h b nq .~Di THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE AND POLITICAL ECONOMY Especially for Use in Colleges, Schools, Clubs, Guilds Printed and Bound in Ireland M. H. GILL & SON, Ltd., Dublin and Waterford The Elements of Social Science and * Political Economy ESPECIALLY FOR USE IN COLLEGES, SCHOOLS, CLUBS, GUILDS, &c. BY THE VEN. ARCHPRIEST LORENZO DARDANO OF THE COLLEGIATE CHURCH, BRONI, NORTHERN ITALY TRANSLATED FROM THE ITALIAN BY THE REV. WILLIAM McLOUGHLIN MOUNT MELLERAY ABBEY, NEAR CAPPOQUIN,' CO. WATERFORD {Cum Permissu Aucioris et Superiontm) New York, Cincinnati, Chicago BENZIGER BROTHERS PRINTERS TO THE PUBLISHERS OF HOLY APOSTOLIC SEE BENZIGER’S MAGAZINE J 9°9 in Ireland TO LEO XIII. WHO RESCUES THE DESOLATE AND WANDER¬ ING CROWDS, RECALLING THEM TO THE ENJOYMENT OF THAT LIGHT WHICH THE GENIUS OF THE WISE, UNITED WITH THE LABOUR OF THE HUMBLE, BRINGS TO MEN— TO LEO XIII. THE UNWEARIED SCOURGER OF EVERY INJUSTICE, INITIATING, BY THE AID OF HIS SONS, “ AN EQUAL ORDER OF THINGS,”—THIS LITTLE BOOK, WRITTEN CHIEFLY FOR YOUNG LEVITES, THAT THEY MAY BECOME FIT IN¬ STRUMENTS IN THE WORK OF REDEMPTION, IS, IN THE 25TH YEAR OF HIS PAPAL REIGN, DEDICATED, WITH ALL DEVOTED¬ NESS, BY THE AUTHOR < '/"T y LETTER FROM CARDINAL RAMPOLLA The Archpriest and Theologian Lorenzo Dardano having, by His Eminence Cardinal Rampolla, presented to His Holiness Pope Leo XIII. a copy of his book on the Elements of Social Science, &c., he received in reply the following much esteemed letter:— Very Reverend Sir, I have placed in the hands of the Holy Father one of the copies that you sent me of your lately published book, The Elements of Social Science and Political Economy. The title alone sufficed to let His Holiness understand that you intended to make easy for young clerics the manner of enriching themselves with know¬ ledge at the present day indispensable to gain that esteem which they require in order to render their ministry acceptable and fruitful. The august Pontiff was much pleased with this testimony of your homage, and, learning that the work had been praised by your Bishop, was still more pleased, trusting that it will do good among students and other young people, to whom it is chiefly addressed. While adding that the Holy Father, as a pledge of his satisfac¬ tion, bestows on you from his heart the blessing which you asked, I thank you for the copy which you so kindly sent to me, and I beg to declare myself, Your most affectionate Servant, M. Card. Rampolla. Rome, October 1, 1902. LETTER OF THE MOST REV. DR. BANDI, BISHOP OF TORTONA, TO THE AUTHOR Tortona, Beginning of the XXV. year of the Pontificate of Leo XIII. My Very Rev. and Dear Archpriest, The information that you give me of having now ready for the press your treatise on Social Science and Political Economy is very gratifying. I knew that you joined the study of social order to that of sacred discipline. I knew of the Circle of Social Studies that flourishes in your parish, receiving light from the Clergy to judge properly of the controversies that occur in our days ; I was always much pleased with it, because I believed, and I still believe, that thus the words of the Pope will have a happy fulfilment. Hence it is natural that I should hail with joy the publication of your work on Social Science. And as I am here, I shall add a few remarks. For priests in ten or twenty years to come, there will be a very serious, a very laborious time. The conscience of the people is to-day awakened after an age of lethargy. Liberalism* had laid this popular conscience on a feather pillow, saying to it: Look, all goes well, just as if you were on the knees of the Church of Jesus Christ! The people disposed themselves to sleep. But liberalism is the selfishness of men who wish to live well, to have all good things to themselves, without a thought for the welfare of others. And thus it happened that, while the people lay asleep under the dose of opium given them, liberalism robbed them of every¬ thing, of every right to civil life, of every right to a life that could be called truly human. To put them into a much deeper sleep, a beautiful song was sung, a 'patriotic song. Such was the per¬ mission of Heaven. A society, having been for some centuries * It may be well to remark that Liberalism denotes the tenets or prin¬ ciples of a Liberal; and that the word “ Liberal ” has many meanings. It is often a party name, used in opposition to Conservative. A Liberal with us is supposed to be free from bigotry or prejudice, to regard all the citizens as entitled to equal justice, and to advocate an extension of popular rights. But on the Continent the name “ Liberal ” is more generally 'given to men who follow the French revolutionary doctrines of 1789, who consider them¬ selves independent of all authority, and who, as far as lies in their power, do evil and prevent good. They are mostly infidels, and are sometimes called anticlericals.— Trans. X LETTER OF MOST REV. DR. BANDI Christian, and then removing little by little from Christ, well deserved that a return to Christ should be a laborious task. The parable of the Prodigal Son should be verified again in society. I have said that the people were asleep : I might have said, intoxicated. In point of fact, the people ran after the enemies of the Church, waving the banner of rebellion. With the help of the people, those enemies accomplished some works, not devoid of value, but without the Church, nay, against the Church; and above the edifice of modern greatness—an edifice grounded on a civilisa¬ tion for centuries Christian—they placed, not the cross, but the flag of apostacy and schism. To deny that our enemies, being masters of the world, have made some conquests, have taken some steps forward, would not be fair, because it is not true; it would be to fail in seeing that the destinies of a society which for a long period had been nourished by Christianity should mature. What our enemies did of them¬ selves was to turn against the Church many works that it would have completed, if it had not been ungratefully driven from public life. And thus they unchristianised industries, arts, literature, patriotism, everything; and they said to the world : See what can be done when faith does not stand in the way, and we do not meet the garb of a priest! But unchristianise the sciences, arts, &c., and raise the standard of battle against Jesus Christ, they will not then utter a cry, nor induce others to do so ; no, certainly not. Their life, how¬ ever decorous among the people, has not the right relations with the animal part of man, which feels more deeply the incon¬ veniences of being physically disturbed. Everything having been laicised, economy, which acts without injury to Christian charity or justice, was also laicised. Society, it was said, in the air of liberty will live well, will live happy, will live prosperous. Where Christianity is not, there is selfishness, and the strongest is the happiest. It was so. The people, whom Christ had ransomed from misery and slavery, found themselves in a worse misery and slavery, and proved for themselves that the yoke of capitalists without conscience is no less heavy than that of pagan masters. The people found that the pillow of feathers gradually turned to one of thorns, and that the song sung for them was only a mockery and a snare. Being ill at ease, they awoke. Such is the point at which we have to-day arrived : the con¬ sciousness of the people is awakened by the stings of poverty, and wishes to know the causes of its distress. This consciousness is not fully formed; but it tends to be so. It is a very serious matter. If the people know that their trouble comes from the need of Christianity, they will return to Christ, to the Church, to the Pope. If the conviction seizes them that Christ and the LETTER OE MOST REV. DR. BANDI xi Church and the Pope will not enter into their sorrows or their joys, they will begin another cycle of incredulity and wretchedness. It will then be necessary to wait until this delusion passes away before a return to Christianity can be expected. Behold the reason why the Clergy, whom their Divine Author calls the light of the world and the salt of the earth, ought to be at their post! Many persons say that they would be glad if the Clergy stood aside, and let men of the world scuffle about economic affairs. As for being glad, I also would be so. I would wish that all the world should be saints, and that nothing should be left for the Clergy but to give Holy Communion, and attend to the per¬ fection of their own souls. But all our wishes do not change the world by one iota. It is what it is, and it shows us in its life that character which events impress on it. Now, we live in the world, and our work ought to be developed according to its wants. Have not worldly goods the destiny from Providence to serve men, to serve all men, for the attainment of their last end ? And if they are turned from this destiny by selfish men who snatch from others, and if any class of society is deprived of its share in the common welfare, will there not be occasion to implore Christ that He may come with a remedy for such evils ? And by whom is He to be brought, if not by the Catholic priest ? To do that, there must be a knowledge of things, there must be a fitness to decide questions, there must be an abundance of clear and precise ideas. If the Clergy are not qualified for these struggles, it will be their lot also to stand aside. Others will form the conscience of the people. They will form it without Christ, and against Christ. Then, if religious apathy characterised the cycle of liberalism, that of socialism will bear the seal of an infernal hatred; and no longer from the lips only of the philosopher, but from those also of the people, will be heard the satanic cry, Let us crush the monster ! Yes, I know that the Church will never die. But I say, what a strange idea do those form of the Church who console them¬ selves with the thought that it cannot perish, when souls are perishing ! The Church, no, it cannot perish for the world, but it can perish for individual souls, for particular nations, which, being torn from it, cannot, either in this life or the next, enjoy the beneficial effects of belonging to it. The Church will not die, but we who have not lent a hand to make it live, we who have betrayed the hopes of Christ, we shall die. This is the reason why, my dear Archpriest, I like to see my Clergy instructed in a modern manner, so that at every moment < they may declare to our modern world the rules of the Redeemer. I am fully aware of an objection that will be made to me. My lord, it will be said, you know that our young men in seminaries have too many studies to occupy their early years : would you wish to add to their number ? LETTER OF MOST KEY. DR. BANDI xii I cannot deny it. I assert only that the study, at least initial, of this important social question, ought to be joined with others. I understand very well that no one can pretend to social science except after deep and earnest study; nor is it my wish hence¬ forward to promote to Holy Orders only sociologists or economists. I desire in my seminary a safe and clear beginning of these studies. I desire the treatment of certain questions, so that account may be made of occasions on which one would have to pronounce theo¬ logically regarding them.* The beginnings in the seminary can be afterwards enlarged upon with fruit and honour by our young clergymen. My dear Archpriest, allow me here to say a word to the Priests, especially the young. When I reflect on you, my dear Priests, I do not know how to free myself from a thought that causes me great pain and anxiety, the thought that you may give yourselves to an idle life. It is so easy. I say the truth, and therefore I say it candidly. If there is any class of persons who have the opportunity of willingly giving themselves to idleness, it is that of Priests, and especially Priests who, scattered here and there through the country, are charged with the care of souls. In most parishes, the work— that work which cannot be omitted without offending the eye—• is reduced to a few hours of the day. Then, in the rest of the day, in the long winter evenings, so many free hours, precious hours for him who understands the importance of work or study, but ruinous hours for him who gives himself to idleness ! Let me say it, my dear friends : if you abandon yourselves to idleness, I am no longer sure of your virtue—of your fidelity to those promises which, at your sacred ordination, you made with all the enthusiasm of a fervent faith. These are the hours, my dear Priests, that you ought to con¬ secrate to studies, especially to those which, scarcely begun in the seminary, ought to be thoroughly mastered, so that you may become Priests such as our times require. Turning again to you, my dear Archpriest, I wish to note a point that will facilitate for us, if fairly awake, the conquest of the people under the white flag of Christian Democracy, and it is « * These same views are very well expressed by the Rev. Dr. John A. Ryan, of St. Paul Seminary, Minnesota, writing in the American Ecclesias¬ tical Review, August, 1908. He says :— “ The importance to the Clergy of an understanding of our social problems will increase with the inevitable increase of the problems themselves. Therefore, the Priest of the future should be equipped to deal intelligently with these problems from the very outset of his ministry. To this end he should receive in the Seminary an amount of social instruction which will be fundamental and scientific ; which will be sufficiently extensive to make him acquainted with the vital facts of current social conditions, tendencies, and doctrines; which will be sufficiently stimulating to give him a lasting interest in these phenomena ; and which will be sufficiently thorough to enable him to deal intelligently, justly, and charitably with the practical situations that he will be compelled to face afterwards.”— Trans. LETTEB OF MOST KEY. DK. BANDI XLll the character, always most conspicuously anticlerical, that socialism takes. The war on St. Alphonsus, a war that cannot be called rational, it is so stupid, so absurd—the hatred against the Clergy that every day appears in the spoken and written words of the socialists, and their campaign in favour of divorce— these facts are a superabundant proof that they do not seek to better the condition of the people, but to unchristianise them. Can even the socialists deny it ? Their publications, in the form of pamphlets or periodicals, are like* so much mud taken from the puddles of Protestantism. It is usual, we admit, to cover this mud with the flowers and fruits of economic amelioration. But all the same : the substance is materialism, irreligion, impiety, apostasy. There is no wish that the people should go to confession, should receive the sacra¬ ments, should believe and follow our Divine Saviour. There is no such wish. On these matters we ought to instruct the good people, that they may know the object of certain speech-makers and editors. We ought at the same time to explain to them the programme of Papal Democracy, and show them how it contains a condemna¬ tion of those who at present flatter them with the mirage of unity. The people will then belong to us, to the Pope, to Christ. And the people, having become entirely Christian, will know how to put an end to the social injustices that oppress the Church and the toilers. I am well aware that some men reason thus :—Let the deluded follow socialism. It is a meteor that will soon pass away, and leave them in darkness and misery. The day of being undeceived will soon arrive, and the workman and the countryman will turn to us. This reasoning fails in charity, and therefore is not Christian. One single hour of moral perversity, of wandering from the right course, ought not to be permitted among our people, in the minds of our brethren, if it can be prevented. Jesus Christ should reign over all minds, and at every moment of our existence. On the other hand, it is not known what road, after delusion, minds betrayed and perplexed may take. They make take, and it is easily done, a more disastrous road, leading them farther and farther from Our Saviour. However—I wish to utter another thought candidly—the continual bringing forward of socialism and socialists, when there is question of exciting Catholics to social action, is not well. It appears as if the socialist propaganda was the only affair about which we ought to be concerned. Now, that is so false that it cannot be borne. I alluded, at the beginning of my remarks (and it would be a subject for long argument), to the slow but disastrous work that liberalism has accomplished, inflicting the most serious injury on the Church and on the poor people. It has treated both as XIV LETTER OF MOST REV. DR. BANDI its own creatures, which it might reform and refashion at pleasure. It made a favour of existence to the people, because their labour gives produce. It showed some favour to the Church, because the Church defends order. And do we not still hear from un¬ conscionable lips that religion means nothing for the people but misfortune ? Now, that one portion of humanity should be oppressed by another is neither justice nor charity. And who are to vindicate the cause of justice or of charity, if not Catholics, and especially the Clergy ? Read and meditate on the Rerum novarum, and you will find that Leo XIII., having laid bare the evils that liberalism has brought on society, calls Catholics to the work of restoration. The Pope does not say : It is the socialists who are ruining every¬ thing, let us oppose them. But he says : It is liberalism that has ruined everything; we ought to reconstruct everything. See how the same Pope speaks in 1903 to Gaspar Decurtius :— Nothing is more pleasing to us than, when an occasion occurs, to show our love and solicitude for the working classes, whose miserable condition w~e wish to see improved, that it may be made worthy of civilised people, under the guidance of justice and charity, which the Christian religion brought to all the earth, and has always promoted more and more. For the nature of our ministry implies that we should be always disposed to bring aid where tribulation calls for comfort, weakness for protection, misery for relief. Moved by a consciousness of this duty, and mindful of the teachings of our Divine Saviour to the human race, we have already uttered to the Catholic world some words of peace and love in the encyclical Rerum novarum, setting forth a sound basis (as all desire) on which to raise an equal order of things, whereby, the old dispute between masters and workmen being ended, a lasting peace may follow for human society. It is clear. The Pope speaks of duty, the duty of bringing about an equal order of things ; therefore, he means that the present order is not an equal one. Socialism, I know, makes things worse, and its action ought to be a strong reason for moving us. But, in charity, let us not say that socialism is what moves us. Society is sick : socialism is the surgeon, who seeks to strangle it, under pretence of curing it. Will it be enough to turn out the ill-omened surgeon ? No; we must try to cure society. It is said, and often said :—In my parish there are no socialists ; therefore Christian Democracy, with its programme of organisa¬ tion, is not required. It is all right in its place. We are sick indeed; but at present there is no danger of anything worse; we do not trouble ourselves about remedies. In such case it should be easily understood that the evil is general, and the remedy ought also to be general. If the Pope has spoken, and he has spoken for all persons and all places, LETTER OF MOST REV. DR. BANDI xv all those excuses are very miserable that would prevent anyone from putting his words in practice. Turning to your little treatise, my dear Archpriest, I express a wish, the wish that it may pass into the hands, not only of the students in our seminary, but also of lay people, especially the young men who are enrolled in our associations. I should wish also that the Clergy connected with these bodies would avail themselves of it to instruct our associates, and to make tliem a little more wide awake. Oh, how many times has there been reason.to lament in our associates a weakness, a fear, that dis¬ banded them at the first breath of^a contrary wind! Why? Because they had not a clear consciousness of their position; they did not know what they were. Let them learn from instruction. Let ideas, ideas, ideas be sown in their minds, though rough. Then will there be men fighting under a conviction. You have done very well in dedicating your book to Leo XIII. Oh, the great Leo ! How he always pleases, how he is always loved, how willingly he is praised ! Is it not so ? His very name is an example, a school, a consolation, an in¬ centive, and a reproof. It is eleven years now since he launched on the world his Rerum novarum. If we had all fallen into rank behind him, if we had all fully understood the meaning of that document, if we had not been sunk in Byzantinism, God knows at what a stage we should be arrived to-day. But reproach ought not to find place at this festive hour, which the Catholic world is celebrating around the great Pope. In a resolute will to labour for the establishment of the programme of Papal Democracy, let my soul exult, and let my hymn end thus : Long live the Pope of the workingmen, long live Leo XIII. ! Yours devotedly, Igino, Bishop. AUTHOR’S PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION A word on what I have proposed to do. I am a poor student, and at the same time a parish priest: two things that agree only in a* so-so way. Study needs quiet, concentration, plenty of time. On the other hand, the care of a parish, especially if somewhat large, is a continual interruption of the head and the heart. The beads must be laid aside, and there are many calls on the pocket. Yet I desire to live the life of our times ; I desire it by nature and by duty. I say by duty, because I cannot imagine a parish priest, or indeed any priest, that lives materially in one world and officially in another. And I know that I do not blaspheme in saying so ; for, with me, the encyclicals of Leo XIII. are not only beautiful things, but solemn commands. And there, I mean in those papal acts, there is lived the life of our times. I study therefore, and as carefully as possible. As during my life I have several times had the honour of taking the chair and calling young clerics around me, to share in the fruits of my studies, such as they were, it has occurred to me that I should string together my notes and present them to young Levites, who may thus be helped to become priests suited to the times and worthy of the Pope. I believe that there is need of acting in a decided manner, and that a circle of the Catholic social propaganda should be established in every parish. Especially should we call the young- men around us, and instruct them, and I should be glad to see this little book in their hands. Such were my views. If I have not succeeded, I shall not be too much grieved. b AUTHOR’S PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION I The favour of the public towards this little book was so great that certainly I should not have dared to expect it. In particular, our venerable seminaries opened their doors kindly to the work. That I am content, all will readily believe. But the reason why I am content, at least the principal reason, will not perhaps be believed by all. No matter : I shall mention it just the same. The cordial welcome given to the book is a sure proof to me that the minds of Catholics, of young Levites, feel the need of quenching their thirst with the water of new ideas—those ideas of which the lamented Leo XIII. was the indefatigable and authoritative advocate. To see souls rushing towards the light is always a consolation; much more, when we are convinced that that light is indispensably necessary for the age in which we live. Meanwhile, the Pope, who blessed this little work when it was first timidly presented to the public, has gone to Heaven. And I, while I prepare this new edition, turn my eyes towards the Chair of Peter, but see him there no more. I see there, however, another man, clothed in white, who likewise smiles, blesses his children in all parts of the world, and continues the mission of Leo XIII. It is Pius X., the new Vicar of Jesus Christ. I, as a devoted son, bow to him, and in his name I present to the public this second edition of my work. I TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE The introductory pages presented by the Author say nearly everything that need be said on the object of this book. As a writer, he distinguishes himself by the facility with which he explains his views, unravels difficulties, and supports his arguments. His style, no less interesting than instructive, is just what might be expected from a scholarly man, convinced of the truths that he inculcates, and experienced in a good method of communicating his knowledge to others. The translation is from the second Italian edition. There is little doubt that an elementary treatise such as the present, derived from sound Christian principles, ought to be exceedingly useful, especially in Ireland, where society, after centuries of trouble, is still much disorganised. Day by day there are discussions in the press and elsewhere on matters con¬ nected with social science; and many men, for want of proper information, are apt to take erroneous views, with injury to themselves and others. If it is a great evil to maintain false maxims, it may be as great a misfortune to let them pass un¬ refuted. The works of such writers on social questions as Hume, Smith, Ricardo, Marx, Mill, Spencer, &c., are so wanting in a moral basis, are so tainted with a disregard and sometimes even a contempt of religion, that little reliance can be placed on any system taught by them. How, indeed, could it be expected that men who err so grossly on the most important of all subjects should be safe guides on other subjects ? Limiting their views entirely to this world, some writing in the interests of the richer classes, others encouraging the poorer classes to the most revolu¬ tionary schemes, they may dazzle by their talents, perhaps naturally of a high order, but they will not be able to direct their fellow-men on the proper course of life. Works of the kind just referred to are very numerous. In the section given to Political Economy in the catalogue of one London xxn TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE publishing house, we have seen mention of nearly eighty authors, among whom there was perhaps not more than one, if even one, a Catholic. How great, therefore, the need of Catholic works on social matters ! The title “ Archpriest," pertaining to the Author, may be new to many; formerly it was common enough in the Church. It denoted the chief Priest of a district, just as Archdeacon denoted chief Deacon and Archbishop chief Bishop. The Arch¬ priest was the Bishop's right-hand man in spiritual matters, as the Archdeacon was in temporal ones. Latterly, the title has disappeared by degrees in many parts of the world. Yet even in the nineteenth century, we find that, through want of Bishops in Holland, three Archpriests (those of Amsterdam, Utrecht, and Zealand) exercised jurisdiction for a time in the name of the Pope. As the author of this work grounds his arguments in great measure on the encyclical letters of the illustrious Pope Leo XIII., who was so competent to examine, to discuss, and to solve the most difficult problems relating to the affairs of mankind, it is hoped that the book in its English form will be found, as in the Italian, a store-house of the best principles for promoting the welfare of society. Possibly the District Councils of Ireland could do much for the benefit of the country by assisting the people of their districts to organise in the manner so strongly and frequently recommended by the author. TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE DEDICATION TO THE POPE . v LETTER PROM CARDINAL RAMPOLLA, ON THE PART OF POPE LEO XIII. ... ... ... ... ... vii LETTER OF THE MOST REV. DR. BANDI, BISHOP OF TORTONA ... ... ... „ ... ... ... ix AUTHOR’S PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION. xvii AUTHOR’S PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION ... xix TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE ... ... ... ... xxi FIRST PART. THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE. CHAPTER I. ORIGIN AND OBJECT OF SOCIETY. SECTION. I. Sociology ... ... ... ... ... ... 1 II. Society ... ... ... ... ... ... 2 III. The First Reason for Society or the Efficient Cause of the Social Fact ... ... ... ... ... 3 IV. The Social Compact ... ... ... ... ... 5 V. Social Duties and Rights ... ... ... ... 5 VI. Life and Social Goods; Public Good and Common Good; Scope of Society ... ... ... ... ... 6 VII. Social Functions; Social Organism ... ... ... 10 VIII. Social Organisations; Business Unions ... ... ... 11 IX. Ancient Slavery and Modern Proletairism ... ... 16 X. The Social Question ... ... ... ... ... 17 XI. Christian Democracy ... ... ... ... ... 19 XII. The Foundations of Social Life ... ...,/ ... ... 22 XIII. Justice and Charity ... ... ... ... ... 23 CHAPTER II. CLEAR IDEAS. I. Social Elements ... ... ... ... ... 27 II. Man ... ... ... ... ... ... ... 27 III. The Human Person: Liberal Idea ... ... ... 27 IV. The Human Person: Christian Idea ... ... ... 30 XXIV CONTENTS SECTION. V. Duties and Rights VI. The Duties of Man VII. The Rights of Man VIII. The Equality of Men ... IX. Wants, Desires, and Pleasures ... CHAPTER III. THE FAMILY. I. The Cellule of Society ... II. Institution of the Family III. Husband, Wife, and Children IV. The Rights and Duties of the Family CHAPTER IV. THE COMMUNE I. Union of Families II. Autonomy of the Commune III. Functions of the Commune IV. Functions of the Commune towards Workpeople ... CHAPTER V. THE STATE AND ITS DUTIES. I. Union of Communes II. Origin and Nature of the State ... III. End and Duties of the State IV. Duties of the State towards the Citizens ... V. Duties of the State towards Itself VI. Duties of the State towards Families VII. Duties of the State towards Communes ... VIII. Duties of the State towards the Church ... IX. Duties of the State towards Private Associations ... CHAPTER VI. THE RIGHTS OF THE STATE. I. Wellbeing of the State ... II. Personal Contribution ... III. Real Contribution CONTENTS XXV $L, CHAPTER VII. AUTHORITY. SECTION. PAGE I. A Natural Hierarchy ... ... ... ... ... 78 II. Origin of Authority ... ... ... ... ... 79 III. Form of Government ... ... ... ... ... 80 IV. The Representative Form ... ... ... ... 81 V. Tlje Sovereignty of the People ... ... ... ... 83 VI. Functions of Social Authority ... , ... ... ... 84 Notes to the First Part ... ... ... ... 87 4 SECOND PART. THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. CHAPTER I. MEANING AND OBJECT OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. I. Utility, Value, and Abundance of Goods ... ... ... 95 II. Laws of Value ... ... ... ... ... 98 III. The Theory of Karl Marx on Value ... ... ... 99 IV. A Moral Foundation ... ... ... ... ... 100 V. Poverty and Pauperism ... ... ... ... 101 VI. The Factors in a Right Ordering of Society ... ... 102 CHAPTER II. PRODUCTION AND DISTRIBUTION OF GOODS. 105 107 108 109 no 113 115 I. The Productive Process II. The Factors in Production IIL Harmony in Work IV. A Great Problem V. Proprietorship or Ownership VL The Right and the Effects of Ownership ... VII. Duties of Political Authority with Regard to Ownership XXVI CONTENTS CHAPTER III. ABUNDANCE OF WORLDLY GOODS. SECTION. I. Nature ... ... ... ... ... II. The Earth III. Land Ownership IV. Land Return V. Which is the Best Form of Ownership ? ... VI. Aid for Small Owners ... PAGE lid 117 118 119 121 122 CHAPTER IV. MAN MUST WORK. I. Lahour ... ... ... ... II. Productivity of Labour III. Relations between Labour and Produce ... IV. Moral Coefficients of Labour V. Physical Coefficients of Labour ... VI. Limits of Labour VII. Labour of Women and Children VIII. Legal Guardianship of Labour ... IX. International Legislation on Labour 125 127 129 130 131 133 138 139 140 CHAPTER V. CAPITAL IS REQUIRED AS WELL AS LABOUR. I. Utility of Capital ... ... ... ... ... 142 II. Different Views of Capital ... ... ... ... 142 III. The Capitalist ... ... ... ... ... 143 IV. The Theory of Marx on Capital ... ... ... ... 143 V. Productivity of Capital ... ... ... ... 144 CHAPTER VI. INDUSTRY. I. Varieties of Industry ... ... ... ... ... 146 II. Small and Large Industries ... ... ... ... 147 III. The Undertaker or Contractor ... ... ... ... 151 IV. The Contract of Labour ... ... ... ... 152 V. The Co-operative System ... ... ... ... 153 VI. Wages ... ... ... ... ... ... 15& CONTENTS xxv ii CHAPTER VII. AGRICULTURAL INDUSTRY. PAGE SECTION. I. Systems and Contracts ... 158 II. Mezzadria or Metayage ... 159 III. Rent ... 161 IV. Perpetual Rent ... 163 V. Rural Wages ... » ... 164 CHAPTER VIII. COMMERCIAL INDUSTRY. I. Transport of Goods ... 165 II. Exchange; Value; Money; Price ... 166 III. Value of Money ... 168 IV. Merchants ; Profits ; Wholesale and Retail Business ... 170 V. Co-operative Societies ... ... 171 CONCLUSION . 171 Notes to the Second Part • • • « • » 173 FIRST PART. THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE. CHAPTER I. ORIGIN AND OBJECT OF SOCIETY. Section I.— Sociology. Sociology means the study or science of society. But this definition of the name is too vague, and has to be made more precise by a definition of the thing. Human society is a fact, a fact so close to man that the mind has not been able to avoid casting a glance at it from the earliest times. But a glance does not make science, which is “ certain and evident knowledge, having its causes in the thing known.” (Cornoldi, La Filos. Scol.) To be a science, therefore, sociology should take a broad view of society, which would embrace all; an accurate view, which could explain all. We shall therefore be able to define sociology as “ a science that studies society in its causes, with the object of procuring its perfection.” This definition requires a few explanations. 1. We say Science , because the precepts that it gives for social wellbeing will be truly good and conducive to their end when they are drawn, by means of study, from the inward nature of society and from the laws that govern it: a process eminently scientific. 2. In its Causes. —By these words the object of sociology is embraced in its entirety, and the knowledge of it will be full— truly scientific. 3. With the Object of Procuring its Perfection. —Sociology is a science most practical; or rather the need of putting it in practice has given rise to it. Its tendency and importance are therefore evident. 1 From these brief remarks on the scope of sociology every one can see how far it reaches, and how, like other sciences, 2 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE it also gives out from its trunk some particular sciences, which relate to special points. Thus politics, finance, political economy, &c., form parts of sociological science. 2 Section II.— Society. As is evident, our study ought to begin by forming an idea of what society is, a just idea—that alone which, drawn from fact, is like a photograph of the truth. And the fact we have present, or rather we are a part of it ourselves. What do we see on earth ? Perhaps men wandering about, like atoms in the air, as unconcerned about one another as the beasts. No; we see on earth men that not only go about like atoms, not only have life like beasts, not only live together, but they constitute a great family, which we are accustomed to call society. A short but accurate analysis of the idea of society is most necessary as a foundation for our study. Society means above all a plurality of creatures. But not this alone ; for then the stars of heaven would be a society. It means aggregation or union; but we do not call a heap of stones or a group of houses a society. It also means living together; but many horses that live together are not a society. Remember, therefore, from the examples given, that an aggregate is not that which merely wants something in order to be a society : for there are aggregates which are essentially incapable of becoming a society. If we with our imagination give life and reason to any of the creatures mentioned, we find no difficulty in saying that they are capable of forming a society. Therefore society cannot be formed except among intelligent beings. But is it enough that they should be intelligent to have society ? No; although intelligent, although living together, many beings are not yet society. There is something wanting that must change the living together from material to formal. To five is to act, and the living together will mean co-operation. Operation is performed by an intelligent being for an end; and the co-operation of many individuals ought to have that end which will be appropriately called the common good.* We shall now be able to define human society as a living together of men that co-operate for the common good. In what this common good is to be placed we shall very soon see. To study society, to examine the laws that govern it so as * According to the outlines just given, the living together (or bodily assemblage) of many persons is the material cause of human society; co¬ operation, the formal cause; and the common good, the final cause.— Trans. THE FIRST REASON FOR SOCIETY 3 to produce a most flourishing condition of social life, is the task of sociology. And this task we shall be able to accomplish if we study the efficient , material , formal , and final causes of society, because we shall then have exhausted the subject. Cornoldi wrote in a general way :—“ It is to be observed that there are four causes—the efficient, the material, the formal, and the final. Now, when these four causes of anything can be ascer¬ tained, to know it with a scientific knowledge, the said causes should be known, since scientific knowledge should be full.” Whether the language of the schools or some other is used, it is certain that our study ought fully to embrace the social fact, to examine it in the matter of which it is composed, in the forces by which it is regulated, and in the end to which it is directed. Section III.— The First Reason for Society or the Efficient Cause of the Social Fact. Let us mention the first or fundamental reason for society, or rather the efficient cause of society, that which answers to the question—Whence comes it that men live in society ? Let us find out the element of this efficiency. We shall suppose that there are only fifteen men on earth, living in different and distant places, so that each one believes himself the only man in the world. What are we to think of them ? That they will feel the affliction of the desert, that from their heart they will heave a sigh, that in morals they will be discouraged. We think so because we are convinced that, if we were placed in like cir¬ cumstances, we should have such sentiments. Let us now imagine that at length each of these men learns that other men exist on earth, far away from him, but men like himself. At this revelation we see their countenances beam with joy. Not only so; but we see them set out in search of one another, and, having met, inquire about the fact and the object of their existence. They find that a chief purpose of living is to live together, that they may help one another to live better, and thus more easily attain the common end. Now, here a question arises : Was it fancy, springing up at the same time in the mind of every man, that urged them to live together and to co-operate, or something else, and if so, what was it ? Let us suppose ourselves to be in the place of these solitary men. On hearing that other men like ourselves exist, what is it that would awake in us the sentiments which we have described ? 1. The need of being with them—in other words, the need of loving them. 2. The desire of having co-operation. Man feels himself 4 THE ELEMENTS OE SOCIAL SCIENCE born for happiness, and he tends to it with all his power. He feels that his joys are few and limited, and that, in the help of others, he can find a strong coefficient. By means of co-operation, sciences, arts, industries, studies, &c., all arise, prosper, flourish, advance. Leo XIII. writes :—“ The daily experience that man makes of the littleness of his power engages and urges him to seek co-operation with others. . . . From this natural pro¬ pensity, as from one germ, comes civil society ; then, from this society, other societies, which, though limited and imperfect, are not less really societies.” {Rerum novarum.) Even the physical life of the solitary man would be so wretched, so miser¬ able, that it could not be called worthy of a rational creature. Man, in order to live, must wage a continual war against nature, which does not bestow its gifts without an expenditure of human strength. This trouble it would often be folly to expect from the solitary man. 3. The need of speaking. I have intelligence, and, therefore, speech. I have need of speaking, and of speaking to one who understands me, and who can give me an answer. The most painful punishment that can be inflicted on a prisoner is silence. So much does man feel this need that, not content with the words of his brethren, he makes the animals, the plants, the stars, all things in creation, speak. 4. The principles of social morals rooted in the heart of man. Let two men meet for the first time in a lonely region. They become companions on the road; and, having discussed how they can best reach the end of their journey, they agree to help each other. Suppose that afterwards one of them deceives the other. The latter will protest against the violation of a moral law—namely, that which intelligent beings ought to observe in society. 5. The fact that at certain periods of childhood and old age, and in other circumstances—for example, in sickness—the life of the solitary man would be impossible. These five elements of sociability, which we find in every man, no man can have put there, but only the Author of man, God Himself. Therefore, the efficient cause of human society is God. Leo XIII. wrote in the encyclical Immortale Dei :—“ It is natural to man that he should five in civil society.” Man has, therefore, a sociable nature : to deny it is to destroy society. Hitherto we have been led by the voice of God, speaking through His creature. But it is not enough. Another word, whoever can understand it, God spoke in favour of the social state of man— it is the dominant note in the harmony of positive revelation. The object of Jesus Christ in becoming man was to lead men to eternal salvation. It is an indispensable condition, established by Him, for attaining this end, to live in society—in that society which is the Catholic Church. SOCIAL DUTIES AND RIGHTS 5 Section IV.— The Social Compact. To our question, “ What is the efficient cause of society ? ” others, not making account of the lessons that we have taught, answered that it was the will of man, which, by a social compact, gave rise to society. Hobbes and Rousseau are recognised as the founders of this frightful philosophy, which has served too much as a basis for all the revolutionists who have troubled the world in these latter days. There is some difference between the two, and it consists in defining the state of men before the famous compact, Hobbes saying that it was one of war and Rousseau one of peace. If the former shows us every man struggling against his brethren for his own happiness, the latter paints every man jogging along happy and content, and singing songs by the light of the moon. Against these fantastic notions, the arguments are too obvious. Suffice it to observe that such notions do not settle the question. If the makers of the social compact were men, they were induced to make it by some impelling force : this force was the true efficient cause. What was it ? * Section V.— Social Duties and Rights. The body of every living being is essentially an organism. It consists of parts, every one of which is the principle of some operation, exercising itself as occasion requires, not merely for its own benefit, but for that of the compound, and therefore for that of each particular part. Thus there is one being, whose unity consists in the principle that animates the different parts and enables them to be mutually useful. That-society may attain its proper scope it must be alive, I mean living that life by which the various members composing it, and animated by the same principle, may become useful to one another. For this it is necessary that the component parts of society should have a reciprocal influence by which they may give to one another the benefit of their activity. Now, mark well. If this influence, with which man acts for himself and for others, is the dictate of his own intelligence, is the recommendation of one or more men, we cannot speak of duties, except in the * The reader will bear in mind what the author has already explained. There are in man five elements of sociability. These tendencies towards society could come only from God, just as gravity in a stone is placed there by Him, and therefore God, the Author of these tendencies, or, in other words, the impelling force, is the efficient cause of human society. The subject is again referred to in the following section.— Trans. 6 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE sense of fidelity to promises made or obligations imposed. But if it is an effect of nature—that is, if it follows from the nature of man—then it is a natural duty imposed on man by his Author. Now that it is this latter thing we, who have shown the efficient cause of society to be God, cannot doubt. Wherefore, we assert, without further discussion, the existence of natural social duties in man. But from one root spring both duties and rights. Called to a special mission, the creature has a duty to fulfil. At the same time it has the right belonging thereto. This is evident. Accordingly, there is no doubt that if man has social duties he has also social rights, and natural rights—that is, rights pertaining to him because he is a man, not because he is a citizen of this or that country—pertaining, therefore, to every man, let it be well known. Yes, man, every man has a right to raise his head in the social assembly and to ask for himself a certain quantity of goods. Society is intended to strengthen the weakness of the individual. This is realised in a twofold order :—(i.) In the case of an attack on individual rights, or on the goods, natural or acquired, by which an individual is rich ; and (ii.) in the insufficiency of individual powers for the realisation of bold aspirations, to which the mind, naturally daring, of the individual is urged. Help for this individual weakness is an essential task of society. It is the advantage that the individual has a right to promise himself. There are therefore negative goods, consisting in the removal of obstacles to the development of individual potentialities, and positive goods, raising the efficacy of personal powers to a higher degree, which the individual has a right to expect from society. Otherwise, the reason for social life would be wanting. Nature would either have stifled the aspirations of his soul, or have given him other means for attaining them. Section VI.— Life and Social Goods ; Public Goods and Common Goods ; Scope of Society. There is often mention of social life and death, of social goods and evils : it is necessary to know the value of these words. When is it that society can be and ought to be called living ? Life is referred metaphorically to the social body. The idea that we have of animal life we transfer to society, in which, if well-ordered, we find a real foundation of analogy. That animal we call living, in which the body and soul are united in such a manner that they form one single being, capable of working for the attainment of the end adapted to it. Men in society are like a body animated by a soul. The con¬ sciousness of social duties is the principle that keeps them united, LIFE AND SOCIAL GOODS 7 and makes them work for an end, which is not that of private individuals, but of society in general. This principle is the soul. We shall, therefore, call living that society in which the con¬ sciousness of social duties is awake and active, leading men to work for the attainment of social goods. But what is meant by social goods ? Consider well that society is a moral body ; and a moral body is never an end to itself. Therefore, it of itself is incapable of the enjoyment of any good : it exists by its component parts, and that good which individuals draw from the existence of society is called the good of the moral body. Social goods are, therefore, those advantages which accrue to men from living in society. Those advantages, as everyone sees, cannot be opposed to the individual good, nor can they be of a nature different from that good; on the contrary, they are its perfection and its crown. Hence, social goods are the comforts and conveniences of living, the easier fulfilment of one’s duties, the more effectual defence of one’s rights, &c.—things which, for man when alone, it would be impossible or very difficult to secure. The Pope writes :—“ It is necessary that civil society, being ordained for the common good, should promote the public prosperity in such a manner that the citizens, while advancing to the possession of that supreme and unchangeable good to which they tend by nature, may not only meet no obstacles, but may have every possible facility for attaining it.” If, in society, this facility is wanting to individuals for the attain¬ ment of their proper end, or, worse, if there are impediments to it, then, instead of social goods, there are evils. Individuals can no longer turn to account their being in society. Everyone will belong to society materially, but not formally. Everyone will give as little as possible to society, from which he expects no return of any kind. The consciousness of social duties will give place to selfishness, which is capable of dragging the citizens into revolution, slaughter, civil war. Such is the condition of a sick society, near to death. We quoted lately the words of the Holy Father in which he says that society is ordained for the common good. Our idea of the common good should be clear, so that it may not be con¬ founded with that of the public good, which is quite a different thing. Well, what is the common good ? Perhaps a good that is opposed to, or naturally differs from, private and individual good ? Let us reflect. The simplest, and at the same time the most philosophical, definition of good for man is this :—The last end is an absolute good, and a relative good is all that which can serve as a means for the attainment of this last end. A good, not here included, cannot be regarded as a true good. 8 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE God has created many goods for man, but these are goods only in so far as they help to gain the last end. Everything in man has been ordained by the Almighty for the securing of this last end. Hence, even his sociability. Being animated by the desire of reaching that end, he ought to procure many goods for his associates, which may all be means of arriving at the last end. Accordingly, the common good is that sum total of advantages which, by reason of being found in society, concerns all those who belong to society. The public good is a thing very different from the common good. The common affects us one by one; the public, all together. There is common wellbeing when all are at their ease; there is public, when the moral body, to which each one belongs, stands well. Under the sway of the sword, though, oppressive, there will be public good, not common good; no, if the innocent are often punished. So much being settled, and placed in connection with what we have explained regarding the true notion of society, we can easily infer that the scope of human society is, not the public good, but the common good. Bosmini, in his Filosofia del Diritto, having examined this matter, concludes thus, and wisely:—“ Therefore, civil society, having been instituted to protect and improve all the rights of its members, acts against its natural office, against the office for which alone it exists, if it injures, instead of helping, a single one of its associates, even though for the benefit of all the others; if it proposes to obtain the good of some, be they most wealthy or most powerful, and not that of all; if, in a word, it is content to promote the so-called public good, instead of the common good.” 3 Accord¬ ingly, that ordinance which, howsoever, succeeds in impoverishing one class for the benefit of another is antisocial, much as it may appear to do good or to accomplish some excellent work. Society there is sick, because it does not attain to the common good. This common good, which is the object of civil society, takes also the name of civilisation, about the meaning of which there is a great want of precision. Some suppose that civilisation consists in an abundance of material goods, in splendour of buildings, &c. We do not deny that these are goods : we say, and we maintain, that the civilisation of a people cannot consist in these things alone, because they do not correspond to all the wants of man, they do not represent all the goods that man requires for the attainment of his last end. In our view, those people are more civilised who by their social state are in a better position to raise their citizens towards their last end. Any¬ thing whatever that proves an obstacle or an impediment to this mission of individuals—although it may be a good in itself— is for the individuals an evil. And to call civilised a society whose existence, whose composition, turns to the direct prejudice LIFE AND SOCIAL GOODS 9 even of a few of those who form part of it, is a strange contradic¬ tion. Let the words that we borrow from Weiss (La Questione Sociale, p. 394) be read :— “ The entire modern school thus answers our question : The final scope of social life is the increase of the public wellbeing. Thereby the fate of our fellowship is sealed. This unfortunate theory is one of the most dangerous equivocations, often per¬ chance a deliberate deception. No one any longer speaks of individual members of the community, but only of social wealth. The wants and capabilities of each particular person are, on principle, laid aside ; on the other hapd, much more attention is bestowed on the dead matter from which the totality of citizens comes forth. The magnificent idea of Christianity, that society is a great organism, wherein every single member holds the place assigned him and has to make his own endeavour for the advantage of all—wherein, however, society should provide for every member—is thus brought down to nothing. Limits for the protection of the individual, gradation of classes, co-ordination among all, are neglected. The cold penny is the only rule. The greatest amount of production possible, accumulations of the highest value, are the ultimate scope. Wealth without obligation; no relative possession, nor even a good footing, for the individual: these are the springs of our social life. Where once the wellbeing of a state was cal¬ culated by the number of those who, at their own expense, could take the field for it and form an army, to-day it is calculated by the sum expended on barracks, on fortresses, and on war material. If one State has millions of money more than another, by that alone it passes for the more fortunate. Who owns the millions, or who is the better of them, it is no matter. Enough that they he dead in the war-chest, or are in the hands of a few nabobs, while just near them are thousands and thousands of poor people in a constant struggle for existence.” Here,- in passing, let it be noted how much the principles of Christianity promote the work of civilisation in society. Christianity has awakened the consciousness of social duties, bringing forward the great precept of charity, which is reduced to this :—“ Eemember that you are not alone in the world, but there is someone else who has a right to be there as well as you. Nor is that enough. You ought also to help him who is a brother to you, that he may attain to his proper end. In helping him you ought to regard him as another self.” What admirable doctrine! The sociology of philosophers ought to produce volumes demonstrating that there is by no means a contradiction between attending to one’s own happiness and attending to social duties, and then wait to have them understood, because he who reads and meditates little cannot well see how society is like a beneficent machine, which makes a superabundant return to the individual 10 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE for all that lie gives to others. Jesus Christ has explained it in a few words : Love thy neighbour as thyself. How happy would society be if all men attended to Him ! To prevent the rich from abusing their position, to the injury of the poor, Christianity sets forth the vanity of riches, and calls the state of the rich a dangerous one. Now, why so, if not because the rich are in danger of giving to themselves what they owe to others ? A contempt of present things, which is preached by the Gospel and which some persons call an obstacle to the civil progress of society, becomes of great efficacy in the work of a perfect civilisa¬ tion, a civilisation true and not ruinous. We saw how false a civilisation is that which gives excessive importance to material goods. Well, the contempt of the Gospel is relative—that is, it falls on a defective civilisation, which apparently is perfect, but in reality is despicable. And thus we explain the words, Blessed are the poor in spirit : a divine maxim by which Jesus Christ gave the great lesson that poverty can be a virtue, and that as a virtue it is commanded for the good of oneself and others. The virtue poverty is a right appreciation that the Christian mind, in whatever circumstances placed, makes of the goods that surround it or that it possesses. As worldly goods have the same destiny for all men—that is, to serve them in reaching an end that is the same for all—this appreciation ought to be alike for all. To rise to such an idea of things in theory and practice is the perfection of the soul, because it is a victory over their seductive powers. It is a good for civil society, because man makes his fellowmen the object of his beneficence. The Church, continuing the work of Jesus Christ, animated by the spirit of His gentle doctrines, must, in the nature of things, exercise a pre-eminently civilising influence on the world. History, if any one consults it dispassionately, offers some splendid pages on this subject, and proves to the Christian philosopher the truth of Toniolo’s words, that civilisation is only the history of man’s union with God. “ Not because,” says Cardinal Parrochi, in his letter to Toniolo, “ civilisation in itself should be confounded with religion, but because there is no true and com¬ plete civilisation unless it is Christian, and Christian civilisation is founded on supernatural principles.” Section VII.— Social Functions ; Social Organism. The human individual lives above himself and above the external world. He is a providential instrument, an enlightened artificer, who transforms things around him into useful articles for himself. This is the work of each individual. The activity, however, of each individual is in some respects exuberant, and in others defective. Should he enter into relations SOCIAL ORGANISATIONS 11 of activity with his own brother, he separates from him if both do not gain. Such is social life, which is the result of separate energies struggling in the body with a two-fold effect, one for the good of the individual himself, the other in favour of the brethren with whom he lives. But it is easily observed that the strength of each individual is too little to be felt in all the social body. A little stream that leaves its banks does not ruffle the surface of the sea ; a big wave runs a long way. Individual social duties fulfilled are small energies, of them¬ selves not felt. What could one tradesman alone, or one pro¬ fessional man alone, do for the common weal ? It is necessary that there should be many individuals following the same trade or the same profession. There is then strong suitable action, which deserves the name of a social function. Turning now to the subject of each social function, we find that it requires many individuals having a community of interests, elements that stand upon the same basis. This basis gives them a special unity, by which they are rightly called classes, and, taking account of the functions that they fulfil, social organs. Behold why and how it ought to be said that human society is an organism—that is, a body resulting from organic parts, like an animal body. Materialistic sociology opposes the individual theory to this idea of a society founded on the theory of social duties. It was Descartes, we may say, who did the honours of the house to atomism, and introduced it to philosophy. Materialism took occasion from it to put on the philosopher’s cloak and appear less beastly. Thus, man was defined as a quantity of atoms, forming a person. If the individual is such, why not society ? So liberalism begins to generalise, and imagines society as a number of individuals scattered over the earth and forming a certain - unitv. Materialism, to preserve a human combination, recognises only the force of cohesion, which binds the atoms together. Liberalism, to unite individuals in society, recognises an agree¬ ment made by them to keep together. Thus, not a superior principle, not an eternal law, not a duty, but a human compact would be the origin of society. Section YIII.—Social Organisations ; Business Unions. Society, we said, should be an organism. Nature itself tells us what should be its chief organs—namely, social classes. These, however, should exist not only in the design of nature, but also in reality. If the individuals, though having common 12 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE interests, are not enfeoffed, are not recognised, they will always be individuals, similar atoms, but they will not be classes. And the society that is thus composed will be a disorganised society— a society of individuals, not of classes. Disorganised society is a body consisting of movable elements without any common centre of gravity. Everyone, being left to his own centripetal force, makes himself the centre of his activity. In this state of affairs it is natural that the elements of stronger wing should fly upwards and the weak fall to the ground. Nowadays we have exactly this kind of disorganised society. There is a society, but, being without organs, it cannot be healthy and vigorous. It must be languid, almost dead. We have been brought to these extremes by a variety of causes. To relieve this poor sick society there is only one remedy, the reconstruction of society, having as a basis the principles of the natural law and of the Gospel. Following the indications of nature, we wish for organisation according to business, that is—we do not wish to have arbitrary criterions in giving life to different classes, but to follow nature, which, having arranged that social good may be obtained by means of different trades or different professions, to which many individuals belong, has also shown us clearly that among individuals of the same occupation, the class, or active organ of the social body, may be and ought to be formed. Can it be formed : We shall say rather that nature itself has formed the social classes, placing groups of individuals in different positions. Only a violent process adopted against the ordinance of nature, wrecking individuals and associations, has been able to destroy the classes and disorganise society. And this is so true that, the classes being destroyed, society was led to reconstitute itself in other classes; and to-day we see it divided into two classes—the grabbers and the beggars, the strong and the weak, the capitalists and the proletaires. Here we have a classification against nature, one that therefore cannot last. And to-day we see a reaction of the social elements against such an organisation. We see these elements swimming in the sea of life, searching for one another, striving to form groups according to the qualities of their homogeneity, according to the designs of nature. Hence it is easy to understand what are the unions that we propose, and what their task. They may be defined associations of individuals having the same occupation, with a view to the defence of their rights and the promotion of their interests. Unions do not tend to eliminate the individual or the family— no, these remain unchanged. They tend to make individuals as well as families strong, able to resist external attacks and to increase their own prosperity. Alone, the individual and the family count for what they are ; organised in classes, each one is of as much value as his class. The task, therefore, of unions SOCIAL ORGANISATIONS 13 is great, comprising all the rights, all the interests, all the just aspirations of their members. This task is usually expressed by saying that the unions ought to represent the classes : an expression that deserves to be weighed for what it is worth, and it is worth very much. It means that the union ought to come forward and place itself in the position of the individual associated to it every time that his welfare is in question. To regard trade or professional unions as having in view only the material welfare of their members is to brutalise man. Man is composed of soul and body, and, wh§n he joins his class, none of its interests, which are connected and inseparable, can be left outside the door. Now, we know that man has religious, moral, economical, and civil interests. The union ought to help him in securing all these interests. For this reason the union will lead to confraternities, to rural chests,* to co-operative societies, to electoral committees, &c. Thus did Professor Toniolo describe the union at the National Congress of Rome. “ Its aims,” he said, “ are not directly lucrative. It certainly intends to give an organic autonomous unity to a class, and as such, to set forth its interests before other classes and before the public powers, to defend its rights, and to promote its religious, social, civil, and material wellbeing.” The encyclical Rerum novarum has some explicit teaching with regard to organisation. The Pope, having recalled the merits of the ancient trade and art corporations, wishes them to be re-established, not indeed such as they were in olden days, because too great a part of the world is changed, but wisely adapted to the conditions and wants of the present day. Behold how he speaks:—“ The advantages of such corporations were most evident to our ancestors ; and not only for the benefit of artisans, but, as many monuments attest, for the honour and perfection of the arts themselves. Assuredly, the progress of culture, the new customs, and the increasing wants of life require that these corporations should adapt themselves to present conditions. We see with pleasure such associations being everywhere formed, either of workmen alone, or of workmen and masters; and it is desirable that their number and their efficiency should increase.” The old corporations or guilds have been renovated and modernised by the counsels of the wise in the unions of which we have been speaking. | * “ Rural Chest ” is a name given in Italy to a kind of village bank.— Trans. f “ The guildsmen were taught to look upon work as a sacred trust, a holy function, the complement of prayer, and the foundation of a virtuous life. Before their eyes were the luminous examples of those blessed toilers, the saints of God, whom they represented with the implements of the various trades; thus the Blessed Virgin Mary was represented as busy at the spinning-wheel, and her holy spouse, St. Joseph, with hammer and saw. 14 THE ELEMENTS OE SOCIAL SCIENCE That these guilds, therefore, are desired by Leo XIII., if not in word, certainly in substance, may be gathered from other points in the encyclical; for instance, where he speaks of the necessity of placing limits to the hours of labour, if he assigns to the State the task of fixing the maximum number, he wishes, however, that the associations should be trusted to decide on the normal length of a day’s work. From what has been said, this subject of organisation appears so important that it may be called the basis of a sociology really democratic or civil. Toniolo says :—“ There is no Catholic social programme of any country that has not inserted as one of its fundamental articles the reconstitution of society by means of classes, and, therefore, by thus organising the classes of the people, does not perform the work of a true Christian democracy ; and that, in fine, by thus providing for the lower classes as well as the upper hierarchy does not contribute to the integral recon¬ struction of Catholic social order.” From the theory just set forth we draw, as so many corollaries, the following conclusions :— 1. Society fives according to nature when men not only have an active consciousness of their social duties, but are also able to make their rights respected, which is the result of organisation. 2. It being an ordinance of nature that various classes of men, called social classes, should exist, and society being intended for the good of men, it is naturally the will of the Author of society that the various classes, not merely one or two, should share in the goods, the social goods, that society produces. 3. If account is made of the end for which the various classes are instituted, which is the common good, it is natural that we should not speak of lower or higher classes, all being equally necessary to attain the object for which society exists. If, how¬ ever, regard is paid to relative functions, then the superiority or the inferiority of the classes arises from the kind of functions that they fulfil. By the Pope, the various classes are called the necessary members of a well-constituted society. As in the human body, there are members higher or lower, stronger or weaker, but all necessary for fife, and therefore, by the title of necessity, all equal among themselves, so it is in the social body.* As every member of the guild had to be of legitimate birth, and of an un¬ blemished and spotless reputation, so his work was to be solid and faultless as the manifestation of his character. Sham and deceit were universally despised, and legal penalties were inflicted on work of inferior quality. To prevent fraud and deception, all trades were under the close inspection of the guild-warders and local authorities.”—From Socialism and Christianity, a very excellent work by the late Dr. Stang, Catholic Bishop of Fall River. New York : Benziger Brothers.— 'Trans. * “ The shameless confiscation of the entire property of the craft-guilds, one of the worst kinds of wanton plunder in European history, perpetrated under Henry VIII. and Edward VI. to fill the royal purse, brought untold misery to the masses of the working people .”—History of Agriculture, by SOCIAL ORGANISATIONS 15 4. Two things are certain—namely, it is the intention of nature that higher and lower classes should exist in society, and it is also the wish of nature that all classes should share in the benefits of society. A third conclusion follows logically: that the upper classes ought to converge to their proper position of kindly guardianship for the lower classes. This, it is understood, is the will of God Himself. Let us hear the words of Leo XIII :— “We would wish that they (the more respectable citizens) should consider that they are not free to care or not for the condition of the lowly, but they are truly bound to have such care. Because the citizen does not live only for himself, but also for the com¬ munity: the contribution that some cannot bring to the common good, let others bring with greater liberality. Of the gravity (. N.B .) of the said duty, they are warned by the superiority of the goods received, for which they will undoubtedly have to render a more strict account to that God who gave them.” ( Graves de eommuni re.) 5. The existence of various social classes being a necessity, in consequence of the common good, a just idea of their rights and duties ought to be formed by taking, as a rule, this reason of their existence. Accordingly, the idea is altogether unwarrant¬ able that is entertained of the upper classes by many liberals, who regard their rank as one granted only for the benefit of those who belong to it—a position of honour, of luxury, of display, of ease, of fine times, &c. It is nothing of the sort. In our view the upper classes have, together with many rights, many and most serious duties, which are the reason of their existence. Without these, neither God nor the world knows what to make of them. Seeing that so many evils at present afflict society, the upper classes have a more grave obligation to come to its relief. The Pope intended weighty words. Yet—and it should be noted, because it is true—the practical life of the privileged classes does not correspond to the importance of this duty. “ The aristocrats,” says Toniolo, “ ennobled by blood and tradition, continue for the most part to live estranged from the debated problems of society, ignorant of their high directive duty, heedless of their immense responsibility. By their conduct they are very often accomplices in that social disorder which they ought to prevent or to remedy.” The Harmels, the De Muns in France, the Decurtiuses in Switzerland, the Toniolos and a few others in Italy, are exceptions. Thorold Rogers. Mr. T. Smith, though making little account of the spolia¬ tion of the monasteries, says of these lay institutions:—“ A case of pure wholesale robbery and plunder. . . . No page so black in English history.” English Guilds (p. xiii.), showing the ordinances of more than a hundred of them, and edited by Mr. Toulmin Smith for the Early English Text Society (1870). Confiscation led to poverty and theft. Under Henry VIII. there were 72,000 thieves arrested and executed.— Trans. 16 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE And the aristocrats do not hear the sound of the coming storm, which is ready to burst upon them, and to announce to them the dilemma of Toniolo —•Either change or disappear ! 4 Section IX. —Ancient Slavery and Modern Proletairism. Society, as we have shown, is a means intended for the welfare of all human beings, who, by the will of their Author, are called to take part in it. When a means is established by nature for the attainment of an end, it ought to attain that end. If not, it is faulty, not what nature intended it to be. This does not mean that every little bit of straw should absolutely and necessarily reach the point towards which it is blown ; no, the present state of things admits of exceptions. These cannot be admitted if there is a notable and direct failure in the attainment of the ends willed by the Creator, when the conditions also willed by Him are placed. Now, we have here three elements of which we must take account: the object intended by the Creator, the subject for whose benefit the object is intended, and the means by which the object is to be obtained for the benefit of the subject. The object is wellbeing, not absolute, but relative, such as can be found here below. By the subject we understand all men, not the most skilful, nor the most active, but all. And the means is society. If, even in a well-ordered society, there cannot be had all the wellbeing possible here below, let that pass; that even there may be some persons who, from manifold causes, do not enjoy the common good, let that pass; but that in an orderly- society there should be a large number of citizens who do not enjoy social goods, and, worse still, that the social condition should be such as directly to produce these misfortunes, tending every moment to increase, this cannot occur and ought not to be. It would be an injury to the Author of nature. These serious inconveniences must naturally happen in a dis¬ organised society. Without well-constructed organs, social functions fail, and true social life cannot exist. We observe two periods of disorganised society—ancient and modern. What did they produce ? The ancient produced slavery. It was a social state in which the greater portion of mankind were given, body and soul, into the power of a small minority. It had no thought, no life, no action, no personality of its own. The slave was a man without rights, a man brought down to zero. The master had his own rights, and those of others: he was a double man, a triple man, a hundred-fold man, according to the number of slaves that he owned. Society was not a benefit for THE SOCIAL QUESTION 17 the slaves; it was rather a press, which crushed every develop¬ ment of personality. All that happened because the monsoon of selfishness blew over the social body, seizing on and swelling up every molecule of it; some, becoming larger, overwhelmed and oppressed the smaller ones. In that world the idea of social duties could find no place. The social body was held fast as in iron fetters. Jesus Christ came to substitute for these fetters the sweet bonds of justice and charity. He proclaimed the natural equality of men, and, to ensure respect for it, made known that there will be a day of general account for all. If men were filled with the spirit of Christianity, there is no doubt that society would be well-constituted, and men would be happy. To make men grow continually stronger in the fulfilment of their duties, the Church, to which was left the task of elaborat¬ ing, developing, and applying the treasures of the Redeemer, instituted corporations, which had so great a share in promoting the happiness of people in the Middle Ages. But these barriers having been broken down, and the Christian spirit driven from hearts by a variety of causes, it was natural that social disorder should again ensue. Slavery, as such, can no longer exist as of yore. Behold, however, proletairism, which, coming under the shade of the tree of liberty, appears less horrible; but it is slavery, real slavery— in some respects worse than the ancient. As a social disease, proletairism is a vicious ordering of society, in which single energies, left in the power of liberty, are turned by selfishness to the benefit of the richer and therefore more powerful classes, called the upper classes. The unfortunate proletaires may be compared to so many particles of dust that fall to the ground and are trampled on by the passers-by. They are a various heterogeneous multitude, ever increasing in number. Poor people, uncertain of life to-morrow! We have said that in some respects the state of proletairism at the present day is beneath that of ancient slavery; and it is true. In point of fact, by the full possession that the strong man obtained of the weak man, the former was in a manner bound to take care of the latter, in order, as is understood, to reap more abundant fruits from him. To-day the possession is not full* and from this point of view it is worse. To-day the strong man commands. He takes the fruits of the weak man; he is master of them. But he is not master of the weak man’s life, the pros¬ perity or the misery of which is very little concern to him. Section X.—The Social Question. The social question looms up before us. It is not wonderful, rather it is A atural, that such should exist. It is the result of a very complex network of causes, which have brought an abnormal B 18 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE discomfort to many men. These, having acquired a conscious¬ ness of their misfortunes and their rights, are indignant against society of the present day, which they regard as the cause of their evils, and they wish it to be destroyed. And thus one thing comes in question—the living in society— about which there should be no question, society being an ordinance of nature. He errs, and greatly errs, who believes that economic discomfort is the only cause of social discontent. We think that there are other causes, many other causes. The great phrase Not in bread alone doth man live belongs indeed to Scripture, but it is also a strong cry of nature. Give men bread, bread, bread, and nothing but bread, and you will soon see them irritated against society, and raising a revolution to destroy it. “ Some men boast, and make others believe, that the so-called social question is only economic; whereas, nothing can be more certain than that it is chiefly moral and religious, and that, there¬ fore, it requires to be explained according to moral and religious laws. Even double the wages of the workman, shorten his hours of toil, lower for him the prices of goods; yet, if you leave him imbued with certain doctrines, and guided by certain examples, which move him to throw off respect for God and to turn to evil customs, your labour and liberality will be lost. . . . Take away from minds those sentiments which are the fruits of a Christian education; take away foresight, moderation, thrift, patience, and other suchlike moral virtues, which reason itself dictates to us, and you will see that every effort to obtain the comforts of life will fail. And this is truly the cause why we have never exhorted Catholics to found guilds and similar institu¬ tions for the betterment of the people without a recommendation at the same time to place them under the auspices of religion, and to encourage them by its constant aid.” (Encyc., Graves de communi re.) We, who lately condemned the proletairism of the present day, loudly condemn the present social constitution that produces it. But we recognise with the Pope, and all wise thinkers, that the tortuous social question is also—nay, is first of all—a moral question. Roused by the great Leo to the work of social restoration, the task before us is extensive and eminently pathological. It is the infusion of a new life, which we ought to bring to the present social settlement—of that life which formed the glory of bygone days, and which ought to form it still more in the present and in the future, taking account of the undeniable and consoling progress that the world has made in what is called the Christian life. Let us again seal what we have said with the w^ords of the encyclical:—“ If there is any remedy for the evils of the world, it cannot be other than a return to Christian life and manners. CHRISTIAN DEMOCRACY 19 It is a solemn principle that, to reform a society in a state of decay, it must be brought back to the principles that gave it being. The perfection of every society consists in tending to and arriving at its object: so that the originating principle of social movements or actions is the same that originated the association. Hence, to deviate from the primitive scope is corruption; to turn to it is salvation. And as this is true of civil society, so it is true of the labouring classes, who form the most numerous portion thereof.” Thus, and thus only, will the difficult question be settled. •» Section XI.— Christian Democracy. At this stage of our studies we can affirm, by way of a conclusion, that a true social arrangement of society will be attained— ,(i.) when the different classes find in society an advantage that corresponds to all their religious, civil, and economical interests, and (ii.) when, therefore, they are so placed respectively in society, and so work together by the exercise of social duties, that the weaker classes have a benefit in living with the stronger. These are two points which we will not here delay to illustrate, because this is not a place for dissertations, and besides they follow from what has been said. A happy use of words gives to a society thus formed the name of a Christian Democracy. Let us study for a while the definition that Toniolo gives of Christian Democracy, and we shall find these two points confirmed. The great sociologist defines it as “ that civil ordinance in which all the social, legal, and economical forces, in the fulness of their development, co-operate proportionally to the common good, turning chiefly to the advantage of the lower classes.” Here we see affirmed the respective location of the various classes in the social body, their co-operation for the common good by the exercise of their different social functions, and the principal advantage being in favour of the lower classes : such ought to be the results of a well-ordered society. Let not the last specification of the social end seem to you a restriction on the common good, as if an unnatural bent were given to social energies. No ; if the common good had not such a specific effect, it would no longer be the common good, and society would not attain its scope. A sufficient reason for the existence of society is the common good—that is, the good of all. To deny that the weaker parts, which are also the more numerous, have need of aid from the upper and powerful classes is to wish that they should not have in society any comfort or support. Our idea of democracy is conformable to that which we have given of society. It ought to be realised that society may be truly civilised. 20 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE It is evident that this idea of social democracy, which is founded on natural law, because it comes from an analysis of the idea of society, is only with difficulty reduced to practice by men who are urged on by the forces of nature alone. Jesus Christ, in the Gospel, raising His voice against the rich and great in favour of the poor and humble, has developed this idea in a very clear light, and by the help of His grace has rendered its observance more easy. The work of redemption is expressed by the Scriptural aphorism, The truth shall make you jree ; and the truth that will make you free will make all free. The truth, preached by Christ on the equality of men, on the end for which earthly things were created, on the love that men owe reciprocally to one another, is that which sets us free individually and collectively. Man, of himself, following the impulse of selfishness, makes another man his slave; one class subjects another. Christ by His truth sets us free. If man takes as the rule of his life the lessons of truth on his last end as well as on the use for which earthly things should serve— Seek ye therefore -first the kingdom of God , and His justice , and all these things shall he added unto you —he will have realised for himself that liberation which Christ brought by means of the truth. And this liberation ought to extend to all that are men : in such a way that if there are, as there will of course be, some more weak, more miserable, to them should revert that excess of strength and wealth which exists in others. “ In the books of the Old and the New Testament this special solicitude embraces not only the labouring or disinherited classes, but extends to such as are lowly, weak, needy, forsaken, no less than to children, to orphans, to widows, to strangers, to the unfortunate. It shows that the title to this special care, on the part of him who is ready to fall, is not merely an economic inferiority, but any deficiency that requires to be supplied from the superabundance of others ; and, moreover, the end to which this kindly treatment of inferiors tends is not only to keep them safe, but to improve their con¬ dition ” (Toniolo). With reason, therefore, does Toniolo conclude that Christianity alone has taught this idea of democracy, and that the elements of it are contained in Holy Writ. There remains another most important question: How is society to be regulated that it may become democratic in this Christian manner ? And here appears the practical programme of Christian Democracy. If, on this ideal Democracy, there is no room for discussion, because, as is said by the instruction of the Congregation for Extraordinary Ecclesiastical A ffairs, it is founded on the natural law and the Gospel precepts, and is therefore unchangeable, the discussion may fall on particular points of the practical CHRISTIAN DEMOCRACY 21 programme. In the encyclicals of Leo XIII. some of these points are clearly indicated, such as the reorganisation of society ; others are deduced from principles already established ; and others again are derived from the lessons of history, from daily experience, and from science. The practical programme is a means to obtain Christian Democracy. Hence, it is not absolutely necessary, nor need it be quite the same for every time and every place. Christian Democratic action has as its object to put in practice that programme which serves to realise the benefits of true Democracy. Among the points of the Democratic Christian programme there is one that regards the intervention of the State. This intervention being indispensable, it may be lawfully invoked when not present. Someone may ask: Is our action political ? May we take our stand on the ground of religion ? May we act in the name of the Church ? These questions were raised specially after the recent instruc¬ tions of the Holy See, and they are most important. The art of ruling people properly, so as to promote the common wellbeing, is called policy. This gives precepts of good government, and even it is subj ect to the moral code, which it can never justly violate. The duty of respect for the moral law regards all political precepts and documents. Within the limits fixed by this law, policy can freely accomplish all its work of thought and deed, like any other science or art. It has, however, this peculiarity, that, in treating of its own object, it meets with the elements of natural or divine law, so that it cannot give a preference to what is forbidden; it cannot, for example, abolish the duty of subjects to obey the constituted authorities. Documents that regard these laws of nature, of God, or of man, it receives from morals, rather than that it creates them. They are the documents that Jesus Christ, who came to perfect, not to destroy, nature, made His own, and constituted as the policy or social economy of the Gospel. Outside these lines policy has a wide margin, all its own, which it may cover with the industrious web of its precepts and its discipline : pure simple policy, which gains more or less credit and strength from the conditions of the people, from the events of the time, and from the manner in which it is carried out. The Church, the guardian of morals and religion, teaches, defends, and considers as her own the first kind of political precepts; and we, her children, can and should defend them in the name of the Church. With regard to other documents of pure policy we, as men and as scientists, can argue, discuss, condemn, or approve, but not in the name of the Church. If one man believes that a republic is a better form of government 22 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE for the people, let him believe it; let him even condemn the man who asserts the contrary. But let him do so in the name of his own reason, not in the name of the Church, which, like morals, stands high above debates and above parties. To make the Church responsible for the views of individuals would, according to the Instruction, be an intolerable abuse. Such, in our opinion, is the order of ideas by which the question of policy in Catholic action is to be judged. Even Catholics, and their associations, can prefer one form of government rather than another ; but let them not say that this preference is that of the Church. History relates of Galileo that he was perfectly free to maintain and defend his system, but not to do so as a doctrine of the Church. Hence, Antoine concludes:—“ So much being granted, it follows that Democracy, in its chief essential meaning, ought to be accepted by all Catholics, because it comes from the essence of the Gospel, and is an efficacious means of promoting concord, while, in its secondary or accidental—that is, political—sense, it can be lawfully accepted or rejected without giving any serious motive of discord among Catholics.” Section XII. —The Foundations of Social Life. Life flourishes in society by the exercise of various functions of the social organs. In proportion to the vigour and spontaneity of these functions, civil life becomes more flourishing, and more fruitful of good. But these functions arise from free and rational elements, which are not moved by blind necessity, but by delibera¬ tion. Now, the power that acts on the will is duty. Therefore, a deep sense of morality is at the root of social functions—that morality which dictates to man his social duties. The morality of the individuals who compose society is, therefore, the first foundation of its life. Morality binds man to an authority above man—to God. The relations that man has with God require religion. Without religion it is absurd to speak of morality. Therefore, religion is also a foundation of the social life. Christianity, that is, Catholicism, which has awakened in individuals the consciousness of social duties—which has disposed minds to sacrifice, to self-denial, to the practice of justice and charity—has contributed wonderfully to the life of society, and may well be declared its most solid foundation. Let us hear Weiss. “ The social question,” he says, “ will give very little trouble from the day in which the foundations of social order— mercy, justice, and fidelity—will again be safe, or, as the noble Le Play used to say, when the Ten Commandments will again become the fundamental laws of our public life. But no one can deny that this basis will never be soundly and durably JUSTICE AND CHARITY 23 established, so as to support the whole world, if religion is not the corner-stone, and if the edifice is not placed in the closest union with the Church.” Section XIII.— Justice and Charity. Reason, with which man is endowed, places between him and creatures devoid of it so great a difference that many expres¬ sions may.be applied to him which could not be at all applied to them. Who, for example, would say that-a plant owns its branch, or that the piece of bread which a dog is eating belongs to it ? No one, except by figurative language. Man was created with a certain degree of reality and another of potentiality. If we mentally analyse the individual man, and observe the elements of his composition, we have material for a proposition of identity—man is the subject, and the sum of the elements the attribute. Now, that the judgment may be exact, it is proper, it is necessary, that the attribute should include not only the real components, but also the potential ones, not because these latter have to-day any value of use, but because they are the basis of a value that man is called to acquire by the exercise of his activity. Every individual man, therefore, is equal to his reality plus his potentiality. He has a right to keep the former; he has a right to develop the latter. This consideration shows us man as if occupying here some ground on which he has not built, but on which he has a good right to build : a moral ground, which, by being a consequence of his rational nature, is naturally his own, no less than his own real individuality. The individual lives, as it were, in a sphere by himself. Every man has his own sphere. The development of each man in his own sphere is, we say, just, or we call it justice. By just we mean that which goes well, evenly, smoothly, as on a level. And it is precisely a levelling of human beings, making account of their reality and potentiality', that is called justice. St. Thomas says, Dicuntur quce cequantur justari (those things which are made equal are said to be made just). And common speech confirms it: two music strings that give the same sound are said to be in just accord. In the social body it is the wish of nature that all men should exist, and that everyone should exist with his own real and poten¬ tial personality, everyone in a space sufficiently commodious that his natural activity may develop itself for his own perfection. If men stand at their posts, if they respect the spheres of those with whom they live, they observe justice, and are just. 24 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE “ Here (in society),” says Weiss, “ every member has his post fixed, which he cannot abandon ; everyone has his duty assigned, to which he should not be unfaithful; everyone has his limit, which he cannot cross without prejudice to others and disadvantage to himself; but everyone has his right secured, to which no one, not even the whole community, can bring detriment.” If one quits his post, and, desirous of greater expansion, invades the space that naturally belongs to another, he violates the right of another, and is said to be unjust. Hence, in our view, justice, objectively considered, is the permanence of the individual within himself, or within the circle of his own individuality ; considered as a commutative virtue, it is the respect that each individual owes to the individuality of another. So much being granted, it is understood how justice is that chain which nature has appointed to bind men together for the forma¬ tion of the social body, or, in short, that it is the cohesive force of the social molecules. Let no one fear that this idea presents justice to us excessively or solely pronounced in favour of the individual. Such would be a very one-sided view. Consider that the individual who shuts himself up altogether in himself separates from others; or that from the very idea of justice there flows a right and a duty—a right to make one’s own one’s own, and a duty to respect the rights of others. Moreover, in the sphere of individual potentiality, which we wish to see safe and respected, we recognise the right of man not to be prevented from the observance of his social duties. And if these are the proximate bonds of the social body, justice is as it were the nervous system. In other words, justice means every man at his post. That every individual should remain at his post is a right and a duty. Because, if he is removed from it, it is also justice that strictly wishes his return or restoration. Between man and man, justice, called commutative, stands as a guardian or an avenger, com¬ manding that everyone should retain his right to equality. Hence it is seen how great is the extent of justice. It reaches as far as man reaches, both physically and morally. To confine it to the economic man, and to the relations that exist on economic grounds between man and man, is to form but a poor idea of it. Nor is the idea of it full or complete if it is not required between moral man and moral man. The analysis of the conditions in which the right of the individual is found and developed is not finished. We must continue it. It is proper to observe that man has before him not only the individual, but, what is much more important, civil society in general. This can bring great advantage or injury to human personality. Now, we know that society exists by an ordinance of nature, JUSTICE AND CHAEITY 25 and exists in favour of the individual. Hence the existence of natural relations between the individual and the social body, of which he is a part. The sum of these relations constitutes social justice. Society exists in favour of individuals, but it also exists by the co-operation of these same individuals. Thus, two series of relations : some go from individuals to the social body, others from the latter to the former. Individuals have the two-fold right of expecting from the social body a defence of their own personality and an increase of their own wellbeing. It is in this two-fold right, of which the individuals the subject and society the term, that social distributive justice consists. Society has a right that the individuals who compose it should contribute to its existence, preservation, and prosperity with that share of real and personal sacrifice which is indispensable, that it may promote the welfare of the individuals themselves. This right is called social contributive or legal justice. Though all this is true, it is at the same time clear that the violation of individual justice is not the only cause that can displace man from his sphere—that can deprive him of the exercise of his rights and of a participation in natural goods. No ; other forces act on man, weary him, and cast him down. His own passions, indulged beyond what is lawful, are the first cause of many losses, and often of total ruin, for the individual. Then, nature does not always give us its works perfect, and often the real man does not arrive at that degree which, in the intention of nature itself, would be required for the development of his potentiality. Often in the struggle for this development the real succumbs by collision with an insurmountable obstacle. All these occurrences are, more or less, misfortunes. Then—I mean when misfortunes strike the individual—shall he be deprived of that to which natural justice gives him a right ? A higher, a broader justice will then sustain him, and it is the justice of Divine Providence. Reason teaches us that, if the distribution of natural goods is to be made according to mutual duties and rights, therefore those goods have a general destination, from which even the distribution of individual justice cannot withdraw them ; and it is the use of them for the wants of all mankind. This justice, in a broad sense, requires that he who holds his own by a strict right, using this same strict right, should give thereof to him who for any reason is deprived of what is needful, and give in pro¬ portion not only to the want of his neighbour, but to the extent of his own superabundance. This justice, which does not grant to the miserable a strict right or claim, is what is called by the sweet name of charity. We see, therefore, how it is reserved for charity to fill up the voids that justice leaves incomplete—to give the finishing strokes to the work. It is thus understood that, for the solution of the 26 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE social question, we ought to come to it first with justice and then, with charity. Where justice is called for, justice ought to be done. Where strict justice does not come in, let charity take its place. Hence, the function of charity is supplementary. While saying so, we do not at all mean to lessen the value of the noblest of Christian virtues (charity), nor in any way to contradict the Pontiff, who calls it a summary law of the whole Gospel. Charity consists essentially in a movement of the heart towards a fellow-being, whom one wishes to help. Justice itself consists in a bending of the will towards the neighbour. The title, which is more strict in justice than in charity, shows the species of the two acts ; but the greater obligation of justice does not take away the obligation of charity. Each fulfils a function indispensable for the right progress of the social body, and fulfils it by the will of God, who will call men to account for their observance of both. Notwithstanding the character of strict obligation that is found in justice, there is nothing to prevent a spontaneous motion from arising in the will by the light of conscience, and leading to the performance of an act that justice commands. Then every¬ one sees that account ought to be made of that spontaneity which appears in a good soul, and logically precedes the obliga¬ tion of justice. A soul eminently Christian always feels in itself those sweet and salutary emotions. Behold why and in what sense Leo XIII. called charity a compendium of the whole gospel. For the rest, what we maintain somewhat diffusely might be clearly recalled even by the words of the same Pontiff in the encyclical Graves de communi :—“ The law of mutual charity, which is, as it were, the perfection of that of justice, imposes the obligation, not only of giving to everyone his own and of invading the rights of none, but also of favouring one another, not only in word and in tongue, but in deed and in truth ” (1 John iii., 18). Nor do we think that he wished the words of St. Paul to be understood in any other sense : Love is the fulfilling of the law (Romans xiii., 10). 5 Themes for Development. —Duty of men to live in society, to perform works of common utility. How the religious orders, &c., can defend them¬ selves with regard to this duty. What was the primitive manner of living in the human family ; if the state of barbarism., dreamt of by some positivists, can be maintained ?—Individual liberty cannot be the only law or ruling cause of social conditions—Explain, according to what we have said, the first point of the Democratic Christian Programme: “ We wish the gradual organisation of society in corporate, autonomous, general, official associations. Let all the citizens belonging to the same business or to groups of analogous occupations unite together, preserving individually their proper function (as masters, managers, workmen, apprentices) in order to discuss and regulate their reciprocal relations, and to safeguard their common interests. We, therefore, ask that the State and all minor public bodies should favour in every manner this tendency to corporate organisation. SOCIAL ELEMENTS 27 especially by giving full liberty and legal recognition to those trade and professional unions which, under the action of private initiative, will be formed ” —Rural unions to be formed in the same way for the benefit of the farming classes : describe their functions—Give a sketch of the statutes of a rural union—History tells of the causes by which the old guilds came to ruin: some causes were intrinsic, because such bodies did not know how to renovate themselves on the arrival of new times and new circumstances ; other causes were extrinsic, and of a political order— Various classes of workingmen ; duty in the contract of labour ; conduct to be observed in case of a strike—The abandonment of Christian principles leads to forgetfulness of social duties, and, therefore, to the injury of society. ■ 4 * CHAPTER II. CLEAR IDEAS. Section I.— Social Elements. If we examine carefully the social body, we ought to arrive at the elements of which it is composed. Taken altogether, they would be called, in scholastic language, the material cause of society. These elements are not all of one kind ; there are more complex ones and less complex ones, which are made up of simple ones, and admit of analysis down to the most simple or the primary. Some complex ones are proximate or immediate compounds; others, remote or mediate. Just as in a material body, there are molecules and atoms. To examine these elements one by one is a vital part of our study. Section II.— Man. The decomposition of the social body gives us human individuals as the ultimate and simplest elements. To form a just idea of a human person is, above all, necessary for the study of social functions, because, as we shall see, the good of the individual is the object of civil society. What then is a human person ? There is the liberal idea, and the Christian idea, of a human person. Let us consider both. Section III.— The Human Person : Liberal Idea. Rationalistic philosophy does not concern itself ver}^ much about the origin of man. It does not believe that it is bound to lose time on such a subject. At most, it says that he came from nature—a saying that offends the nerves of no one, not even of those who have them most sensitive at the sound of the word God. Charles Darwin and his followers apply to the origin of man the system of the transformation of species, which places us in our infant days on the breast of an ape or a baboon. And Darwinism at present enjoys much favour in the liberal camp. 28 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE As a fact, materialists see in man an animal perfected, which lives on earth for a certain number of years, overwhelmed with troubles, cheered by few joys, urged on by instincts that it cannot resist, and at last vanishing like the flame of a lamp that is extinguished. The spiritualists give the body a soul, but they do not raise it, at least in its final state, above matter. They do not wish it to be the queen, but the slave of the body. The socialists lower still more the idea of man. They see in him a machine endowed with the double power of producing and consuming. The steam that puts the machine in motion is pleasure. Production costs fatigue, but it is endured, because the thing produced will satisfy wants—will procure pleasures. These are the liberal ideas about man, which have all a common element, and it is this : man has on earth his proper end or ideal; it consists in enjoying life. The riddle of life is not explained by the socialists, and if any¬ one wishes to know something more about it from them, they answer majestically, Nay ! These modes of considering man do not make, at least in practical life, any difference between him and the brute. Action certainly ought to be directed according to an end : identity of end implies identity of life and conduct. By way of conclusion, this is the place to observe :— 1. Human personality, thus imagined, is degraded ; nor could we know—except perhaps through custom—by what title it might be called human. It is easy to recognise in man something that is not in the brute ; but if this something has not a last end that calls to itself the whole man, with a right to govern him, it ought at least to serve for the attainment of a last end—which, if it is common to man and beast, gives no reason to suppose any superiority in human over beastly life. Both, man and beast, die, and they are only matter. 2. Man thus imagined, a moral law for him can no longer be imagined. On what could it rest ? A moral law that does not lead me to my last end is an absurdity ; and if my last end is here, is to enjoy life, that which brings me to this enjoyment is moral; that which brings me to the greatest enjoyment is most moral. 3. It is absurd to recognise good and bad tendencies in man. Nothing can be more clear. What pleases is good, what dis¬ pleases is bad. How can there be any bad tendencies in man ? And how can it be said that there are instincts or propensities to do evil ? Absurd notions ! All the inclinations of man are good. They are his laws. They are like the reins that nature laid on the back of the first man before letting him take his course, so that they might keep him from breaking his neck. Behold man under the government of nature ! To withdraw him from this government is to spoil what has been well done, is to take the horse out of the hands of its proper driver, is to ruin it. And THE HUMAN PERSON; LIBERAL IDEA 29 this is precisely what, according to Rousseau, happened to man by the fault of society, which was the cause of all his misfortunes. 4. From the idea set forth regarding man it follows that every man is all for himself. If here on earth, where life is soon finished, I have my end, I have a duty and a right to adopt the means for attaining it. To think of my feilowman is to act contrary to my own interest, it is to rob myself, it is to neglect my end. Behold individualism, which makes every man believe himself the whole world ! Behold selfishness, the lord of man’s life ! Duties of justice and charity go thus to ruin, and all by the force of logic ! On this subject the Supreme Pontiff lately wrote with a masterly pen :—“ If man breaks the chains that bind him to God, the absolute and universal legislator and judge, there is nothing left but an appearance of moral law, purely civil, or, as it is said, independent, which, prescinding from the eternal reason and the divine precepts, leads inevitably to the final and fatal consequence of making man a law for himself. He, incapable of rising on the wings of Christian hope to heavenly goods, will seek only earthly food in the enjoyments of life—sharpening the thirst for pleasures, the desire of riches, and a greed for rapid and immediate gains, without regard to justice.” {Lei. Ap., 19. 3.’02.) Hence comes the so-called materialistic idea of history, which— although not expressed by all in the same manner—is in substance that the life of mankind is a great process of evolution. This is accomplished under the influence of economic necessities, and of the tendencies that man has to the pleasures of life. Every act of man has for its reason an economic wrant. To labour and to produce, and to produce in order to find pleasures 1 The very existence of man in society has its foundation in production and in the exchange of products. Thus waites Engel:—“ The ultim ate causes of every social variation and every political revolution are to be sought, not in the heads of men, but in changes of the manner of production, in changes of the methods of barter ; not in the philosophy, but in the economy of a preceding age.” This theory is pleasing to the socialists, and is perhaps the only principle that they have not yet abandoned ; because, according to them, morals and religions are things which, going with the stream of ages, can be excused for a time, or can well enough serve in want of better. But the day will come—that of perfect (and, as they say, stable) evolution—when these poetic legends will fall to the ground, without being thrown down. All this by the force of events, for such legends can be done without. The misfortune is that this theory is nothing but—a theory ! A calm study of the world and of man convinces us of the government of Divine Providence, of the existence of a free and immortal soul in man, and of the duties that man owes to God, to himself, and to his feilowman. 30 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE Section IV.— The Human Person : Christian Idea. Very differently do we Christians think of man; and facts, far from disproving, confirm our ideas. We study the origin of man, and we cannot place it anywhere but in God, from whose hands, by creation, he came forth good, as much so and more than some of our physicists think, and the Scripture also says that God made man right—fecit hominem rectum. We admit, however, that there was a fall, by which human nature was vitiated. Hence those evil tendencies, which, in our view, are an explanation of so many individual and social disorders. In point of fact, we recognise man as composed of soul and body. The soul is in him as the principle of all life and operation. It bears the responsibility of good and evil. We recognise in man a warfare between the superior and the inferior part. In this warfare the nobler part can and should conquer. Created by the Almighty, man must have been, like every other creature, intended by God Himself for an end. On the other hand, the life of man here on earth shows itself insufficient to be his last end. It is wanting in goods, defective in conditions, restricted in limits. It lasts only a few years, and then vanishes : the brilliant light sinks into the grave. Man, at the close of his days, is an incomplete being. Human life has here too many and too evident marks of its transitory character. It is impossible that God should have made man only for this life. We must look for something beyond this world that may be called a life truly worthy of man. Behold ! Reason and religion tell us that the soul cannot perish with the body, after whose death it must find an immortal life. It being always the same individual who lives in this life and in the other, there cannot be two last ends. There must be only one; and the present life must be a preparation for the future life, mortal man for the immortal man. Moreover, man has an advantage over other worldly beings by the gift of liberty, and his actions are the offspring of intelli¬ gence and will. Is he free to direct them to an object that is not his last end ? It is a contradiction. Therefore, it is the will of God that he should subordinate his actions to the attainment of his last end. Thus the future life appears as the moderating rule of everything in the present life. Therefore, eternal life is a reward. If there is a reward given to him who does good, there ought to be a punishment for him who does evil. And there ought to be a judgment, that the reward may be bestowed and the punishment inflicted. All these are things that we know well by faith. DUTIES AND RIGHTS 31 From this mode of regarding man, several consequences follow:— 1. His personality. Man in our view is a being full, perfect, endowed with what is necessary for the attainment of his end, and, in this way, independent. A servant of God, he is the master of himself. The young student need not be reminded by us that, before Christianity, very little value was set on the personality of a human individual. If he possessed something, he was worth something; if he possessed much, he was worth much; if his country had need of him and laid hold of him for some enterprise, he was a man that counted. But the individual alone, the man alone, despoiled of his belongings, was little better than nothing : he was a thing. It is not for nothing that the New Testament speaks so often of the liberty and independence of man. In our times, when some of the clouds rise, we see again the same elimination of human personality. The love of caste is still so prevalent in some regions that it does not permit one man to walk with another whose name is not emblazoned. The State becomes the dispenser of individual rights, which it often violates. The socialists wish to bring us down to zero, delivering us, like a great heap of sand, into the hands of the State. 2. His dignity. For he is placed in an order of beings essen¬ tially superior to beasts. Faith exalts much more the nobility of man, showing him as destined for a supernatural end and endowed by grace with means for its attainment. 3. That he is during the present life in a state of transition, or rather of labour—a labour that ought to be regulated and judged from the point of view of eternal life, in which he will reap all its best fruits. 4. That the last end being rest, satisfaction, enjoyment, man cannot be found perfectly happy on earth. He will be so in the other life, if he has merited it here. 5. The goods, therefore, that man can enjoy here below are not an end for him, but a means to an end. This mode of valuing the goods of time differs essentially from that of the material sociologists, for whom these goods are everything. What a wretched creature would man thus be ! 6. That man ought to be subject to laws, which direct him in such a way that by his conduct he may arrive at his last end. And here come the duties and the rights of man, about which some special words have to be plainly spoken. Section Y.—Duties and Rights. We must set out from the creature. Now, what is a creature ? It is a being that God has placed in existence, destining it for an end, which in the mind and will of God it should attain. The means of travelling to this end, God Himself should have 32 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE given to the creature. To deny this would be to affirm that God wishes it to go thither when there is no road. The road ought to be there; and it certainly is there. The journey is made in different modes, according to the qualities of the creature. If the creature is blind, without a knowledge of its acts, without a consciousness of its end, it runs along the road blindly, like an engine on the rails. The hand of God, which brought it into existence, is its continual guide to the attainment of its end* If the creature is intelligent, and therefore free, the Creator ought not to guide it with an iron hand, if He would not destroy its nature. The Creator then guides it by means of laws, which from on high throw light on the road, and show it the necessity of travelling thereby in order to reach its end. On the fact of a blind creature being drawn by the hand of God to its end, reasoning is not called for. Nothing remains but to admire the omnipotence of God, which is manifested in this wonderful fact. Concerning a creature that is called to accomplish its mission rationally and freely, we must proceed in a different manner. It, knowing itself to be a creature of God, feels that it belongs to Him. It knows that to attain the end for which the Creator gave it existence is the full reason of its being. Free in its acts, it does not feel itself free from the will of its Author. It feels that if it can act against Him physically, it cannot do so morally. Behold the sentiment of duty at work in it! The duty of attaining its end is natural to it, because it comes from the fact of its existence. This duty gives rise to another : that of taking the road that leads to its proper end. Here we have a complex duty : it is developed in many other duties, which the law points out on the road. We said above that the blind creature certainly attains its end, and this certainty we derived from the will of the Creator, whom nothing can resist. Having placed the creature in existence for an end, it is absurd to suppose that He would barricade the road thereto. This arises from the very nature of God, from the very reasons of creation, previously to every condition of a creature. The same holds good of an intelligent and free creature : for it also, by the will of its Author, the road ought to be unobstructed. The rational creature can, therefore, justly require means for the attainment of its end, in a word, for the fulfilment of its duties. This exigency is called a right, and may be defined as that lawful claim which a rational creature has for the use of means leading to an end. We move on. The right is vivified by passing into action : a work is the exercise of right. But here a question arises : are there no limits to the exercise of one’s rights ? To answer, we must dwell for a little on the idea of right, and consider its entity and extent. THE DUTIES OF MAN 33 The former is its existence—the circuit within which its action can be developed : this cannot suffer diminution of any kind. The latter has limits. We must, however, distinguish right from right. First, there is a perfect right. It consists in the use of those goods which are indispensable to man for the attainment of his proper end. To admit limits to the exercise of this right is to violate the course that God has appointed. There is also an imperfect right, and it consists in the use of those means which, wffiile efficacious for the attainment of the last end, are not neces¬ sary or indispensable. These certainly » admit of limitations, when coming into contact with the development of other rights. Such may be :— 1. The proper rights of other men. All men have the same rights. To give complete development to all is impossible. A just measure should be assigned to each. 2. Rights of the same individual, but of a superior order. Thus the perfection of the body cannot be extended so far as to be prejudicial to the perfection of the soul. 3. Rights of civil society. Society derives its rights from its duty of promoting the common good. These rights are superior to individual rights. Section YI.—The Duties of Man. The idea of a creature without destination to an end is absurd. It is also absurd that a free creature should not subordinate its actions to its end. Actions are, as it were, the creatures of an intelligent creature. They ought, therefore, to have their end, which can be no other than that of the creature itself. Hence the duty of man so to direct his actions that they may be referred to the attainment of his last end. Behold how the idea of duty follows from the nature of man ! And this idea is broad: it denotes that there are as many duties as there are means necessary for the attainment of the end. “ That anything has to be done, arises from the necessity of some end. Hence it is manifest that it is of the nature of a precept to imply order to an end, inasmuch as that is commanded which is necessary or expedient to an end. But it happens that to an end many means are necessary or expedient. And thus there may be various precepts regarding various things, inasmuch as they are directed to one end.” ( S . Thom, la 2ae, q. 99.) A creature that attains its end has no longer reason to desire anything : it is perfect. Man, who reasons, ought therefore to endeavour to attain his end, or to be perfect. Considering himself, as in a mirror, man knows that he will be perfect when he fulfils his duties :— Towards God .—By reason man knows that there is a God, c 34 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE liis Creator and Preserver, to whom he should render a pleasing service with all his strength and during his whole life. This is the basis of natural religion, which appears in the duty of prayer, when man recognises the Divine greatness and his own weakness or nothingness—in the duty of dedicating some time to the divine worship—in the duty of complying with the divine will where it is manifest. But it is proved that the will of God has been manifested by revelation, which is, as it were, incarnate in the Catholic Church. It is, therefore, a duty of man to observe the precepts of the Church. Towards Himself. —Man, composed of body and soul, is troubled with various inclinations, which often urge him to incompatible goods. In this struggle, the soul, as the nobler part, ought to obtain the victory. Conti remarked that man is like a sculptor, who makes of himself his own statue. It is also a duty of man to live : life is a trust confided to him, which, like a faithful soldier, he cannot abandon. There is only one absolute master of his life—namely, God. Towards his Neighbour. —Every man has a right to tend to his end, using earthly goods for this purpose. Respect for this right is shown in a number of duties that each individual owes to his fellow-men. Towards Society and towards his Country. —Although the views of man should be turned towards eternity, where his last end is found, yet the inclinations that he has to five here in human society tell him clearly that it is the will of the Creator that he should, by means of society, arrive at his end. This society will be a true society when it leads men most easily towards their end. And whose business is it to make it such, if not that of the individuals who compose it ? They have, therefore, social duties. We have already spoken of them. Society, as we shall see, is made up of particular societies, which are States. And this by the will of the Most High. These particular societies are ordained for the same object—the perfection of the individual, who then feels towards them a warmer, a more special love. Behold the duties towards the State, the nation, the country that is one’s home ! Among the duties of man, we must also place that of labour. Yes, every man, by the very fact that he is a man, is bound to labour. It is proved thus.—Nature has placed man in the midst of a world of good things, but such good things that, if labour is not spent upon them, they cannot satisfy his wants. We have here a general destination, that of all worldly goods for the service of man, and a general necessity, that labour should be spent on these goods, so that they may answer their purpose. Why should any one among us withdraw from these conditions, and enjoy the fruits of another’s labour ? It was not to one man alone, but to every man, that God said, In the sweat of thy face shalt thou eat bread . St. Paul gave an example of untiring THE RIGHTS OF MAN 35 labour to the Thessalonians, and accompanied it with a precept terrible for the slothful: If any man will not work , neither let him eat. And this duty every man has towards God, who made labour a precept; towards himself, on account of the duty of preserving his life ; and towards society, because labour is a social ordinance. In our view, therefore, the conduct of any one who leads an idle and unprofitable life is indefensible. Section VII. —The Rights of Man. We have given the name of right to the lawful power of using anything. Thus understood, the idea of right is clearly distinct from that of duty. To be bound to do anything is a step farther forward than to be able to do it; we speak of juridical, not of physical power. We have seen that, for an intelligent creature, the last end is the root of duties. It is equally true that that end furnishes the creature with the right or power of using the means that conduce to the end. The end is proposed to the creature by God ; in God, therefore, right finds its root and its strength. The end of man being in the future life, he has in the present life the practice of duties and the use of rights. Of the rights of man we must make a short review, keeping in mind what we have already said of man. 1. The right to his own dignity. Man ought to go forward to his end, preserving that personal dignity which has been bestowed on him by his Author. To say the contrary is to say that God wishes man undone, denaturalised, in order that he may be worthy of his end: a blasphemy, as everyone sees, against faith and reason. Therefore man has a right that no power can subject him to a condition of life that is unworthy of his dignity as a rational creature, as a Christian creature. Let us hear the Pope. “ No one can with impunity violate the dignity of man, which God Himself treats with great respect, nor obstruct the way to that perfection which is ordained for the acquisition of eternal life. And, on the other hand, man cannot, even by his own free choice, renounce treatment according to his nature and give up his soul to servitude; because there is not question here of rights whose exercise is free, but of duties towards God, which are absolutely inviolable.” (Rerum novarum.) 2. The right of fulfilling the duties that bind him to God—to perfect his mind with the knowledge of truth, as is required that he may make himself worthy of his last end, and capable of performing here on earth that function which God has assigned him. 3. A right to the use of the things of this world in the mode and measure that are required by his dignity as man and by a co-ordination of human actions to the attainment of the last end. 36 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE Man, making use of earthly things, has a right to satisfy his many wants; and this right he holds from his Creator, who, in the beginning of time, subjected the earth to him and constituted him its king. Now, man has need of bread to restore his strength, as well as of clothing, and a roof to defend him from the injuries of the weather and of wild beasts. All these requirements are included in the expression, Tie must live. Well, everyone knows that there are many ways of living ; between high living and low living there is an immense number of degrees. To what kind of living has man a right ? To a living that is worthy of him, and that corresponds to the exercise of his human rights. Curci says : “ Human bread means that he (the workingman) should have wholesome and sufficient food, clothing according to his station in the city—because I now speak only of artisans— and all that not only for himself, but also for his family, which, keeping within moderate limits, we may suppose to consist of a wife and two little children.” (Hi un Socialismo Cristiano , p. 109.) 4. A right to labour. This is an expression with which much noise has been made through the loud trumpet of the socialists. What do we say ? Does there exist in man, and because he is man, a right to labour ? Let us lay down two propositions, which are beyond all con¬ troversy. First, every man has a right to live, and, therefore, to the use of those means without which he cannot live. Second, every man has a duty to labour : labour is the condition, the natural title for the use of the means that are necessary for life. We may, therefore, draw the conclusion that, as man has a right to live, and as labour is an indispensable condition of life, therefore he has a right to labour. But has every unemployed man a right to contend with his brother, to compel his neighbour to give him work ? Slowly! Let us beware of hasty steps. The simple argument that we have used to show the right to labour will clear the way to know on whom the relative duty rests. In regard to whom does man possess the right to life ? Is it the person who is by nature obliged to give him food, &c. ? No, certainly. This burden God has placed on mankind. He has entrusted the material world to mankind in order that, being properly worked, it may give an abundance of fruits to men living in civil society. These are the conditions of life for every man. Every man, therefore, has a right to labour ; but his claim falls on society. In other words, man has a right that society should be so ordered that there may be labour for him, and, by means of labour, a support or a living. We willingly admit that the duty, on the part of society, of maintaining these conditions of life cannot be fulfilled without the fulfilment of the duty of labour, which is incumbent on those who are able for it. On the other hand, we shall have occasion THE EQUALITY OF MEN 37 to show that the rich have a social duty to traffic in their posses¬ sions. We say a social duty : a duty of whose fulfilment society, and not a private individual, has a right to demand an account, and, in case of necessity, to enforce compliance. 6 Section VIII.— The Equality of Men. God is the absolute Master of all things. Every mastership therefore, even the least over the least of creatures, can be delegated or granted only by God. Man, by means of the rights that God has granted him, has also a certain mastership over the things that surround him. Now, the question is, have all men the same rights ? To clear up this question, we must keep in mind the idea that we have formed of right. As we have said, right is the lawful power of using anything. Everything is used for an end. Whoever goes to an end has a mission, and we may regard the source of this mission as the root of right. Equality of roots implies equality of rights. If, accordingly, we turn to human nature, as it is equal for all man¬ kind, nobody can deny that all mankind have the same natural rights. But from an equality of nature we cannot argue to an equality of the acts in which nature is revealed. And facts prove that if all mankind have the same nature, not all have therefore the same mode of existence. One is of a low, another of a high, stature ; one is of a dull, another of a lively, genius ; one has a strong tendency to this object, another to that object. These are facts, evident and natural. Now, if God places a fact, His voice sounds solemnly in that fact; and the necessary consequences of theTact are no less an expression of the divine will. Our Bishop, Monsignor Bandi, reasons on this matter as follows :— “ Is there any need to spend words in showing that not all men have the same faculties in the same measure ? Facts prove it. One man is of quick, another of slow, genius. This man’s memory is strong ; that man’s weak. Titus finds much pleasure in mathematics ; Sempronius holds them in abhorrence. Dante delights in poetry; our Perosi in music. Even in physical qualities, how many differences ! One man is a giant, another a dwarf. This man is most dexterous, that man most awkward. One man is most quick at work, but rough ; another is slow, but accurate ; a third cannot succeed at all. “ Now, everybody knows that the faculties of man are given by nature. Nature, therefore, intends an inequality among men. To remove it from the world is an impossibility, for every attempt against the nature of things fails. The said inequality turns to the advantage not only of individuals, but of civil society; because social life has need of various aptitudes and 38 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE occupations, and the chief motive that impels men to engage in such occupations is the disparity of their states. ( Rerum nov.) “ Let us beware, therefore, of generalising too much on the Gospel doctrine, all men are equal. Logic and facts would be against us. Men have indeed a substantial and most noble equality ; but it is realised in the natural fact of a most varied inequality. The equality ought not to be exaggerated at the cost of the inequality ; nor the latter at the cost of the former. The pagan world forgot the natural equality, it saw nothing in men but inequality, and it created the opprobrium of slavery, which, blind to human dignity, treated men as mere chattels. Jesus Christ came. By His doctrine He threw light on the dignity of all men; and, for its defence, He consigned it to the keeping of His Church. And the Church has always raised her voice against those who degrade and oppress the weak. Even to-day, those who refuse to take part in the social work of the Redeemer, who still lives in His Church, attach supreme importance to human inequality, and make labourers the slaves of capitalists; and behold, Leo XIII. takes up the defence of working people in his encyclical Rerum novarum ! Even the Socialists, contrary to truth, and therefore contrary to Christ, exaggerating human equality and forgetting the inequality, arrive by an opposite way at the same extreme, and give over the whole human family as slaves into the hands of the State.” ( Pastoral on the Social Question.) We hope, in regard to this point, that it will be observed how the natural inequality of men is admirably adapted by nature to serve in strengthening the social body. The need that every man feels of the help of his brethren, and the exuberance of means by which service can be requited, are so many forces that run through the social body and draw it to unity. We will conclude, therefore, with Leo XIII. in his Rerum novarum :—“ Let this principle be established in the first place, that we ought to endure the condition proper to humanity : to remove all social disparities from the world would be impossible. Socialists indeed attempt it, but every attempt against the nature of things becomes useless. For by nature there are great varieties among men : not all have the same talent, the same skill; they have not health or strength in the same degree; and from these inevitable differences there springs, as a necessary consequence, the difference of social conditions.” Section IX.— Wants, Desires, and Pleasures. Although the last end alone has a perfect enjoyment for man, yet even the use of the means to it is not without some satisfac¬ tion, God wills this, certainly with the view that man, encouraged by a foretaste of future joys, may seek his last end with greater diligence. WANTS, DESIRES, AND PLEASURES 39 Towards the goods of the present life, which are means to an end, there is a multitude of inclinations in man, so that the turning towards them may be not only an effect of reason, but also an impulse of appetite. Thus there are inclinations towards virtue, towards knowledge, towards food, &c. But here we must make a distinction. Some of the inclinations of man arise from real need, which he must satisfy, if he wants to live; for example, the inclination to a moderate use of food, drink, and rest. Others from a natural desire of happiness, wherever it is to be found : such are ,the inclinations to partake of more dainty dishes, to be clothed in a more fashionable style, to, join in amusements, to collect whatever may make his abode more cheerful. Here the question arises : in what measure is man to procure the enjoyments of this life ? The answer must be drawn from that rule which is everything for the creature—namely, the last end. According to the proportion that present goods have with it, we shall learn the duty, the lawfulness, or the prohibition of using them. Hence— 1. Man ought to satisfy his real wants, because it is a duty for him to live, to work, to act; and that he may do so, he requires health and strength, a sound mind and a sound body. 2. Man can take some satisfactions, but in such measure that they may not contrast unfavourably with his last end. 3. Man should abstain from satisfying those inclinations which would place him in opposition with goods of a superior order, with the will of God, with his last end. 4. Man can, through a desire of greater spiritual perfection, abstain from the use of those goods which are not necessary to his preservation, or to his action for his last end, but nobody has a right to impose such abstention on him. 5. Man—that he may pronounce safely on duty, on lawfulness, on unlawfulness, in the use of worldly goods—ought to attend to the teaching of revealed or Christian morality. Man is a creature of God, and such morality is the voice of God. To discuss whether man ought to submit or not would be absurd. 6. Many are the goods that God has created to make man’s dwelling on earth beautiful and commodious. Many are those which are to be acquired by the labour of man, and many by the labour of civil society. As for the first kind, every man has a right to them, in the measure explained. Likewise to the second, because they are the fruit of his labour ; and also to the third, because the^ are no less such. As we shall see, society is a work¬ shop in which all labour, and the fruit is only one. Why, then, if all labour, should any individual be excluded from the enjoy¬ ment of this fruit ? Social position will point out the measure of it, according to justice; total privation of it is certainly injustice. A case may arise in which some one does not labour for the common benefit. If by crime, privation will be a just punishment; if by inability, privation cannot be allowed. If, 40 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE therefore, the progress of time brings to human society a more commodious manner of living, a greater degree of wellbeing, every man has, in the measure aforesaid, a right to it. Themes. —A diversity of conditions may be reconciled with the saying, we are all brethren —In the present state of society the condition of the proletariat is unnatural; what ought to be the characteristics of a social condition, that it may be natural, or rather that it may not be unjust— The right of the individual to better his condition, or to change it. CHAPTER III. THE FAMILY. Section I.— The Cellule of Society. He who, in reply to the question, What are the elements that compose the social body ? should answer that they are human individuals, would give a true answer indeed, but at least in¬ complete. Because, if it is certain that human individuals are the components of society, it is also certain that they are not the proximate components, but that there are other intermediary organic beings, who bind individuals to the social body. Now, proceeding from the more to the less simple, we find a first organism of the greatest importance, which is the Family. The office that it fulfils in the world tells us sufficiently that it accomplishes a design of the Creator. The procreation of man could have occurred without the Family, as among irrational animals. But God so disposed that man should come into life not formed, but to be formed. The task of truly making man belongs to the Family. God has entrusted this duty to the Family; and he strives in vain who attempts to deprive the Family of it. The Family therefore has, in favour of the human individual, a most important mission, a mission that it is sufficient for us to have pointed out. But the Family has another function, which it is our duty to explain and to defend. And this we do from facts. It is a fact that man is elaborated in the bosom of the Family, which after¬ wards gives him mature and full of life to society. Society, therefore, ought to regard the Family as the source of its life, well convinced that it will flourish or decay according as the Family does so. We showed elsewhere that the moral virtues, which adorn associates, are the foundations of a social life truly flourishing. But who is to infuse these virtues, if not the Family, which produces man ? The social body should therefore recognise in Families a natural bellows, whose wholesome breath nourishes its own vitality. THE CELLULE OF SOCIETY 41 Let not the socialists tell us that a substitute for this educational function of the Family may be found in public education, when guardians and teachers take the place of parents. If any one seriously asserts these things, he does not know that, for the efficacy of education, nature itself has laid a foundation in the natural relations that exist between parents and children, by the very fact that the latter have received life from the former. Now, this foundation admits of no substitute. The sweet looks of a mother or the severe ones of a father are always of more avail than a handsome premium or a heavy punishment. But, even granting that this educational function could be fulfilled otherwise, the Family would always have a great social importance. Not because the Family is for society, but its stability contributes very much to the stability of society. The Family is that society of which man, before he is long in the world, feels himself a part. Here the natural bond habituates him to do good to his brethren, to sacrifice himself for them. Here the sentiment of sociability buds and blossoms, as if inadvertently, together with the development of the intellectual faculties. “ From such ( Christian) marriages, cities can, with all reason, expect a stock and succession of citizens who are animated with the best sentiments, and who, accustomed to the love and service of God, regard it as a strict duty to obey those invested with just and lawful authority, to practise benevolence towards all, to give offence to none.” (Encyc. Arcanum.) Thus the Family appears by its nature the first cellule of the social body—a warm cellule—a perennial, ever new source of life. It may be said that nature has, in forming society, acted like a gardener, who, wishing to make a large bunch of flowers, gathers up many little nosegays, and binds them into one. If the string is untied, all the odoriferous nosegays of the superb bouquet are scattered about. It is therefore a matter of social utility that the condition of the Family should be secure and prosperous. Mons. d’Hulst says :—“ The Family, viewed under this aspect, becomes the foundation of society. What is a nation but a large Family, a union of Families ? And how could the assembled groups preserve their unity if the elementary parts of which they are composed lost their particular unity ? Ah, the advocates of extermination are not deceived herein—those men whose wild attempts are the terror of the world, and whose threats weigh like a nightmare on the close of a century that considers itself strong! They know well that, to ruin social order, it is not enough to overthrow a government, because governments return, but it is necessary to ruin the Family, which, once destroyed, cannot without much difficulty be reconstructed.” ( Conf . I.) It is seen hence how much the fate of civil society is bound up with that of Families. “ Matrimony was not instituted merely or even chiefly for the individual; its end was above all 42 THE ELEMENTS OE SOCIAL SCIENCE to establish and to continue human society. Practically indeed, here as everywhere else, the superior end first intended in its institution is usually the last on which people reflect. But no' one is ever justified in neglecting or excluding that end; and if anyone attempts to do so, the public authority is to be mindful of it and to defend it. The Family is without doubt an important factor, not merely by private right, but by public right. Never indeed has a well-ordered society been seen in which great regard was not shown to it. And therefore political authority has a supreme interest, an inalienable right, a serious duty, to occupy itself with useful questions in regard to the Family, especially when they are connected with the public good. If it interferes too much, it passes the limits of its competency. It acts without right; or rather, it acts with injury to the highest rights.” (Weiss, I. c., p. 289.) For the rest, Leo XIII., in the encyclical Quod apostolici muneris , has already said of domestic society that it is the beginning of every city and of every kingdom. Section II. —Institution of the Family. Man has an inclination to be the father of children, who are, as it were, a continuation of his own existence, and to whom, the last evening of his life having arrived, he may leave whatever treasure he has at his disposal. Man feels the need of intimate affections, by which the soul may take counsel for itself, may un¬ bosom itself without fear, without reserve, without circumspection. Man also finds in himself a kind of incompleteness, whereby he seems less fit for certain duties, so that if he fulfils them, there is a want of naturalness or spontaneity about them; and he sees this incompleteness integrated by a like incompleteness, which is found in the other sex, naturally fitted for special duties, and naturally unfitted for others. All this leads instinctively to the union of man and woman. This inclination of man may well be placed among those which he has a right to satisfy ; but it is not a duty for him to do .so, being able to arrive alone at his last end. By the union of man and woman, which is called matrimony, domestic society, or the Family, is begun. Whence is the institution of the Family ? The answer to this question ought to come, as a conclusion, from the preceding section. We there showed that the Family fulfils the intentions of nature for the advantage of the individual and of society. Therefore, nature instituted it, established it for the discharge of certain duties. From this conclusion many truths spring, like shoots from a plant. It is the groundwork of a long disquisition that might be made about the Family, for which this is not the place. HUSBAND, WIFE, AND CHILDREN 43 Because, if the Family is an institution of nature, such also are the conditions that accompany the Family, and that are required for the accomplishment of its functions. Thus we learn—(i.) that no human authority can undo or transform the Family, for there is no authority higher than that of God; (ii.) that the unity and stability of the Family are gifts intrinsic to its nature ; and (iii.) that divorce, tending to the dissolution of the Family, is condemned not only by natural law, but also by social law. We infer that the Family is a natural state, which has its own special existence, its own special end, and therefore its own special rights and duties. Christianity throws a clearer and better light on the Family. According to it, the Family, besides being an institution of nature, is one of grace.* Jesus Christ, recalling matrimony to its first institution, raised it to the dignity of a sacrament. As such, matrimony has rights not only natural, but also sacramental, of which no one can be a judge outside the Church, which continues on earth the mission of Jesus Christ. Very different is the idea that liberal sociology forms of the Family. For it the Family has nothing natural except that it satisfies the natural inclinations of man. Regulated by these, it is not a state, having its own end, its own rights, its own duties, but a something merely accidental. Man adopts it that he may satisfy his passions, that he may be pleased by the sight of a wife and children, that he may enjoy domestic comforts. The liberals have also created a state : a state that lasts as long as it suits, as long as individuals derive advantage or pleasure from it. The step is then easy to divorce. More logical still is the legitimation of free love, which the socialists advocate. Would you judge them wrong, ye liberals ? Section III. —Husband, Wife, and Childken. The subject is often discussed, but, we must say, with much want of care and consideration. Man and woman, beginning to constitute a Family, change very much their condition. This is clear. They begin to form a state, and they must abide the consequences. The Family has a special end, which is that of giving worthy children to society and to God—that is, children well-directed on the road that leads to their last end. This end is to be attained by common co-operation. But * A moderate share of material wellbeing is very necessary for spiritual wellbeing. To take an example, who does not see that if several poor families are crowded together in a small room, as often happens, especially in towns, the danger for morals is very great ? Whereas, if each family had a separate dwelling, of convenient size, and at least some degree of comfort, virtue could easily flourish there.— Trans. 44 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE who will preside over all ? Nature tells us : the man, as the more capable to govern, to defend, to represent. The head of the Family is, therefore, man : it is he that should guide the Family, it is he that should represent it before society. The husband is accordingly the head of the wife. It is written (Eph. v. 23), the husband is the head of the wife, as Christ is the head of the Church: and therefore St. Paul commands wives to be obedient to their husbands. This is true, but in how far are they to obey ? We wish this question to be well observed, because there can be exaggeration here. The husband and the wife, entering a new state, do not lose their own personality, human or Christian. If therefore they find new relations, these ought not to prejudice the rights and duties that they have as human beings and as Christians. In Genesis (ii. 20), we find a true idea of what the wife ought to be with regard to the husband, a heifer like himself. This means that the husband has never any authority to abolish the rights and duties which the wife has as a rational creature or as a Christian. And it is here, in this doctrine, which Christianity has main¬ tained and still boldly maintains against the mania for concen¬ trating all rights in man, that woman ought to recognise her rehabilitation, her true emancipation. Let her think of it. If, by withdrawing from the laws of dis¬ cretion that Christian morality imposes, she withdraws from the Church, she exchanges the yoke of God for that of man. The same is to be said of children who have arrived at the use of reason. Although subject to paternal authority, they have rights and duties that cannot be disregarded. The Sovereign Pontiff, who defends the rights of all, refers to these matters thus :— “ In like manner the right of matrimony was established equal and one for all, taking away the difference that was made by the ancients between slaves and free-born. The rights of the husband and the wife were made equal. As St. Jerome says, among us that which is not lawful to women is not lawful to men, the same obligations are for like conditions. These rights were confirmed by mutual benevolence and reciprocal offices. The dignity of women was guaranteed and safeguarded. It was forbidden to the husband to inflict the penalty of death on the adulterous wife, or to violate by lust his sworn fidelity. “It is likewise of great importance that the Church placed limits, when necessary, to the paternal power, so that there should be no encroachment on the reasonable liberty of sons and daughters who desired marriage ; that, by her decrees, nuptials within certain degrees of consanguinity and affinity were declared null, so that the supernatural love of married persons might extend to a vaster field; that she was careful to remove as far as possible from marriages all error and violence and fraud ; that she wished to preserve the sanctity of the nuptial chamber, the THE EIGHTS AND DUTIES OF THE FAMILY 45 security of persons, the dignity of marriages, and the rights of religion.” (Encyc. Arcanum.) 1 Section IV.— The Rights and Duties of the Family. The Family, having a special existence and a special end, it must have special duties and special rights, which are sacred and inalienable, no less so than those of an individual. If the Family is intended to give citizens to society, it must have the duty and the right to support, to instruct, to educate its own children. Is it right for the father of a Family to let another impose a method of instruction, a kind of education, even though this other should be the State ? The Family is anterior to the State, and, as individuals do not lose their special rights in the Family, so the Family does not lose them by becom¬ ing part of the State. Liberalism denying to the Family any existence outside of that granted by the State, it is natural that no other rights should be recognised in it than those which the State gives. And thus there is a continual intrusion of the State into the Family, every day bringing new rules, as if sooner or later a rule might be expected about the manner of laying the table. The socialists push matters as far as logic can go. They say : If the Family is only what the State wishes, let ns be done with it; let us consign boys and girls to a great public school, in which the State can instruct them, educate them, bring them up as it pleases. On the other hand, the Commune * has also its rights in regard to Families, of which it consists. The welfare that it procures for Families should be a work of co-operation with them—a co-operation that the Commune, in the measure imposed on it by the nature of its functions, has a right to determine. This includes the right to command, to fix, to arrange, and to collect imposts, according to the rules of justice, and sometimes also to require that Families should submit to the Commune the exercise of their right to property. All this is to be observed within the limit set forth by us, that the Com¬ mune is not at all an arbiter of the sacred rights of Families, but only a guardian and promoter of the wellbeing of all, though at times this may be attained only by a serious sacrifice for some. Themes. —Why the accidental and undeniable inconveniences of matrimonial indissolubility are to be tolerated, and how they do not justify divorce—Divorce is a consequence of unchristian theories regarding the Family. * The Continental Commune, in a local sense, is much like a Parish with us. The duties of its administrators correspond in many respects to those of our District Councils. From ten to twenty Communes form a Canton. Local Councils, it has been happily said, are the Primary Schools of freedom.— Trans. 46 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE CHAPTEB IV. THE COMMUNE. Section I. —Union of Families. The Family is immediately intended to aid the work of individuals; as we have seen, it makes a step by itself in the scale of social beings. But the Family is of necessity a small association, limited by the claims of the closest relationship. It soon feels the weakness of its powers, and desires to strengthen them by union with other Families. Such union has been made from the earliest times, and it is realised in the Commune. What then is the Commune ? An Aggregation of Families. Topographical position, facility of communication, similarity of productions, identity of habits, community of interests, &c., determine the several groups of Families, and mark the boundaries of the various Communes. A number of Families, who associate with a view to co-operation in the same district, which forms the basis of a community, are therefore the immediate factors of the Commune. But whence is its origin—from nature or from man ? Communes are a necessity that Families may flourish. In the work of the Commune they feel a power close to them, which is almost their own—a great power, which assists them, defends them, promotes their prosperity. The human individual has need of the assistance of the Commune. In point of fact, besides relations with domestics and neighbours by an unavoidable necessity, there are other relations for which the interference of the Family does not suffice, and which at the same time cannot be considered nor safeguarded, nor even perceived, by the distant government of the State. The work of the Commune is therefore truly required. And when the necessity of things calls for an institution, it may well be said that this institution has its origin in nature. As with all natural things, it is therefore true that Communes have a special existence and personality, have special rights and duties, have a special end. To try to do without them is to do violence to nature. A capital criterion this , said Toniolo at the Congress of Padua, which is to he applied in all its consequences , even -financial. Moreover, nature, in assigning to the Commune a special existence, with a special end, has implicitly shown what ought to be the conditions of its existence. These conditions ought to be observed, if we wish the Commune to attain its object—the good of individuals, of Families, of Society. “ Because,” says Leo XIII., “ it is a law divinely sanctioned that things instituted by nature and by God are found by us so much the more useful AUTONOMY OF THE COMMUNE 47 and salutary as they remain entire and immutable in their natural state. God, the Creator of all things, knew well what was expedient for every institution and its maintenance, and by His will and mind arranged all in such a manner that each should conveniently attain its end. But if the rashness and wickedness of men try to change or to overthrow the order of things providen¬ tially established, then even things instituted with the highest wisdom and greatest advantage begin to do harm or cease to be of any use, whether it is that by change they lose the power of doing good or rather because God wishes to punish the pride and audacity of mortals.” Section II.— Autonomy of the Commune. Whatever is intended by nature for a certain scope has a good right to gather round it all those resources with which nature has provided it for the attainment of that scope. It has there¬ fore a right not to be opposed on its way, a right not to be trifled with, a right to defend itself. This means that it is independent or autonomous. Autonomy is of necessity to be granted to the Commune. It follows as a logical consequence from what we have said in general regarding it. Counsellor Invrea describes autonomy as “ the liberty that the Commune ought to have in working for its own ends, and that naturally implies the faculty of giving laws within certain limits, by means of proper authority, regularly constituted. And this autonomy ought not to have any other limits than those which are required by a necessary harmony with the general ends of the State, and with the obligation that the State has to remove abuses—limits that evidently vary from time to time and from place to place, but always give room for a large communal autonomy ” (II Commune, &c.). It is understood, therefore, that the question of autonomy is one of preservation or destruction, life or death, for Communes. That deleterious force which passed through social life, and un¬ did as much as possible the organisations that it met on its way, dragging with it every reason of justice and right, and concen¬ trating all in the State, if it did not wholly destroy Communes, left them only a little life. The Commune, a natural organisation, is radically destroyed by admitting that its every originating cause, its every function, its every right, is a concession of the State. In our work .of social reconstruction, we must seek and earnestly seek the reconstitution of our Communes: we must seek their full autonomy. The Catholic Congress of Padua declared that, according to an analysis of the idea of public bodies (communal and provincial), these bodies do not appear as affiliations from the central authority 48 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE of the State, but rather, logically and historically, as so many organisations having an origin and a life of their own ; and that, therefore, the powers belonging to them for civil ends cannot be regarded as essentially a delegation of the State. (Atti del Congresso, p. 266.) As a consequence, the autonomy of the Commune requires two things :—(i.) A right to elect its own councillors. That the State should appoint rulers for a Commune, or, with vain and ridiculous pretexts, select the members of a municipal council, is repugnant to communal autonomy, (ii.) Freedom of adminis¬ tration. Communes at the present day are treated worse than minors. Their deliberations have no force of themselves, but from tutorial authority, which, instead of favouring them, destroys (hem in an autocratic manner. We have said that we do not deny to the State an inspection and control of the acts of the Commune ; but we maintain in the following section that there are limits to such interference. Section III.— Functions of the Commune. What are the functions of the Commune we must learn from those social necessities which make us assert the natural existence of this important organism. The Commune that provides for these necessities fulfils its duties. Here it is well to remember that the Commune does not commit that abuse towards individuals and families which the State commits to their prejudice. The Commune is intended to complete the work of inferior bodies, not to be a substitute for them : where their work ends, its work properly begins. It enters, therefore, into the duties of the Commune to provide schools and teachers, good roads, sufficient light, and everything else suited for the convenience of the district, and all this at the least possible sacrifice to families. In some cases it is the duty of the Commune to become a substitute for the family; but why ? Because, through the fault or the misfortune of the family, its work fails. Thus it pertains to the Commune to take care of orphans, to assist the needy, to provide medical attendance for the poor. Invrea says:—“ The idea of functions relating to the Commune is evidently an idea that varies according to circum¬ stances. We may consider as functions normally relating to the Commune those which correspond to local wants—that is, wants which can be sufficiently satisfied by communal organisation.” In short, the action of the Commune ought to be concerned with local interests, limited on one side by the inborn rights of inferior bodies, and on the other by the amount of its' strength, which may require the aid of a higher body, powerful though remote. The following words of Toniolo at the Congress of Padua FUNCTIONS OF COMMUNE TOWARDS WORKPEOPLE 49 throw light on this point:—“ Our Communes were bodies legally perfect, over which at a later period (and history records with what a difficult struggle) the State—that is to say, a higher political body, raised itself, when, in a region comprising many Communes and other autonomous bodies, a distinction was made between the interests of a large sphere and those of a small one. Only then, and with a laborious process, began the work of specifica¬ tion ; but in this sense that a fulness of powers and rights continued to be recognised in local bodies, and only slowly and gradually was a part of the powers transferred to the State with higher authority, as if integrating the powers ,of the Commune. And thus to the legislative faculties of public and private right—to a civil, economical, moral, and politico-military administration of Communes and local bodies—there was added a second legislation, as well as a new kind of territorial administration, which at length came to prevail. This is an historical proof that the State in general drew’ the elements of its historical development from the Communes, and not vice versa .” (Atti del Congresso, p. 248.) We see therefore how well grounded on solid social reasons is the agitation made, and not by Catholics alone, to obtain a large measure of decentralisation in favour of the Communes, which the grasping State of the present day reduces to a condition of little service. From this idea of communal functions, it also follows that the views of those who give the Commune only an economical task are wrong. The Commune ought to integrate the work of families under it, taken as they are, with whatever interests they naturally have. But, besides economical interests, they have moral and religious ones, the guardianship and promotion of which the Commune should take to heart. An interest (we confine ourselves to one) that touches the family in its most sacred rights, is that of public elementary instruction. If there are children of families, it is consequently the right of families to give them such education and instruction as they choose. As the work of families is to be integrated by the more ponderous work of a greater organism, this can only be the Commune, which—the community being like a large family—is in a position to know the desires of the families affiliated to it, and to satisfy them, according to the circumstances and the faculties of the families. And yet is not an attempt often made to con¬ centrate also in the State this task essentially communal ? Section IV.— Functions of the Commune towards Work¬ people. The demands on our time require that, referring to the functions of the Commune in globo, we speak of one in particular, and it is that which ought to be exercised towards poor workpeople. D 50 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE The idea of society, which we have set forth in its place, implies that, on the part of higher bodies and classes, there should be a particular care and protection shown towards those who are in need of help. Nobody will deny that workpeople, however employed, even those who live by the fruits of their own labour, especially in the present state of social disorganisation, are to be regarded as the weakest elements of society. Account being made of these facts, there arises in the Commune an obligation to care in some manner for the labouring classes, and to give them work by which they may become more prosperous. And this obligation urges more now that we have to lament a sad indifference on the part of the State. It would likewise press, even if the State fulfilled its duty—either because the Commune is nearer to the workpeople and knows their ills and the remedies for them better, or because the State would always require the aid of a local body to direct it in different cases. Now, workpeople are found in a triple position before the Commune. The first is when they are directly employed and paid by it. The number of these is increasing every day, because the municipalising of public services is gaining favour. The second is when the system of “ farming ” prevails with the Commune. Then the workpeople depend directly on the “ farmer ” or contractor, and indirectly on the Commune. The third is that which they have with the Commune by the very fact of being members of the community, not having business relations with any local body. It is evident that the Commune has different obligations towards the workpeople according to the different positions that they occupy before it. In the first case, the Commune, besides being the Commune, is also the Undertaker,* and besides being the Undertaker is also the Master of the workpeople. It has therefore to practise a triple duty towards them. That constant and loving patronage wfiiich a master should exercise over his servants, the Commune owes to its workpeople. It should therefore be all watchfulness and energy, so that fair play may be shown to them. It should provide a suitable time¬ table for them, drawn up according to the rules of Christian economy. They should have convenient times for rest, especially festivals. Their self-respect, their dignity, their morals should be guarded. For workpeople of the second position, the Commune has not directly the same obligations, but it has them indirectly. When a man entrusts his work to a contractor, who sees that the v/ork * It must be remembered that here and elsewhere throughout the book the word “ Undertaker ” means one who engages to transact business for others. See especially p. 151.— Trans. UNION OF COMMUNES 51 must be executed by workpeople, be knowingly and willingly places the platform on which the interests of the workpeople are to be found. Hence it is his duty so to regulate the contract that that platform may be safe and sound, and may not bring all to ruin. This the Commune can do by means of social clauses in contracts of “ farming.” Let the Commune include in the contract such conditions that the “ farmer,” in the treatment of the workpeople, cannot violate. Let the wages, the time-table, and the amount of rest be justly arranged. 8 Next come workpeople of the third position, towards whom the Commune has the function of a beneficent guardianship, by the very fact that they are affiliated to it. This function, we must admit, is complex enough; nor can it easily be explained in a short space. We will, however, touch upon its chief points. Above all, the eye of the Commune, in providing for the general good, ought to fix its care and attention on the weakest part. The Commune can very well give, and therefore ought to give, much assistance to those institutions whose scope is to improve the condition of workpeople, to prevent them from being wronged, to enable them to defend themselves. When these are not of a character injurious to individuals or to society, they are to be aided by the Commune. For other tasks with regard to the working classes, it is proper that the Commune should appoint men to conduct a Labour Office or Employment Bureau. This is an institution which at the present day ought to be the creation of communal authority, and ought to have for its scope to take part in all the affairs that, either alone or in conjunction with capital, engage the attention of the working classes of the place. 9 Themes. —Where the establishment of elementary schools by the State takes away every authority and function from Communes, it ought to be opposed—At the communal elections, let candidates of different occupations be chosen, thus realising, as far as possible at the present day, a professional representation—The advantages and the dangers of municipalism. CHAPTER A. THE STATE AND ITS DUTIES. Section I.— Union of Communes. In our work of analysing the organisms that compose the social body, proceeding as usual from the less to the more complex, we have observed a real natural hierarchy of bodies, of which the 52 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE higher find a reason for their existence in the aspirations as well as in the weaknesses of the lower. The Commune is a powerful factor for the wellbeing of families, and consequently of individuals. Yet the force of a commune is not so great that it cannot increase by union, and thus produce a greater amount of well¬ being. And hence we have a union of Communes. Grouped together, they form a more ample society—individuals, families, communes, and other moral bodies—subordinated for the good of all. This society has every facility possible for the attainment of its end. It is the State. Section II.— Origin and Nature of the State. All that we have said in the beginning on the sociability of man finds its full realisation in that civil, perfect, independent society which we call the State. Man cannot be quite happy on earth. But if God has granted him the use of goods here below, and clearly shown it to be His. will that these goods should be procured by means of social inter¬ course, it is evident that, when a people becomes a State, in which the rights of individuals and families are safeguarded, the common wellbeing procured and promoted, it has attained to the temporal designs of God over mankind. Neither domestic nor communal society rules a people to such a degree. These associations have a peculiar determinate end of their own. Within the circuit of a society more vast, and therefore more powerful, man can find his perfection, already begun by means of the family and the commune. One only State, embracing all the human race, might seem to be the design of God. And this was indeed a dream of some conquerors, who, carried away by an unbridled ambition, thought that the Lord God had created the human race in order to give it into their power for amusement. Some socialists too, who walk with their heads in the clouds, have had the same dream. But whoever considers how impossible is such a State—how there could be no civilisation, or prosperity, or wellbeing in it—will easily conclude that it is the will of God for the human race to continue and to flourish in perfection by means of various parti¬ cular societies, each one of them autonomous and independent,, each one of them a State in itself. The origin of the State therefore we must find in the nature of man. This nature, studied, teaches us that man has not only wants, which alone he cannot satisfy, but also duties, which bind him to his kind, or to something universal, to constitute and perfect which God calls him. Hence it is easy for us to form a just idea of what the State is. ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE STATE 53 It is an institution that, by the will of God, exists among men for their good. The State therefore, like everything else coming under the will of God, has an end assigned to it by Him, and hence it has rights and duties, the violation of which is a fault before God. For the most part those who, in their doctrines, have regarded man as separated from God cannot assign to the State that origin which we have assigned to it; the}?- cannot conceive it as we con¬ ceive it; and, according to the evils that they daily meet and wish to remedy, they pantheistically make a God or stoically a mechanism for them. But they forget that their head is not the same thing as logic, and that it is from the latter and not from the former that humanity takes its rule—humanity, too much inclined to the satisfaction of self. What, in point of fact, is the notion held to-day of the State ? That it is nothing but an agglomeration of individuals, who are united for the sake of advantage. This arises from a materialistic idea of man. And thus the individual is the only reason for the existence of the State; and thus the State can have no other duties than those which individuals give it! We say no. We recognise an organism, which is more than a mere assembly or aggregation. It is formed by individuals, and for their good; but it is not simply by their will. The will that obliges them to form it is superior to theirs. In short, between the State as conceived by the liberals and that as conceived by us, there is the same difference as between the members of a body in a group and the body itself. While the members are in each, everyone can see that in the latter case they are marked by an organic unity that is wanting in the former. Ten panes of glass may cover a certain space, but they will not have the same value as one large pane. Let us hear Weiss on this matter :—“ Every State has, as a finite whole, to fulfil a particular destiny. This is what justifies it. This is the mainspring of all its activity, the source of its public law, its vital principle, the foundation of its truth. This axiom of the essential unity of the State is of such importance that perhaps there cannot be any greater.” For us therefore the State is as a person who has his own existence, his own end, his own rights, his own duties. A. creation of God, the State is not God. For the State, as well as for individuals, God is the source of rights and duties. Nothing therefore more absurd than the State-olatry of some politicians, who wish the State to be a law and a rule for itself, and who recognise a law as just, holy, and binding, simply because it has been prepared by the State. There were some who, wishing to gild the idol, broke it in pieces. God and the creature are two contradictory terms; brought near, they destroy each other. A God State—for him who knows how to reason—is no State. 54 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE Section III.— End and Duties of the State. The State therefore, consisting of men, is not a human, but a natural institution. Nature, in favour of the State, spoke clearly enough by the voice of the wants of man, and of his progressive tendencies, which only in the State can find satisfaction. From the nature and origin of the State, we know what ought naturally to be its end. Formed as a consequence of human requirements, the State can have no other end than to satisfy them—to satisfy them in due relation to the last end of man, to satisfy them by making account of an active autonomy in individuals, to satisfy them in the measure dictated by equity and by the possibility of human things. If then man is, as we have said above, destined for a supernatural end, will it be a task of the State to lead man to this end ? No; it would be to require an effect greater than the cause. The State, being a natural institution, provided only with natural means, it cannot be so unnaturalised as to conduct man directly to a supernatural end. God thought of this when forming the Church, a supernatural society, and furnished it with the means necessary for such a purpose. Nevertheless, the State can and should concur indirectly, because, having to procure real good for men, and this being that alone which not only does not hinder, but facilitates the attainment of the last end, it ought to take its rule and measure from this end in the development of its activity. What therefore is the end of the State ? The common good of all the citizens. Leo XIII. has told us, to provide for the common good is the business of the State. (Rerum novarum.) These things we say, remembering what has been already said. We have elsewhere reasoned sufficiently, it seems to us, on the end of civil society—on the goods that the citizens have a natural right to expect from it. Now, the State is civil society in act ; and the end that it ought to set before it is that for which civil association, existing in the form of a State, is destined by nature. The duties of the State may therefore be summed up:—(i.) To use all means necessary for defending those bodies of which it is composed, as well in their real as in their potential personality— as well in the goods that they possess as in the exercise of their just rights, natural or acquired, (ii.) To promote the wellbeing of those bodies, either by facilitating for them the accomplishment of works that they initiate, or by giving completion to great undertakings, which, precisely on account of their greatness, cannot be effected by inferior bodies. DUTIES OF THE STATE TOWARDS CITIZENS 55 Section IV.— Duties of the State towards the Citizens. In the great world of the State, where the crowd makes a fuss, money rattles, and glory dazzles, it is very easy to lose sight of the human being, the smallest of the organisms of which the State consists. Yet this small being is the foundation of the hierarchy of human organisms, because—let us not forget—it is for the wel¬ fare of the individual that nature has appointed the Family, the Commune, and the State. The duty of the State towards the individual has been too much neglected, and has even been denied. But we have said, and we repeat it: every man, because a man, has a right to appear before the social body, or the State, and to demand of it his share in the social good. And if the individual has such a right, the State has naturally some duties towards him. What are they ? The first duty is that of respect for his personality. Man, as we know, is a centre of free movements or actions. This freedom drives man to the apogee of created life, because it constitutes him in a special manner the principle of his acts. If man is free in society to set forth his reasons, to develop his personality, this means that he enjoys civil liberty in the State. And this liberty the State should respect in every citizen. But here a question arises. Is civil liberty of the same extent as natural liberty ? Or can a man do by civil right all that he can do by natural right ? Speaking in the concrete, yes; because, in a strictly natural sense—that is, according to the design of nature—he can only do that which he can do lawfully, or he can only do that which can be reconciled with the State in which nature has disposed that he should five. But, speaking in the abstract, certainly no. Man has a right to use his natural liberty within the limits marked for him by the respect that he owes to the rights of his brethren and of all civil society. The State has a right to enter into the field of those actions which are free to the individual, and to prevent those which conflict with the right of the neighbour or are opposed to the common good ; his other actions, it is its duty to respect and to cause others to respect. This is called the security of civil liberty for the citizens. The individual is like a young tree, which has a right to throw out its branches to the atmosphere of the world : only when they invade the space belonging to another, the State has a right to lop them off. Not only so; but the State has a duty to prevent others from checking by any abuse the free growth of an individual. In defence of the individual right, it is not well that the individual himself should rise up, either because there is danger of hallucina- 56 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE tion in His own cause, or because lie would often be unequal to the task. Who therefore, if not the State, should guard the individual right ? Leo XIII. frankly declares : “ Rights are to be religiously protected wherever they exist; and the public authority, preventing or punishing any violation of them, should secure every one in the possession of his own.” (Rerum novarum.) Hence we infer that it is a duty of the State to form a just conception of the full rights of the human individual, with a view to guard and defend them. Here we find a reason for the conduct that the State ought to observe with regard to morals and religion. We know well that these do not form a proper object for the interference of the State; but for two reasons we maintain that it ought to help them to flourish, and to defend them from outrage. The first reason is that moral and religious, no less than physical, matters are the interests of individuals; for the defence of which all the arguments already set forth hold good. The second is that even those goods which are the direct object of the State are connected with the fate of morals and religion. We will give a third reason, which is the strongest of all. The State is for man, not man for the State. And man ought to be considered and treated according to what he is—that is to say, a creature whom, as we showed in its place, God has destined to lay up stores of merit here for a happy eternity hereafter. This ought not to be forgotten by the State, because it is one of the rights of man; and the State cannot change or destroy that which belongs inviolably to human nature. The State is the servant, not the master, of mankind. It will be useful to confirm this point by some words of the Pope. Leo XIII., after proving the duty of the State to be moral and religious, adds :—“ And this they ( Princes) owe to their subjects. Because all we who breathe are born and destined for that supreme and last good towards which our thoughts ought to be continually turned, that good which is to be found in Heaven after this short and fleeting life. Now, the full and perfect happiness of man depending on the possession of this good, it follows that the attainment of the said end is a matter of such great importance for every one that no greater can be imagined. It is necessary therefore that civil society, intended for the common good, should promote the public prosperity in such a manner that the citizens, while on their way to the acquisition of that supreme and un¬ changeable good which they desire, may not only find no obstacle set before them, but may find every facility provided for their advance. And the chief of all is that due reverence should be shown towards religion, the duties of which make the bond between God and man.” (Encyc. Immortale Dei.) Of these things the State ought to make account in granting or refusing liberty of the Press, of speech, of action. The Pope says :—“ Evil and error cannot have a right to be set forth or DUTIES OF THE STATE TOWARDS CITIZENS 57 propagated. . . . The State is false to the laws prescribed by nature, when, every bridle being removed, full power is left to evil and error to upset minds and to corrupt hearts.” It is not from itself that the State should take a rule for thus controlling the liberty of the citizens, but from that authority which is competent to judge of truth and error, of virtue and vice, of liberty and licence. The State ought also to give its valuable aid to those under¬ takings which, privately initiated, will, when completed, turn to general advantage, moral as well as material. Not only so, but it ought also itself to initiate and complete, within the limits of its power, such things as may tend to the common prosperity and convenience. Father Biederlack observes here very sensibly :— “ This does not mean that it is a duty of the State to take care that every citizen is materially happy; but it ought always to apply itself in such a manner as to enable all the citizens most easily to procure for themselves, by their own activity, those material and intellectual goods which are connected with, temporal well¬ being. Traffic and commerce ought to be facilitated ; agriculture, trades, arts ought to be promoted according to circumstances; schools ought to be opened, in which pupils may have every means of acquiring the knowledge suitable and useful for their condition.” (Introduzione alio Studio della Questione Sociale, p. 136.) Well said. Let us keep in mind the sufficient reason for the existence of the State, which rests entirely on an insufficiency of power in inferior organisms. But when this power is present, the State cannot interfere, setting it aside or substituting a different power. There is another liberty that the State is bound, not always, but in certain circumstances, to respect in citizens, and that is political liberty. Such is the name given to a direct or indirect participation of the citizen in the government. Observe. As for us, any form of government suffices : what chiefly concerns us is that it should be guided by justice. But thereby it is also certain that it can be legitimate, and may grant to the people some participation in the sovereignty, either direct, as in a pure democracy, or indirect, as in a representative government. Hear the Pope :—“ A participation, more or less great, of the citizens in the management of public affairs is not condemned. This participation, in given circumstances and with certain conditions, may be not only a service but a duty.” Admitting therefore the existence of a government more or less democratic, it is bound to respect the political liberty of its subjects. Let the government make a due selection. Let it exclude minors, malefactors, &c. ; but when a man is a man, and conducts himself like a man, let it give him a vote. Are we therefore advocates of universal suffrage ? In theory—yes : it follows from what we have said. In prac¬ tice—we distinguish. We are advocates for it in a state of 58 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE organised society, with, professional representation, because this frees the electors from the seductive influence of human passions. We are not advocates for it in a state of disorganised society, with elections carried by majorities. And this, not on account of defect in that system by itself, but because it is too often accom¬ panied with the wrangling of an excited mob and the venal abuse of a sacred right. And here we think that we may borrow half a page from Eossignoli, who shows how universality of suffrage is to be understood. “ Universal, admitting to the suffrage, as in the Italian Com¬ munes of the middle ages, all heads actual and virtual of families, domiciled in the municipal territory, and including, as now in Canada, widows and marriageable young women. For the exclusion of widows and marriageable young women has no reason when precautions are taken (among these, that the vote need not be given personally) to guard feminine modesty and reserve. On the other hand, the exclusion of this element, so tenaciously conservative, can only help disorderly factions. And much less reason is there for excluding the poor and illiterate. To exclude the poor altogether would be to justify those writers who regard civil society as a company of proprietors, as if Vce soli was said only to proprietors, or as if he who owns nothing but the labour of his hands and his brains is not, as well as others, destined by nature to live in society. And as for the illiterate, why should they be excluded from a vote, unless it is supposed (with what reason does not appear) that the good sense necessary for a citizen in order to call to the government of his Commune those men whom he sees most worthy around him is a fruit derived solely from a study of the alphabet and an examination of the franchise ? ” (Concetto dell ’ Autoritd Politica, p. 180.) Let us make another quotation. It is from the Pope, and regards the exercise of political liberty :—“ Generally speaking, a total abstention from political life would be no less blamable than a refusal to do anything for the common good, especially as Catholics are bound, by reason of their principles, to bring integrity and zeal to the management of affairs.” (Encyc. Immortale Lei.) With a view to this participation of the people in the exercise of sovereign power, Christian Democracy recommends two institutions, of which we shall speak briefly. Professional Representation* —The first is that of professional representation. The representative methods of the present day, formed by means of absolute majorities, have come, in point of fact, to be eminently despotic. They who practise this despotism are the official A., the absentee B., and often the millionaire C. The people indeed give their vote, and give it freely; but what * The reader will observe that the word “ professional ” is here used in its widest sense, including every kind of trade, business, occupation, by which man earns an honest livelihood. See also note 4, p. 87.— Trans. DUTIES OF THE STATE TOWARDS CITIZENS 59 community of interests lias the candidate with the electors to give them any confidence that he will take care of them ? The social pyramid has its steps in the various classes to which the people belong. If a man is taken indifferently from any class, what relations has he with the others, or how can he be their representative ? A stranger to them, it is with difficulty he knows their wants. Not having the same interests, oftener being in antagonism with their interests, he is no way solicitous for them, or he dexterously joins in governing them with such artifice as to throw dust in their eyes and—turn all to his own advantage. The system of professional representation means that the representation of the people should be real, not illusory. It proposes that every class should of necessity have its representative on the boards of public bodies. Let him be taken from the midst of his class. He will then be able for his work. He will feel the wants of his class, which are also his own ; and he will know how to guard, to defend, and to promote its interests. This reform of the elective system is evidently linked with professional organisa¬ tion, to which we ought to bring back society. So long as the present disorganised state continues, Catholics adopt proportional representation as a substitute. Instead of the professional classes, w*e have the different parties that agitate for their rights. Give to each party one or more representatives, according to its numerical power, and you have proportional representation. The Referendum. —This is the second institution to which we refer. It is that of Catholics and others who hold sane modern views. The Referendum consists in this, that those who are chosen to represent the people in the councils of the nation should, in certain grave cases, consult the electoral body before deliberat¬ ing among themselves. It is like a restriction of confidence, a limitation of command, that the electors make in regard to those wffiom they have elected. From the definition it appears :— i. That the scope of the Referendum is not to substitute the people for the directing bodies, nor yet to hold these latter con¬ tinually bound hand and foot, but only, in extraordinary cases, to treat with them about matters of great importance and much interest for the people. ii. That the Referendum is political or administrative, according as the appeal to the people is made by the State or by local administrations. iii. That it can be consultative, if it has only the power to give information and counsel to the directing bodies, in whom there is authority to make no account thereof; and it can be deliberative, if it has power to settle or to postpone a matter of business. Is the Referendum just ? Whoever denies it, should prove that it offends the rights of some one. Of whom ? Is it of the legislator ? But he himself appeals to it, because his responsibility is divisible, and can be shared by the people. 60 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE Is it useful ? We have no doubt of it. First of all we recognise in the people a store of valuable quali¬ ties : sound sense, honesty, generosity, fear of God—blessings that are not always met in such abundance higher up. To call so many fine energies into action is certainly an excellent work. For another reason we regard it as good. The representatives of the people, chosen according to the present system of majorities, are too often the representatives of themselves, or of a party, or of a sect. Such representatives of the people easily attend to every¬ thing but the real interests of the people. The Referendum, is a very efficacious check on the excessive powers of the oligarchy; it is a salutary corrective amid the abuses of the present system. In the Congress of Social Science held at Padua in 1896, Pro¬ fessor Rossi, supported by the wise remarks of Toniolo, expressed himself in favour of a Communal Referendum ,. 10 We shall insist on the ideas of Professor Rossi, and say that if the Communal Referendum had been instituted years ago, many Communes would not to-day be found financially in low condition, because the people would not have been so easily induced to waste their money on foolish expenses. And as for morals, who does not know that the people would not have secularised the schools and hospitals, nor created embarrassments about any manifesta¬ tion of worship ? Nevertheless, we do not admit the Referendum unconditionally. We recognise that the Referendum ought not to be blind, that it supposes in the people sufficient knowledge to judge, and that proper precautions ought to be taken to ascertain the will of the people. For the rest, we Catholics are not the only people who desire the Referendum. It not unfrequently happens that we find ourselves among men of the most opposite parties, not excluding some of the socialists themselves. It seems to us that true democracy requires the Referendum. In what does this democracy consist ? “ In letting all classes share proportionally in public life and enjoy it, without being absorbed or outdone by others, or by a supreme centralising power.’ 5 Just the contrary of what occurs at present. To-day the lower classes are treated as senseless beings, mere matter, at most as good material for the pedestal of somebody’s ambition. This is a state of things condemned by the Pontiff. “ The proletariat,” he says, “ neither more nor less than the rich, are citizens by natural right, true and living members, forming, by means of the family, the social body—not to say that they are the greater number.” But all has not yet been said. Among the multitude of citizens there is one class that—by a necessity of nature—is the most weak, the most exposed therefore to the ill-treatment of those who feel themselves the strongest, and it is the class of those who DUTIES OF THE STATE TOWARDS CITIZENS 61 earn a living by the labour of their hands. For this class the State ought to have a special care and regard. And this for the simple reason, often given, that as society ought to be a state of common wellbeing, it ought to exert itself more where the need is greater. What action the government ought to take in this matter, we shall have occasion to consider elsewhere. Here it will suffice to lay down the principle, and to confirm it with the words of the Pope. “ In making account of private persons, a special regard is to be had for the weak and the poor. The multi¬ tude of tfie rich have perhaps of themselves less need of public defence; the miserable people, in want of support, have the utmost need of finding themselves under the patronage of the State. And therefore the working classes, who are in the number of the weak and needy, require the special care and protection, of the State.” The greatest equity ought to be observed in dispensing to the citizens the fruits of social life, winch is done by observing distri¬ butive justice. The Holy Father says :—“ It should never happen that the civil authority serves only one or a few, it being established for the common good of all.” We should form a clear idea of distributive justice, and we shall do so by taking St. Thomas as our guide. He treats of it at great length in his Summa of Theology (2a 2ge, q. LXI.). The word distributive intimates to us that there is question of dispensing something. But dispensing what ? St. Thomas informs us that the things to be dispensed or distributed are common things. Objects are called common when many have a right to them. To all therefore distribution ought to be made. By what title ? St. Thomas says :— ££ As a part and the whole are in some manner the same thing, so that which is of the whole is in some manner of the part; and thus, when of common goods anything is distributed to individuals, every one in some manner receives what is his own.” Observe the repetition of the words “ in some manner,” which St. Thomas could on no account omit. Farther down he gives the reason :— ££ It must be said that distributive and commutative justice are distinguished not only according to one and many,* but according to the different nature of the debt Because that which is common is due to anv one in quite a different manner from that which is his own.” To that which is common the individual has a right, but not yet a definite concrete right, as he has to that which is properly his own. To that which is common the individual has a certain * Distributive justice is generally said to be that which directs the community or the government in giving honours, offices, or emoluments to each particular member of the community, and commutative justice that which regulates the dealings of one private individual with another. Thus, commutative justice would have reference to one person (or a number of persons morally equivalent to one); distributive, to many.— Trans. 62 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE right not to be questioned, but not determined in substance and measure, and to be determined by a suitable criterion. We said above that every man in the social body has his space, resulting from reality and potentiality, alongside the spaces of his brethren living with him. That one space should respect another is commutative justice. But individuals have before them a greater organism, which, though formed from them, exists by itself. Towards this they have duties and rights. They have duties, which we have examined under the term 44 social.” They have rights : they have a right that the great organism, society, should give them a share in that wellbeing to procure which it exists, and which, being in some manner the property of all, is called common. To place this distribution in the hands of him who commands, the Angelic Doctor says :— <£ The act of distribution, which is of common goods, belongs only to him who presides over the common goods.” And this not at all in an arbitrary manner, or with partiality, but with proportion. With what proportion ? Is it with proportion to how much the individual has contributed to the common good ? But that would suppose society to be a body separated from men rather than consisting of men—a body in which they would make a financial speculation, disposed to remain with it as long as it repaid them in good measure, ready to quit it if it ceased to offer any advantage. That w T e know is not the proportion. Man finding himself in society with a view to his relative wellbeing, subordinated to the attainment of his last end, the proportion will be in accordance with the position that each individual occupies. St. Thomas teaches that, in distributive justice, the quota ought to be proportioned not according to the thing but accord¬ ing to the person. “ In distributive justice,” he says (q. lxi.), “ the mean is not taken according to the equality of one thing to another, but according to the proportion of things to persons, so that as one person exceeds another, the thing which is given to one person may exceed that which is given to another.” Hence account is to be made of the social position that the individual occupies, and therefore of the need or weakness in which he finds himself; and aid is to be given him in proportion. Individual concurrence is the foundation of this right; and whoever culpably fails therein is justly deprived of it. It is according to these rules that the State is to conduct itself towards its subjects, when it calls upon them to contribute, either personally or really, to the common wellbeing ; when it dispenses among them the benefits of social life, howsoever the occasion may occur ; and when it makes use of their aid for the true progress of society. In this salutary theory we discover the foundation of that social legislation which is regarded by liberal theorists as an absurdity, but which is called for by Christian principles, as well DUTIES OF THE STATE TOWARDS ITSELF 63 as by the sad experience that States without it have gone through. Belgium, where the principles of Christian polity have been applied by the Government, has made wise social provision for the future, which some other States are gradually, but too slowly, imitating. Section V.—Duties of the State towards Itself. There is a difference between the citizens and the body of the citizens. The latter has rights and duties; the former have rights with duties. The social body, or State, ought to have such an existence that it may derive therefrom all that wellbeing which the citizens have a right to expect. The State has, there¬ fore, a right to be, and to maintain itself in being. The existence of a State implies a logical process in its history, woven from the reasons of its existence. When neither fraud nor falsehood takes part in it, there are always lawful exigencies of the common welfare that prepare the way for the formation of a State : sometimes these exigencies are not wanting, even though bad and condemnable practices are employed. Such a State has a right to its own preservation, a right that for the good of all is a strict duty. Enemies, internal as well as external, may strive to do injury to a State. From both it ought to defend itself. But here let us be well understood. A State preserves itself not by force of arms, not by iron gates, which effect a compulsory aggregation; but by so acting that men may find in society those advantages which they have a right to promise themselves. This is the way to keep alive and active in them a consciousness of social duties, which we have said is the life of a State. Thus tumults, seditions, rebellions will be avoided. If the flame should • burst out in any turbulent mind, it will not find nourishment, or it will easily be stifled. And thus internal enemies, almost before they are born, will be vanquished. Let the State do its duty, let the State be what it ought to be, and its scope will be attained. There will then be tranquillity, there will then be peace, of which we hear so much talk; yet few consider that substantially it consists in the morality of the citizens and their good standing. “ Those who rule ought to defend society, because nature entrusted this care to the supreme power in such a manner that the public weal is not only the first law, but the sole and whole reason for the existence of a government.” (Rerum novarum.) Independence or autonomy follows from existence. If a State exists lawfully, it has lawfully a right to act, to govern, to regulate its affairs, without being hindered by any other State. This is called the right of nationality, which, in the sense explained by us, has not only not been condemned, but has been taught, and for a long time, by Catholics. 64 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE We said, however, “in the sense explained by us.” Because there is a right of nationality which is properly called modern, and on which the declarations of Catholics are not unanimous. That we may not be misunderstood, it is well to explain here the two senses in which the word “ nation ” may be taken. In the first sense, a nation is a multitude of people having the same laws, under the same sovereign power, which in a certain manner holds in its hands the energies and collects the aspirations of the people scattered over a greater or less extent of territory. Here the nation is equivalent to the State. The right of nationality or independence we have not only not denied to it, but we have purposely defended that right. The word “ nation ” is also taken in an ethnical sense, more conformable to its derivation. It then means a multitude of people, who have natural] y such a sameness of character, of inclination, of language, of soil, that they may well be said to be placed on the same basis or platform. In this sense it will be understood how a nation can be, at least in fact, divided into several States, as also how a State can embrace several nations. Now’ comes a question : has every nation a right to indepen¬ dence or nationality ? That is, have people who are so like in all respects as to be considered a nation, a right to form them¬ selves into an autonomous independent State ? On this right, Catholics are not agreed. Rossignoli argues that it would certainly be desirable, on account of the great advantages that would follow from it, to have every nation a State. He then continues :—“ Until now r we have been with nationalists, with federalists, with advocates of the universal pacification of peoples. But may not the thesis be pushed, as it has been pushed here in Italy by Mamiami, Mancini, and others, so far as to maintain that in a people of a certain race, who live politically in virtue of old historical facts, lawful or unlawful, with another people of a different nationality (Piedmont, for example, politically united to Savoy), there remains a right of secession, if they wish for such ? Let us suppose that Corsica would wish to bid farewell to-morrow without more ado to the French Republic, and the Flemish provinces to Belgium, and Aosta to Italy, and Cyprus and Gibraltar and Malta to England : would they have a right to do so ? And if one of the three ethnical nations that form one nation in the Swiss Republic wished to renew a Sonderbund , separating capriciously from the other two, would these latter quietly tolerate the partition as lawful ? Evidently this new right would not be pleasing to France, or Belgium, or Switzerland, or at present to Italy, which in its time profited so much by it; not only because national self-love would not find its advantage therein, but also because a sufficient reason to justify these lacerations does not DUTIES OF THE STATE TOWARDS FAMILIES 65 appear and cannot be found. We must except the case in which the Government acts the part of a tyrant towards some of the people subject to it, as happens, for example, at the present day, with the Cretes and Armenians, both groaning under the fierce and ignoble yoke of the seraglio of Constantinople. “ An ethnical nation is not a mere geographical expression; still it is not by itself a juridical expression, nor does it denote a moral person. The ethnical nation is virtually, but not actually, a civil society; and, therefore, it cannot boast of a true right to independence, supposing that past historical facts have lawfully united this people to another of a different race in one political body. Such, for example, would be the Austrian Empire, in which, though somewhat uncomfortably, Germans, Sclavs, Magyars, Rumanians, and Italians live together.” {La Liberia Politica, p. 18.) Against this view, Cathrein lays down an absolute proposition, in language as gay as a triumphal march. Professor Ferrari, in a style no less jubilant, opposes both of them thus :—“ Does there exist a right of nationality, or has each nation a natural right to constitute itself a united and independent State ? I believe so; and this right, as D’Azeglio observes (Miei Ricordi, c. iii.), appears to me a logical deduction from the Christian idea, which, granting natural rights to every individual, inasmuch as he is a man, should of its own tendency lead to a recognition of the same rights in nations. . . . The right of nationality therefore appears to me unquestionable; every people has an incontestable right to choose that sovereign and that form of government which will best correspond to its needs and promote its interests. . . . Now, nothing is more capable of understanding or promoting its interests than an autonomous government of its own, with united strength. There¬ fore, every nation has a right to independence and unity.” {II Popolo , &c., 301-2.) It is a duty to act in such a manner that the spirit of Christian Democracy may spread throughout the social body. We have not defined what ought to be the form of government. We do not say what arrangements or laws are necessary for a proper social settlement. But we say that it is a duty that the people should be governed in such a manner that the common wellbeing may be promoted, with a preference of aid for the lower classes. This follows from what we have said regarding the nature of civilisation and of Christian Democracy. Section VI.— Duties of the State towards Families. The State has under it some organisms that it cannot absolutely destroy. They have a fife anterior to its life, and this life they E 66 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE derive from another source. Among these are Families, It is the duty of the State to respect their autonomy, their rights, and their independence of action; moreover, to facilitate prosperity for them. Hence :— 1. It is absolutely forbidden to the State to change the condi¬ tions of the formation of the Family. A work of nature, it ought to remain such. The State can and should regulate or moderate the consequences of matrimony for the good of all; but should accept it from nature, which instituted it, and not pretend to create or modify it. 2. The State ought to guard the free exercise of the authority of parents, who are the natural legislators of the Family. The Pope observes :—“ A Family, no less than a State, is, as we have said, a true society, governed by a power of its own, which is the paternal power. Within the limits determined by its end, the Family has therefore at least equal rights with civil society in the choice and use of the means necessary for its preservation and its just liberty. We have said, at least equal rights; for since domestic society is prior in idea and in fact to civil, it ought like¬ wise to have rights and duties prior and more natural. If the citizens, if families, having entered into the association of civil society, found hindrance instead of help, a diminution instead of a protection of their rights by the commonwealth, such association would be repudiated rather than desired.” (Rerum novarum.) To educate children, to instruct them, is therefore a task of parents. Let the State provide schools and masters that Families w'ould not be able to provide, but for the development and completion of the educational work begun at home, a work that is not to be destroyed. “ The paternal authority is of such a nature that it cannot be abolished or absorbed by the State; for it comes from the same source as human life itself.” (Ibid.) 3. The State ought to look to the stability, unity, and prosperity of Families : this, besides promoting the interests of the individual, likewise promotes those of society. And as it is very important that the Family should hold some family property, the State should facilitate the acquirement of it, and endeavour by oppor¬ tune measures to prevent the waste or ruin of it. 4. Even in functions that properly belong to the Family, the State can interfere for the good of individuals, but only in excep¬ tional cases, when the efforts of the Family fail. “ Certainly, if a Family finds itself reduced to such great distress that it cannot possibly of itself rise therefrom, it is right that extreme necessity should be relieved by public aid ; for each Family is a part of the social body. In like manner if anywhere a grave disturbance of mutual rights occurs within the domestic walls, let the State interfere, and give every one his due. This is not to usurp the rights of citizens, but to safeguard and strengthen them according to the laws of justice.” (Ibid.) DUTIES OF THE STATE TOWARDS THE CHURCH 67 Section VII.— Duties of the State towards Communes. The autonomy of existence and action that we defended against the usurpations of the State for the Individual and the Family, we here defend for the Communes, keeping to the rule that the existence of a body corresponds to its end, and from the end the rights of action are to be determined. Above all, therefore, the State has a duty of respect towards the Communes, whose functions it should not, by an unnatural concentration, usurp. Nor should it permit other bodies to obstruct their development or to do them violence. In saying so, we do not intend to maintain that the State has no office of supervision or direction of the functions of the Com¬ munes—as if, by reason of respect for their autonomy, we main¬ tained that they might lawfully and at pleasure abuse their powers. Certainly not. We say that the interference of the State in communal affairs ought to be limited, like positive action, by the duty that the State has to co-ordinate the functions of inferior organisms to the attainment of the common good, which is the scope of civil society.* Section VIII.— Duties of the State towards the Church. Whether it pleases you or not, ye liberals and socialists, the existence of the Church is an historical fact; and you may see it towering aloft before you, unshaken and indestructible, laden with crowns, resplendent with the tokens of its victories. A society that * A book that has been highly recommended for Irishmen, especially Catholics, who desire to have an intelligent view of the exercise of State authority in Ireland, is Dublin Castle and the Irish People, by Mr. R. Barry O’Brien. It shows the character of the chief officials and the working of the various boards and departments in the Castle during many generations. There is no want of facts or figures, some of which appear almost in¬ credible. Who, for example, would suppose that the civil government of Ireland costs £1 8s. per head of the population every year ? Belgium, with four times the trade of Ireland and a much larger population, is governed at about half this expense. It is hard for a country to prosper when it is overburdened with charges. From the General Report of the Royal Commission (1894) on the Financial Relations between Great Britain and Ireland, signed by eleven of the thirteen members, we learn that Ireland was then taxed beyond her fair share to the extent of about three million pounds annually. Yet this great injustice still continues unremedied. Nay, the annual expenditure is now two millions more than it was at that time. It does not serve much for the honour of England to be spoken of by the President of the United States, Mr. William Taft (in a speech on St. Patrick’s Day, 1909) as follows :—“ The history of Ireland from the time of the English Invasion to Catholic Emancipation is a record of misgovern- ment, intolerance, selfish exploitation, and confiscation on the one hand, and of misery and squalor on the other.” Many persons in the United Kingdom are unaware of the causes of dis¬ content in Ireland, and therefore it is useful to mention where they may find some information on the subject.— Trans. 68 THE ELEMENTS OE SOCIAL SCIENCE has its peculiar end, more universal than that of the State, the Church has also special means for the attainment of that end—its own hierarchy, its own existence. With the State it has the same subject, man, on whom its action and authority fall. The scope of the State is to facilitate for man the attainment of wellbeing here on earth ; that of the Church is to lead him to eternal happiness in heaven, by a due subordination of the present life to the future. The two tasks, far from being opposed, help and complete each other, giving a large field for the action of Church and State. To prevent any encroachment of one on the sphere of the other* their mutual relations must be kept well before the mind. We cannot better point them out than by having recourse to Leo XIII. In his encyclical Immortale Dei he says :— “ Thus God divided the government of the human family between two powers—namely, the ecclesiastical and the civil— one for the superintendence of divine things, the other for that of human things. Both are supreme, each in its order. Each has certain limits within which it is contained, shown by its nature and its immediate purpose; each has a sphere within which it acts by its own right. But because the subject of both powers is one and the same, and it may happen that something, though for a different reason or under a different aspect, may belong to each jurisdiction, Divine Providence, the source of each, has fittingly arranged their course. And those (powers) that are , are ordained of God (Bom. xiii. 1). Were it not so, occasions of contest and conflict would often arise, and man would not seldom be obliged to remain in doubt, like a traveller at a place where the road parts into two roads, not knowing which to take—the two powers commanding contrary things and conscience not per¬ mitting disobedience. “ Now, this is repugnant in the highest degree imaginable to the wisdom and goodness of God, who, even in the physical order, which is so much inferior, directs natural forces and their laws so sweetly and harmoniously that none of them is a hindrance to others, and all conspire most happily to the final scope of the world. Therefore, between the two powers there should be a certain co-ordination, which indeed is not unreasonably compared to that by which soul and body are united in man. The character of the said relations cannot be better known than by considering, as we have said, the nature of each, and making account of the excellence and nobility of their respective ends, one being directly and chiefly intended for the care of temporal things, the other for the acquisition of supernatural and eternal goods. “ Whatever therefore in human things is sacred, whatever pertains to the salvation of souls or the worship of God, whether it is such by its own nature or by reason of the end to which it is referred, all that falls under the jurisdiction of the Church. But it is right that other things, which are of a civil and political nature, should be subject to the civil authority, Jesus Christ DUTIES OF THE STATE TOWARDS ASSOCIATIONS 69 having commanded that the things of Caesar should be rendered to Caesar and the things of God to God. Nevertheless, there are some occasions when another way of concord is opened up to secure the liberty of both—namely, when civil rulers and the Roman Pontiff enter into an agreement about some particular point. In these circumstances, the Church offers the most splendid proofs of her maternal goodness, doing all that she can in the work of conciliation and indulgence.” The encyclical Sapientice Christiance returns to the same ideas thus :— , “ The Church as well as the State has its own domain; and therefore in the administration of affairs neither of them obeys the other within certain limits, determined for each by its immediate end. Whence, however, it is not at all to be inferred that they ought to be disunited, much less hostile. “ And in truth man by his nature is not only a physical being, but also a moral being. Wherefore, from the tranquillity of public order, which is the proximate end of civil society, man seeks the means of promoting his temporal welfare and still more those of perfecting his moral qualities. ... At the same time he wishes, as is just, to find in the Church means adapted to his religious perfection. This perfection consists in the know¬ ledge and practice of the true religion, which, directing all the other moral virtues to God, completes and perfects them. There¬ fore, in framing laws and institutions, regard should be had to the moral and religious dispositions of man, and care taken for his perfection. Nor should anything be commanded or forbidden except with a view to the special end of each of the two societies, civil and religious. “ Accordingly, the Church cannot be indifferent about the laws of the State, not as such, but inasmuch as sometimes, passing beyond their due confines, they invade the rights of the Church. It is rather a duty of the Church, assigned to her by God, to resist, whenever civil law injures religion, and to recommend with all earnestness that the spirit of the Gospel legislation may inspire the laws and institutions of peoples. And because the progress of States depends very much on the character of rulers, the Church cannot show favour or support to those who, attacking her, openly mistake their rights, and endeavour to separate two things that are of their nature inseparable—namely, Religion and the State. On the other hand, she is favourable, as is just, to those who, having a proper idea of the State and of Christian Society, wish that both should work in harmony for the common good.” Section IX.— Duties of the State towards Private Associations. Besides the Family and the Commune, the State often finds within its borders some other associations, which men freely 70 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE institute for their material or moral improvement. The usefulness of these practical schools, as a means of more easily attaining a particular object, man has no need to learn from any master : nature itself teaches it to him. Hence religious, scientific, commercial, industrial, friendly societies; &c., are established by men. The right of founding such societies, man has received from nature. This principle requires to be well remembered by the State, which will find therein a proper and secure basis for its relations with them. Accordingly— 1. The State cannot prohibit or oppose the forming of associa¬ tions that have an honest scope. Only a false idea of an absolute State, the source of all rights and laws, can attribute to the State such a right. The Pope attaches the greatest importance to this point, saying:—“ Now although private societies exist in a State,, and are as it were so many parts of it, yet, speaking generally and absolutely, it is not in the power of the State to prevent them. Because the law of nature grants to man the right of joining in societies, and it is not the business of the State to destroy natural rights, but to defend them. If it forbids such associations, it contradicts itself ; for both it and they exist in virtue of the same principle—namely, that men are naturally inclined to associate.’* (Encyc. Rerum novarum.) By this thesis the right of preventing associations from being formed, or of dissolving them, if already formed, is certainly not denied in an absolute manner to the State. When anv of •/ these societies have as their scope, not the welfare, but the injury of other societies, to forbid or to suppress them is not so much a right as a duty. And this for the evident reason that a right cannot be had from nature to do what frustrates the end of nature. “ There are times, however, when it is proper that the law should prevent associations: as when men combine for a purpose evidently bad, unjust, or dangerous to the commonwealth. In such cases the public authority may justly prohibit associations, or dissolve them if formed.” But this right or duty the State has in favour of nature, if we may so speak, not to its prejudice ; and care must be taken not to go to excess. Above all, the State ought to have a just criterion regarding what is really good and what is not so, and beware of mistaking the defence of its own wellbeing for that of its subjects. u It is necessary, however, to proceed with the utmost caution, lest the rights of citizens should seem to be violated, and evil should be dqne under the pretence of public good. Because laws do not bind unless in so far as they are conformable to right reason, and therefore to the eternal law of God.” 2. It is also a duty of the State to facilitate the formation of societies, to defend their rights, and to respect their autonomy. “ Let the State defend these lawful associations of the citizens ; let it not meddle with their organisation or discipline, which is PERSONAL CONTRIBUTION 71 necessary for unity of action. If the citizens have a right, as they actually have, to join in societies, they have likewise an equal right to choose that kind of management which they judge most conducive to the end proposed.” (Ibid.) Themes.— The prosperity of a State is to be judged by that of the citizens—The injuries that a State often does to Individuals, Families, and Communes, as well as to private associations—Respect for the rights of inferior bodies was secured in a theocratic State—How philosophically false and socially disastrous is the theory that makes the State the source and origin of rights in various bodies—How the part that the State ought to take with 'regard to organisations within its borders may be generally defined—The chief means by which the State -can and should come to the aid of the working classes. CHAPTER YI. THE RIGHTS OF THE STATE. Section I.— Wellbeing oe the State. The State has duties, because it has an end to attain; therefore, it has also rights. This is an evident enthymeme, and is often repeated, like the burden of a song. In regard to whom are the rights ? In regard to those towards w T hom it has duties ; that is to say, its subjects or citizens. What is the source of these rights ? Nature; because from nature the State has command to attain its end. What is the extent of these rights ? As much as is necessary to give to citizenship the greatest possible wellbeing. But the wellbeing of the Individual and the Family is two-fold : domestic and social. The latter integrates, crowns, and perfects the former. Nor can it be said that the social exists, if the domes¬ tic does not also exist. It follows that the State, in demanding its rights, should impose the least possible sacrifice on Individuals and Families. To what contributions is the State entitled ? To two : one personal, the other real. Section II.— Personal Contribution. Without the work of man, nothing can be done. And the State requires that work should be done for it by those to whose advantage its functions tend. To quell seditions—to execute sentences, with a view to the maintenance of private rights and the promotion of the public weal—to defend itself from external aggression, men are necessary ; and men the people ought to give to the State. Hence, the army. It cannot be done without. Care should be taken to have it, and to have it with the least possible expense to 72 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE Families. There are various modes of enrolment, but that is certainly the best which (i.) makes account of the preservation of Families and their relative wellbeing; (ii.) which arranges that there will not, through too much regard for the army, be wanting men of energy and talent for other employments equally necessary to society ; and (iii.) does not withdraw too many hands from labour, for it must always be remembered that, in matters of tribute, necessity is the only lawful title, and that every soldier is a double weight on social finances—that is, through what he costs the treasury and through what he ceases to produce by labour. It may be added for the same reasons that a man ought not to be kept a longer time under arms than is indispensable to make him a soldier. From all this we see how unjustifiable and condemnable is that practice of the present day, too widely spread and accredited, which takes the name of militarism. Through the necessity of defence the army has become an institution in itself, having a reason for its existence in civil society. Therefore the desire to make it every day more powerful by land and sea. Therefore the fabulous sums thrown away on its equipment. We—most friendly towards an army, a force that acts in the hands of the executive power for the greatest good of all—are enemies of the present militarism, which exhausts our resources and is a cause of many private and public misfortunes. Section III.— Real Contribution. To procure the common wellbeing, money is indispensable. This ought to be supplied to the State by the subjects ; and the supply takes the name of imposts or tributes. On the lawfulness of them, we do not think that there is any need to spend words : it is evident. The quantity, however, is limited by social exigencies and by the capabilities of the citizens.* But by social exigencies we are * Speaking of taxation, Mr. O’Brien, in his book, Dublin Castle, quotes the following figures for the year ending the 31st March, 1907 :— Ireland’s gross contribution to Imperial Expenditure ... ... ... £9,490,000 Cost of Administration ... ... 7,678,500 Balance available for Imperial Expenditure £1,811,500 Scotland’s gross contribution to Imperial Expenditure ... ... ... £15,837,000 Cost of Administration ... ... 5,962,500 Balance available for Imperial Expenditure £9,874,500 He then makes a very just comparison. “ Contented Scotland,” he says, “ with a population of 4,472,103, contributes £15,837,000 to the REAL CONTRIBUTION 73 not to understand that fury with which some enthusiastic politi¬ cians are seized for raising theatres, monuments, and palaces, nor revenges taken by the government party, but those works which are required to give the people a comparatively easy life, and which turn in some manner to the benefit of all, rich and poor, high and low. Imposts and Taxes. —The gathering up of money, as arranged by the exchequer, happens in two ways. The subject is obliged to pay an annual contribution to the State ; and the subject who comes within certain conditions ought to pay it without more ado. This is the way of imposts. A subject who avails himself of a service that the State provides for the convenience of all, is obliged to pay a sum to the treasury for it. This is the way of taxes ; for example, the school tax and the postal tax. 11 Lawfulness of Taxes. —A question may be asked : is it just that the State should exact a tribute from those who use an institution Exchequer. Discontented Ireland, with a population of 4,458,775, con¬ tributes the gross sum of £9,490,000. The administration of Scotland, in accordance with the wishes of the Scottish people, and consistently with the prosperity of the country, costs £5,962,500. It costs £7,678,500 to keep Ireland poor and disaffected.” He enters into many details regarding the enormous expenditure of money in Ireland, not properly applied for the benefit of the country. Thus, the Lord Lieutenant receives £20,000 a year (household, fuel, and other charges raise the expense to £35,074), while the President of Switzerland (about half the size of Ireland, yet with a population over three millions) receives only £720. He concludes with some weighty words from Mr. Redmond. “ When Englishmen ask us what we want we answer in a sentence, A measure of legislative autonomy similar to that enjoyed by any of your self-governing Colonies or Dependencies. If you want an illustration look at Canada, look even at the Transvaal. The Transvaal is a new country, yet it enjoys legislative autonomy ; Ireland, a more ancient kingdom than England, does not.” What a telling fact that Australia, New Zealand, Canada, the Cape, the Transvaal, all have their own Parliaments ! None of the members sit in the English Parliament, nor have they any desire to do so. Mr. Sexton, who is deeply versed in finance, has shown that a fair taxation for Ireland after the Union would have been an average of £3,000,000 a year. But Ireland has been obliged since then to pay on an average £6,000,000 a year. At this rate, during the years from 1800 to 1894, she has been unjustly overtaxed to the extent of £282,000,000. How proper, therefore, would it be that England should now strive to make some repara¬ tion to Ireland for the crying wrongs of the past! Many of the English people are well disposed towards Ireland, but perhaps the greatest obstacle in the way of obtaining good laws is the House of Lords. It consists of men of property, who are determined to hold what they possess. In 1810 they refused to efface from the Statute-book a law that inflicted the penalty of death for stealing goods to the amount of five shillings. In 1893 they wrecked Mr. Gladstone’s Home Rule Bill, after it had passed triumphantly through the House of Commons. When will men understand that the peace, welfare, and happiness of the world can never be so well promoted by building “ dreadnoughts ” and inventing other frightful instruments of destruction as by practising the Christian virtues of justice and charity ? Have men no other laws to guide them but those of tigers and wolves ?— Trans . 74 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE established by it for the public ? In principle, we do not see how this can be denied. These institutions are necessary for society. The use is not therefore necessary for every individual; for some it is often superfluous, and even injurious. This is one of the cases in which there is a little friction between the good of society and private good. The system of taxes smooths matters. The government, out of the imposts received, provides institutions for society, consolidating it and giving it liberty : the individual who makes use of them, pays the tax. To supply for the tax by an impost would be to impose a sacrifice on all, and would be contrary to the principle that the individual contribution for the common wellbeing should be made with the least possible sacrifice. The system of taxes has certainly its inconveniences; but to avoid or to lessen them, moderation in taxation ought to be better than an abolition of the system. There are some institutions of which it is well that families make little use—let the tax be higher. There are others the use of which is generally required—let the tax be moderate. Always let the law make account of those who have not means, for whom the use of an institution may be necessary, and it may even be advantageous for the public. Let the tax be then lowered, or dispensed with altogether. Direct and Indirect Imposts. —An impost is called direct when it is required from persons on whom the sacrifice of disbursement really falls. It is called indirect when it is required from persons who are recouped by others : this happens when dealers have to buy at a higher rate from the manufacturers of certain merchandise, but really lay the burden on those who use it, to whose prejudice they indemnify themselves by selling at an increased price. We believe it well to observe at once that indirect taxes fall nearly always on the consumer, direct ones on the producer. As, therefore, the consumption of certain goods is necessary for all men, and that of others superfluous, the indirect tax generalised is of necessity grievous for the poor, to whom the loss of a few pence may be a serious injury, while it would not cause the rich a thought. The indirect impost is, therefore, of its nature antidemocratic. This characteristic requires to be corrected, by abolishing duty on those things which are strictly needed, such as salt, 12 or lowering it very much ; and, on the other hand, increasing it on things of luxury, which are not used from any need, but for the comfort of life. Fundamental Principles of a Just Tributary Law. —From the nature of the relations that exist between the social body and its component parts, the rules of tribute ought to be derived. We have shown it many times. Belations in society run in different directions : some go from the circumference to the centre, and are the contributions of individuals to the State ; others go REAL CONTRIBUTION 75 from the centre to the circumference, and are the benefits that society imparts to its members. The final result of all this activity is in favour of individuals. But this, not as the conse¬ quence of a contract well weighed and stipulated on a utilitarian basis, rather because such was an ordinance of nature, which desires the good of all by means of society, composed of all, and living by the aid of all. The idea often repeated is here again re-echoed—that society is a living body and men are its members. But in a living body the strong members are expected to act strongly ; the weak, weakly. There is, therefore, a solid principle that ought to stand as a foundation of the relations between the citizens and the social body. It may be enunciated thus : Every man, however much he lives for his own advantage, is bound, according to his condition, to live for the advantage of society. The social contribution is a withdrawal of efficiency from individual and domestic goods—just as in an animal body the function exercised by each of the members is a waste, more or less, of it. This must be taken into account. Hence another principle : The social contribution ought to be reckoned according to the sacrifice that it costs anyone to make it. Therefore, there are two coefficients of the social contribution— one objective, which regards the strength of position in life; the other subjective, which regards the sacrifice of private wellbeing. Together they give us the amount of the social contribution. Erom these principles we draw the practical rules of a just tribu¬ tary system :— 1. The impost ought to fall on the income, not on the capital. In good economy, the capital ought not to be exhausted. It does not count as an article of consumption. It is one of the chief fountains from which flow the streams of individual and social wellbeing. The word “ income ” is here taken in its widest sense—that is, embracing all the returns from movable and immovable property. A most vicious transgressor against distributive justice, doing injury to both public and private good, is that system of direct imposts which is regulated entirely or nearly so by the land impost. It is wholly prejudicial to that industry which is the first source of all wellbeing—agriculture. It favours the narrow¬ minded views of speculating capitalists, who, free from money embarrassments, have a field for enriching themselves more and more every day. It destroys the foundation—namely, land property—on which the stability of families depends. 13 2. The impost ought to fall on that part of income which exceeds the requirements of life. Before giving a contribution to society, the individual has a right and a duty to live in himself and by himself : society itself is intended for the wellbeing of the individual. To put an impost on what is required for private 76 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE life is to set society in contradiction with its end. Therefore, it is necessary that a minimum of property should be exempt from imposts. 3. From the surplus left after the requirements of life, the impost ought to be of the least possible amount—so as to procure social good with the least sacrifice of individual good, for the increase of which society itself has been established. 4. The excellence of an impost may follow from other con¬ siderations ; such as (i.) the little displeasure that it causes in the minds of the contributors ; (ii.) the convenience of the time for payment; (iii.) the easy and inexpensive mode of payment; (iv.) the little opportunity given for fraud. Proportionality and Progressiveness of Imposts .—An impost is said to be proportional when it falls on wealth in a direct ratio to the amount thereof. For example, a family has an income of £50 and pays £1 : this impost is said to be proportional if another family that has ten times as much income (£500) pays ten times as much tribute (£10). On the other hand, an impost is said to be progressive if the quota of tribute, instead of remaining constant, increases with the growth of taxable matter. Suppose that an income, while it remains under £50, pays seven per cent.; while it rises higher up to £500, twelve per cent.; then up to £2,500, fifteen per cent.— and you will have progressive impost. Which of the two ought to be adopted in a well-ordered society ? Some maintain the proportional impost, which they regard as socially just because it calls equally on the citizens to concur for the common wellbeing. We hold that only by a forgetfulness of the true idea of society can such an assertion be made ; and we answer that the proportional impost calls indeed proportionally on the economic position of individuals to concur to the common good, but not on the citizens. He who makes account only of the first principle (proportionality) will maintain the proportional impost. On the other hand, he who thinks that the first principle requires to be completed by the second (progressiveness) will say with us that the con¬ currence to the common good ought to be made in such a manner that the sacrifices imposed by it on private good may be relatively equal. But if you take £1 from him who owns £50, and only £10 from him who owns £500, is there equality of sacrifice here ? The progressive impost, therefore, springs from an idea of solidarity, which teaches that the soul of society ought to be well-ordered. We repeat: society is a body, and individuals are its members. But why should the members measure their function according to the function of the weakest, and fulfil it only three or four REAL CONTRIBUTION 77 times more effectively, when tliev are capable of doing it fifteen or twenty times more so ? Among Catholics the progressive impost has counted strong supporters, such as Lugo, Taparelli, Liberatore, &c. ; and to-day, after the official pronouncement made in its favour at the Congress of Padua, we may say that it forms an unquestionable part of the Christian Democratic Programme. We will not yield to the temptation of quoting from a number of authors; for it would delay us too long. But we must not omit one luminous passage in the speech of Toniolo at the Congress of Padua :—“ Permit me to add that this financial doctrine corresponds with the economic doctrine of the decreasing -final utility of riches. Of three equal units of riches possessed by one person, the value of the first unit, which serves for the indispens¬ able wants of life, is Iqigh; but the value of the second, which is employed for accessory wants, is less ; while the value of the third, which is intended for saving, or perhaps for squandering, is still lower. If, therefore, the financier, in order to treat all equally,wishes to collect the same quota of value by title of impost on each unit of riches possessed, he ought to lean more heavily on the second unit than on the first, and still more heavily on the third than on the second. Let this criterion be applied to three graduated contributions, and the equity of the progressive test will be evident. In this sense, the true proportional impost is the progressive one.” ( Atti , p. 262.) The Proportionality of the Indirect Impost .—What we have just said regarding progressivity refers, of course, only to the direct impost, which is capable of both proportionality and progres¬ siveness. On the other hand, the indirect naturally escapes this two-fold control. Falling, not on the income, but on what is consumed of the income, it is necessarily progressive in an inverse sense—that is, it increases the loss to him who has less means. This is easily understood. “ The indirect impost is proportional to the consumption; but the consumption is not proportional to the riches. He who consumes more of a com¬ modity, pays more in proportion to the impost that falls on it. But not with equal proportion does he who is more rich consume more. A concrete case will make the matter more apparent. Let us take wine, for example, considered in regard to a workman who earns £50 a year and a rich man who has an income of £5,000 a year. The former consumes, we shall suppose, a pint of wine every day ; the latter, even if he wished to intoxicate himself and all Ins family, certainly could not consume a hundred pints every day. Yet this quantity would be required in order that the wine tax should be proportional for both. The same may be said of other commodities, common to the rich and the poor, such as flour, salt, oil, &c. This is a great and irremediable disadvantage of the indirect impost; that is to say, it is not proportional, but 78 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE progressive in an inverse ratio to riches. The poorer a man is, the more he has to pay.”* (Liberatori, Principii , pp. 309-310.) Themes. —Instruction is one of the chief needs of a people who wish to be civilised : right and duty of the State to provide it—A monopoly of in¬ struction is not a right of the State : it is an abuse, it is a wrong done to human liberty—It is one thing to abandon instruction, and another to respect private liberty—Social importance of public works—Duties on articles of consumption are often out of proportion and contrary to justice— Whether the progressive impost is a kind of confiscation—An impost ought evidently to have these three characteristics : necessity, proportion with national wealth, and exclusion of privilege—Make a comment on the follow¬ ing words of Bastiat: “ When it is seen among a people that private services are invaded and turned into public services, the law becomes a weapon of spoliation, because it has for its object to change, under the plea of establishing, an equality of services.” (Armonie Econ., c. xvii.) CHAPTER VII. AUTHORITY. Section I.—A Natural Hierarchy. We have elsewhere observed that nature has constituted human beings in a kind of natural hierarchy. Or we might say that society is somewhat like a pyramid, which ascends step by step from its broad base to the top. It requires solidity and stability. Now, in order that society may flourish, it is necessary that everyone should have his own space, and work therein. And he should work not only for his own advantage, but for that of all the other members of society. What will keep everyone at his post, and co-ordinate his action for the benefit of all ? Nature, which has provided for the unity of material bodies by certain laws that are called of cohesion, gravity, &c., has provided for the unity of the moral body, which is society, by moral laws. It is they that, observed, give the human family the true form of society, and violated, make a chaotic mass of restless, discontented, turbulent, unhappy beings. Yet these laws are not enough. The components of the moral body are rational beings, with their own thoughts, their own desires, their own free powers of action. They are also defective, some by malice, others by natural frailty. All this implies a scattering of operations, which, not rightly directed, can ill arrive at the attainment of the common good. Hence the necessity of a regulating principle, which may make all the actions of indivi¬ duals converge to the general welfare. This element is civil authority. Either do not imagine any society among men, or imagine it under the guidance of public * The burden of a tax should be considered not according to what is given, but to what is left.— Trans. ORIGIN OF AUTHORITY 79 power. “ Since no society can exist unless there is some one at the head of it, moving every member efficaciously and similarly towards a common end, it follows that authority is necessary by which civil society may be ruled.” (Encyc. Immortale Dei.) The physiocratics, like Rousseau, had a fine dream that in the most ancient times men were ruled without obedience to any sovereign power. But history is not written with the dreams of Rousseau or of any other such dreamer. History, so far as it extends, tells us of social power, which men obeyed ; and, in parts to which it does not extend, it leaves us to infer that men, precisely because men, did the same. For the .rest, physiocracy would certainly be a beautiful idea, but the misery in which man is placed is a fact; and dreams in opposition to facts are always dreams, even those of a Rousseau. From what has been said of political authority, it follows :— 1. That authority has the same end as society—namely, to pro¬ mote the common wellbeing ; that therefore a government does not exist for itself, but for the good of its subjects. “ The government ought to be for the advantage of the citizens, because the only reason why some men are over others is that they may see to the general welfare.” (Encyc. Immortale Dei.) Justly therefore are we entitled to condemn despotism, tyranny, oligarchy, every abuse of supreme power that turns to the prejudice of the citizens. “ On no account should it occur that civil authority would be employed for the benefit of one or a few, because it was established for the common good of all.” (Ibid.) 2. That it ought to be in the State alone. This is as clear as it is necessary. If there were many authorities, none would be supreme or sovereign. They would require to have a supreme authority, which would subject, unite, and subordinate them. 14 Section II. —Origin of Authority. Authority is desirable in the social body. All admit it, except those who seek disorder. Those who view society from a materialistic standpoint, and therefore give no reason for its existence or give a reason that is no explanation, do not know at what point they can best attack an established authority. Yet authority is of so much importance that the life of the social body depends on it. A false idea, which would set up a weak authority, will have a long task, and will then only shake the walls of the social edifice. Others have recourse to pantheistic explanations. Let him who wishes to walk with his head in the midst of dense clouds concern himself about them. More commonly the origin of authority is said to be in the will of the people. The expression has a fine sound : a pity that it has no substance, or rather is fraught with practical consequences that its followers are the first to condemn. 80 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE Our doctrine is more simple, though not so high-sounding. A short argument : nature is the source of that without which a natural institution cannot exist ; society, a natural institution, cannot exist without public power ; therefore, public power is from nature. Remove the word nature , and put God in its stead. He, the Lord of all things, is the author of sovereign power, as He is the author of man and of the universe. No other origin can be given to public power that does not destroy it. There is question of commanding men : who can do it but a Being superior to men ? “ Authority,” says Pope Leo XIII., “ no less than society, is from nature, and therefore from God. Hence it follows that public power in itself can be derived only from God. For God alone is the true and supreme Lord of the world, to whom all creatures should be submissive. So that those who have the right of commanding, have it from no other source than God, the great Lord of all. There is no power hut from God (Rom. xiii, 1).” (Encyc. Tmmortale Dei.) This basis of sovereign power is the only one, not merely because it is the true one, but because it is the only one possible. To pretend to replace it by another is folly, because every substitute will be either inferior to or equal to man, and, as such, will be without the right of commanding men. This immovable basis being given to public power, Christian sociology provides for the safety of the social body, for public order, for civil prosperity. Behold the explanation why, outside of our walls, there is nothing to be found but conspiracy, rebellion, revolution, anarchy. Section III. —Form of Government. Social authority, residing in the subject that exercises it, is called government. As this subject may be one, or many, or all, there are various forms of government. One person alone can certainly exercise the supreme command, and then there is the monarchical form or a monarchy. If the power rests in a class of the great, then there is the aristocratic form or an aristocracy. If instead all the people hold the public power, then there is the democratic form or a democracy. Thus there are three principal forms. Others might be made by a combination among these. Then we should have mixed forms, of which there are few : one of them is the constitutional monarchy. Which form is to be preferred ? Above all let it be clearly understood that, according to natural justice, none of them has a right of preference to the others. God, who is the Author of authority in the social body, has not specially pointed out in which He wishes it to rest. Any form of government can fulfil the will of God, who wishes that there should be authority ; and REPRESENTATIVE FORM OF GOVERNMENT 81 it suffices. “ The sovereign authority is not by itself necessarily bound to any particular form of government : it can justly assume one or another, provided that such is really capable of promoting the public weal.” (Encyc. Immortale Dei.) The question is therefore to be solved by a consideration of the people’s good, which is the only reason for the existence of supreme power. So much being granted, there is no need for long arguments to prove that any one of the aforesaid forms is good in itself, and calculated to promote the common wellbeing. On this point, Catholic theologians agree : St. Thomas taught it, and Pope Leo XIII' teaches it. As a matter of fact, each of those forms presents special advantages, but at the same time is exposed to particular abuses. Monarchy would seem to be the ideal of governments, because the unity of the subject helps much towards sympathy, firmness, and expedition in command. But one only subject, however excellent, will always be only one man. As such, he can easily err, either through ignorance or through malice, from which originates despotism or tyranny. Democracy, which stands at the other extreme, presents a special and most desirable advantage, if viewed in regard to the autonomy of the citizens. In point of fact, it enlarges the popular mind, breathes the spirit of freedom, feels and provides for the wants of the people. Subj ect to social duties and sharing in social benefits, it is more capable of weighing the exigencies of the common wellbeing and the sacrifices that ought to be imposed on private wellbeing. On the other hand, who does not see that democracy also presents inconveniences, due to the malice of men ? The consciousness of power can rouse cupidities in the people, and lead them to rebellion or to demagogy. Aristocracy has likewise its advantages and inconveniences. Among the latter, not the least is the danger of oligarchy, which is a tyranny so much the worse as it is worse to be under the power of several bad men than of only one. Therefore ? What are we to conclude ? Therefore every form of government is excellent for those who wish it to be so. It is a question of justice, and justice does not consist in the form but in the exercise of authority. For the rest, the manners, the customs, the character of a people, as well as their greatness, may fit them better for one form than for another. Speaking in the abstract, we may say that that form is the best which would try to realise in itself the best qualities of all. This would be the mixed form in which the monarchical element predominates, tempered by aristocracy and democracy. Section IV.— The Representative Form. Among the mixed forms, that which seems to have won the favour of peoples at the present day is the representative. In F 82 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE Europe it is almost generally adopted : great praise has been given and is still given to it. It is reduced to the following heads :—(i.) The sovereignty rests in the people, who exercise it by a chamber of deputies, elected by them. Here we have a democratic basis, (ii.) A chamber of magnates, chosen from the classes most distinguished for their learning, wealth, nobility, or virtue. They are called senators. They balance and temper any immoderateness in the deputies. Here we have the aristocratic element, (iii.) A king, who reigns by the will of the nation, and sanctions with his signature the laws passed by the two chambers—laws that without the royal signature are of no value. The king, however, has not the free exercise of the executive power. This belongs to the ministers, who alone are responsible for it. Hence the saying, “ The king reigns, but he does not govern. 7 ' Deputies, senators, and king are to conduct themselves according to the Constitution, which is a fundamental law of government, a kind of contract entered into between king and people. Is the representative form good ? In itself, it is exceedingly good. It is better than the simple forms, not because these are not in themselves very good, but because it takes good from all three, and gives reason to hope that inconveniences will thus be more easily avoided. The representative form brings together the people, the choicest men, and the king. All very well—a magnificent sight! But in reality does it include the people, the choicest men, and the king ? The king is there, but counts only for what he is considered. Are the people there ? have they their representatives there ? It is an old question. There is the name of representatives of the people, but the true representatives are not there. If we had the people organised, and professional representation had assembled the true delegates of the people, who, having common interests with the people, would take the interests of the people to heart, then with the liveliest enthusiasm would we hail the deputies, in whom we should recognise the people themselves. But the elections of to-day, made according to the system of majorities (we have already referred to it), do not give us in truth the representatives of the people, but the representatives of that party which, at the time of the election, is most powerful in influence, most clever or astute in management, and most abounding in money. The parliament being thus constituted, it is next to impossible that it should work well. It is apt to fall speedily into a sickly state, a state of disastrous inefficiency, which is called parlia¬ mentarism, This word denotes a compendium of all intrigues, all plots against the ministers and the king, all evil artifices that are employed by a group of men who hold power for every purpose except the one for which it was given. THE SOVEREIGNTY OF THE PEOPLE 83 And is true aristocracy represented by the chamber of senators ? Let us hear Rossignoli:— “ That the Senate may correspond wisely to its moderating office, it is necessary above all that it should exercise in reality, and not merely in name, the legislative power. The nomination of the senators ought, therefore, to be left, not to the Crown or in an unlimited number, but in a fixed number and to a body chosen by the electors, so that they may represent in the government something not represented either by the king or by the Chamber. Deplace, for example, in his work, Senats et Chambres Hautes (Hachette, 1891), would wish that the Senate should be an assembly of intelligent men ; but I would add that it should also be an assembly of virtuous men, for then we might expect to find in it good human laws, which may be regarded as a portion of the eternal laws of justice. “ To have a Senate truly conservative, we should not forget the three branches of which the ancient parliaments consisted before absolutism had cast its baneful shadow on Europe—- namely, the ecclesiastical, the baronial, and the popular. The popular would now be represented by the Chamber of Deputies. The baronial, feudalism having fallen, would no longer have any reason for existence, and might be usefully replaced by a pro¬ fessional representation of classes and interests. The Senate would then have men, nominated by legally constituted bodies, who could represent the various departments of science, literature, art, agriculture, industry, commerce—men of the sword and men of state, great lawyers and great financiers— in short, the good sense of the nation. But also the ecclesiastical branch—that is, a representation of the Episcopate, which may be sufficient to prevent anti-Christian legislation—will always be essential to a Senate that wishes to act, as it ought, with modera¬ tion.” (Concetto delVAutorita, &c., p. 79.) Section V.— The Sovereignty of the People. The ideas set forth in the previous sections will help to show what is to be thought about the much-vaunted sovereignty of the people. A little distinction clears the true from the false contained in this well-known formula, which may have a double meaning. The first meaning is the assertion of those who say that authority originated from the people—that, outside of the popular will, there cannot be any source of social power. This is the thought of liberal sociology, and comes straight from Rousseau’s theory on the origin of society. We have not time to talk about it. The origin of society and the origin of authority are on the same logical string. If you attach society to the will of the people, you must also attach authority to it, for authority rules 84 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE society. This is a most deplorable theory, from which come, like threads from a spool, the greatest part of our present social disorders. The Pope, in his encyclical Vigesimum, speaks of it thus :—“ Supposing that authority to rule comes formally from the consent of the multitude, and not from God, the supreme and eternal source of all power, it loses its most august character in the eyes of subjects, and degenerates into an artificial sovereignty, resting on a shaky changeable foundation, such as is the will of men. And are not the effects of it seen even in the public laws, which too often, instead of being written reason (ratio scripta, the dictates of reason expressed in writing), represent only a numerical force, and the prevailing will of political power ? Accordingly, the licentious appetites of the multitude are flattered, the rein on popular passions is slackened, while it fills cities with disturbers of a forced tranquillity, reserving to itself the right of having recourse in extreme cases to violent and sanguinary repressions.” Christian sociology, which maintains that God is the only source of power, absolutely rejects this ill-omened sovereignty of the people. But we can also understand the sovereignty of the people as meaning a sovereignty in fact. As God has not pointed out, either mediately or immediately, the subject in whom authority should rest, undoubtedly it can also rest in the people, who will then be truly sovereign. And this is that popular sovereignty which is not only lawful, but may also become highly efficient. Section VI.— Functions of Social Authority. The duty of guidance, which the social power has to practise in regard to its subjects, requires (i.) that it should issue acts of direction, which are called laws : (ii.) that it should keep an eye on the lives of the citizens, in order to see if the laws are observed ; and (iii.) that it should insist on the observance of these laws— punishing transgressors. These three functions of authority pre¬ suppose a triple power in it—namely, the legislative, the judicial, and the executive. A few words on each :— 1. The Legislative Power .—To discuss whether the civil authority can make laws is to discuss whether it ought to exist. It exists for this purpose. The civil law, therefore, is a general rational command, by which authority obliges all the citizens to concur for the common good. Men are bound to obey the laws : this obedience is a natural duty. To deny it would be to say that nature intends authority for idleness or amusement. But a law ought to be a true law in order to require this obedience—that is, it ought to be rational. To be such, the law ought (i.) not to go against other laws that are superior to it—namely, the natural law and the divine law. FUNCTIONS OF SOCIAL AUTHORITY 85 It is well known that there exist even to-day some State- worshippers who place in the civil law the very source of morality, and call everything good, honest, and just that the law prescribes. According to this theory, if there existed a majority of socialist deputies in a parliament, they might lawfully and officially declare in favour of communism. Can anything be more absurd ? (ii.) The law ought to have as its object the public welfare, not merely private welfare, (iii.) The law ought to be made and promulgated by him who has the plenitude of legislative power, according to the form in which this power becomes actually concrete. An absolute king is the legislator; a constitutional monarch is not such. In the latter case, the legislative power lies with the two chambers, and then the laws decreed have force only in a case of public necessity that admits of no delay. 2. The Judicial Power .—It is immediately linked with the legislative, because the authority to make laws would be of little avail without that of watching over their observance and punishing their violation. The judicial power is, therefore, an intrinsic part of sovereignty, which, to avoid mistakes, entrusts it to wise and upright men, called judges or magistrates. Civil society is like a body, whose living members are held together by a variety of forces. These forces, binding the elements, are the rights and the duties that they have towards one another and towards society. From their exercise a twofold result should follow—namely, the greatest possible private good of individuals, and the common good, which is the completion or crown of the private good. When any part of society is faithful to these laws, faithful to its rights, faithful to its duties, we say that juridical order reigns therein. But it may happen that, through a greediness of increasing private good, some element violates the duty that binds it to its like or to society in general. It may also be that between two elements there arises a controversy on the existence or the absence of a right. In these cases it is said that juridical order is broken, or at least disturbed. It must then be reconstituted for the good of society. Hence the judicial power, which is to judge in the criminal court, when public or private right has been injured, and in the civil court, when the reciprocal rights of individuals among themselves, or even with the State, require a clear and authoritative decision. 3. The Executive Power .—To this expression we must give a meaning somewhat broad. By the exercise of the legislative and judicial powers, such as we have described them, it is too evident that the sovereign authority will not fully succeed in accomplishing its mission of giving being, as Taparelli says, to society. That small remainder of authority, if I may so speak, which is necessary for it, in order that society may be what is to be desired, a moral body, with the greatest possible wellbeing, is contained in the executive power. The duties of the executive 86 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE power are reduced to four by Rossignoli—namely (i.) to carry out the provisions made by tbe legislative power and the sentences passed by the judicial power ; (ii.) to procure order and peace, defending them from enemies internal as well as external; (iii.) to represent the nation before foreigners; and (iv.) to promote the public wellbeing, moral as well as material. The exercise of this power, as is evident, extends (i.) to the appointment of public officials, from which an organised adminis¬ tration will result; (ii.) to the public strength, which ought to flow in some manner from the energies of the nation; and (iii.) to the public treasury, in which the tributes of the citizens are deposited. Themes. —It is not fair to say that the statutes of a society are only conventionalities : the members ought to recognise that certain laws conduce to the object of the society—In like manner it is absurd to say that laws are nothing but an expression of the general will—As laws ought to lead society towards its end, and as a true law cannot be conceived without this scope, he who makes laws should keep in view the end towards which society tends—Herein consists the difference between true and false democracy— Revolutions are often the logical evolutions of false principles applied in the government of a country—Should the laws be equal for all ? NOTES TO THE FIRST PART Note 1, p. 1.—Here and there in the course of our work it may he seen how much civil society is indebted to Christianity. Mean¬ while, we wish to remark that such a thing is quite natural for whoever considers that the object of Our Saviour was to lead men to their last end. If the goods of this world—whatever they are—are goods for man in so far as they are efficacious means for the attainment of the end, it is natural, we repeat, that Christianity, by the virtues which it commands and the vices which it condemns, should become eminently social. Society, as we shall soon see, is a body resulting from a multitude of bodies, but living bodies, earnestly striving towards happiness. To each of these bodies is assigned its own orbit or sphere of action. If everyone re¬ cognises this, and checks his desire of trenching on the limits of others, the moral body is in good condition. If one, if many, if all wish to be without control, it is a game in which the strongest wins; the equilibrium is broken, the body is necessarily undone. Now, to keep men at their posts is what virtue desires; and Christianity, which teaches this, gives efficacious means to attain it—helps wonderfully to promote social harmony, which would be perfect if Christianity were universally followed. Man is naturally social. See how Christ did not come to destroy but to perfect nature. He wishes that man should be saved in society, in that society which bears the name of the Church, to make part in which all the human family who aspire to temporal wellbeing are called. Could the action of this Church be less than useful to social order ? Could it be said that the moral perfection of the individual man would be a hindrance to his civil perfection ? That sounds too contradictory. The beneficent action of the Church for the ad¬ vantage of civil society has been often referred to by Leo XIII. in his public acts, especially in his encyclical Immortale Dei . Therein we read: “The Church therefore, always consistent with herself, if on the one hand she rejects excessive liberty, which, with private and public harm, leads to licentiousness or to slavery, on the other willingly and joyfully embraces the progress that comes with time, when it truly promises to increase the prosperity of the present life, which is a kind of race-course to life without end.” Note 2, p. 2.—A question here presents itself: where are we to begin and how are we to proceed in the study of sociology ? Is it by the inductive or the deductive method ? We must take care not to be ex¬ clusive. Each method gives much help ; and to each we must have recourse. There are moral, un¬ doubted, incontestable principles in human nature, which have logical consequences in social phenomena. The method that leads you to the study of these phenomena is the deductive. There are also real facts in social life, recurring at intervals, happening according to certain rules. From these facts you come by the inductive method to a knowledge of fixed and constant laws. Hence the importance of statistics in studies of this kind. Our method is therefore twofold, deductive and inductive. Note 3, p. 8.—According to Pope Leo XIII., the end of civil society ... is the common good, that is, a good in which each and every one has a proportional share. (See Encyc. Immortale Dei.) Note 4, p. 16.—There are two types of professional unions—the pure and the mixed. The first type is that which assembles in two 88 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE distinct bodies, the workmen and the masters who are engaged in the same industry. In this type a meeting for the settlement of con- troversies and other matters is held by delegates or arbitrators from both unions. The second type is that which assembles in only one association, the workmen and the masters having an affinity of interests. The theoretical question, which type is to be preferred ? admits of much discussion, with little result. As for the practical part, we think that we may well suggest it in words that we take from a letter addressed by Toniolo to Count Medolago Albani. The young student will here find another thesis of supreme importance first explained. Behold how the distinguished master speaks :— “ The last decade of the 19th century (owing in great part to the wise impulse given by the Supreme Pontiff in Rerum novarum) spread social works with rapid progress for the Christian restoration of the people. But the social political anti- Christian reaction , which from countries beyond the Alps found its way into our peninsula, cut short this reconstructive process in May, 1898, and scattered all our institu¬ tions. A moment of trial, before which we confess—if that can help us to a holy and noble regret—we were all unequal to the task per¬ mitted for us by Providence. The Kulturkampf in Germany stirred a people of heroes, and bound fast the great nucleus of the Centre, which gave power and advantage to all German Catholics, even to this day. The furious passage of those few months of absurd persecution— which did so much for socialism— left us divided and degraded by a useless war of words, like a nation about to die. Loud and strong language of protest and encourage¬ ment to the Italian people came from the Pope alone. We shall not now perpetuate the error with mutual recriminations. All of us, old and young, have had our share in the fault against the lawful expectation of the nation and of religion. With this salutary con¬ fession—which we candidly make in our few journals—nothing remains for us but to be confounded, and to be charitable towards one another, in the hope of a better future. “ The stirring of a new life was heard. The theoretical and practical ideas of a popular programme were elaborated among us, more than elsewhere, so that Italy appeared as the land of Christian Democracy. The Pope, fortifying it with limits and guarantees, consecrated it, and made it universal; and thus, taken up with spirit by intelligent and ardent young men, it was by them spread everywhere. They planted in every quarter the banner of Christian Corporations, on which that programme, with great historic meaning, especially at the present day, is summarised. “ And thus to-day there is every¬ where a spring-time of sodalities, of popular classes, which—to interpret, mv illustrious friend, one of vour thoughts—both gladdens and per¬ plexes us. “ Yes, a spring-time that gladdens us. The encyclical Graves de communi appeared and was wisely intended as a rein on the democratic movement—teaching caution and the conditions of success—but at the same time what a powerful and unexpected impulse ! Who could have imagined the concordant echo that followed from so many Bishops in Italy, in favour of energetic popular action ? And the desire for professional unions, which was so little regarded at the Congress of September, 1900, in Rome—who would have supposed that it would so soon flourish again in so many corporate sodalities, springing up everywhere ! “ Yes, a spring-time that gladdens us, but perplexes us. The Socialists understood well—from us as from other sources—the hopes of Christian renovation contained in such an initiative of the Pope, the Clergy, Catholics in general, ardent youths ; and they attacked the rising Catholic corporations with weapons of infidelity, with abusive squibs scattered freely among the people. Will the members of our sodalities hold out against these assaults ; NOTES TO THE FIRST PART 89 and will the defence be sufficient against attempts on faith greater than any that ever the people of Italy endured before ? “ On the other hand, will these new plants have intrinsic strength to grow into mature and fruitful trees ? And you, my illustrious friend, besiege me with practical demands for the solution of such distressing doubts, which seem to settle in the question : How are we to prevent this vegetation from failing, and make sure that our Class Representation will become permanent and vigorous ? “ Perhaps you will find some answer to the problem, truly decisive, in the history and general tendency of the European corpora¬ tive movement, as also in the refutation of some more common objections that I have endeavoured to sum up in the work that I have dedicated to you. Others—simple and candid, but modest—I shall here set forth briefly. “ The object is to form a new popular class—on parallel lines with other superior ones—not only in its organic arrangement, but especially in the spirit that should animate it; and therefore our old men spoke of the esprit de corps. Let us, not deceive ourselves : a social palingen¬ esis is impossible without a moral and religious renovation. We must saturate the corporations with a Christian Catholic spirit. They ought to be great practical schools of ethics and religion. You have said it admirably in your remarks on corporations. “The test of faith is the to be or not to be of future class-associa¬ tions. If we have different types of corporations in England and in Germany, they are due to historical and local causes at work in Protes¬ tant or sceptical regions—in short, to abnormal causes, which cannot last, and which here and there already show signs of change, but which in no case can be a rule for us or for the normal life of society. “ This educational, religious, moral end proposed for our people assembled in corporations truly Christian, as pointed out and enjoined by the Pontiff, will be the vital sap of the new sodalities. Here will be the field for the Clergy of the coming times ; and whoever can work |best in it will find fruits most ready and most ripe. 44 But, for charity’ sake, let us not be stopped in so important a beginning by any stumbling-block or difficulty. The essential point consists in training the corporations to faith and Christian morality. This banner can never, should never, be lowered; and what remains impossible for us is to write at the head of the statutes the rationalistic rule that the members will be neutral. But should the word Catholic be always inserted in their title ? Generally speaking, yes; and the people are rarely inclined to take offence at it; but in exceptional cases, if it were necessary to remove some extrinsic obstacle, we take care of the intrinsic purpose, and omit for a while the name. “ As for the final purpose of wishing to form Catholic corpora¬ tions, does it imply that workmen will not be admitted, unless they are strictly observant in matters of religion ? This is a question for practical good sense. Unsteady and incautious workmen, as the Pope remarked, are tempered to faith and morals within the precincts of Christian corporations ; so, observ¬ ing certain limits of prudence, let us open our arms with a charitable toleration. If our credulous countrymen unfortunately enter the ‘ Labour Rooms,’ they become atheists or socialists ; if tepid work¬ men do not disdain to repair to our 4 Unions,’ it is to be hoped that they will become good Christians. But will the religious practices that may be proposed by the ingenious piety and charity of our priests and the presidents of our sodalities, be obligatory ? Certainly not. The examples of all Europe attest that only those which are free are acceptable and fruitful. But if any one, already connected with a 4 Socialist Club,’ asks to be enrolled in a 4 Catholic Union,’ are we to admit him ? Why close the way against conversion, when there are so many victims of illusion and violence ? On condition, however, that the enrolment by rule in our ranks will be a sincere pledge of a 90 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE speedy joining in fact. But enough of casuistry, intended to give a practical illustration, not to change a systematic theory. “ The systematic principle of wishing to form Christian institu¬ tions that may be socially full of life, is so practical, that it becomes to-day one reason more why we should have two kinds of autono¬ mous corporations, that of masters and that of workpeople, co-ordinated together, and not merely one mixed of the two elements. Have you ever thought, my illustrious friend, what would become of our religious pur¬ pose in the two different cases ? It is not hazardous to say that our people by themselves, in simple ‘ Labour Unions,’ will, sooner or later, under the direct influence of the clergy, become thoroughly Catholic, and Christ will truly return on the shoulders of the people. Confused in mixed corporations with masters, who, as a rule (with praiseworthy exceptions), are in present circumstances and will be ; for a long time, if not sectaries, for the most part liberals—which means rationalists—or at all events cleric o- liberals, it is to be feared that through such influence our work¬ people would be declared neutral, or that religion would be maintained only as an engine of control— generating popular aversion towards it—or at least that the action of the clergy would be impeded, and that these social organisms would be converted into electoral clubs, for the service of the masters and of political programmes more or less antipapal. All these things would be great obstacles to the flourishing of mixed corporations, even where they would find their natural home, for example, in regions where metayage or mezzadria* prevails. And this shows how the religious problem presents itself to all. “ A second condition to give life to the renovated corporations is that the people should find in them all the aid required, not only to defend their class interests, but to promote their material, civil, and moral wellbeing. This is the great lesson that comes to us not only from the history of the past, but from the marvellous and increasing power of corporations in England, Belgium, Germany, France, &c. “ It is proper that we should also introduce and multiply in these corporate citadels all the popular practices, existing or possible, that converge to the elevation of the respective classes. Thus we should have workmen’s banks and rural chests, insurance societies, co-opera¬ tive societies, rent boxes, inns for the people, St. Vincent de Paul Societies (giving help at home), refuges and schools for children, schools of art, educational confer¬ ences, circulating libraries, pious and charitable confraternities, places of conversation, and in fine games and a theatre. Consider, my ex¬ cellent friend, what stability these corporations w T ould acquire when each member, after being enrolled in a particular class, would apply himself to a few of those popular practices which develop and prosper under the guidance of wise leaders. In a short time he would find himself bound to the corporation by numerous interests; so that to separate from it would be to break through a series of concentric circles of wellbeing. Consider also how the people within the precincts of these vast associations, serving them and managed by them (for the people and by the people ), would act with all their mind and heart. They would live like one great family, which would facilitate for them all the lawful satisfactions of a proper and dignified life. And if this family were perfectly Catholic in spirit, what a bright fireside of Christian social life would it present! “Nor are these mere fancies. Apart from the great example of English ^Trade-Unions,’ it suffices to recall the similar Catholic societies in Belgium, such as the ‘ Boerenbond ’ and the ‘People’s House ’ ; and the institutions of the Abbe Cetty at Mulhouse in Alsace, so well adapted for the elevation of the working classes. “ An immense undertaking, I admit; but indispensable to give life to future corporations, and, for * See Second Part, Chapter VII., Section 2.— Trans. NOTES TO THE FIRST PART 91 the rest, not impossible among us, where few of these institutions yet exist. The point therefore is to multiply them, and place them under the shield of the old sodalities, proceeding by degrees. And it seems to me more urgent to begin with the following :—(i.) Mutual Help, well represented, much more than at present, according to social Christian ideas, not merely for material loans; (ii.) a Secretariate for the People —for special business of the members—together with the office of finding occupation for the unemployed ; and (iii.) a Social Presidency, which, besides serving for the administration and for assemblies, may be at the same time a kind of school for technical conferences on art and education, and also a place for ordinary con¬ versation and amusement. All this under the vivifying breath of religion, under the care of an ecclesiastic; and materially sup¬ ported from a fund contributed by the members, and by others, who aid in promoting the interests of all classes. “ This does not appear to me impossible : it concerns a transfor¬ mation and co-ordination rather than a new creation. But unless this work is done, we are convinced that the new corporations will be shadows without a body,\ or at most—as you have written to me— a blaze of straw, which will leave a cloudy darkness after it.” Note 5, p. 26.—The idea of social justice, at least as we have described it, has lately entered minds, but not all. Antoine tells us of a congress in which a lawyer said that the phrase “ social justice ” is one with¬ out meaning. We ourselves hap¬ pened to read in a periodical that social justice is nothing but charity. We do not agree in this view. Charity is always of a secondary or supplementary character. Justice, even social justice, is always the principal bond through which the sympathy of civil society is to be obtained. Note 6, p. 37.—The want of employment is a deplorable fact, too often occurring in the present state of society. Catholics who have studied the matter, propose three remedies :—(i.) Labour Bureaux. These are like so many registry offices. They keep an account of the demand and supply in regard to work, and endeavour to provide for both, (ii.) Houses for Work. Re¬ ceiving public and private aid, they have workshops, in which competent and unemployed men are engaged, (iii.) Boxes for the Unemployed. These give an allowance in money to the unemployed. Those who are enrolled pay a subscription. Bene¬ factors, and sometimes the com¬ munity, assist. This is a point that ought to be a special study with local working societies, so as to apply to the evil that remedy which is found most suitable and efficacious for it. In some places, work is not wanting, but it is confined to two or three industries, which turn to other dis¬ tricts where lower wages are given, and leave a part of the local work¬ people unemployed. In such cases a co-operative society will do good, giving autonomous action. As in other tasks of societies, a federation of them in a province or diocese will also be useful. The reason is always the same : union is strength. Note 7, p. 45.—Social indivi¬ dualism incited the various social elements to the pursuit of greater wellbeing. And, as a consequence, the stronger made little account of scruples ; they trampled on the rights of the weaker elements. Those who naturally had a right to special aid from society found themselves wronged, degraded by society. Poor labourers, children, and women suffered oppression and the loss of their rights. Catholics, intent on the re-integration of every S just right, could not forget woman, whom Jesus Christ had raised from pagan abjection, and liberalism had driven back to a slavery that, though masked, was not less painful and unworthy of her, a creature of God. Hence came a movement in favour of woman, a movement that, like other new movements, was at first opposed, but that is to-day making glorious progress. To this resur¬ rection, eminently Christian, is 92 THE ELEMENTS OF SOCIAL SCIENCE given the name of Christian Feminism —not a very beautiful name, but one that indicates a most beautiful work. This move¬ ment advances daily in elaborating and defining the points of its pro¬ gramme. Among these the most important are the rights that woman has (i.) to be equal with man in regard to moral laws, so that there are not two moralities—one for man and another for woman, as is often pretended ; (ii.) to be free, even against the will of her husband, when there is question of fulfilling her duties as a woman and a Christian ; and (iii.) to be specially protected by society in her relations as daughter, wife, and mother. Nor is there any reason to condemn a certain interest that woman takes in the good ordering of public affairs, in the proper state of civil society ; for it is no hindrance to her duties within the domestic walls. We repeat that there is a pro¬ gramme, and it is developing by degrees. The points of it are found under the accumulated ruins of liberalism, as among the ashes of an old burnt city we meet with treasures of art. Note 8, p. 51.—Although in other places the system of “ social clauses ” has been sooner and more generally practised, yet in Italy there are examples of it. We may refer to that of Turin, which approved of the motion made in the order of the day by the Catholic councillor Ricci, saying: “ The Council, having heard the declara¬ tions of the syndic and the com¬ mittee, decides that in contracts of public service those social clauses should be placed which guard the just freedom and wellbeing of work¬ people, guaranteeing to them specially and always rest on festivals, a fair minimum of wages, and a fair maximum of hours for work. Recourse can be had to mixed commissions, and to the suggestions of technically competent persons, if there should be any difficulty in settling these points.” An identical proposal, made by Alberto Buffa, was approved by the Council of Alexandria in May, 1900. Note 9, p. 51.—The many duties of the Commune towards work¬ people are exceedingly well shown in the work of the lawyer Invrea : II Comune e la sua Funzione Sociale. For the right management of Com¬ munes, Catholics still rely on pro¬ fessional representation in councils, on the referendum, and on pro¬ gressive imposts. Note 10, p. 60.—At the Congress of Social Science, Padua, 1896, the following resolution was adopted : “ Considering that recourse to the electoral body for the more impor¬ tant acts of an administrative economical character (new imposts, loans, alienations or diminutions of patrimony, &c.), and also for the more important acts of a moral character in the Communes, while it stimulates a sense of responsibility in the people, and corrects various defects in the representative system . . . becomes a guarantee for the right, free, and prompt performance of social functions . . . the Congress wishes that until it is legally admitted with deliberative effect, the suitability of its applica¬ tion in a consultative form should be maintained.” ( Atti ). The Con¬ gress of Turin also expresses itself in favour of the Referendum; and the memorial presented to the government by desire of the Con¬ gress of Fiesola asks for the same. It is to be understood, however, that all these remarks refer tb the Communal Referendum. Note 11, p. 73-—“ It may very well happen that a tax and an impost occur in the same payment. We shall find an example in some rules of registration. When a docu¬ ment is registered by authority, and thus becomes more fitted for use as a title or proof, the State renders a service to him in whose favour the registration is made. Now, if for such service a very high remunera¬ tion is required, this high remunera¬ tion is a tax only for a small part; for the greater part, it is an impost. It is exclusively an impost if the registration brings no advantage that cannot be obtained in some other way, or if it is made NOTES TO THE FIRST PART 93 only because prescribed by law.” (Pierson, Problemi, &c., p. 404.) Note 12, p. 74.—“ Salt has no impost in England, Belgium, Portugal, B-oumania. In Russia it is taxed at 8* centimes per kilo¬ gramme, at 15 in Germany, at 8 in Greece, at 10 in France. The centimes of war, scarcely established, were suppressed, and in the worst days the figure never rose higher than 30 cefitimes. Only in Italy has the impost on salt risen to 55 centimes per kilogramme, producing for the State a revenue of 80,616,000 lire, or an average of 3.02 per head. “ Mantegazza has calculated that 7j kilogrammes of salt are necessary for each individual. Now the majority of Italians consume only about 3 kilogrammes on an average.” * (Peopli, Journal des Economistes, Paris, Oct., 1878, p. 151). Note 13, p. 75.—“ We know what regulates the selling value of immovable goods. The value of a farm is equal to the capitalised amount of the return that it pro¬ duces. If the return is 1,000 florins and the rate of interest is 4 per cent., the selling value will be 25,000 florins. What will happen if a farm that has a letting value of 1,000 florins is subjected to a land impost of 10 per cent. ? The selling value of that farm will fall to 22,500 florins : the owner will suffer as if 2,500 florins were taken out of his pocket. The introduction or the increase of a real impost is com¬ pared—and with perfect truth—to a partial expropriation, without in¬ demnity. Such a measure is always very afflicting for the owner at the time.” (Pierson, Problemi, p. 413.) Note 14, p. 79.—We give the name of State to civil society con¬ stituted into an autonomous body for the attainment of the common good. But by a happy abstraction we also give this name to the supreme power, which is the chief part of society. We have said by a happy abstraction, because it is power that gives form to society ; and neatly the whole life of society is centred therein. It is like the heart, which diffuses vigour through the whole social body. To understand well the nature of the State, taken in this secondary sense, is a thing of so much im¬ portance that the formation of true and just ideas regarding social science depends on it. Now this ought not to be difficult for anyone who recalls the points of doctrine on which we have chiefly dwelt. They are so many resting-places on a royal road, from which we have clear and beautiful views. We studied humanity in its origin. We noted the various stages in its development, caused by a primary want or necessity, that of man’s happiness. The desire of happiness is a sap that circulates in hidden channels through all the branches of the human race. It obliges men to join in associations that will satisfy such a want. From man we passed on to the family; from the family to the commune ; and from the commune to civil society. In the study of civil society we find that there is one element above all essential to it: we mean the State. * This would seem to be the quantity used in a year. The kilogramme is equal to a little more than two pounds avoirdupois.— Trans. SECOND PART THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. CHAPTER I. . MEANING AND OBJECT OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. Section I.— Utility, Value, and Abundance oe Goods. We cannot imagine the life of man on this earth without the existence of a multitude of things external to him—things various in quantity, in form, in the use that he makes of them—which serve to satisfy his wants or to procure him enjoyments. We are convinced of these facts by our experience of human life. It is not merely a relation of use that the life of man has with these external things. No, it has other and almost continual relations with them, concurring to their production, their cir¬ culation, their distribution, or their consumption. Man is naturally inclined to occupy himself with his relations in regard to external things, because he depends upon these things for his preservation, and for his more or less prosperous existence. To study, to regulate, and to control such relations that they may have the desired effect is the task of a special science, which takes the name of Economy. If Economy confines itself to study and give laws within the limits of the domestic walls, and settles the administrative ordering of the family, it is called Domestic or Private Economy ( Cossa ). If, with a wider horizon, it studies the nature, the production, the circulation, the distribution of things, calling in all society, not only as a point of departure, that is, as an agent of pro¬ duction, but also as a point of arrival, that is, as a term in whose favour consumption takes place, it is called Social or Political Economy. With regard to the end of Political Economy, Perin speaks thus :—“ The scope that economic science sets before it is one eminently practical. It seeks the method of securing for men who live in society the greatest possible wellbeing, of procuring for them the greatest possible riches, in such a manner that these riches may serve them for the attainment of their last end, which stands highest in the moral order.” (Premiers Princi'pes, &c., p. 3.) How, therefore, shall we define Political Economy ? Without 96 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY any pretensions to suppose that there is only one definition, we shall say that it is a science which studies wealth in its relations with civil society. Boccardo defines it as a science that studies the laws of the production, distribution, and consumption of wealth. (Dizionario d'Econ. Pol., ii., 89.) Cossa says more briefly that it is the doctrine of the social order of wealth. ( Primi Elementi.) But what is meant by wealth ? The common idea of wealth is so simple that it scarcely ever happens to be defined. As for the idea that economists have of it, it is so various and unprecise that it can scarcely be understood. Before entering on this thorny ground, which we would willingly avoid for our own sake and that of the reader, it is necessary that we should refer to some other ideas of much importance. Goods .—The things of which man makes use in order to preserve his life or to procure some satisfaction for himself, have the nature of good. They are, therefore, justly called goods. Utility .—Goods cannot be conceived otherwise than as sub¬ stances that have an aptitude for giving man some satisfaction : this aptitude is called utility. The utility of things, with regard to man, appears in a two-fold way. The first is that of being able to become useful, certain conditions being verified. The second is that of being useful, those conditions already existing, which may be reduced to a knowledge of the properties of the object, and to circumstances of time and place that create in man a need, or only a capacity, for using them with satisfaction. Through want of some of these conditions it happens that some things are called useless, which, if properly known or placed in other circumstances, would be found most useful, and even necessary. Man, composed of matter and spirit, has corporal and spiritual wants, and is capable of various satisfactions. For his corporal nature all those goods are useful, which, being material, are in some degree adapted to his physical constitution, or to the con¬ ditions in which he lives. From the elements that are absolutely necessary for life to the requirements of the most pompous luxury, there is a countless number of material goods that modify the sense of physical wellbeing in man. As regards the spiritual part of man, all those things are useful which, procured, give an intellectual satisfaction to the soul. Economy holds account even of these, both because the satisfac¬ tion of the mind and heart often proceeds from a material object, and because man is not a mere vegetable or animal, but a creature that thinks, reasons, grows perfect, advances in civilisation. Another distinction. “ Among the utilities of which man avails himself some are furnished spontaneously, gratuitously by nature, without any appreciable effort on his part; others, and by far the greater number, he cannot obtain without more or less trouble, if not with the sweat of his brow. Air, light, water UTILITY, VALUE, AND ABUNDANCE OP GOODS 97 are utilities of the former kind, or gratuitous. The properties that human labour confers on matter, such as those of fertility in soil, buildings in stone, machines in iron, and weaving in wool, are utilities of the second kind, or onerous.” (Boccardo, Diz. iv., 545.) The gratuitous utilities are also called natural; the onerous, artificial. It is proper to make a third distinction of goods. Some are offered by nature in such abundance that there is enough, and more than enough, for all, as happens with air and light. There is no reason, therefore, in normal cases, for appropriating them, and hence they are said to be inappropriate. Others, instead, though offered by nature, are limited in quantity ; for example, lands and mines. These are called appropriable. Value .—“ This is of great value to me ” is the expression of a judgment that shows the utility of something for him who wishes to make use of it. Thus a sick man sometimes values a breath of fresh air or a ray of sunshine. Here the word value is identified with that of utility. It means the value of use, an expression that some writers would banish from economic treatises, saying that the word utility suffices. Others wish it to be retained, as that which shows better how the mind appreciates the utility of something. Generally speaking, it is certain that value is often a comparative idea. The utility of one thing is compared with that of another, and a conclusion is drawn as to their equality or inequality. In the former case it is said that one thing is value for another, that they are corn- mutable or exchangeable ; in the latter, it is not so. Barter, accordingly, is the exchange of two equal values : each takes the place of the other in possession. The reason for exchange is altogether subjective : he who parts with value does so because he considers that the value which he receives will be more useful to him. It is clear that the utility of things, or their value of use, is the foundation of their value of exchange. A thing that is not useful is not desired, and no one will give anything to have it. Utility alone, however, does not constitute value. What more useful than air and water ? Yet what value of exchange have they, in normal circumstances ? Another element is needed to complete the idea of value, and it is the difficulty of acquiring the thing that is useful. The first element (utility) is intrinsic and fundamental. The second (difficulty) is extrinsic and acci¬ dental, but it is also necessary and determinative. Some authors place the foundation of value in the cost of a commodity. By cost are understood the expenses, labours, risks, sacrifices, incurred to bring a commodity to an exchange¬ able state. It does not follow that artificial utilities alone would have a value, and natural ones none, because they cost nothing. If this may have had some little truth in primitive society, it cannot well be maintained at the present day. We, all the G 98 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY world, value a commodity according to the service that it renders us by its utility, not according to what its production cost. Wealth .—According to Adam Smith, who is regarded as the father of political economy, wealth is a synonym for value, the value of exchange. He means that only those things which have the capacity of being exchanged for other useful things are wealth. Say and Kicardo held the same opinion. Others, as Boccardo, make wealth a synonym for utility : “ Wealth is all that which serves to satisfy human wants” ( Biz ., iv., 293). Liberatore thinks that appropriable goods alone deserve the name of wealth, and only when they are found in considerable quantity. Section II.— Laws of Value. We must first make a distinction between normal and current value. The normal value is that which is intrinsic to an article of merchandise, comes to it from nature, from the qualities in it, and not from the subjectivities of the moment, either on the part of him who gives or of him who receives. The current value is that which follows the changes of the market. The formulae that express the relations of the different kinds of value with the conditions that accompany merchandise are called laws of value. Let us mention some of them :— 1. “ The value of use, that is, the appreciation of the utility of a thing, is proportional to the nature, gravity, or urgency of the want that the commodity can satisfy, and to the subjective dispositions of him who wishes to use it.” We know that in man there are wants which absolutelv must be satisfied ; and others which, being satisfied, serve only to procure a greater or less degree of wellbeing. As regards the former, necessity pre¬ dominates, and rules the subjective judgment; as regards the latter, the appreciation is arbitrary. Thus it happens that a thing may have value for some, while it has no value for others. Hence justness of ideas, education, moral sentiments, &c., can have an influence on the appreciation of things, and indirectly on the changes of the market. 2. “ The current value of goods stands in a simple ratio to the demand and in an inverse ratio to the supply.” The demand and the supply are two powers that tell on price in the market. A great demand disposes the purchaser to make sacrifices in order to have wares ; a great supply dispenses him from doing so. To find the laws of normal value, we must not forget the dis¬ tinction made between natural and artificial goods. Looking at artificial goods, we observe that some of them are produced in an indefinite quantity; others are of limited production, as, for example, Marsala wine. The law follows :— 3. “ The normal value of artificial goods of indefinite pro¬ duction is determined by their cost, and tends to keep with it.” THEORY OF KARL MARX ON VALUE 99 This law is easily shown to be true. The tailor who makes a coat consumes values or invests them in the coat. It is only natural that an equation should be made between the normal value of the coat and the amount of values consumed, that is to say, the cost. If, on the other hand, I ask a glass of water from a good housewife, who has just drawn it fresh from the well, and she wishes to make me pay, not on account of any trouble that she had in bringing it, but on account of the satisfaction that it gives me, I refuse, and I go to the well myself. In short, utility given is exchanged or sold ; not so with that which is found gratis. The play between demand and supply, to which merchandise is subject in exchange, proves the second part of the law stated. In point of fact, if it happens that by an increased number of consumers the value of merchandise is raised above cost, the producers produce a greater quantity of it, they facilitate the acquisition of it by consumers, and the price is readjusted. Similarly, if the value falls below cost, the producers abstain from production until an equality is re-established. It may happen that various wares of the same kind and the same use cost different sums. What will then be the expression of the normal value ? The lowest, the middle, or the highest ? We distinguish. If the production at the lowest cost can be so abundant as to satisfy the requirements of the market, the lowest cost will be an index of the normal value. But if it is insufficient, the higher cost will then determine the normal value. The producer at the lowest cost is then benefited by the necessity in which the market is placed of having recourse to producers at a higher cost. As for other kinds of goods, the production of which is neces¬ sarily limited, the following law will apply :— 4. “ The normal value of artificial goods of limited increase can exceed the cost of production, which represents the lowest value.” Let us suppose a bottle of true Marsala : above what it cost, the demand and the supply may have a contest, and establish a special value. Even for natural goods there is need of a distinction. There are some that cannot be imitated by art, nor can satisfactory artificial substitutes be found for them. These have no cost; they have, therefore, only a current value. Other natural goods can be imitated by skill, or at least can be replaced by artificial substitutes in the service that they render to man. The normal value of such goods will be regulated by the cost of producing those which are substituted for them. Section III — The Theory of Karl Marx on Value. When we said that the normal value of artificial goods tends to keep near the cost, we were very far from asserting that, among 100 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY the expenses of cost, the labour of man ought not to be counted. To omit it would be injustice. The product costs not only an outlay of capital employed on it, but also an outlay of man’s labour, which labour equals the expenses that are necessary to restore to him his lost strength. Marx, not content with assigning to labour a fair place among the expenses of cost, extends it so far as to absorb all other expenses, and, by making the cost equal to the labour, gives us his theory of value thus :— Value is equal to the labour spent in the production of merchandise. In other words, value is nothing but labour embodied, crystallised : an article of merchandise is worth as much as the labour contained in it. To a first objection against this theory, that one man is slow and another quick at labour, Marx replies that he takes social labour as the unit of comparison, that is, the amount of labour that, making account of social conditions, is normally necessary for the production of anything. This miserable theory, abandoned to-day even by the disciples of Marx, has too many defects to deserve the name of scientific. We, who have studied in facts the idea of value, know what men mean when they say, This is worth that. It is true that Marx would not at all have maintained with so much warmth his theory on value if it had not served him as a hook on which to hang another unfortunate theory regarding the origin of capital. But of this elsewhere. Section IV.—A Moral Foundation. The work of making economy a science or an art entirely autonomous, developing it without any moral idea or principle, finds too many supporters, even among those who have a hundred eyes to shed tears over the economic contests of our day, and not one to see the logical consequences of a material economy that makes no account of morals. We assert that political economy ought to be subject to the laws of morals, not only because human acts are moral acts, but because it should aid in carrying out the designs of Providence. We know that economic goods have one special reason for their existence, which is the use that man makes of them for the attain¬ ment of his last end. We say man in general, that is all mankind, all the human race. Be it that particular individuals, certain conditions being placed, have a right to the use of these goods; still the goods have this destination, to serve all the human race. And that will be a just economic ordering of society in which all mankind will be secured in the use of the goods indispensable for life. It will be just, because the scope intended by nature in regard to such goods will be attained. “ In every well-ordered society,” says the Pope, “ there ought POVERTY AND PAUPERISM 101 to be a sufficient supply of material goods, the use of which is necessary for the practice of virtue ” (Rerum novarum). But virtue is a duty of all mankind. Therefore, there ought to be an abundance of goods for all mankind in a well-ordered society. Thus does God wish society to be constituted. To help in making it such as He wishes is an act of good morals. Justly, therefore, does G. B. Say conclude : “ The study of political economy and the study of morality afford each other a mutual help, without any confusion.” Section V.— Poverty and Pauperism. Goods were created for man, and are continually produced. The position of man with regard to them, by which he has more or less a right to use them, takes special names, which we ought to remember. A man is rich, if he is able to satisfy his various desires. It is clear that there is no state of absolute riches here below, for the great reason that this world was not made by nature to satisfy all human wishes. Man will always be in a state of insufficiency with regard to his desires. He who wants anything is poor, and is said by all to be so. Therefore, all mankind are and always will be poor. To seek perfect riches on earth is to seek what cannot be found. This poverty, however, has innumerable degrees. It is commonly called wealth in him who has abundance of goods to satisfy not only his wants, but his desires of greater wellbeing. It takes the name of ease or sufficiency in him who possesses it without any great difficulty or fatigue for himself or those belong¬ ing to him. It bears the name of poverty in him who wants what is necessary for him, according to his condition. It is called misery, if any one wants what is indispensable for life. “ Pauperism is the state of a number of individuals who are permanently in want of what is absolutely necessary for life.” (Antoine, Corso, &c., p. 608.) It is now easy to understand— 1. That the Author of humanity having appointed that the distribution of goods should be made by property and labour, there will always be poor people in the world. There are always some who, through inability or sloth, do not work, and some who, through punishment or misfortune, are in want of the necessaries of life, according to their condition. These are poor, and to be helped by charity. 2. That, however perfect society may be, it will never succeed in banishing poverty from the face of the earth, because the existence of poor people is an effect of the state in which humanity finds itself. The Pope says :—“ Let it be laid down as a principle that we ought to bear with the condition of humanity. To take all social inequalities from the world would be impossible. The 102 THE ELEMENTS OE POLITICAL ECONOMY Socialists indeed try to do it, but all such attempts against the nature of things are vain.” 3. That there is a poverty which ought to be found in all, and which consists in giving, not only theoretically, but practically, a just appreciation to the things of this earth—regarding them as means bestowed on man for the attainment of his last end. Here the words of the Gospel apply : Blessed are the poor in spirit. 4. That a state of misery is not one of the conditions to which nature has condemned a portion of mankind, but only a con¬ sequence of the conditions in which the human race finds itself. Misery is an exception : it is not the will of God, but is permitted. 5. That poverty is a consequence, not necessary, but eventual and explicable from the vitiated nature of man. Pauperism is an effect of a disordered and unjust social state. 6. That, therefore, that social condition which produces the state of poverty called pauperism is vicious and unnatural. Pauperism differs from poverty in two chief points, (i.) In the cause : poverty comes from misfortune, unforseen changes, idleness, ingratitude, &c. ; pauperism follows social conditions with regard to labour and production, (ii.) In the effect : poverty afflicts this or that individual; pauperism strikes a large number of individuals, and makes a class of the miserable. There are other differences depending on these two. Thus, against poverty a man can often struggle ; against pauperism, never. Poverty is very much the same in extent at all times ; pauperism spreads more or less according to social conditions. Poverty may be fruitful in good : it is often joined with virtue and intelligence. Pauperism is nearly always accompanied with desperation and crime. It is absurd to expect that poverty can be made to disappear altogether from the world : Our Lord says, the poor you have always with you. Pauperism ought to cease : the will of God is that it should cease. The condition of society at the present day is such that pauperism, far from diminishing, is increasing more and more. Unbridled competition, which leaves the weak in the power of the strong—the tax system, which weighs most where it should weigh least—the unprotected state of labour, and, chiefly, the want of conscience with which mutual relations are observed, are all so many causes that nourish pauperism. Section VI.— The Factors in a Eight Ordering of Society. We place here an important question, the solution of which separates us from liberal sociologists. By whose aid ought a right social ordering to be effected ; and, in a special manner, ought the State to interfere with its heavy hand in the production, distribution, &c., of the national riches ? Liberalism answers thus :—“ Individual activity ought to be FACTORS IN A RIGHT ORDERING OF SOCIETY 103 the only factor in regard to the economic position of the citizens. The work of individuals, who oppose and rival one another in the market with a view to their private wellbeing, necessarily creates a condition of things that is beneficial for all the citizens. There is a necessary connection between individual and general pros¬ perity : the former being procured, the latter follows. The State ? Why should the State interfere ? It fulfils its office by being the guardian of individual rights.” In these last words, which show us the erroneous idea that liberalism has of the State, we find the principle that gives rise to economic liberalism, or the system of free competition, accord¬ ing to which it is said that political economy ought to be governed. We might a priori demonstrate how such a theory conflicts with the organic idea of society, with the task that ought to be a special one of the State, and with the most elementary know¬ ledge of the nature of man. We cannot permit that anyone should call us tyrants, or enemies of individual liberty, because we refute the assertions of socialists. We are ready to admit the advantages of free competition, and to defend it in that just measure which the order of things requires. But from the fact that it is attended with some benefits, there is ground to conclude, by a general assertion, that every social economic good is to be traced to free competition, this we cannot admit—just as, while we recognise the benefits of rain, we cannot admit that rain alone will help the fields. The liberalists have written many pages to prove the advantages of free competition in all the vicissitudes through which the markets pass. But many who can argue marvellously on economic laws do not take into account that the application of those laws is entrusted to the free activity of man, and that this too often is not cold or dumb like an economic law, but is subject to the continual breath of human passions, which can turn it out of its natural course. The weak elements have precious interests which in the fluctua¬ tions of free competition can thus be lost—all for the advantage of the insatiable selfishness of the strong. But the erroneousness of economic liberalism is much better shown by its disastrous effects than by subtle disquisitions ; because, with misfortune for all, liberalism has reduced its prin¬ ciples to practice. Capitalism, pauperism, the isolation of the work¬ man, the idleness of multitudes, are the sad consequences of liberal individualism. Alarmed thereby, some of the most earnest supporters of liberalism invoke here and there the intervention of the State. It is a fact well known and felt at the present day that the actual state of society, which is a fruit of. liberalism, cannot be maintained. It ought to be changed. 1 Hence arise two classes of men:— 1. Socialists, who refer all the disastrous effects occasioned by 104 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY economic liberalism to tbe existence of private property, and therefore wish to see it abolished, communism being sub¬ stituted in its place. 2. Social Christians, who wish that a just economic ordering of society should be produced by three factors, (i.) Private Activity. Those who rank as masters or operatives in the economic world ought to govern their mutual relations according to justice, and to be guided by the light of a right social conscience. Leo XIII. therefore calls all to labour for the solution of the social question, which is in great part an economic one. (ii.) The Church. “Nor is it to be supposed that the Church is so entirely devoted to the care of souls that she forgets what pertains to a mortal and earthly life. She wishes and strives most earnestly that the proletariat may emerge from their miser¬ able state and attain to a better condition. And herein she gives no small aid by calling and training men to virtue. For Christian morals, when they are preserved truly such, contribute by themselves to worldly prosperity. . . . The Church concurs directly to the welfare of the proletariat by creating and promoting whatever can contribute to their relief. Nay, in conferring benefits of this kind, she so signalises herself that she elicits the praise even of her enemies.” (Rerum novarum.) (iii.) The State. We refer elsewhere to the duty of the State with regard to the assistance of private activity and the protection of the weak. Rulers ought in the first place to concur to the settlement of the social question “ with all the power of laws and institutions, administering the affairs of the State in such a manner that the natural result may be public and private prosperity.” ( Rerum novarum .) Themes. —Political Economy is both a science and an art—Can a nation «/ that has many great waterfalls be called rich ?—Rossi has asserted that value is “ an expression of the relation that exists between human wants and things in general” : this definition is to be rejected—The Christian idea of riches—It is only in accordance with the Christian idea that riches have a social function—Man can honestly propose to himself to arrive at his greatest wellbeing in this world on condition (i.) of keeping his activity submissive to moral laws, and (ii.) of seeking his advancement through labour—Smith says that the human race is a great commercial society, and every man a trafficker—It has been asserted that value is not in proportion to the intrinsic utility of things, but rather to the service rendered by the producer. (See Boccardo, Econ. Pol. I. 23.) If Christian resignation is a duty, when is it a duty ? and is it a duty in the present state of the poor ?—An economic equality of all mankind is not only impossible, and, if attempted, could not last, but it is irreconcilable with the social condition of man—The wellbeing of man is to be expected only in part from economic goods—What the Church has done for the well¬ being of peoples—The abandonment of Christian principles—above, of justice and charity towards the poor, and below, of mutual solidarity— iB the cause of present social disorders. THE PRODUCTIVE PROCESS 105 CHAPTER II. PRODUCTION AND DISTRIBUTION OF GOODS^ [As Brants has done, we here treat of two subjects together, and this because we believe that it is more natural to do so, and that the reader will thus more easily perceive the connection between producer and product. Let us explain. When studying production, we see the nature of a product, its causes appear distinctly to us, and we weigh the degrees of causality. If immediately we proceed to distribution, the reader does not forget any of the elementary ideas that ought to guide us to an equal distribution, and by one act of the mind he connects, as is ^natural, the production and the distribution of goods. We hope that we are not mistaken.] Section I.— The Productive Process. Man avails himself of the goods of this world. He gathers them to him, applies them to his uses, and by them, if we may so speak, fills up the voids within him, which are called wants. One thing is required, and it is that these goods should have a relation to the wants of man, so that they may satisfy him. They are then immediately useful, because this alone is required that he may apply them to himself or may not abstain from their application. Some goods are placed by nature in a state of immediate utility ; for example, air and light. Others have need of being elaborated—brought to such a state of fitness that they may be immediately useful to man. This can and should be the work of man himself. Immediate utility is the whole reason for appreciating such goods. In a state of mere potential utility, man could not appreciate them ; they would be for him as if they did not exist. Hence the bringing of a thing from a state of potential utility to a state of actual or immediate utility is justly called production. It also happens that a thing, from a state of immediate utility with regard to one want, may pass to a like state with regard to another. This is also called production, because it is always true that the thing has, under the hands of man, gone through a process by which it has acquired a utility that was not in it before. And production is precisely that operation by which new utilities are created. “ A grave error was committed by the Physiocrats* and is committed every day by the multitude, supposing that pro¬ duction consists in bringing into existence things that did not exist before : an error from which arose the famous theory of some French economists, who held that agriculture alone among industries deserves the title of productive, as that which alone * The leader of the Physiocrats was a Frenchman, Francis Quesney (1694-1774). He regarded land as the only source of wealth, taking no account of labour or capital.— Trans, 106 THE ELEMENTS OE POLITICAL ECONOMY creates new matters—adds new things to those from which man derives advantage. “ Whatever may be the kind of industry in which human labour is excercised, it never produces things, but utilities. The labour of all men united could not succeed in forming the smallest particle of matter, as it could not succeed in destroying or annihilating the least atom. To weave a piece of cloth is nothing but to arrange threads of wool in a peculiar manner, more suited to the use for which they are intended. To make a field of wheat or a plantation of trees grow is nothing but to place a certain matter, called seed, in such conditions that it can assimilate to itself the elements of other matters, drawn from air, earth, and water, and thus form a new combination called a plant.” (Boc., Diz., iv., 206.) From what has been said, it is understood that production is very often the destruction of one or more utilities for the acquisi¬ tion of a greater utility. Many a time it happens that the utility of a thing with regard to human -wants in general makes no increase whatever, because the thing undergoes no transformation. It merely changes place ; for example, it passes from a place where there is abun¬ dance of it to another where it is scarce—which is done by means of commerce. This is also called production, because it is always true that the object is brought into a state of immediate utility, which it had not before. We may give the name of productive process to that series of operations necessary to bring an object from the state in which it is found to a state of immediate utility that is desired. It is a laborious process, for it implies the consumption of human strength, of values often great and various, which are called the expenses or the cost of production. The valuation of the product will be the result found by subtract¬ ing the value that the object had, plus the sum of the values of all the expenses of production, from the value that it has acquired. If there is a remainder, the production is remunerative—so much the more as the remainder is greater. This is because the utility introduced into the object is so much more appreciated than the sum of the different utilities that were consumed during the productive process. And if there is no remainder, must we say that production is useless ? No : an advantage has been gained. Values have been destroyed, it is true, but they revive in the product. During the production, moreover, the producers have lived : and this is an advantage. Does not humanity live by the destruction of values ? and if these do good in any way the service rendered by them is an,advantage. Only in the case that the value produced is less than the values consumed, can or should it be said that the pro¬ duction was disadvantageous for the producer or for society. Laws of Production .—Hence it is understood how the climax THE FACTORS IN PRODUCTION 107 of production is reached when the remainder after the subtraction mentioned above increases daily more and more, and how the fundamental law of production is, 44 The maximum by means of the minimum.” Thus the net product will always become more abundant. It is also called income or revenue, from which results the wealth of society. The abundance of a product is not always and wholly for the advantage of him who produces it. Oftentimes it happens that the advantage is all for society and nothing for the producer. If the greater abundance of a product finds in the market the same price as at first, the income of the producer is undoubtedly increased. But if the competition of producers causes a fall in price, a greater supply of the product will turn to the advantage of the consumers, not of the producers. We must not, however, forget that production has naturally as its scope to serve the needs of all civil society by means of consumption. This consideration suggests some other laws to which pro¬ duction is subject. “ Production ought to be proportionate to consumption ”— that is, it ought to be regulated by the wants for which consump¬ tion is required. A product has value inasmuch as it is useful, and it is useful inasmuch as it satisfies a want. If we take away the want, then—weighing every circumstance of to-day and to-morrow—the product has no longer any utility or value. The over-production of an article may occasion evils for producers as well as for workpeople—leading to idleness, vice, &c. “ Production ought to be subordinate to the moral and religious interests of humanity.”—The reasonableness of this law appears from almost every point of view in Christian sociology. The economic man is to be at the service of the moral and religious man. Hence the production of whatever offends good morals ought to be prevented; and the productive process ought to be carried on in such a way as to respect them. Even the preserva¬ tion of the life of man is a moral work ; therefore, confections of noxious elements ought to be prohibited. When a value is consumed in the process of production, we say that it renders a productive service. When, on the other hand, no value succeeds to a value consumed, then there is a mere destruction of utility, and the service is said to be unproductive ; such, for example, is the service of the wine with which I allay thirst. Section II.— The Factors in Production. It is very natural to man to provide for his wants. These wants calling for satisfaction, and the shyness of nature to grant the means, unless constrained to do so, persuade him very soon to 108 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY apply himself to the work of production. To find out the factors in production, we have, therefore, only to examine facts. And facts, in every productive operation, show us always a skilful hand, an object on which this hand works, and an instru¬ ment or means of which it makes use. So it is with the man who tills the field ; so it is with the sculptor who shapes the marble ; so it is always. Do we not here see the factors in pro¬ duction ? They are (i.) nature ; (ii.) labour ; and (iii.) capital. We must not, however, regard these three agents as separated from the person of man, who with his mind and hand directs and governs the productive operation. We shall see in due time how nature acts when 'possessed, by man, how capital springs up and increases under the care of the proprietor—to say nothing of labour, which, apart from man, is not even conceivable, whether we consider the labour of the brains or the labour of the hands. Hence three positions from which men concur to production : as land proprietors, as capitalists, and as industrialists. These three agents should aid one another in the work of production. This result is secured by special contracts, of which it will be necessary to speak. Section III.— Harmony in Work. Facts demonstrate that the abundance and perfection of a product are more notable according as the union of the three agents, nature, labour, and capital, is more strict. It is, therefore, the design of nature that the greatest harmony should reign among them—the source of so much individual and social good. Hence we infer that men, who are respectively invested with proprietorship over nature, over capital, and over labour should—according to the intention of the Creator— agree well together. “In the present question it is a great mistake to suppose that one class is inimical to another, as if nature had made the rich and the poor to be struggling in a continual duel. This is so opposed to reason that, on the contrary, it is most true that, as in the human body the various members agree together and form that order which is called symmetry, so nature desires that the said two classes should live in concord and thus form an equilibrium. Each has need of the other : capital cannot do without labour, nor labour without capital.” {Rerum novarum.) But harmony between moral beings, of unequal condition, ought to be the effect of justice first, and then of charity. Who¬ ever among them finds himself stronger ought not to abuse his strength to the prejudice of others. Not enough. As it is for production for oneself and for the whole human race that the productive faculties are given, and this scope is not attainable without the intimate union of which we speak, we ought to A GREAT PROBLEM 109 sacrifice every particle of self-love. And is the proprietor the stronger ? Let him remember that by an ordinance of nature his lot is not separated from that of the labourer, who is, of necessity, weaker. To this weakness, his strength ought to extend a helping hand. It ought to exercise that material and moral guardianship which every master, let him be a proprietor or a capitalist or an industrialist, owes to his dependants, and which bears the name of Christian Patronage. To this the Pope alluded when he said : “We wish that they (the more 'prominent citizens) would consider that they are not free to care or not about the poor ; they are truly bound to have suph care.” (Encyc. Graves de communi re.) This patronage implies 1. That the labourer ought to be secured beforehand against cases of misfortune. 2. That some plan should be adopted to supply him with means of living in old age, when he can no longer work. On this point, Father Lapeyre, treating of Catholic association, maintains that to farm labourers there ought to be assigned a pension not in money, but in the enjoyment of some land. The learned writer adds that the State could prevent any alienation or sequestration of such ground. A mortgage for old age would thus be taken on the youth of the labourer. By this means the labourer would not be tempted to seek the town, there to enjoy his pension with injury to the family life, which ought not to be brought into troubles away from the cultivation of the beautiful country. 3. The labourer ought to have the protection of his employer, and to feel the benefit of a true and sincere affection. Section IV.—A Great Problem. The distribution of goods is a great problem that interests humanity, and that, not being well solved, gives rise to many and most serious inconveniences—individual, domestic, and social. It is a problem of justice, of morals, of Divine Providence. It consists in this. Worldly goods, of whatever kind, are destined by nature to serve for the satisfaction of all mankind. To answer this purpose, they should pass into the possession of the individual, who, by consumption, destroys what is appreciable in them. And these goods are not originally in the possession of anyone. Nature did not consign to any individual a single particle of worldly goods. By what law is everyone to obtain his respective part ? If in the world there were only a precise quantity of goods, and of those goods alone which are absolutely necessary to maintain life, one single rule would suffice, that of dividing in equal parts the whole mass among all human beings. But nature was 110 THE ELEMENTS OE POLITICAL ECONOMY generous : it lavished goods on humanity ; it gave them not only for the wants but for the conveniences of life. How then are they to be distributed ? Has nature, which did not make the distribution, given us any rules, at least in substance, on the matter, and, if so, what are they ? Here they are :— 1. There are in the world some goods that escape the private possession of everyone. By this fact nature has clearly shown that it does not wish these goods to come into anyone's possession. 2. Of appropriable goods—just because such—nature permits the appropriation, provided it does not interfere with the use that the whole human race should make of them. 3. Nature also wishes the private appropriation of goods, which serves to bring about more easily and fully the object for which they were intended. 4. Nearly all worldly goods are rendered useful to man by means of services for which man fits them. In the same manner as the creation of worldly goods constitutes creative nature their absolute mistress, so the fact by which new utilities are introduced into these goods ought to give to the agents who have a share in it a right of mastership over them. If, therefore, man, as proprietor, capitalist, or labourer, concurs to their production, the produce ought to be his in proportion. 5. Where—in any region—neither proprietorship nor labour gives the quota of produce necessary for human life, there beneficence ought to make its contribution. No creature should perish through want of those means which nature has given in abundance for the subsistence of all. These general rules are the foundation on which Christian economy proceeds in the distribution of the goods of this lower world. Justice and charity are their substance. Section Y.—Proprietorship or Ownership. To arrive at an accurate analysis of the idea of proprietorship or ownership we must set forth clearly the natural relations, or those which nature has placed, between man and the external world. Man ought to live. The external world ought to supply him with the means—on one condition, that he should labour. This world was given to man, not as an individual, but as a species. He then labours, not as a species, but as an individual. The world, in so far as given by nature, has the same relations with all the individuals of the human species. In so far as it ought to be worked by individuals, that it may yield fruit for all, it enters into special relations with those who work it. Can these be relations of ownership ? Let us first of all see what ownership means. The idea of owner¬ ship is elementary ; it is one of those ideas which constitute the PROPRIETORSHIP OR OWNERSHIP 111 patrimony of common sense. To analyse it exactly is, therefore, not easy ; yet to do so is a thing of the utmost importance. We proceed to the attempt with brevity. If I see a man holding an umbrella in his hand, and consider that he not only uses it to keep off the rain, but may make a present of it, or may sell it, and will not allow anyone to snatch it out of his hand, I say that it is his property, or he has the ownership of it. From this fact, which the idea of ownership has suggested to me, I infer that, to constitute it, the right of using a thing is not enough, but one should be able to give it away, and to drive off any person who would try to hinder its use. Ownership, therefore, includes—(i.) a positive right to dispose of a thing as we please, and (ii.) a negative or defensive right, to prevent the thing from passing into the hands of others. Let us now return to our example. There are two facts con¬ nected with the man who carries the umbrella. In the first I see that he may throw it into a fire, and reduce it to ashes, to be blown away by the winds. In the second I see another man who, with a strong arm, snaps the umbrella out of his hand, and takes it off with him. A feeling of reproof and condemnation rises in my soul at each occurrence. In the first case I see a man who abuses what belongs to him. The thing possessed is not absolutely his: it is his because the absolute owner has granted it to him that it may be of service to him. In other words, God, who is the Absolute Master of all things, has given this thing not to him directly, but to mankind, that it may serve them. The power of an individual to take a thing to himself and make it his own is not directly from God, but consequently on the established order. To withdraw things from the design for which God created them and gave them to mankind, is what no owner can lawfully do. He, however, who reduces a thing possessed to such a state that it can no longer be of service to any man, does not offend against what is called commutative justice, which is a relation between two particular individuals, and carries with it the obliga¬ tion of restitution. He does not offend against this justice solely because there is wanting an individual who has for himself alone a right to the use of a thing. But truly he offends against divine justice, which wishes that things created for a purpose should attain it, and does not allow that anyone should hinder them from doing so. To this Absolute Master he should in some manner make satisfaction. He sins also against society, which has a right to use this thing that God created for mankind. A proprietor should always remember that, if the ownership of a thing is his, yet the use of it is, under given conditions, common to the whole human race. Liberalism has created an idea of ownership that cannot be maintained; it is contrary to the designs of the Creator; it is unnatural. Liberalism has substituted the absolute for the 112 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY relative, and constituted the owner a despot over that which he owns. It has removed his obligations from the tablets of the moral law. Accordingly, he stands free from all responsibility, before God and man, in the use of what he calls his own. Owner¬ ship thus conceived, no reason appears why there should be any condemnation for prodigality, luxury, dissipation, &c. But, we repeat, this idea of ownership cannot be admitted. There is a general scope for which God has destined useful things, and from which there should be no deviation: it is the service of the whole human race. Every idea that we form of private ownership ought to be subordinate to this general scope, over the attainment of which God Himself watches. If, under the regime of private ownership, this scope is hindered, ownership goes beyond its limits and requires to be brought back to its duty. The point is this: the reason for the world, external to man, is the service that it renders to the whole human race. Take away this end, and, in the actual order of things, no purpose for its existence can be found. Now, that an individual may possess himself of a thing with the view of attaining fully the end designed by the Creator, we can understand, and it is all right. That he may withdraw the thing from the attainment of this end, either by depriving it of an aptitude for attaining such end, or by turning it entirely to his own service, is absolutely wrong. In such case the thing does not realise the intentions of the Creator ; on the contrary, it frustrates them. From these considerations we conclude:— 1. An owner has not a right to abuse a thing possessed : he cannot destroy it, nor deprive it of the powers with which nature supplies it. 2. He cannot deny the fruits of it to his brethren who have need of them, and who are willing to comply with the conditions that justice requires, so as to attain the scope intended by the Creator. 3. The only admissible idea of a private owner is the evangelical one, which makes him an administrator of goods for the whole human race ; and in this point there is perfect harmony between faith and reason. 4. The idea of ownership given by St. Thomas is true : it should, he says, be so conceived that the thing may be one's own, but the use of it common. According to these ideas, the assertion is very logical that private property has a social function which the owner ought to keep in view when exercising his rights. “ And let no one," says Weiss, “regard this as an injury to personal power, because no one exists outside the social body, nor can anyone be imagined without obligations towards the solidarity of human interests." * * The following remarks of Abbe Naudet in his little work on Sociology (chap, v.) are very just:—“ Say to one of onr great proprietors that he has no right to leave his lands uncultivated, that the land should nourish RIGHT AND EFFECTS OF OWNERSHIP 113 Pope Leo XIII. teaches the social function of ownership, and shows its advantages thus :— “ We have seen that this labour question cannot be solved unless we take as a principle that private ownership should be held sacred. The laws, therefore, ought to favour this right, and to encourage as many as possible to become owners. “ Many advantages will follow from this; and, first of all, a more equal division of national wealth. Revolutions have separated the citizens into two castes, differing widely from each other. On the one side, a powerful faction, because exceedingly rich : which, having in its grasp all kinds of production and traffic, exhausts all the sources of wealth, and exercises great influence on the affairs of State. On the other side, a weak and needy multitude, with ulcerated minds, always ready for dis¬ turbance. Now, if the industry of this multitude were roused with the hope of obtaining some ownership in land, the one class would gradually draw nearer to the other, an end being put to the immense distance between extreme poverty and enormous wealth. “ Moreover, there would be a greater supply in the fruits of the earth. When men know that they work on their own ground, they tire themselves far more willingly; nay, they learn to love the soil cultivated by their own hands, from which they expect not only food, but an abundance of good things for them¬ selves and their families. It is easy to understand how such alacrity tends to increase the produce of the land and the wealth of the nation. “ Another advantage would follow—attachment to their native place. Men would not exchange their own country for a foreign one, if their own enabled them to lead a tolerable life.” (Rerum novarum.) Section VI.— The Right and the Effects of Ownership. The idea of private ownership having been explained, let us see if a right exists to it. We have seen that such a right could be given ; we have now to inquire if it has been given. There are in man some goods so personal that the discussion whether they belong to him who has them cannot be serious. man and not be used, in vast extent, as a hunting-ground for idlers. The great proprietor will look at you in astonishment, and candidly answer : ‘ The land is my own, and I can do what I like with it.’ He is mistaken. He imagines himself honest, and he is in error. He is evidently ignorant of his social duty, because, as Monsignor Ketteler observes in one of his admir¬ able discourses, the doctrine that makes man the God of his property—that gives him the right to destroy the fruits of property, which he ought to distribute among his poor brethren—that gives him the right to satisfy his unbridled sensuality as he pleases, is a doctrine not only unchristian, but unnatural.” — Trans . H 114 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY My mind is mine, the moral energy that carries me to study is mine, just as much as strength belongs to the man who digs with his spade. Such goods nature gives to the individual, and they are naturally his. But of goods that are external to man, can he have ownership ? Masters in natural law bring forward an abundance of arguments to prove that private ownership is a natural right. We w T ill summarise here the arguments of which the Pontiff makes use in Rerum novarum :— 1. There ought to be a proportion between him who uses a thing and the thing itself. Man makes use of the things of this world, and so does the beast. But man excels the beast by reason. Besides the use of external goods, which is proper even to the beast, we must allow to man something more that corresponds to reason, with which he is enriched. This something more is ownership, of which rational creatures, who can adapt the means to the end, are alone capable. As man is rational, he provides for himself against the future. But this cannot be done other¬ wise than by private ownership, with which he secures the means of existence for the morrow. 2. Nature does not yield fruit without labour. But he who labours on a field leaves, as it were, an impress of his own person¬ ality on it. This personality, though infused into an object, does not cease to belong to the labourer. On the other side, it is so incorporated with the object as to make one thing with it. “ Seeing that, to obtain the goods of nature, man employs the industry of his mind and the strength of his body, he thereby makes his own that part of the earth which he brings into cultiva¬ tion, and on which he leaves, as it were, the impress of his personality ; so that he may justly possess that part as his own, and no one has a right to molest him in doing so.” 3. The Pontiff adds the consent of the human race in practically recognising the right of the individual to private ownership, and the sanction that divine and human laws have always given to such a right. We will add an argument that St. Thomas sets forth in an admirable light. There is no need to demonstrate that the means of living for the individual as well as for society, must be derived by labour from nature, and that production will be so much the more abundant as labour will be the more assiduous, but take away from man the right of ownership, and let him learn that the ground on which he works is not his own, that the fruit of his toil and diligence will not be his own, and what will you see ? . . . You will see the spade fall from his hands, and the thoughtful head of the scientist, who is building castles in the air for some new invention, begin to nod with sleep. Ah, com¬ munism ! Communism is a system of universal poltroonery, and, therefore, of famine for all. “ If the way were opened to envy, recrimination, and discord—every stimulus being taken from individual genius and industry—the very sources of riches would DUTIES OF AUTHORITY TO OWNERSHIP 115 be dried up; and the dreamt-of equality would be nothing in fact but universal abjection and misery/’ (Rerum novarum.) If, therefore, without private ownership, the means intended by nature for the preservation of civil society cannot be procured, and this preservation is an ordinance of nature, we must say that private ownership is also an ordinance of nature. Effects of Ownership ).—If the right of the individual to the appropriation of goods cannot be denied, what effect does this right produce in him, when he is lawfully in possession of it ? There are two consequences of ownership. The first is that the owner can dispose at his pleasure of the thing owned. He can, therefore, sell it, make a present of it, &c., within the limits of the just rights of ownership well conceived. The second is that the owner—just because he is the owner—is the master of those products, or of those parts of a product, which are true effects of the productiveness of the thing possessed. The effect being proper to the cause, it should pertain to him to whom the cause itself pertains. 2 Section YII.—Duties of Political Authority with regard to Ownership. To derive the right of private ownership from the supreme authority was, and perhaps still is, a foolish idea of economists not distinguishing well between one thing and another. Political authority— 1. Should safeguard the rights of private ownership : both because the violation of them grievously injures the right of individuals, and because it is disastrous to the public weal. “ It is a principal duty of rulers to secure private ownership by wise laws. It is most necessary, in these times of unrestrained greed, that the people should be kept to their duty ; for, though all may justly strive to improve their condition, yet neither justice nor the public good allows any one to seize the property of another, under the absurd pretence of making an equality in fortunes.” (Rerum novarum.) 2. It can and should, when morality, the public safety, or the public welfare requires it, place limits to the use of private owner¬ ship. Hence the laws that forbid men to carry arms, to sell poisons, &c. 3. It can and should make enactments with regard to services, rights of way, &c. 4. It can, if expedient, limit the rights of hunting, cutting wood, fishing, &c. 5. It has a right of expropriation when the public good requires such, and it exercises the same with the least possible injury to private good. 116 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECO NOME 6. It can and should guard the right of inheritance, and modify it with a view to the welfare of families. 7. In resard to minors, wonem persons misbie to manage their property, it has a right to limit or even to prevent the use thereof. b - xes.—D r. Render said, * ' It is not only an anti-Chgis tian bntaaaMifc- natcral doctrine that makes man a God over his substance, are grants he. the rinht to terra to the satisfaction er his pleasures and his tnrestrained sensuality those fruits of property wmzh he onnnt to distribute among his poor brethren."—Cement IT. in the 13th century permitted, to strangers the cultivation of the third part of an estate on which the owner obstinately refused to permit any : mem: :m by what right !—d: :o*dxng to Henry George.* private ownership is the cause of the intolerable inecuRides that exist am:n-r men—line same e:::e asserts that tae my means :: abolishing present pauperism. whiz-h in z reuses day by day. is me abolition of private ownership—Su Thomas admits that it may in a certain sense be said that God wished the earth to be the common patrimony of ah 2a, 2 m q. lxvL. a. 2 —The difference b*etween ownership and possession—Ownership supposes reason and liberty—What class of people are enemies of pmvate ownership ?— If present social disorders are owing to private ownership 1—Socialism would not remedy present social disorders—What remedies are suggested by Christian Democracy ? CHAPTEE m. 1 ABUNDANCE OF WORLDLY GOODS. Section L—Nattbe. As some philosophers. given to atheism. speak often of nature to avoid mention of God. so sene economists, seized with, a similar desire, speak often of labour, and avoid mention of God even under the name of nature, as if artificial riches were the produce of human activity alone. This slur thrown on nature is unjust, F or on what would the labour of man fad if not on nature 7 It is absurd to suppose that an arm wielded in vacancy can produce anything. Examining nature in connection with the wants of mam to satisfy which it was created, we hud it enriched with a great abundance of elements and powers. Of natural elements, some are brought by nature itself to a state of immediate utility, as fruits : others require to be dug up. as iron : others have to be worked on. and so placed in a condition to be consumed, as wheat. The Creator has given certain powers to nature, by means of which a produce passes to a more or less advanced state of maturity or perfection Of tnese powers some are organic! as the vegetative in plants and reproductive in animals: others * An American author (1539-lStf7b who wrote several books on Land questions. It was only to private ownership in lard that he was opposed. He taught respect for private ownership in everything else.— Tram. THE EARTH 117 are inorganic, as cohesion, gravity, attraction, &c. These powers man can increase, regulate, apply in such a way as to obtain a more abundant, speedy, perfect production. To deny all this abundance of elements and pow T ers that nature supplies to production is necessarily to mistake facts, and to oppose what they clearly teach. Whoever attentively examines productive facts sees at once that the various goods which nature provides for production are diversified in the relations that they can have with man, and in the ways in which they can concur to productive operation. The cultivable earth is certainly the most important of the pro¬ ductive instruments prepared by nature. A waterfall, a mine, a spa, are elements that concur to production in a manner different from that of cultivable ground: but, in common with it, they can enter into the ownership of man. The heat of the sun, the force of the wind, &e., differ in this, that they cannot be appropriated ; but everyone can use them to obtain products. It is, indeed, true that a man with knowledge and skill can obtain from such free elements some special services that a man without ability cannot derive from them. And thus, in a certain way, he takes possession of them; but it is an indirect possession— that is to say, through owning the means that are adapted to obtain such special services. Section II. —The Earth. Providence concurs to the work of production by the power that it continually infuses through natural agencies. Between these agencies a difference must be pointed out: some act as direct causes of production ; others instead as simple instruments that help the work of man. We treat of the former in this section, as they represent nature in its productive work; and we bring them all together under one name, The Earth. The earth produces very little of itself : it requires the labour of man. Man by labour draws the earth near to him, makes it his fellow-labourer, with a view to reap fruit from it. Nature has deposited in the earth a productive virtue, by which it prepares within itself in the most admirable manner the elements of produce. The earth is a producer only in the sense given by us to the word “ production ” : it has not a creative, but a transforming power. If we analyse chemically a little stalk of corn, we find elements that were in the ground by the disposition of nature, or placed there under the form of manure by the hand of man, or drawn from the atmosphere. Accordingly, the earth may well be called a machine, which elaborates certain materials, in order to restore them afterwards in elements of consumption for man. 118 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY Section III. —Land Ownership. Our ancestors showed that they had very precise ideas about the services that the earth renders to the human race when they called it a kind mother ( alma parens). In the same spirit Sully remarks that tillage and pasturage are the two great paps that nourish the human race. We are not going to assert that the cultivation of the earth is alone fruitful. Some have said and written so, but they have said and written wrong. Only a false idea of production could lead to such a strange opinion. We say that even other industries, which, by modifying or transforming the fruits of the earth, adapt them to supply our wants, are productive. We recognise, however, that the earth is the first mother of all pro¬ ductions, that its fruits are the basis of all utilities, and that agriculture is the queen of industries. What, indeed, do other industries do but work on the “ rough materials ” that the earth after labour has given to them ? Hence a special importance attaches to land riches before all others. For if goods are to be valued by the utility that they render to men, land is the place on which all other goods can be raised. Thus Weiss says :—“ Land property united with labour is the primitive form of capital. All forms of movable capital can be reduced to this, and ought to permit of being so reduced— otherwise they are not capital in reality.” (p. 478.) On account of this special importance that agriculture has over other industries, it is highly proper that the owner of land should exercise his social functions and discharge the duties of Christian patronage towards his dependants, lest ownership being dis¬ sociated from labour, the most necessary of industries should be neglected.* “ We do not grow weary of repeating that ownership in general, and land ownership in particular, is not—no, it is not a sinecure, a mere title to income, a guarantee of individual wellbeing, as it was understood in the ancient law of Pagan Rome, and much less is it that open field for the speculation of capitalists which the new paganism of classic economy would make it; but it is an office, a mission, a right confirmed and ennobled by the task of a social function, as has been proclaimed by the Rome of Christian ages, from St. Paul to Leo XIII. Riches, like personal faculties, are subordinated in the plan of nature to purposes assigned for him who holds them, whether as an individual or as a sharer in civil community, and consequently they imply grave responsibilities, both individual and social.” So said Mauri at the Congress of Padua. ( Atti , p. 150.) * A very interesting and instructive book, Contemporary Ireland, by a French gentleman, Mr. L. Paul-Bubois, has lately (1908) appeared. It would be well for Ireland if Englishmen understood Irish affairs as thoroughly as this Frenchman.— Trans. LAND RETURN 119 Section IV. —Land Return. In common language we say that revenue or income or return is the net produce of a productive operation. But we have seen that every produce can be the effect of several causes. Now that fraction of the land produce which is due to the productive force of the soil or farm takes the name of “ land return/'" Let us give an example. Titus sows a quintal of wheat value for 32 lire * ; he spends about 50 lire in manuring it, and 70 lire in wages to labourers. He obtains in produce ten quintals of wheat value for 300 lire. This procluce is due in proportion partly to labour ; partly to capital, that is, seed, manure, plough, &c. ; and partly to the natural powers of the soil. This last portion is called the “ land return.” Hence the difference is seen between return and rent. The rent is the sum paid to the owner for the temporary use of the land in the state in which it is found, and, therefore, with the things that are on it, with the capital invested in it, and making account also of circumstances in which the ground is placed—circumstances that can raise or lower the rent. The “ return ” takes its place in the amount of rent, because no owner gives for nothing the vegetative forces of his land; and, looking into the rent, we shall find, besides the portion that is due as interest on capital, that portion also which corresponds to compensation for the use of the productive forces of the soil. This is the “ land return.” The same quantity of wheat being sown in different fields, and the same amount of capital and labour being expended on it, the produce is not the same; it varies from field to field. Whence the difference ? From the difference of the productive qualities of the respective fields. Therefore, the productive force is not the same in all lands, and accordingly the return is not the same. But return is the fruit of every ground, because in every ground we find productive powers. In every agricultural produce there is a portion that is due to the natural force of the soil from which it is drawn. The Pope calls this productive force “ an inexhaustible fecundity.” ( Rerum novarum.) From these brief remarks it may be gathered that the return is something positive and absolute, as regards the soil, in which are the natural and indestructible forces of production, and as regards the produce, of which a part is undoubtedly due to the aforesaid productiveness. Ricardo, an English economist, framed a theory on return that is certainly very ingenious, and as such deserving of the applause with which it was hailed, but in reality apt only to generate * The word “ quintal ” is derived from L. centum, a hundred. It denotes a measure of 100 Ihs. The Italian lira is equal to about ten pence English. Lire, the plural, is pronounced much like Leary.— Trans. 120 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY confusion, and to take away from return that absolute and positive character which we recognise in it. He substituted a relative for the absolute character of return. He mistook return for its valuation. When is there return according to Ricardo ? Return arises when, in any region, after the cultivation of the better lands, the cultivation of the worse is turned to. The same capital and the same labour spent on the two kinds of land give a greater produce in the former and a less in the latter. The difference is the land return. Even on the same land (still according to Ricardo) the return may be made sensible. Cultivated with a coefficient of 100 between capital and labour, it gives 1,000. If I add a second capital of 100, I shall not have a produce of 2,000, but of 1,700. The difference is due to the strength of the soil, and is the return. We reject this theory, which, if it does not annul the positive existence of land return, never appreciates it, and thus leads to disastrous consequences. Other economists have waged a more exterminating war against land return. They absolutely and always deny it. Their principle is that everything comes from labour. Why does one piece of land produce more than another ? Because it carries labour -within it, spent on it in the past, and capital that was introduced, also a fruit of labour. Marx, setting out from another principle, that all value comes from labour incorporated in produce, arrives at the same con¬ sequence—that is, there ought to be nothing for the owner of a farm by reason of the possession of the farm. If, therefore, a man lets land, to take a price as compensation for the productive¬ ness of the land let by him to a tenant is an injustice. After the arguments used, nothing remains for us but to conclude. Every piece of land is in a way to produce, and, certain conditions being given, does in fact produce a utility, which is called its return. This return belongs to him w r ho lawfully owns the land, because the effect follows the owmer of the cause. Section Y.—Which is the Best Form oe Ownership ? The existence of owners of land follows as a consequence from the state of human affairs. But owners may have small or large properties. And here the question a-rises : which is the best kind of ownership—the small, or the large, or any other ? An excessive smallness of ownership, that which makes neither a people of owners nor a people of beggars, carries with it great inconveniences, and cannot be called useful. It does not place the owner in a position to procure the coefficients of a culture truly productive. Economically, in short, it has a bad effect. Socially it has also another effect to be feared—a proletariat WHICH IS THE BEST FORM OF OWNERSHIP? 121 of country people. From too little ground it is very difficult to rise honestly to a decent position, and very easy to descend to a worse. Thus, a very small property does not suit. Only as an exception is there any utility to be found in it. What about the latifundium or large landed estate ? As an exception, when formed into small properties, it may have some advantages. Certain costly works may be accomplished on the estate of a latifundist. But, as a rule, it has also great incon¬ veniences. It puts the owner into the occasion of giving up the cultivation of land—of abandoning country life, and going away to some city, far from his tenants, there to spend his time in luxury and amusement. He who separates himself entirely from what he possesses, dispenses himself from every burden that possession and pro¬ duction imply, and selfishly secures to himself an income for an easy life, is the most unnatural type of an owner that can be found. Society is indebted to him for nothing—except for the decay that he causes in one of the sources of social wellbeing. Another discreditable side of his character is shown by the latifundist that is unconscious of his social position. He secures an income for himself by means of rent. This is a contract, as we have seen, not in itself to be condemned. And if the lati¬ fundist entered into it mindful of his social duties, he would accompany it with such conditions as to render it useful to his brethren. The division of his property among many small holders would be a means of benefiting them, and placing many families on a way of living, at least not worse than before. But this renting is not without trouble or responsibility. To be free from it, the landlord often has recourse to the system of large rents. He consigns his whole property to one single individual, the middleman, who is placed between him and the cultivators. The conditions of the contract may not be equally advantageous; but at all events the security and the absence of care are a great compensation for any disadvantage. This intermediate master, longing to attain a dignified position, and unable to mount thereto on the small margin left him above the rent—what does he do ? He makes profit out of the poor families of the labourers. Their wages consist of a few quintals of wheat, a little Indian corn, and a small monthly payment of money. As regards the quality of the commodities granted to them, truth compels us to say that what is most worthless, what is most decayed by time, what is considered in the market as fit only for beasts, is the portion of the poor country people. Of the low damp gloomy cabins given them to inhabit, there is no need for a long de¬ scription. And no one dares to object; for the position is pre¬ carious from year to year. Everyone is mindful of St. Martin’s Day and the First of March, which too often present a sorrowful procession of carts, laden with ragged bundles, and stooped 122 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY emaciated figures—pale barefooted children and ill-clothed mothers—who go to another impoverishment, another martyrdom. And if, far off in the gay city, the pleasure-seeker considers that his income is too small, the next settlement day will afford him am opportunity, not to be neglected, of raising the rent. What will the middleman then do ? Unfortunate himself, he considers that he has a right to add new misery to the fate of the miserable tenants, by squeezing them still more. For the rest, it is easy to understand how property accumulated in the hands of a few becomes a source of envy, of greed, and often of fierce conflict in society. The Pope counts among the causes of the social question at the present day that “ wealth is accumu¬ lated in a few hands and poverty widely spread." This is a state of things that cannot be in the designs of Providence : a few privileged men raised high on the throne of ownership, and below, in the shade, a host of miserable wretches. 3 What, therefore, is the best form of ownership ? By “ best" we here understand, not only that which contributes to a more abundant and perfect production, but also that w'hieh helps to attach the family to the domestic roof—fomenting love, peace, and concord, and being a source of life for all civil society. So much being premised, we say that a preference is to be given to moderate ownership. On land that a man can call his own, he lays the basis of improvement for himself and his house. He lives tranquil, looks forward confidently to the future, envies the lot of none. His thoughts are generous, and out of the fruits of his farm he does not grudge something to the needy, some¬ thing for the wants of his country and of his Church. We find such moderate owners here and there over the land, even on the Alpine hills. Their families in the district or parish where they live are like the chief walls of a house : they hold it all well together, they do honour to it. For the good of all, every effort should be made to increase the number of these moderate owners; and it is to be desired that the laws should move in their favour. The Pope says expressly : “ The laws ought to favour this right (of private ownership), and to cause the number of owners to increase as much as possible." And a little before, among the counsels that he gives to the prudent workman, is the following :—“ If he is wise, he will easily turn his mind to thrift, and, corresponding with the impulse of nature, act in such a way that there may remain after his expenses something to be employed in the acquisition of a little property." Section YI.—Aid for Small Owners. The duty of coming to the aid of small ownership, of freeing it from proximate or remote danger of diminution or total ruin, is only too evident. Experience and study will show the most AID FOE SMALL OWNEES 123 effectual means. Before all it is necessary to have recourse to the State, whose intervention is required in a matter that deeply concerns the existence of the people. Let the State promote such a distribution of land property that every day the number of moderate owners may increase. It is understood that public power has not the faculty of taking from one man to give to another. Yet all nations are convinced that certain regulations ought to emanate from public authority, tending to direct the transmission of property towards those centres in which it may contribute most to the common good. The public power will succeed by opportune laws regarding inheritance ; by a more equitable scale of public tributes accord¬ ing to the rules that we have already mentioned ; and by helping those institutions which have as their object the defence of property and the advance of rational agricultural industry. 1. Some people recommend a law of succession that would anticipate or supersede the will of the testator. It should prevent property from being too much diminished by unwise divisions, or becoming, by excessive accumulations in one place, a great estate. Everybody can understand that the question is a knotty one. Others propose that the Hoferrolle should be established. This is the name (German) given to a public register kept by the State, in which every head of a family describes the possession that will pass to one heir, without any division. The Hoferrolle , however, is a poor remedy, because it leaves the effect to the views and wishes of the heads of families, of whom very few know how to rise to a calm consideration of social things. Others again propose the institution of what the Germans call Anerben- recht, and the French call the system of Famille Souche. It consists in this, that, antecedently to all will of a testator, it is settled that a farm shall pass entire to one only heir. To each of the co-heirs a quota will be given—in fixing which the law can intervene, so that the heir may not be burdened with debts. To the co-heirs, instead of capital, either in money or in kind, a quota might be fixed to be paid every year, by way of pension. More useful socially would be an institution that would be in a position to accept the annual incomes fixed for the co-heirs, and to realise the same in capitals, which it would transfer to them. Thus would be formed new centres of ownership and of capital. Our banks might be able to accomplish this work. The portion of the eo heirs is not regulated according to the exchange value of the property inherited, but according to the net produce. And the reason is—if the heir is an honest man, as he ought to be, he will remember that land capital is not to serve for the uses of life. Its produce does so ; because the true inheritance to be divided is the produce. All with a view that neither the Anerbe nor the property may be laden with debt. 2. The country house, the farming implements, and the land 124 THE ELEMENTS OE POLITICAL ECONOMY itself to a certain extent—say two hectares, or about five acres— should not be liable to sequestration or alienation. 3. A tributary system should be adopted by which (i.) a small property—say below one hectare—would be exempt from any succession tax; (ii.) by which he who has more pays more— to be obtained by a progressive impost on large properties ; and (iii.) by which a minimum of agricultural return would be free from all imposts. We have said that the impost should be raised from that which is over and above the wants of individual and domestic life. To tax what is indispensable for life is a social injustice. Now when a rural property is scarcely sufficient to enable the owner, who toils on it, to live there with his family, this property leaves no margin for contributing to the public good. 4 The owner is entitled by social justice to enjoy whatever it yields, (iv.) The system of imposts should extend to every fertile sod, so that, the tributary burden falling on many shoulders, each sod may suffer less. At the present day agriculture groans under the scourge of ma ny charges, while thousands and thousands of speculations, however profitable, are untouched. 5 A bill has been brought in to apply taxation to the returns on commercial transactions. We shall see if it arrives in port. 4. Every means should be taken to facilitate agrarian credit. The owner often finds himself in need of capital to defray the expenses of cultivation. He requires money, he requires credit at the lowest interest. The establishment, therefore, of Raiffeisen Rural Chests and of Social Banks ought to be made easy. There are other forms of agrarian co-operation explained by writers on the subject.* 5. A convenient diminution, if not a total abolition, of standing armies should be made, so as not to withdraw hands from agricul¬ ture, but rather to give them to it. An understanding among different States might here be attended with much good. 6. The organisation of owners should be promoted. It is not at all true that organisation is suited only for the labouring classes. It brings advantage to all the classes that are respectively inferior to the upper classes. Owners must defend themselves against unfair action taken by the government, against over¬ bearing industrialists, against intermediate dealers in buying as well as in selling. The organisation that we have maintained and recommended will serve this purpose admirably. The assistance of private individuals is also to be sought. It gives life to institutions, of which some are a substitute for law, as far as can be, and would not exist if the law existed ; others * See People's Banks, by Henry W. Wolff. London: P. S. King & Son.—Also Political Economy, by C. G. Devas, M.A. London : Long¬ mans, Green & Co.—Much valuable information on organising work can be obtained from the Secretary of the Irish Agricultural Organisation Society, 22 Lincoln Place, Dublin. In 1907 the I.A.O.S. counted 912 branch societies and 82,472 members, with a trade turn-over of £2,017,623.— Trans . LABOUR 125 complete the law, with which and under which they act. The work of individuals will be rendered efficacious by the institution of Secretaryships for the People, Rural Chests, Mutual Help Societies, Banks, Provision Stores, Rural Unions, &c. All, however, should be catholic—that is to say, free from every taint of private speculation. 6 Themes. —Make a short commentary on those words of Return novarum : “ The right of private ownership being derived, not from human but from natural law, the State cannot abolish it, but may temper its use, and harmonise it with the common good. The State is therefore unjust and cruel, if, under the name of tributes, it requires from individuals more than their quota”—The emigration of a multitude of small holders is a sign that land ownership does not give that ease or comfort with which, generally speaking, the small holder is content: what remedies are efficacious to remove or to lessen the social evil of emigration ?—When an individual acquires lawfully the possession of some goods, it does not at all follow that civil society renounces its rights. CHAPTER IV. MAN MUST WORK. Section I.— Labour. Labour means human activity applied to the works of nature, in order to have produce. Man alone is capable of this most noble function, because he alone, having reason, knows how to adapt means to an end—how to direct his powers, that, co¬ operating with nature, he may reap profit from them. We do not give the name labour in its proper sense to the fatigue of oxen or other animals that draw the plough. They weary themselves blindly as brutes. Men alone labour. Labour, however, is certainly fatiguing. Whether it is performed by body or mind, it causes fatigue—to endure which man is not impelled except by proportionate motives. These motives are:—(i.) Necessity. Land not cultivated has a very poor productive power, which is soon exhausted. In order to live, man must consume some useful things, and these he ought to create for himself by labour, (ii.) The desire of being in a better position. Man produces in proportion to the labour that he expends. If he labours more, he produces more for the wants of life, and so he is better off. (iii.) Duty. We Christians recognise this prerogative in labour : it is a duty imposed on us by the Creator. It is, moreover, a punishment here inflicted on the whole human race for original sin. This last motive gives strength to the obligation of labour ; and at the same time explains the condemnation, so grave, so general, to which humanity has been subjected.* * Many labouring men lead a very penitential life. Happy for them when they know how to sanctify their work by pious intentions !— Trans. 126 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY Unchristian sociologists do not recognise these elements of morality in labour, but regard it as a disgrace, a burden, a slavery. With these there can be no love of labour, except in so far as it appears advantageous. History gives an admirable confirmation of what we have just said. What idea of labour was entertained in pagan society ? What account was made of labourers ? Aristotle, in his Politics , says that labour is unworthy of man. Plato, in his Republic, speaks of it only with contempt. Even the great Cicero himself, in the Tusculan Disputations, refers to it as a thing fit only for a barbarous civilisation. Naturally, a like opinion was held of labourers. In those splendid times, they who enjoyed the fruits of the labour of others were those who spoke of them with so little consideration—those magnates who wasted the substance of the people and diverted themselves in the circus. To-day there is again the same contempt for labour. We know districts in which the rich speak of the lower classes with disdain, scorn, and abuse. What injustice and ingratitude ! If such conduct was a blemish on pagan ages, it is also a blemish on ours, which tends to paganism. The same causes, the same effects ! The economy of liberalism regards the value of labour only in its economic relations. With it labour is a necessary fact, because this fact accompanies another fact, which is produce ; and from the value of the latter, it j udges the value of the former. Nor is the conclusion without logic ; the value of a stream of water is known by the benefit that it brings to a meadow. This is the theory of mercenary labour—a theory that, in practice and in times of abundance, satisfies both masters and labourers, but never satisfies human dignity or justice. From the analysis made of labour, it follows that it is essentially a work of man, that is, of a rational creature. It is an act of the reason, which knows, and of the will, which decides. To regard it in a mere mercenary light is to place it on a level with the work of beasts of burden. Yet more. Labour is not chosen by man, but is imposed on him by a precept. A high moral principle presides over the fact of labour. No one, according to our view, can free himself from it. The most comfortable social position can no more dispense a man from this duty than the opportunity of being dishonest can dispense him from the duty of being honest. Production is also benefited by this morality of labour, because the abundance and perfection of produce are sure to be in proportion to the labour, and to the love with which this labour is undergone. It is, therefore, a monstrous injustice to regard labour as an ordinary article of merchandise, and to subject it to the changes of the market. Has labour therefore a value, and what is it ? Yes, it has a value, and by means of a proper contract it may be bartered. PRODUCTIVITY OF LABOUR 127 Hence Christian economists do not hesitate to call it quaedam merx, or merx sui generis, a peculiar kind of merchandise. The exchange of labour, however, is not made for any commodity whatsoever that serves man; but for that commodity which is, in quantity, designed as a tax by nature for the support of him who labours. In short, in the contract of labour there is an exchange of which one quantity is labour, and the other quantity, or term of the equation, should not be simply a commodity, but such a measure of commodity as is naturally required for the maintenance of the labourer. This is an element that ought to enter essentially into the valuation of labour, and make labour worth as much as a man’s life, which depends on it. 7 The fruits of labour we ought to consider, not only in their relation with the individual, but with all society. There are labours that are advantageous to the individual in so far as they are beneficial to society. Their fruits pass to individuals by way of the social body. Such are public works : man enjoys them because he lives in society. There are other labours that do not bear fruit at all for the individual, but for the social body— often not even for the present social body, but for one to come. The man who makes a good his own, in so far (either directly or indirectly) aids society. And thus he fulfils a twofold duty, that of promoting both private and public weal. We must be careful not to give the name of labour only to that movement of the limbs which leads to material produce. Into such an error those may fall who do not consider that man has wants and duties, moral and religious, which he wishes to satisfy—wants and duties to which material production is not superior, but subordinate. If, therefore, these interests exist, and manual labour is not capable of satisfying them, we must admit that there are other labours which are no less important or necessary for the wellbeing of mankind. The social state, for which nature destined man, originates many labours that, without society, would have no reason to exist. Such are all those labours, physical and intellectual, which are required to give existence and increase to private and domestic wellbeing—to which the social body aspires, as to its end. Labour, so ordered as to satisfy the physical and moral wants of man, has every reason for its existence and congruity. If this end is neglected, labour is no longer labour—that is to say, it is no longer a rational use of strength ; it is blind fatigue, like that of a beast; it is a disorder that man ought to banish from his life. How many of those labours which are only beastly fatigues ought to disappear from the world ! Section II. —Productivity of Labour. Is that new utility w T hich follows a productive process due to labour ? Is it due wholly or in part ? 128 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY The first question is therefore an inquiry if labour is pro¬ ductive. Reasoning must lead us to facts. Before production we have elements with an aptitude to become a utility, or rather with power to give existence to a new utility. Untouched by the hand of man, these elements will never produce a utility that does not exist. Let his hand draw near, let labour be spent on them : a new utility exists. To what is it due ? Some one will answer : To nature. In part we do not deny it. In a natural object there is the virtue of a new utility. But such virtue does not come into activity without labour. This consequence shows the causality of labour in produce; it declares the productivity of labour. The encyclical in several places recognises the productivity of labour. Of agricultural labour it says :—“ The soil that is tilled by the hand and skill of the cultivator is no longer what it was before : from being wild it becomes fruitful—from being barren, fertile. These improvements are now so blended with it that for the most part they are inseparable from it/ 5 Further on, it asserts that, to provide society with an abundance of material goods, “ the toil and skill of the poor are most efficacious and necessary, whether applied in fields or in work¬ shops. Indeed it may be said with truth that it is by the labour of the working classes that States grow rich. 55 Is every produce, therefore, properly and entirely due to labour ? Neither one supposition nor the other is true. It is not true that every produce comes from labour, because there are things into the production of which labour does not enter much or little. Fruits given by uncultivated ground are certainly not due in any way to labour. Nor is it true that produce depending on labour is exclusively due to labour. We proved what part nature has in production, and we shall see what part capital has in it. To mistake the causality of nature and capital, by attribut¬ ing it entirely to labour, is not justice, because it is not truth. How far does the productivity of labour extend ? It cannot be generally defined. There are products whose value is due in a greater degree to nature and capital, and in a less degree to labour. We may take as an example a gold ear-ring, whose value is owing chiefly to its precious metal. And there are others in which labour preponderates. A German-silver watch owes its value chiefly to labour, and very little to material. It is, therefore, evident that ownership and labour are the two levers on which the public wellbeing depends. This contribu¬ tion which labour brings to the common prosperity is called the social function of labour. Every good of this world has naturally a two-fold mission— to help the human individual and all mankind in general. Often the social function goes contrary to the individual; often it is not so. But neither society can stop for itself the current that runs generously to benefit the individual, nor can the latter RELATIONS BETWEEN LABOUR AND PRODUCE 129 oppose an obstacle to it when it rushes on to benefit society. This is a principle that often turns up in the course of our thoughts, and it leads us here to assert the social function of labour. Labour produces; and produces for the individual. Quite true. But let us be permitted to ask if, in the intentions of nature, it produces only for the individual. And how would the general end of the preservation of the whole human race be thus attained ? Will it be said, by the labours of each one ? But can each one produce by himself all that he needs ? And if there is anyone who cannot produce, must he perish ? And if anyone, even through idleness, has no produce, and finds himself with empty hands, must he cease to live ? Behold how and why the produce of labour should come forth from the hands of the individual and fall into the bosom of society, carried thither on the streams of justice and charity ! “ Work¬ people concur very much to the common good ... In every well-ordered State there ought to be a sufficient supply of material goods, the use of which is necessary for the practice of virtue. Now, to provide these goods, the labour and skill of the poor, whether employed on the land or in the workshops, are supremely necessary and efficacious. Indeed it may be truly said that it is by the labour of the working classes that States become rich.” (Rerum novarum.) By the light of this function, the labourer grows much in worth and nobility. Outside of it, he makes a miserable figure— all selfishness. We wish him to be what he ought to be, the Angel of Divine Providence. Section III.— Relations between Labour and Produce. Considering labour in relation to produce, we ought to pay attention to three elements :—(i.) The duration of the labour; (ii.) its intensity; and (iii.) the love or diligence with which it is performed. We ought also to consider in produce (i.) its abundance and (ii.) its perfection. Both should accompany produce in order that production may be successful. An abun¬ dant, but imperfect, produce does not satisfy ; a good, but scarce, produce does not suffice. To establish the relation that exists between produce and labour, we must make account of the various elements noted above. If it immediately appears that the quantity of produce is pro¬ portional to the duration of labour, whoever seriously reflects will remember that with the duration of labour its intensity will be inversely proportional; and, likewise the love or diligence in performing it. It is well known then that if an abundance of produce is to be expected from the duration of labour, its excellence or perfection is to be expected rather from the love or diligence with which that labour is performed. i 130 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY We may, therefore, venture to say that the produce obtained by multiplying together the duration, intensity, and diligence of labour is in a direct ratio with the produce obtained by multi¬ plying together the abundance and perfection of the produce. To obtain, therefore, a produce that may satisfy, we must keep an eye on the elements by which labour influences produce, and, having carefully studied their nature, maintain or increase their coefficients, which are, as it were, the sources of all produce.* These sources are moral or physical according as they influence the spiritual or the material part of man. Section IV.— Moral Coeeficients of Labour. It is proper that we should give the first place to moral co¬ efficients. With us a man is a man, and not merely an animal; and his muscles obey the dictates of his will, enlightened by reason. The ox obeys the goad. Not so with man: his goad is his will. The first source of productive labour is, therefore, in the mind ; and those motives, those considerations, which will be capable of deciding the human will to labour will be moral and most powerful coefficients to labour. They are according to the genius, the intellectual views, and even the passions, to which the individual gives himself.-j* We shall refer to the chief of them :— 1. Here we must place the Christian idea of labour. It shows that labour is a duty and a merit. It makes the labourer feel a great dignity—that of being by his work, whatever it may be, a collaborator with Divine Providence. This idea does not demean or deject the labourer, who, therefore, does not hate his condition. On the contrary, he loves it; and, while he wipes away the sweat from his brow, he sings the most j oyous ditties. The idea of the cremationists J regarding labour, common to all those who have no Christian feelings, reduces labour to a necessity. Necessity degrades, and degradation causes hatred. To hear the socialists, one would suppose that they had nothing but praise for labour and labourers ; but at what do they aim ? At the avoidance of labour. They shun it so much that they oblige the State to impose it on them. They are the leaders of * The celebrated American inventor, Edison, has remarked of his wonderful inventions that they are due to 2 per cent of inspiration (derived from books), and 98 per cent, of perspiration (spent on experiments). Plenty of intellectual work !— Trans, f Coefficient is a word often used in Algebra. It generally denotes a figure placed before a letter. Thus, let x represent an unknown quantity. Then 2x represents twice that quantity. Here 2 is the coefficient of x, and 2x is the product (twice x) obtained from the multiplication of a: by 2.— Trans. I A cremationist, it need hardly be said, is one who advocates the burning of the human body after death.— Trans. PHYSICAL COEFFICIENTS OF LABOUR 131 discontented, unprincipled, furious workmen, because full of rancour and hatred. 2. Vocation. A vocation to labour, rather than to anything else, is the call of the Author of man. There is reason to believe that this call will be accompanied with a special fitness for labour. Not even of this element does socialism make account, for it delivers us all, like a flock of sheep, into the hands of the State. The State will then employ us at that work which it judges most useful, and so we must carry the chain. 3. The hope of bettering one’s condition. The workman, no matter how lowly his employment, hopes by labour to enlarge and adorn his house, to obtain more light for his rooms, to furnish his table with food more worthy of himself and his family. He always dreams of a future more prosperous. Poor dreams, which are often only illusions, but dreams that make him live content,' and work well with a healthy stomach and a light heart! According to the Pope, “ the proximate end that the workman proposes to himself is the acquirement of some property.” It is easy to understand how socialism, which would have all classes labouring under the direction of the State, defeats this hope, and thus induces workmen to throw away the spade, the hammer, and the trowel. To these conditions of labour must be added all others that are capable of giving satisfaction to the spiritual part of the workman. A certain variety of work—an honest liberty in fulfilling his duties as a man, a father, a husband, a Christian— a kindly smile beaming on the countenance of the employer— these things console the mind of the workman and continually develop new germs of activity. Section V.— Physical Coefficients of Labour. Having dealt with the nobler part of man, which commands, it is proper that we should consider the inferior part, which, a living instrument, executes the commands given by the former. Poorly can the mind be the centre of strong enterprising energies, if the powers of the body are weak, if the muscles are languid. To be in good form, the man who labours has various needs to be provided for :— 1. An abundant wholesome nutritious food—especially good bread.* To give poor labourers a tainted or decaying food, or food in small quantity, besides being an injustice, is a mistaken speculation. Their labour will be feeble, deficient, and the produce will be scarce. Some employments put a special trial * Some excellent little books on matters of this kind, such as Woman’s Share in the Industrial Revival of Ireland, by the Most Rev. Dr. Kelly, Bishop of Ross, have been published by the Catholic Truth Society of Ireland.— Trans. 132 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY on the vital organs of poor workmen. For these a special kind of sustenance would be required. 2. A healthy dwelling. Nature has granted a real super¬ abundance of some goods that are strictly required. How much air, how much light, it has given ! And why should poor work¬ people be stinted with regard to them ? Their houses should therefore be airy, clean, neat, not damp ; in short, healthy. Improvements of this kind have been undertaken with happy success by Catholics here in Italy, as well as elsewhere. Even economical institutions ought to lend a hand. Government and social bodies ought to facilitate the work. In the Journal of Economists , G. Spera has made some very good remarks on this subject. He shows the model of a workman's house, and proposes to secure the ownership of it to the occupant after a fixed number of years, or even sooner, if the head of the family should be taken away by a premature death.* The breaking up and scattering of a family would thus be avoided. 3. Favourable conditions for work. This applies to work¬ people shut up in close places, where the air is made poisonous even by the work itself. It is a duty of employers to take such precautions as will preserve their workpeople not only from sudden accidents, but from a slow death. As the robust health of work¬ people is a matter of great importance for society, the public power can make such legal regulations as will secure it. 4. A division of labour. Children who work in play divide the labour among them, that is, they assign a task to each one, so that the work may be well done. This shows that the efficacy of a division of labour in obtaining a more abundant and perfect produce is dictated by nature itself. A consciousness of the limits of one's power suggests that, when mind and hand are assiduously applied to the making of one single article, they acquire a technical skill that is of admirable service in expediting and perfecting the operation. A division of labour has always been practised among workingmen. It increases with the increase of industries. Who has not heard that it takes eighteen men to make a pin ? The division of labour also presents great social advantages : it creates in society a great variety of occupa¬ tions, among which each person can choose that for which he feels himself born, and practise it with skill and pleasure.! 5. Machinery. Every contrivance of which man avails himself * It has been calculated that one-fourth the human race die before six years of age, half before sixteen, and that only one person in 100 reaches the age of sixty-five.— Trans. t It would be a blessing if someone, with sufficient knowledge and experience, would compile a little book describing the different trades and other ordinary employments common in Ireland, so that a boy, reading it, would be able to form a good judgment on what occupation would be most suitable for him. We have seen two such works in the German language.— Trans. LIMITS OF LABOUR 133 in performing work may be called a machine, but common use, as well as economic language, keeps this name for a complex mechanism that acts, rather by being guided by man than in aiding him. A machine presents the advantage of a notable decrease in the expenses of production, and, therefore, of the price at which products can be sold. This results from two causes. First, a saving of the workman's hand : a machine can do as much as several or even many men. Secondly, speed : there is little proportion between the amount of work done by a man-and that by a machine in the same time.* The things produced by machines offer ground for a classifica¬ tion of them. Some machines are useful for production in the sense explained : they do quickly what man would require much time to do. Others do what man absolutely could not do : for example, the photographic machine, or camera. 8 Section VI.— Limits of Labour. In the materialistic ideas of man as a machine and labour as an article of merchandise the question whether labour ought to have any limits beyond those imposed by a want of strength or the convenience of the market is idle, not to say absurd. With us the workman is not a machine, but a rational creature, for whom labour ought to be the means of attaining very superior goods. He therefore requires— 1. Rest on festive days. That man cannot labour assiduously all the days of the week is shown by physiological and historical facts. That a day of rest for one and all should be Sunday is shown by reasons from the moral and the religious order, which prove that the workman should rest even on other days, according to laws emanating from religious authority. 2. Rest at night. Nature has many ways of manifesting its laws. The dark curtain that is drawn at the close of a bright day, and the weariness that oppresses the limbs, and the silence that becomes so deep and solemn on all sides, tell clearly that night was destined for the repose of man. Why should economic reasons have power to subvert the ordinances of nature ? 3. A just arrangement of the hours of labour. It is known that the workman cannot give to labour all that time which is not required for sleep. He must take his meals ; he must have some honest recreation; he must give a thought to the care of his * It is said that by machinery coal can be put into ships at the rate of 400 tons an hour ; that a stone-crusher does the work of 600 men; and that a steam-shovel can do as much work in eight minutes as a hand-shovel in ten hours. As a rule, machinery has not lessened, but greatly increased, employment. Provision, however, should be made for men thrown out of work during the period of transition.— Trans. 134 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY family. Even physically, he could not continue in daily labour, say of twelve hours. There is need, therefore, to limit the time of labour, and not to leave it in the hands of masters.* But how many hours of labour ought there to be in the day ? The socialists are thrown into a pleurisy by eight hours, as every¬ body knows. These men, with a view to make an impression on the multitude and to gain a point for themselves, do not care for logic or facts, but indulge in assertions that absolutely cannot stand. How then, in such a case, is a proper measure to be assigned ? We know that there are light labours, heavy ones, and very heavy ones. To subject the workmen of such different occupa¬ tions to one uniform measure would be to commit the grossest injustice under the plea of the most scrupulous justice. We also know that a labour, light for one person, may be very heavy for another. It is proper, therefore, to acknowledge the impossibility of having one fixed rule, and also the need of seeking aid from laws and from the societies of workingmen. Let the law T s deter¬ mine the maximum duration of a day’s work. This can and should be done : there is a certain limit beyond which neither human strength nor moral order permits men to go. And this is the task of the public power. If this task is abandoned to the compacts that are made between masters and workmen, it will fall into the waves of free competi¬ tion, and be engulfed in them, nearly always with loss to the weaker party. The Pope assigns this duty to the State when he says: '* If masters oppress the working classes with unjust burdens, or degrade them by conditions repugnant to human personality and dignity ; if they injure health by excessive work, or by work unsuited to sex or age : in these cases it is evident that the force and authority of the law ought, within certain limits, to interfere.” That the law should not go farther is proved by the impossibility of finding a just, general standard, as well as by the function assigned to the State, which, according to Leo XIII., “ should not undertake more than is required for the remedy of the evil or the removal of the danger.” However, w x e admit that even when the State has done its part, all danger of abuse is not quite taken away. This is what we have wished to be the task of Trade or Class Unions : to which if the State will grant a legal personality, it will have fully dis¬ charged its duty. It is only mediately that the State can come to a practical determination with regard to each kind of labour— that is, by means of assistance from societies of workingmen. * Some people maintain that the man who works eight hours a day can actually do more than the man who works ten. The latter comes home at night quite tired out. Every good master will have a careful eye to the physical, intellectual, and moral welfare of all persons in his employment.— Trans. \ LIMITS OF LABOUB 135 On this point, the Encyclical speaks with admirable clearness:— “It is neither just nor humane to require of a man so much labour as stupefies his mind or enfeebles his body. The activity of man, like all his nature, has limits beyond which it cannot go. His strength is improved by exercise and use, provided, however, that from time to time he has an intermission for rest. The daily work, therefore, should not be prolonged beyond the hours that strength permits. How long the intervals of rest ought to be, must be judged of by the nature of the work, by circumstances of time and place, and by the health of the work¬ men. Those, for example, who work fin quarries, or in mines of iron, copper, &c., far underground, should have shorter hours in proportion as their labour is more trying on health. Begard should also be had to the season of the year, because it not un- frequently happens that labour easily borne at one time is at another intolerable or very difficult.” {Rerum novarum.) For the rest, this point is complex enough at the present day, and may be more so to-morrow or some other time. It is proper, if we would arrive at a solution of it to keep an eye to the relation that it may have with the material and moral welfare of the individual, and with the interests of society in general. In farming, for example, circumstances may occur in which a prolongation of the hours of labour beyond the maximum limit would be a duty. This is when the crops require to be cared for or gathered in, lest the severity of the weather should ruin them. The occasion is urgent, and the work must be finished in a few days. In calamities of this kind, who does not see that the common good permits country people to spend some extra energy for a few days, precisely because, being only for a few days, it cannot seriously injure health ? Without doubt, in such a case, an increase of wages is to be allowed, so that it may be possible for the labourer to have a sustenance proportioned to his greater need. But even this matter should be under certain just rules, lest otherwise, through the excessive greed of an employer, a labourer should agree to a time-table truly inhuman, and be an impoverisher of himself, contrary to the dignity of human nature. The Class Unions have here, as is evident, a great deal to amend. 4. No unfair opposition. The workman, in the struggle that he has to maintain with the employer, finds to-day that, besides society-men, he has other competitors—women and children. Monsignor Bandi speaks on the subject thus :— “ The devouring competition entered homes. It found there some hands unemployed—that is to say, not producing. They were the two hands of the good wife, which took care of everything in the house, and which she clapped with joy on the return of the weary workman. There were also the tender hands of little boys and little maidens, who, like so many angels, filled the house wfith gladness. What are all those hands to do ? Let them 136 THE ELEMENTS OE POLITICAL ECONOMY produce, let them produce : a workman can do very well without so much festivity and poetry, provided he lives ! “ And so crowds of women and children bade farewell to their domestic peace, and took the road to the factory. They worked by day and they worked by night. They worked all the day long, and even on festival days. The modest little girl and the rude little boy worked together. They worked without guardian¬ ship, and without rule, except to work quickly and well; and for so much work they received very, very little reward.” (Pastoral Letter, March 6, 1901.) Now, it is easy to prove that this state of affairs is altogether unnatural. Woman has a mission eminently domestic. Her physical constitution and her duties as a wife and a mother do not permit her to engage in the work of a factory. Schuler informs us that in Switzerland the mortality among working women is 27 per cent, greater than that among working men. The statistics of military recruits say that among the sons of working women the percentage of mortality rises higher than among others. According to the Pope : “ Some kinds of work do not suit woman, born for domestic duties, which are a great protection for her modesty, and have a natural correspondence with the education of children and the wellbeing of the family.” (Rerum novarum.) With regard to the injuries that work does to children, w T e might easily make a long discourse. Physical injuries, because their tender limbs, which require to grow, are oppressed by the weight of work: this may lead to lameness, or some other deformity that will last for a lifetime. Intellectual and moral injuries, because work does not allow them time to adorn their minds with knowledge and to mould their hearts to virtue. Amid the jesting, the licentiousness of an ill-ordered workshop, it may easily be imagined what nobility of sentiment, what correctness of judgment, they can acquire. Let us again quote the encyclical : “As for children, great care should be taken not to let them enter a workshop before their physical, intellectual, and moral powers are sufficiently developed. For as the buds of spring are destroyed by rough weather, so those powers beginning to appear in childhood are destroyed by prema¬ ture excitement, and thus the education of children becomes impossible.” Let no one, therefore, be surprised if Catholics from an early date raised their voices against the labour of women and children. Among the first was the celebrated Bishop of Mayence, Monsignor Ketteler,* who, elected to the Parliament of Berlin, proposed the * Some forty years ago, this great far-seeing Bishop was an enthusiastic advocate for founding societies, unions, guilds, &c., but always on Christian principles, as the certain means of elevating their members intellectually and morally. He met with many obstacles. Prince Bismarck was a bitter enemy of all legislation in favour of the working classes : he would hear of LIMITS OF LABOUR 137 five following points in his social programme :—(i.) The prohibi¬ tion of work to children under fourteen years of age ; (ii.) the prohibition of factory work to married women; (iii.) an obligation of rest on festal days: (iv.) a maximum of ten hours for the day's work; and (v.) the appointment of Inspectors for work. The “ Centre ” warmly supported this programme and carried it triumphantly against all parties, including the socialists, who, during many years, had opposed such bills as were proposed by the “ Centre ” for the protection of the lower classes. no law to limit their hours of work by day or night, to secure days of rest for them, &c. If they wished to improve their condition, they should rely on self-help alone. His so-called Culturkampf (struggle for civilisation) was in reality a cruel persecution of the Church. It did great evil during the ten years of its course. History, however, shows that right ideas cannot be put down, and that the attempt to crush them is soon discovered to be unjust. The year 1890 brought a great change for the better, and Bismarck had to quit Berlin. The Emperor William II. put himself at the head of the movement in favour of labour, and invited all the States of Europe to an International Conference in Berlin on the protection of working people. He wrote personally to the Pope, in order to gain his support for the Con¬ ference. The Pope, in compliance, wrote to the Archbishop of Cologne. Then followed a general pastoral letter from the Bishops of Germany, express¬ ing their warm sympathy with the cause. In 1891 Pope Leo XIII. came out with his grand encyclical on the labour question, Rerum novarum. It is full of philosophy as well as religion, and is justly regarded as a most valuable document from the highest authority. Its principles will hold good till the end of the world. Some of the most important societies now in Germany are the Catholic Workmen’s Society ( Katholischer Arbeiterverein), the People’s Society (Volksverein ), the Workwomen’s Society, the Journeymen’s Society, the Young Men’s Society, the Boys’ Society. When the number of workmen in a locality is not sufficient to form an Arbeiterverein, the Volksverein, in which all classes can join, suits very well. The head-quarters of these societies are at Munich-Gladbach, a large manufacturing town about twelve miles west of Dusseldort. The Workmen’s Societies adopt every imaginable means of improving their condition. They feel that as men and as Christians they are entitled to a fair share in the fruits of civilisation. They have halls, bureaus, reading- rooms, libraries, lectures, discussions, bands, concerts, newspapers, pam¬ phlets, &c. They make Retreats ; they have days of General Communion ; they take part in religious processions. They offer great protection for young men coming into town from the country. Thus they are a powerful bulwark against Socialism, paralysing in many respects its efforts. They give special courses of instruction to trade unions within their own ranks, mindful of the advice of their great champion Mr. Windthorst: “ Catholics, whatever their calling, ought to do everything in the best way.” At the same time all their conduct is regulated by the words of the Gospel: “ What doth it profit a man if he gain the whole world, and suffer the loss of his own soul ? ” The President of every Workmen’s Society is a Priest appointed by the Bishop of the diocese. A Conference is held from time to time by the Presidents, or a Congress by the Delegates of the workmen. Some of these Delegates have even been admitted to an interview with the Lord Chancellor. In 1906 the Alliance of Catholic Workmen’s Societies of West Germany (about a dozen dioceses) counted 656 Societies and 114,613 members ; the Alliance of South Germany 853 Societies, and 105,271 members ; and the Alliance of Berlin 750 Societies and about 100,000 members.— Trans. 138 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY In a point of paramount importance for society at large, in¬ volving the most sacred rights, there is no doubt that the State ought to interfere with wise precautions. 5. An occasional rest during the time of work. Besides the time given to sleep and to meals, the workman ought to have a while, varied according to the season and the work, for honest rest. It is a claim of nature. Trade and other such Unions will do well if, for the advantage both of workers and masters, they draw up a suitable time-table. This is a basis recommended by the Pope : “Asa general rule, it may be said that the amount of rest necessary for a workman ought to be in proportion to the amount of strength consumed by labour ; for the waste of strength ought to be repaired by rest." Nor is it necessary that the workman should expressly stipulate for his rest: nature has made the bargain for him. “ In every agreement that is made between masters and workpeople, it is always a condition, expressed or understood, that there should be proper rest for soul and body. To agree otherwise would be contrary to morals ; for it is never lawful to promise a neglect of the duties that man owes to God and to himself." (Rerum novarum.) Section VII.— Labour oe Women and Children. A question may here arise : Will it, therefore, be said that women, and also children, are to have no labour ? No one intends to maintain such a doctrine. If a general condemnation falls on the labour of women and children, it is because an objectionable state of affairs is only too common. For the rest, if due reserve is secured for the maiden, the wife, the mother, and if they are allowed to fulfil their respective duties, every motive urges that they should apply themselves to some work for the prosperity of the family. The same reasoning holds good for children, who, in proportion to their strength, ought to begin to work, and to lend a hand in carrying the burdens of the family. Indeed the Pope, with great propriety, speaks thus :—“ A work suitable for a strong grown man cannot reason¬ ably be required from a woman or a child." Therefore there is work suitable for woman and child, to which they may well submit. Bather, they ought to do so, because the family is an organism, for whose wellbeing all its members should, according to their strength, combine. On this subject it is to be observed that factories have taken out of the hands of woman many occupations in which she formerly engaged under the shade of the domestic roof. Spinning, weaving, knitting, &c., afforded her employment, without leaving her house, her children, her domestic affairs. Now she has no longer such work: how could she compete with a machine or a LEGAL GUARDIANSHIP OF LABOUR 139 mill ? Treating of family industries, Father Viguerou, in an article that appeared in the Social Reform of Dec. 1, 1901, main¬ tained the necessity of establishing syndicates of women working at home. The Trade Unions will be able to solve, at least in part, this problem. Section YIII.—Legal Guardianship of Labour. In the Rerum novarum, Leo XIII., when speaking of labour, deals minutely with some points to whi'ch social legislation ought to extend. They are (i.) to make rest on festal days obligatory ; (ii.) to guard the moral interests of workpeople; (iii.) to fix the maximum length of a day's w^ork; (iv.) to fix the minimum amount of wages; (v.) to protect women and children from excessive labour; (vi.) to defend Trade Unions, so that when it is not justice for the State to extend its action in any case, they may interfere with practical decisions. As regards this last purpose, the Catholic Social Congress of Genoa did not hesitate to assert that, in an extreme case of general abuses, either on the part of employers or on the part of workpeople, if councils of conciliation and arbitration are unable to prevent strikes or wrongs, it would then be well that the State should interfere, either by transforming those councils into real tribunals with public authority, or by establishing a suitable tribunal that would hear the claims of both parties, and apply in each case the moral law of justice, for which the State ought to provide in its code. Another point (vii.) is to have a Minister of Labour, who, by means of carefully prepared statistics, would see not only the state of agriculture, manufactures, industries in general, but also the condition of the working classes, the lives that they lead, the difficulties that they have to contend with, &c. 9 The justice of such arrangements must be admitted by every¬ body. Why in the world should the law, which is so zealous in protecting the rights of property, leave to the mercy of the strongest the rights of labour ? Is not labour one of the chief levers by which humanity is maintained ? “ It is just that the Government should take an interest in the workingman, so that he may have some share in that abundance which he produces— that, being properly housed, clothed, and fed, he may be able to lead a life less painful. Let it therefore favour as much as possible whatever can improve his condition. It may be assured that this care, far from injuring anyone, will be a benefit for all. Because it could not be for the good of the commonwealth that those persons from whom such important advantages are derived should be sunk in misery." (Rerum novarum.) Catholics have at present a strong and convincing literature that aims at procuring legislation on labour. The studies of Yogelsang and Ratsinger, the speeches of De Mun and Lieber, 140 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY as well as the powerful appeals of Cardinal Manning, are a proof of it. Everyone knows how explicitly and forcibly, in the Congress of Zurich, the views of Catholics were declared in favour of a legal protection for labour. Italy, we regret to say, is still far behind in these matters. Switzerland. Austria. Germanv. France, and Russia have resmla- . 1 7 O tions not yet so much as honoured with a discussion by our legislators. We have the law of 1893, which forbids the employ¬ ment of children in a wandering peddling traffic. We have the law of 1886, which permits (L) the work of children in lighter employments at nine years of age, and in mines, even far under¬ ground, at ten: (ii.) only eight hours of work between nine and ten years of age; (iii.) no dangerous or unhealthy work up to fifteen years: (iv.) no ordinary night work to children under twelve, but in exceptional cases it may occur for six hours : (v.) from twelve to fifteen years, night work only for six hours. In fine, we have the law of 1898 on accidents, and on the institution of a " National Providence Chest/ 5 To these a useful addition has been made by a recent law (June 19, 1902), which raises to twelve the minimum age for the employment of children in factories, and in works (not under¬ ground) connected with caves, mines, and galleries. It forbids night work to boys under fifteen years, and to all girls of minor age. There is the sum total. Free to women anv work, anv contract. « ' » any time table, any wages, any condition ! For the victims of labour the law does not move a finger. 10 We Catholics are, therefore, right when we call not only for an exact application of the few regulations that exist on labour, but for a true renova¬ tion, whatever that costs, of the laws themselves. 11 Section IX.—International Legislation on Labour. Labour is such a fact that it has a connection with all the other facts of social economic life : and its good or ill fate often depends on a cause, or a variety of causes, existing far from it. He who considers that the wases of labour are connected with the prosperity of the master, that the master is influenced by the abundance of the produce, that the value of the produce depends on the largeness of the market—he who considers that, so far as laws go, competition can never be wholly abolished, but, by the present means of transport, may, like a great ocean, rush from country to country, from kin gdom to kingdom— sees at once the lines of legal protection for labour vanish away over the wide world. Grant that one or two States make regulations in favour of the working classes : their efficacy may be little or nothing through the competition of a neigh- bourinr State. INTERNATIONAL LEGISLATION ON LABOUR 141 The protecting State may injure itself and its own industries. In point of fact, if it lessens the length of a day's work, which in an adjacent State is twelve or fourteen hours, how can its manufacturers compete with those on its borders ? A movement for international guardianship was begun in 1857 by Daniel Legrand, of Alsace, who begged of all the governments in Europe to prevent the employment of children under twelve years, and also to forbid night work and Sunday work. Nothing came of it. But an idea so just could not die. In 1862 we find it repeated by the found¬ ation of the “ International Association of Working Men " ; in 1890 by the Berlin Conference ; in 1897 by the Zurich Congress ; and in 1900 by the Paris Congress. All civil governments ought accordingly to agree, as far as possible, on one general basis of labour legislation. It is well known with what wisdom and eloquence the great Christian democrat, Gaspar Decurtius, maintained his thesis at the Zurich Congress. It was after that event that he received a splendid Brief from the Holy Father, confirming the reasonable¬ ness of his views. Thus does the Pope speak :—“ Many argu¬ ments are not needed to prove the reasonableness of such pro¬ vision. For if there is any grave and laudable reason why the public authority should interpose with legislation in defence of the interests of the working classes, there certainly cannot appear any one more grave or laudable than that of protecting the weakness of children and women, from whom the generation to succeed the present will take its rise, and on whom the greatness and power of a people depend. On the other hand, it is evident to all how imperfect would be the protection given to labour by different laws passed by different States. Because, as it often happens that various articles of merchandise, coming from a distant region, meet in one place, to be sold there, the rules for the labour of workmen in one place might turn to the advantage of industry among one people and to the injury of industry among another." Hence it is manifest how praiseworthy is the “ International Association for the Protection of Labour," to whose interests our excellent Toniolo has consecrated so much of his large mind and generous heart. 12 Themes. —Freedom of labour : how it should be understood, and in what sense it is a right of every individual—If laws on labour, imposing a discipline with proper titles, violate the freedom of individuals—To place the working classes in a state of comparative comfort is not only a social duty, but an advantage—In setting a value on labour, some err by defect and others by excess: what are the defects and the excesses to be avoided ?—The division of labour increases with the progress of civilisation. 142 THE ELEMENTS OE POLITICAL ECONOMY CHAPTER Y. CAPITAL IS REQUIRED AS WELL AS LABOUR. Section I. —Utility of Capital. Nature and man are the great sources of production: nature with all its riches, and man with his energy. But these two coefficients would give very little result if a third, which is of immense efficacy in production, were not joined with them. The countryman alone with the field near his door, the fisherman alone with the fish in the neighbouring water, would be of small account. Something more is needed : for the former, manure or seed ; for the latter, a hook or a net. This something, which varies for every kind of labour, and is not always the same for the same labour, is called “ capital.” Section II.— Different Views of Capital. In explaining the idea of capital, there is not among economists that harmony which would be desirable. Let us set forth the chief opinions held about it. Antoine, who asserts that he has first-class authors on his side to show why an economic good may be called capital, will have it to be a thing of some importance. And, therefore, he defines capital as “an economic good of a certain importance.” He afterwards says that capital of enjoyment is destined for con¬ sumption, and capital of production for the formation of a product. Others specify capital from its employment in productive opera¬ tions, and therefore define it as “ any economic good applied to production.” Others again admit the specification of this second opinion, but make an addition to it—that capital is an economic good which is already the effect of a productive opera¬ tion. With Cossa they define capital as “ any product employed in production.” We must keep in mind these different modes of regarding capital, when we read or hear discussions on the matter, so as not to become victims of equivocation. As for what we shall say in this chapter about capital, we premise that we adopt the third opinion, which is that of Cossa. The other two concepts of capital disturb a little, we imagine, that order which helps so much in a scientific treatise. It remains, therefore, clear that by capital we are not forthwith to understand only money. Money cannot of itself be called capital, because, as money, it is incapable of entering as a factor into any productive operation. Money is capital in so far as it is easily convertible into any product whatever, capable of being THE THEORY OF MARX ON CAPITAL 143 employed in successive productions. The meaning of capital is now obvious. When a produce is abundant, the employment of it varies according to views and tastes. One man makes a reserve fund from it for future events ; another devotes it all to consumption, in order to procure himself pleasures; another applies it to a new production; while a fourth divides it conveniently for the three destinations aforesaid. You will not, therefore, be a simpleton if you give the name of capital to an object. The same object, rendering materially the same service, may be capital or not. For example, a house that serves you as a dwelling is not capital; the same house used as a factory is capital. The horse on which you ride for diversion is not capital; but, if you are a medical man, the same horse, which takes you on your visits, is capital. It is very important to distinguish between fixed and circulating capital. If we take the examples of a mill and seed, you under¬ stand at once how the former is such a kind of capital that it is worn by use, but it lasts for many productions : it is fixed capital. The seed is circulating capital, because it serves only once : other productions will require new seed. Even here the same object may be either fixed or circulating capital, according to its destina¬ tion. The ox that serves for labour is fixed capital; the ox that is fed for the shambles is circulating capital. Section III.— The Capitalist. He who is possessed of some capital is called a capitalist. But as there is a common meaning, which is not scientific, given to capital, the same occurs with capitalist. In ordinary language, a capitalist is anyone provided with means, especially money, and in good quantity. We cannot separate the person of the capitalist from capital, and as we consider that capital should be specified from its employ¬ ment in production, so we consider that the capitalist is he who employs his own capital directly in a productive work. We have said directly , because we consider, and we repeat it, that the capitalist is truly a producer by his capital as the labourer is by his labour; and that he is, therefore, subject to changes of prosperity and adversity, not only during the productive period, but in the result of the production. He who, by a contract or in any other way, rids himself of this eventuality, or throws it on the shoulders of another, may, according to our view, be a rich man, but he is not a capitalist. To the latter we attribute rights that we deny to the former. Section IV. —The Theory of Marx on Capital. From his theory on the value of merchandise, Karl Marx derived another, no less famous, on capital. The value of an 144 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY article of merchandise, he says, is nothing but the labour incor¬ porated in it: to buy an article of merchandise is to pay for the labour required to produce it. What then is labour ? An article of merchandise, says Marx. And what is its value ? That which is required to produce it. Now, to produce labour there are physical powers required in the labourer, which, to be maintained, have need of material means. Labour is therefore paid for by supplying the means that preserve the strength of the workman. But labour is a special kind of merchandise—one that produces not only what is necessary to preserve the strength of the workman, but much more : it produces a surplus-value. In short, every product contains the value of labour, that is, what is required for the preservation of the strength of the workman, and yet more—that is to say, the surplus-value. Now, what follows ? That when a capitalist buys the labour of a workman, he pays him in value, but not in surplus-value. He pays him according to what the labourer needs to live, or he pays him nourishment in the wages of so many days, and the surplus-value he keeps for himself. Accumulated surplus-values form capital, which, consequently, is a theft committed to the loss of the labourer, to whom the surplus-value as well as the value of his labour ought to belong. Having shown in a previous chapter how the theory of Marx on value cannot be maintained—having shown what part nature, in addition to labour, has in production—we now hold in our hands the elements of proof that will do justice also to the ingenious theory of Marx on capital. 13 Section V.—Productivity of Capital. The question that we have discussed with regard to nature as well as to labour, that is, if they have each a share in the causality of produce, applies also to capital. What then is to be said of it ? If causality were a thing visible— if that mysterious thread which binds the effect to the cause could be cut, knotted, or twisted at will—we might easily show everyone that it is now simple, now double, now triple ; and that, when it is triple, one of the threads binds to capital its quota of produce. But that thread is invisible, and causality does not appear except in the reality of causes and effects. We know, however, that when we admit a before and an after, and the after evidently depends on the before, causality is there. Now, is it true that if to labour and nature we join the power of capital in production, the produce is greater ? Y es, it is true. There is therefore a before —capital. There is an after —a greater amount of produce. Here we have the relation of dependence ; PRODUCTIVITY OF CAPITAL 145 because there cannot be found outside of capital any other power that could be the cause of that produce. It remains, therefore, that we must acknowledge the productivity of capital. Antoine says :—“ Capital has a double office in production, (i.) As every production requires a certain time, the workman must live on his savings during it, that is to say, with capital, (ii.) Labour requires assistance from the forces of nature, which man, by his activity, turns into useful instruments. Now t , these instruments are capital. That capital thus understood is a means indispensable for production and for an increase of economic goods, is a truth more than evident. Take away provisions, implements, &c., and man will be obliged to seek his daily support in the spontaneous fruits of the earth. The prehistoric man already made use of capital, which consisted of smooth stones, bows and arrows, hooks, &c.—things that he carried with him when going to hunt or to fish.” And here observe how the productive function of capital is accomplished—by the consumption of itself. When speaking of production, we showed that it takes place by the consumption of existing values. The capital is consumed; it loses its value that it may have produce in return. Nor need you urge, against what has been here stated, that fixed capital remains after the productive period. It remains indeed, but no longer what it was : it is worn down, more or less. Its fixity is relative : if it is fixed for a number of productive turns, it at last finds its death in production. It must be renewed. Fixed for a number of productive turns, it is afterwards for a number circulating. From this point of view, capital appears to us as a factor that, disappearing in production, should reappear in produce. So much being granted, the question whether a quota of produce belongs to capital is out of place. Capital produces, and that which is its produce ought to belong to it, or to him who owns it. From the quota of produce that belongs to capital, take away the value of the capital that has been consumed, and you will have the net result or produce, which in economy is called “ profit,” and more frequently “ interest.” That capital has a function in favour of society is only too evident from what we have said of its nature and its productive power. If, a productive enterprise having been completed, and the produce having been divided between master and work¬ man, everything belonging to each party has been consumed, the productive process would never advance. Suppose, instead, that after a first production, all the produce is not consumed, but at least a part is saved, and that this part is employed in the purchase of machines, implements, &c., for a more extensive and rational production—it is clear that there will be a more perfect productive process and a more abundant produce. Without capital, the productive force of the land would be exhausted K 146 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY little by little. In like manner it would be impossible to raise the fine buildings, or to procure the powerful machinery, required for the progressive development of industries. And does not all this become advantageous to society ? The population of the world has been increasing in the course of ages. Where or how would so many new hands have been able to find labour, by which they would procure bread for their families, if they were entirely without capital ? The progress that the world has made in regard to economy, whose benefits we all enjoy, is due mainly to the power of large capitals, which have so immense a part in the productions of the present day. And the hope of greater economic goods pleases humanity. That it is so we bless God, who shows that even from the hardest rock or the most arid soil He can draw bread for His children, who are multiplied on earth. This is a point of view from which it seems to us that large capitals have a providential mission. Themes. —A disciple of Marx, wishing to show that the value of a product is entirely due to labour, argues thus :—“ If from a piece of iron value a shilling, I make a farming implement, its value will become half-a-crown ; the increase of value is due to labour alone ; if now, by my labour, I return this implement to a piece of iron, its value will again become a shilling.” How is he to be answered ?—All kinds of industries, in order to be practised, have need of capital—How an increase of capital is an element of civilisa¬ tion : the larger the capital possessed, the less is the strength of man required in the work of production. CHAPTER VI. INDUSTRY. Section I.—Varieties of Industry. The different modes by which the agents of production accom¬ plish the productive process and attain their scope are called “ industries/' Now, grouping together those which are most alike, we may reduce all industries to three classes.* * * It would be better if many of our young men would turn to some good industry rather than aim at the medical or legal profession. There are too many doctors and lawyers who, notwithstanding the importance of their services, find it no easy matter to earn a respectable livelihood ; whereas, if they had taken to some “ business ” career, they might, with their abilities, have become far more prosperous. We may hope that the new National University in Dublin, directed by an enlightened senate, and giving a better tone to education all over the country, will fit many of its students to take an efficient part in developing by every possible means the material resources of Ireland. This will be the way to have agriculture, manufactures, and commerce flourish. A striking example of the enormous wealth to which some men attain by an industrial pursuit is that of Mr. Andrew Carnegie. Born in 1837, he began, when about ten years of age, to earn his bread as a bobbin-boy in SMALL AND LARGE INDUSTRIES 147 The first consists of those which have for their object to bring ns the fruits of nature, either by taking them without more ado, as the fisherman takes fish, or by co-operating with nature in the production and ripening of a crop, as the farmer does. This industry is said to be “ agricultural/' A second class of industries have as their object to work on the products of other industries, and thereby to give them a utility for us that they had not before. These are called “ manufactur¬ ing" industries. The third class of industries is that whose business it is to carry things to a place where they will have a special utility. These industries are called “ commercial." Section II. —Small and Large Industries. Industry has existed at all times. Man, from the earliest ages, found that he should apply his intellectual and physical powers to natural agents, in order to have production from them. Thus he gives himself to work—devotes himself to industry. Naturally we do not regard man as alone, but in society, and first in domestic society. Here he easily exercised his industry, assisted by those belonging to him, and destined its produce, not only for the use of his own household, but for the use of other persons. From these other persons he expected a return in the fruits of their industry. Industry strictly domestic, although it has ceased in great measure, cannot be said to have entirely disappeared. And for the advantages, especially moral ones, that it brings to the family, in whose bosom it keeps alive a cordial union, which is the founda¬ tion of all their good, it would be very desirable to have it extensively revived. But we must not hesitate to acknowledge that, confined within the domestic walls, it would not be sufficiently productive for the demands of modern society. Very soon, the number of men in the world having increased, the need of a division of labour was felt, and also the need of employing large capital in production, so as to increase its fruit. Alleghany City, Pennsylvania. Retiring from business in 1901, he trans¬ ferred into new hands the Carnegie Steel Co. at a valuation of 500,000,000 dollars, say £100,000,000. Unlike most men of wealth, Mr. Carnegie is not of a grasping character. On the contrary, he has shown himself most generous. With good intentions for the welfare of the poorer classes, he has founded an immense number of libraries ; but, sad to say, it would seem that many of the books placed on the shelves of those libraries would be much better thrown into the fire than placed in the hands of youth. Up to 1904 his benefactions exceeded £14,000,000, of which £11,000,000 were gi\ en in the United States, with the assurance of much more to come. He gave £2,000,000 to the Universities of Scotland, his native country, and £500,000 for improving and beautifying Dunfermline, his native town. Of steel it may be said that through successive improvements in its manufacture it has now twice the strength of iron. It is not fibrous, but of 148 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY And so industry passed beyond the domestic walls, profiting of social inequalities, and engaging other hands for labour, and even some capital, more or less. Here were the small industries, which continued universally until our times. They did not cease to exist through any want of vitality or through an in¬ sufficiency of good results. No, they were suffocated by new conditions that sprang up around them. The history of economy in modern times totally separates its productive facts from those of ancient times. The human genius opened out to marvellous conquests in nature. It seized on new forces, over which it ruled, and, by means of special inventions, made them a suitable substitute for the physical fatigue of man. Behold, therefore, machinery in the field of industry! It. devours much and produces much. On the other hand, the overthrown barriers made communica- equal strength in all directions. Houses, with a steel frame-work, are built to the height of twenty stories, and are common in the United States. The property of Mr. H. H. Rogers, New York (at one time a newsboy),, who carried on the “ Standard Oil ” business, and who died in 1909, was estimated at £10,000,000. A highly useful book, as showing the industries that exist in Ireland, and also those that might be developed in different localities, is The Irish Manu¬ facturers’ Directory and Year-Booh, published annually in Dublin, by Mr. K. J. Kenny, 58 Middle Abbey Street. Another valuable little book is The Key to the World’s Progress, by Mr. C. G. Devas, one of a cheap series by Messrs. Longmans. Its chief object, however, is to show that true progress ought not to be merely material. For temporal glory and prosperity are too often accompanied with a host of vices, which prey like a cancer on the vitals of society ; and the Scripture assures us that sin maketh nations miserable. (Prov. xiv. 34). The success of Mr. Charles Dickens in a literary career was very great—- we might say exceptional. He began life in a blacking-store, and after his death his will showed property to the extent of £80,000. But such success, apart from other considerations, was very small in comparison with that of Mr. Carnegie or Mr. Rogers. A most instructive lecture on the Literary Life, by the Very Rev. P. A. Canon Sheehan, D.D., appeared in the Irish Monthly, April, 1909. Little need be said of students who desire to become priests, or to devote their lives entirely to the service of God. There is ample room for them ; and it is highly creditable to many Catholic families in Ireland that for generations past they have always endeavoured to give at least one of their members to the Church. No more useful or meritorious work can be imagined than to labour for the salvation of souls. It is a pity that more of our young men, especially such as would feel obliged by circumstances to emigrate, do not think of competing for some of the higher situations at home or abroad in the Civil Service, but leave them to be taken by Englishmen and Scotchmen, who are far from being their superiors in genuine talent or ability. N6 doubt there are some dis¬ advantages connected with them, but is there any position in life free from all objection ? If Irishmen were excluded from employment in those rather enviable situations, would there not be loud complaints of such injustice ? The position is respectable, the salary good (sometimes rising above £1,000), the hours of business very moderate, the responsibilities less than in many other conditions of life ; there is an annual vacation; there is leave of absence in case of sickness, with continued pay ; and a liberal pension is allowed on retirement, which takes place at a comparatively early age, when a man SMALL AND LARGE INDUSTRIES 149 tion easy between people and people, and widened immensely the old market-place. Behold the large industries ! These have certainly their advantages, of which economists discourse at great length. Nor without reason; for, having lowered much the price of products, they rendered the acquisition and use of them more easy and therefore more general. We wish, however, to place under the eyes of the student some reflections that are socially of the greatest importance. The large industries are naturally the rivals of the small ones, which can scarcely, except for some special reason here and there, survive. Attracted by the large industries, small patrimonies, which supported many respectable positions, should, by the force of things, flow thither, and there they remained like branches without a trunk, their energies exhausted. Masters became servants; capitalists, workingmen. can still be of much service to his country. To disregard all these advantages, saying that a son of Ireland ought not to be a servant of England (even though his prospects in Ireland may not be good), seems to be a serious mistake, and may leave many a deserving youth to spend his life in a con¬ stant struggle with poverty—a high price to pay for the indulgence of a hobby. No wonder that an intelligent writer in the Irish Educational Review (July, 1909, p. 613) asks :—“ How many Intermediate Exhibitioners have been in menial employment in the City of Cork ? One, I am told, is, or was, a coal heaver; others are earning a scanty wage, barely sufficient to keep soul and body together.” If men insist on a total separation from England, may they not have to wait for it till the Greek Calends ? Is it not better to make a virtue of necessity ? There is no just reason to suppose that a man holding one of those situations would cease to be a patriotic Irishman. He would rather disarm prejudice, and promote the interests of Ireland wherever he went. His experience in different regions would enable him to give prudent advice with regard to matters of trade and commerce. Moreover, he could easily afford to assist his relatives, if they required his aid. But perhaps the best feature of all in the case is that he would have ample opportunity for practising his religious as well as social duties. Some of our Colleges—notably Blackrock—that have applied themselves to the development of this mine, have been wonderfully successful. Candidates require a good all-round education in the first place, and then a special grinding that will fit them to deal accurately with strict examination tests. Careless work has no chance. A limit is put to age. There are other situations of a still higher order in the Civil Service, but we have not referred to them, as they are not open to competition. They are filled by appointment. If Ireland had the same favourable conditions of existence as other countries under English rule, such as Australia, Canada, South Africa, &c., there would be plenty of congenial situations for young Irishmen in their native land, and there would be little need of emigration. It is to be hoped that all situations in the Banks, Railways, &c., of Ireland, which earn their money by Irish business, will soon be thrown open to public competition. Many of those situations, however, will be far less remunera¬ tive and far more risky than those to which we have alluded above. Whatever position in life a man may occupy, he ought to bear a high character for honesty, truthfulness, and all other such virtues, which he should practice not merely from worldly motives, but in accordance with the dictates of a good conscience.— Trans. 150 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY Tlius society, which, in order to have stability, requires many various classes, found itself to consist for the most part of poor workmen, and a small minority of capitalists, rising suddenly and often recklessly to the top of the ladder. We will not say that in these conditions social life is impossible. We will only say that it is possible under one or other of the following alternatives. Either breathe into the social body such an abundant spirit of Christianity as will give the upper classes a proper consciousness of their social duties, so that they— mindful that might is not right—may share with the lower classes, as justice and charity require, those good things of God wdiich their industry has brought forth ; or—because it is in no man’s power to secure that first alternative—guarantee that, by special contracts or provident regulations, the lower classes will be protected under the shield of State supervision from the exorbitant demands of the upper. In taking these precautions, it is proper to bear in mind the numerous abuses for which large industries offer an easy opportunity. Low wages, unhealthy places for work, association of sexes, a time-table inconsistent with age, with sex, with home duties, with decorum, with strength, with humanity—these are grave abuses, which injure families and all society. Leo XIII., after acknowledging that “ the wonderful progress in arts and in new methods of industry, the changed relations between masters and workpeople, the large fortunes accumulated in the hands of a few, the poverty of the multitude, the greater self-reliance and closer combination of the working classes, and a moral deterioration have brought about a conflict,” asserts in clear language that “ there is an obligation on employers to allow workpeople sufficient time to comply wfith their religious duties, not to expose them to corrupting influences and dangerous occasions, not to turn away their minds from the family spirit and the love of thrift, not to impose work on them disproportioned to their strength or unsuited to their age or sex . . . Let capitalists and employers remember that to oppress the poor and needy for the sake of gain, or to traffic in the misery of others, is not allowed by any law, divine or human.” {Rerum novarum.) The large industries, as systematised and managed at the present day, are characterised by a marked separation of labour from capital. These two things, which ought to act in harmony, are formed into two opposing camps, each struggling for a defence and triumph of its own interests. Facts are only too numerous in confirmation of what has been here said. “ By degrees the working classes, isolated and defence¬ less, have been placed at the mercy of inhuman masters, and exposed to the greed of unrestrained competition. . . . These evils have been increased by a monopoly of labour, and by the concentration of all branches of trade in the hands of a few, so that a very small number of rich men have laid on a countless THE UNDERTAKER OR CONTRACTOR 151 multitude of poor people a yoke little better than slavery.’" (Rerum novarum.) Such a state of affairs has been caused for the most part by large industries, which, unless a remedy is applied in time, threaten the very existence of civil society. Section III.— The Undertaker or Contractor. The union of property and labour in a productive work is certainly more effectual when property and labour are in the hands of only one individual. This, however, in the present condition of industry, happens seldom. It oftener happens that two or three individuals are in possession of the pro¬ ductive agents. To bring them together is necessary for production. This is done by means of co-operative societies or the like. But these do not always suit the conditions of the different proprietors. Special contracts are then made, by which it is agreed that one person alone, who is really master neither of capital nor labour, should assume the responsibility of uniting both. And this through special contracts, by which, with confident anticipation, he releases proprietors, capitalists, and labourers from danger of loss in production. He takes all the risk on himself, and proceeds to production. This new character who makes his appearance, in addition to the three agents already mentioned, is called the undertaker or contractor. What, therefore, is an undertaker ? Boccardo defines him as one whose profession consists in conceiving and conducting an agricultural, manufacturing, or commercial enterprise. His essential function in the undertaking to which he devotes himself, and in which many others besides him are concerned, is, says Concede-Seneuil, to foresee and to provide for contingencies; to associate and to direct labour and capital in production; to suit products to the wants of the times ; and to adapt the supply to the demand. “ It is enough,” continues the same author, “ to cast a look on modern society, in order to observe that among those who compete, by any title, in the production of goods, there are three distinct classes. Some persons have capital, and confide to others the care of employing it: they are capitalists. A second class entrust to others the employment of their personal labour : they are men of wages or salary. The last, in fine, study to give of themselves employment to labour and capital, either their own, or received on loan: they are undertakers.” ( Diz ., II., 442.) Is the undertaker a help to production ? Without doubt. He is a man of special technical ability, who groups three agents together, so that the production may be more abundant and perfect. And this is a benefit for all civil society. 152 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY Does he deserve a reward for his work ? Who can doubt it ? What wonder ? His technical ability has had an effect, and the effect ought to be his by every right. This remuneration, which is the portion of the produce due to the technical aid of the undertaker, is called “ profit. 55 Besides the title of causality, there is another of which we must make account in settling the proportion of produce that constitutes profit. It is the risky character that is inseparable from every produce. The undertaker pays by anticipation for labour, rent of land, interest of capital. He then goes forth to take his chance—either a notable profit or a serious loss—not only a loss of profit, but perhaps a wreck of all his anticipations. If the result of a hazardous eventuality is good, to whom ought it to pertain if not to the adventurer ? That is to say, to the undertaker. Section IY.—The Contract of Labour. Labour and capital require to be united. Hence, special contracts for this union. These contracts, as they mostly occur by a bargain that the proprietor or capitalist makes for the work of the labourer, take the name of “ contracts of labour/ 5 What are the coefficients of such a contract ? The liberal school recognises only two—the capitalist and the labourer. It does not care whether there is any freedom of consent between the parties who make a bargain. The contract is thrown on the waves of free competition. We recognise a third coefficient, which, properly speaking, would be the first, and which, as the Pope says, is “ anterior and superior to the free will of the con¬ tracting parties. 55 It is natural justice. Though we have set forth in a former chapter the characteristics of labour that raise it immensely above common merchandise, we admit that the contract of labour is just, and is agreed to freely between two parties. The encyclical makes mention of three coefficients when, speaking of the duties of the workman, it says that he is “ to perform honestly and faithfully the work that was freely and according to equity contracted for. 55 Nor does this natural justice enter into the contract of labour only with regard to wages, but it enters generally, for the defence of every purpose that nature intends by labour. For instance, in regard to rest, to which the workman has a right, the Pope says: —“ In every agreement that is entered into between masters and workmen, there is always the condition, expressed or understood, that both kinds of rest will be allowed. Nor would it be just to agree otherwise; because it is never lawful for anyone to ask or to promise a neglect of the duties that a man owes to God and to himself. 55 (Rerum novarwn.) WAGES 153 Section V. —The Co-operative System. A very obvious mode of uniting capital with labour in production is that of the co-operative societies. They would appear the ideal of industrial enterprises, but they are not equally practical. By the large industries, which require immense capital, they are avoided more and more every day. Brants gives us three types of them. The first type is that of a co-operation of persons. Several workmen place themselves at the head of the enterprise. They study its difficulties, and settle about them. They provide means, work together, and, the production being finished, divide the produce. The second type is that of a co-operation of capitals. They are companies into which it is necessary that each member should enter with some capital. Shares are formed; and each work¬ man, according to the amount of his funds, takes a number of them. In the division of the produce, account is made of the number of shares that each one holds. The third type is that of Societies with participation in benefits. This system is in substance that of men receiving wages, of which we shall soon speak. Its special feature is that, at the end of the production, it calls together the workmen (who have already received their wages), and gives them a portion of the net profits. Section YI.—Wages. The most common mode at present of uniting capital with labour is that of wages. It is a system much exposed to the abuses of capital, and therefore requires to be supplemented by honesty in the contracting parties, and by such regulations as may place them in a position of sufficient freedom. We may, therefore, define wages as that quota which is anticipated on the future produce for the workman by the capitalist or undertaker, who takes on himself the risk of the production. Production, even the most safe or promising, is subject to two conditions, which are inseparable. They are (i.) a certain space of time before having the produce, and (ii.) a more or less probable chance of a result little remunerative, perhaps not at all so, but disastrous. And thus production takes so far a gaming character. The game affects the capitalist; it does not affect the workman. Wages anticipate and secure for the needy workman his quota of the produce. It follows that they are a real advantage for him. A question is asked : Are there any natural principles from which springs the right of a workman to a reward for his work ? There ought to be, and there are, in our opinion, two. The first is that labour is productive. Labour, like everything else 154 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY in the world, is a design of God, and He designed it in so far that, by itself, it can realise the phenomenon of production. Now, common sense teaches that the produce should go to the producer, as to its cause. The encyclical alludes to this principle when it reasons thus :—“ Would it be justice if he who has not laboured should enjoy the fruits of another man’s labour ? As the effect follows its cause, so it is right that the fruit of labour should belong to him who labours.” But the destination of human labour to production cannot be final. Labour has as its end to serve man, by its fruits. Here we see the second principle of wages. The fruit of labour, or the produce, ought, by the arrange¬ ment of nature, to serve for the satisfaction of the wants of him who labours. Behold the words of the Pope : —“ To labour is to exert oneself in order to provide for the wants of life, and especially for its preservation : in the sweat of thy face shalt thou eat bread.” Observe how the first principle brings directly to the capitalist the duty of giving the labourer a just payment, and to the labourer the right of claiming it. The second brings a duty directly to the labourer, who ought to use his wages for his own support. It is also useful to observe how the second principle takes its origin from the first; for we do not mean to say that the labourer has a right to wages by himself, but because his labour is productive. So that if there was a time in history when labour did not produce as much as was required for the support of the labourer, he had not a right to the usual wages, but only to that quota which corresponded to the productivity of his labour. In what measure then are wages due to the workman ? Do the two principles above-mentioned throw any light on the subject ? We believe that theoretically they may indeed supply an answer to the question. The first says that the labourer has a right to the whole quota of produce that is the effect of his labour. Can there be any doubt of it ? The second offers a more specific determination, inasmuch as it also points out the use for which the produce of labour is intended. So that if the whole produce of labour passes naturally into the ownership of the labourer, ■we must remember that of one portion of it the labourer has not the free use : it should be employed as nature wishes. Of the portion that remains, after this appointed use, the labourer, who is master of it, can dispose as he pleases, and therefore can even make a present of it. But we are not yet come to the measure of wages. We have reasoned on the right that the labourer has to a part of the produce. The man under wages, however, wishes to be treated with other considerations. We spoke of a special contract, which contains some favourable elements for the labourer ; and compensation for these elements is made to the capitalist by a particular advantage, which is the probability of a greater quota of produce than would otherwise fall to him. WAGES 155 We see, therefore, that the second principle takes away from the free disposal of the contracting parties a portion of the wages (that which is needed for the wants of the labourer) ; and leaves the rest to the bargain of the labourer with him who buys his labour. The words of the encyclical on this point are well known. The Pope, having shown the opinion of classic economy, which, misunderstanding the natural origin of wages, abandons every¬ thing to the contract between the labourer and the capitalist, says :— ' 4 To this kind of reasoning a fair-minded man cannot easily or entirely agree ; for there is one consideration of the greatest importance that it omits. To labour is to exert oneself in order to provide for the wants of life, and especially for its preservation : in the sweat of thy face shalt thou eat bread. Human labour has, therefore, two characteristics impressed on it by nature. First, it is personal, because the active power belongs to him by whom it is exercised, and for whose advantage it has been given. Secondly, such labour is necessary, because man requires the fruit of labour for the maintenance of life : the preservation of life is an indispensable duty imposed by nature. Now, if we consider labour only inasmuch as it is personal, there is no doubt that the workman can agree to a payment lower than is just; for as he is free to work or not, so he is free to accept small wages or even none at all. But far differently must we judge when account is made not only of personality , but also of necessity : two things separable in thought, but not in reality. The preserva¬ tion of life is a duty, in which no one can fail without crime. Hence follows, as a necessary consequence, the right of seeking means of support, which with poor people are reduced to wages for their work. Let it be granted then that a workman and an employer make a bargain by mutual consent especially with regard to the amount of wages ; there always enters an element of natural justice, anterior and superior to the will of the contracting parties, and it is that the remuneration should not be less than is required for the support of the workman in frugal and decent comfort. If through necessity, or through fear of a worse evil, the workman agrees to harder conditions, which, being imposed by the employer or contractor, must willingly or unwillingly be accepted, this is to suffer violence, against which justice protests/’ We ought not to forget that the labourer is a man, and that therefore wages ought to be sufficient, not for the support of an animal that leads a merely animal life (as the English school would have it), but of an animal that is rational, a human being, who has duties of improvement towards himself and of worship towards God, which he is enabled to discharge by a good use of his wages. The same Holy Father, in the encyclical Graves de communi, explaining the programme of Christian Democracy, says of workmen : —“ That at home and in public they may freely 156 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY comply with their moral and religions duties; that they may feel themselves not to be beasts but men, not pagans but Christians; and that they may thus more easily and earnestly devote themselves to the attainment of the one thing necessary , the supreme good, for which we are born.” A minimum of wages, below which neither the labourer nor the employer can go without offending against natural justice, is shown by what is required for the support of a frugal and well- conducted workman. Take notice, however, of every word. It is said that this is the minimum, but not that it is the maximum. If justice is offended by going below the minimum, it may also be offended by stopping at that amount—if, taking every cir¬ cumstance into account, a sum is not given to the workman pro¬ portional to the productivity of his labour. “ Family wages” are so called because they are sufficient for the support not only of a workman, but also of his family. Now comes the question : Ought the wages of the workman to be “family wages”? Nearly all Catholic economists say so. But they are not unanimous in assigning a title for it. Some maintain that family wages, in the same manner as individual wages, are due by natural justice. Others argue thus : As, the labourer being rational, individual wages ought to correspond to the requirements of a creature endowed with reason, so, having from nature a right to form a family, and, it being formed, having a right to support and educate it, the wages ought to be family wages, in order that the labourer who has a family may be able to fulfil his duties towards it. Such is the opinion of Liberatore, Steccanella, Pottier, and others of great weight. Others, opposing this view, go with Antoine, who derives not from commutative justice, but from social justice, the right of the labourer to sufficient wages for the support of his family : “ but if family wages are not an object of commutative justice, they are not less required by social order or less necessary for the common good of society.” The encyclical (Rer. nov.) does not decide this point. Only on one occasion does it make mention of family wages—where it exhorts the labourer to make a wise use of the fruit of his labour. " When the wages of a workman are sufficient to maintain himself, his wife, and his children in reasonable comfort, he will easily, if he is a wise man, study thrift.” For the rest, Christian Democracy has adopted the principle of family wages, and the Catholic Congress of Social Studies held at Genoa in 1891 solemnly proclaimed the workman's right to them. Another question regarding wages is this : Should the State interfere in the contract of labour, and secure to the labourer at least a minimum of wages ? Some absolutely deny it, and they appeal to the authority of the Pope, whose encyclical is silent WAGES 157 on such a duty in the State. Cathrein would have the State interfere, but only when justice is endangered. The State, he says, can fix the smallest amount of wages, if there is danger of their being lowered beyond the limits of justice ( Philos . Moral., p. 419). Many declare without any hesitation that this is a duty of the State, since it concerns the wellbeing of the workman and his family, and therefore of all society. As for those who maintain that there should be no interference, because the Pope does not claim it, or rather he excludes it, we may be permitted to recall the true terms of the subject, and the manner in which the Pope treats it. 'Two questions appear for consideration : first, if the State ought to fix a minimum of wages for each particular industry; and secondly, if it ought to fix a general minimum, below which no employer could descend. The first question, we believe, ought to be settled by having no interference of the State, because it is beyond the power of the State to have such a knowledge of minute elements as is indispensable for a just rule. Here we believe that between the State and the contracting parties there is room for the action of societies or guilds. And this agrees well with what the encyclical says :—“ In these and similar cases—such as the hours of labour in different trades, the sanitary precautions to be observed in workshops, &c.—that authority may not meddle without cause, especially when there is so great a variety of affairs, times, and places, it will be better to reserve these things for the judgment of Boards, such as we shall mention presently, or to take some other way of protecting, in accordance with justice, the interests of the wage-earners—the State giving, if necessary, its approval and support.” This would suit exceedingly well. The second question we settle by calling for the interference of the State. And it appears to be what the encyclical desires. The Pope treats of this point when he shows what the State ought to do for the solution of the social question. Let us hear how he refers to it:—“ We now approach a subject that is of great importance, and that requires to be well understood, so as not to fall into one or other of two opposite extremes. The amount of wages, we are told, is fixed by free consent. Therefore the employer, having paid the wages, has done his part, and does not seem to owe anything more. Then only is an injustice done if the master does not pay the full wages, or if the workman does not perform the full work agreed to. In these cases, but in no others, it is proper that the State should interfere, so that each one's right may be protected.” Here the Pope sets forth, as everyone sees, the theory of the liberal classical school. He then refutes it. Among the points refuted is this, that the defence of rights as agreed to by the parties is the only reason to justify the interference of the State. But the Pope wishes this inter¬ ference for something more, which is not agreed to by the parties —it urges of itself. And what can this be if not that minimum 158 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY for which we look—that is to say, a decision in regard to the minimum of wages ? As for the exception made by Cathrein, “ if there is danger of wages being lowered beyond the limits of justice,” we do not know why it should be an exception, and not the rule. For there is always danger; and just because such danger threatens the common good, we wish to see it removed by the State. 14 Themes. —Labour is not merchandise ; but, in part at least, it may be valued like merchandise, weighing it between supply and demand— Labourers being disorganised, there is need for a labour market, in which wages would be free from the chances of supply and demand ; the laws of labour should be established in the market; a minimum of wages, and other conditions of justice, should be secured for the labourer. CHAPTER VII. AGRICULTURAL INDUSTRY. Section I.— Systems and Contracts. The ideal of agricultural industry would be that of a working man, who cultivates his own ground, and reaps its fruits for him¬ self and those belonging to him. But, for a very complex variety of causes, this cannot be, except in a few cases. The social fact, as it exists, is that of landlords and tenants. The former own the ground, and have need of tenants for its cultivation. The latter have need of those who will trust the land to them, on which they may expend their labour. Here we see the owner of the ship and the crew : their united efforts are required for a successful voyage. Various systems are proposed for uniting the work of the agriculturist with the land of the proprietor, so that the well¬ being of both parties may be the result. There are three principal systems, of which we ought to make mention: (i.) that of mezzadria or metayage; (ii.) that of rent; and (iii.) that of wages. On these various forms we may pronounce the same judgment as on the various forms of government. They are in themselves all good : each one, however, may be abused by the malice or the greed of men. To obviate abuses, various contracts are strengthened with special conditions, of which some are imposed (and wisely too) by law, others are left to the free will of the contracting parties. In making such engagements, the follow¬ ing considerations should be kept in mind :— 1. Whatever may be the form of contract to which the owner and the worker agree, they ought to remember well that they enter into relations not only economical, but also moral—relations which, besides affecting both, have a great influence on public MEZZADRIA OR METAYAGE 159 life. And this is nothing but the application of a general principle. The material world is subordinated to the moral, and the man who uses the former for the attainment of the ends proposed by the Creator, should act in such a manner that a wave, as large as possible, of morality and religion should enter the ocean of social life. 2. The productive process in agricultural industry takes a longer time than in other industries. The capital and labour that you employ on a field or a vineyard will not give fruit this year. They will give it next year, and for a series of years, longer or shorter according to the generosity with which you treat the soil, and the kind of cultivation that you initiate or promote. 3. It is necessary, as well for the owner as for the worker, and also for the public, that capital should be expended in the cultivation of land. This is a condition required that the soil may act like a machine and give produce for all. Left to itself, or rather subjected to an impoverishing treatment (there is no want of modes), it wastes its resources, and enters into a state of barrenness, not to be remedied in a single year, nor easily. 4. We must take into account that the net produce of the land cannot be separately valued every year. A variety of causes influence agricultural production, so that one year it is abundant, another year scarce. It even happens that a very bad year occurs at intervals : owing to the inclemency of the weather, the harvest is totally ruined, and the net produce is nothing. To provide for this calamity, it is, therefore, proper to take an average on a certain number of harvests. 5. It will be for the advantage of both parties, and more in accordance with the designs of nature, that intercourse between the landlord and the farmer should be direct or immediate. Hence the exclusion, as far as possible, of speculators and middlemen. On every occasion and in every way, let the proprietor be mindful of that Christian patronage which he owes to those who work under him. If he does not deal immediately with them, let him assist them by special clauses , which may protect them from the rapacity of an agent. 15 Section II. —Mezzadria or Metayage. Nature and labour must be united in order to give place to that process which ends in produce. What better arrangement of an industry than that of bringing together the owner and the worker ? This is one of the results of the contract of mezzadria or metayage, which regards the owner and the worker as partners in a company ; the former brings the capital of his property, and the latter the capital of his labour. At the end of the year there is a distribution of the produce. The advantages of this contract are evident. The owner and 160 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY the worker, having a community of interests, find themselves very much in a fraternal state of mind. They are companions ; and if the worker pronounces the word “ master/’ he does not feel it burning on his lips. They run the same risk; nor will the chance of an unfavourable season fall only on one. It is certainly the ideal of an agricultural contract. “ Mezzadria, precisely because it inspires Christian ideas, is the agricultural contract that most raises the legal condition of the cultivator, as a companion of the owner ; that most favours a union of classes, co-ordinating individual to social interests; and that most secures the moral and civil value of the cultivator. It will always, therefore, remain the ideal of Catholic economists.” (Mauri, at the Congress of Padua.) Yet we must not close our eyes to the fact that even this contract often becomes, on one side or the other, ruinous, and therefore unadvisable : not through any defect of the contract, but through the evil minds of the contracting parties. The lot of the mezzadro or metayer is found less pleasant, indeed sad, if the owner lays on him some heavy conditions, in the form of a supplement to the contract, requiring so many days of actual work, lessening the amount of crop by an anticipated percentage, and so on. Even the lot of the owner may be unfortunate. It happens when the mezzadro, not guided in his actions by the light of a Christian conscience, lessens the quantity of crop due to the master; ventures to make unjust anticipations; in short, avails himself of his position as companion to rob with a safe hand. The history of mezzadria is very ancient, and we find among the customs of different localities a great variety of conditions. Many of these no longer suit the requirements of our time and the changed methods of production. Hence the necessity of revising agricultural contracts and framing them to meet the needs of the present day. This task of revision was declared in the Congress of Taranto to be a duty on Catholics, who, in some places, have complied with it, especially for the good of the tillers. A Catholic journal, treating of the subject in a very sensible article, concludes thus:— “We cannot admit a contract of mezzadria unless it has the following provisions : security for the families of the tillers, or for such of them as have permanent employment on the land, that they will receive a portion of the produce sufficient for the wants of life and labour ; compensation for lasting improvements ; safeguarding of the productive powers of the soil; direct co¬ operation, as much as possible, with the owner, in the manage¬ ment of the farm. “ The question of the division of the produce thus becomes a secondary thing. A tiller who, on a fertile or irrigated farm in Piedmont, on land treated according to the Solari* method, *Solari is the name of a celebrated Italian agriculturist,who lately employed chemistry and electricity with much success in the treatment of the soil.— Trans. RENT 161 receives the third part of the produce, will have much more per acre than a tiller who, on some farms in the neighbourhood of Gubbio, receives three-fourths of the produce. The share should never be disproportioned to the labour; nor can the greater fertility of a farm ever be by itself a motive for lessening the share of the tiller. “ The care of the productive powers of the soil requires the aid of the proprietor with capital, and his direct supervision, that which alone recalls land proprietors to the useful exercise of their natural duty of patronage. “ Examining the agricultural contracts of different districts by the light of these principles, Catholic landowners, well inten- tioned, will be the first to acknowledge in what points and in what measure such contracts should be revised—thus cutting away the roots of social agitation. Custom, if it sometimes becomes law, can never be invoked when it violates justice : this would be contrary to our character as Christians.” (Avvenire d’Italia.)™ Section III. —Rent. A system universally known and practised is that of rent. The owner lets to the tenant a farm to be cultivated and reaped by him alone, and receives in compensation an annual amount, either in money or in kind. What characterises this contract is that a return is secured to the owner, and the tenant takes on himself the fortunate or unfortunate result of the harvest. As is evident, this contract presents two elements economically appreciable. One of these is in favour of the owner, and it is the certainty of a moderate return; the other is in favour of the tenant, and it is the expectation of a more abundant income. The certainty indemnifies the former for renouncing a larger return, and the prospect of a plentiful crop seems to the latter a good reason for running the risk of the event. As in mezzadria, the tenant here promises himself a com¬ pensation for his toil. This compensation is reckoned by the remainder that is left or net produce, the rent being deducted. But, as has been said, this remainder cannot be valued except as an average on a number of years. Therefore, it may happen that in some year, for many reasons, there is no remainder. Yet the rent—by the nature of the contract—is equally to be paid. The tenant should therefore be in a position to pay the rent and to defray the expenses of life. Here you see the reason why rent, differing from metayage, is more suited for those places in which country people enjoy a certain economic power. It is a system that presents some special advantages. The tenant, acquiring a certain autonomy, L 162 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY feels that he is not a slave. He works the ground with greater alacrity, and looking forward to the produce, which will be all his own, employs every art to make it abundant. Often this diligence results in domestic fortunes, which contribute so much to the prosperous stability of families. It is necessary, however, that special conditions should accom- pan 3 ^ the contract, so that it may not become ruinous for the tenant. Above all, the amount of rent should be moderate. To fix it, it must be remembered that the tenant has to live by the fruits of his labour; that the quantity of produce for him is un¬ certain, while his wants are certain; that he should have the fruits of his material and intellectual labour, and also' of the capital that almost every day he must expend in order to have profitable cultivation. A considerable time should be allowed for the payment of rent. The land is like a machine that does not give all its produce in a single year. It is providentially economic. Being well nourished, it serves for several crops. Now, the tenant, who wishes to derive profit from his rented farm, should give it good nourishment. He should lay out on it a capital that is his own. Even labour is a capital. It is that of the workingman, and it enters in a manner into the ground ; nor is it wholly exhausted by one harvest. To evict the tenant from the farm after a short time is to prevent him from reaping the fruits of capital that belong to him alone. That clause is also to be condemned which gives the owner the right of evicting the tenant for any failure in the terms agreed to. At least, let it not be so general. The failure may be a thing of little or no consequence, and it may not depend on the will of the tenant. To deprive a man of his only means of existence is neither justice nor charity. On the other hand, the landowner should, by appropriate conditions in the contract, safeguard his own position. Let him not be content with a rent too low. The tenant might then find himself rather much in danger of neglecting cultivation, of yielding to sloth, and thus the land would not bear fruit— which would be an evil for all parties. Let the owner often visit his fields and take note of their improvement. Let him weigh well the material and moral power of his tenants in regard to solvency, and let him look for reasonable security. Let him also endeavour to place such conditions in the contract as will promote religious and virtuous habits among his tenants. As regards security, which, in the great disorders of our times, may justly be required by the owner, and, on the other side, cannot be given by many of the tenants, a proposal of collective rent has been providentially made by Catholics. It works in this way. An association of tenants is formed, which charges itself with the rent of an extent of land proportioned to the amount of capital and labour that it feels itself able to employ. The PERPETUAL RENT 163 cultivation can then be made, either by assigning to each family of the tenants a portion of the ground with all its relative re¬ sponsibilities, or by entering on a common cultivation under the guidance of a technical director chosen by the cultivators. Section IV. —Perpetual Rent. The idea of uniting a landowner and a tenant for ever would appear a mere poetic fancy. I say -poetic fancy, because the miseries with which humanity is afflicted are too well known. Yet this idea, so eminently Christian, was for many centuries a fact. Even in our own times it still exists to some extent by means of the contract that bears the name of emphyteusis. This is a contract by which the owner of an immovable property grants for a long time or for ever the use dominion* of it at an annual fixed rent. The characteristic of this contract is that it separates the direct dominion, which remains with the owner, from the use dominion, which passes to the tenant or emphyteuta. He who reflects ever so little will at once see the economical and social advantages of this contract. The emphyteuta applies himself with great courage to the improvement of his farm. His ideal is always to increase the difference between the net produce that it gives him and the lease rent that he has to pay, certain, as he is, that he and his children will enjoy the fruits of their labour. By emphyteusis the social function of land property, that of providing for the establishment and permanence of families in a particular locality, is doubly fulfilled, the emphyteutic farm recognising two masters. The economical and social benefits of emphyteusis were ex¬ perienced above all in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, when it seemed the only contract offering a means of reducing uncultivated estates to a remunerative condition. Modern legislation has unnaturalised emphyteusis, so changing its conditions as to make it a real sale, though with a long indefinite period for full payment, compensated for by the pay¬ ment of an annual rent. Since the benefits of emphyteusis flow from it as emphyteusis, as that emphyteusis which the Romans and the men of the Middle Ages practised, it is only fair to conclude that the emphyteusis of our days cannot bear the same beneficent fruits. How necessary would it be in this case to return to antiquity ! 17 * An example may help to make this point still more clear. The dominion of use, including usufruct, entitles a tenant to cultivate a farm, and to enjoy all its fruits; but the dominion of ownership of the farm belongs to the landlord. The aforesaid dominion of use, when hereditary, is called emphyteusis. This last word is derived from the Greek emphuteuo, ** I plant or improve land.”— Trans. 164 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY Section V.—Rural Wages. The system of wages is very general in agriculture. The land- owner, taking on himself all the risk and responsibility of his venture, looks forward to a plentiful gain, and from day to day secures for the labourers a produce that supplies their wants. This contract is realised in several ways. Sometimes the owner hires the labourer for a whole year, and pays him in a certain quantity of food, firewood, &c., leaving the rest of the family to think of completing by their labour the earnings of their head. Sometimes the whole family are engaged by the owner : he makes a certain allowance for each person, and he has a right that all their work shall be for his benefit. This kind of contract, if ruled by justice, offers the advantage of securing food for the labourer, and also of enabling him to balance his domestic accounts, and to lay by some savings for future needs. It establishes relations of domesticity and Paternity between the owner and the labourer, when both enter into it with the honesty of a Christian conscience. The owner does not then require an excessive amount of work, or work on festive days; on the contrary, he allows the labourer to feel at ease as a Christian man and a member of a family. Let the owner bear in mind that if the labourer has promised labour, yet labour is not an article of merchandise, nor has the labourer bartered his soul, his dignity, his family. In so far he has promised labour as it is for the good of himself, his soul, his family, and according to the will of God. More frequently it happens that employment is uncertain. The labourers are not sure of work, either on land or in any other way. At every turn of the seasons, they must look out for new work and new masters. They may have to change their work and their masters every week, perhaps every day. Towards these poor men the master risks no obligation, not even that of giving them work; so that there is no resource left for them but to stand in the market-place. This is the place where labour is regarded as a real article of merchandise. In large towns, at an early hour in the morning, the labourers may be seen drawn up in lines like soldiers, with their iron tools on their shoulders— offering their services, and wrangling as if everyone strove to see who could lower the wages most. The amount of wages is thus tossed about on the waves of demand and supply, and there it rests where the strongest wave leaves it. If labour is. urgent, and many men are needed, the amount rises and the labourers are hired. If labour is not urgent and many men are not needed, the amount falls, and a good many are left idle in the market-place. It is easily understood that matters cannot prosper in this way. The labour market is a social disgrace. Labour, if it is to be TRANSPOET OF GOODS 165 ■viewed as a merchandise, is yet a merchandise so peculiar and precious that it essentially differs from all other merchandise. To fix its price then by the sole criterion of demand and supply, and to call that just, is to forget altogether the purpose for which God intended labour, and to abandon every idea of justice. Accordingly, let us conclude :— 1. Rural wages are certainly not of themselves to be con¬ demned. On the contrary, they are an advantage to those labourers who cannot enter into the contract either of mezzadria or rent. 2. It is desirable that fixed permanent wages should be sub¬ stituted for small daily payments. 3. The Christian patronage that a master should practise in regard to his dependants requires that he should have a special consideration for their wants and fatigues. Let him be eager to give them employment, and indulgent in rewarding them, so that they who, in the hour of their master’s need, are all heart and hand for him, may feel, in the hour of their own need, that he has a heart for them. CHAPTER VIII. COMMERCIAL INDUSTRY. Section I.—Transport of Goods. Life has a chequered course. The face of the earth is immense, and its productions are wonderfully various. Climates are different, vegetables are different, minerals are different. It does not follow that the man who lives in one place, and wishes to avail himself of the productions of another, must go thither. The shoulders of men, the backs of animals, the waves of the sea, are admirable means of transport. This is commerce. A question may be asked : is commerce productive ? Some say no ; because it does not impart any new utility to the thing that it transports. A little observation, however, will decide for the affirmative. It is true that change of place does not introduce into an article transported any new element that substantially increases, lessens, or modifies it. Let us, however, remember that the value does not lie in the article, but in its relation with our mind, which regards it as needful or useful. This being granted, everyone understands that an article may have no utility whatever in one place, and, therefore, be of no value (because there is a super¬ abundance of it or no one cares about it), and in another place it may have great value. The art by which it passes from the former to the latter place is that which puts it into the condition of having value. This art is, therefore, a productive industry. 166 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY “ Judging superficially, it may appear that the gain of the merchant is not justifiable. But we must consider (i.) that some producers have often need to sell in large quantities, while pur¬ chasers have the convenience of being able to buy in small quantities; (ii.) that the times seldom correspond when the former are ready to sell and the latter to buy ; and (iii.) that producers and consumers, being seldom much acquainted, do not know how to come into contact for the transaction of business. Commerce, which removes these difficulties, is, therefore, a useful intermediary. In point of fact, wherever industries of all kinds are most advanced, there are large commercial houses, in which different products are collected, and from which they are after¬ wards distributed/' (Agnelli.) Section II.— Exchange ; Value ; Money ; Price. If every man were provided with all that might be useful to him, the notion of value in exchange would have no existence. It would never be necessary that a man should deprive himself of one thing in order to procure another. But such are the conditions in which man lives that he desires many things besides what he requires. Hence the origin of exchange or barter, by which a man gives of his superabundance that he may obtain what he wants. The reason for barter is the utility of things. But not all things that are useful are bartered : only those which have value. Barter, therefore, is an exchange of values. The values that are exchanged ought to be equal; otherwise, there would be in the hands of one of the parties a portion of value without title. Where shall we find the measure of value ? The measure of a quantity ought to be a unit of the same species, constant, pot subject to easy or notable variations. But value is essentially variable, as its constituents are variable, and the conditions that create it are variable. To think, therefore, of a precise absolute measure of value is a mistaken idea. It is necessary to be content with an approximate relative measure, taking as the unit of comparison that value which is least subject to change. Such is the value of the precious metals, from which money is coined. It is proper, however, to observe that the introduction of money into exchange was anterior to the monetary use of those metals. Before thinking of the value of money, a sign was thought of. The barter of merchandise in kind presented, from the earliest days of social life, many difficulties in execution, and a useless expenditure of force. The idea then sprang up of a merchandise that, by common consent, would represent all sorts of merchan¬ dise, and that would, so to say, bring all sorts of merchandise close to hand. Such was the origin of money, which, as a EXCHANGE; VALUE; MONEY; PRICE 167 simple representative sign, may well be formed from a thing of little or no value.* Very soon, however, it was understood how money could be more useful, if, besides having a nominal value, it had also a real value. Thus the introduction of metals into monetary affairs is most ancient. For simple barter, the contract of buying and selling was substituted, at least in common practice. It denotes the exchange of a certain quantity of merchandise for a certain quantity of money. Sale, if well considered, has not a confined scope, but is directed to other sales, until an exchange is effected. Hence Say observes that sale is a half exchange, and Brants calls it a fraction of exchange. The portion of money that is given in purchase takes the name of price. It is substituted for the value, and is an expression of the value. The price is normal or current, and under either form is subject to the same laws as value : (i.) the current price of merchandise is directly proportional to the demand and inversely proportional to the supply ; (ii.) the normal or natural price is regulated by the cost of production, which tends to an equality. We may add another law : (iii.) the current price fluctuates about the natural price, as its centre. The condition of the market may raise the current price above the natural, and thus favour the first producers; but the profit that they make very soon attracts others to engage in the same production. Thus the supply is increased, until the current price is re-adjusted to the normal. In like manner, if, by a particular event—for instance, the offer of an equivalent commodity—the current price falls below the normal, then the number of producers will be lessened, the supply will be diminished, and the price will be recomposed. Christian economists have another term for price. They call it “ just ” when it corresponds with the estimation of the value in which anything is generally held. The classical or liberal school does not admit the possibility of an unjust price. Accord¬ ing to it, all justice is in the hands of the contracting parties : whatever price they agree to is just. We admit not only the intervention of conscience in fixing a just price, but also in certain cases the intervention of the State, (i.) Let the State prohibit private monopolies; that is, of those who gather into their possession a whole produce, so as to sell it at an exorbitant price, (ii.) When producers, taking advantage of a peculiar condition of the market, raise too much the price of goods that are of the utmost necessity, the State can and should interfere to fix the maximum price. No one has a right to promote his own interests with injury to the poor and needy. * Bank notes or postal orders, for example, are in themselves only paper.— Trans. 168 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY Section III.— Value of Money. By value we here mean the same thing as when speaking of other merchandise. We showed that value is the capability of one article in regard to exchange for another. The value of money will be its power to purchase goods. This being granted, it is easily understood that money has a two-fold value—namely, the value of the material of which it is composed, or the real value, and the value of an intermediary merchandise, which is called the conventional value. The former is not reckoned, except in some region where money is considered for the material of wdiich it is composed. However, it is the foundation of the latter, and it ought to be so. Money that has not a real value is a cheat for him who does not know what it is ; offered by way of convention, it is an illusion, to which no people submit. If a man, after a series of bargains, finds himself in possession of coin that has a real value, he has some¬ thing ; if the coin has not a real value, he has nothing. To say the least, it appears strange. Hence it is proper that the nominal should coincide as much as possible with the real value. The conventional value* is certainly what gives a formal character to money, and makes it capable of being what it is— a representative for all kinds of merchandise. And this value, according to definition, serves only for one purpose—exchange. With this service there is money ; without it, none. Hence it comes that money, as such, has only one use—a use that consists in its consumption, that is, in its employment. Money, therefore, has only one scope—exchange. Exchanged, it is consumed ; it no longer exists for him who had it, it exists for him who has it. As then a thing is said to be productive when it is susceptible of a value different from that which it has directly, money, which has only one value, that of exchange, is essentially unproductive. The value of anything being its power of acquisition, it follows that the value of money, like that of all other commodities, is variable. It does not avail to say that a piece of money has always the same name—for instance, a shilling or a crown. Here we do not treat of names, but of things. The value of money is reckoned from the quantity of goods that can be acquired by it. If yesterday I bought a kid for five shillings, and to-day it is worth eight, this is because money has fallen in value. Some one may say : No, it is because the kid has risen in value. The expression is reversed, but it amounts to the same thing. The * Although twenty shillings will buy as much as a sovereign, yet the metal in twenty shillings is worth only about the third part of a sovereign. A silver shilling is in substance worth about four pence. In like manner the metal in 240 pence, instead of being worth a sovereign, is scarcely worth the fourth part of a sovereign.— Trans. VALUE OF MONEY 169 idea of value is a relation—the relation of two interchangeable things. In the act of changing, there is an equality. If the conditions of the things change, this means that their value is changed : that of one is increased, that of the other is diminished. Suppose that yesterday I bought three loaves for sixpence, and to-day I get only one for sixpence : this means that the money which was yesterday worth three loaves is to-day worth only one. Money," says Say, “ is worth what it buys, and is worth neither more nor less." Hence the law : The price of merchandise is inversely propor¬ tional to the real value of money* This law is a consequence of that of supply and demand. The value of money being increased, there is a less supply of it, and a greater supply of the corresponding merchandise. Many Catholic economists admit, in our present economical conditions, a third value of money—namely, a value virtually productive. Money is virtually every kind of merchandise, because every kind of merchandise can be procured with it. He who has money can buy merchandise to be employed in production, and the productive virtue of the merchandise is virtually contained in the money. The consequence is that, when a man lends money to serve as a capital for production, he has a right to require interest. Let us hear Antoine :— “ Money taken on loan can, in special economical circumstances of the time, represent or not things whose use is not distinct from their substance. At one period, most of those who take it on loan do so in order to provide better for their domestic wants or their pleasures ; at another, for the needs of industry or commerce, that is, to exchange it for things whose use is distinct from their dominion. Coin is nothing but a representative of saleable things, and has no other utility for the borrower than that of the things which it represents to him. “ In the former case, money, because it represents things whose use is not distinct from their substance, has not, at ieast generally, any utility distinct from consumption. Hence every agreement by which interest is required for the sum lent is unjust. In the latter case, as it is not unjust to require, besides the capital, a compensation for the service rendered, so it is not unjust, as we have said, to claim, in addition to the restoration of the thing, a payment that corresponds to rent. “ For the rest, we shall not pause to demonstrate that, in the present economic order, money is the equivalent of an endless multitude of things productive of benefits. Once more, this would be to question the reign of modern capitalism." * Lest the meaning of this law should not be obvious to all, it may be well to observe that the higher the price of anything, the lower is the value of money, because a larger sum of money is required to buy it; and the lower the price of anything, the higher is the value of money, because a smaller sum of money suffices to buy it.— Trans. 170 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY Section IV.— Merchants ; Profits ; Wholesale and Retail Business. Merchandise is produced by the hands of a man, and it is then distributed into the hands of a hundred or a thousand men for consumption. But this distribution is not immediate. The merchandise, before reaching the hands of the consumer, passes through the hands of one or more intermediaries, who are thus carriers of it, and who are called merchants. These are true producers. Although, as we have already said, they carry the merchandise such as it leaves the hands of the producer, yet they place it in a state to be useful, with advantage both to the producer and the consumer. They have, therefore, a right to a gain or profit. This gain ought to be realised on the conditions that accompany contracts of buying and selling. They ought to buy at one price and sell at a higher. Their gain, therefore, ought to be made at the expense of the producer and the consumer, for whose advantage they exist and work. Thus commerce or traffic is found to be a field of honest and lawful gain, on which many families prosper. “ But if the service rendered by commerce is useful, yet it is not gratuitous. Everyone can ascertain the difference of price between that which is bought directly from the producer and that which is bought from the vendor. The greater the number of intermediaries the higher does this difference rise : it may arrive at a very large percentage. Therefore the tendency to reduce as much as possible the number of intermediaries is justified.” (Agnelli, Nozicmi, &c., p. 39). But even here it is necessary that the living breath of honesty, the spirit of Christianity, should animate commerce, so that it may not be injurious, but useful, to civil society. Contracts ought to be made with sincerity, on the part of the seller and also on that of the buyer. Blind speculation has unnaturalised commerce, which, instead of being for the benefit of all, is so managed as to make the opulence of a few. The art of devoting oneself to commerce has become the art of turning oneself every way. The profit of the merchant is lawful indeed, if moderate, if without fraud. The man who gives himself to commerce with unbridled conscience thinks only of making a fortune for himself as soon as possible. If he sees the chance of some extraordinary profit, he does not hesitate. Rather he consoles himself, saying : “ It is all business.” And this sort of business often means the ruin of one or more families. The world is full of such examples. Two classes of merchants present themselves in the market— the wholesale and the retail. The former come more in contact with producers, the latter with consumers. Both are useful; but too great a number of them is injurious to all. This is only CO-OPEBATIVE SOCIETIES 171 too clear. When merchandise, going its rounds, gives some profit to very many, it reaches the consumer at an exorbitant price. This man will then buy in smaller quantity, and the injury passes on to the producer, who will find less demand for his goods. Still the consumer casts an eye on them, wishing to have them ; but his means are exhausted. He is unable to procure them, and this want is a loss to other industries. It is evident, there¬ fore, that as a consequence of having a multitude of small merchants or traders, the prices of goods will become high. Section V.— Co-operative Societies. The excessive number of small merchants who speculate on the space that divides the consumer from the producer or from the wholesale merchant has given rise to two great evils. One is the adulteration of merchandise. Either the producer, to save expense in cost, or the intermediary, to create a new source of gain, can adulterate merchandise in a thousand ways. They then require payment for what it ought to be, not for what it is. Oftentimes the adulteration injures the consumer not only in his purse, but also in his health, which is affected by unwhole¬ some or poisonous ingredients. The other evil, already pointed out, is that of charging too much. These two evils are felt chiefly by the poorer classes, who, not having good means, give the preference to wares of a low price. With a view to protect such people from these two evils, Co¬ operative Societies have been established. They have the effect of lessening very much the number of intermediaries, and of bringing the producer more into contact with the consumer. If these Societies are guided and governed by honest, conscientious men, they can be a source of notable gain for the members enrolled in them. Catholics have established some of them here and there amid the blessings of the poor. Themes. —The value of wealth can be neatly defined by its power of acquisition—It is not possible that the value of all wealth should rise or fall at the same time ; while, on the other hand, it is possible that at the same time there may be an increase or decrease of prices—Every variation in the value of money carries with it an inversely proportional variation of price. CONCLUSION. Here we pause. Not at all imagining that we have finished a complete treatise on the matter in hand; but because, having regard to the object of our work, it seems to us that there is 172 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY no other road that we need travel. We have laid down principles, with arguments, from which anyone desirous of further knowledge can proceed to extensive investigations. The first steps being made from these pages, the road will at once open out to more ample studies. If others are pleased also to pause, we venture to hope that such ideas as they have here met will help them to live without being undone in society, which is troubled with so many contests. Making themselves masters of these ideas, they will be able to join in paving the way for the triumph of the Church of Christ, in winch alone is to be found the welfare of individuals and of nations. ‘T NOTES TO THE SECOND PART. Note 1, p. 103.—This mode of considering economical laws comes in a direct line from that humanism which in the 18th century was held as a dogma by philosophers of the Rousseau stamp. For them nature was everything : it had made no mistake, and it could make none. From like philosophy, Smith and Benson went on to assert that men are naturally bound by the law of solidarity, and Bastiat derived his Economical Harmonies —hideous harmonies, which sound sorrowfully in the ears of so many poor people ! The 19th century gave birth to a philosophy that has the same consequences. Spencer and Darwin declare a struggle for existence natural in the world; in which struggle it is too evident that triumph goes with the strong and defeat with the weak. If nature wishes things so, let it alone, let it pass. If it is so, says an Englishman, if the laws of the struggle for existence and the survival of the strongest should be applied as strictly to human society as to plants and animals, then, let us say it plainly, Christianity, which comes to the aid of the poor and weak, and which stretches out its hand to sinners, is mere folly. Jesus of Nazareth spoke in vain, or rather He stood up against the un¬ changeable laws of nature. (See Gregoire, Le Pape, &c., p. 108.) Note 2, p. 115.—Against the theory just stated with regard to ownership, there is an objection made, which, in appearance, is rather formidable. It runs thus :— Is it or is it not true that God gave the earth to the human race, in order to make use of it ? To assert that a man can become master even of a hand’s-breadth of land, and i can keep it from others, is to say that God created that hand’s- breadth for him alone. Can this be maintained ? The objection is propped up by some arguments from the Bible, and even by the text. The earth He has given to the children of men (Ps. cxiii. 16). Thus the difficulty takes the force of that Babylonian confusion of ideas on which it rests. We answer. It is true that God gave to all the human race every hand’s-breadth of land, and that He did not create even a thumb’s- breadth for any one man alone ; and that therefore the human race has a right to every particle of the soil. This universal right does not, however, exclude a particular right. The universal right can only be for use, which certainly is not denied to any one who observes the con¬ ditions intended by the Creator for this use. Rather, this universal right confirms and demands a par¬ ticular right of ownership. Because, as has just been shown by us, there could not be an abundance of pro¬ duce for universal use without private ownership. We may here apply the old saying : “ The big pot is the one that boils worst.” * Weiss speaks well on this subject:— “ No individual has been imme¬ diately invested by God, or as is too commonly said, by nature, with the ownership of this or that special part of the goods of the earth. Only humanity in general has been placed in possession of a real right to the whole. The individual may have a personal right to a part of the whole ; still it is a personal, not a real, right. It is only when fie succeeds, without injury to justice, in turning possibility into reality, claim into appropriation, that his * The meaning of this Italian adage seems to be that, if different kinds of meat and vegetables are put into one large pot, they will nob be so well cooked as if they were put into several small pots. So land, when held by many persons, will be better cared for than when held by only one.— Trans, 174 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY right to anything becomes a right in fact. But he does not thereby deprive society of what previously belonged to it as a whole. Nor does he, because he makes something his own, cease to be a member of society; on the contrary, he is bound to society by new chains. . . . When a man has lawfully and actually acquired the ownership of certain goods, it is not at all necessary that society should re¬ nounce its own rights.” (P. 125.) The encyclical also answers this objection very clearly :— “ That God has given the earth for use and enjoyment to the whole human race is not at all opposed to the right of private ownership. For God granted the earth to men in general, not that He wished them to have a promiscuous dominion of it, but inasmuch as He assigned no portion of it to any person in par¬ ticular, leaving that to be fixed by the industry of men and the laws of different peoples. Moreover, the earth, though divided among in¬ dividuals, remains, nevertheless, for the service and benefit of all, because there is no one in the world who is not fed by it. Those who are without property, supply for it by labour ; so that it may be truly said that the universal means of providing for the wants of life consist in labour—either on one’s own land, or at some industry, the payment for which is derived from the fruits of the earth, or from what is exchanged for them.” (Rerum novarum.) Note 3, p. 122.—It is the thought of early writers, such as Seneca, Pliny, Ammianus Marcellinus, &c., that the ruin of the Roman Empire was to be attributed, among other things, to the inhuman system of large landed estates. Fancy—104 years before Christ, 2,000 masters had the whole Roman territory in their hands. (Cicero, De Officiis, 2, 25, 73.) Under Nero, as Pliny relates, half the province of Africa was the property of six men ! Note 4, p. 124.—In August, 1893, the Abbe Lemire presented himself as a candidate for election with the following programme :—“ I wish that the house and garden, occupied by every workman and his family, and acquired by his labour, should be protected from sequestration, and should be free from imposts and from the expenses of succes¬ sion.” Note 5, p. 124.—To know that in Italy the holdings expropriated by the revenue authorities from 1888 to 1893 (only five years) for non¬ payment of taxes rose to 20,000 lire, is a thing that shocks. How many owners then became poor labourers ! Note 6, p. 125.—Rural Unions are- much the same as Trade Unions, to which they stand in the relation of species to genus. In the great abandonment and distress of the agricultural classes, there ought to be solicitude for them. It might appear that country people, by their position, as mostly small farmers, and especially as honest, timid, far removed from the dis¬ turbance of new ideas, would be insensible to the evils of isolation created by liberalism. But facts prove that, if a little later, yet no less bitterly, the waves of affliction break over them, and the storm rages in the midst of those fields which were formerly so quiet and so silent. There are here immense multi¬ tudes of poor people who, all their life long, know that they belong to *civil society only because the ex¬ chequer is mindful of them ; because the liberal or illiberal trader pre¬ pares unpleasant surprises for them ; because a new storm, which is called a crisis, bursts on their little field or vineyard; because a rumour is come to their ears that prayers and religious instruction have been pro¬ hibited in the schools, and so on. All this means, for the peasantry, that everything most dear to them must be sacrificed according to the pleasure of those who command. To bring these country people into concrete form, to put them in such a position that their influence will tell on public life, is social charity and justice. This is the object of the Rural Unions. NOTES TO THE SECOND PART 175 A model draft of Statutes for Rural Unions was approved of by the Catholic Congress of Pavia. Note 7, p. 127.—The theory of labour as a merchandise is anything but recent: it has a long beard. Before the light of the Gospel shone on the moral side of labour, it was considered only as a necessary phenomenon. Thus viewed, labour is a disgrace, as the galley chains are a disgrace. Labour was re¬ garded as a chain by the pagans, with whom labourers were slaves. The horrible fact of slavery was a consequence of pagan ideas on labour. The pagan theory of labour being renewed by our Antichristians, the same and even worse consequences follow. Labour as a merchandise has given birth to competition, to the bourse, to the market-place; it has confounded contract with justice; it has put the condition of labourers below that of slaves. The ancients bought the labourer and his labour ; they took charge of both. Our moderns buy only the labour. They separate it from the workman, who alone must think of himself, his misery, his present, and his future. Note 8, p. 133.—There is an objection made against machinery, tending to show that it is socially injurious. It is said that it takes the work from workmen, and is the mother of idlers. We admit that the introduction of new machinery may cause a special inconvenience to some per¬ sons who have therefore need of special help. But that the incon¬ venience will have vast proportions or last a long time—no ! Machinery creates new occupations, either for making or for managing itself, or because, by giving its products at a lower price, it puts consumers into a better economical position. This enables them to satisfy new wants, and to originate new manu¬ factures, requiring the employment of workers. Withal we do not venture to say that the objection thus loses all its force. We rather say that there is need of special vigilance on the part of the Government, and of various institutions, that work-people will be protected, so that machinery may be not only economically but socially useful. Note, 9, p. 139.—Those towns which have endeavoured, by the establishment of a Labour Office, to supply for the deficiencies of the law, are worthy of all praise. Note 10, p. 140.—On the very important case of accidents in labour, Italy has nothing but the poor little law of 1898, which imposes an obligation on employers to insure their labourers with the “ National Chest,” or with other institutions, or by means of associations among industrialists themselves. Note 11, p. 140.—The idea of the need of legislation on labour having entered the modern con¬ science, various projects have appeared. We do not consider it our duty to make an exposition of all. We shall merely give the chief points that are proposed by Catholic Sociology:—(i.)The maximum day’s work, ten hours for trades and the like, nine hours in mines ; (ii.) festal rest; (iii.) absolute prohibition of night work to women and children, and limitation of it to men ; (iv.) pro¬ hibition of work to children under fourteen years; (v.) absolute pro¬ hibition of unhealthy or dangerous work to women ; (vi.) prohibition of work to women on Saturday after¬ noon : and this that they may find on Sunday a true rest, a peaceful quiet, which alone is capable of restoring their strength ; (vii.) prohibition of work to women for at least six weeks before they become mothers and for four weeks after; (viii.) insurance arrangements for workmen and their families, but practical and safe arrangements, not easily to be violated by interested persons; (ix.) the appointment of a Minister of Labour, and of some minor bodies, who will facilitate for him the accomplishment of his duties in favour of the working classes. Note 12, p. 141.—Among the ancient pagans there could not 176 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY exist any protection for labour except that which was dictated by individual or social convenience. Labour was secured by means of slavery; labour was secured, but not the labourer. He was fettered. Christianity came, and kindled on earth the fire of charity and justice. Christianity, a religion pre¬ eminently social, had no need of means to guard labour ; itself alone was the strongest guardian. It threw the light of true ideas on labour. For human toil in this life, it announced a reward in the future life. It said that masters and labourers are equal before God; and on behalf of the poor working classes it raised loud the voice of justice and charity. If these instructions and precepts were reduced to practice, who does not see that labour would be pro¬ tected, as property is protected ? The rights of all would be protected. But alas ! by reason of human malice and frailty, the spirit of the Gospel does not circulate through all the windings of the social body, so as to produce its effects. And how did the Church endeavour to apply a remedy to these evils ? In the Middle Ages, it instituted corporations or guilds for the different arts and trades. A long paean might be sung in praise of the social benefits of these corpora¬ tions which the Church, in her maternal solicitude, established for the welfare of poor people. What were they ? The very name “ corporation ” tells that they were associations. They were associa¬ tions of all the workers engaged in the same trade or art. And, you may be assured, they were not sham associations. The workman depen¬ ded for everything on his guild. From it he received occupation, by it his wages were fixed, in it he was helped, and to it he had recourse for the defence of his rights. It was enough to inform the guild of an injury done him, that it should assume his defence as its own. And religion, the sure guarantee for honesty and justice, animated these guilds. Public law made account of them, and respected their decisions. Delabonna says :—These associa¬ tions formed so many families. societies, fraternities, distinguished by their banners and by their half- ecclesiastical, half-secular dress, with particular rules, their own tribunals, paid lawyers, syndics, agents, keepers, sweepers, porters, &c. Thus were distinguished at Florence, says Varchi, the societies of judges, notaries, physicians, merchants, &c. Every association or confraternity had its own head, who at Venice was called “ Gastaldo,” at Milan “ Abbot,” and at Florence “ Prior,” and each one of them had its own holy Patron painted on its banner. It was these associations that made Florence for two centuries the ideal of a democratic people, who are regarded even at the present day with envious admiration. And how does the Church now provide for the guardianship of labour ? By endeavouring to re¬ establish those old guilds, which the revolutionary storm of the last century broke up and scattered over the world. The injunctions of Leo XIII. are so well known that to record them here would be a waste of time. The anxious cares and noble efforts of many excellent Catholics, who have founded such guilds or business unions, are known, as are also known the deplorable indolence and indifference of some short-sighted ones. Note 13, p. 144.—But capital, a strong force in the hands of man, easily offers occasion for great abuses, which fall under the name of capitalism. From the analysis made of capital it follows that it ought to be an instrument of production in the service of labour, and therefore of man, and of all human society. It is by its nature a force, but a force intended to serve. If he who owns this force makes use of if to enslave labour, to domineer over society, to destroy everything according to the rule of his own wishes, what is such conduct but flagrant capitalism? At the present day, capitalism reigns supreme. Amid so many venal souls, and in the weakness to which labour is reduced by the isolation of the working classes, it is natural that capitalism should NOTES TO THE SECOND PART 177 have free play for every act of deceit, of arbitrary and arrogant dealing. It is a deity, ruling the world, and calling that its right which is only brute force. The injury that capitalism does to society is not so easily described. It is like a huge monster, more hungry after a meal than before. By means of labour, it becomes the scope of human life. To it all aspire, as to a position that is the citadel of happiness. Hence contention, demoralisation, &c. Note 14, p. 158.—Treating of wages, an expression, “ natural justice,” fell from our pen for the first time in this work. It was suggested to us by the Pontiff, who, in Rerum novarum, where he speaks of wages, says : “ Let it be granted that a workman and an employer make a bargain by mutual consent, and especially with regard to the amount of wages: there always enters an element of natural justice.” What the Pontiff means by natural justice is explained in the words following, which tell us that natural justice is “ anterior and superior to the will of the contracting parties, and it is that the remunera¬ tion should not be less than is required for the support of the workman in frugal and decent com¬ fort. If through necessity, or through fear of a worse evil, the workman agrees to harder con¬ ditions, which, being imposed by the employer or contractor, must willingly or unwillingly be accepted, this is to suffer violence, against which justice protests.” It is very evident that by natural the Pope means commutative justice. (See Bucceroni, Cas. Consc., p. 245.) For the rest, there is no want of reasons to show how properly commutative justice, which regu¬ lates the relations between master and workman in regard to wages, may be called natural. It is natural justice because it is not the law or the will of man, but nature itself, anterior and superior to every human contract, that binds to a minimum. The abandonment in which laws and social conditions have left work¬ people at the present day, has exasperated their minds. The priva¬ tions to which they are subject, the want of those very goods which are in great part the result of their labour, have raised within them a feeling that they have a right to reaction. The social atmosphere is, in the natural course of things, so formed that this plant of right grows marvellously big, often luxuriating at the cost of duty. And the work¬ people think of throwing on the capitalist the needs with which they find themselves oppressed. They say to him :—“ Either give us what we demand, or not one of us will work any more. Your manufactory will remain empty, and your capital, both fixed and circulating, will bear no fruit.” Behold the strike, which, as it is defended by the lips of liberalists or socialists, has such an absolute character of quarrel that it is altogether unworthy of men ! The capitalist and the workman appear like two giants, each armed to the teeth, and thirsting to destroy his adversary. Is the strike therefore to be absolutely condemned ? Before all things it must be remembered that the strike is accompanied with great inconveniences. It is easy to under¬ stand how the strike is a loss to the employer, who sees his capital use¬ less, and cannot meet his engage¬ ments ; to the workman, who spends his days in idleness ; and to society at large, which finds the sources of its wellbeing dried up. These are direct losses ; and they are accom¬ panied with so many other evils that it would not be easy to count them. Even this point did not escape the attention of the Pope, who says :—“ When workmen have re¬ course to a strike, it is often because the work is too long or too heavy, or because they consider the wages too low. . . . Such strikes are injurious not only to the employers and to the workmen themselves, but to trade and to the general interests of all; and, by the violence and excitement to which they give rise, often endanger the public peace.” Hence Leo XIII. shows that it is a duty of the State to keep an eye on these matters, which are serious, and to prevent them. To prevent M 178 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY them, however, not absolutely, or as if they were absolutely unjust in themselves, but by rendering re¬ course to them unnecessary. The most efficacious and salutary remedy is to be beforehand with the authority of the laws and to prevent the strike, removing in good time the causes from which it is foreseen that a conflict may arise between employers and workpeople.” (Rerum novarum.) Is a strike just ? Who can deny it ? The very theory of economic liberty has no right to proclaim it unjust. In competition everyone thinks of putting himself in a E osition to make his demands felt. iet us, however, say: We would wish society to be so constituted that a strike would be illegal, and therefore unjust; but under the regime of economic liberty this is an extreme measure, which should be tried only after other means have been exhausted. The remarks of Cardinal Manning are well known. He tells us that a strike is a kind of war; if it takes place for a just cause, it is a right, and it is inevit¬ able ; it is the only means of defence in the hands of the workingman. Note 15, p. 159.—We believe that landowners as well as peasants have a special importance in social life, and we would wish account to be made of them, so that laws and private institutions may have regard for them, and endeavour to improve their condition. Property in land has some characteristics that evidently dis¬ tinguish it from all other kinds of property. It is a true property, which makes a real cordial nearness between the owner and the thing owned. The members of a family that own a vineyard, a farm, and a country house, feel their hearts filled with a warm affection for then- property, which they regard as the basis of their life. This contributes to their stability. It helps to make them love the country in which they were born and bred—that country which is like a tender mother to them. The owner of a piece of land lets his sweat fall more abundantly on it, and more willingly sinks his capital in it, because he is not disturbed by any fear that another will right or wrong enjoy its fruits. But who, except a man perfectly secure about the future possession of his farm, will give himself to careful assiduous cultiva¬ tion, which, if it is largely remunera¬ tive, is also expensive ? Now this certainly concerns not only those engaged in rural labour, but society in general, which from no other source than from the pro¬ duce of the earth can derive the first elements of subsistence. But land cannot give these excellent advan¬ tages if it is not sufficiently and properly tilled. It is like a machine, near which nature has placed the machinist—that is, the countryman. The countryman has indeed often to undergo great fatigue ; but nature has made him compensation with special advantages, which he alone enjoys who works on the mountain side, in the vineyard, on the farm, in the pure fresh air, under the azure dome of heaven. Nor is it only the life of the body that is benefited, but also that of the soul. The lofty and spacious sky, the gilt and tinted clouds, the boundless horizon, the green fields, help wonderfully to shake off all moral torpor, to detach the heart from earthly things, and to wrap it up in a little ecstasy of spirituality. Out there in the open country the voice of God is heard, as it was heard in Eden. Hence, in the country the people are more healthy, more robust, more moral, more religious. This is a fact, and you have seen the reasons for it. It follows:—(i.) That it is well for a nation that there should be many toilers on the land. There will then be a greater produce of what is indispensable for the life of all. The country families will be so many nurseries of strong, vigorous lives. There will be blood to circulate by matrimonial alliances through cities and towns; it will keep good, and it will renew the life of the whole nation, (ii.) That the decrease in the number of hands given to agriculture, as shown by late statistics and confirmed by daily experience, is a real public misfortune. The regime of free competition NOTES TO THE SECOND PART 179 has therefore brought many evils on owners and labourers. As for the former, it is enough to consider the condition in which they find them¬ selves when they have to sell their produce. Every other seller puts a price upon his wares, and regulates it according to the cost of produc¬ tion, the expenses of storage, and his individual or domestic wants. Not so with the cultivator of land. He must expect that the market will fix the price. He cannot say : “ These grapes cost me twelve shillings a quintal; I ought to gain more than five shillings a quintal on them, that I may be able to live.” No, if the market so chooses, it will give him only eight or ten shillings a quintal. Not enough yet. The producer produces for one who, not having produce of the same kind, can give him other merchandise in exchange. This means an approaching of the producer to the consumer, which is attended with mutual advantage. Free competition has placed between these two a middleman, who speculates on the contract of barter. These middlemen are intermediate merchants, who find easy admission for their promises to spare producers the trouble of seeking buyers, and consumers that of seeking sellers. In fact they put a tax on both. They tax the former by lowering the price at which they buy in a par¬ ticular region ; they tax the latter by raising the price, so as to make them pay dearly for the service rendered by bringing the desired merchandise within their reach. This intermediate commerce, which, without due restraint under the regime of liberty, makes new re¬ cruits every day, is one of the causes that have very much injured modern agriculture. It is easy to understand how this state of affairs leads to a two-fold prostration, that of the farmer and that of the labourer. The farmer, his means exhausted, has not where¬ with to incur the expenses of a wise improved cultivation. Laden with debts, he drags out a miserable life, and makes the poor labourer drag out a still more miserable one, on whose shoulders alone he can lay a portion of his distress. Thus tillage declines, and the source of national wealth is dried up. The farmer who finds himself thus straitened, endeavours to free himself from his difficulties, and throws, as much as he can, those evils on the labourer. Hence the sad state of many country people at the present day. To come to the aid of the farmer and the labourer is therefore an urgent necessity, and it is at the same time social justice and charity. The ordering of agricul¬ tural industry will be just and profitable when this noble object is kept in view. Note 16, page 161.—Professor Toniolo, in an eloquent speech at the Congress of Padua, referred to these matters thus :—“ Mezzadria, in order to bestow its benefits, knows how to conform to social conditions, and even to agricultural science, things of themselves vari¬ able, and in this way it corresponds better to the idea of justice. If, for example, in some regions of Venetia, where the land is barren or im¬ poverished, a division of the crop in kind were made by halves, the peasant would not have so much as the necessaries of life. And else¬ where, according to the prevailing mode of culture, in which sometimes capital, sometimes labour, has a greater importance, it is natural that a larger share of the crop should fall to one party rather than the other; so that our approval, favourable to this practice, goes directly to unequal partnership in general rather than exclusively to mezzadria. But in such cases the flexibility of the mode of contract is commendable simply because it accommodates itself to equity. “ At the same time there are in this flexibility of the system some essential conditions that cannot be renounced without unnaturalising mezzadria itself. Among these, for example, is the condition that makes mezzadria a company or society, by which both the partners share in the care of the agricultural business and both divide the risks of a return. When instead the owner of the land, who ought to be an enlightened director of the work, neglects it 180 THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY altogether, leaving its cultivation to the experiments of a peasant as in Venetia, or when between himself and the peasant, who, being part¬ ners, ought to be united by the bonds of mutual confidence, a speculator steps in, such as the duty-collector of Sicily, who on the one hand legalises the absence and indifference of the master and on the other cheats and afflicts the workman, there is no longer question of accessory methods or reasonable flexibility, but of violation of the substantial justice to be expected from the contract. Thus there may be a mezzadria merely in name, but in reality a flagrant perversion of it. “ As much may be said with regard to the contributing of capital. The essence of partnership cultiva¬ tion implies that not only the returns should be shared, but also the sacrifices necessary for the agri¬ cultural work. And therefore if one party furnishes labour and personal care in cultivation, and the other, the owner, furnishes land, all the expenses for the preparation of the ground, or for the permanent improvement of it, ought, by the nature of this contract, to be borne by the owner." This fundamental contract being secured, the supply¬ ing of capital for use may vary in proportion according to circum¬ stances, through that elasticity which we have said to be just and beneficial. In which case, however, it not unfrequently happens that on lands whose crops (vines, olives, &c.) give an absolute predominance to a loving intelligent intensity of labour over a small capital for use, all this capital remains for the benefit of the proprietor, without his subtracting anything from the half of the produce justly due to the peasant. On this hypothesis, which has been happily met in Tuscany, as shown by Canon Moretti in his admirable discourse, the sacrifice or merit of the labourer equals that of the owner or capitalist, without any offence of justice. “ But when, in other parts of Italy, we see nominally and even practically maintained the division of the natural produce into half and half, yet a claim made on the peasant for the rent of a cottage built on the farm, for payment in money for the forage of his cattle in the fields, for interest often usurious in regard to the cattle, which the peasant would have been able to expend in cultivation and which the proprietor anticipated, and in fine a succession of presents to the master—in these conditions the mask of mezzadria conceals little less than real slavery with miserable wages. “ It is for this degeneration of the proper economical character of mezzadria that we intend to provide, recalling it to its Christian traditions. Let it also be observed that customs, such as that so happily existing in Tuscany and referred to by Canon Moretti, by which the produce in kind is divided into two equal parts, although the capital, whether exist¬ ing in soil improvement or technical skill, pertains to the proprietor alone, reflect a traditional Christian idea in its highest expression; and it is that the merit and dignity of the mezzadro labourer are so great as to equal the contribution of the proprietor, who gives both land and capital. The history of economy never showed a higher or more practical esteem for labour.” Note 17, p. 163.—The contract of land return offers analogous advantages. It consists in the loan that a creditor makes of a farm, binding himself never to claim it back and reserving to himself an annual pension from it. We say loan to indicate that in such a con¬ tract the tribute-payer acquires not only a use dominion, but also a direct dominion, over the farm, which, for the rest, is saleable, the annual pension being reserved. Manzi remarks that the present conditions of credit have reduced land return to an historic value, and nothing more. But even of it we ought to say, Let the old customs be revived ! M. H. Gill & Son, Limited, Dublin and Waterford.