalism, and science, through all conceivable channels, in order that these best fed of all priests may have their handiwork put an end to. When Englishmen of culture, on the continent, display their Jewish Sabbatarian superstition and other stupid bigotry, we ought to meet it with unconcealed mockery— until they be shamed into common sense. For it is a scandal for Europe, and should be tolerated no longer. Hence one ought never, even in ordinary life, to make the least concession to the English ecclesiastical superstition ; but, wherever it puts in an appearance, to meet it immediately with a most energetic protest. For the effrontery of the Anglican priests and their votaries is even, at the present day, quite incredible, and must be banished to its own island, that it may thus be compelled to play the réle of the ‘owl by day whenever it ventures to let itself be seen on the continent. THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. 17 leads him to limit that in our knowledge which involves the Real, to the qualities inhering in the things as they are in themselves, and to distinguish these from our mere knowledge of them or from that which merely pertains to the Ideal—terming the latter accordingly secondary, but the former primary qualities. This is the origin of the distinction between thing-in-itself and phenomenon, which becomes so important later on in the Kantian philosophy. In Locke, then, we have the true genetic point of connection between the Kantian doctrines and the earlier philosophy. The former were stimulated and more immediately occa- sioned by Hume’s sceptical criticisms of Locke’s doctrines ; while, on the other hand, they have only a polemical relation to the Leibnitz-Wolffian philosophy. The above primary qualities, which are exclusively the determinations of the things-in-themselves, and which hence appertain to these outside and independently of our presentment, resolve themselves entirely into such as cannot be thought away, namely, extension, impenetra- bility, figure, motion or rest, and number. All the re- mainder are recognized as secondary, that is, as creations of the action of those primary qualities on our organs of sense, and consequently as mere feelings in these; such are colour, tone, taste, smell, hardness, softness, smooth- ness, roughness, etc. These, therefore, have no similarity whatever with the quality in the thing-in-itself which excites them, but are reducible to the primary qualities as their causes, such alone being purely objective and really part of the existing things (Ibid., L. L, ¢. 8, § 7, seqq.). Our conceptions of these latter are therefore really true copies, which accurately reproduce the qualities that are present in the things-in-themselves (lc. § 15). I wish the reader joy who really feels here the reductio ad absur- dum of Realism. We see then that Locke deduces from the nature of the things-in-themselves, whose present- c 18 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. ments we receive from without, that which accrucs to the action of the nerves of the sense-organs, an easy, compre- hensible, and indisputable consideration. ut Kant later on made the immeasurably greater step of also deducing what belongs to the action of our brain (that incomparably greater nervous mass); whereby all the above pretended primary qualities sink into secondary ones, and the as. sumed things themselves into mere phenomena, but the real thing-in-itself, now stripped of these qualities, re- mains over as an entirely unknown quantity, a mere x, This assuredly requires a difficult and deep analysis, and one which has long to be defended against the attacks alike of misunderstanding and lack of understanding. Locke does not deduce his primary qualities of things, and does not give any further ground why only these and no others are purely objective, except that they are in- destructible. Now if we investigate for ourselves why he declares some qualities of things which work immediately on the sensibility, and consequently come directly from without, not to be present objectively, while he concedes objectivity to those which, as has since heen recognized, pro- cecd, from the special functions of our intellect, we find the reason to be that the objectively-perceiving consciousness (the consciousness of other things) necessarily requires a complex apparatus, as the function of which it appears, and consequently that its most essential ground-determi- nations are fixed from within. In this way the universal form or mode of perception from which alone the o prigri knowable can proceed, presents itself ax the warp of the perceived world, and accordingly appears ax that which is absolutely necessary, unexceptional, and in no way to be got rid of; sothat it stands as the condition of « verything else in its manifold variety. This is admitted to be, im- mediately, time and space, and that which follows from them, and is only possible through them. In theme) ves THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDBAL AND REAL. 19 time and space are empty. If anything is to come within them, it must appear as matter, that is, as an activity: in other words, as causality, for matter is through and through simply causality: its being consists in its action, and vice versa it is but the objectively-conceived form of the understanding for causality itself. ¢* On the Fourtold Root of the Principle of Cause,” 2nd ed. p. 77: Srd ed. p. 82: as also * World as Will and Presentment.” 2nd ed., vel. i, p. Mand vol. in, pp. 48. 49; Srd ed. vel. i. p. 10, and vol. i, p. 62.) Honce it comes that Locke's primary qualities are merely such as cannot be thought away—a fact which itself clearly enough indicates their subjective origin, as proceeding immediately from the construction of the perceiving apparatus—and he therefore holds for absolutely objective precisely that which, as function of the brain, is much more subjective than the sense-feel- ing, which is oceasioned, or at least more directly deter- mined, from without. In the meantime it is interesting to see how through all these various conceptions and explanations, the problem started by Descartes respecting the relation between the Ideal aud the Real becomes ever more developed and clarified, and the truth thus promoted. It is true this was favoured by the circumstances of the time, or, more correctly, of nature, which, in the short space of two cen- turies, gave birth to and ripened half-a-dozen thinking heads in Europe. By the gift of fortune, in addition, they were enabled, in the midst of a grevelling world struggling after advantage and pleasure, te fellow their noble calling undisturbed by the velping of priests, or the foolish talk and ecaballing of the contemporary professors of philo- sophy, Now Locke, in accordance with his strict empiricism, had deduced the knowledge of the causal relation trom experience, while Hume did net dispute, as he ought to 20 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. have done, this false assumption, but immediately over- shot the mark by the observation, correct in itself, that experience can never give us anything more than a mere sequence of things wpon one another, sensibly and imme- diately, and never a proper consequence and action—t.e., a necessary interconnection. It is well known how the sceptical objection of Hume was the occasion of Kant’s incomparably deeper investigations into the subject, which led him to the result that space and time, no less than causality, are known by us a priori, that is, lie in us before all experience, and hence belong to the subjective side of knowledge. From this it follows farther, that all those primary, that is, absolute qualities of things, which Locke had assigned to them, since they are all composed of pure determinations of time, of space, and of causality, cannot belong to the things-in-themselves, but to our mode of knowledge of the same, and consequently are to be counted to the Ideal and not to the Real. The final consequence of this is that we know the things in no respect as they are in themselves, but solely in their pheno- mena. The Real, the thing-in-itself, therefore remains something wholly unknown, a mere x, and the whole perceivable world accrues to the Ideal as a mere present- ment, a phenomenon, which nevertheless, even as such, in some way involves the Real, as thing-in-itself. From this standpoint I, finally, have made a step, and believe that it will be the last; because I have solved the problem upon which, since Descartes, all philosophizing turns, in that I reduce all being and knowledge to the two elements of our self-consciousness, in other words, to some- thing beyond which there can be no further principle of explanation, since it is the most immediate and therefore ultimate. I have called to mind, what indeed results from the researches of all my predecessors, which I have here noticed, to wit, that the absolute Real or the thing-in-itself THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. 21 can never be given us directly from without, in the way of mere presentment, since it is inevitably in the nature of the latter only to furnish the Ideal; while, on the contrary, since we ourselves are indisputably Real, the knowledge of the Real must in some way or other be derivable from within our own nature. And in fact it here appears, in an immediate manner in consciousness, as will, The line of cleavage between the Real and the Ideal falls therefore, with me, in such wise that the whole perceivable and objectively-presented world, including every man’s body, together with time, space, and causality, in other words, together with the extended of Spinoza, and the matter of Locke, belongs as presentment to the Ideal. But in this case the Will aloneremains as the Real,and this the whole of my predecessors, thoughtlessly and without reflection, had thrown into the Ideal as a mere result of presentment and of thought, Descartes and Spinoza having even identified it with the judgment.’ Ethics is therefore with me directly and incomparably more closely knit to metaphysics than in any other system, and thus the moral significance of the world and of existence is more firmly fixed than ever. But Will and Presentment are fundamentally distinct, inasmuch as they constitute the ultimate and basal opposi- tion in all things in the world and leave nothing remain- ing over. The presented thing and the presentment of it are the same, but only the presented thing, and not the thing in itself. The latter is always Will, it matters not in what form it may appear in presentment. 1 Spinoza, I.c. ; Descartes, ‘‘In meditationibus de prima philo- sophia,” Medit. 4, p. 28. 22 SCHOPENILAVER’S ESSAYS. APPENDIX. EADERS who are familiar with what has passed for philosophy in Germany, in the course of the present century, may perhaps be surprised not to find mentioned in the period between Kant and myself, either the Fichtean Idealism or the system of the Absolute Identity of the Real and Ideal, since they seem specially to belong to our subject. But I have not been able to include them, simply because, in my opinion, Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel are no philosophers, inasmuch as they fail in the first requirement of the philosopher, earnestness and honesty of research. They are mere sophists; they wanted to seem and not to be, and have sought, not the truth, but their own interest and advancement in the world. Places from governments, honoraria from students and booksellers, and as means to this end as much sensation and effect as possible from their sham philosophy—such were the guiding stars and in- spiring genii of these disciples of wisdom. Hence they have not passed the entrance-examination, and so cannot be admitted into the honorable company of the thinkers of the human race. Meanwhile, they have excelled in one thing, and that is, in the art of turning the head of the public and of making themselves pass for what they were not, which requires talent, indeed, but not philosophical talent. That they were incapable of effecting anything solid in philosophy was owing, in the last resort, to the fact that their intellect was not free, but remained in the service of the Will; and in this case, though the intellect can indeed achieve much for this or that purpose, it can do nothing for philosophy any more than for art. For these lay down as their first THE DOCTRINE OF THE. IDEAL AND REAL. 23 condition, that the intellect should act on its own account, and during the time of this activity should cease to be in the service of the will, that is, to have the objects of one’s own personality in view; but when it is itself active, simply of its own motion, it, in accordance with its nature, knows no other purpose than the truth. Hence it does not suttice, in order to be a philosopher, which means lover of wisdom (this being nothing else than truth), to love the truth in so far as it harmonizes with one’s own interest, or with the will of superiors, or the dogmas of the church, or the preju- dices or tastes of contemporaries; as long as one remains in this position, one is only a géAavrog and no gidocopoc. For this title of honour is well and wisely conceived, in that it imphes that one should love the truth earnestly and with one’s whole heart, and therefore unconditionally, without reserve before everything, and in case of necessity even to the defiance of everything. The reason is to be found in the fact above indicated that the intellect has become /ree, in which case it does not even know or understand any other interest than that of truth; the consequence being, that one then acquires an irreconcilable hatred against all lying and deception, no matter what garb they may wear. In this way we are not very likely to get on well in the world, but all the more in philosophy. On the other hand, it isa bad auspice for the latter, if proceeding avowedly from the investigation of truth, we begin, thereupon, to say farewell to all uprightness, honesty, and thoroughness, and are only concerned to make ourselves appear what we are not. In this case one assumes, like the above three sophists, now a false pathos, now an artificially high earnestness, now a mien of infinite superiority, in order to dazzle where one despairs of being able to convince; one writes without con- sideration, because, only thinking of writing, one saves one’s thought up for the purpose of writing; one seeks now to inculcate palpable sophisms as demonstrations, now to 24 SCHOPENHAUER’S ESSAYS. propound hollow and senseless logomachy for deep thoughts; one invokes intellectual intuition or the abso- lute thought and self-movement of conceptions; one challenges expressly the standpoint of “reflection,” that is, of rational thought, straightforward consideration, and honest presentation, in other words, the proper and normal use of the reason generally; one expresses a boundless contempt for the “philosophy of reflection,” by which name is designated every connected course of thought which deduces consequences from principles, such as has constituted every earlier philosophy; and accordingly, if one is only provided with sufficient audacity, and en- couraged by the pitiable spirit of the age, one expresses oneself in some such manner as follows: “It is not difficult to see that the mode of stating a proposition, adducing reasons for it and refuting its opposite in the same way, by reason, is not the form which truth can assume. Truth is the movement of itself within itself,” etc. (Hegel, preface to the “ Phenomenology of the Mind,” p. lvii., in the complete edition, p. 36.) I think it is not difficult to see that whoever puts forward anything like this, is a shameless charlatan, who is anxious to befool simpletons, and who observes that he has found his people in the Germans of the nineteenth century. If accordingly, under pretence of hurrying to the temple of truth, one hands over the bridle to the interests of one’s own person, which looks sideways towards altogether diffe- rent guiding stars, such for instance as the tastes and foibles of contemporaries, the religion of the land, but especially toward the purposes and hints of the governing powers—Oh, how then can one expect to reach the high, abrupt, bald rock on which stands the temple of truth? One may easily attach to oneself, by the sure bond of interest, a crowd of genuinely hopeful disciples, hopeful, that is, for protection and places, who may apparently THE DOCTRINE OF THE IDEAL AND REAL. 25 form a sect, but really a faction, and by whose united stentorian voices one may be proclaimed to all the four winds as a sage without parallel—the interest of the person is satisfied, that of truth betrayed. All this explains the painful feeling which seizes one, when, after the study of real thinkers, such as have been above described, one turns to the writings of Fichte and Schelling, or indeed to the audaciously daubed nonsense of Hegel, produced as it is with a boundless, though justi- fied, confidence in German folly." With the former one had always found an honest investigation of truth, and as honest an endeavour to communicate their thoughts to others. Hence he who reads Locke, Kant, Hume, Male- branche, Spinoza, Descartes, feels himself elevated and pleasurably impressed. This is effected by contact with a noble mind, which has thoughts and awakens thoughts. The reverse of this takes place in reading the above-men- tioned three German sophists.